1,354 184 75MB
English Pages 624
Digitized by the Internet Archive in
2012
http://archive.org/details/advancedcalculusOOwats
Advanced Calculus
Advanced Calculus Second Edition
WATSON FULKS University of Colorado
John Wiley
& Sons, Inc., New York
•
London Sydney Toronto •
•
Copyright
©
1961, 1969 by
John Wiley
&
Sons, Inc.
No part of this book may be reproduced by any means, nor transmitted, nor translated into a machine All Rights reserved.
language without the written permission of the publisher. 10
9
8
7
6
Library of Congress Catalog Card
SBN 471
Number :7 1-76055
28612 5
Printed in the United States of America
Comments on
the
Second Edition
No
major changes from the
first
edition have been
made
in preparing this
second edition. Misprints and errors have been corrected and passages have
been rewritten to improve the exposition. Exercises, have
Many
problems, especially the
A
been redone.
The most significant substantive changes are now mentioned. The discussion of the number system is somewhat expanded. The harder parts of the discussion of limits and continuity, previously postponed to Chapter 6, have been incorporated in Chapter 3. The Heine-Borel theorem both one- and H-dimensional has been included. Sections on the improvement of coninfinite series, both for series of constants and for Fourier vergence of an
—
—
series,
have been added. Finally, the treatment of Fourier
series
has been
generalized to cover improperly square integrable functions. I offer
my
thanks to
all
attention to errors in the
those
first
who took
edition,
and
the time
and trouble to
especially to
and Hugh Maynard who helped me with the preparation of this new
Boulder, Colorado
April 18, 1969
call
my
Harold Finkelstein edition.
Watson Fulks
to the Student
In using this book, you should give
first
attention to the definitions, for they
describe the terminology of mathematics;
and you can no more hope
to
understand mathematics without learning the voacbulary than you can hope to understand any other foreign language without learning
As with any
vocabulary.
other language, mathematics grows partly by acquiring terms
from neighboring languages
(in this case primarily English),
meanings, and appropriating them into
of the subject. Since mathematics, in language,
its
it is
itself.
modifying their
These form the technical terms
this country, is
imbedded
in the English
important to distinguish between technical and nontechnical
usage.
A
word or phrase being defined
is
set in
boldface type, as for example
uniform convergence. Theorems which have names, such as the fundamental
theorem of calculus, equal sign (=)
is
will
have these names
used in two ways.
x2 It will also
mean
means
=
set in boldface.
mean
A
triple-barred
identity, as for instance
-y 2 = (x- y)(x + y).
" defines " or "
f(x)
It will
2x
2
is
+
3
defined by."
For example,
{-1^jc^7}
that the function /is being defined in the designated interval. There
I believe, little
is,
cause for confusion arising from the ambiguous uses here
indicated. vii
To
viii
the Student
In the body of the
For
text,
occur. Unless a section
found
A
occasional reference
is
made to
exercises
by number.
instance, parenthetical remarks such as (see Exercise B7) frequently
in the first set
number
is
indicated, the exercise in question will be
of exercises following the reference.
few more words about study:
in trying to
understand a proof, you
You
should try to analyze the
should look for the driving force behind
it.
proof and decide that a certain idea (or ideas) involved proof turns on
whose presence It is
this, is
is critical,
that the
and that the remaining parts are secondary calculations
clearly
understood once the significant point
is
seen.
desirable to understand the role each proposition plays in the con-
struction of a chapter.
Which
ones,
of preliminary or secondary
you should ask
results,
which are anticlimactic ? The names
yourself, are in the nature
which are of prime importance, and
—lemma,
theorem, corollary
—provide
a rough rule of thumb, but by no means an accurate one. Finally, after all this talk, let
it
be said that no amount of directions on
how
to study can begin to replace a real and growing interest in the material.
Watson Fulks
to the Teacher
This book
is
designed to serve as an introduction to analysis.
have made an
To
this
end
I
backed by geometrical
effort to present analytical proofs
and to place a minimum of reliance on geometrical arguments. In some stress is laid on this in the body of the text. I have not succeeded completely in avoiding some essential use of intuition in the proofs, but I intuition,
fact,
have localized
my
serious transgressions to Chapter 13 wherein are located
Green's, Gauss', and Stokes' theorems and
Like most
my
action.
who
My
defense
would involve more
some of their consequences.
from the narrow path of
stray
is
virtue, I seek to rationalize
simply that to avoid such geometrical arguments
difficult
work than
I feel is
advisable. In attempting to
hold to a course between the heuristics of elementary calculus on the one hand, and the rigor of function theory and topology on the other,
chosen to err in the direction of heuristics in Chapter this
is,
of course, that what
I sacrifice
in logic I
hope
13.
I
have
The motivation
for
to gain in pedagogy.
So much for apologies.
The book
is
divided into three parts, beginning with calculus of functions
of a single real variable. In aspects of the theory.
this part I delineate
The most novel
feature
some of the more is
integral of a continuous function without the use of
makes ties
significant
perhaps the proof of the
uniform continuity. This
possible postponement of the discussion of the
more
difficult
proper-
of continuous functions until the students have gained some maturity. ix
x
To
the Teacher
The middle
part
is
begins with a chapter
concerned with the calculus of several variables.
on
notation consistently and,
It
and uses vector terminology and vector hope, effectively. Chapter 1 1 which is concerned
vectors, I
,
with inverse functions and transformations, contains a proof of the inversion
theorem which
an adaptation of a new proof by Professor H. Yamabe
is
{American Mathematical Monthly LXIV, 1957, pages 725-726), a proof which
can be carried over to certain types of
The
third
and
last
part of the
book
infinite is
dimensional spaces.
concerned with a treatment of the
theory of convergence as applied to infinite series and improper integrals.
The Cauchy criterion forms the basis for a unified treatment of these topics. The problems in each set are classified as A, B, or C Exercises. This classification is to
problems. The
be taken as an approximate grading of the
A
though the computations are
difficulty
of the
Exercises are straightforward applications of the theory, in
somewhat deeper, and
some of them may be a little
the
C
long.
The B
Exercises
Exercises in general are intended to challenge
the better students.
present
I
influence of I
no bibliography, though I must of course acknowledge the books, old and new, upon the shape this one has assumed.
many
gratefully
acknowledge the influence of colleagues with
the manuscript. In particular,
with
who
whom
I
held a
read critically
I
whom I
discussed
must mention Professor Warren Stenberg,
number of conversations and Professor Jack ;
Indritz,
large portions of the manuscript.
Watson Fulks
Contents
PART
CALCULUS OF ONE VARIABLE
I
Chapter
1
The Number System
1.5
The Peano axioms Rational numbers and arithmetic The real numbers completeness Geometry and the number system Bounded sets
1.6
Some
1.7
Absolute value
1.1
1.2 1.3 1
.4
:
Chapter 2 2.1
points of logic
Functions, Sequences, and Limits
1
3 3 5 8 12
14
16
77
22
Mappings, functions, and sequences
22
26
2.2
Limits
2.3
Operations with limits (sequences)
33
2.4
Limits of functions
39
2.5
Operations with limits (functions)
44
2.6
Monotone sequences Monotone functions
48
2.7
50
Contents
xii
Continuity, Differentiability, and
Chapter 3
More
Limits
Uniform continuity
54 54
3.1
Continuity.
3.2
Operations with continuous functions
58
3.3
The intermediate-value property
59
3.4
Inverse functions
61
3.5
Cluster points. Accumulation points
67
3.6
The Cauchy
71
3.7
Limit superior and limit inferior
76
3.8
Deeper properties of continuous functions
79
3.9
The derivative. Chain rule The mean- value theorem
83
3.10
Chapter 4
criterion
Integration
88
99
99
4.1
Introduction
4.2
Preliminary lemmas
101
4.3
The Riemann
107
4.4
Properties of the definite integral
116
4.5
The fundamental theorem of calculus
727
4.6
Further properties of integrals
124
The Elementary Transcendental Functions
Chapter 5 5.1
5.2 5.3
integral
The logarithm The exponential function The circular functions
Chapter 6
Properties of Differential Functions
129 129
132 136 148
6.1
The Cauchy mean- value theorem
148
6.2
L'Hospital's rule
150
6.3
Taylor's formula with remainder
755
6.4
Extreme values
161
PART
VECTOR CALCULUS
167
Vectors and Curves
169
7.1
Introduction and definitions
169
7.2
Vector multiplications
775
182
II
Chapter 7
7.3
The
1A
Linear independence. Bases. Orientation
186
7.5
Vector analytic geometry
190
triple
products
Contents 7.6
Vector spaces of other dimensions:
1.1
Vector functions. Curves
7.8
Rectifiable curves
7.9
Differentiate curves
Chapter 8 8.1
8.2
En
192
196
and arc length
198 201
Functions of Several Variables. Limits and Continuity
A little A little
xiii
topology: open and closed sets
more topology: sequences, cluster accumulation points, Cauchy criterion
210 210
values,
214
8.3
Limits
220
8.4
Vector functions of a vector
223
8.5
Operations with limits
226
8.6
Continuity
227
8.7
Geometrical picture of a function
230
Differentiable Functions
234
Chapter 9
234
9.1
Partial derivatives
9.2
Differentiability. Total differentials
9.3
The gradient
vector.
The
241
del operator. Directional
248
derivatives 9.4
Composite functions. The chain
9.5
The mean-value theorem and Taylor's theorem
9.6
The divergence and
251
rule
for
259
several variables
Chapter 10 10.1
curl of a vector field
Transformations and Implicit Functions. Extreme Values
Transformations. Inverse transformations
261
267
267
10.2
Linear transformations
269
10.3
The
276
inversion theorem
10.4
Global inverses
284
10.5
Curvilinear coordinates
285
10.6
Implicit functions
289
10.7
Extreme values
294
10.8
Extreme values under constraints
297
Chapter 11
303
Multiple Integrals
11.1
Integrals over rectangles
303
11.2
Properties of the integral. Classes of integrable functions
310
11.3
Iterated integrals
311
11.4
Integration over regions. Area and
volume
316
xiv
Contents
Line and Surface Integrals
Chapter 12
325
12.1
Line integrals. Potentials
325
12.2
Green's theorem
336
12.3
Surfaces.
12.4
Surface integrals.
12.5
Stokes' theorem. Orientable surfaces
357
12.6
Some
363
12.7
Change of variables
PART
Area
345
The divergence theorem
351
physical heuristics
365
in multiple integrals
THEORY OF CONVERGENCE
111
Chapter 13
373
375
Infinite Series
13.1
Convergence, absolute and conditional
13.2
Series with non-negative terms:
13.3
Series with non-negative terms. Ratio
Comparison
375 tests
and root
tests.
379
386
Remainders 13.4
Series with variable signs
389
13.5
More
392
delicate tests
13.6
Rearrangements
394
13.7
Improvement of convergence
400
Chapter 14
Sequence and Series of Functions. Uniform Convergence
408
408
14.1
Introduction
14.2
Uniform convergence
409
14.3
Consequences of uniform convergence
415
14 .4
Abel's and Dirichlet's tests
423
14.5
A
427
theorem of Dini
Chapter 15 15.1
The Taylor
Power
Series
series. Interval
of convergence
430 430
436
15.4
Properties of power series The Taylor and Maclaurin series The arithmetic of power series
15.5
Substitution and inversion
455
15.6
Complex
457
15.7
Real analytic functions
15.2 15.3
series
442
447
460
Contents
Improper Integrals
Chapter 16 16.1
Improper
xv
463
Conditional and absolute
integrals.
convergence
463
16.2
Improper
471
integrals with non-negative integrands
16.3
The Cauchy
16.4
An
16.5
Improper multiple
474
principal value
475
alternation test
Chapter 17
integrals
477
-
Integral Representations of Functions
483
17.1
Introduction. Proper integrals
483
17.2
Uniform convergence
487
17.3
Consequences of uniform convergence
493
Gamma
Chapter 18
and Beta Functions. Laplace's Method and Formula
Stirling's
509 509
18.3
The gamma function The beta function Laplace's method
18.4
Stirling's
18.1
18.2
Chapter 19
512 515
formula
520 523
Fourier Series
19.1
Introduction
19.2
The
class
ffl 2
523 •
Approximation
in the
mean.
Bessel's
529
inequality 19.3
Some
19.4
Convergence theorems
19.5
Differentiation
19.6
Sine and cosine series.
19.7
Improvement of convergence
552
19.8
The Fourier
554
19.9
Function spaces. Complete orthonormal
useful
lemmas and
532
536
integration.
Uniform convergence
Change of
544 548
scale
integral sets
560
Elementary Differentiation and Integration Formulas
567
Answers, Hints, and Solutions
569
Index
593
Advanced Calculus
PARTI
CALCULUS OF ONE VARIABLE
CHAPTER
1
The Number System
The Peano Axioms
/./
Any is
study of mathematical analysis has
its
basis in the
number
therefore important for students of analysis to understand
metic can be developed from the natural numbers (another positive integers). It
here however, ;
is
how
system.
It
the arith-
name
for the
not our intention to carry out such a development
we do want to make some comments about the logical structure
of that development.
A
standard starting point in the development of the real numbers
certain set of axioms that were
first
is
a
formulated by the Italian mathematician
Peano. These axioms state that the natural numbers
satisfy certain properties.
From only these properties, making appropriate definitions as we proceed, we can develop all the usual rules of arithmetic. In the terminology of formal logic, we have a set of undefined objects that we choose to name the natural numbers, satisfying Peano's axioms. This means merely that the natural
numbers are taken terms of which
as the basic
"atoms" of our mathematical system
in
we express the other mathematical concepts, but which are
themselves not expressed in more fundamental terms.
Perhaps an easier way to visualize the situation, since after
all
claim that you never heard of arithmetic or rational numbers,
you cannot is this
can verify that the positive integers are a system of objects that do
:
We
satisfy the
5
The Number System
4
Peano axioms.
We
can
now
proceed to recapture
all
we know of arithmetic,
using only those properties stated explicitly in the axioms.
The
five
Peano axioms
follow.
Axiom
1.
Axiom
2.
Axiom
3.
The number
Axiom
4.
If two natural numbers have equal successors, they are themselves
a natural number.
is
I
To every natural number n there is associated another natural number n' called the successor of n.
equal. That is,ifn'
Axiom
= m\
1 is not
Suppose that
5.
=
then n
M
is
in
a unique way
a successor of any natural number.
m.
a collection or set of natural numbers with the
properties 1 is in
(i)
Then
M,
n' is in
(ii)
M whenever n M
the collection
is in
consists
M.
of all natural numbers.
Here equality is used in the sense of numerical identity that is, m = n means that m and n are symbols standing for the same number. Thus we ;
take (i) (ii) (iii)
m — m, m = n implies that n = m, m = n, n = k implies that m = k,
as part of the underlying logic
and do not
list
these as part of our set of
numerical axioms.
Notice that
this list
of properties does not contain any explicit statement
of the linear ordering of numbers. There tinguished by not being a successor. turns out to be n the
way
addition
numbers must 2, 3, 4, 2'
.
.
+ is
line
1
after addition has
defined.
up
after
We 1
is
a "first" one, namely
The successor
n'
been defined. In fact
this is essentially
can then proceed to show that the natural
in their familiar order:
are not given in the axioms, they are defined
.
dis-
1,
of a natural number n
(Since
1, 2, 3, 4,
by 2
=V=1+
1,
3
=
= 2+1,....) Axiom
5 is precisely the principle
of mathematical induction.
It
is
an
important tool in the technical development of the properties of the number
we have been discussing. We shall have occasional use for this principle later, and we shall see that the statement of Axiom 5 is equivalent to the more familiar one given in elementary texts. As indicated earlier, we can start with the natural numbers and, knowing system that
only the properties and relationships stated by the axioms, derive arithmetic.
Why
do you suppose mathematicians
all
of
are interested in starting
Rational Numbers and Arithmetic
m+
from such primitive beginnings ? Are
n
=
n
+ m and m-
truer because they can be derived as a consequence of the sense, quite the contrary
is
from them we can derive
The axioms
true.
m+n=n+m
addition and multiplication), and
One
=
n-
m
any
axioms ? In one
are "true" or valid because
m
and
•
n
=
m
n
(after defining
the other standard rules of arithmetic.
all
aspect of such an approach
n
5
is
aesthetic:
it
gives a clean, beautiful
development of a well-known and useful body of knowledge from simple, precisely stated foundations.
Another somewhat more pragmatic
What
we
result is that
it
serves to help answer
do mathematics without a precise foundation, a "proof" may be any convincing argument, based on what one " knows." But since this knowledge is not well formulated, this may lead to the question,
a proof? If
is
try to
Theorem A may be based eventually on Theorem B, Theorem B may be based on Theorem C, and Theorem C eventually based on circular arguments:
A
again. If the proofs are long
and involved,
it
may
be
spot such
difficult to
Having a well-formulated axiom system reduces the of such mistakes. A proof becomes a logical argument based
circular arguments. possibility
on the axioms, or on previous theorems based on the axioms. Of
directly
course there
is
always the possibility of
human
error, for
everyone makes
mistakes but at least this approach gives a clearer idea of what ;
we
seek in a
proof.
In any case, this
is
an example of what
the study of mathematics.
By
this
is
called the axiomatic approach to
we mean merely
that the whole of a certain
section of mathematics has been reduced to a few statements, plete structure
and the com-
can then be unfolded from these by a study of the logical
consequences of these statements.
Rational Numbers and Arithmetic
1.2
After the salient properties of the natural numbers have been developed, the next step
numbers, you
is
the introduction and study of rational numbers. Rational
will recall, are those
numbers
that can be represented as ratios
of whole numbers; in other words, rational numbers are
We list
common
below certain properties of rationals that can be deduced
fractions.
in the
course
of their development from the natural numbers. Thus these properties of rational
The So a
>
numbers are
actually consequences of the
Peano axioms.
read "
is
greater than," precludes the possibility of equality.
b means that a
is
greater than b. Thus, in particular, a
sign
>
,
is
not equal to
:
:
The Number System
6 b.
The
where, of course, the pi's need not be distinct. This, however, tion to the hypothesis, since n 1.3 b
There
Corollary.
You
are,
as points
is
is
is
a contradic-
expressed as the square of a natural number. |*
no rational number whose square
is 2.
of course, familiar with the geometrical interpretation of numbers
on a
line.
For the purpose of emphasizing certain aspects of
this
we review its main features here. On a straight line we choose and call the origin. We take a convenient unit of a point that we mark length, and to each number x we make correspond the point whose distance from is x measured to the right if x is positive and to the left if x is negative.
interpretation,
Let us note that the arithmetical law
a> finds 1
,
Pz on a
then Pi
Now,
b
>
P
line: If
to the right of
lies
given any rational
P3
to x. Let
U contain
and
number
of
x, the set
all
P2
to the right of
second class
number x
number x
L and
each
R contain all
U
first class
member of L
P on
x and
let
L
contain
itself in either
is
all
the
U or L but not
is less
R
into
classes in
than every
and
L
all
(right
member of
U.
points of the line can be
and
left)
with respect to
points to the right of P and
of P, with the point
let L contain all points to the P itself in either R or L but not in both. For all points
the separation or cut leads to a partition of the line into
that each point in the
L and
two
greater than every element of the
the line, the set of
separated into two subsets or classes
Now
,
and lower) with respect
numbers
divides the rational
the
Similarly for any point
class
P3
numbers can be
rational
U and L (upper
the rationals greater than
all
which each member of
P
c
Such a separation or cut of the rational numbers associated with a
given rational
left
>
.
rationals less than x, with the rational
P. Let
P2
to the right of
lies
t
separated into two subsets or classes
in both.
a
implies
c
geometrical counterpart in the following statement about points
its
P ,P2
b,
first class
each point in
there are points
we mark
L is
R
is
then to the
on the
two
classes such
to the right of every point in the second
fine that
left
of every point in R.
do not correspond
whose distance from
to any rational
we
see
by
Corollary 1.3b that there can be no rational number corresponding to
it.
number. For In
fact, it is
if
not very
that correspond to *
The symbol |
no
will
the point
difficult to
rational
show
is
y/2,
that there are infinitely
number. This means that
be used to denote the end of a proof.
It
if
many
we mark
all
replaces Q.E.D.
points
points
The Real Numbers: Completeness
11
on the line that correspond to rational numbers, there are infinitely many unmarked points left over. Actually, in every interval of the line there are points corresponding to rational numbers and points that correspond to no numbers
rational
(see Exercises
C3 and C4
in Section 1.7).
These considerations lead to the recognition of the existence of gaps or a lack of continuity or completeness in the distribution of rational numbers as
compared with the
on a
distribution of points
line.
We
accept as a basic fact
of geometry that points are continuously distributed on a there are
but take
no gaps or incompletenesses it
in the line.
For
this
line; that
we
offer
is,
that
no proof,
as a geometric axiom.
Although we
no proof of this concept of the continuous distribution of points on a line, we do want to formulate it in a precise form that we can use in our discussion of the number system. The formulation we use is due to the
offer
German mathematician Dedekind, whose
closely.
treatment
Dedekind uses the separation or cut described
the completeness of the line. His formulation
Suppose that
all
is
we
are following
earlier to characterize
as follows.
points on the line are separated into two
nonempty
classes
R is to the right of every point in L. Then there is exactly one point P that produces this cut, and P itself is either the rightmost
R
and
L
so that each point in
point of L or the leftmost point of R.
We offer no proof for this statement, any more than we do for the statement on the line. We take this to be merely
that points are continuously distributed
a precise statement of that continuity or completeness, a formulation that
adapted for the purpose of considering the analogous questions for the
is
dis-
tribution of numbers.
The analogous statement for rational numbers cannot be true. To see this, we need only give one example where it fails, and this example we now describe.
Let the upper class U, corresponding to positive rationals
other rationals. Suppose that the cut
Then
it is
R
for the line, be the set of
whose squares are greater than
possible to
show
is
1
.3b.
of the completeness axiom of the
and
let
L
be
all
all
the
produced by a rational number
(the technical
But this contradicts Corollary
2,
proof will be
omitted) that x = 2
x. 2.
Thus we see that the analogue for rationals,
line, is
not correct.
The final big step in the development of the number system is to define numbers to fill the gaps displayed by the previous remarks. These new numbers are called irrational numbers. The system of numbers consisting of the rationals and irrationals together is called the real-number system. Thus a real number can be either rational or irrational. From now on the term "number" will stand for a real number unless otherwise stated.
The Number System
12
The will
details involved in carrying out the definition of the
We
be omitted.
number
want to emphasize two important
facts
new numbers
about the
real-
system. First, the notions of addition and multiplication can be
defined for real numbers so as to satisfy the properties listed for rationals
under
I
and
II
of Section 1.2; that
we read
is, if
"real
number"
in place
of
"rational number," the conclusions stated there remain true. Second, and
very important, the real-number system
is
complete; that
axiom on the completeness of the
the geometrical
line
is,
the analogue of
can be proved as a
theorem.
Dedekind's Theorem.
///.
two nonempty classes
R
number
in
L. Then there
number
in
L and less
We ments
Suppose that
and L, so
all real
number
that each
a real number x that
is
than or equal to every
numbers are divided
in
R
is
greater than or equal to every
is
number
in
R.
designate this by the numeral III for the following reason. listed
section,
under
I
and
II
of Section
1
.2,
The
state-
together with III of the present
can be taken as an axiom system for the description of the
numbers. That
is, all
properties of the real
into
greater than every
real
numbers can be developed from
these statements alone.
The
scientific
outlined here
importance of the development of the real-number system
is,
of course, that
a cleanly laid out, logical form. the analogy between real
1.4
Geometry and
Analysis
is
puts a large body of useful knowledge into
numbers and points on a
removes analysis from any theorems of calculus can
it
We also want to emphasize that it strengthens
logical
now be
the
the
same time
dependence on geometry. All the basic
given purely arithmetical proofs.
Number System
that branch of mathematics that
is
with limiting operations. Mathematicians, as you last section, like to
line, yet at
concerned with
may have
limits
and
surmised in the
base their study of analysis on arithmetic, with no logical
dependence on geometry. However, as you already know, geometrical pictures can be very enlightening when you are attempting to solve many types of
no objection to using such devices; indeed you should be use them. But use them as guides that give insight, and not, if
problems. There
encouraged to
is
you can possibly avoid
it,
as essential parts of an argument.
Geometrical language, with useful
its
highly suggestive power, can also be very
and can be given arithmetical meaning.
We
define a few geometrical
Geometry and
the
Number System
13
terms here, and others occur intermittently throughout the rest of the book. This, of course, out.
is
an attempt to exploit the geometric analogy we have pointed
We thus rely heavily
we avoid any
well, except in
reasonably essential
We
on geometry
essential use of
Chapter
in
our arguments. In
When we do
13.
way, we are careful to point
where possible
for our inspiration, but
geometry
this
we succeed
lean on geometry in any
this out.
proceed to define a number of geometrical terms. Since there are quite
a few of these, you will want to refer back to this section until you become familiar with
We
these terms.
all
speak of the real-number system as a one-dimensional space, and of
course
we
visualize
it
as a line.
In one-dimensional space
A
point set
An
interval
we
use the
word
point to
mean
" number."
a collection of points.
is
is
a point set described by inequalities of one of the following
types
{a {a fa {a
^ ^ <
if
n
we choose
N=
\/e
TV,
2
N
n
This completes the solution.
Example 3 f(x)
We that
= yJx(Jx~+\
assume that for every x
is,
there
proved in a It will
is
>
a unique positive
D
-Jx\
there
:
{x
>
0}
a unique positive square root;
is
number y
which y 2
for
=
x.
This
will
be
later chapter (see Section 3.4).
know
also be convenient to
a
which we leave as an
2
that
> a>
if
>
a
Ja >
1,
1,
exercise.
Now
y*
i '
y/x+l + from which
it
Jx~
y/\+
seems clear that the
(1/JC)
limit
+
is ^.
1
Hence we consider
/(*)-
Vl +
(1/x)
+
yu a/*) +
2
2
1
l+0/x)-l_ Vl+(l/*)-l < 2(1 + 1) 2(7l + (1/x) + 1) So
if
we
take
XXo
be l/4a or larger, and x
/(*>--
i
X, then i
Tx < 4x^
theorem that establishes a
1
4x
e-
limit very useful for
comparison
Exercises 2. 2d
Theorem.
Proof. Let
=
jc
31
Mw^^Kjjjhery^Jm \/a
—
1.
Then x >
and 1
so for n
^
11
1
=
a
(1
where the
first
inequality
\a
n \
is
=
+
x)
n
^
1
+
— nx 1
< nx
by Bernoulli's inequality. Thus
a
n
X8
A 1.
Exercises Determine whether the following sequences have limit
A
\a n
where
a„
is
-A\ N,
(e)
+\
-Y-. rr + n
A
exists
i
COS cos x.
x {d)
2.3
+\
>
^ then a 2
3.
Prove that
4.
Define lim x _»_ „ f(x).
if
a
1,
limits at infinity. In
JC
(c)
(b)
+ 2,-1
n
•••
rr
Jt
1
cos -
0)
> a > Va >
1.
2* 3
+
+
2
3
Jt
+ -• rr
each case
x>X.
if
a:
2
rr
determine an X(e) such that
\f(x)-A\
oo,
and /(x) ^ #0) ^
h(x).
co.
^0,
n 3 /2 n
^0,
n A \2 n ->0.
(//////:
See Example
2.)
Show
that
Operations with Limits {Sequences)
Show
3.
2
n
that n a ->0,
«V^0,
4
and n a"-+0
above and see the proof of Theorem
there
But n k
^
is
We know
be the limit of the sequence {an }.
that for each
N for which
an
A\
>
if
n
if
k
if
k>N.
N.
k; hence
N
>
N.
Thus
-A\ =
\b k
The following
Theorem.
2.3b
a constant
is
Proof. Let a
=
|
are a collection of standard operational theorems with
which you should become
there
-A\N.
(Why?)
Then
\>\an -a\>\an \-\a\.
(Why?)
Thus \an
(1)
-b\.
\a\\b n
e2
and zero.
make
7V2 such that
\a„
-
a\
N
|6„
-
6|
N2
t
and
Thus
ifn>N= max (JVj, 7V2
from
(3)
\a n
From
bn
-
ab\
this proof,
)
(that
is,
^ Me +
|a|e 2
-s
l
is
2(M +
2(| fll
+
1
N
i-
(Why?)
Then
IM> (4)1*1 Hence
for
n> N
if
n>N,.
(Why?)
t
1
1
b„-b
K
~b
Kb
0.
Show by examples Show
+«
i /
(v
is
*2
1
r
(c)
9.
Vln+l-Vn.
.(./rri-,y
Show
8.
(d)
«
/i
+ 3)
3.
7.
1
3
Exercises
that
6.
and Limits
Functions, Sequences,
which a„ k
$s 0.
Do
and the
Theorem
What
{b n } are divergent sequences, then {a„
same
for {an
—b
2.3g remains valid
modification can
now
and
n)
if
be
+ b„}
{a„/b„}.
there
made
is
in
a subsequence
Theorem 2.3h?
39
Limits of Functions
C 1.
Exercises Show
that
if
and
{a n } converges to zero
{b n }
is
bounded, then {a n b„} converges
to zero. 2.
Evaluate the limit of each of the following sequences.
H ((^)"| (b)
*>y>o. aj>0J=l,2,...k.
ful^J],
x^y>0. ( 1.
= 1 + h and use the binomial theorem.) = (1/n) 2" and show that lim u = a.
(Hint: Set ^/*
n
= a.
Show by examples
that the converse of (a)
Set o n
sequences {a„} such that lim a n
2.4
o-i
= a,
n
,
is
not true; that
but lim a„ does not
is,
there are
exist.
Limits of Functions
For some positive h,
let/(x) be defined in the interval /: {a
except possibly at the point a
borhood of
a.
itself.
Then a number
a (or as * approaches a\ [6 of course depends
on
|/(jc)
We
,
Suppose that lim a n
e,
if
That is,/(x)
is
-A\
there
is
a number
frequently written
00
x
[-»©]
Exercises Evaluate
V(a +
bx)(c
+ 0
2.
Evaluate Vim X->
00
Ux-Vx-yJx+ Vx).
— x ^ for all x > 0, If oxy + by ^ for all x,
If
ax
2
a:
2
>>,
show that a < show that a =
Recall (Section 2.1) the definition of
[x].
6
^
.x-o +
0.
that, for
X 6
-, lim
a
0,
Show
6
lim x-0 + a
1.
# x
a>0, b> 0,
= 0.
Discuss the left-hand limits of these functions.
= e llx for x i^ Set /(x) = e llx /(e llx — 1) x/(x) at x = 0. Set/(x)
C
and discuss the one-sided
x
^
Discuss the one-sided limits at
x
for
and
=
limits of /at
of arc tan
1/x.
Exercises
1.
Prove that
2.
Evaluate
[
^j/x ->
1
as
x
-> oo. (See Exercise
C3 of
Section 2.3.)
V(\+aixKl+a 2 x)---(\+anX)-\ lim x-0
x
— 0.
discuss the one-sided limits of
/and
of
48 3.
Functions, Sequences,
Let x a be the root of ax 2
and Limits
+ bx + c = that has the smaller absolute value. = — c/6 = the root of the limit equation.
6t^0, then \\rc\ a ^ x a happens to the other root? that
4.
if
Prove the " converse " of Theorem 2.4a that x„ -+a, then lim x ^
fl
/(» =
:
If /(*„) ->
A
Show What
for every sequence {*„} such
A.
Monotone Sequences
2.6
A very important class of sequences are monotone or monotonic sequences, More
those that steadily increase or decrease.
monotone-increasing
if its
a n + \^an In the that
case
first
we
sequence {an }
is
elements an satisfy an inequality of the form or
an + 1
>a
n
w=l,2,
,
say that the sequence
nondecreasing. In the second case
it is
precisely, a
....
weakly monotone-increasing or
is
we
say that the sequence
is
strictly
increasing. Monotone-decreasing or nonincreasing sequences are defined
by
reversing the inequalities.
In particular, it
if
a sequence
is strictly
increasing
weakly increasing; but the converse
is
Thus any theorems established
—that
is,
an+1
>
an
—then
of course not necessarily true.
is
for weakly increasing sequences apply to
strictly increasing ones.
We
which
establish the following theorem,
is
a consequence of Theorem
1.5b.
Theorem.
2.6a
Then lim a n
exists
Let {an } be a nondecreasing sequence that
lim an Proof. Since {a n }
by Theorem
1.5b.
want
Let
e
to
>
Hence, for
show
is
=
sup an
a set of numbers that
.
is
that
A
sup an
bounded above, sup an
.
of a
satisfies the definition
be given. By Theorem 1.5a, there
n>
bounded above.
Let
A =
We
is
and
aN
>A —
an
^
aN
A ^
a„
>A -
is
e.
TV,
A ^
>A —
or £,
e,
limit.
an TV for which
exists
Monotone Sequences
49
or, finally,
^A -
N
if
Hence, certainly,
-a \
n
if
n
N.
I
Let {an } be a nonincr easing sequence bounded below,
Then lim an exists and lim an
The proof of
=
an
inf
.
this corollary is similar to that
These simple but important use throughout this book.
of Theorem 2.6a.
powerful tool that we
results supply us with a
As an example,
let
us consider the sequence given
by a„
(You
will see that
series
X?
=l+ we
l
11 - + - =Z "
1
+ 2T+3 + i
o
!
1
^.
are really discussing the convergence of the infinite
1/^9
Clearly
a" +
Hence an+l
show
that
*«
>
an
it is
=
1
,
>a
=
a"
(7TT)!
so that the sequence
monotone-increasing. Let us
is
now
bounded above:
111 + + +-+ -"+ l+-ill + ?+ + +— 1
+ 1+
2!
-4(-3(-D-(«-H
—
a
This, of course,
form from your
is
an idea with which you are already familiar
earliest
in a primitive
concept of a function, because most of the functions
with which you are familiar are continuous, except possibly at a few points.
A function may fail to /may
be continuous at a point a for any of three reasons:
not be defined there; the limit
the limit exists, then the
a.
That
is, it
it may still happen that it is left-continuous may be that
lim /(*)
54
not exist; or if/ is defined at a and
two may not be equal.
If/is not continuous at a point a,
or right-continuous at
may
=
/(«)
55
Continuity. Uniform Continuity
or
lim /(*)
=
/(0.
is,
Clearly /(x)
is
x=
left-continuous at
x=
right-continuous at
we
0. If
limits there,
=
+
1
sgn x (see Section 2.1)
It
.
— 1 and + 1
namely
,
we had taken/(0) = +1, it would be
0. If
take f(0) as anything
x=
neither left nor right continuity at
f(x)
= 0.
0,
although
then f(x) has
else,
has
it
left
and right-hand
respectively. In particular, for the function
we have /(0 -
0)
= - 1,
=
/(0)
0,
/(0
+
0)
should be clear that a necessary and sufficient condition that
continuous at x
=
a
is
that
it
be both
left-
=
/ be^
and right-continuous. (See Theorem
2.4b.)
The
definition of continuity
been defined in for
e,
S terms.
many purposes
A each
depends on the concept of a
We
better to
it is
—
function /, defined in {x e
>
there
a
is
<
jR,
and
let
are so related that
and $[/(*)] = x for every x in D, then $ is The basic inverse-function theorem is the
said to be the inverse function of/.
following.
Theorem.
3.4a
(y).
= y.
3.3b, for
on {a
increasing
then there
< y ^ /?},
each y in {a
continuous function
is
which
U{x)-]
=
(y)
= x.
on
a unique inverse function
/?} j>,
is strictly
there
and
is
will
increasing
exactly one
be denoted
*
62
and More Limits
Continuity, Differentiability,
Taking /of both
sides,
we
get
/WOO] -/(*)Hence the unique function
We yi
can see that
> y>i
>
an d
cj)(y) is
Choose y y and y 2 say Then
increasing, as follows.
is strictly
x t and x 2
let
the inverse of/,
,
respectively, be the corresponding x's.
,
suppose, for contradiction, that
=
*i
Taking /of both
sides,
is
—
^(jo the
•
=J(x )^f(x 2 )=y 2
.
l
we
the continuity,
strict
monotonicity of
.
use a contradiction argument again. Suppose
discontinuous at some point y in {ct^y^p}. Then either 0) < (j)(yo) or (y 2 )
a contradiction, and hence establishes the
To prove that
-
(yo)
For every
x2
;
where b
2
>y
.
(How
byf(x)
= x2
on
can we be sure that
Now on this interval/is strictly increasing:
then
x\
—
x\
= Oq —
x 2 )(x 1
+
x2)
>
0,
x x — x 2 > 0. It is also continuous hence a unique inverse exists. This means that for every y in {0 < y ^ b 2 } there is a unique x such that x 2 = y. since
;
This holds in particular for the given y
By
the
|
.
same type of argument, we can prove the existence of a unique nth
root of any nonnegative number. Since integral powers are also defined,
now
can
define
what we mean by \l~cT
a"
/m
namely ^fa
,
= {^Ja) m
(Exercise
n .
It is
easy to see that
B\ 1).
somewhat more difficult to define a x for arbitrary x. This will be poned to the chapter on the elementary transcendental functions.
It is
A 1.
we
post-
Exercises Determine whether the following functions are continuous indicated. In each case is
where the function
uniformly continuous. (x 2 ,
(a)
fix) (*,
0 n
+ 1 and — 1, e of — 1
l,2,3,....
no one number A such that xn 's do cluster around two distinct
limit, for there is
>
so that for any s
Such a point
.
The
=
w
for large n. But the
and others within
value of the sequence.
+
there are x„'s within e of
precise definition follows.
called a cluster point or cluster value of the sequence {xn } if
is
a subsequence {x„ k } converging to
Similarly, if/ is defined in a deleted
A
:
neighborhood of a, we say that
cluster point or cluster value of /at a if there is a sequence {xn } with
which f(x n ) -> A. For example, the function f(x)
hood of
the origin
sequence {x n }
A
=
and has
{[2/(4«
+
+1
=
sin l/x
is
A
-+
if
A
is
a cluster value
every sequence {x„} with xn -*
is
a
a for
defined in a deleted neighbor-
as a cluster value at 0. If
l)rc]}, this is
xn
we
consider the
immediate.
limit of a sequence or a function is a cluster point or cluster value.
the other hand,
+
called a cluster point or cluster
is
of/
at a, then
a, it is true that
A=
f(xn ) -+A
lim x ^ a f(x)
if
On for
(see Exercise C4,
Section 2.5).
We define a similar concept for sets: set
S
if
point a
a point a
is
an accumulation point of a
every deleted neighborhood of a contains points of S. Note that the itself
may
or
may
not be a
We come to the basic theorem
member of the
on
cluster
set S.
and accumulation
points,
namely
—^—
the Bolzano-Weierstrass theorem.'*
fi
3.5a
Theorem.
A bounded infinite
and a bounded sequence has
set has at least
at least one cluster point.
one accumulation point,
68
and More Limits
Continuity, Differentiability,
We
write out the
sets. The proof for sequences is from the one for sets by replacing such
part of the proof for
first
and can be read
quite similar
off
many members
phrases as "infinitely
S"
of
"
by
an for
many
infinitely
distinct values of w."
S
Proof. Let
be the
S
Since
set.
bounded, there
is
an
is
M such that S
is
contained in the interval
:{-M^x^M}.
I
When we bisect I to form the two closed intervals { — Af^x^O}, {0 ^ x ^ M}, one (or maybe both) of these contains infinitely many members of S", since S is an infinite set. Denote one such interval by I± Bisect It one .
of the two intervals must contain
and continue
it,
intervals I
,
Ix
,
.
,
.
.
,
we denote the end ^ x
ni
for which
\A
—
x n2
\
n2
nk
>
nk _
Pur
next theorem
3.5b
Theorem.
of In tends is
an
is
J
for
which
\A
—
for
which
\A
-
clear that the subsequence {x„
intervals, so that
is
known
Let
In
to zero as
{/„}
at least
in
less
is
infinity, then there is
A and
The requirement /„: (0,
I
can be taken all
in the previous proof,
A and
distinct points,
a fixed positive number
A' are in
If the length
n.
exactly one point that
less
we
see
the intervals.
all
d.
A'.
The
distance
However, the length of /„
than any preassigned positive number,
both
.
t
one such point in
particular, the length
N. There are only number of x's not covered by this bound. Hence, by increasing 1 if such that necessary, we get a number Keep
a
M
finite
M
\xn
Thus
{x„}
is
oo,
we
nk
limit.
a subsequence e/2,
we have
>k>N^j.
get
£
if
F!>Jv(|V
2 This
is
the definition of a limit.
The Cauchy
criterion extends easily to cover the existence of the limit of a
function.
3.6b the case
Theorem.
Let f(x) be defined
of one-sided limits
it
in
a deleted neighborhood of a
need be defined only on one side of a).
and
sufficient condition that \\m x _+ a f(x) exist is that for
3(e)
for which
whenever
\f(x)-f(x')\ 0, there
is
mm
1
an
N
•
•
•
~Xn
)\
-x m _ 2 +
•••
\
+ +
cr r
+
-X
n
\
n
m~n~
l
)
-r such that
there
is
*„
N for
whose points
which x„ lie
above
hence by Theorem 3.5a
But
is finite.
Then for each
£
^A+ A+£ it
>
£
£ .
.
n
if
A
N2
>
.
0,
this
there
is
were not so suppose :
/?,
for
is
also
which
supremum of the
all
is
of
bounded above,
clearly set
ft
^A+£
.
of the cluster
points of {xn }.
I
I
A
A
N there
a subsequence {x„ k },
subsequence
the
is
this
so that for arbitrarily large
has a cluster point
this contradicts the fact that
.
Suppose that
Then
But
t
such that
2 (e)
We prove the first statement.
that there were an exceptional
n>N
if
xn > X — Proof
A
Let {xn } be a sequence for which
an N^e) such that
—e
AA+£ I
I
A
I
glance at the previous figure should convince you of the truth of the
next theorem. 3.7b
Theorem.
\\mxn
In order for
to exist,
it is
necessary and sufficient
that
lim sup
Proof: Necessity. If lim xn consists of exactly
=A
xn = lim exists,
one point, namely
A=
A
X
=
inf xn
.
then the set of cluster points of {xn } itself.
A.
Hence
78
Continuity, Differentiability,
there
is
an
A=
— s< xn < A + -
N2 of that theorem) such that n>
if
supremum of the
n
if
N.
N.
|
lim sup x _* a f(x) or
a,
cluster points
we
a,
>
a point can be defined similarly. Thus,
neighborhood of
in a
any neighborhood of
in
e
e
limit superior of a function at
defined as the
above
and
3.7a, for
can be rewritten as
X, this
/is bounded above is
Then, by Theorem x
\xn
The
X.
N (take N to be the larger of N X
Since
A=
Suppose that
Sufficiency.
and More Limits
of/ at
a. If
/ is
if
Iim^ f(x)
not bounded
say that
lim sup f(x)
= + oo.
x-*a
Similarly
we
define lim infx _ a f(x) or lim x _ /(x) fl
and lim sup x ^ ±o0 f(x) and
liminfx _> ±00 /(x).
The next two theorems proofs are
Theorem.
3.7c
Then for each
are the analogues of the
two previous ones. Their
as exercises (B3).
left
e
>
Let
f be
there
f(x)
^ lim
is
bounded above
in
a deleted neighborhood of
a.
a S^s) such that
sup f(x)
+
£
if
a
and iff is bounded below f(x)
there
is
a S 2 (e) such that
^ lim inf f(x) -
s
if
|/(«-/(«|
=
0,
which contradicts the construction that
l/(xJ-/(OI>«o-
/4
1.
I
Exercises Show
that the following functions are uniformly continuous in the intervals
indicated.
Vx + 2
(a)
.
1,
{O^x^l}.
The Derivative. Chain Rule 1
x2
x
sin
(b)
^ 0,
x
{O^x^l}.
= 0,
jc
1
83
— COS X
x^O,
(c)
x
= 0,
H**4
x^O, id)
x=
[0 (e)
2.
{-l^jt^l}.
* 5 sgnx,
Show
{0^*^!}. 0,
that if f(x)
is
uniformly continuous on an interval
continuous on each subinterval of 3.
Prove Theorem
4.
Let
/ be
1.
it is
uniformly
3.8c. ;
bounded
F is
interval.
Exercise Show
that
-J and f(b
C 1.
then
continuous on a closed bounded interval prove that the range of
also a closed
B
/,
/.
if /is
+ 0)
continuous on an open interval /: {a
both
exist,
< x < b},
then / is uniformly continuous on
and
if f{a
+ 0)
/.
Exercise Give an alternative proof of Theorem 3.8d using the Heine-Borel theorem.
3.9 It is
The Derivative. Chain Rule assumed that you are familiar with elementary
differentiation formulas.
A list of these can be found in the back of the book. Very likely your exposure to formulas involving the logarithm, the exponential,
functions was based on elementary and
of these functions. In Chapter 5
we
somewhat
and the trigonometric
unsatisfactory definitions
define these functions
and put
their
84
Continuity, Differentiability,
and More Limits
on a firmer foundation. In the meantime we
properties
not hesitate to
shall
continue to use these functions as examples. Let / be a function defined in a neighborhood of a point x
A/ Ax
f(x
+h)- f(x
x
called the difference quotient
is
Hm
—
f{x)
)
h
+
/(xp
h)
f(x
off at x
-
/(x
)
(Ax
)
exists, it is called the derivative
of/ at x and
or sometimes, recalling the
x is
Df(x
),
common
/(x)-/(x
= Hm x->x
f'(x
x
-
x
=
h
ratio
^
0),
If
.
h
ft-0
=
x
The
.
)
—x
written
)
notation y =/(x),
dy
dx where the point x
is
indicated by (dy/dx) Xo or
is
implied by the setting of the
problem. If
f\x)
exists for all points
(an interval perhaps),
x
in
called the derived function or the derivative
If/has a derivative
at a point
x
a derivative at every point of a set D,
/'
is
continuous on a
set
it is
x
,
it
has
on D.
If
there.
the one-sided derivatives
may
They can be defined by
m
hm
,-
(1)
/(Xp
+
h)
-
/(X
)
hm
,
n
/i-o+
and
f(x
at a point
x
equality of these
is
The function f(x) =
\x\
/( X
) ,
n a necessary and sufficient condi-
two
limits.
analogous to the proof of Theorem 2.4b, and
derivatives at the origin,
+ h)-
ft-o-
The existence of a derivative tion for the existence is
said to be differentiate
D, we say that /is continuously differentiable
If the derivative fails to exist at a point still exist.
off
said to be differentiate there. If
it is
,
the domain D of f we denote by/'. It is
some subset D' of
defines there a function that
it
The proof of this
is left
as
an
result
exercise.
can easily be shown to have different one-sided
and hence /(x)
If the one-sided derivatives given
by
=
|x| is
not differentiable at x
(1) fail to exist,
=
0.
then a weaker type
may. These are given by
m (2)
,.
hm
h->o+
/(x
+ h)-
f(x
+
0) ,
n
The function sgn x has
hm /i-o-
f(x
+ h)-
f(x
-
0) .
n
derivatives in these senses at the origin,
and the
The Derivative. Chain Rule values of these are equal, but (1).
Furthermore,
There
is
it
85
does not have derivatives there in the sense of
this function is
not differentiable at the origin.
no standard notation
When we
for these one-sided derivatives.
have occasion to use a one-sided derivative, we
which we
state explicitly
mean.
An
important property of differentiable functions
Theorem.
3.9a
x
continuous at
Proof Let
If a function
A =f'(x
),
n -»
S P .{f).
| if
P
and P' are any
p
104
Integration
Proof. This is very easy to prove. Let P" be the common refinement of P and P' formed by taking as partition points all points that occur in P and P'.
Then ijp
The
first
Lemma Our
and
^
^
jjp»
last inequalities are
by
jj
p"
^
r
±t
Lemma
•
4.2b and the middle one by
4.2a.
|
as a lower
now
of lemmas has
series
bounded function
established the following facts.
For any
of numbers formed by the upper sums has
/, the class
bound any lower sum, and conversely
the class of lower
sums has
any upper sum as an upper bound. Thus
infSp^Sy for any partition P'.
Thus
inf
SP
an upper bound for the lower sums, so
is
that inf
^
SP
sup
S P >.
Now inf S P (f) is called the upper Riemann-Darboux integral of / over /: {a < x ^ b}, and sup S P >(f) the lower Riemann-Darboux integral off over /.
They
are written b
inf
S P (f)=~j f(x)dx, a
sup
We
refer to
them simply
SPif) = fj(x)dx.
as the upper and lower integrals.
We
have therefore
proved the following lemma. 4.2d
Lemma.
Iff is a bounded function on ~j
h
/,
b
J(x)dx>jJ(x)dx.
4.2e
Lemma.
Iff is bounded on
and lower bounds for f on
/,
I:
{a^ x
0,
may
P by
or
may
not have a
introducing a partition
induces also partitions of
right
+ SI > J/(x) dx + J'/(x) dx. form a lower bound for
all
the upper
sums on
b
b
Now,
it
Thus
dx > JV(x) dx + ] ]J(x)
(1)
S ab and S* will represent, {a ^ x ^ b} and one over
as with integrals, so that
there are partitions of {a
f(x) dx.
^x^
c}
and
{c
^x^
b} for
which
s«
0,
S
J-e
£p M
k
A, x
- e.
we then have
(5),
0>SP -s> £/(*) dx -
Sp(f,
£
or
J
>
f(x) dx
—
for every
2fi
£.
Thus J
By
a similar argument,
we
> J*/W
Jjc.
get
/
Since the upper integral by definition
is
b
~\
not
the proof.
J(x) less
dx.
than the lower,
this
completes |
Example
Compute x dx. Solution.
The integrand
of the integral
is
clear
4.3e, the integral
is
by
is
both monotone and continuous. The existence
Theorem 4.3a or 4.3b. And since, by Theorem of the Riemann sums, we take a sequence of
either
the limit
The Riemann Integral
simple partitions the upper sum,
Pn
{0, a/n, 2a/n,
:
as
||P||
.
.
,
-» 0, n
(a\
[ka\
- oo
and
a
x dx
it
should happen that
/ is
2
"
a
,
2
n
2
^x
n, and hence = + h where h >
that e"
Write e 2.
1
complete the proof of Theorem
Evaluate the following
limits.
some
In
cases
— x
lim x-0
: 3
lim : »-o log
\-e x%
2
.
X
-.
lim (e*
(d)
-,yr^
2
we
Estimating exactly as before,
get
/2^^Acos0^ J2k -
k
A0
:
@E* -
V
k
2/c
^_ t
:
^
Ask->0, d -—cos d9
n
= — 1 = —sin-. .
2
n/2
Thus
— dd
sin 9
=
cos
0,
—- cos
= —sin
{-oo
)]
d,0)
146
The Elementary Transcendental Functions
P
from
(both 6 and
is
nates of
P
are (cos
are indicated as positive in the figure).
and of
0, sin 9)
rotate the three points clockwise
P'[cos
Then Thus
(
— 6),
the
Q
The
+ ).
P' to Q'.
2
the lower limit taken to be zero?
gives the principal value of the arc cos x. Obtain
Show
)
fe-e\=-cosfe+o\ = smO.
3.
5.
147
x and cos x are
x
x
infinitely differentiate.
formula for arc cos
x.
CHAPTER
6
Properties
of Differentiable Functions
The Cauchy
6.1
In this chapter
Mean
Value Theorem
we obtain some further properties of differentiable functions,
most of which are consequences of the mean value theorem
(3.10c).
We
Cauchy
begin by establishing an extension of this theorem
mean
{a
^
there
is
Suppose that
Theorem.
x
^
b)
and
a point p
in
addition, g(b)
f and g
differentiable on the
are continuous on a closed interval
open interval J: {a