221 83 134MB
English Pages [740] Year 1952
')'
WSmiw lllli will
111
W6m
will fl$>-^^^^$'^)^(c related in the same way, and A follows C but the relation cannot be reversed, then
mal
either
B and the relation cannot be reAnd A and D may belong to the same but B and C cannot. First it is clear
must follow versed.
thing,
is
D
D
D D necessarily
from the following consideration that
[5]
C
follows B. For since either
or
belongs to everything; and since C cannot belong to that to which B belongs, because it carries A along with it and A and B cannot belong to the same thing; it is clear that must follow B. Again since C does not reciprocate with A, but C or belongs to everything, should belong [10] it is possible that A and to the same thing. But B and C cannot belong
D
D
D
same
to the
thing, because
that
B does not
it is
possible that
same time
A
follows C; and so
results. It
reciprocate with
is
clear then
D either, since
D and A should belong at the
same thing. sometimes even in such an arrange[75] ment of terms that one is deceived through not apprehending the opposites rightly, one of which must belong to everything, e.g. we may reason that 'if A and B cannot belong at the same time to the same thing, but it is necessary that one of them should belong to whatever the other does not belong to: and again C and are related in the same way, It
In many things also, to some of which something belongs which does not belong to others, the negation may be true in a similar way, viz. [20] that all are not white or that each is not white, while that each is not-white or all are not-white is false. Similarly also 'every animal
mal
71
something impossible
[75] Privative terms are similarly related to positive terms in respect of this arrangement.
Let
45-46
to the
results
D
and
A
follows everything which
C
follows:
it
B
belongs necessarily to everything to which belongs': but this is false. [20] 'Assume that F stands for the negation will result that
D
H
A and B, and again that stands for the negation of C and D. It is necessary then that either A or F should belong to everything: for of
either the affirmation or the denial
must
be-
H
And
must belong to again either C or everything: for they are related as affirmation and denial. And ex hypothesi A belongs to everything to which C belongs. Therefore [25] belongs to everything to which F belongs. Again since either F or B belongs to long.
H
since
know
H
follows F,
this.
1
If
D'. But this
quence
is
then
is
H
or D, and follow D: for we follows C, B must follow
everything, and similarly either
B must
A
false: for as
we proved 2
the se-
reversed in terms so constituted.
The
perhaps it is not neces[50] sary that A or F should belong to everything, or that F or B should belong to everything: for F is not the denial of A. For notgood is the negation of good: and not-good is not identical with 'neither good nor not-good'. Similarly also with C and D. For two negations have been assumed in respect to one term. fallacy arises because
1
From
ft
39-b 13.
a
39
J 3*
PRIOR ANALYTICS
72
BOOK
53 b
II
B 52b
We have already explained
the figures, the character
[40] premisses,
number of and number of the
when and how
the
a syllogism
is
formed; further what we must look for when 53a refuting and establishing propositions, and how we should investigate a given problem in any branch of inquiry, also by what
belongs to no C, it has been assumed without proof that B does not belong to A, consequently it does not result through the syllogism
means we
shall obtain principles appropriate to
each subject. 2 Since some syllogisms are univer[5]
sal,
others particular,
all
the universal syl-
logisms give more than one result, and of particular syllogisms the affirmative yield more than one, the negative yield only the stated conclusion. For all propositions are convertible save only the particular negative: and the conclusion states one definite thing about another definite thing. Consequently all syllogisms save the particular negative yield
more than
one conclusion, e.g. if A has been proved to be[10] long to all or to some B, then B must belong to some A: and if A has been proved to belong to no B, then B belongs to no A. This is a different conclusion from the former. But if A does not belong to some B, it is not necessary that B should not belong to some A: for it may possibly belong to all A. [75] This then is the reason common to all syllogisms whether universal or particular. But it is possible to give another reason concerning those which are universal. For all the things that are subordinate to the middle term or to the conclusion may be proved by the same syllogism, if the former are placed in the middle, the latter in the conclusion; e.g.
[20] sion
AB
is
subordinate to
D
if
the conclu-
proved through C, whatever
B
or
C must
is
accept the predi-
included in B as in a whole, and B is included in A, then will be included in A. Again if E is included in C as in a whole, and C is included in A, then E will be included in A. Similarly if the syllogism is negative. In the second figure it will be possible [25] to infer only that which is subordinate to the conclusion, e.g. if A belongs to no B and to all C; we conclude that B belongs to no C. If then is subordinate to C, clearly B does not belong to it. But that B does not belong to what is subordinate to A, is not clear by means [30] of the syllogism. And yet B does not belong to E, if E is subordinate to A. But while it has been proved through the syllogism that
cate
A:
for
if
is
D
D
1.
1-26.
27-31.
B
that
But
1
does not belong to E. in particular syllogisms there will be
no
[35] necessity of inferring what is subordinate to the conclusion (for a syllogism does not re-
when
this premiss is particular), but whatsubordinate to the middle term may be inferred, not however through the syllogism, e.g. if A belongs to all B and B to some C. Nothing can be inferred about that which is subordinate to C; something can be inferred about that which is subordinate to B, but not sult
ever
is
[40] through the preceding syllogism. Simother figures. That which is subordinate to the conclusion cannot be proved; ilarly in the
53b the other subordinate can be proved, only not through the syllogism, just as in the universal syllogisms what is subordinate to the midis proved (as we saw) from a premiss not demonstrated: consequently either a conclusion is not possible in the case of uni-
dle term
which
is
versal syllogisms or else
it
is
possible also in
the case of particular syllogisms.
possible for the premisses of the syllogism
It is
[5] to be true, or to be false, or to be the one true, the other false. The conclusion is either
From true premisses it not possible to draw a false conclusion, but a true conclusion may be drawn from false premtrue or false necessarily. is
true
however only
in respect to the fact, reason cannot be established from false premisses: why this is so will isses,
not to the reason.
The
3 [10] be explained in the sequel. First then that it is not possible to
conclusion from true premisses,
false
draw is
a
made
by this consideration. If it is necessary should be when A is, it is necessary that A should not be when B is not. If then A is true, B must be true: otherwise it will turn out [15] that the same thing both is and is not at the same time. But this is impossible. Let it clear
B
that
not, because
A
is
laid
be supposed that
it is
fact
down
as a single term,
possible,
when
a single
given, that something should necessarily
is
not possible. For what rethe conclusion, and the means by which this comes about are at the least three terms, and two relations of subject result.
8
57
For that
necessarily
sults
a
4°- b *7-
is
is
BOOK
54b
[20] and predicate or premisses.
II,
If .then
it
CHAPTERS is
A
belongs to all that to which B beB belongs to all that to which C belongs, it is necessary that A should belong to all that to which C belongs, and this cannot be false: for then the same thing will belong true that
longs,
and that
and not belong at the same time. So A is posited as one thing, being two premisses taken together. The same holds good of negative [25] syllogisms:
it
is
not possible to prove a
from true premisses. But from what is false a true conclusion may be drawn, whether both the premisses are false
false conclusion
or only one, provided that this the premisses indifferently, if wholly false: but if the premiss
is it
is
not either of is taken as not taken as
does not matter which of the [jo] two is false. (1) Let A belong to the whole of C, but to none of the 5s, neither let B belong to C. This is possible, e.g. animal belongs to no stone, nor stone to any man. If
wholly
false, it
taken to belong to all B and B to all belong to all C; consequently though both the premisses are false the conclusion is [35] true: for every man is an animal. Simthen C,
A
A
is
will
with the negative. For it is possible that A nor B should belong to any C, although A belongs to all B, e.g. if the same terms are taken and man is put as middle: for neither animal nor man belongs to any stone, but animal belongs to every man. Consequently if one term is taken to belong to none ilarly
neither
[40] of that to which it does belong, and the other term is taken to belong to all of that to which it does not belong, though both the premisses are false the conclusion will be true. 54a (2) similar proof may be given if each
A
premiss
is
partially false.
(3) But if one only of the premisses is false, when the first premiss is wholly false, e.g. AB, the conclusion will not be true, but if the premiss BC is wholly false, a true conclusion will be possible. I mean by 'wholly false' the contrary [5] of the truth, e.g. if what belongs to none is assumed to belong to all, or if what belongs to
assumed to belong to none. Let A belong no B, and B to all C. If then the premiss BC which I take is true, and the premiss AB is
all is
to
false, viz. that A belongs to all B, it is impossible that the conclusion should be true: for A belonged to none of the Cs, since A be[10] longed to nothing to which B belonged,
wholly
B belonged to all C. Similarly there cannot be a true conclusion if A belongs to all B, and B to all C, but while the true premiss BC is assumed, the wholly false premiss AB is also
and
1-2
73
A
belongs to nothing to which B belongs: here the conclusion must be [75] false. For A will belong to all C, since A belongs to everything to which B belongs, and B to all C. It is clear then that when the first premiss is wholly false, whether affirmative or negative, and the other premiss is true, the conclusion cannot be true. (4) But if the premiss is not wholly false, a true conclusion is possible. For if A belongs to all C and to some B, and if B belongs to all C, [20] e.g. animal to every swan and to some white thing, and white to every swan, then if we take as premisses that A belongs to all B, and B to all C, A will belong to all C truly: for every swan is an animal. Similarly if the state-
assumed,
AB
ment
viz. that
is
negative. For
it
A
possible that
is
[25] should belong to some B and to no C, and that B should belong to all C, e.g. animal to
some white thing, but
to
no snow, and white
then one should assume that A belongs to no B, and B to all C, then A will belong to no C. (5) But if the premiss AB, which is assumed, is wholly true, and the premiss BC is wholly false, a true syllogism will be possible: [jo] for nothing prevents A belonging to all B and to all C, though B belongs to no C, e.g. these being species of the same genus which are not subordinate one to the other: for animal belongs both to horse and to man, but horse to no man. If then it is assumed that A belongs to all B and B to all C, the conclusion will be [55] true, although the premiss BC is wholly false. Similarly if the premiss AB is negative. For it is possible that A should belong neither to any B nor to any C, and that B should not belong to any C, e.g. a genus to species of another genus: for animal belongs neither to to all
snow.
If
music nor to the art of healing, nor does mubelong to the art of healing. If then it is assumed that A belongs to no B, and B to all
54t> sic
C, the conclusion will be true. (6) And if the premiss BC is not wholly but in part only, even so the conclusion
false
may
be true. For nothing prevents
[5] to the whole of B longs to some C, e.g. a
and
A belonging B
of C, while
genus
to
its
species
difference: for animal belongs to every
and
to every footed thing,
and man
footed things though not to
assumed that C,
A
A
belongs to
will belong to all
all.
all
C: and
If
this
man some
to
then
B, and
be-
and
B
it
is
to all
ex hypothesi
AB
is [10] is true. Similarly if the premiss negative. For it is possible that A should
neither belong to any
B
nor to any C, though
PRIOR ANALYTICS
74
B
belongs to some C,
e.g. a genus to the species and its difference: for animal neither belongs to any wisdom nor to any in-
of another genus
stance of 'speculative', but
some
wisdom belongs
instance of 'speculative'. If then
it
to
should
A belongs to no B, and B belong to no C: and this ex
[75] be assumed that to all C,
hy pot he si
A is
will true.
In particular syllogisms
it
is
possible
when
premiss is wholly false, and the other true, that the conclusion should be true; also when the first premiss is false in part, and the the
first
[20] other true; and when the first is true, and the particular is false; and when both are false.
(7) For nothing prevents A belonging to no B, but to some C, and B to some C, e.g. animal belongs to no snow, but to some white thing, and snow to some white thing. If then snow [25] is taken as middle, and animal as first term, and it is assumed that A belongs to the whole of B, and B to some C, then the premiss AB is wholly false, the premiss BC true, and the conclusion true. Similarly if the premiss AB is negative: for it is possible that A should belong to the whole of B, but not to some C, [jo] although B belongs to some C, e.g. animal belongs to every man, but does not follow some white, but man belongs to some white; consequently if man be taken as middle term and it is assumed that A belongs to no B but B belongs to some C, the conclusion will be true although the premiss AB is wholly false. W tne premiss AB is false in part, the [35] conclusion may be true. For nothing prevents A belonging both to B and to some C, and B belonging to some C, e.g. animal to something
W
and to something great, and beautiful belonging to something great. If then A is assumed to belong to all B, and B to some C, the 55a premiss AB will be partially false, the premiss BC will be true, and the conclusion true. Similarly if the premiss AB is negative. For the same terms will serve, and in the same positions, to prove the point. (9) Again if the premiss AB is true, and the [5] premiss BC is false, the conclusion may be true. For nothing prevents A belonging to the whole of B and to some C, while B belongs to no C, e.g. animal to every swan and to some black things, though swan belongs to no black thing. Consequently if it should be assumed that A belongs to all B, and B to some C, the [10] conclusion will be true, although the statement BC is false. Similarly if the premiss AB is negative. For it is possible that A should belong to no B, and not to some C, while B be-
beautiful
55 b
longs to no C, e.g. a genus to the species of another genus and to the accident of its own [75] species: for animal belongs to no number and not to some white things, and number belongs to nothing white. If then number is taken as middle, and it is assumed that A belongs to no B, and B to some C, then A will not belong to some C, which ex hypothesi is true. And the premiss AB is true, the premiss BC false. ( 10) Also if the premiss AB is partially false, [20] and the premiss BC is false too, the conclusion may be true. For nothing prevents A belonging to some B and to some C, though B belongs to no C, e.g. if B is the contrary of C, and both are accidents of the same genus: for animal belongs to some white things and to some black things, but white belongs to no [25] black thing. If then it is assumed that A belongs to all B, and B to some C, the conclusion will be true. Similarly if the premiss AB is negative: for the same terms arranged in the
same way
will serve for the proof.
(11) Also though both premisses are false the conclusion may be true. For it is possible that A may belong to no B and to some C, [50] while B belongs to no C, e.g. a genus in relation to the species of another genus,
own
and
to
animal belongs to no number, but to some white things, and number to nothing white. If then it is assumed that A belongs to all B and B to some the accident of
its
species: for
[35] C> tne conclusion will be true, though both premisses are false. Similarly also if the premiss AB is negative. For nothing prevents A belonging to the whole of B, and not to some C, while B belongs to no C, e.g. animal belongs to every swan, and not to some black things, and swan belongs to nothing black. [40] Consequently if it is assumed that A be55 b longs to no B, and B to some C, then A does not belong to some C. The conclusion then is true, but the premisses are false.
In the middle figure
it is
possible in every
to reach a true conclusion isses,
through
false
way
prem-
whether the syllogisms are universal or when both premisses are wholly
particular, viz.
[5] false; when each is partially false; when one is true, the other wholly false (it does not matter which of the two premisses is false); if both premisses are partially false; if one is quite true, the other partially false; if one is wholly [70] false, the other partially true. For (1) if A belongs to no B and to all C, e.g. animal to no stone and to every horse, then if the prem-
BOOK
56b isses
II,
CHAPTERS
and it is assumed and to no C, though the
are stated contrariwise
that A belongs to all B premisses are wholly false they will yield a true [75] conclusion. Similarly if A belongs to all
B
and
to
no C:
for
we
shall
have the same
syllogism.
(2) Again if one premiss is wholly false, the other wholly true: for nothing prevents A belonging to all B and to all C, though B belongs to no C, e.g. a genus to its co-ordinate species. For animal belongs to every horse and man, [20] and no man is a horse. If then it is assumed that animal belongs to all of the one, and none of the other, the one premiss will be wholly false, the other wholly true, and the conclusion will be true whichever term the
negative statement concerns. (3) Also if one premiss is partially other wholly true. For
it
is
false,
possible that
the
A
should belong to some B and to all C, though [25] B belongs to no C, e.g. animal to some white things and to every raven, though white belongs to no raven. If then it is assumed that A belongs to no B, but to the whole of C, the premiss AB is partially false, the premiss AC wholly true, and the conclusion true. Similarly [jo] if the negative statement is transposed: the proof can be made by means of the same terms. Also if the affirmative premiss is partially false, the negative wholly true, a true conclusion is possible. For nothing prevents A belonging to some B, but not to C as a whole, while B belongs to no C, e.g. animal belongs to some white things, but to no pitch, and [35] white belongs to no pitch. Consequently if it is assumed that A belongs to the whole of B, but to no C, the premiss AB is partially false, the premiss AC is wholly true, and the conclusion is true. (4) And if both the premisses are partially false, the conclusion may be true. For it is possible that A should belong to some B and to [40] some C, and B to no C, e.g. animal to some white things and to some black things, 56 a though white belongs to nothing black. If then it is assumed that A belongs to all B and to no C, both premisses are partially false, but the conclusion is true. Similarly, if the negative premiss is transposed, the proof can be made by means of the same terms. [5] It is clear also that our thesis holds in particular syllogisms. For (5) nothing prevents A belonging to all B and to some C, though B does not belong to some C, e.g. animal to every man and to some white things, though man will not belong to some white things. If
2-4
75
A
belongs to no B and to [10] some C, the universal premiss is wholly false, the particular premiss is true, and the conclusion is true. Similarly if the premiss AB
then
stated that
it is
affirmative: for it is possible that A should belong to no B, and not to some C, though B does not belong to some C, e.g. animal belongs to nothing lifeless, and does not belong to some [75] white things, and lifeless will not belong to some white things. If then it is stated that A belongs to all B and not to some C, the premiss AB which is universal is wholly false, the premiss AC is true, and the conclusion is true. Also a true conclusion is possible when the universal premiss is true, and the particular is false. For nothing prevents A following neither B [20] nor C at all, while B does not belong to some C, e.g. animal belongs to no number nor to anything lifeless, and number does not follow some lifeless things. If then it is stated that A belongs to no B and to some C, the conclusion will be true, and the universal premiss [25] true, but the particular false. Similarly if the premiss which is stated universally is affirmative. For it is possible that A should belong both to B and to C as wholes, though B does not follow some C, e.g. a genus in relation to its species and difference: for animal follows every man and footed things as a whole, but man does not follow every footed thing. Consequently if it is assumed that A belongs [jo] to the whole of B, but does not belong to some C, the universal premiss is true, the paris
ticular false,
and the conclusion
true.
(6) It is clear too that though both premisses are false they may yield a true conclusion, since
possible that
it is
B and
to
C
A
should belong both
though B does not fol[^5] low some C. For if it is assumed that A belongs to no B and to some C, the premisses to
as wholes,
are both false, but the conclusion larly if the universal
premiss
the particular negative. For
A should
follow no
B and
all
is
true. Simi-
is
affirmative
it
is
and
possible that
C, though
B
does
[40] not belong to some C, e.g. animal follows no science but every man, though science does
not follow every man. If then A is assumed to 56 b belong to the whole of B, and not to follow some C, the premisses are false but the conclusion
In
the
is
last
true.
figure
come through what
a is
true
may when both when each is
conclusion
false, alike
[5] premisses are wholly false, partly false, when one premiss is wholly true,
PRIOR ANALYTICS
7* the other false,
when one
premiss
is
partly
and vice versa, and in every other way in which it is possible to alter the premisses. For (i) nothing prevents [10] neither A nor B from belonging to any C, while A belongs to some B, e.g. neither man nor footed follows anything lifeless, though man belongs to some footed things. If then it is assumed that A and B belong to all C, the false,
the other wholly true,
premisses will be wholly false, but the conclusion true. Similarly if one premiss is negative, the other affirmative. For
it
possible that
is
B
A
to all C, [75] should belong to no C, but should not belong to some B, e.g. and that
A
black belongs to no swan, animal to every swan, and animal not to everything black. Con-
57-
belongs to every swan, black to no swan, and [5] black to some animals. Consequently if it is assumed that A and B belong to every C, the premiss BC is wholly true, the premiss AC is wholly false, and the conclusion is true. Similarly if the premiss AC which is assumed is true: the proof can be made through the same
terms.
(4) Again if one premiss is wholly true, the [10] other partly false, the conclusion may be true. For it is possible that B should belong to C, and A to some C, while A belongs to some B, e.g. biped belongs to every man, beautiful not to every man, and beautiful to some bipeds. If then it is assumed that both A and B belong to the whole of C, the premiss BC is all
AC
if it is
assumed that B belongs to all no C, A will not belong to some [20] B: and the conclusion is true, though the
wholly
to
[75] conclusion true. Similarly if of the premisses assumed is true and BC partly false,
premisses are
a true conclusion
sequently C, and
A
false.
(2) Also if each premiss is partly false, the conclusion may be true. For nothing prevents both A and B from belonging to some C while
A
belongs to some B, e.g. white and beautiful belong to some animals, and white to some beautiful things. If then it is stated that A and [25] B belong to all C, the premisses are partially false, but the conclusion is true. Similarly is stated as negative. For if the premiss nothing prevents A from not belonging, and B from belonging, to some C, while A does not belong to all B, e.g. white does not belong to
AC
some animals, beautiful belongs to some ani[jo] mals, and white does not belong to everything beautiful. Consequently if it is assumed that A belongs to no C, and B to all C, both premisses are partly
false,
but the conclusion
is
true.
is
one of the premisses assumed
(3)Similarly
if
wholly
the other wholly true. For
false,
it is
premiss
true, the
partly false, the
AC
is
possible: this can be proved,
same terms
the
if
Also the conclusion is
as before are
may
be true
if
negative, the other affirmative.
transposed.
one premiss
For
since
it
B
should belong to the whole of C, and A to some C, and, when they are so, [20] that A should not belong to all B, therefore it is assumed that B belongs to the whole of C, and A to no C, the negative premiss is partly false, the other premiss wholly true, and the conclusion is true. Again since it has been proved that if A belongs to no C and B to some C, it is possible that A should not belong to [25] some C, it is clear that if the premiss AC is wholly true, and the premiss BC partly false, it is possible that the conclusion should be true. For if it is assumed that A belongs to no C, and B to all C, the premiss AC is wholly true, and the premiss BC is partly false. is
possible that
(5) It is clear also in the case of particular syllogisms that a true conclusion may come
A and B should follow all C, does not belong to some B, e.g. animal and white follow every swan, though animal does not belong to everything white. Taking these then as terms, if one assumes that B belongs to the whole of C, but A does not belong to C at all, the premiss BC will be wholly true, the premiss wholly false, and
[50] through what is false, in every possible way. For the same terms must be taken as have been taken when the premisses are universal, positive terms in positive syllogisms, negative terms in negative. For it makes no difference to the setting out of the terms, whether one assumes that what belongs to none belongs to all
the conclusion true. Similarly
all.
possible that both [
35] though
A
AC
if
the statement
AC
true, the [40] BC is false, the statement conclusion may be true. The same terms will
57 a
both the premisses assumed are affirmative, the conclusion may be true. For nothing prevents B from following all C, and A from not belonging to C at all, though A belongs to some B, e.g. animal serve for the proof. Also
if
[^5] or that
The same
It is
what belongs
to
some belongs
to
applies to negative statements.
clear then that
if
the conclusion
the premisses of the argument either all or some of them; but
is false,
must be
when
false,
the con-
is true, it is not necessary that the premshould be true, either one or all, yet it is
clusion isses
possible,
though no part of the syllogism is may none the
[40] true, that the conclusion
BOOK
58*
II,
CHAPTERS
be true; but it is not necessitated; The rea57 b son is that when two things are so related to one another, that if the one is, the other necessarily is, then if the latter is not, the former will not be either, but if the latter is, it is not necessary that the former should be. But it is impossible that the same thing should be necessitated by the being and by the not-being of the same thing. I mean, for example, that it is impossible that B should necessarily be great [5] since A is white and that B should necessarily be great since A is not white. For whenever since this, A, is white it is necessary that that, B, should be great, and since B is great that C should not be white, then it is necessary if A is white that C should not be white. And whenever it is necessary, since one of two [10] things is, that the other should be, it is necessary, if the latter is not, that the former (viz. A) should not be. If then B is not great A cannot be white. But if, when A is not white, it is necessary that B should be great, it necessarily results that if B is not great, B itless
self is great.
(But
this
is
impossible.) For
if
B
not great, A will necessarily not be white. If [75] then when this is not white B must be great, it results that if B is not great, it is great, is
just as if
it
were proved through three terms.
Circular and reciprocal proof means proof by means of the conclusion, i.e. by converting one of the premisses simply and inferring the [20] other premiss which was original syllogism: e.g. suppose essary to prove that
A
assumed it
belongs to
in the has been necall
C, and
it
has been proved through B; suppose that A should now be proved to belong to B by assuming that A belongs to C, and C to B so A belongs to B: but in the first syllogism the
—
[25] converse was assumed, viz. that B belongs to C. Or suppose it is necessary to prove
B belongs to C, and A is assumed to belong to C, which was the conclusion of the first syllogism, and B to belong to A: but the con-
that
verse
was assumed
in the earlier syllogism, viz.
A
belongs to B. In no other way is reciprocal proof possible. If another term is taken as middle, the proof is not circular: for neither that
[50] of the propositions assumed is the same one of the accepted terms is taken
as before: if
one of the premisses of the first syllogism can be assumed in the second: for if both of them are taken the same conclusion as
as middle, only
before will result: but it must be different. If the terms are not convertible, one of the prem-
isses
4-5
77
from which the syllogism
results
must be to dem-
undemonstrated: for it is not possible onstrate through these terms that the third belongs to the middle or the middle to the first. [35] If the terms are convertible, it is possible to demonstrate everything reciprocally, e.g. if A and B and C are convertible with one another. Suppose the proposition AC has been demonstrated through B as middle term, and again the proposition AB through the conclusion and the premiss BC converted, and simi[40] larly the proposition BC through the conclusion and the premiss AB converted. But it 58 a is necessary to prove both the premiss CB, and the premiss BA: for we have used these alone without demonstrating them. If then it is
assumed that B belongs to all C, and A, we shall have a syllogism relating [5] all
Again if A, and A
it
to
C B
to all
to A. assumed that C belongs to all B, C must belong to all B. is
In both these syllogisms the premiss
CA
has
been assumed without being demonstrated: the other premisses had ex hypothesi been proved. Consequently if we succeed in demonstrating this premiss, all the premisses will have been [10] proved reciprocally. If then it is assumed that C belongs to all B, and B to all A, both the premisses assumed have been proved, and C must belong to A. It is clear then that only if the terms are convertible is circular and reciprocal demonstration possible (if the terms are not convertible, the matter stands as we said [75] above). But it turns out in these also that we use for the demonstration the very thing that is being proved: for C is proved of B, and B of A, by assuming that C is said of A, and C is proved of A through these premisses, so that [20] we use the conclusion for the demonstration.
In negative syllogisms reciprocal proof
is
as
belong to all C, and A to none of the Bs: we conclude that A belongs to none of the Cs. If again it is necessary to prove that A belongs to none of the Bs (which was pre[25] viously assumed) A must belong to no C, and C to all B: thus the previous premiss is reversed. If it is necessary to prove that B befollows. Let
B
longs to C, the proposition
AB
must no longer
be converted as before: for the premiss 'B belongs to no A' is identical with the premiss 'A
belongs to no B\ But we must assume that B belongs to all of that to none of which A be[30] longs. Let A belong to none of the Cs (which was the previous conclusion) and assume that B belongs to all of that to none of which A belongs. It is necessary then that B
PRIOR ANALYTICS
78
should belong to
all
C. Consequently each of
the three propositions has been sion,
and
sume
the conclusion
this
is
made
a conclu-
circular demonstration,
[35] the premisses, premiss.
to as-
and the converse of one of and deduce the remaining
In particular syllogisms
it is
not possible to
demonstrate the universal premiss through the other propositions, but the particular premiss can be demonstrated. Clearly it is impossible to demonstrate the universal premiss: for what is proved through propositions is universal [40] which are universal, but the conclusion is not universal, and the proof must start from the conclusion and the other premiss. Further a syllogism cannot be made at all if the other 58 b premiss is converted: for the result is that both premisses are particular. But the particular premiss may be proved. Suppose that A has been proved of some C through B. If then it is assumed that B belongs to all A, and the con[5] elusion is retained. B will belong to some C: for we obtain the first figure and A is middle.
But
if
the syllogism
is
negative,
it
is
not
possible to prove the universal premiss, for the
reason given above. But it is possible to prove the particular premiss, if the proposition AB is
converted as in the universal syllogism,
[10] 'B belongs to some of that to which does not belong': otherwise
A
gism
i.e.
some of no syllo-
results because the particular premiss
is
negative.
6 second figure it is not possible to prove an affirmative proposition in this way, but a negative proposition may be proved. An [75] affirmative proposition is not proved because both premisses of the new syllogism are not affirmative (for the conclusion is negative) but an affirmative proposition is (as we saw) proved from premisses which are both affirmative. The negative is proved as follows. Let A belong to all B, and to no C: we conclude that [20] B belongs to no C. If then it is assumed that B belongs to all A, it is necessary that A should belong to no C: for we get the second figure, with B as middle. But if the premiss In the
AB
was negative, and the other affirmative, have the first figure. For C belongs to all A, and B to no C, consequently B belongs [25] to no A: neither then does A belong to B. Through the conclusion, therefore, and one premiss, we get no syllogism, but if another premiss is assumed in addition, a syllogism will be possible. But if the syllogism is not uni-
we
shall
59a
premiss cannot be proved, we gave above, but the [?o] particular premiss can be proved whenever the universal statement is affirmative. Let A belong to all B, and not to all C: the conclusion is BC. If then it is assumed that B belongs to all A, but not to all C, A will not belong to some C, B being middle. But if the universal premiss is negative, the premiss will not be demonstrated by the conversion of AB: for it [^5] turns out that either both or one of the premisses is negative; consequently a syllogism will not be possible. But the proof will proceed as in the universal syllogisms, if it is assumed that A belongs to some of that to some of which B does not belong. versal, the universal
for the
same reason
1
as
AC
In the third figure, [40]
when both
taken universally,
is
it
premisses are not possible to
prove them reciprocally: for that which is universal is proved through statements which are 59 a universal, but the conclusion in this figure is always particular, so that it is clear that it is not possible at all to prove through this figure the universal premiss. But if one premiss is universal, the other particular, proof of the latter will sometimes be possible, sometimes not. When both the premisses assumed are affirma[5] tive, and the universal concerns the minor extreme, proof will be possible, but when it concerns the other extreme, impossible. Let A belong to all C and B to some C: the conclusion is the statement AB. If then it is assumed that C belongs to all A, it has been proved that C belongs to some B, but that B belongs to some C has not been proved. And yet it is nec[10] essary, if C belongs to some B, that B should belong to some C. But it is not the same that this should belong to that, and that to this: but we must assume besides that if this belongs to some of that, that belongs to some of this.
But
if
this
is
assumed the syllogism no
longer results from the conclusion and the oth[75] er premiss. But if B belongs to all C, and to some C, it will be possible to prove the
A
proposition
AC, when
it is
assumed
that
C
be-
A
to some B. For if C belongs to all B, and longs to all B and A to some B, it is necessary that A should belong to some C, B being middle. And whenever one premiss is affirmative,
the other negative,
and the
affirmative
is
uni-
premiss can be proved. Let B [20] belong to all C, and A not to some C: the conclusion is that A does not belong to some
versal, the other
lft
3 8.
BOOK
60*
II,
CHAPTERS 5-8 A will belong, not to
then it is assumed further that C belongs to all B, it is necessary that A should not belong to some C, B being middle. But when the negative premiss is universal, the other prem1 ie] iss is not proved, except as before, viz. if it is assumed that that belongs to some of that, to some of which this does not belong, e.g. if A belongs to no C, and B to some C: the conclusion is that A does not belong to some B. If then it is assumed that C belongs to some of that to some of which A does not belong, it is necessary that C should belong to some of the Bs. In no other way is it possible by converting [50] the universal premiss to prove the other: for in no other way can a syllogism be formed. It is clear then that in the first figure reciprocal proof is made both through the third and through the first figure if the conclusion is affirmative through the first; if the conclusion [35] is negative through the last. For it is assumed that that belongs to all of that to none of which this belongs. In the middle figure, when the syllogism is universal, proof is possible through the second figure and through the first, but when particular through the second and the last. In the third figure all proofs are B.
If
—
made through
itself. It is
clear also that in the
[40] third figure and in the middle figure those syllogisms which are not made through
those figures themselves either are not of the nature of circular proof or are imperfect. 8
59 b To convert a syllogism means to alter the conclusion and make another syllogism to prove that either the extreme cannot belong to the middle or the middle to the last term. For if the conclusion has been it is necessary, changed into its opposite and one of the premisses stands, that the other premiss should be [5] destroyed. For if it should stand, the con-
must
stand.
It
whether the conclusion
is
clusion also
contradictory or into
its
makes
a difference
converted into
its
same whichever form the
contrary. For the
syllogism does not result
conversion takes. This will be made clear by the sequel. By contradictory opposition I mean the opposition of 'to all' to 'not to all', and of 'to some' to 'to none' ; by contrary opposition I
mean
[10]
the opposition of
'to all' to 'to
none',
some' to 'not to some'. Suppose that A has been proved of C, through B as middle term. If then it should be assumed that A belongs to no C, but to all B, B will belong to no C. And if A belongs to no C, and B to all C,
and of
*
b
58
'to
9.
[75] B. For (as
79
no B at all, but not to all we saw) the universal is not
2 last figure. In a word it is not possible to refute universally by conversion the premiss which concerns the major extreme: for the refutation always proceeds through the third figure; since it is necessary to take both fremisses in reference to the minor extreme. 20] Similarly if the syllogism is negative. Suppose it has been proved that A belongs to no C through B. Then if it is assumed that A belongs to all C, and to no B, B will belong to none of the Cs. And if A and B belong to all C, A will belong to some B: but in the original premiss it belonged to no B. [25] If the conclusion is converted into its contradictory, the syllogisms will be contradictory and not universal. For one premiss is particular, so that the conclusion also will be particular. Let the syllogism be affirmative, and let it be converted as stated. Then if A belongs not to all C, but to all B, B will belong not to all [jo] C. And if A belongs not to all C, but B belongs to all C, A will belong not to all B. Similarly if the syllogism is negative. For if A belongs to some C, and to no B, B will belong, not to no C at all, but not to some C. And if A belongs to some C, and B to all C, as was [55] originally assumed, A will belong to some B. In particular syllogisms when the conclusion is converted into its contradictory, both premisses may be refuted, but when it is converted
proved through the
—
into
its
contrary, neither. For the result
is
no
3 [40] longer, as in the universal syllogisms, a refutation in which the conclusion reached by
60 a conversion
lacks universality, but no refuSuppose that A has been proved of some C. If then it is assumed that A belongs to no C, and B to some C, A will not belong to some B: and if A belongs to no C, but to all B, B will belong to no C. Thus both premisses are refuted. But neither can be refuted if the tation at
all.
is converted into its contrary. does not belong to some C, but to all B, then B will not belong to some C. But the original premiss is not yet refuted: for it is possible that B should belong to some C, and should not belong to some C. The universal premiss AB cannot be affected by a syllogism at all: for if A does not belong to some of the [10] Cs, but B belongs to some of the Cs, neither of the premisses is universal. Similarly if the syllogism is negative: for if it should be assumed that A belongs to all C, both prem-
[5] conclusion
For
if
« 1. 6.
A
'11.
[3-20, 23-4.
PRIOR ANALYTICS
8o isses
sumed
A
to all
are refuted: but if the assumption is that belongs to some C, neither premiss is refuted. The proof is the same as before.
to
60 b
belong to some C. Again
C and A
to
some C,
whichever form the conversion of the conmay take. For the conclusion of the refutation will always be in the third figure, and it,
clusion
in this figure (as sal
syllogism.
in a if
manner
The
we saw
1
)
there
is
no univer-
other premiss can be refuted
similar to the conversion:
the conclusion of the
first
I
syllogism
mean, is
con-
[20] verted into its contrary, the conclusion of the refutation will be the contrary of the minor
premiss of the
first,
no C: conclusion BC.
B
belongs to
A
all
into
if
A
the contradictory. Let
If
its
contradictory,
belong to all B and to then it is assumed that
C, and the proposition
AB
belong to all C, since the first figure is produced. If B belongs to all C, and [25] A to no C, then A belongs not to all B: the figure is the last. But if the conclusion BC is converted into its contradictory the premiss AB will be refuted as before, the premiss AC by its contradictory. For if B belongs to some C, and A to no C, then A will not belong to some B. Again if B belongs to some C, and [jo] A to all B, A will belong to some C, so stands,
will
,
that the syllogism results in the contradictory
minor premiss.
of the
given
if
A
similar proof can be
the premisses are transposed in respect
of their quality. If
the syllogism
is
particular,
when
1
1.
6.
is
2
b 59 39-60*
1.
6oa 5-14.
B
belongs
is
if
the
affirmative.
10
In the third figure when the conclusion is converted into its contrary, neither of the premisses can be refuted in any of the syllogisms, but when the conclusion is converted into its contradictory, both premisses may be
refuted and in all the moods. Suppose it has been proved that A belongs to some B, C being [10] taken as middle, and the premisses being universal. If then it is assumed that A does not belong to some B, but B belongs to all C, no syllogism is formed about A and C. Nor if A does not belong to some B, but belongs to all C, will a syllogism be possible about B and C. A similar proof can be given [75] if the premisses are not universal. For either both premisses arrived at by the conversion must be particular, or the universal premiss must refer to the minor extreme. But we
found that no syllogism is possible thus either 3 in the first or in the middle figure. But if the conclusion
is
converted into
its
contradictory,
[20] both the premisses can be refuted. For if belongs to no B, and B to all C, then be-
A
A
longs to no C: again if A belongs to no B, and to all C, B belongs to no C. And similarly if
one of the premisses is not universal. For if A belongs to no B, and B to some C, A will not belong to some C: if A belongs to no B, and to [25] all C, B will belong to no C.
the con-
converted into its contrary neither premiss can be refuted, as also happened in the 2 first figure, but if the conclusion is converted into contradictory, both premisses can its [35] be refuted. Suppose that A belongs to no B, and to some C: the conclusion is BC. If then it is assumed that B belongs to some C, and the statement AB stands, the conclusion will be that A does not belong to some C. But the original statement has not been refuted: for it is possible that A should belong to some C and also not to some C. Again if B belongs to some [40] C and A to some C, no syllogism will be possible: for neither of the premisses taken is 60 b universal. Consequently the proposition AB is not refuted. But if the conclusion is converted into its contradictory, both premisses can be refuted. For if B belongs to all C, and A to no B, A will belong to no C: but it was as-
clusion
if
will belong to
some B. The same proof can be given [5] universal statement
[75] In the second figure it is not possible to refute the premiss which concerns the major extreme by establishing something contrary to
A
Similarly
if
the original syllogism
is
nega-
Suppose it has been proved that A does not belong to some B, BC being affirmative, tive.
AC
being negative: for it was thus that, as we saw, 4 a syllogism could be made. Whenever then the contrary of the conclusion is assumed a syllogism will not be possible. For if A be[30] longs to some B, and B to all C, no syllogism is possible (as we saw 5 ) about A and C. Nor, if A belongs to some B, and to no C, was a syllogism possible concerning B and C.
Therefore the premisses are not refuted. But
when
the contradictory of the conclusion
is
as-
sumed, they are refuted. For if A belongs to [55] all B, and B to C, A belongs to all C: but A was supposed originally to belong to no C. Again if A belongs to all B, and to no C, then B belongs to no C: but it was supposed to belong to
all
C.
A
similar proof
26a 17-21, 27* 4-12. 5 2 6a 30-6.
3
4
28 b
is
1-4,
possible 11
I5-29
10.
if
the
61 b premisses are not universal.
BOOK II, CHAPTERS 8-11 For AC becomes true. Similarly
and negative, the other premiss parand affirmative. If then A belongs to all [40] B, and B to some C, it results that A belongs to some C: but it was supposed to belong to no C. Again if A belongs to all B, and to no 61 a C, then B belongs to no C: but it was assumed to belong to some C. If A belongs to some B and B to some C, no syllogism results: nor yet if A belongs to some B, and to no C. Thus in one way the premisses are refuted, in
81 in the other figures: for
moods admit
ever
the reduction per impossibile.
way
they are not. has been said it is clear how a syllogism results in each figure when the conclusion is converted; when a result contrary to the other [5]
From what
the premiss, the premiss,
and when is
a result contradictory to
obtained.
It is clear
that in the
figure the syllogisms are formed through the middle and the last figures, and the premiss which concerns the minor extreme is always [10] refuted through the middle figure, the
first
premiss which concerns the major through the last figure. In the second figure syllogisms proceed through the first and the last figures, and the premiss which concerns the minor extreme is always refuted through the first figure, the premiss which concerns the major extreme
admit
of conversion
universal
ticular
whatalso of
All the problems can be proved per impos-
excepting the universal
sibile in all the figures,
[35] affirmative, which is proved in the middle and third figures, but not in the first. Sup-
pose that A belongs not to all B, or to no B, and take besides another premiss concerning either of the terms, viz. that C belongs to all A, or that B belongs to all D; thus we get the [40] first figure. If then it is supposed that A does not belong to all B, no syllogism results whichever term the assumed premiss concerns; 61 b but if it is supposed that A belongs to no B, when the premiss is assumed as well we shall prove syllogistically what is false, but not the problem proposed. For if A belongs to no B, and B belongs to all D, A belongs to no [5] D. Let this be impossible: it is false then that A belongs to no B. But the universal affirmative is not necessarily true if the universal negative is false. But if the premiss CA is as-
BD
sumed
no syllogism
[75] is always refuted through the first figure, the premiss which concerns the minor through
results, nor does it supposed that A does not belong to all B. Consequently it is clear that the universal affirmative cannot be proved in the first figure per impossibile. [10] But the particular affirmative and the universal and particular negatives can all be proved. Suppose that A belongs to no B, and let it have been assumed that B belongs to all
the middle figure.
or to
through the
last.
tion proceeds
In the third figure the refutafirst and the middle
through the
figures; the premiss
which concerns the major
n then what conversion is, how it is effected in each figure, and what syllogism results. The syllogism per impossible is proved when the contradictory of the conclusion is [20] stated and another premiss is assumed; it can be made in all the figures. For it resembles conversion, differing only in this: conversion takes place after a syllogism has been formed and both the premisses have been taken, but a reduction to the impossible takes place not because the contradictory has been already, but because it is clear 2 [ 5] agreed to that it is true. The terms are alike in both, and the premisses of both are taken in the same way. For example if A belongs to all B, C being middle, then if it is supposed that A does not belong to all B or belongs to no B, but to all C (which was admitted to be true), it fol[50] lows that C belongs to no B or not to all B. But this is impossible: consequently the supposition is false: its contradictory then is It is clear
do
so
as well,
when
it is
some C. Then
should belong to no is
A
impossible (for
C
it
is
necessary that
or not to
let it
all
A
C. But this
be true and clear that
C): consequently if this is [75] false, it is necessary that A should belong to some B. But if the other premiss assumed belongs to
all
relates to A, no syllogism will be possible. Nor can a conclusion be drawn when the contrary of the conclusion is supposed, e.g. that A does not belong to some B. Clearly then we must suppose the contradictory. Again suppose that A belongs to some B, and let it have been assumed that C belongs to [20] all A. It is necessary then that C should belong to some B. But let this be impossible, so
that the supposition
A
is
false: in that case
We
it
is
belongs to no B. may proceed in the same way if the proposition CA has been taken as negative. But if the premiss assumed concerns B, no syllogism will be possible. If the contrary is supposed, we shall have a syllogism and an impossible conclusion, but [25] the problem in hand is not proved. Suppose that A belongs to all B, and let it have true that
PRIOR ANALYTICS
82
been assumed that essary then that this
is
C
C
belongs to all A. It is necshould belong to all B. But
impossible, so that
longs to
all
B. But
it
is
false that
A
concerns B, nothing is proved. is that A belongs not to all [40] but to some B, it is not proved that A belongs not to all B, but that it belongs to no B. For if A belongs to some B, and C to all A, then C will belong to some B. If then this is impossible, it is false that A belongs to some 62a B; consequently it is true that A belongs to no B. But if this is proved, the truth is refuted as well; for the original conclusion was that A belongs to some B, and does not belong to some B. Further the impossible does not result from the hypothesis: for then the hypothe[5] sis would be false, since it is impossible to draw a false conclusion from true premisses: but in fact it is true: for A belongs to some B. Consequently we must not suppose that A belongs to some B, but that it belongs to all B. Similarly if we should be proving that A does not belong to some B: for if 'not to belong to some' and 'to belong not to all' have the same [10] meaning, the demonstration of both will be identical. It is clear then that not the contrary but the contradictory ought to be supposed in all the syllogisms. For thus we shall have necessity of inference, and the claim we make is one that will be generally accepted. For if of everything one or other of two contradictory statements holds good, then if it is proved that the negation does not hold, the affirmation must be [75] true. Again if it is not admitted that the affirmation is true, the claim that the negation is true will be generally accepted. But in neither way does it suit to maintain the contrary: for it is not necessary that if the universal negtive is false, the universal affirmative should be the hypothesis
is it
generally accepted that
if
the one
be-
must suppose that it belongs to all B: for if A belongs to all B, and C to all A, then C belongs [^5] to all B; so that if this is impossible, the hypothesis is false. Similarly if the other premiss assumed concerns B. The same results if the original proposition CA was negative: for thus also we get a syllogism. But if the negaIf
nor
false the other is true.
is
12
we have not yet shown it to be
necessary that A belongs to no B, if it does not [jo] belong to all B. Similarly if the other premiss taken concerns B; we shall have a syllogism and a conclusion which is impossible, but the hypothesis is not refuted. Therefore it is the contradictory that we must suppose. To prove that A does not belong to all B, we
tive proposition
true,
62 b
[20]
It is
clear then that in the first figure all
problems except the universal affirmative are proved per impossibile. But in the middle and the last figures this also is proved. Suppose that A does not belong to all B, and let it have been assumed that A belongs to all C. If then [25]
A
belongs not to
will not belong to all B.
all
all C, C impossible
B, but to
But
this
is
(for suppose it to be clear that C belongs to all B): consequently the hypothesis is false. It is true then that A belongs to all B. But if the contrary is supposed, we shall have a syllogism
and a
result which is impossible: but the probjo] lem in hand is not proved. For if A belongs to no B, and to all C, C will belong to no B. This is impossible; so that it is false that [
A
belongs to no B. But though this is false, it does not follow that it is true that A belongs to all B.
When A belongs to some B, suppose that A belongs to no B, and let A belong to all C. It is necessary then that C should belong to no [35] B. Consequently, if this is impossible, A must belong to some B. But if it is supposed that A does not belong to some B, we shall have the same results as in the first figure. 1 Again suppose that A belongs to some B, and let A belong to no C. It is necessary then that C should not belong to some B. But originally it belonged to all B, consequently the hy[40] pothesis is false: A then will belong to
no
B.
When A
does not belong to all B, suppose it to all B, and to no C. It is necessary then that C should belong to no B. But this is impossible: so that it is true that A does not belong to all B. It is clear then that all the syllogisms can be formed in the middle figure.
62 b does belong
[5] Similarly they can all be formed in the last does not belong to some figure. Suppose that
A
belongs to all B: then A does not beIf then this is impossible, it is long to some false that A does not belong to some B; so that it is true that A belongs to all B. But if it is supposed that A belongs to no B, we shall have a syllogism and a conclusion which is impossible: but the problem in hand is not proved: [10] for if the contrary is supposed, we shall B, but
C
C
have the same 1
6i b 39-62* 8.
results as before. 2 a
28-32.
2
BOOK
63 b
CHAPTERS
II,
prove that A belongs to some B, this hypothesis must be made. If A belongs to no B, and C to some B, A will belong not to all C. If then this is false, it is true that A belongs to some B. [75] When A belongs to no B, suppose A belongs to some B, and let it have been assumed that C belongs to all B. Then it is necessary that A should belong to some C. But ex hy~ pothesi it belongs to no C, so that it is false that A belongs to some B. But if it is supposed that A belongs to all B, the problem is not proved. But this hypothesis must be made if we are [20] to prove that A belongs not to all B. For if A belongs to all B and C to some B, then A
But
to
belongs to some C. But this we assumed not to be so, so it is false that A belongs to all B. But in that case it is true that A belongs not to all B. If however it is assumed that A belongs
some B, we
to
fore.
shall
have the same
result as be-
clear then that in all the syllogisms
It is
which proceed per impossibile the contradictory must be assumed. And it is plain that in the middle figure an affirmative conclusion, and in the last figure a universal conclusion, are proved in a way.
M Demonstration per impossibile
differs
from
os-
[30] tensive proof in that it posits what it wishes to refute by reduction to a statement ad-
mitted to be false; whereas ostensive proof starts from admitted positions. Both, indeed, take two premisses that are admitted, but the latter takes the premisses from which the syl-
logism starts, the former takes one of these, along with the contradictory of the original [35] conclusion. Also in the ostensive proof it is not necessary that the conclusion should be known, nor that one should suppose before-
hand
that
it is
true or not: in the other
necessary to suppose beforehand that true. It
makes no
clusion
is
it
it is
is
not
difference whether the con-
affirmative or negative; the
method
Everything which is concluded ostensively can be proved per impos[40] sibile, and that which is proved per impossibile can be proved ostensively, through is
the
the
same
in both cases.
same terms. Whenever the syllogism
is
63 a formed in the first figure, the truth will be found in the middle or the last figure, if negative in the
Whenever 1
14
83
whatever the problem
may
found be.
in the first,
Whenever
the
[5] syllogism is formed in the last figure, the truth will be found in the first and middle fig-
affirmative in the
negative in has been proved to belong to no B, or not to all B, through the first figure. Then the hypothesis must have been that A belongs to some #, and the original ures,
if
the middle. Suppose that
first, if
A
[jo] premisses that C belongs to all A and to no B. For thus the syllogism was made and the impossible conclusion reached. But this is the middle figure, if C belongs to all A and to no B. And it is clear from these premisses that A belongs to no B. Similarly if A has bsen proved [75] not to belong to all B. For the hypothesis is that A belongs to all B; and the original
premisses are that C belongs to all A but not to all B. Similarly too, if the premiss CA should be negative: for thus also we have the middle
Again suppose it has been proved that belongs to some B. The hypothesis here is [20] that A belongs to no B; and the original premisses that B belongs to all C, and A either figure.
A
1
[25]
11
die figure, the truth will be
middle,
if
affirmative in the
the syllogism
6i b 39-62* 8.
is
formed
in the
last.
mid-
to all or to
get
what
to all C,
is
some C:
for in this
we have
way we
A
and
the last figure.
And
impossible. But
if
B
shall
belong
it is
clear
from these premisses that A must belong to some B. Similarly if B or A should be assumed to belong to some C. [25] Again suppose it has been proved in the middle figure that A belongs to all B. Then the hypothesis must have been that A belongs not to all B, and the original premisses that A belongs to all C, and C to all B: for thus we shall get what is impossible. But if A belongs to all C, and C to all B, we have the first figure. Similarly [30] to
if it
has been proved that
some B:
A
belongs
for the hypothesis then
must
A
belongs to no B, and the original premisses that A belongs to all C, and C to some B. If the syllogism is negative, the hypothesis must have been that A belongs to some B, and the original premisses that A belongs to no C, and C to all B, so that the first [35] fig ure results. If the syllogism is not universal, but proof has been given that A does not belong to some B, we may infer in the same way. The hypothesis is that A belongs to all B, the original premisses that A belongs to no C, and C belongs to some B: for thus we
have been that
get the
first figure.
[40] Again suppose it has been proved in the third figure that belongs to all B. Then the
A
hypothesis must have been that A belongs not 63 b to all B, and the original premisses that
PRIOR ANALYTICS
84
C
belongs to
thus
we
original
all
A
B, and
belongs to
C; for
all
what is impossible. And the premisses form the first figure. Simshall get
demonstration establishes a particular proposition: the hypothesis then must have been that A belongs to no B, and the origin] inal premisses that C belongs to some B,
ilarly if the
64
possible because opposites affirm
is
same predicate of the same the middle term in the first figure the
a
and deny and
subject,
is not predicated of both extremes, but one thing is denied of it, and it is affirmed of something else: but
such premisses are not opposed.
the hypothesis
[40] In the middle figure a syllogism can be of contradictories and of contraries. Let stand for good, let B and C stand for
to
64 a
and
A
to all C. If the syllogism
is
negative,
must have been that A belongs some B, and the original premisses that C belongs to no A and to all B, and this is the
middle is
figure. Similarly
the demonstration
if
not universal. The hypothesis will then be A belongs to all B, the premisses that
[10] that
C
belongs to no
A
and
to
some B: and
this
is
the middle figure. It is
clear then that
same terms
possible
it is
to prove each of the
tensively as well. Similarly if
it
through the problems os-
will be possible
the syllogisms are ostensive to reduce
them
[75] ad impossibile in the terms which have been taken, whenever the contradictory of the
conclusion of the ostensive syllogism is taken as a premiss. For the syllogisms become identical with those which are obtained by means of conversion, so that
the figures through
be solved.
It is
we
obtain immediately
which each problem
will
clear then that every thesis can
be proved in both ways,
per impossibile is not possible to
i.e.
[20] and ostensively, and it separate one method from the other.
made both
A
is
longs to
good, and no science
B and
all
no C: no
to
no C,
science then
is
is
so that
good, A bebelongs to
B
a science. Similarly
after taking 'every science
if
good' one took [5] 'the science of medicine is not good'; for A belongs to all B but to no C, so that a particular science will not be a science. Again, a particular science will not be a science if A belongs to all C but to no B, and B is science, C medicine, and A supposition: for after taking 'no science is supposition', one has assumed is
[10] that a particular science is supposition. differs from the preceding be-
This syllogism
cause the relations between the terms are reversed: before, the affirmative statement concerned B, now it concerns C. Similarly if one premiss is not universal: for the middle term is
always that which is stated negatively of one extreme, and affirmatively of the other. Conse[75] quently it is possible that contradictories
may
lead to a conclusion,
in every
15
one assumes that every
science. If then
science
mood, but only
though not always or the terms subordi-
if
nate to the middle are such that they are either
In what figure it is possible to draw a conclusion from premisses which are opposed, and in what figure this is not possible, will be made clear in this way. Verbally four kinds of opposition are possible, viz. universal affirmative to
identical or related as
whole
to part.
Otherwise
impossible: for the premisses cannot any-
it is
how
be either contraries or contradictories.
[20] In the third figure an affirmative syllogism can never be made out of opposite prem-
[25] universal negative, universal affirmative
isses,
to particular negative, particular affirmative to
first
for the reason given in reference to the 1
figure; but a negative syllogism
is
possible
universal contraries, the universal affirmative
whether the terms are universal or not. Let B and C stand for science, A for medicine. If [25] then one should assume that all medicine is science and that no medicine is science, he has asumed that B belongs to all A and C to no A, so that a particular science will not be a
and the universal negative,
science. Similarly
universal negative,
and particular
affirmative
to particular negative: but really there are only
three:
for the
particular affirmative
is
only
verbally opposed to the particular negative.
the genuine opposites
I
[30] is good', 'no science call contradictories.
call
is
Of
those which are
e.g. 'every science
good'; the others
I
In the first figure no syllogism whether affirmative or negative can be made out of op-
posed premisses: no affirmative syllogism is possible because both premisses must be affirmative, but opposites are, the one affirmative, [35] tne other negative:
no negative syllogism
sumed
if
the premiss
BA
is
not
as-
For if some medicine is science and again no medicine is science, it [30] results that some science is not science.
The
universally.
premisses are contrary
en universally;
if
one
is
if
the terms are tak-
particular, they are
contradictory.
We must x
6 3b 33-
recognize that
it is
possible to take
BOOK
65* opposites in the
way we
II,
CHAPTERS
escape notice. But it is possible to establish one part of a contradiction through other premisses, or to assume it in the way suggested 1
ways;
versal affirmative
of the other; here too the
[10] contrary to the fact, e.g. if a thing is good, it is proved that it is not good, if an animal, that it is not an animal, because the syllogism springs out of a contradiction and the terms presupposed are either identical or related as whole and part. It is evident also that in fallacious reasonings nothing prevents a contradiction to the hypothesis from resulting, e.g. if something is odd, it is not odd. For the [75] syllogism owed tradictory premisses;
its
contrariety to
its
con-
we assume
such premisses we shall get a result that contradicts our hypothesis. But we must recognize that contraries cannot be inferred from a single syllogism in such a way that we conclude that what is not good is good, or anything of that sort, [20] unless a self-contradictory premiss is at once asumed, e.g. 'every animal is white and not white', and we proceed 'man is an animal'. Either we must introduce the contradiction by an additional assumption, assuming, e.g., that every science is supposition, and then assuming 'Medicine is a science, but none of it is suppois
the
if
mode
[25] tions are made), or we two syllogisms. In no other
was
said before,
is it
viii. 1.
2
which refutamust argue from
in
way than
this, as
possible that the premisses
should be really contrary. 1
[50] proposed; but this happens in many ways. reason syllogistically at all, or
A man may not
is
between the terms may be reversed. Similarly in the third figure. So it is clear in [5] how many ways and in what figures a syllogism can be made by means of premisses which are opposed. It is clear too that from false premisses it is possible to draw a true conclusion, as has been 2 said before, but it is not possible if the premisses are opposed. For the syllogism is always
(which
a
and negative, or universal
relation
sition'
is
problem
lish the antecedent by means of its consequents; for demonstration proceeds from what
and the relations between the terms may be 64 b reversed; e.g. A may belong to all B and to no C, or to all C and to no B, or to all of all
the original question
species of failure to demonstrate the
may be assumed as premwe may have either uni-
it
[40] affirmative and particular negative, or particular affirmative and universal negative,
the one, not to
To beg and assume
may argue from premisses which are less known or equally unknown, or he may estab-
to affirmative statements,
in six
16
follows that op-
in the Topics. Since there are three oppositions
isses
85
said, viz. 'all science
[35] 1S g°°d' and 'no science is good' or 'some science is not good'. This does not usually
posite statements
14-16
Chapters 2-4.
he
and is prior. Now begging the none of these: but since we get to know some things naturally through themselves, and other things by means of sonnets] thing else (the first principles through themselves, what is subordinate to them through something else), whenever a man tries to prove what is not self-evident by means of
more
certain
question
is
then he begs the original question. This be done by assuming what is in question at once; it is also possible to make a transits] tion to other things which would naturally be proved through the thesis proposed, and itself,
may
65 a demonstrate it through them, e.g. if A should be proved through B, and B through C, though it was natural that C should be proved through A: for it turns out that those who reason thus are proving A by means of itself. This is what those persons do who suppose that they [5] are constructing parallel straight lines: for fail to see that they are assuming facts
they
which
it
is
impossible to demonstrate unless it turns out that those
the parallels exist. So
who
reason thus merely say a particular thing in this way everything will be self-
is, if it is:
evident. But that
is
impossible.
A
belongs [10] If then it is uncertain whether to C, and also whether belongs to B, and if
A that A
one should assume does belong to B, it is not yet clear whether he begs the original question, but it is evident that he is not demon-
what is as uncertain as the quesanswered cannot be a principle of a demonstration. If however B is so related to C strating: for
tion to be
that they are identical, or
if
they are plainly
[75] convertible, or the one belongs to the other, the original question is begged. For one
might equally well prove that A belongs to B through those terms if they are convertible. But if they are not convertible, it is the fact that they are not that prevents such a demonstration, not the method of demonstrating. But if one were to make the conversion, then he would be doing what we have described 3 a
In
11.
1-4.
PRIOR ANALYTICS
86
and
effecting a
reciprocal
proof with
three
66
sive proofs: since
an assumption
if
propositions.
syllogism can no longer be
Similarly if he should assume that B be[20] longs to C, this being as uncertain as the belongs to C, the question question whether
to
A
is
not yet begged, but no demonstration
made.
If
however
A
and B are
is
identical either
because they are convertible or because A follows B, then the question is begged for the same reason as before. For we have explained the
meaning
of begging
[25] proving that means of itself.
which
the question, viz.
is
not self-evident by
then begging the question is proving what not self-evident by means of itself, in other words failing to prove when the failure is due to the thesis to be proved and the premiss If
is
through which
it is proved being equally unbecause predicates which are identical belong to the same subject, or because the same predicate belongs to subjects which are identical, the question may be begged in [50] the middle and third figures in both ways, though, if the syllogism is affirmative, only in the third and first figures. If the syllogism is
certain, either
it.
drawn
is
s
refuted, a
in reference
clear then that the expression 'false
It is
[10] cause' can only be used in the case of a reductio ad impossibile, and when the original
hypothesis
is
so related to the impossible con-
clusion, that the conclusion results indifferent-
whether the hypothesis is made or not. The most obvious case of the irrelevance of an assumption to a conclusion which is false is when a syllogism drawn from middle terms to an [75] impossible conclusion is independent of the hypothesis, as we have explained in the Topics. For to put that which is not the cause as the cause, is just this: e.g. if a man, wishing ly
1
to
prove that the diagonal of the square
is
in-
commensurate with the side, should try to prove Zeno's theorem that motion is impossible, and so establish a reductio ad impossi[20] bile: for Zeno's false theorem has no connexion at all with the original assumption. Another case is where the impossible conclusion is
terms in negative syllogisms are not converti[^5] ble. In scientific demonstrations the question is begged when the terms are really related in the manner described, in dialectical arguments when they are according to common
connected with the hypothesis, but does not result from it. This may happen whether one traces the connexion upwards or downwards, [ 2 5] e -g- if it i s laid down that A belongs to B, B to C, and C to D, and it should be false that B belongs to D: for if we eliminated A and assumed all the same that B belongs to C and C to D, the false conclusion would not depend on the original hypothesis. Or again trace the connexion upwards; e.g. suppose that A [30] belongs to B, E to A, and F to E, it being false that F belongs to A. In this way too the impossible conclusion would result, though the
opinion so related.
original hypothesis
begged when identical same subject; and both premisses do not beg the question indif-
negative, the question
is
predicates are denied of the ferently (in a similar
way
the question
may
be
begged in the middle figure), because the
were eliminated. But the
impossible conclusion ought to be connected
not the reason why the result is false', which we frequently make in argument, is made primarily in the case of [40] a reductio ad impossible, to rebut the
The
objection that 'this
is
proposition which was being proved by the re65 b duction. For unless a man has contradicted
he will not say, 'False cause', but urge that something false has been assumed in the earlier parts of the argument; nor will he use the formula in the case of an ostensive proof; for here what one denies is not assumed as a premiss. Further when anything is refuted ostensively by the terms ABC, it can[5] not be objected that the syllogism does not
this proposition
depend on the assumption
laid
use the expression 'false cause',
gism
is
down. For we
when
the syllo-
concluded in spite of the refutation of but that is not possible in osten-
this position;
with the original terms: in this way it will depend on the hypothesis, e.g. when one traces the connexion downwards, the impossible Cottle ] elusion must be connected with that term
which
is
predicate in the hypothesis: for
if it
A
should belong to D, the false conclusion will no longer result after A has been eliminated. If one traces the connexion upwards, the impossible conclusion must be connected with that term which is
impossible that
is
subject in the hypothesis: for
if it is
impossi-
F
should belong to B, the impossible conclusion will disappear if B is eliminated. [40] Similarly when the syllogisms are nega-
ble that
tive. It is clear then that when the impossibility not related to the original terms, the false conclusion does not result on account of the
66 a is
1
On
h Sophistical Refutations, i6j 21-36.
BOOK
66 b
II,
CHAPTERS
assumption. Or perhaps even so it may sometimes be independent. For if it were laid down bethat A belongs not to B but to K, and that [5] longs to C and C to D, the impossible con-
K
would
one takes the terms in an ascending series. Consequently since the impossibility results whether the first assumption is suppressed or not, it would appear to be independent of that assumption. Or perhaps we ought not to understand the stateclusion
ment
still
stand. Similarly
if
conclusion results independently of the assumption, in the sense that if something else were supposed the impossithat the false
[10] bility
when
would
result; but rather
we mean
assumption is eliminated, the same impossibility results through the remaining premisses; since it is not perhaps absurd that the same false result should follow that
from
the
several
first
hypotheses, e.g.
that
two right
ought in attack to try This will be possible first, if, instead drawing the conclusions of preliminary [ ^5] of
their admissions, they to conceal.
syllogisms, they take the necessary premisses
and leave the conclusions ondly tions
angles.
18 false
argument depends on the
if
first
false
it. Every syllogism is made out of two or more premisses. If then the false conclusion is drawn from two premisses, one or both of them must be false: for (as we proved ) a false syllogism cannot be drawn from true [20] premisses. But if the premisses are more than two, e.g. if C is established through A and B, and these through D, E, F, and G, one of these higher propositions must be false, and on this the argument depends: for A and B are inferred by means of D, E, F, and G. Therefore the conclusion and the error results from
statement in
1
which are
against us
we must
take care, whenever
an opponent asks us to admit the reason without the conclusions, not to grant him the same term twice over in his premisses, since we know that a syllogism cannot be drawn without a middle term, and that term which is stated more than once is the middle. How we ought to watch the middle in reference to each [30] conclusion, is evident from our knowing what kind of thesis is proved in each figure. This will not escape us since we know how we are maintaining the argument. That which we urge men to beware of in l
b 53 11-25.
closely connected they take as
connected by middle terms. For example suppose that A is
to be inferred to be true of F; B, C,
D, and
E
being middle terms. One ought then to ask whether A belongs to B, and next whether belongs to E, instead of asking whether B be[40] longs to C; after that he may ask whether 66 b B belongs to C, and so on. If the syllogism is drawn through one middle term, he ought to begin with that: in this way he will most likely deceive his opponent.
D
20 Since
we know when
[5]
formed and how
it is
clear
when
its
a syllogism can be terms must be related,
refutation will be possible
impossible.
A
refutation
is
and
possible
whether everything is conceded, or the answers I mean, being affirmative, the other negative). For as has been shown a syllogism is possible whether the terms are related in affirmative propositions or one propoalternate (one,
sition
is
affirmative, the other negative: con-
[10]
what
down
is
contrary to
the conclusion, a refutation
must take which es-
sequently,
if
is
laid
place: for a refutation
is
a syllogism
tablishes the contradictory. But if nothing is conceded, a refutation is impossible: for no 2 syllogism is possible (as we saw ) when all the terms are negative: therefore no refutation is possible.
For
refutation
In order to avoid having a syllogism
drawn
the dark; sec-
if
a refutation
were
possible, a
[75] syllogism must be possible; although if a syllogism is possible it does not follow that a
one of them.
[25]
in
instead of inviting assent to proposi-
far as possible those that are not
when
A
87
parallels
meet, both on the assumption that the interior angle is greater than the exterior and on the assumption that a triangle contains more than [75]
16-21
is
not possible
if
possible. Similarly refutation
nothing
is
is
conceded universally:
since the fields of refutation
and syllogism are
defined in the same way. 21
sometimes happens that just as we are deceived in the arrangement of the terms, so error may arise in our thought about them, It
same predimore than one subject immediately, but although knowing the one, a [20] e.g.
if it is
possible that the
cate should belong to
man may
forget the other
posite true.
C
Suppose that
A
and think the opbelongs to B and to
in virtue of their nature, 2
4I
b 6.
and that
B and C
PRIOR ANALYTICS
88
belong to
all
thinks that
A
to
D in the same way.
A
belongs to
no C, and
C
to all
all
If
B, and
D, he
then a
B
to
will both
man
D, but
know
67 b
biguous, meaning to have the knowledge either of the universal or of the particulars. Thus then he knows that C contains two right
[25] and not know the same thing in respect of the same thing. Again if a man were to make a mistake about the members of a single
angles with a knowledge of the universal, but
series; e.g.
suppose A belongs to B, B to C, and D, but some one thinks that A belongs to all B, but to no C: he will both know that A [30] belongs to D, and think that it does not. Does he then maintain after this simply that what he knows, he does not think? For he knows in a way that A belongs to C through
trary to his ignorance.
C
Meno
to
included in the whole; so in a way, this he maintains he does not think at all: but that is imB, since the part
that
is
what he knows
possible.
[35] In the former case, where the middle term does not belong to the same series, it is not possible to think both the premisses with reference to each of the two middle terms: e.g. that A belongs to all B, but to no C, and both B and C belong to all D. For it turns out that the first premiss of the one syllogism is either wholly or partially contrary to the first premiss of the other. For if he thinks that A belongs to [40] everything to which B belongs, and he that B belongs to D, then he knows belongs to D. Consequently if again he thinks that A belongs to nothing to which C belongs, he thinks that A does not belong to some of that to which B belongs; but if he thinks that A belongs to everything to which B belongs, and again thinks that A does not be-
67 a knows that
A
long to some of that to which B belongs, these [5] beliefs are wholly or partially contrary. In this way then it is not possible to think; but nothing prevents a man thinking one premiss of each syllogism or both premisses of one of the two syllogisms: e.g. A belongs to all B, and B to D, and again A belongs to no C. An error of this kind is similar to the error into which we fall concerning particulars: e.g. if A [10] belongs to all B, and B to all C, A will belong to all C. If then a man knows that A belongs to everything to which B belongs, he knows that A belongs to C. But nothing prevents his being ignorant that C exists; e.g. let A stand for two right angles, B for triangle,
C for a particular diagram man might think that C did
of a triangle.
A
though [75] he knew that every triangle contains two right angles; consequently he will know and not know the same thing at the same time. For the expression 'to know that every triangle has its angles equal to two right angles' is amnot
exist,
[20] not with a knowledge of the particulars; consequently his knowledge will not be con1
learning
that
is
The argument in the recollection may be
way. For it never hapwith a foreknowledge of the particular, but along with the process of being led to see the general principle he receives a knowledge of the particulars, by an act (as it were) of recognition. For we know some criticized in a similar
pens that a
man
starts
things directly; e.g. that the angles are equal
know
[25] to two right angles, if we figure is a triangle. Similarly in
By
a
knowledge
that the
other cases.
we see know them by
of the universal then
the particulars, but the kind of
all
we do
not
knowledge which
proper to
is
them; consequently it is possible that we may make mistakes about them, but not that we should have the knowledge and error that are contrary to one another: rather we have the
knowledge
of the universal but
make
a mis-
[30] take in apprehending the particular. Sim2 ilarly in the cases stated above. The error in respect of the middle term
the
is
not contrary to
knowledge obtained through the syllogism,
nor is the thought in respect of one middle term contrary to that in respect of the other.
Nothing prevents a man who knows both that A belongs to the whole of B, and that B again belongs to C, thinking that A does not belong [^5] to C, e.g. knowing that every mule is sterile and that this is a mule, and thinking that this animal is with foal: for he does not
know
that
A
belongs to C, unless he considers
two propositions together. So it is evident that if he knows the one and does not know the
the other, he will
fall
into error.
And this
is
the
relation of knowledge of the universal to 67 b knowledge of the particular. For we know
no
sensible thing, once
it
has passed beyond
the range of our senses, even
have perceived versal
and
it,
except by
if
we happen
means
the possession of the
to
of the uni-
knowledge
proper to the particular, but without the actual exercise of that knowledge. For to know is used in three senses: it may mean either to have knowledge of the universal or to [5] have knowledge proper to the matter in hand or to exercise such knowledge: consequently three kinds of error also are possible. Nothing then prevents a man both knowing
which
1
is
Plato,
Meno,
81.
2
66 b 20-6, 26-30
BOOK
68'
CHAPTERS
II,
and being mistaken about the same thing, provided that his knowledge and his error are not contrary. And this happens also to the man whose knowledge is limited to each of the premisses and who has not previously considered the particular question. For when he thinks that the mule is with foal he has not the knowledge in the sense of its actual ex[10] ercise, nor on the other hand has his thought caused an error contrary to his knowledge: for the error contrary to the knowledge of the universal would be a syllogism. But he who thinks the essence of good is the essence of bad will think the same thing to be the essence of good and the essence of bad. Let A stand for the essence of good and B for the essence of bad, and again C for the essence of [75] good. Since then he thinks B and C identical, he will think that C is B, and similarly that B is A, consequently that C is A. For just as we saw that if B is true of all of which C is true, and A is true of all of which B is true, A is
true of C, similarly with the
word
'think'.
[20] Similarly also with the word 'is'; for we saw that if C is the same as B, and B as A, C is the same as A. Similarly therefore with 'opine'.
Perhaps then
this
will grant the first point. is
false,
that
is
necessary
if
a
man
But presumably that
any one could suppose the
es-
sence of good to be the essence of bad, save [25] incidentally. For it is possible to think this in
many
different ways.
But we must con-
sider this matter better.
22
Whenever
the extremes are convertible
it
is
A
A
and C are convertible and C bethen if longs to everything to which A belongs, B is [jo] convertible with A, and B belongs to everything to which A belongs, through C as middle, and C is convertible with B through A as middle. Similarly if the conclusion is negative, e.g. if B belongs to C, but A does not belong to B, neither will A belong to C. If then B is convertible with A, C will be convertible [35] with A. Suppose B does not belong to A; neither then will C: for ex hypothesi B belonged to all C. And if C is convertible with B, B is convertible also with A: for C is said of
which
B
is
vertible in relation to
said.
A
convertible in relation to
68 a
that to
which
B
And
if
C
is
con-
and to B, B also A. For C belongs
belongs: but
belong to that to which
89
alone starts from the conclusion; the preceding moods do not do so as in the affirmative syllo-
A and B are convertible, and C and D, and if A or C must beanything whatever, then B and D will
gism. Again
if
[5] similarly
long to be such that one or other belongs to anything whatever. For since B belongs to that to which A belongs, and belongs to that to which C belongs, and since A or C belongs to everything, but not together, it is clear that B or belongs to everything, but not together. For example if that which is uncreated is incorruptible and that which is incorruptible is un-
D
D
created,
it
is
necessary that
what
is
created
[10] should be corruptible and what is corruptible should have been created. For two syl-
logisms have been put together. Again if A or belongs to everything and if C or belongs to everything, but they cannot belong together,
D
B
and C are convertible B and D For if B does not belong to something to which D belongs, it is clear that [75] A belongs to it. But if A then C: for they are convertible. Therefore C and D belong together. But this is impossible. When A belongs to the whole of B and to C and is affirmed of nothing else, and B also belongs to all C, it is necessary that A and B should be convertible: for since A is said of B and C only, and B [20] is affirmed both of itself and of C, it is clear that B will be said of everything of which A is said, except A itself. Again when A and B belong to the whole of C, and C is convertible then
when
A
are convertible.
with B, it is necessary that A should belong to B: for since A belongs to all C, and C to B by conversion, A will belong to all B.
all
necessary that the middle should be convertible belongs to C through B, with both. For if
that of all of
21-22
A
C
belongs.
is
to
does not
And
this
two opposites A and B, A is and similarly D is preferable to C, then if A and C together are preferable to B and D together, A must be preferable to D. For A is an object of desire to the same extent as B is an object of aversion, since they are opposites: and C is similarly related to D, [25] When, of preferable to B,
since they also are opposites. If then
A
is
an
same extent as D, B is an object of aversion to the same extent as C (since each is to the same extent as each the one an object of aversion, the other an object of desire). Therefore both A and C together, and B and D together, will be equally objects of desire or aversion. But since A and C are preferable to B and D, A cannot be equal[jo] object of desire to the
D
with D; for then B along with desirable with A along with is preferable to A, then B [55] C. But if must be less an object of aversion than C: for ly desirable
would be equally
D
PRIOR ANALYTICS
9o the less
is
opposed
to the less.
But the greater
good and lesser evil are preferable to the lesser good and greater evil: the whole BD then is preferable to the whole AC. But ex hypothesi this is not so. A then is preferable to C consequently is less an object of aversion than B. If then every lover in virtue of his
D, and
[40] love would prefer A, viz. that the beloved should be such as to grant a favour, and yet should not grant it (for which C stands), the beloved's granting the favour (repre-
to
68 b sented by D) without being such
as to
grant it (represented by 5), it is clear that A (being of such a nature) is preferable to granting the favour. To receive affection then is
Love more dependent on friendship than on
preferable in love to sexual intercourse.
then
is
intercourse. [5]
And
if
is
it
Intercourse then either
is
is
not an end at
its
all
end. or
is
relative to the further end, the receiv-
ing of affection.
And
of the other desires
indeed the same
and
is
true
clear then
how
the terms are related in
conversion, and in respect of being in a higher
degree objects of aversion or of desire. We [10] must now state that not only dialectical and demonstrative syllogisms are formed by means of the aforesaid figures, but also rhetorical syllogisms and in general any form of persuasion, however it may be presented. For every belief comes either through syllogism or
from induction. [75]
Now
induction, or rather the syllogism
which springs out
of induction, consists in es-
tablishing syllogistically a relation between one extreme and the middle by means of the other extreme, e.g. if B is the middle term between A and C, it consists in proving through C that
A
belongs to B. For this is the manner in which we make inductions. For example let A stand for long-lived, B for bileless, and C [20] for the particular long-lived animals, e.g. horse, mule. then belongs to the whole
A
man,
of C: for whatever
B
is
bileless is long-lived.
But
also ('not possessing bile') belongs to all C.
C
is convertible with B, and the middle not wider in extension, it is necessary that A should belong to B. For it has already 1 [25] been proved that if two things belong to
If
then
term
is
same thing, and the extreme is convertible with one of them, then the other predicate will belong to the predicate that is converted. the
la 21-25.
clearer to us.
is
24
We
have an 'example' when the major term is proved to belong to the middle by means of a term which resembles the third. It ought to be known both that the middle belongs to the [40] third term, and that the first belongs to that which resembles the third. For example
arts.
23 It is
induction
most dependent on
receiving affection, then this
an end
69*
But we must apprehend C as made up of all the particulars. For induction proceeds through an enumeration of all the cases. [30] Such is the syllogism which establishes the first and immediate premiss: for where there is a middle term the syllogism proceeds through the middle term; when there is no middle term, through induction. And in a way induction is opposed to syllogism: for the latter proves the major term to belong to the third term by means of the middle, the former proves the major to belong to the middle [55] by means of the third. In the order of nature, syllogism through the middle term is prior and better known, but syllogism through
let A be evil, B making war against neigh69 a bours, C Athenians against Thebans, D Thebans against Phocians. If then we wish to prove that to fight with the Thebans is an evil, we must assume that to fight against neighbours is an evil. Evidence of this is obtained from similar cases, e.g. that the war against [5] the Phocians was an evil to the Thebans.
Since then to fight against neighbours is an and to fight against the Thebans is to fight
evil,
against neighbours,
it
Thebans
is
against the that
B
belongs to
C
is
an and
clear that evil.
to
D
Now
to fight it is
clear
(for both are
making war upon
one's neighbours) belongs to (for the war against [jo] the Phocians did not turn out well for the Thebans): but that A belongs to B will be
cases of
and
that
D
A
proved through D. Similarly if the belief in the relation of the middle term to the extreme should be produced by several similar cases. Clearly then to argue by example is neither like reasoning from part to whole, nor like reasoning from whole to part, but rather rea[75] soning from part to part, when both par-
same term, and from induction, because induction starting from all the 2 particular cases proves (as we saw ) that the major term belongs to the middle, and does not apply the syllogistic conclusion to the minor term, whereas argument by example does ticulars are subordinate to the
one of them
2
Chapter
23.
is
known.
It differs
BOOK
70*
make
this application
proof from
all
II,
and does not draw
CHAPTERS its
22-26
we
are opposites, so that that the
the particular cases.
9*
gel the
not subjects of a single science: this proof the third figure: for
[20] By reduction we mean an argument in which the first term clearly belongs to the middle, but the relation of the middle to the last term is uncertain though equally or more
probable than the conclusion; or again an argument in which the terms intermediate between the last term and the middle are few. For in
any of these cases it turns out that we approach more nearly to knowledge. For example let A [25] stand for what can be taught, B for knowledge, C for justice. Now it is clear that
knowledge can be taught: but it is uncertain whether virtue is knowledge. If now the statement BC is equally or more probable than
AC, we have
a reduction: for
we
are nearer to
knowledge, since we have taken a new term, being so far without knowledge that A belongs to C. Or again suppose that the terms intermediate between B and C are few: for [30] thus too we are nearer knowledge. For example let D stand for squaring, E for rectilinear figure, F for circle. If there were only one term intermediate between E and F (viz. that the circle
made equal
is
to a rectilinear
help of lunules), we should be near to knowledge. But when BC is not [35] more probable than AC, and the intermediate terms are not few, I do not call this re-
figure by the
duction: nor again is
when
the statement
immediate: for such a statement
is
BC
knowl-
edge.
objection
An
brought in two ways and
is
through two figures; in two ways because every objection
is
either universal or particular,
by two figures because objections are brought in opposition to the premiss, and opposites can [5] be proved only in the first and third figures. If a man maintains a universal affirmative, we reply with a universal or a particular negative; the former is proved from the first figure, the latter from the third. For example let A stand for there being a single science, B for contraries.
If
a
man
premises that con-
traries are subjects of a single science, the ob-
[10] jection may be either that opposites are never subjects of a single science, and contraries
C
(the
is
in
know-
of a single science.
[75] Similarly if the premiss objected to is negative. For if a man maintains that con-
we
traries are not subjects of a single science,
reply either that contraries, e.g.
opposites or that certain
all
what
is
healthy and what
same from the
is
sickly, are subjects of the
science: the
former argument issues
first,
ter
from the third
In general
if
a
the
lat-
figure.
man
urges a universal objec-
[20] tion he must frame his contradiction with reference to the universal of the terms taken by
opponent,
his
e.g.
if
a
man
maintains that
same science, opponent must reply that there is a single science of all opposites. Thus we must have the first figure: for the term which embraces the original subject becomes the middle term. contraries are not subjects of the his
the objection
If
must frame a
term
is
particular, the objector
his contradiction
relatively to
ponent's premiss
is
with reference to
which the subject of
his op-
universal, e.g. he will point
[25] out that the knowable and the unknowable are not subjects of the same science: 'contraries' is universal relatively to these.
And we
have the third figure: for the particular term assumed is middle, e.g. the knowable and the unknowable. Premisses from which it is possi-
draw the contrary conclusion are what from when we try to make objec-
start
[30] tions. Consequently
ticular at all or not in universal syllogisms.
69 b
true of
traries,
we 26
it is
and the unknowable) that they are conand it is false that they are the subjects
able
ble to
An objection is a premiss contrary to a premiss. It differs from a premiss, because it may be particular, but a premiss either cannot be par-
or
first figure,
knowable and the unknowable are
we
bring objections them only are opposite syllogisms possible, since the second figure cannot produce an affirmative concluin these figures only: for in
sion.
Besides, an objection in the middle figure
would require
a fuller
argument,
e.g.
if
it
should not be granted that A belongs to B, because C does not follow B. This can be made [55] clear only by other premisses. But an objection ought not to turn off into other things, but have its new premiss quite clear immediately. For this reason also this is the only figure from which proof by signs cannot be obtained. We must consider later the other kinds of
namely the objection from contrafrom similars, and from common opinion, 70* and inquire whether a particular objection cannot be elicited from the first figure or a negative objection from the second. objection, ries,
PRIOR ANALYTICS
92
70 b
essary that she should be with child.
27
A
and a sign are not identical, is a generally approved proposition: what men know to happen or not to [5] happen, to be or not to be, for the most part thus and thus, is a probability, e.g. 'the enprobability
but a probability
vious hate', 'the beloved
means
show
A sign
affection'.
a demonstrative proposition necessary
or generally approved: for anything such that when it is another thing is, or when it has into being the other has come into being before or after, is a sign of the other's being or an enthymeme having come into being.
come
Now
[10] is a syllogism starting from probabilities or signs, and a sign may be taken in three ways, corresponding to the position of the middle
term the
in the figures.
first
For
it
may
be taken as in
figure or the second or the third. For
example the proof that a woman is with child because she has milk is in the first figure: for [75] to have milk is the middle term. Let A represent to be with child, B to have milk, C that wise men are good, good, comes through the last figure. Let A stand for good, B for wise men, C for Pittacus. It is true then to affirm both A and B of C: only men do not say the latter, because they know it, though they state the for[20] mer. The proof that a woman is with
woman. The proof
since Pittacus
is
child because she
is
pale
is
meant
to
come
through the middle figure: for since paleness follows women with child and is a concomitant of this woman, people suppose it has been proved that she is with child. Let A stand for paleness, B for being with child, C for woman. Now if the one proposition is stated, we have [25] only a sign, but
if
the other
well, a syllogism, e.g. 'Pittacus
is
stated as
generous,
is
men are generous and Pittacus Or again 'Wise men are good,
since ambitious is
ambitious.'
since Pittacus
is
not only good but wise.' In this
way then syllogisms are formed, only that which proceeds through the if it is
true (for
it
is
first
figure
is
irrefutable
universal), that
[jo] proceeds through the last figure
is
which refuta-
ble even
if the conclusion is true, since the syllogism is not universal nor correlative to the matter in question: for though Pittacus is good, it is not therefore necessary that all other wise men should be good. But the syllogism which proceeds through the middle figure is always
refutable in any case: for a syllogism can never
[35] be formed
when
the terms are related in
way: for though a woman with child is pale, and this woman also is pale, it is not necthis
Truth
then may be found in signs whatever their kind, but they have the differences we have stated. b
70
We
stated,
must either divide signs in the way and among them designate the middle
term as the index (for people call that the index which makes us know, and the middle term above all has this character), or else we must call the arguments derived from the extremes signs, that derived from the middle term the index: for that which is proved [5] through the first figure is most generally accepted and most true. It is possible to infer character from features, if it is granted that the body and the soul are changed together by the natural affections: I say 'natural', for though perhaps by learning music a man has made some change in his [10] soul, this is not one of those affections
which are natural to us; rather I refer to pasand desires when I speak of natural emotions. If then this were granted and also that for each change there is a corresponding sign, and we could state the affection and sign proper to each kind of animal, we shall be able to infer character from features. For if there is an affection which belongs properly to an individsions
[75] ual kind, e.g. courage to lions, it is necessary that there should be a sign of it: for ex
hypothesi body and soul are affected together.
Suppose
this sign
is
the possession of large ex-
may
belong to other kinds also though not universally. For the sign is proper in the sense stated, because the affection is proper to the whole kind, though not proper to it alone, according to our usual manner of [20] speaking. The same thing then will be found in another kind, and man may be brave, and some other kinds of animal as well. They will then have the sign: for ex hypothesi there is one sign corresponding to each affection. If then this is so, and we can collect signs of this sort in these animals which have only one afbut each affection has fection proper to them its sign, since it is necessary that it should have [25] a single sign we shall then be able to infer character from features. But if the kind as a whole has two properties, e.g. if the lion is both brave and generous, how shall we know which of the signs which are its proper concomitants is the sign of a particular affection? Perhaps if both belong to some other kind though not to the whole of it, and if, in those kinds in which each is found though not in the tremities: this
—
—
whole of
their
members, some members pos-
BOOK
70 b sess
II,
CHAPTER
one of the affections and not die other:
man
brave but not generous, but two signs, large extremities, it is clear that this is the sign of courage in the lion also. To judge character from fea-
e.g. if a
is
[jo] possesses, of the
tures, then,
is
middle term treme, but
is
possible in the first figure
if
the
convertible with the first exwider than the third term and
is
27
not convertible with courage,
93 it:
e.g. let
A
stand for
B for large extremities, and C for lion,
[55] B then belongs to everything to which C belongs, but also to others. But A belongs to
everything to which B belongs, and to nothing besides, but is convertible with B: otherwise, there would not be a single sign correlative with each affection.
CONTENTS: POSTERIOR ANALYTICS BOOK
timate subject fixed? (3) supposing both priattribute and ultimate subject fixed?
I
mary BERLIN NOS.
CHAP. i.
The
knowledge; 2.
7i a
student's need of pre-existent its
yi b 8
meaning
Enunciation,
Contradiction,
82 s 36 demonstration cannot develop an indefinite regress, then negative
21. If affirmative
demonstration cannot
Proposition,
Axiom, Hypothesis,
Basic truth, Thesis,
Defi-
Two
erroneous views of
72 b 5
scientific
futility of circular
attribute: 'True in every in-
73 s 21 25.
Causes through which
we
ously suppose a conclusion
when
universal
it
is
not;
errone-
74
s
26.
4
commensurate and
how
to avoid this
27.
The
premisses of demonstration must
74 b 5
28.
be necessary and essential 7.
The
premisses and conclusion of a
demonstration must
fall
75
s
38
86 a 31
and nega- 87 s
The
superiority of affirmative
live
demonstration to reductio ad itnpossibile
The more
abstract science
What
is
the prior
1
87 s 31
science
constitutes the unity of a
87 s 38
Chance conjunctions are not demon-
there
tions of
may
be several demonstra-
8715 5
one connexion 87b 18
strable
Only
eternal connexions can be demonstrated Demonstration must proceed from
The The
superiority of affirmative to nega-
30.
within a single genus;
b 2i
31.
75 b 36
32.
75
different sorts of basic truth
function of the
common
axioms
There can be no demonstration through sense-perception Different sciences must possess differ-
87b 27 88 a 17
ent basic truths
cept in the case of subalternate sciences
11.
The
How
the basic premisses peculiar to each science, ex-
10.
12
demonstration
29.
tion
9.
84 b 3 85**
science
the three constituent elements of demonstra-
8.
82 b 36
in the nega-
superiority of universal to particu-
and the more accurate
error 6.
is
dvc demonstration
versal', 'Accidental' 5.
The lar
'Commensurate and uni-
'Essential',
(2)
23. Corollaries 24.
Types of
and
tive
demonstra-
tion
stance',
analytic proofs that
the answer to both (1)
knowledge; the 4.
and
22. Dialectical
nition 3.
(2) are
tive
nature of scientific knowledge;
of
tively,
I
nature
the conditions of demonstration; the
The
82 a 2i answered negabe in the negathe answer to (3) must
and
20. If (1)
33.
76 s 31 a
34.
77 5
The
relation of opinion to
knowledge
Quick wit: the faculty of instantaneously hitting upon the middle term
88 b 30
89b 10
in demonstration s 77 36
12.
The
13.
form; formal fallacy; the growth of a science The difference between knowledge 78 s 22
scientific
of the fact 14.
The
first
scientific
premiss in interrogative
and knowledge
figure
is
2.
s 16
3.
The four possible forms of inquiry 89b 21 They all concern the middle term 89 b 36 The difference between definition and 90 s 35
4.
Essential nature cannot be
the true type of
79
1.
demonstration
syllogism a
Immediate negative propositions
16.
Ignorance as erroneous inference
17.
Ignorance as erroneous inference when the premisses are mediate Ignorance as the negation of knowl-
the premisses are
when
79 33 b 79 23
immediate
5.
8ob 16 6.
8i a 37
(1)
indefi-
Attempts
to
definition of
8i b 10
supposing the
primary attribute fixed? (2) supposing the
Essential nature cannot be inferred by
9i b
1
prove a thing's essential
92 s 6
nature either hypothetically or through the
7.
Can demonstration develop an
91 s 12
division
edge, e.g. such as must result from the lack of
nite regress of premisses,
demon-
strated
a sense 19.
II
of the reasoned fact
15.
18.
BOOK
ul-
8.
95
its
contrary beg the question
Definition does not touch the question 92 s 33 of existence; demonstration proves existence;
hence definition cannot demonstrate Yet only demonstration can reveal the
93 s
1
CONTENTS
96 essential nature of things
other than themselves 9-
That which premisses
10. 1
1.
12.
—
is is
—
which have
i.e.
self-caused
15
— the
basic
several causes as
93 21
16.
question of time in causal infer-
a 94 20
17.
a 95 io
How How
98 s 24
the effect
is
present,
is
the cause
where cause and
effect are
Different causes
may produce
effect,
is
s
98 35 impossible
commensurate s
the 99 1 but not in things specifically iden-
tical
to obtain the definition of a sub-
96 a 2o
18.
stance; the use of division for this purpose 14.
If
same
ence 13-
will often serve to prove
also present? Plurality of causes
93b 28
middle terms
One middle
several connexions
grasped immediately
Types of definition
The The
cause
attributes
to select a
demonstration
connexion for
98
19.
99b true cause of a connexion is the 7 proximate and not the more universal cause How the individual mind comes to 99b i5
The
know
the basic truths
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS BOOK
I
are not predicable of anything else as subject)
7l a
All
instruction given or received by
way
are only learnt in this way,
all
matical sciences and
all
as subject to a major. Before
The mathe-
the species of such instruction.
other speculative disci-
[25] elusion,
known
the clearly
enthymeme,
sume
particular.
a
[75] of the
means to
so
make
meaning
and
so;
as
you says
regards
the double assumption
of the
word and
the ex-
The
Recognition of a truth
may
in
tain as factors both previous also
some cases conknowledge and
knowledge acquired simultaneously with
that recognition
—knowledge,
that he
came
to
know
the semicircle' to
'this figure
be a
triangle.
not.
how
1
in the
A man is asked, 'Do you, or do know that every pair is even?' He he does know it. The questioner then pronot,
form
'every
number which you know
[5] construed as applicable to
instance of the thing.
to
On
any and every
the other hand,
I imnothing to prevent a man in one sense knowing what he is learning, in another not knowing it. The strange thing would be, not if in some sense he knew what he was learning, but if he were to know it in that precise sense and manner in which he was learning it.
agine there
him
inscribed in
For some
Note: The bold face numbers and letters are approximate indications of the pages and columns of the standard Berlin Greek text; the bracketed numbers, of the lines in the Greek text; they are here assigned as they Oxford
manner
be such', or 'every rectilinear figure which you know to be such': the predicate is always
things (viz. the singulars finally reached which
are assigned in the
in a
the existence of this triangle,
dilemma
in the
this latter, of the
under the universal and therein already virtually known. For example, the student knew beforehand that the [20] angles of every triangle are equal to two right angles; but it was only at the actual moment at which he was being led on to recogparticulars actually falling
nize this as true in the instance before
a con-
duces a particular pair, of the existence, and so a fortiori of the evenness, of which he was unaware. The solution which some people offer is to assert that they do not know that every pair is even, but only that everything which they 71 b know to be a pair is even: yet what they know to be even is that of which they have demonstrated evenness, i.e. what they made the subject of their premiss, viz. not merely every triangle or number which they know to be such, but any and every number or triangle without reservation. For no premiss is ever couched
reason is that these several objects are not equally obvious to us. istence of the thing.
drew
should perhaps say that in a
people offer.
that every predicate can be either truly
we have
he was led on to
Meno: either a man will learn nothing or what he already knows; for [50] we cannot accept the solution which some the
affirmed or truly denied of any subject, and 'unit'
here no
could he know without qualification that its angles were equal to two right angles? No: clearly he \nows not without qualification but only in the sense that he \nows universally. If this distinction is not drawn, we are faced with
pre-existent
that 'triangle'
\now
term
form of syllogism. knowledge required is of two kinds. In some cases admission of the fact must be assumed, in others comprehension of the meaning of the term used, and sometimes both assumptions are essential. Thus, we as-
The
is
he did not in an unqualified sense of the
If
Again, the persuasion exerted by rhetorical arguments is in principle the same, since they [10] use either example, a kind of induction, or
we
manner he knew,
premisses, induction exhibiting the universal in
there
recognition or before he actually
plines are acquired in this way, and so are the two forms of dialectical reasoning, syllogistic [5] and inductive; for each of these latter make use of old knowledge to impart new, the syllogism assuming an audience that accepts its as implicit
i.e.
recognition through a middle of a minor term
argument proceeds from pre-existent knowledge. This becomes evident upon a survey of
of
We
is
suppose ourselves to possess unqualified knowledge of a thing, as opposed to
scientific 1
translation.
97
Plato,
Meno, 80
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS
98
knowing
it
in the accidental
way
in
which the
[10] sophist knows, when we think that we know the cause on which the fact depends, as
the cause of that fact and of no other, and, further, that the fact could not be other than it
Now
is.
that scientific
—
knowing
is
something
evident witness both those who and those who actually possess it, since the former merely imagine themselves to be, while the latter are also actually, in the condition described. Consequently the proper of this sort
is
claim
falsely
it
[75] object of unqualified scientific knowledge something which cannot be other than it is.
is
There may be another manner of knowing as well
—that
What I we do know by
will be discussed later.
now
1
assert is that at all events demonstration. By demonstration I mean a syllogism productive of scientific knowledge, a syllogism, that is, the grasp of which is eo ipso such knowledge. Assuming then that my the-
the nature of scientific
sis as to
knowing
is
cor-
premisses of demonstrated knowledge must be true, primary, immediate, better known than and prior to the conclusion, [20]
which
the
rect,
further related to
is
them
as effect to
cause. Unless these conditions are satisfied, the basic truths will not be 'appropriate'
to the
Syllogism there may indeed be without these conditions, but such syllogism, not being productive of scientific knowledge, will not be demonstration. The premisses must conclusion.
[25] be true: for that
known
non-existent
—we cannot know,
demonknowledge must be primary, I mean that they must be the 'appropriate' basic truths, for I identify primary premiss and basic
other. In saying that the premisses of strated
A 'basic truth' in a demonstration is an immediate proposition. An immediate proposition is one which has no other proposition prior to it. A proposition is either part of an
truth.
enunciation,
i.e. it
predicates a single attribute
of a single subject. If a proposition
[10]
dialecti-
is
assumes either part indifferently demonstrative, it lays down one part to
cal,
if it is
it
the definite exclusion of the other because that part
The term
'enunciation' denotes
ei-
ther part of a contradiction indifferently.
A
true.
is
contradiction
is
an opposition which of
its
own
nature excludes a middle. The part of a contradiction which conjoins a predicate with a
an affirmation; the part disjoining I call an immediate basic [75] truth of syllogism a 'thesis' when, though it is not susceptible of proof by the teacher, yet subject
them
is
is
a negation.
ignorance of it does not constitute a total bar to progress on the part of the pupil: one which the pupil must know if he is to learn anything
whatever
is
an axiom.
I
call it
cause there are such truths and the
name
an axiom be-
we
give
them
of axioms par excellence. If a thesis
e.g. that
assumes one part or the other of an enuncia[20] tion, i.e. asserts either the existence or the non-existence of a subject, it is a hypothesis; if
the diagonal of a square side.
is
are those further from sense. Now the most universal causes are furthest from sense and particular causes are nearest to sense, and [5] they are thus exactly opposed to one an-
known
commensurate with The premisses must be primary and
cannot be its
which
72*
is
indemonstrable; otherwise they will require demonstration in order to be known, since to have knowledge, if it be not accidental knowledge, of things which are demonstrable, means precisely to have a demonstration of them. The premisses must be the causes of the conclusion, better known than it, and prior to it; its causes,
it
does not so assert,
tion
is
it is
a definition. Defini-
a 'thesis' or a 'laying
since the arithmetician lays
a unit
is
something down', it
down
that to be
to be quantitatively indivisible; but
it
this
not a hypothesis, for to define what a unit is is not the same as to affirm its existence. [25] Now since the required ground of our knowledge i.e. of our conviction of a fact is the possession of such a syllogism as we call demonstration, and the ground of the syllo-
antecedent knowledge being not our mere understanding of the meaning, but knowledge of
gism is the facts constituting its premisses, we must not only know the primary premisses
Now 'prior' and 'better known* ambiguous terms, for there is a difference between what is prior and better known in the 72 a order of being and what is prior and better known to man. I mean that objects nearer to sense are prior and better known to man; objects without qualification prior and better
some if not all of them beforehand, but know them better than the conclusion: for the cause
[30] since we possess scientific knowledge of a thing only when we know its cause; prior, in order to be causes; antecedently
known,
the fact as well. are
1
Cf. the following chapter and
ch. 19.
more
particularly
11,
is
—
—
—
of an attribute's inherence in a subject always itself
inheres in the subject
more firmly than
that attribute; e.g. the cause of our loving anyis dearer to us than the object of our [50] love. So since the primary premisses are i.e. of our convicthe cause of our knowledge
thing
tion
—
—
it
follows that
we know them
better
BOOK
7V that
more convinced
are
is,
of
them
I,
CHAPTERS
—than
their consequences, precisely because of our
knowledge knowledge
of the latter
is
the effect of our
of the premisses. Now a man cannot believe in anything more than in the things he knows, unless he has either actual
knowledge of
it
or something better than ac-
knowledge. But we are faced with this [35] paradox if a student whose belief rests on demonstration has not prior knowledge; a man must believe in some, if not in all, of the basic truths more than in the conclusion. Moreover, tual
a
if
man
sets
out to acquire the scientific
knowledge that comes through demonstration, he must not only have a better knowledge of the basic truths and a firmer conviction of them than of the connexion which is being 72 b demonstrated: more than this, nothing must be more certain or better known to him than these basic truths in their character as fundamental premisses the contradicting which lead to the opposed and erroneous conclusion. For indeed the conviction of pure science must be unshakable.
[5] Some hold that, owing to the necessity of knowing the primary premisses, there is no sci-
knowledge. Others think there is, but that all truths are demonstrable. Neither doctrine is either true or a necessary deduction from the premisses. The first school, assuming that there is no way of knowing other than by demonstration, maintain that an infinite regress is involved, on the ground that if behind the prior stands no primary, we could not [10] know the posterior through the prior (wherein they are right, for one cannot traverse an infinite series): if on the other hand they the series terminates and there are primary say entific
—
—
unknowable because incapable of demonstration, which according to them is the only form of knowledge. And since premisses, yet these are
thus one cannot know the primary premisses, knowledge of the conclusions which follow
from them properly
is
not pure scientific knowledge nor at all, but rests on the mere
knowing
supposition that the premisses are true.
The
[75] other party agree with them as regards knowing, holding that it is only possible by
demonstration, but they see no difficulty in holding that all truths are demonstrated, on the ground that demonstration may be circular
and
reciprocal.
Our own is
knowledge demonstrative: on the contrary, knowledge doctrine
is
that not
all
of the
2-3
99
immediate premisses
is
independent of
[20] demonstration. (The necessity of this is obvious; for since we must know the prior premisses from which the demonstration is drawn, and since the regress must end in im-
mediate truths, those truths must be indemonSuch, then, is our doctrine, and in addition we maintain that besides scientific
strable.)
knowledge there is its originative source which enables us to recognize the definitions. demonstration must be based on [25]
Now
premisses prior to and better known than the conclusion; and the same things cannot simultaneously be both prior and posterior to one another: so circular demonstration
is
clearly
not possible in the unqualified sense of 'demonstration', but only possible if 'demonstration' be extended to include that other method of
argument which
on a distinction between and truths without qualification prior, i.e. the method by which induction [jo] produces knowledge. But if we accept this extension of its meaning, our definition of unqualified knowledge will prove faulty; for there seem to be two kinds of it. Perhaps, however, the second form of demonstration, that which proceeds from truths better known to rests
truths prior to us
us,
is
not demonstration in the unqualified
sense of the term.
The advocates of circular demonstration are not only faced with the difficulty we have just stated: in addition their theory reduces to the mere statement that if a thing exists, then it does exist an easy way of proving anything.
—
That
this is so can be clearly shown by taking three terms, for to constitute the circle
[55]
makes no difference whether many terms or few or even only two are taken. Thus by direct proof, if A is, B must be; if B is, C must be; therefore if A is, C must be. Since then by the circular proof if A is, B must be, and if 73 a B is, A must be, A may be substituted for C above. Then 'if B is, A must be' 'if B is, C must be', which above gave the conclusion 'if A is, C must be': but C and A have been identified. Consequently the upholders of cirit
—
—
=
cular demonstration are in the position of sayis, must be a simple way [5] ing that if
A
A
—
of proving anything. Moreover, even such cir-
cular demonstration
is
impossible except in the
case of attributes that imply one another, viz. 'peculiar' properties.
Now, it has been shown that the positing of one thing be it one term or one premiss never involves a necessary consequent: two
—
1
1
Prior Analytics,
I,
25.
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS
100
[10] premisses constitute the first and smallest foundation for drawing a conclusion at all and therefore a fortiori for the demonstrative syllogism of science. If, then, A is implied in B and C, and B and C are reciprocally implied in one another and in A, it is possible, as has been
shown prove
all
my
1
writings on the syllogism, to the assumptions on which the original
in
conclusion rested, by circular demonstration in [75] the first figure. But it has also been shown that in the other figures either no conclusion
is
possible,
or at
none which
least
2 proves both the original premisses. Proposinot convertible which are the terms of tions
73 b
which they belong
tain subjects, the subjects to
are contained in the attribute's
Thus
own
defining
and curved belong to [40] line, odd and even, prime and compound, square and oblong, to number; and also 73 b the formula defining any one of these at-
formula.
straight
tributes contains
ber as the case
Extending tributes,
its
may
subject
—
e.g. line or
num-
be.
this classification to all other at-
distinguish those that answer the
I
above description as belonging essentially to their respective subjects; whereas attributes re-
two ways
lated in neither of these jects
I call
to their sub-
accidents or 'coincidents'; e.g. musi-
cannot be circularly demonstrated at all, and since convertible terms occur rarely in actual demonstrations, it is clearly frivolous and impossible to say that demonstration is reciprocal [20] and that therefore everything can be
cal or
demonstrated.
as substance, in the sense of
white
is
a 'coincident' of animal.
[5] Further (a) that is essential which is not predicated of a subject other than itself: e.g. 'the
walking [thing]' walks and
is
white in
virtue of being something else besides; where-
whatever signifies somewhat', is not what it is in virtue of being something else besides. Things, then, not a 'this
Since the object of pure scientific knowledge cannot be other than it is, the truth obtained by demonstrative knowledge will be necessary. And since demonstrative knowledge is only present when we have a demonstration, it follows that demonstration is an inference from necessary premisses. So
we must
consider
are the premisses of demonstration
[25] is their character: let us define what we
and
—
i.e.
what what
as a preliminary,
mean by an
attribute
an 'essenand a 'commensurate and uni-
'true in every instance of its subject', tial'
attribute,
versal' attribute.
what one
is
I call
'true in every instance'
truly predicable of all instances
to the exclusion of others
—and
—not of
at all times,
not at this or that time only; e.g. if animal is [_?o] truly predicable of every instance of man, then if it be true to say 'this is a man', 'this is an animal' is also true, and if the one be true now the other is true now. corresponding account holds if point is in every instance predicable as contained in line. There is evidence for
A
this
in the
fact that the objection
we
raise
against a proposition put to us as true in every instance is either an instance in which, or an occasion on which, it is not true. Essential attributes are (1) such as belong to their subtil ) ect as elements in its essential nature (e.g.
predicated of a subject predicated of a subject
call essential;
things
call accidental
or 'co-
I I
incidental'.
[10] In another sense again (b) a thing consequentially connected with anything is essential; one not so connected is 'coincidental'. An example of the latter is 'While he was walking it lightened': the lightning was not due to his walking; it was, we should say, a coincidence. If, on the other hand, there is a consequential
connexion, the predication
when
is
essential; e.g.
if
a
being cut, then its death is also essentially connected with the cut[75] ting, because the cutting was the cause of death, not death a 'coincident' of the cutting. So far then as concerns the sphere of connexions scientifically known in the unqualified sense of that term, all attributes which (within that sphere) are essential either in the sense that their subjects are contained in them, or in the sense that they are contained in their sub-
beast dies
jects,
its
throat
is
are necessary as well as consequentially
connected with their subjects. For it is impossible for them not to inhere in their subjects either simply or in the qualified sense that one or other of a pair of opposites must inhere in [20] the subject; e.g. in line must be either straightness or curvature, in
number
either
the very being or 'substance' of triangle
oddness or evenness. For within a single identical genus the contrary of a given attribute is
is
either
line): (2) such that, while they
not odd is even, inasmuch as within this sphere even is a necessary consequent of not-odd. So, since any given
line thus belongs to triangle, point to line; for
and line composed of these elements, which are contained in the formulae defining triangle and 1
Ibid., 11, 5.
2 Ibid., 11,
5 and 6.
belong to cer-
within
its
privative or
number what
is
its
contradictory; e.g.
BOOK
74*
must be
predicate
any
I,
CHAPTERS
either affirmed or. denied of
subject, essential attributes
must inhere
in
their subjects of necessity.
we have established the disbetween the attribute which is 'true in every instance' and the 'essential' attribute. I term 'commensurately universal' an attribute which belongs to every instance of its subject, and to every instance essentially and as such; from which it clearly follows that all commensurate universals inhere necessarily in their subjects. The essential attribute, and the [25] Thus, then,
tinction
attribute that belongs to identical. E.g. point
and
its
subject as such, are
straight belong to line
[30] essentially, for they belong to line as such; and triangle as such has two right angles, for
equal to two right angles. An attribute belongs commensurately and universally to a subject when it can be shown to belong to any random instance of that subject and when the subject is the first thing to which it can be shown to belong. Thus, e.g. it is
essentially
(1) the equality of its angles to two right anis not a commensurately universal attri-
gles
bute of figure. For though it is possible to [35] show that a figure has its angles equal to two right angles, this attribute cannot be demonstrated of any figure selected at haphazard,
nor in demonstrating does one take a figure at random a square is a figure but its angles are not equal to two right angles. On the other hand, any isosceles triangle has its angles equal
—
to
two right
angles, yet isosceles triangle
is
not
the primary subject of this attribute but triangle
is
prior.
So whatever can be shown
to
have
[40] its angles equal to two right angles, or to possess any other attribute, in any random in-
—
and primarily that is the first which the predicate in question belongs commensurately and universally,
stance of itself subject to
74 a and the demonstration, in the essential sense, of any predicate is the proof of it as belonging to this first subject commensurately and universally:
while the proof of
the other subjects to
which
it
as
belonging to
is demand unessential equality to two right it
attaches
onstration only in a secondary sense.
Nor
again (2)
is
angles a commensurately universal attribute of isosceles;
We fall
it is
of wider application.
must not
fail
that
we
the sense in
We
is
often not in
primary and commensurately univerwhich we think we prove it make this mistake ( 1 ) when the subject
[5] fact sal in so.
to observe
into error because our conclusion
3-5
101
an individual or individuals above which there is no universal to be found: (2) when the subjects belong to different species and there is a higher universal, but it has no name: (3) when the subject which the demonstrator takes as a whole is really only a part of a larger whole; for then the demonstration will be true is
[10] of the individual instances within the part and will hold in every instance of it, yet the demonstration will not be true of this subject
primarily and commensurately and uni-
versally.
subject
When
universally, that is
a demonstration
primarily and is
is
true of a
commensurately and
to be taken to
true of a given subject primarily
mean and
that
it
as such.
Case (3) may be thus exemplified. If a proof were given that perpendiculars to the same line are parallel, it might be supposed that lines thus perpendicular were the proper subject of the demonstration because being parallel is true of every instance of them. But it is not so, [75] for the parallelism depends not on these angles being equal to one another because each is a right angle, but simply on their being equal to one another. An example of ( 1 ) would be as follows: if isosceles were the only triangle, it would be thought to have its angles equal to
two right angles qua isosceles. An instance of (2) would be the law that proportionals alternate. Alternation used to be
demonstrated sepnumbers, lines, solids, and durations, though it could have been proved of [20] them all by a single demonstration. Be-
arately of
was no single name to denote that which numbers, lengths, durations, and solids are identical, and because they differed specifically from one another, this property was proved of each of them separately. To-day, however, the proof is commensurately universal, for they do not possess this attribute qua lines or qua numbers, but qua manifesting this generic character which they are postulated as cause there in
[25] possessing universally. Hence, even if one prove of each kind of triangle that its angles are equal to two right angles, whether by
means
of the
same or
different proofs;
still,
as
long as one treats separately equilateral, scalene, and isosceles, one does not yet know, except sophistically, that triangle has its angles equal to two right angles, nor does one yet know that triangle has this property commensurately and universally, even if there is no other species of triangle but these. For one does [50] not know that triangle as such has this property, nor even that 'all' triangles have it unless 'all' means 'each taken singly': if 'all'
—
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS
102
means 'as a whole class', none in which one does not recognize
then, though there be
property, one does not
When,
know
it
of
'all
this
triangles'.
knowledge fail of commensurate universality, and when it is unqualified knowledge? If triangle be identical in then, does our
with each or
essence with equilateral,
i.e.
equilaterals, then clearly
we have
knowledge:
if
on the other hand
all
75*
necessary premisses. For though you may reason from true premisses without demonstrat-
your premisses are necessary you demonstrate in such necessity you have at once a distinctive character of demonstration. That demonstration proceeds from necessary premisses is also indicated by the ing, yet
if
—
will assuredly
unqualified
fact that the objection
be not, and
fessed demonstration
it
the attribute belongs to equilateral qua trianle; then our knowledge fails of commensurate
55] universality. 'But', it will be asked, 'does belong to the subject of which it
we
is
raise against a pro-
that a premiss of
so far as our opponent's previous
shows how naive
this attribute
goes. This
has been demonstrated qua triangle or qua isosceles? What is the point at which the sub-
one's basic truths rightly chosen
ject to
what
which
belongs
it
subject can
it
primary?
is
(i.e.
to
be demonstrated as belong-
ing commensurately and universally?)' Clearly this point is the first term in which it is found to inhere as the elimination of inferior differentiae proceeds. Thus the angles of a
brazen
equal to two right
isosceles triangle are
and isosceles and the attribute remains. 'But' you may say 74 b 'eliminate figure or limit, and the attribute vanishes.' True, but figure and limit are not the first differentiae whose elimination destroys the attribute. 'Then what is the first?' If angles: but eliminate brazen
—
it is
triangle,
it
will be in virtue of triangle that
the attribute belongs to
which
it is
predicable,
the other subjects of
all
and
triangle
is
the sub-
which it can be demonstrated as belonging commensurately and universally.
ject to
it is
—
whether we think [20] not a necessary truth it altogether devoid of necessity, or at any rate it
is
argument to suppose
if one starts with a proposition which is (1) popularly accepted and (2) true, such as the sophists' assumption that to know is the same as to possess knowledge. For (1) popular acceptance or re1
jection
is
no
criterion of a basic truth,
which
can only be the primary law of the genus constituting the subject matter of the demonstra[25] tion; and (2) not all truth is 'appropriate'. further proof that the conclusion must be
A
the development of necessary premisses follows.
Where demonstration
is
is
possible,
as
one
who can give no account which includes the cause has no scientific knowledge. If, then, we suppose a syllogism in which, though essarily inheres in C, yet B, the
the demonstration,
is
A
nec-
middle term of
not necessarily connected
A
and C, then the man who argues thus [jo] has no reasoned knowledge of the conclu-
with
sion, since this conclusion does not
owe
its
ne-
middle term; for though the conclusion is necessary, the mediating link is a contingent fact. Or again, if a man is without knowledge now, though he still retains the steps of the argument, though there is no change in himself or in the fact and no lapse of memory on his part; then neither had he knowledge previously. But the mediating link, not being necessary, may have perished in the [^5] interval; and if so, though there be no change in him nor in the fact, and though he will still retain the steps of the argument, yet he has not knowledge, and therefore had not knowledge before. Even if the link has not accessity to the
[5]
Demonstrative knowledge must
rest
on
necessary basic truths; for the object of scientific knowledge cannot be other than it is.
Now
attributes attaching essentially to their subjects
attach necessarily to them: for essential attributes are either elements in the essential nature of their subjects, or contain their subjects as
elements in their pairs of opposites
own
essential nature.
which the
are necessary because one
(The
latter class includes
member
or the other
[10] necessarily inheres.) It follows from this that premisses of the demonstrative syllogism
must be connexions plained: for tially or else
all
essential in the sense ex-
attributes
be accidental,
must inhere essenand accidental attri-
butes are not necessary to their subjects.
We
must
either state the case thus, or else
premise that the conclusion of demonstration is necessary and that a demonstrated conclusion cannot be other than it is, and then infer that [75] the conclusion must be developed from
tually perished but
is
liable to perish, this situ-
and might occur. But such a condition cannot be knowledge. 75 a When the conclusion is necessary, the middle through which it was proved may yet ation
is
possible
You can in fact even from a non-necessary you can infer the true from the
quite easily be non-necessary. infer the necessary
premiss, just as 1
Plato, Euthydemus, 277.
BOOK
75 b not true. is
On
the other hand,
necessary the conclusion
when
I,
CHAPTERS
the middle
must be necessary;
[5] just as true premisses always give a true is necessarily predicated conclusion. Thus, if
A
of
B and B
of C, then
cated of C. But
when
A
is
necessarily predi-
the conclusion
is
non-
necessary the middle cannot be necessary eibe predicated non-necessarily ther. Thus: let
A
[10] of C but necessarily of B, necessary predicate of C; then
necessary predicate of C, it is
and
let
B
be a
which
too will be a by hypothesis
up, then: demonstrative knowledge must be knowledge of a necessary nexus, and therefore must clearly be obtained through a
To sum
necessary middle term; otherwise its possessor will know neither the cause nor the fact that a necessary connexion.
Either he will mistake the non-necessary for and believe the necessity of the
the necessary
knowing it, or else he will not even believe it in which case he will be equally ignorant, whether he actually infers the mere fact through middle terms or the reaconclusion without
—
soned fact and from immediate premisses. Of accidents that are not essential according to our definition of essential there is no demonstrative knowledge; for since an accident, in [20] the sense in which I here speak of it, may also not inhere, it is impossible to prove its inherence as a necessary conclusion. A difficulty, however, might be raised as to why in dialectic, if the conclusion is not a necessary connexion, such and such determinate premisses should be proposed in order to deal with such and such determinate problems. Would not the result be the same if one asked any questions
whatever and then merely stated one's conclu[25] sion? The solution is that determinate questions have to be put, not because the replies
to
them
facts affirmed
affirm facts
which
necessitate
by the conclusion, but because
these answers are propositions
which
if
the an-
swerer affirm, he must affirm the conclusion and affirm it with truth if they are true. Since it is just those attributes within every genus which are essential and possessed by their respective subjects as such that are necessary, it is clear that both the conclusions and [50] the premisses of demonstrations which
produce
scientific
knowledge are
essential.
For
accidents are not necessary: and, further, since accidents are not necessary one does not necessarily
follows that
It
have reasoned knowledge of a conclusion (this is so even if the acci-
drawn from them
dental premisses are invariable but not essen-
we cannot
from one genus
pass
is
103
through signs; for though the conclusion be actually essential, one will not know it as essential nor know its reason); but [35] to have reasoned knowledge of a conclusion is to know it through its cause. We may conclude that the middle must be consequentially connected with the minor, and the major with the middle. as in proofs
tial,
A
not.
[75] his conclusion
5-7
in demonstrating
to another.
We
for instance, prove geometrical truths
cannot,
by
metic. For there are three elements in
arith-
demon-
[40] stration: (1) what is proved, the conclusion an attribute inhering essentially in a ge-
—
75 b nus; (2) the axioms,
i.e.
axioms which are
premisses of demonstration; (3) the subjectgenus whose attributes, i.e. essential properties, are revealed by the demonstration. The axioms which are premisses of demonstration may be identical in two or more sciences: but in the case of two different genera such as arithmetic and geometry you cannot apply arithmetical demonstration to the properties [5] of magnitudes unless the magnitudes in question are numbers. in certain cases
How
1 will explain later. Arithmetical demonstration and the other
transference
is
possible
I
sciences likewise possess, each of them, their
own
genera; so that
pass
from one sphere
must be
if
the demonstration to another, the
is
to
genus
some extent the not so, transference is clearly impossible, because the extreme and the middle terms must be drawn from the same genus: otherwise, as predicated, they will not either absolutely or to
same.
[10]
If this
is
be essential and will thus be accidents. That is why it cannot be proved by geometry that op-
under one science, nor even that two cubes is a cube. Nor can the theorem of any one science be demonstrated by
posites fall
the product of
[75] means of another science, unless these theorems are related as subordinate to superior (e.g. as optical theorems to geometry or harmonic theorems to arithmetic). Geometry again cannot prove of lines any property which they do not possess qua lines, i.e. in virtue of the fundamental truths of their peculiar genus: it cannot show, for example, that the straight line
is
the most beautiful of lines or the con-
do not belong to lines in virtue of their peculiar genus, but through some property which it shares [20] with other genera. trary of the circle; for these qualities
x
Cf.
1,
9 and 13.
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS
104
76 a
propriate' to
the subject
—unless
we know,
property of possessing angles equal to two right angles as belonging to that subject in e.g. the
It is also clear that if the premisses from which the syllogism proceeds are commensurately universal, the conclusion of such dem-
—demonstration, — must be
onstration
i.e.
in the unquali-
Therefore no attribute can be demonstrated nor known by fied sense
eternal.
also
strictly scientific
ishable things.
knowledge
to inhere in per-
The proof can
only be acciden-
[25] tal, because the attribute's connexion with its perishable subject is not commensurately
universal but temporary and special. If such a demonstration is made, one premiss must be perishable and not commensurately universal (perishable because only if it is perishable will the conclusion be perishable; not commensurately universal, because the predicate will be
which from
and
inheres essentially,
it
basic
premisses
essential
priate' to that subject: so that
if
as inferred
and 'approthat middle
term also belongs essentially to the minor, the middle must belong to the same kind as the major and minor terms. The only exceptions to this rule are such cases as theorems in harmonics which are demonstrable by arithmetic. [10] Such theorems are proved by the same middle terms as arithmetical properties, but with a qualification the fact falls under a separate science (for the subject genus is sep-
—
arate), but the reasoned fact concerns the superior science, to which the attributes essentially belong. Thus, even these apparent excep-
and
tions
show
not of others); so that the conclusion can only be that a fact is true at the moment not com[jo] mensurately and universally. The same is
ic]
strable except
sciences have the requisite identity of char-
true of definitions, since a definition
acter.
predicable of
some
instances of the subject
—
is
either a
primary premiss or a conclusion of a demonstration, or else only differs from a demonstration in the order of its terms. Demonstration and science of merely frequent occurrences are, e.g. of eclipse as happening to the moon as such, clearly eternal: whereas so far as they
—
are not eternal they are not fully
commensu-
[55] rate. Other subjects too have properties attaching to them in the same way as eclipse attaches to the
It is clear
that
moon.
if
the conclusion
is
to
show an dem-
attribute inhering as such, nothing can be
onstrated except from
its
'appropriate' basic
truths. Consequently a proof even from true, indemonstrable, and immediate premisses does [40] not constitute knowledge. Such proof s are like Bryson's method of squaring the circle; for they operate by taking as their middle a common
character
—a
character, therefore,
76 a subject may share with another
which the
—and con-
sequently they apply equally to subjects differThey therefore afford knowledge of an attribute only as inhering accidentally, not as belonging to its subject as such: otherwise they would not have been applicable to another genus.
ent in kind.
Our knowledge
of
any
attribute's
that
is
no
less
attribute
from
its
is
strictly
demon-
'appropriate' basic
however, in the case of these
truths, which,
It
no
evident that the peculiar basic
indemonfrom which they might
truths of each inhering attribute are strable; for basic truths
be deduced would be basic truths of all that is, and the science to which they belonged would possess universal sovereignty. This
knows
is
so be-
whose knowledge is deduced from higher causes, for his knowledge [20] is from prior premisses when it derives from causes themselves uncaused: hence, if he knows better than others or best of all, his knowledge would be science in a higher or the cause he
better
highest degree. But, as things are, demonstrais not transferable to another genus, with such exceptions as we have mentioned of the application of geometrical demonstrations to theorems in mechanics or optics, or of arith[25] metical demonstrations to those of harmonics. It is hard to be sure whether one knows or not; for it is hard to be sure whether one's knowledge is based on the basic truths appropriate to each attribute the differentia of think we have scientific true knowledge. knowledge if we have reasoned from true and primary premisses. But that is not so: the conclusion must be homogeneous with the basic
tion
—
We
[jo] facts of the science.
connexion
with a subject is accidental unless we know that connexion through the middle term in [5] virtue of which it inheres, and as an inference from basic premisses essential and 'ap-
10
the basic truths of every genus those elements in it the existence of which cannot be proved. As regards both these primary truths I
call
BOOK
IT
L
CHAPTERS
and the attributes dependent on them the meaning of the name is assumed. The fact of their existence as regards the primary truths must be assumed; but it has to be proved of the remainder, the attributes. Thus we assume the meaning alike of unity, straight, and tri[35] angular; but while as regards unity and magnitude we assume also the fact of their existence, in the case of the remainder proof is required.
Of
the basic truths used in the demonstrative
8-11
105
Nevertheless in the nature of the case the essential elements of demonstration are three: the subject, the attributes, and the basic premisses. That which expresses necessary self-grounded
and which we must necessarily believe, is both from the hypotheses of a science and from illegitimate postulate I say 'must believe', because all syllogism, and therefore
fact,
distinct
—
a fortiori demonstration, is addressed not to the [25] spoken word, but to the discourse within the soul, and though we can always raise ob-
some are peculiar to each science, and some are common, but common only in the
jections to the
sense of analogous, being of use only in so far province of the science in question.
capable of proof but assumed by the teacher without proof is, if the pupil believes and accepts it, hypothesis, though only in a limited
40] Peculiar truths are, e.g. the definitions of
sense hypothesis
sciences
as they fall within the ]
ine
and
straight;
'take equals
Only
so
genus constituting the
common
truths are such as
from equals and equals remain'.
much
of these
common
truths
is
re-
within the genus in question: 76 b for a truth of this kind will have the same force even if not used generally but applied by the geometer only to magnitudes, or by the arithmetician only to numbers. Also peculiar to quired as
falls
a science are the subjects the existence as well as the meaning of which it assumes, and the essential attributes of
which
it
investigates, e.g.
spoken word,
we cannot always
course
—that
is,
inward disThat which is
to the
object.
relatively to the pu-
[30] pil; if the pupil has no opinion or a contrary opinion on the matter, the same assumption
an illegitimate postulate. Therein
is
the distinction between hypothesis and
mate
postulate: the latter
is
lies
illegiti-
the contrary of the
opinion, demonstrable, but assumed
pupil's
and used without demonstration. [55] The definition viz. those which are not
—
expressed as statements that anything is or is not are not hypotheses: but it is in the prem-
—
isses of a science that its
hypotheses are con-
[5] in arithmetic units, in geometry points and lines. Both the existence and the meaning of
tained. Definitions require only to be under-
the subjects are assumed by these sciences; but
contended that the pupil's hearing is also an hypothesis required by the teacher. Hypoth-
of their essential attributes only the meaning is assumed. For example arithmetic assumes the
meaning
of
odd and even, square and cube,
geometry that of incommensurable, or of deflection or verging of lines, whereas the existence of these attributes is demonstrated by [10] means of the axioms and from previous conclusions as premisses.
Astronomy
too pro-
ceeds in the same way. For indeed every demonstrative science has three elements: (1) that
genus whose essenexamines; (2) the so-called [75] axioms, which are primary premisses of its demonstration; (3) the attributes, the meaning of which it assumes. Yet some sciences may very well pass over some of these elements; e.g. we might not expressly posit the existence of the genus if its existence were obvious (for instance, the existence of hot and cold is more evident than that of number); or we might omit to assume expressly the meaning of the attributes if it were well understood. In the [20] same way the meaning of axioms, such as 'Take equals from equals and equals remain', is well known and so not expressly assumed.
which tial
it
posits, the subject
attributes
it
stood,
eses,
and
this
is
not hypothesis
on the contrary, postulate
—unless
facts
it
on the
be
be-
ing of which depends the being of the fact [40] inferred. Nor are the geometer's hypoth-
some have held, urging that one must not employ falsehood and that the geom-
eses false, as
eter line
is
uttering falsehood in stating that the
which he draws
when
it
is
is
a foot long or straight,
actually neither.
The
truth
is
that
77 a the geometer does not draw any conclusion from the being of the particular line of which he speaks, but from what his diagrams symbolize.
A
further distinction
is
that
all
hy-
potheses and illegitimate postulates are either universal or particular, whereas a definition is neither.
n [5] So demonstration does not necessarily imply the being of Forms nor a One beside a
Many, but
it
bility of truly
without
this
universal, dle
does necessarily imply the possipredicating one of many; since
and
possibility if
we cannot
save the
the universal goes, the mid-
term goes with
it,
and
so demonstration be-
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS
io6
77 h
comes impossible. We conclude, then, that there must be a single identical term unequivocally predicable of a
[w] The law
number
of individuals.
12 If a syllogistic
osition
when the conclusion also has to be expressed in that form; in which case the proof lays down as its major premiss that
clusion
it is
demonstration except
the
major
is
truly affirmed of the
falsely denied. It
ever,
if
we add
makes no
middle but
difference,
how-
to the middle, or again to the
minor term, the corresponding negative. For [75] grant a minor term of which it is true to
man
predicate
—even —
if it
be also true to predi-
not-man of it still grant simply that man animal and not not-animal, and the conclu-
cate is
sion follows: for Callias
it
will
still
—even be — animal and if it
be true to say that
also true to say that not-
not not-animal. The is predicable not only of the middle, but of something other than the middle as well, being of wider appli[20] cation; so that the conclusion is not affected even if the middle is extended to cover the original middle term and also what is not Callias
reason
is
is
that the major term
the original middle term.
The law
that every predicate can be either
truly affirmed or truly denied of every subject is posited by such demonstration as uses reductio ad impossibile, and then not always universally, but so far as it is requisite; within the
limits, that
is,
of the genus
—the genus,
I
mean
1 have already explained ), to which the [25] man of science applies his demonstrations. In virtue of the common elements of demonstration I mean the common axioms which are used as premisses of demonstration, not the subjects nor the attributes demonall the sciences strated as belonging to them have communion with one another, and in communion with them all is dialectic and any science which might attempt a universal proof of axioms such as the law of excluded middle, [jo] the law that the subtraction of equals from equals leaves equal remainders, or other axioms of the same kind. Dialectic has no definite sphere of this kind, not being confined to a single genus. Otherwise its method would not
(as
I
—
—
be interrogative; for the interrogative method is barred to the demonstrator, who cannot use the opposite facts to prove the [55] This
was shown
in
gism. 2 l 2
Cf. 75 a 42fF. and 76b 13. Prior Analytics, 1. 1.
same nexus.
my work on
the syllo-
question
is
equivalent to a prop-
embodying one of the two sides of a contradiction, and if each science has its peculiar propositions from which its peculiar con-
impossible to affirm and deny simultaneously the same predicate of the same subject is not expressly posited by any that
is
developed, then there
such a thing
is
as a distinctively scientific question,
and
it
is
the interrogative form of the premisses from which the 'appropriate' conclusion of each sci[40] ence is developed. Hence it is clear that not every question will be relevant to geometry, nor to medicine, nor to any other science: only 77 h those questions will be geometrical which form premisses for the proof of the theorems of
geometry or of any other science, such as which uses the same basic truths as ge-
optics,
Of the other sciences the like is true. these questions the geometer is bound to
ometry.
Of
give his account, using the basic truths of gein conjunction with his previous con-
ometry
[5] elusions; of the basic truths the geometer, as such, is not bound to give any account. The like
is
There is a which we may put
true of the other sciences.
limit, then, to the questions
man of science; nor is each man of science bound to answer all inquiries on each several subject, but only such as fall within the defined field of his own science. If, then, in controversy with a geometer qua geometer the disputant confines himself to geometry and to each
[10] proves anything from geometrical premhe is clearly to be applauded; if he goes
isses,
outside these he will be at fault, and obviously cannot even refute the geometer except accidentally.
One
should therefore not discuss ge-
ometry among those who are not geometers, for in such a company an unsound argument will pass unnoticed. This is correspondingly true in [75] the other sciences. Since there are 'geometrical' questions, does it follow that there are also distinctively 'un-
geometrical' questions? Further, in each special science geometry for instance what kind
—
of error
is it
that
—
may vitiate
questions,
and
yet
not exclude them from that science? Again, is the erroneous conclusion one constructed from premisses opposite to the true premisses, or is [20] it formal fallacy though drawn from geometrical premisses? Or, perhaps, the erroneous conclusion is due to the drawing of premisses from another science; e.g. in a geometrical controversy a musical question is distinctively ungeometrical, whereas the notion that parallels meet is in one sense geometrical, being ungeometrical in a different fashion: the reason
BOOK
78 h
I,
CHAPTERS
being that 'ungeometrical', like 'unrhythmical', is equivocal, meaning in the one case not ge[25] ometry at It is this
this
kind
i.e.
bad geometry? on premisses of
in the other
all,
error based
—'of the science but error,
false
—that
is
the
contrary of science. In mathematics the formal fallacy is not so common, because it is the middle term in which the ambiguity lies, since the
major is predicated of the whole of the middle [50] and the middle of the whole of the minor (the predicate of course never has the prefix and in mathematics one can, so to speak,
'all');
middle terms with an intellectual while in dialectic the ambiguity may escape detection. E.g. 'Is every circle a figure?' A diagram shows that this is so, but the minor premiss 'Are epics circles?' is shown by the diagram to be false. If a proof has an inductive minor premiss, [35] one should not bring an 'objection' against it. For since every premiss must be applicable to a number of cases (otherwise it will not be true in every instance, which, since the syllosee these
vision,
gism proceeds from universals, it must be), then assuredly the same is true of an 'objection'; since premisses and 'objections' are so far the same that anything which can be validly advanced as an 'objection' must be such that it could take the form of a premiss, either [40] demonstrative or dialectical. On the other hand, arguments formally illogical do sometimes occur through taking as middles mere
major and minor terms.
attributes of the
78 a instance of
An
Caeneus' proof that fire increases in geometrical proportion: 'Fire', he argues, 'increases rapidly, and so does geometrical proportion'. There is no syllogism so, but there
is
this
a syllogism
is
if
the most rapidly increas-
ing proportion is geometrical and the most rapidly increasing proportion is attributable to [5] fire in its motion. Sometimes, no doubt, it is impossible to reason from premisses predicating sible,
false
mere attributes: but sometimes it is posthough the possibility is overlooked. If
premisses could never give true concluwould be easy, for premisses
sions 'resolution'
and conclusion would in that case inevitably reciprocate. I might then argue thus: let A be an existing fact; let the existence of A imply such and such facts actually known to me to exist, which we may call B. I can now, since they reciprocate, infer A from B. [10] Reciprocation of premisses and concluis more frequent in mathematics, because mathematics takes definitions, but never an a second characteraccident, for its premisses
sion
—
11-13
107
mathematical
istic
distinguishing
from
dialectical disputations.
reasoning
A
science expands not by the interposition of fresh middle terms, but by the apposition of
fresh extreme terms. E.g.
A
is
predicated of B,
[75] B of C, C of D, and so indefinitely. Or the expansion may be lateral: e.g. one major,
A, may be proved of two minors, C and E. Thus let A represent number a number or number taken indeterminately; B determinate odd number; C any particular odd [20] number. We can then predicate A of C. represent determinate even numNext let ber, and E even number. Then A is predicable
D
ofE.
Knowledge
of the fact differs
from knowledge
To begin
with, they differ
of the reasoned fact.
within the same science and in two ways: (1) when the premisses of the syllogism are not [25] immediate (for then the proximate cause a necessary condiis not contained in them tion of knowledge of the reasoned fact): (2) when the premisses are immediate, but instead of the cause the better known of the two reciprocals is taken as the middle; for of two reciprocally predicable terms the one which is not the cause may quite easily be the better
—
known and
so
become the middle term of the
demonstration. Thus (2) (a) you might prove [jo] as follows that the planets are near because they do not twinkle: let C be the planets, B not twinkling, A proximity. Then B is predicable of C; for the planets do not twinkle. But A is also predicable of B, since that which does not twinkle is near we must take this truth [55] as having been reached by induction or sense-perception. Therefore A is a necessary
—
predicate of C; so that
we have demonstrated
that the planets are near. This syllogism, then,
proves not the reasoned fact but only the fact; since they are not near because they do not twinkle, but, because they are near, do not twinkle. The major and middle of the proof, however, may be reversed, and then the dem[40] onstration will be of the reasoned fact. let C be the planets, B proximity,
A
78 b Thus:
not twinkling. Then B is an attribute of C, and A not twinkling of B. Consequently A is predicable of C, and the syllogism proves the reasoned fact, since its middle term is the proximate cause. Another example is the inference
—
—
that the
moon
[5] waxing. is spherical,
is spherical from its manner of Thus: since that which so waxes and since the moon so waxes,
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS
o8 clearly the
moon
spherical.
is
Put
in this
form,
79.
matical and nautical astronomy, mathematical
the syllogism turns out to be proof of the fact, but if the middle and major be reversed it is
and acoustical harmonics.) Here
proof of the reasoned fact; since the moon is not spherical because it waxes in a certain manner, but waxes in such a manner because it is [10] spherical. (Let C be the moon, B spherical, and A waxing.) Again (b), in cases where the cause and the effect are not reciprocal and
fact, of
is the better known, the fact is demonstrated but not the reasoned fact. This also occurs (1) when the middle falls outside the
particular instances.
the effect
major and minor, for here too the strict cause is not given, and so the demonstration is of the [75] fact, not of the reasoned fact. For example, the question 'Why does not a wall breathe?' might be answered, 'Because it is not an animal'; but that answer would not give the strict cause, because if not being an animal causes the absence of respiration, then being an animal should be the cause of respiration, according to the rule that if the negation of x [20] causes the non-inherence of y, the affirmation of x causes the inherence of y; e.g. if the disproportion of the hot and cold elements is the cause of ill health, their proportion is the cause of health; and conversely, if the assertion of x causes the inherence of y, the negation of x must cause y's non-inherence. But in the case given this consequence does not result; for not every animal breathes. A syllogism with this kind of cause takes place in the second figure. Thus: let A be animal, B respiration, C [25] wall. Then all that breathes
A
is
predicable of
all
B
(for
is animal), but of no C; and consequently B is predicable of no C; that is, the wall does not breathe. Such causes are like
far-fetched explanations,
which
precisely con-
making
the cause too remote, as in [30] Anacharsis' account of why the Scythians have no flute-players; namely because they sist
in
have no vines. Thus, then, do the syllogism of the fact and the syllogism of the reasoned fact differ within one science and according to the position of the middle terms. But there is another way too in which the fact and the reasoned fact differ,
and
that
is
when
they are investigated respec-
by different sciences. This occurs in the case of problems related to one another as
ts]
tively
subordinate and
superior,
as
when
optical
problems are subordinated to geometry, mechanical problems to stereometry, harmonic problems to arithmetic, the data of observation [40] to astronomy. (Some of these sciences 79 a bear almost the same name; e.g. mathe-
the busi-
it is
know know the
ness of the empirical observers to
soned
the mathematicians to
the rea-
fact; for the latter are in possession of
the demonstrations giving the causes,
often ignorant of the fact: just as
and are
we have
often
[5] a clear insight into a universal, but through lack of observation are ignorant of some of its
These connexions have a though they are manifestations of forms. For the mathematical sciences concern forms: they do not demonstrate properties of a substratum, since, even though perceptible existence
the geometrical subjects are predicable as prop-
substratum, it is not as thus predicable that the mathematician demon-
erties of a perceptible
[10] strates properties of them.
As
optics
lated to geometry, so another science
is
is
re-
related
namely the theory of the rainbow. Here knowledge of the fact is within the province of the natural philosopher, knowledge
to optics,
of the reasoned fact within that of the optician, either
optician.
qua optician or qua mathematical
Many
sciences not standing in this
mutual relation enter into medicine and geometry: it
it
is
at
points; e.g.
the physician's
[75] business to know that circular wounds heal more slowly, the geometer's to know the
reason why.
Of
all
Thus, all
the figures the most scientific it is
is
the
first.
the vehicle of the demonstrations of
the mathematical sciences, such as arith-
metic, geometry,
and
optics,
and
practically of
[20] all sciences that investigate causes: for the syllogism of the reasoned fact is either exclusively or generally speaking
—a
and
in
most
second proof that this figure is the most scientific; for grasp of a reasoned conclusion is the primary condition of knowledge. Thirdly, the first is the only figure [25] which enables us to pursue knowledge of the essence of a thing. In the second figure no affirmative conclusion is possible, and knowledge of a thing's essence must be affirmative; while in the third figure the conclusion can be affirmative, but cannot be universal, and essence must have a universal character: e.g. man is not two-footed animal in any qualified sense, but universally. Finally, the first figure [30] has no need of the others, while it is by cases in this figure
first that the other two figures are and have their intervals closepacked until immediate premisses are reached.
means
of the
developed,
BOOK
80*
Clearly, therefore, the first figure
mary condition
is
I,
CHAPTERS
the pri-
of knowledge.
13-16
109
[25] ( 1 ) Let us first consider propositions asserting a predicate's immediate connexion with
or disconnexion
from
a subject. Here,
may befall one in may arise where one
positive error
A may (as we saw) be connected with a subject B, so its disconnexion may be atomic. I call 'atomic' connexions or disconnexions which involve no [35] intermediate term; since in that case the connexion or disconnexion will not be mediated by something other than the terms themselves. It follows that if either A or B, or both A and B, have a genus, their disconnexion cannot be primary. Thus: let C be the genus of A. Then, if C is not the genus of B for A may well have a genus which is not the genus of there will be a syllogism proving A's [40] B Just as an attribute
atomically
—
—
disconnexion from
79 b
B
all
thus:
A is C,
no B is C, no B is A. Or if it is B which has a genus D, we have all£isD, noD is A, :. no B is A, by syllogism; [5] and the proof will be similar if both A and B have a genus. That the genus of A need not be the genus of B and vice versa, is shown by :.
the existence of mutually exclusive coordinate
no term
series of predication. If
ACD
...
series
BEF
mer
series
.
.
—
in the series
predicable of any term in the
is
is
.,
and
if
G —a
term
in the for-
the genus of A, clearly
G
will
[10] not be the genus of B; since, if it were, the series would not be mutually exclusive. So if B has a genus, it will not be the genus of A. If, on the other hand, neither A nor B has a genus and A does not inhere in B, this disconnexion must be atomic. If there be a middle term, one or other of them is bound to have a
also
[75] genus, for the syllogism will be either in the first or the second figure. If it is in the first,
B
will
ing
it
either
have a genus
must be
A
or
B
—
for the premiss contain-
affirmative;
if
in the second,
indifferently, since syllogism
is
contained in a negative [20] premiss, but not if both premisses are
possible
if
either
is
negative.
stated
true,
directly beways; for it lieves a connexion or disconnexion as well as where one's belief is acquired by inference. The error, however, that consists in a direct belief is without complication; but the error which here concerns resulting from inference us takes many forms. Thus, let A be atomically disconnected from all B: then the conclu|jo] sion inferred through a middle term C, that all B is A, will be a case of error produced by syllogism. Now, two cases are possible. Either (a) both premisses, or (b) one premiss only, may be false, (a) If neither A is an attribute of any C nor C of any B, whereas the contrary was posited in both cases, both prem-
—
—
W M De false. (C may quite well be A and B that C is neither subordinate to A nor a universal attribute of B: for B, since A was said to be primarily disconnected from B cannot have a genus, and A ie]
i
sses
so related to
y
need not necessarily be a universal attribute of all things. Consequently both premisses may [40] be false.) On the other hand, (b) one of the premisses may be true, though not either 80 a indifferently but only the major A-C; since, B having no genus, the premiss C-B will always be false, while A-C may be true. This is the case if, for example, A is related atomically to both C and B; because when the same term is related atomically to more terms than one, neither of those terms will belong to the other. [5]
It is,
of course, equally the case
if
A-C
not atomic.
is
Error of attribution, then, occurs through and in this form only for we
—
these causes
found that no syllogism of universal attribu1 tion was possible in any figure but the first. On the other hand, an error of non-attribution
may
occur either in the
first
or in the second
figure. Let us therefore first explain the various
forms
it
takes in the
first
figure
and the char-
[10] acter of the premisses in each case.
may
occur when both premisses are supposing A atomically connected with both C and B, if it be then assumed that no C is A, and all B is C, both premisses are (c) It
false; e.g.
it is clear that one thing may be atomdisconnected from another, and we have
Hence ically
it is
alternative
when and how
this
is
possible.
false.
(d) 16
—defined
Ignorance
not as the negation of
knowledge but as a positive error produced by inference.
state of
mind
—
is
It is
also possible
when one
is false.
This
be either premiss indifferently. A-C may be true, C-B false A-C true because A is not an attribute of all things, C-B false be[75]
1
may
Prior Analytics,
i.
i
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS
no
cause C, which never has the attribute A, cannot be an attribute of B; for if C-B were true, the premiss A-C would no longer be true, and [20] besides if both premisses were true, the
conclusion would be true. be true and
B
contain
A-C
Or
as genera,
C and A one of them must be sub-
ordinate to the other, so that takes the
makes
form
it
clear
No C
both if
the premiss
A, it will be false. This that whether either or both is
[25] premisses are false, the conclusion will equally be false. In the second figure the premisses cannot
both be wholly
false; for if all
B
A, no mid-
is
dle term can be with truth universally affirmed
of one extreme
and universally denied of the
[50] other: but premisses in which the middle is affirmed of one extreme and denied of the if one is to Therefore if, taken in this way, they are wholly false, their contraries conversely should be wholly true. But this is impossible. On the other hand, there is nothing to prevent both premisses being par-
other are the necessary condition
get a valid inference at
all.
some A is C and some B is C, then if it is premised that all A is C and no B is C, both premisses are false, yet partially, not wholly, false. The same is true if the major is made negative instead of tially false; e.g. if actually
[55]
Or one premiss may
be wholly false, be either of them. Thus, supposing that actually an attribute of all A must also be [40] an attribute of all B, then if C is yet taken
the minor.
and
80 b
it
may
to be a universal attribute of all
versally non-attributable to B,
C-B
C-A
s
[75] propositions erroneous inference will be possible not only when both premisses are false
but also
when
only one
is
false.
C-B may
again,
false; e.g. if
81
A but uni-
will be true
(2) In the case of attributes not atomically
connected with or disconnected from their subjects, (a) (i) as long as the false conclusion is inferred through the 'appropriate' middle, only [20] the major and not both premisses can be false. By 'appropriate middle' I mean the middle term through which the contradictory i.e. the true conclusion is inferrible. Thus, let A be attributable to B through a middle term C: then, since to produce a conclusion the premiss C-B must be taken affirmatively, it is clear that [25] this premiss must always be true, for its quality is not changed. But the major A-C is false, for it is by a change in the quality of AC that the conclusion becomes its contradictory i.e. true. Similarly (ii) if the middle is taken from another series of predication; e.g. suppose to be not only contained within A as a part within its whole but also predicable of all B. Then the premiss D-B must remain un|jo] changed, but the quality of A-D must be changed; so that D-B is always true, A-D al-
—
—
—
D
ways
false.
Such error
practically identical
is
with that which is inferred through the 'appropriate' middle. On the other hand, (b) if the conclusion is not inferred through the 'appropriate' middle (i) when the middle is subordinate to A but is predicable of no B, [35] both premisses must be false, because if there is to be a conclusion both must be posited
—
Again, actually that which is an B will not be an attribute of all A either; for if it be an attribute of all A, it will also be an attribute of all B, which is contrary to supposition; but if C be nevertheless assumed to be a universal attribute of A, but [5] an attribute of no B, then the premiss C-B is true but the major is false. The case is similar if the major is made the negative premiss. For in fact what is an attribute of no A will not be an attribute of any B either; and if it be
what is actually the become false: e.g. suppose that actually all D is A but no B is D; then if these premisses are changed in quality, a conclusion will follow and both of the new
yet
assumed that C is universally non-attribuA, but a universal attribute of B, the [10] premiss C-A is true but the minor wholly false. Again, in fact it is false to assume that that which is an attribute of all B is an attribute of no A, for if it be an attribute of all 5, it must be an attribute of some A. If then C is nevertheless assumed to be an attribute of all B but of no A, C-B will be true but C-A false.
false.
table to
[5] When the erroneous inference is in the second figure, both premisses cannot be entirely false; since if B is subordinate to A, there can be no middle predicable of all of one extreme and of none of the other, as was stated before. One premiss, however, may be false, and it may be either of them. Thus, if C is [10] actually an attribute of both A and B, but
but
false.
attribute of
It
is
no
thus clear that in the case of atomic
as asserting the contrary of fact,
and
so posited both
[40] premisses will be false. When, however, (ii) the middle is not subordinate to A,
D
81 a
A-D
will be true,
D-B
false
A-D
true be-
cause A was not subordinate to D, D-B false because if it had been true, the conclusion too would have been true; but it is ex hy pot he si
1
1
Cf. 80* 29.
BOOK CHAPTERS 16-19 of A only and [5] exist in isolation —
81 b is
to be
an attribute
not of B, C-A will be true, C-B false: or again if C be assumed to be attributable to B but to no A, C-B will be true, C-A false.
We have stated when and through what 1 I 5] kinds of premisses error will result in cases where the erroneous conclusion is negative. If the conclusion is affirmative, (a) (i) it may be inferred through the 'appropriate' middle term. In this case both premisses cannot be
we
false since, as
said before,
main unchanged if there is and consequently A-C, the
1
C-B must
quality of
which
is
2
D-B must remain unchanged, while the quality of A-D must be converted, and the type of is
the same as before.
The middle may
be inappropriate. subordinate to A, A-D will be true, but D-B false; since A may quite well be predicable of several terms no one of which can be subordinated to another. If, however, (ii) is not subordinate to A, obviously A-D, since it is affirmed, will always be false, while [25] (b)
Then
(i) if
D
is
D
D-B may
be either true or false; for
A may
[jo] very well be an attribute of no D, whereas
B
is
D,
e.g.
no science
is
animal,
all
music
Equally well A may be an attribute no D, and D of no B. It emerges, then, that the middle term is not subordinate to the
science.
is
of if
major, not only both premisses but either singly may be false. [35]
Thus we have made
it
clear
it
is
re-
the case also with regard to negative error; for
error
consequently impossible to come to grasp universals except through induction. But induction is impossible for those who have not sense-perception. For it is sense-perception alone which is adequate for grasping the particulars: they cannot be objects of scientific knowledge, because neither can universals give us knowledge of them without induction, nor can we get it through induction without sense-perception. l
to be a conclusion,
[20] changed, will always be false. This is equally true if (ii) the middle is taken from another series of predication, as was stated to be
all
in
I,
assumed
how many
varieties of erroneous inference are liable to
happen and through what kinds of premisses they occur, in the case both of immediate and
It is clear, then, that these are the fundamentals and so-called hypotheses of syllogism. [75] Assume them as they have been stated, and proof is bound to follow proof that A inheres in C through B, and again that A in-
other.
—
B
through some other middle term, B inheres in C. If our reasoning aims at gaining credence and so is merely dialectical, it is obvious that we have only to see that our inference is based on premheres in
and
similarly that
[20] isses as credible as possible: so that
if
a
middle term between A and B is credible though not real, one can reason through it and complete a dialectical syllogism. If, however, one is aiming at truth, one must be guided by the real connexions of subjects and attributes. Thus: since there are attributes which are predicated of a subject essentially or naturally not, that is, in [25] and not coincidentally the sense in which we say "That white (thing)
—
is
a man',
cation as
of demonstrable truths.
9
[10] Every syllogism is effected by means of three terms. One kind of syllogism serves to prove that A inheres in C by showing that A inheres in B and B in C; the other is negative and one of its premisses asserts one term of another, while the other denies one term of an-
which
not the same
is
when we
say 'The
mode
man
is
of predi-
white': the
man
18 It is
also clear that the loss of
any one of the
senses entails the loss of a corresponding portion of knowledge,
and
that, since
we
learn
either by induction or by demonstration, this
knowledge cannot be acquired. Thus 81 b demonstration develops from universals, induction from particulars; but since it is possi[40]
with even the socalled mathematical abstractions only through induction i.e. only because each subject genus possesses, in virtue of a determinate mathematical character, certain properties which can be treated as separate even though they do not ble to familiarize the pupil
—
1
Cf. 8o b 17-26.
2
Cf. 8ob 26-32.
is white not because he is something else but because he is man, but the white is man because 'being white' coincides with 'humanity' within one substratum therefore there are terms such as are naturally subjects of predi-
—
[30] cates. Suppose, then, C such a term not attributable to anything else as to a subject, but the proximate subject of the attribute itself
B—i.e. ther E
so that
B-C
The first question or can
is
immediate; suppose fur-
related immediately to F,
it
is,
must
and
F
to B.
this series terminate,
proceed to infinity ?
The second
ques-
Suppose nothing is essentially predicated of A, but A is predicated priand of no intermediate prior [^5] marily of term, and suppose similarly related to G and tion
is
as follows:
H
H
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS
112
G to B; then can
it
much
this series also terminate, or
There
is
this
difference between the questions:
the
first is, is it
not
must
too proceed to infinity?
itself
possible to start
from that which
attributable to anything else but
is
is
the
[40] subject of attributes, and ascend to infinThe second is the problem whether one
ity?
can
from that which
start
82 a not
itself a
is
a predicate but
subject of predicates,
and de-
scend to infinity ? A third question is, if the extreme terms are fixed, can there be an infinity of middles? I mean this: suppose for example that A inheres in C and B is intermediate be-
tween them, but between B and A there are [5] other middles, and between these again fresh middles; can these proceed to infinity or can they not? This is the equivalent of inquiring, do demonstrations proceed to infinity, i.e. is everything demonstrable? Or do ultimate subject and primary attribute limit one an-
82 b
[25] termediates
—
call
them BB'B"
.
.
.
—are
then clearly you might descend from A and find one term predicated of another ad infinitum, since you have an infinity of terms between you and F; and equally, if you ascend from F, there are infinite terms between you infinite,
and A.
It follows that if these processes are impossible there cannot be an infinity of inter-
mediates between A and F. Nor is it of any [30] effect to urge that some terms of the series AB F are contiguous so as to exclude intermediates, while others cannot be taken into the argument at all: whichever terms of .
.
B
the series
.
.
.
I
.
take, the
number
of inter-
mediates in the direction either of A or of F must be finite or infinite: where the infinite
whether from the first term or is of no moment, for the suc[35] ceeding terms in any case are infinite in number.
series starts,
from
a later one,
other?
hold that the same questions arise with re[10] gard to negative conclusions and premisses: viz. if A is attributable to no B, then either this predication will be primary, or there will be an intermediate term prior to B to which A is not attributable G, let us say,
21
I
which still
attributable to all
is
be another term
attributable to all G. I
B—and
H prior
The same
to
there
may
G, which
is
questions arise,
because in these cases too either the series which A is not attributable is
say,
of prior terms to infinite or
it
terminates.
[75] One cannot ask the same questions in the case of reciprocating terms, since when subject
and predicate are convertible there
is
neither primary nor ultimate subject, seeing that
all
qua
the reciprocals
subjects stand in
one another, whether we say that the subject has an infinity of attributes or that both subjects and attributes and we raised the question in both cases are infinite in number. These questions then cannot be asked unless, indeed, the terms can reciprocate by two different modes, by accidental [20] predication in one relation and natural the
same
relation to
—
—
—
predication in the other.
20
Now,
it is
clear that
if
the predications termi*
nate in both the upward and the downward direction (by 'upward' I mean the ascent to
more
'downward' the dethe middle terms cannot be infinite in number. For suppose that A is predicated of F, and that the inthe
scent
to
universal, by
the
more
particular),
Further,
if in affirmative demonstration the terminates in both directions, clearly it will terminate too in negative demonstration. Let us assume that we cannot proceed to infin-
series
by ascending from the ultimate term (by 'ultimate term' I mean a term such as F 82 b was, not itself attributable to a subject but itself the subject of attributes), or by descending towards an ultimate from the primary term (by 'primary term' I mean a term predicate of a subject but not itself a subject). If this assumption is justified, the series will also terminate in the case of negation. For a negative conclusion can be proved in all three fig[5] ures. In the first figure it is proved thus: no B is A all C is B. In packing the interval B-C we must reach immediate propositions as is always the case with the minor premiss ity either
y
since B-C is affirmative. As regards the other premiss it is plain that if the major term is denied of a term prior to B, will have to be [10] predicable of all B, and if the major is denied of yet another term prior to D, this term must be predicable of all D. Consequently, since the ascending series is finite, the descent will also terminate and there will be a
D
D
A
which is primarily non-predicable. In the second figure the syllogism is, all A is
subject of
B, no
C
is
B,
.
.
no
C
is
A.
If
proof of this
is
[75] required, plainly it may be shown either in the first figure as above, in the second as here, or in the third. The first figure has been discussed,
and we
will proceed to display the
second, proof by which will be as follows:
all
BOOK
83 b
B B
is
D, no
C
D
is
.
.
.,
since
CHAPTERS
I,
required that
it is
should be a subject of which a predicate is is to be proved not to has a further predicate belong to C, then which is denied of C. Therefore, since the suc[20] cession of predicates affirmed of an ever affirmed. Next, since
D
D
higher universal terminates, the succession of predicates denied terminates too. third figure shows it as follows: all B A, some B is not C, :. some A is not C. This premiss, i.e. C-B, will be proved either in the same figure or in one of the two figures [25] discussed above. In the first and second
The
affirm 'the log
figure,
we
use the third
E
shall take as premisses, all
E is not
some
we
is
B,
is
jects also terminates, plainly the series of
more
universal non-predicables will terminate also.
Even supposing to
now
[50]
ond or
in the first figure,
third
nate, for the if
that the proof
is
not confined
one method, but employs them
finite
—even
now
all
is
in the sec-
so the regress will termi-
methods are
finite in
number, and
things are combined in a finite
of ways, the result
and
must be
number
may
be
made
te]
nates in both these cases
clear
by the following dialectical considera-
tions.
22 In the case of predicates constituting the essential nature of a thing, it clearly terminates, seeing that if definition is possible, or in other
form is knowable, and an cannot be traversed, predicates constituting a thing's essential nature must be 83 a finite in number. But as regards predicates generally we have the following prefatory remarks to make. (1) We can affirm without falsehood 'the white (thing) is walking', and 'that big (thing) is a log'; or again, 'the log is if
essential
infinite series
big',
and
'the
differs in the
man two
walks'. But the affirmation cases.
When
I
affirm 'the
white is a log', I mean that something which happens to be white is a log not that white is the substratum in which log inheres, for it was not qua white or qua a species of white that the white (thing) came to be a log, and the white (thing) is consequently not a log except incidentally. On the other hand, when I [5]
I
if I
said 'the musician 'the
contrary, log
is
man who
musician is white'); on the here the substratum the sub-
to be a
—
stratum which actually came to be white, and did so qua wood or qua a species of wood and qua nothing else. If
we must
lay
down
a rule, let us entitle the
[75] latter kind of statement predication, and the former not predication at all, or not strict
but accidental predication. 'White' and 'log' will thus serve as types respectively of predicate
and
We
subject.
shall
assume, then, that the predicate
is
[20] invariably predicated strictly and not accidentally of the subject, for on such predication demonstrations
depend
follows from this that is
when
for their force.
It
a single attribute
predicated of a single subject, the predicate
must
affirm of the subject either
constituting
some way
its
some element
essential nature, or that
it is
in
qualified, quantified, essentially re-
lated, active, passive, placed, or dated.
(2) Predicates which signify substance sigis identical with the predi-
nify that the subject
finite.
Thus it is plain that the regress of middles terminates in the case of negative demonstration, if it does so also in the case of affirmative demonstration. That in fact the regress termi-
words,
do not mean that which happens also to be a
white',
which would mean
white,'
happens also
C, and this premiss again will be
proved by a similar prosyllogism. But since it is assumed that the series of descending sub-
is
[10] something else, log, is white (as I should
is
figures the series terminates. If
"3
19-22
—
cate or with a species of the predicate. Predi-
[25] cates not signifying substance which are predicated of a subject not identical with themselves or
with a species of themselves are
dental or coincidental; e.g. white
is
acci-
a coinci-
dent of man, seeing that man is not identical with white or a species of white, but rather with animal, since man is identical with a spe[50] cies of animal. These predicates which do not signify substance must be predicates of some other subject, and nothing can be white which is not also other than white. The Forms we can dispense with, for they are mere sound without sense; and even if there are such things, they are not relevant to our discussion, since demonstrations are concerned with predi[35] cates sucn as we nave defined. (3 ) If A is a quality of B, B cannot be a quala quality of a quality. Therefore A ity of A and B cannot be predicated reciprocally of one another in strict predication: they can be affirmed without falsehood of one another, but not genuinely predicated of each other. For one alternative is that they should be substantially predicated of one another, i.e. B would become
—
—
83 b the genus or differentia of A the predicate now become subject. But it has been
shown
that in these substantial predications
neither the ascending predicates nor the de-
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS
II 4
scending subjects form an infinite series; e.g. neither the series, man is biped, biped is animal, &c, nor the series predicating animal of
man, man
of Callias, Callias of a further sub-
an element of its essential nature, is inFor all such substance is definable, finite. [5] and an infinite series cannot be traversed in thought: consequently neither the ascent nor ject as
the descent
infinite, since a
is
predicates were infinite
Hence they
substance whose
would not be this its
would equate a
own
species.
Nor
(the other alternative) can a quale be recipro-
nor any term belonging to an adjectival category of another such term, except by accidental predication; for all such predicates are coincidents and are cally predicated of a quale,
predicated of substances.
On
the other
in proof of the impossibility of
cending
series
subject as
an
hand
infinite as-
—every predication displays the
somehow
as characterized tival categories,
qualified or quantified or
under one of the other adjecor else is an element in its sub-
[75] stantial nature: these latter are limited in number, and the number of the widest kinds under which predications fall is also limited, for every predication
somehow
as
must exhibit
its
subject
qualified, quantified, essentially
related, acting or suffering, or in
some place
some time. assume first that predication implies a single subject and a single attribute, and secondly that predicates which are not substantial are not predicated of one another. We assume this because such predicates are all coincidents, and though some are essential coincidents, others or at I
[20] of a different type, yet we maintain that of them alike are predicated of some sub-
all
stratum and that a coincident is never a substratum since we do not class as a coincident anything which does not owe its designation to its being something other than itself, but always hold that any coincident is predicated of some substratum other than itself, and that another group of coincidents may have a different substratum. Subject to these assumptions [25] then, neither the ascending nor the descending series of predication in which a single
—
attribute finite.
is
predicated of a single subject
is
in-
For the subjects of which coincidents are
predicated are as
many
as the constitutive ele-
which are
84-
finite.
(B) primarily predicable of the first and that the series must end with a [30] term (A) not predicable of any term prior to the last subject of which it was predicated (B), and of which no term prior to it is predicable.
The argument we have given
is one of the an alternative proof follows.
so-called proofs;
Predicates so related to their subjects that there are other predicates prior to them predicable of those subjects are demonstrable; but of demonstrable propositions one cannot have something
than knowledge, nor can one without demonstration. Secondly, a consequent is only known through an better
[35]
know them if
antecedent (viz. premisses prior to it) and we neither know this antecedent nor have something better than knowledge of it, then we shall not
have
scientific
sequent. Therefore,
demonstration to ification
if
knowledge
of the con-
possible through
is
it
know anything without
and not merely
as
qual-
dependent on the
—
acceptance of certain premisses i.e. hypothetically the series of intermediate predications 84a must terminate. If it does not terminate,
—
and beyond any predicate taken as higher than another there remains another still higher, then every predicate is demonstrable. Consequently, since these demonstrable predicates are infinite in number and therefore cannot be traversed, we shall not know them by demonstration. If, therefore, we have not something better than [5] knowledge of them, we cannot through demonstration have unqualified but only hypothetical science of anything. As dialectical proofs of our contention these may carry conviction, but an analytic process will
show more
briefly that neither the ascent
nor the descent of predication can be infinite in [10] the demonstrative sciences which are the object of our investigation. Demonstration proves the inherence of essential attributes in things.
two
Now
attributes
may
be essential for
reasons: either because they are elements
in the essential nature of their subjects, or because their subjects are elements in their essential nature. An example of the latter is odd as
an attribute of number
—though
it is
number's
[75] attribute, yet number itself is an element in the definition of odd; of the former, multiplicity
in the ascending series are contained those con-
in the definition of
—both
a
attribute,
ments of each individual substance, and these seen are not infinite in number, while elements with their coincidents
is
attribute
we have stitutive
We conclude that there
given subject (D) of which some attribute (C) is primarily predicable; that there must be an
definable.
will not be predicated each as the
genus of the other; for [10] genus with one of
of
which are elements number. In neither kind of
or the indivisible,
attribution can the terms be infinite.
They
are
BOOK
84 b
I,
CHAPTERS
is related to the term number, for this would mean the inherence in odd of another attribute of odd in whose nature odd was an essential [20] element: but then number will be an ultimate subject of the whole infinite chain of attributes, and be an element in the definition of each of them. Hence, since an infinity of at-
not infinite where each
"5
22-23
from one another. But
differ
this
is
not always
we take B as
definition cannot inhere in a single thing, the
the commiddle in virtue of which A inheres in C [10] and D, clearly B would inhere in C and D through a second common middle, and this through a in turn would inhere in C and third, so that between two terms an infinity of intermediates would fall an impossibility. Thus it need not always be in virtue of a common middle term that a single attribute in-
Note, more-
heres in several subjects, since there must be
below
it
as
odd
to
is
tributes such as contain their subject in their
ascending
series is equally finite.
over, that all such attributes
the ultimate subject
number
ber and
—
in
must
so inhere in
numbe commen-
e.g. its attributes in
them
—
as to
surate with the subject and not of wider extent.
[25] Attributes which are essential elements in the nature of their subjects are equally finite: otherwise definition would be impossible.
Hence, if all the attributes predicated are essential and these cannot be infinite, the ascending series will terminate, and consequently the descending series too. If this is so,
it
follows that the intermediates
the case: for, were
so, if
it
mon
D
—
[75] immediate intervals. Yet
common
proved
to be
to
two
if
the attribute
subjects
to be
is
one of their essential attributes, the middle terms involved must be within one subject genus and be derived from the same group of immediate premisses; for we have seen that processes of proof cannot pass from one genus to another. It is
1
also clear that
when A
inheres in B, this
[20] can be demonstrated if there is a middle term. Further, the 'elements' of such a conclusion are the premisses containing the mid-
and they are
num-
between any two terms are also always limited in number. An immediately obvious con-
dle in question,
[30] sequence of this is that demonstrations necessarily involve basic truths, and that the contention of some referred, to at the outset
immediate propositions or at least such immediate propositions as are universal are the 'elements'. If, on the other hand, there is no middle term, demonstration ceases to be pos-
—
truths are demonstrable is mistaken. there are basic truths, (a) not all truths are demonstrable, and (b) an infinite regress is impossible; since if either (a) or (b) were not that
all
For
if
would mean that no interval was im[35] mediate and indivisible, but that all in-
a fact,
it
identical in
ber with the middle terms, seeing that the
—
sible:
we
Similarly
on the way
are if
—
A
to the basic truths.
does not inhere in B, this can
be demonstrated
if there is a middle term or a [25] term prior to B in which A does not inhere: otherwise there is no demonstration and
were divisible. This is true because a conclusion is demonstrated by the interposition, not the apposition, of a fresh term. If such interposition could continue to infinity there might be an infinite number of terms between any two terms; but this is impossible if both
a basic truth
84 b
monstrable basic truths asserting that
tervals
the ascending and descending series of
predication terminate; and of this fact, which shown dialectically, analytic proof
before was
has
now
been given.
as
many
clusion as there are middle terms, since
onstration rests; and as there are
an evident corollary of these conclusions
that
if
same attribute A inheres in two and D predicable either not at all, or
the
terms C [5] not of all instances, of one another, it does not always belong to them in virtue of a comIsosceles
and scalene possess
the attribute of having their angles equal to
two
right angles in virtue of a
for they possess
it
common middle;
in so far as they are both a
certain kind of figure,
and not
in so far as they
is
some
inde-
'this is
that' or that 'this inheres in that', so there are
[30] others denying that 'this is that' or that inheres in that' in fact some basic truths
—
and some
When we are
It is
it
middle terms
on which the dem-
that are the basic premisses
'this
23
middle term.
reached. There are, moreover,
propositions containing these
will affirm
mon
is
'elements' of the demonstrated con-
will
deny being.
prove a conclusion, we must take a primary essential predicate suppose it C of the subject /3, and then suppose A similarly predicable of C. If we proceed in this
—
to
—
manner, no proposition or attribute which falls beyond A is admitted in the proof: the interval is constantly condensed until subject and predi[35] cate become indivisible, i.e. one. We have our unit when the premiss becomes immediate, since the immediate premiss alone is a single * 1.
7.
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS
n6
premiss in the unqualified sense of 'single'. And as in other spheres the basic element is simple but not identical in all in a system of weight it is the mina, in music the quarterso in syllogism the unit is an tone, and so on 85° immediate premiss, and in the knowledge that demonstration gives it is an intuition. In syllogisms, then, which prove the inherence of
—
—
an
attribute,
nothing
outside the major
falls
term. In the case of negative syllogisms on the other hand, (i) in the first figure nothing falls outside the major term whose inherence is in
85 b
whereas particular demonstration proves that the subject
itself is x.
The
demonstration, then,
that a subject, as such, possesses an attribute
is
and if the particular rather than the commensurately universal form so superior. If this
is so,
[jo] demonstrates, particular demonstration
is
superior.
(2) The universal has not a separate being over against groups of singulars. Demonstration nevertheless creates the opinion that
its
question; e.g. to prove through a middle C that A does not inhere in B the premisses re-
conditioned by something like this some separate entity belonging to the real world; that, for instance, of triangle or of figure or number, over against particular trian-
[5] quired are, all B is C, no C is A. Then if it has to be proved that no C is A, a middle must
[35] gl es > figures, and numbers. But demonstration which touches the real and will not
be found between will never vary. (2) If
means all
E,
A and C;
this
procedure
D
E is not by C; no E, or not C; then the middle will never fall bewe have
yond E, and
E
is
to
show all
that
D
is
the subject of
which
D
is
to
be denied in the conclusion. [10] (3) In the third figure the middle will
never
fall
beyond the
limits of the subject
the attribute denied of
and
it.
24 Since demonstrations universal
surately
may
be either
commen-
or particular, and
affirmative or negative;
either
the question arises,
[75] which form is the better? And the same question may be put in regard to so-called 'direct' demonstration and reductio ad impossible. Let us first examine the commensurately
and the particular forms, and when up this problem proceed to 'direct' demonstration and reductio ad
universal
we have discuss
cleared
impossibile.
The
we have
greater
mislead
is
superior to that which
and
is
knowledge of
a particular in-
moves among commensu-
Now
delusory.
rately universal demonstration
is of the latter kind: if we engage in it we find ourselves reasoning after a fashion well illustrated by the argument that the proportionate is what an-
swers to the definition of some entity which is neither line, number, solid, nor plane, but a 85 b proportionate apart from all these. Since, then, such a proof is characteristically commensurate and universal, and less touches reality than does particular demonstration, and creates a false opinion, it will follow that com-
mensurate and universal lar
is
inferior to particu-
demonstration.
We may retort thus. applies sal
no more
to
( 1 ) The first argument commensurate and univer-
than to particular demonstration.
If
equal-
ly] ity to two right angles is attributable to its subject not qua isosceles but qua triangle, he
who knows that isosceles possesses that attribute knows
the subject as
qua
attribute, to a less degree
following considerations might lead some minds to prefer particular demonstration. ( 1 ) The superior demonstration is the demonstration which gives us greater knowledge (for this is the ideal of demonstration), and [20]
—
is
unrealities
of the premisses,
is
and
function
itself
possessing the
who knows To sum up the
than he
that triangle has that attribute.
whole matter: if a subject is proved to possess qua triangle an attribute which it does not in fact possess qua triangle, that is not demonstration: but if it does possess it qua triangle, the rule applies that the greater knowledge is
when we know it in itself than when we know it through something else; e.g. we know Coriscus the musician better when we [25] know that Coriscus is musical than when we know only that man is musical, and a like argument holds in all other cases. But commen-
does possess it. Since, then, triangle is the wider [10] term, and there is one identical definition of triangle i.e. the term is not equivocal and since equality to two right angles be-
surately universal demonstration, instead of proving that the subject itself actually is x, proves only that something else is x e.g. in attempting to prove that isosceles is x, it proves not that isosceles but only that triangle is x
longs to all triangles, it is isosceles qua triangle and not triangle qua isosceles which has its angles so related. It follows that he who knows a connexion universally has greater knowledge of it as it in fact is than he who knows the
dividual
—
—
his
who knows
tribute
—
qua
the subject as possessing
that in virtue of
which
it
its at-
actually
—
BOOK
86 a
I,
CHAPTERS
and the inference is that commenand universal is superior to particular
23-24
117
particular;
isosceles, there still
surate
86 a has
demonstration. If
[75] (2)
—
the
if
i.e.
equivocal ing not
there
is
a single identical definition
commensurate universal
—then the universal
less
is
un-
will possess be-
but more than some of the particu-
remains the question 'Why and its answer
isosceles this attribute?'
'Because it is a triangle, and a triangle has it because a triangle is a rectilinear figure.' If rectilinear figure possesses the property for no further reason, at this point we have full knowledge but at this point our knowledge
—
prise the imperishable, particulars that tend to
has become commensurately universal, and so we conclude that commensurately universal
perish.
demonstration
(3) Because the universal has a single meaning, we are not therefore compelled to suppose
(6)
lars,
inasmuch
as
is
it
universals
that in these examples
stance apart
than
from
we need make
it
has being as a sub-
particulars
its
which com-
—any
more
a similar supposition in
the other cases of unequivocal universal predication, viz.
where the predicate
signifies not
substance but quality, essential related-
[20]
ness, or action. If
tained, the
blame
such a supposition is enternot with the demonstra-
rests
is
superior.
The more demonstration becomes more
lar the
particu-
sinks into an indeterminate
it
manifold, while universal demonstration tends [5] to the simple and determinate. But objects so far as they are an indeterminate manifold are unintelligible, so far as they are determinate, intelligible: they are therefore intelligible rather in so far as they are universal than in so far as they are particular. From this it follows that universals are
more demonstrable: but
the
and correlative increase concomitantly, of the more demonstrable there will be fuller demonstration. Hence the commensurate and universal form, being more truly demon-
lar
[10] stration,
tion but with the hearer.
since relative
(4) Demonstration is syllogism that proves the cause, i.e. the reasoned fact, and it is rather
commensurate universal than the particuwhich is causative (as may be shown thus: that which possesses an attribute through its
[25] own essential nature is itself the cause of the inherence, and the commensurate univer-
primary; hence the commensurate universal is the cause). Consequently commensurately universal demonstration is superior as more especially proving the cause, that is the reasoned fact. (5) Our search for the reason ceases, and we think that we know, when the coming to be or existence of the fact before us is not due to the coming to be or existence of some other fact, for the last step of a search thus conducted is [30] eo ipso the end and limit of the problem. Thus: 'Why did he come?' 'To get the money wherewith to pay a debt that he might thereby do what was right.' When in this regress we can no longer find an efficient or final cause, we regard the last step of it as the end of and the coming or being or coming to be we regard ourselves as then only having full knowledge of the reason why he came. sal is
—
—
—
—
[35]
If>
then,
all
in this respect,
knowledge
we have
causes and reasons are alike
and
if
this
is
the
means
to full
in the case of final causes such as
exemplified,
it
follows that in the case
knowledge is atno longer inheres beThus, when we learn
of the other causes also full
tained
when an
attribute
cause of something
else.
that exterior angles are equal to four right angles because they are the exterior angles of
an
(7) things
is
the superior.
Demonstration is
which
two which commensu-
teaches
preferable to demonstration
teaches only one.
He who possesses
demonstration knows the particular as well, but he who possesses particular demonstration does not know the universal. So that this is an additional reason for preferring commensurately universal demonstration. And there is yet this further argument: (8) Proof becomes more and more proof of the commensurate universal as its middle term approaches nearer to the basic truth, and noth[75] ing is so near as the immediate premiss which is itself the basic truth. If, then, proof from the basic truth is more accurate than proof not so derived, demonstration which depends more closely on it is more accurate than demonstration which is less closely dependent. But commensurately universal demonstration is characterized by this closer dependence, and is therefore superior. Thus, if A had to be proved to inhere in D, and the middles were B and C, B being the higher term would ren[20] der the demonstration which it mediated rately universal
the
more
Some lectical.
universal.
of these arguments, however, are dia-
The
clearest indication of the preced-
ence of commensurately universal demonstration is as follows: if of two propositions, a prior and a posterior, we have a grasp of the prior, we have a kind of knowledge a poten-
—
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS
n8
—
For examone knows that the angles of all triangles are equal to two right angles, one grasp
tial
[25]
of the posterior as well.
pie, if
—
—
knows
that the isospotentially in a sense angles also are equal to two right angles, even if one does not know that the isosceles is a triangle; but to grasp this posterior proposiceles'
tion
is
by no means to
know
the
rate universal either potentially
commensuor actually.
Moreover, commensurately universal demonstration is through and through intelligible; [jo] particular demonstration issues in senseperception. 25
The preceding arguments
constitute our de-
fence of the superiority of commensurately universal to particular demonstration.
That affirm-
demonstration excels negative
ative
shown
may
be
as follows.
We
lowing additional
rule: as the demonstration expands, the affirmative premisses must increase in number, but there cannot be more [75] than one negative premiss in each complete proof. Thus, suppose no B is A, and all C is B. Then if both the premisses are to be again expanded, a middle must be interposed. Let us interpose between A and B, and E between B and C. Then clearly E is affirmatively reis affirmatively [20] lated to B and C, while related to B but negatively to A; for all B is D, but there must be no which is A. Thus there proves to be a single negative premiss, A-D. In the further prosyllogisms too it is the same, because in the terms of an affirmative syllogism the middle is always related affirmatively to both extremes; in a negative syllogism it [25] must be negatively related only to one of them, and so this negation comes to be a single negative premiss, the other premisses being
D
D
D
may assume the superiority ceteris (1) paribus of the demonstration which derives from fewer postulates or hypotheses in short [55] from fewer premisses; for, given that all these are equally well known, where they are fewer knowledge will be more speedily acquired, and that is a desideratum. The argu-
affirmative.
ment implied in our contention that demonstration from fewer assumptions is superior may be set out in universal form as follows. Assuming that in both cases alike the middle terms are known, and that middles which are
logism
known than such as are postesuppose two demonstrations of the inherence of A in E> the one proving it 86 b through the middles B, C and D, the other through F and G. Then A-D is known to the same degree as A-E (in the second proof), but A-D is better known than and
plains denial
—
prior are better rior,
we may
prior to
A-E
(in the
first
proof); since
A-E
proved through A-D, and the ground is more certain than the conclusion. [5] Hence demonstration by fewer premisses is ceteris paribus superior. Now both affirmative and negative demonstration operate through three terms and two premisses, but whereas the former assumes only that something is, the latter assumes both that something is and that something else is not, and thus operating through more kinds of premiss is inis
ferior. 1 [10] (2) It has been proved that no conclusion follows if both premisses are negative, but that one must be negative, the other affirma-
tive. 1
So we are compelled
Prior Analytics,
1.
7.
to lay
down
the fol-
87*
is
proved
then, that through
If,
is
a better
which
known and more
a truth certain
and if the negative proposition is proved through the affirmative and not vice versa, affirmative demonstration, being prior and bettruth,
ter
known and more certain, will be superior. The basic truth of demonstrative syl-
[30] (3)
is
the universal immediate premiss,
the universal premiss
asserts
in
and
affirmative
demonstration and in negative denies: and the affirmative proposition
known than
prior to
is
and
better
the negative (since affirmation ex-
and
is
prior to denial, just as be-
m
[35] S 1S prior to not-being). It follows that the basic premiss of affirmative demonstration is
superior to that of negative demonstration,
and the demonstration which uses superior basic premisses
is
superior.
(4) Affirmative demonstration is more of the nature of a basic form of proof, because it is a sine
qua non
of negative demonstration.
26
87* Since affirmative demonstration to negative,
it is
is
superior
clearly superior also to reduc-
ad impossibile. We must first make certain what is the difference between negative demonstration and reductio ad impossibile. Let us suppose that no B is A, and that all C is B: the conclusion necessarily follows that no C is A. tio
[5] If these premisses are assumed, therefore, is the negative demonstration that no C is
A
Reductio ad impossibile, on the other hand, proceeds as follows. Supposing we are to prove that A does not inhere in B, we have
direct.
to
assume that
it
does inhere, and further that
BOOK
87 b
B
CHAPTERS
I,
24-30
119
inheres in C, with the resulting inference
that
A
inheres in C. This
known and admitted
we have
to
and we
impossibility;
A
cannot inhere in B. [10] then infer that Thus if the inherence of B in C is not ques-
B
tioned, A's inherence in
The
is
28
suppose a
impossible.
A
single science
gle genus, viz.
parts of this total subject properties.
When
87 b
is
the
One
proofs: they differ according to
the falsity of the conclusion
is
the better
[75]
known, we use reductio ad impossible;
when
the major premiss of the syllogism
the
is
more obvious, we use direct demonstration. All the same the proposition denying A of B is, in the order of being, prior to that denying A of C; for premisses are prior to the conclusion which follows from them, and 'no C is A' is the conclusion, 'no B is A' one of its premisses. [20] For the destructive result of reductio ad impossibile is not a proper conclusion, nor are its antecedents proper premisses. On the contrary: the constituents of syllogism are premisses related to one another as whole to part or part to whole, whereas the premisses A-C and [25] A-B are not thus related to one another. Now the superior demonstration is that which proceeds from better known and prior premisses, and while both these forms depend for credence on the not-being of something, yet the source of the one is prior to that of the other. Therefore negative demonstration will have an unqualified superiority to reductio ad impossibile, and affirmative demonstration, being superior to negative, will consequently [jo] be superior also to reductio ad impossibile.
The fact
science
knowledge fact,
once of the not of the fact by at
fact, is
the
more
—
the
i.e.
their essential
from another when
science differs
their
source nor
are derived those of the one science
from those
of the other. This
is
verified
when we
reach the indemonstrable premisses of a science, for they must be within one genus with
and
conclusions:
its
this
conclusions proved by
one genus
in
—
i.e.
are
again
is
verified
means of them homogeneous.
the with-
if
fall
29 [5] the
One
can have several demonstrations of
same connexion not only by taking from the same series of predication middles which are other than the immediately cohering term
—
by taking C, D, and F severally to prove also by taking a middle from another series. Thus let A be change, alterae.g.
A-B—but
D
tion of a property,
We
relaxation.
D
B
feeling pleasure,
and
G
can then without falsehood of B and A of D, for he who
[10] predicate pleased suffers alteration of a property, and
is
that
which
we can and
changes. Again, without falsehood,
alters a property
predicate
G of B; for
A
of
G
to feel pleasure
is
to relax,
and
change. So the conclusion can be drawn through middles which are different, i.e. not in the same series yet not so that neither of these middles is predicable of the [75] other, for they must both be attributable to relax
is
to
—
some one
subject.
further point worth investigating
many ways
of proving the
is
how
same conclusion can
be obtained by varying the figure.
ex-
30
science.
science such as arithmetic,
a sin-
common
A
without the reasoned
and the prior
A
is
and of the reasoned
itself
act
which
—and
basic truths have neither a
to
27
is
the subjects constituted out
of the primary entities of the genus
same in both which of the negative propositions is the better known, the one denying A of B or the one denying A of C. order of the terms
one whose domain
is
all
which
is
not a
There
is
no knowledge by demonstration
of
qua inhering in a substratum, is more exact than and prior to a science like harmonics, which is a science of properties inhering in a substratum; and similarly a science like arithmetic, which is constituted of fewer basic elements, is more exact than and prior to geometry, which requires
chance conjunctions; for chance conjunctions exist neither by necessity nor as general con[20] nexions but comprise what comes to be as something distinct from these. Now demonstration is concerned only with one or other of these two; for all reasoning proceeds from nec-
[35] additional elements. What I mean by 'additional elements' is this: a unit is substance with position; the latter contains an ad-
ing necessary if the premisses are necessary and 2 general if the premisses are general. Con[ 5] sequently, if chance conjunctions are neither general nor necessary, they are not demon-
ditional element.
strable.
science of properties
stance without position, while a point
is
sub-
essary or general premisses, the conclusion be-
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS
120 3i
knowledge
Scientific
is
not possible through
Even if perception as a faculty is of 'the such' and not merely of a 'this somewhat', yet one must at any rate actually perceive a 'this somewhat', and at a defi[30] nite present place and time: but that which is commensurately universal and true the act of perception.
in all cases
one cannot perceive, since
it is
not
and it is not 'now'; if it were, it would the term not be commensurately universal we apply to what is always and everywhere. 'this'
—
Seeing,
that
therefore,
demonstrations
are
commensurately universal and universals imperceptible,
we
clearly cannot obtain scientific
knowledge by the act of perception: nay, obvious that even if it were possible to perceive that a triangle has its angles equal to two right angles, we should still be looking for a demonstration we should not (as some say) possess knowledge of it; for perception must be of a particular, whereas scientific knowledge involves the recognition of the [^5] is
it
—
88 b
[75] saw the pores in the glass and the light passing through, the reason of the kindling would be clear to us because we should at the same time see it in each instance and intuit that it must be so in all instances.
32 All syllogisms cannot
may
This
truths.
[20] a true inference is possible premisses, yet this occurs once only
A, for instance,
is
is
Then again, (2) falsehoods are derived from a single identical set of principles: there are falsehoods which are the not
all
and cannot coexist, and 'justice is cowand 'man is ox'; 'the
contraries of one another
'man
greater',
we
if
truly predicable of C, but B,
differ in kind.
ardice';
commensurate universal. I do not, of course, deny that by watching the frequent recur-
false
mean
false,
equal
but not the reasoned fact at is not of the
I
nevertheless,
[40] light, we should not know the cause of 88 a the eclipse: we should perceive the present since the act of perception
from
—
both A-B and B-C being if middles are taken to prove these premisses, they will be false be[25] cause every conclusion which is a falsehood has false premisses, while true conclusions have true premisses, and false and true the middle,
false;
e.g.
fact of the eclipse,
have the same basic first of all by the
shown
following dialectical considerations. (1) Some syllogisms are true and some false: for though
commensurate universal. So if we were on the moon, and saw the earth shutting out the sun's
all,
be
'justice is injustice',
is
horse',
is
and
'the
equal
is less.'
From
[30] our established principles we may argue the case as follows, confining ourselves therefore to true conclusions.
inferred
them
from the same
in fact
Not even
all
basic truths;
these are
many
have basic truths which
of
differ
onstration, for the
and are not transferable; units, for which are without position, cannot take the place of points, which have position.
elicited
The
rence of this event the
commensurate
might, after tracking
universal, possess a
dem-
commensurate universal is from the several groups of singulars. [5] The commensurate universal is precious because it makes clear the cause; so that in the case of facts like these which have a cause other than themselves universal knowledge is more precious than sense-perceptions and than intuition. (As regards primary truths there is of course a different account to be given. ) Hence it is clear that knowledge of things demon1
strable
cannot be acquired by perception, un-
[10] less the term perception is applied to the possession of scientific knowledge through
demonstration. Nevertheless certain points do arise with regard to connexions to be proved which are referred for their explanation to a failure
in
when an
sense-perception:
act of vision
there
are
cases
would terminate our
we
in-
should be knowing, but because we should have elicited the universal from seeing; if, for example, we quiry, not because in seeing
l
C£., e.g., ioo b 12.
generically instance,
transferred terms could only
fit
in as
mid-
[55] die terms or as major or minor terms, or else have some of the other terms between
them, others outside them. Nor can any of the common axioms such, serve I mean, as the law of excluded middle as premisses for the proof of all conclusions. 8S h For the kinds of being are different, and some attributes attach to quanta and some to qualia only and proof is achieved by means of the common axioms taken in conjunction with these several kinds and their attributes. Again, it is not true that the basic truths are [5] much fewer than the conclusions, for the basic truths are the premisses, and the premisses are formed by the apposition of a fresh extreme term or the interposition of a fresh middle. Moreover, the number of conclusions is indefinite, though the number of middle
— —
;
terms
is
finite;
and
lastly
some
of the basic
truths are necessary, others variable.
BOOK
89*
Looking the
at
number
in this
it
way we
of conclusions
I,
CHAPTERS
see that, since indefinite, the
is
31-33
121
monstrable knowledge, which is the grasping of 89a the immediate premiss. Since then ration-
and opinion, and what
basic truths cannot be identical or limited in
al intuition, science,
on the other hand, identity is used in another sense, and it is said, e.g. 'these and no other are the fundamental truths of geometry, these the fundamentals of calculation, these again of medicine'; would the statement
revealed by these terms, are the only things that can be 'true', it follows that it is opinion
[io] number.
If,
mean anything
except that the sciences have
To
basic truths?
call
them
identical because
they are self-identical is absurd, since everything can be identified with everything in that [75] sense of identity. Nor again can the contention that truths
all
mean
conclusions have the same basic
that
from the mass
of
all
possible
premisses any conclusion may be drawn. That would be exceedingly naive, for it is not the case in the clearly evident mathematical ences, nor
is
it
possible in analysis, since
sciit is
the immediate premisses which are the basic truths, and a fresh conclusion is only formed [20] by the addition of a
new immediate prem-
be admitted that it is these primary immediate premisses which are basic truths, each subject-genus will provide one basic truth. If, however, it is not argued that from the mass of all possible premisses any conclusion may iss:
but
if it
be proved, nor yet admitted that basic truths differ so as to be generically different for each science, it remains to consider the possibility that, while the basic truths of all knowledge are within one genus, special premisses are re[25] quired to prove special conclusions. But that this cannot be the case has been shown by our proof that the basic truths of things generically different themselves differ generically.
For fundamental truths are of two kinds, those which are premisses of demonstration and the subject-genus; and though the former are common, the latter number, for instance, and magnitude are peculiar.
—
—
33
knowledge and its object differ from opinion and the object of opinion in that scientific knowledge is commensurately universal and proceeds by necessary connexions, and that which is necessary cannot be otherwise. So though there are things which are true and real and yet can be otherwise, scientific knowledge clearly does not concern them: if it did, things which can be otherwise [35] would be incapable of being otherwise. Nor are they any concern of rational intuition by rational intuition I mean an originative source of scientific knowledge nor of inde[30] Scientific
—
—
is
concerned with that which may be and can be otherwise: opinion in fact is the grasp of a premiss which is immediate but not necessary. This view also fits the [5] observed facts, for opinion is unstable, and so is the kind of being we have described as its
that
is
true or false,
when a man thinks a truth incapable of being otherwise he always thinks
object. Besides,
that he
knows
it,
never that he opines
it.
He
thinks that he opines when he thinks that a connexion, though actually so, may quite easily
be otherwise; for he believes that such is the [10] proper object of opinion, while the necessary is the object of knowledge. In what sense, then, can the same thing be the object of both opinion and knowledge?
And
any one chooses to maintain that all knows he can also opine, why should not opinion be knowledge? For he that knows and he that opines will follow the same train of thought through the same middle terms until the immediate premisses are reached; if
that he
[75] because it is possible to opine not only the fact but also the reasoned fact, and the is the middle term; so that, since the former knows, he that opines also has knowl-
reason edge.
The
truth perhaps
is
that
if
a
man
grasp
truths that cannot be other than they are, in
way in which he grasps the definitions through which demonstrations take place, he will have not opinion but knowledge: if on the other hand he apprehends these attributes as
the
inhering in their subjects, but not in virtue of the subjects' substance and essential nature, he [20] possesses opinion and not genuine knowledge; and his opinion, if obtained through immediate premisses, will be both of the fact and of the reasoned fact; if not so obtained, of the fact alone. The object of opinion and knowledge is not quite identical; it is only in a sense identical, just as the object of true
[25] opinion
is
in a sense identical.
and
false
The
sense
which some maintain that true and false opinion can have the same object leads them in
to
embrace many strange doctrines,
particular-
what a man opines falsely he does not opine at all. There are really many senses of 'identical', and in one sense the object of true and false opinion can be the same, ly the
doctrine that
in another
it
cannot. Thus, to have a true opin-
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS
122 ion that the diagonal
is
commensurate with
would be absurd: but because the diagonal with which they are both concerned is the same, the two opinions have objects so [?o] the side
far the
same: on the other hand, as regards
their essential definable nature these objects differ. The identity of the objects of knowledge and opinion is similar. Knowledge is the apprehension of, e.g. the attribute 'animal' as incapable of being otherwise, opinion the apprehension of 'animal' as capable of being [35] otherwise e.g. the apprehension that animal is an element in the essential nature of man is knowledge; the apprehension of animal as predicable of man but not as an element in man's essential nature is opinion: man is the subject in both judgements, but the mode of in-
—
man
[5]
may
90*
not essentially animal, that assume, may be other than animal. is
is,
we
Further consideration of modes of thinking their distribution under the heads of discursive thought, intuition, science, art, practical wisdom, and metaphysical thinking, be-
and
longs rather partly to natural science, partly to moral philosophy.
34 [10]
Quick wit
is
a faculty of hitting
upon the
This also shows that one cannot opine and know the same thing simultaneously; for then one would apprehend the same thing as both capable and incapable of being otherwise an
middle term instantaneously. It would be exemplified by a man who saw that the moon has her bright side always turned towards the sun, and quickly grasped the cause of this, namely that she borrows her light from him; or observed somebody in conversation with a man of wealth and divined that he was borrowing money, or that the friendship of these people sprang from a common enmity. In all these instances he has seen the major and minor terms [75] and then grasped the causes, the middle
89 b
Knowledge and opinion of same thing can co-exist in two different
terms.
people in the sense we have explained, but not simultaneously in the same person. That would involve a man's simultaneously apprehending,
ward',
herence
differs.
—
the
e.g.
impossibility.
(1) that
man
is
essentially
cannot be other than animal
animal
—and
—
i.e.
(2) that
A
Let
B
from the sun', C the moon. B, 'lighted from the sun', is predicable of C, the moon, and A, 'having her bright side
Then
towards the source of her light', is predicable [20] of B. So A is predicable of C through B.
BOOK
II
are the
two questions we ask; but
jects of
The
kinds of question
we
ask are as
many
as
which we know. They are ( 1 ) whether the connexion of an in fact four: attribute with a thing is a fact, (2) what is the reason of the connexion, (3) whether a thing [25] exists, (4) what is the nature of the thing. Thus, when our question concerns a complex of thing and attribute and we ask whether the the kinds of things
—
— —
thus or otherwise qualified whether, sun suffers eclipse or not then we are asking as to the fact of a connexion. That our inquiry ceases with the discovery that the
thing
is
e.g. the
sun does suffer eclipse
is
an indication of
this;
we know from the start that the sun suffers eclipse, we do not inquire whether it does so or not. On the other hand, when we know the fact we ask the reason; as, for example, when we know that the sun is being eclipsed
and
[jo]
if
and that an earthquake
is
in progress,
the reason of eclipse or earthquake into
we inquire. Where a complex
is
it is
which
concerned, then, those
represent 'bright side turned sun'lighted
inquiry
we have
for
some
ob-
a different kind of
question to ask, such as whether there is or not a centaur or a God. (By 'is or is not'
mean
'is
tion'; as
On
or
is
not,
opposed to
is I
without further qualifica'is
or
is
not (e.g.) white'.)
when we have ascertained existence, we inquire as to its na-
the other hand,
the thing's
ture, asking, for instance, 'what, then,
[35] or 'what
is
is
God?'
man?'.
These, then, are the four kinds of question we ask, and it is in the answers to these questions that our knowledge consists. Now when we ask whether a connexion is a fact, or whether a thing without qualification is, we are really asking whether the connexion or the thing has a 'middle'; and when we have ascertained either that the connexion i.e. ascertained is a fact or that the thing is either the partial or the unqualified being of 90 a the thing and are proceeding to ask the reason of the connexion or the nature of the
—
—
BOOK
90b
we
thing, then
CHAPTERS 33-34— BOOK
I,
are asking
what the 'middle'
is.
(By distinguishing the fact of the connexion and the existence of the thing as respectively the partial and the unqualified being of the ask 'does the moon moon wax?', the question concerns a part of the thing's being; for what we are asking in such questions is whether a thing is this or that, i.e. has or has not this or that attribute: whereas, if we ask whether the moon or night exists, the question concerns the unqualified being of a thing.) conclude that in all our inquiries we [5] are asking either whether there is a 'middle' or what the 'middle' is: for the 'middle' here is precisely the cause, and it is the cause that we seek in all our inquiries. Thus, 'Does the moon suffer eclipse?' means 'Is there or is there not a thing,
I
mean
that
if
we
suffer eclipse?', or 'does the
We
if
CHAPTERS
II,
we were on
the
1-3
moon we
123
should not be
in-
quiring either as to the fact or the reason, but both fact and reason would be obvious simultaneously. For the act of perception would have enabled us to know the universal too; since, the present fact of an eclipse being evident, perception would then at the same time give us the present fact of the earth's screening the [50] sun's light, universal.
Thus, ture is
is
and from
this
would
arise the
we maintain, to know a thing's naknow the reason why it is; and this
as
to
equally true of things in so far as they are
opposed to being possessed of some attribute, and in so far as they are said to be possessed of some attribute such as equal to two right angles, or said without qualification to be as
greater or
less.
cause producing eclipse of the moon?', and when we have learnt that there is, our next question
'What, then,
is,
is
this cause?'; for the
—
cause through which a thing is not is this [10] or that, i.e. has this or that attribute,
—
but without qualification is and the cause through which it is not is without qualification, but is this or that as having some essential attribute or some accident are both alike the 'middle'. By that which is without qualifica-
—
—
tion
mean
I
the subject, e.g.
moon
or earth or
sun or triangle; by that which a subject
[35] ^ is clear, then, that all questions are a search for a 'middle'. Let us now state how essential nature is revealed, and in what way it can be reduced to demonstration; what defini-
tion
is,
and what things are
definable.
And
let
which these 90 b questions raise, beginning what we have to say with a point most intimately connected us
first
with
discuss certain difficulties
our
immediately
preceding
remarks,
vation of the moon's light by the interposition
namely the doubt that might be felt as to whether or not it is possible to know the same thing in the same relation, both by definition and by demonstration. It might, I mean, be urged that definition is held to concern essential nature and is in every case universal and affirmative; whereas, on the other hand, some [5] conclusions are negative and some are not
of the earth' are identical with the question
universal; e.g.
the
sense)
partial
I
mean
a
is
(in
property, e.g.
eclipse, equality or inequality, interposition or
non-interposition. is
For
in all these
examples
clear that the nature of the thing
it
and the
[75] reason of the fact are identical: the question 'What is eclipse?' and its answer 'The pri-
'What
is
the reason of eclipse?' or
moon
'Why
does
tive,
none
in
again, not even
note concordant?'
sions as these
ratio it
is
suffer eclipse?'
is
equivalent to
'Is
their
commensurate?'; and when we find that commensurate, we ask 'What, then, is
the
first
has
its
And
the third are universal.
and the reply 'Because of the failure of light through the earth's shutting it out'. Again, for 'What is a concord? A commensurate numerical ratio of a high and a low note', we may substitute 'What reason [20] makes a high and a low note concordant? Their relation according to a commensurate numerical ratio.' 'Are the high and the low the
in the second figure are nega-
all
all
affirmative conclusions in
figure are definable, e.g. 'every triangle
An
angles equal to two right angles'.
argument proving this difference between demonstration and definition is that to have scientific knowledge of the demonstrable is [10] identical with possessing a demonstration it: hence if demonstration of such conclu-
of
is
possible, there clearly cannot
also be definition of them. If there could,
might know such
definition without possessing the
their ratio?'.
its
Cases in which the 'middle' is sensible show [25] that the object of our inquiry is always the 'middle': we inquire, because we have not perceived it, whether there is or is not a 'middle' causing, e.g. an eclipse. On the other hand,
stration of
it;
one
a conclusion also in virtue of
for there
is
demon-
nothing to stop our
having the one without the other. Induction too will sufficiently convince us of [75] this difference; for never yet by defining anything essential attribute or accident did
—
—
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS
I2 4
we
get
knowledge of it. Again, if to define is knowledge of a substance, at any
to acquire
rate such attributes are not substances. It is evident, then, that not everything demonstrable can be defined. What then? Can everything definable be demonstrated, or not? There is one of our previous arguments which [20] covers this too. Of a single thing qua single there is a single scientific knowledge. Hence, since to know the demonstrable scientifically is to possess the demonstration of it, posan impossible consequence will follow: session of its definition without its demonstration will give knowledge of the demonstrable. Moreover, the basic premisses of demonstrations are definitions, and it has already been shown 1 that these will be found indemonstra[25] ble; either the basic premisses will be demonstrable and will depend on prior premisses, and the regress will be endless; or the primary truths will be indemonstrable definitions. But if the definable and the demonstrable are not wholly the same, may they yet be partially the same? Or is that impossible, because there can be no demonstration of the defin[30] able? There can be none, because definition is of the essential nature or being of something, and all demonstrations evidently posit and assume the essential nature mathematical demonstrations, for example, the nature of unity and the odd, and all the other sciences likewise. Moreover, every demonstration proves a predicate of a subject as attaching or as not attaching to it, but in definition one thing is [35] not predicated of another; we do not, e.g. predicate animal of biped nor biped of animal, nor yet figure of plane plane not being figure nor figure plane. Again, to prove essential nature is not the same as to prove the fact of a 91 a connexion. Now definition reveals essential nature, demonstration reveals that a given attribute attaches or does not attach to a given subject; but different things require different demonstrations unless the one demonstration is related to the other as part to whole. I add this because if all triangles have been proved to possess angles equal to two right angles, then this attribute has been proved to attach to
—
—
—
—
isosceles ; for isosceles
is
a part of
which
all tri-
[5] angles constitute the whole. But in the case before us the fact and the essential nature
are not so related to one another, since the one
not a part of the other. So it emerges that not all the definable is demonstrable nor all the demonstrable definis
1
Cf. 72 b 18-25 and 84* 30-* 2.
91'
and we may draw the general conclusion is no identical object of which it is possible to possess both a definition and a demable;
that there
[10] onstration. nition
It
follows obviously that defi-
and demonstration are neither
identical
nor contained either within the other: if they were, their objects would be related either as
whole and
identical or as
part.
So much, then,
for the first stage of our probnext step is to raise the question whether syllogism i.e. demonstration of the
The
lem.
—
definable nature
—
possible or, as our recent
is
argument assumed, impossible. We might argue it impossible on the lowing grounds:
fol-
(a) syllogism proves an at-
through the middle term; [75] on the other hand (b) its definable nature is both 'peculiar' to a subject and predicated of it as belonging to its essence. But in tribute of a subject
that case ( 1 ) the subject, its definition, and the middle term connecting them must be reciprocally predicable of one another; for if A is 'peculiar' to C, obviously
B
and
to
C—in
universally of
A
ing to
is
'peculiar' to
also
its
all
all
B
terms are 'pecul-
one another: and further (2)
iar' to
heres in the essence of [20]
A
fact all three
B and B
is
C as belonging to
must be predicated
of
if
A
in-
predicated
C's essence,
C
as belong-
essence.
If one does not take this relation as thus duplicated if, that is, A is predicated as being of the essence of B, but B is not of the essence of the subjects of which it is predicated A
—
will not necessarily be predicated of C as belonging to its essence. So both premisses will predicate essence, and consequently B also will be predicated of C as its essence. Since, there[25] fore, both premisses do predicate essence
—
definable
i.e.
form
— C's definable form
will
appear in the middle term before the conclusion
is
drawn.
We may
generalize by supposing that
possible to prove the essential nature of
Let
C
be man,
A
man's
essential nature
we
all
are to syllogize,
A
is
—two-
Then, must be predicated of
footed animal, or aught else if
may
it
man.
it
be.
B. But this premiss will be mediated by a
[50] fresh definition, which consequently will also be the essential nature of man. Therefore the argument assumes what it has to prove, since is,
the
B
too
is
the essential nature of
man.
It
however, the case in which there are only
—
two premisses i.e. in which the premisses and immediate which we ought
are primary
—
92
BOOK
a
because
to investigate
II,
CHAPTERS
best illustrates the
it
point under discussion. [55] Thus they who prove the essential nature
man
3-6
125
[25] not the whole of this formula be true of man, and yet not exhibit his essential nature or definable
form? Again, what guarantee
is
or anything else through recip-
there against an unessential addition, or against
rocating terms beg the question. It would be begging the question, for example, to contend
the omission of the final or of an intermediate determinant of the substantial being? The champion of division might here urge that though these lapses do occur, yet we can
of soul or
is that which causes its own life, what causes its own life is a selfmoving number; for one would have to postu-
that the soul
and
that
solve that difficulty
the attributes
if all
we
as-
late that the soul is a self-moving number in 91 b the sense of being identical with it. For if
and
A
division the requisite uninterrupted sequence
is
B of
predicable as a
A will
C,
mere consequent of
not on that account be the defin-
A
able form of C:
Even
B inasmuch
B
still it
as
merely be what
will
true to say of C.
of A,
B and
if
A
is
predicated of
identical
is
with a species an animal
—
be animal, just as
an animal
is
all
will not follow: being
since [5] is predicated of being a man true that in all instances to be human
man
was
it
it
also
is
—but not
it is is
to
true that every as identical
with
being man. We conclude, then, that unless one takes both the premisses as predicating essence, one cannot infer that
A
is
the definable
form and
es-
sume
are constituents of the definable form,
if,
of terms,
[30]
what
and omit nothing; and
we cannot
fail to fulfil
—
—
further question be (ultimately) incapable of fresh specific division. Nevertheless,
we
reply,
division does not involve inference;
if it
gives
knowledge, it gives it in another way. Nor is there any absurdity in this: induction, perhaps, is not demonstration any more than is division, yet it does make evident some truth. Yet to [^5] state a definition reached by division is
ing the conclusion, what the definable form of [10] C is; so that there has been no inference, for one has begged the question.
the alleged necessity by
Nor, as was said in
method
my
formal
logic,
1
is
of division a process of inference at
the all,
no point does the characterization of the subject follow necessarily from the premising of certain other facts: division demonic] strates as little as does induction. For in a genuine demonstration the conclusion must not be put as a question nor depend on a concession, but must follow necessarily from its premisses, even if the respondent deny it. The definer asks 'Is man animal or inanimate?' and since at
—
—
are
drawn without
pothetically,
the complete formula,
terrestrial-animal, does not follow necessarily
from the premisses: this too is an assumption, and equally an assumption whether the division comprises
many
differentiae or few. (Indeed
used by those who proceed by it, even truths that can be inferred actually fail to appear as such.) For why should as this
1
method
of division
Cf. Prior Analytics,
i.
31.
is
conclusions
which the inference is open to a ques-
as to the reason for it, so definitions reached by division invite the same question. 92 a Thus to the question 'What is the essential nature of man?' the divider replies 'Animal, mortal, footed, biped, wingless'; and when at each step he is asked 'Why?', he will say, and, as he thinks, proves by division, that all animal is mortal or immortal: but such a formula taken in its entirety is not definition; so that even if division does demonstrate its formula, definition at any rate does not turn [5] out to be a conclusion of inference.
haustive division of animal into terrestrial and [20] aquatic, he assumes that man is terrestrial. is
when
tion
Can we
man
as,
their appropriate middles,
follows from the premisses
then assumes he has not inferred that man is animal. Next, when presented with an ex-
Moreover, that
if
to be divided falls
not to state a conclusion:
suming B
if
that indeed
these conditions
whole into the division at each stage, and none of it is omitted; and that this the dividendum must without is
one does so take them, in asone will have assumed, before draw-
sence of C: but
we produce by
postulating the genus,
what and substantially is, but hyby premising (1) that its de-
nevertheless actually demonstrate
a thing essentially
finable
form
tributes of
i.e.
is
its
constituted by the 'peculiar' atessential nature; (2) that such
and such are the only attributes of its essential and that the complete synthesis of them since in this is peculiar to the thing; and thus
nature,
—
synthesis consists the being of the thing
taining our conclusion?
Or
is
—ob-
the truth that,
[10] since proof must be through the middle term, the definable form is once more assumed in this minor premiss too?
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS
126
we do
Further, just as in syllogizing
not
premise what syllogistic inference is (since the premisses from which we conclude must be related as
form within the syllogism but remain
whole and
must not
fall
part), so the definable
outside the premisses posited.
It is
only against
[75] a doubt as to its having been a syllogistic inference at all that we have to defend our ar-
gument as conforming to the definition of syllogism. It is only when some one doubts whether form conforming to the definition of definable form which we assumed. Hence syllogistic inference must be possible the conclusion proved
we have
that
to
defend
is
it
the definable
as
even without the express statement of what syllogism
is
or
what definable form
The following
[20]
is.
type of hypothetical proof
also begs the question. If evil
is
definable as
and the definition of a thing's contrary if it has one is the contrary of the thing's definition; then, if good is the contrary of evil and the indivisible of the divisible, we conclude that to be good is essentially to be indivisible. The question is begged because definable form is assumed as a premiss, and as a premiss which is to prove definable form. 'But [25] not the same definable form', you may object. That I admit, for in demonstrations also the divisible,
—
—
we premise that 'this' is predicable of 'that'; but in this premiss the term we assert of the minor is neither the major itself nor a term identical in definition, or convertible,
with the
major. Again, both proof by division and the syllogism just described are open to the question why man should be animal-biped-terrestrial and not merely animal and terrestrial, since [50] what they premise does not ensure that the predicates shall constitute a genuine unity and not merely belong to a single subject as do musical and grammatical when predicated of the
same man.
How
then by definition shall
we prove
sub-
We
cannot [55] stance or essential nature? show it as a fresh fact necessarily following
from the assumption of premisses admitted to be facts the method of demonstration: we may not proceed as by induction to establish a
—
universal on the evidence of groups of particulars
which
no exception, because inducwhat the essential nature of a but that it has or has not some
offer
tion proves not 92 b thing is
Therefore, since presumably one cannot prove essential nature by an appeal to attribute.
92 b
sense perception or by pointing with the finger, what other method remains?
To
another way: how shall we by prove essential nature? He who knows what human or any other nature is, [5] must know also that man exists; for no one knows the nature of what does not exist one can know the meaning of the phrase or name 'goat-stag' but not what the essential nature of a goat-stag is. But further, if definition can prove what is the essential nature of a thing, can it also prove that it exists? And how will it prove them both by the same process, since definition exhibits one single thing and dem[10] onstration another single thing, and what human nature is and the fact that man exists are not the same thing? Then too we hold that it is by demonstration that the being of everything must be proved unless indeed to be were its essence; and, since being is not a genus, it is not the essence of anything. Hence the being of anything as fact is matter for derai-
put
it
definition
—
—
—
—
ls]
onstration;
and
this
is
the actual proce-
dure of the sciences, for the geometer assumes the meaning of the word triangle, but that it is possessed of some attribute he proves. What is it, then, that we shall prove in defining essential nature? Triangle? In that case a man will know by definition what a thing's nature is without knowing whether it exists. But that is impossible.
Moreover it is clear, if we consider the methods of defining actually in use, that definidoes not prove that the thing defined if there does actually exist something which is equidistant from a centre, yet why should the thing named in the definition exist? Why, in other words, should this be the formula defining circle? One might equally well call it the definition of mountain copper. For definitions do not carry a further guarantee that the thing defined can exist or that it is what they claim to define: one can [25] always ask why. Since, therefore, to define is to prove either a thing's essential nature or the meaning of its name, we may conclude that definition, if it in no sense proves essential nature, is a set of tion
[20] exists: since even
words signifying precisely what a name signifies. But that were a strange consequence; for ( 1 ) both what is not substance and what does not exist at all would be definable, since even non-existents can be signified by a name: (2) [jo] all sets of words or sentences would be definitions, since any kind of sentence could be given a name; so that we should all be talking
BOOK
93 b
CHAPTERS
II,
and even the Iliad would be a definition: (3) no demonstration can prove that any particular name means any particular thing: neither, therefore, do definitions, in addition to revealing the meaning of a name, also reveal that the name has this meaning. It ap[35] P ears tnen from these considerations that neither definition and syllogism nor their objects are identical, and further that definition neither demonstrates nor proves anything, and that knowledge of essential nature is not to be in definitions,
6-8
127
[20] rant whether it exists we cannot know its essential nature. Moreover we are aware
whether a thing exists or not sometimes through apprehending an element in its character, and sometimes accidentally, as, for example, when we are aware of thunder as a noise in the clouds, of eclipse as a privation of
man
light, or of
we have
[25] exists,
tion.
ture; for
even of
We
must now
and consider which of these conclusions are sound and which are not, and what is the nature of definition, and whether essential nature is in any sense demonstrable and definable or in none.
Now
to
know
its
essential nature
is,
we
as
same as to know the cause of a thing's existence, and the proof of this depends on the [5] fact that a thing must have a cause. Moresaid,
1
the
over, this cause
either identical with the es-
is
sential nature of the thing or distinct
and
if its
cause
is
distinct
from
it,
from
it;
the essential
nature of the thing is either demonstrable or indemonstrable. Consequently, if the cause is distinct from the thing's essential nature and demonstration is possible, the cause must be
exists
often as
awareness of its essential nanot got genuine knowledge
existence,
its
is
As
we have
essential nature
start afresh
species of animal, or
knowledge that the thing we must be in a wholly negative
state as regards
93*
some
accidental
obtained either by definition or by demonstra-
8
as
of the soul as a self-moving thing.
and
to search for a thing's
when we
are
unaware
to search for nothing.
hand, whenever
On
that
we apprehend an element
the thing's character there
is
less
it
the other in
difficulty.
Thus it follows that the degree of our knowledge of a thing's essential nature is determined by the sense in which we are aware that it exists. Let us then take the following as our first instance of being aware of an element in the [jo] essential nature. Let A be eclipse, C the moon, B the earth's acting as a screen. Now to ask whether the moon is eclipsed or not is to ask whether or not B has occurred. But that is precisely the same as asking whether A has a defining condition; and if this condition actually exists,
Or
again
we assert that A also actually exists. we may ask which side of a contra-
the middle term, and, the conclusion proved being universal and affirmative, the proof is in
diction the defining condition necessitates: does it make the angles of a triangle equal or not
So the method just examined through another essential nature [10] would be one way of proving essential
equal to two right angles? When we have found the answer, if the premisses are im[55] mediate, we know fact and reason to gether; if they are not immediate, we know the fact without the reason, as in the following example: let C be the moon, A eclipse, B the
the
first figure.
of proving
it
nature, because a conclusion containing essential
nature must be inferred through a middle is an essential nature just as a 'peculiar'
which
property must be inferred through a middle which is a 'peculiar' property; so that of the two definable natures of a single thing this
one and not the other. was said before 2 that this method could not amount to demonstration of essential
method
Now
will prove it
—
nature
it is
actually a dialectical proof of
[75] so let us begin again
method
it
it
and explain by what
can be demonstrated.
When we
are
aware of a fact we seek its reason, and though sometimes the fact and the reason dawn on us simultaneously, yet we cannot apprehend the reason a moment sooner than the fact; and clearly in just the same way we cannot apprehend a thing's definable form without apprehending that it exists, since while we are igno-
moon
fails to produce shadows and though no visible body intervenes between us and her. Then if B, failure to produce shadows in spite of the ab93 b sence of an intervening body, is attributable to C, and A, eclipse, is attributable to B, it
fact that the
though she
is full
moon is eclipsed, but the reanot yet clear, and we know that eclipse exists, but we do not know what its essential nature is. But when it is clear that A is attributable to C and we proceed to ask the reason of this fact, we are inquiring what is the [5] nature of B: is it the earth's acting as a is
clear that the
son
why
is
screen, or the tion ?
But
B
is
moon's rotation or her
extinc-
the definition of the other term,
viz. in these
examples, of the major term A;
for eclipse
constituted by the earth acting as
is
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS
128 a screen. Thus, (i)
quenching of
'What
fire in cloud',
thunder?' 'Because
it
fire
is thunder?' 'The and (2) 'Why does is quenched in the
[10] cloud', are equivalent. Let C be cloud, thunder, B the quenching of fire. Then B
is
is
quenched and B assuredly the definition of the major term A.
attributable to C, cloud, since fire in
A
and A,
it;
noise,
is
is
attributable to B;
there be a further mediating cause of B, it will be one of the remaining partial definitions If
of A.
—
i.e. no dethat, while there is no syllogism monstrative syllogism of essential nature, yet it is through syllogism, viz. demonstrative syl-
—
logism, that essential nature is exhibited. So we conclude that neither can the essential nature
which has
of anything
demonstration, nor
be
can
be demonstrated; and this
it
from
a cause distinct
known without
itself
is
what we con-
[20] tended in our preliminary discussions.
1
dentally in a single subject.
That then is one way of defining definition. Another kind of definition is a formula exhibiting the cause of a thing's existence.
94 a the former
signifies
while some things have from themselves, others have
a cause distinct
evident that there are essential are immediate, that
Hence it is natures which
not.
and what some
are basic premisses;
is
of these not only that they are but also
they are must be assumed or revealed in is the actual procedure of the arithmetician, who assumes both the na[25] ture and the existence of unit. On the
the latter will clearly be a l8 contigu-
movements per
The unmovable (226 b 10) The meaning of 'together,' 'intermediate,'
'successive,
10.
BOOK Whatever
ous,' 'continuous' 4.
The
unity and diversity of move-
227b 3
6.
moved
is
VII
moved by
is
something There is a first movent which by anything else (242 s 19)
ments 5.
That which has not parts cannot move 24o b 8 Can change be infinite? (241 s 26)
22Q a 7 Contrariety of movement 229^ 22 Contrariety of movement and rest Contrariety of natural and unnatural movement or rest (23o a 18)
is
24^24 not
The movent and
the moved are together All alteration pertains to sensible
moved 243 a 3 b 245 2
qualities
BOOK 1.
Every continuum
consists of con-
23i a 20
BOOK
tinuous and divisible parts 2.
(Continued)
3.
A moment
4.
ing is moved, or rests, Whatever is moved is
is
indivisible
and noth-
in a
232 a 23 b 233 32
moment
divisible
5.
Whatever has changed as
is,
as
soon
has changed, in that to which
it
4.
similarly divided (235 s 13)
changed That in which
(directly)
it
235^6 it
has changed
is
5.
has in-
6.
divisible (235 b 32)
6.
In change there is a last but no first element (236^ 7) In whatever time a thing changes 236 b 20 (directly), it changes in any part of that time Whatever changes has changed before, and whatever has changed, before was changing (2 3 6
7.
The
b
finitude or infinity of
move-
b 23 7 23
to rest, and of rest 238 b 23 thing that is moved in any time directly is in no part of that time in a part of the space through which it moves (239 s 23) 2 39b 5 9. Refutation of the arguments against the possibility of movement
Of coming
There are things that are some253*21 times in movement, sometimes at rest b Whatever is in movement is moved 254 7 by something else The first movent is not moved 256*3 by anything outside itself The first movent is immovable (257*31) The immovable first movent is 258 b 10 eternal and one
The
first
tally
(259* 20)
movent
is
Locomotion
is
not is
moved even
8.
Only
circular
inciden-
eternal (259b 32)
the primary kind of
or change locomotion (261*28)
ment, of extension, and of the moved 8.
movement
movement No movement
32)
2 5 2b 7
Refutation of objections to the
The primum mobile 7.
250 b 10
movement
eternity of 3.
VIII
There always has been and always will be
2.
movement (234b 2i) The time, the movement, the being-in-motion, the moving body, and the sphere of movement, all
1.
234° 10
Classification of
are
248 s 10 249b 26
Comparison of movements Proportion of movements
VI
is
260* 20
continuous except
movement can be
26 b 26
continuous and infinite 9.
A
[o.
265* 13 movement is the primary kind of locomotion Confirmation of the above doctrines (265* 27) 266* 10 The first movent has no parts nor magnitude, and is at the circumference of the
Circular
world.
PHYSICS BOOK 184 a [10] When the any department, have
objects of
an inquiry, in
principles, conditions, or
through acquaintance with these that knowledge, that is to say scientific knowledge, is attained. For we do not think that we know a thing until we are acquainted with its primary conditions or first principles, and have carried our analysis as far as its simplest eleelements,
it is
ments. Plainly therefore in the science of Nat/5] ture, as in other branches of study, our first task will be to try to determine what relates to its principles.
The natural way of doing this is to start from the things which are more knowable and obvious to us and proceed towards those which are clearer and more knowable by nature; for the same things are not 'knowable relatively to us' and 'knowable' without qualification. So in the present inquiry we must follow this method and advance from what is more obscure by [20] nature, but clearer to us, towards what is more clear and more knowable by nature. Now what is to us plain and obvious at first is rather confused masses, the elements and principles of which become known to us later by analysis. Thus we must advance from generalities to particulars; for it is a whole that is [25] best known to sense-perception, and a generality is a kind of whole, comprehending
many
things within
of the 'round',
name
formula.
the
to
means vaguely
Much
its
and
all
women
(a) one,
it
must be
particular senses. all
men
either (i) motionless, assert, or (ii) in
;
Oxford
—
tioned, there
principle
is
a principle
must be the
no longer, since a some thing
principle of
or things. [5] To inquire therefore whether Being is in this sense would be like arguing against
one any
ing a merely contentious argument
Note: The bold face numbers and letters are approximate indications of the pages and columns of the standard Berlin Greek text; the bracketed numbers, of the lines in the Greek text they are here assigned as they are assigned in the
this
for a different science or for
thesis as that
'mother', but later on
Parmenides and Melissus
—
being a question one common to all so a man investigating principles cannot argue with one who denies their existence. For if Being is just one, and one in the way men-
principles of his science
e.g.
its
[75] The principles in question must be either (a) one or (b) more than one. If
one or many.
def-
name,
the
distinguishes each of them.
as
is
Now
to investigate whether Being is one and motionless is not a contribution to the sci185 a ence of Nature. For just as the geometer has nothing more to say to one who denies the
[25]
A
Similarly a child begins by calling 'father',
ment
other position maintained for the sake of argument (such as the Heraclitean thesis, or such a
a sort of whole:
inition analyses this into
motion, as the physicists hold, some declaring air to be the first principle, others water. If (b) more than one, then either (i) a finite or (ii) an infinite plurality. If (i) finite (but more than one), then either two or three or [20] four or some other number. If (ii) infinite, then either as Democritus believed one in kind, but differing in shape or form; or different in kind and even contrary. A similar inquiry is made by those who inquire into the number of existents: for they inquire whether the ultimate constituents of existing things are one or many, and if many, whether a finite or an infinite plurality. So they too are inquiring whether the principle or ele-
in the relation
like parts.
it,
184b [10] same thing happens
I
translation.
259
Being
is
one man) or
like refut-
—
a descrip-
which applies to the arguments both of Melissus and of Parmenides: their premisses [10] are false and their conclusions do not follow. Or rather the argument of Melissus is gross and palpable and offers no difficulty at all: accept one ridiculous proposition and the a simple enough proceeding. rest follows We physicists, on the other hand, must take tion
—
for granted that the things that exist by nature are, either all or
which
is
indeed
some
made
motion by induction.
of them, in
plain
Moreover, no man of science is bound to solve [75] every kind of difficulty that may be raised, but only as many as are drawn falsely from the principles of the science: it is not our business
PHYSICS
260
do not
to refute those that
just as
arise in this
way:
the duty of the geometer to refute
it is
the squaring of the circle by means of segments, but it is not his duty to refute Antiphon's proof. At the same time the holders of the theory of which we are speaking do inci-
Na-
dentally raise physical questions, though ture
is
not their subject: so
it
will perhaps be
spend a few words on them, espeas the inquiry is not without scientific
186 a
on its own whether the part and the whole are one or more than one, and how they can be one or many, and, if they are more than gument, account
yet deserving consideration
—namely,
what sense they are more than one. (Similarly with the parts of wholes which are [75] not continuous.) Further, if each of the
one, in
two
parts
is
indivisibly
one with the whole, the be indivisibly one
as well to
difficulty arises that they will
cially
with each other also. But to proceed: If (b) their One is one as indivisible, nothing will have quantity or quality, and so the one will not be infinite, as Melissus says nor, indeed, limited, as Parmenides says, for though the limit is indivisible,
interest.
'[20]
The most
pertinent question with which
to begin will be this: In
ed that
many
all
what
sense
things are one? For
senses.
is it
'is' is
Do they mean that all
assert-
used in
things
'are'
substance or quantities or qualities? And, furone man, ther, are all things one substance one horse, or one soul or quality and that one white or hot or something [25] and the same of the kind? These are all very different doctrines and all impossible to maintain. For if both substance and quantity and qual-
—
ity are, then,
—
—
whether these
exist
independently
of each other or not, Being will be If
on the other hand
it
is
many.
asserted that
all
things are quality or quantity, then, whether substance exists or not, an absurdity results, if
indeed the impossible can properly be For none of the others can exist independently: substance alone is independent: for everything is predicated of substance as subject. Now Melissus says that Being is infinite. It is then a quantity. For the infinite is in the category of quantity, whereas substance or quality or affection cannot be infinite except through a concomitant attribute, that is, if at 185 b the same time they are also quantities. For to define the infinite you must use quantity in your formula, but not substance or quality. If then Being is both substance and quantity, it is two, not one: if only substance, it is not infinite and has no magnitude; for to have that it will have to be a quantity. [5] Again, 'one' itself, no less than 'being', is used in many senses, so we must consider in what sense the word is used when it is said that [30]
called absurd.
the All
is
one.
Now we
say that (a) the continuous
or that (b) the indivisible
is
is
one
one, or (c) things
and the same,
the limited
is
not.
But if (c) all things are one in the sense of having the same definition, like 'raiment' and [20] 'dress', then it turns out that they are maintaining the Heraclitean doctrine, for it will be the same thing 'to be good' and 'to be bad', and 'to be good' and 'to be not good', and so the same thing will be 'good' and 'not good', and man and horse; in fact, their view will be, not that all things are one, but that they are nothing; and that 'to be of such-and-such a quality' is the same as 'to be of such-and-such a size'.
[25]
Even
were
the
more
recent of the ancient think-
same thing should turn out in their hands both one and many. So some, like Lycophron, were led to omit 'is',
ers
in a pother lest the
mode of expression and has been whitened' instead of 'is white', and 'walks' instead of 'is walking', for [50] fear that if they added the word 'is' they should be making the one to be many as if 'one' and 'being' were always used in one and the same sense. What 'is' may be many either in definition (for example 'to be white' is one thing, 'to be musical' another, yet the same others to change the say 'the
man
—
may
is many) or by whole and its parts. On this 186 a point, indeed, they were already getting into difficulties and admitted that the one was many as if there was any difficulty about the same thing being both one and many, provided
thing
be both, so the one
division, as the
—
these are not opposites; for 'one'
that
mean
may
either 'potentially one' or 'actually one'.
when
their essence is one and 'drink'. If (a) their One is one in the sense of con[10] tinuous, it is many, for the continuous is divisible ad infinitum. There is, indeed, a difficulty about part and
are said to be 'one',
—
as 'liquor'
whole, perhaps not relevant to the present ar-
we approach the thesis in this way seems impossible for all things to be one. Further, the arguments they use to prove their position are not difficult to expose. For both of them reason contentiously I mean both MeIf,
[5]
then, it
—
BOOK
186 b
I,
CHAPTERS
lissus
Hence
false
anything
and Parmenides. [Their premisses are and their conclusions do not follow. Or rather the argument of Melissus is gross and palpable and offers no difficulty at all: admit one ridiculous proposition and the rest follows a simple enough proceeding.] [10] The fallacy of Melissus is obvious. For he
—
supposes that the assumption 'what has come into being always has a beginning' justifies the assumption 'what has not come into being has no beginning'. Then this also is absurd, that in every case there should be a beginning of the thing not of the time and not only in the case of coming to be in the full sense but also in the
—
case of
coming
to
have a quality
—
as
if
change
[75] never took place suddenly. Again, does it follow that Being, if one, is motionless? Why should it not move, the whole of it within itself,
parts
as
of
it
do which are
unities,
this water? Again, why is qualitative change impossible? But, further, Being cannot [20] be one in form, though it may be in what it is made of. (Even some of the physicists hold it to be one in the latter way, though not in the former.) Man obviously differs from horse in form, and contraries from each other. The same kind of argument holds good against Parmenides also, besides any that may apply specially to his view: the answer to him being that 'this is not true' and 'that does not follow'. His assumption that one is used in a
e.g.
because it is used in His conclusion does not follow, take only white things, and if
single sense only
[25] several.
because
if
we
is false,
2-3
261
'substance' will not be a predicate of else.
For the subject cannot be a be-
means
several things, in such something. But ex hypothesi 'being' means only one thing. If, then, 'substance' is not attributed to anything, but other things are attributed to it, how [5] does 'substance' mean what is rather than what is not? For suppose that 'substance' is
ing, unless 'being' a
way
that each
is
also 'white'. Since the definition of the latter
white, as nothing it
which
is
follows that 'white'
is
is
even be attributed to
different (for being cannot
is
not 'substance'),
not-being
—and that
not in the sense of a particular not-being, but in the sense that it is not at all. Hence 'sub[10] stance' is not; for it is true to say that it white, which we found to mean not-being.
is
If to
avoid this we say that even 'white' means it follows that 'being' has more than
substance,
one meaning. In particular, then, Being will not have nitude,
if it is
magtwo
substance. For each of the
must be in a different sense. (2) Substance is plainly divisible into other substances, if we consider the mere nature of a [75] definition. For instance, if 'man' is a sub-
parts
and 'biped' must also be subFor if not substances, they must be attributes and if attributes, attributes either of (a) man or of (b) some other subject. But neistance, 'animal' stances.
ther
possible.
is
An
(a) [20]
—
is either that which may or not belong to the subject or that in
attribute
may
whose
definition the subject of
Thus
which it is an an exam-
meaning, none the less what is white will be many and not one. For what is white will not be one either in the sense
attribute
continuous or in the sense that it must be defined in only one way. 'Whiteness' will be different from 'what has whiteness'. Nor does this mean that there is anything that can [50] exist separately, over and above what is
attribute snubness. Further, the definition of
'white' has a single
that
it is
white. For 'whiteness' and 'that which
is
white'
differ in definition, not in the sense that they are
which can exist apart from each other. But Parmenides had not come in sight of this
things
distinction. It is
necessary for him, then, to assume not
only that 'being' has the same meaning, of whatever it is predicated, but further that it
means ( 1 ) what just is and (2) what is just one. It must be so, for (1) an attribute is predicated of some subject, so that the subject to [55] which 'being' is attributed will not be, as it is something different from 'being'. Some186 b thing, therefore, which is not will be.
is
involved.
'sitting' is
ple of a separable attribute, while 'snubness'
contains the definition of 'nose', to which the
whole
is
we
not contained in the definitions of
the contents or elements of the definitory for-
mula; that of 'man' for instance in [25] that of 'white is so,
and
if
'biped'
man' is
'biped', or
in 'white'. If then this
supposed to be an
attri-
bute of 'man', it must be either separable, so that 'man' might possibly not be 'biped', or the definition of 'man' must come into the defini-
—
which [50] tion of 'biped' the converse is the case.
is
impossible, as
on the other hand, we suppose that and 'animal' are attributes not of man but of something else, and are not each of them a substance, then 'man' too will be an attribute of something else. But we must assume that substance is not the attribute of anything, and that the subject of which both 'biped' and 'animal' and each separately are predicated is the (b)
'biped'
If,
PHYSICS
262 subject also of the
[35] Are
complex 'biped animal'.
we
then to say that the All is composed of indivisible substances? Some thinkers 187 a did, in point of fact, give way to both arguments. To the argument that all things are
being means one thing, they conceded is; to that from bisection, they yielded by positing atomic magnitudes. But obviously it is not true that if being means one thing, and cannot at the same time mean the [5] contradictory of this, there will be nothing which is not, for even if what is not cannot be without qualification, there is no reason why it should not be a particular not-being. To say that all things will be one, if there is nothing besides Being itself, is absurd. For who understands 'being itself to be anything but a particular substance? But if this is so, there is nothing to prevent there being many beings, as has been said. [10] It is, then, clearly impossible for Being to be one in this sense.
one
if
that not-being
The
physicists
modes
on the other hand have two
of explanation.
make the underlying body one one of the three or something else which is denser than fire and rarer than air [75] then generate everything else from this, and obtain multiplicity by condensation and
—
The
first set
either
rarefaction.
Now
these are contraries,
may
which
be generalized into 'excess and defect'. except Plato's 'Great and Small' that he make these his matter, the one his form, while the others treat the one which underlies
—
(Compare
as
matter and the contraries as differentiae,
i.e.
forms). [20] The second set assert that the contrarieties are contained in the one and emerge from it
by segregation, for example Anaximander and also all those who assert that 'what is' is one and many, like Empedocles and Anaxagoras; for they too produce other things from their mixture by segregation. These differ, however, from each other in that the former imagines a cycle of such changes, the latter a single series. [25] Anaxagoras again made both his 'homceomerous' substances and his contraries infinite in multitude, whereas Empedocles posits only the so-called elements.
The
theory of Anaxagoras that the princiwas probably due
ples are infinite in multitude
common
opinion of the physicists that nothing comes into being from not-being. For this is the reason why they use to his acceptance of the
187 b
[30] the phrase 'all things were together' and the coming into being of such and such a kind of thing
reduced to change of quality, while of combination and separation. Moreover, the fact that the contraries proceed from each other led them to the conclusion. is
some spoke
The
one, they reasoned,
must have already
ex-
the other; for since everything that
isted in
comes into being must arise either from what is or from what is not, and it is impossible for it to arise from what is not (on this point all the physicists agree), they thought that the [35] truth of the alternative necessarily
fol-
lowed, namely that things come into being out of existent things, i.e. out of things already present, but imperceptible to our senses because 187 b of the smallness of their bulk. So they assert that everything has been mixed in everything, because they saw everything arising out of everything. But things, as they say, appear different from one another and receive different names according to the nature of the particles which are numerically predominant among the innumerable constituents of the mixture. For nothing, they say, is purely and entirely [5] white or black or sweet, bone or flesh, but the nature of a thing is held to be that of which it contains the most.
Now
(1) the infinite
what unknowable
able, so that
size
is
finite in variety of
is
qua
infinite
infinite in
is
unknow-
multitude or
and what is inunknowable in qual-
in quantity,
kind
is
But the principles in question are inboth in multitude and in kind. Therefore it is impossible to know things which are composed of them; for it is when we know the nature and quantity of its components that we suppose we know a complex. Further (2) if the parts of a whole may be of [10]
ity.
finite
any
size in the direction either of greatness or
[75] of smallness (by 'parts' I mean components into which a whole can be divided and which are actually present in it), it is necessary that the
whole thing
itself
Clearly, therefore, since
may
it is
be of any
size.
impossible for an
animal or plant to be indefinitely big or small, its parts be such, or the whole will be the same. But flesh, bone, and the like are
neither can
[20] the parts of animals, and the fruits are the parts of plants. Hence it is obvious that neither flesh, bone, nor any such thing can be of indefinite size in the direction either of the
greater or of the
less.
to the theory all such things are already present in one another and do not come into being but are constituents
Again (3) according
BOOK
188 b
which are separated its designation from
out,
and a thing
I,
CHAPTERS
receives
its chief constituent. Furanything may come out of anything water by segregation from flesh and flesh from [25] water. Hence, since every finite body is exhausted by the repeated abstraction of a finite body, it seems obviously to follow that everything cannot subsist in everything else. For let flesh be extracted from water and again more flesh be produced from the remainder by repeating the process of separation: then, even though the quantity separated out will continually decrease, still it will not fall below a cer[30] tain magnitude. If, therefore, the process comes to an end, everything will not be in ev-
—
ther,
erything else (for there will be no flesh in the remaining water); if on the other hand it does not, and further extraction is always possible, there will be an infinite multitude of finite equal particles in a finite quantity which is [55] impossible. Another proof may be added: Since every body must diminish in size when something is taken from it, and flesh is quantitatively definite in respect both of greatness and smallness, it is clear that from the mini-
—
mum
quantity of flesh no body can be sepa188* rated out; for the flesh left would be less than the minimum of flesh. Lastly (4) in each of his infinite bodies there would be already present infinite flesh and blood and brain having a distinct existence, however, from one another, and no less real than the infinite bodies, and each infinite:
—
which [5]
is
The
contrary to reason. statement that complete separation
never will take place is correct enough, though Anaxagoras is not fully aware of what it means. For affections are indeed inseparable. If then colours and states had entered into the mixture, and if separation took place, there would be a 'white' or a 'healthy' which was nothing but white or healthy, i.e. was not the predicate of a subject. So his 'Mind' is an absurd person
aiming at the impossible, if he is supposed to [10] wish to separate them, and it is impossible to do so, both in respect of quantity and of quality of quantity, because there is no minimum magnitude, and of quality, because af-
—
fections are inseparable.
Nor
is
Anaxagoras right about the coming
homogeneous bodies. It is true there is which clay is divided into pieces of clay, but there is another in which it is not. [75] Water and air are, and are generated 'from' each other, but not in the way in which bricks come 'from' a house and again a house
3-5
263
and
'from' bricks;
is
it
better
number
smaller and finite
to
assume a
of principles,
as
Empedocles does.
making
All thinkers then agree in traries principles,
All as one
both those
who
the con-
describe the
and unmoved (for even Parmeni-
[20] des treats hot and cold as principles under the names of fire and earth) and those too
who
use the rare and the dense.
true of Democritus also, with his void, both of
which
he
exist,
The same
is
plenum and
says, the
one as
Again he speaks of differences in position, shape, and order, and these are genera of which the species are contraries, namely, of position, above and below, before and behind; of shape, angular and [25] angle-less, straight and round. being, the other as not-being.
It is plain then that they all in one way or another identify the contraries with the principles. And with good reason. For first principles must not be derived from one another nor from anything else, while everything has to be derived from them. But these conditions are fulfilled by the primary contraries, which are not derived from anything else because they are primary, nor from each other because they
are contraries.
[jo] But at as a
we must
reasoned
see
how
this
can be arrived
result, as well as in the
way
just indicated.
Our
first
presupposition must be that in nais acted on by, any oth-
ture nothing acts on, or
er thing at random, nor may anything come from anything else, unless we mean that it does so in virtue of a concomitant attribute. For [35] how could 'white' come from 'musical', unless 'musical' happened to be an attribute of the not-white or of the black? No, 'white' comes from 'not-white' and not from any 'not-white', but from black or some intermedi188 b ate colour. Similarly, 'musical' comes to be from 'not-musical', but not from any thing other than musical, but from 'unmusical' or any intermediate state there may be. Nor again do things pass into the first chance
—
thing; 'white' does not pass into 'musical' (except,
it
may be,
concomitant attrinot into any not white, but into black
in virtue of a
bute), but into 'not-white'
—and
to be of
chance thing which
a sense in
or an intermediate colour; 'musical' passes into
—
is
and not into any chance [5] 'not-musical' thing other than musical, but into 'unmusical' or any intermediate state there may be. The same holds of other things also: even
PHYSICS
264
things which are not simple but complex fol[10] low the same principle, but the opposite state has tice
not received a name, so we fail to noWhat is in tune must come from
the fact.
not in tune, and vice versa; the tuned and not into any untunedness, but into the corresponding oppo[75] site. It does not matter whether we take
what
is
passes into untunedness
—
attunement, order, or composition for our illustration; the principle is obviously the same in all, and in fact applies equally to the production of a house, a statue, or any other complex. A house comes from certain things in a certain state of separation instead of conjunction, a statue (or any other thing that has been [20] shaped) from shapelessness each of these objects being partly order and partly
—
composition. If then this
is true, everything that comes to be or passes away from, or passes into, its contrary or an intermediate state. But the intermecoldiates are derived from the contraries ours, for instance, from black and white. Ev[25] ery thing, therefore, that comes to be by a natural process is either a contrary or a prod-
—
uct of contraries.
Up
to this point
we have
practically
had
most of the other writers on the subject with I have said already for all of them identify their elements, and what they call their principles, with the contraries, giving no rea1
us, as
:
son indeed for the theory, but contrained as it were by the truth itself. They differ, however, [30] from one another in that some assume contraries which are more primary, others con-
which are less so: some those more knowable in the order of explanation, others those more familiar to sense. For some make hot and cold, or again moist and dry, the conditions of becoming; while others make odd [55] and even, or again Love and Strife; and these differ from each other in the way mentraries
tioned.
Hence
their principles are in
one sense the
same, in another different; different certainly, as indeed most people think, but the same in189 a asmuch as they are analogous; for all are taken from the same table of columns, 2 some of the pairs being wider, others narrower in extent. In this way then their theories are both
189 a
the order of explanation, the particular in the order of sense: for explanation has to do with the universal, sense with the particular.) The and the small', for example, belong to the
great
former
class,
'the
dense and the
rare' to the
latter.
[10]
It is
clear then that
our principles must be
contraries.
The are
next question is whether the principles two or three or more in number.
One
they cannot be, for there cannot be one Nor can they be innumerable, be-
contrary.
if so, Being will not be knowable: and any one genus there is only one contrariety, and substance is one genus: also a finite num[75] ber is sufficient, and a finite number, such as the principles of Empedocles, is better than an infinite multitude; for Empedocles pro-
cause,
in
fesses
to obtain
Anaxagoras
from
his principles all
that
from his innumerable principles. Lastly, some contraries are more primary than others, and some arise from others for example sweet and bitter, white and black whereas the principles must always remain principles. [20] This will suffice to show that the prin-
—
obtains
—
one nor innumerable. Granted, then, that they are a limited number, it is plausible to suppose them more than two. For it is difficult to see how either density should be of such a nature as to act in any way ciples are neither
rarity or rarity on density. The same is true any other pair of contraries; for Love does [25] not gather Strife together and make things out of it, nor does Strife make anything out of Love, but both act on a third thing different from both. Some indeed assume more than one such thing from which they construct the world of nature. Other objections to the view that it is not necessary to assume a third principle as a substratum may be added. (1) We do not find
on of
that the contraries constitute the substance of
[30] any thing. But what is a first principle ought not to be the predicate of any subject. If
explanation, others
to
it were, there would be a principle of the supposed principle: for the subject is a principle, and prior presumably to what is predicated of it. Again (2) we hold that a substance is not contrary to another substance. How then can substance be derived from what are not substances? Or how can non-substances be prior
[5] sense.
in
to substance?
the
same and
different,
worse; some, as traries
1
aj
what
9 3°»
I
have
some
better,
some
said, take as their con-
more knowable in the order what is more familiar (The universal is more knowable is
2
Metaphysics,
1.
986* 23.
of
If
then
we
accept both the former argument
BOOK
190[ £5] and
CHAPTERS
somewhat
spoken of by
investigate the characteristics of special cases.
the contraries, such as
those
who
is
We
describe the All as one nature
water or fire or what is intermediate between them. What is intermediate seems preferable; for fire, earth, air, and water are already in[5] volved with pairs of contraries. There is, therefore, much to be said for those who make the underlying substance different from these four; of the rest, the next best choice is air, as presenting sensible differences in a less degree than the others; and after air, water. All, however, agree in this, that they differentiate their
of the contraries, such as density
[10] and rarity and more and less, which may of course be generalized, as has already been said,
1
into excess
and
trine too (that the
265
as the substratum of
sume 189 b
One by means
5-7
following the natural order of inquiry if we speak first of common characteristics, and then
we must, to preserve both, as-
this one,
a third
I,
defect.
One and
Indeed excess
this doc-
and defect
would appear to be of old standing, though in different forms; for the early thinkers made the two the active
are the principles of things)
say that one thing comes to be from another thing, and one sort of thing from another sort of thing, both in the case of simple and of
complex things. I mean the following. We can say (1) the 'man becomes musical', (2) what [55] is 'not-musical becomes musical', or (3) 190* the 'not-musical man becomes a musical man Now what becomes in (1) and (2) man and 'not musical'- I call simple, and what each becomes 'musical' simple also. But when (3) we say the 'not-musical man becomes a musical man', both what becomes and what it becomes are complex. [5] As regards one of these simple 'things that become' we say not only 'this becomes so-andso', but also 'from being this, comes to be soand-so', as 'from being not-musical comes to be musical'; as regards the other we do not say this in all cases, as we do not say ( 1 ) 'from be-
—
man he came to be man became musical'.
—
and the one the passive principle, whereas [75] some of the more recent maintain the
ing a
reverse.
When a 'simple' thing something, in one case ( 1 )
To
suppose then that the elements are three in number would seem, from these and similar considerations, a plausible
before.
are
2
On
view, as
I
said
the other hand, the view that they
more than
three in
number would seem
to
be untenable. For the one substratum is sufficient to be [20] acted on; but if we have four contraries, there will be two contrarieties, and we shall have to suppose an intermediate nature for each pair separately. If, on the other hand, the contrarieties, being two, can generate from each other, the second contrariety will be super-
Moreover, it is impossible that there should be more than one primary contrariety. For substance is a single genus of being, so that the principles can differ only as prior and [25] posterior, not in genus; in a single genus there is always a single contrariety, all the other contrarieties in it being held to be refluous.
musical or exist, either
in the
187* l6.
2a 2I.
way we
are describing that, as
we
say,
must always be an underlying something, [75] namely that which becomes, and that this, though always one numerically, in form at least is not one. (By that I mean that it can be described in different ways.) For 'to be man' is not the same as 'to be unmusical'. One part survives, the other does not: what is not an there
opposite survives
(for
'man' survives), but
'not-musical' or 'unmusical' does not survive,
compound of the two, name'unmusical man'. We speak of 'becoming that from this' in-
[20] nor does the
of
1
unmusical does not continue to simply or combined with the sub-
is
These distinctions drawn, one can gather Irom surveying the various cases of becoming
then that the number of elements more than two or three; but whether two or three is, as I said, a question of
[jo] We will now give our own account, approaching the question first with reference to becoming in its widest sense: for we shall be
become
ject.
It is clear
considerable difficulty.
said to
survives through
it does not. For and is such even when he becomes musical, whereas what is not
ly
neither one nor
is it
the process, in the other (2) [10] the man remains a man
ducible to one. is
musical' but only 'the
becoming that' more in the case what does not survive the change 'becoming musical from unmusical', not 'from man' stead of 'this
—but
there are exceptions, as
—
we sometimes
[25] use the latter form of expression even of what survives; we speak of 'a statue coming to
be from bronze', not of the 'bronze becoming The change, however, from an opposite which does not survive is described indif-
a statue'.
PHYSICS
266 ferently in both ways, 'becoming that this'
or 'this
[jo]
'the
becoming
that'.
We
from
say both that
unmusical becomes musical', and
'from unmusical he becomes musical'. And so both forms are used of the complex, 'becoming a musical man from an unmusical that
man', and 'an unmusical sical man'.
man becoming
a
mu-
But there are different senses of 'coming to In some cases we do not use the expression 'come to be', but 'come to be so-and-so'. Only substances are said to 'come to be' in the be'.
than substance it is plain that there must be some subject, namely, that which becomes. For we know that when a thing comes to be of such a quantity or quality sucn a relation, time, or place, a [35] or subject is always presupposed, since substance alone is not predicated of another subject, but everything else of substance. 190 b But that substances too, and anything else that can be said 'to be' without qualification, come to be from some substratum, will appear on examination. For we find in every case something that underlies from which proin all cases other
m
ceeds that which comes to be; for instance, ani-
mals and plants from seed. [5] Generally things which come to be, come to be in different ways: (1) by change of shape, as a statue; (2) by addition, as things which grow; (3) by taking away, as the Hermes from the stone; (4) by putting together, as a house; (5) by alteration, as things
which
'turn' in respect of their material sub-
stance.
plain that these are all cases of coming from a substratum. [10] Thus, clearly, from what has been said, whatever comes to be is always complex. There something which is, on the one hand, (a) comes into existence, and again (b) something which becomes that the latter (b) in two senses, either the subject or the opposite. By It is
—
the 'opposite'
I
mean
the 'unmusical', by the
and similarly I call the absence [75] of shape or form or order the 'opposite', and the bronze or stone or gold the 'subject'. Plainly then, if there are conditions and principles which constitute natural objects and from which they primarily are or have come to be have come to be, I mean, what each is said to be in its essential nature, not what each 'subject' 'man',
—
—
concomitant attribute plainly ] ly, I say, everything comes to be from both subject and form. For 'musical man' is com-
is
—
—
in respect of a
And
incidental in the process.)
—
the positive
one the order, the acquired music, or any similar predicate. is
There
is
a sense, therefore, in
art of
which we must
declare the principles to be two, and a sense in [30] which they are three; a sense in which the say for example contraries are the principles
—
and the unmusical, the hot and the and a sense cold, the tuned and the untuned in which they are not, since it is impossible for the contraries to be acted on by each other. But this difficulty also is solved by the fact that the substratum is different from the contraries, the musical
—
not a contrary. The prinway, not more in number than the contraries, but as it were two, nor yet precisely two, since there is a difference 191 a of essential nature, but three. For 'to be [55] for
is
it
itself
ciples therefore are, in a
man'
from
different
is
be unformed' from
'to
We
have
now
'to 'to
generation, and
and
it is
be unmusical', and be bronze'.
stated the
how
number
of the prin-
which are subject
ciples of natural objects
the
number
is
to
reached:
must be a substratum and that the contraries must
clear that there
for the contraries,
to be
1
posed (in a way) of 'man' and 'musical': you can analyse it into the definitions of its elements. It is clear then that what comes to be will come to be from these elements. Now the subject is one numerically, though it is two in form. (For it is the man, the gold the 'matter' generally that is counted, for [25] it is more of the nature of a 'this', and what comes to be does not come from it in virtue of a concomitant attribute; the privation, on the other hand, and the contrary are
form
unqualified sense.
Now
191
[5] be two. (Yet in another way of putting it is not necessary, as one of the contraries
this
will serve to effect the
change by
its
successive
absence and presence.) The underlying nature entific
bronze
is an object of sciknowledge, by an analogy. For as the
wood
to the statue, the
is
to the bed,
[10] or the matter and the formless before receiving form to any thing which has form, so is the underlying nature to substance, i.e. the
'this'
or existent.
is one principle (though not one or existent in the same sense as the 'this'), and the definition was one as we agreed; then fur-
This then
ther there
is its
contrary, the privation. In
sense these are two, and in
what
what
sense more,
[75] has been stated above. Briefly, we ex1 plained first that only the contraries were principles, 1
Chapter
and
2
later that a 2
5.
Chapter
6.
substratum was
in-
BOOK
191 b dispensable,
and
that the principles
I,
CHAPTERS
were three;
1
[10]
It
7-9
267
was through
make
failure to
this dis-
our last statement has elucidated the difference between the contraries, the mutual rela-
tinction that those thinkers gave the matter up,
and the nature of the substratum. Whether the form or the sub-
farther astray as to suppose that nothing else
tion of the principles,
the essential nature of a physical obnot yet clear. But that the prinis ject [20] ciples are three, and in what sense, and the
stratum
way
in
is
which each
is
a principle,
is
and through
So much then for the question of the number and the nature of the principles.
so
much
comes to be or exists apart from Being itself, thus doing away with all becoming. We ourselves are in agreement with them in holding that nothing can be said without qualification to
clear.
went
this error that they
theless
come from what
we maintain
be from what
is
not'
—that
But never-
not.
is
may 'come
that a thing
to
in a qualified
is,
[75] sense. For a thing comes to be from the privation, which in its own nature is not-being.
proceed to show that the
diffi-
—
culty of the early thinkers, as well as our
own,
sult.
We
will
now
solved in this
is
way
they say that none of the things that are either comes to be or passes out of existence, because what comes to be must do so either from what is or from what is not, both of which are im[30] possible. For what is cannot come to be (because it is already), and from what is not
nothing could have come to be (because something must be present as a substratum). So too they exaggerated the consequence of this, and went so far as to deny even the existence of a plurality of things, maintaining that only Being itself is. Such then was their opinion, and such the reason for its adoption. explanation on the other hand is that comes to be from what is or from what is not', 'what is not or what is [_?5] does something or has something done to it or becomes some particular thing', are to be taken (in the first way of putting our explana191 b tion) in the same sense as 'a doctor does
in the
something or has something done to him', 'is or becomes something from being a doctor'. These expressions may be taken in two senses, and so too, clearly, may 'from being', and 'beis
acted on'.
A
doctor builds a
qua housebuilder, and qua doctor, but qua turns gray, not [5] darkhaired. On the other hand he doctors or fails to doctor qua doctor. But we are using qua
doctor, but
words most appropriately when we say that
Chapter
7.
and
it is
thought to be
come
way described from what is not. same way we maintain that nothing
comes not
to be
come
from being, and that being does
to be except in a qualified sense. In
way, however, it does, just as animal might come to be from animal, and an animal [20] of a certain kind from an animal of a certain kind. Thus, suppose a dog to come to be from a horse. The dog would then, it is true, come to be from animal (as well as from an animal of a certain kind) but not as animal, for that is already there. But if anything is to become an animal, not in a qualified sense, it will not be from animal: and if being, not nor from not-being either, [25] from being that
—
for
it
being'
has been explained
we mean from
Note further
that
2
that by 'from notnot-being qua not-being.
we do
not subvert the
principle that everything either
is
or
is
not.
This then is one way of solving the difficulty. Another consists in pointing out that the same things can be explained in terms of potentiality and actuality. But this has been done with greater precision elsewhere. 3
we
which condeny the existence of some of the things we mentioned are now solved. For it was this reason which also caused some of the earlier thinkers to turn so far aside from the road which leads to coming to be and passing away and change generally. If they had [jo] So, as
said, the difficulties
strain people to
come in sight of this nature, would have been dispelled.
all
their ignorance
a
doctor does something or undergoes something, or becomes something from being a doctor, if he does, undergoes, or becomes qua doctor. Clearly then also 'to come to be so-andso from not-being' means 'qua not-being'. 1
this causes surprise,
In the
Our
the phrases 'something
ing acts or
Yet
impossible that something should
alone.
The first of those who studied science were [25] misled in their search for truth and the nature of things by their inexperience, which as it were thrust them into another path. So
house, not
this not surviving as a constituent of the re-
[35] Others, indeed, have apprehended the
nature in question, but not adequately. In the first place they allow that a thing
may
come
not-
2 1.
9.
to be 8
without qualification from Metaphysics, ix, and v
(
i
o 1 7* 35~b
9).
PHYSICS
268
being, accepting on this point the statement of 192* Parmenides. Secondly, they think that if is one numerically, it must have also only a single potentiality which is
the substratum
—
a very different thing.
Now we
and privation, namely the matter, virtue of an attribute
distinguish matter
and hold that one of
these,
not-being only in which it has, while the privation in is
its
own
[5] nature is not-being; and that the matter is nearly, in a sense is, substance, while the priva-
They, on the other hand, and Small alike with notbeing, and that whether they are taken together as one or separately. Their triad is therefore of quite a different kind from ours. For they got so far as to see that there must [jo] be some underlying nature, but they make it one for even if one philosopher 1 makes a dyad of it, which he calls Great and Small, the effect is the same, for he overlooked the other nature. For the one which persists is a joint cause, with the form, of what comes to be a mother, as it were. But the negative part [75] of the contrariety may often seem, if you concentrate your attention on it as an evil
tion in
no sense
is.
identify their Great
—
—
agent, not to exist at
it,
the other such as of
ally destructive.
its
own
nature to de-
and yearn for it. But the consequence of view is that the contrary desires its own [20] extinction. Yet the form cannot desire
sire
for
it
is
contrary desire
not defective; it,
is
nor can the
for contraries are
mutu-
The
truth
is
what
that
de-
matter, as the female desires
—
and the ugly the beautiful only the ugly or the female not per se but per accidens. the male
The matter comes
[25]
one
in
to be
and
sense, while in another
which contains the
that
own
it
ceases to be
As
does not.
privation,
it
ceases to
what ceases to be contained within it. But as potentiality it does not cease to be in its own nature, but is necessarily outside the sphere of becoming and ceasing to be. For if it came to be, something must have existed as a primary substratum from which it should come and [50] which should persist in it; but this is its own special nature, so that it will be before coming to be. (For my definition of matter is just this the primary substratum of each thing, from which it comes to be without qualbe in
its
the privation
nature, for
—
is
—
ification,
And
if it
so
last,
it
and which ceases to be will
it
persists in
the result.)
will pass into that at the
have ceased
to be before ceasing
to be.
The
accurate determination of the
ciple in respect of form, it is
or
whether
it
what they
prin-
first
one or
is
are,
is
the
[35] province of the primary type of science; so these questions may stand over till then. 2
192 b But of the
we
shall
low.
natural, i.e. perishable, forms speak in the expositions which fol-
3
The
their
itself,
the form
sires
many and what
all.
For admitting with them that there is something divine, good, and desirable, we hold that there are two other principles, the one contrary to
192 b
above, then,
may
be taken as sufficient
to establish that there are principles
they are and
make
BOOK
how many
a fresh start
there are.
and what
Now
let
us
and proceed.
II
i.e.
—have
in so far as they are products of art
All the things mentioned present a feature
no innate impulse to change. But in so far as they happen to be composed of stone or of [20] earth or of a mixture of the two, they do have such an impulse, and just to that extent which seems to indicate that nature is a source or cause of being moved and of being at rest in that to which it belongs primarily, in virtue of itself and not in virtue of a concomitant
which they
attribute.
Of things that from other
exist,
some exist by nature, some
causes.
'By nature' the animals and their parts
exist,
[10] and the plants and the simple bodies (earth, fire, air, water) for we say that these
—
and the
like exist 'by nature'.
from things which are not Each of them has within itself a principle of motion and of stationari[75] ness (in respect of place, or of growth and
in
differ
constituted by nature.
by way of alteration). On the other hand, a bed and a coat and anything else of that sort, qua receiving these designations
I
say 'not in virtue of a concomitant attri-
bute', because (for instance) a
man who
doctor might cure himself. Nevertheless
is
a
it is
decrease, or
1
Plato.
2
Metaphysics, xii. 7-9. the rest of the Physics, the On the Heavens, On Generation and Corruption, etc. (especially On Generation 8 I.e.
and Corruption,
11).
193 b
BOOK
not in so far as he
is
CHAPTER 9— BOOK
I,
a patient that he pos-
[25] sesses the art of medicine:
it
merely has
happened that the same man is doctor and paand that is why these attributes are not tient always found together. So it is with all other artificial products. None of them has in itself the source of its own production. But while in some cases (for instance houses and the other products of manual labour) that principle is in something else external to the thing, in others those which may cause a change in [30]
—
—
themselves in virtue of a concomitant attribute it lies in the things themselves (but not in virtue of what they are). 'Nature' then is what has been stated.
—
which have a principle them is a substance; for
Things 'have
a nature'
II,
CHAPTER
269
1
[20] say bronze (or gold) to water, bones (or wood) to earth and so on, that (they say)
would be their nature and essence. Consequently some assert earth, others fire or air or water or some or all of these, to be the nature For whatever any one have this character whether one thing or more than one thing [25] this or these he declared to be the whole
of the things that are.
of
them supposed
of substance,
to
all else
being
its
affections, states,
or dispositions. Every such thing they held to
be eternal (for it could not pass into anything else), but other things to come into being and cease to be times without number.
This then that
it is
is
one account of
'nature',
namely
the immediate material substratum of
Each of and nature always implies a which it inheres.
things which have in themselves a principle of
[^5] The term 'according to nature' is applied to all these things and also to the attributes which belong to them in virtue of what they
defini-
of this kind. it
a subject,
is
subject in
be carwhich is not a 'nature' nor 'has ried upwards a nature' but is 'by nature' or 'according to are, for instance the
—
property of
fire to
nature'.
193a
What
nature
is,
has been stated.
ture',
would be absurd
and the meaning and 'according to naThat nature exists, it
then,
of the terms 'by nature'
to try to prove; for
many
it
is
ob-
motion or change. [jo] Another account is that 'nature' shape or form which is specified in the
is
the
tion of the thing.
For the word 'nature' is applied to what is according to nature and the natural in the same way as 'art' is applied to what is artistic or a work of art. should not say in the latter case that there is anything artistic about a thing, if it is a bed only potentially, not yet having the form of a bed; nor should we call
We
[55] ural
a
it
work
of art.
The same
compounds. What
bone has not yet
is
own
is
true of nat-
potentially flesh or
not is the mark of a man tinguish what is self-evident from what is not. (This state of mind is clearly possible. A man blind from birth might reason about colours. Presumably therefore such persons must be
and does not form specks'5 ified in the definition, which we name in defining what flesh or bone is. Thus in the second sense of 'nature' it would be the shape or form (not separable except in statement) of [5] things which have in themselves a source
talking about words without any thought to
of motion.
correspond.)
man,
vious that there are [5]
and
Some
to
prove what
things of this kind,
obvious by what is who is unable to dis-
is
identify the nature or substance of a
[10] natural object with that immediate constituent of it which taken by itself is without
arrangement,
e.g. the
wood
is
the 'nature' of
the bed, and the bronze the 'nature' of the statue.
As an
indication of this Antiphon points out you planted a bed and the rotting wood acquired the power of sending up a shoot, it would not be a bed that would come up, but wood which shows that the arrangement in [75] accordance with the rules of the art is merely an incidental attribute, whereas the real that
if
—
nature is the other, which, further, persists continuously through the process of making.
But has
if
itself
the material of each of these objects the
same
relation to
something
else,
its
exist 'by nature', until
is
it
'nature',
receives the
(The combination of the two, e.g. not 'nature' but 'by nature' or 'nat-
ural'.)
The form indeed matter; for a thing
what
it
is
when
it
is
'nature' rather than the
more properly
said to be has attained to fulfilment
is
than when it exists potentially. Again man is born from man, but not bed from bed. That is why people say that the figure is not the nature if the bed [10] of a bed, but the wood is sprouted not a bed but wood would come up. But even if the figure is art, then on the same principle the shape of man is his nature. For man is born from man. We also speak of a thing's nature as being exhibited in the process of growth by which its nature is attained. The 'nature' in this sense is not like 'doctoring', which leads not to the [75] art of doctoring but to health. Doctoring
—
PHYSICS
270
must
from the
194 b
not lead to it. But it is not in this way that nature (in the one sense) is related to nature (in the other). What grows
matical lines, but ematical.
qua growing grows from something
the matter,
start
art,
into
something. Into what then does it grow? Not into that from which it arose but into that to which it tends. The shape then is nature. 'Shape' and 'nature', it should be added, are [20] used in two senses. For the privation too is in a way form. But whether in unqualified
coming to be there is privation, i.e. a contrary what comes to be, we must consider later. 1
to
qua
physical, not
qua math-
Since 'nature' has two senses, the form and
we must investigate its objects as the essence of snubness. That is, such things are neither independent of matter nor
we would
can be defined in terms of matter only. Here [75] too indeed one might raise a difficulty. Since there are two natures, with which is the Or should he investigate the combination of the two? But if the combination of the two, then also each severally.
physicist concerned?
Does
belong then to the same or to different know each severally? If we look at the ancients, physics would [20] seem to be concerned with the matter. (It was only very slightly that Empedocles and Democritus touched on the forms and the it
sciences to
We
have distinguished, then, the different in which the term 'nature' is used. The next point to consider is how the mathematician differs from the physicist. Obviously physical bodies contain surfaces and volumes,
ways
and
and these are the
essence.)
the writers on physics obviously do discuss [jo] their shape also and whether the earth
But if on the other hand art imitates nature, and it is the part of the same discipline to know the form and the matter up to a point (e.g. the doctor has a knowledge of health and also of bile and phlegm, in which health is realized, and the builder both of the form of the house [25] and of the matter, namely that it is bricks and beams, and so forth): if this is so, it would be the part of physics also to know na-
and
ture in both
lines
points,
subject-
matter of mathematics. [25] Further, is astronomy different from physics or a department of it ? It seems absurd that the physicist should be supposed to
the nature of sun or moon, but not to
any
know know
of their essential attributes, particularly as
the world are spherical or not.
Now
the mathematician, though
he too treats of these things, nevertheless does not treat of them as the limits of a physical body; nor does he consider the attributes indicated as the attributes of such bodies. That is why he separates them; for in thought they are separable from motion, and it makes no difference, nor does any falsity result, if they are
senses.
its
Again, 'that for the sake of which', or the end, belongs to the same department of knowledge as the means. But the nature is the end or 'that for the sake of which'. For if a thing undergoes a continuous change and there is a stage
which
this stage
is last,
is
the end or
[50] 'that for the sake of which'. (That is why the poet was carried away into making an
when he
[35] separated. The holders of the theory of the same, though they are not aware
absurd statement
Forms do
for the sake of
of
every stage that is last claims to be an end, but only that which is best.) For the arts make their material (some simply 'make' it, others make it serviceable), and we use everything as if it was there for our [55] sake. (We also are in a sense an end.
it;
for they separate the objects of physics,
which are less separable than those of mathe194 a matics. This becomes plain if one tries to state in each of the two cases the definitions of the things and of their attributes. 'Odd' and 'even', 'straight' and 'curved', and likewise 'number', 'line', and 'figure', do not involve [5] motion; not so 'flesh' and 'bone' and 'man'
—
these are defined like 'snub nose', not like
'curved'.
Similar evidence
is
supplied by the
more
physical of the branches of mathematics, such as optics, harmonics, in a
way
and astronomy. These are While
the converse of geometry.
geometry investigates physical lines but not [10] qua physical, optics investigates mathe1 On Generation and Corruption, 1. 3.
That
born'.
for the sake of which' has
the distinction
osophy. 3 )
is
made
end For not
said 'he has the
which he was
in our
2
two
senses:
work On
Phil-
which govern 194 b the matter and have knowledge are two, namely the art which uses the product and the art which directs the production of it. That is
why but
arts, therefore,
the using art also
it
differs in that
as the art 8
The
which
Kock, Com. An.
* I.e. in
is
it
is
in a sense directive;
knows
the form, where-
directive as being concerned
Fr. in, p. 493. De Philosophia.
the dialogue
195
BOOK
J
II,
CHAPTERS
1-3
271
which are brought about something else as means
with production knows the matter. For the
the intermediate steps
helmsman knows and prescribes what sort helm should have, the other from what wood it should be made and by means of what operations. In the products of art, however, we make the material with a view to
through the action of towards the end, e.g. reduction of flesh, purging, drugs, or surgical instruments are means 195 a towards health. All these things are 'for
[5]
of form a
the function, whereas in the products of nature
the sake of the end, though they differ from one another in that some are activities, others
the matter
instruments.
is
there
all
along.
Again, matter is a relative term: to each form there corresponds a special matter. How far then must the physicist know the form or [10] essence? Up to a point, perhaps, as the doctor must know sinew or the smith bronze
understands the purpose of each): and the physicist is concerned only with things whose forms are separable indeed, but (i.e.
until
he
do not
exist apart
ten by
man and
of existence
from matter.
Man
by the sun as well.
is
begot-
The mode
and essence of the separable
it
is
[75] the business of the primary type of phi-
losophy to define.
Now that we have established these distinctions, we must
proceed to consider causes, their char-
and number. Knowledge is the object of our inquiry, and men do not think they know acter
a thing
till
they have grasped the 'why' of
it
[20] (which is to grasp its primary cause). So clearly we too must do this as regards both
coming
to be and passing away and every kind of physical change, in order that, know-
ing their principles, we may try to refer to these principles each of our problems. In one sense, then, (1) that out of which a thing comes to be and which persists, is called
bronze of the statue, the silver [25] of the bowl, and the genera of which the bronze and the silver are species. In another sense (2) the form or the arche'cause', e.g. the
type,
i.e.
the statement of the essence,
and
its
genera, are called 'causes' (e.g. of the octave
This then perhaps exhausts the number of in which the term 'cause' is used.
ways
As
the
word has
several senses,
that there are several causes of the
it
follows
same thing
(not merely in virtue of a concomitant attri[5] bute), e.g. both the art of the sculptor and the bronze are causes of the statue. These are causes of the statue qua statue, not in virtue of anything else that it may be only not in the same way, the one being the material cause, the other the cause whence the motion comes. Some things cause each other recipro[10] cally, e.g. hard work causes fitness and vice versa, but again not in the same way, but the one as end, the other as the origin of change. Further the same thing is the cause of contrary results. For that which by its pres-
—
ence brings about one result is sometimes blamed for bringing about the contrary by its absence. Thus we ascribe the wreck of a ship to the absence of the pilot whose presence was the cause of its safety. [75] All the causes now mentioned fall into four familiar divisions. The letters are the causes of syllables, the material of artificial products, fire, &c, of bodies, the parts of the whole, and the premisses of the conclusion, in the sense of 'that
from which'. Of
these pairs
[20] the one set are causes in the sense of substratum, e.g. the parts, the other set in the
—
the whole and the combinaand the form. But the seed and the doctor and the adviser, and generally the maker, are all sources whence the change or stationariness sense of essence tion
the relation of 2 1, and generally number), and the parts in the definition. Again (3) the primary source of the change [50] or coming to rest; e.g. the man who gave
originates, while the others are causes in the
advice
it.
:
child,
is
a cause, the father
is
cause of the
and generally what makes of what causes change of what
made and what
is is
changed.
Again (4) in the sense of end or 'that for the sake of which' a thing is done, e.g. health the cause of walking about. ('Why is he walking about?' we say. 'To be healthy', and, having said that, we think we have assigned [35] the cause.) The same is true also of all is
sense of the end or the good of the rest; for 'that for the sake of which' means what is best
[25] and the end of the things that lead up to (Whether we say the 'good itself or the 'ap-
parent good' makes no difference.) Such then is the number and nature of the kinds of cause. Now the modes of causation are many, though when brought under heads they too can be reduced in number. For 'cause' is used in many senses and even within the same kind [50] one may be prior to another (e.g. the doctor and the expert are causes of health, the
PHYSICS
272 relation 2
and number of the octave), and inclusive to what is particular.
1
:
always what
is
196
[jo]
number of
causes and the
modes
a
of causa-
tion.
Another mode of causation is the incidental and its genera, e.g. in one way 'Polyclitus', in another 'sculptor' is the cause of a statue, be[^5] cause 'being Polyclitus' and 'sculptor' are incidentally conjoined. Also the classes in which the incidental attribute is included; thus 'a man' could be said to be the cause of a
195 b statue
An
or,
generally,
'a
living creature'.
may
be more or less remote, e.g. suppose that 'a pale man' or 'a musical man' were said to be the cause of the incidental attribute too
statue.
All causes, both proper [5] be
spoken of either
and
incidental,
may
as potential or as ac-
tual; e.g. the cause of a
house being built
is
either 'house-builder' or 'house-builder building'.
Similar
distinctions
can be
made
in
the
things of which the causes are causes, e.g. of 'this statue' or of 'statue' or of 'image' generally, of 'this terial'
bronze' or of 'bronze' or of 'ma-
generally. So too with the incidental at-
[10] tributes. Again we may use a complex expression for either and say, e.g. neither 'Polyclitus'
nor 'sculptor' but 'Polyclitus, sculp-
tor'.
All these various uses, however,
come
to six
number, under each of which again the usage is twofold. Cause means either what is
But chance
also
among
causes:
and
come
and spontaneity are reckoned
many
to be as a result of
We
spontaneity.
[5] ilarly in other cases of chance possible, they maintain, to find
which
is
the cause; but real,
particular or a genus, or an incidental attri-
are by chance
either as actual or as potential. is
at
The
difference
much, that causes which are actually work and particular exist and cease to exist this
simultaneously with their effect, e.g. this healing person with this being-healed person and that housebuilding man with that being-built house; but this is not always true of potential [20] causes the house and the housebuilder do not pass away simultaneously. In investigating the cause of each thing it is always necessary to seek what is most precise (as also in other things): thus man builds because he is a builder, and a builder builds in virtue of his art of building. This last cause then is prior: and so generally. [25] Further, generic effects should be assigned to generic causes, particular effects to
—
particular causes, e.g. statue to sculptor, this statue to this sculptor;
and powers are
relative
to possible effects, actually operating causes to
things which are actually being effected.
This must
suffice
for our account of the
not chance, for
if
it
that they too did not believe that anything
chance. But there
[75] bute or a genus of that, and these either complex or each by itself; and all six
always something
it is
would seem strange indeed, and the question might be raised, why on earth none of the wise men of old in speaking of the causes of generation and decay took ac[10] count of chance; whence it would seem chance were
in
as a
things are said both to be
chance and must inquire therefore in what manner chance and spontaneity are present among the causes enumerated, and [35] whether they are the same or different, and generally what chance and spontaneity are. Some people even question whether they are 196a real or not. They say that nothing happens by chance, but that everything which we ascribe to chance or spontaneity has some definite cause, e.g. coming 'by chance' into the market and finding there a man whom one wanted but did not expect to meet is due to one's wish to go and buy in the market. Simto
is
is
by
a further circumstance that
Many
things both come to be and and spontaneity, and although all know that each of them can be ascribed to some cause (as the old argument said which surprising.
is
[75] denied chance), nevertheless they speak of some of these things as happening by chance
and others to
have
way
not.
For
this reason also they
at least referred to the
ought
matter in some
or other.
Certainly the early physicists found no place
among the
causes which they recogmind, fire, or the like. This is strange, whether they supposed that there is no such thing as chance or whether they [20] thought there is but omitted to mention it and that too when they sometimes used it, as Empedocles does when he says that the air is not always separated into the highest region, but 'as it may chance'. At any rate he says in his cosmogony that 'it happened to run that for chance
nized
—
love, strife,
—
way
1
but it often ran otherwise.' us also that most of the parts of animals came to be by chance. [25] There are some too who ascribe this heavenly sphere and all the worlds to spon-
He
1
at that time,
tells
Fr. g 3 .
BOOK
197« taneity.
They
taneously,
i.e.
II,
CHAPTERS
say that the vortex arose sponthe motion that separated and
arranged in its present order all that exists. This statement might well cause surprise. For they are asserting that chance is not responsible for the existence or generation of animals and [jo] plants, nature or mind or something of the kind being the cause of them (for it is not any chance thing that comes from a given seed but an olive from one kind and a man from another); and yet at the same time they assert
3-5
273
applicable. (Events that are for the sake of
something include whatever may be done thought or of nature.) Things of
result of
kind, then,
when
they
come
as a this
to pass incidental-
be 'by chance'. For just as a thing something either in virtue of itself or incidentally, so may it be a cause. For instance,
ly are said to
[25]
is
the housebuilding faculty
is
in virtue of itself
the cause of a house, whereas the pale or the
that the heavenly sphere
musical is the incidental cause. That which is per se cause of the effect is determinate, but the incidental cause is indeterminable, for the pos-
visible things arose spontaneously,
sible attributes of
and the divinest of having no and [55] such cause as is assigned to animals plants. Yet if this is so, it is a fact which deserves to be dwelt upon, and something might 196 b well have been said about it. For besides the other absurdities of the statement,
it
make
it
is
the
more absurd
that people should
when they see nothing coming to be spontaneously in the heavens, but much happening by chance among the things which as they say are not
due
to chance;
whereas
we
should have
expected exactly the opposite. believe that [5] Others there are who, indeed, chance is a cause, but that it is inscrutable to human intelligence, as being a divine thing
and
mystery. inquire what chance and they are the same or whether are, spontaneity full of
Thus we must
different,
and how they
fit
into our division of
causes.
able.
To resume
of the things that come to pass by necessity and always, or for the most part. But as there is a events third class of events besides these two which all say are 'by chance' it is plain that
—
—
such a thing as chance and spontaneity; [75] for we know that things of this kind are due to chance and that things due to chance are
there
is
of this kind.
But, secondly,
some events
are for the sake
of something, others not. Again,
some
of the
accordance with deliberate intention, others not, but both are in the class of things which are for the sake of something. [20] Hence it is clear that even among the
former
class are in
things which are outside the necessary and the
normal, there are some in connexion withwhich the phrase 'for the sake of something' is
thing of this events which
are for the sake of something,
it is said to be spontaneous or by chance. (The distinction between the two must be made later 1 for the present it is sufficient if it is plain that both are in the sphere of things done for the sake of something.)
—
Example:
A man
is
engaged in collecting He would have gone
subscriptions for a feast.
such and such a place for the purpose of if he had known. He [^5] actually went there for another purpose, and it was only incidentally that he got his money by going there; and this was not due to the fact that he went there as a rule or neces197 a sarily, nor is the end effected (getting the money) a cause present in himself it belongs to the class of things that are intentional to
getting the money,
—
when
others for the most part. It is clearly of neither of these that chance is said to be the cause, nor can the 'effect of chance' be identified with any
when a among
[jo] kind comes to pass
and the [10] First then we observe that some things always come to pass in the same way, and
an individual are innumerthen;
result of intelligent deliberation. It
is
these conditions are satisfied that the
man
is said to have gone 'by chance'. If he had gone of deliberate purpose and for the sake of this if he always or normally went there when he was collecting payments he would not be said to have gone 'by chance'. [5] It is clear then that chance is an incidental
—
—
cause in the sphere of those actions for the sake which involve purpose. Intelligent reflection, then, and chance are in the
of something
same sphere,
for purpose implies intelligent
reflection. It is necessary, no doubt, that the causes of what comes to pass by chance be indefinite; and that is why chance is supposed to belong to the class of the indefinite and to be in[10] scrutable to man, and why it might be
that, in a way, nothing occurs by chance. For all these statements are correct, because they are well grounded. Things do, in a way, occur by chance, for they occur incidentally and chance is an incidental cause. But
thought
1
In chapter
6.
PHYSICS
2 74
—
not the cause without qualification of anything; for instance, a housebuilder is the cause of a house; incidentally, a fluteplayer may be so. [75] And the causes of the man's coming and getting the money (when he did not come for the sake of that) are innumerable. He may strictly
—
it
is
have wished to see somebody or been following somebody or avoiding somebody, or may have gone to see a spectacle. Thus to say that chance is a thing contrary to rule is correct. For 'rule' applies to what is always true or true for the most part, whereas chance be[20] longs to a third type of event. Hence, to conclude, since causes of this kind are indefinite, chance too is indefinite. (Yet in some cases one might raise the question whether any incidental fact might be the cause of the chance occurrence, e.g. of health the fresh air or the sun's heat
may
be the cause, but having had
one's hair
cut cannot; for
causes are
more
some
incidental
relevant to the effect than
others.)
[25] Chance or fortune the result is good, 'evil'
is
called 'good'
when
when The
is evil.
it
197 b
[5] well-doing.
Hence what
is
not capable of
moral action cannot do anything by chance. Thus an inanimate thing or a lower animal or a child cannot do anything by chance, because it is incapable of deliberate intention; nor can 'good fortune' or 'ill fortune' be ascribed to them, except metaphorically, as Protarchus, 1 for example, said that the stones of which altars are
made
are fortunate because they are
[10] held in honour, while their fellows are trodden under foot. Even these things, how-
way be affected by chance, when dealing with them does something to them by chance, but not otherwise.
ever, can in a
who
one
is
The spontaneous on
hand
is
found
[75] both in the lower animals and in
many
inanimate objects. horse
the
though
his
the other
We
say, for
example, that
came 'spontaneously', because, coming saved him, he did not come
for the sake of safety. Again, the tripod 'of itself,
because, though
on
its
fall
for the sake of that.
when
it fell it
feet so as to serve for a seat,
Hence
it
is
clear that events
long to the general
it
fell
stood
did not
which (1)
class of things that
be-
may
of considerable magni-
come to pass for the sake of something, (2) do not come to pass for the sake of what actually
Thus one who comes within an ace of some great evil or great good is said to be fortunate or unfortunate. The mind affirms the
and (3) have an external cause, may be [20] described by the phrase 'from spontaneity'. These 'spontaneous' events are said to be
terms 'good fortune' and
when
either result
is
'ill
fortune' are used
tude.
presence of the attribute, ignoring the hair's [50] breadth of difference. Further, it is with reason that good fortune is regarded as unstable; for chance is unstable, as none of the things which result from it can be invariable or
normal.
Both are then, as I have said, incidental both chance and spontaneity in the sphere of things which are capable of coming to pass not necessarily, nor normally, and with [35] reference to such of these as might come
causes
—
—
to pass for the sake of something.
differ in that 'spontaneity' is the wider term. Every result of chance is from what is spontaneous, but not everything that is from what is spontaneous is from chance.
results
from chance
are appropriate to agents that are capable of
good fortune and of moral action
'from chance' if they have the further charbeing the objects of deliberate intention and due to agents capable of that mode of action. This is indicated by the phrase 'in vain', which is used when A, which is for the sake of B, does not result in B. For instance, taking a walk is for the sake of evacuation of the bowels; if this does not follow after walk-
acteristics of
we have walked 'in vain' and walking was 'vain'. This implies that [25] what is naturally the means to an end is 'in vain', when it does not effect the end towards which it was the natural means for it would be absurd for a man to say that he had bathed in vain because the sun was not eclipsed, since the one was not done with a view ing,
we
say that
that the
—
They
197 b Chance and what
results,
generally.
Therefore necessarily chance is in the sphere of moral actions. This is indicated by the fact that good fortune is thought to be the same, or nearly the same, as happiness, and happiness to be a kind of moral action, since it is
Thus the spontaneous is even according to its derivation the case in which the thing itself happens in vain. The stone that [50] struck the man did not fall for the pur-
to the other.
pose of striking him; therefore it fell spontaneously, because it might have fallen by the action of an agent and for the purpose of striking. The difference between spontaneity 1
Probably the reference
is
to the Protarchus described
as a pupil of Gorgias in Plato, Philebus, 58.
BOOK
198 b and what
II,
CHAPTERS
by chance is greatest in things that come to be by nature; for when anything
comes
results
to be contrary to nature,
[35] that
it
came
to be
we do
not say
by chance, but by spon-
Yet strictly this too is different from the spontaneous proper; for the cause of the latter is external, that of the former internal. 198* We have now explained what chance is
taneity.
and what spontaneity is, and in what they differ from each other. Both belong to the mode of causation 'source of change', for either some natural or some intelligent agent is always the cause; but in this sort of causation the of possible causes
is
number
and chance are causes of which though they might result from
[5 J Spontaneity
ef-
in-
have in
been caused by something incidentally. Now since nothing which is incidental is prior to what is per se, it is clear that no incidental cause can be prior to a cause per se. Spontaneity and chance, fact
therefore, are posterior to intelligence
and na-
[10] ture. Hence, however true it may be that the heavens are due to spontaneity, it will still
be true that intelligence and nature will be and of many things in
prior causes of this All it
*75
structible things.
The
question 'why', then,
besides.
answered by and to the respect of com-
is
reference to the matter, to the form,
primary moving cause. For in
mostly in this last way that 'what comes to be after what? what was the primary agent or patient ? and so at each step of the series. [55] Now the principles which cause motion in a physical way are two, of which one is not physical, as it has no principle of motion in ing to be
it
is
causes are investigated
infinite.
fects
telligence or nature,
5-8
such as are not of this kind are no longer inside the province of physics, for they cause motion not by possessing motion or a source of motion in themselves, but being themselves incapable of motion. Hence there are three [jo] branches of study, one of things which are incapable of motion, the second of things in motion, but indestructible, the third of de-
—
'
198 b itself. Of this kind is whatever causes movement, not being itself moved, such as ( 1 that which is completely unchangeable, the primary reality, and (2) the essence of that which is coming to be, i.e. the form; for this is the end or 'that for the sake of which'. Hence since nature is for the sake of something, we must know this cause also. We must [5] explain the 'why' in all the senses of the ( 1 ) that from this that will nec-
term, namely, It is
clear then that there are causes,
and that
number of them is what we have The number is the same as that of the
essarily result ('from this' either
without qual-
most cases); (2) that
must
[75] the
ification or in
stated.
be so if that is to be so' (as the conclusion presupposes the premisses); (3) that this was the essence of the thing; and (4) because it is better thus (not without qualification, but with reference to the essential nature in each case).
comprehended under the question 'why'. 'why' is referred ultimately either (1), in things which do not involve motion, e.g. in mathematics, to the 'what' (to the definition of 'straight line' or 'commensurable', &c), or (2) to what initiated a motion, e.g. 'why did they go to war? because there had been a raid'; [20] or (3) we are inquiring 'for the sake of what?' 'that they may rule'; or (4), in the case of things that come into being, we are looking for the matter. The causes, therefore, things
The
—
—
are these
Now,
and
so
many
in
number.
the causes being four,
it
is
the busi-
know
about them all, and if he refers his problems back to all of them, he will assign the 'why' in the way roper to his science the matter, the form, the f25] mover, 'that for the sake of which'. The
ness of the physicist to
—
last
three often coincide; for the 'what'
and
'that for the sake of which' are one, while the primary source of motion is the same in species as these (for
man
generates man), and so
which cause movement by being themselves moved; and too,
in general, are all things
'this
8
We
[jo] must explain then (1) that Nature belongs to the class of causes which act for the sake of something; (2) about the necessary and its place in physical problems, for all writers ascribe things to this cause, arguing that since the hot and the cold, &c, are of such and such a kind, therefore certain things necessarily are and come to be and if they mention any other [75] cause (one his 'friendship and strife', another his 'mind'), it is only to touch on it, and then good-bye to it. difficulty presents itself: why should not nature work, not for the sake of something, nor because it is better so, but just as the sky rains, not in order to make the corn grow, but
—
A
What is drawn up must cool, and what has been cooled must become water
of necessity ?
[20]
and descend, the
result of this being that the
PHYSICS
276 corn grows. Similarly
if a man's crop is spoiled on the threshing-floor, the rain did not fall for the sake of this in order that the crop might
—
—
be spoiled but that result just followed. Why then should it not be the same with the parts in nature, e.g. that our teeth should come up
—
the front teeth sharp, fitted for of necessity [25] tearing, the molars broad and useful for
grinding
down
the food
arise for this end, but
—
since they did not
was merely
it
a coinci-
dent result; and so with all other parts in which we suppose that there is purpose? Wherever then all the parts came about just what they would have been if they had come [jo] to be for an end, such things survived, being organized spontaneously in a fitting way; whereas those which grew otherwise perished and continue to perish, as Empedocles 1 says his 'man-faced ox-progeny' did.
Such are the arguments (and others of the kind) which may cause difficulty on this point. Yet it is impossible that this should be the true view. For teeth and all other natural [55] things either invariably or normally come about in a given way; but of not one of the results of chance or spontaneity is this true. We do not ascribe to chance or mere coinci199 a dence the frequency of rain in winter, but frequent rain in summer we do; nor heat in the dog-days, but only if we have it in winter. If then, it is agreed that things are either the result of coincidence or for an end, and these cannot be the result of coincidence or [5] spontaneity, it follows that they must be for an end; and that such things are all due to
nature even the champions of the theory which is before us would agree. Therefore action for an end is present in things which come to be
and are by nature. Further, where a
has a completion,
series
all
the preceding steps are for the sake of that. surely as in intelligent action, so in na-
Now
[10] ture; action,
action
if is
and
as in nature, so
nothing
interferes.
for the sake of
it is
Now
in each
intelligent
an end; therefore the
Thus if a house, made by nature, it would have been made in the same way as it is now by art; and if things made by nature were made also by art, they would come to be in the same way as by nature. Each step then nature of things also is e.g. had been a thing
so.
[75] in the series is for the sake of the next; art partly completes what nature
and generally
cannot bring to a her. 1
If,
finish,
and
partly imitates
therefore, artificial products are for the
Ft.6i.2.
199 b
sake of an end,
The
products.
so clearly also are natural
relation
the
of
later
to
the
terms of the series is the same in both. [20] This is most obvious in the animals other than man: they make things neither by art nor after inquiry or deliberation. Wherefore people discuss whether it is by intelligence or by some other faculty that these creatures work, spiders, ants, and the like. By gradual advance earlier
in this direction
we come
to see clearly that in
[25] plants too that is produced which is conducive to the end leaves, e.g. grow to pro-
—
vide shade for the fruit. If then
it is both by nature and for an end that the swallow makes
nest
its
and the spider
its
web, and plants grow and send their
leaves for the sake of the fruit
down
(not up) for the sake of nourishplain that this kind of cause is [jo] operative in things which come to be and
roots
ment,
it
is
And
since 'nature' means two and the form, of which the latter is the end, and since all the rest is for the sake of the end, the form must be the
are by nature.
things, the matter
cause in the sense of 'that for the sake of which'. Now mistakes come to pass even in the operations of art: the
grammarian makes
a
mistake in writing and the doctor pours out [55] the wrong dose. Hence clearly mistakes 199 b are possible in the operations of nature also. If then in art there are cases in which
what is rightly produced serves a purpose, and if where mistakes occur there was a purpose in what was attempted, only it was not attained, so must it be also in natural products, and [5] monstrosities will be failures in the purThus in the original combina-
posive effort.
tions the 'ox-progeny' if they failed to reach a determinate end must have arisen through the corruption of some principle corresponding to is now the seed. Further, seed must have come into being first, and not straightway the animals: the
what
words 'whole-natured meant seed. Again, in plants too [10]
means
ganization
to end,
is
less.
first
we
.' 2 .
.
must have
find the relation of
though the degree of
Were
or-
there then in plants
'manheaded ox-progeny', or not? An absurd suggestion; yet there must have been, if there were also 'olive-headed vine-progeny', like the
such things among animals. Moreover, among the seeds anything must have come to be at random. But the person who asserts this entirely does away with 'na2
Empedocles, Fr. 62.
4.
BOOK
200b and what
ture'
exists
II,
'by nature'.
CHAPTERS
For
[75] those things are natural which, by a continuous movement originated from an internal
some completion: the same not reached from every prin-
principle, arrive at
completion is ciple; nor any chance completion, but always the tendency in each is towards the same end, if there is no impediment. The end and the means towards it may come [20] about by chance. We say, for instance, that a stranger has come by chance, paid the ransom, and gone away, when he does so as if he had come for that purpose, though it was not for that that he came. This is incidental, for chance is an incidental cause, as I remarked before. 1 But when an event takes flace always or for the most part, it is not 25] incidental or by chance. In natural products the sequence is invariable, if there is no impediment. It is absurd to suppose that purpose is not present because we do not observe the agent deliberating. Art does not deliberate. If the ship-building art were in the wood, produce the same results by nature. fore,
purpose
is
present in
art,
it
would
it
If,
is
there-
present
[jo] also in nature. The best illustration is doctoring himself: nature is like
a doctor that.
It is plain then that nature is a cause, a cause that operates for a purpose.
As regards what
is
'of necessity',
we must
ask
[35] whether the necessity is 'hypothetical', or 'simple' as well. The current view places what is
of necessity in the process of production, just
200* as if one were to suppose that the wall of a house necessarily comes to be because what is heavy is naturally carried downwards and what is light to the top, wherefore the stones and foundations take the lowest place, with earth above because it is lighter, and wood at [5] the top of all as being the lightest. Whereas, though the wall does not come to be without these,
it is
material cause:
not due to these, except as its it comes to be for the sake of
and guarding certain things. Similarly in all other things which involve production for an end; the product cannot come to be without things which have a necessary nature, but it is not due to these (except as its ma[10] terial); it comes to be for an end. For instance, why is a saw such as it is? To effect so-and-so and for the sake of so-and-so. This sheltering
1
io6 b 23-7.
8-9
277
end, however, cannot be realized unless the saw is made of iron. It is, therefore, necessary it to be of iron, if we are to have a saw and perform the operation of sawing. What is necessary then, is necessary on a hypothesis; it
for
is
not a result necessarily determined by anteis in the matter, while 'that
cedents. Necessity
for the sake of which'
in the definition.
is
[75] Necessity in mathematics is in a way similar to necessity in things which come to be
through the operation straight line
is
what
it
is
it
But not conversely; though
gles are not equal to
straight line
is
two
a
necessary that
the angles of a triangle should equal angles.
Since
nature.
of is,
two if
right
the an-
right angles, then the
not what
it
is
either.
But in
come to be for an end, the reverse is true. If the end is to exist or does exist, [20] that also which precedes it will exist or things which
does exist; otherwise just as there, if the conclusion is not true, the premiss will not be true, so here the end or 'that for the sake of which' will not exist. For this too is itself a starting-point, but of the reasoning, not of the action; while in mathematics the startingpoint is the starting-point of the reasoning only, as there is no action. If then there is to be [25] a house, such-and-such things must be made or be there already or exist, or generally the matter relative to the end, bricks and stones if it is a house. But the end is not due to these except as the matter, nor will it come to exist because of them. Yet if they do not exist at all, neither will the house, or the saw the former in the absence of stones, the latter in the absence of iron just as in the other case the premisses will not be true, if the angles of the triangle are not equal to two right
—
—
angles.
[jo]
The
what we
necessary in nature, then,
is
plainly
by the name of matter, and the changes in it. Both causes must be stated by the physicist, but especially the end; for that is
call
and and the
the cause of the matter, not vice versa;
the end
is
beginning [55]
'that for the sake of which', starts
from the
definition
or es-
sence; as in artificial products, since a
200b house is of such-and-such a kind, certain things must necessarily come to be or be there already, or since health
must necessarily come
is
this,
these things
to be or be there already.
Similarly if man is this, then these; if these, then those. Perhaps the necessary is present also in the definition.
For
if
one defines the
[5] operation of sawing as being a certain kind of dividing, then this cannot come about un-
PHYSICS
278
saw has
the
less
and
teeth of a certain kind;
these cannot be unless
it is
of iron.
For
in the
201*
definition too there are it
BOOK
were,
some
parts that are, as
matter.
its
III
Now each
of these belongs to
all its
subjects
two ways: namely (1) substance
in either of
Nature
has been defined as a 'principle of moand change', and it is the subject of our inquiry. We must therefore see that we understand the meaning of 'motion'; for if it were unknown, the meaning of 'nature' too would
the one
tion
(2) in quality, white and black; (3) in quantity, complete and incomplete; (4) in respect of locomotion, upwards and downwards as
many
be unknown.
types of motion or change as there are
mean-
[75] When we have determined the nature of motion, our next task will be to attack in the same way the terms which are involved in it. Now motion is supposed to belong to the class of things which are continuous; and the infinite presents itself first in the continuous that is how it comes about that 'infinite' is often used in definitions of the continuous
ings of the
('what
is
infinitely divisible
is
continuous').
[20] Besides these, place, void, and time are thought to be necessary conditions of motion. Clearly, then, for these reasons
and
also be-
cause the attributes mentioned are common to, and coextensive with, all the objects of our science,
and
we must
first
take each of
them
in
hand
positive form, the other privation;
is
[5]
and heavy. Hence there are
or light
We
word
now
have
'is'.
before us the distinctions in
the various classes of being between fully real
[10] Def.
The
is
it
what
—namely, of what
alterable
is
what can be increased and its what can be decreased (there is no common name), increase and decrease: of what can come to be and can pass away, coming to be and passing away: of what can be carried along, locomotion.
[75]
Examples
motion.
When
will elucidate this definition of
the buildable, in so far as
ing, leaping, ripening, ageing.
To begin then, We may start by
as
we
said,
with motion.
and
also in fulfilment
what
an-
'relative'
is
used with
move and what can be moved. For 'what can cause movement' is relative to 'what can be moved', and vice versa. Again, there is no such thing as motion over and above the things. It is always with respect to substance or to quantity or to quality or to
what changes changes. But
it is imanything com[35] mon to these which is neither 'this' nor 201 a quantum nor quale nor any of the other
possible, as
we
The same
thing,
if it is
built,
of a certain kind, can
hot and actually cold. will act and be acted on by one another in many ways: each of them will be capable at the same time of causing alteration and of being altered. Hence, too, what effects motion as a physical agent can be moved:
'this',
[50] reference to (1) excess and defect, (2) agent and patient and generally what can
place that
roll-
being
it is
exists as potential
—one being a
being.
word
this
building. Similarly, learning, doctoring,
fully real,
[20] be both potential and fully real, not indeed at the same time or not in the same re-
other 'so much', a third 'such', and similarly in each of the other modes of the predication of
Further, the
is
it is
and
is
what what
distinguishing (1) exists in a state of fulfilment only, (2) exists as potential, (3)
mo-
altera-
opposite
butes.
[25]
qua
ble, alteration: of
just that,
it.
is
exists poten-
exists potentially, is
For the investigation of special attributes comes after that of the common attridiscuss
what
potential.
fulfilment of
so far as
tially, in
tion
and what
assert, to find
predicates. Hence neither will motion and change have reference to something over and above the things mentioned, for there is nothing over and above them.
but
spect,
e.g. potentially
Hence at once such things
when
a thing of this kind causes motion,
it is
moved. This, indeed, has led some people to suppose that every mover is moved. But this question depends on another set of arguments, and the truth will be made [25]
itself also
clear later.
1
It is
motion, though
possible for a thing to cause it is itself
incapable of being
moved. the fulfilment of what is potential when already fully real and operates not as itself
It is it is
but as movable, that is motion. What I mean by 'as' is this: Bronze is potentially a statue. [50] But it is not the fulfilment of bronze as bronze which is motion. For 'to be bronze' and 'to be a certain potentiality* are not the same. 1 viii. 5.
BOOK
202*
II,
CHAPTER 9— BOOK
they were identical without qualification,
If
in definition, the fulfilment of
i.e.
bronze as bronze
would have been motion. But they are not the same, as has been said. (This is obvious in con[35] traries. 'To be capable of health' and 'to be capable of illness' are not the same, for if 201 b they were there would be no difference between being ill and being well. Yet the subis
—
humour
—
—
both of health and of sickness whether it is one and the same.) or blood We can distinguish, then, between the two just as, to give another example, 'colour' and
ject
'visible' are different
filment of
what
is
—and
clearly
it is
the ful-
potential as potential that
is
So this, precisely, is motion. Further it is evident that motion is an attribute of a thing just when it is fully real in this way, and neither before nor after. For each thing of this kind is capable of being at one time actual, at another not. Take for instance [5] motion.
the buildable as buildable. The actuality of the [10] buildable as buildable is the process of
building. For the actuality of the buildable must be either this or the house. But when there
is
a house, the buildable
buildable.
On
the other hand,
which is being built. The being built must be the kind quired. But building is a kind the same account will apply to able
is
it is
no longer the build-
process then of of actuality reof motion,
III,
CHAPTERS
yet a thing that
motion
is
This It is
and
also
from the
otherwise.
could not easily put motion and change genus this is plain if we consider where some people put it; they identify motion [20] with 'difference' or 'inequality' or 'not being'; but such things are not necessarily moved, whether they are 'different' or 'unequal' or
One
—
Nor
change either to or from from their opposites. The reason why they put motion into these is thought to be some[ 2 5] genera is that it thing indefinite, and the principles in the sec'non-existent'
;
is
these rather than to or
ond column are indefinite because they are privative: none of them is either 'this' or 'such' or comes under any of the other modes of predication. The reason in turn why motion is thought to be indefinite
cannot be an actuality a thing that is merely capable of having a [ jo] certain size is not undergoing change, nor is
that
it
classed simply as a potentiality or as
—
but
is
why
it is
hard
what motion is. with privation or with
to grasp it
none of There remains then the [55] suggested mode of definition, namely that 202 a it is a sort of actuality, or actuality of the potentiality or with sheer actuality, yet
these seems possible.
kind described, hard
to grasp,
but not incapa-
ble of existing.
The mover too is moved, as has been said every mover, that is, which is capable of mo-
—
and whose immobility is rest when a is subject to motion its immobility is rest. [5] For to act on the movable as such is just to move it. But this it does by contact, so that at the same time it is also acted on. Hence we can define motion as the fulfilment of the movable qua movable, the cause of the attribute being contact with what can move, so that the mover is also acted on. The mover or agent will always be the vehicle of a form, either a 'this' or tion,
thing
[10] a 'such', which, when it acts, will be the source and cause of the change, e.g. the full-
formed man begets man.
man from what
is
poten-
tially
ble
in another
and
and
The soundness of this definition is evident both when we consider the accounts of motion it
to be a sort of actuality,
necessary to class
solution of the difficulty that
about the motion
defining
actually of a certain size,
is
thought
incomplete, the reason for this view being that the potential whose actuality it is is incomplete.
The
that the others have given,
279
the other kinds
[75] also.
difficulty of
1-3
—
is
plain. It
—whether
is
it is
is
raised
in the
mova-
the fulfilment of this poten-
and by the action
of that which has the power of causing motion; and the actuality of that which has the power of causing motion is [75] not other than the actuality of the movable, for it must be the fulfilment of both. A thing is capable of causing motion because it can do this, it is a mover because it actually does it. But it is on the movable that it is capable of acting. Hence there is a single actuality of both alike, just as one to two and two to one are the same interval, and the steep ascent and tiality,
—
[20] the steep descent are one for these are one and the same, although they can be described in different ways. So it is with the mover
and the moved.
This view has a dialectical difficulty. Perhaps it is necessary that the actuality of the agent and that of the patient should not be the same. The one is 'agency' and the other 'patiency'; and the outcome and completion of the one is an 'action', that of the other a 'passion'. [25] Since then they are both motions, we may ask: in
what are
they,
if
they are different?
PHYSICS
280
Either (a) both are in what is acted on and moved, or (b) the agency is in the agent and the patiency in the patient. (If we ought to call the latter also 'agency', the word would be used in two senses.) Now, in alternative (b), the motion will be in the mover, for the same statement will hold of 'mover' and 'moved'. Hence either every
mover
moved, or, though having moved. If on the other hand (a) both are in what is moved and acted on both the agency and the patiency (e.g. both teaching and learning, though they are two, in the learner), then, first, [jo]
motion,
it
will be
will not be
—
203
from each other, that the two are one and the same. To generalize, teaching is not the same as learnare at a distance vectors
AB
ing, or
agency as patiency, in the
and
BA
X
and the 'actualization of Y through the action of X' differ in definition. What then Motion is, has been stated both generally and particularly. It is not difficult to see
how
each of
[25] teration
qua
is
its
types will be defined
alterable (or,
more
what can be acted
—generally and again
ticular case, building, healing, &c.
ject
How
will there
alterations of quality in one subtowards one definite quality? The thing is
al-
scientifically, the ful-
filment of what can act and
each, and, a second absurdity, a thing will have
same time.
—
the fulfillment of the alterable
on, as such)
at the
full sense,
[20] though they belong to the same subject, the motion; for the 'actualization of in Y'
the actuality of each will not be present in
two motions [35] De two
1
in
each par-
A
similar
definition will apply to each of the other kinds
of motion.
impossible: the actualization will be one.
202 b But (some one
will say)
it is
contrary to
reason to suppose that there should be one identical actualization of two things which are different in kind. Yet there will be, if teaching
and learning are the same, and agency and patiency. To teach will be the same as to learn, and to act the same as to be acted on the
—
teacher will necessarily be learning everything that he teaches, and the agent will be acted on. [5]
One may
reply:
not absurd that the actualization of one thing should be in another. Teaching is the activity of a person who can teach, yet the ( 1 ) It is
—
operation is performed on some patient it is not cut adrift from a subject, but is of A on B. (2) There is nothing to prevent two things having one and the same actualization, provided the actualizations are not described in the same way, but are related as what can act to
what
is
acting.
[10] (3)
Nor
is
it
necessary that the teacher
should learn, even if to act and to be acted on are one and the same, provided they are not the
same
in definition (as 'raiment'
and 'dress'),
but are the same merely in the sense in which the road from Thebes to Athens and the road from Athens to Thebes are the same, as has been explained above. 1 For it is not things which are in a way the same that have all their [75] attributes the same, but only such as have the same definition. But indeed it by no means follows from the fact that teaching is the same
same as to teach, any more than it follows from the fact that there is one distance between two things which as learning, that to learn
»Cf. E i8-20.
is
the
[jo]
The
spatial
science of nature is concerned with magnitudes and motion and time, and
each of these at least is necessarily infinite or even if some things dealt with by the science are not, e.g. a quality or a point it is not necessary perhaps that such things should be put under either head. Hence it is incumbent on the person who specializes in physics [^5] to discuss the infinite and to inquire whether there is such a thing or not, and, if finite,
—
there
is,
what
it is.
The
appropriateness to the science of this problem is clearly indicated. All who have
203 a touched on this kind of science in a way worth considering have formulated views about the infinite, and indeed, to a man, make it
a principle of things.
(1) Some, as the Pythagoreans and Plato, [5] make the infinite a principle in the sense of a self-subsistent substance, and not as a mere
some other thing. Only the Pythagoreans place the infinite among the objects of sense (they do not regard number as separable from these), and assert that what is outside the heaven is infinite. Plato, on the other hand, holds that there is no body outside (the Forms are not outside, because they are nowhere), yet that the infinite is present not only in the objects of sense but in the Forms also. attribute of
[10] Further, the Pythagoreans identify the inwith the even. For this, they say, when
finite
it is cut off and shut in by the odd, provides things with the element of infinity. An indica-
tion of this
the
is
gnomons
what happens with numbers. If are placed round the one, and
without the one, in the one construction the
204
BOOK
s
III,
CHAPTERS
always different, in the [75] other it is always the same. But Plato has two infinites, the Great and the Small. The physicists, on the other hand, all of them, always regard the infinite as an attribute figure that results
of a substance
is
which
is
different
from
it
and
3-4
281
to be the principle of other things,
causes, such as
Mind
or Friendship. Further
they identify it with the Divine, for it is 'deathless and imperishable' as Anaximander says,
with the majority of the physicists.
them. Those who make them limited in number never make them infinite in amount. But those who make the elements infinite in num[20] ber, as Anaxagoras and Democritus do, say that the infinite is continuous by contact
comes mainly from
compounded
infinite.
of the
homogeneous parts accord-
mixture in the same way as the All, on the ground of the observed fact that anything comes out of anything. For it is probably for this reason that he maintains that once upon a [25] time all things were together. (This flesh and this bone were together, and so of any thing: therefore all things:
and
at the
same
time too.) For there is a beginning of separation, not only for each thing, but for all. Each thing that comes to be comes from a similar body, and there is a coming to be of all things,
same time. Hence [50] there must also be an origin of coming to be. One such source there is which he calls Mind, and Mind begins its work of thinking from some starting-point. So necessarily all things must have been together at a certain time, and must have begun to be moved at a though
not,
it is
true, at the
certain time.
Democritus, for his part, asserts the connamely that no element arises from another element. Nevertheless for him the comtrary,
203 b mon body is a source of all things, differing from part to part in size and in shape. It is clear then from these considerations that the inquiry concerns the physicist.
Nor
is
without reason that they all make it a principle or source. We cannot say that the infinite it
(1)
From
the nature of time
for
is infi-
it
—
(2) From the division of magnitudes for the mathematicians also use the notion of the (3) If coming to be and passing away do not give out, it is only because that from which things
come
to be
is
infinite.
[20] (4) Because the limited always finds its limit in something, so that there must be no if everything is always limited by something different from itself. (5) Most of all, a reason which is peculiarly appropriate and presents the difficulty that is felt by everybody not only number but also mathematical magnitudes and what is outside the heaven are supposed to be infinite because they never give out in our thought.
limit,
—
[25]
The
last fact (that
what
outside
is
infinite,
and that there
worlds.
Why
is
an
is infi-
body
nite) leads people to suppose that
infinite
also
is
number
of
should there be body in one part Grant only
of the void rather than in another?
that mass is anywhere and it follows that it must be everywhere. Also, if void and place are infinite, there must be infinite body too, for in the case of eternal things what may be must be. [50] But the problem of the infinite is difficult: many contradictions result whether we supto exist or not to exist. If
pose
it
have
still
to ask
how
it
exists; as a
as the essential attribute of
some
neither way, yet none the less
thing which
is
are infinitely
many?
infinite or
it
exists,
entity?
is
er there
is
a sensible
we
substance or
Or
in
there some-
some things which
204 a The problem, however, which
finite.
im
—
nite.
Everything is either a source or derived from a source. But there cannot be a source of the infinite or limitless, for that would be a limit of it. Further, as it is a beginning, it is both
completion, and also a termination of all passzo] ing away. That is why, as we say, there is no principle of this, but it is this which is held
infinite
five considerations:
belongs to the physicist
uncreatable and indestructible. For there must be a point at which what has come to be reaches
of the
Belief in the existence
[75]
has no effect, and the only effectiveness which we can ascribe to it is that of a principle. [5]
to en-
compass all and to steer all, as those assert who do not recognize, alongside the infinite, other
belongs to the class of the so-called elements water or air or what is intermediate between
ing to the one, of the seed-mass of the atomic shapes according to the other. Further, Anaxagoras held that any part is a
and
specially
whethmagnitude which is inis
to investigate
We
must begin by distinguishing the various senses in which the term 'infinite' is used. ( 1 ) What is incapable of being gone through, because it is not in its nature to be gone through (the sense
in
which the voice
is
'invisi-
ble').
(2) What admits of being gone through, the process however having no termination, or
PHYSICS
282
what
(3)
scarcely
admits
of
gone
being
[5] through.
What
(4)
naturally admits of being gone
through, but is not actually gone through or does not actually reach an end. Further, everything that is infinite may be so in respect of addition or division or both.
204 b
be present in mathematical objects and things which are intelligible and do not have exten-
204 b
sion, as well as among sensible objects. inquiry (as physicists) is limited to its spe-
Our
cial subject-matter,
the objects of sense,
and we
have to ask whether there is or is not among them a body which is infinite in the direction of increase.
Now
it
impossible that the infinite should
is
be a thing which
from
is
itself infinite,
sensible objects. If the infinite
separable is
neither
We may begin with a dialectical argument and show as follows that there is no such thing. [5] If 'bounded by a surface' is the definition of body there cannot be an infinite body either Nor can number taken number or that
[10] a magnitude nor an aggregate, but is itself a substance and not an attribute, it will be
intelligible or sensible.
indivisible; for the divisible must be either a magnitude or an aggregate. But if indivisible,
which has number is numerable. If then the numerable can be numbered, it would also be possible to go through the infinite. [10] If, on the other hand, we investigate the question more in accordance with principles
then not
infinite,
except in the sense (1) in
which the voice is 'invisible'. But this is not the sense in which it is used by those who say that the infinite exsts, nor that in which we are investigating it, namely as (2), 'that which cannot be gone through'. But if the infinite exists [75] as an attribute, it would not be, qua infinite, an element in substances, any more than the invisible would be an element of speech, though the voice is invisible. Further,
how
can the
thing, unless both
which
way ?
it is
If
infinite
[20]
an
infinite
be
itself
any
number and magnitude,
of
essential attribute, exist in that
they are not substances, a fortiori the is
It is
appropriate to physics, the same result.
we
are led as follows to
The infinite body must be either (1) compound, or (2) simple; yet neither alternative is
possible.
if
(1) Compound the infinite body will not be, the elements are finite in number. For they
must be more than one, and the contraries must always balance, and no one of them can be infinite. [
If
one of the bodies
g ree short of the other
J 5]
falls in
amount while
pose
fire is finite in
plain, too, that the infinite cannot be
and
a given quantity of fire exceeds in
predicated of a subject. Hence it will be either [25] indivisible or divisible into infinites. But
same thing cannot be many
just as part of air
is air,
infinites.
(Yet
so a part of the infinite
would be infinite, if it is supposed to be a substance and principle.) Therefore the infinite must be without parts and indivisible. But this cannot be true of what is infinite in full completion: for it must be a definite quantity. Suppose then that infinity belongs to substance as an attribute. But, if so, it cannot, as [50] we have said, be described as a principle, but rather that of which it is an attribute the air or the even number. Thus the view of those who speak after the manner of the Pythagoreans is absurd. With the same breath they treat the infinite as substance, and divide it into parts. This discussion, however, involves the more [55] general question whether the infinite can
—
the it
same amount of
is
any
air in
numerically definite
—the
body.
On
ratio
the other hand,
it is
all
power
provided
directions
impossible
what has and the infinite
that each should be infinite. 'Body'
[20] extension in
—sup-
air is infinite
infinite body and annihilate the
will obviously prevail over finite
any de-
in potency
not.
an actual thing and a substance and principle. For any part of it that is taken will be infinite, if it has parts: for 'to be infinite' and 'the infinite' are the same, if it is a substance and not
the
in abstraction be infinite, for
is
what is boundlessly extended, so that the inbody would be extended in all directions ad infinitum. Nor (2) can the infinite body be one and simple, whether it is, as some hold, a thing over and above the elements (from which they genis
finite
erate the elements) or
is
not thus qualified.
We
must consider the former alternative; for there are some people who make this the infinite, and not air or water, in order that (a)
[25] the other elements may not be annihilated by the element which is infinite. They have contrariety with each other air is cold, water moist, fire hot; if one were infinite, the others by now would have ceased to be. As it is, they
—
say, the infinite
is
different
from them and
is
their source. It is
impossible, however, that there should
BOOK
205 b
III,
CHAPTERS
[30] be such a body; not because it is infinite that point a general proof can be given which applies equally to all, air, water, or any-
—on
—
thing else but simply because there is, as a matter of fact, no such sensible body, alongside the so-called elements. Everything can be resolved into the elements of which it is composed. Hence the body in question would have been present in our world here, alongside air and fire and earth and water: but nothing of the kind
is
[35] (&)
N° r
fire
283
[25] what is contrary to it. (This indeed is the reason why none of the physicists made fire or earth the one infinite body, but either water or air or what is intermediate between them, because the abode of each of the two was plainly
determinate, while the others have an ambigu-
ous place between up and down.)
But (ii) if the parts are infinite in number and simple, their proper places too will be infinite in number, and the same will be true of [jo] the elements themselves. If that
observed.
can
4-5
or any other of the ele-
ments be infinite. For generally, and apart from 205 a the question of how any of them could be infinite, the All, even if it were limited, cannot either be or become one of them, as Heraclitus says that at some time all things become fire. (The same argument applies also to the [5] one which the physicists suppose to exist alongside the elements: for everything changes from contrary to contrary, e.g. from hot to
sible,
and the places are
must be
finite,
finite; for the place
is
impos-
the whole too
and the body can-
each other. Neither is the whole place larger than what can be filled by the body (and then the body would no longer be [55] infinite), nor is the body larger than the place; for either there would be an empty space or a body whose nature it is to be nowhere. 205 b Anaxagoras gives an absurd account of not but
why
fit
the infinite
is
at rest.
He
says that the in-
an infinite sensible body. The following arguments give a general demonstration that it is not possible. [10] It is the nature of every kind of sensible body to be somewhere, and there is a place appropriate to each, the same for the part and for the whole, e.g. for the whole earth and for a single clod, and for fire and for a spark. Suppose (a) that the infinite sensible body is homogeneous. Then each part will be either immovable or always being carried along. Yet neither is possible. For why downwards rather than upwards or in any other direction? I mean, e.g. if you take a clod, where will it be [75] moved or where will it be at rest? For ex hypothesi the place of the body akin to it is infinite. Will it occupy the whole place, then?
being fixed. This because it is in itself, since nothing else conon the assumption that wherever anytains it [5] thing is, it is there by its own nature. But this is not true: a thing could be somewhere by compulsion, and not where it is its nature to be. Even if it is true as true can be that the whole is not moved (for what is fixed by itself and is in itself must be immovable), yet we must explain why it is not its nature to be moved. It is not enough just to make this statement and then decamp. Anything else might [10] be in a state of rest, but there is no reason why it should not be its nature to be moved. The earth is not carried along, and would not be carried along if it were infinite, provided it is held together by the centre. But it would not be because there was no other region in which it could be carried along that it would remain at the centre, but because this is its nature. Yet
And how ? What
in this case also
finite itself is the
cold).
The preceding cases serves to
consideration of the various it is or is not
show us whether
possible that there should be
rest
and
be ?
It
it
of
its
then will be the nature of
movement, or where
will either be at
will not be
—then
where But
—then
home everywhere it will be moved
moved; or it
will not
come
its
will they
every-
to rest.
if (b) the All has dissimilar parts, the proper places of the parts will be dissimilar [20] also, and the body of the All will have no
unity except that of contact. Then, further, the parts will be either finite or infinite in variety
of kind, (i) Finite they cannot be, for
All
is
if
the
some of them would have while the others were not, e.g.
to be infinite,
to be infinite,
or water will be infinite. But, as we have seen before, such an element would destroy
fire
cause of
its
—
we may
say that
it
fixes itself.
then in the case of the earth, supposed to be [75] infinite, it is at rest, not because it is infinite, but because it has weight and what is heavy rests at the centre and the earth is at the centre, similarly the infinite also would rest in itself, not because it is infinite and fixes itself, but owing to some other cause. If
Another
emerges at the same time. body ought to remain at rest. Just as the infinite remains at rest in itself because it fixes itself, so too any part of it [20] you may take will remain in itself. The appropriate places of the whole and of the part are alike, e.g. of the whole earth and
Any
difficulty
part of the infinite
PHYSICS
284 of a clod the appropriate place
gion; of
fire as a
is
the lower re-
whole and of a spark, the up-
per region. If, therefore, to be in itself is the place of the infinite, that also will be appropriate to the part.
Therefore
it
will
remain in
it-
self.
In general, the view that there is an infinite [25] body is plainly incompatible with the doctrine that there
necessarily a proper place for
is
every sensible body has either weight or lightness, and if a body has a natural locomotion towards the centre if it is
each kind of body,
if
heavy, and upwards if it is light. This would to be true of the infinite also. But neither character can belong to it: it cannot be either as a whole, nor can it be half the one and half [50] the other. For how should you divide it?
need
how can the infinite have the one part up and the other down, or an extremity and a
or
centre ?
general,
an
if it is
is
in place,
impossible that there should be
infinite place,
206 a
and
if
every body
is
in place,
there cannot be an infinite body.
Surely what
and what
is
is
in a special place
in place
is
is
in place,
in a special place. Just,
—
that then, as the infinite cannot be quantity it has a particular quantity,
would imply that e.g. two or three
—
cubits; quantity just
means
so a thing's being in place means [5] these that it is somewhere, and that is either up or
down or in some other of the six differences of position: but each of these is a limit. It is plain from these arguments that there is
no body which
is
But on the other hand to suppose that the indoes not exist in any way leads obviously
many impossible consequences:
[10] a beginning
we have
as
(There
is
no
seen, magnitude is not acBut by division it is infinite.
difficulty in refuting the
indivisible lines.)
The
theory of
alternative then remains
that the infinite has a potential existence.
But the phrase 'potential existence' is ambiguous. When we speak of the potential existence of a statue we mean that there will be an [20] actual statue.
There
nite.
word
many
not so with the infian actual infinite. The
It is
will not be
and we say that the which we say 'it is day' or 'it is the games', because one thing after another is always coming into existence. For of these things too the distinction between potential and actual existence holds. We say that there are Olympic games, both in the sense that they may occur and that they are actually ochas
'is'
infinite
'is'
senses,
in the sense in
curring.
The
—
ways
infinite
exhibits itself in different
man, and For generally the infinite has this mode of existence: one thing is always being taken after another, and each in time, in the generations of
in the division of magnitudes.
is taken is always finite, but always Again, 'being' has more than one [30] sense, so that we must not regard the infinite as a 'this', such as a man or a horse, but must suppose it to exist in the sense in which we speak of the day or the games as existing things whose being has not come to them like that of a substance, but consists in a process of coming to be or passing away; definite if you like at each stage, yet always different.
thing that different.
206 b But when this takes place in spatial magnitudes, what is taken perists, while in the succession of time and of men it takes place by the passing away of these in such a way that the source of supply never gives out.
In a way the infinite by addition is the same thing as the infinite by division. In a finite magnitude, the infinite by addition comes
actually infinite.
finite
to
Now,
tually infinite.
[25]
and the kinds or differences of place are up-down, before-behind, right-left; and these distinctions hold not only in relation to us and by arbitrary [35] agreement, but also in the whole itself. But in the infinite body they cannot exist. In Further, every sensible body
206 b
there will be
and an end of time, a mag-
about in a way inverse to that of the other. For [5] in proportion as we see division going on, in the same proportion we see addition being
made
to
what
is
already
marked
off.
For
if
we
nitude will not be divisible into magnitudes, number will not be infinite. If, then, in view of the above considerations, neither alternative seems possible, an arbiter must be called in;
take a determinate part of a finite magnitude and add another part determined by the same ratio (not taking in the same amount of the original whole), and so on, we shall not trav-
and
[10] erse the given magnitude. But if we increase the ratio of the part, so as always to take in the same amount, we shall traverse the mag-
is a sense in which the infinite and another in which it does not. We must keep in mind that the word 'is' means either what potentially is or what fully is.
clearly there
exists
[75] Further, a thing tion or by division.
is
infinite either
by addi-
magnitude is exhausted by means of any determinate quantity however
nitude, for every finite small.
BOOK
207 b
The
III,
CHAPTERS
no other way, and by reduction. It exists fully in the sense in which we say 'it is day' or 'it is the games'; and poinfinite, then, exists in
but in this
way
it
does
exist, potentially
[75] tentially as matter exists, not independently as what is finite does. By addition then, also, there is potentially an infinite, namely, what we have described as being in a sense the same as the infinite in respect of division. For it will always be possible to take something ab extra. Yet the sum of the parts taken will not exceed every determinate magnitude, just as in the direction of division every determinate magnitude is surpassed in smallness and there will be a smaller part. [20] But in respect of addition there cannot be an infinite which even potentially exceeds every assignable magnitude, unless it has the at-
tribute of being actually infinite, as the physi-
hold to be true of the body which is outside the world, whose essential nature is air or something of the kind. But if there cannot be
cists
way
in this
a sensible
body which
is
infinite in
[25] the full sense, evidently there can no more be a body which is potentially infinite in respect of addition, except as the inverse of the infinite
by division, as
we have said. made the
this reason that Plato also
It is
for
infinites
supposed to be possible to exceed all limits and to proceed ad infinitum in the direction both of increase and of reduction. Yet though he makes the infinites two, he does not use them. For in the
two
in
number, because
it
is
[50] numbers the infinite in the direction of reduction is not present, as the monad is the smallest; nor is the infinite in the direction of increase, for the parts number only up to the
out to be the contrary of what it is said to be. It is not what has nothing 207 a outside it that is infinite, but what always has something outside it. This is indicated by infinite turns
the fact that rings also that have
described as 'endless', because sible to take a part
part.
The
ilarity,
which
is
it is
description depends
but
it is
not true in the
on a
certain sim-
full sense of the
is
taken should never be the same. In is not satisfied:
only the adjacent part from which the is
Our
—
[10] ing is wanting, as a whole man or a whole box. What is true of each particular is
—
whole as such the whole is that of which nothing is outside. On the other hand that from which something is absent and outside, however small that may be, is not 'all'. 'Whole' and 'complete' are either quite identical or closely akin. Nothing is complete (reXetov) which has no end (reXos ) and the end is a limit. [75] Hence Parmenides must be thought to true of the
;
have spoken better than Melissus. The latter says that the whole is infinite, but the former describes it as limited, 'equally balanced from 1 the middle'. For to connect the infinite with not like joining two this they get the dignity they ascribe to the infinite its contain[20] ing all things and holding the all in itthe
all
and the whole
pieces of string; for
self
—from
whole. ness
It is
its
is
it is
from
—
having a certain similarity
to the
in fact the matter of the complete-
which belongs to size, and what whole, though not in the full
tially a
is
poten-
sense. It
divisible both in the direction of reduction
is
and of the inverse addition.
It is
a
limited; not, however, in virtue of ture, but in virtue of
what
is
whole and its
own
other than
na-
it.
It
does not contain, but, in so far as it is infinite, [25] is contained. Consequently, also, it is unknowable, qua infinite; for the matter has no form. (Hence it is plain that the infinite stands in the relation of part rather
than of whole.
For the matter is part of the whole, as the bronze is of the bronze statue.) If it contains in
new
different.
definition then
is
and the small ought to it is absurd and imposunknowable and indeterminate should contain and determine.
ligible things the great
[50] contain them. But sible to suppose that the
always pos-
outside a given
the circle, the latter condition part
ready ta\en. On the other hand, what has nothing outside it is complete and whole. For thus we define the whole that from which noth-
no bezel are
it is
[5] word. This condition alone is not sufficient: it is necessary also that the next part
which
285
the case of sensible things, in the case of intel-
decad.
The
5-7
as follows:
A quantity is infinite if it is such that we can always ta\e a part outside what has been al-
reasonable that there should not be held an infinite in respect of addition such as to surpass every magnitude, but that there It is
to be
should be thought to be such an infinite in the For the matter and the [35] infinite are contained inside what contains them, while it is the form which con207 b tains. It is natural too to suppose that in direction of division.
number there is a limit in the direction of the minimum, and that in the other direction every assigned number is surpassed. In magnitude, 1
Fr. 8. 44.
PHYSICS
286
on the contrary, every assigned magnitude
is
surpassed in the direction of smallness, while [5] in the other direction there is no infinite magnitude. The reason is that what is one is indivisible
one man, not
hand
may be, e.g. a man is many. Number on the other
whatever
it
and a certain quantity of them. Hence number must stop at the indivisible: for 'two' and 'three' are merely derivative terms, and so with each of the other [10] numbers. But in the direction of largeness
is
it
a plurality of 'ones'
is
number:
from the process of bisection, and its infinnot a permanent actuality but consists a process of coming to be, like time and the
ity is
number of time. [75] With magnitudes is
but there
continuous is
no
is
holds.
divided ad infinitum,
infinite in the direction of in-
For the size which it can potentially be, can also actually be. Hence since no sensible magnitude is infinite, it is impossible to exceed every assigned magnitude; for if it were possi[20] ble there would be something bigger than crease.
the heavens.
not the same in magnitude in the sense of a single nature, but its secondary sense depends on infinite
is
and movement and time, its
infinite instead,
while
its
existence will be in the sphere of real magnitudes.
[55] In the fourfold plain that the infinite
scheme of is
causes,
it
is
a cause in the sense of
matter, and that its essence is privation, the 208 a subject as such being what is continuous and sensible. All the other thinkers, too, evi-
—
dently treat the infinite as matter that is why it is inconsistent in them to make it what contains, and not what is contained.
primary sense,
i.e.
movement
is
called infi-
magnitude covered by the movement (or alteration or growth), and time because of the movement. (I use these terms [25] for the moment. Later I shall explain what each of them means, and also why every magnitude is divisible into magnitudes.) nite in virtue of the
Our account
remains to dispose of the arguments to support the view that the infinite exists not only potentially but as a separate thing. Some have no cogency; others can be met by fresh objections that are valid. (1) In order that coming to be should not fail, it is not necessary that there should be a [5]
It
which are supposed
sensible
the contrary
it
The
have such an
always possible to think of a larger number of times a magnitude
ble
What
to
for the
can be bisected is infinite. Hence this infinite is potential, never actual: the number of parts that can be taken always surpasses any assigned number. But this number is not separa-
in
208*
them
does not rob the mathemati-
passing
body which is actually infinite. The of one thing may be the coming
away
[10] to be of another, the All being limited. (2) There is a difference between touching
and being limited. The former is relative to something and is the touching of something (for everything that touches touches some-
and further is an attribute of some one which are limited. On the other hand, what is limited is not limited in relation thing),
of the things
Again, contact is not necessarily between any two things taken at ran-
to anything.
possible
dom. [75] (3)
is.
existence of the infinite in the direction of in-
finite,
crease, in the sense of the untraversable. In point of fact they do not need the infinite and [50] do not use it. They postulate only that the
part that
be produced as far as they wish. It is possible to have divided in the same ratio as the largest quantity another magnitude of any size you like. Hence, for the purposes of proof, it will make no difference to
on mere thinking
is absurd, not in the thing might think that one is
The thought is an accident. Time indeed and movement
[20] (a)
may
rely
but in the thought. One of us is bigger than he is and magnify him ad infinitum. But it does not follow that he is bigger than the size we are, just because some one thinks he is, but only because he is the size he
cians of their science, by disproving the actual
finite straight line
To
for then the excess or defect
and
are in-
also thinking, in the sense that each is
taken passes in succession out of
existence.
(b) Magnitude is not infinite either in the of reduction or of magnification in thought. This concludes my account of the way in which the infinite exists, and of the way in which it does not exist, and of what it is.
way
BOOK
209 a
III,
CHAPTERS 7-8— BOOK
BOOK
IV,
CHAPTER
287
1
IV
have no
real place, they nevertheless, in respect
of their position relatively to us, have a right
The
must have
physicist
a
knowledge
Place, too, as well as of the infinite
whether there
manner
of
its
[30] because
is
such a thing or not,
existence
all
of
—namely, and the —both
and what
it
is
suppose that things which ex-
ist are somewhere (the non-existent is nowhere where is the goat-stag or the sphinx? ), and because 'motion' in its most general and primary sense is change of place, which we call
—
'locomotion'.
The
question,
difficulties.
An
what
is
place? presents many all the relevant
examination of
seems to lead to divergent conclusions. Moreover, we have inherited nothing from previous thinkers, whether in the way of
and
water has gone out as from a vessel, air is present. When therefore another body occupies [ 5] this same place, the place is thought to be dif-
account of it when he made chaos first, At least he says: First of all things came chaos to being, then broad-breasted earth ^
[jo]
implying that things need to have space first, because he thought, with most people, that everything its
can
else
others,
exist,
is
mar-
a
while
it
can exist without the for place does not
first;
pass out of existence
when
the things in
are annihilated.
True, but even if we suppose its existence question of its nature presents dif-
settled, the
they passed was something different from both. Further, the typical locomotions of the elementary natural bodies namely, fire, earth, and the like show not only that place is some-
ficulty
[10] thing, but also that it exerts a certain influence. Each is carried to its own place, if it is
must be
and take precedence of all other which nothing
must needs be
the place or space into
—
in place. If this
[35] things. For that without
it
—
somewhere and
vellous thing,
209 a
formerly contained water, so that clearly which and out of which
is
nature, the potency of place
it
air
in
rect
ferent
from all the bodies which come to be in and replace one another. What now contains
them only
and that every sensible body is in place. Hesiod too might be held to have given a cor-
[35]
vious from the fact of mutual replacement. Where water now is, there in turn, when the
ascribed to
bodies,
facts
a statement of difficulties or of a solution. 208 b The existence of place is held to be ob-
left as attributes
consequence of their relative position, not having by nature these various characteristics. [25] Again, the theory that the void exists involves the existence of place: for one would define void as place bereft of body. These considerations then would lead us to suppose that place is something distinct from
—
whether it is some sort of 'bulk' of body or some entity other than that, for we must first determine its genus.
Now
it has three dimensions, length, [5] (1) breadth, depth, the dimensions by which all
body
also
is
bounded. But the place cannot be were there would be two bodies
not hindered, the one up, the other down. Now these are regions or kinds of place up and
body; for
the rest of the six directions. Nor do such distinctions (up and down and right and
(2) Further, if body has a place and space, clearly so too have surface and the other limits of body; for the same statement will apply
—
down and
[75] left, &c.) hold only in relation to us. To us they are not always the same but change with the direction in which we are turned: that is why the same thing may be both right and left, up and down, before and behind. But in nature each is distinct, taken apart by itself. It is not every chance direction which is 'up', but where fire and what is light are carried; [20] similarly, too, 'down' is not any chance direction but where what has weight and what is
made
of earth are carried
—the implication
being that these places do not differ merely in relative position, but also as possessing distinct
potencies. This jects
is
made
plain also by the ob-
studied by mathematics.
Though
they
in the
to
if it
same
place.
them: where the bounding planes of the
[10] water were, there in turn will be those of the air. But when we come to a point we can-
not
make
Hence
if
from the
a distinction between
it
and
the place of a point
is
not different
point,
its
place.
no more will that of any of the and place will not be somefrom each of them. the world then are we to sup-
others be different,
thing different
(3) What in pose place to be ? If it has the sort of nature described, it cannot be an element or composed [75] of elements, whether these be corporeal or incorporeal: for while it has size, it has not 1 Theogony, n6f.
PHYSICS
2 88
body. But the elements of sensible bodies are bodies, while nothing that has size results from a combination of intelligible elements. (4) Also we may ask: of what in things is space the cause? None of the four modes of causation can be ascribed to it. It is neither [20] cause in the sense of the matter of existents (for nothing is composed of it), nor as the form and definition of things, nor as end, nor
does
it
move
existents.
(5) Further, too, if it is itself an existent, where will it be? Zeno's difficulty demands an explanation: for if everything that exists has a [25] place, place too will have a place, on ad infinitum.
(6) Again, just as every body too, every place has a body in
is it.
and
so
their place
is
and space are
pant'
identical. (It
is different from what he says in [75] his so-called 'unwritten teaching'. Nevertheless, he did identify place and space.) I men-
tion Plato because, while
all hold place to be something, he alone tried to say what it is. In view of these facts we should naturally
expect to find difficulty in determining what is, if indeed it is one of these two things, [20] matter or form. They demand a very
place
close scrutiny, especially as
it
it
any
at
is
—
not easy to
rate not difficult to see that
The form and from the thing,
the matter are not separate
neither less
is
recognize them apart.
What
nor greater than they are. By asking these questions, then, we must not only raise the whole problem about place [30] as to what it is, but even whether there is such a thing.
'partici-
true, in-
'participant'
But then
is
deed, that the account he gives there of the
place cannot be either of them.
we say about growing things? It follows from these premisses that their place must if
matter and space are the same; for the
in place, so,
shall
grow with them,
210 a
whereas the place can be separated. As we pointed out, 2 where air was, water in turn comes to be, the one replacing the other; and [25] similarly with other bodies. Hence the place of a thing is neither a part nor a state of it, but is separable from it. For place is supposed to be something like a vessel the vessel being a transportable place. But the vessel is no part of the thing.
—
it is separable from the not the form: qua containing, it different from the matter. Also it is held that what is anywhere is both
[jo] In so far then as
We
may icating B
distinguish generally between pred-
A because it (A) is itself, and besomething else; and particularly between place which is common and in which cause
of
primarily by each. I mean, for instance, that you are now in the heavens because you are in the air and it is in the heavens; and you are in the air because you are on the earth; and simile] larly on the earth because you are in this place which contains no more than you. 209 b Now if place is what primarily contains each body, it would be a limit, so that the place would be the form or shape of each body by which the magnitude or the matter of the magnitude is defined: for this is the limit of each
body.
we
look at the question in this is its form. But, if we regard the place as the extension of the magni[5]
way
If,
then,
the place of a thing
tude,
is
it is
bodies are, and the special place occupied
all
thing,
it is
the matter. For this
the magnitude:
it is
what
is
is
different
from
contained and de-
itself
it
is
something and that there
thing outside
ought to
gress,
[55]
numbers
ticipates' is
it.
is
(Plato of course, tell
us
why
—whether
a different
if
we may
di-
form and the
the
are not in place,
place
is
if
what
'what parparticipates
the Great and the Small or the matter, as he
210a
called
it
in writing in the
Timaeus.) 3
how
could a body be carried to its was the matter or the form? It is impossible that what has no reference to motion or the distinction of up and down can be place. So place must be looked for among things which have these characteristics. [5] If the place is in the thing (it must be if it is either shape or matter) place will have a place: for both the form and the indeterminate undergo change and motion along with the thing, and are not always in the same place, but are where the thing is. Hence the place will Further,
own place,
if
place
fined by the form, as by a bounding plane. Matter or the indeterminate is of this nature;
have a place.
when
[10] the place has been destroyed, for the resulting body is not in the same place. What
the boundary
and
attributes of a sphere
[10] are taken away, nothing but the matter
is
l
5*
when water
is
sort of destruction then
left.
This
Further,
is
why
Plato in the
Timaeus
1
This concludes
says that 2
2o8 b
2.
52.
my
is
produced from
air,
that?
statement of the rea-
BOOK
210 b sons
why
space
IV,
CHAPTERS
must be something, and again
of the difficulties that
may
be raised about
its
essential nature.
it
1-4
289
resides in the visible surface.
We
cannot go
[5] further and say that it is in surface in virtue of something other than itself. (Yet it is not in itself: though these are in a way the differ in essence, each having a special nature and capacity, 'surface' and
same thing,) they
The next step we must many senses one thing
take is
to see in
is
said to be
how an-
'in'
'white'.
Thus
other. (1)
[75]
As
the finger
is 'in'
the
hand and gen-
erally the part 'in' the whole.
is
(2) As the whole is 'in' the parts: for there no whole over and above the parts. (3) As man is 'in' animal and generally spe-
genus.
cies 'in'
(4)
As
the genus
is 'in'
the species and gen-
erally the part of the specific
form
the
'in'
if
we look
at the
matter inductively
we
any of the senses that have been distinguished; and it can be seen by argument that it is impossible. [10] For each of two things will have to be both, e.g. the jar will have to be both vessel and wine, and the wine both wine and jar, if
do not find anything
it is
to be 'in' itself in
possible for a thing to be in itself; so that,
however true
it
might be
were in each wine in virtue
that they
definition of the specific form.
other, the jar will receive the
[20] (5) As health is 'in' the hot and the cold and generally the form 'in' the matter. (6) As the affairs of Greece centre 'in' the king, and generally events centre 'in' their
[75] not of its being wine but of the wine's being wine, and the wine will be in the jar in virtue not of its being a jar but of the jar's being a jar. Now that they are different in re-
primary motive agent.
spect of their essence
(7) its
As
the existence of a thing centres
good and generally
for the sake of which'
'in' its it
end,
i.e.
'in'
in 'that
exists.
(8) In the strictest sense of all, as a thing is 'in' a vessel, and generally 'in' place. [25] One might raise the question whether a
thing can be in itself, or whether nothing can be in itself everything being either wowhere
—
or in something else.
ambiguous; we may mean or qua something else. When there are parts of a whole the one that in which a thing is, the other the thing which is in it the whole will be described as being in itself. For a thing is described in
The
question
the thing
qua
is
itself
—
—
terms of its parts, as well as in terms of the thing as a whole, e.g. a man is said to be white because tr^e visible surface of him is white, or to be scientific because his thinking faculty [30] has been trained. The jar then will not be in itself and the wine will not be in itself.
But the
jar of
wine
will: for the contents
the container are both parts of the
and
same whole.
In this sense then, but not primarily, a thing
can be in
itself,
namely, as 'white' is in body is in body), and science
is
evident; for 'that in
which something is' and 'that which would be differently defined.
—
primarily.
Zeno's problem
—that
if
because
it is
in body,
or as the hot
body
is 'in'
as
in
is
in
body because
an
affection.
So we
escape the infinite regress. is no (what contains in the different from what is con-
Another thing what is
part of strict
sense
is
is
plain: since the vessel
in
it
tained), place could not be either the matter
or the form of the thing contained, but
—
must
[30] be different for the latter, both the matter and the shape, are parts of what is con-
This then
and
something
—
of the difficulties involved.
man
is
[25] deed in that as 'in' place, but as health is 'in' the hot as a positive determination of it
tained.
parts, a thing will be in itself, as 'white'
Place
—
must be in something is not difficult to solve. There is nothing to prevent the first place from being 'in' something else not init
in the mind. 210b It is from these,
which are 'parts' (in the sense at least of being 'in' the man), that the man is called white, &c. But the jar and the wine in separation are not parts of a whole, though together they are. So when there are
it'
Nor is it possible for a thing to be in itself even incidentally: for two things would be at [20] the same time in the same thing. The if a thing whose nature jar would be in itself it is to receive can be in itself; and that which it receives, namely (if wine) wine, will be in it. Obviously then a thing cannot be in itself
(for the visible surface is
in
is
What
may
then after
serve as a critical statement
all
may
is
place?
The answer
to
be elucidated as follows. Let us take for granted about it the various characteristics which are supposed correctly to this question
PHYSICS
290 belong to ( i )
essentially.
it
Place
is
We assume
what contains
that of
then
which
it is
the place.
21 l a (2) Place is no part of the thing. (3) The immediate place of a thing is neither less nor greater than the thing. (4) Place can be left behind by the thing
and
is
separable. In addition:
[5] carried to its appropriate place and rests there, and this makes the place either up or
these
we must try to make
foundations,
[10] the cause of the trouble and of the diffiabout it. Such is the most satisfactory
culties
kind of exposition. First then we must understand that place would not have been thought of, if there had not been a special kind of motion, namely
that with respect to place.
It is chiefly
for this
reason that we suppose the heaven also to be in place, because it is in constant movement. Of this kind of change there are two species locomotion on the one hand and, on the other, [75] increase and diminution. For these too involve variation of place: what was then in this place has
now
in turn
changed
to
what
is
larger or smaller.
when we
say a thing
is
'moved', the
predicate either (1) belongs to it actually, in virtue of its own nature, or (2) in virtue of something conjoined with it. In the latter case
be either (a) something which by its own [20] nature is capable of being moved, e.g. the parts of the body or the nail in the ship, or (b) something which is not in itself capable of being moved, but is always moved through its conjunction with something else, as 'whiteness' or 'science'. These have changed their place only because the subjects to which they belong
it
may
do
so.
We
say that a thing
is
in the world, in the
[25] sense of in place, because it is in the air, and the air is in the world; and when we say
we do not mean it is in every but that it is in the air because of the outer surface of the air which surrounds it is
in the air,
part of the
it;
for
if all
a thing
not in the sense of in place, but as a part in a whole. But when the thing is separate and in it is
air,
the air were
its
place, the place of
would not be equal
to the thing
immediately
'in'
of the surrounding body,
neither a part of
than
its
what
is
the inner surface
and in
it
this surface
is
nor yet greater
extension, but equal to
it;
for the ex-
which touch are coincident. one body is in continuity with an-
tremities of things
Further, laid
complete the theory. We ought to our investigation such as will render an account of place, and will not only solve the difficulties connected with it, but will also show that the attributes supposed to belong to it do really belong to it, and further will make clear
Again,
which it is supposed to be, and which the primary place in which a thing is actually is. When what surrounds, then, is not separate [30] from the thing, but is in continuity with it, the thing is said to be in what surrounds it,
contact,
(5) All place admits of the distinction of up and down, and each of the bodies is naturally
down. Having
211 b
if
[35] other, it is not moved in that but with that. On the other hand it is moved in that if it is
separate.
what contains 21 l b
It
makes no
difference whether
moved or not. Again, when it is not separate is
it is described as a part in a whole, as the pupil in the eye or the hand in the body: when it is sep-
water in the cask or the wine in hand is moved with the body and the water in the cask. [5] It will now be plain from these consideraarate, as the
the jar. For the
what place is. There are just four things which place must be one the shape, or the matter, or some sort of extension between the bounding surfaces of the containing body, or this boundary itself if it contains no extension over and above the bulk of the body which comes to be in it. Three of these it obviously cannot be: tions
—
of
[10] (1) The shape is supposed to be place because it surrounds, for the extremities of what contains and of what is contained are coincident. Both the shape and the place, it is true, are boundaries. But not of the same
thing: the the place
contains
form
is
is
the boundary of the thing,
the boundary of the body
which
it.
(2) The extension between the extremities is thought to be something, because what is contained and separate may often be changed [75] while the container remains the same (as water may be poured from a vessel) the assumption being that the extension is something over and above the body displaced. But there is no such extension. One of the bodies which change places and are naturally capable of being in contact with the container falls in whichever it may chance to be. If there were an extension which were such [20] as to exist independently and be permanent, there would be an infinity of places in the same thing. For when the water and the air change places, all the portions of the two
—
BOOK
212 b
IV,
CHAPTERS
together will play the same part in the whole which was previously played by all the water in the vessel; at the same time the place too will be undergoing change; so that there will be another place which is the place of the [25] place, and many places will be coincident. There is not a different place of the part, in which it is moved, when the whole vessel
changes
place:
its
it is
always the same: for
it
(proximate) place where they are that the air and the water (or the parts of the water) succeed each other, not in that place in is
in the
4-5
291
what contains plays the part of a
river,
vessel
rather than that of place. Place on the other
hand
rather
is
what
is
motionless:
rather the whole river that a
whole
it is
is
so
it
is
place, because as
motionless.
Hence we conclude that the innermost motionless boundary of what contains is place. [20]
This explains
why
the middle of the heaven
and the surface which
faces us of the rotating system are held to be 'up' and 'down' in the
strict
and
always
fullest sense for all
men:
for the
one
while the inner side of the rotating body remains always coincident with is
at rest,
which they come to be, which is part of the which is the place of the whole world. [3°] (3) The matter, too, might seem to be place, at least if we consider it in what is at rest and is thus separate but in continuity. For just as in change of quality there is something which was formerly black and is now white, or formerly soft and now hard this is just
contains in the direction of the outermost part of the universe, and the outermost part itself,
why we
are up.
place
—
because
say that the matter exists
presents a similar
it
[55] thought to say so because
exist
—only
—so
place,
phenomenon,
in the
one case
we
what was air is now water, in where air formerly was there
now
is
before,
1
is
contains
water. But the matter, as
we
said
neither separable from the thing nor
it,
what what
is is
down, the boundary which contains in the direction of the middle of the universe, and the middle itself, are down, and that which carried
For
is
the other because
212*
[25] itself. Hence since the light is naturally carried up, and the heavy
is thought to be a were a vessel, i.e. a
this reason, too, place
kind of surface, and as
it
container of the thing. [50] Further, place is coincident with the thing, for boundaries are coincident with the
bounded.
whereas place has both character-
istics. if place is none of the three form nor the matter nor an extension which is always there, different from, and over and above, the extension of the thing place necessarily is the [5] which is displaced one of the four which is left, namely, the boundary of the containing body at which it is in contact with the contained body. (By the contained body is meant what can be moved
Well, then,
neither the
—
by
way
of locomotion.)
is thought to be something important and hard to grasp, both because the matter and the shape present themselves along with it, and because the displacement of the body
Place
that
is
moved
takes place in a stationary con-
[10] tainer, for
it
seems possible that there is other than the
should be an interval which bodies which are moved.
The
air, too,
which
is
to be incorporeal, contributes something to the belief: it is not only the boundaries of the vessel which seem to be place, but also what is between them, regarded as empty. Just, in fact, as the vessel is transportable [75] place, so place is a non-portable vessel. So when what is within a thing which is moved, is moved and changes its place, as a boat on a
thought
1
209 b 22-32.
If then a body has another body outside it and containing it, it is in place, and if not, not. That is why, even if there were to be water which had not a container, the parts of it, on the one hand, will be moved (for one part is contained in another), while, on the other hand, the whole will be moved in one sense, [55] but not in another. For as a whole it does not simultaneously change its place, though it 21 b will be moved in a circle: for this place is the place of its parts. (Some things are moved, not up and down, but in a circle; others up and down, such things namely as admit of condensation and rarefaction.) As was explained, 2 some things are potentially in place,
others actually. So,
when you
have a homogeneous substance which
is
con-
[5] tinuous, the parts are potentially in place: when the parts are separated, but in contact, like a heap, they are actually in place.
Again, (1) some things are per se namely every body which is movable
in place,
either by
of locomotion or by way of increase is per somewhere, but the heaven, as has been 3 said, is not anywhere as a whole, nor in any [10] place, if at least, as we must suppose, no
way se
7-b5-
%
3*
PHYSICS
292
body contains it. On the line on which it is moved, its parts have place: for each is contiguous to the next. But (2) other things are in place indirectly, through something conjoined with them, as the soul and the heaven. in place, for all
its
The
latter
parts are: for
in a way, on the orb
is,
one part contains another. That is why the upper part is moved in a circle, while the All [75] is not anywhere. For what is somewhere is itself something, and there must be alongside it some other thing wherein it is and which contains it. But alongside the All or the Whole there is nothing outside the All, and for this reason all things are in the heaven; for the heaven, we may say, is the All. Yet their not the same as the heaven. It is part the innermost part of it, which is in
place of
is
it,
[20] contact with the movable body; and for this reason the earth is in water, and this in
and the aether in heaven, but we cannot go on and say that the heaven is in anything else. It is clear, too, from these considerations that all the problems which were raised about place will be solved when it is explained in this way: (1) There is no necessity that the place should grow with the body in it, the
air,
and the
air in the aether,
[25]
Nor that a point should have a place, (3) Nor that two bodies should be in the
same
place,
(2)
These [5]
distinctions will be
fully later.
was necessary
1
On
the
to refer to
drawn more
care-
present occasion
them: what has
it
now
been stated obscurely will then be made more clear. If the matter and the fulfilment are the same thing (for water is both, the one potentially, the other completely), water will be related to air in a way as part to whole. That is why these have contact: it is organic union when both become actually one. [10] This concludes my account of place both of its existence and of its nature.
The
investigation of similar questions about
must be held whether exists or what it
the void, also,
to belong to the
physicist
it
—namely
and how place.
it
The views taken of it
is
exists
or not,
—
just as
about
involve arguments
both for and against, in much the same sort [75] of way. For those who hold that the void exists regard it as a sort of place or vessel which is supposed to be 'full' when it holds the bulk which it is capable of containing, 'void' when it is deprived of that as if 'void' and 'full' and 'place' denoted the same thing,
—
though the essence of the three is different. [20] We must begin the inquiry by putting
down
the account given by those
who
say that
then the account of those who say does not exist, and third the current
exists,
it
that
Nor
213 b
it
is between the boundaries of any body which may chance to be there, not an interval in body. Further, (5) place is also somewhere, not in
view on these questions. Those who try to show that the void does not exist do not disprove what people really mean by it, but only their erroneous way of speaking; this is true of Anaxagoras and of those
the sense of being in a place, but as the limit
who
(4)
that place should be a corporeal in-
what
terval: for
the place
is
is
place, but only
Also (6)
it
way. They merely give an ingenious demonstration that air is something by
reasonable that each kind of
and showing the resistance of the air, and by cutting it off in clepsydras. But people really mean that there is an empty interval in which there is no sensible body. They hold that everything which is is [jo] body and say that what has nothing in it at all is void (so what is full of air is void).
is is
movable body. is
[jo] body should be carried to its own place. For a body which is next in the series and in contact (not by compulsion) is akin, and bodies which are united do not affect each other, while those which are in contact interact on each other. Nor (7) is it without reason that each should remain naturally in its proper place. For this part has the
same
relation to
its
place, as a
I35] separable part to its whole, as when one 21 3 a moves a part of water or air: so, too, air is related to water, for the one is like matter, the other form water is the matter of air, air as it were the actuality of water, for water is potentially air, while air is potentially water, though in another way.
—
refute the existence of the void in this
in
in the limited; for not everything that
[25]
—
straining wine-skins
It is
not then the existence of air that needs
to be proved, but the non-existence of
an
inter-
val, different
from the
bodies, either separable
or actual
interval
which divides the whole
body
—an
so as to break
its
continuity, as
Democ-
ritus and Leucippus hold, and many 21 3 b physicists or even perhaps as
—
other
some-
thing which is outside the whole body, which remains continuous. 1
On
Generation and Corruption,
1.
3.
BOOK
214 a
IV,
CHAPTERS
These people, then, have not reached even the threshold of the problem, but rather those who say that the void exists.
They
( 1 )
argue, for one thing, that change
(i.e. locomotion and increase) would not be. For it is maintained that motion would seem not to exist, if there were no void, since what is full cannot contain anything more. If it could, and there were two bodies in the same place, it would also be true that any
place
in
[5]
number
of bodies could be together; for
it
is
impossible to draw a line of division beyond which the statement would become untrue. If this were possible, it would follow also that
thus also
body would contain the
the smallest
[10]
greatest; for
'many
a
little
makes
many equal bodies can be can many unequal bodies. if
a mickle':
together, so
from these considimmovable; for if it
Melissus, indeed, infers erations that the All
is
were moved there must, he void
is
not
among
This argument, then, they
says, be void,
but
the things that exist. is
one way in which
show that there is a void. 2 They reason from the ( )
skins into which the wine has been decanted, which implies that the compressed body contracts into the voids present in
Again (3)
increase, too,
[20] place always by
means
is
thought to take
of void, for nutri-
in place, void
is
place in
weight or lightness. Hence, by a syllogism, what has nothing heavy or light in it, is void. This result, then, as I have said, is reached [5] by syllogism. It would be absurd to suppose that the point is void; for the void must be place which has in it an interval in tangible body. But at all events we observe then that in one way the void is described as what is not full of body perceptible to touch; and what has heaviness and lightness is perceptible to touch. So we would raise the question: what would they is say of an interval that has colour or sound [10] it void or not? Clearly they would reply that if it could receive what is tangible it was
—
and
void,
if
not, not.
way
which there some say that the void is the matter of the body (they identify the place, too, with this), and in this In another
no
'this'
void
is
that in
or corporeal substance. So
they speak incorrectly; for the matter [75] separable
from the
is
not
things, but they are
inquiring about the void as about something separable.
we have determined
Since
it.
293 is
which there is no body, so that where there is no body, there must be void. 214 a Every body, again, they suppose to be tangible; and of this nature is whatever has
is
fact that some 1 I 5] things are observed to contract and be compressed, as people say that a cask will hold the wine which formerly filled it, along with the
5-7
while every body
the nature of
and void must, if it exists, be place deprived of body, and we have stated both in what sense place exists and in what sense it does not, it is plain that on this showing void
place,
body, and it is impossible for two bodies to be together. A proof of this they find also in what happens to ashes, which absorb as
does not
much water as the empty vessel. The Pythagoreans, too, (4) held
[20] for the void is meant to be, not body but rather an interval in body. This is why the
ment
is
that void
and that it enters the heaven itself, which as it were inhales it, from the infinite air. Further it is the void which distinguishes the na[25] tures of things, as if it were like what separates and distinguishes the terms of a series. This holds primarily in the numbers, for
exists
the void distinguishes their nature.
These, then, and so many, are the main grounds on which people have argued for and against the existence of the void.
[jo]
As
true,
we must
which view is determine the meaning of the
a step towards settling
name.
The
void
is
thought to be place with noth-
ing in it. The reason for this is that people take what exists to be body, and hold that
unseparated or separated;
thought to be something,
viz.
because
and for the same reasons. For the fact of motion in respect of place comes to the aid place
is,
both of those who maintain that place is something over and above the bodies that come to occupy it, and of those who maintain that the void is something. They state that the void is the condition of movement in the
which movement takes place; would be the kind of thing that
sense of that in
[25]
and
this
some say place is. But there is no necessity for there being a void if there is movement. It is not in the least needed for
void
is
exist, either
a
as a condition of
reason
which,
movement
in general,
incidentally,
escaped
Melissus; viz. that the full can suffer qualitative change.
But not even movement in respect of place
PHYSICS
294 involves a void; for bodies
make room [jo]
for
may
simultaneously
one another, though there
no
is
and apart from the movement. And this is plain
separate
interval
bodies that are in
even in the rotaion of continuous things, as in that of liquids.
And
things can also be compressed not into
a void but because they squeeze out
contained in them ter
compressed the
is
214 b
air
within
what
is
when wa-
(as, for instance, it is
squeezed
out); and things can increase in size not
215'
body
placed as a whole in a place conceived
is
of as separate
and permanent;
what rather turns out
to be the case,
any and every part of the body
is
bodies may be increased otherwise than by the addition of body, or there may be two bodies in the same place (in which case they are claiming to solve a quite general difficulty, but are not proving the existence of void), or the
whole body must be void, every part and
is
if it is
increased by
The same argument
increased in
means
of void.
applies to the ashes.
one
if
[30] studies the matter, is the opposite, that not a single thing can be moved if there is a void; for as with those who for a like reason
admits no difference. 215 a The second reason
increased, or
it,
it
only by the entrance of something but also by qualitative change; e.g. if water were to be transformed into air. In general, both the argument about increase of size and that about water poured on to the [5] ashes get in their own way. For either not is
for a part of
be placed apart, will not be in a place but in the whole. Further, if separate place does not exist, neither will void. If people say that the void must exist, as being necessary if there is to be movement, unless
say the earth is at rest, so, too, in the void things must be at rest; for there is no place to which things can move more or less than to another; since the void in so far as it is void
this: all
is
movement
either compulsory or according to nature,
and if there is compulsory movement there must also be natural (for compulsory movement is contrary to nature, and movement contrary to nature is posterior to that according to nature, so that if each of the natural bodies has not a natural movement, none of the [5] other movements can exist); but how can there be natural movement if there is no dif-
[10] It is evident, then, that it is easy to refute the arguments by which they prove the ex-
ference throughout the void or the infinite?
istence of the void.
or
For
in so far as
down
void,
up
is
no void
some maintain.
ex-
each of the simple bodies has a natural locomotion, isting separately, as
upward and
e.g. fire
earth
If
downward and
[75] towards the middle of the universe, it is clear that it cannot be the void that is the condition of locomotion.
be the condition of? dition of
What,
It is
movement
then, will the void
thought to be the con-
in respect of place,
and
it
not the condition of this. Again, if void is a sort of place deprived of body, when there is a void where will a body placed in it move to ? It certainly cannot move into the whole of the void. The same argu[20] ment applies as against those who think is
that place
things
is
something separate, into which
are carried;
placed in
it
move, or
viz.
rest?
how will what is Much the same ar-
gument will apply to the void as to the 'up' and 'down' in place, as is natural enough since those
void
make
And
in
who it
maintain the existence of the
a place.
what way
will things be present
[25] either in place or in the void? expected result does not take place
For the
when
a
infinite, there will
and
be no up
in so far as
it
is
a
no whit from down; for as no difference in what is nothing,
differs
[jo] there
Let us explain again that there
it is
or middle,
is
none
in the void (for the void seems to be a non-existent and a privation of being), but natural locomotion seems to be differenti-
there
is
ated, so that the things that exist by nature
must be
differentiated. Either, then, nothing
has a natural locomotion, or
else there is
no
void.
Further, in point of fact things that are
thrown move though that which gave them their impulse
is
not touching them, either by
[75] reason of mutual replacement, as some maintain, or because the air that has been
pushed pushes them with a movement quicker than the natural locomotion of the projectile
wherewith it moves to its proper place. But in a void none of these things can take place, nor can anything be moved save as that which is carried is moved. Further, no one could say why a thing once [20] set in motion should stop anywhere; for why should it stop here rather than here? So that a thing will either be at rest or must be moved ad infinitum, unless something more powerful get in
its
way.
Further, things are
now
thought to move
216
BOOK
s
IV,
CHAPTERS
but in a void this quality is present equally everywhere, so that things should move in all directions. Further, the truth of what we assert is plain [25] from the following considerations. We see the same weight or body moving faster than another for two reasons, either because there is a difference in what it moves through, into the void because
it
yields;
7-8
29:
Z which
stance
exceeds air in thickness in the
which the time E bears to the time Z be as much thinner than exceeds H, A, if it moves through Z,
[50] ratio
H. For
A
E
as
the body
if
will traverse
216 a
it
time inverse to the speed of
in a
other things being equal, the moving body differs from the other owing to excess of weight
movement, i.e. in a time equal to H. If, then, there is no body in Z, A will traverse Z still more quickly. But we supposed that its traverse of Z when Z was void occupied the time H. So that it will traverse Z in an equal time whether Z be full or void. But this is im-
or of lightness.
possible. It
as
between water,
Now cause
it
medium
the
and
earth, or because,
causes a difference be-
impedes the moving thing, most of
moving
if it is
air,
all
in the opposite direction, but in
[50] a secondary degree even if it is at rest; especially a medium that is not easily di-
and
vided, i.e. a medium that is somewhat dense. 215 b A, then, will move through B in time I\ and through A, which is thinner, in time E (if the length of B is equal to A), in proportion to the density of the hindering body. For let B be water and A air; then by so much as [5] air is thinner and more incorporeal than water, A will move through A faster than through B. Let the speed have the same ratio to the speed, then, that air has to water.
Then
twice as thin, the body will traverse B in twice the time that it does A, and the time T will be twice the time E. And always, by so if air is
medium is more incorporeal and more easily divided, the faster will be the movement. Now there is no ratio in which the void is exceeded by body, as there is no ratio of to a number. For if 4 exceeds 3 by 1, and 2 by more than 1, and 1 by still more than it exceeds 2, [75] still there is no ratio by which it exceeds o; for that which exceeds must be divisible into the excess + that which is exceeded, so that 4 will be what it exceeds o by + 0. For this
much
[10]
and
as the
less resistant
reason, too, a line does not exceed a point
unless
it is
composed
to
of points! Similarly the
movement through
the other, but
if
a
thing moves through the thickest medium such and such a distance in such and such a time, it moves through the void with a speed beyond any ratio. For let Z be void, equal in magnitude to B and to A. Then if is to traverse
A
and move through
it
in a certain time,
H,
a
[25] time less than E, however, the void will bear this ratio to the full. But in a time equal to
H,
A will
traverse the part
of A.
will surely also traverse in that time
And
which
it
any sub-
is
it
plain, then, that
will
if
there
move through any
is
a time
part of the
void, this impossible result will follow:
it
will
be found to traverse a certain distance, whether this be full or void, in an equal time; for there will be some body which is in the [5]
same
ratio to the other
body
as the
time
is
to
the time.
To sum sult
the matter up, the cause of this reobvious, viz. that between any two
is
movements
there
is
a ratio (for they occupy
[10] time, and there is a ratio between any two times, so long as both are finite), but is no ratio of void to full. These are the consequences that result from a difference in the media; the following depend upon an excess of one moving body over another. We see that bodies which have a greater impulse either of weight or of light-
there
ly] ness, if they are alike move faster over an equal
in other respects,
and in the magnitudes bear to each other. Therefore they will also move through the void with this ratio of speed. But that is impossible; for why should one move faster? (In moving through plena it must be so; for ratio
which
space,
their
the greater divides
them
by
faster
its
force.
For a moving thing cleaves the medium either by its shape, or by the impulse which the body [20] that ity.
But
It is
carried along or
is
Therefore
sesses.)
[20] void can bear no ratio to the full, and therefore neither can movement through the
one
in
the
this
is
is
is
projected pos-
will possess equal veloc-
impossible.
evident from
that, if there is
all
what has been
said, then,
a void, a result follows
the very opposite of the reason for
those
who
believe in a void set
movement
think that
if
exist, the
void cannot
itself;
[25]
but this is
is
it
up.
which which
They
in respect of place
is
to
separated all by the same as to say that place exist,
a separate cavity;
and
this has already
been stated to be impossible. But even if we consider it on its own merits the so-called vacuum will be found to be really vacuous. For as, if one puts a cube in water, an amount of water equal to the cube will be
PHYSICS
296
but the effect is imperceptible to sense. And indeed always, in the [30] case of any body that can be displaced, it must, if it is not compressed, be displaced in the direction in which it is its nature to be displaced always either down, if its locomodisplaced; so too in air;
—
tion
is
downwards as
in the case of earth, or up,
or in both directions
if it is fire,
—whatever be
the nature of the inserted body.
void this
is
impossible; for
it is
Now
in the
not body; the
void must have penetrated the cube to a dis[^5] tance equal to that which this portion of void formerly occupied in the void, just as if 216 b the water or air had not been displaced by the wooden cube, but had penetrated right
through it. But the cube also has a magnitude equal to that occupied by the void; a magnitude which, if it is also hot or cold, or heavy or light, is [5] none the less different in essence from all its attributes, even if it is not separable from them; I mean the volume of the wooden cube. So that even if it were separated from everything else and were neither heavy nor light, it will occupy an equal amount of void, and fill
same place, as the part of place or of the void equal to itself. How then will the body of [10] the cube differ from the void or place that is equal to it? And if there can be two such the
why
things,
cannot there be any number coin-
ciding? This, then, is one absurd and impossible implication of the theory. It is also evident that
same volume even if it an attribute possessed by all other bodies also. Therefore if this differs in no respect from its place, why need we assume a place for bodies over and above the the cube will have this is
displaced,
which
is
volume of each, if their volume be conceived [75] of as free from attributes? It contributes nothing to the situation interval
attached to
it
if
there
as well.
is
an equal
[Further,
it
by the study of moving things what sort of thing void is. But in fact it is found nowhere in the world. For air is somenor, thing, though it does not seem to be so for that matter, would water, if fishes were
ought to be
clear
—
made
of iron; for the discrimination of the
tangible
is
by touch.]
[20] It is clear, then, from these considerations that there is no separate void.
217*
can things contract and be comif this were not to take place, [25] either there would be no movement at
say, neither
pressed. But
would bulge, as Xuthus and water must always change into equal amounts (e.g. if air has been made out of a cupful of water, at the same time out of an equal amount of air a cupful of water must have been made), or void must necessarily exist; for compression and expansion cannot or the universe
all,
said, or air
take place otherwise.
Now, if they mean by the rare that which many voids existing separately, it is plain
[jo]
has
that if void cannot exist separate any more than a place can exist with an extension all to itself, neither can the rare exist in this sense. But if they mean that there is void, not separately existent, but still present in the rare, this is less impossible, yet, first, the void turns out not to be a condition of all movement, but [_?5] only of movement upwards (for the rare 21 7 a is light, which is the reason why they say fire is rare) second, the void turns out to be a condition of movement not as that in which it takes place, but in that the void carries things up as skins by being carried up themselves carry up what is continuous with them. Yet how can void have a local movement or a place? For thus that into which void moves is till then void of a void. [5] Again, how will they explain, in the case ;
movement downwards? the rarer and more void a thing is the quicker it will move upwards, if it were completely void it would move with a of
what
And
it is
is
heavy,
its
plain that
maximum
if
speed! But perhaps even this
possible, that
it
should
move
at all; the
is
im-
same
reason which showed that in the void all things are incapable of moving shows that the void
cannot move, viz. the fact that the speeds are incomparable. [10] Since we deny that a void exists, but for the rest the problem has been truly stated, that either there will be
no movement,
if
there
is
not to be condensation and rarefaction, or the universe will bulge, or a transformation of water into air will always be balanced by an equal transformation of air into water (for it is clear that the air produced from water is bulkier [75] than the water): it is necessary therefore, if compression does not exist, either that the next portion will be pushed outwards and
make There are some who think that the existence of rarity and density shows that there is a void. If rarity and density do not exist, they
where
the outermost part bulge, or that someelse there must be an equal amount of
water produced out of air, so that the entire bulk of the whole may be equal, or that noth-
BOOK
218 a
IV,
CHAPTERS
ing moves. For when anything is displaced this will always happen, unless it comes round in a circle; but locomotion is not always circular,
but sometimes in a straight line. [20] These then are the reasons for which they might say that there is a void; our statement is
based on the assumption that there is a single matter for contraries, hot and cold and the other natural contrarieties, and that what exists
produced from a potential existent, and that matter is not separable from the Cottle ] traries but its being is different, and that a single matter may serve for colour and heat and cold. The same matter also serves for both a large and a small body. This is evident; for when air is produced from water, the same matter has become something different, not by acquiring an addition to it, but has become actually what it was potentially, and, again, water is produced from air in the same way, the [50] change being sometimes from smallness to greatness, and sometimes from greatness to smallness. Similarly, therefore, if air which is large in extent comes to have a smaller volume, or becomes greater from being smaller, it is the matter which is potentially both that comes actually
is
each of the two. as the same matter becomes hot from being cold, and cold from being hot, because it was potentially both, so too from hot it can 21 7 b become more hot, though nothing in the matter has become hot that was not hot when the thing was less hot; just as, if the arc or curve of a greater circle becomes that of a smaller, whether it remains the same or becomes a different curve, convexity has not come [5] to exist in anything that was not convex but straight (for differences of degree do not depend on an intermission of the quality); nor can we get any portion of a flame, in which both heat and whiteness are not present. So too, then, is the earlier heat related to the later. to be
For
So that the greatness and smallness, also, of the volume are extended, not by the matter's acquiring anything new, but because the sensible
matter
is
potentially matter for both states; so
[10] that the same thing is dense and rare, the two qualities have one matter.
The dense
is
heavy, and the rare
is
and
light.
[Again, as the arc of a circle when contracted into a smaller space does not acquire a new part which is convex, but what was there has been contracted; and as any part of fire that [75] one takes will be hot; so, too, it is all a question of contraction and expansion of the
8-10
297
same matter.] There are two types in each case, both in the dense and in the rare; for both the heavy and the hard are thought to be dense, and contrariwise both the light and the soft are rare; and weight and hardness fail to coincide in the case of lead and iron. [20] From what has been said it is evident, then, that void does not exist either separate (either absolutely separate or as a separate ele-
ment
one
in the rare) or potentially, unless
willing to call the condition of
movement
is
void,
whatever it may be. At that rate the matter of the heavy and the light, qua matter of them, would be the void; for the dense and the rare are productive of locomotion in virtue of this [25J contrariety, and in virtue of their hardness and softness productive of passivity and impassivity,
i.e.
not of locomotion but rather of
qualitative change.
So much, then, for the discussion of the void, and of the sense in which it exists and the sense in which it does not exist. 10
Next
subjects menTime. The best plan will be to begin by working out the difficulties connected for discussion after the
[jo] tioned
with First,
it,
is
making use
does
it
of the current arguments.
belong to the
class of things that
do not
exist or to that of things that
Then then:
secondly, the
make one
what
following suspect that
is
its
nature?
considerations it
exist?
To
start,
would
either does not exist
and in an obscure way. One part of it has been and is not, while the other 218 a is going to be and is not yet. Yet time both infinite time and any time you like to take is made up of these. One would naturally suppose that what is made up of things which do not exist could have no share in reality. at all or barely,
—
Further,
if
a divisible thing
when
is
to exist,
it is
some of its [5] parts must exist. But of time some parts have been, while others have to be, and no part of it is, though it is divisible. For what is necessary that,
it
exists, all
or
'now' is not a part: a part is a measure of the whole, which must be made up of parts. Time, on the other hand, is not held to be made up of 'nows'.
Again, the 'now' which seems to bound the and the future does it always remain one [10] and the same or is it always other and other? It is hard to say. (1) If it is always different and different, and if none of the parts in time which are other and other are simultaneous (unless the past
—
PHYSICS
298
one contains and the other is contained, as the shorter time is by the longer), and if the 'now' which is not, but formerly was, must have [75] ceased-to-be at some time, the 'nows' too cannot be simultaneous with one another, but the prior 'now' must always have ceased-to-be. But the prior 'now' cannot have ceased-to-be in itself (since it then existed); yet it cannot have ceased-to-be in another 'now'. For we may lay it down that one 'now' cannot be next to another, any more than point to point. If then it did not cease-to-be in the next 'now' [20] but in another, it would exist simultaneously with the innumerable 'nows' between the
—which
two
is
is
it
a
it is
which moves or But time is present equally everywhere and with all things. Again, (b) change is always faster or slower, [75] whereas time is not: for 'fast' and 'slow' are defined by time 'fast' is what moves much changes
may chance
itself
to be.
—
in a short time, 'slow'
what moves
in a
little
long time; but time is not defined by time, by being either a certain amount or a certain kind of
it.
Clearly then
it is
(We
not movement.
need
[20] not distinguish at present between 'movement' and 'change'.) 11
possible for the
'now' to remain always the same. No determinate divisible thing has a single termination, in
or where the thing
impossible.
Yes, but (2) neither
whether
219*
continuously extended in one or the 'now' is
more than one dimension: but termination, and it is possible
to cut off a
[25] determinate time. Further, if coincidence in time (i.e. being neither prior nor posterior)
But neither does time exist without change; for when the state of our own minds does not change at all, or we have not noticed its changing, we do not realize that time has elapsed, any more than those who are fabled to [25] sleep among the heroes in Sardinia do when they are awakened; for they connect the earlier 'now' with the later and make them
one and the same "now" ', both what is before and what is after
one, cutting out the interval because of their
same 'now', things which happened ten thousand years ago would be simultaneous with what has happened to-day, and nothing would be before or after anything else,
were not different but one and the same, there would not have been time, so too when
means then,
to be 'in
if
are in this
failure to notice
it.
So, just as,
the 'now'
if
[jo] This
its difference escapes our notice the interval does not seem to be time. If, then, the non-realiza[ jo] tion of the existence of time happens to us
culties
when we do
may serve as a statement of the diffiabout the attributes of time. As to what time is or what is its nature, the traditional accounts give us as little light as the preliminary problems which we have worked through. Some
assert that
it is
218 b the whole, others
(1) the
that
it is
movement
of
(2) the sphere
itself. ( 1 ) Yet part, too, of the revolution is a time, but it certainly is not a revolution: for what is taken is part of a revolution, not a revolution. Besides, if there were more heavens than one, the movement of any of them equally would be time, so that there would be many times at the
same time. [5] (2) Those who said that time is the sphere of the whole thought so, no doubt, on the ground that all things are in time and all things are in the sphere of the whole.
view
is
too naive for
it
to be
The
worth while
consider the impossibilities implied in
to
it.
But as time is most usually supposed to be (3) motion and a kind of change, we must consider this view. [10]
Now
each thing
(a) the change or is
movement
of
only in the thing which changes
not distinguish any change, but
the soul seems to stay in one indivisible state,
and when we perceive and distinguish we say time has elapsed, evidently time
not inde-
is
pendent of movement and change.
219 a
dent, then, that time
is
neither
It
is
evi-
movement
nor independent of movement. We must take this as our starting-point and since we wish to know what try to discover time is what exactly it has to do with movement. Now we perceive movement and time together: for even when it is dark and we are not [5] being affected through the body, if any movement takes place in the mind we at once suppose that some time also has elapsed; and not only that but also, when some time is thought to have passed, some movement also along with it seems to have taken place. Hence time is either movement or something that belongs to movement. Since then it is not movement, it must be the other. [10] But what is moved is moved from something to something, and all magnitude is continuous. Therefore the movement goes with the magnitude. Because the magnitude is con-
—
—
BOOK
220*
movement
tinuous, the ous,
and
the time that has passed
is
CHAPTERS
IV,
must be continu-
movement, then the time;
the
if
too
for
always thought to be
movement. The distinction of 'before' and 'after' holds primarily, then, in place; and there in virtue in proportion to the
[75] of relative position. Since then 'before'
hold in magnitude, they must hold also in movement, these corresponding to those. But also in time the distinction of 'before' and 'after' must hold, for time and movement always correspond with each other. The
and
'after'
'before'
and
'after' in
motion
is
identical in sub-
[20] stratum with motion yet differs from
it
and is not identical with motion. But we apprehend time only when we have marked motion, marking it by 'before' and 'after'; and it is only when we have perceived 'before' and 'after' in motion that we say that [25] time has elapsed. Now we mark them by judging that A and B are different, and that some third thing is intermediate to them. in definition,
When we
think of the extremes as different
from the middle and the mind pronounces that the 'nows' are two, one before and one after, it is
then that
we
say that there
is
time,
and this that we say is time. For what bounded by the 'now' is thought to be time we may assume this.
is
[30] When, therefore, we perceive the 'now' as one, and neither as before and after in a motion
nor as an identity but in relation to a 'before' and an 'after', no time is thought to have elapsed, because there has been no motion either. On the other hand, when we do per219 b ceive a 'before' and an 'after', then we say numthat there is time. For time is just this ber of motion in respect of 'before' and 'after'. Hence time is not movement, but only movement in so far as it admits of enumeration. A proof of this: we discriminate the more or the less by number, but more or less movement by time. Time then is a kind of number. (Num[5] ber, we must note, is used in two senses both of what is counted or the countable and also of that with which we count. Time obviously is what is counted, not that with which we count: there are different kinds of thing.) Just as motion is a perpetual succession, so [10] also is time. But every simultaneous time is self-identical; for the 'now' as a subject is an identity, but it accepts different attributes. The 'now' measures time, in so far as time involves
—
the 'before
and
The 'now' other
it
is
after'.
one sense is the same, in annot the same. In so far as it is in in
10-11
299
(which is just what being now was supposed to mean), but [75] substratum is an identity: for motion, was said, goes with magnitude, and time, succession,
it is
different
1
its its
as as
we
maintain, with motion. Similarly, then, there corresponds to the point the body which
and by which we are aware of and of the 'before and after' involved in it. This is an identical substratum (whether a point or a stone or something else
is
carried along,
the motion
of the kind), but
it
has different attributes
—
[20] as the sophists assume that Coriscus' being in the Lyceum is a different thing from Coriscus' being in the market-place.
body which far as
there.
is
carried along
is
And
the
different, in so
it is at one time here and at another But the 'now' corresponds to the body
that is carried along, as time corresponds to the motion. For it is by means of the body that is carried along that we become aware of the 'be[25] fore and after' in the motion, and if we regard these as countable we get the 'now'. Hence in these also the 'now' as substratum remains
the same (for it is what is before and movement), but what is predicated
after in
of
it
is
and after' is numerable that we get the 'now'. This is what is most knowable: for, similarly, motion is known because of that which is moved, locomotion because of that which is carried. [30] For what is carried is a real thing, the movement is not. Thus what is called 'now' in one sense is always the same; in another it is not the same: for this is true also of what is different; for
it is
in so far as the 'before
carried.
Clearly, too, if there were no time, there 220 a would be no 'now', and vice versa. Just as the moving body and its locomotion involve each other mutually, so too do the number of the moving body and the number of its locomotion. For the number of the locomotion is time, while the 'now' corresponds to the moving body, and is like the unit of number. Time, then, also is both made continuous by [5] the 'now' and divided at it. For here too
there
is
a correspondence with the locomotion
and the moving body. For the motion or locomotion is made one by the thing which is moved, because it is one not because it is one in its own nature (for there might be pauses in
—
—
movement of such a thing) but because it one in definition: for this determines the movement as 'before' and 'after'. Here, too, [10] there is a correspondence with the point; for the point also both connects and terminates the is
PHYSICS
300
—
the length it is the beginning of one and the end of another. But when you take it in this way, using the one point as two, a pause is necessary, if the same point is to be the beginning and the end. The 'now' on the other hand, since the body carried is moving, is always different.
Hence time
not
is
number
in the sense in
which there cause
it
is 'number' of the same point bebeginning and end, but rather as
is
[75] the extremities of a line form a number, as the parts of the line do so, both for
and not
the reason given (for we can use the middle point as two, so that on that analogy time might stand still), and further because obviously the 'now' is no part of time nor the section
any part of the movement, any more than
the points are parts of the line
—
for
it
is
[20] lines that are parts of one line. In so far then as the 'now' is a boundary,
two it is
(e.g. ten)
is
number
the
of these horses,
and
belongs also elsewhere. It
is
then, that time
clear,
movement
[25]
and is continuous what is continuous.
after',
of
is
'number of and an attribute
in respect of the before
since
it is
The smallest number, in the strict sense of the word 'number', is two. But of number as concrete, sometimes there is a minimum, somee.g. of a 'line',
of multiplicity
two
is
the smallest in respect
(or,
if
you
like,
one),
[30] but in respect of size there is no minimum; for every line is divided ad infinitum.
Hence the
it is
so
minimum
extent there
is
with time. In respect of number is one (or two); in point of
no minimum. that time
is not described as but as many or few and as long or short. For as continuous it is long or short and as a number many or few, but it is not fast or slow any more than any number with which we number is fast or slow. [5] Further, there is the same time everywhere at once, but not the same time before and after, for while the present change is one, the change which has happened and that which will happen are different. Time is not number with which we count, but the number of things which are counted, and this according as it occurs before or after is always different, [10] for the 'nows' are different. And the num-
It is clear, too,
220b
fast or slow,
—
—
movement can
be one and the same again and
again, so too can time, e.g. a year or a spring or
an autumn. [75] Not only do we measure the movement by the time, but also the time by the movement, because they define each other. The time marks the movement, since it is its num-
and the movement the time. We describe much or little, measuring it by the movement, just as we know the number by what is numbered, e.g. the number of the [20] horses by one horse as the unit. For we ber,
the time as
know how many
horses there are by the use of
number; and again by using the one horse
the
as unit
we know
the
number
of the horses
it-
with the time and the movement; for we measure the movement by the time and vice versa. It is natural that this should happen; [25] for the movement goes with the distance and the time with the movement, because they are quanta and continuous and divisible. The movement has these attributes because the distance is of this nature, and the time has them because of the movement. And we measure both the distance by the movement and the movement by the distance; for we say that the road is long, if the journey is long, and that [30] this is long, if the road is long the time,
So
it is
—
12
times not:
s
ber of a hundred horses and a hundred men is the same, but the things numbered are different the horses from the men. Further, as a
self.
not time, but an attribute of it; in so far as it numbers, it is number; for boundaries belong only to that which they bound, but number
221
too, if the
movement, and the movement,
if
the time.
221 a Time is a measure of motion and of being moved, and it measures the motion by determining a motion which will measure exactly the whole motion, as the cubit does the length by determining an amount which will measure out the whole. Further 'to be in time' means, for movement, that both it and its essence are measured by time (for simultaneously it measly] ures both the movement and its essence, and this is what being in time means for it, that its essence should be measured). Clearly then 'to be in time' has the same
meaning
for other things also, namely, that
measured by time. 'To one of two things: (1) to exist [70] when time exists, (2) as we say of some things that they are 'in number'. The latter
their being should be
be in time'
means
—
is
either
what
is
a part or
mode
of
num-
something which belongs to number or that things have a number. Now, since time is number, the 'now' and ber
in general,
—
[75] the 'before' and the like are in time, just and 'odd' and 'even' are in number,
as 'unit'
BOOK
222'
CHAPTERS
IV,
one set belongs to number, the other to time. But things are in time as they are in number. If this is so, they are contained by time as things in place are contained by place. Plainly, too, to be in time does not mean to [20] co-exist with time, any more than to be in motion or in place means to co-exist with motion or place. For if 'to be in something' is to mean this, then all things will be in anything, and the heaven will be in a grain; for when the grain is, then also is the heaven. But this is a merely incidental conjunction, whereas the in the sense that the
i.e.
which
necessarily involved: that
other
is
is
in
[25]
time necessarily involves that there
is
when
and that which is in motion that there is motion when it is. Since what is 'in time' is so in the same sense as what is in number is so, a time greater than everything in time can be found. So it is time
it is,
necessary that all the things in time should be contained by time, just like other things also which are 'in anything', e.g. the things 'in flace'
jo]
by place,
A
thing, then, will be affected by time,
we
just as
are accustomed to say that time
wastes things away, and that
all
things
old through time, and that there
is
grow
oblivion
to the lapse of time, but we do not 221 b say the same of getting to know or of becoming young or fair. For time is by its
owing
nature the cause rather of decay, since it is the number of change, and change removes
what
is.
Hence,
plainly, things
which are always
are
not, as such, in time, for they are not contained
by time, nor is their being measured by time. [5] A proof of this is that none of them is affected by time, which indicates that they are not in time. Since time is the measure of motion, it will be the measure of rest too indirectly. For all rest is in time. For it does not follow that what is in time is moved, though what is in motion [10] is necessarily moved. For time is not motion, but 'number of motion': and what is at rest, also, can be in the number of motion. Not everything that is not in motion can be said to be 'at rest' but only that which can be moved, though it actually is not moved, as was said above. 1
—
—
'To be in number' means that there is a [75] number of the thing, and that its being is measured by the number in which it is. Hence if a thing is 'in time' it will be measured by 1
202*
4.
11-13
301
what is moved the one qua moved, the it will measure their mo-
time. But time will measure
and what
is
at rest,
other qua at rest; for
and rest respectively. Hence what is moved will not be measurable
tion
by the time simply in so far as it has quantity, [20] but in so far as its motion has quantity.
Thus none moved nor time'
is 'to
of the things
which are neither
at rest are in time: for 'to be in
be measured by time', while time
the measure of motion and rest.
is
Plainly, then, neither will everything that does not exist be in time, i.e. those non-existent things that cannot exist, as the diagonal cannot be commensurate with the side. [25] Generally, if time is directly the measure of motion and indirectly of other things, it is clear that a thing whose existence is measured by it will have its existence in rest or motion. Those things therefore which are subject to perishing and becoming generally, tho.se
—
which
at
one time
exist, at
another do not
[50] are necessarily in time: for there is a greater time which will extend both beyond
and beyond the time which measures their existence. Of things which do not exist but are contained by time some were, 222 a e.g. Homer once was, some will be, e.g. a future event; this depends on the direction in which time contains them; if on both, they have both modes of existence. As to such things as it does not contain in any way, they neither were nor are nor will be. These are those nonexistents whose opposites always are, as the [5] incommensurability of the diagonal always and this will not be in time. Nor will the is commensurability, therefore; hence this eternally is not, because it is contrary to what their existence
—
A
thing whose contrary is not and not be, and it is of such things that there is coming to be and passing eternally
is.
eternal can be
away. !3
The 'now'
[10] said
and
2
is the link of time, as has been connects past and future time), a limit of time (for it is the beginning
(for
it is
it
and the end of the other). But this it is with the point, which is divides potentially, and in so far as it
of the one is
not obvious as
fixed. It
[75] is dividing the 'now' is always different, but in so far as it connects it is always the same, as it is with mathematical lines. For the intellect it is not always one and the same point, since it is other and other when one divides 2
220*
5.
PHYSICS
302 the line; but in so far as
same in every respect. So the 'now' also is
it
is
one,
it
is
the
223
'Lately',
if
'Long ago' in
one way a potential
dividing of time, in another the termination of both parts, and their unity. And the dividing and the uniting are the same thing and in the same reference, but in essence they are not the
the time
[75] 'Suddenly' refers to what has departed its former condition in a time impercepti-
from
ble because of
its
the wisest of
which is not 'sometime', every time will be determined. Will time then fail ? Surely not, if motion al[30] ways exists. Is time then always different or does the same time recur? Clearly time is,
same way as motion is. For if one and same motion sometimes recurs, it will be one and the same time, and if not, not. 222 b Since the 'now' is an end and a beginning of time, not of the same time however, but the end of that which is past and the beginning of that which is to come, it follows that, as the circle has its convexity and its concavity, in a sense, in the same thing, so time is always at a beginning and at an end. And for in the
Paron
called
also forget;
it
the nature
their
former
things
things, but the
Pythagorean
the most stupid, because in
and
clear then that
all
for
all
it is
from
come into being which reason some called it
condition. In time
and pass away;
'at some time' there will be a flood; for it must be determined with reference to the 'now'. There will thus be a determinate time from this 'now' to that, and there was such in reference to the past event. But if there be no time
smallness; but
of all change to alter things
[20] So one kind of 'now' is described in this way: another is when the time is near this
[25] relation to the first of the two types of 'now', e.g. 'at some time' Troy was taken, and
near the existing now.
refers to the distant past.
same.
kind of 'now'. 'He will come now' because he will come to-day; 'he has come now' because he came to-day. But the things in the Iliad have not happened 'now', nor is the flood 'now' not that the time from now to them is not continuous, but because they are not near. 'At some time' means a time determined in
is
s
was the truer view. must be in itself, as we
his
it
it
we
It
is
said
1
the condition of destruction [20] before, rather than of coming into being (for change,
makes things depart from
in itself,
mer
their for-
condition), and only incidentally of com-
ing into being, and of being. A sufficient evidence of this is that nothing comes into being without itself moving somehow and acting, but a thing can be destroyed even if it does not move at all. And this is what, as a rule, we [25] chiefly mean by a thing's being destroyed by time. Still, time does not work even this change; even this sort of change takes place incidentally in time.
We
have
stated, then, that time exists and and in how many senses we speak of the 'now', and what 'at some time', 'lately', 'presently' or 'just', 'long ago', and 'suddenly' mean.
what
it
is,
the
this reason
it
seems to be always different; for
[5] the 'now' is not the beginning and the end of the same thing; if it were, it would be at the
same time and sites.
And
in the
same
time will not
respect
two oppo-
fail; for it is
always
at
moves is in time; for the distinction of and slower exists in reference to all change, since it is found in every instance. In the phrase 'moving faster' I refer to that which 223 a changes before another into the condition in question, when it moves over the same interval and with a regular movement; e.g. in the that
faster
case of locomotion,
'Presently' or 'just' refers to the part of fu-
[10] ture time which is near the indivisible present 'now' ('When do you walk?' 'Present-
because the time in which he is going to do near), and to the part of past time which is not far from the 'now' ('When do you walk?' 'I have just been walking'). But to say that Troy has just been taken we do not say that, because it is too far from the 'now'. 'Lately', too, refers to the part of past time which is near the present 'now'. 'When did you go?' ly',
is
—
if
both things
move along
the circumference of a circle, or both along a straight line;
But what
a beginning.
so
14 [50] These distinctions having been drawn, it is evident that every change and everything
is
and
similarly in
before
is
all
in time; for
other cases.
we
say 'be-
and 'after' with reference to the distance from the 'now', and the 'now' is the boundary of the past and the future; so that since 'nows' are in time, the before and the after will be in time too; for in that in which the 'now' is, the distance from the 'now' will also be. But 'before' is used contrariwise with refer[10] ence to past and to future time; for in the past we call 'before' what is farther from the 'now', and 'after' what is nearer, but in the [5] fore'
224
BOOK
s
future ther
we
the nearer 'before'
call
'after'.
So that since the
IV,
and the
'before'
is
CHAPTERS 13-14 farNow there is
in time,
[75] and every movement involves a 'before', evidently every change and every movement is in time. It is also worth considering how time can be related to the soul; and why time is thought to be in everything, both in earth and in sea and in heaven. Is it because it is an attribute, or state, or movement (since it is the number of movement) and all these things are mov-
able (for they are
[20]
movement
potentiality
and
Whether exist or not,
if
all
in place),
and time and
are together, both in respect of
is
Now
in respect of actuality?
soul did not exist time a question that
may
would
fairly
be
asked; for if there cannot be some one to count there cannot be anything that can be counted, so that evidently there cannot be number; for number is either what has been, or what can [25] be, counted. But if nothing but soul, or in soul reason, is qualified to count, there would not be time unless there were soul, but only
which time is an attribute, i.e. if movement can exist without soul, and the before and after are attributes of movement, and time is these qua numerable. One might also raise the question what sort [30] of movement time is the number of. Must we not say 'of any kind'? For things both come into being in time and pass away, and grow, and are altered in time, and are moved locally; thus it is of each movement qua movement that of
that time
the
is
number
the number.
And
of continuous
so
it
is
303
such a thing as locomotion, and in locomotion there is included circular movement, and everything is measured by some one thing homogeneous with it, units by a unit, horses by a horse, and similarly times 1 [75] by some definite time, and, as we said, time is measured by motion as well as motion by time (this being so because by a motion definite in time the quantity both of the motion and of the time is measured): if, then, what is first is the measure of everything homogeneous with it, regular circular motion is above all else the measure, because the num-
simply
movement, not of
any particular kind of it. 223 b But other things as well may have been moved now, and there would be a number of each of the two movements. Is there another time, then, and will there be two equal times at once? Surely not. For a time that is both equal and simultaneous is one and the same time, and even those that are not simultaneous are one in kind; for if there were dogs, and [5] horses, and seven of each, it would be the same number. So, too, movements that have simultaneous limits have the same time, yet the one may in fact be fast and the other not, and one may be locomotion and the other alteration; still the time of the two changes is the same if their number also is equal and simul[10] taneous; and for this reason, while the movements are different and separate, the time
[20] ber of this is the best known. neither alteration nor increase nor coming into
being can be regular, but locomotion can be. This also is why time is thought to be the movement of the sphere, viz. because the other movements are measured by this, and time by this movement. This also explains the common saying that [25] there
human is
natural
affairs
a circle in
all
form
a circle,
and that
other things that have a
movement and coming
into being
and
passing away. This is because all other things are discriminated by time, and end and begin as
though conforming to a cycle; for even time thought to be a circle. And this opin-
itself is
[50]
ion again
is
held because time
is
the
measure of this kind of locomotion and is itself measured by such. So that to say that the things that come into being form a circle is to say that there is a circle of time; and this is to say that it is measured by the circular movement; for apart from the meas224 a ure nothing else to be measured is observed; the whole is just a plurality of measures. It is
said rightly, too, that the
number
of the
same number if the two numbers are equal, but not the same decad or the same ten; just as the equilateral [5] and the scalene are not the same triangle, yet they are the same figure, because they are both triangles. For things are called the same so-and-so if they do not differ by a differentia sheep and of the dogs
of that thing, but not differs
from
the
is
if
they do; e.g. triangle
triangle by a differentia of
tri-
angle, therefore they are different triangles;
but they do not differ by a differentia of figure, but are in one and the same division of it. For a figure of the one kind
is
a circle
and
a figure
is
[70] of another kind of triangle, and a triangle of one kind is equilateral and a triangle of
of equal
another kind scalene. They are the same figure,
everywhere the same, because the number and simultaneous movements is everywhere one and the same.
1
220b 28.
PHYSICS
3 o4
and
then,
that, triangle,
but not the same
tri-
number of two groups same number (for their number does
angle. Therefore the also
is
the
not differ by a differentia of number), but it not the same decad; for the things of which
is
224b
asserted differ; one
group are dogs, and the
other horses. [75]
We have now
discussed time
—both time
is
itself
and the matters appropriate
to the con-
it
sideration of
it.
BOOK V Everything which changes does three senses.
It
as for instance
so in
one of
may change (1) accidentally, when we say that something
musical walks, that which walks being something in which aptitude for music is an accident. Again (2) a thing is said without qualification to change because something belonging to it changes, i.e. in statements which refer [25] to part of the thing in question: thus the body is restored to health because the eye or the chest, that is to say a part of the whole body, is restored to health. And above all there is (3) the case of a thing which is in motion neither accidentally nor in respect of something else belonging to it, but in virtue of being itself directly in motion. Here we have a thing which is essentially movable: and that which is so is a different thing according to the particular variety of motion: for instance it may be a thing capable of alteration: and within the sphere of alteration it is again a different thing according [50] as it is capable of being restored to health or capable of being heated. And there are the same distinctions in the case of the mover: (1) one thing causes motion accidentally, (2) another partially (because something belonging to it causes motion), (3) another of itself directly, as, for instance, the
hand
strikes.
tors: (a)
We have,
physician heals, the
then, the following fac-
on the one hand that which directly and (b) on the other hand that
causes motion,
which
is
in motion: further,
we have
(c) that
nor experienced by the form or the place or the quantity. So we are left with a mover, a moved, and a goal of motion. I do not include the starting-point of motion: for it is the goal rather than the starting-point of motion that gives its name to a particular process of change. Thus 'perishing' is change to not-being, though it is also true that that which perishes changes from being: and 'becoming' is change to being,
though
it is
also
change from not-being.
Now
a definition of motion has been giv[10] en above, 1 from which it will be seen that every goal of motion, whether it be a form, an affection, or a place,
stance,
may be raised. Affections, it may be motions, and whiteness is an affection: thus there may be change to a motion. To this [75] we may reply that it is not whiteness but whitening that is a motion. Here also the same distinctions are to be observed: a goal of motion may be so accidentally, or partially and with reference to something other than itself,
said, are
and with no reference to anything which is becoming white changes accidentally to an object of or directly else:
for instance, a thing
thought, the colour being only accidentally the [20] object of thought; it changes to colour, because white is a part of colour, or to Europe, because Athens is a part of Europe; but it changes essentially to white colour. It is now clear in what sense a thing is in motion essentially,
accidentally, or in respect of
other than
itself,
'itself directly' is
224 b from which and
clear that the
which it proceeds: for every motion proceeds from something and to something, that which is directly in motion being distinct from that to which it is in motion and that from which it is in motion:
we may
take the three things 'wood', 'hot', and 'cold', of which the first is that which is in motion, the second is that to which the motion proceeds, and the third is for instance,
from which it proceeds. This being so, it is clear that the motion is in the wood, not in [5] its form: for the motion is neither caused
that
as, for in-
heat. Here, however, a
difficulty
[55] in which motion takes place, namely time, and (distinct from these three) (d) that (e) that to
immovable,
is
knowledge and
[25] that
mover and which
is
in
what
something
sense the phrase
used in the case both of the of the
motion
is
moved: and
Now
also
it is
not in the form but in
in motion, that
able in activity'.
may
and
is
to say 'the
mov-
accidental change
leave out of account: for
it is
to be
we
found
any time, and in any respect. Change which is not accidental on the other hand is not to be found in everything, but only in everything, at
in contraries, in things intermediate
between
[30] contraries, and in contradictories, as be proved by induction. An intermediate
may may
be a starting-point of change, since for the 1
20I a 10.
BOOK
225 b
purposes of the change
two
either of
IV,
serves as contrary to
it
contraries: for the intermediate
in a sense the extremes.
is
CHAPTER 14— BOOK
Hence we speak
of
for
CHAPTERS
V,
1-2
although that which
305 or
'not-white'
is
'not-good'
may
nevertheless be in motion ac-
cidentally
(for
example that which is 'notwhich is
the intermediate as in a sense a contrary rela-
white' might be a man), yet that
tively to the extremes and of either extreme as a contrary relatively to the intermediate: for instance, the central note is low relatively to the highest and high relatively to the lowest,
without qualification 'not-so-and-so' cannot in [25] any sense be in motion: therefore it is impossible for that which is not to be in motion. This being so, it follows that 'becoming' cannot be a motion: for it is that which 'is not' that 'becomes'. For however true it may
and grey
light relatively to black
is
and dark
relatively to white.
And
change is from somesomething as the word itself (lj,eTa(3o\r)) indicates, implying something 'after' (fxeTa ) something else, that is to say something earlier and something later that which changes must change in one of four ways: from subject to subject, from subject to non[5] subject, from non-subject to subject, or from non-subject to non-subject, where by 'subject' I mean what is affirmatively expressed. So it follows necessarily from what has been said above that there are only three kinds of change, that from subject to subject, that from subject to non-subject, and that from non[35]
since every
225 a thing
to
—
—
1
[10] subject to subject: for the fourth conceivable kind, that from non-subject to non-
not change, as in that case there is no opposition either of contraries or of consubject,
is
tradictories.
Now
change from non-subject
to
subject,
the relation being that of contradiction, is 'coming to be' 'unqualified coming to be'
—
when
the change takes place in an unqualified
way, 'particular coming to be' when the change is change in a particular character: for instance, a change from not-white to white is a coming to be of the particular thing, white, while [75] change from unqualified not-being to being is coming to be in an unqualified way, in respect of which we say that a thing 'comes to be' without qualification, not that it 'comes to be'
some
particular thing.
ject to non-subject
when
perishing'
not-being,
change
is
Change from
'perishing'
the change
'particular
is
sub—'unqualified
from being
perishing'
when
coming
same
as that
made
in the case
'is
not' in respect of the affirma-
similarly
it is
224b 28, 29.
'is
not'
And not'
[30] There are these difficulties, then, in the of the assumption that that which 'is not'
can be in motion: and
it
may
be further ob-
which is which 'is not' is not would be somewhere.
jected that, whereas everything
in
motion
in
is
in space, that
space: for then
it
is not a motion: for a contrary either another mo-
So, too, 'perishing'
motion has
for
tion or rest,
whereas 'perishing'
its
is
the contrary
of 'becoming'. Since, then, every motion is a kind of change, and there are only the three kinds of 2 [35] change mentioned above, and since of these three those which take the form of 'be-
225 b coming' and 'perishing', that is to say those which imply a relation of contradiction, are not motions:
it
necessarily follows that only
motion. And an inbe allowed to
change from subject
to subject
every such subject
either a contrary or
is
is
termediate (for a privation may rank as a contrary) and can be affirmatively expressed, as naked, toothless, or black. If, then, [5] the categories are severally distinguished as Being, Quality, Place, Time, Relation, Quantity,
and Activity or
Passivity,
it
necessarily
follows that there are three kinds of motion qualitative, quantitative,
and
local.
[10] In respect of Substance there is no mobecause Substance has no contrary among
tion,
of Relation: for
Nor is there motion in respect it may happen that when one
correlative changes, the other, although this
does not
itself
change,
is
Nor
only potentially 'is', that is to say the opposite of that which actually 'is' in an unqualified sense: 1
'is
way
which
it
neverthe-
impossible for that which
so that in these cases the
not' in the sense that
it is
which
to be at rest.
tion or negation of a predicate, nor of that 'is
that
that in an unqualified sense 'becomes'.
things that are.
to be.
Now
which
it is
to
the expression 'not-being' is used in [20] several senses: and there can be motion neither of that
accidentally 'becomes',
it
less correct to say that
the
to the opposite negation, the distinc-
tion being the
of
is
be that
is
Patient
no longer motion is
there motion in respect of
—
in fact there can never be
mover and moved, because 2
1.7.
applicable, accidental.
Agent and motion of
there cannot be
PHYSICS
3°6
[75] motion of motion or becoming of becoming or in general change of change. For in the first place there are two senses in which motion of motion is conceivable. (1) The motion of which there is motion might be conceived as subject; e.g. a man is in motion because he changes from fair to dark. Can it be that in this sense motion grows hot or cold, or [20] changes place, or increases or decreases? Impossible: for change is not a subject. Or (2) can there be motion of motion in the sense that some other subject changes from a change to another mode of being, as e.g. a man changes
from
falling
ill
to getting well?
Even
this
is
possible only in an accidental sense. For, what-
ever the subject
movement another. (And
may
be,
change the same is
from one form to [25] holds good of becoming and perishing, except that in these processes we have a change
kind of opposite, while the change to a different kind.) So, if there is to be motion of motion, that which is changing from health to sickness must simultaneously be changing from this very change to another. It is clear, then, that by the time that it has become sick, it must also have changed to whatever may be the other change concerned (for that it should be at rest, though logically possible, is excluded by the theory). Moreover this other can never be any casual change, but must be a change from [50] something definite to some other definite thing. So in this case it must be the opposite to
a particular
other, motion,
is
a
change, viz. convalescence. It is only accidentally that there can be change of change, e.g. there
is
a change
from remembering
to for-
getting only because the subject of this change
changes
at
one time
to
knowledge,
at
another
motion, it ing contrary
lar
coming to becoming quently, that
if
there
is
to be
change
and becoming of becoming, we shall have an infinite regress. Thus if one of a series [35] of changes is to be a change of change, 226 a the preceding change must also be so: e.g. if simple becoming was ever in process of becoming, then that which was becoming simple becoming was also in process of becoming, so that we should not yet have arrived at what was in process of simple becoming but only at what was already in process of becoming in process of becoming. And this again was someof change
time in process of becoming, so that even then we should not have arrived at what was in process of simple becoming. And since in an infinite series there is no first term, here there will be no first stage and therefore no follow-
is
also capable of the correspond-
motion or the corresponding rest, and a thing that is capable of also capable of perishing: conse-
is
if
there be
which
is
becoming of becoming, becoming is in
process of
in
process of perishing at the very
moment when
has reached the stage of becoming: since it cannot be in process of perishing when it is just beginning to become or after it has ceased it
to
become: for that which
ishing
must be
is
in process of per-
in existence.
[10] Fourthly, there must be a substrate underlying all processes of becoming and chang-
What
can this be in the present case? It body or the soul that undergoes alteration: what is it that correspondingly becomes motion or becoming? And again what is the goal of their motion? It must be the motion or becoming of something from something to something else. But in what sense [75] can this be so? For the becoming of learning cannot be learning: so neither can the becoming of becoming be becoming, nor can the becoming of any process be that process. Finally, since there are three kinds of motion, the substratum and the goal of motion must be one or other of these, e.g. locomotion will have to be altered or to be locally moved. To sum up, then, since everything that is moved is moved in one of three ways, either ing.
either the
is
accidentally, or partially, or essentially,
change
[20] can change only accidentally, as e.g. when a man who is being restored to health runs or learns:
and accidental change we have long
ago 1 decided
to ignorance.
In the second place,
226"
[5] ing stage either. On this hypothesis, then, nothing can become or be moved or change. Thirdly, if a thing is capable of any particu-
to leave out of account.
motion can belong neither to Being nor to Relation nor to Agent and Patient, it remains that there can be motion only in respect of Quality, Quantity, and Place: for [25] with each of these we have a pair of contraries. Motion in respect of Quality let us call Since, then,
alteration, a general designation that
is
used to
include both contraries: and by Quality I do not here mean a property of substance (in that sense that tion
is
which
constitutes a specific distinc-
a quality) but a passive quality in vir-
is said to be acted on or being acted on. Motion in [30] respect of Quantity has no name that includes both contraries, but it is called increase or decrease according as one or the other is
tue of
which
a thing
to be incapable of
1
224b 26.
ij
BOOK
227"
V,
CHAPTERS
motion in the direction of complete magnitude is increase, motion in the contrary direction is decrease. Motion in respect of Place has no name either general or particular: but we may designate it by the general name of locomotion, though strictly the term 'locomotion' is applicable to things that change their place only when they have not [35] tne power to come to a stand, and to things that do not move themselves locally. 226 b Change within the same kind from a lesser to a greater or from a greater to a lesser degree is alteration: for it is motion either from a contrary or to a contrary, whether in an unqualified or in a qualified sense: for change to a lesser degree of a quality will be called change to the contrary of that quality, [5] and change to a greater degree of a quality will be regarded as change from the contrary of that quality to the quality itself. It makes no difference whether the change be qualified or unqualified, except that in the former case the contraries will have to be contrary to one another only in a qualified sense: and a thing's designated: that
is
to say
possessing a quality in a greater or in a lesser degree means the presence or absence in it of
2-3
307
Things are said to be together in place when they are in one place (in the strictest sense of the word 'place') and to be apart when they are in different places.
Things are
said to be in contact
when
their
extremities are together.
That which a changing thing, if it changes [25] continuously in a natural manner, naturally reaches before it reaches that to which it
changes
last, is
between. Thus 'between' im-
plies the presence of at least three things: for
change it is the contrary that is and a thing is moved continuously if it leaves no gap or only the smallest possible gap not in the time (for a gap in in the material in a process of 'last':
—
the time does not prevent things having a 'be-
tween', while, on the other hand, there is nothing to prevent the highest note sounding [30] immediately after the lowest) but in the material in which the motion takes place. This is manifestly true not only in local changes but in every other kind as well. (Now every 227 a [7] change implies a pair of opposites,
and opposites may be
either contraries or con-
tradictories; since then contradiction
admits of
clear, then, that there are
no mean term, it is obvious that 'between' must imply a pair of contraries.) That is locally con226 b [32] trary which is most distant in a
of motion.
straight line: for the shortest line
more
or less of the opposite quality. It is now only these three kinds
The term 'immovable' we
apply in the first place to that which is absolutely incapable of being moved (just as we correspondingly apply the term invisible to sound); in the sec[10]
ond
place to that
which
culty after a long time or
—
is
moved with
diffi-
whose movement is what we describe as
slow at the start in fact, hard to move; and in the third place to that which is naturally designed for and capable of motion, but is not in motion when, where, and as it naturally would be so. This last is the only kind of immovable thing of which I use the term 'being at
rest':
for rest
is
con-
[75] trary to motion, so that rest will be negation of motion in that which is capable of
admitting motion. The foregoing remarks are sufficient to explain the essential nature of motion and rest, the number of kinds of change, and the different varieties of motion.
Let us
now
gether'
and
[20] ous',
proceed to define the terms
succession',
and
to
'to-
'apart', 'in contact', 'between', 'in
show
of these terms
is
and 'continuwhat circumstances each
limited,
and that which
is
is
definitely
definitely limited
constitutes a measure.
A [_?5]
thing
is
'in succession'
when
it
the beginning in position or in
is
after
form or
in some other respect in which it is definitely 227 a so regarded, and when further there is nothing of the same kind as itself between it and that to which it is in succession, e.g. a line or lines
if it is
a line, a unit or units
if it is
nothing to prevent something of a different kind being between). For that which is in succession is in succession to a particular thing, and is something posterior: for one is not 'in succession' to [5] two, nor is the first day of the month to be second: in each case the latter is 'in succession' a unit, a house
if it is
a house (there
is
to the former.
A
thing that
is
in succession
and touches
is
[10] 'contiguous'. The 'continuous' is a subdivision of the contiguous: things are called
continuous when the touching limits of each become one and the same and are, as the word implies, contained in each other: continuity is impossible if these extremities are two. This
makes
plain that continuity be-
'contiguous',
definition
in
longs to things that naturally in virtue of their [75] mutual contact form a unity. And in
naturally applicable.
it
PHYSICS
3 o8
whatever way that which holds them together is one, so too will the whole be one, e.g. by a rivet or glue or contact or organic union. obvious that of these terms 'in succesin order of analysis: for that which touches is necessarily in succession, but not It is
sion'
is first
in succession touches: and so property of things prior in [20] definition, e.g. numbers, while contact is not. And if there is continuity there is necessarily contact, but if there is contact, that alone
everything that succession
is
is
a
does not imply continuity: for the extremities may be 'together' without necessarily being one: but they cannot be one without being necessarily together. So natural junction is
of things
coming to be: for the extremities must come into contact if they are to be
last in
necessarily
[25] naturally joined: but things that are in contact are not all naturally joined, while there is no contact clearly there is no natural
junction either. Hence,
if
as
some say
'point'
have an independent existence of their own, it is impossible for the two to be identical: for points can touch while units can [30] only be in succession. Moreover, there can always be something between points (for all lines are intermediate between points), whereas it is not necessary that there should possibly be anything between units: for there can be nothing between the numbers one and
and
'unit'
two.
We have now defined what is meant by 'to227 b gether' and 'apart', 'contact', 'between' and 'in succession', 'contiguous' and 'continuous': and we have shown in what circumstances each of these terms
There are many senses to be 'one': for
we
in
is
applicable.
which motion
use the term 'one' in
said
is
many
senses.
Motion [5]
is
one generically according
different categories to
which
assigned: thus any locomotion cally
any other
with
alteration
is
it
to the
may
be
one generilocomotion, whereas is
different generically
from
loco-
motion.
Motion is one specifically when besides being one generically it also takes place in a species incapable of subdivision: e.g. colour has spedifferences: therefore blackening and whitening differ specifically; but at all events every whitening will be specifically the same with every other whitening and every blackening with every other blackening. But white[10] ness is not further subdivided by specific cific
228*
any whitening
differences: hence
is
specifically
one with any other whitening. Where it happens that the genus is at the same time a species, it is clear that the motion will then in a sense be one specifically though not in an unqualified sense: learning is an example of this, knowledge being on the one hand a species of apprehension and on the other hand a genus including the various knowledges. A difficulty, however, may be raised as to whether a mo[75] tion is specifically one when the same thing changes from the same to the same, e.g. when one point changes again and again from a particular place to a particular place:
motion
is
if
this
motion will motion, and rolling
specifically one, circular
be the same as rectilinear the same as walking. But
is
not this difficulty
removed by the principle already laid down that if that in which the motion takes place is specifically different (as in the present instance
the circular path
is
specifically different
from
[20] the straight) the motion itself is also different? have explained, then, what is
We
meant by saying
that
motion
is
one generically
or one specifically. is one in an unqualified sense when one essentially or numerically: and the
Motion it
is
following distinctions will
make
clear
what
kind of motion is. There are three classes of things in connexion with which we speak of motion, the 'that which', the 'that in which', and the 'that during which'. I mean that there [25] must be something that is in motion, e.g. a man or gold, and it must be in motion in something, e.g. a place or an affection, and during something, for all motion takes place during a time. Of these three it is the thing in which the motion takes place that makes it one generically or specifically, it is the thing moved that makes the motion one in subject, and it is the time that makes it consecutive: but it is the three together that make it one without qualification: to effect this, that in [50] which the motion takes place (the species) must be one and incapable of subdivision, that during which it takes place (the time) must be one and unintermittent, and that which is in motion must be one not in an accidental sense (i.e. it must be one as the white that blackens is one or Coriscus who walks is one, not in the accidental sense in 228 a which Coriscus and white may be one), nor merely in virtue of community of nature (for there might be a case of two men being restored to health at the same time in the same way, e.g. from inflammation of the eye, yet this
—
BOOK
228 b this
motion
cifically
V,
CHAPTERS
not really one, but only spe-
is
one).
Suppose, however, that Socrates undergoes an alteration specifically the same but at one time and again at another: in this case if it is possible for that which ceased to be again to come into being and remain numerically the [5] same, then this motion too will be one: otherwise it will be the same but not one. And
akin to this difficulty there is another; viz. is health one? and generally are the states and
one
affections in bodies severally
them Thus
in essence al-
clear) the things that contain are obviously in motion and in flux?
though (as
is
if a person's health at daybreak and at [10] the present moment is one and the same, why should not this health be numerically one
with that which he recovers after an interval ?
The same argument applies in each case. There is, however, we may answer, this difference: that
if
the states are
two then
it
follows simply
from this fact that the activities must also in point of number be two (for only that which is numerically one can give rise to an activity [75] that is numerically one), but if the state is one, this is not in itself enough to make us regard the activity also as one: for when a man ceases walking, the walking no longer is, but it will again be if he begins to walk again. But, be this as it may, if in the above instance the health is one and the same, then it must be
which
possible for that
come
to be
and
is
one and the same to
to cease to be
many
times.
3-4
309
ends of the two things are one. Hence motions [jo] may be consecutive or successive in virtue of the time being continuous, but there can be continuity only in virtue of the motions themselves being continuous, that is when the end of each is one with the end of the other. Mo228 b tion, therefore, that is in an unqualified sense continuous and one must be specifically the same, of one thing, and in one time. Unity is required in respect of time in order that there may be no interval of immobility, for
where there is intermission of motion there must be rest, and a motion that includes intervals of rest will be not one but many, so that [5] a motion that is interrupted by stationariness is not one or continuous, and it is so interrupted if there is an interval of time. And though of a motion that is not specifically one (even
if
the time
unintermittent) the time
is
and motion that is one [10] must be specifically one, though motion that is specifically one is not necessarily one in an unqualified sense. We have now explained what we mean when we call a motion one is
one, the motion
specifically different,
is
so cannot really be one, for
without qualification. Further, a motion
is
also said to be
nerically, specifically, or essentially
one ge-
when
it is
complete, just as in other cases completeness
and wholeness are
characteristics of
one: and sometimes a motion even plete
is
if
what
is
incom-
said to be one, provided only that
it is
continuous.
ent inquiry.
[75] And besides the cases already mentioned there is another in which a motion is said to be
tion that
[20] Since every motion is continuous, a mois one in an unqualified sense must
motion that
motion is divisible) be continuous, and a continuous motion must be one. There will not be continuity between any motion and any other indiscriminately any more than there is between any two things chosen at random in any other sphere: there can be continuity only when the extremities of the two things are one. Now some things have no extremities at all: and the extremities of others differ spe[25] cifically although we give them the same
that
However, these
difficulties lie
outside our pres-
(since every
name
of 'end':
how
should
e.g.
the 'end' of a
and the 'end' of walking touch or come to be one ? Motions that are not the same either specifically or generically may, it is true, be consecutive (e.g. a man may run and then at once fall ill of a fever), and again, in the line
torch-race we have consecutive but not continuous locomotion: for according to our definition there can be continuity only when the
one, viz.
title
when
it
is
regular: for in a sense a
is not regarded as one, belonging rather to that which is reg-
is
irregular
ular, as a straight line
is
regular, the irregular
being as such divisible. But the difference would seem to be one of degree. In every kind of motion we may have regularity or irregu[20] larity: thus there may be regular alteration, and locomotion in a regular path, e.g. in a circle or on a straight line, and it is the same with regard to increase and decrease. The difference that makes a motion irregular is sometimes to be found in its path: thus a motion cannot be regular if its path is an irregular magnitude, e.g. a broken line, a spiral, or any other magnitude that is not such that any part of it taken at random fits on to any other that [25] may be chosen. Sometimes it is found neither in the place nor in the time nor in the goal but in the manner of the motion: for in some cases the motion is differentiated by
PHYSICS
310 quickness and slowness: thus
if
its
velocity
is
229 b
tion to a contrary or to an intermediate (of
however, we shall speak later), 1 but changing to a contrary rather than changing from a contrary would seem to be the
uniform a motion is regular, if not it is irregular. So quickness and slowness are not species of motion nor do they constitute specific dif-
this,
ferences of motion, because this distinction occurs in connexion with all the distinct species [jo] of motion. The same is true of heaviness
cause of the contrariety of motions, the latter being the loss, the former the gain, of con-
and lightness when they refer to the same thing: e.g. they do not specifically distinguish earth from itself or fire from itself. Irregular 229 a motion, therefore, while in virtue of being continuous gree, as
is
it
is
one,
is
so in a lesser de-
the case with locomotion in a broken
and a lesser degree of something always means an admixture of its contrary. And since
line:
is one can be both regular motions that are consecutive [5] but not specifically the same cannot be one and continuous: for how should a motion composed of alteration and locomotion be regular? If a motion is to be regular its parts ought to fit one another.
every motion that
and
irregular,
[25] trariness. Moreover, each several motion takes its name rather from the goal than from the starting-point of change, e.g. motion to
health
we
call
ease sickening.
convalescence, motion to dis-
Thus we
are left with motions
and motions respecfrom the opposite contraries. Now it would seem that motions to contraries are at the same time motions from contraries (though their essence may not be the same; 'to health' is distinct, I mean, from 'from disease', and 'from health' from 'to disrespectively to contraries,
contraries
to
tively
ease').
[30] Since then change differs from motion (motion being change from a particular subject to a particular subject),
it
follows that con-
trary motions are motions respectively
We have further to determine what motions are contrary to each other, and to determine sim-
with rest. And we have first to decide whether contrary motions are motions
ilarly
how
it is
from and to the same thing, e.g. [10] a motion from health and a motion to health (where the opposition, it would seem, is of the same kind as that between coming to be and ceasing to be); or motions respectively from contraries, e.g. a motion from health and a motion from disease; or motions respectively to contraries, e.g. a motion to health and a motion to disease; or motions respectively from a contrary and to the opposite contrary, e.g. a motion from health and a motion to disease; or motions respectively from a contrary to the opposite contrary and from the latter to the former, e.g. a motion from health to disease and a motion from disease to health: for motions [75] must be contrary to one another in one or more of these ways, as there is no other way in which they can be opposed. Now motions respectively from a contrary and to the opposite contrary, e.g. a motion from health and a motion to disease, are not contrary motions: for they are one and the respectively
same. (Yet their essence
is
not the same, just
changing from health is different from changing to disease.) Nor are motions re[20] spectively from a contrary and from the
as
opposite contrary contrary motions, for a tion from a contrary is at the same time a
momo-
from
a
contrary to the opposite contrary and from the 229 b latter to the former, e.g. a motion from health to disease and a motion from disease to health. Moreover, the consideration of particular
examples will also show what kinds of
processes are generally recognized as contrary:
thus falling ill is regarded as contrary to recov[5] ering one's health, these processes having contrary goals, and being taught as contrary to being led into error by another, it being possible to
one's ilarly
acquire error, like knowledge, either by
own agency or by that of another. Simwe have upward locomotion and down-
ward locomotion, which
are contrary length-
and locomotion which are contrary breadthwise, and forward locomotion and backward locomotion, which too are contraries. On the other wise, locomotion to the right
to the left,
[10]
hand, a process simply to a contrary, that denoted by the expression 'becom-
e.g.
ing white', where no starting-point is specified, is a change but not a motion. And in all cases of a thing that has no contrary we
have as contraries change from and change to the
same
thing.
Thus coming
to be
is
contrary
and losing to gaining. But these are changes and not motions. And wher[75] ever a pair of contraries admit of an intermediate, motions to that intermediate must be held to be in a sense motions to one or other of to ceasing to be,
the contraries: for the intermediate serves as a contrary for the purposes of the motion, in 1
1.
28 sqq.
BOOK
230b
V,
CHAPTERS
whichever direction the change may be, e.g. grey in a motion from grey to white takes the place of black as starting-point, in a motion from white to grey it takes the place of black as goal, and in a motion from black to grey it takes the place of white as goal: for the middle [20] is opposed in a sense to either of the ex1 tremes, as has been said above. Thus we see that two motions are contrary to each other only when one is a motion from a contrary to the opposite contrary and the other is a motion
from the
latter to the
former.
4-6
3"
[10] there be a particular subject, absence of change in its being will be contrary to absence its not-being. And here a difficulty be raised: if not-being is not a particular something, what is it, it may be asked, that is contrary to absence of change in a thing's being? and is this absence of change a state of rest? If it is, then either it is not true that every state of rest is contrary to a motion or else
of change in
may
coming
to be
and ceasing
to be are motion.
[75] It is clear then that, since we exclude these from among motions, we must not say that this absence of change
we must But since a motion appears to have contrary it not only another motion but also a state of rest, we must determine how this is so. A motion has for its contrary in the strict sense of the term another motion, but it also has for an opposite a state of rest (for rest is the priva[25] tion of motion and the privation of anything may be called its contrary), and motion of one kind has for its opposite rest of that kind, e.g. local motion has local rest. This statement, however, needs further qualification: there remains the question, is the opposite of remaining at a particular place motion from or motion to that place? It is surely clear that since there are two subjects between which [jo] motion takes place, motion from one of these (A) to its contrary (B) has for its opposite remaining in A, while the reverse motion has for its opposite remaining in B. At the same time these two are also contrary to each other: to
for
would be absurd to suppose that there and not opposite states of
it
are contrary motions
230*
of rest in contraries are optake an example, a state of rest in ( 1 ) contrary to a state of rest in dis-
rest. States
posed.
To
health
is
and (2) the motion to which it is conis that from health to disease. For (2) it would be absurd that its contrary motion should be that from disease to health, since motion to that in which a thing is at rest is [5] rather a coming to rest, the coming to rest being found to come into being simultaneously with the motion; and one of these two motions it must be. And (1) rest in whiteness is of ease,
trary
and
call
say that it
it is
is
a state of rest:
similar to a state of rest
absence of change.
And
change from it and the thing's coming to be is change to it. Again, a further difficulty may be raised. How is it, it may be asked, that whereas in local change both remaining and moving may [20] be natural or unnatural, in the other changes this is not so? e.g. alteration is not now
and now unnatural, for convalescence no more natural or unnatural than falling ill, whitening no more natural or unnatural than blackening; so, too, with increase and decrease: natural is
these are not contrary to each other in the sense
[25] that either of them is natural while the other is unnatural, nor is one increase contrary to
another in this sense; and the same account be given of becoming and perishing: it is
may
not true that becoming
is natural and perishing unnatural (for growing old is natural), nor do we observe one becoming to be natural
and another unnatural. We answer that if [50] what happens under violence is unnatural, then violent perishing is unnatural and as such contrary to natural perishing. Are there then also some becomings that are violent and not the result of natural necessity, and are therefore contrary to natural becomings, and 230 b violent increases and decreases, e.g. the rapid growth to maturity of profligates and the rapid ripening of seeds even when not packed close in the earth?
And how
is it
[5] urally according as they
throw
from being and change
the critical days or not. But,
it
such things there is no remaining though there is absence of change. Should
tion. So, too, of
some
with
we may
tions? Surely just the same:
no mo-
will have
its
course not contrary to rest in health. Of all things that have no contraries there are opposite changes (viz. change from the thing and change to the thing, e.g. change to being), but
it
contrary either nothing or absence of change in the thing's not-being, or the ceasing to be of the thing: for such ceasing to be is for
altera-
say that
alterations are violent while others are
natural, e.g. patients alter naturally or unnat-
may
off fevers
on
be objected, then we shall have perishings contrary to one another, not to becoming. Certainly: and why should not this in a sense be so? Thus it is so if
PHYSICS
3 12
one perishing is pleasant and another painful: and so one perishing will be contrary to another not in an unqualified sense, but in so far as one has this quality and the other that. [10] Now motions and states of rest universalthe manner described upward motion and rest above are
ly exhibit contrariety in 1
above, e.g.
downward motion and
respectively contrary to
below, these being instances of local conand upward locomotion belongs nat-
rest
trariety;
urally to fire
and downward
to earth,
i.e.
the
locomotions of the two are contrary to each other.
And
down
unnaturally: and
moves up naturally and its natural motion is contrary to its unnatural mo-
again, fire
[75] certainly Similarly
with remaining: remaining above is contrary to motion from above downwards, and to earth this remaining comes unnaturally, this motion naturally. So the unnatural remaining of a thing is contrary to its natural motion, just as we find a similar contion.
[20] trariety in the motion of the same thing: one of its motions, the upward or the downward, will be natural, the other unnatural. Here, however, the question arises, has every state of rest that is not permanent a becoming,
and
is
this
If so, there
at
is
becoming a coming to a standstill ? must be a becoming of that which unnaturally, e.g. of earth at rest
rest
23 1«
it still appears to have that which is [30] being discarded, so that if a state of rest is itself contrary to the motion from the state
thing,
of rest to its contrary, the contraries rest and motion will be simultaneously predicable of the same thing. May we not say, however, that in so far as the thing
is still
stationary
it is
in a
state of rest in a qualified sense? For, in fact,
whenever
a thing
is
in
motion, part of
the starting-point while part
is
it is
at
at the goal to
23 a which it is changing: and consequently a motion finds its true contrary rather in another motion than in a state of rest. With regard to motion and rest, then, we have now explained in what sense each of them is one and under what conditions they exhibit contrariety.
[With regard
to coming to a standstill the be raised whether there is an opposite state of rest to unnatural as well as to natural motions. It would be absurd if this
[5]
question
may
were not the case: for a thing may remain still merely under violence: thus we shall have a thing being in a non-permanent state of rest without having become so. But it is clear that it must be the case: for just as there is unnatural motion, so, too, a thing may be in an un[10] natural state of rest. Further, some things have a natural and an unnatural motion,
coming
to a standstill.
has a natural upward motion and an unnatural downward motion: is it, then, this unnatural downward motion or is it the nat-
of that
which comes
ural
above: and therefore this earth during the time that it was being carried violently upward was
But whereas the velocity to a standstill seems always to increase, the velocity of that which is [25] carried violently seems always to decrease: so it will be in a state of rest without having become so. Moreover 'coming to a standstill' is generally tical
recognized to be iden-
or at least concomitant with the locomo-
proper place. There is also another difficulty involved in the view that remaining in a particular place is
tion of a thing to
its
contrary to motion from that place. For
a thing
is
moving from
when
or discarding some-
e.g. fire
downward motion of earth that is contrary upward motion? Surely it is
to the natural
it though not in motion of earth is contrary inasmuch as the motion of fire is [75] also natural, whereas the upward motion
clear that both are contrary to
the
same
of fire
sense: the natural
as
being natural
remaining. But there would seem to be a sense in
which a
state of rest
understood as defined above 2 being 'continuous' if their extrem-
'in succession' are
ities
are one, 'in contact'
together,
of their 1
and
own
In chapter
5.
if
their extremities are
nothing kind intermediate between them 'in succession' if
2 v. 3.
there
is
a
motion are op-
VI
—nothing that
—things
and
posites.]
BOOK Now if the terms 'continuous', 'in contact', and
contrary to the
is
downward motion of fire as being unnatural. The same is true of the corresponding cases of
is
continuous can be composed
[25] of indivisibles: e.g. a line cannot be composed of points, the line being continuous and the point indivisible. For the extremities of
two points can neither be one (since of an indivisible there can be no extremity as distinct from some other part) nor together (since that which has no parts can have no extremity, the
BOOK
232*
V,
CHAPTER 6— BOOK
extremity and the thing of which it is the extremity being distinct). Moreover, if that which is continuous is [_?o] composed of points, these points must be either continuous or in contact with
one anand the same reasoning applies in the
other:
231^ case
of
all indivisibles.
Now
for the rea-
son given above they cannot be continuous: and one thing can be in contact with another only if whole is in contact with whole or part with part or part with whole. But since indivisibles have no parts, they must be in contact with one another as whole with whole. And if they are in contact with one another as whole with whole, they will not be continuous: [5] for that which is continuous has distinct
and these parts
parts:
into
are different in this way,
which
i.e.
Nor, again, can a point be
it is
divisible
spatially separate.
in succession to a
point or a moment to a moment in such a way that length can be composed of points or time of
moments:
for things are in succession
if
nothing of their own kind intermediate between them, whereas that which is intermediate between points is always a line and that which is intermediate between moments is always a period of time. [10] Again, if length and time could thus be composed of indivisibles, they could be divided into indivisibles, since each is divisible into the parts of which it is composed. But, as we saw, no continuous thing is divisible into things without parts. Nor can there be anything of any other kind intermediate between the parts or between the moments: for if there could be any such thing it is clear that it must be either there
is
indivisible or divisible, it
must be
and
if
it
is
divisible,
divisible either into indivisibles or
into divisibles that are infinitely divisible, in
which
case
it is
[75] Moreover,
tinuous
is
continuous. it is
divisible
plain that everything coninto divisibles
that are
were divisible into indivisibles, we should have an indivisible in contact with an indivisible, since the extremities of things that are continuous with one another are one and are in contact. The same reasoning applies equally to magnitude, to time, and to motion: either all of these are composed of indivisibles and are divisible into indivisibles, or none. This may be [20] made clear as follows. If a magnitude is composed of indivisibles, the motion over that magnitude must be composed of corresponding indivisible motions: e.g. if the magnitude ABr is composed of the indivisibles A, B, I\ infinitely divisible: for if
it
VI,
CHAPTER
1
313
each corresponding part of the motion AEZ [25] of 12 over ABr is indivisible. Therefore, since where there is motion there must be something that is in motion, and where there is something in motion there must be motion, therefore the being-moved will also be com-
posed of indivisibles. So 12 traversed A when its motion was A, B when its motion was E,
and T similarly when its motion was Z. Now a thing that is in motion from one place to another cannot at the moment when it was in motion both be in motion and at the same time have completed its motion at the place to which it was in motion: e.g. if a man is walking to Thebes, he cannot be walking to Thebes [30] and at the same time have completed his walk to Thebes: and, as we saw, 12 traverses 232 a the partless section A in virtue of the presence of the motion A. Consequently, if 12 actually passed through A after being in process of passing through, the motion must be divisible: for at the time when 12 was passing through, it neither was at rest nor had completed its passage but was in an intermediate state: while if it is passing through and has completed its passage at the same moment, [5] then that which is walking will at the moment when it is walking have completed its walk and will be in the place to which it is walking; that is to say, it will have completed its motion at the place to which it is in motion. And if a thing is in motion over the whole ABT and its motion is the three A, E, and Z, and if it is not in motion at all over the partless section A but has completed its motion over it, then the motion will consist not of motions but of starts, and will take place by a thing's having completed a motion without being in motion: for on this assumption it has completed its passage through A without pass[10] ing through it. So it will be possible for a thing to have completed a walk without ever walking: for on this assumption it has completed a walk over a particular distance without walking over that distance. Since, then, everything must be either at rest or in motion, and 12 is therefore at rest in each of the sections A, B, and T, it follows that a thing can be continuously at rest and at the same time in motion: for, as we saw, 12 is in motion over the whole ABr and at rest in any part (and conse[75] quently in the whole) of it. Moreover, if the indivisibles composing AEZ are motions, it would be possible for a thing in spite of the presence in it of motion to be not in motion but at rest, while if they are not motions, it would
PHYSICS
3M
be possible for motion to be composed of something other than motions. And if length and motion are thus indivisible, it is neither more nor less necessary that
time also be similarly indivisible, that
is
to
composed of indivisible moments: for if [20] the whole distance is divisible and an
say be
equal
will
velocity
through
less of
it
cause
thing
a
in less time, the
to
also be divisible,
and conversely,
which
carried over the section
a thing
is
divisible, this section
And
since every
magnitudes
—
for
A
must
magnitude
if
pass
time must the time in
A
is
also be divisible.
is
divisible into
we have shown
that
it is
im-
possible for anything continuous to be composed of indivisible parts, and every magniit necessarily follows [25] tude is continuous that the quicker of two things traverses a greater magnitude in an equal time, an equal
—
and
magni-
magnitude
in less time,
tude in
time, in conformity with the defi-
less
a greater
nition sometimes given of 'the quicker'. Sup-
A
is quicker than B. Now since of pose that two things that which changes sooner is quicker, in the time ZH, in which A has [50] changed from T to A, B will not yet have arrived at A but will be short of it: so that in an equal time the quicker will pass over a greater magnitude. More than this, it will pass over a greater magnitude in less time: for in has arrived at A, B being the time in which
A
let us say, at E. Then in has occupied the whole time 23 b arriving at A, it will have arrived at in less time than this, say ZK. Now the magnitude TO that A has passed over is greater than the magnitude TE, and the time ZK is less than the whole time ZH: so that the quicker
the slower has arrived, since
ZH
A
will pass over a greater
[5]
And from
this
it
magnitude is
in less time.
also clear that the
quicker will pass over an equal magnitude in less time than the slower. For since it passes over the greater magnitude in less time than the slower, and (regarded by itself) passes over the greater in more time than AH the lesser, the time IIP in which it passes over will be more than the time IIS in which [10] it passes over AS: so that, the time IIP being less than the time IIX in which the slower passes over AS, the time H£ will also be less than the time IIX: for it is less than the time IIP, and that which is less than something else that is less than a thing is also itself less than that thing. Hence it follows that the
AM AM
233*
quicker will traverse an equal magnitude in less time than the slower. Again, since the mot/5] tion of anything must always occupy either an equal time or less or more time in comparison with that of another thing, and since, whereas a thing is slower if its motion occupies more time and of equal velocity if its motion occupies an equal time, the quicker is neither of equal velocity nor slower, it follows that the motion of the quicker can occupy neither an equal time nor more time. It can only be, then, that it occupies less time, and thus we get the necessary consequence that the quicker will pass over an equal magnitude [20] (as well as a greater) in less time than the slower.
And since every motion is in time and a momay occupy any time, and the motion of everything that is in motion may be either tion
quicker or slower, both quicker motion and slower motion may occupy any time: and this being so, it necessarily follows that time also is continuous. By continuous I mean that which is
divisible into divisibles that are infinitely
[25] divisible: and if we take this as the definition of continuous, it follows necessarily that
time
is
continuous. For since
it
has been
shown mag-
that the quicker will pass over an equal
less time than the slower, suppose quicker and B slower, and that the [50] slower has traversed the magnitude TA in the time ZH. Now it is clear that the quicker will traverse the same magnitude in less time than this: let us say in the time Z9. Again, since the quicker has passed over the whole TA in the time ZO, the slower will in the same time pass over TK, say, which is less 233 a than TA. And since B, the slower, has passed over TK in the time Z6, the quicker will pass over it in less time: so that the time ZO will again be divided. And if this is diwill also be divided vided the magnitude just as TA was: and again, if the magnitude is divided, the time will also be divided. And [5] we can carry on this process for ever, taking the slower after the quicker and the quicker after the slower alternately, and using what has been demonstrated at each stage as a new point of departure: for the quicker will divide the time and the slower will divide the length. If, then, this alternation always holds good, and at every turn involves a division, it [10] is evident that all time must be continuous. And at the same time it is clear that all magnitude is also continuous; for the divisions of which time and magnitude respec-
nitude in that
A
is
TK
BOOK
233 b
VI,
CHAPTERS
same and equal. Moreover, the current popular arguments make it plain that, if time is continuous, magnitude is continuous also, inasmuch as a thing passes over half a given magnitude in half the lively are susceptible are the
[75] time taken to cover the whole: in fact without qualification it passes over a less magnitude in less time; for the divisions of time and of magnitude will be the same. And if either is infinite, so is the other, and the one is so in the same way as the other; i.e. if time is infinite in respect of
its
extremities, length
also infinite in respect of
time
is
infinite
[20] length
and magnitude
bility:
respect
in
extremities:
its
of
is
if
divisibility,
also infinite in respect of divisi-
is
both respects,
if
time
is
also infinite in both respects.
is
infinite in
Hence Zeno's argument makes
a false as-
sumption in asserting that it is impossible for a thing to pass over or severally to come in contact with infinite things in a finite time. For there are two senses in which length and time and generally anything continuous are called
[25]
'infinite':
they are called so either in re-
spect of divisibility or in respect of their ex-
So while a thing in a finite time cannot come in contact with things quantitatively infinite, it can come in contact with things intremities.
finite in respect of divisibility: for in this sense
and
we
1-3
magnitude
3i5
Moreover, if it is the case that infinite time is not occupied in passing over every magnitude, but it is possible to pass over some magnitude, say BE, in a finite [10] time, and if this BE measures the whole of which it is a part, and if an equal magnitude is passed over in an equal time, then it follows that the time like the magnitude is finite. That infinite time will not be occupied in passing over BE is evident if the time be taken as limited in one direction: for as the part will be passed over in less time than the whole, the time occupied in traversing this part must be finite, the limit in one direction being given. The same reasoning will also show the falsity of the assumption that infinite length can be divisible.
is
[75] traversed in a finite time. It is evident, then, from what has been said that neither a line nor a surface nor in fact anything continuous can be indivisible. This conclusion follows not only from the present argument but from the consideration that the opposite assumption implies the di-
For since the disand slower may apply to [20] motions occupying any period of time and in an equal time the quicker passes over a greater length, it may happen that it will pass over a length twice, or one and a half times, as visibility of the indivisible.
tinction of quicker
find
great as that passed over by the slower: for
that the time occupied by the passage over the
their respective velocities may stand to one another in this proportion. Suppose, then, that the quicker has in the same time been carried over a length one and a half times as great as that traversed by the slower, and that the re-
the time
itself is also infinite:
so
not a finite but an infinite time, and the contact with the infinites is made by means of moments not finite but infinite in [jo] infinite
is
number.
The passage over the infinite, then, cannot occupy a finite time, and the passage over the finite cannot occupy an infinite time: if the time is infinite the magnitude must be infinite also,
and
if
the
magnitude
may
is
infinite, so also is
shown
spective magnitudes are divided, that of the quicker, the magnitude ABrA, into three indivisibles,
and
that of the slower into the
two
[25] indivisibles EZ, ZH. Then the time may also be divided into three indivisibles, for an
be the segment that it has thus passed over. (This will be either an exact measure of AB or less or greater than an exact measure: it makes no difference which it is.)
equal magnitude will be passed over in an equal time. Suppose then that it is thus divided into KA, AM, MN. Again, since in the same time the slower has been carried over EZ, ZH, the time may also be similarly divided into two. Thus the indivisible will be divisible, and that [jo] which has no parts will be passed over not in an indivisible but in a greater time. It is evident, therefore, that nothing continuous is without parts.
Then, since a magnitude equal to BE will always be passed over in an equal time, and BE [5] measures the whole magnitude, the whole
The
the time. This
be
as follows.
Let
AB
be a finite magnitude, and let us suppose that it is traversed in infinite time T, and let [_J5J a finite period TA of the time be taken. 233 b Now in this period the thing in motion will pass over a certain
tude:
let
segment of the magni-
BE
time occupied in passing over AB will be finite: for it will be divisible into periods equal in number to the segments into which the
present also
—
is necessarily indivisible the not in the sense in which the word is applied to one thing in virtue of another, but in its proper and primary sense; in
present, that
is,
PHYSICS
7l6
inherent in all time. For something that is an extremity of the past (no part of the future being on this side of it) and also of the future (no part of the past being on the other side of it): it is, as we have said, a limit of both. And if it is once shown that it is essentially of this character and one and the same, it will at once [55] which sense 234* the present
ersing
is
present, whereas
be evident also that it is indivisible. [5] Now the present that is the extremity of
both times must be one and the same: for if each extremity were different, the one could not be in succession to the other, because nothing continuous can be composed of things having no parts: and if the one is apart from the other, there will be time intermediate between them, because everything continuous is such that there is something intermediate between its limits and described by the same name as itself. But if the intermediate thing is time, it will be 2 [10] divisible: for all time has been shown to be divisible. Thus on this assumption the is
divisible.
But
if
the present
is
divisi-
be part of the past in the future and part of the future in the past: for past time will be marked off from future time at the actual point of division. Also the present will [75] be a present not in the proper sense but in ble, there will
virtue of something else: for the division yields
it
which
will not be a division proper. Further-
more, there will be a part of the present that
is
and a part that is future, and it will not always be the same part that is past or future: in fact one and the same present will not be past
simultaneous: for the time
may
be divided at many points. If, therefore, the present cannot possibly have these characteristics, it follows that it must be the same present that belongs [20] to each of the two times. But if this is so it is evident that the present is also indivisible: for if it is divisible it will be involved in the
same implications as before. It is clear, then, from what has been said that time contains something indivisible, and this is what we call a present.
We
will
now show
that nothing can be in
[25] motion in a present. For if this is possible, there can be both quicker and slower motion in the present.
N
Suppose then that
in the present
AB.
the quicker has traversed the distance
That being
so,
the slower will in the
present traverse a distance less than
AT. But the
same
AB,
say
since the slower will have occupied
whole
Thus we shall have we found it
it is
1
present
234b
present
in
traversing
Ar,
the
[50] quicker will occupy less than this in trav1 2 Chapter 222a 12. 2.
it.
impossible, therefore, for anything to be
It is
motion
in
a division of the to be indivisible.
in a present.
Nor can anything be at rest in a present: 3 as we were saying, that only can be at
for,
rest
which
is naturally designed to be in motion but not in motion when, where, or as it would naturally be so: since, therefore, nothing is is
naturally designed to be in motion in a present, that nothing can be at rest in a
clear
is
it
present either.
Moreover, inasmuch as
it is
the
same present
[35] that belongs to both the times, and it is possible for a thing to be in motion throughout
one time and to be at rest throughout the other, and that which is in motion or at rest for the whole of a time will be in motion or at rest as the case may be in any part of it
234 b
in
which
it
is
naturally designed to be in
mo-
tion or at rest: this being so, the assumption
motion or
that there can be will carry
with
rest in a present
the implication that the
it
same
thing can at the same time be at rest and in motion: for both the times have the same extremity, viz. the present. [5] Again,
we imply part
is
what
it
when we that
its
say that a thing is at rest, condition in whole and in
time of speaking uniform with was previously: but the present con-
at the
no 'previously': consequently, there can be no rest in it. It follows then that the motion of that which
tains
in
is
rest
motion and the rest must occupy time.
of that
which
is
at
[10] Further, everything that changes must be For since every change is from some-
divisible.
thing to something, and when a thing is at the goal of its change it is no longer changing, and when both it itself and all its parts are at the starting-point of (for that
which
its is
change it is not changing whole and in part in an
in
unvarying condition is not in a state of [75] change); it follows, therefore, that part of that which is changing must be at the startingpoint and part at the goal: for as a whole it cannot be in both or in neither. (Here by 'goal of change' I mean that which comes first in the process of change: e.g. in a process of change from white the goal in question will be grey, not black: for
it is
not necessary that that which
[20] is changing should be at either of the extremes.) It is evident, therefore, that 8
226 b 12 sqq.
BOOK
235 b
everything that changes must be
.
VI,
CHAPTERS
divisible.
Now motion is divisible in two senses. In the first
place
that
it
it is
time
divisible in virtue of the
occupies. In the second place
it is
divis-
according to the motions of the several which is in motion: e.g. if the whole Ar is in motion, there will be a motion of AB and a motion of Br. That being so, let ible
parts of that
AB
and EZ the be the motion of the part [25] motion of the part BI\ Then the whole AZ must be the motion of Ar: for AZ must
AE
constitute the
and of
parts.
its
AT
[75] follows that the time, the motion, the being-in-motion, the thing that is in motion,
and the sphere of the motion must all be sussame divisions (though spheres of motion are not all divisible in a like man-
ceptible of the
AE
ner: thus quantity
dentally divisible).
inasmuch
as
But the motion of a thing can never
be constituted by the motion of something else: consequently the whole motion is the mo-
whole magnitude. Again, since every motion is a motion of something, and the whole motion AZ is not the motion of either of the parts (for each of the parts AE, EZ is the motion of one of the [30] parts AB, Br ) or of anything else (for, the whole motion being the motion of a whole, the parts of the motion are the motions of the parts of that whole: and the parts of AZ are the motions of AB, Br and of nothing else: 1 for, as we saw, a motion that is one cannot be the motion of more things than one): since this is so, the whole motion will be the motion tion of the
magnitude ABI\
of the
3i7
motion is in time and all time is divisible, and in less time the motion is less, it follows that every motion must be divisible according to time. And since everything that is in motion is in motion in a certain sphere and for a certain time and has a motion belonging to it, it all
constitute the motions of each
motion of
EZ severally
3-4
essentially, quality acci-
is
For suppose that A is the time occupied by the motion B. Then if all the [20] time has been occupied by the whole motion, it will take less of the motion to occupy half the time, less again to occupy a further subdivision of the time, and so on to infinity. Again, the time will be divisible similarly to the motion: for if the whole motion occupies all the time half the motion will occupy half the time, and less of the motion again will occupy less of the time. [25] In the same way the being-in-motion will also be divisible.
For
Then
in-motion.
let
the
T
be the whole beingbeing-in-motion that
corresponds to half the motion will be less than the whole being-in-motion, that which corresponds to a quarter of the motion will be less
again,
and
so
on
to infinity.
Moreover by
Again, if there is a motion of the whole other than AZ, say 01, the motion of each of the parts may be subtracted from it: and these [55] motions will be equal to AE, EZ respec-
out successively the being-in-motion corresponding to each of the two motions Ar (say) and TE, we may argue that the whole
235 a tively: for the motion of that which is one must be one. So if the whole motion 01
whole motion (for
may
be divided into the motions of the parts, AZ: if on the other hand there is any remainder, say KI, this will be a
01
will be equal to
[5] motion of nothing: for it can be the motion neither of the whole nor of the parts (as
setting
[jo] being-in-motion will correspond to the if it were some other beingin-motion that corresponded to the whole motion, there would be more than one being-inmotion corresponding to the same motion), the argument being the same as that whereby
we showed 2
the motion of that which is one must be one) nor of anything else: for a motion that is con-
thing: for
tinuous must be the motion of things that are continuous. And the same result follows if the
tions,
01
division of
reveals a surplus
on the
the motions of the parts. Consequently, impossible, the whole motion
is
same
as
and equal
to
side of if
this
must be the
AZ.
This then is what is meant by the division of motion according to the motions of the
must be applicable
parts:
and
that
divisible into parts.
is
it
to everything
[10] Motion is also susceptible of another kind of division, that according to time. For since 1
223b
1
sqq.
if
motion of a thing is dimotions of the parts of the
that the
visible into the
we
take separately the being-in-
motion corresponding
we
motion
two mowhole being-in-
to each of the
shall see that the
continuous. reasoning will show the divisibility of the length, and in fact of everything that forms a sphere of change (though some is
The same
[55] of these are only accidentally divisible because that which changes is so): for the division of one term will involve the division of all.
So, too, in the matter of their being finite
or infinite, they will
all
alike be either the
one
235 b or the other. And we now see that in most cases the fact that all the terms are divisi2
b 234 24
sqq., especially
234b
34 sqq.
PHYSICS
3 i8
consequence of the that the thing that changes is divisible or
ble or infinite fact
infinite:
is
a direct
for the attributes 'divisible'
and
'in-
belong in the first instance to the thing [5] that changes. That divisibility does so we have already shown: that infinity does so will 2 be made clear in what follows. finite'
1
Since everything that changes changes from something to something, that which has changed must at the moment when it has first changed be in that to which it has changed. For
which changes retires from or leaves that from which it changes: and leaving, if not identical with changing, is at any rate a con-
that
[10] sequence of
And
it.
if
leaving
is
a conse-
quence of changing, having left is a consequence of having changed: for there is a like relation between the two in each case. One kind of change, then, being change in a relation of contradiction, where a thing has changed from not-being to being it has left [75] not-being. Therefore it will be in being: for everything must either be or not be. It is evident, then, that in contradictory change that which has changed must be in that to which it has changed. And if this is true in this kind of change,
it
will be true in all other kinds as
what holds good in the good likewise in the case
well: for in this matter
case of one will hold
of the rest.
Moreover,
if
we
take each kind of change
separately, the truth of our conclusion will be
equally evident, on the ground that that which
has changed must be somewhere or in some[20] thing. For, since it has left that from which
has changed and must be somewhere, it must be either in that to which it has changed or in something else. If, then, that which has changed to B is in something other than B, say T, it must again be changing from T to B: for it cannot be assumed that there is no interval be-
it
[25] ous.
tween T and B, since change is continuThus we have the result that the thing
moment when it has changed, is changing to that to which it has changed, which is impossible: that which has changed, therefore, must be in that to which it has changed. So it is evident likewise that that that has changed, at the
which has come
to be, at the
moment when
it
has come to be, will be, and that which has ceased to be will not-be: for what we have said applies universally to every kind of change, and its truth is most obvious in the case of *
Chapter
7.
236«
[30] contradictory change. It is clear, then, that that which has changed, at the moment
when
it has first changed, has changed.
is
in that to
which
it
We
will now show that the 'primary when' which that which has changed effected the completion of its change must be indivisible, where by 'primary' I mean possessing the characteristics in question of itself and not in virtue of the possession of them by something else belonging to it. For let AT be divisible, and [55] let it be divided at B. If then the completion of change has been effected in AB or again in BI\ AT cannot be the primary thing in which the completion of change has been effected. If, on the other hand, it has been changing in both AB and Br (for it must either have changed or be changing in each of 236a them), it must have been changing in the whole Ar: but our assumption was that
in
AT
only the completion of the equally impossible to suppose that one part of Ar contains the process and the other the completion of the change: for then contains
change.
It is
we
shall have something prior to what is primary. So that in which the completion of change has been effected must be indivisible.
[5]
It
is
also evident, therefore, that that in
which that which has ceased to be has ceased to be and that in which that which has come to be has come to be are indivisible. But there are two senses of the expression 'the primary when in which something has changed'. On the one hand it may mean the primary when containing the completion of the process of change the moment when it is correct to say 'it has changed': on the other hand it may mean the primary when containing the beginning of the process of change. Now the [10] primary when that has reference to the end of the change is something really existent: for a change may really be completed, and there is such a thing as an end of change, which we have in fact shown to be indivisible because it is a limit. But that which has reference to the beginning is not existent at all: for there is no such thing as a beginning of a process of change, and the time occupied by the change does not contain any primary when [75] in which the change began. For suppose that AA is such a primary when. Then it can-
—
not be indivisible: for, if it were, the moment immediately preceding the change and the moment in which the change begins would be consecutive (and moments cannot be consecutive). Again, if the changing thing is at
BOOK
237' rest in the
may
TA
whole preceding time
suppose that
AA
at rest),
it is
it is
VI,
(for
CHAPTERS
we
at rest in
A
without parts, it will simultaneously be at rest and have changed: for it is [20] at rest in A and has changed in A. Since then AA is not without parts, it must be divisible, and the changing thing must have also: so if
changed changed
AA
in
every part of
it
(for
if
it
has
two parts into which has not changed in the whole
in neither of the
divided,
is
either:
is
if,
it
on the other hand,
in process of
it is
change in both parts, it is likewise in process of change in the whole: and if, again, it has changed in one of the two parts, the whole is not the primary when in which it has changed: [25] it must therefore have changed in every part). It is evident, then, that with reference to the beginning of change there is no primary when in which change has been effected: for the divisions are infinite. So, too, of that which has changed there is no primary part that has changed. For suppose that of AE the primary part that has changed is AZ (everything that changes having been [jo] shown to be divisible): and let GI be the time in which AZ has changed. If, then, in the whole time AZ has changed, in half the time 1
there will be a part that has changed, less than
AZ: and again there and yet aninfinity. Thus of that which
and therefore prior
to
will be another part prior to this,
and
other,
so
on
to
changes there cannot be any primary part that [55] has changed. It is evident, then, from what has been said, that neither of that which changes nor of the time in which it changes is there any primary part. 236 b With regard, however, to the actual subthat is to say that in respect of ject of change which a thing changes there is a difference to be observed. For in a process of change we may distinguish three terms that which changes,
—
— —
which it changes, and the actual subchange, e.g. the man, the time, and the fair complexion. Of these the man and the time [5] are divisible: but with the fair complexion it is otherwise (though they are all divisible that in
ject of
which the
fair coman accident is For of actual subjects of change it
accidentally, for that in
plexion or any other quality divisible).
will be seen that those
is
which are
classed as es-
not accidentally, divisible have no [10] primary part. Take the case of magnitudes: let AB be a magnitude, and suppose that it has moved from B to a primary 'where' T. Then if Br is taken to be indivisible, two sentially,
1
234
b iosqq.
4-6
3*9
things without parts will have to be contiguous (which is impossible): if on the other hand it
taken to be divisible, there will be something to T to which the magnitude has changed, and something else again prior to that, and so on to infinity, because the process [75] of division may be continued without end. Thus there can be no primary 'where' to which a thing has changed. And if we take the case of quantitative change, we shall get a like result, for here too the change is in something continuous. It is evident, then, that only in qualitative motion can there be anything essenis
prior
tially indivisible.
[20] time,
Now everything that and that
in
two
changes changes in
senses: for the time in
which a thing is said to change may be the primary time, or on the other hand it may have an extended reference, as e.g. when we say that a thing changes in a particular year because it changes in a particular day. That being so, that which changes must be changing in any part of the primary time in which it changes. This is clear from our definition of 2
'primary', in
which the word
may
is
said to express
however, be made evident by the following argument. Let XP be the pri[25] mary time in which that which is in motion is in motion: and (as all time is divisible) let it be divided at K. Now in the time it either is in motion or is not in motion, and the same is likewise true of the time KP. Then if it is in motion in neither of the two parts, it will be at rest in the whole: for it is impossible that it should be in motion in a time in no [50] part of which it is in motion. If on the other hand it is in motion in only one of the two parts of the time, XP cannot be the primary time in which it is in motion: for its motion will have reference to a time other than XP. It must, then, have been in motion in any part of XP. And now that this has been proved, it is evident that everything that is in motion must have been in motion before. For if that which is in motion has traversed the distance KA in [55] the primary time XP, in half the time a thing that is in motion with equal velocity and began its motion at the same time will have traversed half the distance. But if this second thing whose velocity is equal has traversed a just this:
it
also,
XK
237 a
certain distance in a certain time, the
original
thing that
is
in
motion must have
PHYSICS
320
same distance in the same time. which is in motion must have been
traversed the
Hence
that
Again, if by taking the extreme moment of for it is the moment that defines [5] the time the time, and time is that which is intermediwe are enabled to say ate between moments that motion has taken place in the whole time XP or in fact in any period of it, motion may likewise be said to have taken place in every other such period. But half the time finds an extreme in the point of division. Therefore motion will have taken place in half the time and in fact in any part of it: for as soon as any division is made there is always a time defined by moments. If, then, all time is divisible, and [10] that which is intermediate between moments is time, everything that is changing must have completed an infinite number of changes. Again, since a thing that changes continuously and has not perished or ceased from its change must either be changing or have changed in any part of the time of its change,
—
—
and it
since
it
cannot be changing in a moment, it must have changed at every
follows that
[75] moment in the time: consequently, since the moments are infinite in number, every-
thing that infinite
is
changing must have completed an
number
of changes.
And not only must that which is changing have changed, but that which has changed must also previously have been changing, since everything that has changed from something [20] to something has changed in a period of time. For suppose that a thing has changed from A to B in a moment. Now the moment in which it has changed cannot be the same as that in which it is at A (since in that case it would be in A and B at once): for we have shown above that that which has changed, when it has changed, is not in that from which it has changed. If, on the other hand, it is a different moment, there will be a period of time intermediate between the two: for, as we 1
saw,
2
moments
are not consecutive. Since, then,
[25] it has changed in a period of time, and all time is divisible, in half the time it will have completed another change, in a quarter another, and so on to infinity: consequently when it has changed, it must have previously been changing. Moreover, the truth of what has been said is more evident in the case of magnitude, because [jo] the magnitude over which what is changing changes is continuous. For suppose that a 1
b 235 6sqq.
thing has changed from F to A. Then if TA is indivisible, two things without parts will be consecutive. But since this
motion before.
in
237 b
2
23i b 6sqq.
is
impossible, that
which is intermediate between them must be a magnitude and divisible into an infinite numsegments: consequently, before the completed, the thing changes to those segments. Everything that has changed, therefore, must previously have been changing: for [55] the same proof also holds good of change 237 b with respect to what is not continuous, changes, that is to say, between contraries and ber
of
change
is
between contradictories. In such cases we have only to take the time in which a thing has changed and again apply the same reasoning. So that which has changed must have been changing and that which is changing must have changed, and a process of change is preceded by a completion of change and a com[5] pletion by a process: and we can never take any stage and say that it is absolutely the first. The reason of this is that no two things without parts can be contiguous, and therefore in change the process of division is infinite, just as lines may be infinitely divided so that one part
is
continually increasing and the other
continually decreasing. [10] So it is evident also that that which has become must previously have been in process of becoming, and that which is in process of becoming must previously have become, everything (that is) that is divisible and continuous: though it is not always the actual thing that is in process of becoming of which this is true:
sometimes
it is
something
some part of the thing
else,
that
is
to say,
in question, e.g. the
foundation-stone of a house. So, too, in the case of that which is perishing and that which has
which becomes and that which perishes must contain an element of infiniteness as an immediate consequence of perished: for that
[75] the fact that they are continuous things: so a thing cannot be in process of becom-
and
ing without having become or have become without having been in process of becoming. So, too, in the case of perishing and having perished: perishing must be preceded by having perished, and having perished must be preceded by perishing. It is evident, then, that that which has become must previously have been
and that which is in becoming must previously have all magnitudes and all periods of
in process of becoming,
[20] process of
become: for time are infinitely divisible. Consequently no absolutely first stage of change can be represented by any particular
BOOK
238 b part of space or time
may
thing
VI,
CHAPTERS
which the .changing
occupy.
Now
since the motion of everything that is in motion occupies a period of time, and a greater magnitude is traversed in a longer time, it is impossible that a thing should undergo a finite [25] motion in an infinite time, if this is understood to mean not that the same motion or
a part of
it is
continually repeated, but that the
6-7
321
equal, are none the less limited in magnitude);
while on the other hand the finite stretch of motion AB is a certain multiple of AE: consequently the motion AB must be accomplished in a finite time. Moreover it is the same with coming to rest as with motion. And so it is impossible for one and the same thing to be infinitely in process of
becoming or of perishing.
The same reasoning
[20] finite
will prove that in a time there cannot be an infinite extent of
motion or of coming
to rest,
whether the mo-
time is occupied by the whole finite motion. In all cases where a thing is in motion with uniform velocity it is clear that
tion
the finite magnitude
in size individually
whole, of the magnitude will be traversed, because we assume that the traversing of the whole occupies all the time. Again, in another equal part of the time another part of the mag[25] nitude will be traversed: and similarly in each part of the time that we take, whether equal or unequal to the part originally taken.
the whole time
It
whole
infinite
we take
is
traversed in a finite
motion which shall be a measure of the whole, the whole motion is completed in as many equal periods of time. For
if
a part of the
[50] the time as there are parts of the motion. Consequently, since these parts are finite, both
and in number collectively, must also be finite: for it will
if we take a part which shall be a measure of the whole time, in this part a certain fraction, not the
regular or irregular. For
is
makes no
difference whether the parts are
be a multiple of the portion, equal to the time occupied in completing the aforesaid part mul-
equal or not, if only each is finite: for it is clear that while the time is exhausted by the
by the number of the parts. makes no difference even if the velocnot uniform. For let us suppose that the
will not be thus exhausted, since the process of
tiplied
But
it
subtraction of
its
parts, the infinite
magnitude
which a thing has been moved in the given and let TA be the infinite time. Now if 238 a one part of the stretch must have been
is finite both in respect of the quantity subtracted and of the number of times a subtraction is made. Consequently the infinite magnitude will not be traversed in a [50] finite time: and it makes no difference
traversed before another part (this
whether the magnitude
ity is
[55] line
AB
represents a finite stretch over
time,
in the earlier
and
is
clear, that
in the later part of the time a
different part of the stretch has been traversed: for as the time lengthens a different part of
the motion will always be completed in
it,
subtraction
is
infinite in only
direction or in both: for the
one
same reasoning
will hold good.
This having been proved,
it is
evident that
neither can a finite magnitude traverse an in-
[5] whether the thing in motion changes with uniform velocity or not: and whether the rate of motion increases or diminishes or remains stationary this is none the less so), let us then take AE a part of the whole stretch of motion AB which shall be a measure of AB. Now this part of the motion occupies a certain period of the infinite time: it cannot itself occupy an infinite time, for we are assuming that that is occupied by the whole AB. And if again I take
finite
[10] another part equal to AE, that also must occupy a finite time in consequence of the
the finite, the finite could traverse the infinite;
same assumption. And if I go on taking parts in this way, on the one hand there is no part which will be a measure of the infinite time (for the infinite cannot be composed of finite parts whether equal or unequal, because there must be some unity which will be a measure [75] of things finite in multitude or in magnitude, which, whether they are equal or un-
the thing in motion; either case involves the
magnitude in a finite time, the reason being the same as that given above: in part of [55] the time it will traverse a finite magnitude and in each several part likewise, so that in the
whole time
it
will traverse a finite
mag-
nitude.
And 238 b
since a finite
erse
an
magnitude
will not trav-
infinite in a finite time,
it is
clear
that neither will an infinite traverse a finite in
a finite time. for
it
For
makes no
if
the infinite could traverse
difference
which of the two
is
traversing of the infinite by the finite. For [5] when the infinite tion a part of it, say
magnitude
TA,
A
is
in
mo-
occupy the finite B, and then another, and then another, and so on to infinity. Thus the two results will coincide: the infinite will have completed a motion over the finite and the finite will have will
PHYSICS
3 22
traversed the infinite: for
it
would seem
to be
[w]
impossible for the motion of the infinite over the finite to occur in any way other than by the finite traversing the infinite either by
locomotion over fore, since this
it
is
or by measuring
it.
There-
impossible, the infinite can-
not traverse the finite. Nor again will the infinite traverse the infinite in a finite time. Otherwise it would also [75] traverse the finite, for the infinite includes the the
finite.
We
can further prove this in as our start-
same way by taking the time
ing-point. Since, then,
it
is
established that in a finite
time neither will the finite traverse the infinite, nor the infinite the finite, nor the infinite the [20] infinite, it is evident also that in a finite time there cannot be infinite motion: for what difference does it make whether we take the motion or the magnitude to be infinite? If either of the two is infinite, the other must be so likewise: for all locomotion is in space.
Since everything to which motion or rest is is in motion or at rest in the natural
natural
and manner, that which is coming it is coming to a stand, must [25] be in motion: for if it is not in motion it must be at rest: but that which is at rest cannot be coming to rest. From this it evidently follows that coming to a stand must occupy a period of time: for the motion of that which is in motion occupies a period of time, and that which is coming to a stand has been shown to be in motion: consequently coming to a stand must occupy a period of time. Again, since the terms 'quicker' and 'slower' [50] are used only of that which occupies a period of time, and the process of coming to a stand may be quicker or slower, the same contime, place, to a stand,
when
clusion follows.
And that which is coming to a stand must be coming
to a stand in any part of the primary time in which it is coming to a stand. For if it is coming to a stand in neither of two parts into which the time may be divided, it cannot be coming to a stand in the whole time, with the result that that which is coming to a stand will not be coming to a stand. If on the other hand it is coming to a stand in only one of the two parts of the time, the whole cannot be the pri[35] mary time in which it is coming to a stand: for it is coming to a stand in the whole time not primarily but in virtue of something distinct from itself, the argument being the
same
239a that
as
which we used above about
things in motion. 1
And just as there is no primary time in which that which is in motion is in motion, so 239 a too there is no primary time in which that which is coming to a stand is coming to a stand, there being no primary stage either of being in motion or of coming to a stand. For let AB be the primary time in which a thing is coming to a stand. Now AB cannot be without parts: for there cannot be motion in that which is without parts, because the moving thing would necessarily have been already moved for part of the time of its movement: [5] and that which is coming to a stand has been shown to be in motion. But since AB is therefore divisible, the thing is coming to a stand in every one of the parts of AB: for we have shown above 2 that it is coming to a stand in every one of the parts in which it is primarily coming to a stand. Since then, that in which primarily a thing is coming to a stand must be a period of time and not something indivisible, and since all time is infinitely divisible, there cannot be anything in which primarily it is coming to a stand. [10] Nor again can there be a primary time at which the being at rest of that which is at rest occurred: for it cannot have occurred in that which has no parts, because there cannot be motion in that which is indivisible, and that in which rest takes place is the same as that in which motion takes place: for we defined 3 a state of rest to be the state of a thing to which motion is natural but which is not in motion when (that is to say in that in which) motion would be natural to it. Again, our use of the [75] phrase 'being at rest' also implies that the previous state of a thing is still unaltered, not one point only but two at least being thus
needed
to
that in
which
determine its presence: consequently a thing is at rest cannot be without parts. Since, then it is divisible, it must be a period of time, and the thing must be at rest in every one of its parts, as may be shown by the same method as that used above in similar demonstrations. [20] So there can be no primary part of the time: and the reason is that rest and motion are always in a period of time, and a period of time has no primary part any more than a magnitude or in fact anything continuous: for everything continuous is divisible into an infinite
number
And 1
of parts.
since everything that 2 238b Chapter 6. 31 sqq.
is
in
motion 8
is
in
226 b 12 sqq.
BOOK
240*
VI,
CHAPTERS
motion in a period of time and changes from something to something, when its motion is comprised within a particular period of time that is to say when it fills the whole essentially [25] and not merely a part of the time in ques-
—
—
impossible that in that time that which is in motion should be over against some particular thing primarily. For if a thing tion
it
is
and each of
itself
parts
its
—occupies the same
space for a definite period of time, it is at rest: it is in just these circumstances that we use
7-9
The second amounts
[75] est
3 23 the so-called 'Achilles',
is
and
it
to this, that in a race the quick-
runner can never overtake the slowest, since
the pursuer
must
first
reach the point whence
the pursued started, so that the slower
must
always hold a lead. This argument is the same in principle as that which depends on bisec-
though
tion,
differs
it
from
it
in that the spaces
we successively have to deal are not divided into halves. The result of the ar-
with which [20]
gument
primarily changing, over
is that the slower is not overtaken: but proceeds along the same lines as the bisection-argument (for in both a division of the space in a certain way leads to the result that the goal is not reached, though the 'Achilles' goes further in that it affirms that even the quickest runner in legendary tradition must
against any particular thing (for the whole period of time is divisible), so that in one part
[25] fail in his pursuit of the slowest), so that the solution must be the same. And the axiom
for
the term 'being at after another
it
rest'
—when
at
one
moment
can be said with truth that a
and its parts, occupies the same [jo] space. So if this is being at rest it is impossible for that which is changing to be as a whole, thing, itself
at the
of
time
when
it is
after another
it
thing, itself
and
space. If this
is
sition
is
will be true to say that the
it
parts, occupies the
its
same
not so and the aforesaid propomoment, then
true only at a single
the thing will be over against a particular thing not for any period of time but only at a
moment
that limits the time. It
moment
is
true that at
always over against 239 b something stationary: but it is not at rest: for at a moment it is not possible for anything to be either in motion or at rest. So while [35] any
it
is
which is in motion is motion and is opposite
it
is
at a
moment
not in
some
particular thing, it cannot in a period of time be over against that which is at rest: for that would involve the conclusion that that which is in locomotion is at rest.
[5] Zeno's reasoning, however, is fallacious, when he says that if everything when it occupies an equal space
is
at rest,
and
if
that
which
false:
it is
is at rest, which from the assumption that time is composed of moments: if this assumption is
the effect that the flying arrow result follows
not granted, the conclusion will not follow.
The
true to say that that
it is
which holds
a lead is never overtaken not overtaken, it is true, while it holds a lead: but it is overtaken nevertheless if it is granted that it traverses the finite distance prescribed. These then are two of his arguments. [jo] The third is that already given above, to
that that
fourth argument
two rows
number of bodies of equal size, passing each other on a race-course as they proceed with equal velocity in opposite directions, the one row originally occupying the space (between the goal and the middle point of the course and the other that between the middle [35] point and the starting-post. This, he thinks, involves the conclusion that half a giv-
en time
is
equal to double that time. The fallacy
240 a
visibles.
A,
[10] Zeno's arguments about motion, which cause so much disquietude to those who try to
[5] B, B . size to A,
problems that they present, are four in number. The first asserts the non-existence of motion on the ground that that which is in locomotion must arrive at the half-way stage before it arrives at the goal. This we have dis-
of the course
cussed above. 1
follow:
in
solve the
that concerning the
row being composed
of an equal
locomotion is always occupying such a space at any moment, the flying arrow is therefore motionless. This is false, for time is not composed of indivisible moments any more than any other magnitude is composed of indiis
is
of bodies, each
of the reasoning lies in the assumption
body occupies an equal time in passing with equal velocity a body that is in motion that a
false.
body of equal size that is at rest; which is For instance (so runs the argument), let
A
... be the stationary bodies of equal size,
and
a
.
.
the bodies, equal in
A
.
.,
.
number and
in
originally occupying the half
from the starting-post to the midand I\ T those originally occupying the other half from the goal to the middle of the A's, equal in number, size, and vedle of the A's,
locity to B,
B
.
.
.
First, as the B's
.
.
.
Then
.
three consequences
and the T's pass one another,
PHYSICS
324
B
T
same mo-
it is
B. Secondly,
else
[10] at this moment the first T has passed all the A's, whereas the first B has passed only half
that
the
first
ment
reaches the last
as the first
T
at the
reaches the
last
the A's, and has consequently occupied only half the time occupied by the first T, since each
241-
same with the sphere and everything whose motion is confined within the space the
it
occupies.
10
Our
Nor in reference to contradictory change shall we find anything unanswerable in the ar[20] gument that if a thing is changing from
that that which is without motion except accidentally: i.e. it can be in motion only in so far as the body or the magnitude is in motion and the [10] partless is in motion by inclusion therein, just as that which is in a boat may be in motion in consequence of the locomotion of the boat, or a part may be in motion in virtue of the motion of the whole. (It must be remembered, however, that by 'that which is without parts' I mean that which is quantitatively indivisible (and that the case of the motion of a part is not exactly parallel) for parts have motions belonging essentially and severally to [75] themselves distinct from the motion of the whole. The distinction may be seen most
not-white, say, to white, and
in neither con-
clearly in the case of a revolving sphere, in
will be neither white nor not-
which the velocities of the parts near the centre and of those on the surface are different from one another and from that of the whole; this implies that there is not one motion but many). As we have said, then, that which is without parts can be in motion in the sense in which a man sitting in a boat is in motion when the boat is travelling, but it cannot be in motion of [20] itself. For suppose that it is changing from AB to Br either from one magnitude to another, or from one form to another, or from some state to its contradictory and let A be the primary time in which it undergoes the change. Then in the time in which it is changing it must be either in AB or in Br or partly [25] in one and partly in the other: for this, as
two occupies an equal time in passing each A. Thirdly, at the same moment all the B's have passed all the T's: for the first T and of the
the
first
B
will simultaneously reach the oppo-
[75] site ends of the course, since (so says Zeno) the time occupied by the first T in passing each of the B's is equal to that occupied by it in pass-
ing each of the A's, because an equal time is occupied by both the first B and the first V in passing all the A's. This is the argument, but it presupposed the aforesaid fallacious assumption.
is
:
dition, then
it
is
white: for the fact that it is not wholly in either condition will not preclude us from calling it
We
call a thing white or white or not-white. not-white not necessarily because it is wholly either one or the other, but because most of its
parts or the
most
essential parts of
it
are so: not
[25] being in a certain condition is different from not being wholly in that condition. So, too, in the case of
being and not-being and
all
other conditions which stand in a contradictory relation: while the changing thing must of necessity be in
one of the two opposites,
it
is
never wholly in either. Again, in the case of circles and spheres and everything whose motion is confined within the space that it occupies, it is not true to say [jo] that the motion can be nothing but rest, on the ground that such things in motion, themselves and their parts, will occupy the same position for a period of time, and that therefore they will be at once at rest and in motion. For in the first place the parts do not occupy the same position for any period of time: and in the second place the whole also is al-
ways changing
240b
next point
parts cannot be in
to a different position: for
if
we
take the orbit as described from a point
A
on a circumference, it will not be the same as from B or T or any other point on the same circumference except in an
the orbit as described
accidental sense, the sense that
which
a musical
man
is
the
is
same
to say in as a
man.
[5] Thus one orbit is always changing into another, and the thing will never be at rest. And
—
—
we
saw, 1
is
true of everything that
is
changing.
Now it cannot be partly in each of the two:
for
then it would be divisible into parts. Nor again can it be in Br: for then it will have completed the change, whereas the assumption is that the change is in process. It remains, then, that in the time in which it is changing, it is in AB. That being so, it will be at rest: for, as we saw, 2 to be in the same condition for a period of time [30] is to be at rest. So it is not possible for that which has no parts to be in motion or to change in any way: for only one condition could have made it possible for it to have motion, viz. that time should be composed of moments, in which case at any moment it would have completed a 241 a motion or a change, so that it would never be in motion, but would always have been in *
234'
sqq.
2239*27.
BOOK
241 b
VI,
CHAPTERS 1
motion. But this we have already shown above to be impossible: time is not composed of moments, just as a line is not composed of points, and motion is not composed of starts: for this [5] theory simply makes motion consist of indivisibles in exactly the same way as time is made to consist of moments or a length of be shown in the following way no motion of a point or of any other indivisible. That which is in motion can never traverse a space greater than itself without first traversing a space equal to or less than itself. That being so, it is evident that the point [10] also must first traverse a space equal to or it
may
that there can be
less than itself. But since it is indivisible, there can be no space less than itself for it to traverse first: so it will have to traverse a distance equal
to
itself.
Thus
the line will be
points, for the point, as
it
composed of
continually traverses
a distance equal to itself, will be a measure of the whole line. But since this is impossible, it is likewise impossible for the indivisible to be in
motion. [75] Again, since motion is always in a period of time and never in a moment, and all time is divisible, for everything that is in motion there must be a time less than that in which it trav-
For that in which it is in motion will be a time, because all motion is in a period of time; and all time has erses a distance as great as itself.
been shown above 2 to be divisible. Therefore, if a point is in motion, there must be a time less than that in which it has itself traversed [20] any distance. But this is impossible, for in less time it must traverse less distance, and thus the indivisible will be divisible into something less than itself, just as the time is so divisible: the fact being that the only condition under which that which is without parts and indivisible could be in motion would have been the possibility of the infinitely small being in mo[25] tion in a moment: for in the two questhat of motion in a moment and that of
tions
—
motion of something principle
is
indivisible
—the
same
involved.
Our
next point is that no process of change every change, whether between contradictories or between contraries, is a change from something to something. Thus in contradictory changes the positive or the negais
infinite: for
1
is
325
the case
the limit of
may
be,
coming
is
the limit, e.g. being
to be
the limit of ceasing to be:
and not-being is and in contrary
changes the particular contraries are the limits, [50] since these are the extreme points of any such process of change, and consequently of every process of alteration: for alteration is alcontraries. Similar-
ways dependent upon some
points.
Again,
tive, as
9-10
23i b 18 sqq.
2
232 b 23 sqq.
ly contraries are the
extreme points of processes
and decrease: the limit of increase be found in the complete magnitude prop-
of increase is
to b er to the peculiar nature of the thing that
24 is
increasing, while the limit of decrease
complete
is
the
such magnitude. Locomotion, it is true, we cannot show to be finite in this way, since it is not always between contraries. But since that which cannot be cut (in the sense that it is inconceivable that it should be cut, the term 'cannot' being used in several loss of
—
since it is inconceivable that that [5] senses) in this sense cannot be cut should be in
which
and generally that that which cannot come to be should be in process of coming to be, it follows that it is inconceivable that that which cannot complete a change should be in process of changing to that to which it cannot complete a change. If, then, it is to be assumed that that which process of being cut,
is
in locomotion
is
in process of changing,
must be capable of completing the change. Consequently its motion is not infinite, and [10] it will not be in locomotion over an it
infinite distance, for
it
cannot traverse such a
distance. It is
evident, then, that a process of
change
cannot be infinite in the sense that it is not defined by limits. But it remains to be considered whether it is possible in the sense that one and the same process of change may be infinite in respect of the time which it occupies. If it is not one process, it would seem that there is nothing [/5J to prevent its being infinite in this sense; e.g. if a process of locomotion be succeeded by a process of alteration and that by a process of increase and that again by a process of coming to be: in this way there may be motion for ever so far as the time is concerned, but it will not be one motion, because all these motions do not compose one. If it is to be one process, no motion can be infinite in respect of the time that it occupies, with the single exception of rota[20] tory locomotion.
PHYSICS
326
BOOK
242 b
VII For
let us suppose that this the series to be infinite. Let
Everything
that
is
in
motion must be moved
[25] by something. For if of its motion in itself it
moved
has not the source evident that it is by something other than itself, for there it
is
must be something else that moves it. If on the other hand it has the source of its motion in itself, let AB be taken to represent that which is in motion essentially of itself and not in virtue of the fact that something belonging to it is in motion. Now in the first place to assume that [30] AB, because it is in motion as a whole and
moved by anything external to itself, is moved by itself this is just as if, supposing that KA is moving AM and is also itself in motion, we were to deny that KM is moved is
not
—
therefore
by anything on the ground that
it is
moving
not evident
and which moved. In the second place that which is in motion without being moved by anything does not necessarily cease from its 242* motion because something else is at rest, but a thing must be moved by something if the fact of something else having ceased from its motion causes it to be at rest. Thus, if this is accepted, everything that is in motion must be [5] moved by something. For AB, which has been taken to represent that which is in motion, must be divisible, since everything that is in motion is divisible. Let it be divided, then,
which
is
the part that
the part that
at T.
is
it
is
Now if TB is not in motion, then AB will it is clear that Ar if it
not be in motion: for
would be
in
is,
motion while
Br
is
at rest,
and
AB
cannot be in motion essentially [10] thus is in moand primarily. But ex hypothesi
AB
and primarily. Therefore if TB is not in motion AB will be at rest. But we have agreed that that which is at rest if something else is not in motion must be moved by
tion essentially
something. Consequently, everything that is in motion must be moved by something: for that [75] which is in motion will always be divisible, and if a part of it is not in motion the whole must be at rest. Since everything that is in motion must be moved by something, let us take the case in which a thing is in locomotion and is moved by something that is itself in motion, and that again is moved by something else that is in motion, and that by something else, and so on con[20] tinually: then the series cannot go on to infinity, but there must be some first movent.
not so and take then be moved by B, B by I\ T by A, and so on, each member of the series being moved by that which comes next to it. Then since ex hypothesi the movent is
A
while causing motion is also itself in motion, and the motion of the moved and the motion of the movent must proceed simultaneously (for the movent is causing motion and the [25] moved is being moved simultaneously) it evident that the respective motions of A, B,
is
T, and each of the other moved movents are simultaneous. Let us take the motion of each
and let E be the motion of A, Z of and G respectively the motions of T for though they are all moved severally one by another, yet we may still take the motion of each as numerically one, since every mo[50] tion is from something to something and separately
and and A
H
B,
:
not infinite in respect of its extreme points. a motion that is numerically one I mean a motion that proceeds from something numeriis
By
one and the same to something numerione and the same in a period of time numerically one and the same: for a motion may
cally cally
[35] be the same generically, specifically, or numerically it is generically the same if it belongs :
same category, e.g. substance or quality: it is specifically the same if it proceeds from something specifically the same to something specifically the same, e.g. from white to black or from good to bad, which is not of a kind specifically 242b distinct: it is numerically the same if it proceeds from something numerically one to something numerically one in the same period of time, e.g. from a particular white to a particular black, or from a particular place to a parto the
ticular place, in a particular period of time: for
and the same, would no longer be numerically one though it would still be specifically one.
if
the period of time were not one
the motion
We have dealt with this question above. Now let us further take the time in which A has 1
[4,8]
completed its motion, and let it be represented by K. Then since the motion of A is finite the time will also be finite. But since the movents and the things moved are infinite, the motion EZH0, i.e. the motion that is composed of all [75] the individual motions, must be infinite. For the motions of A, B, and the others may be equal, or the motions of the others may be greater: but assuming what is conceivable, we *v. 4 (227b 3 sqq.).
BOOK
243 b
find that whether they are equal or
VII,
some
CHAPTERS
are
another.
1-2
And
327
since there are three kinds of
mo-
whole motion is infimotion of A and that of each of the others are simultaneous, the whole motion must occupy the same time as the motion of A: but the time occupied by the motion of A is finite: consequently the motion will be infinite in a finite time, which is impossible. It might be thought that what we set out to [20] prove has thus been shown, but our argu-
and quantitative, there must also be three kinds of movent, that which causes locomotion, that which causes alteration, and that which causes increase or de-
ment so far does not prove it, because it does not yet prove that anything impossible results from the contrary supposition: for in a finite time there may be an infinite motion, though
themselves
greater, in both cases the
And
nite.
since the
not of one thing, but of many: and in the case we are considering this is so: for each thing accomplishes its own motion, and there that
is
no impossibility the
versally
moved
many
things being in
But
(as
in
tion simultaneously.
if
we
mo-
see to be uni-
which primarily is and corporeally must be either
case)
locally
that
[25] in contact with or continuous with that which moves it, the things moved and the movents
must be continuous or
in contact
another, so that together they
all
with one
form
a single
whether this unity is finite or infinite makes no difference to our present argument; for in any case since the things in motion are infinite in number the whole motion will be inunity:
finite,
tion
if,
is
as
theoretically possible, each
is
mo-
either equal to or greater than that
which follows
in the series: for
it
which
as actual that
is
we
shall take
theoretically possible.
[30] If, then, A, B, I\ A form an infinite magnitude that passes through the motion EZH in the finite time K, this involves the conclusion that an infinite motion is passed through
and whether the magnitude
in a finite time: in question
is
finite or infinite this is in either
must come movent and
case impossible. Therefore the series to
a
an end, and there must be a
moved:
first
243 a
for the fact that this impossibil-
ity results
particular case
sumed
is
first
only from the assumption of a immaterial, since the case as-
is
theoretically possible,
and the assumpought not to
tion of a theoretically possible case
give rise to any impossible result.
tion, local, qualitative,
[10]
crease.
Let us begin with locomotion, for this is the primary motion. Everything that is in locomotion is moved either by itself or by something else. In the case of things that are moved by
movent
it is
evident that the
moved and
the
are together: for they contain within
themselves their first movent, so that there is [75] nothing in between. The motion of things that are moved by something else must proceed in one of four ways: for there are four kinds of locomotion caused by something other than that which is in motion, viz. pulling, pushing, carrying, and twirling. All forms of locomotion are reducible to these. Thus pushing on is a form of pushing in which that which is causing motion away from itself follows up that which it pushes and continues to push it: pushing off occurs when the movent does not follow up the thing that it has moved: throw[20] ing when the movent causes a motion 243 b away from itself more violent than the natural locomotion of the thing moved, which
continues its course so long as it is controlled by the motion imparted to it. Again, pushing apart and pushing together are forms respectively of pushing off and pulling: pushing apart is pushing off, which may be a motion either away from the pusher or away from something [5] else, while pushing together is pulling, which may be a motion towards something else as well as towards the puller. We may similarly classify all the varieties of these last
two,
e.g.
packing and combing: the former is a form of pushing together, the latter a form of pushing apart.
The same
is
true of the other processes
and separation (they will all be be forms of pushing apart or of push-
of combination
found
to
ing together), except such as are involved in the processes of
becoming and perishing. (At
[10] the same time it is evident that there is no other kind of motion but combination and sepa-
may all be apportioned to one or other of those already mentioned.) Again, inhaling is a form of pulling, exhaling a form of ration: for they
That which
is
the
in the sense that
first it
movement
of a thing
supplies not 'that for the
sake of which' but the source of the motion is always together with that which is moved by it (by 'together' I mean that there is nothing [5] intermediate between them). This is universally true
wherever one thing
is
moved by
pushing: and the same is true of spitting and of all other motions that proceed through the body, whether secretive or assimilative, the assimilative being forms of pulling, the secretive [75] of pushing off. All other kinds of locomotion must be similarly reduced, for they all fall
PHYSICS And one
328
under one or other of our four heads. and twirling are reducible to pulling and pushing. For carrying always follows one of the other three methods, for that which is carried is in motion accidentally, because it is in or upon something that is [20] in motion, and that which carries it is in doing so being either pulled or pushed or again, of these four, carrying
244 a
twirled; thus carrying belongs to
other three kinds of motion in twirling for that
is
a
compound
which
is
all
the
common. And
of pulling
and pushing,
twirling a thing must be pull-
ing one part of the thing and pushing another part, since it impels one part away from itself and another part towards itself. If, therefore, it can be shown that that which is pushing and that which is pulling are adjacent respectively to that which is being pushed and that which [5] is being pulled, it will be evident that in all locomotion there is nothing intermediate be-
tween moved and movent. But the former fact is clear even from the definitions of pushing and pulling, for pushing is motion to something else from oneself or from something else, and pulling is motion from something else to oneself or to something else, when the motion of that which is pulling is quicker than the mo[10] tion that would separate from one another the two things that are continuous: for it is this that causes one thing to be pulled on along with the other. (It might indeed be thought that there is a form of pulling that arises in another way: that wood, e.g. pulls fire in a manner different from that described above. But it makes no difference whether that which pulls is in motion or is stationary when it is pulling: in the latter case it pulls to the place where it is, while in the former it pulls to the place where it was.) Now it is impossible to move anything [75] either from oneself to something else or from something else to oneself without being
244 b
in contact with
it: it is
evident, therefore,
locomotion there is nothing intermediate between moved and movent. Nor again is there anything intermediate between that which undergoes and that which causes alteration: this can be proved by inducthat in
all
245
s
another are sensible characteristics: for every body differs from another in possessing a
greater or lesser istics
number
of sensible character-
or in possessing the
same
teristics in a greater or lesser
alteration of that
which undergoes
also caused by the
[5]
istics,
sensible charac-
degree. But the alteration
is
above-mentioned character-
which are
affections of
some
particu-
underlying quality. Thus we say that a thing is altered by becoming hot or sweet or thick or dry or white: and we make these asserlar
tions alike of what is inanimate and of what is animate, and further, where animate things are in question, we make them both of the parts
no power of sense-perception and of [10] the senses themselves. For in a way even the senses undergo alteration, since the active sense is a motion through the body in the that have
course of which the sense tain
way.
We see,
is
affected in a cer-
then, that the animate
is
ca-
pable of every kind of alteration of which the inanimate is capable: but the inanimate is not capable of every kind of alteration of which the animate
is
capable, since
it is
not capable of
alteration in respect of the senses:
moreover
[75] the inanimate is unconscious of being af245 a fected by alteration, whereas the animate is conscious of it, though there is nothing to prevent the animate also being unconscious of it when the process of the alteration does not concern the senses. Since, then, the alteration of that which undergoes alteration is caused by sensible things, in every case of such alteration
it is
that
evident that the respective extremities of which causes and that which undergoes
[5] alteration are adjacent. Thus the air is continuous with that which causes the alteration, and the body that undergoes alteration is continuous with the air. Again, the colour is con-
tinuous with the light and the light with the sight. And the same is true of hearing and smelling: for the primary movent in respect to the
moved
is
the
air.
tasting, the flavour
is
Similarly, in the case of
adjacent to the sense of same in the case of
[70] taste. And it is just the things that are inanimate sense-perception.
Thus
and incapable of
there can be nothing
tive extremities of that
which causes and that which undergoes alteration are adjacent. For
intermediate between that which undergoes and that which causes alteration. Nor, again, can there be anything interme-
our assumption is that things that are undergoing alteration are altered in virtue of their being affected in respect of their so-called affec-
diate between that which suffers and that which causes increase: for the part of the latter that starts the increase does so by becoming at-
tion: for in every case
we
tive qualities, since that
quality
is
find that the respec-
which
altered in so far as
the characteristics in
of a certain
is
it is
and from
sensible,
which bodies
differ
tached in such a way to the former that the whole becomes one. Again, the decrease of that which suffers decrease is caused by a part of
BOOK
246 b
VII,
CHAPTERS
the thing becoming detached. So that which [75] causes increase and that which causes de-
must be continuous with that which suffers increase and that which suffers decrease respectively: and if two things are continuous crease
with one another there can be nothing intermediate between them. It is evident, therefore, that between the ex245 b tremities of the moved and the movent that are respectively to the
moved
there
first is
and
last in
reference
nothing intermediate.
2-3
329
into existence that are altered,
ing
is
and
their
becom-
not an alteration.
[jo] Again, acquired states, whether of the
body or of the soul, are not alterations. For some are excellences and others are defects, and neither excellence nor defect is an altera-
when anyproper excellence we call it ferfect, since it is then if ever that we have a 75] thing in its natural state: e.g. we have a perfect circle when we have one as good as possible), while defect is a perishing of or departion: excellence
thing acquires
is
a perfection (for
its
from this condition. So just as when speaking of a house we do not call its arrival at perfection an alteration (for it would be absurd to suppose that the coping or the tiling is an alter[20] ation or that in receiving its coping or its tiling a house is altered and not perfected), the same also holds good in the case of excellences and defects and of the persons or things that 246 b possess or acquire them: for excellences are perfections of a thing's nature and defects are departures from it: consequently they are not alterations. ture
Everything, tion
is
we
that
say,
undergoes
altered by sensible causes,
altera-
and there
is
alteration only in things that are said to be essentially affected
by sensible things. The truth
[5] of this is to be seen from the following considerations. Of all other things it would be
most natural to suppose that there is alteration in figures and shapes, and in acquired states and in the processes of acquiring and losing these: but as a matter of fact in neither of these
two
classes of things
In the
first place,
is
there alteration.
when
a particular forma-
Further,
we
say that
all
excellences
depend
[10] tion of a thing is completed, we do not call it by the name of its material: e.g. we do
upon
not call the statue 'bronze' or the pyramid 'wax' or the bed 'wood', but we use a derived expression and call them 'of bronze', 'waxen', and 'wooden' respectively. But when a thing has
regard as consisting in a blending of hot and cold elements within the body in due proportion, in relation either to one another or to the surrounding atmosphere: and in like manner we regard beauty, strength, and all the other bodily excellences and defects. Each of them exists in virtue of a particular relation and puts
been affected and altered in any way we still call it by the original name: thus we speak of the bronze or the wax being dry or fluid or hard or hot. [75] And not only so: we also speak of the particular fluid or hot substance as being bronze, giving the material the same name as that which we use to describe the affection. 246 a Since, therefore, having regard to the figure or shape of a thing we no longer call that which has become of a certain figure by the name of the material that exhibits the figure, whereas having regard to a thing's affections
we
still call it by the name of its evident that becomings of the former kind cannot be alterations.
or alterations material,
it
is
Moreover it would seem absurd even to speak in this way, to speak, that is to say, of a [5] man or house or anything else that has come into existence as having been altered. Though it may be true that every such becoming is necessarily the result of something's being altered, the result, e.g. of the material's being condensed or rarefied or heated or cooled, nevertheless it is not the things that are coming
Thus
particular relations.
and
lences such as health
a
bodily excel-
good
state of
body
we
[5]
that
which
possesses
tion with regard to
in a
it
good or bad condi-
proper affections, where
its
by 'proper' affections
I
mean
those influences
from the natural constitution of a thing tend to promote or destroy its existence. Since, that
[70] then, relatives are neither themselves alterations nor the subjects of alteration or of becom-
ing or in fact of any change whatever, it is evident that neither states nor the processes of losing and acquiring states are alterations, though it may be true that their becoming or perishing [75] is necessarily, like the becoming or perishing of a specific character or form, the result of the alteration of certain other things, e.g. hot
and cold or dry and wet elements or the elements, whatever they may be, on which the states primarily depend. For each several bodily
defect or excellence involves a relation with
those things from
which the possessor
defect or excellence
is
teration: thus excellence disposes to be unaffected
of the
naturally subject to its
al-
possessor
by these influences or to be
af-
PHYSICS
330
them that ought to be admitwhile defect disposes its possessor to be affected by them or to be unaffected by those of them that ought to be admitted. [20] And the case is similar in regard to the
248*
fected by those of
tivity of these states, unless
ted,
there
247 a
which
states of the soul, all of
(like those
of body) exist in virtue of particular relations, the excellences being perfections of nature and
from it: moreover, excellence puts its possessor in good condition, while defect puts its possessor in a bad condition, to meet his proper affections. Consequently these cannot any more than the bodily states be alter[5] ations, nor can the processes of losing and acquiring them be so, though their becoming the defects departures
is
necessarily the result of an alteration of the
and
sensitive part of the soul,
sensible objects: for all
this
is
altered by
moral excellence
is
con-
cerned with bodily pleasures and pains, which again depend either upon acting or upon reor upon anticipating. Now those depend upon action are determined by
a
is
becoming of
vision
that the activity in question
And
it
thought that
is
and touching and
is
similar to these.)
knowledge
the original acquisition of
is
not a becoming or an alteration: for the terms [10] 'knowing' and 'understanding' imply that the intellect has reached a state of rest and
come
to a standstill,
and there
no becoming
is
we have can have a becoming. Moreover, just as to say, when any one has that leads to a state of rest, since, as
said above,
1
no change
at all
passed from a state of intoxication or sleep or disease to the contrary state, that he has become [75] possessed of knowledge again is incorrect in spite of the fact that he was previously incapable of using his knowledge, so, too, when
any one originally acquires the state, it is incorrect to say that he becomes possessed of knowledge: for the possession of understanding and knowledge is produced by the soul's settling
membering
down
that
Hence, too, in learning and in forming judgements on matters relating to their sense-percep248 a tions children are inferior to adults owing to the great amount of restlessness and motion in their souls. Nature itself causes the soul
[10] sense-perception,
by something
i.e.
they are stimulated
and those that depend
sensible:
upon memory
or anticipation are likewise to be traced to sense-perception, for in these cases
pleasure
is
felt either in
remembering what one
has experienced or in anticipating what one is going to experience. Thus all pleasure of this
kind must be produced by sensible things: and since the presence in any one of moral defect or excellence involves the presence in him of [75] pleasure or pain (with which moral excellence and defect are always concerned), and these pleasures
and pains are
alterations of the
evident that the loss and acquisition of these states no less than the loss and acquisition of the states of the body must be the sensitive part,
it is
out of the restlessness
down and come
to settle
the performance of
some
natural to
it.
to a state of rest for
its functions, while performance of others other things do so: but in either case the result is brought about through the alteration of something in the body, as we see in the case of the use and activ[5] ity of the intellect arising from a man's becoming sober or being awakened. It is evident, then, from the preceding argument that alteration and being altered occur in sensible things
of
for the
and
in the sensitive part of the soul, and, ex-
cept accidentally, in nothing else.
something else. Conbecoming is accompa-
result of the alteration of
sequently, though their
nied by an alteration, they are not themselves alterations. 247 b Again, the states of the intellectual part
of the soul are not alterations, nor
becoming more true it
of the possession of
depends upon a particular
ther,
it is
evident that there
there any
is
of them. In the first place
it is
time, then
fur-
to a straight line, or, of course, the
no becoming
of
which is potentially posknowledge becomes actually possessed of it not by being set in motion at all itself [5] but by reason of the presence of something i.e. it is it
when
it
knows
meets with the particular
in a
we may have
that
these states. For that
object that
is
And
sessed of
else:
difficulty
knowledge
relation. is
much
A
may be raised as to whether commensurable with every other or not. Now if they are all commensurable and if two things to have the same velocity must accomplish an equal motion in an equal [70]
every motion
manner
the particular
through its knowledge of the universal. (Again, there is no becoming of the actual use and ac-
a circumference equal
one
may
greater or less than the other. Further,
if
be
one
thing alters and another accomplishes a locomotion in an equal time, we may have an alter[75] ation and a locomotion equal to one another: thus an affection will be equal to a length, which is impossible. But is it not only equal motion is accomplished by two things in an equal time that the velocities of
when an 1
v. 2 (225 b 15 sqq.).
BOOK
249*
VII,
CHAPTERS
the two are equal? Now an affection cannot be equal to a length. Therefore there cannot be an alteration equal to or less than a locomotion: and consequently it is not the case that every motion is commensurable with every other.
But
how
will our conclusion
and the
case of the circle
work out
straight line?
It
in the
would
be absurd to suppose that the motion of one [20] thing in a circle and of another in a straight line cannot be similar, but that the one must inevitably move more quickly or more slowly than the other, just as if the course of one were downhill and of the other uphill. Moreover it does not as a matter of fact make
any difference to the argument to say that the one motion must inevitably be quicker or slower than the other: for then the circumference can be greater or less than the straight line;
and
if
so
possible for the
it is
[25] For
if
A
in the time
passes over the distance B'
248 b
two
to be equal.
the quicker (B)
and the slower (T)
passes over the distance r", B' will be
greater than T':
for this
is
what we
1
motion implies that one thing traverses an equal
'quicker' to
mean: and
so quicker
took
3-4
are not
commensurable
up the same position and say that the term 'much' is equivocal? In fact there are some terms of which even the definitions are equivocal; e.g. if 'much' were defined as 'so much and more', 'so much' would mean something different in different cases: 'equal' is similarly equivocal; and 'one' again is perhaps in[20] evitably an equivocal term; and if 'one' is equivocal, so is 'two'. Otherwise why is it that some things are commensurable while others are not,
if
the nature of the attribute in the
is
really
carrying the attribute?
A
two motions
are
commen-
[5] surable, we are confronted with the consestated above, viz. that there may be a
quence
straight line equal to a circle. But these are not commensurable: and so the corresponding motions are not commensurable either. But may we say that things are always commensurable if the same terms are applied to
them without equivocation? e.g. a pen, a wine, and the highest note in a scale are not commensurable: we cannot say whether any one of them is sharper than any other: and why is this? they are incommensurable because it is only equivocally that the same term 'sharp' is applied to them: whereas the highest note in a scale is commensurable with the leading-note, because the term 'sharp' has the same meaning [10] as applied to both. Can it be, then, that the term 'quick' has not the same meaning as
applied to straight motion and to circular tion respectively ? If so, far less will
same meaning
it
mo-
have the
as applied to alteration
and
to
locomotion.
Or
we
in the first place deny that things commensurable if the same terms are applied to them without equivocation ? For shall
are always 1
vi.
2(232* 25 sqq.).
which
ference in that
dis-
is
primarily capable of
Thus horse and dog are commensurable that we may say which is
the whiteness
the
two
one and the same? Can it be that the incommensurability of two things in respect of any attribute is due to a dif-
cases
over a part of the circle equal to T', while V in passing over r'« will occupy the whole of less, if
or, if
take
so
the
it:
is
also
A
in respect of
not considered satisfactory, 'double' at any rate would seem to have the same meaning as applied to each (denoting in each case the proportion of two to one), yet water and air are not commensurable in re[75] spect of it. But here again may we not
this illustration
tance in less time than another: consequently in which B will pass there will be a part of
None
331
the term 'much' has the same meaning whether applied to water or to air, yet water and air
the whiter, since that face:
and
is
which primarily contains
the same in both, viz. the sur-
commensurable in But water and speech are not
similarly they are
respect of size.
commensurable in respect of clearness, since that which primarily contains the attribute is [25] different in the two cases. It would seem, however, that we must reject this solution, since clearly
we
could thus
make
all
equivocal
and say merely that that which contains each of them is different in dif249 a ferent cases: thus 'equality', 'sweetness', and 'whiteness' will severally always be the same, though that which contains them is different in different cases. Moreover, it is not any casual thing that is capable of carrying any atattributes univocal
tribute: each single attribute can be carried primarily only by one single thing. Must we then say that, if two things are to be commensurable in respect of any attribute, not only must the attribute in question be applicable to both without equivocation, but there must also be no specific differences either in the attribute itself or in that which contains the that these, I mean, must not be [5] attribute divisible in the way in which colour is divided into kinds? Thus in this respect one thing will not be commensurable with another, i.e. we cannot say that one is more coloured than the other where only colour in general and not any
—
249b
PHYSICS
33 2 particular colour
mensurable
is
meant; but they are com-
in respect of whiteness.
Similarly in the case of motion:
particular instances of whiteness or sweetness
same or different?
are the
two things
are of the same velocity if they occupy an equal time in accomplishing a certain equal amount of motion. Suppose, then, that in a certain time an alteration is undergone by one half of a body's length and a locomotion is accomplished by [10] the other half: can be say that in this case the alteration is equal to the locomotion and of the same velocity ? That would be absurd, and
the reason is that there are different species of motion. And if in consequence of this we must say that two things are of equal velocity if they accomplish locomotion over an equal distance in an equal tme, we have to admit the equality of a straight line and a circumference. What, then, is the reason of this? Is it that locomo-
Is it
enough
that
it
appears different in one subject from what it appears in another? Or must there be no same-
And further, where alteration is in how is one alteration to be of equal with another? One person may be
ness at all?
question, velocity
cured quickly and another slowly, and cures [30] may also be simultaneous: so that, recovery of health being an alteration, we have here alterations of equal velocity, since each altera249 b tion occupies an equal time. But what alteration? We cannot here speak of an 'equal' alteration: what corresponds in the category of quality to equality in the category of quantity is
'likeness'.
However,
let
us say that there
is
[75] tion
is
a genus?
equal velocity where the same change is accom[5] plished in an equal time. Are we, then, to find the commensurability in the subject of
(We may
leave the time out of account, since
the affection or in the affection itself? In the case
one and the same.) If the lines are specifically different, the locomotions also differ specifically from one another: for locomotion
been considering it is the fact one and the same that enables us to arrive at the conclusion that the one alteration is neither more nor less than the other, but that both are alike. If on the other hand the af-
that
is
a
genus or that
line
is
is
specifically differentiated
according to the over which it
specific differentiation of that
takes place. (It it
is
also similarly differentiated,
would seem, accordingly
of the locomotion
as the instrument
different: thus if feet are walking, if wings it is flying; but perhaps we should rather say that this is not so, and that in this case the differences in the locomotion are merely differences of posture in that which is in motion.) We may say, therefore, that things are of equal velocity [20] if in an equal time they traverse the same magnitude: and when I call it 'the same' I
the instrument,
mean
that
it
is
it is
contains no specific difference and
no difference in the motion that takes place over it. So we have now to consider how motion is differentiated: and this discussion serves to show that the genus is not a unity but contains a plurality latent in it and distinct from it, and that in the case of equivocal terms sometimes the different senses in which they are used are far removed from one another, while sometimes there is a certain likeness between them, and sometimes again they are therefore
nearly related either generically or analogical-
with the result that they seem not to be equivocal though they really are. [25] When, then, is there a difference of spely,
cies
?
Is
subject
an attribute is
specifically different if the
different while the attribute
is
the
same, or must the attribute itself be different as well? And how are we to define the limits of a species? What will enable us to decide that
that
we have
that health
fection
is
just
is
two cases, e.g. when form of becoming white
different in the
the alterations take the
and becoming healthy respectively, here there no sameness or equality or likeness inas-
is
much
as
the difference in the affections at
makes the alterations specifically different, and there is no unity of alteration any more than there would be unity of locomotion under like conditions. So we must find out how many species there are of alteration and of lo[10] once
comotion respectively. Now if the things that are in motion that is to say, the things to which the motions belong essentially and not
—
accidentally
—
differ specifically,
then their
re-
spective motions will also differ specifically:
if
on the other hand they differ generically or numerically, the motions also will differ generically or numerically as the case may be. But [75] there still remains the question whether, supposing that two alterations are of equal velocity, we ought to look for this equality in the sameness (or likeness) of the affections, or in the things altered, to see e.g. whether a certain quantity of each has become white. Or ought we not rather to look for it in both ? That is to say, the alterations are the same or different according as the affections are the same or different, while they are equal or unequal according as the things altered are equal or unequal.
And now we must
consider the same ques-
BOOK
250b
VII,
CHAPTERS
becoming and perishone becoming of equal velocity
[20] tion in the case of
how
ing:
is
with another? They are of equal velocity if in an equal time there are produced two things
same and specifically inseparable, two men (not merely generically inseparaas e.g. two animals). Similarly one is quick-
that are the e.g.
ble
er than the other
an equal time the prod-
in
if
two
cases. I state it thus because we have no pair of terms that will convey this 'difference' in the way in which unlikeness is conveyed. If we adopt the theory
uct
is
that
different in the
it is
number
that constitutes being,
we may
indeed speak of a 'greater number' and a 'lesser number' within the same species, but there is no common term that will include both relations, nor are there terms to express each of [25] them separately in the same way as we indicate a higher degree or preponderance of
an
affection by 'more', of a quantity by 'greater.'
Now
since wherever there is a movent, its motion always acts upon something, is always in something, and always extends to something (by 'is always in something' I mean that it occupies a time: and by 'extends to something' I
mean that it involves the traversing of a certain amount of distance: for at any moment when is causing motion, it also has caused motion, so that there must always be a certain amount of distance that has been traversed and a certain amount of time that has been occu-
a thing
A
the movent have moved [30] pied). If, then, 250a B a distance T in a time A, then in the
same time the same
force
A
move 14 B /2 A it will move will
twice the distance T, and in l /2 B the whole distance T: for thus the rules of l
proportion will be observed. Again if a given [5] force move a given weight a certain distance in a certain time and half the distance in half the time, half the motive
half the weight the
time. Let
power
same distance
E represent
move
will
same power A
in the
half the motive
and Z half the weight B: then the ratio between the motive power and the weight in the one case is similar and proportionate to the ratio in the other, so that
each force will cause the
4-5
333
and the whole of T is proportionate to that between A and E (whatever fraction of A E may [75] be): in fact it might well be that it will cause no motion at all; for it does not follow that, if a given motive power causes a certain amount of motion, half that power will cause motion either of any particular amount or in any length of time: otherwise one man might move a ship, since both the motive power of the ship-haulers and the distance that they all cause the ship to traverse are divisible into as many parts as there are men. Hence Zeno's rea[20] soning is false when he argues that there no part of the millet that does not make a
is
sound: for there
is
no reason why any such
part should not in any length of time
move
the air that the whole bushel
falling. In fact
it
does not of
fail to
moves
in
move even would move if
itself
such a quantity of the air as it this part were by itself: for no part even exists otherwise than potentially. [25] If on the other hand we have two forces each of which separately moves one of two weights a given distance in a given time, then the forces in combination will move the combined weights an equal distance in an equal time: for in this case the rules of proportion apply. Then does this hold good of alteration and of increase also? Surely it does, for in any given case we have a definite thing that causes in[30] crease and a definite thing that suffers increase, and the one causes and the other suffers a
certain
amount
amount
of
increase
of time. Similarly
in
a
we have
certain
a definite
thing that causes alteration and a definite thing
undergoes alteration, and a certain amount, or rather degree, of alteration is comthat
250 b
pleted in a certain
amount
of time: thus
twice as much alteration will be completed and conversely twice as much in twice as
much time
alteration will
occupy twice
the alteration of half of half as
much
its
as
much
time:
and
object will occupy
time and in half as
much
time
half of the object will be altered: or again, in
same amount of time it will be altered twice much. On the other hand if that which causes alteration or increase causes a certain amount of inthe
as
same distance to be traversed in the same time. [10] But if E move Z a distance T in a time A,
crease or alteration respectively in a certain
does not necessarily follow that E can move twice Z half the distance T in the same time.
low that half the force
it
A
If, then, move B a distance T in a time A, it does not follow that E, being half of A, will in the time A or in any fraction of it cause B to
traverse a part of
T
the ratio between
which
amount
does not necessarily folwill occupy twice the time in altering or increasing the object, or that in twice the time the alteration or increase will be completed by it: it may happen that there will be no alteration or increase at all, the case being the same as with the weight. [5]
of time,
it
PHYSICS
334
BOOK
25 V
VIII nature, but also for the investigation of the First Principle.
It remains to consider the following ques-
Was
becoming of motion before which it had no being, and is it perishing again so as to leave nothing in motion? Or are we to say that it never had any becoming and is not perishing, but always was and always will be? Is it in fact an immortal never-failing tion.
there ever a
property of things that are, a sort of life as were to all naturally constituted things?
it
Now
the existence of motion is asserted have anything to say about nature, because they all concern themselves with the construction of the world and study the ques[75]
by
all
who
becoming and perishing, which proccome about without the existence of motion. But those who say that there is an infinite number of worlds, some of which are in process of becoming while others are in tion of
esses could not
[20] process of perishing, assert that there
is al-
ways motion (for these processes of becoming and perishing of the worlds necessarily involve motion), whereas those who hold that there is only one world, whether everlasting or not, make corresponding assumptions in regard to motion. If then it is possible that at any time nothing should be in motion, this must come about in one of two ways: either in the manner described by Anaxagoras, who says that all [25] things were together and at rest for an infinite period of time, and that then Mind intro-
Let us take our start from what we have al1 ready laid down in our course on Physics. Motion,
we
say,
is
the fulfilment of the movable in
[10] so far as it is movable. Each kind of motion, therefore, necessarily involves the pres-
ence of the things that are capable of that motion. In fact, even apart from the definition of motion, every one would admit that in each kind of motion it is that which is capable of that motion that is in motion: thus it is that which is capable of alteration that is altered, and that which is capable of local change that [75] is in locomotion: and so there must be something capable of being burned before there can be a process of being burned, and something capable of burning before there can be a process of burning. Moreover, these things also must either have a beginning before which they had no being, or they must be eternal. Now if there was a becoming of every movable thing, it follows that before the motion in question another change or motion must have taken place in which that which was capable of being
moved
or of causing motion
had
its
becoming.
[20] To suppose, on the other hand, that these things were in being throughout all previous
time without there being any motion appears unreasonable on a moment's thought, and still more unreasonable, we shall find, on further consideration. For if we are to say that, while
duced motion and separated them; or in the manner described by Empedocles, according to whom the universe is alternately in motion and in motion, when Love is making the at rest one out of many, or Strife is making many out of one, and at rest in the intermediate periods
on the one hand things that are movand on the other hand things that are motive, there is a time when there is a first movent and a first moved, and another time when there is no such thing but only something that is at [25] rest, then this thing that is at rest must
account being as follows: hath learned to spring from Manifold,
previously have been in process of change: for there must have been some cause of its rest,
—
of time
—
his
[jo] 'Since
One
And One
disjoined makes Manifold arise,
251 a Thus they Become, nor
stable
their
is
life:
But
since their motion
must
alternate
be,
Thus have they ever Rest upon
their
round': for
we must suppose
that he
means by
[5] they alternate from the one other. must consider, then,
We
this that
motion
how
matabout of importance, not only for the study of
ter stands, for the discovery of the truth it is
to the
this
there are
able,
being the privation of motion. Therefore, first change there will be a previous change. For some things cause motion in only one way, while others can produce either of two contrary motions: thus fire causes heating [50] but not cooling, whereas it would seem that knowledge may be directed to two contrary ends while remaining one and the same. Even in the former class, however, there seems to be something similar, for a cold thing in a sense causes heating by turning away and retiring, just as one possessed of knowledge volrest
before this
BOOK
252*
makes an error when knowledge in the reverse way. But
untarily b
25
VIII,
he uses his at
any
rate all things that are capable respectively of
and being affected, or of causing moand being moved, are capable of it not un-
affecting tion
der
all
conditions, but only
when
they are in a
and approach one another: so it is on the approach of one thing to another that the one causes motion and the other is moved, and when they are present under such conditions as rendered the one motive and [5] the other movable. So if the motion was not always in process, it is clear that they must particular condition
in a condition not
have been
them capable
such as to render
moved and and one or other of them
respectively of being
of causing motion,
must have been in process of change: for in what is relative this is a necessary consequence: e.g. if
one thing
is
double another
when
before
was not so, one or other of them, if not both, must have been in process of change. It follows, it
CHAPTER
1
335
ing of motion would involve, as
we
saw, the [50] existence of a process of change previous to the first, in the same way a perishing of motion
would involve the
existence of a process of
change subsequent to the last: for when a thing ceases to be moved, it does not therefore at the same time cease to be movable e.g. the cessation of the process of being burned does not in-
—
volve the cessation of the capacity of being burned, since a thing may be capable of being burned without being in process of being burned nor, when a thing ceases to be movent, does it therefore at the same time cease to 252 a be motive. Again, the destructive agent will have to be destroyed, after what it destroys has been destroyed, and then that which has the capacity of destroying it will have to be destroyed afterwards, (so that there will be a process of change subsequent to the last,) for being destroyed also is a kind of change. If,
—
which we are
then, the view
criticizing in-
then, that there will be a process of change pre-
volves these impossible consequences,
vious to the
motion is eternal and cannot have existed at one time and not at another: in fact, such a view can hardly be described as anything else
how can there be any 'before' without the existence of time? Or how can there be any time without the existence of motion ? If, then, time is the number of motion or itself a kind of motion, it follows that, if there is always time, motion must also be eternal. But so far as time is concerned we see that all with one exception are in agreement [10] (Further,
and
'after'
in saying that
it is
uncreated: in
fact,
it is
just
Democritus to show that things cannot have had a becoming: for
[75] this that enables all
uncreated. Plato alone asserts 1 the creation of time, saying that it had a becoming together with the universe, the unitime, he says,
is
verse according to
Now ble
him having had
a becoming.
and is unthinkaapart from the moment, and the moment
[20]
since time cannot exist
is
a kind of middle-point, uniting as
it
both a beginning and an end, a beginning of future time and an end of past time, it follows that there must always be time: for the extremity of the last period of time that we take must be found in some moment, since time contains no point of contact for us except [25] the moment. Therefore, since the moment is both a beginning and an end, there must always be time on both sides of it. But if this is true of time, it is evident that it must also be true of motion, time being a kind of affection of motion.) The same reasoning will also serve to show the imperishability of motion: just as a becomdoes in
1
itself
Aristotle
is
it is
clear
that
frrst.
thinking of a passage in the Timaeus (38).
than fantastic. [5]
And much
the
same may be
said of the
and must be regarded as a principle, as would seem to be the view of Empedocles when he says that the constitution of the world is of necessity such that Love and Strife alternately predominate and cause motion, while in the inview that such
is
the ordinance of nature
that this
termediate period of time there is a state of rest. [10] Probably also those who, like Anaxagoras, assert a
single principle
(of
motion) would
hold this view. But that which is produced or directed by nature can never be anything disorderly: for nature is everywhere the cause of order. Moreover, there is no ratio in the relation of the infinite to the infinite, whereas order always means ratio. But if we say that there is first
a state of rest for an infinite time,
and
[75] then motion is started at some moment, and that the fact that it is this rather than a
moment is of no importance, and inno order, then we can no longer say that nature's work: for if anything is of a cer-
previous volves it is
tain character naturally,
and
it
either
is
so invari-
not sometimes of this and sometimes of another character (e.g. fire, which
ably
is
upwards naturally, does not sometimes do so and sometimes not) or there is a ratio in
travels
the variation.
It
[20] say with
who may
would be better, therefore, to Empedocles and any one else
have maintained such a theory as
PHYSICS
33 6 his that the universe
is
alternately at rest
and
in
motion: for in a system of this kind we have at once a certain order. But even here the holder of the theory ought not only to assert the fact: he ought to explain the cause of it: i.e. he should not make any mere assumption or lay down any gratuitous axiom, but should em[25] ploy either inductive or demonstrative reasoning. The Love and Strife postulated by Empedocles are not in themselves causes of the fact in question, nor is it of the essence of either that it should be so, the essential function of the former being to unite, of the latter to separate. If he is to go on to explain this alternate predominance, he should adduce cases where such a state of things exists, as he points to the fact that among mankind we have something that unites men, namely Love, while on the [30] other hand enemies avoid one another: thus from the observed fact that this occurs in certain cases comes the assumption that it oc-
some argument is needed to explain why the predominance of each of the two forces lasts for an equal period of time. But it is a wrong assumption to suppose universally that we have
curs also in the universe. Then, again,
an adequate
first
principle in virtue of the fact
that something always so.
is
so or always
Thus Democritus reduces
happens
the causes that
explain nature to the fact that things happened
same way as they happen now: but he does not think fit to seek for
in the past in the
[35]
253«
must be bounded by the contraries its course, and no motion can go on Secondly,
we
that
mark
to infinity.
see that a thing that neither
motion nor contains any motion within
in
is it-
can be
set in motion; e.g. inanimate things (whether the whole or some part is in question) not in motion but at rest, are at [75] some moment set in motion: whereas, if motion cannot have a becoming before which it had no being, these things ought to be either always or never in motion. Thirdly, the fact is evident above all in the case of animate beings: for it sometimes happens that there is no motion in us and we are quite still, and that nevertheless we are then at self
that are
some moment
set in
motion, that
is
to say
it
sometimes happens that we produce a begin[20] ning of motion in ourselves spontaneously without anything having set us in motion from without. We see nothing like this in the case of inanimate things, which are always set in motion by something else from without: the animal, on the other hand, we say, moves itself: therefore, if an animal is ever in a state of absolute rest, we have a motionless thing in which motion can be produced from the thing itself, and not from without. Now if this [25] can occur in an animal, why should not
same be true also of the universe as a whole? If it can occur in a small world it could also occur in a great one: and if it can occur in the
the world,
it
could also occur in the infinite;
25
b a first principle to explain this 'always':
that
so,
while his theory
be in motion or at rest. Of these objections, then, the first-mentioned
is
right in so far as
it
is
applied to certain individual cases, he is wrong in making it of universal application. Thus, a
two right
triangle always has
its
angles equal to
angles, but there
is
nevertheless an ulterior
cause of the eternity of this truth, whereas
first
and have no ulterior conclude what we have to
is, if
the infinite could as a whole possibly
—
that motion to opposites [30] the same and numerically one
statement; in fact, this
same
may be advanced against not difficult to dispose of. The chief considerations that might be thought to that
this position are
motion may exist though at one had not existed at all are the following: First, it may be said that no process of change is eternal: for the nature of all change [10] is such that it proceeds from something to something, so that every process of change indicate that
time
a correct
may
motion of that which is one and the always one and the same. (I mean that e.g. we may question whether the note given by a single string is one and the
ble for the
[5] cause. Let this say in support of
The arguments
not always is
be said to be a necessary conclusion, provided that it is possi-
principles are eternal
our contention that there never was a time when there was not motion, and never will be a time when there will not be motion.
is
—
to be not
same, or is different each time the string is struck, although the string is in the same condition and is moved in the same way.) But [35] still, however this may be, there is nothing to prevent there being a motion that is the 253 a same in virtue of being continuous and 1 eternal: we shall have something to say later
make this point clearer. As regards the second objection, no absurd-
that will
it
involved in the fact that something not motion may be set in motion, that which caused the motion from without being at one ity is
in
1
Chapter
8.
BOOK
253 b
VIII,
CHAPTERS
time present, and at another absent. Nevertheless, how this can be so remains matter for in-
how
quiry;
it
comes about,
I
mean, that the
same motive force at one time causes a thing motion, and at another does not do so:
to be in
[5] for the difficulty raised why really amounts to this
—
things are not always at
ways
in
The
rest,
by our objector is
it
some
that
and the
rest al-
motion?
third objection
may
be thought to pre-
more difficulty than the others, namely, that which alleges that motion arises in things in which it did not exist before, and adduces sent
in
proof the case of animate things: thus an
[10] animal is first at rest and afterwards walks, not having been set in motion apparent-
by anything from without. This, however, is false: for we observe that there is always some part of the animal's organism in motion, and the cause of the motion of this part is not the animal itself, but, it may be, its environment. Moreover, we say that the animal itself originates not all of its motions but its locomotion. [75] So it may well be the case or rather we may perhaps say that it must necessarily be that many motions are produced in the case the body by its environment, and some of these ly
—
—
and whole animal in motion: this is what happens when animals are asleep: though there is then no perceptive motion in them, there is some motion that causes [20] them to wake up again. But we will leave set in
motion the
again then
this
intellect or the appetite,
sets the
this point also to be elucidated at a later
1
stage
in our discussion.
Our enquiry
will resolve itself at the outset into
a consideration of the above-mentioned prob-
lem
—what can be the reason why some things
world at one time are in motion and at another are at rest again? Now one of three things must be true: either all things are al25] ways at rest, or all things are always in motion, or some things are in motion and others at rest: and in this last case again either the things that are in motion are always in motion and the things that are at rest are always at rest, or they are all constituted so as to be capable alike of motion and of rest; or there is in the
ii
yet a third possibility
that
some things
in the
—
remaining it may be world are always mo-
always in motion, while others again admit of both conditions. This last is [jo] the account of the matter that we must tionless, others
1
Chapter 6^
1-3
337
give: for herein lies the solution of all the
and the conclusion of the upon which we are engaged.
culties raised
tigation
To
diffi-
inves-
rest, and an attempt to show the theory to be reasonable, would be an instance of intellectual weakness: it would call in question a whole system, not a particular [25] detail: moreover, it would be an attack not only on the physicist but on almost all sciences and all received opinions, since motion 253 b plays a part in all of them. Further, just as in arguments about mathematics objections that involve first principles do not affect the mathematician and the other sciences are in
maintain that
all
things are at
to disregard sense-perception in
similar case
point that
—
—
so, too,
we have
objections involving the
just raised
do not
affect the
[5] physicist: for it is a fundamental assumption with him that motion is ultimately refer-
able to nature herself.
The assertion that all we may fairly regard as it
less
is
though
things are in motion
equally
false,
though
subversive of physical science:
for
our course on physics it was laid down that rest no less than motion is ultimately referable to nature herself, nevertheless motion is the characteristic fact of nature: moreover, the view is actually held by some that not [10] merely some things but all things in the world are in motion and always in motion, though we cannot apprehend the fact by in
Although the supporters of do not state clearly what kind of motion they mean, or whether they mean all kinds, it is no hard matter to reply to them: sense-perception. this theory
thus we may point out that there cannot be a continuous process either of increase or of decrease: that which comes between the two has [75] to be included. The theory resembles that about the stone being worn away by the drop of water or split by plants growing out of it: if so much has been extruded or removed by the drop, it does not follow that half the amount has previously been extruded or removed in half the time: the case of the hauled ship is exactly comparable: here we have so many drops setting so much in motion, but a part of them will not set as much in motion in any period of time.
The amount removed
is,
it
is
true, di-
[20] visible into a number of parts, but no one of these was set in motion separately: they were in motion together. It is evident, then, from the fact that the decrease is divisible
all set
that
into an infinite
number
of parts
it
does not
fol-
low that some part must always be passing away: it all passes away at a particular mo-
PHYSICS
33«
ment. Similarly, too, in the case of any alteration whatever if that which suffers alteration is
infinitely divisible
does not follow from
it
[25] this that the same is true of the alteration itself, which often occurs all at once, as in
when any one
freezing. Again,
must follow
there
a period of
restoration to health
is
has fallen ill, time in which his
in the future: the proc-
change cannot take place in an instant: the change cannot be a change to anything
ess of
yet
The
else but health.
assertion, therefore, that
continuous is an extravagant calico] ing into question of the obvious: for alteration is a change from one contrary to another. Moreover, we notice that a stone becomes neither harder nor softer. Again, in the matter of locomotion, it would be a strange thing if a stone could be falling or resting on the ground without our being able to perceive the fact. Further, it is a law of nature that earth and all other bodies should remain in [35] their proper places and be moved from them only by violence: from the fact then that some of them are in their proper places it follows that in respect of place also all things can254 a not be in motion. These and other similar arguments, then, should convince us that alteration
it is
ways
is
impossible either that in
motion or that
all
all
things are
al-
things are always
at rest.
Nor ways
be that some things are alothers always in motion, and
again can
at
rest,
it
nothing sometimes at rest and sometimes in [5] motion. This theory must be pronounced impossible on the same grounds as those previously mentioned: viz. that we see the abovementioned changes occurring in the case of the
same
things.
We
may
further point out that
the defender of this position
is
fighting against
the obvious, for on this theory there can be no such thing as increase: nor can there be any
such thing as compulsory motion,
if it
is
im-
possible that a thing can be at rest before being
[10] set in motion unnaturally. This theory, then, does away with becoming and perishing.
Moreover, motion, it would seem, is generally thought to be a sort of becoming and perishing, for that to which a thing changes comes to be, or occupancy of it comes to be, and that from which a thing changes ceases to be, or there ceases to be occupancy of it. It is clear, therefore, that there are cases of occasional motion
and occasional
254 b
ments previously advanced. We must take our from the possibilities that we
start as before
distinguished just above. Either all things are at rest, or all things are in motion, or some things are at rest and others in motion. And if
some things
are at rest and others in motion, must be that either all things are sometimes at rest and sometimes in motion, or some things are always at rest and the remainder always in motion, or some of the things are always at rest and others always in motion while others again are sometimes at rest and sometimes in motion. Now we have
[20] then
it
said before that
should be at
it is
rest:
impossible that
repeat that assertion.
We
may
all
things
we may now
nevertheless
point out that,
[25] even if it is really the case, as certain persons assert, that the existent is infinite and moit certainly does not appear to be so if follow sense-perception: many things that exist appear to be in motion. Now if there is such a thing as false opinion or opinion at all,
tionless,
we
is also motion; and similarly if there is such a thing as imagination, or if it is the case that anything seems to be different at different times: for imagination and opinion are [jo] thought to be motions of a kind. But to investigate this question at all to seek a reasoned justification of a belief with regard to
there
—
which we are too well off to require reasoned implies bad judgement of what is better and what is worse, what commends itself to belief and what does not, what is ultimate and what is not. It is likewise impossible that all things should be in motion or that some things should be always in motion and [55] the remainder always at rest. We have sufficient ground for rejecting all these theories in the single fact that we see some things that 254 b are sometimes in motion and sometimes at rest. It is evident, therefore, that it is no less impossible that some things should be always in motion and the remainder always at rest justification
—
than that all things should be at rest or that all things should be in motion continuously. It remains, then, to consider whether all things are so constituted as to be capable both of being in motion and of being at rest, or whether, [5] while some things are so constituted, some are always at rest and some are always in motion: for it is this last view that we have to show to be true.
rest.
We
have now to take the assertion that [75] all things are sometimes at rest and sometimes in
motion and
to confront
it
with the argu-
Now
of things that cause motion or suffer mosome the motion is accidental, to others
tion, to
255
BOOK
J
essential: thus
accidental to
it is
CHAPTERS
VIII,
what merely
3-4
339
would be experienced
cases that difficulty
belongs to or contains as a part a thing that causes motion or suffers motion, essential to a [10] thing that causes motion or suffers motion not merely by belonging to such a thing or
deciding whence the motion
containing
their
it
as a part.
Of things to which the motion is essential some derive their motion from themselves, others from something else: and in some cases their
motion
is
and
natural, in others violent
Thus
unnatural.
in things that derive their
[75] motion from themselves, e.g. all animals, the motion is natural (for when an animal is in motion its motion is derived from itself): and
whenever the source in the thing itself
that thing
is
of the
we
motion
of a thing
is
say that the motion of
natural. Therefore the animal as a
whole moves itself naturally: but the body ol the animal may be in motion unnaturally as well as naturally: it depends upon the kind ol motion that it may chance to be suffering and [20] the kind of element of which it is composed. And the motion of things that derive their motion from something else is in some cases natural, in other unnatural: e.g.
upward
motion of earthy things and downward motion of fire are unnatural. Moreover the parts of animals are often in motion in an unnatural way, their positions and the character of the motion being abnormal. The fact that a thing [25] that is in motion derives its motion from something is most evident in things that are in motion unnaturally, because in such cases it is clear that the motion is derived from something other than the thing itself. Next to things that are in motion unnaturally those whose motion while natural is derived from themselves
—
e.g.
animals
—make
this fact clear: for
not as to whether the motion is derived from something but as to how we ought to distinguish in the thing behere the uncertainty
is
motion
is
however,
is
pre-
last
distinguished.
Where
we
things derive their
motion from something else we distinguished [55] the cases in which the motion is unnatural: we are left with those that are to be contrasted with the others by reason of the fact 255 a that the motion is natural. It is in these
violent:
tion to their proper positions
—the —
light thing
up and the heavy thing down
their
natural; but in this latter case
it
evident, as
it is
when
the motion
is is
motion is no longer
unnatural,
[5] whence their motion is derived. It is impossible to say that their motion is derived
from themselves: this is a characteristic of life and peculiar to living things. Further, if it were, it would have been in their power to stop themselves cause to
(I
itself to
walk), and
mean walk
if e.g. a thing can can also cause itself not
that it
on power
so, since
this supposition fire
of upward locomoshould also possess the [10] power of downward locomotion. Moreover if things move themselves, it would be unreasonable to suppose that in only one kind of motion is their motion derived from themselves. Again, how can anything of continuous and naturally connected substance move itself? In so far as a thing is one and continuous not merely in virtue of contact, it is impassive: it is only in so far as a thing is divided that one part of it is by nature active and another [ 15] passive. Therefore none of the things that we are now considering move themselves (for they are of naturally connected substance), nor does anything else that is continuous: in each itself
tion,
possesses the
case the
is
it
movent must be separate from the
we see to be the case with inanimate when an animate thing moves them. It
moved, things
clear that
is
it
as
the fact that these things also always derive
motion from something: what it is would become evident if we were to distinguish the their
different kinds of cause.
The above-mentioned distinctions can made in the case of things that cause
capable of difficulty,
would properly occupy, when they are in mo-
verse of those they
naturally (e.g.
greatest
When
these things are in motion to positions the re-
tion.
The
in
derived, e.g. in
and heavy things.
the case of light
tween the movent and the moved. It would [50] seem that in animals, just as in ships and things not naturally organized, that which causes motion is separate from that which suffers motion, and that it is only in this sense that the animal as a whole causes its own mo-
sented by the remaining case of those that
is
[20]
also be
motion: some of them are capable of causing (e.g. the lever is not naturally capable of moving the weight), others
motion unnaturally
and
what is actually hot is naturally moving what is potentially hot):
similarly in the case of
all
other things of
this kind.
In the
same way,
too,
what
is
potentially of
a certain quality or of a certain quantity or in a
[25] certain place is naturally movable when it contains the corresponding principle in itself
and not accidentally (for the same thing may be both of a certain quality and of a certain
PHYSICS
340
an accidental, not an So when fire moved by something the motion is
quantity, but the one
is
essential property of the other).
or earth violent it
is
when
it is
unnatural, and natural
when
brings to actuality the proper activities that
[30] they potentially possess. But the fact that the term 'potentially' is used in more than one sense
the reason
is
why
not evident whence
it is
such motions as the upward motion of
downward motion
the
One who
is
fire
and
of earth are derived.
learning a
science
potentially
knows it in a different sense from one who while already possessing the knowledge is not actually exercising it. Wherever we have something capable of acting and something capable of being correspondingly acted on, in the event [^5] of any such pair being in contact what is 255 b potential becomes at times actual: e.g. the learner becomes from one potential something another potential something: for one who possesses knowledge of a science but is not actually exercising
knows
it
though not
potentially in a sense,
the science in the
same
knew it potentially before he learnt And when he is in this condition, if some-
some hindrance
thing does not prevent him, he actively exercises his
knowledge: otherwise he would be in knowing. In re-
the contradictory state of not
[5] gard to natural bodies also the case is simiThus what is cold is potentially hot: then
lar.
a change takes place
and
it is fire,
with heavy and
from heavy,
e.g. air
thing that
first
and
actually light,
its
is
burns, it.
So,
generated from water (for water is light: light
[10] the air
it
and hinders
unless something prevents too,
and is
is
potentially light),
and
will at once realize
proper activity as such unless something
prevents
it.
The
activity of lightness consists in
it
does not occupy an upper if what hinders it is
[20] position, whereas,
removed,
it
realizes
to rise higher.
The
its
activity
and continues what is of
process whereby
a certain quality
changes to a condition of
tive existence
similar: thus the exercise of
is
ac-
knowledge follows at once upon the possession it unless something prevents it. So, too, what
of is
of a certain quantity extends itself over a
something prevents it. The thing in a sense is and in a sense is not moved by one who moves what is obstructing and [25] preventing its motion (e.g. one who pulls certain space unless
a pillar from under a roof or one who removes a stone from a wineskin in the water is the accidental cause of motion): and in the same way the real cause of the motion of a ball rebounding from a wall is not the wall but the thrower. So it is clear that in all these cases the
away
[50] thing does not move itself, but it contains within itself the source of motion not of moving something or of causing motion, but of
—
suffering
sense as he it.
256 a
If
it.
then the motion of
all
things that are in
motion is either natural or unnatural and violent, and all things whose motion is violent and unnatural are moved by something, and something other than themselves, and again all things whose motion is natural are moved by something both those that are moved by themselves and those that are not moved by them[^5] selves (e.g. light things and heavy things, 256 a which are moved either by that which brought the thing into existence as such and made it light and heavy, or by that which released what was hindering and preventing it); then all things that are in motion must be
—
moved by something.
the light thing being in a certain situation,
namely high up: when
it is
in the contrary situ-
being prevented from rising. The case is similar also in regard to quantity and quality. But, be it noted, this is the question we are trying to answer how can we account for the motion of light things and heavy things to their proper situations? The reason for it is [75] that they have a natural tendency respectively towards a certain position: and this conation,
it is
—
stitutes the essence of lightness and heaviness, the former being determined by an upward, the latter by a downward, tendency. As we
have said, a thing may be potentially light or heavy in more senses than one. Thus not only when a thing is water is it in a sense potentially light,
but
when
it
it may be still be that through
has become air
potentially light: for
it
may
Now
this may come about in either of two ways. Either the movent is not itself responsible for the motion, which is to be referred
to
something
[5] or the
else
movent
which moves the movent, is itself
responsible for the
motion. Further, in the latter case, either the movent immediately precedes the last thing in the series, or there may be one or more intermediate links: e.g. the stick moves the stone and is moved by the hand, which again is moved by the man: in the man, however, we have reached a movent that is not so in virtue of being moved by something else. Now we say that the thing is moved both by the last and by the first movent in the series, but more
BOOK
256 b
CHAPTERS
VIII,
[10] strictly by the first, since the .first movent moves the last, whereas the last does not move the first, and the first will move the
thing without the
last,
not the stick will not
but the
last will
move it without the first: e.g. move anything unless it is itself moved by
the
then everything that is in motion must be moved by something, and the movent must either itself be moved by something else or not, [75] and in the former case there must be some first movent that is not itself moved by
man.
If
while in the case of the immediof this kind there is no need of an intermediate movent that is also moved (for it is impossible that there should be an infinite series of movents, each of which is
anything ate
else,
movent being
moved by something
else, since in an inno first term) if then everything that is in motion is moved by some[20] thing, and the first movent is moved but itself
—
finite series there is
not by anything
else, it
much
be
moved by
4-5
movent
And
way we
we
result as follows.
motion is an accidental attribute of the movements in question, so that each of them moves something while being itself in motion, but not always because
it
is itself
in motion, or
it
not accidental but an essential attribute. Let us consider the former alternative. If then it is an accidental attribute, it is not necessary that that which is in motion should be in motion: and if this is so it is clear that there may be a time when nothing that exists is in motion, since the accidental is not [10] necessary but contingent. Now if we asis
sume
the existence of a possibility, any con-
we
thereby reach will not be an it may be contrary to But the non-existence of motion is an im-
clusion that
though
impossibility, fact.
somewhere and not be infinite. Thus, if the stick moves something in virtue of being moved by the hand, the hand moves the stick: and if something else moves with the hand, the hand also is moved by something different from itself. So when motion by means of an instrument is at each stage caused by something different from the instrument, this must always be preceded by something else which imparts motion with itself. Therefore, if this last movent is in motion and there 256 b is nothing else that moves it, it must move itself. So this reasoning also shows that, when a thing is moved, if it is not moved immediately by something that moves itself, the
same
[5] If everything that is in motion is moved by something that is in motion, either this being in
possibility:
stop
consider the matter in yet a third
shall get this
This same argument may also be stated in another way as follows. Every movent moves something and moves it with something, either with itself or with something else: e.g. a man moves a thing either himself or with a stick, and a thing is knocked down either by the [25] wind itself or by a stone propelled by the wind. But it is impossible for that with which a thing is moved to move it without being moved by that which imparts motion by its own agency: on the other hand, if a thing imparts motion by its own agency, it is not necessary that there should be anything else with which it imparts motion, whereas if there is a different thing with which it imparts motion, there must be something that imparts motion not with something else but with itself, or else there will be an infinite series. If, then, anything is a movent while being itself moved,
must
to a
of this kind. if
itself.
[50] the series
34 1
some time or other
series brings us at
there
for
we have shown above
1
that
must always be motion.
Moreover, the conclusion to which we have been led is a reasonable one. For there must be three things the moved, the movent, and the [75] instrument of motion. Now the moved must be in motion, but it need not move anything else: the instrument of motion must both move something else and be itself in motion (for it changes together with the moved, with
—
which
it
and continuous,
in contact
is
clear in the
case of things that
move
as
is
other
things locally, in which case the two things
must up to a certain point be in contact): and the movent that is to say, that which causes motion in such a manner that it is not merely the instrument of motion must be unmoved.
—
—
[20] last
Now we
term in
have visual experience of the
this series,
namely that which has
the capacity of being in motion, but does not contain a motive principle, and also of that
which
is
in
motion but
not by anything
else:
is
it is
moved by
itself
and
reasonable, therefore,
not to say necessary, to suppose the existence of the third term also, that which causes motion but is itself unmoved. So, too, Anaxagoras [25] is right when he says that Mind passive and unmixed, since he makes principle of motion: for
it
is
im-
it
the
could cause motion
in this sense only by being itself
unmoved, and
have supreme control only by being unmixed. We will now take the second alternative. If the movent 1 Chapter 1.
is
not accidentally but necessarily
PHYSICS
34 2 in
— so that
motion
if it
were not
would not move anything
in
motion, it movent,
— then the
motion, must be in motion [50] in one of two ways: it is moved either as that is which is moved with the same kind of motion, or with a different kind either that in so far as
it
in
is
—
257 b
exercises that capacity, has as such a capacity for being made healthy, and that which has a capacity for building has as such a capacity for
being
built. It will
have the capacity for being
moved either immediately or through one more links (as it will if, while everything
thus or
which is heating, I mean, is itself in process of becoming hot, that which is making healthy in process of becoming healthy, and that which is
that has a capacity for causing
causing locomotion in process of locomotion, or else that which is making healthy is, let us say, in process of locomotion, and that which is
for suffering
causing locomotion in process of, say, increase. But it is evident that this is impossible. For if we adopt the first assumption we have to make it apply within each of the very lowest species 25 7 a into which motion can be divided: e.g. we must say that if some one is teaching some lesson in geometry, he
is
also in process of be-
ing taught that same lesson in geometry, and if he is throwing he is in process of being
that
such a capacity for being
motion has
as
moved by something
[20] else, the motion that
it has the capacity not that with which it affects what is next to it, but a motion of a different kind; e.g. that which has a capacity for making healthy might as such have a capacity for learn-
is
ing: the series, however, could be traced back,
we
as
we
said before, until at some time or other arrived at the same kind of motion).
the
Now
first
ond
is
alternative
fantastic:
it
is is
and the secabsurd that that which
impossible,
has a capacity for causing alteration should as [25] such necessarily have a capacity, let us say, for increase. It is not necessary, therefore,
same manner. Or if we reassumption we must say that one kind of motion is derived from another; e.g. that that which is causing locomotion is in process
that that
[5] of increase, that which is causing this increase is in process of being altered by some-
in motion will derive its motion either from something that is at rest or from itself. But if there were any need to consider which of the two, that which moves itself or that which is moved by something else, is the cause and principle of motion, every one would decide [jo] for the former: for that which is itself
thrown
in just the
ject this
thing tion
else,
is
and that which
is
causing this altera-
some
in process of suffering
different
kind of motion. But the series must stop somewhere, since the kinds of motion are limited;
and
if
we
say that the process
which
is
reversible,
and
causing alteration is in process of locomotion, we do no more than if we had said at the outset that that which is causing locomotion is in process of locomotion, and [10] that one who is teaching is in process of being taught: for it is clear that everything that that
that
is
moved
is
is
moved by
the
movent
that
is
which is moved should always be moved by something else that is itself moved
by something else: so there will be an end to the series. Consequently the first thing that is
independently a cause is always prior as a cause to that which is so only in virtue of being itself dependent upon something else that makes it
so.
We
must therefore make
a fresh start
and
consider the question; if a thing moves itself, in what sense and in what manner does it do
Now
motion must be
further back in the series as well as by that
so?
which immediately moves it: movent is that which more
infinitely divisible, for it has been shown al257 b ready 1 in our general course on Physics,
But
this
is
strictly
of course impossible: for
the consequence that one process of learning as
in fact the earlier
teaching
who
what he
necessarily
is
is
moves it
teaching
is
volved
that,
since
in
teaching, where-
implies
possessing
knowledge, and learning not possessing Still more unreasonable is the consequence [75]
it.
involves
everything that
moved is moved by something that moved by something else, everything
is
it.
inis
itself
that has
a capacity for causing motion has as such a corresponding capacity for being moved: i.e. it will have a capacity for being moved in the sense in which one might say that everything that has a capacity for making healthy, and
everything that
is
in
that everything that is essentially in motion is continuous. Now it is impossible that that which moves itself should in its entirety move itself: for then, while being specifically one and indivisible, it would as a whole both un-
dergo and cause the same locomotion or alteration: thus it would at the same time be both [5] teaching and being taught (the same thing), or both restoring to and being restored to the same health. Moreover, we have established the fact that it is the movable that is
moved; and
this
is
potentially, not actually, in
motion, but the potential x The reference is apparently
is
in process to actu-
to vi. 4 (234 b 10 sqq.).
258
BOOK
£
VIII,
an incomplete actuality of the movable. The movent on the other hand ality,
is
and motion
is
already in activity: e.g.
it is
which is hot that which pro-
that
that produces heat: in fact,
duces the form [10] sesses
move
it.
itself as
is always something that posConsequently (if a thing can a whole), the same thing in re-
same thing may be at the same time both hot and not hot. So, too, in every other case where the movent must be described spect of the
by the same name in the same sense as the moved. Therefore when a thing moves itself it is one part of it that is the movent and another part that is moved. But it is not self-moving in the sense that each of the two parts is moved by the other part: the following considerations [75]
make
this evident. In the first place,
it
each of the two parts is to move the other, there will be no first movent. If a thing is moved by a series of movents, that which is earlier in the series is more the cause of its being
which comes next, and will movent: for we found that there are two kinds of movent, that which is itself moved by something else and that which derives its motion from itself: and that which is further from the thing that is moved is nearer to the principle of motion than that [20] which is intermediate. In the second place, there is no necessity for the movent part
moved than be
more
to be
that
truly the
moved by anything but
itself:
so
it
can
only be accidentally that the other part moves it in return. I take then the possible case of its not moving it: then there will be a part that is
an unmoved movent. no necessity for the movent to be moved in return: on the contrary the necessity that there should always be motion makes it necessary that there should be
moved and
a part that
is
In the third place, there
some movent [25] by
that
itself.
is
is
either
unmoved or moved we should
In the fourth place
then have a thing undergoing the same motion it is causing that which is producing heat, therefore, being heated. But as a matter of fact that which primarily moves itself cannot contain either a single part that moves itself or a number of parts each of which moves itself. For, if the whole is moved by itself, it must be moved either by some part of itself or [50] as a whole by itself as a whole. If, then, it is moved in virtue of some part of it being moved by that part itself, it is this part that will be the primary self-movent, since, if this part is separated from the whole, the part will still move itself, but the whole will do so no longer. If on the other hand the whole is moved that
—
CHAPTER by
5
343
must be accidentally move themselves: and therefore,
as a whole,
itself
that the parts
it
their self-motion not being necessary,
258 a take the
we may moved
case of their not being
by themselves. Therefore in the whole of the thing we may distinguish that which imparts motion without itself being moved and that which is moved: for only in this way is it possible for a thing to be self-moved. Further, if
moves itself we may distinguish in it which imparts the motion and that which moved: so while we say that AB is moved by
the whole that is
itself,
[5]
And
we may
also say that
it is
moved by
which imparts motion may be either a thing that is moved by something else or a thing that is unmoved, and that which A.
is
since that
moved may
motion
be either a thing that imparts
something else or a thing that does not, that which moves itself must be composed of something that is unmoved but imparts motion and also of something that is moved but does not necessarily impart motion but may or may not do so. Thus let A be something that imparts motion but is unmoved, B something that is moved by A and moves T, T some[10] thing that is moved by B but moves nothto
ing (granted that we eventually arrive at T take it that there is only one inter-
we may
mediate term, though there
Then
ABT
the whole
may
moves
be more).
But if I imparting motion and B being moved, whereas T will not move itself or in fact be moved at all. Nor [75] again will BT move itself apart from A: for B imparts motion only through being moved by something else, not through being moved by any part of itself. So only AB moves take
away
itself.
T,
AB
will
move
That which moves
itself.
itself,
itself,
A
therefore,
must
comprise something that imparts motion but is unmoved and something that is moved but [20] does not necessarily move anything else: and each of these two things, or at any rate one of them, must be in contact with the other. If, then, that which imparts motion is a continuous substance that which is moved must of course be so it is clear that it is not through some part of the whole being of such a nature
—
—
moving itself that the whole moves itself as a whole, both being moved and imparting motion through [25] containing a part that imparts motion and a part that is moved. It does not impart motion as a whole nor is it moved as a whole: it is A alone that imparts motion and B alone that is moved. It is not true, further, that T is moved by A, which is impossible. as to be capable of
moves
itself:
it
PHYSICS
344
Here a difficulty arises: if something is taken away from A (supposing that that which imparts motion but is unmoved is a continuous substance), or from B the part that is moved, will the remainder of A continue to impart mo[30] tion or the remainder of B continue to be moved? If so, it will not be AB primarily that is moved by itself, since, when something is taken away from AB, the remainder of AB will still continue to move itself. Perhaps we 258 b may state the case thus: there is nothing to prevent each of the two parts, or at any rate one of them, that which is moved, being divisible is
though actually undivided,
divided
of the
it
so that
if it
capacity:
ity of
is
evident
which primarily imparts motion is unmoved: for, whether the series is closed at once by that which is in motion but moved by something else deriving its motion directly from the first unmoved, or whether the motion is derived from what is in motion but moves itself and stops its own motion, on both supthe result that in
things being in motion that
imparts motion
is
all
cases of
which primarily
unmoved.
[10] Since there must always be motion without intermission, there must necessarily be something, one thing or it may be a plurality, that first imparts motion, and this first movent must be unmoved. Now the question whether each of the things that are unmoved but impart motion is eternal is irrelevant to our present argument: but the following considerations will make it clear that there must necessarily be some such thing, which, while it has the capacof moving something moved and exempt from
is itself unchange, which [75] can affect it neither in an unqualified nor in an accidental sense. Let us suppose, if any one likes, that in the case of certain things it is possible for them at different times to be and not to be, without any process of becoming and perishing (in fact it would seem to be necessary, if a thing that has not parts at one time is and at another time is not, that any such thing should without undergoing any process of change at one time be and at another time [20] not be). And let us further suppose it
ity
possible that
some
else,
all
principles that are
clearly be
move themselves
certain particular things, while others
other things.
The
eternity
and continu-
the process cannot be caused either by
any one of them singly or by the sum of them, is
[5] that that
we have
something that causes at one time to be and at another not to be. For, since nothing that has not parts can be in motion, that which [25] moves itself must as a whole have magnitude, though nothing that we have said makes this necessarily true of every movent. So the fact that some things become and others perish, and that this is so continuously, cannot be caused by any one of those things that, though they are unmoved, do not always exist: nor again can it be caused by any of those which things that
residing primarily in
so there
things that are potentially divisible. From what has been said, then, it
positions
must
there
move move
and
to prevent self-motion
are and at another time are not. Even so, this cannot be true of all such principles, since
nothing
will not continue in the possession
same
259*
unmoved
but capable of imparting motion at one time
must be eterand necessary, whereas the sum of these movents is infinite and they do not all exist together. It is clear, then, that though there [jo] because this causal relation
nal
may
be countless instances of the perishing of
259 a some
principles that are unmoved but impart motion, and though many things that move themselves perish and are succeeded by others that come into being, and though one thing that is unmoved moves one thing while another moves another, nevertheless there is something that comprehends them all, and that as something apart from each one of them, and this
it is
that
is
some
the cause of the fact that
things are and others are not and of the con[5] tinuous process of change: and this causes the motion of the other movents, while they are the causes of the
motion of other things.
Motion, then, being eternal, the first movent, if there is but one, will be eternal also: if there are more than one, there will be a plurality of such eternal movents. We ought, however, to suppose that there is one rather than many, and a finite rather than an infinite number. When the consequences of either assumption are the same, we should always assume that things are finite rather than infinite in number, since [10] in things constituted by nature that which is finite and that which is better ought, if possible, to be present rather than the reverse: and here it is sufficient to assume only one movent, the first of unmoved things, which being eternal will be the principle of motion to everything else. The following argument also makes it evident that the first movent must be something that is one and eternal. We have shown that Chapter 1. 1
260
BOOK
a
VIII,
CHAPTERS
must always be motion. That being so, motion must also be continuous, because what is always is continuous, whereas what is merely in succession is not continuous. But further, if motion is continuous, it is one: and it is one only if the movent and the moved that constitute it are each of them one, since in the [75] there
event of a thing's being moved now by one thing and now by another the whole motion will not be continuous but successive. [20] Moreover a conviction that there is a first unmoved something may be reached not only from the foregoing arguments, but also by considering again the principles operative in movit is evident that among existing
ents.
Now
things there are
some
that are sometimes in
motion and sometimes served above to make it 1
at rest.
This
clear that
it is
fact has
not true
things are in motion or that all things are at rest or that some things are al[25] ways at rest and the remainder always in
either that
all
5-6
345
connected with other natural motions in animals, which they do not experience through their
own
[10]
crease,
instrumentality, e.g. increase, de-
and
respiration:
these
are
ex-
perienced by every animal while it is at rest and not in motion in respect of the motion set up by its own agency: here the motion is caused by the atmosphere and by many things that enter into the animal: thus in some cases the cause is nourishment: when it is being digested animals sleep, and when it is being distributed
through the system they awake and move first principle of this motion being thus originally derived from outside. Therefore animals are not always in continuous motion by their own agency: it is some[75] thing else that moves them, itself being in motion and changing as it comes into relation with each several thing that moves itself. (Moreover in all these self-moving things the themselves, the
we wish
to explain
movent and cause of their self-motion is moved by itself, though in an accidental sense: that is to say, the body changes its place, so that that which is in the body changes its place also and is a self-movent through its [20] exercise of leverage.) Hence we may con-
also the nature of each of the other
two kinds
fidently conclude that
motion: on
this
matter proof
is
supplied by
things that fluctuate between the two and have the capacity of being sometimes in motion and sometimes at rest. The existence of things of this
kind
is
clear to all: but
some things that are always unmoved and some things that are always in motion. In the course of our argument [jo] directed to this end we established the and show
that there are
fact that everything that is in motion is moved by something, and that the movent is either unmoved or in motion, and that, if it is in motion, it is moved either by itself or by something else and so on throughout the series: and so we proceeded to the position that the first
first
itself
selves
should cause continuous motion. So the neshould be motion continuously requires that there should be a first movent that is unmoved even accidentally, if, as we 2 [25] have said, there is to be in the world of things an unceasing and undying motion, and
cessity that there
the world
is
motion to be moved is that which moves itself, and the first principle of the whole series is 259 b the unmoved. Further it is evident from
the
first
1
Chapter
3.
remain permanently
self-conif
the
permanent, the universe must also be permanent, since it is continuous with principle
have the characteristic of moving themselves, animal kingdom and the whole class of living things. This being so, then, the view was suggested that perhaps it may be possible for motion to come to be in a thing without having been in existence at all before, because we [5] see this actually occurring in animals: they are unmoved at one time and then again they are in motion, as it seems. We must grasp the fact, therefore, that animals move themselves only with one kind of motion, and that this is not strictly originated by them. The cause of it is not derived from the animal itself: it is
to
tained and within the same limits: for first
e.g. the
a thing belongs to the
it
principle that directly causes things that are in
actual observation that there are things that
if
unmoved movents that are also themmoved accidentally, it is impossible that
class of
is
principle.
(We must
distinguish,
however, between accidental motion of a thing by itself and such motion by something else, the former being confined to perishable things, whereas the latter belongs also to certain first principles of heavenly bodies, of all those, that [jo] is to say, that experience more than one locomotion.)
And 260*
further,
if
there
this nature, a
is
always something of that is itself un-
movent
moved and eternal, then that which moved by it must be eternal. Indeed
is
first
this is
from the consideration that there would otherwise be no becoming and perishing and no change of any kind in other things, which require something that is in motion to clear also
2
Chapter
1.
260 b
PHYSICS
34 6
move them: for the motion imparted by the unmoved will always be imparted in the same way and be one and the same, since the unmoved does not itself change in relation to [5] that which is moved by it. But that which is moved by something that, though it is in motion, is moved directly by the unmoved stands in varying relations to the things that it moves, so that the motion that it causes will not be always the same: by reason of the fact
thus
itself:
ment
it
is
said that contrary
to contrary: but
growth
by things becoming like to
is
is
nourish-
effected only
There must be is this change contrary. But the fact like.
alteration, then, in that there
260 b from contrary that a thing
is
to
altered requires that there should
be something that alters
makes so
it is
it,
something
e.g. that
the potentially hot into the actually hot: plain that the movent does not maintain
as has been said, since it remains permanently simple and unvarying and in the same state, will cause motion that is one and
uniform relation to it but is at one time nearer to and at another farther from that [5] which is altered: and we cannot have this without locomotion. If, therefore, there must always be motion, there must also always be locomotion as the primary motion, and, if there is a primary as distinguished from a secondary form of locomotion, it must be the primary form. Again, all affections have their origin in condensation and rarefaction: thus [10] heavy and light, soft and hard, hot and cold, are considered to be forms of density and rarity. But condensation and rarefaction are nothing more than combination and separation, processes in accordance with which substances are said to become and perish: and in being combined and separated things must change in respect of place. And further, when a thing is increased or decreased its magnitude changes in respect of place. [75] Again, there is another point of view from which it will be clearly seen that locomo-
simple.
tion
that it occupies contrary positions or assumes contrary forms at different times it will pro[10] duce contrary motions in each several thing that it moves and will cause it to be at
another time in motion. then, has served to clear up the point about which we raised a
one time
at rest
and
at
The foregoing argument,
difficulty at the outset
1
—why
that instead
is it
things being either in motion or at
of
all
or
some things being always
rest,
motion and the
in
remainder always at rest, there are things that are sometimes in motion and sometimes not?
The
cause of this
is
now
while some things are
unmoved movent and
plain:
because,
is
it
moved by an
eternal
are therefore always in
[75] motion, other things are moved by a movent that is in motion and changing, so that they too must change. But the unmoved movent,
a
is
primary. As in the case of other things
so too in the case of
may [20] This matter will be made clearer, however, if we start afresh from another point.
We
must consider whether
not possible that there should be a continuous motion, and, if it is
possible,
which
it is
this
is
motion
the primary motion: for
is
or
it is
is,
and which
plain that
if
must always be motion, and a particular motion is primary and continuous, then it is [25] this motion that is imparted by the first movent, and so it is necessarily one and the same and continuous and primary. Now of the three kinds of motion that there are motion in respect of magnitude, motion in respect of affection, and motion in respect of place it is this last, which we call locomotion, that must be primary. This may be shown as there
— —
follows.
It is
impossible that there should be
[jo] increase without the previous occurrence of alteration: for that
though itself, is 1
in a sense
it is
which
3.
what
by what
is
A
thing
is
said
when, if it does not exist, the others will not exist, whereas it can exist without the others: and there is also priority in time and priority in perfection of exto be prior to other things
Let us begin, then, with the first sense. be motion continuously, and there may be continuously either continuous motion or successive motion, the former, however, in a higher degree than the latter: moreover it is better that it should be continuous rather than successive motion, and we always assume the presence in nature of the better, if it be possible: since, then, continuous 2 motion is possible (this will be proved later: istence.
[20]
Now there must
for the present let us take
it
for granted),
and
[25] no other motion can be continuous except locomotion, locomotion must be primary. For there
is
no
necessity for the subject of locomo-
like
tion to be the subject either of increase or of alteration, nor need it become or perish: on the
unlike
other hand there cannot be any one of these
increased,
increased by
in a sense increased
Chapter
is
motion the word 'primary'
be used in several senses.
is
al-
2
Chapter
8.
BOOK
261 b
VIII,
CHAPTERS
fr-7
347
when
a thing
processes without the existence of the continu-
in quantity
ous motion imparted by the first movent. Secondly, locomotion must be primary in time: for this is the only motion possible for [jo] eternal things. It is true indeed that, in the case of any individual thing that has a becoming, locomotion must be the last of its motions: for after its becoming it first experiences alteration and increase, and locomotion is a motion that belongs to such things only when they 261 a are perfected. But there must previously be something else that is in process of locomo-
creased.
Above
motion
in respect of place,
tion to be the cause even of the becoming of things that become, without itself being in process of becoming, as e.g. the begotten is pre-
ceded by what begot it: otherwise becoming might be thought to be the primary motion on the ground that the thing must first become. [5] But though this is so in the case of any individual thing that becomes, nevertheless before anything becomes, something else must be in motion, not itself becoming but being, and before this there must again be something else. And since becoming cannot be primary for, if it were, everything that is in motion would it is plain that no one of the mobe perishable tions next in order can be prior to locomotion. [10] By the motions next in order I mean increase and then alteration, decrease, and perishing. All these are posterior to becoming: consequently, if not even becoming is prior to locomotion, then no one of the other processes of change is so either.
—
—
Thirdly, that which is in process of becoming appears universally as something imperfect and proceeding to a first principle: and so what is posterior in the order of becoming is prior in the order of nature. Now all things that go through the process of becoming acquire locomotion last. It is this that accounts for the fact
some
strictest sense itself;
[25]
all it is
is
increased or de-
plain that this motion, is
what
in the
is
produced by that which moves
but
the self-movent that
it is
we
de-
clare to be the first principle of things that are
moved and impart motion and
the primary
source to which things that are in motion are to be referred. It is clear, then, from the foregoing arguments that locomotion is the primary motion. We have now to show which kind of locomotion is primary. The same process of reasoning will also make clear at the same time the truth of the assumption we have made both now and 1
[jo] at a previous stage that
it is
possible that
continuous and eternal. Now it is clear from the following considerations that no other than locomotion can be continuous. Every other motion and change is from an opposite to an opposite: thus for the processes of becoming and perishing the limits there should be a motion that
are the existent
is
and the non-existent,
for alter-
ation the various pairs of contrary affections,
[55] and for increase and decrease either greatness and smallness or perfection and imperfection of
magnitude: and changes
to the respec-
tive contraries are contrary changes. 261 b thing that
Now
a
undergoing any particular kind of motion, but though previously existent has not always undergone it, must previously have been at rest so far as that motion is concerned. It is clear, then, that for the changing is
thing the contraries will be states of
we have
rest.
And
a similar result in the case of changes
becoming and perishwhether regarded simply as such without qualification or as affecting something in parthat are not motions: for ing,
[5] ticular, are opposites: therefore provided it impossible for a thing to undergo opposite
is
many
at the same time, the change will not be continuous, but a period of time will inter-
prior to
vene between the opposite processes. The question whether these contradictory changes are contraries or not makes no difference, provided only it is impossible for them both to be present to the same thing at the same time: the point is of no importance to the argument. Nor [10] does it matter if the thing need not rest in
[75] that
living things, e.g. plants
and
kinds of animals, owing to lack of the requisite organ, are entirely without motion, whereas others acquire it in the course of their being perfected. Therefore, if the degree in which things possess locomotion corresponds to the degree in which they have realized their natural development, then this motion must be all
others in respect of perfection of ex-
[20] istence:
and not only
also because a thing that
is
for this reason but in
motion
loses
its
changes
the contradictory state, or
essential character less in the process of
may
tion than in
and that perishing
locomoany other kind of motion: it is the only motion that does not involve a change of being in the sense in which there is a change in quality when a thing is altered and a change
if
there
is
rest as a contrary to the process of
be true that the non-existent is
1
it is 11
253 29.
state of
change: it not at rest,
a process to the non-exist-
ent. All that matters
time:
is
no
is
the intervention of a
this that prevents the
change from
PHYSICS
34«
being continuous: so, too, in our previous instances the important thing was not the relation of contrariety but the impossibility of the two processes being present to a thing at the [75] same time. And there is no need to be disturbed by the fact that on this showing there may be more than one contrary to the same thing, that a particular motion will be contrary both to rest and to motion in the contrary direction. We have only to grasp the fact that a particular motion is in a sense the opposite both of a state of rest and of the contrary motion, in the same way as that which is of equal or standard measure is the opposite both of that which it and of that which it surpasses, and [20] that it is impossible for the opposite motions or changes to be present to a thing at the same time. Furthermore, in the case of becom-
surpasses
ing and perishing it would seem to be an utterabsurd thing if as soon as anything has become it must necessarily perish and cannot conly
tinue to exist for any time: and, if this is true of becoming and perishing, we have fair grounds [25] for inferring the same to be true of the other kinds of change, since it would be in the
natural order of things that they should be uni-
form
in this respect.
form or magnitude): and contraries are specifically not one and the same but distinct: and within the sphere of place we have the above-mentioned distinctions. Moreover we have an indication that motion from A to B is the contrary of motion from B to A in the fact that, if they occur at the same time, they arrest and stop either place or affection or essential [5]
a circle: the
sarily implies
now
rotatory or rectilinear or a
compound
of the
two: consequently, if one of the former two is not continuous, that which is composed of [jo] them both cannot be continuous either. Now it is plain that if the locomotion of a thing is rectilinear and finite it is not continuous locomotion: for the thing must turn back, and that which turns back in a straight line undergoes two contrary locomotions, since, so far as motion in respect of place is concerned, upward motion is the contrary of downward motion, forward motion of backward motion, and mo-
^^
of motion to the right, [35] ti on t0 tne these being the pairs of contraries in the sphere
262 a
of place. But
we have
and continuous motion
already
1
defined
motion of a and operating within a sphere admitting of no further specific differentiation (for we have three things to consider, first that which is in motion, single
to be
single thing in a single period of time
man
e.g. a iv.
4
.
coming to
a straight line that
it is
a stand, not only
is
or a god, secondly the 'when' of the
when
traversed, but also in
[75] the case of locomotion in a circle (which not the same thing as rotatory locomotion:
is
when
for,
may
a thing merely traverses a circle,
it
course without a break or turn back again when it has reached either proceed
on
its
same point from which
it
started).
We may
assure ourselves of the necessity of this
proceed to maintain that it is possible that there should be an infinite motion that is single and continuous, and that this motion is rotatory motion. The motion of everything that is in process of locomotion is either
Let us
And
the same is true in the case of motion from A towards B is the contrary of the motion from A towards T: for [10] even if they are continuous and there is no turning back they arrest each other, because contraries annihilate or obstruct one another. On the other hand lateral motion is not the contrary of upward motion. But what shows most clearly that rectilinear motion cannot be continuous is the fact that turning back neces-
each other.
the 8
262*
motion, that is to say, the time, and thirdly the sphere within which it operates, which may be
to a stand not only tion,
but also on theoretical grounds.
start as follows:
point,
coming
on the strength of observa-
we have
We
may
three points, starting-
middle-point, and finishing-point,
of
[20 J which the middle-point in virtue of the relations in which it stands severally to the other
two is both a starting-point and a finishing-point, and though numerically one is theoretically two.
We
have further the distinction between the and the actual. So in the straight line in question any one of the points lying between the two extremes is potentially a middle-point: but it is not actually so unless that which is in motion divides the line by coming to a stand at that point and beginning its motion again: thus [25] the middle-point becomes both a startingpotential
point and a goal, the starting-point of the latter part and the finishing-point of the first part of in the the motion. This is the case e.g. when
A
locomotion comes to a stand at B and starts again towards V: but when its motion is continuous A cannot either have come to be or have ceased to be at the point B: it can [jo] only have been there at the moment of passing, its passage not being contained within any period of time except the whole of which course of
its
the particular
moment
is
a dividing-point.
To
263
BOOK
s
CHAPTERS
VIII,
has come to be and ceased to be there will involve the consequence that A in the course of its locomotion will always be coming to a stand: for it is impossible that 262 b should simultaneously have come to be at B and ceased to be there, so that the two things
maintain that
it
A
must have happened at different points of time, and therefore there will be the intervening period of time: consequently
A
will be in a state
and similarly at all other points, since the same reasoning holds good in every [5] case. When to A, that which is in process of
of rest at B,
locomotion, B, the middle-point, serves both as
and as a starting-point for its must come to a stand at B, because two just as one might do in thought.
a finishing-point
motion,
A
makes it However, the point A is the real starting-point at which the moving body has ceased to be, and it
it is
at
T
that
it
has really
come
when
to be
its
and it comes to a stand. So this is how we must meet the difficulty that [10] then arises, which is as follows. Suppose
course
finished
is
A
prothe line E is equal to the line Z, that ceeds in continuous locomotion from the extreme point of E to T, and that, at the moment
when
A
is
at the point B,
A
is
proceeding in
uniform locomotion and with the same velocity as A from the extremity of Z to H: then, says before A the argument, A will have reached has reached T: for that which makes an earlier start and departure must make an earlier ar-
H
7-8
neously be there
we cannot argue
should come to a stand there. Therefore we must not hold that there was a moment when A came to be at B and that at the it
same moment A was in motion from the extremity of Z: for the fact of A's having come to [20] be at B will involve the fact of its also ceasing to be there, and the two events will not
A
at a sectional
Now
it
stands in these same two respective relations
263 a
to the
two motions. Therefore
which
that
turns back in traversing a rectilinear course
must ly
in so
doing come to a stand. Consequent-
there cannot be a continuous rectilinear
tion that
is
The same method should replying to those [5] Zeno's
mo-
eternal.
who
also be
adopted in
ask, in the terms of
argument, whether we admit that
before any distance can be traversed half the distance
must be
traversed, that these half-dis-
tances are infinite in
number, and that
it is
im-
num-
possible to traverse distances infinite in
—
or some on the lines of this same argument put the questions in another form, and would have us grant that in the time during which a motion is in progress it should be possible to reckon a half-motion before the whole for
ber
we
every half-distance that
which
sary that
A
one is actual, and regarded from below it is a finishing-point, while regarded from above it is a starting-point, so that
first
will not
at
potential: but this
we
it
will be neces-
is
is
ber,
it
H
[30] necessarily one that is actually, not pothe point in the middle
tentially, existent.
be and ceased to be at B: otherwise
happen
that
point of time and has not come to be or ceased to be there. For here the goal that is reached is
the result that
arrive later: for this to
it
moment. And here we cannot apply the argument used to solve the difficulty stated above:
[75] rival: the reason, then, for the late arrival is that it has not simultaneously come to of
A
349
would simultaand not be there at the same
taneously, for in that case
[10] ersed
when
get, so that
we have reckoned an is
we have
the whole distance
is
trav-
numNow when
infinite
admittedly impossible.
discussed the question of motion
we
1
put forward a solution of this difficulty turning on the fact that the period of time occupied in traversing the distance contains within itself an infinite number of units: there is no absurdity, we said, in supposing the traversing of in-
and the elepresent in the time no less
finite distances in infinite time,
ment
of infinity
is
be simultaneous, whereas the truth is that is at B at a sectional point of time and does not occupy time there. In this case, therefore, where
[75] than in the distance. But, although this so lution is adequate as a reply to the questioner
the motion of a thing
ble in a finite time to traverse or reckon
sible to use this
er
hand
in
its
is
continuous,
form of expression.
it is
On
impos-
the oth-
in the case of a thing that turns
course
we must do
so.
For suppose
back
H in
its locomotion proceeds to A and then turns back and proceeds downwards again: then the extreme point A has served as
the course of
finishing-point
and
as starting-point for
point thus serving as two: therefore [25] have
come
come
to be at
A
to a stand there:
it
it,
H
one
must
cannot have
and departed from
A
simul-
(the question asked being whether finite
number
it is
of units), nevertheless as
possi-
an an
in-
ac-
count of the fact and explanation of its true nature it is inadequate. For suppose the distance to be left out of account and the question asked to be no longer whether it is possible in a finite [20] time to traverse an infinite number of distances, and suppose that the inquiry is made to refer to the time taken by itself (for the time contains an infinite number of divisions): then Wt, 2 (233* 21 sqq.), and
vi. 9.
PHYSICS
350
no longer be adequate, and apply the truth that we enunciated in
264 a white in the whole of A, but must say that
this solution will
it is
we must
so in all of it except the last moment T. T belongs already to the later period, and if in the whole of A not-white was in process of becoming and white of perishing, at T the process is complete. And so T is the first moment at which it is true to call the thing white or notwhite respectively. Otherwise a thing may be non-existent at the moment when it has become and existent at the moment when it has perished: or else it must be possible for a thing at [25] the same time to be white and not white and in fact to be existent and non-existent. Fur-
our recent discussion, stating it in the following way. In the act of dividing the continuous distance into two halves one point is treated as two, since
we make
it
a starting-point
same
and a
finishing-point:
and
lyl duced by
the act of reckoning halves as
this
result
is
also pro-
well as by the act of dividing into halves. But if divisions are made in this way, neither the dis-
tance nor the motion will be continuous: for to be continuous must relate to continuous: and though what is continuous contains an infinite number of halves, they are not actual but potential halves. If the halves are made actual, we shall get not a continuous but an intermittent motion. In the case
motion
what
if it is
is
[50] of reckoning the halves,
it is
clear that this
result follows: for then one point must be reck263 b oned as two: it will be the finishing-point
and the starting-point of the not the one continuous whole but the two halves. Therefore to the question whether it is possible to pass through an infinite number of units either of time or of distance we must reply that in a sense it is and of the one half other,
if
we reckon
in a sense
it is
not. If the units are actual,
[5] not possible: sible.
For
if
they are potential,
in the course of a
it is
it is
pos-
continuous motion
the traveller has traversed an infinite
number
an accidental sense but not in an unqualified sense: for though it is an accidental characteristic of the distance to be an infinite number of half-distances, this is not its real and of units in
essential character. It
[10]
we hold from
is
also plain that unless
that the point of time that divides
always belongs only to the is concerned, we shall be involved in the consequence that the same thing is at the same moment existent and not existent, and that a thing is not existent at the moment when it has become. It is true that the point is common to both times, the earlier as well as the later, and that, while numerically one and the same, it is theoretically not so, being the finishing-point of the one and the starting-point of the other: but so far as the thing is concerned it belongs to the later stage of what [75] happens to it. Let us suppose a time ABr and a thing A, A being white in the time A and not-white in the time B. Then A is at the moment T white and not-white: for if we were right in saying that it is white during the whole time A, it is true to call it white at any moment of A, and not-white in B, and T is in both A [20] and B. We must not allow, therefore, that
earlier
later
later so far as the
thing
it is
ther,
if
anything that
exists after
having been
previously non-existent must become existent
and does not exist when it is becoming, time cannot be divisible into time-atoms. For suppose that A was becoming white in the time A and that at another time B, a time-atom consecutive with the last atom of A, A has already become white and so is white at that moment: [jo] then, inasmuch as in the time A it was becoming white and so was not white and at the moment B it is white, there must have been a becoming between A and B and therefore also a time in which the becoming took 264 a place. On the other hand, those who deny atoms of time (as we do) are not affected by this argument: according to them A has become and so is white at the last point of the actual time in which it was becoming white: and this point has no other point consecutive with or in succession to it, whereas time-atoms are conceived as successive. Moreover it is clear that if A was becoming white in the whole [5] time A, the time occupied by it in having become white in addition to having been in process of becoming white is no more than all that it occupied in the mere process of becoming white. These and
arguments from the fact that they have a special bearing on the point at issue. If we look at the question from the point of view of general theory, the same such-like, then, are the
for our conclusion that derive cogency
would also appear to be indicated by the following arguments. Everything whose motion is continuous must, on arriving at any [10] point in the course of its locomotion, have been previously also in process of locomotion to that point, if it is not forced out of its path by anything: e.g. on arriving at B a thing must also have been in process of locomotion to B, and that not merely when it was near to B, but result
from the moment of its starting on its course, since there can be no reason for its being so at
264 b
BOOK
any particular stage rather than
at
an
VIII,
earlier
one. So, too, in the case of the other kinds of we are to suppose that a thing motion.
Now
proceeds in locomotion from
A to V and that at
[75] the moment of its arrival at T the continuity of its motion is unbroken and will remain it has arrived back at A. Then when it undergoing locomotion from A to T it is at the same time undergoing also its locomotion to A from V: consequently it is simultaneously undergoing two contrary motions, since the two motions that follow the same straight line
so until
is
are contrary to each other. With this consequence there also follows another: we have a
thing that
in process of
is
change from a
posi-
has not yet been: so, inasmuch impossible, the thing must come to a
tion in
which
as this
is
it
[20] stand at T. Therefore the motion is not a single motion, since motion that is interrupted
by stationariness is not single. Further, the following argument will serve better to
make
this point clear universally in
respect of every kind of motion. If the
motion
undergone by that which is in motion is always one of those already enumerated, and the state of rest that it undergoes is one of those that are the opposites of the motions (for we found that there could be no other besides these), and moreover that which is undergoing but does not always undergo a particular motion (by [25] this I mean one of the various specifically 1
some particular part of the whole motion) must have been previously un-
distinct motions, not
dergoing the state of rest that is the opposite of the motion, the state of rest being privation of motion; then, inasmuch as the two motions that follow the
motions, and
same
it is
straight line are contrary
impossible for a thing to un-
dergo simultaneously two contrary motions, that which is undergoing locomotion from A [jo] to T cannot also simultaneously be undergoing locomotion from T to A: and since the latter locomotion is not simultaneous with the former but is still to be undergone, before it is undergone there must occur a state of rest at T: for this, as we found, 2 is the state of rest that is the opposite of the motion from T. The foregoing argument, then, makes it plain that the motion in question is not continuous.
264b Our next argument has
a
more
special
bearing than the foregoing on the point at issue. will suppose that there has occurred in something simultaneously a perishing of not-white and a becoming of white. Then if the
We
alteration to white 1
v. 2,
2
v.
and from white
6 (229b 28 sqq.)
is
a continu-
CHAPTER
35i
8
ous process and the white does not remain any [5] time, there must have occurred simultaneously a perishing of not-white, a becoming of white, and a becoming of not-white: for the time of the three will be the same. Again, from the continuity of the time in which the motion takes place we cannot infer continuity in the motion, but only successiveness: in fact, how could contraries, e.g. whiteness
and blackness, meet
in the
same extreme
point?
On
the other hand, in motion on a circular
we shall find singleness and continuity: for here we are met by no impossible consequence:
line
which is in motion from A will in same direction of energy be simultaneously in motion to A (since it is in motion to the point at which it will finally arrive), and yet will not be undergoing two contrary or opposite motions: for a motion to a point and a motion from that point are not always contra[10] that
virtue of the
ries or opposites: they are contraries only if they are on the same straight line (for then
[75] they are contrary to one another in respect of place, as e.g. the two motions along the
diameter of the
circle, since
the ends of this are
from one anand they are opposites only if they are along the same line. Therefore in the case we at the greatest possible distance
other),
now considering there is nothing to prevent the motion being continuous and free from all intermission: for rotatory motion is moare
tion of a thing
from
its
its place, wheremotion from its
place to
[20] as rectilinear motion place to another place.
is
Moreover the progress of rotatory motion never localized within certain
fixed
is
limits,
whereas that of rectilinear motion repeatedly is so. Now a motion that is always shifting its ground from moment to moment can be continuous: but a motion that is repeatedly localized within certain fixed limits cannot be so, since then the same thing would have to undergo simultaneously two opposite motions. So, too, there cannot be continuous motion in a [25] semicircle or in any other arc of a circle, since here also the
same ground must be travtwo contrary processes of
ersed repeatedly and
change must occur. The reason is that in these motions the starting-point and the termination do not coincide, whereas in motion over a circle they do coincide, and so this is the only perfect motion. This differentiation also provides another means of showing that the other kinds of motion cannot be continuous either: for in all of
265 b
PHYSICS
352
[jo] them we find that there is the same ground to be traversed repeatedly; thus in alteration there are the intermediate stages of the and in quantitative change there are
process,
the intervening degrees of magnitude: and in becoming and perishing the same thing is true. It makes no difference whether we take the intermediate stages of the process to be few or many, or whether we add or subtract one: for 265 a in either case we find that there is still the same ground to be traversed repeatedly. Moreover it is plain from what has been said that
those physicists
who
assert that all
sensible
things are always in motion are wrong: for their motion must be one or other of the mo[5] tions just mentioned: in fact they mostly conceive it as alteration (things are always in flux
and decay, they say), and they go so far as even of becoming and perishing as a
to speak
On
the other hand, our
argument has enabled us
to assert the fact, ap-
process of alteration.
plying universally to all motions, that no motion admits of continuity except rotatory motion: consequently neither alteration nor inneed now [10] crease admits of continuity. say no more in support of the position that there is no process of change that admits of infinity or continuity except rotatory locomotion.
We
whether locomotion or motion of any other kind, can be so, since in all of them rest must occur and with the occurrence of rest the motion has perished. Moreover the result at which we have arrived, that rotatory motion is single and continuous, and rectilinear motion is not, is a reasonable one. In rectilinear motion we have a definite starting-point, finishing-point, [jo] and middle-point, which all have their place in
finish
its
limits of
we
said before,
1
is
either rotatory or rectilinear
compound
of the two: and the two former must be prior to the last, since they are the elements of which the latter consists. Moreover rotatory locomotion is prior to rectilinear
[75] or a
locomotion, because it which may be
plete,
more simple and comshown as follows. The
is
motion canno such thing as an
straight line traversed in rectilinear
not be infinite: for there
is
infinite straight line; and even if there were, it would not be traversed by anything in motion: for the impossible does not happen and it is im-
[20] possible to traverse an infinite distance. rectilinear motion on a finite
On the other hand
turns back a composite motwo motions, while if it does not turn back it is incomplete and perishable: and in the order of nature, of definition, and of straight line
is if it
tion, in fact
time alike the complete is prior to the incomplete and the imperishable to the perishable. Again, a motion that admits of being eternal is [25] prior to one that does not. Now rotatory motion can be eternal: but no other motion, Chapter 8 (26
b 28).
that there
is
a point
when anything is at the whether at the startingthe finishing-point, it must be in a course,
its
state of rest).
On
the other
hand
in circular
motion there are no such definite points: for why should any one point on the line be a limit rather than any other? Any one point as much as any other is alike starting-point, middlepoint, and finishing-point, so that we can say of certain things both that they are always and that they never are at a starting-point and at a 265 b finishing-point (so that a revolving sphere, while at rest, for
place).
The
it
in motion,
it is
is
also in a sense
continues to occupy the same
reason of this
is
that in this case
all
these characteristics belong to the centre: that is
can now be shown plainly that rotation is the primary locomotion. Every locomotion, as
way
course (for
point or at
to say, the centre
dle-point, It
in such a
it
from which that which is in motion can be said to start and a point at which it can be said to
is
alike starting-point, mid-
and finishing-point of the space
trav-
not a [5] point on the circular line, there is no point at which that which is in process of locomotion ersed; consequently since this point
is
having traversed its locomotion it is proceeding always about a central point and not to an extreme point: therefore it remains still, and the whole is in a sense always at rest as well as continuously in motion. Our next point gives a convertible result: on the one hand, because rotation is the measure of motions it must be the primary motion (for all things are meas[10] ured by what is primary): on the other hand, because rotation is the primary motion it is the measure of all other motions. Again, rotatory motion is also the only motion that admits of being regular. In rectilinear locomotion can be in a state of
course, because in
rest as
its
f
the motion of things in leaving the startingpoint is not uniform with their motion in ap-
proaching the finishing-point, since the velocity of a thing always increases proportionately as it removes itself farther from its position of rest: on the other hand rotatory motion is the only motion whose course is naturally such that [75]
it
has no starting-point or finishing-point is determined from elsewhere.
in itself but
BOOK
266 b
VIII,
CHAPTERS
As to locomotion being the primary motion, this is a truth that is attested by all who have ever made mention of motion in their theories: they all assign their first principles of motion to things that impart motion of this kind. Thus 'separation' and 'combination' are motions in [20] respect of place, and the motion imparted by 'Love' and 'Strife' takes these forms, the latter 'separating' and the former 'combining'. Anaxagoras, too, says that 'Mind', his first movent, 'separates'. Similarly those who assert no cause of this kind but say that 'void' accounts they also hold that the mo[25] for motion tion of natural substance is motion in respect of place: for their motion that is accounted for by 'void' is locomotion, and its sphere of operation may be said to be place. Moreover they are of opinion that the primary substances are not subject to any of the other motions, though
—
compounds
the things that are
of these sub-
stances are so subject: the processes of increase
and decrease and
alteration, they say, are effects
[50] of the 'combination' and 'separation' of 'atoms'. It is the same, too, with those who make out that the becoming or perishing of a
accounted for by 'density' or 'rarity': by 'combination' and 'separation' that the place of these things in their systems is determined. Moreover to these we may add those who make Soul the cause of motion: for they say that things that undergo motion have as thing for
is
it is
which moves itself: and when animals and all living things move 266 a themselves, the motion is motion in retheir first principle 'that
it is to be noted that we motion' in the strict sense
spect of place. Finally
say that a thing
'is
in
of the term only
when
respect of place:
if
its
motion
a thing
is
is
motion
in
in process of in-
undergoing some altersame place, in motion in some particular
crease or decrease or
is
ation while remaining at rest in the
we
say that
respect:
it is
we do
not say that
it
'is
in motion'
[5] without qualification. Our present position, then,
is this: We have argued that there always was motion and always will be motion throughout all time, and we have explained what is the first principle of this eternal motion: we have explained further which is the primary motion and which is the only motion that can be eternal: and we have pronounced the first movent to be unmoved.
10
We
have now to assert that the first mov[10] ent must be without parts and without magnitude, beginning with the establishment of the
8-10
353
premisses on which this conclusion depends. One of these premisses is that nothing finite
can cause motion during an infinite time. We have three things, the movent, the moved, and thirdly that in which the motion takes place, namely the time: and these are either all infinite that is to say two of them or all finite or partly [75] or one of them finite and partly infinite. Let A be the movent, B the moved, and T the infinite time. Now let us suppose that A moves
— —
E, a part of B.
Then
the time occupied by this
motion cannot be equal to T: for the greater the amount moved, the longer the time occupied. It
follows that the time
Z
is
not infinite.
Now
add to A I shall use up A and by continuing to add to E I shall [20] use up B: but I shall not use up the time
we
see that by continuing to
by continually subtracting a corresponding amount from it, because it is infinite. Consequently the duration of the part of T which is occupied by all A in moving the whole of B, will be finite. Therefore a finite thing cannot impart to anything an infinite motion. It is clear, then, that
it is
impossible for the finite to
cause motion during an infinite time. [25] It has now to be shown that in no case is possible for an infinite force to reside in a fi-
it
magnitude. This can be shown as follows: it for granted that the greater force is always that which in less time than another does an equal amount of work when engaged in heating, for example, or in any activity sweetening or throwing; in fact, in causing any kind of motion. Then that on which the forces act must be affected to some extent by our supposed finite magnitude possessing an infinite force as well as by anything else, in fact to a greater extent than by anything else, since the [50] infinite force is greater than any other. But then there cannot be any time in which its action could take place. Suppose that A is the time occupied by the infinite power in the performance of an act of heating or pushing, and that AB is the time occupied by a finite power in the performance of the same act: then by 266 b adding to the latter another finite power nite
we
take
—
and continually increasing the magnitude of the power so added I shall at some time or other reach a point at which the finite power has completed the motive act in the time A: for by continual addition to a finite magnitude I must arrive at a magnitude that exceeds any assigned limit, and in the same way by continual subtraction I must arrive at one that falls short of any assigned limit. So we get the result that the finite force will occupy the same amount of
PHYSICS
354
performing the motive act as the infi[5] nite force. But this is impossible. Therefore nothing finite can possess an infinite force. So
time
in
also impossible for a finite force to reside
it
is
in
an
magnitude.
It is
true that a great-
er force can reside in a lesser
magnitude: but
infinite
the superiority of any such greater force can be still greater if the magnitude in which it resides
is
nitude.
greater.
Now let AB be an infinite mag-
Then Br
possesses a certain force that
occupies a certain time, let us say the time EZ, [10] in moving A. Now if I take a magnitude twice as great at Br, the time occupied by this will be half of EZ be the proportion): so we may call this time ZH. That being so, by continually taking a greater magnitude in this way I shall never arrive at the full AB, whereas I shall always be getting a lesser fraction of the time originally given. Therefore the force must [75] be infinite, since it exceeds any finite force. Moreover the time occupied by the action of any finite force must also be finite: for if a given force moves something in a certain time, a greater force will do so in a lesser time, but still a definite time, in inverse proportion. But
magnitude (assuming
a force
in
moving A
this to
must always be
ber or a magnitude
infinite
—
—
just as a
num-
exceeds all definite [20] limits. This point may also be proved in another way by taking a finite magnitude in which there resides a force the same in kind as that which resides in the infinite magnitude, is
if it
—
measure of the finite force residing in the infinite magnitude. [25] It is plain, then, from the foregoing arguments that it is impossible for an infinite force to reside in a finite magnitude or for a finite force to reside in an infinite magnitude. But so that this force will be a
before proceeding to our conclusion it will be well to discuss a difficulty that arises in con-
nexion with locomotion. If everything that is in motion with the exception of things that move themselves is moved by something else, how is it that some things, e.g. things thrown, continue to be in motion when their movent is no longer in contact with them? If we say [jo] that the movent in such cases moves something else at the same time, that the thrower e.g. also moves the air, and that this in being moved is also a movent, then it would be no more possible for this second thing than for the original thing to be in motion when the original movent is not in contact with it or moving it: all the things moved would have to be in motion simultaneously and also to have ceased simultaneously to be in motion when the orig-
267 a
267* inal
like the
movent
magnet,
move them, even
ceases to
makes
which
if,
has moved capable of being a movent. Therefore, while we must accept this explanation to the extent of saying that the original movent gives it
that
it
the power of being a movent either to air or to water or to something else of the kind, nat[5] urally adapted for imparting and undergoing motion, we must say further that this thing does not cease simultaneously to impart motion and to undergo motion: it ceases to be in
motion
at the
move
moment when
its
movent
ceases
remains a movent, and so it causes something else consecutive with it to be in motion, and of this again the same may be said. The motion begins to cease when the motive force produced in one member of the consecutive series is at each stage less than that possessed by the preceding member, and it finally ceases when one member no longer causes the next member to be a movent but [10] only causes it to be in motion. The motion of these last two of the one as movent to
it,
but
it
still
—
—
and of the other as moved must cease simultaneously, and with this the whole motion ceases. Now the things in which this motion is produced are things that admit of being sometimes in motion and sometimes at rest, and the motion is not continuous but only appears so: for it is motion of things that are either successive or in contact, there being not
[75] one movent but a number of movents consecutive with one another: and so motion of this kind takes place in air
and water. Some
'mutual replacement': but we must recognize that the difficulty raised cannot be solved otherwise than in the way we have described. So far as they are affected by 'mutual replacement', all the members of the series are moved and impart motion simultaneously, so that their motions also cease simultaneously: but our present problem concerns the appearance of continuous motion in a sin[20] gle thing, and therefore, since it cannot be moved throughout its motion by the same movent, the question is, what moves it? Resuming our main argument, we proceed from the positions that there must be continuous motion in the world of things, that this is a single motion, that a single motion must be a say that
it
is
motion of a magnitude (for that which is without magnitude cannot be in motion), and that the magnitude must be a single magnitude moved by a single movent (for otherwise there will not be continuous motion but a consecutive series of separate motions), and that if the
BOOK
267 b movent
is
a single thing,
[25] motion or
itself
it is
unmoved:
VIII,
either itself in if,
then,
it is
in
motion, it will have to be subject to the same conditions as that which it moves, that is to say it will itself be in process of change and in be267 b ing so will also have to be moved by something: so we have a series that must come to an end, and a point will be reached at which motion is imparted by something that is unmoved. Thus we have a movent that has no to change along with that which it moves but will be able to cause motion always (for the causing of motion under these conditions involves no effort): and this motion alone is regular, or at least it is so in a higher degree than any other, since the movent is never sub[5] ject to any change. So, too, in order that
need
the motion
may
character, the
continue to be of the same
moved must not be
subject to
change in respect of its relation to the movent. Moreover the movent must occupy either the centre or the circumference, since these are the first principles from which a sphere is derived.
But the things nearest the movent are those whose motion is quickest, and in this case it is the motion of the circumference that is the quickest: therefore the
movent occupies the
circumference.
There
is
a further difficulty in supposing
it
anything that is in motion to cause motion continuously and not merely in [10] the way in which it is caused by something repeatedly pushing (in which case the continuity amounts to no more than successiveto be possible for
CHAPTER
10
355
Such a movent must either itself continue to push or pull or perform both these actions, or else the action must be taken up by something else and be passed on from one movness).
ent to another (the process that we described before as occurring in the case of things thrown, since the air or the water, being divisible, is a
movent only
in virtue of the fact that
different parts of the air are
moved one
after
[75] another): and in either case the motion cannot be a single motion, but only a consecutive series of motions.
The
only continuous
which is caused by the unmoved movent: and this motion is continuous because the movent remains always invariable, so that its relation to that which it moves remains also invariable and continuous. motion, then,
Now that the
is
that
that these points are settled, first
it is
clear
unmoved movent cannot have any
magnitude. For
if it
has magnitude, this must
be either a finite or an infinite magnitude. Now 1 [20] we have already proved in our course on Physics that there cannot be an infinite magni-
and we have now proved that it is immagnitude to have an infinite force, and also that it is impossible for a thing to be moved by a finite magnitude during an infinite time. But the first movent causes a motion that is eternal and does tude:
possible for a finite
[25]
cause
it
during an
infinite time.
visible
and
nitude. 1
in. 5.
is
without parts
It
is
movent is indiand without mag-
clear, therefore, that the first
CONTENTS: ON THE HEAVENS Of the Heavenly
BOOK
Bodies
9.
BERLIN NOS.
CHAP. 1.
The
2.
That in addition
268 a
subject of inquiry
element, the
fifth
268 b
to the four ele-
ments, earth, water,
air,
and
movement
fire,
of
there
which
is
10. 11.
I
12.
1
is
a
cir-
13.
body is exempt from and decay
269b 18
That the circular movement has no contrary That no body is infinite: (i) Not the primary body, or fifth element
27ob 3i
That
this
alteration 4.
5.
6. 7.
14.
27i b
10.
11.
1.
Heaven That the Heaven
is
indestructible: (i)
Review of previous
and
'indestructible',
and of
3.
4.
That every simple body possesses 300*20 a natural movement; that this movement is
15 279 4
5.
2.
Of
bodies subject to generation:
(i)
What the
That the elements are limited 302 b 10 number; the view of Leucippus and De-
(ii)
this
That the elements cannot be
(iii)
6.
That the elements are not
(iv)
eternal, but are generated out of
their op-
Of
(v)
the
eration: the
planation by planes refuted II 8.
result
283 b 26
4.
which the spatial 284 b 6 up and down, right and left, can be attributed to the Heaven Why there is a plurality of move286 a 3 ments and of bodies within the Heaven That the Heaven is perfectly 286 b 10
5.
Why
BOOK 1.
2.
IV
meaning of the terms and Might'
Review of previous
307b 29
theories con-
308*34
Explanation of the variety of mo-
310* 14
cerning these
287b 22
tions exhibited
one direction rather than the other
8.
the
'heavy'
3.
revolves in
Of
3o6 b 3 by their shapes
Refutation of the attempt to
(vi)
differentiate the elements
spherical
7.
304b 24 one another
of their gen305*34 view of Empedocles and the ex-
the sense in
Heaven
303 b 9
manner
oppositions,
first
302* 10
elements are
reduced to one
theories 28o b 1
7.
Corroboration of
Of
in
281 s 28
Proof of the thesis
1.
6.
298*24
bodies into
mocritus refuted
ungenerated and
Definition of the terms 'ungen-
the
of
generation
Proved by the principles of 277b 26 form and matter, the three different senses of the term 'heaven' being explained. Corollary: There is no place or void or time outside the
BOOK
3.
the analysis
stated;
either upward or downward; how unnatural movement occurs. General results concerning
(ii)
(iii)
Bodies
planes refuted 2.
posites 12.
296* 24
III
Previous theories concerning generation
276** 18 That there cannot be more than one Heaven: (i) Proved from a consideration of the natural movements and places of the
crated'
at rest at the centre,
1
s 273 6 s 274 30
of the other elements
it is
spherical in shape
BOOK
impossible
(ii)
That
(ii)
Of the Sublunary
elements 9.
s1
and
In general, an infinite body
(iii) is
8.
None
(ii)
Of their order 291 30 291° n Of their spherical shape (vi) Solution of two problems 29i b 24 concerning their order and movements Of the Earth: (i) Review of pre293 15 (iv)
(v)
vious theories
cular 3.
That no 'harmony of the 290b 12 from their movement
(iii)
spheres' results
I
4.
That the movement of the first 288 a 13 Heaven is regular Of the stars: (i) That they are not 289 a 11 composed of fire (ii) That their movement is due 289b 1 to the movement of circles to which they are
Of
by the elements
the distinctive constitution
and
311* 15
properties of the four elements 5.
In
what sense the matter of which 312* 22 composed may be regarded
the elements are
one That the shape of a body cannot as
6.
attached
313* 14 account for the direction, but only for the pace, of
357
its
movement
ON THE HEAVENS BOOK
268 a The
science
which has
to
clearly concerns itself for the
do with nature most part with
bodies and magnitudes and their properties and movements, but also with the principles of this sort of substance, as
many
as they
may
be.
some [5] For of things constituted by nature are bodies and magnitudes, some possess body and magnitude, and some are principles of things which possess these. is
which
that
is
Now
divisible into parts
pable of subdivision, and a body is
every
three a
always that
is
ca-
which
A magnitude if divisible two ways a surface, and if body. Beyond these there is no other
way
one way
continuum
a
is
divisible.
a line,
if
[10] magnitude, because the three dimensions
are
all
that there, are,
ble in three directions
and that which is
divisible in
is
all.
divisi-
For, as
beginning and middle and end give the number of an 'all', and the number they give is the triad. And so, having taken these three from nature as (so to speak) laws of it, we make
number
say 'both', but not
number
to
priated.
And
'all':
which the term in this, as
three
'all'
is
the
said,
we do
determined by the three dimensions, an 'all'. But if it is divisible in three dimensions it is every way divisible, while the [25] other magnitudes are divisible in one diis
sort
Oxford
would
cease to
We
it
mula, since each possesses every dimension. But each is determined relatively to that part which is next to it by contact, for which reason each
them is in a sense many bodies. But the whole of which they are parts must necessarily be complete, and thus, in accordance with the [10] meaning of the word, have being, not in some respect only, but in every respect.
question as to the nature of the whole, it is infinite in size or limited in its tomass, is a matter for subsequent inquiry. 1 specifically distinct.
whole
Let us take
this
[75] as our starting-point. All natural bodies and magnitudes we hold to be, as such, capable
we say, is their prinmovement that is as we term it, is either
of locomotion; for nature, ciple of
movement. 2 But
in place, all locomotion,
downward movements
all
are in a straight line,
'upward' meaning motion away from the centre, and 'downward' motion towards it. All simple motion, then, must be motion either away from or towards or about the centre. This [25] seems to be in exact accord with what we said above: as body found its completion in
being con-
Note: The bold face numbers and letters are approximate indications of the pages and columns of the standard Berlin Greek text; the bracketed numbers, of the lines in the Greek text; they are here assigned as they are assigned in the
it
[20] straight and the circular line, are the only simple magnitudes. Now revolution about the centre is circular motion, while the upward and
mension or in two alone: for the divisibility and continuity of magnitudes depend upon the one
could,
complete magnitude.
straight or circular or a combination of these two, which are the only simple movements. And the reason of this is that these two, the
is, is
of the dimensions,
we
is
We will now speak of those parts of the
which they are applied, body alone among magnitudes can be complete. For it
number
if
only in virtue of a defect in it; and that which is complete cannot be de[5] fective, since it has being in every respect. Now bodies which are classed as parts of the whole are each complete according to our for-
which are
in that to
that
For
be true that body could pass beyond
tal
first
[20] but follow the lead which nature gives. Therefore, since 'every' and 'all' and 'complete' do not differ from one another in respect of form, but only, if at all, in their matter and
alone
face to body.
whether
has been appro-
we have
We
The
three in the
worship of the Gods. Further, we use the terms in practice in this way. Of two things, or men,
we
tinuous in one direction, another in two, another in all. All magnitudes, then, which are divisible are also continuous. Whether we can also say that whatever is continuous is divisible [50] does not yet, on our present grounds, appear. One thing, however, is clear. cannot 268 b pass beyond body to a further kind, as we passed from length to surface, and from sur-
of
the Pythagoreans say, the world and all that is in it is determined by the number three, since
[75] further use of the
I
1
translation.
359
See chapter
7.
2
Cf. Physics, i92 b 20.
ON THE HEAVENS
360 three dimensions, so itself in
its
movement completes
three forms.
Bodies are either simple or compounded of such; and by simple bodies I mean those which possess a principle of
nature, such as fire
movement
in their
and earth with
own
their kinds,
and whatever is akin to them. Necessarily, then, [jo] movements also will be either simple or simple in the case of in some sort compound 269* the simple bodies, compound in that of the composite and in the latter case the motion will be that of the simple body which pre-
—
—
composition. Supposing, then, that such a thing as simple movement, and
vails in the
there
is
269 b
straight upward and earthy bodies straight downward towards the centre since this is so, it follows that circular movement also must be the movement of some simple body. For the movement of composite bodies is, as we said,
—
determined by that simple body which prepon[jo] derates in the composition. These premises clearly give the conclusion that there is in nature some bodily substance other than the formations we know, prior to them all and more divine than they. But it may also be
proved as follows.
We may take
—
movement is an instance of it, and movement of a simple body is simple and simple movement is of a simple body (for if it is movement of a compound it will be in
269 b
[5] virtue of a prevailing simple element), then there must necessarily be some simple
natural to these bodies,
natural to another
that circular
is
that both
case with the
body which revolves naturally and in virtue of its own nature with a circular movement. By constraint, of course, it may be brought to move with the motion of something else different from itself, but it cannot so move naturally, since there is one sort of movement natural to each of the simple bodies. Again, if the unnatural movement is the contrary of the natural and [10] a thing can have no more than one contrary, it will follow that circular movement, being a simple motion, must be unnatural, if it is not natural, to the body moved. If then (1) the body, whose movement is circular, is fire or some other element, its natural motion must be the contrary of the circular motion. But a single thing has a single contrary; and upward and downward motion are the contraries of one [75] another. If, on the other hand, (2) the body moving with this circular motion which is unnatural to it is something different from the elements, there will be some other motion which is natural to it. But this cannot be. For if the natural motion is upward, it will be fire or air, and if downward, water or earth. Further, this circular motion is necessarily primary. For [20] the perfect is naturally prior to the imperfect, and the circle is a perfect thing. This cannot be said of any straight line: not of an infinite line; for, if it were perfect, it would have a limit and an end: nor of any finite line; for in every case there is something beyond it, since any finite line can be extended. And so, since the prior movement belongs to the body which
—
[25] is naturally prior, and circular movement prior to straight, and movement in a straight
is
line
belongs to simple bodies
—
fire
moving
it
that
all
move-
ment is either natural or unnatural, and that the movement which is unnatural to one body as, for instance, is
the
upward and downward move-
[55] ments, which are natural and unnatural to fire and earth respectively. It necessarily follows that circular movement, being unof
some
is
other. Further,
movement
the natural
if,
movement
on the one hand,
cir-
natural to something, it must surely be some simple and primary body
cular
is
ordained to move with a natural ciris ordained to fly up and earth down. If, on the other hand, the movement of the rotating bodies about the centre is unnatural, it would be remarkable and indeed quite inconceivable that this movement alone should be continuous and eternal, being
which
is
[5] cular motion, as fire
nevertheless contrary to nature.
evidence of [10]
And
moved ral to
At any rate the show that it
other cases goes to
the unnatural
is
away.
all
so,
if,
as
which quickest passes some say, the body so
this movement is just as unnatudownward movement; for any one
is fire,
it
as
can see that
from the
fire
centre.
fore,
we may
[75]
is
moves
On
in a straight line
all
away
these grounds, there-
infer with confidence that there something beyond the bodies that are about us on this earth, different and separate from them; and that the superior glory of its nature is proportionate to its distance from this world of ours.
In consequence of what has been said, in part by way of assumption and in part by way of it is clear that not every body either pos[20] sesses lightness or heaviness. As a preliminary we must explain in what sense we are us-
proof,
ing the words 'heavy' and 'light', sufficiently, at our present purpose: we can examine the terms more closely later, when we come to consider their essential nature. Let us then apply the term 'heavy' to that which naturally least, for
BOOK
270 b
1,
CHAPTERS
moves towards the centre, and 'light' to that which moves naturally away from the centre. The heaviest thing will be that which sinks to [25] the bottom of all things that move downward, and the lightest that which rises to the surface of everything that moves upward. Now, necessarily, everything which moves either up or
down
possesses lightness or heaviness or both
—but not both
relatively to the same thing: for things are heavy and light relatively to one an-
instance, is light relatively to waand water light relatively to earth. The body, then, which moves in a circle cannot
other;
air, for
ter,
[30]
possibly possess either heaviness or lightness.
For neither naturally nor unnaturally can it move either towards or away from the centre.
Movement belong to
in a straight line certainly does not
it
naturally, since one sort of
move-
we saw, appropriate to each simple body, and so we should be compelled to iden[35] tify it with one of the bodies which move in this way. Suppose, then, that the movement is unnatural. In that case, if it is the downward 270* movement which is unnatural, the upward movement will be natural; and if it is the upward which is unnatural, the downward will be natural. For we decided that of contrary ment
as
is,
movements,
if
the one
is
unnatural to anything,
it. But since the natwhole and of its part of earth, for instance, as a whole and of a small have one and the same direction, it [5] clod results, in the first place, that this body can possess no lightness or heaviness at all (for that would mean that it could move by its own nature either from or towards the centre, which, as we know, is impossible); and, secondly, that
the other will be natural to ural
movement
of the
—
it
cannot possibly
move
in the
way
of locomo-
tion by being forced violently aside in
an up-
[10] ward or downward direction. For neither naturally nor unnaturally can it move with any
other motion but part of
it,
its
own,
any which applies to
either itself or
since the reasoning
the whole applies also to the part. It is equally reasonable to assume that this body will be ungenerated and indestructible and exempt from increase and alteration, since everything that comes to be comes into being [75] from its contrary and in some substrate, and passes away likewise in a substrate by the
action of the contrary into the contrary, as explained in our opening discussions. 1
we
Now
the motions of contraries are contrary. If then
body can have no contrary, because there can be no contrary motion to the circular, nathis
iPhysics,
1.
7-9.
2-3
361
[20] ture seems justly to have exempted from contraries the body which was to be ungener-
ated and indestructible. For that generation
which
is
and decay
it is
in contraries
subsist.
Again, that
subject to increase increases
upon con-
with a kindred body, which is resolved [25] into its matter. But there is nothing out of which this body can have been generated. And if it is exempt from increase and diminution, the same reasoning leads us to suppose tact
For alteration is and qualitative states and dispositions, such as health and disease, do not come into being without changes of properties. But all natural bodies which [30] change their properties we see to be subject without exception to increase and diminution. This is the case, for instance, with the bodies of animals and their parts and with vegetable bodies, and similarly also with those of the elements. And so, if the body which moves with a circular motion cannot admit of inthat
it
is
movement
also unalterable.
in respect of quality;
[55] crease or diminution, it is reasonable to it is also unalterable.
suppose that
270 b The
reasons why the primary body is and not subject to increase or diminution, but unaging and unalterable and unmodified, will be clear from what has been said to any one who believes in our assumptions. Our theory seems to confirm experience and to be [5] confirmed by it. For all men have some conception of the nature of the gods, and all eternal
who
believe in the existence of gods at all, whether barbarian or Greek, agree in allotting
the highest place to the deity, surely because
they suppose that immortal
is linked with immortal and regard any other supposition as in[10] conceivable. If then there is, as there certainly is, anything divine, what we have just said about the primary bodily substance was well said. The mere evidence of the senses is enough to convince us of this, at least with human certainty. For in the whole range of time past, so far as our inherited records reach, no [75] change appears to have taken place either in the whole scheme of the outermost heaven or in any of its proper parts. The common name, too, which has been handed down from our distant ancestors even to our own day, seems to show that they conceived of it in the fashion which we have been expressing. The
same
ideas,
one must
believe, recur in
men's
[20] minds not once or twice but again and again. And so, implying that the primary body is
something
else
beyond
earth, fire, air,
water, they gave the highest place a
name
and of
its
ON THE HEAVENS
362
aither, derived from the fact that it 'runs always' for an eternity of time. Anaxagoras, [25] however, scandalously misuses this name,
own,
taking aither as equivalent to fire. It is also clear from what has been said why the number of what we call simple bodies cannot be greater than
it is.
The motion
of a sim-
be simple, and we assert that there are only these two simple motions, ple
body must
iself
[jo] the circular
and the
straight, the latter
being subdivided into motion away from and motion towards the centre.
That there
is
no other form of motion op-
posed as contrary to the circular may be proved in various ways. In the first place, there is an obvious tendency to oppose the straight line to [55] the circular. For concave and convex are 271 a not only regarded as opposed to one another, but they are also coupled together and treated as a unity in opposition to the straight. And so, if there is a contrary to circular motion,
motion in a straight line must be recognized as having the best claim to that name. But the two forms of rectilinear motion are opposed to one [5] another by reason of their places; for up and down is a difference and a contrary opposition in place. Secondly, it may be thought that the
same reasoning which holds good of the rec-
path applies also the circular, movement from A to B being opposed as contrary to movement from B to A. But what is meant is still rectilinear motion. For that is limited to a [10] single path, while the circular paths which pass through the same two points are infinite in number. Even if we are confined to the sin-
tilinear
and the opposition is between to D and from D to C along that semicircle, the case is no better. For the motion is the same as that along the diameter,
gle semicircle
movement from C
since
we
invariably regard the distance be-
tween two points as the length of the straight line which joins them. It is no more satisfactory to construct a circle and treat motion [75] along one semicircle as contrary to motion along the other. For example, taking a complete circle, motion from E to F on the semicircle G may be opposed to motion from F to E on the semicircle H. But even supposing these are contraries, it in no way follows that the reverse motions on the complete circumference [20] are contraries. Nor again can motion along the circle from A to B be regarded as the contrary of motion from AtoC: for the motion goes from the same point towards the same
271 b
and contrary motion was distinguished motion from a contrary to its contrary. And even if the motion round a circle is the contrary of the reverse motion, one of the two would be ineffective: for both move to the same point, because that which moves in a circle, at what[25] ever point it begins, must necessarily pass through all the contrary places alike. (By contrarieties of place I mean up and down, back and front, and right and left; and the contrary oppositions of movements are determined by point, as
One
those of places.)
of the motions, then,
would be ineffective, for if the two motions were of equal strength, there would be no movement either way, and if one of the two [50] were preponderant, the other would be inoperative. So that if both bodies were there, one of them, inasmuch as it would not be moving with its own movement, would be useless, in the sense in which a shoe is useless when it is not worn. But God and nature create nothing that has not
its
271 b This being
use.
we must go on to conwhich remain. First, is there
clear,
sider the questions
an
infinite body, as the majority of the ancient philosophers thought, or is this an impossibility? The decision of this question, either way,
not unimportant, but rather all-imporour search for the truth. It is this problem which has practically always been the source of the differences of those who have written about nature as a whole. So it has been [5]
is
tant, to
and so it must be; since the least initial deviation from the truth is multiplied later a thou[10] sandfold. Admit, for instance, the existence of a minimum magnitude, and you will find that the minimum which you have introduced, small as
it is,
causes the greatest truths
of mathematics to totter.
principle tent;
is
The
great rather in
reason
is
that a
power than
in ex-
hence that which was small
at the start
Now
the concep-
turns out a giant at the end.
tion of the infinite possesses this ciples,
and indeed
power
of prin-
in the sphere of quantity
[75] possesses it in a higher degree than any other conception; so that it is in no way absurd or unreasonable that the assumption that an infinite body exists should be of peculiar moment to our inquiry.
now
discuss,
The
infinite,
then,
we must
opening the whole matter from
the beginning.
Every body
is
necessarily to be classed either
as simple or as composite; the infinite body,
therefore, will be either simple or composite.
BOOK
272 b clear, further, that
I,
CHAPTERS
the simple
[20] But it is bodies are finite, the composite must also be finite, since that which is composed of bodies if
number and in magnitude is itfinite both self finite in respect of number and magnitude: in
quantity
its
is
in fact the
same
as that of the
bodies which compose it. What remains for us to consider, then, is whether any of the simple bodies can be infinite in magnitude, or wheth[25] er this
mary body
is
first,
impossible. Let us try the priand then go on to consider the
others.
must
3-5
363
(3) That the infinite cannot move may also be shown as follows. Let A be finite line mova.
ing past the
finite line,
B.
Of
B and B
of
A
pass clear of
A
necessity
at the
will
same mo-
[25] ment; for each overlaps the other to precisely the same extent. Now if the two were both moving, and moving in contrary directions, clear of one another more rapone were still and the other moving past it, less rapidly; provided that the speed of the latter were the same in both cases. This, however, is clear: that it is impossible to traverse an
they
would pass
idly;
if
nec-
infinite line in a finite time. Infinite time, then,
essarily be finite in every respect, for the fol-
[jo] would be required. (This we demonstrated above in the discussion of movement. ) And
The body which moves
in a circle
the body so moving is infinite, the radii drawn from the centre will be |jo] infinite. But the space between infinite radii is infinite: and by the space between the
lowing reasons. (1)
radii
I
mean
If
which no magnicontact with the two lines can
the area outside
tude which is in be conceived as falling. This, I say, will be infinite: first, because in the case of finite radii it 272 a is always finite; and secondly, because in it one can always go on to a width greater than any given width; thus the reasoning which forces us to believe in infinite number, because is no maximum, applies also to the space between the radii. Now the infinite cannot be traversed, and if the body is infinite the interval between the radii is necessarily infinite: circu[5] lar motion therefore is an impossibility. Yet our eyes tell us that the heavens revolve in a circle, and by argument also we have determined that there is something to which circu-
there
lar
movement
belongs.
from a finite time a finite time be subtracted, what remains must be finite and (2) Again,
if
have a beginning. And if the time of a journey [10] has a beginning, there must be a beginning also of the movement, and consequently also of the distance traversed. This applies universally. Take a line, ACE, infinite in one direction, E, and another line, BB, infinite in both directions. Let ACE describe a circle, ret/5] volving upon C as centre. In its movement it will cut BB continuously for a certain time. This will be a finite time, since the total time is finite in which the heavens complete their circular orbit, and consequently the time subtracted from it, during which the one line in its motion cuts the other, is also finite. Therefore there will be a point at which ACE began for the first time to cut BB. This, however, is impossible. The infinite, then, cannot revolve in [20] a circle; nor could the world, if it were infinite.
1
makes no difference whether a finite is pass272 b ing by an infinite or an infinite by a fiit
nite. For when A is passing B, then B overlaps A, and it makes no difference whether B is moved or unmoved, except that, if both move, they pass clear of one another more quickly. It is, however, quite possible that a moving line should in certain cases pass one which is stationary quicker than it passes one moving in an [5] opposite direction. One has only to imagine the movement to be slow where both move and much faster where one is stationary. To suppose one line stationary, then, makes no difficulty for our argument, since it is quite
A to pass B at a slower rate when both are moving than when only one is. If, [10] therefore, the time which the finite moving line takes to pass the other is infinite, then necessarily the time occupied by the motion of possible for
the infinite past the finite the infinite to
move
at all
is
is
also infinite.
possible; since the very smallest
ceivable
must take an
For
thus absolutely im-
movement con-
infinity of time.
More-
over the heavens certainly revolve, and they complete their circular orbit in a finite time; so [75] that they pass round the whole extent of any line within their orbit, such as the finite line
AB. The revolving body,
therefore, can-
not be infinite. (4) Again, as a line which has a limit cannot be infinite, or, if it is infinite, is so only in length, so a surface cannot be infinite in that
which it has a limit; or, indeed, if it completely determinate, in any respect what[20] ever. Whether it be a square or a circle or a sphere, it cannot be infinite, any more than a foot-rule can. There is then no such thing as an infinite sphere or square or circle, and where there is no circle there can be no circular moverespect in is
ment, and similarly where there ^Physics, vi. 7.
is
no
infinite
ON THE HEAVENS
3 64 at all there
from ing
this
itself
can be no infinite movement; and follows that, an infinite circle be-
it
an impossibility, there can be no
cir-
cular motion of an infinite body. [25] (5) Again, take a centre C, an infinite line,
to
it,
AB, another infinite line at right angles E, and a moving radius, CD. CD will
never cease contact with E, but the position cutting will always be something like CE,
CD
E
at F.
The
infinite line, therefore, refuses to
complete the circle. [3°] (6) Again, if the heaven is infinite and moves in a circle, we shall have to admit that in a finite time it has traversed the infinite. For suppose the fixed heaven infinite, and that which moves within it equal to it. It results that when the infinite body has completed its revolution, it has traversed an infinite equal to
273 a
itself in a finite
time. But that
we know
to be impossible.
(7) It can also be shown, conversely, that the time of revolution is finite, the area traversed must also be finite; but the area trav-
if
ersed
was equal
to itself; therefore,
it is
itself
finite.
[5]
We
have
now shown
moves
in a circle
has
limit.
its
is
that the
body which
not endless or infinite, but
Further, neither that which moves towards nor that which moves away from the centre
can be infinite. For the upward and downward motions are contraries and are therefore motions towards contrary places. But if one of a [10] pair of contraries is determinate, the other must be determinate also. Now the centre is determined; for, from whatever point the body
which sinks
to the
bottom
starts its
downward
cannot go farther than the centre. The centre, therefore, being determinate, the upper place must also be determinate. But if these two places are determined and finite, the [75] corresponding bodies must also be finite.
motion,
it
if up and down are determinate, the intermediate place is also necessarily determinate. For, if it is indeterminate, the movement within it will be infinite; and that we have already shown to be an impossibility. 1 The middle region then is determinate, and consequent-
Further,
any body which either is in it, or might be in determinate. But the bodies which move [20] up and down may be in it, since the one
ly
it, is
moves naturally away from the centre and the other towards 1
it.
Physics, viii. 8.
273 b
From
this alone it is clear that an infinite an impossibility; but there is a further point. If there is no such thing as infinite weight, then it follows that none of these bodies can be infinite. For the supposed infinite [25] body would have to be infinite in weight.
body
is
(The same argument
applies to lightness: for
one supposition involves infinite weight, so the infinity of the body which rises to the surface involves infinite lightness.) This is proved as follows. Assume the weight to be finite, and take an infinite body, AB, of the weight C. Subtract from the infinite body a fi[30] nite mass, BD, the weight of which shall be E. E then is less than C, since it is the weight of a lesser mass. Suppose then that the smaller as the
goes into the greater a certain
number
of times,
273 b and take BF bearing the same proportion to BD which the greater weight bears to the smaller. For you may subtract as much as you please from an infinite. If now the masses are proportionate to the weights, and the lesser weight is that of the lesser mass, the greater [5] must be that of the greater. The weights, therefore, of the finite and of the infinite body are equal. Again, if the weight of a greater body is greater than that of a less, the weight of GB will be greater than that of FB; and thus the weight of the finite body is greater than that of the infinite. And, further, the weight of unequal masses will be the same, since the infinite and the finite cannot be equal. It does [10] not matter whether the weights are commensurable or not. If (a) they are incommensurable the same reasoning holds. For instance, suppose E multiplied by three is rather more than C: the weight of three masses of the full size of BD will be greater than C. We thus ar[75] rive at the same impossibility as before. Again (b) we may assume weights which are commensurate; for it makes no difference whether we begin with the weight or with the mass. For example, assume the weight E to be commensurate with C, and take from the infinite mass a part BD of weight E. Then let a [20] mass BF be taken having the same proportion to BD which the two weights have to one another. (For the mass being infinite you may subtract from it as much as you please.) These assumed bodies will be commensurate in mass and in weight alike. Nor again does it make any difference to our demonstration whether the total mass has its weight equally or unequally distributed. For it must always be [25] possible to take from the infinite mass a body of equal weight to BD by diminishing or
BOOK
274 b
I,
CHAPTERS
increasing the size of the section to the necessary extent.
From what we have
said, then,
it is
clear that
the weight of the infinite body cannot be finite. have therefore It must then be infinite.
We
only to show this to be impossible in order to prove an infinite body impossible. But the im[30] possibility of infinite weight can be shown in the following way. A given weight moves a given distance in a given time; a weight which as great
is
and more moves the same distance being in inverse pro-
in a less time, the times
274 a portion one weight
is
to the weights.
twice another,
it
For instance,
It
necessarily follows
from
And though you may
movement can be
con-
[10] tinually diminished, yet there is no miniif there were, would it help us. For
mum. Nor,
finite body could have been found greater than the given finite in the same proportion which is supposed to hold between the infinite and the given finite; so that an infinite and a finite weight must have traversed an equal distance in equal time. But that is impossible. Again, whatever the time, so long as it is finite, [75] in which the infinite performs the motion, a finite weight must necessarily move a certain
some
finite distance in that
same time. Infinite weight and the same reasoning
therefore impossible,
is
applies also to infinite lightness. Bodies then of infinite
weight and of
infinite lightness are
equally impossible. is
no
we have shown
1
Physics, in. 4-8.
infinite it,
must necessarily be either fiand if infinite, either of similar
[30] Every body nite or infinite,
or of dissimilar parts.
If its
parts are dissimilar,
is
evident,
our original presuppositions
if
274 b remain unchallenged. For the primary movements being finite in number, the kinds of simple body are necessarily also finite, since
the
movement of a simple body is simple, and movements are finite, and every nat-
the simple
body must always have
its
Now if the infinite body
is
ural
[5] of a finite
must
parts
that
pose
number
it.
composed
of kinds, then each of
to say, the water, fire,
is
proper motion. to be
its
necessarily be infinite in quantity,
But
this
is
&c, which com-
we
impossible, because, as
have already shown, infinite weight and lightness do not exist. Moreover it would be necessary also that their places should be infinite in [10] extent, so that the movements too of all these bodies would be infinite. But this is not possible,
if
we
are to hold to the truth of our
and to the view that which moves downward, nor, by the same reasoning, that which moves upward, can prolong its movement to infinity. For it is true in regard to quality, quantity, and place alike that any process of change is impossible [75] which can have no end. I mean that if it original presuppositions
neither that
is
impossible for a thing to have
come
white, or a cubit long, or in Egypt,
impossible for
it
be any of these.
body may be shown, by a detailed considera[20] tion of the various cases. But it may also be shown universally, not only by such reasoning as we advanced in our discussion of princi1 ples (though in that passage we have already determined universally the sense in which the existence of an infinite is to be asserted or denied), but also suitably to our present purpose in the following way. That will lead us to a fur[25] ther question. Even if the total mass is not
That there
as
us treat of the infinite uni-
let
finite
this that infi-
a time inversely proportionate to its greatness, cannot move at all. The time should be less in proportion as the weight is greater. But there is no proportion between the infinite and the finite: proportion can only hold between a less say that the time of the
however,
First,
versally.
finite
if there is such a thing, being, on [5] the one hand, as great and more than as great as the finite, will move accordingly, but being, on the other hand, compelled to move in
a greater finite time.
infinite, it yet be great enough to admit a plurality of universes. The question might possibly be raised whether there is any obstacle to our believing that there are other universes composed on the pattern of our own, more than one, though stopping short of infinity.
finite
nite weight,
and
365
may
they must represent either a finite or an infinite number of kinds. That the kinds cannot be in-
will take half as
long over a given movement. Further, a weight traverses any finite distance in a time.
if
5-7
to be
moving
to be in process of
It is
to be
it is
also
coming
to
thus impossible for a thing
to a place at
which
in
its
motion
can never by any possibility arrive. Again, suppose the body to exist in dispersion, it may be maintained none the less that the total of all it
these scattered particles, say, of
fire, is infinite.
[20] But body we saw to be that which has extension every way. can there be several
How
dissimilar elements, each infinite?
have to be It is
finite
For,
infinitely
Each would
extended every way.
no more conceivable, again, that the
in-
should exist as a whole of similar parts. in the first place, there is no other
ON THE HEAVENS
$66
movement beyond
those mentioned: one of them. And if [25] so, wc shall have to admit either infinite weight or infinite lightness. Nor, secondly, could the body whose movement is circular be (straight)
we must
therefore give
infinite, since
move
it is
it
would be
as
[30] Moreover, in general, it is impossible that the infinite should move at all. If it did, it would move either naturally or by constraint:
and
if by constraint, it possesses also a natural motion, that is to say, there is another place,
which
infinite like itself, to is
it
move. But
will
impossible.
That
in general
is
it
impossible for the
infi-
upon by the finite or to act upon it may be shown as follows. 275 a (1. The infinite cannot be acted upon by nite to be acted
the finite) Let A be an infinite, B a finite, C the time of a given movement produced by one in the other. Suppose, then, that
A
was heated,
or impelled, or modified in any way, or caused to
undergo any
B
in the
suming
sort of
time C. Let
movement whatever, by
D be less than B; and, as-
that a lesser agent
moves
a lesser pa-
an equal time, call the quantity is to B, so is thus modified by D, E. Then, as E to some finite quantum. We assume that the alteration of equal by equal takes equal time, and the alteration of less by less or of greater by greater takes the same time, if the quantity of the patient is such as to keep the proportion [10] which obtains between the agents, greater and less. If so, no movement can be caused in the infinite by any finite agent in any time whatever. For a less agent will produce that movement in a less patient in an equal time, [5] tient in
D
and the proportionate equivalent of that pano proportion holds between finite and infinite. (2. The infinite cannot act upon the finite.) Nor, again, can the infinite produce a move[75] ment in the finite in any time whatever. Let A be an infinite, B a finite, C the time of action. In the time C, D will produce that mo-
tient will be a finite quantity, since
tion in a patient less than B, say F. Then take E, bearing the same proportion to as the
D
BF bears to F. E will produce the moin BF in the time C. Thus the finite and
can
infinite
effect this
movement.
nothing can For such time
infinite time, in that
move another
or be moved by it. has no limit, while the action and reaction have.
impossible for the infinite to
in a circle. This, indeed,
good as saying that the heavens are infinite, which we have shown to be impossible.
that
which the And, as to
275 b
There
(3.
no interaction between
is
infi-
Nor can infinite be acted upon in any way by infinite. Let A and B be infinites,
nites) [25]
CD being the time of the action of A upon B. Now the whole B was modified in a certain and the part of this infinite, E, cannot be same time, since we assume that a less quantity makes the movement in a less time. Let E then, when acted upon by A, [30] complete the movement in the time D. Then, as D is to CD, so is E to some finite part of B. This part will necessarily be moved by A in the time CD. For we suppose that the same agent produces a given effect on a greater and 275 b a smaller mass in longer and shorter times, the times and masses varying proportionately. There is thus no finite time in which infinites can move one another. Is their time then infinite? No, for infinite time has no end, but the movement communicated has. [5] If therefore every perceptible body possesses the power of acting or of being acted upon, or both of these, it is impossible that an infinite body should be perceptible. All bodies, however, that occupy place are perceptible. There is therefore no infinite body beyond the time,
so modified in the
heaven.
Nor again
extent beyond
it.
is
there anything of limited
And
so
beyond the heaven you suppose it an
For
if
[10] object of intelligence,
it
there
is
no body
at
all.
will be in a place
—since place what 'within' and 'beyond' denote —and therefore an object of perception. is
But nothing that
is not in a place is perceptible. question may also be examined in the light of more general considerations as follows. The infinite, considered as a whole of similar parts, cannot, on the one hand, move in a cir-
The
cle.
For there
is
no centre of the
infinite,
and
[75] that which moves in a circle moves about the centre. Nor again can the infinite move in a straight line.
For there would have
other place infinite like its
natural
movement
great, for the goal of
its
to be anbe the goal of and another, equally unnatural movement. itself to
movement
whole
Moreover, whether
tion
natural or constrained, in either case the force [20] which causes its motion will have to be in-
[20] the infinite effect the
equal times. But this
sumption
is
is
same
alteration in
impossible; for the as-
that the greater effects
it
in a short-
same with any time that can be taken, so that there will no time in
er time. It will be the
finite.
For
its
rectilinear
infinite force
is
force of
an
is
infinite
body, and of an infinite body the force is infinite. So the motive body also will be infinite. (The proof of this is given in our discussion of
BOOK
276 b 1
movement, where
it
shown
1,
CHAPTERS
no finite power, and no infinite then that which moves
is
that
thing possesses infinite thing finite power.) If naturally can also move unnaturally, there will
[25] be two infinites, one which causes, and another which exhibits the latter motion. Again, what is it that moves the infinite? If it moves itself, it
sibly be
must be animate. But how can it posconceived as an infinite animal? And
7-8
367
by constraint. place in
A
which
thing moves naturally to a
without constraint, and
rests
it
rests naturally in a
rests
it
by constraint, and
ther, its
if
which
rests
contrary
is
natural.
then,
If,
the centre here,
its
power.
rests
[30] If the whole
is
else that
not continuous, but
exists,
Democritus and Leucippus think, in the form of parts separated by void, there must
as
necessarily be one
movement
of all the multi-
tude. They are distinguished, we are told, from 276 a one another by their figures; but their na-
ture
is
one, like
many
pieces of gold separated
from one another. But each piece must, as we assert, have the same motion. For a single clod moves to the same place as the whole mass of earth, and a spark to the same place as the whole mass of fire. So that if it be weight that all possess, no body is, strictly speaking, light: and if [5] lightness be universal, none is heavy. Moreover, whatever possesses weight or lightness will have its place either at one of the extremes or in the middle region. But this is impossible while the world is conceived as infi-
And,
which has no centre or extreme limit, no up or down, gives the bod[10] ies no place for their motion; and without that movement is impossible. A thing must move either naturally or unnaturally, and the two movements are determined by the proper and alien places. Again, a place in which a thing rests or to which it moves unnaturally, [75] must be the natural place for some other nite.
generally, that
body, as experience shows. Necessarily, therefore, not everything possesses weight or lightness, but some things do and some do not. From these arguments then it is clear that the body of the universe is not infinite. 8
We
must now proceed to explain why there cannot be more than one heaven the further question mentioned above. For it may be thought that we have not proved universally [20] of bodies that none whatever can exist outside our universe, and that our argument applied only to those of indeterminate extent.
Now 1
—
all
things rest and
Physics, viii. 10.
move
naturally
and
by constraint in
it
moves from
something
moves
moves by constraint. Fura given movement is due to constraint,
a place to
straint that earth
is
it
[25] without constraint. On the other hand, a thing moves by constraint to a place in which
moves it, there will be two infinites, that which moves and that which is moved, differing in their form and there
if
which
place to
it
is
movement from
there will be natural,
and
if
by con-
a certain place to
here to
earth from there
here without constraint, its movement hith-
[30] er will be natural. And the natural movement in each case is one. Further, these worlds,
being similar in nature to ours, must all be composed of the same bodies as it. Moreover each of the bodies, fire, I mean, and earth and 276 b their intermediates, must have the same power as in our world. For if these names are used equivocally, if the identity of name does not rest upon an identity of form in these elements and ours, then the whole to which they belong can only be called a world by equivoca[5] tion. Clearly, then, one of the bodies will
move
naturally
away from
the centre
and an-
other towards the centre, since fire must be identical with fire, earth with earth, and so on,
fragments of each are identical in this world. That this must be the case is evident
as the
from the principles laid down in our discusmovements, 2 for these are limited number, and the distinction of the elements in [10] depends upon the distinction of the movements. Therefore, since the movements are the same, the elements must also be the same everywhere. The particles of earth, then, in another world move naturally also to our centre and its fire to our circumference. This, [75] however, is impossible, since, if it were sion of the
true, earth
must, in
wards, and
fire to
its
the earth of our world
away from
own
world,
the centre; in the
the centre
move
up-
same way
must move naturally it moves towards
when
the centre of another universe. This follows from the supposed juxtaposition of the worlds. For either we must refuse to admit the iden[20] tical nature of the simple bodies in the various universes, or, admitting this, we must
make
the centre
and the extremity one
gested. This being so,
it
as sug-
follows that there
cannot be more worlds than one. To postulate a difference of nature in the simple bodies according as they are more or less distant from their proper places is unrea2
Above, Chapters
2-4.
ON THE HEAVENS
368
277 b
sonable.
For what difference can it make whether we say that a thing is this distance [25] away or that? One would have to sup-
but to opposite points; and since the opposition in place is between above and below, these will be the limits of their movement. (Even in
pose a difference proportionate to the distance and increasing with it, but the form is in fact the same. Moreover, the bodies must have some
circular
movement,
since the fact that they
quite evident. Are
we
move
is
to say then that all their
movements, even those which are mutually to constraint? No, for a body which has no natural movement at all
contrary, are due
cannot be moved by constraint. If then the [30] bodies have a natural movement, the movement of the particular instances of each form must necessarily have for goal a place numerically one, i.e. a particular centre or a particular extremity. If it be suggested that the goal in each case is one in form but numer277* ically more than one, on the analogy of particulars which are many though each undifferentiated in form, we reply that the variety of goal cannot be limited to this portion or that but must extend to all alike. For all are equally undifferentiated in form, but any one [5] is different numerically from any other.
movement
there
is
a sort of opposition
between the ends of the diameter, though the movement as a whole has no contrary: so that [25] here too the movement has in a sense an opposed and finite goal.) There must therefore be some end to locomotion: it cannot continue to infinity.
This conclusion that local movement is not continued to infinity is corroborated by the fact that earth moves more quickly the nearer it is
to the centre,
and
fire
[30] the upper place. But
the nearer if
it
is
to
movement were
infinite speed would be infinite also; and if speed then weight and lightness. For as superior speed in downward movement implies superior weight, so infinite increase of weight
necessitates infinite increase of speed.
277 b Further, it is not the action of another body that makes one of these bodies move up and the other down; nor is it constraint, like the 'extrusion' of some writers. For in that
differs
mass of fire or earth the slower would be the upward or downward movement; but the fact is the reverse: the greater the mass of fire or earth the quicker [5] always is its movement towards its own place. Again, the speed of the movement would not increase towards the end if it were due to constraint or extrusion; for a constrained movement always diminishes in speed as the source
must
of constraint becomes
What
I
mean
is
this:
if
the portions in this
to one another another world, then the portion which is taken hence will not behave differently either from the portions in another world or from those in the same world, but similarly to them, since in form no portion
world behave similarly both
and
to those in
from another. The result is that we abandon our present assumptions [10] or assert that the centre and the extremity are each numerically one. But this being so, the heaven, by the same evidence and the same necessary inferences, must be one only and no either
more.
A
consideration of the other kinds of move-
ment
also makes it plain that there is some point to which earth and fire move naturally. For in general that which is moved changes
[75] from something into something, the starting-point and the goal being different in
form, and always
For inchange from disease to health, to increase is to change from smallness to greatness. Locomotion must be similar: for it also has its goal and startingpoint and therefore the starting-point and it is
a finite change.
stance, to recover health
is
to
—
movement must differ movement of coming to
the goal of the natural
—
form just as the [20] health does not take any direction which chance or the wishes of the mover may select. in
Thus,
too, fire
and earth move not
to infinity
case the larger the
more distant, and a body moves without constraint to the place whence it was moved by constraint.
A
consideration of these points, then, gives
adequate assurance of the truth of our contentions. The same could also be shown with the [10] aid of the discussions which fall under
from the nature of movement, which must be eternal both here and in the other worlds. It is plain, too, from the following considerations that the universe must be one. The bodily elements are three, and thereFirst Philosophy, as well as
the circular
in]
fore the places of the elements will be
three also; the place, sinks to the bottom,
first, of the body which namely the region about
the centre; the place, secondly, of the revolving
body, namely the outermost place, and thirdly, the intermediate place, belonging to the intermediate body. Here in this third place will be the body
which
rises to the surface; since, if
not here, it will be elsewhere, and it cannot be elsewhere: for we have two bodies, one weight-
BOOK
278 b
L
CHAPTERS
one endowed with weight, and below is [20] the place of the body endowed with weight, since the region about the centre has been given to the heavy body. And its position cannot be unnatural to it, for it would have to be natural to something else, and there is nothing else. It must then occupy the intermediate place. What distinctions there are within the intermediate itself we will explain less,
later on.
We
now
said enough to make plain and number of the bodily elements, the place of each, and further, in gen-
have
the character
[25] eral, places are.
how many
in
number
the various
in matter
is
We
We
This may, of course, sometimes
ticular thing.
might be, for instance, that only could be found; yet none the less the difference will remain between the being of
one
it
circle
circle
and of
this particular circle, the
one be-
ing form, the other form in matter, i.e. a par[10] ticular thing. Now since the universe is perceptible it must be regarded as a particular; for everything that is perceptible subsists, as we
know,
But if it is a particular, there between the being of 'this universe' and of 'universe' unqualified. There is a difference, then, between 'this universe' and simple 'universe'; the second is form and [75] shape, the first form in combination with matter; and any shape or form has, or may have, more than one particular instance. in matter.
will be a distinction
On
the supposition of
Forms such
as
some
a fact of observation that the
form are several or number. Hence there either
[20] in
may
be,
more heavens than
one.
infinite are, or
On
these
might be inferred either that there are or that there might be several heavens. We must, however, return and ask how much of this argument is correct and how grounds, then,
much
it
not.
Now
it is
quite right to say that the formula
from the matter must be diffrom that of the shape in the mat-
of the shape apart
and we may allow
not,
show not only that the heaven is one, but also that more than one heaven is impossible, and, further, that, as exempt from decay may and generation, the heaven is eternal. begin by raising a difficulty. From one point of [jo] view it might seem impossible that the heaven should be one and unique, since in all formations and products whether of nature or of art we can distinguish the shape in itself and the shape in combination with matter. For 278 a instance the form of the sphere is one thing and the gold or bronze sphere another; the shape of the circle again is one thing, the bronze or wooden circle another. For when we state the essential nature of the sphere or circle we do not include in the formula gold or [5] bronze, because they do not belong to the essence, but if we are speaking of the copper or gold sphere we do include them. still make the distinction even if we cannot conceive or apprehend any other example beside the par-
it is
particulars of like
[25] ferent
We must
369
must be the case, and equally on the view that no such entity has a separate existence. For in every case in which the essence assert, this
ter,
be the case:
8-9
this to be true.
We
are
however, therefore compelled to assert a
Such a plurality is in fact world contains the entirety of matter, as in fact it does. But perhaps our contention can be made clearer in this way. Suppose 'aquilinity' to be curvature in the nose [jo] or flesh, and flesh to be the matter of aquilinity. Suppose further, that all flesh came together into a single whole of flesh endowed with this aquiline quality. Then neither would there be, nor could there arise, any other thing that was aquiline. Similarly, suppose flesh and bones to be the matter of man, and suppose a [ J5] man to be created of all flesh and all bones plurality of worlds.
impossible
if
this
The possibility of anbe removed. Whatever case 278 b you took it would be the same. The general rule is this: a thing whose essence resides in indissoluble union.
other
man would
substratum of matter can never come into being in the absence of all matter. Now the universe is certainly a particular and a material thing: if however, it is composed not of a part [5] but of the whole of matter, then though the being of 'universe' and of 'this universe' in a
are
still
distinct, yet there is
and no
no other universe, being made, be-
possibility of others
cause
all the matter is already included in this. remains, then, only to prove that it is composed of all natural perceptible body. It
[10] First, however, we must explain what 'heaven' and in how many senses
mean by
we we
use the word, in order to make clearer the obour inquiry, (a) In one sense, then, we
ject of
call 'heaven' the substance of the extreme circumference of the whole, or that natural body whose place is at the extreme circumference.
We
recognize habitually a special right to the [75] name 'heaven' in the extremity or upper region, which we take to be the seat of all that is
divine, (b) In another sense,
we
use this
ON THE HEAVENS
370
279 b
name for the body continuous with the extreme circumference which contains the moon,
time is the number of movement. But in the absence of natural body there is no movement,
the sun, and some of the stars; these we say are 'in the heaven', (c) In yet another sense
and outside the heaven, as we have shown, body neither exists nor can come to exist. It is
give the name to all body included within [20] the extreme circumference, since we habitually call the whole or totality 'the heaven'. The word, then, is used in three senses. Now the whole included within the extreme circumference must be composed of all physical and sensible body, because there neither is, nor can come into being, any body outside the [25] heaven. For if there is a natural body outside the extreme circumference it must be either a simple or a composite body, and its
clear then that there
must be either natural or unnatural. But it cannot be any of the simple bodies. For, first, it has been shown that that which moves [jo] in a circle cannot change its place. And, secondly, it cannot be that which moves from the centre or that which lies lowest. Naturally
the period of
we
position
1
is neither place, nor void, nor time, outside the heaven. Hence whatever is there, is of such a nature as not to occupy any place, nor does time age it; nor is there any [20] change in any of the things which lie beyond the outermost motion; they continue through their entire duration unalterable and unmodified, living the best and most selfsufficient of lives. As a matter of fact, this word
'duration' possessed a divine significance for
the ancients, for the fulfilment life
which includes
of any creature, outside of
which no natural development can
fall,
has
[25] been called its duration. On the same principle the fulfilment of the whole heaven,
which includes
the fulfilment infinity,
is
time and
all
— name based upon the always—duration immortal and
'duration'
a
they could not be there, since their proper places are elsewhere; and if these are there unnaturally, the exterior place will be natural
divine.
some other body, since a place which is unmust be natural to another: but we saw that there is no other body besides
but others feebly, enjoy. So, too, in its concerning the divine, popular philosophy often propounds the view that
to
natural to one body [35] these.
2
Then
it
not possible that any
is
279 a simple body should be outside the heaven. But, if no simple body, neither can any mixed body be there: for the presence of the simple body is involved in the presence of the mixture. Further neither can any body come into that place: for it will do so either naturally or unnaturally, and will be either sim[5] pie or composite; so that the same argument will apply, since it makes no difference whether the question 'could
then
A
come
is
to exist?'
'does
A
exist?'
or
The world
as a whole, therefore, includes appropriate matter, which is, as we saw, natural perceptible body. So that neither are there now, nor have there ever been, nor can
all its
[10] there ever be formed more heavens than one, but this heaven of ours is one and unique
and complete. It is therefore evident that there is also no place or void or time outside the heaven. For in every place body can be present; and void
which the presence of [75] body, though not actual, is possible; and said to be that in
1
it
derive the being and
[jo] other things,
some more or
Chapters 2 and 3 above. Chapter 2 above.
life
which
less articu-
lately
discussions
whatever is divine, whatever is primary and supreme, is necessarily unchangeable. This fact confirms what we have said. For there is nothing else stronger than it to move it since that
—
—
would mean more divine and it has no 279 b defect and lacks none of its proper excellences. Its unceasing movement, then, is also [35]
reasonable, since everything ceases to
when
it
comes
whose path
is
move
proper place, but the body the circle has one and the same to
its
place for starting-point
and
goal.
10
it is
ence.
2
it is
From
From our arguments
evident not only that there is not, but also that there could never come to be, any bodily mass whatever outside the circumfer-
is
fact that
Having
established these distinctions,
we may
now
proceed to the question whether the heaven is ungenerated or generated, indestructible or destructible. Let us start with a review of the theories of other thinkers; for the proofs of a theory are difficulties for the contrary theory. Besides, those who have first heard the pleas of our adversaries will be more likely to credit the [10] assertions which we are going to make. We shall be less open to the charge of procuring judgement by default. To give a satisfac[5]
tory decision as to the truth to be rather
it
is
necessary
an arbitrator than a party
to the
dispute.
That the world was generated all are agreed, some say that it is eternal,
but, generation over,
BOOK
280 b
I,
CHAPTERS
any other natural formation. Others again, with Emped[75] ocles of Acragas and Heraclitus of
others say that
it is
destructible like
Ephesus, believe that there
is
alternation in
which takes now this and continues without
the destructive process,
now
direction,
that,
Now
was generated and
yet
to assert the impossible; for
we
to assert that
eternal
is
it
cannot reasonably attribute to anything any characteristics but those which observation [20] detects in many or all instances. But in this case the facts point the other way: generated things are seen always to be destroyed. Further, a thing whose present state had no
beginning and which could not have been other than it was at any previous moment throughout its entire duration, cannot possibly be changed. For there will have to be some cause of change, and if this had been present earlier it would have made possible another condition of that to which any other condition [25] was impossible. Suppose that the world was formed out of elements which were formerly otherwise conditioned than as they are now. Then (1) if their condition was always so and could not have been otherwise, the world could never have come into being. And (2) if the world did come into being, then, clearly, their condition must have been capable of change and not eternal: after combination therefore they will be dispersed, just as in the came into combina-
past after dispersion they tion,
tradiction.
371
The
ordered,
it is
said,
1
arose out of
and the same thing cannot be same time both ordered and unordered; there must be a process and a lapse of time separating the two states. In the figure, on the [10] other hand, there is no temporal separa-
the unordered; at the
is clear then that the universe cannot be at once eternal and generated. To say that the universe alternately combines and dissolves is no more paradoxical than to make it eternal but varying in shape. It is as if one were to think that there was now
tion. It
end. is
9-11
and
this process either
has been, or could
[75] destruction and now existence when from a child a man is generated, and from a man a
when the elements not a chance system and combination, but the very same as before especially on the view of those who hold this theory, since they say that the contrary is the cause of each state. So that if the totality of [20] body, which is a continuum, is now in this order or disposition and now in that, and if the combination of the whole is a world or heaven, then it will not be the world that comes into being and is destroyed, but only its For
child.
is
it
come together
clear that
the result
is
—
dispositions.
the world
If
possible to
is believed to be one, it is imsuppose that it should be, as a generated and then destroyed,
whole, first never to reappear; since before it came into [25] being there was always present the combination prior to it, and that, we hold, could never change if it was never generated. If, on the other hand, the worlds are infinite in num-
more
[50] have been, indefinitely repeated. But if this is so, the world cannot be indestructible, and it does not matter whether the change of
this
condition has actually occurred or remains a
possible both for the ungenerated to be de-
possibility.
[30] stroyed and for the generated to persist undestroyed. (This is held in the Timaeus, where Plato says that the heaven, though it was generated, will none the less exist to
Some
who
hold that the world, though indestructible, was yet generated, try to support their case by a parallel which is illusory. They say that in their statements about its generation they are doing what geometri[35] cians do when they construct their figures, not implying that the universe really had a beginning, but for didactic reasons facilitat280* ing understanding by exhibiting the object, like the figure, as in course of formation. The two cases, as we said, are not parallel; of those
for, in the
construction of the figure,
when
the
various steps are completed the required figure forthwith results; but in these other dem-
what
is not that which was cannot be so; for antecedent and consequent, as assumed, are in con-
onstrations
results
[5] required. Indeed
it
ber the view is,
what
or
is
is
plausible.
But whether from
not, impossible will be clear
follows.
For there are some
who
think
it
So far as the heaven is concerned we have answered this view with arguments appropriate to the nature of the heaven: on the eternity.)
general question
we examine
we
shall attain clearness
when
the matter universally. 11
280b
We
must
first
distinguish the senses in
which we use the words 'ungenerated' and 'generated', 'destructible' and 'indestructible'. These have many meanings, and though it may make no difference to the argument, yet some confusion of mind must result from treating *Cp. Plato, Timaeus, 30.
ON THE HEAVENS
372 [5] as
uniform
in
its
word which has sevThe character which
use a
eral distinct applications.
is the ground of the predication will always remain obscure. The word 'ungenerated' then is used (a) in one sense whenever something now is which formerly was not, no process of becoming or change being involved. Such is the case, according to some, with contact and motion, since there is no process of coming to be in contact
used in another sense, is capable of coming [10] to be, with or without process, does not exist; such a thing is ungenerated in the sense that its generation is not a fact but a possibility. ( partake of evil; for the bad itself is [35] one of the two elements. But the other school does not treat the good and the bad even as
principles; yet in
all
things the good
is
in the
highest degree a principle. The school we first mentioned is right in saying that it is a principle, but how the good is a principle they do not
—
whether as end or as mover or as form. 1075 b Empedocles also has a paradoxical view; for he identifies the good with love, but say
is a principle both as mover (for it brings things together) and as matter (for it is part even if it happens that of the mixture).
this
Now
[5] the
same thing
is
a principle both as mat-
ter and as mover, still the being, at least, of the two is not the same. In which respect then is love It is paradoxical also that strife should be imperishable; the nature of his 'evil'
a principle?
is
just strife.
Anaxagoras makes the good a motive principle; for his 'reason' moves things. But it moves them for an end, which must be something other than it, except according to our way of stating the case; for, on our view, the [10] medical art is in a sense health. It is paradoxical also not to suppose a contrary to the
good,
i.e.
contraries
to reason.
make no
But
all
who
speak of the
use of the contraries, unless
bring their views into shape. And why some things are perishable and others imperishable,
we
no one
tells
us; for they
make
all
some make
this
existing things out of the non-
and others
make
to avoid the necessity of things one.
all
why should there always be becomand what is the cause of becoming? this no one tells us. And those who suppose two principles must suppose another, a superior principle, and so must those who believe in the Forms; for why did things come to participate, or why do they participate, in the [20] Forms? And all other thinkers are conFurther,
—
ing,
by the necessary consequence that something contrary to Wisdom, i.e. to the highest knowledge; but we are not. For there is nothing contrary to that which is primary; for all contraries have matter, and things that have matter exist only potentially; and the ignorance which is contrary to any knowledge leads to an object contrary to the object of the knowledge; but what is primary has no fronted there
is
contrary.
[25] Again,
if
besides sensible things no others
be no first principle, no order, no becoming, no heavenly bodies, but each exist, there will
principle will have a principle before
it,
the accounts of the theologians and
the nat-
ural philosophers.
But
if
the
Forms
all
or the
as in
num-
bers are to exist, they will be causes of nothing;
not that, at least not of movement. Furhow is extension, i.e. a continuum, to be produced out of unextended parts? For number will not, either as mover or as form, proor
if
ther,
[30] duce a continuum. But again there cannot be any contrary that is also essentially a pro-
ductive or
moving
possible for
it
principle; for
not to be.
Or
it
would be
at least its action
would be posterior to its potency. The world, then, would not be eternal. But it is; one of these premisses, then, must be denied. And we have said how this must be done. Further, in virtue of what the numbers, or the soul and [35] tne body, or in general the form and the thing, are one of this no one tells us anything;
—
nor can any one that the
who
say
tell,
unless he says, as
we
do,
mover makes them one. And those mathematical number is first and go
on to generate one kind of substance after an1076 a other and give different principles for each, make the substance of the universe a mere series of episodes (for one substance has no influence on another by its existence or nonexistence), and they give us many governing principles; but the world refuses to be governed badly.
'The rule of many
existing
things out of the same principles. Further, [75]
existent;
1076'
there be.' 1 1
Cf. Iliad,
11.
204.
is
not good; one ruler
let
BOOK
1076 b
XII,
CHAPTER 10— BOOK
BOOK
XIII,
CHAPTERS
1-2
607
XIII subject of our discussion will be not
they exist but
We
have stated what
is
how they
whether
exist.
the substance of sension physics 1
ble things, dealing in the treatise
2 with matter, and later with the substance existence. Now since actual has [10] which our inquiry is whether there is or is not besides the sensible substances any which is immovable and eternal, and, if there is, what it is, we must first consider what is said by others, so that, if there is anything which they say wrongly,
time that the doctrine in question is an artificial one, has been said already in our discussion of 4 difficulties we have pointed out that it is imb 1076 possible for two solids to be in the same place, and also that according to the same argu-
we may
ment
not be liable to the same objections, is any opinion common to them and us, we shall have no private grievance [75] against ourselves on that account; for one must be content to state some points better than while,
if
there
and others no worse.
one's predecessors,
Two
opinions are held on this subject;
said that the objects of
bers
and
lines
and the
mathematics
like
—
i.e.
it is
num-
—are substances, and
again that the Ideas are substances. And since (1) some recognize these as two different [20] classes the Ideas and the mathematical numbers, and (2) some recognize both as having one nature, while (3) some others say that the mathematical substances are the only substances, we must consider first the objects of mathematics, not qualifying them by any other characteristic not asking, for instance, whether they are in fact Ideas or not, or whether they are the principles and substances [25] of existing things or not, but only wheth-
—
—
er as objects of mathematics they exist or not,
and
if
this
we must
they exist,
how
they exist.
Then
separately consider the
after
Ideas
themselves in a general way, and only as far as the accepted mode of treatment demands; for most of the points have been repeatedly made even by the discussions outside our school, and, further, the greater part of our account must [30] finish by throwing light on that inquiry, 3 viz. when we examine whether the substances and the principles of existing things are numbers
and
Ideas; for after the discussion of the
Ideas this remains as a third inquiry. If
some
impossible for mathematical objects and at the same
it is
to exist in sensible things,
;
the other powers
and
characteristics also
should exist in sensible things and none of them separately. This we have said already. But, further, it is obvious that on this theory it is impossible for any body whatever to be di[5] vided; for it would have to be divided at a plane, and the plane at a line, and the line at a point, so that if the point cannot be divided, neither can the line, and if the line cannot, neither can the plane nor the solid. What difference, then, does it make whether sensible things are such indivisible entities, or, without [10] being so themselves, have indivisible entities in them? The result will be the same; if the sensible entities are divided the others will be divided too, or else not even the sensible entities can be divided. But, again, it is not possible that such entities should exist separately. For if besides the sensible solids there are to be other solids which are separate solids,
it
from them and prior is
to the sensible
plain that besides the planes also
[75] there must be other and separate planes and points and lines; for consistency requires this. But if these exist, again besides the planes and lines and points of the mathematical solid there must be others which are separate. (For incomposites are prior to compounds; and if there are, prior to the sensible bodies, bodies
[20] which are not sensible, by the same argument the planes which exist by themselves must be prior to those which are in the motion-
Therefore these will be planes and than those that exist along with the mathematical solids to which these thinkers less solids.
lines other
the objects of mathematics exist, they
exist either in sensible objects, as
That
must
say, or
assign separate existence; for the latter exist
[35] separate from sensible objects (and this also is said by some); or if they exist in neither
along with the mathematical solids, while the others are prior to the mathematical solids.) [25] Again, therefore, there will be, belonging
of these ways, either they do not exist, or they exist only in
some
1
Physics,
3
Cf. chapters 6-9.
1.
2
special sense.
Metaphysics, vn,
vm,
So that the ix.
to these planes, lines,
will
have to
be,
4Cf. in. 998*7-19.
and prior
to
them
there
by the same argument, other
METAPHYSICS
6o8
lines and points; and prior to these points in the prior lines there will have to be other points, though there will be no others prior to (i) the accumulation becomes abthese.
Now
we
surd; for
find ourselves with one set of
apart from the sensible solids; three sets of planes apart from the sensible planes those which exist apart from the sensi[jo]
solids
—
and those and those which
in the
ble planes,
mathematical
sol-
from those in the mathematical solids; four sets of lines, and five sets of points. With which of these, then, ids,
exist apart
will the mathematical sciences deal? Certainly not with the planes and lines and points in the [55] motionless solid; for science always deals with what is prior. And (2) the same account will apply also to numbers; for there will be a
from each set of from each set of realities, sense and again from those
different set of units apart
and
points,
from the
also apart
objects of
1077 b
posterior; for the incomplete spatial
magnitude
in the order of generation prior,
but in the
is
order of substance posterior, as the
lifeless is
to the living.
[20] Again, by virtue of what, and when, wil! mathematical magnitudes be one? For things in our perceptible world are one in virtue of soul, or of a part of soul, or of something else that is reasonable enough; when these are not present, the thing is a plurality, and splits up into parts. But in the case of the subjects of mathematics, which are divisible and are quantities, what is the cause of their being one and holding together? Again, the modes of generation of the objects of mathematics show that we are right. For the dimension first generated is length, [25] then comes breadth, lastly depth, and the
process
is
complete.
If,
then, that
posterior in the order of generation
which is
is
prior in
of thought; so that there will be various classes
the order of substantiality, the solid will be
of mathematical numbers.
prior to the plane
how is it possible to solve the questions which we have already enumerated in our
also
Again,
1
For the objects of from sensible things just as the objects of geometry will; but how is it possible that a heaven and its parts or anything else which has movement discussion of difficulties
1077
a
astronomy will
?
exist apart
—
and the
line.
can
shape, as the soul perhaps
Therefore well,
it
is
sights.
plain that the other senses as
and the other
objects of sense, will exist
why should one not? And if this
apart; for
set of
them do
so
and
another is so, there will also be animals existing apart, since there will be senses.
Again, there are certain mathematical theo-
way
Again, the solid is a sort of substance; for it already has in a sense completeness. But how
should exist apart? Similarly also the objects
and
in this
senses.
of optics and of harmonics will exist apart; for [5] there will be both voice and sight besides the sensible or individual voices
And
both more complete and more whole, because it can become animate. How, on the other hand, could a line or a plane be animate ? [jo] The supposition passes the power of our it is
lines
be substances? Neither as a form or
like the solid; for
is,
nor as matter,
we have no
experience of
anything that can be put together out of lines [ £5] or planes or points, while if these had been a sort of material substance, we should have observed things which could be put together out of them. 1077 b Grant, then, that they are prior in definition. Still not all things that are prior in definition are also prior in substantiality.
For
[10] rems that are universal, extending beyond these substances. Here then we shall have
when
another intermediate substance separate both
in the
from the Ideas and from the intermediates, a substance which is neither number nor points
things are prior in definition to those whose definitions are compounded out of their defi-
And
those things are prior in substantiality which
separated from other things surpass
power
them
of independent existence, but
the former entities should exist separate from
and these two properties are not coFor if attributes do not exist apart from the substances (e.g. a 'mobile' or a
sensible things.
'pale'), pale is prior to the pale
nor spatial magnitude nor time. impossible, plainly
And,
it
is
if
this is
also impossible that
nitions; [5]
extensive.
man
in defini-
[75] to the truth and to the usual views follow, one is to suppose the objects of mathematics to exist thus as separate entities. For because
but not in substantiality. For it cannot exist separately, but is always along with the concrete thing; and by the concrete thing I mean the pale man. Therefore it is plain that
they exist thus they must be prior to sensible spatial magnitudes, but in truth they must be
that
in general, conclusion contrary alike
if
tion,
neither
is
which
the result of abstraction prior nor is
produced by adding determinants it is by adding a determi-
[10] posterior; for
BOOK
1078 s
XIII,
CHAPTERS
nant to pale that we speak of the pale man. It has, then, been sufficiently pointed out that the objects of mathematics are not substances in a higher degree than bodies are, and that they are not prior to sensibles in being, but only in definition, and that they cannot exist
somewhere apart. But since it was not possible [75] for them to exist in sensibles either, it is plain that they either do not exist at all or exist in a special sense and therefore do not 'exist' without qualification. For 'exist' has
many
For
senses.
just as the universal propositions of
mathe-
matics deal not with objects which exist separately, apart from extended magnitudes and from numbers, but with magnitudes and numbers, not however qua such as to have magni[20] tude or to be divisible, clearly it is possible that there should also be both propositions
sensibles.
virtue of
2-3
609
Many properties attach to things in their own nature as possessed of each
such character; e.g. there are attributes peculiar to the animal qua female or qua male (yet there is no 'female' nor 'male' separate from animals); so that there are also attributes which belong to things merely as lengths or as planes. And in proportion as we are dealing with things which are prior in definition and sim-
knowledge has more accuracy, which abstracts from spatial magnitude is more precise than one which takes it into account; and a science is most precise if it abstracts from movement, but if it takes account of movement, it is most precise if it deals with the primary movement, for this is the simplest; and of this again uniform movement is the sim[10] pier, our
i.e.
simplicity. Therefore a science
plest form.
The same account may
and demonstrations about sensible magnitudes, not however qua sensible but qua possessed of certain definite qualities. For as there are many
and numbers; but the
propositions about things merely considered as
ceeds in
[25) in motion, apart
thing
is
and from
their
from what each such accidents, and as it is not
therefore necessary that there should be either a mobile separate
from
sensibles, or a distinct
mobile entity in the sensibles, so too in the case of mobiles there will be propositions and sci-
them however not qua mobile but only qua bodies, or again only qua [50] planes, or only qua lines, or qua divisibles, or qua indivisibles having position, or only qua indivisibles. Thus since it is true to say
ences,
which
treat
without qualification that not only things are separable but also things which are inseparable exist (for instance, that mobiles exist), it is true also to say without qualification that the objects of mathematics exist, and with the character ascribed to them by mathe-
which
maticians.
And
as
it is
true to say of the other
sciences too, without qualification, that they
deal with such
what
and such
it
pale, if the healthy thing
is
is
ence has the healthy as
its
—
not with not with the
a subject
accidental to
[35]
(e.g.
pale,
and the
sci-
subject), but with
—
which is the subject of each science with 1078 a the healthy if it treats its object qua healthy, with man if qua man: so too is it with geometry; if its subjects happen to be sensible, though it does not treat them qua
that
—
mathematical sciences will not for nor, on the [5] other hand, of other things separate from
sensible, the
that reason be sciences of sensibles
—
be given of har-
[75] monies and optics; for neither considers its objects qua sight or qua voice, but qua lines latter
are
attributes
And
mechanics too prothe same way. Therefore if we sup-
proper to the former.
pose attributes separated from their fellowand make any inquiry concerning
attributes
them
as such,
we
shall not for this reason be
any more than when one draws a line on the ground and calls it a foot long when it in error,
[20] is not; for the error premisses.
Each question
is
not included in the
will be best investigated in
—
way by setting up by an act of separation what is not separate, as the arithmetician and the geometer do. For a man qua man is one inthis
divisible thing; and the arithmetician supposed one indivisible thing, and then considered whether any attribute belongs to a man qua indivisible. But the geometer treats him neither [25] qua man nor qua indivisible, but as a solid. For evidently the properties which would have belonged to him even if perchance he had not been indivisible, can belong to him even apart from these attributes. Thus, then, geometers speak correctly; they talk about existing [30] things, and their subjects do exist; for being has two forms it exists not only in com-
—
plete reality but also materially.
Now
good and the beautiful are
since the
former always implies conduct as its subject, while the beautiful is found also in motionless things), those who assert that the mathematical sciences say nothing of the different (for the
beautiful or the
good are
in error.
For these
[35] sciences say and prove a great deal about
METAPHYSICS
6io
them; if they do not expressly mention them, but prove attributes which are their results or their definitions, it is not true to say that they tell us nothing about them. The chief forms of beauty are order and symmetry and definite-
1078 b ness, which the mathematical sciences demonstrate in a special degree. And since these (e.g. order and definiteness) are obviously causes of sciences
must
many
things, evidently these
treat this sort of causative prin-
ciple also (i.e. the beautiful) as in
some
sense
But we shall speak more plainly elsewhere about these matters. [5] a cause.
So much then for the objects of mathematics; we have said that they exist and in what sense they exist, and in what sense they are prior and in what sense not prior. Now, regarding the Ideas, we must first examine the ideal [10] theory itself, not connecting it in any way with the nature of numbers, but treating it in the form in which it was originally understood by those who first maintained the existence of the Ideas. The supporters of the ideal theory were led to it because on the question about the truth of things they accepted the Heraclitean sayings which describe all sensible [75] things as ever passing away, so that if
knowledge or thought is to have an object, there must be some other and permanent entities, apart from those which are sensible; for there could be no knowledge of things which were in a state of flux. But when Socrates was occupying himself with the excellences of character, and in connexion with them became the first to raise the problem of universal definition (for of the physicists Democritus only [20] touched on the subject to a small extent,
and defined,
and the had before this few things, whose definitions after a fashion, the hot
cold; while the Pythagoreans
treated of a
marriage
e.g. those of opportunity, justice, or
—they connected with numbers; but
it
was
nat-
ural that Socrates should be seeking the essence, for he was seeking to syllogize, and 'what a thing is' is the starting-point of syllo[25] gisms; for there was as yet none of the dialectical power which enables people even without knowledge of the essence to speculate about contraries and inquire whether the same science deals with contraries; for two things may be fairly ascribed to Socrates inductive arguments and universal definition, both of which are concerned with the starting-point but Socrates did not make [30] of science):
—
—
1079 a
the universals or the definitions exist apart: they, however, gave them separate existence,
and
was the kind
of thing they called followed for them, almost by the same argument, that there must be Ideas of all things that are spoken of universally, and it was almost as if a man wished to count certain things, and while they were few this
Ideas. Therefore
it
[55] thought he would not be able to count them, but made more of them and then counted them; for the Forms are, one may say, more numerous than the particular sensible 1079 a things, yet it was in seeking the causes of these that they proceeded from them to the Forms. For to each thing there answers an
which has the same name and
entity
exists
apart from the substances, and so also in the case of all other groups there is a one over
many, whether these be Again, of the ways
of this in
world or
eternal.
which it is proved none is convincing;
[5] that the Forms exist, for from some no inference necessarily follows,
and from some arise Forms even of things of which they think there are no Forms. For according to the arguments from the sciences there will be Forms of all things of which there are sciences, and according to the argument of the 'one over many' there will be [10] Forms even of negations, and according to the argument that thought has an object
when
the individual object has perished, there
Forms of perishable things; for we have an image of these. Again, of the most accurate arguments, some lead to Ideas of relations, of which they say there is no independent class, and others introduce the 'third man'. And in general the arguments for the Forms will be
whose existence the believers more zealous than for the exist-
destroy things for in
Forms
are
[75] ence of the Ideas; for it follows that not the dyad but number is first, and that prior to
number
is
the relative,
the absolute
—besides
and that all
this
is
prior to
the other points on
which
certain people, by following out the opinions held about the Forms, came into con-
with the principles of the theory. Again, according to the assumption
flict
on
[20] which the belief in the Ideas rests, there will be Forms not only of substances but also
many other things; for the concept is single not only in the case of substances, but also in that of non-substances, and there are sciences of other things than substance; and a thousand other such difficulties confront them. But acof
cording to the necessities of the case and the [25] opinions about the Forms, if they can be
BOOK
1080«
XIII,
CHAPTERS
shared in there must be Ideas of substances only. For they are not shared in incidentally, but each Form must be shared in as something not predicated of a subject. (By 'being shared in incidentally' I mean that if a thing shares in 'double itself, it shares also in 'eternal', but incidentally; for 'the double' happens to be [50] eternal.) Therefore the Forms will be
same names indicate suband in the ideal world (or what will be the meaning of saying that there is something apart from the particulars the one over many?). And if the Ideas and the things that share in them have the same form, there will be something common: for why should '2' be one and the same in the perish[55] able 2's, or in the 2's which are many but eternal, and not the same in the '2 itself as in the individual 2? But if they have not the same 1079 b form, they will have only the name in common, and it is as if one were to call both Callias and a piece of wood a 'man', without observing any community between substance. But the
stance in this
—
them. But
we
are to suppose that in other respects the common definitions apply to the Forms, e.g. that 'plane figure' and the other if
the circle[5] parts of the definition apply to but 'what really is' has to be added, we
itself,
must inquire whether this meaningless. For to what is
To
is
not absolutely
this to be
added?
'centre' or to 'plane' or to all the parts of
the definition? For
all
the elements in the es-
sence are Ideas, e.g. 'animal' and 'two-footed'. [10] Further, there must be some Ideal answering to 'plane' above, some nature which will
be present in
Above
all
all
the
Forms as
their genus.
one might discuss the question what
in the world the
Forms
contribute to sensible
3-6
easy to collect to
611
many and
insuperable objections
such a view. But, further,
all
other things cannot
come
[25] from the Forms in any of the usual senses of 'from'. And to say that they are patterns and
them
to use empty For what is it that works, looking to the Ideas? And any thing can both be and come into being without being copied from something else, so that, whether Socrates exists or not, a man like Soc[30] rates might come to be. And evidently this might be so even if Socrates were eternal. And there will be several patterns of the same thing, and therefore several Forms; e.g. 'animal' and 'two-footed', and also 'man-himself, will be Forms of man. Again, the Forms are
the other things share in
words and
is
poetical metaphors.
patterns not only of sensible things, but of
Forms themselves
also;
i.e.
the genus
is
the
pattern of the various forms-of-a-genus; therefore the
same thing
will be pattern
and copy.
[35] Again, it would seem impossible that sub1080a stance and that whose substance it is
should exist apart; how, therefore, could the Ideas, being the substances of things, exist apart ? 1
Phaedo the case is stated in this way that the Forms are causes both of being and of becoming. Yet though the Forms exist, still things do not come into being, unless there is something to originate movement; and many other things come into being (e.g. a house or a [5] ring) of which they say there are no Forms. Clearly therefore even the things of which they say there are Ideas can both be and come into being owing to such causes as produce the things just mentioned, and not owing to the Forms. But regarding the Ideas it is possible, both in this way and by more abstract and
—
In the
[10] accurate arguments, to collect many obwe have considered.
jections like those
things, either to those that are eternal or to
those that come into being and cease to be; for they cause neither movement nor any change [75] in them. But again they help in no wise either towards the knowledge of other things (for they are not even the substance of these,
would have been
in them), or towards they are not in the individuals which share in them; though if they were, they might be thought to be causes, as white
else they
their being,
if
causes whiteness in a white object by entering
composition. But this argument, which was used first by Anaxagoras, and later [20] into
its
by Eudoxus in his discussion of difficulties and by certain others, is very easily upset; for it is
Since
we have
discussed these points,
to consider again the results
it is
regarding
well
numnum-
which confront those who say that and first causes [75] of things. If number is an entity and its substance is nothing other than just number, as some say, it follows that either (1) there is a first in it and a second, each being different in species, and either (a) this is true of the units without exception, and any unit is inasbers
bers are separable substances
—
[20] sociable with any unit, or (h) they are all without exception successive, and any of them
METAPHYSICS
6l2 arc associablc with any, as they say
the case
is
with mathematical number; for in mathematical number no one unit is in any way different
from another. Or (c) some units must be associable and some not; e.g. suppose that 2 is first after 1, and then comes 3 and then the rest [25] of the number series, and the units in each
number
first
2 are associable with one another, and
are associable, e.g. those in the
those in the first 3 with one another, and so with the other numbers; but the units in the '2-itself are inassociable with those in the '3-
and similarly
itself;
in the case of the other
And so while mathecounted thus after 1, 2 (which consists of another 1 besides the former 1), and 3 (which consists of another 1 besides these two), and the other numbers similarly, ideal number is counted thus after 1, a distinct 2 which does not include the first 1, and [jo] successive numbers.
matical
number
—
is
—
a 3 which does not include the 2, and the rest of the number series similarly. Or (2) one kind [55] of
number must be
named, 1 one
cians speak of, last
2
must be
like the first that was which the mathematiand that which we have named
like that
a third kind.
Again, these kinds of numbers must either 1080b be separable from things, or not separable but in objects of perception (not however in the way which we first considered, 3 but
1081'
consisting of abstract units; they suppose the [20] units to have spatial magnitude. But how
was constructed so as to have magniseem unable to say. Another thinker says the first kind of number, that of the Forms, alone exists, and some the
first
1
tude, they
say mathematical
The
number
is
identical with this.
and solids is simFor some think that those which are the objects of mathematics are different from those [25] which come after the Ideas; and of those who express themselves otherwise some speak of the objects of mathematics and in a mathematical way viz. those who do not make the Ideas numbers nor say that Ideas exist; and case of lines, planes,
ilar.
—
others speak of the objects of mathematics, but not mathematically; for they say that neither is every spatial magnitude divisible into magnify] tudes, nor do any two units taken at ran-
dom make
2.
All
who
say the
is
1
an element
and principle of things suppose numbers
to
consist of abstract units, except the Pythago-
reans; but they suppose the numbers to have magnitude, as has been said before. 4 It is clear
from this statement, then, in how many ways numbers may be described, and that all the [35] wa ys have been mentioned; and all these views are impossible, but some perhaps more than others.
in the sense that objects of perception consists
of
numbers which are present
in
one kind and not another, or
them)
all
—either
of them.
[5] These are of necessity the only ways in which the numbers can exist. And of those who say that the 1 is the beginning and substance and element of all things, and that number is formed from the 1 and something else, almost
every one has described these ways; only
are inassociable.
number
no one has
in
one of
said all the units
And this has happened
reason-
[10] ably enough; for there can be no way besides those mentioned. Some say both kinds
number
exist, that which has a before and being identical with the Ideas, and mathematical number being different from the Ideas and from sensible things, and both being sep-
of
after
arable
from
and others say
sensible things;
[75] mathematical number alone exists, as the of realities, separate from sensible things.
first
And the Pythagoreans, also, believe in one kind number
—
the mathematical only they say it not separate but sensible substances are formed out of it. For they construct the whole universe out of numbers only not numbers
of
;
is
—
1
11.
5-20. 1
2
11.
23-35.
3
Cf
.
1
076* 3 8- b
1 1
First, then, let us inquire if the units are associ-
1081 a able or inassociable, and if inassociable, in which of the two ways we distinguished. For it is possible that any unity is inassociable with any, and it is possible that those in the '2itself are inassociable with those in the '3itself,
and, generally, that those in each ideal are inassociable with those in other
number
Now
(1) if all units are as[5] ideal numbers. sociable and without difference, we get mathe-
—
number only one kind of number, and the Ideas cannot be the numbers. For what sort of number will man-himself or animal-itself or any other Form be? There is one Idea of each thing, e.g. one of man-himself and matical
[10] another one of animal-itself but the simand undifferentiated numbers are infinite;
ilar
ly many, so that any particular 3 is no more man-himself than any other 3. But if the Ideas are not numbers, neither can they exist at all. For from what principles will the Ideas come? [75] It is number that comes from the 1 and
the indefinite dyad,
ments are said *
I.19.
and the
principles or ele-
to be principles
and elements of
BOOK
1082s
CHAPTERS
XIII,
number, and the Ideas cannot be ranked as either prior or posterior to the numbers. But (2) if the units are inassociable, and inassociable in the sense that any is inassociable with any other, number of this sort cannot be mathematical number; for mathematical numunits,
ber consists of undifferentiated
[20]
and the truths proved of it suit this character. Nor can it be ideal number. For 2 will not proceed immediately from 1 and the indefinite dyad, and be followed by the successive num-
—
&-7
613
becomes part 1 [20] of 3, and 3 of 4, and the same happens in the case of the succeeding numbers, but they say 4 came from the first 2 and the indefinite 2, which makes it two 2's other than the them, from the 2 and the
for 2
;
—
2-itself; if not,
and one other 2
the 2-itself will be a part of 4 will be added. And similarly 2
[25] will consist of the i-itself and another 1; if this is so, the other element cannot be an
but
indefinite 2; for
it
generates one unit, not, as
the indefinite 2 does, a definite
2.
ideal 2 are generated at the
Again, besides the 3-itself and the 2-itself how can there be other 3's and 2's? And how
as the first holder of the theory said,
do they
bers, as they say '2, 3, 4'
for the units in the
same time, whether, from unequals (coming into being when these were [25] equalized) or in some other way since,
—
if
one unit
is
to be prior to the other,
it
will be
composed of these; for when there is one thing prior and another posterior, the resultant of these will be prior to one and prior also to the 2
posterior to the other.
1 -itself, and again a next after the second and next but one after the first 1, so the units must be prior to the numbers after which they are named when we count them; e.g. there will be a third unit in 2 before 3 exists, and a fourth
others and next after the third
which
is
—
a fifth in 3 before the numbers 4 and 5 none of these thinkers has [35] exist. said the units are inassociable in this way, but
and
—Now
according to their principles it is reasonable that they should be so even in this way, though
1081 b in truth it is impossible. For it is reasonable both that the units should have pri-
and posteriority if there is a first unit or and also that the 2's should if there is a first 2; for after the first it is reasonable and
and posterior units?
absurd and fictitious, and there cannot be a first 2 and then a 3-itself. Yet there must, if the 1 and the indefinite dyad are to be is
the elements. But it
the results are impossible,
if
also impossible that these are the gen-
is
erating principles. the units, then, are differentiated, each
If
[3°] Again, since the i-itself is first, and then there is a particular 1 which is first among the
consist of prior
[jo] All this
from each, these
results
and others similar
to
[55] these follow of necessity. But (3) if those in different numbers are differentiated, but
same number are alone undifferfrom one another, even so the difficulties that follow are no less. E.g. in the 10-itself 1082* there are ten units, and the 10 is composed both of them and of two 5's. But since the 10-itself is not any chance number nor composed of any chance 5's or, for that matter, units the units in this 10 must differ. For [5] if they do not differ, neither will the 5's of which the 10 consists differ; but since these differ, the units also will differ. But if they differ, will there be no other 5's in the 10 but only those in the
entiated
—
—
ority
these two, or will there be others? If there are
first 1,
there are, what them? For there is no other 10 in the 10 but itself. But it is actually necessary on their view that the 4 should
[5] necessary that there should be a second, if a second, a third, and so with the others
and
successively.
same time,
(And
to say both things at the
and another unit is second after the ideal 1, and that a 2 is first after it, is impossible.) But they make a first unit or 1, but not also a second and a third, and a first 2, but not also a second and a third. that a unit
is first
[10] Clearly, also, it is not possible, if all the units are inassociable, that there should be a
and a 3-itself; and so with the other numbers. For whether the units are undifferentiated or different each from each, number must be counted by addition, e.g. 2 by adding [75] another 1 to the one, 3 by adding another 1 to the two, and 4 similarly. This being so, numbers cannot be generated as they generate 2-itself
not, this
is
paradoxical; and
if
[jo] sort of 10 will consist of
not consist of any chance 2's; for the indefinite 2, as they say, received the definite 2 and made
two
2's; for its
nature was to double what
it
received.
[75] Again, as to the 2 being an entity apart its two units, and the 3 an entity apart its three units, how is this possible?
from from
Either by one's sharing in the other, as 'pale
man'
is
different
from
shares in these), or
of the other, as 'man'
and
'pale'
and 'man' (for
when one is
is
different
it
a differentia
from 'animal'
'two-footed'.
[20] Again, some things are one by contact, some by intermixture, some by position; none of which can belong to the units of which the 2
METAPHYSICS
614
or the 3 consists; but as two men are not a unity apart from both, so must it be with the
And
units.
their being indivisible will
the a
first
make
[25] no difference to them; for points too are indivisible, but yet a pair of them is nothing
1083«
But
2-itself.
and
Nor
this
not possible,
is
there
if
number. the Ideas be numbers. For
is
a second
will
particular point they are right
who
in this
claim that
get, that
it
follows that there are prior and
must be different, if there are to be 1 [25] Ideas; as has been said before. For the Form is unique; but if the units are not different, the 2's and the 3's also will not be different.
posterior
2's,
and similarly with the other num-
This
For
let
apart from the two.
But
we must
consequence also
this
not for-
the 4 be simultaneous; [3°] Y et these are prior to those in the 8, and as the 2 generated them, they generated the 4's bers.
the
2's in
in the 8-itself. Therefore
if
the
first
Idea, these 2's also will be Ideas of
And
the
same account
2
is
an
some kind.
applies to the units;
[35] f° r the units in the first 2 generate the four in 4, so that all the units come to be Ideas
and an Idea
composed
will be
of Ideas.
Clearly therefore those things also of which these posite,
happen
to be the Ideas will be comone might say that animals are
e.g.
composed of animals,
there are Ideas of
if
them.
1082 b In general, to differentiate the units in any way is an absurdity and a fiction; and by a
the units
is
all Forms will be parts of one Form. And with a view to their hypothesis their statements are right, but as a whole they are wrong; for their view is very destructive, since they will [55] admit that this question itself affords some difficulty whether, when we count and say '1, 2, 3,' we count by addition or by separate portions. But we do both; and so it is absurd to reason back from this problem to so
so
—
great a difference of essence.
1083* First of is
all
number but
which
especially that
of abstract units
—so
that
if
consists
one number
neither greater nor less than another,
is
equal to it; but things that are equal and in no wise differentiated we take to be the same when we are speaking of numbers. If not, not even the 2's
in
the
10-itself
it is
will be undifferentiated,
2'
'1,
and
and number must be
unequal
thus
ceed by adding to the given number; for if we [jo] do, neither will the numbers be generated from the indefinite dyad, nor can a number be an Idea; for then one Idea will be in another,
fiction I mean a forced statement made to suit a hypothesis. For neither in quantity nor in [5] quality do we see unit differing from unit,
either equal or
must say that —why they —we do not pro-
also the reason
when we count
8 all it is
the differentia of a
if it
well to determine
number
—and of
what
a unit,
has a differentia. Units must differ either
and neither
in quantity or in quality;
of these
seems to be possible. But number qua number differs in quantity.
And
if
the units also did
number would differ from number, though equal in number of units.
differ in quantity,
[5]
Again, are the
first
units greater or smaller,
and
[10] though they are equal; for what reason will the man who alleges that they are not
do the
differentiated be able to give?
Again, if every unit another unit makes two, a unit from the 2-itself and one from the 3-itself will make a 2. Now (a) this will consist of differentiated units; and (/3) will it be
can they differ in quality. For no attribute can [10] attach to them; for even to numbers quality is said to belong after quantity. Again, quality could not come to them either from the 1 or the dyad; for the former has no quality,
prior to the 3 or posterior ? It rather seems that [75] it must be prior; for one of the units is
and the latter gives quantity; for this what makes things to be many. If the
simultaneous with the 3, and the other is simultaneous with the 2. And we, for our part, suppose that in general 1 and 1, whether the things are equal or unequal, is 2, e.g. the good and the bad, or a man and a horse; but those who hold these views say that not even two units
[75] really otherwise, they should state this quite at the beginning and determine if pos-
+
are
ones increase or diminish? All
these are irrational suppositions.
sible,
But neither
entity
regarding the differentia of the unit,
must exist, and, they mean. it
failing this,
what
is
facts are
why
differentia
Evidently then, if the Ideas are numbers, the all be associable, nor can they be [20] inassociable in either of the two ways.
units cannot
2.
[20] If the
later
number
than that of the
of the 3-itself
2, this is
greater, clearly there
equal to the
2,
is
is
surprising; also a
so that this
is
not greater
and
number
if it is
in
it
not different from
But neither
is
the
way
in
which some others
speak about numbers correct. These are those 1
1081*5-17.
BOOK
1084*
CHAPTERS
XIII,
who do
7-8
615
number has no such nature as it separable set up for it. Again, does each unit come from the
not think there are Ideas, either without qualification or as identified with certain numbers, but think the objects of mathematics
evidently
and the numbers are the first of existing things, and the 1 -itself is the starting-point of
and the
paradoxical that there should be a 1 which is first of i's, as they say, but not a 2 [25] which is first of 2's, nor a 3 of 3's; for the
[25] neither does each thing contain all the elements, nor are the units without difference;
exist
them.
It is
same reasoning
applies to
with regard to number are poses mathematical
then, the facts
all. If,
number
and one sup-
so,
alone to
exist,
the
not the starting-point (for this sort of 1 [jo] must differ from the other units; and if this is so, there must also be a 2 which is first of 2's, and similarly with the other successive numbers). But if the 1 is the starting-point, the truth about the numbers must rather be what Plato used to say, and there must be a first 2 1
is
and the numbers must not be associable w tn one another. But if on the other hand [35] one supposes this, many impossible results, as we have said, 1 follow. But either this or the other must be the case, so that if neither is,
and
3,
i
number cannot 1083 b
It
is
third version
exist separately.
evident, also, is
the worst,
from
this that the
—the view
ideal
and
those
who make
small, equalized, or one
small, another
from the great? (a)
If
great
from the the latter,
the great and in another the contrary in its nature to the great. Again, how is it with the units in the
one there
for in
small,
which
is
is
3-itself ? One of them is an odd unit. But perhaps it is for this reason that they give i-itself the middle place in odd numbers, (b) But if [jo] each of the two units consists of both the
and the small, equalized, how will the 2, which is a single thing, consist of the great and the small? Or how will it differ from the unit? great
Again, the unit is prior to the 2; for when it is destroyed the 2 is destroyed. It must, then, be the Idea of an Idea since it is prior to an Idea, [35] and
it must have come into being before what, then? Not from the indefinite dyad, for its function was to double. Again, number must be either infinite or finite; for these thinkers think of number as capable of existing separately, so that it is not it.
From
1084a
mathematical number is the same. For two mistakes must then meet in the one opinion. [5] (1) Mathematical number cannot be of this sort, but the holder of this view has to spin it out by making suppositions peculiar to himself. And (2) he must also admit all the consequences that confront those who speak of
numbers is always odd or of an even number; in one way, when 1 operates on an even number, an odd number is produced; in
number in the sense The Pythagorean
[5] another way, when 2 operates, the numbers got from 1 by doubling are produced; in
.
of 'Forms'.
version in one
way
affords
fewer difficulties than those before named, but in another way has others peculiar to itself. [10] For not thinking of number as capable of existing separately removes many of the impossible consequences; but that bodies should be composed of numbers, and that this should be mathematical number, is impossible. For it is not true to speak of indivisible spatial magnitudes; and however much there might be magnitudes of this sort, units at least have not [75] magnitude; and how can a magnitude be
composed of indivisibles? But arithmetical number, at least, consists of units, while these thinkers identify
any as
number with
real things; at
rate they apply their propositions to bodies
if
they consisted of those numbers.
If,
then,
it is
necessary,
if
number
is
a
self-
[20] subsistent real thing, that it should exist one of these ways which have been men-
in
tioned, 1
Cf.
1
2
and
if it
cannot exist in any of these,
o8ob 37-1 083*
17.
2
! 080"* 1
5-b 36.
tives
possible that neither of those alterna-
should be true. Clearly
finite; for infinite
number
is
it
cannot be
neither
in-
odd nor
even, but the generation of the generation either of an
another way, when the odd numbers operate, the other even numbers are produced. Again, if every Idea is an Idea of something, and the
numbers are
Ideas, infinite
number
itself will
be an Idea of something, either of some sensible thing or of something else. Yet this is not possible in
view of their
reasonable in
thesis
any more than
itself, at least if
it is
they arrange the
Ideas as they do. [10] But if number is finite, how far does it go? With regard to this not only the fact but the reason should be stated. But if number goes
only up to 10, as some say, firstly the Forms will soon run short; e.g. if 3 is man-himself, what number will be the horse-itself ? The series [75] of the numbers which are the several things-themselves goes up to 10. It must, then, be one of the numbers within these limits; for is these that are substances and Ideas. Yet they will run short; for the various forms of animal will outnumber them. At the same time it
it
METAPHYSICS
6i6
way
the 3 is man-himself, the other 3's are so also (for those in identical [20] numbers are similar), so that there will is
clear that
if
bi an infinite
in this
number
and
of
numbers
Idea, each of the
men;
if each 3 is an will be man-himself,
men.
not, they will at least be
if
the smaller
number
And
if
part of the greater (be-
is
ing number of such a sort that the units in the associable), then if the 4-itself is an Idea of something, e.g. of 'horse' or of 'white', man will be a part of horse, if man is [25] 2. It is paradoxical also that there should be an Idea of 10, but not of 11, nor of the succeeding numbers. Again, there both are and come to be certain things of which there are no Forms; why, then, are there not Forms of infer that the Forms are not them also? causes. Again, it is paradoxical if the numberseries up to 10 is more of a real thing and a [50] Form than 10 itself. There is no genera-
same number are
We
and there
tion of the former as one thing,
At
least
—
is
exist separately,
—
number
is
one
or 3 or 2? Inascomposite, 1 is prior,
prior
1,
but inasmuch as the universal and the form is [5] prior, the number is prior; for each of the is
part of the
number
acts as
number form.
as
its
And
matter, and
in a sense the
right angle is prior to the acute, because it is determinate and in virtue of its definition; but in a sense the acute is prior, because it is a part and the right angle is divided into acute angles. [10] As matter, then, the acute angle and the element and the unit are prior, but in respect of the form and of the substance as expressed in the definition, the right angle, and the whole consisting of the matter and the form, are prior; for the concrete thing
is
nearer to the
form and to what is expressed in the definition, though in generation it is later. How then is 1
has been said, the right angle prior to the acute,
and each
is
is
thought
and the acute
to be
to the right,
one. Accordingly they
make
1
the
But this is impossible. For the universal is one as form or substance, while the element is one as a part or as [20] matter. For each of the two is in a sense one in truth each of the two units exists potentially (at least if the number is a unity and starting-point in both ways.
—
i.e. if different numbers conof differentiated units, as they say), but
not like a heap, sist
not in complete reality; and the cause of the fell into is that they were conducting their inquiry at the same time from the standpoint of mathematics and from that of
error they
[25] universal definitions, so that (1) from the
number can
might ask which
the
in time. In the starting-point? As
former standpoint they treated unity, their
;
units
1
first
principle, as a point; for the unit
is
a point
out of the smallest parts, as some others also have done. Therefore the unit becomes the matter of numbers and at the same time prior
e.g.
as the
is
the void, proportion, the odd,
rivatives
much
and the other
of
is
and the others of this kind within the decade. For some things, e.g. movement and rest, good and bad, they assign to the originative prin[35] ciples, and the others to the numbers. This for if the is why they identify the odd with 1 odd implied 3, how would 5 be odd? Again, spatial magnitudes and all such things are explained without going beyond a definite num1084 b ber; e.g. the first, the indivisible, line, then the 2, &c; these entities also extend only up to 10. if
definition
without position. They put things together
series.
Again,
in
which way, then,
they generate the de-
complete
—
one
work on the assumpnumbers up to 10 is a
the latter. But they try to tion that the series of
1085*
they say; but both the universal, and the particular or the element, are indivisible. But [75] they are starting-points in different ways, ble,
the starting-point? Because
it is
not
divisi-
to 2;
and again
posterior, 2 being treated as a
[30] whole, a unity, and a form. But (2) because they were seeking the universal they
which can be predicated of a number, as in this sense also a part of the number. But these characteristics cannot belong at the same time to the same thing. If the i-itself must be unitary (for it differs in nothing from other i's except that it is the starting-point), and the 2 is divisible but the unit is not, the unit must be liker the i-itself [35] than the 2 is. But if the unit is liker it, it must be liker to the unit than to the 2; therefore each of the units in 2 must be prior to the 2. But they deny this; at least they generate 1085 a the 2 first. Again, if the 2-itself is a unity and the 3-itself is one also, both form a 2. From what, then, is this 2 produced? treated the unity
not contact in numbers, but sucbetween the units between which there is nothing, e.g. between those in 2 or in [5] 3, one might ask whether these succeed the i-itself or not, and whether, of the terms that Since there
is
cession, viz.
succeed it, 2 or either of the units in 2 is prior. Similar difficulties occur with regard to the the line, classes of things posterior to number, the plane, and the solid. For some construct
—
BOOK
1086 a
and
these out of the species of the 'great
XIII,
CHAPTERS
small';
[10] e.g. lines from the 'long and short', planes from the 'broad and narrow', masses from the 'deep and shallow'; which are species of the 'great
and
small'.
And
the originative principle
of such things which answers to the
1
different
thinkers describe in different ways. And in [75] these also the impossibilities, the fictions, and the contradictions of all probability are seen to be innumerable. For (i) the geometrical classes are severed from one another, unless the principles of these are implied in one an-
other in such a
way
that the 'broad
and nar-
row' is also 'long and short' (but if this is so, the plane will be line and the solid a plane; again, how will angles and figures and such [20] things be explained?). And (ii) the same happens as in regard to number; for 'long and short', &c, are attributes of magnitude, but magnitude does not consist of these, any more than the line consists of 'straight and curved', or solids of 'smooth and rough'. (All these views share a difficulty which occurs with regard to species-of-a-genus, when one posits the universals, viz. whether it is [25] animal-itself or something other than animal-itself that is in the particular animal. True, if the universal is not separable from
no
sensible things, this will present
but
if
those
the
1
who
and the numbers are
difficulty;
separable, as
express these views say,
easy to solve the difficulty,
if
it
may
one
not apply
is
the words 'not easy' to the impossible. For
when we apprehend
the unity in
2,
or in gen-
[30] eral in a number, do we apprehend a thing-itself or something else?).
Some, then, generate spatial magnitudes from matter of this sort, others from the point and the point is thought by them to be not 1 but something like 1 and from other matter
—
—
like plurality,
[35]
which
but not identical with
principles
difficulties occur.
For
none the
if
less
the matter
is
617
number out
definite dyad.
of the one
and the
in-
For the one view generates num-
ber from the universally predicated plurality,
and not from
a particular plurality;
other generates
from a particular
it
and the
plurality,
but the first; for 2 is said to be a 'first plurality'. [10] Therefore there is practically no difference, but the same difficulties will follow, is it intermixture or position or blending or generation? and so on. Above all one might press the question 'if each unit is one, what does it come from?' Certainly each is not the one-itself. It must, then, come from the oneitself
and
plurality, or a part of plurality.
sible, for it is
from a part
is
a plurality
it
will be a plurality
unit will be divisible)
is
many
of plurality involves
objections; for (a) each of the parts indivisible (or
To
imposindivisible; and to generate it
[75] say that the unit
other
must be and the
and the elements
will
[20] not be the one and plurality; for the single units do not come from plurality and the one.
Again, (/3) the holder of this view does nothing but presuppose another number; for his plurality of indivisibles
we must
is
a
number. Again,
inquire, in view of this theory also,
whether the number is infinite or finite. For there was at first, as it seems, a plurality that [25] was itself finite, from which and from the one comes the finite number of units. And there
and
another plurality that
is
is
plurality-itself
which sort of plurality, then, is the element which co-operates with the one? One might inquire similarly about the point, i.e. the element out of which they make spatial magnitudes. For surely this is not the one and only point; at any rate, then, let them say out of what each of the other [jo] points is formed. Certainly not of some infinite plurality;
distance
-f-
the point-itself.
Nor
again can
it;
about
there be indivisible parts of a distance, as the
the
same
elements out of which the units are said to be
one, line
made are indivisible parts of plurality; for number consists of indivisibles, but spatial
and plane and solid will be the same; for from the same elements will come one and the same 1085 b thing. But if the matters are more than one, and there is one for the line and a second for the plane and another for the solid, they either are implied in one another or not, so that the same results will follow even so; for either the plane will not contain a line or
be a line. Again,
construct
8-9
it
will
magnitudes do not. All these objections, then, and others of the make it evident that number and
[55] sort spatial
magnitudes cannot
exist
things. Again, the discord about
apart from numbers be-
1086a tween the various versions it is
is a sign that the incorrectness of the alleged facts them-
selves that brings confusion into the theories.
how number
can consist of the one [5] and plurality, they make no attempt to explain; but however they express themselves, the same objections arise as confront those who
For those who make the objects of mathematics alone exist apart from sensible things, seeing the difficulty about the Forms and their [5] fictitiousness, abandoned ideal number and
METAPHYSICS
6i8 posited mathematical. But those
who wished
to
same time also numbers, but did not see, if one assumed these principles, how mathematical number was to exist apart from ideal, made ideal and mathematical number the same in words, since in fact
make
Forms
the
at the
—
[10] mathematical number has been destroyed; for they state hypotheses peculiar to themselves
and not those of mathematics. supposed that the Forms
Forms
numbers and
are
And
exist
he
who first
and that the
that the objects of
mathematics exist, naturally separated the two. Therefore it turns out that all of them are right in some respect, but on the whole not right. And they themselves confirm this, for their state[75] ments do not agree but conflict. The cause that their hypotheses
is
and
their principles are
And it is hard to make a good case out of bad materials, according to Epicharmus 'as false.
1
:
soon as
'tis
said,
'tis
seen to be wrong.'
But regarding numbers the questions we have raised and the conclusions we have reached are sufficient (for while he who is already convinced might be further convinced [20] by a longer discussion, one not yet convinced would not come any nearer to conviction); regarding the first principles and the first causes and elements, the views expressed by those who discuss only sensible substance have been partly stated in our works on na2 ture, and partly do not belong to the present inquiry; but the views of those who assert that [25]
there are other substances besides the
sensible must be considered next after those we have been mentioning. Since, then, some say that the Ideas and the numbers are such substances, and that the elements of these are elements and principles of real things, we must inquire regarding these what they say and in
what sense they say it. Those who posit numbers only, and [jo] mathematical, must be considered but as regards those
who
these later;
believe in the Ideas
one might survey at the same time their way of thinking and the difficulty into which they fall. For they at the same time make the Ideas universal and again treat them as separable and as individuals. That this is not possible has 3 [35] been argued before. The reason why those versal
who
described their substances as uni-
combined these two
one thing,
is
characteristics in
that they did not
make
substances
1
Fr. 14, Diels, Vorsokratiker. 1. 4-6; On the Heavens, in. 3-4; and Corruption, 1. 1 2
Physics,
3
in. 1003* 7-17.
On
Generation
1086 b
identical with sensible things. They thought that the particulars in the sensible world were
1086 b
in a state of flux and none of them remained, but that the universal was apart from these and something different. And Socrates gave the impulse to this theory, as we said in our earlier discussion, 4 by reason of his definitions, but he did not separate universals from individuals; and in this he thought rightly, in [5] not separating them. This is plain from the results; for without the universal it is not possible to get knowledge, but the separation is the cause of the objections that arise with regard to the Ideas. His successors, however, treating it as necessary, if there are to be any
substances besides the sensible and transient substances, that they must be separable, had no others, but gave separate existence to these uni-
[10] versally predicated substances, so that it followed that universals and individuals were almost the same sort of thing. This in itself, then,
would be one
difficulty in the
view
we
have mentioned. 10
Let us
now mention
a point
which presents
certain difficulty both to those
who
a
believe in
and to those who do not, and which was stated before, at the beginning, among the problems. If we do not suppose substances to be separate, and in the way in which the Ideas
[75]
individual things are said to be separate, we shall destroy substance in the sense in which
we understand
'substance'; but
substances to be separable,
how
if
we conceive we to con-
are
and their principles ? [20] If they are individual and not universal, (a) real things will be just of the same number
ceive their elements
as the elements, and (b) the elements will not be knowable. For (a) let the syllables in speech be substances, and their elements elements of substances; then there must be only one ba and [25] one of each of the syllables, since they are not universal and the same in form but each is one in number and a 'this' and not a kind possessed of a common name (and again they suppose that the 'just what a thing is' is in each case one). And if the syllables are unique, so too are the parts of which they consist; there will not, then, be more a's than one, nor more [30] than one of any of the other elements, on the same principle on which an identical syllable cannot exist in the plural number. But if this is so, there will not be other things existing besides the elements, but only the elements. 4 i78 b 17-30.
BOOK
1087 b
CHAPTERS 9-10— BOOK
XIII,
(b) Again, the elements will not be even knowable; for they are not universal, ana knowl1
edge
is
of universals. This is clear from demonand from definitions; for we do not
strations
conclude that this triangle has
its
angles equal
[55] to two right angles, unless every triangle has its angles equal to two right angles, nor that this man is an animal, unless every man is
an animal. But if the principles are universal, either the
1087 a substances composed
of
them
are also
or non-substance will be prior to substance; for the universal is not a substance, but the element or principle is universal, and universal,
the element or principle is prior to the things of which it is the principle or element. [5] All these difficulties follow naturally, when they make the Ideas out of elements and at the
same time claim that apart from the substances which have the same form there are Ideas, a single separate entity. But if, e.g. in the case of the elements of speech, the as and the £'s may quite well be many and there need be no aitself and ^-itself besides the many, there may
CHAPTER
XIV,
be, so far as this goes,
an
619
1
infinite
number
of
[10] similar syllables. The statement that all knowledge is universal, so that the principles of
things must also be universal and not separate substances, presents indeed, of all the points we have mentioned, the greatest difficulty, but yet the statement
in a sense true, although in a
is
For knowledge, like the know', means two things, of which one is potential and one actual. The potency, being, as matter, universal and indefinite, deals with the universal and indefinite; but the actuality, being definite, deals with a definite object, being a 'this', it deals with a 'this'. But per accidens sight sees universal colour, because [75] sense
verb
not.
it is
'to
which it sees is colour; and this individual a which the grammarian investigates is an a. For if the principles must be universal, what is derived from them must also be universal, as in demonstrations; and if this is so, there will be nothing capable i.e. no substance. But of separate existence evidently in a sense knowledge is universal, [25] and in a sense it is not. this individual colour
[20]
—
BOOK XIV
—matter
for the
One, and others making plu-
matter for the One. (The former generate numbers out of the dyad of the unequal, i.e. of the great and small, and the other thinker we have referred to generates them out of plurality, while according to both it is generated by the essence of the One.) For even the philosopher who says the unequal and the One are [10] the elements, and the unequal is a dyad rality
Regarding this kind of substance, what we have said must be taken as sufficient. All philosophers
make
the
first
principles contraries:
[50] as in natural things, so also in the case of unchangeable substances. But since there can-
not be anything prior to the first principle of things, the principle cannot be the principle
all
something else. To white is a principle, not qua anything else but qua
and yet be an suggest this first
is
attribute of
like saying that the
white, but yet that
it is
predicable of a subject,
being white presupposes its [55] being something else; this is absurd, for then that subject will be prior. But all things which are generated from their contraries involve an i.e.
that
its
underlying subject; a subject, then, must be present in the case of contraries, if anywhere. 1087 b All contraries, then, are always predi-
and none can exist apart, but appearances suggest that there is nothing contrary to substance, argument confirms
cable of a subject, just as
this. all
No
contrary, then,
is
the
first
things in the full sense; the
principle of
first
principle
something different. But these thinkers make one of the con[5] traries matter, some making the unequal
is
which they take
to be the essence of plurality
composed of the great and small, treats the unequal, or the great and the small, as being one, and does not draw the distinction that they are one in definition, but not in number. But they do not describe rightly even the principles which they call elements, for some name the great and the small with the One and treat [75] these three as elements of numbers, two being matter, one the form; while others name the many and few, because the great and the small are more appropriate in their nature to magnitude than to number; and others name rather the universal character common — which exceeds and that which
to these
'that
ceeded'.
None
is
ex-
of these varieties of opinion
makes any difference to speak some of the consequences; they [20] abstract objections, which
of, in
view of
affect only the
these thinkers take care to avoid because the demonstrations they themselves offer are abstract, with this
—
METAPHYSICS
620
exception, that if the exceeding and the exceeded are the principles, and not the great and the small, consistency requires that num-
come from the elements before 2 number is more universal than 2, as exceeding and the exceeded are more uni-
ber should
does; for the
[25] versal than the great and the small. But as is, they say one of these things but do not say the other. Others oppose the different and it
the other to the One, ity to
the One. But
consist of contraries,
and others oppose if,
plural-
as they claim, things
and
to the
One
either
nothing contrary, or if there is to be anything it is plurality, and the unequal is contrary to the equal, and the different to the same, there
is
[50 J and the other to the thing itself, those who oppose the One to plurality have most claim to plausibility, but even their view is inadequate, for the One would on their view be a few; for plurality
is
opposed to fewness, and the many
to the few.
'The one' evidently means a measure. And in every case there is some underlying thing with [55] a distinct nature of its own, e.g. in the scale a quarter-tone, in spatial magnitude a finger or a foot or something of the sort, in
rhythms a beat or a syllable; and similarly in 1088 a gravity it is a definite weight; and in the same way in all cases, in qualities a quality, in quantities a quantity (and the measure is indivisible, in the former case in kind, and in the latter to the sense); which implies that the one is not in itself the substance of anything.
And
this
is
reasonable; for 'the one'
means the
[5] measure of some plurality, and 'number' means a measured plurality and a plurality of measures. (Thus it is natural that one is not a number; for the measure is not measures, but both the measure and the one are startingpoints.) The measure must always be some identical thing predicable of all the things it measures, e.g. if the things are horses, the measure is 'horse', and if they are men, 'man'. If [10] they are a man, a horse, and a god, the measure is perhaps 'living being', and the number of them will be a number of living beings. If the things are 'man' and 'pale' and 'walking', these will scarcely have a number, because all belong to a subject which is one and the same in number, yet the number of these will be a number of 'kinds' or of some such term.
Those who treat the unequal as one thing, and the dyad as an indefinite compound of great and small, say what is very far from being probable or possible. For (a) these are
1088 b
modifications and accidents, rather than subnumbers and magnitudes the many
—
strata, of
and few of number, and the great and small of magnitude like even and odd, smooth and [20] rough, straight and curved. Again, (b) apart from this mistake, the great and the small, and so on, must be relative to something; but what is relative is least of all things a kind of entity or substance, and is posterior to quality and quantity; and the relative is an accident [25] of quantity, as was said, not its matter, since something with a distinct nature of its own must serve as matter both to the relative in general and to its parts and kinds. For there
—
nothing either great or small, many or few, something else, which without having a nature of its own is many or few, great or small, or relative to something is
or, in general, relative to
A
else.
sign that the relative
is
least of all a
[30] substance and a real thing is the fact that it alone has no proper generation or destruction or movement, as in respect of quantity is increase and diminution, in respect of quality alteration, in respect of place locomo-
there
tion, in respect of substance
simple generation
and destruction. In respect of relation there is no proper change; for, without changing, a thing will be now greater and now less or [35] equal, if that with which it is compared 1088 b has changed in quantity. And (c) the matter of each thing, and therefore of substance, must be that which is potentially of the nature in question; but the relative is neither potentially nor actually substance. It is strange, then, or rather impossible, to make not-substance an element in,
and prior
to,
substance;
for all the categories are posterior to substance.
Again, (d) elements are not predicated of the things of which they are elements, but many [5] and few are predicated both apart and to-
gether of number, and long and short of the line, and both broad and narrow apply to the plane. If there is a plurality, then, of which the one term, viz. few, is always predicated, e.g. 2
(which cannot be many, for if it were many, 1 would be few), there must be also one which is [10] absolutely many, e.g. 10 is many (if there is no number which is greater than 10), or 10,000.
How then, in view of this, can number
consist of
few and many? Either both ought
to be predicated of
it,
or neither; but in fact
only the one or the other
is
predicated.
[75]
We
must inquire
generally,
whether eternal
[75] things can consist of elements.
If
they do,
BOOK
1089 b
CHAPTERS
XIV,
1-2
621
what
sort of 'one', then, are all the
they will have matter; for everything that consists of elements is composite. Since, then, even
categories),
which it had it come into being, have come into being, and since everything comes to be what it comes to be out of that which is it potentially (for it could not have come to be out of that which had not this capacity, nor could it consist of such elements), and since the potential can be this being so, how[20] either actual or not,
[10] not to be? Is it the substances that are one, or the affections and similarly the other so that the categories as well, or all together
if
a thing exists for ever, out of that of consists it would necessarily also, if
—
number
ever everlasting
or anything else that
must be capable of not existing, just as that which is any number of years old is as capable of not existing as that which is a has matter
is, it
day old;
this
if
is
capable of not existing, so
is
things that are,
non-being
if
is
to be supposed
—
much' and the other categories that indicate each some one class of being will all be one? But it is strange, or rather impossible, that the coming into play 'this'
and the
and the
'such'
'so
of a single thing should bring of that
which
much', part a
'so
it
about that part
a 'this', part a 'such', part a
is is
'here'.
[75] Secondly, of what sort of non-being and being do the things that are consist? For 'non-
being' also has
and
many
senses, since 'being' has;
man' means not being a
'not being a
cer-
which has lasted for a time so long that it has no limit. They cannot, then, be eternal, since that which is capable of not existing is not eternal, as we had occasion to show in [25] another context. If that which we are now saying is true universally that no suband if stance is eternal unless it is actuality
tain substance, 'not being straight' not being
the elements are matter that underlies substance, no eternal substance can have elements
that are, the false
that
1
—
—
it, of which it consists. There are some who describe the element which acts with the One as an indefinite dyad, and object to 'the unequal', reasonably enough,
present in
[30] because of the ensuing difficulties; but they have got rid only of those objections which inevitably arise from the treatment of the un-
equal,
which
i.e.
the relative, as an element; those from this opinion must con-
arise apart
front even these thinkers, whether it is ideal number, or mathematical, that they construct
of a certain quality, 'not being three cubits long' not being of a certain quantity.
What
being and non-being, then, by their
sort of
union pluralize the things that are? This 3 [20] thinker means by the non-being the union of which with being pluralizes the things
why
and the character of
falsity.
used to be said that we must assume something that is false, as geometers assume the line which is not a foot long to be a foot long. But this cannot be so. For neither do geometers assume anything false (for the enunciation is extraneous to the inference), nor is it [25] non-being in this sense that the things that are are generated from or resolved into. But since 'non-being' taken in its various cases has
This
as
is
also
many
it
and beand so is
senses as there are categories,
sides this the false
the potential,
it
is
is
man from
said not to be,
from
this that
generation
the fact that they framed the difficulty in an obsolete form. For they thought that all things
which is not man but [30] potentially man, and white from that which is not white but potentially white, and this whether it is some one thing that is generated or many.
would be one (viz. Being itself), if one did not join issue with and refute the saying of
sense
Parmenides: 2
things that are
proceeds,
out of those elements. [35] There 1089 a into
are
many causes which led them off
these explanations,
and
especially
that are
lines
'For never will this be proved, that things 7 that are not are.
They thought
it
necessary to prove that that
—
But,
—
first, if
'being' has
means sometimes is
many
senses (for
it
substance, sometimes that
it
of a certain quality, sometimes that
certain quantity, 1
Cf. ix, io5ob 7
2
Fr. 7 .
fif.;
and
it is
of a
at other times the other
On the Heavens, 1.
12.
question evidently of
'the
and
is,
bodies.
how
being, in the
many; for the generated are numbers and
substances',
Now
it is
is
strange to inquire
how
which is not is; for only thus of that which is and something else could the things that are be composed, if they are many. [5]
The
that
being in the sense of the 'what' is many, [35] and not how either qualities or quantities
many. For surely the indefinite dyad or and the small' is not a reason why there should be two kinds of white or many 1089 b colours or flavours or shapes; for then these also would be numbers and units. But if they had attacked these other categories, they would have seen the cause of the plurality in substances also; for the same thing or someare
'the great
3
Plato;
cf.
Sophist, 237, 240.
METAPHYSICS
622
thing analogous is the cause. This aberration is the reason also why in seeking the opposite [5] of being and the one, from which with being and the one the things that are proceed, they posited the relative term (i.e. the unequal), which is neither the contrary nor the contradictory of these, and is one kind of being as 'what' and quality also are. They should have asked this question also, how relative terms are many and not one. But as it is, they inquire how there are many units [10] besides the first 1, but do not go on to inquire how there are many unequals besides the unequal. Yet they use them and speak of
and small, many and few (from which proceed numbers), long and short (from which proceeds the line), broad and narrow (from which proceeds the plane), deep and shallow (from which proceed solids); and they speak great
more kinds
of yet
of relative term.
why
the reason, then,
there
What
is
a plurality of
is
these? necessary, then, as
It is
[75]
we
say, to pre-
suppose for each thing that which is it potentially; and the holder of these views further
what
declared 'this'
—
and
that
is
which
a substance but
viz. that
it is
is
the relative (as
'the qualitative'),
which
potentially a
is
not in if
itself being he had said
was much more necessary, as we said, if he was inquiring how beings are many, not to inquire about those in the same category how 1
it
—
many
substances or
many
qualities
how
beings as a whole are many; for some some modifications, some relations. In the categories other than substance there is yet another problem involved in the [25] existence of plurality. Since they are not
but
are substances,
separable tities
from substances,
many
are
becomes and
is
and quansubstratum
qualities
just because their
many;
yet there ought to be a
matter for each category; only
it
cannot be
separable from substances. But in the case of 'thises', it is possible to explain how the 'this' is
many
things, unless a thing
[50] as both a 'this' The difficulty arising
and the 'what' whence or how
visible. If, then, the quantitative
are different,
we
are not told
1090 a the 'what' is many; but if any one says they are the same, he has to face many inconsistencies.
One might fix one's attention also on the question, regarding the numbers, what justifies the belief that they exist. To the believer in Ideas they provide
some
sort of cause for ex-
[5] isting things, since each number is an Idea, and the Idea is to other things somehow or
other the cause of their being; for let this supposition be granted them. But as for him who
does not hold this view because he sees the inherent objections to the Ideas (so that it is not for this reason that he posits numbers), but
who
mathematical number,
posits
why must
[10] we believe his statement that such number exists, and of what use is such number to other things? Neither does he who says it ex-
maintain that it is the cause of anything (he rather says it is a thing existing by itself), nor is it observed to be the cause of anything; for the theorems of arithmeticians will all be [75] found true even of sensible things, as was ists
said before.
2
neither potentially
is
the one or being, nor the negation of the one [20] nor of being, but one among beings. And
there are
1090*
iS5] quantity, and so does the 'unit', unless it means a measure or the quantitatively indi-
is
to be treated
and a general character. from the facts about sub-
As
for those, then,
exist
and
to be
who
suppose the Ideas to
numbers, by their assumption
in virtue of the
method
of setting out each
—
term apart from its instances of the unity of each general term they try at least to explain
somehow why number must
exist.
Since their
reasons, however, are neither conclusive nor in
themselves possible, one must not, for these reasons at
least, assert
the existence of number.
[20] Again, the Pythagoreans, because they saw many attributes of numbers belonging to sensible bodies, supposed real things to be
bers
—not
num-
separable numbers, however,
but
which real things consist. But why? Because the attributes of numbers are present in a musical scale and in the heavens and in
numbers
of
[25] many other things. Those, however, who say that mathematical number alone exists
if
the
'this'
cannot according to their hypotheses say anything of this sort, but it used to be urged that these sensible things could not be the subject of the sciences. But we maintain that they are,
are not the same,
we
are not told
as
stances
many
is
rather this,
how
there are actually
substances and not one.
and the quantitative how and why the things that are are many, but how quantities are many. For all 'number' means a But further,
la
34-
we
said before.
objects of
3
And
it
is
evident that the
mathematics do not
2
Cf. xiii.
3, esp.
3
Cf. xiii.
3.
io77 b 17-22.
exist apart; for
BOOK
1091 a
XIV,
CHAPTERS
they existed apart their attributes would not the [50] have been present in bodies. Pythagoreans in this point are open to no obif
Now
but in that they construct natural bodies out of numbers, things that have lightness and weight out of things that have not weight or lightness, they seem to speak of another heaven and other bodies, not of the sensijection;
[55] ble. But those who make number separaassume that it both exists and is separable
2-3
623
things? These contribute nothing, as the objects of mathematics contribute nothing. But
any theorem true of them, unless change the objects of mathematics and invent doctrines of our own. But it is not [jo] hard to assume any random hypotheses and spin out a long string of conclusions. These thinkers, then, are wrong in this way, in wanting to unite the objects of mathematics with not even
is
we want
to
And
who
two
ble
the Ideas.
because the axioms would not be true of sensible things, while the statements of mathematics
kinds of number, that of the Forms and that which is mathematical, neither have said nor can say how mathematical number is to exist and of what it is to consist. For they place it
are true
and
and
'greet the soul';
similarly with
the spatial magnitudes of mathematics.
1090 b
It
is
evident, then, both that the rival theory
and that the diffinow, why if numbers are
will say the contrary of this,
culty in
we
1
raised just
no way present
in sensible things their at-
tributes are present in sensible things, has to be
solved by those
who
hold these views.
[5] There are some who, because the point is the limit and extreme of the line, the line of the plane, and the plane of the solid, think there must be real things of this sort. We must therefore examine this argument too, and see whether it is not remarkably weak. For (i) ex-
tremes are not substances, but rather all these [10] things are limits. For even walking, and movement in general, has a limit, so that on their theory this will be a 'this' and a substance. But that is absurd. Not but what (ii) even if they are substances, they will all be the substances of the sensible things in this world; for
is
it
Why
to these that the
argument applied.
then should they be capable of existing
apart ?
Again, if we are not too easily satisfied, we may, regarding all number and the objects of mathematics, press this difficulty, that they con[75] tribute nothing to one another, the prior to the posterior; for if number did not exist,
none the those
less spatial
who maintain
magnitudes would
exist for
the existence of the objects
and if spatial magnitudes and sensible bodies would
of mathematics only,
did not exist.
exist, soul
But the observed
facts
show
that nature
[20] is not a series of episodes, like a bad tragedy. As for the believers in the Ideas, this
them; for they construct spatial magnitudes out of matter and number, lines
difficulty misses
out of the number 2, planes doubtless out of out of 4, or they use other numbers,
3, solids
—
which makes no difference. But will these magnitudes be Ideas, or what is their manner of [25] existence, and what do they contribute to la29.
those
first
posited
[35] between ideal and sensible number. If it consists of the great and small, it will be the same as the other ideal number (he (i)
—
makes
—
magnitudes out of some other small and great). And if (ii) he names some 1091 a other element, he will be making his spatial
elements rather many. And if the principle of each of the two kinds of number is a 1, unity will be something common to these, and we must inquire how the one is these many things, while at the same time number, according to him, cannot be generated except from one and an indefinite dyad. [5] All this is absurd, and conflicts both with itself and with the probabilities, and we seem to see in it Simonides' 'long rigmarole' 2 ; for the long rigmarole comes into play, like those of slaves, when men have nothing sound to say. And the very elements the great and the small seem to cry out against the violence [10] that is done to them; for they cannot in any way generate numbers other than those got from 1 by doubling. It is strange also to attribute generation to
—
—
things that are eternal, or rather this the things that are impossible.
is
one of
There need be
no doubt whether the Pythagoreans attribute [75] generation to them or not; for they say plainly that when the one had been constructed, whether out of planes or of surface or of seed or of elements which they cannot eximmediately the nearest part of the unand limited by the limit. But since they are constructing a world and wish to speak the language of natural science, it is fair to make some examination of their physical theories, but to let them press,
limited began to be constrained
[20] off from the present inquiry; for we are investigating the principles at work in un-
changeable things, so that it is numbers of this kind whose genesis we must study. 2
Simonides Ceius, Fr. 189. Bergk.
METAPHYSICS
624
1092 s
and most
self-sufficient this
These thinkers say there is no generation of odd number, which evidently implies that there is generation of the even; and some present the even as produced first from unequals when these are the great and the small [25] equalized. The inequality, then, must bethe
—
—
long to them before they are equalized. If they had always been equalized, they would not have been unequal before; for there is nothing before that which is always. Therefore evidently
they are not giving their account of the gen-
eration of
numbers merely
to assist contempla-
tion of their nature.
A
and a reproach to any one who [jo] finds it no difficulty, are contained in the question how the elements and the principles are related to the good and the beautiful; the difficulty is this, whether any of the elements is such a thing as we mean by the good itself and the best, or this is not so, but these are later difficulty,
than the elements. The theologians with some thinkers of the presto] ent day, who answer the question in the negative, and say that both the good and the beautiful appear in the nature of things only when that nature has made some progress. (This they do to avoid a real objection which in origin
seem
to agree
confronts those
who
say, as
some
do, that the
1091 b one is a first principle. The objection arises not from their ascribing goodness to the first principle as an attribute, but from their making the one a principle and a principle in the sense of an element and generating number from the one.) The old poets agree with this inasmuch as they say that not those who [5] are first in time, e.g. Night and Heaven or Chaos or Ocean, reign and rule, but Zeus. These poets, however, are led to speak thus
—
—
only because they think of the rulers of the world as changing; for those of them who combine the two characters in that they do not use mythical language throughout, e.g. Pherecydes [10] and some others, make the original generating agent the Best, and so do the Magi, and
some of the later sages also, e.g. both Empedocles and Anaxagoras, of whom one made love an element, and the other made reason a principle.
Of
those
who maintain
of the unchangeable substances
the existence
some
very quality
—
—
self-
and self-maintenance belongs primarily in some other way than as a good. But indeed it can be for no other reason indesufficiency
than because its nagood. Therefore to say that the first [20] principle is good is probably correct; but that this principle should be the One or, if not that, at least an element, and an element of structible or self-sufficient
ture
is
numbers,
impossible. Powerful objections
is
avoid which some have given up the theory (viz. those who agree that the One is a first principle and element, but only of mathematical number). For on this view all the units arise, to
[25] become identical with species of good, and there is a great profusion of goods. Again, if the Forms are numbers, all the Forms are identical with species of good. But let a man assume Ideas of anything he pleases. If these are Ideas only of goods, the Ideas will not be substances; but if the Ideas are also Ideas of substances, all animals and plants and all indi-
viduals that share in Ideas will be good, [jo] These absurdities follow, and it also follows that the contrary element, whether it is i.e. the great and (Hence one thinker avoided attaching the good to the One, because it would necessarily follow, since generation is from contraries, that badness is the
plurality or the unequal,
small,
the bad-itself.
is
fundamental nature of plurality; while others [35] sa Y inequality follows, then, that
is
all
—the One
the nature of the bad.)
It
things partake of the bad
itself, and that numbers more undiluted form than 1092a spatial magnitudes, and that the bad is the space in which the good is realized, and that it partakes in and desires that which tends
except one
partake of
to destroy trary.
that
for contrary tends to destroy con-
it;
And
if,
which
actual fire
in a
it
is is
bad will be
as
we were
saying, the matter
is
potentially each thing, e.g. that of
that
which
is
potentially
fire,
the
just the potentially good.
[5] All these objections, then, follow, partly because they make every principle an element, partly because they make contraries principles, partly because they make the One a principle, partly because they treat the numbers as the first substances, and as capable of existing apart,
and
as
Forms.
say the
One
itself is the good itself; but they thought substance lay mainly in its unity. [75] This, then, is the problem, which of the
its
—
two ways strange
if
of speaking
is
which
is
to that
If,
then,
it is
equally impossible not to put the
would be
good among the first principles and to put it among them in this way, evidently the prin-
primary and eternal
[10] ciples are not being correctly described,
right. It
BOOK
1092 b nor are the
first
substances.
Nor
XIV,
does any one
conceive the matter correctly if he compares the principles of the universe to that of animals
and
plants,
on the ground that the more comcomes from the indefinite and inwhich is what leads this thinker to
plete always
complete
—
say that this
is
also true of the first principles of
reality, so that the
One
[75] existing thing. This in this world of animals ciples it is
not
a
itself is is
not even an
incorrect, for
and plants the
pound
the contrary destroys 1
it,
e.g. 'strife' de-
should not; for
not to that that it is contrary). Once more, it has not been determined at all in which way numbers are the causes of subwhether (1) as boundstances and of being
first.
out of place, also, to generate place simultaneously with the mathematical solids (for
and
hence they are separate in place; but mathe[20] matical objects are nowhere), and to say that they must be somewhere, but not say what kind of thing their place is.
Those who say that existing things come from elements and that the first of existing things are the numbers, should have first distinguished the senses in which one thing comes from another, and then said in which sense number comes from its first principles. By intermixture ? But ( 1 ) not everything is [25] capable of intermixture, and (2) that which is produced by it is different from its elements, and on this view the one will not remain separate or a distinct entity; but they want it to be so. By juxtaposition, like a syllable? But then (1) the elements must have position; and (2)
who
thinks of number will be able to think of the unity and the plurality apart; number then will be this a unit and plurality, or the
he
one contrary the compound is or has come to Again, why in the world do the other things that come from contraries, or that have contraries, perish (even when all of the contrary is used to produce them), while number [5] does not? Nothing is said about this. Yet whether present or not present in the combe.
prin-
from which these come are complete; for that produces a man, and the seed is
peculiar to the individual things,
625
stroys the 'mixture'
man
is
4-6
even
It is
place
CHAPTERS
—
one and the unequal. Again, coming from certain things means in one sense that these are still to be found in the product, and in another that they are not; in [30] which sense does number come from
(yet
it
—
(as points are of spatial
aries
magnitudes).
[10] This is how Eurytus decided what was the number of what (e.g. one of man and an-
other of horse), viz. by imitating the figures of living things with pebbles, as some people bring numbers into the forms of triangle and
Or (2) is it because harmony is a ratio [75] of numbers, and so is man and everything else? But how are the attributes white square.
—
—
and sweet and hot numbers? Evidently it is not the numbers that are the essence or the causes of the form; for the ratio
while the number
is
is
the essence,
the matter. E.g. the es-
is number only in this way, 'three parts of fire and two of earth'. 2 And a number, whatever number it is, is al-
sence of flesh or bone
ways
a
number
of certain things, either of
parts of fire or earth or of units; but the es-
[20] sence thing to so
is
that there
much
is
so
much
of one
of another in the mixture;
and this is no longer a number but a ratio of mixture of numbers, whether these are corporeal or of any other kind. Number, then, whether it be number in gen-
number which consists of abstract neither the cause as agent, nor the mat-
eral or the
units, ter,
is
nor the ratio and form of things. Nor, of the final cause.
[25] course,
is it
ated can
One might
also raise the question
ent in
good
Only things that are genercome from elements which are presthem. Does number come, then, from its
it
is
these elements?
elements as from seed? But nothing can be excreted from that it
come from
its
which
contrary,
is
its
indivisible.
Does
contrary not per-
But all things that come in this way from something else which does per[35] sist. Since, then, one thinker places the 1 as contrary to plurality, and another places it 1092 b as contrary to the unequal, treating the 1 as equal, number must be being treated as coming from contraries. There is, then, something else that persists, from which and from sisting?
come
also
is
what the from numbers because expressible by a number,
that things get
their composition
is
by one which is an odd number. For in either
by honey-water is no more wholesome if it is mixed in the proportion of three times three, but it would do more good if it were in no particular ratio but well diluted than if it were numerically expressible [30] but strong. Again, the ratios of mixtures are expressed by the adding of numbers, not 1
Cf. Empedocles, Fr. 17.
2
Cf. Empedocles, Fr. 96.
easily calculable or fact
METAPHYSICS
626 by mere numbers;
e.g.
it is
'three parts to two',
not 'three times two'. For in any multiplication the genus of the things multiplied must be the same; therefore the product 1x2x3 must be measurable by 1, and 4x5x6 by 4, and therefore
products into which the same factor enters must be measurable by that factor. The number of fire, then, cannot be 2x5x3x6, and at the same time that of water 2x3. 1093* If all things must share in number, it must follow that many things are the same, and the same number must belong to one thing all
[55]
to another. Is number the cause, then, and does the thing exist because of its number, or is this not certain? E.g. the motions of the sun [5] have a number, and again those of the moon, yes, and the life and prime of each
and
—
1093 b
These people are like the old-fashioned Homeric scholars, who see small resemblances but neglect great ones.
Some
say that there are
many
such cases, e.g. that the middle strings [50] are represented by nine and eight, and that the epic verse has seventeen syllables, which is equal in number to the two strings,
and that the scansion is, in the right half of 1093 b the line nine syllables, and in the left eight.
And
letters
from alpha
they say that the distance in the to omega is equal to that from the lowest note of the flute to the highest, and that the number of this note is equal to [5] that of the whole choir of heaven. It may be suspected that no one could find difficulty either in stating such analogies or in finding them in eternal things, since they can be found
some of these some cubes, and some equal, others double? There is no reason why they should not, and indeed they must move within these limits, since all things were assumed to share in number. And it was assumed that things that differed might fall under the [10] same number. Therefore if the same number had belonged to certain things, these would have been the same as one another, since they would have had the same form of number; e.g. sun and moon would have been the same. But why need these numbers be causes ? There
even in perishable things. But the lauded characteristics of numbers, and the contraries of these, and generally the mathematical relations, as some describe them,
are seven vowels, the scale consists of seven
particular kind of
animal.
Why,
numbers be
then, should not
squares,
strings, the Pleiades are seven, at seven
lose their teeth (at least
some
do,
animals
though some
[75] do not), and the champions who fought against Thebes were seven. Is it then because the number is the kind of number it is, that the champions were seven or the Pleiad consists
Surely the champions were seven because there were seven gates or for some other reason, and the Pleiad we count as seven, as we count the Bear as twelve, while other peoples count more stars in both. Nay, of seven stars?
E, ^, and Z are concords and that because there are three concords, the double consonants also are three. [20] they even say that
They
quite neglect the fact that there might be
making them
causes of nature, seem,
when we
[10] inspect them in this way, to vanish; for none of them is a cause in any of the senses that have been distinguished in reference to 1
In a sense, however, they plain that goodness belongs to numbers, and that the odd, the straight, the square, the
first
make
principles.
it
the potencies of certain numbers, are in the of the beautiful. For the seasons and a
column [75]
number go
together;
and
the other agreements that they collect
from the theorems of mathematics all have meaning. Hence they are like coincidences. For they are accidents, but the things that agree are all appropriate to one another, and one by analogy. For in each category of being an analogous term is found as the straight is this
—
[20] in length, so is the level in surface, perhaps the odd in number, and the white in colour.
Again,
it is
not the ideal numbers that are
phenomena and the like numbers differ from one an-
the causes of musical (for equal ideal
other in form; for even the units do); so that we need not assume Ideas for this reason at
a thousand such letters; for one symbol might
least.
be assigned to TP. But if they say that each of these three is equal to two of the other letters, and no other is so, and if the cause is that
These, then, are the results of the theory, and [2$] yet more might be brought together. The fact that our opponnts have much trouble with
there are three parts of the
mouth and one each applied to sigma, it is for this reason that there are only three, not because [25] the concords are three; since as a matter of fact the concords are more than three, but of double consonants there cannot be more.
the generation of
letter is in
make
numbers and can
in
no way
a system of them, seems to indicate that the objects of mathematics are not separable from sensible things, as some say, and that
they are not the l
Cf.V. 1,2.
first principles.
ON THE SOUL
CONTENTS: ON THE SOUL I
BERLIN NOS. i.
The
2.
The
dignity, usefulness,
and
402 a
diffi-
I
culty of Psychology
12. d 403 20
opinions of early thinkers
Refutation of the view which as-
4.
The
movement to the soul harmony
BOOK 1-2.
soul not
moved with
non-local
(4o8 a 34~4o8 b 29) The soul not a self-moving 409b 18) 5. 5.
The
soul
movement
3.
number (4o8 b 30-
not composed of
s1
409 31
elements (409 b 19-41 i a 7) The soul not present in all things (411* 7-23)
The unity
1.
6.
The double operation of mind The practical mind, and the differ-
8.
412*1
9.
"
10.
4.
The The
414a 27 415a 14
5.
Sense-perception
6.
The
faculties of the soul
nutritive faculty
different kinds of sensible
4i6 b 32 4i8 a 6
Sight and
object
i
Problems about the motive faculty
432 a 15
The
liv-
a 433 8
relations of the facul-
b 433 3i a 434 23
cause of the
11.
{Continued)
12.
The mutual
13.
629
43i a
and the contemplative 431° 20
ties
4i8 a 26
it
43o a 26
Comparison of mind with sense and with imagination
of its
427 s1 16
movement
of
ing things
object 7.
425b 11
429 a 10 43o a 10
mind mind
Active
ence between
Second definition of soul
3.
Thinking, perceiving, and imagining distinguished (427 s i7~427b 26) Imagination (427b 27-429** 9) Passive
7.
4i3 a
2.
424° 20
of the external
5.
II
First definition of soul
The number
4.
of the soul (41 i a 24-41 i b 30)
BOOK
424 a 16
III
senses (424 b 20-2. 426 b 7) 2. Common sense (426 b 8~427 a 16)
(407b 27- o8 a 34) 4
The
422 a 8 422 b 17
General characteristics of the ex-
405b 32 407b 27
soul not a
42i a 6
ternal senses
about the soul 3.
signs
4i9b 3
Hearing and its object 9. Smell and its object 10. Taste and its object n. Touch and its object 8.
BOOK
of soul,
and
their fitness for the conditions
life
(Continued)
435
a
n
ON THE SOUL BOOK
I
no doubt, it is necessary to determine which of the summa genera soul lies, what
First,
in
402 a Holding of any kind
we do
as
prized, one kind of its
that,
while knowledge
honoured and
a thing to be
is
may, either by reason of and
it
greater exactness or of a higher dignity
greater wonderfulness in its objects, be more honourable and precious than another, on both accounts we should naturally be led to place in
the front rank the study of the soul. The knowledge of the soul admittedly contributes [5] greatly to the advance of truth in general,
and, above
all,
to
our understanding of Nature,
in
some
for the soul
is
animal
Our aim
stand,
life.
first its essential
properties; of these
sense the principle of
is
nature,
some
and under-
to grasp
and secondly
its
are taught to be af-
fections proper to the soul
itself,
while others
are considered to attach to the animal
owing
within it of soul. attain any assured knowledge about
to the presence
To
[10]
the soul
is
the world.
presents
one of the most difficult things in the form of question which here
As
itself, viz.
the question
recurs in other fields,
there
was some
it
single
'What
is
it?',
is
hesitations
we begin
still
tion
is
402 b
meth-
form the starting-points must be different, as e.g. bers and surfaces.
—
with what facts For the facts which
beset us
the inquiry ?
difficulties
in different subjects
in the case of
num-
Note: The bold face numbers and letters are approximate indications of the pages and columns of the standard Berlin Greek text; the bracketed numbers, of the lines in the Greek text; they are here assigned as they are assigned in the Oxford translation. 63'
Our answer
it
not
to this ques-
of the greatest importance.
We
must consider
also whether soul is without parts, and whether it is everywhere homogeneous or not; and if not homogeneous, whether its various forms are divisible or
is
different specifically or generically:
up
to the
who
have discussed and investigated soul seem to have confined thempresent time those [5] selves to the
human
soul.
ful not to ignore the question
We must
be care-
whether soul can
be defined in a single unambiguous formula, as is the case with animal, or whether we must not give a separate formula for each sort of it, as we do for horse, dog, man, god (in the latter
—and so too every —being treated
case the 'universal' animal
other
'common
predicate'
Further,
of inquiry ap-
some other known method,
shall
to the class of potential existents, or is
rather an actuality?
method
for derived properties the single
and
remaining kinds of predicates which we have [25] distinguished? Further, does soul belong
ther as nothing at
od of demonstration); in that case what we should have to seek for would be this unique method. But if there is no such single and general method for solving the question of essence, our task becomes still more difficult; in the case of each different subject we shall have to determine the appropriate process of investigation. If to this there be a clear answer, e.g. that the process is demonstration or division, or [20]
this-somewhat,' a substance, or is it quantum, or some other of the
might be supposed that
flicable to all objects whose essential nature 75] we are endeavouring to ascertain (as
there
it is; is it 'a
a quale or a
all
ei-
or as a later product).
if what exists is not a plurality of souls, but a plurality of parts of one soul, which
ought we
to investigate first, the
whole soul or
[10] its parts? (It is also a difficult problem to decide which of these parts are in nature distinct
we
from one another.) Again, which ought
to investigate first, these parts or their func-
tions,
mind
of sensation,
or thinking, the faculty or the act
and
so
on?
If
the investigation of
the functions precedes that of the parts, the further question suggests
itself:
ought we not
before either to consider the correlative objects, [75] e.g. of sense or thought? It seems not only useful for the discovery of the causes of the
derived properties of substances to be acquainted with the essential nature of those substances (as in mathematics it is useful for the understanding of the property of the equality of the [20] interior angles of a triangle to two right angles to know the essential nature of the straight and the curved or of the line and the plane) but also conversely, for the knowledge of the essential nature of a substance is largely promoted by an acquaintance with its proper-
ON THE SOUL
632 ties: for,
when we
are able to give an account
conformable to experience of properties of a substance,
all
we
or most of the
shall be in the
most favourable position to say something worth saying about the essential nature of that [25] subject; in all demonstration a definition of the essence is required as a starting-point, so
which do not enable us to discover the derived properties, or which fail to 403 a facilitate even a conjecture about them, must obviously, one and all, be dialectical and that definitions
futile.
A
further problem presented by the affec-
tions of soul
is
this: are
complex of body and
among them determine
they
all
soul, or
affections of the is
there any one
peculiar to the soul by itself?
this
indispensable but
is
To
difficult. If
[5] we consider the majority of them, there seems to be no case in which the soul can act or be acted upon without involving the body; e.g.
anger, courage, appetite, and
sensation
Thinking seems the most probable exception; but if this too proves to be a form of
generally.
imagination or to be impossible without imagination, it too requires a body as a condition of [10] its existence. If there is any way of acting or being acted upon proper to soul, soul will be
capable of separate existence; if there is none, its separate existence is impossible. In the latter case,
it
many in
it,
will be like
what
properties arising
is straight, which has from the straightness
touching a bronze sphere at a though straightness divorced from the
e.g. that of
point,
other constituents of the straight thing cannot
touch
it
way;
in this
cannot be so divorced at
it
[75] all, since it is always found in a body. It therefore seems that all the affections of soul
—
involve a body passion, gentleness, fear, pity, courage, joy, loving, and hating; in all these there is a concurrent affection of the body. In support of this we may point to the fact that,
while sometimes on the occasion of violent and striking occurrences there is no excite-
ment
[20] feeble viz.
or fear
felt,
on others
faint
and
stimulations produce these emotions,
when
the
body
tension resembling
angry. Here
is
a
is
its
still
already in a state of
condition
when we
are
clearer case: in the ab-
sence of any external cause of terror we find ourselves experiencing the feelings of a man in terror.
From
all this it is
obvious that the
affections of soul are enmattered formulable
essences.
[25] Consequently their definitions ought to correspond, e.g. anger should be defined as a
403 b
mode of movement of such and such a body (or part or faculty of a body) by this or that cause and for this or that end. That is precisely why the study of the soul must fall with-
certain
in the science of Nature, at least so far as in
Hence
its
manifests this double character. a physicist would define an affection of
affections
it
[30] soul differently from a dialectician; the would define e.g. anger as the appetite
latter
for returning pain for pain, or
something
like
while the former would define it as a boiling of the blood or warm substance surround403 b ing the heart. The latter assigns the material conditions, the former the form or formulable essence; for what he states is the formulable essence of the fact, though for its actual existence there must be embodiment of it in a material such as is described by the other. Thus the essence of a house is assigned in such a formula as 'a shelter against destruction by [5] wind, rain, and heat'; the physicist would describe it as 'stones, bricks, and timbers'; but that,
there
is
would
third
a
possible
description
was that form
which
matewith that purpose or end. Which, then, among these is entitled to be regarded as the genuine physicist? The one who confines himself to the material, or the one who restricts himself to the formulable essence alone? Is it not rather the one who combines both in a single formula ? If this is so, how are we to characterize the other two? Must we not say that there is no type of thinker who concerns himself with those qualities or attributes of the say that
it
in that
rial
material which are in fact inseparable from the material,
and without attempting even in them? The physicist
[10] thought to separate
who
concerns himself with all the propand passive of bodies or materials thus or thus defined; attributes not considered as being of this character he leaves to others, in certain cases it may be to a specialist, e.g. a carpenter or a physician, in others (a) where they is
he
erties active
are inseparable in fact, but are separable
any particular kind of body by an [75]
straction,
to
the
from
effort of ab-
mathematician,
(b)
where they are separate both in fact and in thought from body altogether, to the First Philosopher or metaphysician. But we must return from this digression, and repeat that the affections of soul are inseparable from the material substratum of animal life, to which we have seen that such affections, e.g. passion and fear, attach, and have not the same mode of being as a line or a plane.
BOOK
404 b
I,
CHAPTERS
1-2
633
what moved These motes were referred to because they are seen always in movement, clared the motes in air, others
them, to be
[20] For our study of soul it is necessary, while formulating the problems of which in our further advance we are to find the solutions, to call into council the views of those of our predecessors who have declared any opinion on this subject, in order that we may profit by whatever is sound in their suggestions and avoid their errors.
The chiefly
is an exwhich have
starting-point of our inquiry
position of those characteristics
been held to belong to soul in
[25]
nature.
above
all
Two
characteristic
its
very
marks have
others been recognized as distinguish-
ing that which has soul in it from that which has not movement and sensation. It may be said that these two are what our predecessors
—
have fixed upon as characteristic of
soul.
what originates movement is both pre-eminently and primarily soul; believing that what is not itself moved cannot origi-
Some
say that
[30] nate
movement
in another, they arrived
view that soul belongs to the class of things in movement. This is what led Democat the
ritus to say that soul
404a
is
a sort of fire or hot sub-
stance; his 'forms' or
atoms are
infinite
number; those which are spherical he calls fire and soul, and compares them to the motes in the air which we see in shafts of light coming through windows; the mixture of seeds of all sorts he calls the elements of the whole of [5] Nature (Leucippus gives a similar account); the spherical atoms are identified with soul because atoms of that shape are most adapted to permeate everywhere, and to set all in
soul.
even in a complete calm. [20] The same tendency
who
define soul as that
seem is
is what and that while alone moves itself.
moved by soul, it This belief arises from their never seeing anything originating movement which is not first all else is
moved.
itself
[25] Similarly also Anaxagoras (and whoever agrees with him in saying that mind set the
whole in movement) declares the moving cause of things to be soul. His position must, however, be distinguished from that of Democritus. Democritus roundly identifies soul
and mind, for he identifies what appears with what is true that is why he commends Ho-
—
mer
with thought he does not employ mind as a special faculty dealing with truth, but identifor the phrase 'Hector lay
[jo] distraught'
404 b
1
;
and mind. What Anaxagoras them is more obscure; in many he tells us that the cause of beauty and soul
fies
says about
places
is mind, elsewhere that it is soul; it is found, he says, in all animals, great and small, [5] high and low, but mind (in the sense of intelligence) appears not to belong alike to all animals, and indeed not even to all human be-
order
ings.
who had special
All those, then,
what has
regard to the
moved, adopted the view that soul is to be identified with what is eminently originative of movement. All, on fact that
soul in
who
what has
it
[10] piration as the characteristic mark of life; as the environment compresses the bodies of
eral
animals, and tends to extrude those atoms
elements, each of
which impart movement to them, because they themselves are never at rest, there must be a reinforcement of these by similar atoms coming in from without in the act of respiration; for they prevent the extrusion of those which are already within by counteracting the compressing and consolidating force of the environment; and animals continue to live only [75] so long as they are able to maintain this
words
doctrine of the Pythagoreans seems to rest upon the same ideas; some of them de-
those
itself; all
view that movement
to hold the
the other hand,
The
shown by
closest to the nature of soul,
the others moving by being themselves in movement. This implies the view that soul is identical with what produces movement in animals. That is why, further, they regard res-
resistance.
is
which moves
soul in
it is
looked to the fact that
knows
or perceives
what
is,
identify soul with the principle or principles
[10] of Nature, according as they admit sevsuch principles or one only. Thus Em-
pedocles declares that
it is
them
formed out of
all his
also being soul; his
are:
'tis by Earth we see Earth, by Water Water, By Ether Ether divine, by Fire destructive
For
Fire,
[75]
By Love Love, and Hate by
In the same
way
Plato in the
cruel Hate. 2
Timaeus3
fash-
ions the soul out of his elements; for like, he holds, is known by like, and things are formed out of the principles or elements, so that soul 1
Iliad, xxiii. 698.
2
Fr. 109, Diels.
3
35 S.
ON THE SOUL
634
must be so too. Similarly 'On Philosophy' it was
also in his lectures set
forth
the
that
[20] Animal-itself is compounded of the Idea of the One together with the primary
itself
length, breadth, objects of
its
and depth, everything else, the
perception, being similarly consti-
Again he puts his view in yet other Mind is the monad, science or knowledge the dyad (because it goes undeviatingly from one point to another), opinion the numtuted.
terms:
ber of the plane, sensation the
number
of the
numbers are by him expressly identiwith the Forms themselves or principles,
solid; the
fied
and are formed out of the elements; now [25] things are apprehended either by mind or science or opinion or sensation, and these same numbers are the Forms of things.
Some
both premisses, both originative of movement and cognitive, have compounded it of both and declared the soul to be a self-moving thinkers, accepting
viz. that the soul
is
number. [30] As to the nature and number of the
opinions differ. The difference is greatest between those who regard them as corporeal and those who regard them as incor-
and from both dissent those who and draw their principles from
poreal,
make
a blend
both sources.
The number
of principles
is
also
some admit one only, others assert There is a consequent diversity in their
in dispute; several.
several accounts of soul; they assume, naturally
enough, that what native of
is
in
its
own
nature origi-
movement must be among what
is
[5] primordial. That has led some to regard it as fire, for fire is the subtlest of the elements
and nearest to incorporeality; most primary sense, fire both originates
movement
further, in the is
moved and
in all the others.
Democritus has expressed himself more ingeniously than the rest on the grounds for ascribing each of these two characters to soul; soul and mind are, he says, one and the same [10] thing, and this thing must be one of the primary and indivisible bodies, and of originating
fineness of grain
he says that of
power
its
movement must be due and the shape of
all
its
to
its
atoms;
the shapes the spherical
is
and that this is the shape of of both fire and mind.
the most mobile, the particles
Anaxagoras, as we said above, 1 seems to distinguish between soul and mind, but in practice he treats them as a single substance, except [75] that it is mind that he specially posits as the principle of all things; at any rate what he 1
4o
b 1-6.
that
is
mind
alone of
all
that
is is
simple,
unmixed, and pure. He assigns both characteristics, knowing and origination of movement, to the same principle, when he says that it was mind that set the whole in movement. Thales, too, to judge from what is recorded about him, seems to have held soul to be a mo[20] tive force, since he said that the magnet has a soul in it because it moves the iron.
Diogenes (and others) held the soul to be air because he believed air to be finest in grain and
grounds of the powers of knowing and originating movement. As the primordial principle from which all other things are derived, it is cognia
first
principle; therein lay the
soul's
tive; as finest in grain,
it
has the power to origi-
nate movement. [25] Heraclitus too says that the first principle the 'warm exhalation' of which, accord-
—
ing to him, everything else
—
composed is is most inthat what is in
is
soul; further, that this exhalation
corporeal and in ceaseless flux; first
principles
405 a
says
405 b
movement
requires that what knows it should be in movement; and that all that is has its being essentially in movement (herein agreeing with the majority).
Alcmaeon
also
seems to have held a similar
[50] view about soul; he says that
immor-
it is
because it resembles 'the immortals/ and that this immortality belongs to it in virtue of tal
movement; for all the 'things dimoon, sun, the planets, and the whole heavens, are in perpetual movement. 405 b Of more superficial writers, some, e.g. Hippo, have pronounced it to be water; they seem to have argued from the fact that the seed of all animals is fluid, for Hippo tries to refute those who say that the soul is blood, on the ground that the seed, which is the primorceaseless
its
vine,'
dial soul,
[5]
is
not blood.
Another group
hold
it
(Critias, for
example) did
to be blood; they take perception to be
the most characteristic attribute of soul,
hold that perceptiveness
is
due
and
to the nature
of blood.
Each of the elements has thus found its parexcept earth earth has found no sup-
tisan,
porter unless
—
we count
as
such those
[10] declared soul to be, or to be of, all the elements. All, then, it
who have
compounded
may
be said,
characterize the soul by three marks,
Move-
ment, Sensation, Incorporeality, and each of these is traced back to the first principles. That is why (with one exception) all those who define the soul by its power of knowing make it either an element or constructed out of the ele-
BOOK
406 b
I,
CHAPTERS
ments. The language they all use is similar; [75] like, they say, is known by like- as the soul knows everything, they construct it out of
Hence
the principles.
all
who admit
those
all
but one cause or element, make the soul also one (e.g. fire or air), while those who admit a multiplicity of principles
The
multiple.
[20] alone says that
nothing in
make
exception
mind
is is
the soul also
Anaxagoras; he
impassible and has
common with anything else. But, how or in virtue of what cause can
if
this is so,
it
know? That Anaxagoras
has not explained,
nor can any answer be inferred from his words. All who acknowledge pairs of opposites
among
their principles, construct the soul also
out of these contraries, while those who admit one contrary of each pair, [25] e.g. either hot or cold, likewise make the soul some one of these. That is why, also, they
as principles only
allow themselves to be guided by the names; those who identify soul with the hot argue that derived from {eiv (to boil), identify it with the cold say \pvxh ) is so called from the process
(to live)
£rjv
while those that soul
(
is
who
and refrigeration ( kcit&vM-is ). Such are the traditional opinions concerning soul, together with the grounds on which they are maintained.
of respiration [jo]
2-3
635
moved' and participates in such direct movement. There are four species of movement locomotion, alteration, diminution, growth; consequently if the soul is moved, it must be moved with one or several or all of these species of movement. Now if its movement is not [75] incidental, there must be a movement
—
natural to it, and, if so, as all the species enumerated involve place, place must be natural to it. But if the essence of soul be to move itself, its being moved cannot be incidental to it, as it is to what is white or three cubits long; they too can be moved, but only incidentally what
—
moved
which
and 'three cubits long' are the attributes, the body in [20] which they inhere; hence they have no is
place:
that of
is
but
if
movement,
it
'white'
the soul naturally partakes in follows that
it
must have a
place.
Further, if there be a movement natural to the soul, there must be a counter-movement unnatural to it, and conversely. The same applies to rest as well as to
movement;
for the
terminus ad quern of a thing's natural move[25] ment is the place of its natural rest, and similarly the terminus ad quern of its enforced
movement is the place of its enforced rest. But what meaning can be attached to enforced movements or rests of the soul, it is difficult even to imagine.
We
must begin our examination with move-
ment; for doubtless, not only essence of soul
406*
who
able of ity
of
that
false that the
correctly described by those
is
say that
moving)
is it
what moves (or
it is
itself,
but
it
is
is
cap-
an impossibil-
movement should -be even an
attribute
it.
We no
have already 1 pointed out that
necessity that
what
originates
there*
is
movement
be moved. There are two senses in which anything may be moved either (a) indirectly, owing to something other than itself,
should
itself
—
owing to itself. Things are moved' which are moved as being contained in something which is moved, e.g. [5] or (^) directly,
'indirectly
sailors in a ship, for they are moved in a different sense from that in which the ship is moved; the ship is 'directly moved', they are 'indi-
moved', because they are in a moving vessel. This is clear if we consider their limbs; the movement proper to the legs (and so to man) is walking, and in this case the sailors [10] are not walking. Recognizing the double sense of 'being moved', what we have to consider now is whether the soul is 'directly
rectly
1
Physics, viii. 5, especially 257*
3i-258 b
9.
Further, if the natural movement of the soul be upward, the soul must be fire; if downward, it must be earth; for upward and downward movements are the definitory characteristics of these bodies. The same reasoning applies to the intermediate movements, termini, and bodies.
[30] Further, since the soul is observed to origmovement in the body, it is reasonable to
inate
suppose that
it
transmits to the body the move-
ments by which
moved, and so, reinfer from the movements of the body back to similar move406b ments of the soul. Now the body is moved from place to place with movements of locomotion. Hence it would follow that the soul too must in accordance with the body change either its place as a whole or the relait itself
versing the order,
tive places of its parts.
possibility
body and
is
we may
This carries with it the might even quit its and with this would be
that the soul re-enter
it,
involved the possibility of a resurrection of ani[5] mals from the dead. But, it may be contended, the soul can be moved indirectly by
something
else; for an animal can be pushed out of its course. Yes, but that to whose essence belongs the power of being moved by itself,
ON THE SOUL
63 6
cannot be moved by something
else except in-
what is good by or in itself goodness to something external to it or to some end to which it is a means. [10] If the soul is moved, the most probable view is that what moves it is sensible things.
cidentally, just as
cannot owe
We itself,
its
must note also that, if the soul moves it must be the mover itself that is moved,
so that
it
follows that
if
movement
is
in every
which is in movement, in that respect in which it is said to be moved, the movement of the soul must be a departure from its essential nature, at least if
case a displacement of that
self-movement
its
is
essential to
not
it,
inci-
dental.
[75] Some go so far as to hold that the movements which the soul imparts to the body in which it is are the same in kind as those with which it itself is moved. An example of this is Democritus, who uses language like that of the comic dramatist Philippus, who accounts for the movements that Daedalus imparted to his wooden Aphrodite by saying that he poured quicksilver into it; similarly Democritus says [20] that the spherical atoms which according
owing to their own movements draw the whole body after them and so produce its movements. We must urge the question whether it is these very same atoms which produce rest also how they could do so, it is difficult and even impossible to say. And, in general, we may object that it is not in this way that the soul appears it is [25] to originate movement in animals
him
to
constitute soul,
ceaseless
—
—
through intention or process of thinking. It is
in the
same fashion
that the
Timaeus
also tries to give a physical account of
how
1
the
moves its body; the soul, it is there said, is in movement, and so owing to their mutual implication moves the body also. After compounding the soul-substance out of the elements and dividing it in accordance with the harmonic numbers, in order that it may possoul
[50] sess a connate sensibility for 'harmony' and that the whole may move in movements
well attuned, the
Demiurge bent
line into a circle; this single circle
the straight
he divided
into two circles united at two common points; 407 a one of these he subdivided into seven circles. All this implies that the movements of
the soul are identified with the local move-
ments of the heavens.
Now,
in the first place,
that the soul
is
it is
a mistake to say
a spatial magnitude. It
is
evi-
dent that Plato means the soul of the whole to 1
35ff-
407"
be like the sort of soul which is called mind [5] not like the sensitive or the desiderative soul, for the movements of neither of these are circular.
Now
the sense in
mind is one and continuous in which the process of thinking is
and thinking is identical with the thoughts which are its parts; these have a serial unity like that of number, not a unity like that of a spatial magnitude. Hence mind cannot have so,
mind is either withcontinuous in some other way
that kind of unity either;
out parts or
is
than that which characterizes a spatial magnitude. How, indeed, if it were a spatial magni[10] tude, could mind possibly think? Will it think with any one indifferently of its parts? In this case, the 'part' must be understood either in the sense of a spatial magnitude or in the sense of a point (if a point can be called a part of a spatial magnitude). If
we
accept the
being infinite in number, obviously the mind can never exhaustively traverse them; if the former, the mind must think the same thing over and over again, indeed an infinite number of times (whereas [75] it is manifestly possible to think a thing once only). If contact of any part whatsoever of itself with the object is all that is required, latter alternative, the points
why need mind move magnitude
sess
in a circle, or indeed pos-
at all?
On
contact with the whole
the other hand,
circle
is
if
necessary,
what meaning can be given
to the contact of the could what has no parts think what has parts, or what has parts think what has none? must identify the circle referred to with mind; for it is mind whose [20] movement is thinking, and it is the circle
parts? Further,
how
We
whose movement ing
is
a
which has be mind. If
is
revolution, so that
movement
this characteristic
the circular
if
think-
of revolution, the circle
movement
movement must is
eternal, there
must be something which mind is always thinking what can this be? For all practical
—
on ess,
for the sake of
and
all
close in the
—
they all go something outside the proc-
processes of thinking have limits
theoretical processes
same way
come
to a
as the phrases in speech
which express processes and results of think[25] ing. Every such linguistic phrase is either definitory or demonstrative. Demonstration has both a starting-point and may be said to end in a conclusion or inferred result; even if the process never reaches final completion, at
never returns upon itself again to its it goes on assuming a fresh middle term or a fresh extreme, and moves straight
any
rate
it
starting-point,
408
BOOK
s
forward, but circular
movement
I,
returns to
CHAPTERS
3-4
637
its
[30] starting-point. Definitions, too, are closed
There
groups of terms. Further, ed,
if
same revolution
the
mind must
repeatedly
is
think the
repeat-
same
object.
Further, thinking has more resemblance to coming to rest or arrest than to a movement; the same may be said of inferring. It might also be urged that what is difficult and enforced is incompatible with blessedness; 407 b if the movement of the soul is not of its essence, movement of the soul must be contrary to its nature. It must also be painful for the soul to be inextricably bound up with the body; nay more, if, as is frequently said and a
widely accepted, it is better for mind not to be embodied, the union must be for it undesirable.
[5] Further, the cause of the revolution of the is left obscure. It is not the essence of
heavens
soul which is the cause ment that movement
— soul —nor
of this circular is
move-
only incidental to
a fortiori, the body its cause. not even asserted that it is better that soul should be so moved; and yet the reason for which God caused the soul to move in [jo] a circle can only have been that move-
Again,
is,
it is
ment was
better for
it
than
rest,
and movement
of this kind better than any other. But since this sort of consideration is more appropriate to another field of speculation, let us dismiss it for the present.
The view we have company with most
just
been examining, in
theories about the soul, in-
volves the following absurdity: they all join [75] the soul to a body, or place it in a body,
which
yet another theory about soul,
is
has commended itself to many as no less probable than any of those we have hitherto mentioned, and has rendered public account [30] of itself in the court of popular discussion. Its supporters say that the soul
harmony
of harmony, for (a)
is
is
a
kind
a blend or
composition of contraries, and (b) the body
compounded out however,
is
of
contraries.
is
Harmony,
a certain proportion or composition
and soul can be
of the constituents blended,
neither the one nor the other of these. Further,
power of originating movement cannot belong to a harmony, while almost all concur in regarding this as a principal attribute of soul. 408 a It is more appropriate to call health (or generally one of the good states of the body) a harmony than to predicate it of the soul. The absurdity becomes most apparent when we try the
and passive affections of harmony; the necessary readjust-
to attribute the active
the soul to a
ment
of their conceptions
[5] in using the
is
difficult.
Further,
word 'harmony' we have one
two cases in our mind; the most proper sense is in relation to spatial magnitudes which have motion and position, where harmony means the disposition and cohesion of their parts in such a manner as to prevent the introduction into the whole of anything homogeneous with it, and the secondary sense, derived from the former, is that in which it or other of
means the
ratio
between the constituents so
blended; in neither of these senses T
[
o] ble to predicate
harmony
it
of soul.
in the sense of the
mode
body
is it
That
plausi-
soul
is
a
of composi-
view
without adding any specification of the reason
tion of the parts of the
of their union, or of the bodily conditions re-
refutable; for there are
quired for it. Yet such explanation can scarcely be omitted; for some community of nature is presupposed by the fact that the one acts and the other is acted upon, the one moves and the other is moved; interaction always implies a special nature in the two interagents. All, how-
and those variously compounded; of what
[20] ever, that these thinkers do is to describe the specific characteristics of the soul; they do
not try to determine anything about the body which is to contain it, as if it were possible, as in the Pythagorean myths, that any soul could be clothed upon with any body an absurd view, for each body seems to have a form and shape of its own. It is as absurd as to say that the art of carpentry could embody itself in [25] flutes; each art must use its tools, each soul its body.
—
bodily part
many
is
a
easily
composite parts
mind or the sensitive or the apmode of composition ? And mode of composition which con-
is
petitive faculty the
what
is
the
each of them? It is equally absurd to identify the soul with the ratio of the mixture; [75] for the mixture which makes flesh has a different ratio between the elements from that which makes bone. The consequence of this view will therefore be that distributed throughout the whole body there will be many souls, since every one of the bodily parts is a different mixture of the elements, and the ratio of mixture is in each case a harmony, i.e. stitutes
a soul.
From Empedocles at any rate we might demand an answer to the following question
ON THE SOUL
63 8
body between the [20] elements: is the soul identical with this ratio, or is it not rather something over and above this which is formed in the parts? Is love the cause of any and every mixture, or for he says that each of the parts of the
what
is
it
in virtue of a ratio
is
only of those that are in the right ratio? Is love this ratio itself, or is love something over and above this? Such are the problems raised by this account. But, on the other hand, if the soul
is
from the mixture, why does
different
it
[25] disappear at one and the same moment with that relation between the elements which constitutes flesh or the other parts of the ani-
mal body? Further, if the soul is not identical with the ratio of mixture, and it is consequently not the case that each of the parts has a soul,
what
is
soul quits the
That the or be
which perishes when the
that
body ?
in a circle,
is
clear
harmony, from what we
[50] have said. Yet that it can be moved inci1 dentally is, as we said above, possible, and
even that in a sense
can move
it
the sense that the vehicle in
moved, and moved by
moved
the soul be
it;
in
itself, i.e.
in
which it is can be no other sense can
in space.
More legitimate doubts might remain as to movement in view of the following facts. 408 b We speak of the soul as being pained or
its
pleased, being bold or fearful, being angry, perceiving, thinking. All these are regarded as
modes of movement, and hence ferred that the soul
it might be inmoved. This, however, follow. We may admit to
is
does not necessarily [5] the full that being pained or pleased, or
movements (each of them ing moved'), and that the movement is thinking, are
a 'beorigi-
nated by the soul. For example we may regard anger or fear as such and such movements of the heart, and thinking as such and such another movement of that organ, or of some other; these modifications may arise either from changes of place in certain parts or from quali[10] tative alterations (the special nature of the
parts
and the
special
modes
of
their
changes being for our present purpose irrelevant). Yet to say that it is the soul which is angry is as inexact as it would be to say that it is the soul that weaves webs or builds houses. It is doubtless better to avoid saying that the soul pities or learns or thinks
man who
and rather
to say
does this with his soul. [75] What we mean is not that the movement is in the soul, but that sometimes it terminates
that
1
it is
406* 30
the
ff.,
b5-8.
s
and sometimes starts from it, sensacoming from without inwards, and reminiscence starting from the soul and terminating with the movements, actual or residin the soul
tion e.g.
ual, in the sense organs.
The case of mind is different; it seems to be an independent substance implanted within the soul and to be incapable of being deit could be destroyed at all, it would be under the blunting influence of old age.
stroyed. If
[20]
What
really
happens
in respect of
mind
age is, however, exactly parallel to what happens in the case of the sense organs; if the old man could recover the proper kind of eye, he would see just as well as the young man. in old
The
incapacity of old age
tion not of the soul but of in
is
due
mind
to
an
affec-
vehicle, as occurs
its
drunkenness or disease. Thus
old age the activity of
soul cannot either be a
moved
409
it
is
that in
or intellectual ap-
prehension declines only through the decay of part; mind itself is impas[25] sible. Thinking, loving, and hating are affections not of mind, but of that which has mind, so far as it has it. That is why, when this vehicle decays, memory and love cease; they were activities not of mind, but of the composite which has perished; mind is, no doubt,
some other inward
something more divine and impassible. That [50] the soul cannot be moved is therefore clear from what we have said, and if it cannot be moved at all, manifestly it cannot be moved by itself. Of all the opinions we have enumerated, by far the most unreasonable is that which declares the soul to be a self-moving number; it involves in the
first
place
all
the impossibilities
which follow from regarding the soul as moved, and in the second special absurdities which follow from calling it a number. How 409 a are we to imagine a unit being moved? By what agency? What sort of movement can be attributed to what is without parts or inis both originacapable of being
ternal differences? If the unit tive of
movement and
itself
moved,
it must contain difference. Further, since they say a moving line generates a surface and a moving point a line,
[5] the
movements
be lines (for a point
of the psychic units is
must
a unit having position,
and the number of the soul is, of course, somewhere and has position). Again, if from a number a number or a unit is
subtracted, the remainder
is
another
num-
and many animals when divided continue to live, and each segment is thought to retain the same kind of soul. ber; but plants
BOOK
410*
I,
CHAPTERS
[10] It must be all the same whether we speak of units or corpuscles; for if the spherical
atoms of Democritus became points, nothing being retained but their being a quantum, there must remain in each a moving and a part, just as there is in what is continuwhat happens has nothing to do with the size of the atoms, it depends solely upon their [75] being a quantum. That is why there must
4-5
639
quence that follows is that the animal must be moved by its number precisely in the way that Democritus explained its being moved by his spherical psychic atoms. it
What
make whether we speak
difference does
of small spheres or
moved
of large units, or, quite simply, of units in
ous;
[10] movement? One way or another, the movements of the animal must be due to their movements. Hence those who combine movement and number in the same subject lay themselves open to these and many other simi-
be something to originate movement in the units. If in the animal what originates movement is the soul, so also must it be in the case of the number, so that not the mover and the moved together, but the mover only, will be the soul. units
to
But how
is it
function
this
fulfil
one of the
possible for
of originating
movement? There must be some
difference be-
[20] tween such a unit and all the other units, and what difference can there be between one
placed unit and another except a difference of position? If then, on the other hand, these psy-
body are different from the points of the body, there will be two sets of units both occupying the same place; for each unit will occupy a point. And yet, if there can be two, why cannot there be an infinite number? For if things can occupy an indivisible place, they must themselves be indivisible. [25] If, on the other hand, the points of the body are identical with the units whose numchic units within the
ber
the soul, or
is
the
if
number
of the points
lar absurdities. It is
—
it is impossible that they should even be attributes of it. The point is clear if the [75] attempt be made to start from this as the account of soul and explain from it
soul
ment and number do not jecture
about the
as
we have
said,
1
that
this
kind of body, is on the other entangled in the absurdity peculiar to Democritus' way of describing the manner in which movement is b
409 originated by soul. For if the soul is present throughout the whole percipient body, there must, if the soul be a kind of body, be two bodies in the same place; and for those
who
call it a
number, there must be many
[5] points at one point, or every body must have a soul, unless the soul be a different sort
number
—
than the sum of the points existing in a body. Another conse-
of
1
b
4 o8 33
ff.
other, that
is,
even con-
properties
of
Such are the three ways ers declared
in which soul has one group of thinkto be that which is most orig-
it
movement because it moves itanother group to be the subtlest and most nearly incorporeal of all kinds of body. We have now sufficiently set forth the difficulties [20] inative of
self,
and inconsistencies to which these theories exposed. It remains now to examine the doctrine that soul is composed of the
elements.
is,
facilitate
derivative
traditionally been defined;
finity of points.
result
e.g.
soul.
are
The
soul,
reasoning, sensation, pleasure, pain, &c. For, 2 to repeat what we have said earlier, move-
body is the soul, why have not all bodies souls? For all bodies contain points or an in-
view, while on the one side identical with that of those who maintain that soul is a subtle
and actions of the
the affections
in the
Further, how is it possible for these points to be isolated or separated from their bodies, [50] seeing that lines cannot be resolved into points?
impossible not only that
these characters should give the definition of
The
reason assigned for this doctrine is that may perceive or come to know everything that is, but the theory necessarily
thus the soul
[25] involves
itself in
many
impossibilities. Its
upholders assume that like is known only by like, and imagine that by declaring the soul to be composed of the elements they succeed in identifying the soul with all the things it is capable of apprehending. But the elements are not the only things it knows; there are many
more exactly, an infinite number of formed out of the elements. Let us ad-
others, or, others,
[50] mit that the soul
knows
or perceives the
elements out of which each of these composites is made up; but by what means will it know or perceive the composite whole, e.g. what God, man, flesh, bone (or any other compound) is? For each is, not merely the ele-
410 a ments of which it is composed, but those elements combined in a determinate mode or ratio, as Empedocles himself says of bone, 2
402 b 25-403*
2.
ON THE SOUL
640
The \indly Earth
in
its
broad-bosomed moulds
1
Won of clear Water two parts out of eight And four of Fire; and so white bones were [5]
formed.
Nothing, therefore, will be gained by the presence of the elements in the soul, unless there be also present there the various formulae of proportion and the various compositions
Each element will indeed know its fellow outside, but there will be no knowledge of bone or man, unless they
in accordance with them.
too are present in the constitution of the soul.
[10] The impossibility of this needs no pointing out; for who would suggest that stone or man could enter into the constitution of the soul? The same applies to 'the good' and 'the
and
so on.
Further, the
word
not-good',
may
it
be used of a
quantum, or
has
Does the
many meanings:
or substance, or of a
of a quale, or of
kinds of predicates [75]
'is'
'this'
any other of the
we have
soul consist of
distinguished. all
of these or
not? It does not appear that all have common elements. Is the soul formed out of those elements alone which enter into substances ? If so, how will it be able to know each of the other kinds of thing? Will it be said that each kind of thing has elements or principles of its own, and that the soul is formed out of the whole of [20] these? In that case, the soul must be a
quantum and a quale and a substance. But all that can be made out of the elements of a quantum is a quantum, not a substance. These (and others like them) are the consequences of the view that the soul is composed of all the elements. It is absurd, also, to say both (a) that like is not capable of being affected by like, and (b) that like is perceived or known by like, for [25] perceiving, and also both thinking and knowing, are, on their own assumption, ways
moved. There are many puzzles and difficulties raised by saying, as Empedocles does, that each set of things is known by means of its corporeal elements and by reference to something in soul which is like them, and additionof being affected or
[30] al testimony is furnished by this new consideration; for all the parts of the animal body
which consist wholly of earth such as bones, 41 b sinews, and hair seem to be wholly insensitive and consequently not perceptive even of objects earthy like themselves, as they ought to 1
have been. Fr. 96, Diels.
410 b
Further, each of the principles will have far
more ignorance than knowledge, for though each of them will know one thing, there will be many of which it will be ignorant. Empedocles at any rate must conclude that his God [5]
is
the least intelligent of
him alone
is
it
all
true that there
beings, for of is
one thing,
which he does not know, while there is nothing which mortal beings do not know, for there is nothing which does not enter into Strife,
their composition.
In general, we may ask, Why has not everything a soul, since everything either is an ele-
ment, or
is
formed out of one or several or all Each must certainly know
of the elements?
one or several or all. [10] The problem might also be raised, What is that which unifies the elements into a soul ? The elements correspond, it would appear, to the matter; what unites them, whatever it is, is the supremely important factor. But it is impossible that there should be something superior to, and dominant over, the soul (and a fortiori over the mind); it is reasonable to hold that mind is by nature most primordial [75] and dominant, while their statement is that it is the elements which are first of all that
is.
who
All, both those
assert that the soul, be-
knowledge or perception of what is, is compounded out of the elements, and those who assert that it is of all things the most originative of movement, fail to take into con-
cause of
its
sideration all kinds of soul. In fact (1) not all beings that perceive can originate movement;
there appear to be certain animals
which are
[20] stationary, and yet local movement is the only one, so it seems, which the soul originates in animals.
against
all
And those
(2) the same objection holds construct mind and the
who
perceptive faculty out of the elements; for
it
appears that plants live, and yet are not endowed with locomotion or perception, while a large number of animals are without dis-
Even if these points were waived and mind admitted to be a part of the [25] soul (and so too the perceptive faculty), still, even so, there would be kinds and parts of soul of which they had failed to give any accourse of reason.
count.
The same
objection
lies
against the view ex-
pressed in the 'Orphic' poems: there it is said that the soul comes in from the whole when breathing takes place, being borne in upon the
Now
this cannot take place in the [30] winds. case of plants, nor indeed in the case of cer-
BOOK
411 b
I,
CHAPTER
tain classes of animal, for not all classes of
41 l a animal breathe. This
fact has
escaped the
If
we must
construct the soul out of the
there
no
is
tion;
suppose
to
necessity
that all the elements enter into
construc-
its
one element in each pair of contraries
will suffice to enable
it
to
know
both that
ele-
it
the curved
its
able
us
—the carpenter's rule enables us —but what curved does not en-
to
is
distinguish
to
either
itself
the
or
straight.
Certain thinkers say that soul
is
intermin-
gled in the whole universe, and it is perhaps for that reason that Thales came to the opinion that all things are full of gods. This presents
some
[10]
when
difficulties: it
Why
does
the
resides in air or fire not
soul
form an
animal, while it does so when it resides in mixtures of the elements, and that although it is held to be of higher quality when contained in the former?
why
(One might add
the question,
maintained to be higher and more immortal than that in animals.) Both possible ways of replying to the former fuestion lead to absurdity or paradox; for it 75] is beyond paradox to say that fire or air is an animal, and it is absurd to refuse the name of animal to what has soul in it. The opinion that the elements have soul in them seems to have arisen from the doctrine that a whole must be homogeneous with its parts. If it is true that animals become animate by the soul in air
it is
some quite other cause?
[5] that
both
whether
41 l b with the whole soul we think, perceive, ourselves, act or are acted upon, or whether each of them requires a different part of the soul? So too with regard to life. Does it depend on one of the parts of soul ? Or is it dependent on more than one ? Or on all ? Or has
[5] ment itself and its contrary. By means of the straight line we know both itself and
test
641 i.e.
move
notice of the holders of this view.
elements,
5
bute of the soul as a whole,
is
drawing into themselves a portion of what surrounds them, the partisans of this view are
Some hold
that the soul
is
divisible,
and
one part thinks, another desires. If, then, nature admits of its being divided, what
can it be that holds the parts together? Surely not the body; on the contrary it seems rather to be the soul that holds the body together; at
any
when
the soul departs the body disinand decays. If, then, there is something else which makes the soul one, this unifying agency would have the best right to the [10] name of soul, and we shall have to repeat for it the question: Is it one or multipartite? If it is one, why not at once admit that 'the rate
tegrates
is one? If it has parts, once more the quesmust be put: What holds its parts together, and so ad infinitum? The question might also be raised about the
soul'
tion
parts of the soul:
What
is
the separate role of
each in relation to the body ? For, if the whole [75] soul holds together the whole body, we should expect each part of the soul to hold together a part of the body. But this seems an impossibility; it is difficult even to imagine what sort of bodily part mind will hold together, or It is
how
it
will
do
this.
a fact of observation that plants
and
cer-
[20] tain insects go on living when divided into segments; this means that each of the seg-
ments has a soul in it identical in species, though not numerically identical in the differ-
bound to say that the soul of the Whole too is [20] homogeneous with all its parts. If the air
ent segments, for both of the segments for a
homogeneous, but soul heterogeneous, clearly while some part of soul will exist
movement. That
sucked in
is
in the inbreathed air,
The
soul
must
that there are
which
it is
some other part will not. homogeneous, or such
either be
some
not to be found. has been said it
knowing
as
is
all
the
now clear that
[25] ent all the parts of soul, and the souls so present are homogeneous with one another and with the whole; this means that the sev-
an attribute of soul cannot be ex-
speak of soul as moved. But since (a) knowand further (b) desiring, wishing, and generally all other modes of appetition, belong to soul, and (c) the local [50] movements of animals, and (d) growth, maturity, and decay are produced by the soul, we must ask whether each of these is an attriing, perceiving, opining,
But,
same, in each of the bodily parts there are pres-
[25] plained by soul's being composed of the elements, and that it is neither sound nor true to
necessary for self-maintenance.
in
parts of the
From what
Whole
time possess the power of sensation and local this does not last is not surprising, for they no longer possess the organs
eral parts of the soul are indisseverable
from
one another, although the whole soul is divisible. It seems also that the principle found in plants is also a kind of soul; for this is the only principle which is common to both animals and plants; and this exists in isolation from the principle of sensation, though there [30] is nothing which has the latter without the former.
ON THE SOUL
642
BOOK
412 b
II
in spite of their
extreme simplicity are 'organs';
e.g. the leaf serves to shelter the pericarp, the
412 a Let the foregoing
our account which have
suffice as
of the views concerning the soul
been handed on by our predecessors;
now
dismiss
them and make
as
us
let
were a com-
it
endeavouring to give a pre-
pletely fresh start,
[5] cise answer to the question, What is soul ? i.e. to formulate the most general possible defi-
nition of
it.
We are in the habit of recognizing, as one determinate kind of what is, substance, and that in several senses, (a) in the sense of matter or that which in itself is not 'a this', and (b) in the sense of form or essence, which is that precisely in virtue of called
that
'a this',
which
and
which
compounded
is
a
thing
is
thirdly (c) in the sense of of both (a)
and
Now
matter is potentiality, form ac[10] (b). tuality; of the latter there are two grades re-
one another as exercise of knowledge. lated to
knowledge
e.g.
to the
pericarp to shelter the fruit, while the roots of mouth of animals, both serving for the absorption of food. If, then, we have to give a general formula applants are analogous to the
[5] plicable to all kinds of soul, we must describe it as the first grade of actuality of a nat-
body. That is why we can wholly dismiss as unnecessary the question whether the soul and the body are one: it is as meaningless as to ask whether the wax and the shape given to it by the stamp are one, or generally the matter of a thing and that of which it is the matter. Unity has many senses (as many as 'is' has), but the most proper and fundamental sense of both is the relation of an actuality to that of which it is the actuality. [10] We have now given an answer to the question, What is soul? an answer which apural organized
—
plies to
its
full extent. It
which corresponds
the sense
Among substances are by general consent reckoned bodies and especially natural bodies;
in
it
is
substance in
to the definitive
formula of a thing's essence. That means that
for they are the principles of all other bodies.
it is 'the essential whatness' of a body of the character just assigned. Suppose that what is
Of
literally
some have
natural bodies not; by
ers
life
we mean
life
in
them, oth-
self-nutrition
and
[75] growth (with its correlative decay). It follows that every natural body which has life in
it is
a substance in the sense of a composite.
But since it is also a body of such and such a kind, viz. having life, the body cannot be soul; the body is the subject or matter, not what is attributed to it. Hence the soul must be a sub[20] stance in the sense of the form of a natural body having life potentially within it. But substance is actuality, and thus soul is the actuality of a body as above characterized. Now the word actuality has two senses corresponding respectively to the possession of knowledge and the actual exercise of knowledge. It is obvious that the soul
is
actuality in the first sense,
knowledge as possessed, for both [25] sleeping and waking presuppose the existence of soul, and of these waking corresponds to actual knowing, sleeping to knowl-
viz. that of
edge possessed but not employed, and, in the history of the individual, knowledge comes before
its
employment
That
is
why
or exercise.
the soul
is
the
first
grade of
ac-
body having life potenThe body so described is a body
tuality of a natural tially in
it.
412 b which
is
organized.
The
parts of plants
body,
its
an
'organ', like
an axe, were a natural would have been
'essential whatness',
and so its soul; if this disappeared would have ceased to be an axe, ex[75] cept in name. As it is, it is just an axe; it wants the character which is required to its
essence,
from
it, it
make
its
whatness or formulable essence a soul; it would have had to be a natural body of a particular kind, viz. one having in for that,
the power of setting itself in movement and arresting itself. Next, apply this doctrine itself
in the case of the 'parts' of the living body.
—
Suppose that the eye were an animal sight would have been its soul, for sight is the substance or essence of the eye
which corresponds
[20] to the formula, the eye being merely the matter of seeing; when seeing is removed
—
is no longer an eye, except in name it no more a real eye than the eye of a statue or of a painted figure. We must now extend our consideration from the 'parts' to the whole living body; for what the departmental sense is to the bodily part which is its organ, that the whole faculty of sense is to the whole sensitive body as such. [25] We must not understand by that which is 'potentially capable of living' what has lost the soul it had, but only what still retains it;
the eye
is
BOOK
413 b
CHAPTERS
II,
1-2
643
but seeds and fruits are bodies which possess
down, and everything that grows
the qualification. Consequently, while waking is actuality in a sense corresponding to the cut413 a ting and the seeing, the soul is actuality
bulk alike in both directions or indeed in all, [30] and continues to live so long as it can absorb nutriment. This power of self-nutrition can be isolated from the other powers mentioned, but not they from it in mortal beings at least. The fact is obvious in plants; for it is the only psychic
in the sense corresponding to the and the power in the tool; the
sight
power of body cor-
responds to what exists in potentiality; as the pupil plus the power of sight constitutes the eye, so the soul plus the body constitutes the animal.
From soul
is
this
indubitably follows that the its body, or at any rate
it
inseparable from
increases
its
—
power they possess. 413 b This is the originative power the possession of which leads us to speak of things as living at
all,
but
is
it
the possession of sensa-
has parts) of them is noth-
tion that leads us for the first time to speak of
ing but the actualities of their bodily parts. Yet some may be separable because they are not the actualities of any body at all. Further, we
which possess no power of local movement but do possess the power of sensation we call animals and not merely living things. The primary form of sense is touch, which [5] belongs to all animals. Just as the power of self-nutrition can be isolated from touch and
that certain parts of
it
[5] for the actuality of
are (if
some
it
have no light on the problem whether the soul not be the actuality of its body in the
may
sense in
which the
sailor
is
the actuality of the
living things as animals; for even those beings
ship.
sensation generally, so touch can be isolated
This must suffice as our sketch or outline [10] determination of the nature of soul.
of self-nutrition
from
all
other forms of sense. (By the power
power of the and animals: Since what
is
clear or logically
emerges from what
more evident
confused but more observable by us, we must reconsider our results from this point of view. For it is not enough for a definitive formula to express as [75] most
now do
in itself
the
mere
is
fact;
must
it
in-
clude and exhibit the ground also. At present definitions are given in a form analogous to the conclusion of a syllogism; e.g. What is squaring? The construction of an equilateral rectangle equal to a given oblong rectangle. Such a definition is in form equivalent to a
One
that tells us that squaring
we mean which
soul all
is
that departmental
common
to plants
animals whatsoever are ob-
served to have the sense of touch.)
What
the
[10] explanation of these two facts is, we must 1 discuss later. At present we must confine ourselves to saying that soul
phenomena and by
is
powers of
the
is
the source of these
characterized by them, viz. self-nutrition,
sensation,
thinking, and motivity. Is
And
each of these a soul or a part of a soul? if
a part, a part in
A
what sense?
part
merely distinguishable by definition or a part [75] distinct in local situation as well? In the case of certain of these powers, the answers to
is
these questions are easy, in the case of others
which is a mean proportional between the two unequal sides of the given rectangle discloses the ground of what is
what to say. Just as in the case which when divided are observed to continue to live though removed to a distance from one another (thus showing that in their
conclusion.
the discovery of a line
defined.
We
resume our inquiry from a fresh [20] starting-point by calling attention to the fact that
what has
soul in
not, in that the
it
from what has
differs
former displays
life.
Now
this
word has more than one
sense,
and provided
any one alone of these
found
in a thing
say that thing
is
is
living. Living, that
is,
we may
mean thinking
or perception or local move-
ment and
or
rest,
movement
in the sense of
[25] nutrition, decay and growth. Hence we think of plants also as living, for they are observed to possess in themselves an originative power through which they increase or decrease in all spatial directions; they grow up and
we
are puzzled
of plants
case the soul of each individual plant before
division
we
so
was
actually one, potentially
many),
notice a similar result in other varieties
[20] of soul, i.e. in insects which have been cut in two; each of the segments possesses both
sensation and local
movement; and if sensaimagination and appeti-
tion, necessarily also
tion; for,
where there
is
sensation, there
is
also
pleasure and pain, and, where these, necessarily
also desire.
We
have no evidence as yet about mind or
[25] the power to think; it seems to be a widely different kind of soul, differing as what is 1
in. 12, esp.
a b 434 22-30, io
ff.
ON THE SOUL
6 44 eternal
from what
is
perishable;
it
alone
is
ca-
pable of existence in isolation from all other psychic powers. All the other parts of soul, it evident from what we have said, are, in spite of certain statements to the contrary, incapable
414 b
served fact; the actuality of any given thing can only be realized in what is already potentially that
thing,
i.e.
in a
From
matter of
its
own
ap-
is
propriate to
of separate existence though, of course, distin-
soul is an actuality or formulable essence of something that possesses a potentiality of being
guishable by definition. If opining is distinct [30] from perceiving, to be capable of opining and to be capable of perceiving must be dis-
and so with
tinct,
all
the other forms of living
some animals possess all these parts of soul, some certain of them only, others one only (this is what enables us to classify animals); the cause must 414a be considered later. A similar arrangement is found also within the field of the senses; some classes of animals have all the senses, some only certain of them, others only one, the most indispensable, touch. Since the expression 'that whereby we live [5] and perceive' has two meanings, just like the expression 'that whereby we know' that may mean either (a) knowledge or (b) the soul, for we can speak of knowing by or with either, and similarly that whereby we are in above enumerated.
Further,
1
—
health
may
be either (a) health or (b) the
body or some part of the body; and since of the two terms thus contrasted knowledge or health or
if
is
we
the
name
so express
—
of a form, essence, or ratio, it
an actuality of a recipient
[10] matter knowledge of what is capable of knowing, health of what is capable of being
made
healthy (for the operation of that which capable of originating change terminates and has its seat in what is changed or altered); further, since it is the soul by or with which it folprimarily we live, perceive, and think: is
—
lows that the soul must be a ratio or formulable essence, not a matter or subject. For, as we 2 said, the word substance has three meanings [75] form, matter, and the complex of both and of these three what is called matter is po-
what is called form actuality. Since then the complex here is the living thing, the
tentiality,
body cannot be the actuality of the soul; it is the soul which is the actuality of a certain kind of body. Hence the Tightness of the view that the soul cannot be without a body, while it can[20] not be a body; it is not a body but something relative to a body. That is why it is in a body, and a body of a definite kind. It was a mistake, therefore, to do as former thinkers did, merely to fit it into a body without adding a definite specification of the kind or character [25] of that body. Reflection confirms the ob111.
12, 13.
2
412*7.
it.
all
this
it
follows that
besouled.
Of
the psychic powers above enumerated 3 some kinds of living things, as we have said, 4 possess all, some less than all, others one only, [jo] Those we have mentioned are the nutritive,
the appetitive, the sensory, the locomo-
tive,
and the power
none but the
first,
of thinking. Plants have
the nutritive, while another
order of living things has this plus the sensory. If any order of living things has the sen-
414 b sory,
must
it
petite
is
also
have the appetitive; for ap-
the genus of which desire, passion,
and wish are the
species;
now
all
animals have
and whatever has a sense has the capacity for pleasure and pain and therefore has pleasant and painful objects present to it, and wherever these are present, one sense
at least, viz. touch,
[5] there is desire, for desire of what is pleasant. Further,
is
the sense for food (for touch
just appetition
all
animals have
the sense for food); the food of all living things consists of what is dry, moist, hot, cold, and these are the is
apprehended by touch; all other senapprehended by touch only [10] indirectly. Sounds, colours, and odours contribute nothing to nutriment; flavours fall qualities
sible qualities are
within the
field of tangible qualities.
Hunger
and thirst are forms of desire, hunger a desire for what is dry and hot, thirst a desire for what is cold and moist; flavour is a sort of seasoning added to both. We must later 5 clear up these [75] points, but at present it may be enough to say that all animals that possess the sense of touch have also appetition. The case of imagi-
nation
is
obscure;
we must examine
it
later.
6
Certain kinds of animals possess in addition the power of locomotion, and still another order of animate beings, i.e. man and possibly another order like man or superior to him, the [20] power of thinking, i.e. mind. It is now evident that a single definition can be given of soul only in the same sense as one can be given of figure. For, as in that case there
distinguishable 3 5
and apart from
is
no
figure
triangle,
&c,
4 a b a b 4 i3 3 2 -4i4 i4 i 3 23-5, i 1-13,21-4. b 18-21); Sense and the Sensi11, in. 12 (434
Chapter
ble, 4.
6111.3,11 (433 b 3 I -434a 7)-
BOOK
415 b so here there
no
is
soul apart
II,
CHAPTERS
from the forms
of soul just enumerated. It is true that a highly general definition can be given for figure
which
will
fit
figures without expressing
all
the peculiar nature of any figure. So here in the case of soul and its specific forms. Hence [25]
it
is
demand which
absurd in this and similar cases to an absolutely general definition
will fail to express the peculiar nature
is, or again, omitting this, to look for separate definitions corresponding to each infima species. The cases of figure and
of anything that
soul are exactly parallel; for the particulars sub-
sumed under
—figures [50]
ries,
the
contains
tially
common name
—
its
both cases
predecessor, e.g. the square
the triangle, the sensory tive.
in
and living beings constitute a seeach successive term of which poten-
Hence we must ask
der of living things,
power the
self-nutri-
in the case of
What
each or-
What man? Why the serial way must form is its
soul,
i.e.
the soul of plant, animal,
is
terms are related in this
415 a the
subject of later examination.
1
But the
power of perception is never found apart from the power of self-nutrition,
facts are that the
—
—
in plants the latter is found isolated from the former. Again, no sense is found apart from that of touch, while touch is found
while
[5] by itself;
many
animals have neither sight,
hearing, nor smell. Again, that possess sense
among living
things
some have the power of loco-
motion, some not. Lastly, certain living beings a small minority possess calculation and thought, for (among mortal beings) those which possess calculation have all the other [10] powers above mentioned, while the converse does not hold indeed some live by imagination alone, while others have not even imagination. The mind that knows with immediate intuition presents a different problem. It is evident that the way to give the most adequate definition of soul is to seek in the case of each of its forms for the most appropri-
—
—
—
ate definition.
2-4
645
der of investigation the question of what an agent does precedes the question, what enables [20] it to do what it does. If this is correct, we must on the same ground go yet another step farther back and have some clear view of the objects of each; thus we must start with these objects, e.g. with food, with what is perceptible, or with what is intelligible. It follows that first of all we must treat of nutrition and reproduction, for the nutritive soul is found along with all the others and is the most primitive and widely distributed power of soul, being indeed that one in virtue [25] of which all are said to have life. The acts in which it manifests itself are reproduction and the use of food reproduction, I say, because for any living thing that has reached its normal development and which is unmutilated, and whose mode of generation is not spontaneous, the most natural act is the production of another like itself, an animal producing an
—
animal, a plant a plant, in order that, as far as its nature allows, it may partake in the eternal
415 b and divine. That is the goal towards which all things strive, that for the sake of which they do whatsoever their nature renders
The phrase 'for the sake of which' is ambiguous; it may mean either (a) the end to achieve which, or (b) the being in whose interest, the act is done. Since then no living thing is able to partake in what is eternal and divine by uninterrupted continuance (for nothing perishable can for ever remain one and [5] the same), it tries to achieve that end in possible.
way
the only
possible to
it,
and
varying degrees; so
success
is
pos-
remains not indeed as the self-same individual but continues its existence in something li\e itself not numerically but specifically one. sible in
it
—
The soul is the cause or source of the living The terms cause and source have many
body.
But the soul
senses.
is
the cause of
alike in all three senses
[10] recognize.
movement,
it is
which we
its
body
explicitly
(a) the source or origin of (b) the end, it is (c) the es-
It is
sence of the whole living body.
That necessary for the student of these forms of soul first to find a definition of each, ex-
It is
it is
the essence being,
the is
and
last, is clear;
for in everything
identical with the
ground of
[75] pressive of what it is, and then to investigate its derivative properties, &c. But if we are
their being
to express what each is, viz. what the thinking power is, or the perceptive, or the nutritive, we must go farther back and first give an ac-
source. Further, the actuality of whatever
count of thinking or perceiving, for in the or1
in. 12, 13.
its
here, in the case of living things, is
to live,
and of their being and them is the cause or
their living the soul in
potential
is
identical
with
its
formulable
is
es-
sence.
[75]
It
is
manifest that the soul is also the its body. For Nature, like mind,
final cause of
ON THE SOUL
6^6
416 b
always does whatever it does for the sake of something, which something is its end. To that something corresponds in the case of animals the soul and in this it follows the order of nature; all natural bodies are organs of the soul. This is true of those that enter into the
belong to the side of formulable essence rather than that of matter. Nutrition and reproduction are due to one
which
sake of which', viz. (a) the end to achieve which, and (b) the being in whose interest,
food that this psychic power is distinguished from all the others. The current view is that what serves as food to a living thing is what is contrary to it not that in every pair of contraries each is food to the other: to be food a contrary must not only be transformable into
anything
the other
constitution of plants as well as of those
enter into that of animals. This shows that that
We
[20] for the sake of which they are is soul. recall the two senses of 'that for the
must here
We
or
is
is
done.
must maintain,
further, that the soul
also the cause of the living
body
source of local movement.
The power
is
as the original
and the same psychic power.
It is necessary give precision to our account of. food, for it is by this function of absorbing
first to
[20]
—
and
vice versa,
it
must
also in so do-
ing increase the bulk of the other. Many a contrary is transformed into its other and vice
changes which constitute growth and decay; nothing grows or decays naturally except what feeds itself, and nothing feeds itself except
versa, where neither is even a quantum and so cannot increase in bulk, e.g. an invalid into a [25] healthy subject. It is clear that not even those contraries which satisfy both the conditions mentioned above are food to one another in precisely the same sense; water may be said to feed fire, but not fire water. Where the members of the pair are elementary bodies only one of the contraries, it would appear, can be said to feed the other. But there is a diffi-
what has
culty here.
motion things.
not found, however, in
is
of loco-
all
living
But change of quality and change of
quantity are also due to the soul. Sensation is held to be a qualitative alteration, and nothing except what has soul in it is capable of sensa-
The same
[25] tion.
holds of the quantitative
a share of soul in
Empedocles in plants
is
is
wrong
in
it.
adding that growth
to be explained,
the
downward
rooting by the natural tendency of earth to 416* travel downwards, and the upward branching by the similar natural tendency of fire to travel upwards. For he misinterprets up and down; up and down are not for all things what they are for the whole Cosmos: if we are to distinguish and identify organs according [5] to their functions, the roots of plants are
analogous to the head in animals. Further, we must ask what is the force that holds together the earth and the fire which tend to travel in contrary directions;
if
there
is
no counteract-
ing force, they will be torn asunder; if there is, this must be the soul and the cause of nutrition and growth. By some the element of fire is held to be the cause of nutrition and growth,
alone of the primary bodies or eleobserved to feed and increase itself. Hence the suggestion that in both plants and animals it is it which is the operative force. A concurrent cause in a sense it certainly is, but [75] not the principal cause, that is rather the soul; for while the growth of fire goes on without limit so long as there is a supply of fuel, in the case of all complex wholes formed in the course of nature there is a limit or ratio which determines their size and increase, and limit and ratio are marks of soul but not of fire, and [10] for
ments
is
it
One
[jo]
is
like.
Another
set of
thinkers assert that like
fed, as well as increased in
amount, by maintain the very reverse, viz. that what feeds and what is fed are contrary to one another; like, they argue, is incapable of being affected by like; but food is changed in the process of digestion, and change is always to what is opposite or to [35]
what
is
b acted
41
set, as
we have
said,
intermediate. Further, food
upon by what
is
nourished by it, not the other way round, as timber is worked by a carpenter and not conversely; there is a change in the carpenter but it is merely a change from not-working to working. In answering this problem it makes all the difference whether we mean by 'the food' the 'finis
ished' or the 'raw' product. If
we
use the
word
food of both, viz. of the completely undigested and the completely digested matter, we can [5] justify both the rival accounts of it; taking food in the sense of undigested matter, it is the contrary of what is fed by it, taking it as digested it is like what is fed by it. Consequently it is clear that in a certain sense we may say that both parties are right, both
wrong. Since nothing except fed,
what
because
it
is
fed
is
what
is
alive can be
the besouled body and just
has soul in
it.
Hence food
is
essen-
[10] tially related to what has soul in it. Food has a power which is other than the power to
BOOK
417*
what
increase the bulk of
what has
forth as
may
increase
what has
its
soul in
is
it is
fed by
II,
CHAPTERS
so far
quantum, food
a
quantity, but
it;
it is
only so far
a 'this-somewhat' or substance that food acts as food; in that case it maintains the being of what is fed, and that continues to be what it is so long as the process as
soul in
it is
[75] of nutrition continues. Further, it is the agent in generation, i.e. not the generation of the individual fed but the reproduction of another like it; the substance of the individual fed is already in existence; the existence of no substance is a self-generation but only a self-
maintenance.
Hence the psychic power which we are now studying may be described as that which tends to maintain whatever has this power in it of continuing such as it was, and food helps it to do its work. That is why, if deprived of food, it
must
[20]
The
process of nutrition involves three
what is fed, (b) that wherewith it is fed, (c) what does the feeding; of these (c) is the first soul, (a) the body which has that soul in it, (b) the food. But since it is right to call things after the ends they realize, and the factors, (a)
end of
this soul is to
like that in
which
generate another being
it is,
the
soul ought to
first
[25] be named the reproductive soul. The expression (b) 'wherewith it is fed' is ambigu-
ous just as ship
hand
is
is
the expression 'wherewith the
steered'; that
may mean
or (ii) the rudder,
moved and
sets in
merely moved.
i.e.
either (i) the
either (i)
movement, or
(ii)
what what
is
is
We can apply this
analogy here if we recall that all food must be capable of being digested, and that what produces digestion is warmth; that is why everything that has
warmth. [30] We have now given an outline account of the nature of food; further details must be soul in
it
possesses
given in the appropriate place.
these distinctions let us now speak of sensation in the widest sense. Sensa1 tion depends, as we have said, on a process of movement or affection from without, for it is held to be some sort of change of quality. Now
Having made
[55] some thinkers assert that like is affected only by like; in what sense this is possible and
41
a
in
what
sense impossible,
we have
ex-
plained in our general discussion of acting and being acted upon. 2 1
2
4i5 b 24, cf. 410* 25. On Generation and Corruption, 323b
647
arises a
of sense ?
that
It is clear
what
is
sensitive
it
so
ablaze.
In reply
we must
recall that
we use the word
[10] 'perceive' in two ways, for we say (a) that what has the power to hear or see, 'sees' or 'hears',
even though
also (b) that
it is
what
at the
moment asleep,
actually seeing or
is
hearing, 'sees' or 'hears'. Hence 'sense' too must have two meanings, sense potential, and sense actual. Similarly 'to be a sentient' means either (a) to have a certain power or (b) to
manifest a certain activity. To begin with, for [75] a time, let us speak as if there were no difference between (i) being moved or affected, and (ii) being active, for movement is a kind of activity an imperfect kind, as has elsewhere been explained. 3 Everything that is
—
acted upon or moved is acted upon by an agent which is actually at work. Hence it is that in one sense, as has already been stated, 4 what [20] acts and what is acted upon are like, in another unlike, i.e. prior to and during the change the two factors are unlike, after it
like.
But we must now distinguish not only between what is potential and what is actual but also different senses in which things can be said to be potential or actual;
up
to
now we
have been speaking as if each of these phrases had only one sense. We can speak of something as 'a knower' either {a) as when we say that man is a knower, meaning that man falls within the class of beings that know or have [25] knowledge, or (b) as when we are speaking of a man who possesses a knowledge of grammar; each of these is so called as having in him a certain potentiality, but there is a difference between their respective potentialities,
the one (a) being a potential knower, because his
kind or matter
is
such and such, the other
(b), because he can in the absence of any external counteracting cause realize his
i8ff.
is
only potentially, not actually. The power of sense is parallel to what is combustible, for that never ignites itself spontaneously, but requires an agent which has the power of starting ignition; otherwise it could have set itself on fire, and would not have needed actual fire to set
and
cease to be.
4-5
problem: why do we not perceive the senses themselves as well as the external objects of sense, or why without the stimulation of external objects do they not produce sensation, seeing that they contain in [5] themselves fire, earth, and all the other elements, which are the direct or indirect objects
Here
* Physics,
20 b 3 1 257b 8. ,
*
4 1 6* 2Q-
b
9.
knowl-
ON THE SOUL
64 8
knowing
This implies a third meaning of 'a knower' (c), one who is already realizing his knowledge he is a knower in actuality and in the most proper [jo] sense is knowing, e.g. this A. Both the former are potential knowers, who realize their respective potentialities, the one (a) by change of quality, i.e. repeated transitions from one state to its opposite under instruction, the other (b) by the transition from the 41 b inactive possession of sense or grammar to their active exercise. The two kinds of tran-
edge
in actual
at will.
—
hends is individuals, while what knowledge apprehends is universals, and these are in a sense within the soul. That is why a man can exercise his knowledge when he wishes, but his sensation does not depend upon himself [25] a sensible object must be there. A similar statement must be made about our knowledge of what is sensible on the same ground, viz.
—
that the sensible objects are individual
A
[5] and the other potential. For what possesses knowledge becomes an actual knower by a transition which is either not an alteration of it at all (being in reality a development into its true self or actuality) or at least an alteration in a quite different sense from the usual meaning. Hence it is wrong to speak of a wise man as being 'altered' when he uses his wisdom, just as it would be absurd to speak of a builder as
being altered when he building a house. [10]
What
is
using his
knowing
in the case of
skill
in
or under-
standing leads from potentiality to actuality ought not to be called teaching but something else. That which starting with the power to
know
knowledge through knows and has teaching either (a) ought not to
power
be said [75]
of
'to
who
actually
be acted upon' at
must recognize two
all
or (b)
we
senses of alteration,
viz. (i) the substitution of
one quality for an-
other, the first being the contrary of the sec-
ond, or quality ity
(ii)
the development of an existent
from
potentiality in the direction of fix-
or nature.
In the case of what first
ex-
later
more appropriate occasion may be
1
found thoroughly to clear up all this. At pres[jo] ent it must be enough to recognize the distinctions already drawn; a thing may be
two senses, (a) which we might say of a boy that he may become a general or (b) in the sense in which we might say the same of an adult, and there are two corresponding senses 418 a of the term 'a potential sentient'. There are no separate names for the two stages of said to be potential in either of in the sense in
we have
potentiality;
different
pointed out that they are
We
and how they are
different. cannot help using the incorrect terms 'being acted
upon or altered' of the two transitions inAs we have said, 2 what has the power sensation of is potentially like what the pervolved.
ceived object
is
actually; that
beginning of the process of
while at the being acted up-
is,
its
on the two interacting factors are dissimilar, [5] at the end the one acted upon is assimilated to the other and is identical in quality with it.
learns or acquires
the agency of one the
and
ternal.
sition are distinct.
Also the expression 'to be acted upon' has more than one meaning; it may mean either (a) the extinction of one of two contraries by the other, or (b) the maintenance of what is potential by the agency of what is actual and already like what is acted upon, with such likeness as is compatible with one's being actual
418-
heard, &c, are outside. The ground of this difference is that what actual sensation appre-
transition
is
due
is
to possess sense, the
to the action of the
male
In dealing with each of the senses we shall have first to speak of the objects which are perceptible by each.
The term
'object of sense'
two kinds of our language, directly perceptible, while the remaining one is only incidentally perceptible. Of the first two kinds one (a) consists of what is perceptible by a single sense, [10] the other (b) of what is perceptible by any and all of the senses. I call by the name of covers three kinds of objects,
which
are, in
special object of this or that sense that
which
parent and takes place before birth so that at birth the living thing is, in respect of sensation, at the stage which corresponds to the posses-
cannot be perceived by any other sense than that one and in respect of which no error is
sion of knowledge.
ject of sight,
Actual sensation corre-
sponds to the stage of the exercise of knowledge. But between the two cases compared [20] there is a difference; the objects that exthe sensory powers to activity, the seen, the
cite
possible; in this sense colour
is
the special ob-
sound of hearing, flavour of
taste.
Touch, indeed, discriminates more than one set of different qualities. Each sense has one [75] kind of object which it discerns, and nev1
ni. 4, 5.
2
417® 12-20.
BOOK
419* er errs in reporting that
what
is
before
II, it
CHAPTERS is
colour or sound (though it may err as to what it is that is coloured or where that is, or what it
is
that
is
objects are
sounding or where that is.) Such what we propose to call the special
objects of this or that sense.
'Common number,
are
sensibles'
movement,
rest,
magnitude; these are not pe-
figure,
culiar to any one sense, but are common to all. There are at any rate certain kinds of movement which are perceptible both by touch and
by
We
speak of an incidental object of sense [20] where e.g. the white object which we see is the son of Diares; here because 'being the son of is
incidental to
the directly visible
white patch we speak of the son of Diares as being (incidentally) perceived or seen by us. Because this is only incidentally an object of sense, it in no way as such affects the senses. Of the two former kinds, both of which are in their own nature perceptible by sense, the first
kind
6 49
same in both and is also found in the eternal body which constitutes the uppermost shell of the physical Cosmos. Of this substance light the activity of what is transis the activity
—
parent so far forth as it has in it the determi[10] nate power of becoming transparent; where this power is present, there is also the potentiality of the contrary, viz. darkness. Light is as it were the proper colour of what is
and
transparent, ly
transparent
whenever the
exists
is
potential-
excited to actuality by the in-
fluence of fire or something resembling 'the
sight.
Diares'
5-7
—that of —constitute
objects of the
special
several
the objects of sense in the [25] strictest sense of the term and it is to them that in the nature of things the structure
senses
of each several sense
is
adapted.
uppermost body'; for fire too contains someis one and the same with the sub-
thing which
stance in question.
We
have now explained what the transparand what light is; light is neither fire nor any kind whatsoever of body nor an efflux [75] from any kind of body (if it were, it would again itself be a kind of body) it is the presence of fire or something resembling fire in what is transparent. It is certainly not a body, for two bodies cannot be present in the same place. The opposite of light is darkness; darkness is the absence from what is transparent
is
—
ent of the corresponding positive state above characterized; clearly therefore, light is just the presence of that.
Empedocles (and with him all others used the same forms of expression) was wrong in speaking of light as 'travelling' or being at a given moment between the earth [20]
The
object of sight
the visible, and
is
what
is visible is (a) colour and (b) a certain kind of object which can be described in words but which has no single name; what we mean by (b) will be abundantly clear as we proceed.
Whatever is visible what lies upon what [50] ble; 'in that visibility
its
own
is is
colour and colour is in its own nature visi-
nature' here
means not
involved in the definition of what thus underlies colour, but that that substratum contains in itself the cause of visibility. Every colour has in it the power to set in movement what is actually transparent; that is
who
and
envelope,
its
movement being unob-
its
servable by us; that view
the clear evidence of
served facts;
if
is
contrary both to
argument and
to the obthe distance traversed were
[25] short, the movement might have been unobservable, but where the distance is from ex-
treme East to extreme West, the draught upon our powers of belief is too great.
What
constitutes its very nature. That not visible except with the help of light; it is only in light that the colour of a thing is seen. Hence our first task is to explain
is what what can take on sound is what is soundless; what is colourless includes (a) what is transparent and (b) what is invisible or scarcely visible, i.e. what is [50] 'dark'. The latter (b) is the same as what
what
is
418 b power is
why
it is
light
Now
is.
there clearly
is
something which
is
in itself
is
capable of taking on colour
is
colourless, as
transparent,
course
when
when
it is
and by 'transparent' I mean what [5] is visible, and yet not visible in itself, but rather owing its visibility to the colour of something else; of this character are air, water, and many solid bodies. Neither air nor water
same substance which
transparent because it is air or water; they are transparent because each of them has contained in it a certain substance which is the
sight
transparent,
is
potentially, not of
is
it
actually transparent; is
now
it is
darkness,
the
now
light.
419 a Not everything that is visible depends upon light for its visibility. This is only true of the 'proper' colour of things.
which
Some
objects of
in light are invisible, in darkness
stimulate the sense; that fiery or shining.
This
is,
things that appear
class of objects
has no
ON THE SOUL
650 simple
common name,
but instances of
it
are
[5] fungi, flesh, heads, scales, and eyes of fish. In none of these is what is seen their own
'proper' colour.
Why we
other question.
At present what
is anobvious is that what is seen in light is always colour. That is why without the help of light colour remains invisible. Its being colour at all means
[10] precisely
its
having in
movement what
in
parent, and, as
what
see these at all
is
it
the
is
power
—
[35] smell
I
say 'in water' because animals
that live in water as well as those that live on 419 b land seem to possess the sense of smell,
and
'in air'
because
man and all
seen, the actuality of
transparent is just light. following experiment makes the necessity of a medium clear. If what has colour is placed in immediate contact with the eye, it cannot be seen. Colour sets in movement not the sense organ but what is transparent, e.g. the air, and that, extending continuously from [75] the object to the organ, sets the latter in movement. Democritus misrepresents the facts when he expresses the opinion that if the inis
The
other land ani-
mals that breathe, perceive smells only when they breathe air in. The explanation of this too will be given later. 2 8
to set
already actually trans-
we have
419 b
Now
let us,
to begin with,
tinctions about
make
certain dis-
sound and hearing.
[5] Sound may mean either of two things (a) actual, and (b) potential, sound. There are certain things which, as we say, 'have no
sound', e.g. sponges or wool, others which have, e.g. bronze and in general all things which are smooth and solid the latter are
—
between. Hence it is indispensable that there if there were [20] be something in between nothing, so far from seeing with greater distinctness, we should see nothing at all. We have now explained the cause why colour cannot be seen otherwise than in light. Fire on the other hand is seen both in darkness and in light; this double possibility follows necessarily from our theory, for it is just fire that makes what is potentially transparent
sound because they can make a sound, i.e. can generate actual sound between themselves and the organ of hearing. Actual sound requires for its occurrence ii) two such bodies and (iii) a space befi, 10] tween them; for it is generated by an impact. Hence it is impossible for one body only to generate a sound there must be a body impinging and a body impinged upon; what sounds does so by striking against something else, and this is impossible without a movement from place to place. As we have said, not all bodies can by impact on one another produce sound; impact on wool makes no sound, while the impact on [75] bronze or any body which is smooth and hollow does. Bronze gives out a sound when struck because it is smooth; bodies which are hollow owing to reflection repeat the original impact over and over again, the body original-
actually transparent.
ly set in
were empty one could
an an impossibility. Seeing is due to an affection or change of what has the perceptive faculty, and it cannot be affected by the seen colour itself; it remains that it must be affected by what comes terspace
distinctly see
ant on the vault of the sky; that
is
—
The same account
holds also of sound and smell; if the object of either of these senses is in immediate contact with the organ no sensation is produced. In both cases the object sets [25]
movement only what
lies between, and this organ in movement: if what sounds or smells is brought into immediate contact with the organ, no sensation will be [jo] produced. The same, in spite of all appearances, applies also to touch and taste; why there is this apparent difference will be clear 1 later. What comes between in the case of sounds is air; the corresponding medium in the case of smell has no name. But, corresponding to what is transparent in the case of colour, there is a quality found both in air and
in
in turn sets the
water, which serves as a 1
4« b 34ff-
medium
for
what has
said to have a
—
movement being unable
to escape
from the concavity. Further, we must remark that sound is heard both in air and in water, though less distinctly in the latter. Yet neither air nor water is
the principal cause of sound.
What
is
re-
[20] quired for the production of sound is an impact of two solids against one another and against the air. The latter condition is satisfied
when
That
is
why
sharp blow, of the
upon does not retreat not dissipated by it. must be struck with a sudden
the air impinged
before the blow, it
i.e. is
if it is
to
sound
whip must outrun
air, just as
—the movement
the dispersion of the
one might get in a stroke
or whirl of sand as
it
at a
heap
was traveling rapidly
past.
[25]
An
echo occurs, when, a mass of
*42i b 13-422"
6.
air
hav-
BOOK
420**
II,
CHAPTERS
7-8
651
bounded, and prevented
reverberate like a horn; the air inside the ear
from dissipation by the containing walls of a by the impinging body and set in movement by it rebounds from this mass of air like a ball from a wall. It is probable that in all generation of sound echo takes place, though it is frequently only indistinctly heard. What happens here must be analogous to what happens in the case of light; otherwise it would light is always reflected [jo] not be diffused and outside what was directly illuminated by the sun there would be
has always a movement of its own, but the sound we hear is always the sounding of something else, not of the organ itself. That is why we say that we hear with what is empty and echoes, viz. because what we hear with is a
ing been
unified,
vessel, the air originally struck
—
blank darkness; but this reflected light is not always strong enough, as it is when it is reflected from water, bronze, and other smooth bodies, to cast a
guishing It is
shadow, which
is
the distin-
mark by which we recognize
rightly said that
light.
an empty space plays
the chief part in the production of hearing, for is the air,
what people mean by 'the vacuum' which is what causes hearing, when
that air
is
movement as one continuous mass; but owing to its friability it emits no sound, being dissipated by impinging upon any sur420 a face which is not smooth. When the surface on which it impinges is quite smooth, what is produced by the original impact is a set in
[35]
united mass, a result due to the smoothness of the surface with which the air is in contact at the other end. What has the power of producing sound is what has the power of setting in movement a single mass of air which is continuous from the impinging body up to the organ of hearing. The organ of hearing is physically united with air, and because it is in air, the air inside [5] is moved concurrently with the air outside. Hence animals do not hear with all parts of their bodies, nor
do
all
parts admit of the en-
trance of air; for even the part
which can be
moved and can sound has not air everywhere in it. Air in itself is, owing to its friability, quite soundless; only when its dissipation is prevented is its movement sound. The air in chamber just to prevent movement, in order that the [10] animal may accurately apprehend all varieties of the movements of the air outside. That is why we hear also in water, viz. because the water cannot get into the air chamber or even, owing to the spirals, into the outer the ear
is
built into a
this dissipating
happen, hearing ceases, as it the tympanic membrane is dam-
ear. If this does
also does
if
aged, just as sight ceases if the membrane covering the pupil is damaged. It is also a test of [75] deafness whether the ear does or does not
chamber which contains
Which
is it
a
bounded mass of air. body
that 'sounds', the striking
Is not the answer 'it is both, but each in a different way'? Sound is a movement of what can rebound from a smooth surface when struck against it. As we have explained not everything sounds when it strikes or is struck, e.g. if one needle is struck against another, neither emits any sound. In order, [25] therefore, that sound may be generated; what is struck must be smooth, to enable the air to rebound and be shaken off from it in one
or the struck? [20]
1
piece.
The
between different sounding in actual sound; as without the help of light colours remain invisible, so without the help of actual sound the distinctions between acute and grave sounds remain inaudible. Acute and grave are here metaphors, transferred from their proper sphere, viz. that of touch, where they mean bodies
distinctions
show themselves only
what moves the sense what moves the sense little in a long time. Not that what is sharp really moves fast, and what is grave, [jo] respectively (a)
much
in a short time, (b)
slowly, but that the difference in the qualities
and the other movement is due to There seems to be a between what is acute or grave to hearing and what is sharp or blunt to touch; what is sharp as it were stabs, while what is blunt pushes, the one producing its efof the one
their respective speeds. 420b sort of parallelism
fect in a short, the other in a
the one
is
long time, so that
quick, the other slow.
[5] Let the foregoing suffice as an analysis of sound. Voice is a kind of sound characteristic of what has soul in it; nothing that is without soul utters voice, it being only by a metaphor that we speak of the voice of the flute or the
what (being without soul) power of producing a succession of notes which differ in length and pitch and timbre. The metaphor is based on the fact that all these differences are found also in voice. lyre or generally of
possesses the
Many animals are voiceless, e.g. all non-sanguineous animals and among sanguineous ani[10] mals fish. This is just what we should exis a certain movement of air. those in the Achelous, which are
pect, since voice
The x
fish, like
^6,
13.
ON THE SOUL
65 2
said to have voice, really make the sounds with their gills or some similar organ. Voice is the sound made by an animal, and that with a special organ. As we saw, everything that makes a sound does so by the impact of something (a) [75] against something else, (b) across a space, (c) filled with air; hence it is only to be expected that no animals utter voice except those
Once air is inbreathed, Natwo different purposes, as the used both for tasting and for articuthat case of the two functions tasting
421 b
Why
they do not [5] or take in air. tion belonging to another inquiry. 2
the distinguishing characteristic of the object of smell is less obvious than those of sound or
The ground
which take
in air.
colour.
for
of smell
tongue
is
lating; in is
necessary for the animal's existence (hence
it
is
found more widely distributed), while
articulate speech
is
a luxury subserving
its
pos-
former case [20] Nature employs the breath both as an in-
sessor's well-being; similarly in the
dispensable
means
to the regulation of the in-
ner temperature of the living body and also as the matter of articulate voice, in the interests of
its
use
possessor's well-being.
indispensable
is
Why
its
former
must be discussed
else-
where. 1
The organ
of respiration
is
the windpipe,
and the organ to which this is related as means to end is the lungs. The latter is the part of the body by which the temperature of land [25] animals is raised above that of all others. But what primarily requires the air drawn in
by respiration is not only this but the region surrounding the heart. That is why when animals breathe the air must penetrate inwards. Voice then is the impact of the inbreathed air against the 'windpipe', and the agent that produces the impact is the soul resident in these parts of the body. Not every sound, as we [30] said, made by an animal is voice (even with the tongue we may merely make a sound which is not voice, or without the tongue as in coughing); what produces the impact must have soul in it and must be accompanied by an act of imagination, for voice is a sound with a meaning, and is not merely the result of any impact of the breath as in coughing; in voice the breath in the windpipe is used as an instrument to knock with against the walls of the 421 a windpipe. This is confirmed by our inability to speak when we are breathing either out or in we can only do so by holding our breath; we make the movements with the breath so checked. It is clear also why fish are voiceless; they have no windpipe. And they have no windpipe because they do not breathe
—
1
On
Breathing, 478* 28;
On
the Parts
of Animals, 642*
a ques-
Smell and its object are much less easy to determine than what we have hitherto discussed;
ture uses
it
is
is
less
of this
is
that our
power
discriminating and in general
[10] inferior to that of many species of animals; men have a poor sense of smell and our
apprehension of its proper objects is inseparably bound up with and so confused by pleasure and pain, which shows that in us the organ is inaccurate. It is probable that there is a parallel failure in the perception of colour
by animals that have hard eyes: probably they discriminate differences of colour only by the presence or absence of what excites fear, and [75] that it is thus that human beings distinguish smells. It seems that there is an analogy
between smell and taste, and that the species of tastes run parallel to those of smells the only difference being that our sense of taste is more discriminating than our sense of smell, because the former is a modification of touch, which reaches in man the maximum of dis-
—
criminative accuracy. While in respect of all [20] the other senses we fall below many species of animals, in respect of all
touch
we
far excel
other species in exactness of discrimination.
That
is
why man
animals. This
is
the most intelligent of
all
confirmed by the fact that it is to differences in the organ of touch and to nothing else that the differences between man is
man in respect of natural endowment are men whose flesh is hard are ill-endowed [25] by nature, men whose flesh is soft, well-
and
due;
endowed.
As flavours may be divided into (a) sweet, (b) bitter, so with smells. In some things the flavour and the smell have the same quality, i.e. both are sweet or both bitter, in others they diverge. Similarly a smell, like a flavour, may [50] be pungent, astringent, acid, or succulent. But, as we said, because smells are much less easy to discriminate than flavours, the names of these varieties are applied to smells only 421 b metaphorically; for example 'sweet' is extended from the taste to the smell of saffron or honey, 'pungent' to that of thyme, and so on. In the same sense in which hearing has for 2
Cf.
On
Breathing, 474 b 25-9, 476* 6-15;
Animals, 669* 2-5.
On the Parts of
BOOK
422*
II,
CHAPTERS
and the inaudible, [5] sight both the visible and the invisible, smell has for its object both the odorous and its
object both the audible
may
be either (a) what has no smell at all, or (b) what has a small or feeble smell. The same ambiguity the inodorous. 'Inodorous'
word
lurks in the
i.e.
through
air or
water
—
add wa-
I
ter,
distance
has any scent. That
if it
why
is
the
following facts constitute a problem for us. All animals smell in the same way, but man smells only when he inhales; if he exhales or holds his breath, he ceases to smell, no difference being [75] made whether the odorous object is distant or near, or even placed inside the nose and actually on the wall of the nostril; it is a disability
common
to all the senses not to per-
what is in immediate contact with the organ of sense, but our failure to apprehend what is odorous without the help of inhalation is peculiar (the fact is obvious on making the experiment). Now since bloodless animals do [20] not breathe, they must, it might be argued, have some novel sense not reckoned ceive
among this
is
the usual five.
Our
impossible, since
it
reply is
must be
scent that
ceived; a sense that apprehends
what
is
is
that per-
odor-
ous and what has a good or bad odour cannot be anything but smell. Further, they are observed to be deleteriously effected by the same strong odours as man is, e.g. bitumen, sulphur, [25] and the like. These animals must be able to smell without being able to breathe. The probable explanation is that in man the organ of smell has a certain superiority over that in all other animals just as his eyes have over those of hard-eyed animals. Man's eyes have in the eyelids a kind of shelter or envelope, which must be shifted or drawn back in order [30] that we may see, while hardeyed animals have nothing of the kind, but at once see what-
of smell
the transparent
422 a mals, uncurtained, while is
in others
which
probably has a curtain over it, drawn back in inhalation, owing to it
the dilating of the veins or pores. That explains also why such animals cannot smell un-
is
tangible.
Hence,
if
we
lived
we
should perceive a sweet object introduced into the water, but the water would not be the medium through which we perceived; our perception would be due to the solution of the sweet substance in what we imbibed, just as if it were mixed with some drink. There is no parallel here to the percepin water,
tion of colour,
which
is
due neither
to
any
blending of anything with anything, nor to any efflux of anything from anything. In the [75] case of taste, there is nothing corresponding to the medium in the case of the senses previously discussed; but as the object of sight is
colour, so the object of taste
is
flavour.
But
nothing excites a perception of flavour without
what acts upon the sense of must be either actually or potentially liquid like what is saline; it must be both (a) itself easily dissolved, and (b) capable of disthe help of liquid;
taste
[20] solving along with itself the tongue. Taste apprehends both (a) what has taste and (b) what has no taste, if we mean by (b) what
has only a slight or feeble flavour or what tends to destroy the sense of taste. In this it is exactly parallel to sight, which apprehends both
what
and what is invisible (for darkand yet is discriminated by sight; so is, in a different way, what is overbrilliant), and to hearing, which apprehends both sound and silence, of which the one is [25] audible and the other inaudible, and also ness
is
is
visible
invisible
over-loud sound. This corresponds in the case of hearing to over-bright light in the case of sense
which
dry as flavours
potentially dry.
matter, and this
sight.
itself in
is
moist. Consequently the organ
can be tasted is always something that can be touched, and just for that reason it cannot be perceived through an interposed foreign body, for touch means the absence of any in[10] tervening body. Further, the flavoured and tasteable body is suspended in a liquid
medium.
take in air
is
is
What
Similarly in certain species of animals the organ of smell is like the eye of hard-eyed ani-
ever presents
come from what
Smells
from what
10
because water-animals too (both sanguineous and non-sanguineous) seem to smell just as much as land-animals; at any rate some of them make directly for their food from a [jo]
653
[5] der water; to smell they must first inhale, and that they cannot do under water.
'tasteless'.
Smelling, like the operation of the senses previously examined, takes place through a
medium,
8-10
As is
a faint
sound
is
'inaudible', so in a
a loud or violent sound.
The word
'in-
and similar privative terms cover not only (a) what is simply without some power, but also (b) what is adapted by nature to have it but has not it or has it only in a very low
visible'
degree, as
low
is
when we
'footless'
say that a species of swal-
or that a variety of fruit
is
ON THE SOUL
654
So too
'stoneless'.
what can be
[30]
taste has as
its
object both
—
and the tasteless the what has little flavour or
tasted
latter in the sense of
a bad flavour or one destructive of taste.
difference between
what
The
and what is not seems to rest ultimately on that between what is drinkable and what is undrinkable both are tasteable, but the latter is bad and is
tasteless
tends to destroy taste, while the former
normal stimulus of
What
is
the
423
s
range between a single pair of contraries, white and black for sight, acute and grave for [25] hearing, bitter and sweet for taste; but in the field of
what
is
tangible
we
find several
such pairs, hot cold, dry moist, hard
soft, &c.
This problem finds a partial solution, when is
it
recalled that in the case of the other senses
more than one
pair of contraries are to be met with, e.g. in sound not only acute and grave
is
[30] but loud and soft, smooth and rough, &c; there are similar contrasts in the field of colour.
tasted is liquid, the perception cannot be either (a) actually liquid or (b) incapable of becoming
Nevertheless we are unable clearly to detect in the case of touch what the single subject is
common
the
taste.
is
object of both touch
drinkable
and
taste.
422 b Since what can be organ for
its
Tasting means a being affected by what can be tasted as such; hence the organ of taste must be liquefied, and so to start with must be non-liquid but capable of liquefaction without loss of its distinctive nature. This is [5] confirmed by the fact that the tongue cannot taste either when it is too dry or when it is liquid.
too moist; in the latter case to a contact
what occurs
is
due
with the pre-existent moisture in
when after a foretaste of we try to taste another flavour; it is in this way that sick persons find everything they taste bitter, viz. because, when the tongue
some strong
itself,
flavour
they taste, their tongues are overflowing with
which underlies the contrasted qualities and corresponds to sound in the case of hearing. To the question whether the organ of touch lies inward or not (i.e. whether we need look any farther than the flesh), no indication in 423 a favour of the second answer can be drawn from the fact that if the object comes into contact with the flesh
stretching
web
is
it
same manner
as before, yet
would
report
plays in touch very
on the
and the
bitter,
(b) secondary, viz.
side of the sweet, the succulent, (ii)
on the side of the bitter, the saline, (iii) between these come the pungent, the harsh, the astringent, and the acid; these pretty well exhaust the varieties of flavour.
It
follows that
[75] what has the power of tasting is potentially of that kind, and that what able ally
what has the power of making what it itself already is. is
what
is
is
taste-
it
actu-
11
Whatever can be
said of
what
is
tangible,
can be said of touch, and vice versa; if touch is not a single sense but a group of senses, there must be several kinds of what is tangible. It is a problem whether touch is a single sense or a [20] group of senses. It is also a problem, what is the organ of touch; is it or is it not the flesh (including what in certain animals is homologous with flesh)? On the second view, flesh is 'the medium' of touch, the real organ being situated farther inward. The problem arises because the field of each sense is according to the accepted view determined as the
at
once per-
is
reported in the
it is
clear that the
organ is not in this membrane. If the mem[5] brane could be grown on to the flesh, the
[10] The species of flavour are, as in the case of colour, (a) simple, i.e. the two contraries, (i)
is
tight over the flesh, as soon as this
touched the sensation
bitter moisture.
the sweet
it
For even under present conditions if the experiment is made of making a web and
ceived.
travel
still
quicker.
much
the
The
flesh
same part
as
would be played in the other senses by an airenvelope growing round our body; had we such an envelope attached to us we should have supposed that it was by a single organ that
we
perceived sounds, colours, and smells,
and we should have taken
sight, hearing,
and
[10] smell to be a single sense. But as it is, because that through which the different move-
ments are transmitted is not naturally attached to our bodies, the difference of the various sense-organs is too plain to miss. But in the case of touch the obscurity remains. There must be such a naturally attached
no living body could be it must be something solid. Consequently it must be composed of earth along with these, which is just what flesh and its analogue in animals which have no true flesh tend to be. Hence of neces[75] sity the medium through which are trans'medium'
as flesh, for
constructed of air or water;
mitted the manifoldly contrasted tactual qualities must be a body naturally attached to the organism. That they are manifold is clear when we consider touching with the tongue; we apprehend at the tongue all tangible qualities as
well as flavour. Suppose
all
the rest of
424
BOOK
a
II,
CHAPTERS
was, like the tongue, sensitive to flavour, we should have identified the sense of [20] taste and the sense of touch; what saves us from this identification is the fact that touch
our
flesh
and taste are not always found together in the same part of the body. The following problem might be raised. Let us assume that every body has depth, i.e. has three dimensions, and that if two bodies have a third body between them they cannot be in contact with one another; let
us
[25]
remember that what is liquid is a body and must be or contain water, and that if
two bodies touch one another under water, touching surfaces cannot be dry, but
their
must have water between, viz. the water which wets their bounding surfaces; from all this it follows that in water two bodies cannot be in contact with one another. The same holds of two bodies in air air being to bodies in air precisely what water is to bodies in wa-
—
[50] ter
—but the
facts are
not so evident to
10-11
to the real
655
organs of touch and
taste, as air
and
water are to those of sight, hearing, and smell. [20] Hence in neither the one case nor the other can there be any perception of an object if it is placed immediately upon the organ, e.g. if a white object is placed on the surface of the eye. This again shows that what has the power of perceiving the tangible
Only with
so
would there be
is
seated inside.
a complete analogy
if you on the organ it is not per[25] ceived, here if you place it on the flesh it is perceived; therefore flesh is not the organ
the other senses. In their case
all
place the object
medium
but the
of touch.
What
can be touched are distinctive qualiof body as body; by such differences I
ties
mean viz,
those which characterize the elements, hot cold, dry moist, of which we have
[jo] spoken earlier in our treatise on the ele-
ments. is
1
The organ
that of touch
for the perception of these
—that part of the body
in
which
our observation, because we live in air, just as animals that live in water would not notice that the things which touch one another in 423 b water have wet surfaces. The problem,
primarily the sense of touch resides. This is that part which is potentially such as its object
does the perception of all objects of sense take place in the same way, or does it not, e.g. taste and touch requiring contact (as they are commonly thought to do), while all
424a something such as it itself actually is makes the other such because the other is already potentially such. That is why when an
then,
is:
other senses perceive over a distance ? The distinction is unsound; we perceive what is hard [5] or soft, as well as the objects of hearing, and smell, through a 'medium', only that
sight,
the latter are perceived over a greater distance than the former; that is why the facts escape our notice. For we do perceive everything through a medium; but in these cases the fact
what we said before, touch were a membrane
escapes us. Yet, to repeat if
the
medium
for
separating us from the object without our observing its existence, we should be relatively to [10]
it
in the
same condition
as
we
are
now
to
water in which we are immersed; in their case we fancy we can touch objects, nothing coming in between us and them. But there remains this difference between what can be touched and what can be seen or can sound; in the latter two cases we perceive because the medium produces a certain effect upon us, whereas in the perception of objects of touch we are affected not by but along with the meair or
[75] dium; it is as if a man were struck through his shield, where the shock is not first given to the shield and passed on to the man, but the concussion of both is simultaneous. In general, flesh and the tongue are related
is
actually: for all sense-perception
of being so affected; so that that
is
a process
which makes
is equally hot and cold or hard and soft we cannot perceive; what we perceive must have a degree of the sensible quality lying beyond the neutral point. This implies that the sense itself is a 'mean' between any two opposite qualities which determine the field of [5] that sense. It is to this that it owes its power of discerning the objects in that field.
object of touch
What
is
'in
the middle'
relatively to either
is
fitted to discern;
extreme
in the place of the other.
can put
it
As what
is
itself
to per-
white and black must, to begin be actually neither but potentially either (and so with all the other sense-organs), ceive both
with,
so the organ of touch must be neither hot nor cold.
had for its what was visible and what was (and there was a parallel truth about
[10] Further, as in a sense sight object both invisible all
the other senses discussed),
2
so touch has
what is tangible and what is intangible. Here by 'intangible' is meant (a) what like air possesses some quality of tangible things in a very slight degree and (b) what possesses it in an excessive degree, as defor
its
object both
structive things do. 1
2
On Generation and Corruption, 42i b 3-6, 422*29.
II.
2, 3.
ON THE SOUL
65 6
We
have now given an outline account [75] of each of the several senses.
424 b
b
424 perature can be lowered or raised. The explanation is that they have no mean of contrary qualities,
and
so
no principle
in
them
The
capable of taking on the forms of sensible objects without their matter; in the case of plants the affection is an affection by form-and-matter
every sense
together.
12
following results applying to any and may now be formulated. (A) By a 'sense' is meant what has the pow-
er of receiving into itself the sensible forms of
things without the matter. This must be conceived of as taking place in the way in which a piece of wax takes on the impress of a signet[20] ring without the iron or gold;
what produces the impression bronze or gold, but stitution
the sense
makes no
we
say that
a signet of
particular metallic con-
its
difference: in a similar
affected by
is
is
what
is
way
coloured or
fla-
voured or sounding, but it is indifferent what in each case the substance is; what alone mat-
what
ters is
quality
it
has,
i.e.
in
what
ratio its
The problem might be raised: Can what cannot smell be said to be affected by [5] smells or what cannot see by colours, and so on? It might be said that a smell is just what can be smelt, and if it produces any effect it can only be so as to make something smell it, and it might be argued that what cannot smell cannot be affected by smells and further that what can smell can be affected by it only in so far as it has in it the power to smell (similarly with the proper objects of all the other senses). Indeed that this is so is made quite evident as [10] follows. Light or darkness, sounds and
what does not these but the bodies which
smells leave bodies quite unaffected;
constituents are combined.
affect bodies
(B) By 'an organ of sense' is meant that in which ultimately such a power is seated. [25] The sense and its organ are the same in
are their vehicles, e.g.
but their essence
fact,
What
not the same.
is
of course, a spatial magnitude, but
perceives
is,
we must
not admit that either the having the
power
to perceive or the sense itself
nitude;
what they
are
is
is
a
a certain ratio or
magpow-
er in a magnitude. This enables us to explain
why
objects of sense
which
possess one of
two
opposite sensible qualities in a degree largely in excess of the other opposite destroy the or[3°] g ans °f sense; if the movement set up by an object is too strong for the organ, the equipoise of contrary qualities in the organ, just is
its
sensory power,
is
disturbed;
which
it is
pre-
concord and tone are destroyed by too violently twanging the strings of a lyre. This explains also why plants cannot perceive, in spite of their having a portion of soul in them and obviously being affected by tangible objects themselves; for undoubtedly their temcisely as
is
what
splits
the trunk of
not the sound of the thunder but the air which accompanies thunder. Yes, but, it may be objected, bodies are affected by what is tangible and by flavours. If not, by what are things that are without soul affected, i.e. ala tree
is
tered in quality ?
Must we
not, then,
the objects of the other senses also
them?
admit that
may
affect
not the true account this, that all bodies are capable of being affected by smells [75] and sounds, but that some on being acted upon, having no boundaries of their own, disintegrate, as in the instance of air, which does become odorous, showing that some effect is produced on it by what is odorous ? But smelling is more than such an affection by what is odorous what more ? Is not the answer that, while the air owing to the momentary duration of the action upon it of what is odorous does itself become perceptible to the sense of smell, smelling is an observing of the result Is
produced ?
BOOK
III
sence of a sense necessarily involves absence of and if (1) all objects that we
a sense-organ;
That
[20]
to the five taste,
touch
there is no enumerated
sixth sense in addition
—
sight, hearing, smell,
—may be established by the follow-
ing considerations: If
we have
actually sensation of everything
which touch can give us sensation (for all [25] the qualities of the tangible qua tangible are perceived by us through touch); and if ab-
of
them are which sense we actually
perceive by immediate contact with perceptible by touch,
and (2) all objects that we perceive through media, i.e. without immediate contact, [50] are perceptible by or through the simple elements, e.g. air and water (and this is so arranged that (a) if more than one kind of sensible object is perceivable through a single mepossess,
BOOK
425 b
II,
11-12— BOOK
CHAPTERS
dium, the possessor of a sense-organ homogeneous with that medium has the power of perceiving both kinds of objects; for example, if the sense-organ
is
made
of
air,
and
air
is
a
425 a the same kind of
sensible objects, as e.g.
CHAPTERS
1-2
657
Cleon's son but as white, and the white thing which we really perceive happens to be Cleon's son.
me-
dium both for sound and for colour; and that (b) if more than one medium can transmit
III,
But
in the
there
case of the
already in
is
common
sensibles
us a general sensibility
which enables us to perceive them directly; there is therefore no special sense required for
water as well as air can transmit colour, both being transparent, then the possessor of either alone will be able to perceive the kind of objects transmissible through both); and if of the
their perception:
simple elements two only, air and water, go to form sense-organs (for the pupil is made of water, the organ of hearing is made of air, and the organ of smell of one or other of these
objects incidentally; not because the percipient
found either in none or an essential condition of and earth either in none or, if all sensibility anywhere, specially mingled with the components of the organ of touch; wherefore it would remain that there can be no sense-organ formed of anything except water and air); and if these sense-organs are actually found in cer[5] two, while fire is warmth being in all
—
—
tain animals;
—then
the possible senses are
all
[10] possessed by those animals that are not imperfect or mutilated (for even the mole is observed to have eyes 'beneath its skin); so that, if there is no fifth element and no property other than those which belong to the four
elements of our world, no sense can be wanting to such animals. Further, there cannot be a special sense[75] organ for the common sensibles either, i.e.
the objects
which we perceive
incidentally
through this or that special sense, e.g. movement, rest, figure, magnitude, number, unity; for all these we perceive by movement, e.g. magnitude by movement, and therefore also figure (for figure is a species of magnitude), what is at rest by the absence of movement: number is perceived by the negation of continuity, and by the special sensibles; for each sense perceives one class of sensible objects. So [20] that it is clearly impossible that there should be a special sense for any one of the
common
sensibles, e.g.
movement;
for, if that
our perception of it would be exactly parallel to our present perception of what is sweet by vision. That is so because we have a sense for each of the two qualities, in virtue of which when they happen to meet in one sensible object we are aware of both contemporaneously. If it were not like this our per-
were
so,
[25] ception of the
common
always be incidental, Cleon's son, where
we
i.e.
as
is
qualities
would
the perception of
perceive
him not
as
of
if
there were, our perception
them would have been
exactly like
what has
been above 1 described.
The
[50] sense
is
this or that special sense,
form
all
senses perceive each other's special
but because
a unity: this incidental perception
takes place whenever sense is directed at one and the same moment to two disparate qualities in one and the same object, e.g. to the bit425 b terness and the yellowness of bile, the assertion of the identity of both cannot be the act of either of the senses;
sense, e.g. the belief that
hence the illusion of a thing is yellow it
if
is bile.
might be asked why we have more senses
It
[5] than one. Is it to prevent a failure to apprehend the common sensibles, e.g. movement,
magnitude, and number, which go along with Had we no sense but
the special sensibles?
sight, and that sense no object but white, they would have tended to escape our notice and everything would have merged for us into an
indistinguishable identity because of the concomitance of colour and magnitude. As it is, the fact that the common sensibles are given in the objects of more than one sense reveals [10] their distinction from each and all of the special sensibles.
Since that
it
we
is
through sense that
are seeing or hearing,
we
it
we
are
must be
aware either
aware of seeing, or by some sense other than sight. But the sense that gives us this new sensation must perceive both sight and its object, viz. colour: so that either ( 1 ) there will be two senses both percipient of the same sensible object, or (2) the sense must [75] be percipient of itself. Further, even if the sense which perceives sight were different from sight, we must either fall into an infinite regress, or we must somewhere assume a sense which is aware of itself. If so, we ought to do by sight that
are
this in the first case.
This presents a sight
is
just to see,
difficulty: if to perceive
and what
(or the coloured), then Ml. 24-7.
if
is
we
seen
is
by
colour
are to see that
ON THE SOUL
65 8
which
sees, that
which
sees originally
must be
[20] coloured. It is clear therefore that 'to perceive by sight' has more than one meaning; for
when we
by sight that
426 b
&c, while
ing,
as
potentialities
one of them
[20] may exist without the other. The earlier students of nature were mistaken in their view
discriminate darkness from light, though not in the same way as we distinguish one colour from another. Further, in a sense even that
was no white or black, no savour. This statement of theirs is partly true, partly false: 'sense' and 'the sensible object' are ambiguous terms, i.e.
which
may
even
are not seeing,
it is
we
sees is coloured;
sense-organ
is
for in each case the
capable of receiving the sensible
object without
its
matter.
That
is
why
even
that without sight there
without
taste
denote either potentialities or actualities:
[25] the statement is true of the latter, false of the former. This ambiguity they wholly
[25] when the sensible objects are gone the sensings and imaginings continue to exist in
failed to notice.
the sense-organs.
voice
voice always implies a concord,
of the percipient sense is one and the same activity, and yet the distinctipn between their
and if the and the hearing of it are in one sense one and the same, and if concord always implies a ratio, hearing as well as what is heard must [jo] be a ratio. That is why the excess of ei-
being remains. Take as
ther the sharp or the
The
activity of the sensible object
and that
illustration
actual
sound and actual hearing: a man may have hearing and yet not be hearing, and that which has a sound is not always sounding. But when that which can hear is actively hearing and [jo] that which can sound is sounding, then the actual hearing and the actual sound are merged in one (these one might call respec426 a tively hearkening and sounding). If it is true that the movement, both the acting and the being acted upon, is to be found in that which is acted upon, both the sound and the hearing so far as it is actual must be found in that which has the faculty of hearing; for
in the passive factor that the actuality
it is
of the active or motive factor is realized; that [5] is why that which causes movement may be at rest.
Now
sound
just
the actuality of that which can sound or sounding, and the actuality of that which can hear is hearing or hearkening; 'sound' and 'hearing' are both ambiguous. The same account applies to the other senses and their objects. For as the-acting-and[10] being-acted-upon is to be found in the is
passive, not in the active factor, so also the actuality of the sensible object
and that of the
sensitive subject are both realized in the latter.
But while
in
some
cases each aspect of the total
actuality has a distinct
name,
e.g.
sounding and
hearkening, in some one or other
is
nameless,
e.g. the actuality of sight is called seeing,
the actuality of colour has
no name: the
but
actu-
ality of the faculty of taste is called tasting,
but
no name. Since the of the sensible object and of
the actuality of flavour has
[75] actualities the sensitive faculty are one actuality in spite
modes of being, and actual sounding appear and disappear from existence at one and the same moment, and so actual savour and actual tastof the difference between their actual hearing
If
426 b (So
flat
destroys the hearing.
also in the case of savours excess de-
and in the case of colours excessive brightness or darkness destroys stroys the sense of taste,
and in the case of smell excess of strength whether in the direction of sweetness or bitterness is destructive.) This shows that the sight,
the sense
That
is
pleasant
a ratio.
why when the
is
also
the objects of sense are (1) sensible extremes such as
acid or sweet or salt being pure
and unmixed
are brought into the proper ratio; then they are
and in general what is blended more pleasant than the sharp or the flat alone; or, to touch, that which is capable of be[5] pleasant:
is
ing either
warmed
or chilled: the sense and
the ratio are identical: while (2) in excess the sensible extremes are painful or destructive.
Each sense then is relative to its particular group of sensible qualities: it is found in a sense-organ as such and discriminates the differences which exist within that group; e.g. [10] sight discriminates white and black, taste sweet and bitter, and so in all cases. Since we also discriminate white from sweet, and indeed each sensible quality from every other, with what do we perceive that they are different? It must be by sense; for what is before us is [75] sensible objects. (Hence it is also obvious that the flesh cannot be the ultimate sense-or-
gan: if it were, the discriminating power could not do its work without immediate contact
with the object.) Therefore ( 1 ) discrimination between white and sweet cannot be effected by two agencies which remain separate; both the qualities discriminated must be present to something that is one and single. On any other supposition even if I perceived sweet and you perceived [20] white, the difference between them would
BOOK
427 b be apparent. What
III,
CHAPTERS
two things are difsweet is different from
says that
must be one; for what asserts this difference must be self-identical, and as what asserts, so also what thinks or perceives. That it is not possible by means of two agencies which remain separate to discriminate two objects which are* separate, is therefore obvious; and that (2) it is not possible to do this in separate movements of time may be seen if we look at it as follows. For as what asserts the difference between the good and the bad is one and the [25] same, so also the time at which it asserts the one to be different and the other to be different
white. Therefore
ferent
is
not accidental to the assertion (as
for instance
do not it
when I now
assert that there
asserts thus
it is
assert a difference but is
now
a difference);
—both now and that the objects
now; the objects therefore must be present at one and the same moment. Both the discriminating power and the time of its exercise must be one and undivided. are different
But,
it
may
be objected,
it is
impossible that
what is self-identical should be moved at Dne and the same time with contrary movements in so far as it is undivided, and in an undivided moment of time. For if what is sweet be the quality perceived, it moves the [50]
sense
or thought in this
determinate way,
427 a while what is bitter moves it in a contrary way, and what is white in a different way. Is it the case then that what discriminates, though both numerically one and indivisible, is at the same time divided in its being? In one sense, it is what is divided that perceives two separate objects at once, but in
another sense
it
does
it
2-3
659
takes the limit as two,
separate objects with
what
in a sense
takes
it
with what single
is
About
to be affected at
one and the same
that sensation
it
moment by
to be the case
and thinking are properly
so de-
scribed.
[10] The answer is that just as what is called a 'point' is, as being at once one and two, properly said to be divisible, so here, that
discriminates in a single
is
qua undivided one, and
moment
which active
of time, while so far forth
twice over uses the same dot
as
it is
at
one and the same time. So far forth then as
divisible
it
is it
divid-
does so
activity a
its
the principle in virtue of
which we
[75] say that animals are percipient, let this discussion suffice.
There are two distinctive peculiarities by reference to which we characterize the soul (1) local movement and (2) thinking, discriminating, and perceiving. Thinking both speculative and practical is regarded as akin to [20] a form of perceiving; for in the one as well as the other the soul discriminates and is cognizant of something which is. Indeed the ancients go so far as to identify thinking and perceiving; e.g. Empedocles says Tor 'tis in respect of what is present that man's wit is in2 creased', and again 'Whence it befalls them from time to time to think diverse thoughts', 3 [25] and Homer's phrase 'For suchlike is man's mind' means the same. They all look upon thinking as a bodily process like perceiving, and hold that like is \nown as well as 1
perceived by
like, as
I
explained at the begin-
ning of our discussion. 4 Yet they ought at the same time to have accounted for error also; for 427 b it is more intimately connected with animal existence and the soul continues longer in the state of error than in that of truth. They cannot escape the dilemma: either (1) whatever seems is true (and there are some who accept this) or (2) error is contact with the un-
one and the same.
the forms of both, assuming
as one,
two
of time.
may
—
it
one and occupies in
moment
well as
be both contraries at once potentially, it cannot be self-identical in its being it must lose its unity by being put into activity. It is not possible to be at once white and black, and therefore it must also be impossible for a thing
discriminates
ed: while so far as
qua undivided; for it is divisible in its being, but spatially and numerically undivided. [5] But is not this impossible? For while it is true that what is self-identical and undivided so
it
like; for that
like
by
[5]
But
is
the opposite of the
knowing
of
like. it is
a received principle that error as
knowledge
in respect to contraries
is
That perceiving and practical thinking are not identical is therefore obvious; for the former is universal in the animal world, the latter is found in only a small division of it. Further, speculative thinking is also distinct from perceiving I mean that in which we find
—
Tightness
and wrongness
—rightness
in
pru-
[10] dence, knowledge, true opinion, wrongness in their opposites; for perception of the special objects of sense ror,
and
sible
is
found
to think falsely
thought
is
Odyssey,
always free from
as well as
found only where there 2
iFr. 106. 3
is
in all animals, while
xvm.
Fr. 108.
136.
4 404**
8-18.
it is
truly, is
er-
pos-
and
discourse
ON THE SOUL
66o
of reason as well as sensibility. For imagination
different
is
from
either perceiving or dis-
[75] cursive thinking, though
not found
it is
without sensation, or judgement without it. That this activity is not the same kind of thinking as judgement is obvious. For imagining lies within our own power whenever we wish (e.g. we can call up a picture, as in the practice of mnemonics by the use of mental im[20] ages), but in forming opinions we are not free: we cannot escape the alternative of falsehood or truth. Further, when we think something to be fearful or threatening, emotion is immediately produced, and so too with what is encouraging; but when we merely imagine we remain as unaffected as persons who are looking at a painting of some dreadful or encouraging scene. Again within the field
428 b
remains therefore to see
It
if it is opinion, be either true or false. [20] But opinion involves belief (for without belief in what we opine we cannot have an opinion), and in the brutes though we often
for opinion
may
find imagination ther, every
belief
we
opinion
never find
belief.
Fur-
accompanied by belief, by conviction, and conviction by disis
course of reason: while there are some of the brutes in which we find imagination, without discourse of reason. It is clear then that imagi[25] nation cannot, again, be ( 1 ) opinion plus sensation, or (2) opinion mediated by sensa-
is
blend of opinion and sensation; both for these reasons and because the content of the supposed opinion cannot be different from that of the sensation (I mean that imagination must be the blending of the perception of white with the opinion that it is white: it could scarcely be a blend [jo] of the opinion that it is good with the perception that it is white): to imagine is there428 b fore (on this view) identical with the thinking of exactly the same as what one in
ment: we must therefore
the strictest sense perceives. But
[25] of judgement itself we find varieties knowledge, opinion, prudence, and their opposites; of the differences between these I must speak elsewhere. Thinking is different from perceiving and
held to be in part imagination, in part judgefirst mark off the sphere of imagination and then speak of judge428 a ment. If then imagination is that in virtue of
which an image
excluding
arises for us,
metaphorical uses of the term,
is
a single
it
faculty or disposition relative to images, in vir-
which we discriminate and are
tue of
error or not?
we do
The
either in
faculties in virtue of
which
this are sense, opinion, science, intelli-
gence. [5]
That imagination
is
not sense
is
the following considerations: Sense
clear is
from
either a
faculty or an activity, e.g. sight or seeing: imagination takes place in the absence of both, as e.g. in dreams. (2)
Again, sense
is
always
present, imagination not. If actual imagination
and actual sensation were the same, imagination would be found in all the brutes: this is [10] held not to be the case; e.g. it is not found in ants or bees or grubs. (3) Again, sensations are always true, imaginations are for the most
part false. (4) Once more, even in ordinary speech, we do not, when sense functions precisely
with regard to
agine
it
some
failure of accuracy in
to be a
its
object, say that
we
im-
man, but rather when there its
exercise.
is
And
[75] (5), as we were saying before, visions appear to us even when our eyes are shut. Neither is imagination any of the things that are 1
never in error: e.g. knowledge or intelligence; for imagination may be false. ill. 7-8.
tion, or (3) a
this is impossible
ine
is
sometimes
false
what we imagthough our contempora-
neous judgement about it is true; e.g. we imagine the sun to be a foot in diameter though we are convinced that it is larger than the inhabited part of the earth, and the following dilemma presents itself. Either (a) while the fact has not changed and the [5] observer has neither forgotten nor lost belief in the true opinion which he had, that opinion has disappeared, or (b) if he retains it then his opinion is at once true and false. A true opinion, however, becomes false only when the fact alters without being noticed.
Imagination
is
therefore neither any one of
the states enumerated, nor
compounded out
of
them. [70] But since when one thing has been set in motion another thing may be moved by it, and imagination is held to be a movement and to
be impossible without sensation, i.e. to in beings that are percipient and to have content what can be perceived, and movement may be produced by actual tion
and that movement
is
its
since sensa-
necessarily similar
in character to the sensation itself, this
ment must be (1)
occur for
move-
necessarily (a) incapable of
[75] existing apart from sensation, (b) incapable of existing except when we perceive, (2) such that in virtue of its possession that in which it is found may present various phe-
BOOK
429 b
III,
CHAPTERS
nomena both active and passive, and (3) such that it may be either true or false. The reason of the last characteristic is as follows. Perception (1) of the special objects of sense is never in error or admits the least possible amount of falsehood. (2) That of the
concomitance of the objects concomitant with the sensible qualities comes next: in this case [20] certainly we may be deceived; for while the perception that there is white before us cannot be false, the perception that what is white is this or that may be false. (3) Third
comes the perception of the universal attributes which accompany the concomitant objects to which the special sensibles attach (I mean e.g. of movement and magnitude); it is in respect of these that the greatest
sense-illusion
is
amount
of
possible.
[25] The motion which is due to the activity of sense in these three modes of its exercise will differ from the activity of sense; (1) the first
from error while the sensation is present; (2) and (3) the others may be erroneous whether it is present kind of derived motion
or absent, especially
is
when
free
the object of per-
[50] ception is far of?. If then imagination preno other features than those enumerated
3-4
661
while impassible, capable of receiving the object; that is, must be potentially identical in character with its object without being the object. Mind must be related to what be,
form of an
is
thinkable, as sense
is
to
what
is
ity.
(by
Thus that in the soul which is called mind mind I mean that whereby the soul thinks
and judges) is, before it thinks, not actually any real thing. For this reason it cannot reasonably be regarded as blended with the body: [25] if so, it would acquire some quality, e.g.
warmth
or cold, or even have an organ like
the sensitive faculty: as
good idea though (1)
a
it is, it
has none.
this description
intellective soul,
this is the
Observation of the sense-organs and their [jo] impassibility of the sensitive
(fyavraala (imagination)