Advanced calculus


333 82 22MB

English Pages 496

Report DMCA / Copyright

DOWNLOAD PDF FILE

Table of contents :
a - 0001
a - 0002
a - 0003
a - 0004
a - 0005
a - 0006
a - 0007
a - 0008
a - 0009
a - 0010
a - 0011
a - 0012
a - 0013
a - 0014
a - 0015
a - 0016
a - 0017
a - 0018
a - 0019
a - 0020
a - 0021
a - 0022
a - 0023
a - 0024
a - 0025
a - 0026
a - 0027
a - 0028
a - 0029
a - 0030
a - 0031
a - 0032
a - 0033
a - 0034
a - 0035
a - 0036
a - 0037
a - 0038
a - 0039
a - 0040
a - 0041
a - 0042
a - 0043
a - 0044
a - 0045
a - 0046
a - 0047
a - 0048
a - 0049
a - 0050
a - 0051
a - 0052
a - 0053
a - 0054
a - 0055
a - 0056
a - 0057
a - 0058
a - 0059
a - 0060
a - 0061
a - 0062
a - 0063
a - 0064
a - 0065
a - 0066
a - 0067
a - 0068
a - 0069
a - 0070
a - 0071
a - 0072
a - 0073
a - 0074
a - 0075
a - 0076
a - 0077
a - 0078
a - 0079
a - 0080
a - 0081
a - 0082
a - 0083
a - 0084
a - 0085
a - 0086
a - 0087
a - 0088
a - 0089
a - 0090
a - 0091
a - 0092
a - 0093
a - 0094
a - 0095
a - 0096
a - 0097
a - 0098
a - 0099
a - 0100
a - 0101
a - 0102
a - 0103
a - 0104
a - 0105
a - 0106
a - 0107
a - 0108
a - 0109
a - 0110
a - 0111
a - 0112
a - 0113
a - 0114
a - 0115
a - 0116
a - 0117
a - 0118
a - 0119
a - 0120
a - 0121
a - 0122
a - 0123
a - 0124
a - 0125
a - 0126
a - 0127
a - 0128
a - 0129
a - 0130
a - 0131
a - 0132
a - 0133
a - 0134
a - 0135
a - 0136
a - 0137
a - 0138
a - 0139
a - 0140
a - 0141
a - 0142
a - 0143
a - 0144
a - 0145
a - 0146
a - 0147
a - 0148
a - 0149
a - 0150
a - 0151
a - 0152
a - 0153
a - 0154
a - 0155
a - 0156
a - 0157
a - 0158
a - 0159
a - 0160
a - 0161
a - 0162
a - 0163
a - 0164
a - 0165
a - 0166
a - 0167
a - 0168
a - 0169
a - 0170
a - 0171
a - 0172
a - 0173
a - 0174
a - 0175
a - 0176
a - 0177
a - 0178
a - 0179
a - 0180
a - 0181
a - 0182
a - 0183
a - 0184
a - 0185
a - 0186
a - 0187
a - 0188
a - 0189
a - 0190
a - 0191
a - 0192
a - 0193
a - 0194
a - 0195
a - 0196
a - 0197
a - 0198
a - 0199
a - 0200
a - 0201
a - 0202
a - 0203
a - 0204
a - 0205
a - 0206
a - 0207
a - 0208
a - 0209
a - 0210
a - 0211
a - 0212
a - 0213
a - 0214
a - 0215
a - 0216
a - 0217
a - 0218
a - 0219
a - 0220
a - 0221
a - 0222
a - 0223
a - 0224
a - 0225
a - 0226
a - 0227
a - 0228
a - 0229
a - 0230
a - 0231
a - 0232
a - 0233
a - 0234
a - 0235
a - 0236
a - 0237
a - 0238
a - 0239
a - 0240
a - 0241
a - 0242
a - 0243
a - 0244
a - 0245
a - 0246
a - 0247
a - 0248
a - 0249
a - 0250
a - 0251
a - 0252
a - 0253
a - 0254
a - 0255
a - 0256
a - 0257
a - 0258
a - 0259
a - 0260
a - 0261
a - 0262
a - 0263
a - 0264
a - 0265
a - 0266
a - 0267
a - 0268
a - 0269
a - 0270
a - 0271
a - 0272
a - 0273
a - 0274
a - 0275
a - 0276
a - 0277
a - 0278
a - 0279
a - 0280
a - 0281
a - 0282
a - 0283
a - 0284
a - 0285
a - 0286
a - 0287
a - 0288
a - 0289
a - 0290
a - 0291
a - 0292
a - 0293
a - 0294
a - 0295
a - 0296
a - 0297
a - 0298
a - 0299
a - 0300
a - 0301
a - 0302
a - 0303
a - 0304
a - 0305
a - 0306
a - 0307
a - 0308
a - 0309
a - 0310
a - 0311
a - 0312
a - 0313
a - 0314
a - 0315
a - 0316
a - 0317
a - 0318
a - 0319
a - 0320
a - 0321
a - 0322
a - 0323
a - 0324
a - 0325
a - 0326
a - 0327
a - 0328
a - 0329
a - 0330
a - 0331
a - 0332
a - 0333
a - 0334
a - 0335
a - 0336
a - 0337
a - 0338
a - 0339
a - 0340
a - 0341
a - 0342
a - 0343
a - 0344
a - 0345
a - 0346
a - 0347
a - 0348
a - 0349
a - 0350
a - 0351
a - 0352
a - 0353
a - 0354
a - 0355
a - 0356
a - 0357
a - 0358
a - 0359
a - 0360
a - 0361
a - 0362
a - 0363
a - 0364
a - 0365
a - 0366
a - 0367
a - 0368
a - 0369
a - 0370
a - 0371
a - 0372
a - 0373
a - 0374
a - 0375
a - 0376
a - 0377
a - 0378
a - 0379
a - 0380
a - 0381
a - 0382
a - 0383
a - 0384
a - 0385
a - 0386
a - 0387
a - 0388
a - 0389
a - 0390
a - 0391
a - 0392
a - 0393
a - 0394
a - 0395
a - 0396
a - 0397
a - 0398
a - 0399
a - 0400
a - 0401
a - 0402
a - 0403
a - 0404
a - 0405
a - 0406
a - 0407
a - 0408
a - 0409
a - 0410
a - 0411
a - 0412
a - 0413
a - 0414
a - 0415
a - 0416
a - 0417
a - 0418
a - 0419
a - 0420
a - 0421
a - 0422
a - 0423
a - 0424
a - 0425
a - 0426
a - 0427
a - 0428
a - 0429
a - 0430
a - 0431
a - 0432
a - 0433
a - 0434
a - 0435
a - 0436
a - 0437
a - 0438
a - 0439
a - 0440
a - 0441
a - 0442
a - 0443
a - 0444
a - 0445
a - 0446
a - 0447
a - 0448
a - 0449
a - 0450
a - 0451
a - 0452
a - 0453
a - 0454
a - 0455
a - 0456
a - 0457
a - 0458
a - 0459
a - 0460
a - 0461
a - 0462
a - 0463
a - 0464
a - 0465
a - 0466
a - 0467
a - 0468
a - 0469
a - 0470
a - 0471
a - 0472
a - 0473
a - 0474
a - 0475
a - 0476
a - 0477
a - 0478
a - 0479
a - 0480
a - 0481
a - 0482
a - 0483
a - 0484
a - 0485
a - 0486
a - 0487
a - 0488
a - 0489
a - 0490
a - 0491
a - 0492
a - 0493
a - 0494
a - 0495
a - 0496
Recommend Papers

Advanced calculus

  • 0 0 0
  • Like this paper and download? You can publish your own PDF file online for free in a few minutes! Sign Up
File loading please wait...
Citation preview

ADVANCED CALCULUS_ ALLEN DEVINATZ

Northwestern University

_./

HOLT, RINEHART AND WINSTON New York Montreal

Chicago Toronto

San Francisco London

Atlanta

Dallas

Copyright

© 1968

by Holt, Rinehart and Winston, Inc.

All Rights Reserved Library of Congress Catalog Card Number: 68-18409

2689453 Printed in the United States of America

1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9

PREFACE The contents of this book represent a somewhat expanded version of a one-year course that I have given from time to time since 1961.

Those taking the course have been mainly undergraduate and first­

year graduate students concentrating in mathematics. Occasionally,

students from engineering and the physical sciences have taken the

course and have told me they enjoyed it. I recommend that students

who select a course such as this should generally have a little more

mathematical maturity than that afforded by the usual freshman­

sophomore courses in the calculus. One excellent way to gain such

maturity is through a beginning course in linear algebra, although the contents of such a course are not a specific prerequisite for the under­ standing of this book.

Section 1.1 on logic is to be read by the student. Of course, such a

brief introduction is not intended to teach the student the elements

of logic, but rather to make him aware of the formal processes involved

in mathematical reasoning. It may not be too well understood on the

first reading, but if the student will reread it several times during the course, it probably will begin to appear more reasonable. The notation

of the propositional calculus is to be viewed as a concise shorthand for

mathematical statements. My experience has been that students learn to use the notation in a reasonable way in a relatively short time and with very little trouble.

For those instructors who do not wish to spend time on an extended

treatment of the real number system, I have arranged matters so that

they can begin the discussion o(real numbers with Section 1.8. In that section, I have given what amounts to a set of axioms for the real num­

ber system, the more usual starting point for a beginning course in

analysis.

If, in going through the material, my peers should at times accuse

me of being pedantic, I plead guilty to the charge; my aim in doing this has been deliberate. All too often students beginning the serious

study of mathematics get the idea that a vague or seemingly trivial

point should be waved away. I have triecrto convey the idea to the novice

that he should be sure that he can really prove these seemingly trivial

points.

As far as the differential calculus is concerned, there is probably not too much choice in the way one can proceed. As for the integral

calculus, I have chosen the more cumbersome and less general method

of Riemann-Darboux integration and Jordan content rather than one iii

of the more modern theories of measure and integration. Although I do not feel that a historical approach to a subject i� necessarily always

the best, in the case of integration my view is that a student cannot fully appreciate or even fully understand the more modern theories until he has seen the gradual and natural evolution of the ideas involved. I make absolutely no claims to originality. I have no gimmicks or

special pedagogical devices as aids in understanding. Mathematics is a difficult subject; I have tried to set down a small but important portion of it in as straightforward, clean, and concise a way as I know how, consistent with the level of student to whom it is addressed. Only the readers can ultimately decide whether or not I have succeeded. I am grateful to several friends for their help in preparing the manu­

script. I am deeply indebted to Sam Lachterman of St. Louis University. He read the entire manuscript, pointed out a large, but finite, number of errors, and showed me how to make several proofs in a shorter and more elegant way. Jacob K. Goldhaber of the University of Maryland read several of the chapters and gave me some excellent advice. Thanks are also due to my former colleagues, Sebastian Koh and A. Edward Nussbaum of Washington University. The former used a preliminary version of the first five chapters in his class and made several sugges­ tions for improvement, while I had several helpful conversations with the latter on the subject matter of the book. Above all I am grateful to the various classes of students who endured varying versions of the course. Evanston, Illinois March 1968

A. D.

CONTENTS

v

Preface

CHAPTER 1

I

THE REAL NUMBER SYSTEM

I. I

Some Ideas about Logic

1.2 1.3 1.4 1.5 1.6 1. 7 1.8 1. 9

Sets Relations and Functions The Natural Numbers The Integers and the Rationals Countability The Reals A Review of the Real Number System and Sequences

Properties of the Reals

CHAPTER 2 2.1 2.2 2.3 2.4

The Heine-Borel Theorem and Uniform Corttinuity Monotone Functions Limit Superior and Limit Inferior

I

Convergence Tests Decimal Expansions Sequences and Series of Functions Infinite Products

I

69 76 84 90

INFINITE SERIES

Series of Real Numbers

CHAPTER 4 4.1 4.2 4.3 4.4

LIMITS

The Limit Concept and Continuity

CHAPTER 3 3.1 3.2 3.3 3.4 3.5

I

1 16 22 26 31 38 44 55 62

99 110 118 126 131

DIFFERENTIATION

The Derivative Concept Differentiation Rules Mean Value Theorems Taylor's Remainder Formulas

138 145 149 158 v

4.5 4.6

Power Series The Weierstrass Approximation Theorem

165 178

CHAPTER 5 I INTEGRATION 5.1 5.2 5.3 5.4 5.5

Riemann-Darboux Integrals Properties and Existence of Riemann-Darboux Integrals Improper Integrals Riemann-Stiel tj es Integrals

183 190 201 210

Functions of Bounded Variation and the Existence of Riemann-Stiel tj es Integrals

217

CHAPTER 6 j HIGHER DIMENSIONAL SPACE 6.1 6.2 6.3 6.4 6.5 6.6 6.7

Real Vector Spaces Euclidean Spaces Topology in En Continuous Functions Linear Transformations Determinants Function Spaces

228 235 241 248 256 274 293

CHAPTER 7 I HIGHER DIMENSIONAL DIFFERENTIATION 7.1 7.2 7.3 7.4 7.5 7.6

Motivation Directional Derivatives and Differentials Differentiation Rules Higher-Order Differentials and Taylor's Theorem The Inverse and Implicit Function Theorems Maxima and Minima

CHAPTER

305 309 319 324 332 344

8 I HIGHER DIMENSIONAL INTEGRATION

8.1 8.2 8.3

Riemann-Darboux Integrals Jordan Content Existence and Properties of Riemann-Darboux Integrals

353 359 366

8.4 8.5

Iterated Integration The Transformation Theorem for Integrals

CHAPTER 9

I

374 380

THE INTEGRATION OF DIFFERENTIAL FORMS

I. LINE INTEGRALS

9.1 9.2 9.3 9.4

Motivation and Definitions The Length of a Curve A Special Case of Stokes' Theorem Closed and Exact Differentials

396 403 407 416

II. SURFACE INTEGRALS

9.5 9.6 9.7 9.8 9.9 9.10

Motivation and Definitions The Algebra of Differential Fonns Closed and Exact Forms Manifolds Integration on Manifolds Stokes' Theorem

Symbols Index

429 437 452 455 461 467 479 482

2 I THE REAL NUMBER SYSTEM

new statements that are called true. In this sense mathematics is a complicated game and truth has nothing to do with reality (whatever that elusive thing is!) or various concepts of truth discussed by the philosophers. Truth, for us, shall be something prescribed by a set of rules. To be somewhat more specific, a branch of mathematics is usually constructed in the following way. A small number of statements are written down which are called axioms and these are arbitrarily called true and the letter 't' assigned to them. By means of a given rule, from each true statement a new statement can be formed which is called false and the letter 'f' is assigned to these. Then there are vari­ ous rules for assigning 't' or 'f' to new statements formed from col­ lections of statements that already have 't' or 'f' values attached to them. This enlarges our collection of statements with 't' or 'f' attached to them. We can then use our rules on this enlarged collection to get a possibly still larger collection of statements haviilg 't' or 'f' values attached to them. We can then apply the rules again to get a possibly still larger collection of statements having 't' or 'f' assigned to them, and so on. It is always our hope that in starting from the given axioms and applying our rules that we will not get a statement that has both letters 't' and 'f' attached to it. If we get a statement with both 't' and 'f' at­ tached to it, we say that our axioms are inconsistent. If this is never the case, we say our axioms are consistent. For a consistent set of axioms, those statements taking on the value 't' are called lemmas. propositions, theorems, and corollaries. It is not always clear which true statements should bear which names.

However,

current usage seems to suggest the following rules. A theorem is an important true statement. A lemma is a true statement that is used in constructing the proof of another true statement and usually does not have wider applicability. A corollary is a true statement that is an immediate consequence of a true statement. Finally, a proposition is a true statement that is not a lemma or corollary but is not important enough to be called a theorem.

Many people also use the word

'scholium' to play the same role as the word 'proposition' or even possibly to be a true statement that is not as important as a proposition. We shall now give some rules for forming new statements from given statements A and B that have values 't' or 'f'. That is to say, we shall construct new statements containing the statements A or B or both and give rules for assigning 't' or 'f' to the new statements. We shall do this by means of a truth table, which will list the symbol 't' or 'f' to be given to a new statement given the various combinations of 't' and 'f' values that A and B can take on. a.

Negation

-

A

(To be read: not A.)

I.I

A

-A

t

f

SOME IDEAS ABOUT LOGIC I 3

f b.

Implication A =>B (To be read: A implies B, or if A then B, or B if A, or A only if B, or A is a sufficient condition for B, or B 1s a necessary con­ dition for A.) A

c.

B

A =>B

t

t

t

t

f

f

f

t

t

f

f

t

B

A&B

Conjunction A&B (To be read: A and B.) A

d.

t

t

t

t

f

f

f

t

f

f

f

f

Disjunction AVB (To be read: A or B.) A

B

AVB

t

t

t t

t

f

f

t

t

f

f

f

The preceding truth tables give a prescription for the use of the symbols

'-

' '==i, & ' ,' and 'V'. As such, we can loosely think of these ,

tables as giving a meaning to statements containing these symbols. We shall try to explain this in more detail. In our previous discussion we have used the word 'statement' as if this were a well-known concept to the reader. Actually we think the reader has a good idea of this concept, but we shall be pedantic and

4 I THE REAL NUMBER SYSTEM

comment on it further. To form a statement in the written English language, for example, we begin with an alphabet consisting of 52 Latin letters (lower case and capitals), the various punctuation marks, and various other symbols such as parentheses, brackets, and so forth. We may even suppose the alphabet contains a symbol that cannot be seen-an empty space. A statement in the English language, meaningful or not, is a string of these symbols usually placed in a horizontal row, and one has a rule to tell where a statement begins and where it ends. A string of Latin letters that begins and ends witl) the empty-space

symbol and has no empty-space symbol in betwee'n is called a word. A string of objects beginning with two empty-space symbols and a

capital Latin letter and ending with a period, and having no period in between is called a sentence, and so forth. Statements in mathematics are formed in the same way, that is, by placing symbols in various positions. However, it is usually the case that we form these statements from a different collection of symbols than those that we use for the English language. The symbols '

-

' ·�. '&', ,

and 'V' are part of our mathematical alphabet. Now, what we have described as statements of the written English language cannot be said to constitute the written English language. Most of the strings of symbols that would be written down would not be meaningful. The meaningful statements are those prescribed by means of lists of words contained in dictionaries and by means of the rules of grammar. A moment's reflection is enough to convince us that for someone who does not already know the written English language it would be impossible to describe the rules of grammar or how to use a dictionary in terms of the written language. The various rules must be described in terms of a different language that is understood by the learner. For a child this is usually done by means of a spoken language, and for someone who understands a different written lan­ guage such as, for example, Hebrew or Sanskrit, the rules of written English can be described in terms of those languages. The same situation persists with regard to the mathematical language. In the mathematical language we say that the meaningful statements are those which can be assigned a value 't' or 'f'. The rules whereby we describe which mathematical statements are meaningful must be prescribed by a language outside the mathematical language. For us, the describing language is the English language. We are assuming that a truth table is part of the English language, since if we had a mind to do it we could describe these tables in terms of the conventional lan­ guage. So we see that truth tables are nothing more than rules, written in a language that we presumably understand, which describes which statements in our mathematical language are meaningful. Of course, .we have some intuitive ideas of what we want and these prescriptions

I.I

SOME IDEAS ABOUT LOGIC I 5

of the truth tables are nothing more than formalizations of these intuitive ideas. Let us give an example that illustrates how the truth-table method works. Let us suppose that

A, B,

and

are statements that can be

C

given 't' or 'f' values. We wish to show that the statement

[(A�B)

(B�C)] �[A �CJ

&

always has a 't' value regardless of the values taken on by

A, B, and C. 'A�B', E for 'A�C'. The table

To get the table to fit on one page, let us set 'D' for

'B�C',

'F' for

'(A�B)

&

(B�C)',

and 'G' for

'

'

looks as follows.

A

B

c

D

E

F

G

F�G

t

t

t

t

t

t

t

t

t

f

t

f

t

f

t

t

t

t

f

t

f

f

f

t

t

f

f

f

t

f

f

t t

f

t

t

t

t

t

t

f

t

f

t

f

f

t

t

f

f

t

t

t

t

t

t

f

f

f

t

t

t

t

t

Since the last column always has the 't' value we have shown what we set out to show. Once we have given the basic symbols of our mathematical language we can

define

point we can

new symbols in terms of our basic symbols. As a case in

define

the equivalence symbol

� · .·

When we write

A�B, this is to be read: A is equivalent with

B. It is sometimes also read: 'A�B' is defined as another repre­ for the statement (A�B) & (B�A), which is in terms of symbols of our mathematical language. Once 'A�B' has

A if and only if B. sentation the basic

The set of symbols

been defined, we coan consider it as the name of a statement. It is easily seen that the statement A and

A�B has

the value 't' attached to it whenever

both haye the 't' value or whenever A and B both have the 'f' value. Otherwise A�B has the 'f' value attached to it.

B

In the above paragraph we have used a short symbol to replace a more cumbersome one. This is, in essence, the nature of a definition. A definition gives a (usually shorter) new name to something that can be described in terms of known symbols or names. The object, as in any other language, is for efficiency in expression, which leads to efficiency in thought. The criteria of a definition is that it should only

6 I THE REAL NUMBER SYSTEM

introduce new symbols or names for groups of known symbols and we should not be able to obtain any true statements by use of the defini­ tion that could not be obtained without it. In other words, we should think of definitions as simply introducing a system of shorthand into the mathematical language. Suppose now that we have a set of statements Hi, H2,

·

·

·

,

Hn which

are meaningf ul in the sense that they have 't' op-"f' values attached to them. In addition, we suppose that there are statements A1,







, Am

so that each H k is composed of some of the A; together with the logical symbols '-','==?',etc. It may not, in general,be known whether the A; are meaningful. Further, suppose C is a statement that is composed of some of the A; and the logical symbols, and we don't know in general whether C is meaningful. However, suppose that under the supposi­

tion that A1,







, Am can be given 't' or 'f' values we find by the use of

our truth-table rules that Hi & H2 &

·

·

·

& Hn ==* C

always has a 't' value. Then,if all the H k have the 't' value we shall give C a 't' value. This is a new rule for giving statements 't' or 'f' values and

is usually called the rule of inference. Our hope here,as with the truth­ table rules, is that starting from our axioms we cannot also give C an 'f' value,that is, -C cannot be given a 't' value by the scheme that has been outlined. As an example of this new rule,suppose A1 =*A2 and A2 =*A3 are axioms and therefore have 't' values, even though we don't know whether A1, A2, and A3 can be given 't' or 'f' values. However, under the supposition that they are meaningful we have established by a truth table that

always has a 't' value. Hence we would give A 1 ==* A3 a 't' value. Another example is

If Ai and A1 ==*A2 have 't' values,we would assign the 't' value to A2• In case a statement can be given a 't' value by means of the rules we have prescribed,then the statement is said to be derived or proved from the axioms. Suppose a statement C has a 't' value and it is obtained by our rules through an implication Hi & H2 &

·

·

·

& Hn -==*C .

Each

H k is in turn either an axiom or obtained through an implication of

a conjunction of other statements, and so forth, until we finally get back to where all the statements appearing in the conjunction on the left are axioms. The collection of all such statements is called the derivation or proof of C. However, it would be quite impractical to list all these statements beginning with the axioms and, as the reader well knows

1.1

SOME IDEAS ABOUT LOGIC 17

from experience, in practice a proof usually consists of just a portion of this collection. In other words, the proof starts with known true statements that have been proved elsewhere and proceeds from there. The set of rules we have given above is usually called the pmposi­ tional cakulus or sometimes a model for the propositional calculus. However, the symbols we introduced, and the rules for their use, are not rich enough to provide an adequate basis for most of the discourse of mathematics. Hence we shall introduce some new symbols together with rules for their use which in formal studies of logic is called the

predicate cakulus. A good deal of mathematics is described in the lan­ guage of the predicate calculus, usually at an informal level, since a very formal approach gets very cumbersome and may often interfere with understanding. However, there are some situations in which a formal approach may very much clarify and facilitate the handling of complicated situations. We have in mind the precise statements of complicated definitions and, in particular, the negating of complicated statements. Suppose that

Q(x) is a statement that depends on a variable 'x'. The

reader may think of a variable as the name of an unspecified object that can be replaced by any member of a specified set. The counterpart of a variable in the English language is a pronoun or a common noun.

x is not a specified object, in general it would make no sense to Q(x). However, by adding certain quali­ fying statements to Q(x) it may be possible to do so. One of these qualifying statements is 'for every x,' which in symbols is '(x)' or 'Vx.'

Since

associate a 't' or 'f' value with

We may then write down a statement:

(i)(Q(x)) This is to be read: For every

or

Vx Q(x).

x the statement Q(x) is true. Another x', which in symbols is '(3x).'

qualifying statement is 'there exists an

We may then write down another statement:

(3x)(Q(x)) . This is to be read: There exists an

x such that Q(x) is true. It may now

be possible to attach 't' or 'f' values to these statements. The symbols

'(x)' and 'Vx' are called universal quantifiers and the symbol '(3x)' is existential quantifier. It is also possible that we may have a statement Q(x, y) which depends

called an

on two variables and we may write down a statement:

(x)(y)(Q(x,y)). This is to be read:

For every

x and for every

is true. We may also write down a statement:

(x)(3 y)(Q(x,y)).

y the statement

Q(x, y)

8

I THE REAL NUMBER SYSTEM

This statement is to be read: For every x there exists a y such that Q(x, y)

is true. Clearly, the statements

(x)(3y)(Q(x, y)) and (3y)(x)(Q(x, y))

are different statements simply because the symbols are placed in a different order. However, even intuitively they cannot be considered equivalent. In the second case y is independent of which whereas in the first case y may depend on

x is chosen, x. As an example, suppose

x and y may be replaced by real numbers. We may then write the true statement:

(x)(3y)(x




(x)(-Q(x)).

Using these rules we can negate more complicated expressions. For

example,

is equivalent to

SOME IDEAS ABOUT LOGIC) 9

1.1

This is done by negating one at a time; that is, we consider

Q1(x1) = (x2) (3x3) (3x4)(xs) (Q(x., and then

-(x1)(Q1(x1))

is equivalent to

·

·

·

,xs))

(3xi)(-Q1(x1)),

and con­

tinue on in this way. Now, let us go on to some of the other rules. Usually it is necessary to start a chain of proof by means of known true statements that in­ volve quantifiers. A broad description of the rules is as follows. First, have a consistent way of removing the quantifiers from the known true statements. Next manipulate the resulting quantifier free statements by the rules of the propositional calculus. Finally, have a consistent way of replacing the quantifiers. The final quantified statement can be given a 't' value provided we have used all the rules correctly. We believe that the rules of manipulating with quantifiers are best explained by means of examples. Let us first look at a simple situation involving only universal quantifiers. Suppose statements involving the variable

'x',

P(x), Q(x), and R(x)

are

and it is known that the statements

(x)(P(x) => Q(x)), (x)(Q(x) =>R(x)), are true, that is, have a 't' value attached to them. It would seem natural, at least from the rules given for the propositional calculus, that we should be able to conclude that the statement

(x)(P(x) =>R(x)) has a 't' value attached to it. The rule here is to remove the universal quantifiers to get the statements

P(x) => Q(x), Q(x) =>R(x). Consider each of these two statements to have the 't' value attached to it even though with the variable

'x'

the statements may have no mean­

ing. However, we are thinking that if we replace

x

by any member of

a given set, then the statements will be true. By the methods of the propositional calculus we conclude that

{[P(x) => Q(x)J

&

[Q(x) =>R(x)]} => {P(x) =>R(x)}

is a true statement. Consequently, by the rule of inference we conclude that

P(x) =>R(x) is a true statement. The rule now is to add the universal quantifier and get the statement

(x)(P(x) =>R(x)).

10 I THE REAL NUMBER SYSTEM

Let us now look at a simple situation that involves an existential quan­ tifier. Suppose it is known that the statements (x) (P(x) :::} Q(x)), (3x)(P(x)) are true. It would seem reasonable that the rules we give should lead to the conclusion that the statement (3x)(Q(x)) is true. Now, the statement (3x)(P(x)) has the intuitive meaning that P(x) is true when x is replaced by only certain members (possibly only one) of a specified set. Hence the rule we now formulate is that when an existential quantifier is removed, the variable 'x' shall be replaced by a symbol that stands for a definite but unspecified member of some set. This is in accordance with the conventions used in ordinary mathe­ matical discourse. For the purpose of this discussion let us use the beginning letters of the Latin alphabet to stand for these definite but unspecified symbols. Consequently, remove the existential quantifier to obtain the statement P(a). If we remove the universal quantifier from the statement (x)(P(x) :::} Q(x))to get the statement P(x) :::} Q(x), then there would be no way for us to proceed. For the statement {P(a) & [P(x) :::} Q(x)]}:::} Q(a) is not a true statement according to truth-table methods. But {P(a) & [P(a) :::} Q(a)]} :::} Q(a) is a true statement, and by the rule of inference we conclude that Q(a) is a true statement. Hence we adopt the rule that whenever a universal quantifier is removed, we may retain the variable 'x' or replace it by one of the letters 'a', 'b', and so on, which stand for definite but unspecified objects. The tactics depend on just what is intended to be accomplished. Once we have established that Q(a) is true, we want to reinstate a quantifier. The rule is that whenever the letters 'a', 'b', and so on, appear in our statements, they can be quantified by existential quantifiers. Hence we get that the statement (3x)(Q(x)) is to be given a t value. '

'

In removing existential quantifiers, the rule we made is that the letters usually reserved for variables are replaced by other letters. This is done to serve as a warning that, when we reach the point where we want to reinstate quantifiers, we should not add a universal quanti­ fier where we should have added an existential quantifier. As an exam-

1.1

SOME IDEAS ABOUT LOGIC

I

11

ple of the type of difficulty that could arise if we did not follow this procedure, let us consider the statements: (x)(x< 1�x+1xy ¥ x). (x)(3y)(-[x ¥ 0 &xy ¥ l]).

We shall adopt the naive, intuitive point of view that a set is a collection of objects without questioning what these words mean. The term

'b EB' is to be read: b is an element of the set B. Often a set will be specified by some descriptive property. For example, suppose that

Q(x)is a sentence containing a variable 'x'. Then we can form the class 'x' make the sentence Q true. We denote this by means of the term '{x: Q(x)}', and this is to be read: The collection of all xsuch that Q(x) is true. As in the situation for quantifiers, x is understood to vary over a specified set. The set consisting of the one element a will be designated by '{a}', the set consisting of the two elements a and b will be designated by '{a, b}', and so on. Given two elements a EA and b EB we can form the ordered pair (a, b). The reason we use the word 'ordered' is that in general {a, b) and (b, a)are not considered the s.ame object. Indeed, the ordered pairs (a, b) and {a1, b1) shall be identified if and only if a= a1 and b= b1• Recall that the symbol '=' has the meaning that the symbols that stand of all objects that when their names are substituted for

to the left and right of it are simply different names for the same object and we adopted the rule that different names for the same object may be used interchangeably in any expression. From two setsA and B we can form a new set, the Cartesian product A X B, which is defined by the equality AX B

= { (x, y) : x EA & y E B}.

(l.2.1)

1.2

SETS I 17

We can also form the intersection of two sets defined by the equality

A n B={x:x EA & x EB}.

(1.2.2)

More generally, if� is a collection of sets we shall define

n {A:A EV'6}

=

{x: (A)(A Et16 =>x EA)},

(l.2.2')

that is, the collection of all elements each of which belongs to every set in x EB) .

(l.2.6)

18 j THE REAL NUMBER SYSTEM

The term

B.

If

'A CB ' is to be read: A is contained in B, or A is a subset A CB and A =fa B, A is called a proper subset of B. Two sets are

of to

be identified if and only if they are contained in each other, that is,

(1.2. 7)

A=B �(ACB&BCA).

Since we have taken equality as a primitive logical notion, the equiv­ alence ( l.2. 7) is to be viewed as an axiom rather than as a definition of equality between sets. For, from the rule we have adopted for the symbol'=', it is a simple matter to prove that

A=B =:}(A CB&BCA). However, the converse implication cannot be proved and in axiomatic set theory it is usually adopted as an axiom, provided equality is taken as a logical notion. Actually in making the definition (l.2.6) and in taking as an axiom (I. 2. 7) we should have used the universal quantifiers

'(A)'

and

'(B)',

so that these statements would refer to all pairs of sets

rather than to two particular sets. In our previous discussion we have introduced a new symbolism,

'{x: Q(x)}',

which has not been defined in terms of the symbolism of

the predicate calculus. Hence we must either define this symbol in terms of the rules of the predicate calculus or else give new rules for operating with statements that contain these symbols. The first method is clearly the preferable one. Hence we take the symbol

'{x: Q(x)}'

to

be a name for that set for which the following statement is true:

(y)(y E{x : Q(x)}�Q(y)). A moment's reflection is enough to convince us that the intuitive meaning of this statement is the same as the intuitive meaning we previously gave to the term As an example,

A n B

'{x: Q(x)}'.

is to be defined as that set for which the

following statement is true:

(x) (x EAn B � [x EA &x EB]).

(l.2.8)

Let us prove that the following statement is true:

An BCA. First,

removing

the

universal

(l.2.9)

quantifier from (l.2.8) we get the

statement:

x EA n B � [x EA &x E B],

(l.2.9')

which for the purpose of applying the rules of the propositional cal­ culus is assumed to have a 't' value. The truth-table method of the prop­ ositional calculus tells us that the following statement has a 't' value:

{x EA n B � [x EA&x E B]} =:} {x EA n B =:} [x EA &x EB]}.

(1.2.lO)

1.2

SETS j 19

From (l.2.9), (1.2.10), and the rule of inference we find that the follow­ ing statement is true:

x EA n B ""* [x EA

&

x E B].

(l.2.11)

The rules of the propositional calculus tell us that the following is true [Exercise 2(c) of Section 1.1]:

[x EA

&

x E BJ ===* x EA.

Designating the statement (l.2.11) by by

'S(x)',

'R(x)'

(l.2.12)

and the statement (l.2.12)

we get the following true statement:

[R(x)

&

S(x)] ===* [x EAn B ===*x EA].

(l.2.13)

Using the rule of inference the following statement has a 't' value:

x EAn B ===*x EA.

(l.2.14)

Adding a universal quantifier we get the following true statement:

(x)(x EAn B ===*x EA).

(l.2.15)

Using the statement (l.2.6) and the rules of the propositional calculus, we arrive at the true statement

(x)(x EA n B ===*x EA) ===*An BC A.

(l.2.16)

Using the fact that statements (1.2.15) and (1.2.16) are true, by the rule of inference we finally arrive at the true statement:

An BC A. We have presented above a formal proof of the last statement, being careful to point out at each stage exactly what was being used. Of course, we could have developed a scheme so that the proof would have been more mechanical and the amount of space needed to write it down would have been much less. Nevertheless, we think the reader now sees how cumbersome a formal proof can be, even of the simplest statements. For this pragmatic reason most of the discourse of mathe­ matics is carried on in an informal way. In an informal proof we do not write down all the steps but only those considered to be essential. This is analogous to the situation when in making an arithmetic or algebraic computation we usually do not take cognizance of the fact that we are using, for example, the commutative or associative laws, but suppose these are standard facts which the reader recognizes. For example, the chain of argument leading from ( l .2.9) to (l.2.11) or the chain of argument leading from (1.2.11) to (l.2.14) is usually considered a standard argument and would not be mentioned in an informal proof. Of course, just how much is written down is at the discretion of the writer. Usually enough should

20 I THE REAL NUMBER SYSTEM

be written down so that it would be clear how to make the formal proof if any question should arise about the validity of the informal proof. As an example of an informal proof let us show the following:

A

n

(B

B)

u

(A

(B U C)� [x EA

&

x EB U C].

u

C)

(A

=

n

n

C).

We have

x EA

n

Also,

x EB UC� [x EB V x EC]. Now, it is easily checked by a truth table that [ (x EA) & (x EB V x E C)] � [ (x EA & x EB) V (x EA

&

x EC)].

The disjunction on the right is equivalent with

x E (A

n

B)

u

(A

n

C).

Consequently, we have shown that

x EA

n

(B

u

C)� x E (A

n

B)

u

(A

n

C)'

which gives the equality we are seeking. Of course, proving such an equality or discovering it may be two dif­ ferent matters. Often the way to discover such an equality is by looking at the Venn diagram. In this case the set in question is shown by the cross-sectioned area in Fig. l.2.3.

FIGURE 1.2.3

The reader may now object that we have not defined the symbol 'E' in terms of the symbols of the predicate calculus. This is true, and in a formal development of mathematics it is necessary to give the rules or axioms that prescribe the use of this symbol. The situation is analogous to that of Euclidean geometry, where points and lines are taken as undefined objects and a set of axioms are given that give the relation­ ships between points and lines. In axiomatic set theory, sets and the symbol

'E' are taken as undefined things and a set of axioms is given that

will allow us to develop the kind of a theory of sets which seems intui-

1.2 SETS I 21

tively reasonable to us. These axioms deal mainly with prescribing the conditions under which new sets can be formed from given sets. For example, in axiomatic set theory the facts that

AnB and A

x

B can

be taken to be sets are usually given by axioms. In connection with the set

A

X

B, the notion of ordered pair can be defined by use of the

axioms. To try to give a reasonable axiomatic approach to set theory would be too difficult at this stage and would delay our study of the calculus for a long time. Hence, as we mentioned at the beginning of the dis­ cussion on sets, we shall suppose that everyone understands what a set is and we shall allow operations on sets and the construction of sets that seem intuitively reasonable. Such a procedure can, on occasion, lead to serious philosophical difficulties, but we shall pretend that they don't exist. Finally, let us remark that it is convenient to consider the set that has no elements. It is defined by the equality

0= {x: x � x}. The set 0 is called the null set or the empty set or the void set.

D Exercises 1.

Draw Venn diagrams for the sets

A \B, Ac, and An(BU C).

Give a schematic diagram (not a Venn diagram) for a Cartesian product set.

2.

Give formal proofs of the following statements: (a)

AU(BU C)=(AU B)U C. An(Bn C)=(AnB)n c. (c) (Ac)c =A. (d) An Ac= 0. (b)

3.

Prove the following:

(A u B) n c=(An C) u (Bn C).. (AnB) u c = (A u C)n(B u C). (c) An(A u B)=A. (d) AU(AnB)=A. (a)

(b)

4.

Prove the following: (a) (b)

5.

(An B)C=AC u Be. (A u BY=ACnBe.

Using the results of Exercises 2, 3, and 4, find the complements

of the following sets: (a) (b)

AU B U cc. An(BU(C U D)c).

22 I THE REAL NUMBER SYSTEM

6.

(c)

(A u BC)n (A u (Bn cc)).

(d)

0.

Prove the following by using the results of Exercise 3: If An B=An C and A U B=A U C, then B = C.

7.

Show the following: (a) (b)

8.

If A,, is any collection of sets and B is any set, show the following: (a) (b)

9.

(b)

Bn u {A:AEA,, }= u {AnB:AEA,,}. B u n {A:AEA,, }= n {A u B:A E A,,}.

If A,, is any collection of sets, show the following: (a) (b)

11.

B U U{A:AEA,, }= U {A U B:A EA,,}. Bn n{A:AE.A,,}= n{AnB:AE.A,,}.

If A,, is any collection of sets and B is any set, show the following: (a)

10.

A�B;,,,_A\(A\B). An B= A\(A\B).

-n c

( U{A: A E.A,,})c= n{Ac:AEA,,}. ( n{A :AE.A,,})c= U{Ac:AEA,,}.

If A,, is any collection of sets and B is any set, use the results of

the previous three exercises to show the following: (a) (b)

1.3

B\ U{A:A Evt}= n{B\A : AE vt} . B\ n {A :A Evt}= U {B\A :AE vt} .

RELATIONS AND FUNCTIONS

The concept of the Cartesian product of two sets leads to the concept of a relation. We shall first give a formal definition and then comment on the meaning.

1.3.1

Definition.

A relation is a subset of a Cart.esian product set.

If R is a relation, the set £>(R)={x :(3y)((x, y)ER)} is carted the do­ main of R and the set 5t(R)={y :(3x )((x, y)ER)} is called the range ofR. The relation defined by R-1={(y,x):(x,y)ER} is caUed the inverse of the relation R. If A is any set, then the set R-1(A)={x:(3y)(yEA &

(x, y)ER} is called the inverse image of A under R. An example of a relation is the following. Let A be the set consisting of all men in the United States and B the set of all people in the United States. Let R be the set of all (x,y)EA x B so that x EA and y is a rela­ tive of x. Since R is a subset of a Cartesian product it is a relation. Note that we also have R C B X B. The domain of R is the set of elements which are first members of the ordered pairs that are in R. In this case

1.3

RELATIONS AND FUNCTIONS I 23

this is A. t Suppose C is the subset consisting of those people in B who have at least one living male relative. It is probably true that C ¥- B. At any rate, C is the set of elements which are the second members of the ordered pairs that are in Rand hence is the range of R. Note that it is not true that R=A X C, although certainly R C A X C. The situation where to each element in the domain of a relation there corresponds only one element in the range so that the resulting ordered pair is in the relation is of special significance . Such relations are called functions and we now give the formal definition.

1.3.2

Definition.

A function F is a relation with the additional property

that

(x)(y)(z)([(x,y)

E

F & (x,z )

E F]

==>y=z)'.

For example, if A and B are the sets given above, then the set of all

(x, y)

E A X B with

x

a husband and y his legal wife is a function. A

more pertinent example of the distinction between a relation and a function is perhaps the following:

{ (x,y) : x2 + y2= 1} is a relation. { (x, y) : x2 + y2= 1 and y;a. O} is a

function.

Some people prefer the words multivalued function in place of the word 'relation.' If Fis a function and

(x, y)

E F, then the usual convention is to de­

note the second member y by notation. The element

F(x)

F(x).

We shall follow this convenient

is called the value of Fat

x, and

we also

often speak of it as the map of x under F. In case Fmaps distinct elements of its domain into distinct elements of its range the function

F

is said

to be one to one. The formal definition is the following

1.3.3

Definition.

A function F is

said to be one to one

(x)(y)(F(x)=F(y) x =y). In the statement above the variables are, of course, understood to represent elements of J?>(F). In case F is a one-to-one function, it is clear that �1 is also a function. However, we shall state this as a formal proposition and leave the proof as an exercise.

1.3.4

Proposition.

If F is a one-to-one function, then p-i is also a one­

to-one function. Given two or more functions there may be ways of combining these tWe are supposing that every man has a relative.

24 I THE REAL NUMBER SYSTEM

functions to get a new function. We shall give one way here, the

com­

position of two functions. We shall give other ways later. 1.3.5 Definition. If F and G are functions, then F 0 G is that function having domain {x: G(x) EE(F) } and Vx EJ0(F 0 G) ,

F0G(x) =F(G(x) ) . In very formal terms we can write

F0G= {(x,y) : (3z) ((x,z) EG & (z,y) EF) }. By an abuse of language we shall often designate the range of a function

f by the symbol

{J(x) : x EE(f)}. If A is a set, we can define a new function g as that subset off consisting of those ordered pairs (possibly void) whose first members belong to

A.

We shall often write

g=JIA. If

A

C

E(f ) ,when

we write

f(A) = {f(x) : x EA}, we are referring to the range of

g.

A function is an important special type of relation. There is another

special type of relation, an

equivalence relation, which plays an extremely

important role in all branches of mathematics.

1.3.6 Definition. A relation R is said to be an equivalence relation if and only if the following are satisfied: (a) (b)

(x) (y) ((x,y) ER ==> (y,x) ER) . (symmetric) (x) (y) (z) ([(x,y) ER & (y,z) ER] =>(x,z) ER) . (transitive)

Many authors prefer to talk about an equivalence relation

X and (c)

R

on a set

add the condition

(x) (x EX=> (x,x) ER) .

(reflexive)

The condition (c) simply assures us that

X

C

,B (R) .

In fact, from

(a) and (b) it is easy to prove the following:

(x) (x E,B(R) ==> (x,x) ER) . (x, y) ER, then (y,x) ER. (x,y) ER & (y,x) ==> (x,x) ER.

Indeed, (a) tells us that if (b) we get that

Hence from

We shall usually denote an equivalence relation by the symbol'=' and instead of

'(x,y) E='we

shall write

'x

=

y'.

It is not hard to check that

1.3

RELATIONS AND FUNCTIONS I 25

it is possible to use the symbol ·�· to define an equivalence relation in the Cartesian product XX X, where X is the set of all meaningful state­ ments. We shall soon meet other familiar equivalence relations. 1.3.7 Theorem. Let X be a set and = an equiva/.ence relation having domain and range the set X. There is a collection 6 of subsets of X so that X=U{E :EE6}, where VE, F E 6, E ¥= F �E n F = 0 and x,y E E � x = y; x = y � 3E E 6 so that x,yE E. (The sets E E 6 are called equivalence classes.) Proof. For every x E X let E(x) = {y : y = x}. Since, as we have shown, xE ..e (=) �x = x, it follows that xE E(x) . For any sets E(x) and E(y) suppose E(x) n E(y) ¥= 0 and let z E E(x) n E(y) . We have z = x and for w E E(x) we have w = x. From the symmetry condition (a) we get x = z, and thus from the transitivity condition (b) we get w = x & x = z �w = z. On the other hand, z = y, and hence from (b) w = z & z = y �w ;,, y. Hence we have shown that w E E(x) �w E E(y) , which means E(x) CE(y) . By making the same kind of argument for the set E(y) we arrive at the conclusion that E(y) CE(x) . This shows E(x) =E(y) . If we now take 8 = {E(x) : xE X}, we see that the theorem is proved. D Exercises I.

Letf be a function and A,B CJ?J(f). Show the following: (a) A CB �l(A) Cl(B). (b) l(A U B) =l(A) U l(B). (c) l(A\B) Cl(A). (d) l(A n B) c l(A) n l(B).

2. Prove Proposition 1.3.4: The inverse of a one-to-one function is a function, which is also one to one. 3. =x.

If l is a one-to-one function, show that Vx

4. Let following: (a) (b) (c) (d)

E

..e(J), 1-1 l(x) 0

f be a function and A and B subsets of �(f). Prove the A CB �1-1(A) C1-1(B). 1-1(A U B) 1-1(A) U 1-1(B). l-1(A\B) =l-1(A) \j-1(B). 1-1(A n B) =1-1 (A) n l-1(B). =

26 j THE REAL NUMBER SYSTEM 5.

Give an example which shows that we may not have equality in

Exercise l(d). However, show that if f is a one-to-one function we get equality. Suppose f and g are functions such that tR- (g) C JFJ(J) and E "® (g), f g(x) =x. Show that g is one to one. If, in addition, tR-(J) C "®(g) and Vy E"®(J), g0f(y) =y. show thatf=g-1•

6.

Vx

7.

o

Define a relation on the set Z of integers by writing n

=

m �n

- m is divisible by 5. Show that this is an equivalence relation. How many

equivalence classes are there?

8. =

For ordered pairs (x, y) and ( u, v) of real numbers write (x, y)

(u, v) �there exists a real number t > 0 so that (x,y) =(tu, tv). Show

that this is an equivalence relation and give a geometric description of the equivalence classes.

9.

Suppose R is a relation with the following properties: y E tR- ( R) ::::} (y, y) E R.

(a)

(/3)

(x,y ) , ( z,y ) E R::::} ( z,x ) E R.

Prove that (x, y) E R ::::} (y,x) E R.

1.4

THE NATURAL NUMBERS

In this section we shall give a set of axioms for the natural numbers and derive some of their more important properties. The proofs we give will be informal, as explained in Section 1.2, and the set theory we shall use will be intuitive. One may, quite legitimately, ask why we bother to be so formal about the development of the real number system when we are being so informal about logic and set theory. One answer is that the first serious questions about the nature of mathematics arose in connection with the real numbers, first among the ancient Greeks and later again among the nineteenth-century mathematicians. Hence an enormous amount of intellect and energy have been expended in trying to clarify the nature of these objects. Many people seem to feel that between certain limits these efforts have been successful agd that a usable system can be obtained from a few psychologically satis­ fying and clearly stated principles or axioms. Of course, there may be sharp disagreement on just where to start and how far one can go without getting involved in contradictions. We shall start with a set of axioms that are not as minimal and/or perhaps not as intuitively satisfactory as others. However, we feel they are reasonably satisfac­ tory and have the advantage that the development of the real numbers can proceed quite rapidly from them. The name 'the natural numbers' is given to any set N together with two functions + and following axioms:

·

each with domain N X N and range in N satisfying the

1.4

(a)

THE NATURAL NUMBERS I 27

(x)(y)(x+ y=y+ x). (x)(y)(x·y=y·x).

(a') (b)

(commutative laws)

(b')

(x)(y)(z)(x+(y+z)=(x+y)+z). (x)(y)(z)(x (y z)=(x y) · z).

(associative laws)

(c)

(x)(y)(z)(x

(distributive law)

·

·

·

·

(y+z) =x · y+x · z).

(d)

1E

(e)

N & (x)(x

x, y in N, one (I) x=y. (2) (3z)(x=y+z). (3) (3z)(y=x+z).

·

1

=

For every

x). and only one of the following is possible: (trichotomy/aw)

M C N , the following is true: [I E M & (x)(xE M�x+ IE M)] �M=N.

(f)

For every

(induction)

Using these axioms it is immediately possible to prove a number of results about the natural numbers

N.

[We are using

'N'

to designate the

natural numbers, although strictly speaking we should use the triple

'(N + , , )'.] ·

However, let us first make some comments about the

previous axioms. The axioms (a) through (c) are of course the familiar ones from arithmetic. The first part of the cortjunction of axiom (d) says that

N

=/:-

0 and names a particular element. The second part of

the axiom states a property for this element. Axiom (e) has been stated rather informally for the sake of clarity. It simply says that we can have one and only one possibility; either

x

and y are the same,

x

is greater

than y, or xis less than y. More formally, we could have given this axiom in terms of two axioms: ( e' )

(x)(y)(x =/:- y ¢:::> (3z)( y=x+z_ V x=y+ z)) . (x)(y)((3z)(y=x+z)�- (3z)(x=y+z)).

(e")

The last axiom (f) is often stated in the following way: If P (x) is a state­ ment depending on

x,

then

[P( I) & (x)(P(x)�P(x+ I))]�(x)(P(x)).

(f')

This can be translated to our statement (f) by the following device. Set

M={x: P(x)}; then if (f') is true, (f) is true for

M,

and vice versa.

Let us now give some examples that show how these axioms may be used to obtain other true statements about that

N

N.

Our first statement says

has no zero element; actually it says more.

1.4.1

Proposition.

There is no

x

and no y in

that is,

-(3x)(3y)(x+y=x).

N,

so that

x + y=x;

28 [ THE REAL NUMBER SYSTEM

Proof. We shall prove this by contradiction. Suppose (3x)(3y) (x+ y=x). This implies

(3x)(3y)((x=x) & (x+y=x)), which contradicts the trichotomy axiom (e). Our next statement is to the effect that we have a cancellation law in N with respect to multiplication.

Proposition.

1.4.2

If x· z=y z, then x= y, and vice versa, that is, ·

(x) (y)(z)(x ·z=y

·

z �x=y).

Proof. The fact that x=y=>x ·z=y z follows from our rules x and y are different names for the same thing and hence we may •

that

use them interchangeably in any expression. Hence we must prove the implication

(x)(y)(z)(x·z=y·z=>x=y). Suppose this 1s not true.

Then using our rule for negating statements we have

(3x) (3 y)(3z)(x·z=y



z &

x

=F

y).

(l.4.1)

By the trichotomy axiom (e) [or (e')]

x

=;/:

y=>(3w) (x=y+w Vy=x+ w),

and by the distributive law the latter statement implies

x

=F

y=>(3w)(x ·z=y·z+w · z Vy·z=x · z+ w · z).

(l.4.2)

Hence from ( 1.4.1) and (l.4.2) we get

[(3x) (3y)(3z) (x z=y · z & x =F y)] => [ (3x) (3 y)(3z) (x · z=y· z & (3w)(x z=y · z+ w ·

·

·

z Vy· z=x ·z+w

·

z) ) ],

which contradicts the trichotomy axiom.

1.4.3

Definition (x)(y)(x < y�(3z) (y=x+z)), (x)(y)(x�y�x x+ z� y+ w). Proof.

Exercise.

1.4.5

Proposition (x) (1 �x).

Proof..

Let us set

M= {x: 1.;;: x}.

that is,

1.4

Clearly 1

THE NATURAL NUMBERS I 29

{x)(x+ 1 E M). The latter statement follows from x+ 1 and z = I. Hence {x)(x E M =:::} x+1 E M), and by the principle of induction it follows that M = N. EM

and

Definition l.4.3 by putting y

=

The next statement is to the effect that there is no natural number between two successive natural numbers.

1.4.6

Proposition

-(3x)(3y)(x k C\ &2-(1T n) We =

to be the smallest element in

1Tn+i (n+ 1)




1T(j) < 1T(k) and if l E C and I� 1T(n) for some l E gi( 1T). To prove these statements we first note that if

property thatj
S/4.

50 I THE REAL NUMBER SYSTEM

If we now call the isomorphic image of

r

in R by the same name, we

have proved the lemma.

1.7 .15

Theorem. R+ is Archimedian-ordered in the sense that

(x)(y)(x,y ER+=>(3n)(n

EN

& x:;;; ny).

Proof. By the previous lemma 3 r,s E Q.+ , so that 0 < r < y and x < s < x + 1. Since Q.+ is Archimedian-ordered (Exercise 13 of Section 1.5), 3n E N, so thatx < s:;;; nr < ny. ·

1.7 .16

range R+

The absolute value is that function with domainRand {O} defined by the following:

Definition. U

{

x ¢:::) x �0, lxl = -x ¢:::) x 0. :;;; 1. 7.17

For everyx and yin R,

Theorem.

x:;;; lxl, -x:;;; lxl, lxl =I-xi, llxl - IYll:;;; Ix+ YI:;;; lxl + IYI· Proof.

See Propositions 1 5. 7 and l.5.8. .

The important question now arises as to what happens if we repeat the process for

real

Cauchy sequences that we have just gone through

for rational Cauchy sequences. Theorem l.7.20 below shows that we get nothing new.

A real sequence is a function with domain N0=N U {0} and range in R. A real Cauchy sequence x is a sequence such that Ve>0, 3N so that if n,m EN0 and n,m �N, then lx(n)- x(m) I 0=> (3N) (n) (m)(n,m E N0 & n,m�N=> lx(n) - x(m) I 0, 3N so that Vn E N0 with n�N, lx(n)- al < E. If the real sequence x has a limit a we say that x is convergent, and also x converges to a. In the formalism of the predicate calculus the definition of a limit would be as follows:

a ER is

a limit of the real sequence

x ¢:::)

(e)(E>0=>(3N)(n)(n E N0 & n�N=>lx(n)- al ((/2),

€-

[r-;;{P) - r(p) ] > (@),

N.

If we now identify € with the constant Cauchy sequence defined by

r;{jj)

=

€, we have shown that for Vn � N the Cauchy sequences

r.-+ [�-T] are positive, where

r is

r. ..- [.... rn .. -r'] ....

and

the rational Cauchy sequence that evaluated at

p is r(p). If we take the equivalence classes of these sequences we get R(T,') + R(T,;'- r) > 0

R("f;) - R(T,;- r) > 0.

and

If we now set

a= R(T), then from the facts that and

r(n) = R (r,;-),

52 J THE REAL NUMBER SYSTEM

we have arrived at the conclusion that

Vn ;;;.: N,

lr(n)-al < E. x is a real Cauchy sequence. Using the Archimedian Un={m: m E Z & x(n) .;;; m/n} is nonvoid and hence, by the well ordering of N (see Exercise 17 of Section 1.5), Un has a minimal element mn. If we set r(n)= mn/n, then from the fact that (mn-I)/n < x(n) we get 0 .;;; r(n) - x(n) < I/n. Since x is a Cauchy sequence, the sequence r defined by the numbers r(n) is Cauchy. Indeed, Ve> 0, 3e' E Q+ with e' < E and 3M so that n,m ;;;.: M ==> lx(n) -x(m)I < e'/2. Hence, if n,m;;;.: max {M, 4/e}, we have Suppose now that

ordering of R+, the set

lr(n)-r(m)I .;;; lr(n)-x(n)I +lx(n)-x(m)I I I +ix(m)-r(m)I

0, 3N so that n

� N implies

lx(n) - al < e/2. Therefore, if

n,m

� N,

lx(n) - x(m) I



lx(n) - al

+

la - x(m) I
(j) < (k) means that the range of is

denumerable. Hence, speaking loosely, "picks out" an infinite num­ ber of the ordered pairs

(n, x(n)) to form the sequence y. As a simple (x(n)) to be the sequence given by x(n) = n2

example, suppose we take +

2. Take (n) =2n

+ l; then

y(n) = x (n) = (2n 0

+

1)2

+

2

=

4n2

+

4n

+ 3.

54 I THE REAL NUMBER SYSTEM

D Exercises I.

Use the principle of induction to show the following inequalities: (a)

h

0

;;,.

&

n

E

N0 =>

n( (1+h) n ;;,. 1+nh+ 0

(b)



h



I

(I - h) n h

(c)



N0 => n (n 1 - nh+

h2•

E

0, n. E N, n

;;,.

(I+h) n 2.

n

&

n; I)

;;,. 2 =>

;;,. 1+nh +

2



; I) h2•

h2•

Show that every finite set in R has a unique maximum element

and a unique m in imum element. Use this fact to give another proof of Lemma 1.7.7.

3.

Show that there is always an irrational (not rational) number

between any two real numbers. Recall that there exists an irrational number:

\/2.

If

lxl
1, show that Vk E

5.

If

6.

For every

x

as

n-oo.

N

E R, show that

xn ,-o n.

as

n-oo.

x(n) -a, y(n) - b as n - oo, and x(n)y(n) -ab as n -oo. 7.

If

8.

If

(x(n))

show that

x(n) + y(n) -a+ b

is a convergent sequence, show that every subsequence

(x (n)). Conversely, if every "proper" (x(n)) converges, then (x(n)) converges. By a "proper" subsequence we mean a subsequence x , where (m) (3n) (n ;;,. m & (n+I) > (n)+1). converges to the same limit as

subsequence of

0

9.

W ithout using Theorem 1.7.20, show that if a subsequence of a

Cauchy sequence converges, then the Cauchy sequence itself converges.

10.

Suppose

x(n) -a

as

n-oo and 3N such lx(n) - bl

What can be said about

la - bl

?




1.8

If

11.

A REVIEW OF THE REAL NUMBER SYSTEM AND SEQUENCES I 55

as

x(n)- a

show that

n- oo,

lx(n) I - lal

as

n- oo.

Give an

example that shows that the converse is not always true. For what value(s) of

12.

If

a,

if any, is it

(x(n))

always

true that

lx(n) I -l al



x(n) -a?

is a sequence and

x(2n) -a, x(2n

+

as

1) -a

n-

oo,

show that

x(n)-a 13.

Let

(s(n)) be

as

n-oo.

a sequence and set

x z


x+ IE M, then

M=N. Indeed, M is an inductive set and hence NC M. Since MC N we must have M=N. Now that we have N we can state the next property of the real number system. (i)

For every x and yin R with x that x < ny (Archimedian ordering).

> 0

and y>

0,

there is an n in N so

To state our last and rather crucial property for the real number system, it is necessary to consider the concepts of a sequence, a Cauchy sequence, and a limit of a sequence. For this purpose we have the follow­ ing definitions:

58 I THE REAL NUMBER SYSTEM 1.8.4 A (real) sequence is a function with domain N0 =N U {O} and range in R. A sequence will usually be denoted by the term '(x(n)) ' or ' (x n) ', and this is to indicate that x(n) or Xn is the value of the Junction at n E N0• A sequence (y(n)) is said to be a subsequence of (x(n)) there is a function with domain N0 and range in N0 so that j < k ==> (j) < (k) and y(n)=x((n)). 1.8.5

The absolute value is the function defined by lx. l =

1.8.6

{

xx �0, -x. x < 0.

The following properties hold for the absolute value: -x � lxl, x � lxl, x I l l- IYI I � Ix+ YI

We are, incidentally, using

a



b



lxl =I-xi, x l l+ IYI ·

to mean

a < b

or

a=b.

1.8.7 A sequence (x(n)) is said to be a Cauchy sequence VE > 0, 3N so that if m,n�N, then lx(n) - x(m) I < E. 1.8.8 A sequence (x(n)) is said to have a limit 3a such that VE > 0, 3N so that n �N ==> lx(n)- al < E. The number a is said to be the limit of (x(n)). If a sequence has a limit, it is said to be convergent. We can now state a crucial property of the real number s ystem:

Every Cauchy sequence has a limit.

(j )

Let us note that if a sequence has a limit, then the limit must be

unique. 3N so

Indeed, suppose that

that

a and bare limits of (x(n)). Then VE > 0, n �N ==> lx(n) - al < E/2 and lx(n) - bl < E/2. Hence we

have VE > 0,

la- bl If



S =la - bl > 0,

la- x(n)I+ lx(n) - bl
is true and very easy to prove:

1.8.9

Every convergent sequence is Cauchy.

Indeed, suppose x(n) - a. This means that V e> 0, 3N so that n;:;,: N� lx(n)-al < e/2. Hence, if m,n;:;,: N, we get, using the triangle inequality,

lx(n)-x(m)I ,,;;:; lx(n)-al+lx(m)-al < e. This, of course, proves that

(x(n))

is Cauchy.

1.8.10 Every convergent sequence is bounrkd; tha t is, 3M so that Vn EN0, lx(n)I,,;;:; M.

n;:;,: N � lx(n) - al < 1. Hence n;:;,: N� lx(n)I,,;;:; I+lx(a)I. Let L = max{x(n): n E( O, N) } and M= max(L, I+lal). Clearly Vn E No, lx(n)I,,;;:; M. Suppose

x(n) -a;

then 3N so that

using the triangle inequality, we get that

1.8.11

defined

as

The sum and product of two sequences (x(n)) and (y(n)) are follows: (x+y)(n) = x(n)+y(n), (xy) (n) = x(n)y(n).

Note we have reverted to the custom of dropping the symbol

'·'

for

multiplication.

1.8.12

If x(n) - a and y(n) -b, then (x+y)(n) - a+b, (xy)(n) -ab.

x(n) -a and y(n) -b mean first of all that 3M> 1, Vn EN0, lx(n)I ,,;;:; M, and ly(n) I ,,;;:; M. S econd, Ve> 0, 3N n;:;,: N� lx(n) - al < e/2M, ly(n)-bl < e/2M. Hence, if n;:;,: N,

The facts that so that so that

l(x+y)(n)- (a+b )I,,;;:; lx(n)- al +ly(n)-bl < e, I(xy)(n)- abl ,,;;:; ly(n)I lx(n)-al +lal ly(n)-b I ,,;;:; M {lx(n)- al+ly(n)-bl} < e. In the last part of the above proof we have used the fact that lx(n)I ,,;;:; M for all

n EN0 � lal ,,;;:; M.

We shall leave the verification of this simple

fact to the reader. In 1.8.2 we defined the natural numbers. Now take

-N= {x: -x EN}, Z=-N UN U{O}.

60 I THE REAL NUMBER SYSTEM

The set Z is, of course, called

the integers. The rational numbers is the

set Q=

{m/n: m,n

We are, of course, writing

1.8.13

Vx

E R,

E Z,

n

¥-

O}.

m/n for m( l/n).

The rationals are dense in the reals in the sense that VE 3r E Q, so that Ix - rl < E.

> 0 and

3n E N so that lxl < n, -n < x < n. Again, using Archimedian ordering, 3m E N so that l/m < E. Let k E N be the smallest natural number so thatx,,;:;; -n + k/m. Then -n + (k - I)/m < x and if we set r = -n + k/m, we have Ix - rl = -n + k/m - x < k/m - (k - l)/m < E. Indeed, by the Archimedian ordering of R,

or,

equivalently,

In the previous proof we have made use of some facts about the relation < without explicitly mentioning them. For example, we said

lxl < n is equivalent to the fact that -n < x and x < n. Indeed, x ,,;:;; lxl we get from (g) that x < n, and from -x ,,;:;; lxl we get -x < n, and from (e) and (h), n + x > 0. Now, using (d), (e), and (h) we get x = -n + n + x > -n + 0 = -n, which is what we set out to prove. that

from

The reverse implication follows in a similarly easy way. Note we are using the usual convention thatx -

y= x

+

(-y). We are sure the reader

can fill in the details of proofs of other facts. Aside from the fact that the rationals are dense in the reals, they also have the property that they have the "same number': of elements as the positive integers. More formally this can be written as follows:

1.8.14

There exists a one-to-one function with domain

N and range Q.

The proof of this statement can be found in Section 1.6. More gen­ erally we can make the following definition:

1.8.15 A set tion with domain

A N

is said to be denumerable and range A .

¢::> there

exists a one-to-one func­

Another way of phrasing 1.8.14 is to say that the rationals are denum­ erable. We can also talk about finite sets.

1.8.16 A set A is said to be finite ¢::>A is the null set, in which case we say that A has zero elements, or else there is a one-to-one function with domain the {k: k E N & 1,,;:;; k,,;:;; n} and range A, in which case we say set (I, n) A has n elements. A set that is either finite or denumerable is called countable. =

D Exercises Use only statements (a) through U> as axioms in proving the following:

1.8

A REVIEW OF THE REAL NUMBER SYSTEM AND SEQUENCES J 61

1.

Show that -(x+y) =-x+ (-y) and (xy)-1=x-1 y-1.

2.

If n,m E N, then n +m E N and n

3.

Show that 0 < 1.

4.

For every n E N, 1 :;:;; n.

·

m E N.

5. It is not true that there is an n E N and an m E N so that n 0, 3x(n) such that 0 < lx(n) - al < e. Now, Ve> 0, 3N such that n;;;., N � ly(n) - al < e/2. Also, Vn;;;., N, 3n1;;;., n so that lx(n1) - y(n) I < e/2 and Vm> n1, 3n2;;;., m so that lx(n2) - y(m) I < e/2. Hence 3n1 and 3n2> n1 so that Jx(n1) - al lx(n2) -al Since (b)

x(n1) #- x(n2),

� �

lx(n1) - y(n) I + ly(n) - al < e, lx(n2) - y(m) I + ly(m) - al < e.

it follows that either

x(n1) #-a or x(n2) #-a.

Suppose now that A is any bounded infinite set in R. One way

of trying to reduce this case to the previous case is to try to choose a denumerable set inA. However, since it is not clear how to do this using only the axiom of induction, we shall proceed in a slightly different way. Let us set

m =infA,

M=supA.

These numbers exist by virtue of the Theorem 1.9.5. Next, let us put P = {x:

x

mA & Theorem 1.9.3 =>A & Theorem 1.9.5 =>A & Theorem 1.9.7.

[Incidentally, the reason we did not use Theorem 1.9.3 directly in the proof of Theorem l.9.7(a) in taking a as the limit of the monotone sequence (y(n)) is that we wanted to establish the above chain of impli­ cation.] If we can show that A & Theorem I. 9.7 => A & (j), then all these statements are equivalent and any one of the statements of Theorems 1.9.3, 1.9.5, or 1.9.7 can be used in place of U). 1.9.8

Theorem.

A

& Theorem 1.9.7 =>A & ( j ) .

Proof. Let (x(n)) be a real Cauchy sequence. We distinguish two cases. (a) The range of (x(n)) is finite. In this case 3N so that n,m � N => x(n) x(m). Indeed, if this is not the case, Vk, 3nk � k & 3mk � k such that lx(nk) - x(mk) I sk > 0. By hypothesis, it is immediate that the collection of numbers {Sk} is finite. Let 8 be the minimum of these numbers and E 8/2. Since (x(n)) is Cauchy, 3L such that k � L => lx(nk) - x(mk) I < E, which is a contradiction. Take a = x(n) for n � N, and this is clearly the limit of (x(n)). (b) The range of (x(n)) is infinite. Let a be an accumulation point of the range of (x(n)), which exists by Theorem 1.9.7. Since (x(n)) is Cauchy, 3N so that n,m � N => lx(n) - x(m) I < e/2. Now a is an accumulation point of the set {x(n): n � N}. Therefore, 3n1 � N so that lx(n1) a l < e/2. Hence, for any n � N, =

=

=

-

lx(n)

-

a l ,,;;;;

lx(n1) - al+ lx(n) - x(n1) I
n, Inc., Boston, 1961.

68 I THE REAL NUMBER SYSTEM D Exercises 1.

If

A and B are bounded subsets of R and A C B, show that l.u.b. A � l.u.b. B, g.l.b. B � g.l.b. A.

2.

If

A and B are bounded subsets of R, show that sup A U B =max(sup A, sup B), inf AU B =min(inf A, inf B).

3.

If

A C R and A has an upper bound that belongs to A, show A.

that this upper bound must be sup 4.

If a set

A has a l.u.b. that does not belong to A, show that this

l.u.b. is an accumulation point of A.

of

5. If A is a denumerable set in R and a is an accumulation point A, show that there is a sequence in A which converges to a. If you

use the axiom of induction, be sure you use it carefully and correctly.

6.

(a)

Show that the l.u.b. of the range of a bounded monotone

nondecreasing sequence is the limit of the sequence. (b)

Show that if a subsequence of a monotone nondecreasing

sequence is bounded, then the sequence is bounded.

7.

Show that the sequence defined by the following expression is

monotone increasing and bounded:

3 a(n) = 2 8.

·

5

·

·

·

·

4

·

·

·

(2n+ 3) 2(n+ l)'

n

EN0•

Assuming the binomial theorem as known, show that the se­

quence defined as follows is monotone increasing and bounded:

(

a(n) = I +

)

I "+1 , n+1

n

EN0•

The reader may recognize that the limit of this sequence is designated by 'e'.

9. Show that Va � 0 and V n EN, there is a unique y � 0 so that =a. Designate this unique y by 'a1/n' and show that if 0 � a < b, then a 1 1n < blln, and conversely. " y

10.

Prove that lim11_00 n11" =1. [Hint: Set n11" =I+

n =(I+

a11

) n � [n(n-1)/2!]

2 an ,

an

and hence

for n � 2.]

11.

Show that lim.,._00 n!/nn

12.

What is the set of all accumulation points of the subset of the

=

0.

rationals of the form

n,p,q

EN?

CHAPTER

21 LIMITS

We have already discussed the concept of function in Section 1.3. In this and in the next few chapters we shall be exclusively interested in those functions which have their domains and ranges in the real number system. A real sequence is an example of such a function. To discuss the properties of real-valued functions, it is convenient to introduce some notation and terminology for certain sets of real numbers. We shall define

]a,b[= {x: a(J) and V€ > 0, 3S > 0 such tliat Ix - al (f), then for f to be continuous at a, it is necessary and sufficient that

limf(x) =f(a).

x-a

2.1.6 Proposition. If a function f is continuous at a, then a E J0(J) and for every sequence (xn) with range in 1€>(J) and Xn � a, we have f(xn)

74 I LIMITS

--+f(a). (AC) Conversely, if a E �(J), and for every sequence (xn) with range n i �(J) if Xn --+ a impl iesf(xn) --+f(a), then f is continuous at a. ,

Proof. If f is continuous at a, then Ve> 0, 3o > 0 so that Ix- al < o and x E �(J) � lf(x)-f(a)I< e. Also 3N so that n � N � lxn - al< o. Hence n � N � IJ(xn)-f(a)I< e, which is the proof of the first sentence. To prove the second statement, let us assume to the contrary that

0 so that Vo > 0 there exists an x E �(J) Ix- al< o and IJ(x)- J(a)I � e0. For n E N0, let On= I/ (n +I) and An= {x: x E �(J) & Ix- al< On & IJ(x)-f(a)I � eo}. Each set An is nonvoid and hence by (AC) there exists a sequence (xn) so that Xn E An. Clearly Xn--+ a, but since Vn E N0, IJ(xn)- J(a)I it is not true. Then 3e0>

so that



e0,

we get a contradiction.

2.1.7 Theorem. If f and g are continuous at a E �(J) n �(g), thenf + g and Jg are contn i uous at a, and if g(a) ¥- O,f/g is a/,so continuous ata. Proof. to

f

and

In case

g,

a

is an accumulation point of the domain common

then the theorem is an immediate consequence of Proposi­

tion 2.1.4 and the remark made prior to Proposition 2.1.6. In case

a

is not an accumulation point of the common domain, all the functions listed are automatically continuous.

2.1.8 Theorem. If f and g are functions, if g is continuous at a and f continuous at b= g(a): then f 0 g is continuous at a. (See Defin ition 1.3.5 for f0 g.) is

Sincefis continuous at b, Ve> 0, 311 > 0 so that IY - bl < '11 y E �(J) � IJ(y) -f(b) I < e. Also, since g is continuous at a, 3 o> 0 s o that Ix- al< o and x E �(g) � lg(x) - g(a) I< '11· Hence

Proof.

and

IJ0 g(x)- Jo g(a)I< e Ix- al


0

THE LIMIT CONCEPT AND CONTINUITY 175

a E ]O, I]. We know that 38(E, a) , depending Ix - al < 8 and x E ]O, I] � ll(x) - l(a) I < E.

and

so that

Therefore,

and this in turn implies that

Ix - al x � 1.

since

Hence for fixed

E,

is fixed and

E goes

to zero,

EXa




r},

r }.

These are monotone nonincreasing and nondecreasing functions, respectively, and we define Jim f(x) = Jim ;,(r),

x-oo

r-ao

Jim f(x) = Jim f_t(r). x-oo

r-oo

We can consider oo as an accumulation point of Je(f) since every open interval I ( oo) contains a point of Je(f). If f is a bounded sequence, the latter quantities are called the limit superior and the limit inferior of the sequence, since the domain of a sequence has no finite accumu­ lation point. We shall leave to the reader the easy task of formulating these notions at -oo. It is possible to get a geometric meaning of the previous definition which may make it more understandable. The number ih(r) may be thought of as measuring the size of the largest peak off as x varies over the deleted interval {x: 0 < Ix - al < r}, and 'Pr(r) measures the depth of the deepest valley. As r decreases to zero, the size of the largest peak decreases to �1(0+) and the size of the deepest valley shortens to 'f'r(O+). - As an example, let us consider the function given by f(x) =sin (l/x) for x � 0. A sketch of the graph of this function is shown in Fig. 2.4.1.

92 I LIMITS

-1 7T

-1

-2

Figure 2.4.1

As x - 0, we get an infinite number of peaks and valleys of this function. It is clear that Vr > 0, �(r) 1, !e(r)= -1. Hence =

lim sin (l/x). = 1,

x-o

lim sin (l/x) x-o

=

-1.

'

Note that this function does not have a limit at x 2.4.2

Proposition.

=

0.

The function f has the limit l at a¢:::a :>

is an

accumu­

lation point of �(f) and lim f(x)= l

=

lim f(x).

Proof. Suppose f(x) - z as x - a. This means Ve> 0, 38> 0 so that x E �(f) and 0 < Ix - a l < 8 � l f (x) - l l < e. It follows that if 0 < r ,,,-;; 8, then l�1(r) - ll ,,,-;; e and l 0, 38> 0 so that 1�1(8) - l l < e and l lim (Jg) (x).

x:::;o

x:::;o

x=o

2.4

LIMIT SUPERIOR AND LIMIT INFERIOR I 95

For the second exampie take

J(x) =I+ sin(l/x), Clearly

g(x) = cos(I/x),

x

¥=

0.

f(x) � 0 for all x in its domain, and g changes sign infinitely

often in any neighborhood of zero. If we take xk so that I/xk =

k = 0,

±

1, · · · , we

(2k+ 1)7T,

get

Hence

(Jg)(x)

lim

� -1.

x-o

On the other hand, limf(x)

x-o

= 0,

lim

x-o

g(x) =-1 ,

which leads to the inequality lim

x-o

f(x) lim g(x) > lim (Jg)(x). x-o

x-o

Finally, as a third example we consider

f(x) =-1 +sin (I/x), If we take

g(x) = -1 +cos (l/x).

xk so that l/xk = (2k+ 1)7T, k= 0, 1, 2, ···,we get f(xk)g(xk) = 2

and therefore lim

x-o

But lim J(x) x-o

=

lim

x-o

(Jg)(x) �2.

g(x) = 0 and consequently we get limf(x) lim g(x) < lim (Jg)(x).

x-o

x-o

x-o

Let us 'finish this section by giving an application of the use of the concept of limit superior and limit inferior. This involves an extension of the idea of a Cauchy sequence.

2.4.4 Proposition. Suppose f is a function, a is an accumulation point of �(J ) and Ve > 0, 38 > 0 so that 0 < Ix-al < a, 0 < l y-al 0 so that V8 with �(J ) so that 0 < IY - al < a and -

.

96 I LIMITS

lf(y) - ll < E/2. Suppose we have taken 8 small enough so that x,y E �(f ) and 0 < Ix - a l < 8 and 0 < IY a l < 8 � l f(x) -f(y)I < e/2. Then we get -

lf(x) - ll



IJ(x) - f(y)I

+

lf(y) - ll < E.

D Exercises 1.

that

If f is bounded and

a

is an accumulation point of �(f ), show

Jim - f(x)-= -lim f(x). x-a

x-a

2. Show that the inequalities in Theorem 2.4.3(b) are reversed if f and g are nonpositive. 3. If f is a bounded nonnegative function and a is an accumulation point of �(f ), show that Va � 0,

Jim r) ), where cl> is a one-to-one function with domain and range N0• 0

0

It turns out that every rearrangement of an infinite series is conver­ gent if and only if the series whose terms are the absolute values of the terms of the original series is convergent. We first give a formal definition.

3.1.5 Definition. An infinite series (a, u(a)) is said to be absolutely convergent� the sequence u( lal) is convergent, where Vn E N0, lal =la l If an infinite series is convergent, but not absolutely convergent, it is called conditionally convergent. n

n .

A natural question is whether or not conditionally convergent series exist. The answer is in the affirmative and an example is given .by the senes

102 I INFINITE SERIES

f

k=O

( (-I)k ) · k+I

This series is certainly not absolutely convergent, since the series of absolute values is the harmonic series. The fact that the series is con­ vergent is a consequence of Leibnitz' criteria, which will be established in Section 3.2.

3.1.6 Lemma. If V k finite subset of N0, then

ak

E N0,

�0,

, )),

we

3.1

Thus 0,,;;;;

an+,,;;;; Ian!, 0,,;;;; an-,,;;;; Ian!, and an=an+ - an-. n n "' L ak±,,;;;; L lakl ,,;;;; L lakl, k=O

and sirice

SERIFS OF REAL NUMBERS I 103

1. By the definition of limit

superior, VN, 3n � N so that

lanl11n

p- E,

>

or, what is the same thing,

lanl

(p - E)n

>

> 1.

lanl � 0 and thus u(jai) cannot con­ lanl11n is unbounded and clearly we get

Consequently, it is not true that verge. If p = oo, the sequence

the same result.

Let us prove the converges of �k=i First, if

k

E

N and n >

k,

we have

n!

>

(l/n!)

kn-k+1.

Consequently, for all sufficiently large

( n ! )l/n This shows that

. hm

n,

kkJn

>

by means of the root test.

( )l/n 1 -1

n-"' n.

>

k/2.

=O,

and the series converges by the root test.

3.2.3 3N so

Suppose (an)

D'Alembert's Ratio Test. � N ===>an¥- 0. Define

that n

is

a sequence for which

l aann l 1 aan+n1 1

+l , R =Im . 1 -n-

QO

r=I.1m

n:::"OO

If R < 1, u(jai) Proof.

is

convergent and if r

-- .

> 1,

u{iai)

is

divergent.

This is an immediate consequence of the root test and the

chain of inequalities, ll·m

n-co

1 aan+n 1 1

.;;;;

· 1 lffi

n-oo

I an 111n

112 I INFINITE SERIES

We shall leave the proof of these inequalities to Exercise 1 at the end of the secu'on. The convergence of the series of factorials that we have considered previously is also an immediate consequence of the ratio test since

n!/ (n + I) != l/n

+

1�0.

The ratio test, when it works, is usually very easy to apply and hence is very useful. When it fails it may be possible to apply a slightly sharper variant of it.

Raabe's Test. Suppose (an) is a sequence for which 3N so that ¥- 0. Let us put

3.2.4

n

�N => a

n

a

n- ( -la·ann+i I) , n n(1-1 aann+il)·

= lim n

1

oo

{3= lim -

If

a

oo

> 1, er(lal) is convergent and if (3

Proof.

Thus

If

a

kjak+il jak+il

> 1,

a

la�:l l

< k (

Hencek

Vp so that

0

1, er( lal) is divergent.


p > 1, 3 K so thatk


-x·

- I) lakl + ( I - p) lakl, or, rearranging terms, we get




lakak+1 1

> l

_

f!..

k

Therefore,

j

so that k a k + il is monotone increasing ask increases. For fixed andk � p we get

p

�K

lak+1I > (p- 1) lavlfk. Consequently, er (lal) diverges by comparison with the harmonic series.

3.%

CONVERGENCE TESTS I I 13

Both the root test and the ratio test fail for the series

i

k=l

{: ) 2

·

However, Raabe's test will show this is convergent. Indeed,

Thus I

( -

k

k +I

)

2

I > I - I+ 2/k

=k

2 + 2'

and hence Jim

k-oo

(k +

2 ) [l

-

(k/k + 1)2]

=Jim

k-oo

k [I

-

(k/k + 1)2 ]

;:.;,: 2.

3.2.5 Cauchy's Condensation Test. If (an) is a monotone nonin­ creasing sequence with nonnegative terms, then the following series converge or diverge simultaneously:

Proof.

The sequences of partial sums of these series are monotone

nondecreasing. If a monotone nondecreasing sequence has a subse­ quence that is bounded, then the sequence is bounded and thus con­ vergent.

If the sequence is divergent, then every subsequence is

unbounded. Using the monotone nonincreasing character of (an) we get 2k+l-1

L a;,,;;; 2ka 2k,,;;;

J=2k

2

2k-1

L

i=2k-1

where the sum on the right is taken to be 2a0 if

k =0

to

k

=

n we

k = 0.

Summing from

get

u(a)2 n+l-i,,;;;

n

ao + L

k=O

2k a2k,,;;; 2u(a) 2n_1•

This set of inequalities when taken together with the comments in the first paragraph constitute the proof. As an example of the use of the condensation test, let us consider the convergence properties of the

p series,

114 I INFINITE SERIES

Recall that for p

=

1 we called this the harmonic series and showed it

diverged. Hence the comparison test shows that the p series diverges for p < 1. We can apply the condensation test only for p � 0, since otherwise the sequence ( l/nP) is increasing. For p � 0 we must examine the convergence of the series 00

'L

k=O

k ( l/2 1 and diverges for p � 1 . There is another very useful test for absolute convergence called the integral test. We shall take this up in Chapter 5. For now let us turn to some other convergence tests which are not specifically tests for abso­ lute convergence. Let us first prove a result called the Abel sum mation form ula. In Chapter 5 we shall recognize this formula as a special case of integration by parts for Riemann-Stieltjes integrals. For every pair of sequences (a,,) and (b,,)

Lemma (Abel).

3.2.6

n

L

k=O

akbk

=

bn+1 u(a)n -

n

L

k=O

(bk+1 - bk ) u(ah.

We have, upon setting u(a)_1

Proof.

=

(3.2.l)

0,

ak = u(ah- u(ah 1· Therefore, n

L

k=O

akbk=

n

L

k=O

bku(ah-

n

L

k=I

bk u(ah-1

·

(3.2.2)

The last sum begins at k= 1, since u(a)_1= 0. This last sum can also be written n

L

k=O

bk+1

j so that (3.3.2)

b would have an expansion of the form j-1

b= :L bkf3k + 2w. k=l b is in the complement of C. Also, j, so that bk ¥ 0; otherwise we see from (3.3.2) that "' J-1 b= :L bkf3k + :L 2t3k, k=l k=;+l

which contradicts the fact that

3k

>

which would contradict the fact that

bE cc. Let us set

J-1 q/3i-l = :L bk/3k. k=l

VkE{ 1, j - 1 ), bk is even, we see that q is even and moreover 31-1• By what we have just proved,

Since

q


n, we again get a contradiction. 2n-1 intervals of the form lq,n that we have described. Since each such interval has length l/3 n, the sum of their lengths add up to 2n-i /3n . Hence the sum of the lengths of the pair­ contradicts the fact that p #

For fixed n there are exactly

wise disjoint intervals which make up cc is

n=I Every point of the Cantor set is an accumulation point of C. A closed set with this property is called a perfect set. The proof is very easy. Suppose

a EC and

akE{O,2},

124 J INFINITE SERIES

where

ak



0 for

an infinite number of

series are all different from

k. Then the partial sums of this

belong to C, and converge to

a,

a.

If, on

the other hand,

ak then for

n

>

E

{O, 2},

j, the numbers

are in C, are different from

a, and converge The Cantor set is uncountable. The proof

to

a.

is also rather easy, being

simply an application of the Cantor diagonal process. Suppose C is countable and is a one-to-one function with domain N and range C. Set

ak=(k)

and define

{

ak=

0¢::::}a\=2, 2¢=}akk=O .

Clearly, the number determined by the sequence

(ak)

in its ternary

expansion belongs to C but is not in the range of . Collecting all the previous results we have proved the following theorem.

3.3.4 Theorem. The Cantor set is an uncountable perfect set in [O, 1) whose complement consists of the union of pairwise disjoint open intervals, the sum of whose lengths is 1. It is interesting and instructive to look at the geometric positions of the intervals that comprise cc (see Fig. 3.3. l ). The interval I 0, 1 is

] 1/3, 2/3[,

0

that is, the "middle third" of the interval [O,

1 9

2 9

2 3

1 3

7 9

1].

8 9

The interval

1

FIGURE 3.3. 1

/0,2 is

] 1/9, 2/9[,

and the interval /2,2 is

)7/9, 8/9[.

These intervals

represent the "middle thirds" of the intervals that remain after I 0, 1 is removed. Proceeding in this way, by removing the "middle thirds" of the intervals that remain after any given stage, after a denumerable number of steps we are left with Cantor's set.

3.3

DECIMAL EXPANSIONS I 125

O Exercises 1.

If

m,p, n E N, m

write

p /mn 2.

If

>

n

=

p,m E N, m

1,

L

k Pk/m ,

>

1,

k=l

p < mn,

and

show that it is possible to

pk E ( 0, m

-

1 ).

show that p has a unique representation

in the form

Pk E (O,m-1), Pn¥- 0. (Hint:

Exercise

1

may be helpful.)

3. A sequence (ak) is said to eventually periodic{:::::> 3N and 3 p E N so that k ;:_;,,, N ==> ak+P = ak. If m E N and m > 1, we know that every a E;:: [O, I] can be written

ak E (O,m-1). Show that 4.

a

is rational{:::::>

Suppose that

(ak)

is eventually periodic.

m E N, m > 1, and suppose we make the decimal [ 0, 1 J unique by taking the representing

expansion of any number in

series of a terminating decimal as a finite sum. Show that 00

L

k=I if and only if A=

5.

k ak/m


m,

n � L lik(x )I k=m+l

=

l 0,

is conditionally convergent� the infinite series

is conditionally convergent. 6.

Suppose

the infinite

product

nk,,,O (I

+

ak)

is conditionally

convergent. Use the results of Exercise 5 to show that Va E R, a¥- 0, there is a rearrangement of the product which converges to a.

CHAPTER

41

DIFFERENTIATION

4.1

THE DERIVATIVE CONCEPT

When speaking about the derivative of a function at a point, it is usual to take the domain of the function an open interval or an open set, and, of course, the point to be in this open set. However, situations often arise where functions are defined on closed intervals, and it is conven­ ient to talk about the derivatives of the functions at the end points of the intervals. It is for this reason that we give the following slightly more general definition.

4.1.1 E

Definition. A function f is said to have a derivative at a � a £J(f ), a is an accumulation point of£J(f ), and . f(x) - f(a) lIm x-a

x-a

exists. In case this limit exists, it is called the derivative of f at a and is denoted by any one of the symbols 'f'(a)', 'df(a)/dx', or 'D f(a)'. If f is differentiable at every point of its domain it is called differentiable. The derivative of a function f is that function f' (or dj/dx or DJ) with domain £J(J') = {x:f'(x) exists} (possibly void) whose value at the point a E £J(f') is the derivative of f at a. From a logical point of view the notation

DJ,

for the derivative of a

D as a function with all real-valued functions each having domain

function, is the most suitable. For we can consider domain the collection &I of

in R (including that function whose domain is the null set), and the range of

D

is also in &I. Then we can define

D2 = D oD, D3 = D2 oD,

and so on. !his "definition by induction" is made precise in the follow­ ing way. It can be proved by induction that there exists a unique func­ tion

F with

domain N and range in the collection of functions each

having domain &I and range in &I so that

F(l) = D , If we set

F(n+I) =F(n) oD .

D11 =F(n), then V f E &I we call D"f the nth derivative 'j11 < » and 'df11/dx"'. We also set D0J =f

of

f.

Other notations are

4.1.2

at a� a lll8

Definition. E

We shall say that a function f is n-times differentiable £J(J 0, l/2n < S, and m be that integer so that m/2n �a < (m + 1) /2n. Set b1 m/2n, b2 = (m + l )/2n, and b = (b1 + b2)/2. If k > n, then sincefk has period l/2k, we have f (b1) =f (b) =fk(b2). If k < n, let p be that integer so k k that p/2k �b1 < (p + 1) /2k. Then, of course, p/2k < b< (p + 1) /2k and p/2k < b2 � (p + l)/2k. If pis even we have, for j E (1, 2), =

fk(b2) - fdb1) fk(bj)-h(b) = = 2k' b; -b b2 -b1 and, if pis odd,

In either event, if k >

n

or k
(f )

n

J:>(g).

h is

Formula (b) is a consequence of the equation

(Jg)(a+h)- (Jg)(a) h =f(a+h) the fact that

g(a+

�)

-

g(a)

+g(a)

f(a+h -f(a) '

k

f is continuous at a, and the fact that a limit of a sum and

product is the sum of the limits and the product of the limits, respect­ ively. Formula (c) is a consequence of the equation

(I/g)(a+h)- (I/g)(a) g(a+h)- g(a) -1 - g(a h)g(a) h h + _

a, and the fact that the limit of a product g is continuous and g(a) "" 0, g(a+h) ""0 for all sufficiently small h for which a+h E J:>(g). the fact that g is continuous at

is the product of the limits. Note that since

Theorem (Chain Rule). If f and g are functions with �(g) J:>(f ), and g'(a) and f '(g(a)) exist, then (f g)'(a) exists and

4.2.2 C

0

(fog)'(a)=f '(g(a))g'(a). Proof.

The most natural way to begin to construct a proof is to

consider the equality

(f

0

g)(a+h)- (f g)(a) h 0

=

f(g(a+h)) - f(g(a)) g(a+h)- g(a). h g(a+h)- g(a)

Since g has a derivative at a, it is continuous at a and hence as h - 0, g(a+h)- g(a) - 0. Consequently, taking limits on both sides of the

4.2

DIFFERENTIATION RULES I 147

above equality we should get the formula stated in the theorem. The

g(a + h) - g(a)

one possible difficulty with this method is that be zero for an infinite number of values of

h

could

in every neighborhood of

zero. Hence it would not always be possible to divide by the quantity

g(a + h)-g(a).

Consequently, we must proceed in a somewhat dif­

ferent way.

f is differentiable 81 & y E .B(J ) ==>

Since
0, 381

at

>

0

so that

IY - g(a)I

IJ(y)-f(g(a))-j'(g(a))(y-g(a))I:;;; e,ly-g(a)I. Also, since g is differentiable at

a, Ve1 > 0, 38> 0

& x E .B(g) ==> lg(x)-g(a)I < 81 and ·

Hence, if

so that

(4.2.1)

Ix-al

lg(x)-g(a)-g'(a)(x-a)I:;;; e,lx-al.

Ix-al


0 so that Ix - al < 83 and x E Je(g) l ( ) - g(a)I < 82• Hence if -al < 83 and x E Je(g), we have from (4.2.6)



IJ(g(x))-f(g(a))-f'(g(a))(g(x) - g(a))I



eiJg(x)- g(a)I. , (4.2_6 )

Let us put 8 =min (8i. 83) and m = I/If'(g(a))I· If we use (4.2.5) and (4.2.6'), then Vx E Je(g) with Ix-al < 8, we get

lg(x) -g(a)-Cfoc:l���) �

I E1 m{lg(x)-g(a) I+ Ix-a} l . (x-a)

(4.2.7)

Now set M= I (f0g)' (a)I and use the triangle inequality on (4.27) to get (I - me1)

lg(x) -g(a)I



m(E1+ M) Ix.:._ al .

Take E1 < l/2m, and we get

lg(x)-g(a)I



(I+ 2Mm) Ix - al .

If we use this inequality in the right side of (4.2.7) and set A=

2m(I + mM), we get

(fog)'(a) lg(x)-g(a)- f' (x-a)I (g(a))



e1 A Ix - al .

(4.2.8)

Thus Ve> 0, take e1 < min(e/A,l/2m), and we see that 38> 0 so that 0 < Ix-al < 8 and x E Je(g) � -g�(a � ) l�g(�x� x) � -a

_

(f g)'(a) < E f'(g(a)) 0

I

(4.2.9)

·

In Theorem 4.2.2 we demanded that �(g) C Je(f ) to ensure that a is an accumulation point off0g so that we could talk about (f0g)'(a). InTheorem 4.2.3we needed�(g) C Je(f ),since an examination of the proof reveals that otherwise (4.2.9) would not necessarily be valid for all x E Je(g) for which 0 < -al < 8.

REMARKS.

Ix

D Exercises

Use the rules for differentiation to establish the following: (a) If f(x)= xn, Vx E Rand fixed n E N0, then f is differ­ entiable. 1.

4.3

MEAN VALUE THEOREMS j 149

(b) If c is a constant and f is differentiable at a, then cf is differentiable at a. (c) Any polynomial function of degree n E N0,

p(x)

=

n

L

k=O

akxk,

is differentiable. Use Theorem 4.2.3 to solve Exercise 1 of Section 4.1.

2.

3. Assume the results of Exercise l of Section 4.1 as known. Supposefand g are functions with se(g) C £>(!), f'(y) exists and is continuous in an open interval around g(a), J'(g(a)) # 0, and (J g)' (a) exists. Use the chain rule (Theorem 4.2.2) and the results of Exercise 1 of Section 4.1 to show that g'(a) exists and 0

g'(a) = (f g)'(a)/J'(g(a)). 0

4. Compute the derivative of e (x ) =ex and assuming the deriva­ tive of the logarithm function is known, use the chain rule to show that the following functions are differentiable and compute their derivatives: a> 0, Vx ER. (a) J(x) = ax = e x loga' Vx> 0, a ER. (b) J(x ) = xa =ea logx'

5. Assuming that the logarithm is a differentiable function, use Theorem 4.2.3 (and not the chain rule) to show that the functions in (a) and (b) of Exercise 4 are differentiable. 6. Suppose that f and g are n times differentiable functions on ]a, b[. If h is the product off and g, prove Leibnitz's formula for the nth derivative of h,

h(x) =

n ) pn-k>(x)g/-l(x)' ( k=O

i

k

where

4.3

MEAN VALUE THEOREMS

All the mean value theorems of the differential calculus are based on two principles: (a) a continuous function on a compact set assumes a maximum and a minimum, and (b) if a differentiable function is defined in an open interval about a point where it has a local maximum or mini­ mum, then the derivative must be zero at this local maximum or minimum.

150 I DIFFERENTIATION

4.3.1

Theorem. If f is a function with JF>(f) = ]a, b[, a< b, and a local maximum or local minimum at c, and if moreover f' (c) exists, f has if then f'(c) =0. Proof.

Let us suppose that

f(c + h - f(c)

k

{;;;:.:

has a local minimum at

f

0

if h > 0 ,

.;;; 0

if h< 0 .

c.

Then

From this we see that the limit of the difference quotient, as

h - 0,

must be zero.

4.3.2

If f is a continuous function with JF>(f) = [a, b] , a< b , f(a) =f(b) = 0, and f is differentiable on ]a, b[, then 3c E ]a, b[ so that f' (c) = 0. Proof.

Rolle's Theorem.

Since

f

is continuous on the compact set

[a, b],

it has a

maximum and a minimum on this interval. If the maximum and mini­ mum are taken on at the end points, we havef(x) hence the theorem is true. If

c

E

]a, b[, then

f

=0

for every x and

has a local maximum or minimum at

by Theorem 4.3.1,

f'(c) = 0.

4.3.3 Mean Value Theorem. If f is a continuous function with JF>(f) = [a, b], a< b, and f is differentiable on ]a, b[, then 3c E ]a, b[ such that

f(b) - f(a) = f'(c) . b-a Proof.

From a geometric point of view, the Mean Value Theorem

says that there is a point on the graph off where the tangent line to

f

is parallel to the line joining

(a, f(a))

to

(b,f(b)), Fig. 4.3.1. The (a,f(a)) and (b,f(b)) is

equation of the straight line through the points

f(b)-f(a) y=f(a) + (x-a). b-a y

a

c

Figure 4.3. 1

b

4.!

MEAN VALUE THEOREMS I 151

The difference between y andf(x) is

F(x)

=

f(b) - f(a) x a f(a) + b-a ( - )- f(x).

Now, F is a function which is continuous on

]a, b[, and F(a) F(b) 0. Hence F and find a c E ]a, b[ such that =

=

F'(c)

=

f(b)- (a) c f b-a - f'( )

differentiable on

=

0.

If f and g are continuous b, and have derivatives on ]a, b[, then

Generalized Mean Value Theorem.

4.3.4

functions defined on [a,b], a 3c E ]a, b[ such that


0. =

The statement

P(l)

is a statement of the Mean Value Theorem and

hence is true. Assume

P(n- l) g(x)

n> l

is true for =

and set

6hf(x) . h [a, b- h] and is n- l [a, b], then x + (n- l)h P(n- l) to g and find a

The function g is defined and continuous on times differentiable on E

[a, b - h].

81

so that

]a, b- h[.

If

x + nh

E

Consequently, we may apply

0 < 81 < 1. Now,

1 g(x + (n - l) 81h) =

x u(x) exists on ]a, b[, show that

J(x+h) - 2f(x) +f(x-h) r 1(2)(x) =hi_?;! . h2 (Hint: Use L'Hospital's rule.) 11. Suppose f is differentiable on [a, b] and f' (a) =a, f' (b) =f3 . Show that f ' takes on all values between a and f3. [Hint: If 'Y is strictly between a and {3, show that g(x) J(x) - ')l(x - a) takes on its maxi­ mum or its minimum in the open interval ]a, b[. This result is often called Darboux's theorem or property.] =

12. Let (r n) be a sequence whose range consists of all rationals in ]O, I[. Show that

4.4

TAYLOR'S REMAINDER FORMULAS

If f is a polynomial of degree n - I and a E R, then we may write

f(x) =ao+a1(x-a)

+

·

·

·+an_1(x-a)11-1•

By successive differentiation of both sides of this equation at a we find

that

J(a) ak=�,

kE (O,n-1).

For a general function defined on an interval [a, b], and which 1s

n - I times differentiable there, we write f(x)

=

n-1 j(a)

L

k=O

k-!

-

-

(x - a)k + R,.(x, a) , -

where this formula serves to define Rn· The problem is to find a con­ venient form for the remainder R,.. Any such formula is called a

Taylor's remainder formula,

4.4 TAYLOR'S REMAINDER FORMULAS I 159 although none of the expressions for

Rn

is

due to Taylor himself. The method for obtaining expressions for the remainder is an application of Rolle's theorem.

Suppose J n - l continuous derivatives on [a, b], and n times differentiable on ]a, b[. Further suppose and '11 are continuous on [a, b], differentiable on ]a, b[ and Vx,y ]a, b[ with a y x, the determinant (y) '11'(y) I '(x) 'l'(x) I Then Vx ]a, b], 3c ]a, x[, so that n (x - a)k Rn(X, a), f(x)=k=OL-1 jk(a) l where (a) (a) n I p> Rn (x, a)= - -1I(x) , (-c)--v'{!'1-1 (x) '-(c-)- (n -(lc)) ! (x - c)n-1. (x) v(x) I F [a, x], a x b, ]a, x[, 3c ]a, x[ F'(c) '(c) 'l''(c) F(a) «l>(a) 'l'(a) = F(x) «l>(x) '11 (x) a t b, -1 J ,L -(t) (x - t)k. F(t) J(x) - nk=O k. F [a, b] ]a, b[ F'(t)=- (x(n--t)n)-1! pn>(t). F(a)=Rn (x, a), F(x) Rn(x,a), 4.4.1

Theorem. t is

has

E


(c) (x-c)n-1, '(c) (n-1) !

The Roche form of the remainder: Rn(x,a)=

(c)

pn>(c) 1 ! (x-a)P(x-c)n-v, )

p{n-

a< c< x.

The Lagrange form of the remainder: f(c) R (x,a)=--1- (x-a)n, n n.

(d)

a< c< x.

a< c< x.

The Cauchy form of the remainder: - pn>(c) Rn(x,a)l (x-a)(x-c)n-1, (n- )!

Proof.

a< c< x.

To prove (a) choose 'I' any nonzero constant and apply

Theorem 4.4.l. To prove (b) set (t) = (x-t)v, 1 � (a). To prove (c) and (d), REMARK:

p set = n

p and

=

p



n, in part

1 in part (b), respectively.

In Theorem 4.4.1 and Corollary 4.4.2 for the sake of

convenience in the statements and proofs we have expanded about the left end point a. Clearly, everything will be equally valid if we

expand around the right end point b. In the future we shall use this fact without comment even though we refer to Theorem 4.4.1 or Corol­ lary 4.4.2.

The Taylor remainder formulas give a very convenient method for deciding when a given infinitely differentiable function is the sum of

a convergent infinite series. For example, Vn E N0 the nth derivative of the exponential function is again the exponential function. If we use the Lagrange form of the remainder we may write

ex=

n-1 xk ec L-+x n' ! n!

k�O

k

where c is a number between x and 0 and depends on both n and x.

If lxl � b, then

4.4

Since

bn/n! � 0

TAYLOR'S REMAINDER FORMULAS I

161

(Exercise 6 of Section l. 7), we see that the remainder

goes uniformly to zero in

[-b,b].

Thus .,

ex=:Lxk/k!, k=O

and the convergence of the series on the right is uniform on every compact set in

R.

The proof we have given above to show that the exponential func­ tion is the sum of an infinite series leads immediately to a more general result: If a function f is defined and infinitely differentiable in an open interval

I(a)

about the point

compact subinterval of

I(a)

a,

and if

(J'kl)

when restricted to every

is uniformly bounded, then

f(x) =

.,

L

k=O

r

.

I(a). Indeed, M= sup{IJ'k>(x)I: x E j

and the convergence is uniform on every compact set in

j= {x: Ix - al ,,;;; b } C I(a) and & k E N0}. Using the Lagrange form of for x E ],

suppose

lpn>(c)

let

the remainder again, we get

IRn(x,a)I= -1 - (x-a)n n. This estimate on

Rn

gives the result.

I

bn .;;M-,. n.

Actually, it is a rather interesting fact that the conclusions we have obtained in the previous paragraph will follow from the considerably milder assumption that all the derivatives are uniformly bounded below (or above). This fact is due to Serge Bernstein. Before we prove Bern­ stein's theorem we shall prove a lemma. The development we give is taken from the book by W. Maak,

An Introduction to Modern Calculus, I 963.

Holt, Rinehart and Winston, Inc., New York,

4.4.3 Lemma. Suppose J has do main [a,b] , is infinitely differentiable, and 3m > 0 so that Vx in [a, b] and Vn E N0,

-m

,,;_:;

pn>(x) .

Then 3M so that Vx E [a,b[ and Vn E N0, j Proof.

Suppose, at first, that

remainder,

Vx E [a,b[, we

f (b) where

x

(x)I� (b -x)n Let us use the Cauchy form of the remainder in Taylor's formula:

pn>(O R (x,c)= (x-c)(x-On-1• n (n-I)! Using the above estimate for

IJ({)I.

I Rn(x, c) I � nM If

c




0 uniformly for

This proves the theorem, since the last statement of

the theorem is obvious.

The last theorem gives a sufficient condition in order that a function

may be represented by a special kind of infinite series. Such functions

have a special name that we emphasize by a formal definition.

4.4.5 Definition. If f is an infinitely differentiable function having an open domain whose values in some open interval about the point a can be represented as

f(x)

=

"'

( a

k=O

k.

) :L J -,- - (x-a)k,

then f is said to be analytic at a. The series is called the Taylor expansion of f at a. If f is analytic at every point of its domain it is called analytic. We should point out that if a function is infinitely differentiable in

the neighborhood of a point it does not necessarily mean that the func­

(

tion is analytic at the point. For example, the function given by

f(x)

is infinitely differentiable and

Section 4.1 ). Hence, if

f

e-1/x• '

x

0,

x

=I=

0,

=

=

0,

Vn E N0, pn>(O)

=

0 (see Exercise 6 of

were analytic at zero, it would of necessity have

to have zero values at every point of some neighborhood of the origin,

which of course it doesn't.

164 I DIFFERENTIATION

0 Exercises 1. Do Exercise 10 of Section 4.3 by using an appropriate form of Taylor's remainder formula and assuming thatj is continuous .

2.

Let f be the function with domain ]-1, 1[ defined by

f(x) =1

1 -

x.

Show that f is analytic at zero and that its Taylor expansion at zero converges uniformly on every compact subset of ]-1, 1[. 3. Generalizing the considerations of Exercise 2, letfa be the func­ tion with domain ]-1, 1 [ defined by a

ER.

Show that fa is analytic at zero and its Taylor expansion at zero con­ verges uniformly on every compact subset of ]-1, 1[. 4.

Show that the function f with domain J-1, 1[ defined by f(x) =log (I - x)

is analytic at zero and its Taylor expansion at zero converges uniformly on every compact subset of ]-1, 1[. 5. We have shown in Section 4.3 that the exponential function with values e3' is analytic at zero and its Taylor expansion converges at every point of R. Hence we may write 00

e= L llk' k=O

=

n

L

l/k! + Rn+1·

k=O

Show that Rn+i < I/n!n. This estimate for Rn+i shows that e is irrational. Indeed , if e is rational it can be written e = p/q, p, q E N and q

L k=O

llk' < pfq
(c)

POWER SERIES I 165

k [ g(x) - k=O 'f gk< >�a)(x - a)k ] pn>(c). . By choosing g to be a suitable function, obtain the Taylor formula with Lagrange remainder. Give an example of a function

8.

f that is defined and infinitely

differentiable in a neighborhood of zero so that in some interval

� �

f(

x) =

J 1.

Indeed, the proof of the Cauchy root test shows that the absolute con­ vergence is uniform on every compact subinterval of

]a - r, a+ r[.

However, the uniform convergence is also easily established by means of the Weierstrass M Test. For, if 0 < and hence

�k..olc kl Ix - al k

s < r,

then

�k"'o le kls k converges

converges uniformly in the interval

[a - s, a+ s]. The number

r

power series and

of (4.5.1) is called the

]a - r, a+ r[ is

radius of convergence of the given interval of convergence.

called the

The question as to whether a convergent power series is always the Taylor expansion of an analytic function is answered by the next two results.

4.5.2 Theorem. If the power series �k..o (ck(x - a)k) has a nonzero radius of convergence r , then the function f defined on ]a - r, a+ r[ by 00

J(x) = L cdx - a)k k=O is infinitely differentiable and 00

f' (x)

=

L kck(x - a)k-l,

k=l where the latter series also has the radius of convergence r. Proof. tion 2.4)

Since (Exercise 10 of Section I. 9 and Exercise 5 of Sec­

4.5

POWER SERIES I 167

it follows that both of the series above have the same radius of con­ vergence. If we set

fk(x) =ck (x-a) k, then

fk

is differentiable and by Theorem 4.5. l and the first paragraph

of the proof of this theorem it follows that 00

2

k=O

(fk')

is uniformly convergent on any compact subinterval of the interval of convergence. Thus we may apply Corollary 4.2.5 on termwise differen­ tiation of a series to arrive at the differentiation formula of this theorem. The fact that the limit of the power series is infinitely differentiable follows by use of the axiom of induction.

If the power series �k..o (ck(x - a)k) has a n onzero radiu s of convergence r, an d if 4.5.3

Corollary.

00

f (x) then Vn

2

=

k=O

ck (x-a)k,

]a - r, a+ r[,

E

E N0,

Cn Proof.

pn>(x) x

=

pn>(a)/n!

By the use of the previous theorem and the axiom of induc­

Vn

tion it is easy to establish that

Setting

x

=

a

E N0,

00

=

L k(k - 1)

k=n

· · ·

(k- n

+ I)c k(x-a)k-n.

in both sides gives the formula for

Cn .

If we formally multiply two Maclaurin series together and collect terms all having the same powers of 00

L

n=O

(anxn ) ·

x,

we get 00

00

( bnxn) = L (cnxn), n=O n=O

L

where

Cn

n

=

2 akbn-k·

k=O

The power series on the right is called the

Cauchy product

of the series

on the left. The natural question to ask concerns the value of the radius of convergence of the Cauchy product in relation to the radii of con­ vergence of the series that make up the product. We shall prove a theorem of this nature for series of constant terms that will immediately answer this question for power· series.

168 I DIFFERENTIATION

4.5.4 Definition. If (a,CT(a)) and (b,CT(b)) are infinite series, then the Cauchy product of these series is the series (c,CT (c)) , where Cn =

n L a kbn-k· k=O

(4.5.2)

The following theorem about Cauchy products is somewhat more general than is needed to establish the facts about Cauchy products of power series. The proof would be somewhat easier if we demanded that both series be absolutely convergent.

4.5.5 Theorem (Mertens). If (a, A, it follows that Ik= U {I*:I* EA k} and hence (Exercise 2 at the end of this section ) I I kl

L

=

II*I.

/*EAk

Ifm*(/*)=inf {f (x) :x EI*} andI* Ch, it is clear that m k ,,;_;; m* (/*). Thus we get n

L mk IIkl k=l

n

L 2, m*(I*)I I *!. k=l J•E A k Since A*= {/*: I* EA k & k E (l, n) }, it follows that the right side of the above inequality is precisely !l1(A*) . This proves the left-hand in­ equality of Lemma 5.1.6. The right-hand inequality follows by similar reasoning, and the middle inequality is obvious. ,,;_;;

Proof of Theorem 5.1.5. Suppose that the Riemann integral of f exists. f must be bounded (Exercise 4 of Section 5.1) and VE > 0 there is a decomposition A of [a, b] such that

-e/2 < R1(A, {xk}) -R(J) < e/2.

(5.1.l)

We shall suppose that a < b, since otherwise the fact that D( f ) exists and is equal to R(f ) is trivial. If we choose xk EI k so that Mk -f(xk) < e/2(b - a), then -

D1(A) -R1(A, {xk})

n

I kl < e/2. 2, (Mk - J (xk))I (5.1.2) k=l On the other hand, if we choosexk E Ik so thatf(xk) - mk < e/2(b- a), we get (5.1.3) =

186

\INTEGRATION

From (5.1.1) and (5.1.2) and the definition of D(J) we get D(J) - R(J) � l5t Q_there are decompositiOns .6.1 and .6.2 so that D(f) -[21(.6.1) < e, and DtC.6.2) -D(f) < e. If .6., is the common refinement of .6.1 and .6.2, then Lemma 5.1.6 gives =

=

D(f) - []t(.6..)
.6., ==::} 5. 1. 7



Proof. If the Riemann-Darboux integral off exists, then Ve> 0, 3A, so that A > A, and A' > .6., ==::} \R1(A, {xd) R(J) I < e/2, \R1(.6.', {x'd) - R (J) I < e/2. Hence, by the triangle inequality, �

\RtC.6., {xd) -R,(.6.', {xk}) I < e. Conversely, suppose R1 is Cauchy. The method of obtaining a limit is a variation on the theme of the proof of Proposition 2.4.4. There exists a decomposition A0 so that .6.> A0 ==::} \R1(.6., {xk}) -R , (.6.o, {xok}) \ < 1 . Hence A>A0 ==::} \R1 (A, {xk}) I is bounded by 1 + \R1(A0, {x0k}) \. For every .6.>.6.0 let us set -;;;(A) =sup {R1(.6. ', {x�})

:

A' >A},

Jim R1= inf{-;;;(.6.) :A>A0}. We claim that Jim R1 is the Riemann integral off. First, note that A*> A =}�(A*)� ;;J(A). Next Ve> 0, 3A1 >Ao so that (5.1.7)

5.1

RIEMANN-DARBOUX INTEGRALS I 187

Also, 3A2 >-A0 so that A, A*>- A2 ==:} IR1(A, {xd)-R1(A*, {x\}) I


- A, and A' >-A,==:}

IR1(A, {xk}) -R1(A', {x�})I

< E.

Let A1,, A2,, and A3, be the subsets of A, which are decompositions of [a,c], [c,d], and [d,b], respectively. If A2 is a decomposition of [c,d] and A2 >-A2. , then A= A1, U A2 U A3, is a decomposition of [a� b],which is a refinement ofA,. IfA '2>-A2, and A' = A1, U A'2 U A3., then

Hence R0 is Cauchy and the theorem follows from Theorem 5.1.7. 5.1.9 Theorem. If f and g are Riemann-Darboux integrable functions de.fined on [a,b] , then ( a) for all real numbers a and f3, af + {3g is integrable, (b) f g is integrable, and (c) Ill is integrable.

188 I INTEGRATION

Proof.

For every

E

>

0 , 3d, so that d

>-

d, ==?

I �1 af(xk)IIkl - J:f(x) I I� J3g(xk)IIkl - J3 J: g(x) l


p (t) dt. (n - I)!

PROPERTIES AND EXISTENCE OF RIEMANN-DARBOUX INTEGRALS I 193

5.2

If {3 ;;;.:

a

and

g is

integrable on

[a,{3], define

J: g(t) dt - J: g(t) dt. =

With this definition, the formula for Rn is valid as well for a � Hence

� l) ! J:

Rn(X,c) = (n

c



(x - t)n-ipn>(t) dt.

x



b.

(5.2.1)

5.2.4 Theorem. If g is a continuous increasing function on [a,b J and difef rentiable on ]a,b[, f is defined on se(g) and integrable, and (f 0 g)g' is integrable, then

fg(b) f(x)

d:x=

g(a)

fb f0g(x)g' (x)

d:x.

a

If d { [ak,bk]: k E (1, n)} is a decomposition of [a,b], { [a'k,b'k]: k E (1, n)}, where a'k = g(ak), b'k g(bk) is a de­ composition of [g(a),g(b)]. Conversely, since g is continuous and increasing, it is one to one and every decomposition of [g(a),g(b)] comes from a decomposition of [a,b J in this way. Further, xk E [ak,bk] x'k = g(xk) E [a'k,b'k] and d1 >-d d'1 >-d'. Since f is integrable, for every E > 0 there exists a decomposition d', of [g(a),g(b)] so that if a' >-d'., then

Proof.

d'

then

=

=

=

IR1(d', {x'd) - Jg(b)f(x) I

d:x
0, we have

J:+h J(t) dt- J: f(t) dt= J:+h f(t) dt, rx J(x)= ldx +h f(x) dt. 1

Hence

k

F(x+h -F(x) f(x)

f is continuous at x, Ve > IJ(t) - f(x) I < E. If we take h

Since =>

I

r

h\"«}

l * J:+h IJ(t) - f(x)I dt. :o;;;

0, 38 so that

It - xi

< 8 &

t

E

fe(f)

< 8, we are led to the conclusion

F (x+h)-F (x) =J(x) . h

5.2

If

h

PROPERTIES AND EXISTENCE OF RIEMANN-DARBOUX INTEGRALS I 195

< 0, a similar argument shows that

lim

h)'O

F(x + h) - F(x) = J(x) , h

which concludes the proof of the theorem.

5.2.6 First Mean Value Theorem. If f and g are defined on [a, b], g � 0, Jg and g are integrable, and J is bounded, then there exists a number c such that inf J ::% c ::% sup f and

J: J(x)g(x) Proof.

Let

dx= c

m =inf f, M =sup

J: g(x)

f. Since

dx.

mg(x)

::%

J(x)g(x)

::%

Mg(x),

it follows that

m Now, if

J: g(x)

J: g(x)

f J(x)g(x)

dx ::%

dx ::% M

J: g(x)

dx.

dx= 0, then the theorem is clearly true. If

J: g(x)

dx

> 0, set

c=

J: J(x)g(x) /J: g(x)

and it is immediate that

dx

m

::%

c

::%

dx,

M.

5.2. 7 Second Mean Value Theorem. If f and g are defined on [a, b], g � 0, Jg and g are integrable, J is bounded, and m ::% inf J ::% sup J ::% M , then 3c E [a, b] such that .

f J(x)g(x) Proof.

dx= m

Define the function

G(x)= m G

J: g(x)

G

on

dx + M

[a, b]

J: g(t) dt

+

M

f g(x)

dx.

by the equation

f g(t) dt.

is a continuous function (Exercise 4 of Section 5.2) and

min

G

::%

G(b) = m

J: g(t) dt J: J(t)g(t) dt M J: g(t) dt= G(a) ::%

::%

Since

G

takes on all values between min

G

::% max

and max

G,

G.

and since the

196 I INTEGRATION

above inequality shows that

J: f(t)g(t) dt

maximum and minimum, 3c E

G(c)

=

[a, b]

is a number between this

such that

J: J(t)g(t) dt

.

This proves the theorem. We shall now present a theorem concerning the integration of a unifotmly convergent sequence of integrable functions. The theorem is useful for a wide variety of purposes.

5.2.8 Theorem. If Un) is a sequence of functions each of which is de­ fined on [a, b] and integ;rable, and if fn - f uniformly on [a, b], then f is integrable and

J: fn(x)

dx -

J: f(x)

dx.

Proof. For every e > 0, 3N so that n � N and x E [a, b] => lfn(x) - J(x) I < e/3(b- a). In particular, this means that for every set A C [a, b], and Vn � N,

lsup{fn(x): x Iinf Un(x): x Fix

m

� N and let

E E

A} - sup{f(x): x A} - inf {f(x): x

E E

A}I � e/3(b- a), A}I � e/3(b- a).

a. be a decomposition of [a, b] so that .:1

ID rm (.:1) - 12rm (.:1) I


-

=>

·

Hence

ID,(.:1) -Q,(.:1) I � ID,(.:1)

-

i5,m ( .:1) I+ ID,m( .:1 ) - Q,m(.:1) I +

Thus

f

is integrable. Further,

I J:fn(x)

dx-

n

ll21m(.:1) - l2r(.:1) I

< E



� N =>

J: !(x) dxl J: lfn(x)- f (x)I �

dx � e/3,

which concludes the proof.

,,,/

If Cfn) is a sequence of functions each of which is defined on [a, b] and integrable, and if Lk,,,0 (fk) is uniformly convergent to f on [a, b], then f is integ;rable and 5.2.9

Corollary.

We shall leave the obvious proof of this corollary for the reader. We should remark that it is possible to relax the hypothesis about the uni-

5.2

PROPERTIES AND EXISTENCE OF RIEMANN-DARBOUX INTEGRAl.S I 197

form convergence of the sequence

(Jn) and still obtain the conclusion

of theorem 5.2.8. However, the hypothesis cannot be relaxed all the way to pointwise convergence as the following simple example shows.

Un) is the sequence of functions, each having domain [O, l]

Suppose

(

and defined in the following way:

fn(x)

=

n+ l

{::}

x E ]0,1/(n+ I)],

0,

otherwise.

It is not hard to check that each

fn(x)



0. But Vn E N0,

fn is integrable and Vx E [O,l],

If a sequence Un) converges pointwise to an integrable function J and if the sequence is uniformly bounded, then the conclusion of Theorem 5.2.8 remains valid. The proof of this result belongs more properly to the circle of ideas connected with the Lebesgue theory of integration and we shall not prove it in this book. Note that in our previous example the sequence of functions does not remain uniformly bounded. We shall now finish this section by giving two different sufficient conditions that a Riemann-Darboux integral of a function exists. Al­ though the conditions we shall give are not necessary conditions, they nevertheless are broad enough to be very useful in a wide variety of circumstances.

5.2.10 Theorem. If f is defined on [a, b] and is monotone nondecreas­ ing [nonincreasing], then f has a Riemann-Darboux integral. Proof.

Let

a= {lk:

k E (l,n)} be any decomposition of [a,b].

Suppose that the intervals Ik

= [ak, bk] are named so that a1 =a, n. Since f is nondecreasing, the mini­ mum and maximum off restricted to Ik are taken on at ak and bk ,

bn

=

b, and ak

=

bk-I for 1 < k

.,;;

respectively. Hence

n,(a) = f(a2)(a2 - a1) + J(a3)(a3 - a2)+ ...+ f(b) (b - an)' Q,(a) =f(a1)(a2 - a1)+ f(a2)(a3 - a2)+

-

·

·

·

+ f(an)(b - an).

Thus

D,(a) - Q,(a) Now, for

E

>

"

=

_L

k=l

[f(ak+1) - f(ak)] [ak+i - ak],

0, choose a so that 1a1
( (x - c)s

by making the change of variable t= (x- c)s + c in ;;:. 0, pn> is nondecreasing and thus for x > c,

J 1. Thus the p series converges {:=:} p > 1 .

Let us give another example that shows how the techniques used in the proof of the integral test can be used to obtain rather refined esti­ mates for certain finite sums. Let us show that

n k}: =2

1

k log k = -

log logn + a+ bn,

where a is a constant that satisfies

0 < a
0 it is clear from the formula

- loge= that the function with domain

I.I dt

]O, l]



-

t

and values l/t does not have a

5.3

IMPROPER INTEGRAIS I 207

convergent improper integral of the second kind. On the other hand, for

E

>

0,

. [f-· -+ dt f dt t t ] 1

hm E-0

-1

E

-

=0.

If an integral of a function exists in this sense, we say that

f

has a

convergent Cauchy principal value integral. We give the formal defini­ tion below.

Definition. Suppose f has domain [a,b] \{c}, c E ]a,b[, and with O f dt +

c+E

f(t) dt.

Then the ordered pair (f, I (J)) is called a Cauchy principal value integral. Similarly, if f has domain ]-oo,oo[ and Vx � 0, Jl[-x,x] is integrable, and I(j) I(f )(x) =

J:/(t) dt,

then the ordered pair (f, I (f)) is also called a Cauchy principal value inte­ gral. The Cauchy principal value integral (f, I (f)) is said to be convergent ¢=>Jim,_0I(J)(e) or limx-ool(J)(x) exists, and the latter numbers are called Cauchy principal values. We shall now give some examples which show that the symmetry used in the definition of the Cauchy principal value may be very important. Since

t2

sin

t

is an odd function, its integral over

the integral of 1/ ( 1 +t2) over . IJill x-oo

[-x,x]

x 1 +

I

-x

t2

[-x,x]

is 2 Arc tan

sin

1 +t2

t

dt

=

is zero. Also

Thus

x.

7T.

On the other hand,

x+17 1 +t2 sin

f

1

-x

+ t2

t

dt = 2

Arc tan

and thus the limit does not exist as

x+2

cos

x+

f

x+1l

x

I - sin t dt, 1 + t2

x �- oo.

By the same type of reasoning we find that .

x

hm

x-oo

On the other hand, x-00

Jim

f

2x

I

..!.2 .±..i_ dt = Jim

-xI+t

x -co

I+t dt = 7T. t2

-x 1 +

-

fx

-x

..!..±.2 .i_ dt+Jim l+t

x-co

f

2x

x

..!..±..i_ dt. I+t2

208 j INTEGRATION

Now,

2X df J x-00 x I+t2 . 2x -1-t - dt I . x-oo Jx +t2 x-oo •

hm

=

hm

Thus

=

0

-

2

hm log

(1+4x2 2) 1+x

. zx,I+t +t2 dt + x-oo J-x 1

hm

=

7T

=

log 2 .

log 2.

The definitions we have written down do not exhaust all the possi­ bilities for defining improper integrals and the reader can undoubtedly think of cases we have not discussed. However, in most instances a suitable definition of an improper integral will be either a variant or a combination of the definitions we have discussed. Some of the follow­ ing exercises are designed to exhibit the various possibilities.

D Exercises I.

State and prove results analogous to Theorems 5.3.2 and 5.3.3

for Cauchy principal value integrals.

2.

Discuss the convergence of the following improper integrals: (a)

(b)

(c)

3.

1

·

1

Discuss the convergence of the following improper integrals: (a)

(b)

(c) 4.

!100 (/� 1). L"" C2� ) J:""C3 � ) ·

L1 (t t dt). J: c- � t dt) . in/2 ( � ) · 0 log

in

t

cost

For what values of (a)

f000 (t"'e-1 dt).

a

will the following integrals converge?

5.3

(b) (c)

5.

IMPROPER INTEGRALS I 209

J: (;!). Loo (;!).

Discuss the convergence of the following integrals: (a ) (b)

L (k )· J:oo C�( (2 ) J-oooo ( t2 t I tltl1/2 ) dt 00



(c)

6.

1112

For what values of ( a) (b) (c)

7.

+

00

f C � t)a ) J: ( � J· L"' Ca ��g t) · 1

( lo

a



will the following integrals converge?

.

r I g

Show the following:

i"' --t dt J"' --t dt. t2 t sin 2

sin

=

0

0

8.

State and prove an analogue of Abel's test for improper integrals.

9.

State and prove an analogue of Dirichlet's test for improper

integrals.

IO.

Discuss the convergence of the following integrals:

(a ) (b) (c)

I I.

L"' ( � t dt) . "' L ( I t� ti dt ) . oo C�! t dt . ) L( i 5

si

Use the integral test to establish convergence or divergence of

the following series: (a)

""

L

k=I

(k3e-k).

210 I INTEGRATION 00

(b) (c)

L

k=2

((log k)P/k).

� ( k (log �og k)")

·

Let p and q be fixed integers p �

12.

an=

pn

L k=qn+l

q �

1

1 and let

k

Use the ideas involved in the proof of the integral test to establish that

(�)

an� log (Hint:

"1 L-

k=l k

where a is constant and 13.

0
(D1.o)} D1 , 0(d)

=

L mk[g(bk)-g(ak) ],

=

=

=

[l(f,g)

=

su p {!l1.0(d):

d E £>([21,0)}

=

J: J: f(x) dg(x) ,

arJ,d call these numbers the upper and lower Darboux-Stieltjes integrals of f with respect to g, respectively. In case D(f,g) [l(f,g) D(f,g), we say that f is Darboux-Stieltjes integrable with respect to g and call D(f,g) the Darboux-Stieltjes integral of f with respect to g. =

=

212 I INTEGRATION

The fundamental theorem here, as in the case of Riemann-Darboux integrals, is the following:

5.4.3 Theorem. If f is bounded and g is monotone nondecreasing, then the Riemann-Stieltjes integral of f with respect to g exists if and only if the Darboux-Stieltjes integral exists and if they exist they are equal. The proof of this theorem follows the details of the proof of Theorem

5.1.5, and we shall not reproduce it here. 5.4.4 Theorem. The Riemann-Stieltjes integral of the function f with respect to g exists¢=? the function S1,0 is Cauchy in the sense that VE > 0, 3a, so that a >- A. and a' >- a. ==>

ISr.o(a,{xd)-Sr.o(a',{x'k}I




n

=

=

L 1cxk> [g(bk> - g(ak> 1 k=I L f(xk)g'(xk)(bk - a k)= R10,(a, {xd). k=I

Since the limits on the left side and on the right side exist, they must be equal. This establishes the theorem. An immediate corollary of Theorem if we take

f(x) =

5.4.7

is Theorem

5.2.2. Indeed,

1, and note that

J: dg(x)

we immediately have Theorem

=

g(b) - g(a) ,

5.2.2.

The next theorem is integration

by parts for Riemann-Stieltjes integrals. When taken in conjunction with the previous theorem, it is seen to yield Corollary

5.2.3.

. ned on [a, b] and if the integral 5.4.8 Theorem. If f and g are defi offwith respect to g exists, then the integral ofg with respect to fexists and

J: f(x) dg(x) J: g(x) df(x) +

=

=

f(b)g(b) - f(a)g(a)

J: df(x)g(x).

214 I INTEGRATION

Proof.

.1 {h: k E ( l, n)} [ak,bk]. We may write

Let

where/k =

=

be any decomposition of

[a,b],

n

S0j.1, {xd) = L g(xk)[f(bk) - f(ak)], k=l On the other hand, n

f(b)g(b) - J(a)g(a) = L [f(bk)g(bk) - f(ak)g(ak)]. k=l Hence

f(b)g(b) - f(a)g(a) - S0,1('1, {xk}) n

=L

k=l

Now

[ak,xk] .1'

[xk,bk] = [ak, bk]

U

=

f(bk)[g(bk) - g(xk)]

n

+

L f(ak)[g(xk) - g(ak)]. k=l

and hence

{[ak,xk]: k E (l,n)}

U

{ [xk,bk]: k E (l,n)}

is a decomposition of [a,b] and indeed is a refinement of a. We may therefore write

S0,,(a, {xk}) x'k = ak for [xk, bk]. Since, by

where

= f(b)g(b)

the interval hypothesis,

- f(a)g(a) - S1,0('11, {x'k}) ,

[ak, xk] S(f,g)

and

x'k =bk

for the interval

exists, the conclusion of the

theorem is an immediate consequence of the last equality. The generalization of Theorem 5.2.4 is the following:

Theorem. If g is defined, increasing, and continuous on [a,b], and h are defined on [g(a),g(b)], and the Riemann-Stieltjes integral of f fwith respect to h exists, then the integral off g with respect to h g exists, and 5.4.9

0

fg(b) J(x) dh(x) =fb f o

.12 0 so that \lx,y � M Ix

IJ(x)-f(y) I

E

12 - Yl 1 •

Isf necessarily of bounded variation? 9.

[a, b] ,

Suppose f is defined on

[a, b] and 3M> 0 so that Vx,y

IJ(x)-f(y)I

� M Ix-

E

YI·

If g is any continuous function, show that the Riemann-Stieltjes integral off with respect tog exists.

5.5

FUNCTIONS OF BOUNDED VARIATION I 227

IO. Suppose f is continuous and of bounded variation on [a, b]. Show that

If f(x) dg(x) I J: lf(x) I ldg(x) I, �

where ldg(x) I is another symbol for dv0(x).

6j HIGHER­

CHAPTER

DIMENSIONAL SPACE

In the previous chapters we have developed the essentials of the calculus for real-valued functions with domains in the real number system. The topics we have developed include ( 1) the real number system, (2) sequences and series, (3) real-valued continuous functions, (4) differen­ tiable functions, and (5) integration theory. The object of the remaining chapters will be to extend some of these theories to higher-dimensional situations. Some results extend in a straightforward manner. On the other hand, there are other results that are very simple and easy to prove in the one-dimensional case which become rather complicated and far-reaching theories in the higher-dimensional case. For example, the simple fact that a differentiable monotone function has an inverse that is also a differentiable monotone function generalizes to the con­ siderably more difficult inverse function theorem. The rather elemen­ tary formula for the integration of a derivative becomes a much more complicated theorem that requires considerably more algebraic and analytic machinery for its proof. This theorem is generally called

Stokes' theorem, but the names of Gauss and Green may also be associated with it. In this chapter we shall lay the basic foundation for the subsequent chapters. We shall discuss real vector spaces with a certain distance function acting on pairs of points and shall also discuss general proper­ ties of continuous functions as well as special continuous functions called ·

linear transformations.

6.1

REAL VECTOR SPACES

We shall begin our discussion with the n-fold Cartesian product Rn of the real numbers. The set Rn shall be defined as the set of all n-tuples

(x1,

·



" · ,x

),

where

x

k

ER fork E (l,n).

A much more formal

definition of Rn can be given as the collection of all functions with domain the set

(1, n)

and range in R. Indeed, a little reflection will

convince the reader that one reasonable way to define an n-tuple is as a function with doIJlain

(1, n)

and range in R. We shall continue to

use the very suggestive notation that we have indicated above. We shall now introduce two functions + and

· ,

the first one having

domain Rn X R" and range R" and the second one having domain 228

6.1

REAL VECTOR SPACES j 229

R X Rn and range Rn . These functions are defined by the equalities

(x 1, ... ,xn) + (y1, ...,yn) = (xl + y1, ... ,xn + yn), a· (x1,

•• •



,xn)= (ax1,





·

,

axn).

The triple (Rn,+, ) is a prototype example of what we shall call a real n-dimensional vector space and we shall designate it by vn. By an abuse of language we shall write x E vn rather than x E Rn when we want to emphasize that we are working with a vector space, and shall speak of the elements of vn rather than the elements of Rn. The ele­ ments of vn shall be called points or vectors and we shall designate them by letters without superscripts; for example, ·

x= (x1

'







'xn).

However, in two and three dimensions we shall often revert to the standard notations (x,y) and (x,y,z). As is usual, when we "multiply" a vector by a scalar (an element of R) we shall drop the dot. The numbers k x will be called the components of the vector x. The zero vector, 0, is that one for which every component is the zero element of R. We shall also set-x= (-I)x. 6.1.1 Definition. A finite set {xk: k E (1,m)} c vn, where if j =i' k, then X; =i' xk is said to be linearly independent for every finite set { ak: k E (l,m)}CR: m

L

k=l

akxk=O::::::} ak=O,

Vk E (l,m).

A set of vectors zn vn that is not linearly independent is called linearly de­ pendent. REMARl{S: In using the notation {xk: k E (1, m)} we are already specifying a function with domain (1,m) and range in vn by means of the equality (k) xk. The set {xk: k E (I, m)} is the range of, and if this set contains more than one element there is more than one function with domain (I, m) and with range {xk: k E (1,m)}. In some instances, for example when we talk about matrices, it is im­ portant to know exactly which function we are using. If this is the case, we shall call the function an ordered m-tuple of vectors and denote it by (x1 , , Xm). Ordinarily it is only the range of the function that is important. For exampk, the first sentence in Definition 6, I. I should perhaps more properly be stated as follows: Afinite nonvoid set A C vn is said to be linearly independent for every function a with domain A and range in R we have =







L XEA

a(x)x

=

0 ::::::}

a(x) =

0,

Vx E A.

230 I HIGHER-DIMENSIONAL SPACE

Suppose A has m elements and is any one-to-one function with domain (l,m) and range A. If we put xk = (k) and ak = a( xk) , then (referring to the introduction to Chapter 3) we get

2:

m

a(x)x

=

.xEA

2:

k=l

m

a((k) )(k) =

2:

k=l

akxk .

Hence, we have shown that Definition 6.1. l is independent of . In using the notation {xk: k E (l,m)} we usually mean that if j ¥- k, then x; ¥- xk> although this is not generally the case when we use the notation (x1, Xm ) . •

6.1.2

space of



· ,

Definition. vn

A nonempty subset L C vn is said to be a linear sub­ or a linear manifold ¢::::> V x, y E L and Va , f3 E R, ax + {3y

EL. 6.1.3 Definition. A vector x E vn is said to be a linear combination of the vectors in the set {xk : k E (1, m)} C vn ¢::::> there exist numbers a1 , am E R so that •



The last definition should perhaps more properly be stated as follows: vector x E vn is said to be a linear combination of the vectors in the finite set A C vn ¢::::> there exists a function a with domain A and range in R A

so that

As in the discussion of Definition 6.1.1, the sum on the right is quite independent of any function with domain ( 1, m) and range A. Thus Definition 6.1.3 really makes sense quite independent of which function from (1, m) onto {xk: k E (1, m)} we are using to define the sum. The terminology and notations we have adopted in the formal defini­ tions 6.1.1 and 6.1.3 are more classical and standard than those we have used in the rewritten versions of these definitions. Hence, if the reader will keep in mind what is involved, there seems to be no real reason to change from the classical terminology and notations, and we shall use them in the future without further comment.

6.1.4 Definition. If L is a linear subspace of vn, then a set {xk: k E (I , m)} C L is said to generate L ¢::::> every x E L is a linear combination of the vectors in {xk : k E (1, m)} . A set of vectors that generates L is called a basis for L ¢::::> the set is linearly independent. It is clear that every finite set {xk: k E (1, n)} C vn generates a linear subspace of vn, namely, the set of linear combinations of the vectors of the given set.

6.1

REAL VECTOR SPACES I 231

As an example of a basis for vn consider the vectors

(6.1.1) where

eki =0

ifj ¥-

k

k ek =1.

and

Of course, a vector space may have

many different bases, and for example a basis of

V3

is given by the

three vectors

X1=(1,0,0},

X3 = (1,1,l) .

X2=(1,l,O),

We shall leave the verification to the reader.

6.1.5

Theorem.

the linear subspace of s:;;:;; r. Proof.

If {yk: k E (1,s) } is a linearly independent set in vn generated by the set {x k: k E (1, r) } C vn, then

Since y1 ¥-

0, we

may write

r Y1 = L 0 so that

is convex and thus, by Corollary 6.3.12, is

connected. Hence every element in

B (x,p)

is equivalent to

x

and thus

is in E. Hence E is· open. Suppose

n

Q" is QA

times, and

the Cartesian product of the rationals =

Q" n A;

rational components. Since

that is,

A

QA

is open,

Q with

itself

is the set of points in A with

QA

is denumerable. (Proof?)

Let be a one-to-one function with domain N and range

QA·

If E is a

component of A, let

NE= {n: n E N & (n) Since E is open,

NE

E E}.

is nonvoid and thus by the well-ordering principle

it has a minimal element

nE.

Let qr be that function whose domain con­

sists of the equivalence classes E and defined by qr(E) The one-to-one function

0

= nE.

qr has range a subset of

QA,

and thus its

range is countable. This means the collection of components of A is countable.

6.3

6.3.16

Corollary.

TOPOLOGY

IN E"

I 247

If A C E1 is open, then A is the countable union of

open intervals. Proof.

From the last corollary,

A

is the countable union of open

connected sets. Since by Theorem 5.3.10, every connected set in E1 is an interval, the proof is complete.

INTERIORS AND BOUNDARIES

The concepts of the interior and boundary of a set in En will be of some importance in Chapter 8 when we discuss Jordan content and the theory of integration in higher dimensions. In somewhat loose language the interior of a set

A

is the largest open set that is contained in

A.

The

boundary of A is the set of points that do not belong to the interior of

A

or the interior of Ac. The formal definition is as follows.

Definition. If A C E", then the interior of A, denoted by A0, the union of all open sets contained in A. The boundary of A, denoted {3A, is the set A\A0• 6.3.17

is

A0 � 38 > 0, so that B(x, 8) CA. Also we think {3A � V8 > 0, B(x, 8) n A =t= 0 and B(x, 8) n AC boundary of a set is clearly a closed set and, if A C B, then

It is clear that it is clear that

=t= 0. The A° C B0•

x

x

E

E

It is quite possible that a set may be rather "thin" and yet its boundary may be rather "thick." For example, the rationals in

[O, I]

are in some

sense rather "thin" but the boundary of this set consists of the whole interval

[O, l].

Note that this set of rationals has no interior. A single

point in En is an example of a closed set with no interior. The reader may easily construct an example of a denumerable closed set, which consequently has no interior. The Cantor set is an example of a closed set with no interior which nevertheless has an uncountable number of points.

D Exercises In the following exercises all sets are to be taken in En, unless otherwise specified. I.

Show that the intersection of any finite number of relatively

open sets is relatively open and the union of any number of relatively open sets is relatively open.

2.

Show that the union of any finite number of relatively closed sets

is relatively closed and the intersection of any number of relatively closed sets is relatively closed.

248 I HIGHER-DIMENSIONAL SPACE

3.

Suppose

tively closed. If

U is a relatively open set in A. Show C is a relatively closed set in A, show

that that

A\U is A\C is

rela­ rela­

tively open. 4.

Let

C be relatively compact in A. d

then

5.

3c E C,

so that d

Prove that a set

inf {Ix

=

=

A

le

-

-

A

If

E A, is it true that if we set

E C},

x

al?

C En is connected{:::::} the subsets of A which

are both open and closed relative to

6.

al :

If a

A

and B are connected and

A

are

A

itself and the null set.

n B � 0, show that

A

U Bis

connected.

7.

Let

A

be a connected set in En , and A its closure. If A C B C

A,

show that Bis connected.

8.

A

If

C En and B C Em, show that

A

X B is open in £1•+m

{:::A ::}

X Bis closed in £1•+m

{:::::}A

and B are open. 9.

A

If

C En and B C Em, show that

A

and Bare closed.

10.

If A C En and B C Em, show that

A

X Bis compact{:::::} A and B

are compact.

11.

Show that a sequence with range in E" is convergent if and only

if it is a Cauchy sequence.

12.

If

A

C En and B C Em, show that

A

X Bis connected

{:::A ::}

and

Bare connected.

13.

Show the following: (a) (b)

14.

=

=

[A0 U (Ac)oy. (AoV\ (Ac)o.

Show the following: (a) (b)

6.4

{3A {3A

A is closed{:::::} {3A A is open {:::::} {3A

C C

A. Ac.

CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS

In Chapter 2 we discussed the limit and continuity concept for functions having their domains and ranges in R. We shall now do the same for functions having their domains in En, n � 1, and ranges in E"', m � 1. The definitions are essentially identical and the theorems and their proofs are, by and large, the same. Hence we shall not present as de­ tailed a study here as we did in Chapter 2, but shall limit ourselves to those matters for which a slightly different formulation than given in Chapter 2 may lead to deeper insights.

6.4

6.4.1

Definition.

CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS I 249

If f is a function with J0 ( f) C P and�f ( ) C Em

and a is an accumulation point of J0 f ( ), then I is said to have the limit l at a

¢=}VE> 0,38> Oso thatx

E [B ( a ,8)\ { a }] n J0 ( f) �l x ( )EB (l ,

E) .

In case f has a limit at a we write, as usual, Jimf x ( )= l

x-a

6.4.2

Definition.

or f ( x) - l

asx- a.

If f is a function with J0 ( f) C En and�( f) C Em,

then f is said to be continuous at a¢::::} a E J0 ( f) and VE> 0, 38> 0 so that x E B ( a 8) n J0 ( f)�f ( x) E B f ( a), E). ( ,

The function I

ZS

said to be continuous ¢:::f :} is continuous at every point of its domain.

The concept of continuity at a point is a local concept, that is, de­ pends only on the values that the given function takes on in some neigh­ borhood of the given point. However, a continuous function has a "global" characterization that is important and useful.

6.4.3

Theorem.

A function f with J0 ( f) C P and �f ( ) C Em

is

( is relatively open in J0 J ( ). continuous ¢:::f:} or every openU C Em, 11 - U)

Proof. Suppose f is continuous andU C E'n is open. If 11 - U ( ) is void, it is open relative to J0 f ( ) and we are done. If f1 - U ( ) � 0, let x E 1-1 ( U); sinceUis open,3p> Oso thatB ( f ( x),p) CU. From the continuity off, 38( x,p), so that y E B ( x,8) n J0 ( f) � f ( y) E B J ( x)),p), which in turn implies that B ( ( x,8) n J0 ( f) Cf1 - U ( ). If we set ( U ) }, Ef-1 x ( 8 , )x V= U {B : then Vis open andf1 - U) ( = V n J0 ( f). Conversely, supposef1 - U) ( is relatively open in J0 ( f) for every openU C Em. Let a E J0 ( f) and takeU =B ( f ( a), E); then there is an open V C En so thatf1 U) = V n J0 ( f). Since Vis open,38 > 0, - ( so that B ( a8) , C V. Hence f takes B ( a8) , n J0 ( f) into B ( f ( a ) E), which is the definition of continuity at a. This completes the proof. ,

6.4.4

Definition.

A function f is said to be an open function or an open

map¢::::} for every relatively open A C J0 f ( ),f ( A)is relatively open in�J ( ).

As we shall see in Chapter 7, open maps play a relatively important role in many considerations. Right now, Theorem 6.4.3 leads imme­ diately to the following corollary.

6.4.5

Corollary.

If f is a one-to-one open map, then f 1 - is continuous.

250 I HIGHER-DIMENSIONAL SPACE

Now, an open one-to-one map need not itself be continuous as the reader may easily verify (for example, refer to Theorem 2.3.6). A function that is one-to-one and f and f-1 are continuous is called a homeomorphism or wpologfral map. So, a Continuous one-to-one open map is topological. Exercise 4 at the end of this section will give another condition for a continuous one-to-one function to be topological.

6A.6

§Tl(j)

Theorem.

CEm

If f is a continuous function with �(J) and if �(J) is compact, then §Tl(j) is compact.

C E"

and

Let U be an open covering of

§Tl(j). For every U E U, there exists an open V CE" so that f-1(U) V n �(f). The collec­ tion of such Vis an open covering for �(f), and hence there are a finite number that cover �(f). Hence there are a finite number of elements of U that cover §Tl (f). Proof.

=

6.4. 1 Corollary. If f is continuous and �(f) is compact, then f is bounded; that is, §Tl (J) is bounded. Proof.

§Tl(j) compact and therefore is bounded.

6.4.8 Corollary. If f is real-valued and continuous and �(f) compact, then f assumes its maximum and its minimum on �(f).

CE"

is

Proof.

Since §Tl(j) C E1 is compact, it is closed and bounded. §Tl(f) must contain its supremum and infimum, which are the maximum and minimum of f, respectively. Hence

6.4.9 Definition. A function f with �(J) CE" and §Tl(j) C Em is said to be uniformly continuous¢::::} VE> 0, 38 > 0 so that x y E �(f) and x y E B(O, o) �f(x) - f(y) E B(O, E). ,

-

6.4.10

Theorem.

If f is continuous and �(f) is compact, then f is

uniformly continuous. Proof.

See the proof of Theorem 2.2.9.

In the one-dimensional case we showed (Theorem 2.2.14) that every continuous function with a closed interval domain takes on all values between its maximum and its minimum. This fact generalizes in a very interesting way for functions with domains and ranges in higher­ dimensional space.

6.4.11

§Tl(j)

Theorem.

C Em

If f is a continuous function with �(J) and if JEJ(J) is connected, then §Tl(j) is connected.

CE"

and

6.4

CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS I 251

Proof. Suppose U and V are open in Em, f'/C,(f) C U U V, and U n f'/C,(f) and V n f'/C,(J) are disjoint. Then 1-1(U) l-1(U n f'/C,(f)) and 1-1(V) l-1(V n f'/C,(J)) are disjoint and open relative to tB(J), and cB(J) l-1(U) U l-1(V). Since cB(J) is connected, one of the setsj-1(U) or 1-1(V) must be the null set and hence the corresponding set U n f'/C,(f) or V n f'/C,(J) must be the null set. Thus f'/C,(J) must be connected. Theorem 6.4.11 is an important aid in deciding whether or not a set in higher dimensions is connected. For example, the proof of Corollary 6.3.12 can be made in the following way. Suppose C is a convex set in En and C A U B, where A and B are nonvoid disjoint relatively open sets in C. Let x E A and y E B, and set =

=

=

=

l(t)

=

(I- t)x + ty,

t

for

[O, l].

E

The function f is continuous and since its domain is connected its range is connected. Butf'/C,(J) [f'/C, (J) n A] U [f'/C, (J) n BJ, where clearly, f'/C,(J) n A and f'/C,(J) n B are disjoint, nonvoid, relatively open sets in �(f). This is a contradiction. We think it is clear that the procedure we have just given can be generalized in a very simple way. =

Definition. A set A C E" is said to be arcwise connected � A, there exists a continuous function f, with domain [0, 1 J and range in A, so thatl(O) x andl(I) y. 6.4.12

V x, y E

=

6.4.13

=

Proposition.

Every arcwise connected set is connected.

The details of the proof are essentially the same as the proof we have just given above for convex sets, and we shall leave it as an exercise. As an example of how Proposition 6.4.13 can be used, let us consider the ring in E2, which is the set

{x: 0 < r ,,,,; lxJ ,,,,; r }. 1 2 A and let (J and

,(f2 ) [O, l] (see Theorem 3.3.2) and that &',(J ) [O, l] X [O, l]. To show that f is continuous, it is enough to show that f1 and f2 are continuous. l/3 2

Theorem. A linear transformation T is one-to-one (nonsingular) the range of T has the same dimension as the domain of T.

Proof.

{uk: k E (l,r)} is a basis for .B(T). Since T is !R-(T) is a linear combination of the vectors in the set {T(uk): k E (I, r)}. Hence, if under the assumption that T Suppose

linear, every element in

is one to one we can show that this latter set is linearly independent, we will have proved the necessity. If T is one to one it follows that

T(uk)

¥- 0

Vk E (1,r) , since

0 is

the only vector taken into 0. Suppose that

� akT(uk)=r( t1 ak uk )

=

0.

SinceTis one to one, we get

{uk: k E ( 1, r)} is a linearly independent set we have ak 0, \fk E (l,r). Conversely, suppose the range of T has the same dimension as its domain. We must show that T(x) T(y) ==}x=y. Using the linearity of T, this is equivalent with showing that T(x) 0 =::::} x=0. Let us write

and since

=

=

=

then

T(x)

=

0 =::::} r

L

k=I

ak T(uk)

=

0.

!R-(T) is r,and, as we have already !R-(T) is generated by the set {T(uk): k E ( 1, r)}. Consequently, this latter set is linearly independent and Vk E (l,r), ak=O. Hence x 0 and the proof of the theorem is complete. Now, by hypothesis, the dimension of

noted,

=

is

6.5.3 Definition. The dimension of the range of a linear transformation called the rank of the linear transformation.

258 I HIGHER-DIMENSIONAL SPACE

Suppose L and M are linear subspaces in V" and vm, respectively, and

S and T are linear transformations each having domain L and a E R we define

range in M. If for

(aT)(x) (S + T) (x)

= =

aT(x), S( x) + T(x),

then these two operations will make the set of all linear transformations with domain L and range in M into a vector space. Indeed, this vector space is finite-dimensional, and if

p is the dimension of L and q is the

dimension of M, then its dimension is

pq.

We have asked the reader to

verify these facts in Exercise 4 at the end of this section. There is a very useful representation for linear transformations by means of

matrices. It is at this point that it becomes important to con­

sider a basis of a vector space as a function rather than as a set (see the discussion in Section 6.1 ). We shall use the terminology

ordered basis

for such a function. Suppose

A is a linear transformation with domain L and range in (u1, · ,up ) and (v 1, · ,Vq) be ordered bases

the linear space M. Let









for L and M, respectively. Then we may write

A(uk)

q

=

2:

j=l

ajkVj,

kE(l,p).

The array of numbers

a21

a12 a22

a,. a2P

aql

aq2

aqp

[""

]

matrix. More specifically it is called a matrix repre­ sentation for A with respect to the ordered pair of ordered bases ((u1, · · · ,up) , (v1, · · · , vq)) . From a very formal point of view, a is called a

qXp

q Xp

matrix is a function with domain (I, q)

Suppose N. Let

( w1,

X (I,p)

and range in R.

B is a linear transformation with domain M and range in •

)

· , wr



be an ordered basis for N and let us compute the

r X p matrix representation of B A with respect to the ordered pair ((ui. ,up), ( w1, · · · , wr)) . Let the matrix entries of B with respect to the ordered pair of ordered bases ((v1, Vq) , (w1, , Wr) ) be denoted by b;k· Then we have 0

·

·

·







,

q

B

0

A (uk)

=

2:

j=l

a;kB(v;)

kE(l,p).







6.5

LINEAR TRANSFORMATIONS I 259

It follows that if c1k is in the lth row and kth column of the matrix representation of B

0

A with respect to the given bases, then c 1k

q

=

L i=I

b1;a;k·

This serves to define a multiplication 0£ matrices,

l

bu b21

b12 b22

b,. b2q

au a21

a12 a22

alp a2P

Cu C21

C12 C22

Ct p c 2P

br i

br2

b rq

a q,

aq2

aqp

Crt

cr2

C rp

Thus we see that we get c1k by "multiplying" the lth row of the matrix of B with the kth column of the matrix of A; that is, bu is multiplied by a;k and then the result is summed over j to get c1k. Suppose now that A is a linear transformation with domain a linear subspace L C vn and range in L. Let 'U (u 1, up) be an ordered basis for L and let us designate the matrix representation of A with respect to the pair ('U,'U) by [a;k]. We want to investigate the ques­ =







,

tion of how the matrix representation changes when we pick a new

ordered basis 'U' = (u'i. · · ·, u'v) for Land get a matrix representation

[a' ;k] with respect to the pair ( 'U', 'U'). From this point on,for the sake of simplicity, let us agree that if [au] is a matrix representation of A with respect to a pair of ordered bases ( 'U,'U) we shall say that A has the matrix represen­ tation [au] with respect to the basis 'U. Let Q be the linear transformation with domain and range L that is

defined by

This means Q(uk) = u'k> and we may write

u'k = Q(ud =

p

L

j=l

Q;ku;.

Hence the matrix representation of Q with respect to the basis

'U

is

[q;k]. Clearly, Q is nonsingular,since i:he dimension of &e,(Q) is the same as the dimension of ..e(Q). Let Q-1 be the inverse of Q and suppose its matrix representation with respect to the basis 'U is [ru]. Let us now compute the matrix representation of A with respect to the basis

'U'.

We have

A(u'k) = A Q(uk) = 0

p

L j=l

s;ku;.

260 I HIGHER-DIMENSIONAL SPACE

where

s ik

p

L a i,qlk· l=l

=

Now,

Q-1 (u i)

p

=

L ruui. l=l

Q, and note that Q( u 1)

and if we compose both sides with

=

u' 1, we get

Using this in the expansion for A (u'k) we get A (u'k)

Hence, if we write

[q;k]-1

� [� rlisik ] u'1•

=

1

for the matrix

[rik],

we have

(6.5.1) In Section

6.6 we shall show how to compute the numbers r ik in terms

of the entries of

[q;k].

Let us now turn our attention to properties of a linear transformation that are connected with the inner product, or, what is the same thing, with the length function on

vn x vn.

Theorem. Let T be a linear transformation whose domain is a C En and range is in Em. There exists an M > 0 so that

6.5.4

linear subspace L Vx EL,

IT(x) I

� M

lxl.

(6.5.2)

In particular this means that T is uniformly continuous. Proof.

x EL,

Let

{ uk: k E (I, p)}

be any orthonormal basis for

we may write

lxl2 If we apply the transform

p

=

T we

T(x)

L 1gk12• k=l

get p

=

L gk T(uk), k=I

L.

If

6.5

LINEAR TRANSFORMATIONS I 261

and taking the norm of both sides and using the triangle inequality we get p

IT(x)I :!SL ltkl IT(uk )I. k=l Now use the Cauchy-Buajakovsky-Schwarz inequality on the right to give

IT(x)i :!S

{� IT(uk)l2 f'2 {� ltkl2 r2•

This is the inequality (6.5.2). Now, replace

x by x - y and

use the linearity of T to give

IT(x) - T(y)I :!SMix - YI. This proves the uniform continuity.

6.5.5

3m>

0,

Corollary. If T is a nonsingular linear transformation, then so that Vx E JV(T),

mlxl :!S IT(x)I. 11 is a linear transformation, it follows by the previous 3M> 0 so that Vy E JV(T�1), l11(y)I :!SM IYI. But Vx E JV(T), 3y E JV( 11) , so that T(x) =y. Hence lxl -:!SM IT(x)I, and, taking m l/M, we are finished. For any linear transformation T let us set Proof.

Since

theorem that

=

llTll =inf {M: Vx Clearly,

Vx

E

JV(T) we

E

JV(T),

!T(x)I :!SM !xi}.

(6.5.3)

have

IT(x)I :!S llTll lxl. The real number defined by (6.5.3) is called the norm of T and it defines a distance function on the vector space of all linear transformations with domain a fixed space Land range in a fixed space M. For this distance

function to. be useful, the triangle inequality should be satisfied and this is seen as follows. Let

S

be another linear transformation with

domain Land range in M. Then

Vx

EL we have

! (T+ S)(x)I :!S IT(x)I + !S(x)I :!S {llTll + llSll} !xi. This shows immediately that

!IT+ Sii :!S llTll + !!Sil. It is also a very simple matter to check that

llaTll

=

la l llTll.

Va

E R,

262 I HIGHER-DIMENSIONAL SPACE

and that

We shall leave the proofs of these simple facts as an exercise. There are other expressions for 11Tll that are often very useful. For example,

llTll=sup{IT(x)I: lxl=l}. The proof of this is very simple. Indeed, if

(6.5.3')

lxl= 1, IT(x) I .;; IITll,

and

hence the right side of (6.5.3 ') is dominated by II Tll. On the other hand, let M0 be the right side of (6.5.3'). Then,

IT(x) /lxl ) I .;; From this it follows that

IT(x)I .;;

Vx

oF- 0,

M o.

M0 lxl and hence

llTll.;;

M0• This

E � (T)}.

(6.5.3")

shows the equality. Another useful expression is

llTll

=sup {IT(x )

·YI: lxl= IYI = 1 & Y

To prove this, let us first note that if

Vz

L

is a linear subspace of

En,

then

EL,

lzl

=sup { lz

·YI: IYI

=

1 &

y E

(6.5.4)

L}.

Indeed, if M1 is the right side of (6.5.4) the Cauchy-Bunjakovsky­

Schwarz inequality shows that M1.;; take y=z/lzl. Then

lzl=z · z/lzl

lz l .

On the other hand, if

z

.;; M1, which shows equality. If z

oF- 0, =

0,

the equality (6.5.4) is obvious. To prove (6.5.3"), let M0 be the right side of that equation. From the Cauchy-Bunjakovsky-Schwarz inequality we get

.;; llTll,

lxl=IYI= 1. Hence Mo.;; llTllget Vx, so that l xl = 1 ,

for

(6.5.4) we

IT(x)I=sup { IT(x) ·YI: IYI

IT(x) ·YI .;; IT(x)I

On the other hand, from

=

l}.;;

M o.

Hence, from (6.5.3'),

llTll =sup { IT(x)I: lxl=l}.;; 6.5.6

Definition.

linear functional.

A

Mo.

linear transformation with range in

R

is called a

Linear functionals have very interesting and useful representations, as the next theorem will show.

6.5. 7

Theorem.

there exists a unique y

If A is a linear functional with domain L C En, then so that Vx EL,

EL

A(x)=x ·

y.

6.5

LINEAR TRANSFORMATIONS I 263

Proof. Let {uk: k E ( 1, p)} be an orthonormal basis for L. If x E L, we may write

A(x)

p

=

L

k=l

�kA(uk) .

If we set n

y= L A(uk ) uk> k=l A(x) =x y. z E L, so that Vx E L, A(x) =x ·z. Then Vx EL, x ·(y - z) =0. In particular, take x y - z and we get jy - zj =0, which implies y=z. it is clear that

·

Suppose

=

6.5.8 Theorem. Let A be a linear transformation with domain L C En and range in M C E'n. Then there exists a unique linear transformation A1 with domain M and range in L so that Vx EL and Vy E M A(x) ·y=x·A1(y).

(6.5.5)

y E Mand set Ay(x) =A(x) y. Since Ay is a linear func­ L, it follows from the last theorem that 3 a unique y1 E L so that Vx E L Proof.

Fix

·

tional with domain

A(x)·y=x·y1• Since

Aay+13Ax) =aAy(x)

+

(6.5.5')

f3Az(x) it follows that

(ay + {3z)1 =ay1 + {3z1• y1, it follows that A1 is a linear transformation L. Since the yl for which (6.5.5') holds is unique, it follows that there is only one linear transformation A' for which (6.5.5) holds. Hence, if we set

A1(y)

=

with domain M and range in

6.5.9 Theorem. If A is a linear transformation with domain Land range in M, if N(A) = {x: A(x) =O} is the null space of A, and if N(A)l. is the orthogonal complement of N(A) in L, then

N(A)l. =�(A1). Proof.

For every

x E N(A) and Vy E M, we have A(x) ·y=x·A1(y)=O.

�(A1) C N(A)l.. On the other hand, suppose 3z E N(A)l.\ �(A1). Because �(A1) C N(A)l., without loss of generality we may

Thus

264 I HIGHER-DIMENSIONAL SPACE

suppose that

z

E

&2.(A1).J..

Thus we have

Vy

E M,

A(z) · y=z·A1(y)=O, from which it follows, upon setting y E N(A) n N(A).J.. It follows that

=A(z), that A(z)=0,

z

Hence

N(A).J.=&C.(A1).

6.5.10

Corollary.

For every linear transformation A, rank

Proof. Since

The range of

AJN(A).J.

and hence

z= 0, which is a contradiction.

A

A=

rank

A1•

is clearly the same as the range of AJN(A).J..

is a nonsingular linear transformation, we have rank

A=dim N(A).J. =dim

&i (A1) =rank

A1•

The linear transformation A1 is called the transpose of A with respect to the space M. If A has the matrix representation [aid with respect to the ordered orthonormal bases ((u1, · · ·, up) , (v1, · · ·, Vq)), it is interesting and useful to comp ute the matrix representation of ((v1, • · - , Vq) , (u1,· · ,u p)) We have

respect to the bases

-

A1

with

.

q

A(ud = L aikvi, i=I

and thus

On the other hand, p

A1(vJ = L a1ki uk k=I

and hence

Thus

The matrix

[a1Jk] is called the transpose of the matrix [aik] and is a [aik]1•

p X q matrix. It is usually denoted by

The rank of a linear transformation can be comp uted from its matrix representation with respect to any ordered p air of ordered bases. The p recise facts are given in the following proposition.

6.5.11 Proposition. If [aii] is the q X p matrix representation of a linear transformation A with respect to any ordered pair of ordered bases, q then the rank of A is the dimension of the linear subspace in V generated by the column vectors {ak=(a1k,· · ·,aqk): k E (I,p)}, which is the same

6.5 LINEAR TRANSFORMATIONS I 265

as the dimension of the linear subspace of VP generated by the {bk= (ak1, · akp): k E(l,q)}. ·

row

vectors

· ,

) is an ordered basis for "®(A) and �(A). If r is the rank of A, then there is a set {A(uk; ): i E( 1, r)} of r linearly independent vectors that generate �(A). Suppose that {a; : i E (1, r)} Suppose

Proof.

(v1,





·,Vq)

(u1,

·

·

· ,Up

is an ordered basis for a linear space that contains

C Rand

Since

q A(uk1) = L aik; vi J=l

� a;A(uk1) =i� (�a; aik;)vi = 0, Vi E(l,r), a1=0. Thus the vectors {ak;: i E(l,r)} Vq . To show that these vectors generate the same space as the vectors {ak: k E( 1, p)}, we first note that Vuk there exist numbers {/3;k: i E (1, r)} so that it follows that

are linearly independent in

A(ud

r

=

L /3;kA(uk;)

i=l

Hence r

jE(l,q).

aik = L /3; kaik; , i=l

But this says that n

ak= L /3;kak;, i=l

which proves the assertion about the vectors To prove the assertion about the vectors · ·

· ,

ep)

be an ordered orthonormal basis

{ak: k E {l,p)}. {bk: k E (1, q)}, let ( e1, for £P and (f 1, · · ·,fq)

Eq. Let B be the linear transforma­ q tion with domain £P, range in E , and whose matrix representation with respect to ((e1,· ·,ep), (f1,· ·,fq)) is [aid· By what we have proved in the previous paragraph rank B = rank A. Also, we know from Corollary 6.5.10 that rank B1 = rank B. The matrix representation of B1 with respect to ( (f1, · , fq), (e1, ep)) is a p X q matrix with column vectors the set {bk: k E ( 1, q)}. Thus from the first paragraph be an ordered orthonormal basis for













· ,

of the proof, the dimension of the linear space generated by these vectors in

VP is rank B1 =rank A. This completes the proof.

266 I HIGHER-DIMENSIONAL SPACE SPECIAL LINEAR TRANSFORMATIONS

Projections. Suppose M is a linear subspace of En and Lis a linear M. If V- is the orthogonal complement of L in M, then Vx E M there is a unique y E L and a unique yl. E LL so that

subspace of

x

=

l y + y ..

The last statement is just Proposition

6.2. IO(b). Let us defn i e a linear P with domain M and range L by the equation

transformation

P(x) =y. The linear transformation

P is called the projection of M onto L. It has

the following properties: (a) (b)

x E L¢:::P :> (x) =x. p2 = p p=p.

(c)

P=P1•

0

We shall leave these simple facts as an exercise for the reader. If

{uk:

k

E (I, r)} is an orthonormal basis for the linear space L, P(x) in terms of this basis. Indeed,

it is a simple matter to compute let us write

r

P(x) = L akuk. k =l If we take the dot product of both sides with respect to

ak=P(x)

·

uk=x

·

uk, we get

uk.

The last equality follows from the facts that

P1

=

P and P(uk) = uk.

Hence r

P(x) = L (x k=l

·

uk)uk.

Let us use the idea of projection to obtain the

spherical representation P1 be the projection of En onto the linear subspace 1 O}. P1 may also be described as the projection of {x: x E En & x En onto the space generated by the vectors {ek: k E (2, n)}. Here we i are taking ek (e/, ekn ) where ek = 0 ¢::::> j # k, el= 1. Let P2 2 1 be the projection of En onto the linear subspace {x: x E En & x = x O}. The projection of P2 may also be described as the projection of En onto the space generated by {ek: k E (3,n)}. Note that �(P2) =�(P2j�(P1)), so that P2 restricted to �(P1) is the projection of the latter subspace onto the subspace �(P2). In general, let Pi, j E (I, n I), be the projection of En onto the subspace {x: x E En 1 & x = x; =O}. Clearly, the last subspace is the space generated by {ek: k E (j + l,n)}, and �(Pi)=�(Pij�(Pi_1)),j E (2,n-1). 1 The vector (t , 0; , 0) is the projection of t onto the subspace generated by e1, and we have of a vector in En. Let =

=

·

·

· ,

·

·

=

-

·

·

·

=

,

6.5

LINEAR TRANSFORMATIONS J 267

Now, there exists a unique 81E[O,1T] so that cos81 = (t provided It I =fa 0. Hence we get (1 = ltl

COS

·

e 1)/ltl,

(JI,

The number 81 may be considered as the measure of the angle between the vectors t and e1. Since t= (t e1)e1 +P1(t) and e1 and P 1(t) are orthogonal, we have ·

But, we also have ltl2 cos2 81 + ltl2 sin281 = ltl2, so that IP1(t)l2= ltl2 sin281• Since 81E [O,1T] , sin 81 � 0, so that 1 IP 1(t)I = ltl sin 8 . Now, let us repeat this process with the vector P1(t) playing the role oft and P playing the role of P1• We find that 2 O ) = (P1(t) e2)e2, (0, t2, 0, ·

·

·

·

,

and there exists a unique 82E [O,1T] so that cos 82 = (P1(t) IP 1(t)I , provided, of course, that P1(t) =fa 0. We then get t2= IPdt)I cos 82= ltl sin 81 cos 82,

·

e 2)/

IP2(t)I = IP1(t)I sin 82= ltl sin 81 sin 82• The number 82 may be considered the measure of the angle between P 1(t) and e (Fig. 6.5.1). 2 x3

FIGURE 6.5.1

268 I HIGHER-DIMENSIONAL SPACE

If P n ( t) =F -2

0 , then none of the vectors t, P 1 ( t) , P P ( t) , 1 2 P (t) is zero, and we can proceed by induction and 1 2 find that there exist unique (Jk E [ 0, 'TT] , k E(l,n - I), so that Vk E(l,n-1), tk = It I sin 61 sin 62 • • sin (Jk-i cos (Jk,

Pn_

°

P,._3

°

·

,

°

·

·

-

·

·

0



and moreover

It" I = Iti

sin 61 sin 62 ••• sin en-2 sin en-I.

The last equation comes from the fact that

(O , If

t = 0,

·

·

· ,

0 , t") =

Pn -1

°

Pn

-2

°

·

·

·

0

P1 (t) = P n (t). -1

these equations Still hold, but the numbers

(JI,



••,en -I

are no longer uniquely determined. Indeed, any numbers will do. If

P1(t) =O , then from the equation j P 1 ( t ) j = ltl sin 61, it 0 or 61 ='TT. Again the equations above hold, but now (}2, en-i are no longer uniquely determined and again any num­ bers will work. Proceeding in this way, we see that if t =F 0 and V k E (I, n - 2), (Jk E ]O,'TT[, then the vector t uniquely determines the numbers (Jk, Vk E (I, n I). Unfortunately the last equation is an equation for It" I rather than t". If we wish to remove the absolute value sign, it may no longer be true that we can take en-I E [0,7T]. However, if Vk E(l,n-2), (Jk E )0,'TT[, then sin 61 ••• sin en-2 =F 0, and there exists a unique en-I E [0,27T[ so that t

0,

=F

but

follows that 61 •



=

· ,

-

tn-I tn

= It I

= It I

sin 61





-

sin en-2 cos en-l'

sin e1 • • • sin en-2 sin en-1.

en-1) where p ;:;. 0, E (I, n-2) and en-1 E [O,27T]. Let S0 be this with p > 0, (Jk E ]O,7r[ for k E( l, n - 2) and en-i

Let S be the collection of n-tuples (p, 61, ••

(Jk E [O,'TT]

set of n-tuples

E [O,27T [.

We have proved the following result.

The function with domain t1

=

t2

=

tk

=

tn-I tn

· ,

for k

S

defined by

ltl cos 61

Iti

sin 61 cos 62

It I

sin 61 sin 62 •

= It I = It I





sin

(Jk-l

cos

(Jk

(6.5.6)

sin 61 sin 62 ••• sin en-2 cos en-I sin 61 sin 62 • • • sin en-2 sin en-I

'

has range all of E". If this function is restricted to S then it is one to one and its range is all of E" with the exception of the subspace generated by the set {e1:j E(l,n-2)} U {O}. 0,

6.5

Note that if

n

= 2,

the formulas

LINEAR TRANSFORMATIONS I 269

(6.5.6) give the ordinary transforma­

tion from "polar coordinates" to "rectangular coordinates," and the

exceptional set is { 0}.

Symmetric Transformations. and

A is

linear transformation If

Suppose Lis a linear subspace of En

a linear transformation with

( u1, • •

·

,

ur

)

A is

J0(A) =Land .92.(A) RA = A1•

is an ordered orthonormal basis for Land

the matrix representation of

A with

A=A1,

we get that

[a;;]

is

respect to this basis, it follows from

A1

our discussion about the matrix representation of But since

C L. The

said to be symmetric

a1ii =a;;=aii.

that

a1;;=a;;.

Any matrix whose entries

symmetric.

satisfy the last relation is called

There is a method of computing the norm of a symmetric transforma­ tion that is usually more convenient than the methods we have indicated previously. Let us set

M=sup{IA(x) ·xi: lxl so that

Vx E

En,

M

IA(x) ·xi �M lxl2• �sup { IA(x)

=

l} ,

It is clear that

·YI: lxl =IYI

=

l}= llA ll.

On the other hand , a direct computation shows that 1

A(x) ·y = [A(x+y) "4

·

(x+y)-A(x-y) · (x-y)].

From the facts that

l[A (x+y) · (x+y)-A(x-y)

·

(x-y)]I �M[lx+yl2+lx-yl2]

Ix+Y l2+Ix - Y l2 = 2[lxl2 + IYl�J, we get

llAll =sup {IA(x) · YI: lxl =IYI = l} �M. Consequently, we have the following equality for symmetric transfor­ mations: sup {IA(x) Since

IA(x) xi ·

·xi: lxl = l}

=

llAll.

(6.5.7)

is a continuous real-valued function and the unit

sphere in L,S ={ x:

lxl = l},

is compact it follows that

3x0 E S,

llAll =max {IA(x) ·xi: x ES}=IA(x0) x01. •

Let us set

µ,0=A(x0) • x0• A direct computation shows that

0 � IA(xo ) - 1-toxol2 =IA(xo )J2-J.to2•

so that

270 I HIGHER-DIMENSIONAL SPACE

Since

IA(xo ) I

llAII= 11.to l.

:!f::

it follows that

IA(xo)-µ,o xol2=0. This means that

(6.5.8) Any number

µ,0

for which there exists a nonzero vector

x0 E�(A)

for which

(6.5.8) is satisfied is called an eigenvalue or proper value of the linear transformation A . Any nonzero vector that satisfies (6.5.8) is

called an

eigenvector

or

proper vector

A.

for

Our previous discussion shows

that a symmetric transformation has an eigenvalue. The corresponding eigenvectors are not unique, since clearly any element in the linear space generated by an eigenvector satisfies the relation

(6.5.8).

A., let MA be the linear subspace of all vectors in L that satisfy the relation Ax=A.x. It is clear that A takes every element in MA into an element in MA. If A is symmetric, then it is also true that A takes every element in MA.l into MA.l· To prove this last statement, let x EMA1-; then Vy EMA we have x · y=0. Now, Vy EMA, since A(y) EMA and x EMA.l we get For a given eigenvalue

A(x) · y = x µ,0

A(y)

A.(x

=

·

y)=0.

A(x) EMA.l'

This means Let

·

be the eigenvalue whose existence we established several

paragraphs back. Let

A1

A

be the restriction of

to

Mµ.,,1-;

that is,

A,= AIMµ..1-. A1 is a symmetric linear trans­

As we have shown in the last paragraph, formation with domain

Mµ./

and range in the same linear subspace.

Hence, by the same existence proof as before, there exists a

x1 EMµ./,

so that

lx1I =I

µ,1

and an

and

Proceeding in this way (formally, by induction!) we find that there is an ordered orthonormal basis

{ A.i.

·

·

· ,

A. r}

so that

(v1,





·

,

v r)

for L and eigenvalues

A vk= A.k vk. A. k are the same. Mµ.i is more than 1.

We are not excluding the possibility that some of the This can happen, for example, if the dimension of With respect to the ordered basjs sentation of

A

is

A.,

(v1,





0 0

· ,

vr)

the matrix repre­

6.5

LINEAR TRANSFORMATIONS I 271

where the entries off of the main diagonal are zero. This means that

[a;i],

the matrix

which is the matrix representation of

( u1,

to the ordered basis





Ur)

• ,

,

A

with respect

is similar to a diagonal matrix in the

sense that there is an invertible matrix

[bii]

so that

is the given diagonal matrix. Because of this, we usually say that a symmetric matrix is diagonalizable. Let us suppose that we have numbered the eigenvalues so that

>..

>--1 �

2











>..r.

For

x

E L let us write

Hence we get

r A(x) = L xk>..kvk> k=l r A(x) . x L >..k(xk)2. k=l =

This shows that

Vx

E L,

>--rlxl2 �A(x) · x �>..1 lxl2• Indeed, as the reader may easily verify,

{A(x) · x: lxl = l}, {A(x) x: lxl = l}.

>..1 =sup

>..r =inf

·

Orthogonal Transformations. and

A

Let L be a linear subspace of E"

a linear transformation with

linear transformation

=Ix!.

A

£l(A)

=

�(A) C L. The Vx E L, IA (x) I

L and

is said to be orthogonal (J) =C, fk(J) C En and so that Vx EC and Va f(ax) = af(x). Show that 3M> 0, so that Vx E C, IJ(x)I 8.

ER with

a;;.:

0,

� Mlxl.

Let f be a function with domain En and range in E'n which is

additive; that is,

Vx, y

E En

J (x + y)= J(x) Show that if f is continuous at

J(y).

+

x= 0,

then it is continuous at every

point of En.

9.

Let

Ay be

the linear functional defined on En by the equation

Ay(x) =x y. ·

Show that

10.

Let

A

be an orthogonal linear transformation with domain and

range a linear subspace L C En. Suppose orthonormal basis of L and

[aii]

( u1,





·

,

ur

)

is any ordered

the matrix representation of

A

with

respect to this basis. Show that

r

L aiiakJ

=

if

0

i # k.

j=I

11.

Let

A

be a symmetric transformation with domain a linear sub­

space L C En and range in E". Let of

A

[aiJ]

be the matrix representation

with respect to the ordered orthonormal basis

that there is a matrix

[biJ]

( u1,





·,Ur

).

Show

that is the matrix representation of an

orthogonal transformation from L onto L so that

is a diagonal matrix.

12.

If L and Mare linear subspaces of E" that have the same dimen­

sion, show that there is a linear transformation range M so that

13.

Vx

Show that if

E L,

A

IA (x) I= lxl.

A

with domain L and

is a linear transformation with domain L C En

and rangeM C E" so that

Vx

E L,

IA (x) I= lxl , then A can be extended

to be an orthogonal transformation with domain and range E".

14. that P2

Let P be a symmetric linear transformation with the property =

P. Show that P is the projection of its domain onto its range.

Give an example that shows that P2= P does not imply that P is a symmetric linear transformation.

274 I HIGHER-DIMENSIONAL SPACE

15. of

Let

�(A),

A

be a symmetric linear transformation, M a linear subspace

and

P the projection A= A P.

into itself¢::::? P

16.

If

P is

0

x

�(A)

onto M. Show that

a nonzero projection show that

vector in En and of

of

A

takes M

a

x

11P11= 1 .

If y is a nonzero

is any vector in En, use the formula for the projection

onto the linear space generated by y and the result of the first sen­

tence of this exercise to give another proof of the Cauchy-Bunjakovsky­ Schwarz inequality.

17.

6.6

Show that a linear transformation is an open map.

DETERMINANTS

In his study of elementary algebra the reader has undoubtedly come across the notion of determinants and has learned enough of their properties to be able to use them for solving systems of linear equations. Our purpose in this section is to derive a number of properties of determinants in a rigorous way since they are very important quantities in the higher-dimensional calculus. Before we discuss determinants, it is necessary to discuss a certain class of functions, called

permutations,

which take finite sets onto them­

selves.

Definition. Let S be a finite set. A one-to-one function 0,

If we set

B= u {B(xk,o): k E (l,p)}, then

Vx EB, p

Let us

(x)= L 'Pk(x) # 0. k=l define hk on K by putting Vx EK hk(x)

=

cpk(x)/(x).

We see immediately that this set of functions has the required properties. This completes the proof. REMARK:

The set of functions

{hk: k E (1,p)}

that we used in the

proof of the previous theorem is called a subordinate to the covering

partition of unity for K {B(xk,o): k E (I,p)}. We shall meet

these objects again later on, especially when we study integration on manifolds.

300 I HIGHER-DIMENSIONAL SPACE THE STONE-WEIERSTRASS THEOREM

We now come to an important generalization of the Weierstrass ap­ proximation theorem which was proved in Section 4.6. This generalized theorem was proved by M. H. Stone in a context that is more general than we shall present it, although the proof is the same. The reason we do not present the theorem in as general a context as originally given is that a discussion of the relevant concepts would take us too far afield. The theorem we shall state is valid only for

C1(K), where K is a compact C(K) in place

set in En. For the sake of simplicity we shall simply write of

C1(K).

Definiti.on. A set A C C(K) is said to be an algebra 0 and Vx EK, 38(x,e) so that Vf EA and

Vy EK for which lx-yl < 8(x,e) we have IJ(x)-J(y)I
0, we must have L(v) L(O) L1(0) = 0, we have shown that L = L1.

Since for fixed Further, since

=

L1(v).

=

7 .2.3 Proposition. If a function has a differential at a point a, then the function must be continuous at a. The simple proof of this fact was given in Section

7.1

and we shall

not repeat it here. However, we should call attention to the fact that the proof of Proposition

7.2.3

very definitely requires the use of the

linearity of the differential. On the other hand, the proof given above of the unicity of the function L which satisfies the conditions of Defi­ nition

7.2.2 requires only the homogeneity of L;

that is,

L(au)

=

aL(u).

Proposition. If f is a function with domain in E" and range in and has a differential at a, then Vu E En, Duf(a) exists and

7 .2.4 Em

Duf(a) Proof.

Suppose

Ve> 0, 38> 0

so

u

E E"

that

Vh

=

and

df(a) (u) . lul

=

E R with

1. Now, Va E -B(J)0 and 0 < lhl < 8 we have a+hu

312 I HIGHER-DIMENSIONAL DIFFERENTIATION

E -B{f) and

If we divide by

e lhl.

IJ(a+ hu) - f(a) -df(a)(hu)I



lhl and note that df(a) is linear,

we see that the proposi­

tion is proved in this case.

v E

If

E" and

v



0, then upon setting u = v/lvl we see that lul = 1.

Thus 1 Dv11v1f(a) = � df(a)(v).

But

Va E R, a



0,

f(a+ hau) -J(a) f(a+ hau) -f(a) ' -a ha h _

Duf(a) exists. then Dauf(a) exists and is equal to aDuf(a). lvlDv11vif(a) =Dvf(a). Finally, since Dof(a) = df(a)(O) = 0, we

so that if Thus

have completed the proof of the proposition. REMARK:

For future reference, let us call attention to the fact that

during the proof of the last theorem we have shown that if exists then

Va E R, Dauf(a) exists and

Duf(a)

Dauf(a) = aDuf(a) . As we saw at the end of Section 7.1, the converse of the last proposi­ tion is not true. That is to say, if necessarily true that

f

Vu E

has a differential at

E",

a.

Duf(a)

exists, it is not

Indeed, the example we

gave showed the existence of a function all of whose directional deriva­ tives exist at the origin but the function itself is not continuous at the origin.

However, if in addition to the existence of the directional

derivatives of a function at a point, the directional derivatives are continuous, then the function has a differential at the point. This is shown by the next theorem, which actually proves somewhat more.

7 .2.5 Theorem. Suppose f is a function with domain in E" and range in Em, {µ.k: k E (l,n)} is a basis for En, 3i E (l,n) so that Dµ.J(a) exists, and there is a ball B(a,p) C -B{f) so that Vj E (1, n) \{i}, B(a,p) C -B(Dµ.J) and Dµ.J is continuous at a. Then df(a) exists. Proof.

We shall break the proof into several steps.

Suppose u and v are linearly independent vectors in En so that Dvf(a) exists, B(a, p) C -B(Duf) and Duf is continuous at a. Then Ve> 0, 3S > 0 so that Va,f3 E R with lau +f3vl < S we have (a)

lf(a +au+ {3v) - f(a) -aDuf(a) - f3Dvf(a)I

� E

lau+ f3vl.

(7.2.2)

7.2 DIRECTIONAL DERIVATIVES AND DIFFERENTIALS I 313

From the definition of the directional derivative, so that if

lf3vl


0,

381

> 0,

then

IJ(a+{3v) - f(a)-f3Dvf(a)I :;;;

E

lf3vl .

Next, let us set

F(a, {3) = f(a+au+{3v), a+au+{3v

where we suppose that

laul + lf3vl

D1F(a, {3)

=

=

=

Since

f/2,(F )

l lim _ h-0 h

lim

h-0

[F(a+ h, {3)-F(a, {3)]

J [f(a+ (a+h)u+{3v) - f(a +au+{3v)] h

Duf(a+au+{3v).

C Em we may write

F(a, {3) where

E JFJ(f); this is certainly true if

< p. We have

f/2,(Fk)

m

=

L Fk(a, {3)ek>

k=l

C R. Using the one-dimensional mean value theorem

we get

Fk(a, {3)-Fk(O, {3) aDufk(a+Ok u+{3v), where 0 :;;; I O i :;;; lal. By hypothesis, Duf is continuous at a and k 38 with 0 < 8 < p, so that if laul + lf3vl < 8 , then 2 2 2 IJ(a+au+{3v) - f(a+{3v) - aDuf(a)I :;;; E laul. J k(a+au+{3v) - J k(a+{3v)

=

=

thus

If we now write

f(a+au+{3v)-J(a) and

take

we have

=

J(a+au+{3v)-f(a+{3v) + f(a+{3v)-J(a),

83 = min (81 , 8 ), 2

then

Va, {3

E R with

IJ(a+au+{3v) - f(a)-aDuf(a)-f3Dvf(a)I :;;; e

laul +lf3vl

[laul +lf3vlJ.


1, k < n - 1 and P(k) is true. Suppose u is a nonzero linear combination of (k + 1) vectors in A. Then 3l E (1, n) \{i}, so that u1 u - u1µ,1 is a linear combination of k vectors in A. From the hypothesis P (k), Va E R, Du1+aµ./(a) exists and where

u

ment:

=

=

=

=

j¢i Now, by part (a) of the proof, -.

(7.2.3") since by hypothesis

B (a, p) and is continuous at a. P(k) =::::} P(k + 1) and the induction is com­ Vu E E",D,,f(a) exists and (7.2.3) holds.

D,,1µ.J

is defined on

Thus (7.2.3') holds. Hence plete. This shows that

The second statement of part (b) is an immediate consequence of the

1 u µ,1 and u1 +aµ,; are linearly independent, the fact that D,,1µ.J is defined on B(a, p) and continuous at a, formula (7.2.3"), and the

fact that

inequality (7.2.2). (c) . The function f has a differential at a. From part (b) we know that Vu E E",D,,f(a) exists. If we set L(u) D,,f(a), then (7.2.3) shows =

7.2

DIRECTIONAL DERIVATIVES AND DIFFERENTIALS I 315

(7.2.1) is satisfied for (7.2.4). This completes the proof.

that L is a linear transformation. The fact that L is simply the inequality

The last theorem is usually stated in terms of the basis

REMARK:

{ei: j

E

( l, n)}

since in practical situations the partial derivatives

of a function are usually the easiest to compute. The fact that we stated the theorem in the form that allowed one directional derivative merely to exist and not necessarily be continuous at

a was not done for reasons of sophistry. This was done to include the n 1, where a function has a differential at a point if it has a

case

=

derivative at the point, regardless of whether or not the function has a derivative in the neighborhood of the point. Indeed, iff has domain in R and is differentiable at

a,

then

df(a) (u)

Vu

=

E R,

uf' (a) .

Let us now note a particularly useful matrix form of the differential of a function at a point. Suppose f is a function with domain in range in

Em

and

df(a)

En

and

exists. Let us find the matrix representation of

this differential with respect to the ordered pair of ordered bases,

( (e1,





·,en), (e., · · ·,em)). If m

¥-

n,

we are using the same symbol

ek

to stand for different vectors in different dimensional spaces. However, we think that no confusion will result. We may write

df(a) (ek)

=

m Dd(a) = L DdJ(a)ei.

Thus the matrix representation of

df(a)

with respect to this ordered

pair of ordered bases is

(7.2.5)

This matrix is called the

Jacobian matrix

of f at

a,

and, if

n

=

determinant of this matrix is called simply the Jacobian off at

a

m,

the

and is

denoted by ]J(a) . Of course, the reader should be aware of the fact that the Jacobian matrix of a function can exist at a point without the func­ tion having a differential at the point in question. If f has a differential at

a,

df(a) (u) in J and the components of u with (e., · · ·,en)· We already noted such a then it is easy to compute

terms of the partial derivatives of respect to the ordered basis form in formula

(7.2.3). In general let us write

!16 I HIGHER-DIMENSIONAL DIFFERENTIATION

and apply the linear transformation df(a) to both sides. Noting that df(a)(e ) k

=

D f(a), we get k df(a)(u)

n

=

L

k=l

ukD f(a). k

(7.2.6)

The last formula can be put into a form that we feel sure the reader has seen in elementary calculus, even though the meaning may not have been clear at that time. For every k E

(1, n),

let xk be that function with domain En and

range E1 defined by (7.2.7) Note that we have also used the same symbol 'xk• as a variable. We think it will always be clear from the context in which way we are using this symbol, and when we use it as a function it will be clear on which space it is acting. The function xk is clearly a projection and an almost trivial calculation shows that Vx, u E En Duxk(x)= uk. Since Vu E En, this is a continuous function of x, 0 so that

since

lg(x) - g(a) - dg(a)(x - a)I ,,;;: E Ix - al/2M, g(x) I g(a) - 11


0 so that Vu E Eq, ldf(b)(u) I � N lu l. Hence =

l df(b)(g(x)-g(a))-df(b) 0dg(a)(x-a)I � N lg(x)-g(a)-dg(a)(x-a) I. Next, Ve> 0, 38' > 0 so that Vx

E

cB(g) with Ix-al

lg(x)-g(a)-dg(a)(x-a)I




0 so that Vx with lg(x) -g(a)I < 8" we have =

IJ0g(x) -f(b)-df(b)(g(x)-b)I Let us set 8 min(8', 8"/L); then Vx have from (7.3.2) through (7.3.5), =

E



E

(7.3.4)

cB(f 0g)

e lg(x) -bl/2L .

cB(J 0 g) with Ix-al

(7.3.5)
0, 38 > 0 so that \Ohek + O'td

\Di Dkf(a + Ohek 0

+

O'tei)

-




Di Dkf(a) I 0


P ( q +

1) ,

=

q+

1. Hence

and the corollary is proved.

function f is said to belong to the class Ck ¢:::::> all of the partial derivatives of f of order � k have domain £J (f) and are con­ tinuous. The function f is said to belong to the class C00 ¢:::::> all of partial deriva­ tives of f (of all orders) have domain £J (f) and are continuous. 7 .4.4

Definition.

A

Ck, then from Corollary 7.4.3 it follows that any partial deriva­ f of order � k is independent of the manner in which the partial

If f E tive of

derivatives are composed. Hence the operator D'>, which we shall define in an informal way below, becomes rather useful. Suppose that C En and

se(f)

C Em and a=

(a1,





·,an), where a,.

set

E

£J(f)

N . We shall 0 (7.4.5)

If

J

E

Ck and lal

� k, we shall set

DJ= (J] where

0Dkk (f),

(7.4.6)

)

D k"k is ak compositions of Dk and Dk0f

=

f.

The notation

D"f

has become popular with the advent of the modern theory of partial differential equations.

7 .4.5 Definition. Suppose f is a function with domain in En and range in Em which has a differential at the point a and Vj E ( 1, k - 1 ) and V (u 1 , · · ·, ui), where u; E E", the function II;-!:1 DuJ has a differential at a. Then V ( u1, , uk) we set °







dkJ(a) (u1,

k





·, ud =fl 0D u J(a) , i=l

(7.4.7)

and call dkf(a) the kth -order differential of f at a. If u1 = u2 = · · ·= uk= u, we shall set

dkj(a) (u)k

=

dkJ(a) (u, · ·

· ,

u),

(7.4.8)

and d0f(a) (u)0= J(a). A special case of Theorem

7 .2.5 says that if a function has continuous

first partials at a point, then the function has a differential at the point.

7.4 HIGHER-ORDER DIFFERENTIALS AND TAYLOR'S THEOREM j 329

The same type of result holds for kth-order differentials, although for the sake of simplicity we shall state it in a slightly less general form than is possible.

7 .4.6 Theorem. Suppose f has domain in En and range in Em, and there is a ball B(a, p) C JFJ (J), so that all the partials of f of order� k, (k � 1)

have B(a,p) in their domains and are continuous there. Then f has a kth­ order differential at every x E B(a,p) and dkJ(x) (u1 ,





· ,

uk )

L n

i1=1 Proof.

U1;,







uk 1 k

k

IJ

j=l

0

D1if(x).

(7.4.9)

Let P(k) be the statement of the theorem. The statement

P(l) is true by Theorem 7.2.5. Assume P(k) is true and we shall try to prove P(k

+ 1).

Since the hypotheses of P (k

+ 1)

imply the hypoth­

eses of P(k), it follows from P(k) thatf has a kth-order differential at every point of B(a,p) and (7.4.9) holds. Each function on the right side of (7.4.9) has, by the hypotheses of P(k +

1),

continuous first partials on

B (a, p), and thus by Theorem

7.2.5 has a differential at each point of this ball. Further, Vuk+l E E11 and Vx E B( a,p)

(fI

Duk+1

J=l

0

)

D;J (x)

=

.

±

'k+I =1

uk+1ik+1 D;k+1

( fJ

o

)

D;J (x).

J=l

Hence, if we apply Duk+1 to both sides of (7.4.9) and use the last equality

we see that the induction is complete. REMARK:

Clearly there is nothing special about partial derivatives

and we could have stated the previous theorem in terms of the direc­ tional derivatives of any basis for £11• Note that the right side of (7.4.9) shows that

dkf(x) is multilinear.

As an exampie of the formula (7.4.9) let us write down

d 3f(x) (u)3 in

terms of the more classical terminology for partial derivatives. We have

d3f(x) (u)3

L L .L ii i2uia u u . 1 =1 11=1 n

n

=

.

11

a3J(x) axiaaxt.ax;"

t3=l 2 i where of course u i is the ii component of the vector u.

7 .4. 7 Theorem. Suppose f is a real-valued function with JFJ(J) C En, and the line segment L {x: x th + (1 - t)a & t E [O, l]} is contained in JFJ(J). If Vk E (1, m) and Vx E L, f has a kth-order differential dkf(x), then Vx E L, 3c E L so that c yx + (1- y)a, y E JO, 1 [, and =

=

=

330 j HIGHER-DIMENSIONAL DIFFERENTIATION

f(x)= Proof.

For

1 m-1 1 L kl. dkf(a)(x - a)k +m.1 dmf(c)(x - a)m. k� -

VtE [O, l]

(7.4.10)

let us set

F(t)

=

f(tx +(I - t) a) .

Since xEL we may write x rb +(I - r)a with TE[O, l]. Hence tx +(I - t)a= trb +(I - tr)a with trE [O, l]. Thus tx + (I - t)a is in L and hence by the chain rule, VtE [0, 1], =

F'(t)

=

df(tx +(I - t)a)(x - a).

It follows by an easy induction argument that

E[O, l]

VkE (1, m)

and

Vt

we have

p(t) = dkf(tx +(1 - t)a)(x - a)k . If we apply the one-dimensional Taylor formula with the Lagrange form of the remainder, Corollary

F (I)=

4.4 .2(c),

we get

i 1i p(O) +� p (y)' m.

k k=O .

If we substitute in for

F(l), p(O),

and

yE]O,l[.

p(y)

we have completed

the proof of the theorem. The above theorem is valid only for real-valued functions. However, by applying it component wise to a function whose range is in

m

>

1,

Em,

we do get a Taylor remainder formula. However, the reader

should be cautioned that the same point

c

will not work for all com­

ponents and will in general change with the different components. There is an integral formula for the Taylor remainder that looks like the integral remainder formula for functions defined in R. The integral formula does not require that that if

f( t)= �k1!:1 Jk ( t)e k

f

be real-valued. We only note

is a continuous function with domain

[a, b]

we define

7 .4. 7 Theorem. Suppose the hypotheses of theorem 7.4.7 are satisfied and in addition VxEL, dmf(tx +(I - t)a)(x - a)m is a continuous func­ tion of t. Then VxEL,

m-1 1 f(x)= L I dkf(a)(x - a)k k. k=O ·

7.4

HIGHER-ORDER DIFFERENTIALS AND TAYLOR'S THEOREM I 331

As in the proof of Theorem 7.4.7 we set

Proof.

F (t)

=

f(tx + (I - t) a) .

Then by the formula (5.2. l) we get

F(l)

=

I - t)m�1 pcm>(t)dt. �i � F(O) + Jo{ 1 ((m-1) .

k=Ok.

If we substitute in for p ck>(O) and F(l) we get formula (7.4.10'), which concludes the proof.

If we assume that f E cm, then we can write formulas (7.4.10) or (7.4.10') in the terminology of the operators na. In this case Corollary 7.4.3 tells us that it doesn't matter in which order the Di; are applied and we can write, fork� m,

ii dkf(x)(u)k

where

U

"

=

=

L u"caDaf(x), 1al=k

fl '/=1 ( U j)a;, and Ca is a constant independent of j and X.

This can be proved by an easy induction argument onk. Suppose pis a polynomial of

n

variables of degree m; that is,

p(x) = L Pa (X - a)", lai"'m

where (x - a)a =Ilj= (xi - ai )ai. From Theorem 7.4.7 we can write

1 p(x) = L (x - a)acaDap(a), lal.:;m

since the (m + l)st remainder vanishes. If lal � m and we apply n

a

to

both sides of this equation, we get

a!Pa= Dap(a) =a!caDap(a),

where a!= nil aj ! . If we choose pso that Pa ¥- 0, we see that Ca= I/a!

Thus we can write the formula (7.4.10) in the form

1 1 f(x) = L -, naf(a)(x - a)a + L I naf(c)(x - a)o:. a a. lal=m . lal.:;m-1 D Exercises 1.

Compute d3f(a)(x - a)3 for the following functions at the given

point a:

(a) (b) (c)

2.

f(x1, x2, x3) (x2)2 + 2x1 (x2)2 + (x3)2, a= (I, 0, -1). f(x1, x2, x3) =sin (x1 + x2 + x3), a= 0. f(x1' x2) =ex•x•, a= 0. =

Write Taylor's formula about (0, 0) for

f(x1, x2) =sin (x1 + ex•) form=3.

332 I HIGHER-DIMENSIONAL DIFFERENTIATION

3.

Suppose

p(x1' x2)

=

x1 (x2)2 + 3(x1)2 x2

x1 + 2.

+

Write this polynomial as a polynomial in powers of 4.

f E C2 and Dif(a) Dd(a) JFJ(f), show 3M > 0 so that Vb E

Suppose

convex set in

=

IJ(b) - f(a)I

=

,,s; Mlb

(x1 - 1)

and

(x2

-

1).

0. If B is a compact

B

- a l2 •

C"' and JFJ(f) is an JFJ(f) is a convex set containing a E JFJ(f), and 3M so that Va andVx E B, ID"f(x)I :s; M. Show that Vx E B, the remainder in Taylor's formula goes to zero as m -'> oo. 5.

Suppose

open set in E

6.

n .

f

is a real-valued function of class

Suppose B C

State and prove an analogue of Bernstein's theorem, 4.4.4, for

functions with domain in E n,

7.5

n > 1.

THE INVERSE AND IMPLICIT FUNCTION THEOREMS

f is a function with domain in E", range in Em and df(a) exists. df(a)(x - a) + f(a) approximates f(x) very closely in a neighbor­ hood of a we might hope that if df(a) is nonsingular, then f itself, re­ stricted to a neighborhood of a, is a one-to-one function. It turns out Suppose

Since

that this is essentially the case and our first object in this section is to prove this, and indeed somewhat more.

7.5.1 Proposition. Suppose f is of class C1 with an open domain in E" and range in Em. For every compact set K C JFJ(f) and Ve > 0, 3 f> > 0 so that Vx, y E K with Ix - YI < f> and Vu E E" we have

ldf(x)(u) -df(y)(u)I

,,s;

elul,

IJ(x) - f(y) - df(x)(x - y)I Proof.

Let

S

=

{u: u

E P &

lul

=

l}

(7.5.1)

,,s;

elx - YI.

(7.5.2)

be the unit sphere in E".

From the expansion

df(x)(u)

n

=

L uiDJ!(x),

j=l

df(x)(u) is continuous on the Cartesian product JFJ(f) X S. If we restrict df(x)(u) to K X S, the restricted function is uniformly continuous. Thus Ve> 0, 36 > 0 so that Vx, y E K with Ix - YI < a, and Vu ¥- 0 we have it is clear that

ldf(x)(u/lul) - df(y)(u/lul)I lul

we get

e.

df(x) and df(y), if we multiply the (7.5.1). I(u 0, (7.5.1) is clearly true.

Using the homogeneity of equality by


(f ) so that Vx,y E B(a, 8(a)) we have (7.5.1). Using the mean value theorem, Vu E £711 there is a c on the straight line joining x and y so that C

[f(x)-f(y)-df(x)(x-y) ]

·

u= [df(c)(x-y)-df(x)(x-y)]

·

u.

Replace u by [f(x) - f(y)-df(x)(x -y) J and for the corresponding c we get, using the C-B-S inequality,

lf(x)-f(y)-df(x)(x-y)I



ldf(c)(x-y)-df(x)(x-y)I.

If we now use the estimate (7.5.1) on the right, we have (7.5.2) in

B(a,8(a)).

The collection {B(a, 8(a)/2):a EK} is an open covering for Kand thus reduces to a finite subcovering {B(ai,8(a;)/2):J E (l,q)}. Let 8=min{8{ai)/2:J E (l,q)} and suppose x,y EK with lx-yl < 8. Now 3J E ( 1, q) so that Ix -a; I < 8. Thus IY-aiI � IY -xi + Ix-a;I < 8(ai) . Hence x,y E B(a;, 8(a;)), and since we have the estimate (7.5.2) in this ball we have concluded the proof. 7 .5.2 Corollary. If f satisfies the hypotheses of Proposition 7.5.1 and 3a E JE>{f ) so that df(a) is nonsingular, then there exists a ball B(a, 8) C JE>(f ) and 3m > 0, so that Vx E B(a,8) and Vu EEn we have

ldf(x)(u)I



m lul.

(7.5.3)

Moreover, if df(x) is nonsingular for every x in a compact set K C JE>(f ), then 3m > 0 so that (7.5.3) holds Vx EK. Proof. Since df(a) is nonsingular, it follows from Corollary 6.5.5 that 3 m > 0 so that Vu EE" jdf(a)(u)I � 2m lul. Now, from Proposi­ tion 7.5.1, 38 > 0 so that Vx E B(a,8) and Vu EE" we have

ldf(a) (u)I -jdf(x)(u)I



m lul.

Thus

jdf(x)(u) I



ldf(a)(u)I-m lul



m lul.

To prove the second statement, it follows from what we have just proved, that Va EK, 38(a) > 0 and 3m(a) > 0 so that (7.5.3) holds Vx E B(a,8(a)) , provided m is replaced by m(a). The collection {B(a,8 (a)):a EK} is an open covering for K and thus reduces to a finite subcovering {B(a;,8(aj)):J E (l,q)}. If we now take m= min {m(a;):J E (l,q)} we have completed the proof. The next two propositions constitute essentially the proof of the Inverse Function Theorem.

3M I

HIGHER-DIMENSIONAL DIFFERENTIATION

Supposef E C1 has (an open) domain in En, range in Em, and df(a) is nonsingular. Then there exists a ball B(a, 8) C �(f) and 3m > 0 so that Vx E B(a,8), df(x) is nonsingular and Vx,y E B(a, 8), IJ(x) - f(y)I � m Ix-YI. In particular th,is means that JIB(a, 8) is a one-to-one function. 7.5.3

Proposition.

Proof. From Corollary 7.5.2 there exists a ball B(a,281) C 3m > 0 so that Vx E B(a, 281) and Vu E En we have

�(J)

and

ldf(x) (u) I

2m l ul.



(7.5.3')

If we take K as the closure of B(a, 81), then it follows from Proposition

7.5.l

Thus

that

38,0

8 < 81, so that Vx,y EK with lx-yl IJ(x)-f(y) - df(x) (x-y)I ,,;;; m Ix - YI.

Vx,y

E


(!) so that f(a)=0 and df(a) is of rank n. Then there is an open set U C Em containing 0, an open set V C £>(!) containing a, a function g with £>(g) U and !R,(g) C V which satisfies the following: (a) g(O)=a. (b) f g(t)=0, Vt E £>(g). gE Cq and Vt E U, rank dg(t) m. (c) (d) If x E V and f(x)=0, then x E !R,(g).

=

0

=

Proof.

Let us identify Em+n with E"' XE" in the obvious way, and

X {O} of Em+n andE" with the subspace {O} XE" of Em+n. Let M be any linear subspace of Em+n of dimension n so that the range of df(a) IM is E". Let P be the projection of Em+n onto M 1. and A any linear transformation of Em+n into itself which takes M 1. onto E"'. This is possible, since dim M n and thus dim M 1.= m. identify Em with the subspace E"'

=

(See Exercises 12 and 13 of Section 6.5.) If

Vx E £>(!)

we set

F(x)=(A0P(x),f(x)) , then

F

is a function of class Cq with domain

Further,

Vu EEm+n

£>(/)

and range in E"'+".

we have

dF(a)(u)=(dA0P(a)(u),df(a)(u)) =(A0P(u),df(a)(u)). dF(a) is Em+n. Indeed, let (v1,v2) EEm+n and u1 E Af1. A0P(u1)=v1,u2EM so that df(a)(u2)=v2-df(a)(u1), and u=u1 +u2• Then A 0P(u)=v1, df(a)(u)=v2, and we see that dF(a)(u)=(v1,v2). Consequently dF(a) has rank m + n, which means The range of so

that

it is nonsingular. If we apply the Inverse Function Theorem to F, we find that there is an open set V C

£>(/)

containing

a

and an open set W C Em+n contain­

ing F(a) so that FIV is a one-to-one function with range Wand having an inverse function

G

of class Cq. Set

W1= { T:

T EE"' & (T,0) E W}.

It is clear that W1 is open in Em and is nonvoid, since For every

T E W1

A P (a) E W1 . 0

let u s set

h(T)=G(T,0). Then

h E Cq

and since

d G (T,0)

is nonsingular it follows that

dG(T,O)JE"' has rank

m.

But

Vu EE"'

we have

7.5

THE INVERSE AND IMPLICIT FUNCTION THEOREMS I 341

d G(r,O) (u,O) = Hence rank dh(T)

=

m



i=I

uiDiG(r,O) =dh(r) (u).

m.

Now,

h(A0P(a))=G(A0P(a),O)=G(A0P(a),f(a)) (7.5.8)

=G°F (a)=a. Further,

Vr

E W1

(AoPoh(r) ,Jo h(r)) =F 0h(r) =F 0 G((T, O)) =( T, 0). Thus, we get

AoP0h(r)=r ,

(7.5.9)

f 0h(r)=O. x

Note also, if

E V and

f(x)=0, then F(x)

(7.5.10) E Wand

x = Go F (x) =G(A0P(x), O) =h(A0P(x)). 0P(a)={t: t U let us set

Finally,let us setU=W1-A &

T

E W1}



Then

Vt

E

g (t)=h(r), Clearly

E Em &

(7.5.11)

t=r-A0P(a)

t=r-A0P (a).

g satisfies the conclusions of Theorem 7.5.7, condition (d)

coming from (7.5.11). The proof is complete. Condition (d) is a uniqueness condition on

� (g) rather than on g

itself. We can get any number of other functions that satisfy the con­

g with a function of class cq U onto itself, leaves the origin fixed, and is of rank m at every point of U. To pin down the uniqueness of g, the Implicit Func­

clusions of the theorem by composing that takes

tion Theorem is usually stated in a special form. We state this as a corollary, although it is really a corollary of the proof.

7.5.8 Corollary. Suppose f is of cl ass Cq, q � 1, eB(f) CE"' X En, and �(f) C En. Suppose further that (a,b) E eB(f) so that f(a,b) =0 and duf(a,b) is nonsingul ar, where duf(a,b) is the differenti al of the func­ tion with dom ain in En and val u es f(a,y). Then there is an op en set U CEm cont aining a and an op en set YC E" cont aining b, so that UXYC eB(f) and a function g with eB(g)=U and �(g) CYthat satisfies the following: (a') g (a) =b. (b') f(x,g (x))=0, Vx E eB(g). (c') g E Cq. (d') If (x,y) E UXYand f(x,y)=O,then y=g (x).

342 I HIGHER-DIMENSIONAL DIFFERENTIATION

We shall use the notations of the proof of the last theorem,

Proof.

Em X En by (x,y). E". From the formula

except that we shall designate the elements of Let

u= (0, u 2)

E Em X 11

df(a,b)(u) = L u2iD +d(a,b) =duf(a,b)(u2) , m ;�1 duf(a,b) is nonsingular and f76(df(a,b)) C E", we df(a, b) has rank n. Let M=E"; then, of course, the orthogonal complement of Min Em+n is Em. As in the proof of Theorem 7.5.7 we let P be the projection of Em+n onto Em so that V (x,y) E Em+n we have P(x,y) =x. We take A to be the identity transformation of£"'+" onto itself. Hence the function F of the last theorem becomes and the fact that

see that

F(x,y) = (x,f(x,y)). If we apply the proof of the last theorem, we find that there is an open neighborhood U C C �(J)

Em containing a and an open neighborhood U X Y (a,b) and a function h(x) = (h1(x),h2(x)) of

containing

class cq with domain u and range in u x y so that from

(7.5.8) we have

h(P(a,b)) =h(a) = (a,b). Thus

Further, from

(7.5.9)

we have

h1(x) =P0h(x) =x , and thus from

(7.5.10)

w e get

f0h(x) =f(x,h2(x)) =O. g=h2, then condition (a'), (b') and (c') are satisfied. (x,y) EU X Y and f(x,y) =O; then (x,y) E �(F) and F(x,y) = (x,O). Applying the inverse function G and recalling that G (x,O) =h(x) we get If we take

To prove the unicity condition (d') let us suppose

·

(x,y)

=

G

°

F(x,y) = G (x,O) = (x,g (x)),

from which it follows that

y = g (x). This completes the proof. duf(a,b) is the matrix

Of course, the Jacobian matrix of

Dm+d1(a,b)

1 Dm+nf (a,b) Dm+nf"(a,b)

As we remarked after the proof of the Inverse Function Theorem, the easiest way to check that

duf(a,b) is nonsingular is to check that the

Jacobian, that is, the determinant of the above matrix, does not vanish.

7.5 THE INVERSE AND IMPLICIT FUNCTION THEOREMS j 1143

The reader may find it instructive to go back and review the examples given before Theorem 7 .5. 7 in the light of that theorem and its corollary.

O Exercises 1.

Define a function f on

E2 by means of the equations

f'(x,y)=x2-y2, f2(x,y)= 2xy. Show that f has a nonsingular differential at every point except the origin and thus at every point of E2\ { (0,O)} is

locally a

one-to-one func­

tion. Show thatf is not a one-to-one function. Is the restriction off to some neighborhood of

(0,O) a one-to-one function? [Note: From the z=x + iy, then f'(x,y) is the real part of z2 and f2(x,y) is its imaginary part.]

point of view of complex variables, if we set

2.

Letf be that function on

f'(x,y)=

{x

+

E2 defined by

x2 sin (I/x) {::::> x

0

oF-

0,

if x = 0,

f2(x,y)=y. Show that

df(O,O) is nonsingular but thatf is not a one-to-one function df(x,y) nonsingular for every

on any neighborhood of the origin. Is

(x,y) in some neighborhood of the origin? 3.

(a)

Suppose that f is a real-valued function defined on

E2 by

f(x,y)=x-y2· Does there exist a real-valued function g defined in a neighborhood of

x=0 so that f(x,g(x)) =O? (b)

Suppose thatf is the same function as in part (a). Show that

there is a unique function so that 4.

f(x,g(x))

=

g defined on a suitable neighborhood of x = 1

0 and g(x)

>

0.

Suppose that f is a real-valued function on

E2 defined by

f(x,y)=x2 - y2. How many continuous functions g do there exist, defined on a neighbor­ hood of x= 0 so that

f(x,g (x))= 0? Are there more functions for which

this is true if we remove the requirement of continuity on g?

5.

Suppose f has domain

E2 and is defined by the equations

f'(x,y)= e cosy, x

f2(x,y) =ex sin y.

344 I HIGHER-DIMENSIONAL DIFFERENTIATION

Show that

f/2,(J)

=

E2 \ {O}. Isfa one-to-one function? Isflocally one­

to-one? Note that in terms of the complex variable is the real part of

6.

f2 (x, y)

ez,

z

= x + iy , f1 (x, y)

is its imaginary part.

If the open set U of Corollary 7.5.8 is connected and his a con­

tinuous function with domain U which satisfies (a') and (b'), show that

h=g. 7.

Suppose

f

is a real-valued function with

J0(J)

C E2 and satis­

fies the hypotheses of Corollary 7.5.8. Compute the derivative of g in terms of the partial derivatives off. Extend the results of Exercise 7 to higher dimensions, that is,

8.

where the domain and range off are in higher dimensions. In fact, show that

d g(x) = -dyf(x, g (x))- 1 [Hint:

Vu

Note that

0

dxf(x, g (x)).

E Em and Vv E En·

dxf (x, y)(u) = df(x, y)(u, O) , dyf(x, y)(v) = df(x, y)(O, v) .] 9.

Suppose

f

E

C1

with domain in En and range in Em and

is nonsingular. Show that there is a ball B (a,

=JIB(a, p),

then

Va

E R so that

a= 1, 3m

lg(x)-g(y) I lx-yl"

Suppose

lim

lg( x) - g(y)I Ix - YI

f

E

C1

·

0,

>



m

·

Vu

Vx E J0(f ) , [Hint: Use the [J(x)-J(y)] when u = x - y.] E E",

u

=ft 0, and

=ft 0. Show thatfis a one-to-one function.

mean value theorem on

7 .6

df(a) g

so that if

and its domain is a convex set in E" and its

range is in En. Suppose further that

u df(x)(u)

J0(J)

> 0

lx-yl-O 10.

C

1 we have

Jim

lx-yl-O and if

a
0, then since dk is a continuous function, p so thatVe E B(a, cr ) andVk E (I, n), dk(c) > 0. Thus from (7.6.3), (7.6.4), and Theorem 6.6.14 it follows that Vx E B(a,cr), f(x) - f(a) > 0, and hence f(a) is a local minimum for J. k IfVk E (l,n), (-I) d(a) < 0, then arguing the same way as above and using Corollary 6.6.15, we find that f(a) is a local maximum for J. If Vk

3cr



To prove the last statement of the theorem we use the last statement in

6.6.15. This tells us that 3u, v E En, so that T(a)(u) u > 0, and T(a)(v) v < 0. Since the functions with values T(x)(u) u and T(x)(v) v are continuous, there is a ball B(a, 'Y)) C �(f) so that Ve E B(a, 'Y)), T(c)(u) u > 0 and T(c)(v) v < 0. Now VOi E R, Ol� 0, andVe E B(a,'Y)), Corollary

·

·

·

·

·

·

T(c)(Olu) OlU = 10ll2 T(c)(u) u > 0, ·

T(c)(Oiv)

·

·

OlV = 10ll2 T(c)(v) v < 0 . ·

e > 0, 3a E R, a � 0, so that IOlul < e and IOlvl < e. Sup­ pose 0 < e < 'Y), and we set y =au+ a and z =av+ a. Then y, z E B(a, e) and from (7.6.3) and (7.6.4), For every

7.6 MAXIMA AND MINIMA I 347

J(y) - f(a)= T(c)(y - a) ·(y - a)= T(c)(au) ·au> 0, f(z) - f(a) =T(c' )(z - a) Thus the function with values borhood of

a

so that

a

(z - a)= T(c')(av) ·av< 0.

·

f(x) - f(a)

changes sign in every neigh­

is at a saddle point for

f

LAGRANGE MULTIPLIERS

If

f

is a real-valued function with

le(J)

C E", it very often happens

that we are not interested in the local extrema offbut rather in the local

extrema of a new function g that is Usually the subset of

le(f )

f

restricted to a subset of

le(f ). {x:

we are interested in is given by a set

h(x)=O} n le(J), where his a function with domain in E" and range m ,,;;:; n. This is a standard type of problem that arises, for example,

in Em,

in classical analytical mechanics. It is usually called an extremal problem

for funder the constraint

h(x)=0.

The method of Lagrange multipliers gives a necessary condition

that a point

h(x)=0.

a

should be at a local extremum of funder the constraint

Actually, it is based on Theorem 7.6.2, being an elaboration

on that theme.

7.6.5

Theorem. Suppose f and h are of class C1 with (open) domains Suppose also that f is real-valued, f/2,(h) C Em, m ,,;;:; n, and Vx E le(h), dh(x) has rank m. A necessary condition that a be at a local ex­ tremum for f restricted to the set {x: h(x)=O} n le(J) is that 3A. E Em, so that the function F with domain [le(J) n le (h)] X Em and de.fined by

in

E".

(7.6.5)

F(x,y)=f(x) + h(x) : y has a critical point at (a, A.); that is,

dF(a, A.)= df(a) + Proof.

We shall suppose that

m

L

k=I

A_k dhk(a)= 0.

(7.6.6)

m< n, since otherwise, as we shall h(a)=0, and rank dh(a)= m,

show later, the theorem is trivial. Since

according to the Implicit Function Theorem 7.5.7, there exists an open set U C En-m containing the origin, and a function g of class C1 with domain U, so that

Vt

E U, rank

dg(t)=n - m, h

0

and

g(t)=0,

g{O)

=a.

Since

g{O) E le(J), g is continuous, and le(J) is open, there is a B{O,p) CU so that t E B{O,p) ::::::}g(t) E le(J). Consequently, since a is at a local extremum for frestricted to {x: h(x)=O} n le(J), it follows that t =0 is at a local extremum for the function f g, and is ball

0

an interior point of the domain of this function. We may apply Theorem

7.6.2 to f

0

g, and

also use the fact that h

0

g

is the zero function, to

348 I HIGHER-DIMENSIONAL DIFFERENTIATION

get the following two equations:

dh

0

g(0) = dh (a)

df

0

g(O)= df(a)

0

dg ( 0)

=

O,

(7.6.7)

dg(O)= 0.

0

Let N be the null space of dh(a) and N1- its orthogonal complement in En. Now, �(dh(a))= �(dh(a) IN1-), and dh(a) IN1- is a one-to-one func­ tion. Hence, since rank dh(a)= m, we must have dim N1-= m, and since dim N + dim N 1n, we must have dim N=n - m. Since rank dg(0) =n - m, it follows from the first equality of (7.6.7) that N �(dg(O)). Since df(a) is a linear functional on E", it follows from Theorem 6.5.7 that 3b EE" so that Vu EEn, =

=

df(a)(u) From the second equality of

df(a)

0

=

u · b.

(7.6.8)

(7.6.7) we get Vu EEn,

dg(O)(u)

=

dg(O)(u)

·

b= 0.

Thus b E N1-. Now, from Theorem 6.5.9 we know that �(dh(a)1) =N1-. Thus 3.A EE"', so that

b= -dh(a)1(A). If we use this in

(7.6.8) we get Vu EE", df(a)(u)= -dh(a)(u) ·A.

Now,

(7.6.9)

Vu EE" and Vv EE"',

dF(a,A)(u,v) = df(a)(u)+ dh(a)(u) ·A+ h(a) where, of course, by

·

dy(v),

(7.6.10)

dy we mean the differential of that function defined (x,y) is y. Since h(a) 0, it follows from

on E" XE'" whose value at

=

(7.6.9) and (7.6.10) that dF(a, A)= df(a)+

m

L

k=l

_Ak dhk(a)

=

0.

n= m, then we cannot use the preceding technique since g does dh (a) has an inverse and thus dh(a)1 has an inverse. So again 3.A EEn so that b=-dh(a)1(A). We can then If

not exist. However, in this case

proceed exactly as before. However, this situation is really trivial, since

h is one to one in a neighborhood of a and thus a is the only point in h(a) 0. Consequently, a is an isolated point of {x: h(x)= O} n .B(J). Of course, J restricted to this set still has a relative maximum and minimum at a. The proof is concluded. If we write (7.6.6) in terms of partial derivatives we get n equations: the neighborhood where

Dk f(a)+

m

L i=l

=

A1Dkhi (a)

=

0,

VkE(l,n).

(7.6.11)

MAXIMA AND MINIMA I 349

7.6

From the fact that

h(a)=0 we get m more equations hi(a)=O,

VjE(l,m).

(7.6.12)

If in the set of equations (7.6.11) and (7.6.12) we replace (a,>.) by (x,y), then these equations can be viewed as a system of m+n equa­ tions in m+ n unknowns, x1, xn and y1, ym. The points that are at the relative extrema of J under the constraint h(x)=0 must be among the solutions of this system of m+ n equations. The auxiliary solutions A.1, ·,Am are called Lagrange multifJliers. Unless the functions f and h are relatively simple, the method of •





·

,

·



·

,



Lagrange multipliers is difficult to apply. However, we shall now give an example which shows that it can lead to nice results. We shall obtain the so-called

geometric-arithmetic means inequality. Other examples of

its uses are given in the exercises at the end of the chapter. We shall prove the following statement: IJVk

E (l,n), ak;;,: 0, th en

( J1n ak )l/n �:;;1 � ak. n

(7.6.13)

To prove this, we shall find the maximum of the function

f(x)

=

under the constraint

(il x1 )2.

xi

>

0,

Vj E (1, n) ,

n h(x)= L (xi)2 -1=0. J=l

By use of the method of Lagrange multipliers, the local extrema are contained among the solutions to the

n+ 1 equations

kE(l,n), n

(7.6.14)

L (xi)2=1. i=l

S�ppose

(b,A.) is a solution of the above system. If we multiply the kth (7.6.14) by b k we get

equation in

(7.6.15) If we sum up over k and use the last equation of

(7.6.14)

we get

nf(b)+A.=0. Putting this value of

A. into (7.6.15) we get, Vk E (l,n), (bk)2= l/n,

(7.6.16)

350 I HIGHER-DIMENSIONAL DIFFERENTIATION

and thus

A= -n•-n.

(7.6.16')

It is not difficult to check that the numbers given by (7.6.16) and (7.6.16') constitute a solution of the system (7.6.14) and thus this sys­

f is defined. To see f, let us extend J, in the obvious way, to a continuous function F defined on the set D {x: x E E" & Vj E (l, n), xi ;;;.: O}. If Sis the unit sphere in En, then since F is continuous, FI (D n S) must take on a maximum and minimum. Clearly, t_he minimum is taken on when 3j E (l, n) so that xi= 0, and the minimum is 0. Thus the maximum of FI (D n S) is taken on when Vj E (l, n), xi> 0, and by Theorem 7.6.5 the point where the tem has a unique solution in the domain where

whether this solution leads to an extremum for

=

maximum is taken on must satisfy the system (7 .6.14). If we specify that Vj E

(l, n), xi> 0,

this system has a unique solution. Hence it

follows that the maximum is taken on at the point whose components are given by (7.6.16).

k



C R+,yk= (a )112,y= ( y1,· · -,yn) ,xk=yk/lyl, k x�) . Then !xi = l and by what we have proved pre­

(l,n)}

Let {a : k E

and x = (x1,



·

,

viously we have

But

The last inequality is precisely (7.6.13). In case 3j E

(l, n)

so that

a;=0, the inequality (7.6.13) is obviously true. O Exercises I.

Suppose A is a compact set in

E"

with a nonvoid interior A0,

and f is a real, continuous function with domain A which has a differen­ tial at every point of A0• If Vx E {3A =A\A0, f(x) so that df(a) =

2.

0.

Let f be a real-valued function defined on

f(x,y) = ax2 If

a

-,!:. 0

and b2 - 4ac =

0,

Let

+

bxy

+

J has = (O, 0).

show that

or a relative minimum at (x,y)

3.

=

0,

show 3 a E A0

This generalizes Rolle's theorem.

E2

by the equation

cy2• either a relative maximum

f be that real-valued function defined on E2 by the f(x,y)

=

1 x2 + xy + 2 y3. 1

equation

7.6

MAXIMA AND MINIMA\ 351

Find all the relative maxima and minima for f restricted to the triangle and its interior which has vertices at the points

( -1, 6) .

(-1, 2 ) , (-2, 4), f restricted to

What is the maximum and minimum of

and this

triangle and its interior? 4.

Let

f be

that real-valued function defined by the equation

1

1

J(x,y) =2+2+2xy, x y

x=F-0, y=F-0.

Find all the critical points of the function and decide whether they are at a relative minima, a relative maxima, or at a saddle point. 5.

Let P be that plane in £3 whose equation is

3x+ y- 2z = 5.

(12, 1, 5)

Find that point on P whose distance from the point

is a mini­

mum.

6.

Find the shortest distance from the point

surface in £3 whose equation is

7.

Let

f

xy - z=0.

{3, 3,-1) to the

be a real-valued function with domain £2 given by the

equation

f(x,y) = ax2 + bxy2+cy4. b2 - 4ac > 0, then f does not have a relative extremum at a2 + {32 ¥- 0, and t E R, the function defined by g,,13 (t) =f(at,f3 t) has a relative minimum at t=0 if a > 0 and a relative maximum at t= 0 if a< 0. Show that if

0.

However, if

8. & Vj

f is that real-valued function (1, n), xi> O}, and defined by

Suppose E

with

.B{f) = {x: x

E En

1 n n i=t

f(x) =- L xi. Use the method of Lagrange multipliers to find the minimum of this function under the constraint n

h(x) =TI xi - 1=0. i=l

Deduce the geometric-arithmetic means inequality 9.

(a)

(7.6.13).

For fixed positive p and q, let f be that function defined on

the open first quadrant of £2 by the equation

Show that the minimum off under the' constraint

352 I HIGHER-DIMENSIONAL DIFFERENTIATION

h(x,y)=xy-1=0 is

(l/p) + (l/q). (b)

b� 0,

Use the result of part (a) to show that if

(l/p) + (l/q)

1 , and

=

a�

0 and

p

> 1 and

q

> 1,

then

b a2 b2•

This is a generalization of the result that 2a

b]

10.

[a,



+

Suppose f and g are nonnegative continuous functions on and

h

is nondecreasing on the same interval. Use Exercise 9(b)

p

to show that if

> 1andq>1, and

(l/p) + (l/q)

1 , then

b (x)q dh(x) ]l/q . afb f(x)g(x) dh(x) [ fab f(x)P dh(x) ]l/p [ fag =



This is known as Halder's If p

=

1 and

=

q

oo,

inequality.

define

[ abg(x)q dh(x) ]l/Q f

=sup g.

Show that Holder's inequality is true in this case also.

11. and

= 1,

and

� ak 12.

p� 1 k� 0 bk� 0, [� ak rp [� b kqrq.

Use the results of Exercise

(l/p) + (l/q)

Vk

h �

E

10

to show that if

(l,n), a

for 1 � p
A,�

IRf(A,{xd)-Rf(A',{xD)I


n2 so that

(8.1.2) Since n' >n2, it follows that Vn >n2 we get

IS(n) -S(n') I < E/2.

(8.1.3)

From the inequalities (8.1.2) and (8.1.3) we get that n >n2 ==}

0 � ip( n2) -S(n) < E .

(8.1.4)

From condition (c) 3N E n1 and N >n2• Hence if n >N we get from (8.1.1) and (8.1.4) and the monotone character of 7P that

0 � (,O(n) -s < E, 0 � �(n) -S(n) < E. From these two inequalities it is immediately clear that n >N ==}

IS(n)-sl < E . Let us see how we can apply this concept to the various definitions of limit that we have given. In case is taken as the relation �- Suppose f is a real-valued function with rB(J) C En and a is an accumulation point of rB(J). If x, y E rB(J) \{a} set x >yIx -al � IY-al. It is easily checked

·

358 J HIGHER-DIMENSIONAL INTEGRATION

�(J) \{a} �(J) \{a} a a. (A*, {xk*}) >- (A, {xd) A*

that is a directed set under this relation. The function J restricted to the directed set is a net and the function f has the limit l at the net f has the limit l at In the case of the function Rf we take ,;Vas the domain of Rf and define is a refinement Note that with this definition our discussion of Cauchy nets provides a general proof for Theorems 5.1.7 and 8.1.6. For the functions Df and[]! we can take ,;V as the set of all decompositions of the given interval I and take as a refinement of Then Df becomes a monotone non­ increasing net and !2.f a monotone nondecreasing net. The numbers are the limits of these nets, respectively. and Of course, everything we have said for real nets will work as well for vector-valued nets with ranges in E", n � 1.

A* >-A A* D(J) Q(J)

A.

A.

D Exercises I. Suppose that f and g are real-valued bounded functions each having as domain the closed interval I C E". Show that

I [f(x) +g(x)] dx,,,:; If(x) dx+ Ig(x) dx, Lf(x) dx+ J g(x) dx,,,:; L [J(x) + g(x)] dx, 2. Suppose f and g are bounded real-valued functions having as common domain the closed interval I C E". If show that

If(x) dx,,,:; Lg(x) dx, Lf(x) dx,,,:; Lg(x) dx.

f,,,:; g

3. Suppose f is a bounded integrable function with domain the closed ·interval I C E" and J is a closed subinterval of /. Is it always true that

4. Suppose that I and j are closed intervals in E" so that I U J is an interval and I n j is at most an (n !)-dimensional interval. If J is a real bounded function with domain I U J, show that -

T 1x(g(A))


0 so that Vx ,y E c®(J) with lx-yl < S, we have IJ(x)-f(y)I < E. Proof. Suppose x E c®(J). By the definition of Lim and Lim, 3B(x ,S(x)) so that Vy E B(x,S (x)) n c®(J) we have

Lim J(t) - E/4 �x


0 the compact set f!(f, e) = {x: w(f, x) � e} has zero Jordan content. Proof.

and V'Y/>

Suppose f has a Riemann-Darboux integral. Then Ve> 0, there exists a decomposition a of I so that

0

o � Dr(a) -!21(a) � L [M(}) -m(])J Ill< ET/. JEA

Let a' = {]: } Ea & } n f!(f, e) oF- 0}; if} Ea', it follows that M(}) - m ( } ) � e. Also, since f!(f, E) c u {]: J Ea'} it follows from Theorem 8.2.4 that ,

x( n (f, e) ) � x ( u {]: J E a' } ) � L I J I . JEil.'

Consequently,

ex(f!(f, e) ) � L [M(})

-

m(]) ] 11 I < ET/.

JEA'

Hence VT/ >

0

we have

x(f!(f, e) )


0 , !f!(f, e)! there is a decomposition a of I so that

jjX[!(f, 0 so that Vx , y EK with lx-yl< 8 we have IJ(x) - J(y) I < 2E. Let al be a refinement of a so that I al I < 8. Let a1* be the set of all }1 in a1 so that 3] E a* with }1 C}. If L Ea*1, then

368 I HIGHER-DIMENSIONAL INTEGRATION

clearly

IJI,

M(L)

-

m(L)

:s;;

2e.

Consequently, if

M

is an upper bound for

we have 0 :s;;

i5,(Li1) - Q,(6.1)

L

=

[M(]) - m(]) ] IJ I

JE!J.1*

+

[M(])

L

-

m(]) ] Ill

JE!J.1/!J.1*

:s;;

2e II I+2MDxn 0, 3p > 0 so that Vx E B(a, p) n I will be needed later on. Since

set/, it is enough to show that

we have Lim t-a

f(t) - T}/2


0 so that

J\!l(f, e)

Vx

E

B(a, p)

n

I,

is relatively open in/.

Suppose A is a bounded set in En. Then XA of A is continuous except at the points of every x E {3A, w(xA, x) =I and thus Ve so that 0 < E :s;; 1, = {3A . Embed A into an interval I and the last theorem tells

Proof of Theorem 8.2.5. the characteristic function

{3A. For n (XA' E) us that

if and only if

L

XA (x) dx =

J!l(xA, e) I = lf3A I

I

XA (x) dx

= 0. An immediate corollary of Theorems

8.3.2 and 8.2.5

is the following.

8.3.3 Corollary. Suppose A is aJordan-measurable set and f is a bounded continuous real-valued function with J:>(J) =A. Then f has a Riemann­ Darboux integral.

8.3

Proof.

{3A.

EXISTENCE AND PROPERTIES OF RIEMANN-DARBOUX INTEGRALS I 369

A into I; then fA is continuous except possibly on 0, O(JA, e) C {3A, so that applying Theorem 8.2.4 8.2.5 we get IO(JA, e) I 0. The proof is completed by

Embed

Thus V e >

and Theorem

=

an application of Theorem 8.3.2. To put the result of Theorem 8.3.2 into a more usable form, it is necessary to introduce the concept of an outer Lebesgue measure. The outer Lebesgue measure can be defined in a manner analogous to formula (8.2.6). The basic difference is that in defining outer Lebesgue measure we allow a countable number of intervals in the covering, rather than only a finite number, as in the case of outer Jordan content. Although this does not seem to be much of a difference, actually it turns out to be quite profound, and ultimately leads to a theory of integration that is much more flexible and useful than the theory of Riemann-Darboux integration.

8.3.4

Definition.

as

If A

1(A)

C En,

=

g.Lb.

the outer Lebesgue measure of A is defined

{ � 111:

0 and

Vk

E

N0,

so that

L III .;;;1(4>(k)) +E/2k. Now,

'U

U {'Uk: k E N0} is an open covering for Band hence

=

1(B).;;;

� (� III ) .;;; �1((k)) +E





Since this is true,

VE>

0 we have proved (a). Part (b) is an immediate

consequence of the fact that every covering for B is a covering for

A.

The last proposition says, in particular, that the union of a countable number of sets of zero Lebesgue measure is again a set of zero Lebesgue measure. The reader should not come to the conclusion that sets of zero Lebesgue measure consist only of a countable number of points. Indeed, Cantor's set has zero Lebesgue measure and we have asked the reader to verify this in Exercise IO at the end of this section. We now give a connection between outer Lebesgue measure and outer Jordan content.

Proposition.

8.3.6

IfA is a bounded set in E", then 1(A).;;; x(A),

(8.3.6)

and equality maintains if A is compact. Proof.

E> {Ik: k

For every

of closed intervals

0, there is a covering of A by a finite number E

(1, m)}

so that

k=I Clearly,

Vk

E

( 1, m) _

there exists an open interval J k so that Ik C J k and m

>...;;; :L lhl k=I


0, 3 8 with 0 < 8 < 8' so that Vx, y E K with Ix - YI < 8 we have -71 < lfn(Y)l- IJg(x)I
0 there

is any n-dimensional interval in K with that

m

L lhl :s; III. k=I

and Let

a k be

the center of

I k.

Then using

(8.5. 7)

it follows is a finite

we get

Jg(I)J 0, 38> 0 so that x,y EBand Jx -yJ < 8 =>

Proof.

and AC

Jg(x)-g(y)-dg(x)(x-y)J

:s;

E

Jx-yJ.

{h: k E (l,m)} be a covering for Aby cubes so E (1,m)} C B, the center of h is in A, d(Ik) < 8 and

Let

(8.5.9) that

U {I k: k

m

L II kl :s; 2nx(B). k=I The factor

2"

I k in A. (8.5.9) we get

is needed to make sure we can get the center of

Let] be any one of these cubes and a its center. Then from

Jg(x) -g(a)-dg(a)(x-a) I :s; elVn, where 2l is the side length of]. Since

j11(a)

=

(8.5.9')

0, the rank of dg(a) is r 1/4}. 4.

{(x,y) : (x - 1) 2 l}, {(x,y): (x-1/2)2+y2 > 1/4},

to the four regions


k=l

8 .5

THE TRANSFORMATION THEOREM FOR INTEGRALS I 395

is a one-to-one function, and the Hessian off

Hr(x) = det[D; Dkf(x)] 0

¥-

0,

Vx

E

JE>(f).

Let A be a bounded Jordan-measurable set with A C JE>(f). Show that

IL H�x) I = l(Vf)-1 (A)I. 5.

Show that

J:., e-x• dx = y/;. Do this as follows: First note that

Change to polar coordinates and use the transformation theorem on the integral on the right. Do all this carefully, justifying each step. 6. Compute the volume of the unit ball B (0, I) in En by changing to spherical coordinates (see Section 6.5 and Exercise 8 of Section 8.4). [Hint: Use induction to show that the Jacobian of the spherical coordi­ nate transformation in En is

pn-l (sin (J1 )n-2 ( sin (J2)n-3 .. . (sin on-2).] 7. Suppose g is a function of class C1 with an open domain in E2 so that Vx E JE>(g),J0(x) ¥- 0. Give an example which shows that the transformation theorem may not necessarily be valid for this type of g. 8. Suppose his a linear transformation with domain E" and range in En. If A CE" is Jordan measurable show that h(A)is Jordan measur­ able. [Hint: If h is singular, then dim t1a. and Vtk

9.2

= where

l7Jkl


ak+1 [.

w

=

df 'Y

Let

be a decomposition of the domain of

so

Using Theorems 5.2.1 (d) and 5.2.2 we get

J

w=

'Y

J

df=

'Y

=

Since

w

y

over

is closed,

y

is zero.

m

.L

fak+l dj

y(t) dt dt

o

k=l ak m L [J y(ak+i) - f y(ak)] k=l 0

y(a1)= y(am+1),

0

and it follows that the integral of

To prove the converse we may assume, without loss of generality, that

.B(w)

is arcwise connected. Otherwise we can work with each open

component of

.B(w).

x0

Fix a point

E

.B(w) and Vx .B(w) with x0

be a piecewise smooth oriented curve in and

x

the final point of

yx·

.B(w)

let

'Yx

Let us set

This defines a function of independent of the choice

E

the initial point

yx· We claim of 'Yx· Indeed,

that for fixed

x0

and

x

it is

ax is another piece­ x0 to x. If yx has that its domain is [b, c].

suppose

wise smooth oriented curve which proceeds from domain

[a, b]

suppose

Define

{3(t)=

ax

is parameterized so

{ 'Yx(l),

Vt Vt

ax(b + c - t) ,

[a, b], [b. c].

E E

Then f3 defines a piecewise smooth closed oriented curve

m

.B(w).

Hence

Thus for fixed

x0

we may set

f(x)= F(yx) , and this defines a real-valued function on

w= df u E En

We shall show that

.B(w). Now, let B(x, 8). Let us set C

'Yx+hu(t) -

Since and

h

.B(w)

E R so that

{ 'Yx{t)' -b)u, x+h(t

.B(w).

is open

Vt Vt

E E

38 > 0 so that B(x, 8) hot=- 0 and x+hu E

[a, b], [b, b + I).

418 I THE INTEGRATION OF DIFFERENTIAL FORMS

Hence we get

{f w- w } J b+t n d k (t) f "' Wk (t) dt =dt h

J(x+hu)-f(x) ! = h h

'Yx

'Yx+hu

I

'Y

'Y x+hu

x+hu

,,,c., b k=I (b+I n wk(x +h(t-b)u)uk dt. =J b o



Ash� 0 we get

n Duf(x)= L wdx)uk = w(x)(u). k=I Vu E En the right side is a continuous function of x, it follows that df(x) exists, and hence w(x)=df(x). 1 In case w is of class C it is possible to give conditions on the partials of wk so that w is "locally exact." For the moment we shall restrict our­ 2 selves to the case where �(w) is an open set in E • Later on we shall n consider the case where �(w) C E . Let B be an open ball in �(w)

Since

and] an interval inB. From Stokes' theorem we get

If Now, if

V(x,y)

[D1w2-D2w1] dxdy =

iJ

w.

EB,

D1w2(x,y)=D2w1(x,y) , w

then we get that the line integral of

along every oriented rectangle

in Bis zero . Now, if

(a,b) is

the center ofBand

(x,y)

EB, set

r W1(t,b) dt+I: Wz(X, t) dt , f2(x,y)= J: w2(a, t) dt+ J: w1(t,y) dt.

f1(X, y) =

The number f1 (x,y) is the line integral of

w

along the curve consisting

of the horizontal straight line proceeding from the vertical straight line from

(x,b)

to

(x,y).

the line integral consisting of the vertical line to to

(a,y) (x,y).

and then the horizontal straight line Since the line integral of

inBis zero, it follows that

V(x,y)

w

(a,b) to (x,b) and then The number /2(x,y) is proceeding from (a,b) proceeding from (a,y)

around every oriented rectangle

EB,f1(x,y) = f2(x,y). Now, a simple

calculation shows that

Dz/1(x,y)=w2(x,y),

Dif2(x,y)=w1(x,y).

9.4 CLOSED AND EXACT DIFFERENTIALS I 419

Since w1 and

w2 are continuous,

if we setf

=

f1

=

f2, then from Theorem df(x, y). Thus

7.2.5 it follows that df(x, y) exists and of course w(x, y)

wlB

=

is exact.

The discussion of the last paragraph prompts us to make the following definition.

9.4.3 Definition. A differential form w with domain an open set in En 1 is said to be closed� w is of class C and Vj, k E (I, n) and Vx E E(w),

DJwk(x)

=

Dkwi(x).

A little later on we shall present a definition of a closed differential

form in a much more compact and more easily remembered notation. For now, let us remark that we have proved above that every closed differential form with domain in E2 is "locally exact" in the sense that the restriction of the closed form to any ball in its domain is exact. However, it is not necessarily true that a closed form is "globally exact." For example, the form

x

- ......:::.1_ w(x, y) 2 + 2 dx x y

is defined on

2 £ \{0}

+ z--- 2 +y x

and is closed. However,

dy

w

is not an exact form.

Indeed, if J is any interval in E2 containing the origin in its interior, then (see Exercise 7 of Section 9.3)

l

w#-0.

aJ

It follows from Theorem 9.4.2 that

w

is not exact, even though it is

locally exact. From the previous example it would seem that for a closed form to be exact, there would need to be additional conditions on its domain. This is actually the case, and for the purpose of obtaining these addi­ tional conditions we introduce the following definition. To make the notation easier we shall suppose, for the remainder of this section, that we shall only work with representatives from a given curve that have domain

[O, l].

9.4.4 Definition. Two closed, piecewise smooth, oriented curves 'Yo and y 1 in a set E C En are said to be homotopic in E� there exists a continuous function r with domain [O, l] X [O, l] that is piecewise smooth in each variable, has range in E, VT E [O, l], f(T, O] f(T, 1), and Vt E [O, l], , t t y y O, t and f( 0(t), 1( ). f( ) l ) A piecewise smooth oriented curve y in E is said to be homotopic to zero in E� y is homotopic in E to a constant curve; that is, a curve 'Yo so that Vt E [O, l], y0(t) y0(0). =

=

=

=

420 I THE INT.EGRATION OF DIFFERENTIAL FORMS

It is not difficult to establish the fact that the homotopy relation is an equivalence relation, so that the piecewise smooth oriented curves in a given region break up into pairwise disjoint homotopy classes. It is also not difficult to show (Exercise 7 of Section 9.4) that the homotopy relation, 9.4.4, is independent of the piecewise smo9th representatives we pick from each curve. If every closed, piecewise smooth oriented curve in an arcwise con­ nected region is homotopic to zero, then we say that the region is simply

connected. From the point of view of the homotopy relation, the last statement says that a region is simply connected if all the closed, oriented, piecewise smooth curves belong to the same homotopy class.

9.4.5 Definition. An open set /€) C E" is said to be simply connected /€) is connected and every piecewise smooth, closed oriented curve in /€) is homotopic to zero. Roughly speaking, a simply connected set in

E2 is one that has no

holes in it. Of course in higher dimensions we no longer have such a simple interpretation. An example of an arcwise connected set in

E3

that is not simply connected is an anchor ring. For the purpose of giving an example, let us note that if an open set in

E" can be contracted to a point by means of straight lines, then the

set is simply connected. To be more precise, let us say that the set

S C En is star-shaped with respect to the point a E S Vx E S, the straight line L= {y: y ( 1 - t)a + tx & t E [O, l]} belongs to S. Of course, =

every convex set is star-shaped with respect to every point in the set. Suppose S is open and is star-shaped with respect to

a E S. If y is

a piecewise smooth, oriented closed curve in S, set

f ( T, t) = (1 - T) a + TY (t) , Clearly, variable,

VT E [O, l].

f has range in S, is continuous, is piecewise smooth in each f( T, O) = f(T, l) , f(O , t ) = a , and f(l,t)=y(t). Thus y is

homotopic to zero.

We want ultimately to prove that every closed first-order differential form defined on a simply connected domain is exact. First, we shall prove that every closed form on an open domain is locally exact. We have proved this previously for closed forms having domains in

E2,

making use of the Stokes-Green-Gauss theorem. Although we could still make use of this theorem in higher dimensions, it is much simpler to proceed by a more direct method. Of course, since we know what we are looking for, it is easy to discover a direct method of proof.

9.4.6 Theorem. Every closed first-order differential form with domain an open set in E" is locally exact; that is, its restriction to every open ball in its domain is exact.

9.4

Proof.

Let

w be

a first-order closed differential form with domain an

open set in En and suppose

B(a, r)

x

[O,I]

CLOSED AND EXACT DIFFERENTIALS I 421

C

B(a, r)

.e9(w).

Define the functions on

by

s(x,t) Clearly, for fixed

x,

=

( I - t)a + tx.

the range of

s

is the straight line joining

x

and

a.

Let us set

If we apply the operator

Di to

both sides we may use Theorem

8.4.3

to move this operator from the outside to the inside of the integral. Now,

[

Di wk

o

s(x,t)

ask(x,t) ask(x,t) = [Di wk0s(x,t)] at at ask(x, t) . +Wk0s(x,t) Dj at

J

Further, using the chain rule, and noting the form of

s,

we get

Diwk0s(x,t) = tDiwk(s(x,t)). Also,

· ask (x,t) D) at Now use the fact that

w

=

- = 8)k

l

l 0

j

j ¥= k.

=

k,

is closed so that

Thus we have

- t aw;0s(x,t) + Wj at

(

o S X,

t).

Consequently,

(1 aw-0 ) s(x , t) dt+ (1 Wj0s(x,t) dt. DJ(x) =Jot Jo at If we integrate the first integral hy parts we get

DJ(x) = w;(x). Since

w

equal to

is continuous, it follows that

w(x).

df(x)

exists and, of course, is

422 I THE INTEGRATION OF DIFFERENTIAL FORMS

The theorem we have just proved is one of the crucial steps in showing that every closed first-order differential form in a simply connected region is exact. A second cruc�al step is the following lemma. For the

a curve a is in a 8-neighborhood of the curve 1' if there are representatives of each curve so that

purposes of this lemma we shall say

sup{ja(t) - y(t) I: t Suppose w domain an open set in En. For .,®(w) , 3 8 > 0 so that for every with a ( 0) = 1'(0) , a (I) =1' (I) 9.4. 7

Lemma.

Proof.

Let

compact and and

Vx

E

28

is a closed first-order differential form with every piecewise smooth, oriented curve 1' in piecewise smooth, oriented curve a in .,®(w) and a in a 8-neighborhood of 1' we have

B(y(T), 28)

y, by

to >

.,®(w)c. Since 5C,(y) is 0. For every T E [O, I]

set

f

w

+

'Y,.

(0, T]

5C,(y)

be the distance from

.,®(w)c is closed, it follows that 8 J,(x) =

where

[O, I]} < 8.

E

f,

w,

s-r.x

is that oriented curve which has a representative defined on

y ,(t) = y(t ) ,

and

s,,x(t) =(I - t)y(T) + tx, t E (0, I]. As the Vx E B(y(T), 28), df,(x) = w(x).

proof the last theorem shows, Next,

Vx

E

B(a(T), 8)

let us set

g,(x) =

J

w+

a,

where

a,

w,

TT,X

y,, and, of course, r, ,x(t ) B(a(T), 8), dg,(x) = w(x). that Vx E B(a(T),8)

is defined in a manner similar to

=(I - t)a(T) + Since

J

B(a(T), 8)

Vx

tx. We also get that C

B(y(T), 28)

it follows

E

d[f,(x) - g,(x)] =0 , from which it follows that there is a number

Vx

E

c(T)

so that

B(a(r) ;8),

f,(x) - g,(x) =c(T). We think it is clear that

c

is a continuous function of

T.

Let us put

To= sup{T: c(T) =O}. The set on the right is nonvoid since is well defined and we claim

To< I.

Take

To< T1 �I

so

To= I. that t

0

certainly belongs to it. Thus

To

For suppose to the contrary that E

[T0,T1] =}y(t)

E

B(y(T0),28)

CLOSED AND EXACT DIFFERENTIALS I 423

9.4

a(t) E B(a(To), 6) . It is possible to do this because of the continuity y and a. Now, Vx E B(y(T0), 26) let us define

and of

Vt Vt Vt The function

f3x

oriented curve in

E E E

[T0, T i], [Ti.Ti+ l]' [T1 + l, Ti+ 2].

is the representative of a piecewise smooth, closed,

B(y(T0), 26)

(Fig. 9.4.1). From Theorems 9.4.6 and

FIGURE 9.4.1

9.4.2 it follows that

{ w= J f3x This shows that

Vx

J

w-

'Yn

E

J

w+

'YTO

f

w-

8n,x

f

8To,x

w=O.

B(y(T0), 26) , J,0(x) =f,,(x).

In exactly the same way we get that

Vx

E

B{a(T0), 6)

g,0 (x) =g,,(x). Thus

Vx

E

B(a(r0), 8)

we get

c(Ti) =f,,(x) - g"(x)

=

f,0(x) - g,0(x)

=

c(T0) = 0,

which, of course, is a contradiction. Consequently, since

y( 1) = a ( 1),

we get

fi(y(l)) =g1(a(l)). But this says nothing more than

9.4.8 Theorem. Suppose w is a closed first-order differential form with domain an open set in En. If a and f3 are oriented, piecewise smooth closed

424 I THE INTEGRATION OF DIFFERENTIAL FORMS

curves in .® ( w) , and are homotopic in .® (w) , then

Proof.

We shall divide the proof into two parts.

a(O) = a(l) = {3(0) = /3(1). [O,l] which gives the homotopy between a and /3, and let us suppose that VT E [O,l],f(T,O)= f(T, I)= a(O). Also, suppose that f(O,t) = a(t),f(l,t) = {3(t). Let E be the set of all points a E [O,l] with the property that VT E [O,a] (a)

To begin with, we shall suppose that

[O,l]

Let r be a function on

x

I.

w=

where

f7(t)= f(T,t).

J

w,

a

fT

The set E is a nonvoid set, since

To= sup E Lemma 9.4. 7, 3 e > 0 so

0

EE. Further,

it is clearly bounded. Hence,

is well defined. We claim

To= 1. Indeed, by

that if y is in an

e

neighbor­

hood of rTO> then

I.fTO

w=

J')'

w

3o > 0

Now, since r is uniformly continuous,

Vt

E

so that

lro - Tl < o �

[O, I], lf(T,t)-f(To,t)j
m, it is still true that

flC,(T)

If

=

Em

tell

(9.5.1)

is in an m-dimensional subspace of

E", which is identifiable with E"' through an orthogonal transformation U of E" onto itself. Hence we now

T(A)

define

the m-dimensional content of

by

IT(A)I =IV T(A)I. 0

(9.5.2)

430 I THE INTEGRATION OF DIFFERENTIAL FORMS

The content on the right is computable by (9.5.1). Of course, we must make sure that the definition (9.5.2) is independent of the orthogonal transformation U which takes §Tt(T) into Em. Indeed, suppose V1 is another such orthogonal transformation. Now, if T is singular, the dimension of §Tt( U T) and §Tt(V1 ° T) is less than m and thus 0

IV

0

T(A)I = IV1°T(A)I=0.

If Tis nonsingular, then W = V1 ° v-1IEm is an orthogonal transforma­ tion of Em onto itself. Thus IV

0

T(A)I = ldet V Tl IAI = ldet W V Tl A I I = ldet V1 ° Tl IAI = IV1°T(A)I. 0

0

0

Let us now give an effective way of computing the right side of (9.5.2) so that the operator V does not intervene. Let us first note that T1 T is a nonnegative symmetric linear transformation from E"' into itself, that is, Vu E Em, T1 T(u)· u;:,, 0. Thus this linear transformation has a matrix representation consisting of nonnegative eigenvalues down the main diagonal (see Section 6.5). Suppose we arrange them in nondecreasing order d