The Visibility of the Image: History and Perspectives of Formal Aesthetics 9781474232647, 9781474232654, 9781474232678

Now available in English for the first time, The Visibility of the Image explores the development of an influential aest

169 32 5MB

English Pages [282] Year 2016

Report DMCA / Copyright

DOWNLOAD PDF FILE

Table of contents :
Cover
Half-title
Title
Copyright
Contents
List of Figures
Foreword to the New Edition (2008)
Introduction
1. The Beginnings of Formal Aesthetics: Robert Zimmermann (1824– 1898)
1.1 Formal logic as a model for formal aesthetics
1.2 The programme: A structural theory of the picture surface
1.3 Perspectives and problems in Herbartianism
2. Formal Aesthetics and Relational Logic: Alois Riegl (1858–1905)
2.1 Transitions on the pictorial surface
2.2 Kunstwollen (the will to art): Making unlike things the same
2.3 Intensional and extensional relational logic
3. The Logic of Ways of Seeing: Heinrich Wölffl in (1864–1945)
3.1 The relational logic of an image
3.2 Formal and transcendental aesthetics
3.3 The conditionality of perception
4. From the Way of Seeing to Visibility: Konrad Fiedler (1841–1895)
4.1 The paradigms of formal aesthetics
4.2 Images produced technically: ‘For their visibility’s sake alone’
4.3 The disappearance of artistic claims to truth
5. Phenomenological Reduction and Pictorial Abstraction: Maurice Merleau- Ponty (1908–1961)
5.1 Formal aesthetics and reduction
5.2 Visibility as quiddity
5.3 The abstract image
6 From the Formula to Formative Discourse: Charles William Morris (1901–1979)
6.1 Images about images
6.2 Images as formulae
6.3 Th e formative discourse of fast image sequences
Notes
Bibliography
Index
Recommend Papers

The Visibility of the Image: History and Perspectives of  Formal Aesthetics
 9781474232647, 9781474232654, 9781474232678

  • 0 0 0
  • Like this paper and download? You can publish your own PDF file online for free in a few minutes! Sign Up
File loading please wait...
Citation preview

The Visibility of the Image

Also available from Bloomsbury Academic Aesthetic Theory, Theodor W. Adorno Beauty and the End of Art, Sonia Sedivy The Bloomsbury Companion to Aesthetics, edited by Anna Christina Ribeiro The Cultural Promise of the Aesthetic, Monique Roelofs The Philosophy of Perception, Lambert Wiesing

The Visibility of the Image History and Perspectives of Formal Aesthetics Lambert Wiesing Translated by Nancy Ann Roth

BLOOMSBURY ACADEMIC Bloomsbury Publishing Plc 50 Bedford Square, London, WC1B 3DP, UK BLOOMSBURY, BLOOMSBURY ACADEMIC and the Diana logo are trademarks of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc Originally published in German as Die Sichtbarkeit des Bildes. Geschichteund Perspektiven der formalen Ästhetik, Lambert Wiesing © Campus Verlag GmbH All rights reserved and controlled by Campus Verlag GmbH First published in English 2016 Paperback edition first published 2018 English language translation © Bloomsbury Publishing Plc, 2016 Cover design: Catherine Wood Cover image © Silke Rehberg All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or any information storage or retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the publishers. Bloomsbury Publishing Plc does not have any control over, or responsibility for, any third-party websites referred to or in this book. All internet addresses given in this book were correct at the time of going to press. The author and publisher regret any inconvenience caused if addresses have changed or sites have ceased to exist, but can accept no responsibility for any such changes. A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Wiesing, Lambert, author. The visibility of the image : history and perspectives of formal aesthetics / Lambert Wiesing; translated by Nancy Ann Roth. Sichtbarkeit des Bildes. New York : Bloomsbury, 2016. | Includes bibliographical references and index. LCCN 2016012989 (print) | LCCN 2016021740 (ebook) | ISBN 9781474232647 (hardback) | ISBN 9781474233316 (pbk.) | ISBN 9781474232678 (epdf) | ISBN 9781474232661 (epub) LCSH: Aesthetics, Modern–19th century. | Aesthetics, Modern–20th century. | Art–Philosophy–History–19th century. | Art–Philosophy–History–20th century. LCC BH193 .W4713 2016 (print) | LCC BH193 (ebook) | DDC 111/.85–dc23 LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2016012989 ISBN:

HB: 978-1-4742-3264-7 PB: 978-1-350-06402-7 ePDF: 978-1-4742-3267-8 eBook: 978-1-4742-3266-1

Typeset by Newgen Knowledge Works (P) Ltd., Chennai, India To find out more about our authors and books visit www.bloomsbury.com and sign up for our newsletters.

Contents List of Figures Foreword to the New Edition (2008) Introduction 1

2

3

4

5

The Beginnings of Formal Aesthetics:  Robert Zimmermann (1824–1898) 1.1 Formal logic as a model for formal aesthetics 1.2 The programme: A structural theory of the picture surface 1.3 Perspectives and problems in Herbartianism Formal Aesthetics and Relational Logic: Alois Riegl (1858–1905) 2.1 Transitions on the pictorial surface 2.2 Kunstwollen (the will to art): Making unlike things the same 2.3 Intensional and extensional relational logic The Logic of Ways of Seeing: Heinrich Wölfflin (1864–1945) 3.1 The relational logic of an image 3.2 Formal and transcendental aesthetics 3.3 The conditionality of perception From the Way of Seeing to Visibility: Konrad Fiedler (1841–1895) 4.1 The paradigms of formal aesthetics 4.2 Images produced technically: ‘For their visibility’s sake alone’ 4.3 The disappearance of artistic claims to truth Phenomenological Reduction and Pictorial Abstraction: Maurice Merleau-Ponty (1908–1961) 5.1 Formal aesthetics and reduction 5.2 Visibility as quiddity 5.3 The abstract image

vii ix 1

15 15 22 31 39 39 47 57 69 69 86 93 107 107 125 145

157 157 165 171

vi

6

Contents

From the Formula to Formative Discourse: Charles William Morris (1901–1979) 6.1 Images about images 6.2 Images as formulae 6.3 The formative discourse of fast image sequences

Notes Bibliography Index

179 179 184 191 203 231 253

List of Figures 1 Hergé. Image of the ship Sirius from the comic series Tintin, Red Rackham’s Treasure, 1944 2 J. M. W. Turner, Staffa, oil on canvas, 1832 3 Vector and Raster (pixels). Illustration from the manual for Adobe Illustrator 6.0, Adobe Systems Incorporated, 1995 4 Illustration from auto motor und sport, 1993

Foreword to the New Edition (2008) From a contemporary perspective, I  find it nearly incomprehensible:  in The Visibility of the Image, I use the expression Bildtheorie [image theory] only twice (pp. 18 and 172), just in passing, and without any further consideration I speak of the theory of the image, too, only twice (pp. 40 and 126). It irritates me that these concepts are used so infrequently, because I am sure that if I were writing the book today, they would appear dozens of times. At present I  know of no other concept that would describe the contents and intention of this book so tellingly: in The Visibility of the Image I try to sketch out a theory of the image. As I  was writing the book in the early 1990s, however  – it was first available in bookstores in November of 1996 – ‘Bildtheorie’ was not commonly used in German intellectual discourse. Intensive research and thinking about images and all their forms was underway in a wide range of disciplines, but it just was not normally referred to as ‘image theory’. The term Bildtheorie, if it was heard at all, had a completely different meaning, namely in the context of Wittgenstein’s early understanding of a proposition. The concepts Bildwissenschaft [visual culture] and ‘semiotics of the image’ were certainly available, although not yet nearly as familiar as they are today. One tends to forget that people spoke of Bilderkunde [the lore of images] in the 1980s and early 1990s. Yet whatever concepts were in circulation, the expression ‘Bildtheorie’ didn’t quite fit – at least it was not present in my vocabulary. If Bildtheorie was used before the turn of the millennium at all, I think I’m justified in saying that it had no specific use: it was not positioned centrally, either as a title or in a definition. How the situation has changed! Those with even a superficial interest in images are continually running across the concept of Bildtheorie: it is used in the titles and programming of essays, books, conferences and research projects – usually as if the meaning is obvious. There are posts, courses of study and professorships dedicated to image theory: all these are phenomena of roughly the past ten years. In a very short time, the concept of Bildtheorie has developed from a peripheral term into a well-used programmatic category. It should be noted, however, that I am thinking about the history of the term, and not about the issues to which it refers. These are without a doubt much older, not to say almost as old as philosophy itself: Plato had an image theory, but it was never designated

x

Foreword to the New Edition (2008)

as such. It has rather been the custom to speak of Plato’s aesthetic – his theory of mimesis or of art. We know that sometimes detailed, widespread reflections are identified only in connection with a new discipline later – and this is not at all rare in philosophy. The sudden rise in the popularity of the concept Bildtheorie has a distinct parallel in the history of the concept of Erkenntnistheorie [epistemology]: a concept which was also late to emerge (in middle of the nineteenth century), as the designation for an independent discipline, despite contributions that reach back to antiquity. The pattern seems to be repeating itself with the emergence of Bildtheorie, except that it has just happened recently. With regard to the new edition of The Visibility of the Image, I  ask myself whether there is good reason to return to the concept of Bildtheorie now, and why I use the term so much more frequently now. If it is more than a matter of fashion, quickly forgotten, then some differentiation process must have begun since the first publication of The Visibility of the Image. Grounds must have been articulated on which Bildtheorie could be established as an independent subdiscipline within philosophy, and this as a disciplinary project distinguishable both from visual culture outside philosophy, and from semiotics and aesthetics inside philosophy. These grounds must further have been persuasive and effective very quickly – at least quickly enough for concepts such as ‘Bildwissenschaft’ or ‘semiotics of the image’ or ‘aesthetics’ to appear to me now as perhaps not exactly wrong, but not at all appropriate or even specific enough for the contents of The Visibility of the Image. I hardly use them at all any more in describing the intentions of the book, and would like to briefly explain the reasons. First, the concept of Bildwissenschaft [visual culture]: in recent years it has become a kind of catchall term for any kind of disciplined engagement with images. Someone not wanting to be too specific might be better off speaking in the plural, of ‘visual culture studies’ so as to signal a reference to the many ways images are studied. No doubt The Visibility of the Image does contribute to visual culture in this vague sense – although the term never appears in it, and this seems right to me in light of recent developments in the area of visual culture in the narrower sense. But the inquiry I pursue in The Visibility of the Image can be distinguished from the problem of visual culture:  despite the range of disciplinary traditions, themes and methods that were used at the time to found a putatively new discipline, everyone agrees that visual culture embraces images in all media and all historical forms as its field of research. Quite often one hears it said that visual culture is clearly separate from art history on these grounds; according to this view, art history is concerned exclusively with a few images in museums, and that visual culture, by contrast, is concerned with all images. To

Foreword to the New Edition (2008)

xi

me this opposition seems contrived and unnatural. Art history has to be at the heart of visual culture, simply and convincingly because art history has been engaged with the project the longest. The historical reasons art history cannot be accused of having restricted its concern to artistically valuable images have been stated clearly and repeatedly; the pertinent works of Gottfried Boehm, Horst Bredekamp or Hans Belting come to mind. Their central argument goes: to draw a boundary between an inherited art history and a putatively new visual culture is not only incompatible with the history of pictorial theory in the history of art, but also unachievable: since the history of art has always been a comparative discipline, it neither can nor will concentrate on a few images having the status of art. An art history free of self-imposed obstructions must pay theoretical attention to all images, even if only to be able to notice what is extraordinary about art; art history is, therefore, the true Bildwissenschaft. From this point of view, it is confusing to call for a new discipline of Bildwissenschaft in order to expand the restricted field of art history. More than a few art historians rightly reject the programme of visual culture as an alternative to art history. Yet whatever we may think about disputes about the field of visual culture, and whoever ultimately takes responsibility for researching the ever-increasing body of images human beings produce – whether a new visual culture, an old art history or an art history as visual culture – the key point is that it is all only indirectly related to image theory. In a disciplined study of images, the concern is always with concrete things; real objects are to be researched, their origins, their psychological effects, their medial conditions, their social and contextual meanings, their historical contexts and many more basic empirical aspects, and it is exactly this basic empirical orientation that in German sets Bildwissenschaft [visual culture] apart from Bildtheorie [image theory]. The difference can be pinpointed with the following statement: both visual culture and image theory are concerned with all images, but only image theory is concerned with the question of everything an image is. The difference in interests, themes and methods is enormous, especially with respect to the way an answer is to be defended. A theoretical question about an image cannot be answered through empirical observations, but only through philosophical work on concepts. Someone who is researching an image has already categorized it as an image. This is the critical difference:  an image theory is not concerned with that which has already been categorized, but rather with the categorization itself, and that means: in image theory, the main concern is with the concept of the image. One would like to know what is meant when something is called an image, or which characteristics this something must have in order to be an

xii

Foreword to the New Edition (2008)

image. It is about the way images relate to the world in principle. It is not the concrete image that is of interest, but rather the image as a medium. In contrast to visual culture, image theory pursues a fundamentally different – complementary, rather than competitive  – form of inquiry, in which the concrete image figures not as the object of research, but as an example for statements in principle about what it is to be an image. One could speak of image theory’s affiliation with philosophy, which is appropriately indicated by the word ‘theory’. For a discipline that designates itself a science is as a rule an empirical science; social science or communication science comes to mind. ‘Theory’, on the other hand, is a perfectly standard designation for subdisciplines of philosophy, as is the case for the theory of consciousness or the theory of knowledge. In short, the accelerating spread of image theory is the result of having recognized problems following on from a heightened concern with images in the so-called iconic turn at the time, and of a need for philosophical reflection on those problems. Yet that is just one reason, namely the one for the heightened interest in the philosophy of the image at that time in the first place. Another reason seems to me to be ultimately more important and noteworthy, namely that contemporary interest in philosophical image theory is a critical response to one extremely widespread understanding of the image. This means the following: even before the boom in image theory, there were subdisciplines or at least areas of research within philosophy that by tradition felt, and to some extent still feel, that the philosophy of the image lies within their purview. I remember well: when I showed my work on The Visibility of the Image to friends and colleagues at the time I  was writing, most of them knew immediately:  the topic belongs in semiotics or aesthetics. These are two classical locations within philosophy where categorical problems about the nature of images are addressed, and these are exactly the disciplines that require image theory to explain how it is different from them, and why an additional field of inquiry is therefore necessary. Within philosophy, interest in image theory at that time actually arose from a two-fold process of delimitation: one with respect to semiotics, and the other with respect of aesthetics. I would like to take up the differentiation of image theory from semiotics first, for it seems a particularly clear case:  From the standpoint of semiotics, the establishment of image theory as an academic field is a broadly superfluous and competitive development. Semiotics takes itself to be the central discipline of the philosophical investigation of the image – and this for the following reason: because in semiotics, there is a remarkable unanimity about the view that all images are always and necessarily signs. From the assumption that all images

Foreword to the New Edition (2008)

xiii

are signs, it follows that images are within the competence of the theory of signs. A variant of this argument can be found in Nelson Goodman’s book Languages of Art: An Approach to a Theory of Symbols (1968). As is clear from the subtitle alone, the goal is not an image theory, but rather the design of a theory of symbols. Since all images are symbols, there is no need for a special image theory, only for a general theory of symbols to be adapted to images. The difference is one of words only: it makes no difference to the argument whether a science of signs is called ‘symbol theory’ or ‘semiotics’. Either way, images fall within the competence of the discipline concerned with signs, because images are signs. With this, it also becomes clear that the disciplinary alignment of images within this science stands or falls with the premise of images really always having to be signs or symbols. But this very premise was being challenged just as philosophical image theory was heating up. There is a relationship between, on the one hand, resistance to the semiotic dogma of the status of images as signs and, on the other, the rise of image theory as a disciplinary alternative. To put it another way:  the criticism of the idea that an image is necessarily a sign corresponds to a doubt about whether semiotics or language theory as such could be suitable frameworks for philosophical reflection on the concept of the image at all. The problem is whether treating images semiotically or language-theoretically does not in itself imply a prejudice that is, from an image-theoretical standpoint, doubtful: namely that it is critical for the image to have the character of a sign. By this point it is clear that discussions about the status of images as signs, discussions that are often heated, are not about marginal matters; rather their resolutions serve to set the direction for future work. With The Visibility of the Image I am trying to make a systematic contribution to this ongoing discussion; my main thesis with respect to this issue appears on page 124–5: ‘The pure visibility of an image can be, but need not be a sign.’ In The Visibility of the Image, I take the view that images are not signs eo ipso. This follows necessarily from the condition that signs always arise through use. An object is a sign exactly at the point someone uses the object to refer to something. This is the reason the concept of a sign is a prime example of a concept of function: such a concept labels a function that something must serve in order to be something. As a result, there can be no things that are signs in themselves. That an object is a sign is no more observable in this object than the fact that it is a gift. The same applies to images:  they only become signs through use. And yet – and this is the crucial point – objects do not become images through use, which is the reason the concept of an image, by contrast to that of a sign, is not a concept of function. Whether an object is an image

xiv

Foreword to the New Edition (2008)

can be established through observation, in fact only through observation. For being an image is a perceptible quality of things and not the result of a use of things. Exactly this perceptible quality, which determines whether something is an image, is what I try to describe in The Visibility of the Image: images are different from normal objects in their visibility. So clearly I will have to suggest a term for this special visibility of the image. I do this by reaching back to available categories and speaking of ‘pure visibility’, a term that first appears not, as one often reads, in Konrad Fiedler, but in Benedetto Croce (although in a review of a text of Fiedler’s). With this concept, the main thesis of this book can be simply formulated: images are distinguished from other objects not through their qualities as signs, but through their pure visibility. Visibility is, for any visible thing in the world, a visibility ‘attached’ to substance, as the metaphor goes on to say. That is, the visibility of something in the world is a sensible characteristic of a substance that is present, to which, however, more than just this one sensible characteristic is attached. If something can be seen, then this same something can also be heard, smelt and tasted. Only with an image is there a break in the accessibility of the same thing to multiple senses, so that it is possible to see something in an image that is not materially present. What can be seen in an image is not really present, but rather has an artificial presence. This is the case only for an object that one believes he is seeing when looking at an image. Now this image object is not the material image carrier, which may consist of canvas or paper, but rather what Günther Anders calls the ‘phantom’, that becomes visible on the image carrier: something that becomes visible, but that cannot be tasted, smelt or heard: an image appears through the production of something exclusively visible. Hence the suggestion that we speak of ‘pure visibility’ – and this terminological suggestion still seems entirely appropriate to me today, although in discussion I repeatedly noticed some strong aversions to the word ‘pure’. It turns out that its double meaning is exactly what makes it so appropriate; one meaning of ‘pure’ is simply ‘exclusive’. I owe my use of the unconventional expression ‘only-visible’ (‘nursichtbar’ is unconventional in German as well.) to Robert Musil (p. 131). But ‘pure’ also has the meaning ‘clean’ and ‘not dirty’, and this meaning, too, has a resonance in the context of thinking about pure visibility. Compared to the visibility of the world, the visibility of the image is a visibility cleansed of brute materiality; the image makes it possible to see a world unencumbered by physical forces. To speak of this artificial visibility of the image as pure visibility is to imply that it is an advantage for something to become visible in an image, cleansed of mundane traffic in causes and effects.

Foreword to the New Edition (2008)

xv

It is obvious that images can be signs; but before an image can be used as a sign, it must show something that can then be used as a sign. Only then can there be any use of this emerging image object as a sign. I believe I have described this in The Visibility of the Image: ‘That an image can also be a sign is the product of a subsequent use of pure visibility as a sign for that to which it bears some similarity.’ (p. 124). Still, I have not actually pursued the task of analysing this subsequent use of the image as a sign any further. In The Visibility of the Image, what is done to an image by using it to establish a reference to something remains unresolved; I first tried to set out the principles of the retrospective use of images as signs in the texts for Artificial Presence of 2005. It was not because of limited time or space that this happened only later, in a second book, but because in The Visibility of the Image I was not interested in the use of the images as signs, but in just the reverse, namely in the idea that there are images that exist for their visibility alone, and whose use as signs would be foreign to the purpose. An image theory focussed exclusively on the visibility of the image is repeatedly accused of one-sidedness, of having overlooked many other aspects of images; a problematic reduction is unavoidably bound up with such thematic concentration: in a theory that reduces the image to one aspect, many important characteristics, such as its materiality, its meaning, its historical context and its producer’s intentions are ruled out. Such a reduction was exactly my intention, and I defend it in The Visibility of the Image as an advantage for the following reason: the image must be reduced to its essential aspect because it is about the answer to the question of what an image is. But because it is about the necessary aspects of image, the thesis of pure visibility does not imply that visibility is the only noteworthy aspect of images, and most assuredly does not imply that this is the only important aspect of art works – The Visibility of the Image is not a theory of art. Who would seriously want to claim that in looking at art, it is the pure visibility of what is depicted alone that matters, and that the materiality and meaning of the work should be pointedly ignored? This book has a completely different kind of purpose:  it is an effort to explain what makes something an image? In answering this indubitably special question, the materiality in any one case and the possibly extant meaning of the object play no part. An object simply cannot be identified as an image on the grounds of any particular contents or on the basis of the materials or production techniques. Something is an image if something is visible on it that is ‘only-visible’. To define being an image as the production of pure visibility therefore does not deny that other aspects of an image may be, and often are, far more important for the observer in observing this image, even if they do not explain why

xvi

Foreword to the New Edition (2008)

this object is an image: of course the unique attraction and value of many images lies in the way the material has been handled, and one should not therefore turn away from such an image; of course the use of symbols is a feature of many images which one should not overlook; of course there are images that are valued because they are supposed to be art – yet neither their materiality nor their symbolism nor their status as art can explain why, for any particular image, we are dealing with an image. In fact it is not so remarkable, and is well known in other contexts, for the defining feature of something not to necessarily be the feature that is of interest to someone: if you love a person, for example, then in all probability you will not be doing it on account of the features this person has which could be used to explain why the love object is a person. The same holds for looking at images: the reasons something is an image should by no means be the only reasons for looking at the image. There are such reasons, nevertheless, and there are also images that are produced and looked at for these reasons. In fact I am particularly concerned to show that this quality of physics-free, pure visibility, attributable to any image, is in fact not always the reason an image has been made or viewed, but that it is the case for some images, and in fact especially for those that figure among the new images of the twentieth century. The Visibility of the Image advances the argument that new image forms arose in the twentieth century that cannot be explained by way of technical changes in media, but that can be approached through formal aesthetics: they can be interpreted as attempts to produce asemantic images for the sake of their visibility. With respect to these special formal images I am thinking of certain collages, certain video clips, computer games and animations – and today they still seem to me to be the most important examples. I would like to show, with these images, that a formal image theory is not only equipped with a descriptive dimension, but that it is also implicitly bound up with a kind of production maxim. In this book, I have formulated that maxim as follows: ‘Stop trying to interpret visible reality in the production of an image, and try instead to understand the creation of an image as the building of an object in which visibility becomes an independent form of being!’ (p. 125). That is the place in the book – and I am glad to be able to say it is the only place – where I needed to fill gaps in for the new edition: here a reference to Jean-Paul Sartre is needed. It was clear to me that his position with respect to the theory of images coincided in its central aspects with my own reflections. But unfortunately it only occurred to me several months after the publication of The Visibility of the Image that Sartre’s statement in What Is Literature? of 1948, about the contingent status of the image as a sign, was so similar, that his

Foreword to the New Edition (2008)

xvii

view of asemantic images was a call to make images without semiotic function; the following quotation should not have been omitted from The Visibility of the Image: ‘The painter does not want to create a thing. And if he puts together red, yellow, and green, there is no reason for the ensemble to have a definable signification, that is, to refer particularly to another object. [. . .] But, you will say, suppose the painter does houses? That’s just it. He makes them, that is, he creates an imaginary house on the canvas and not a sign of a house. And the house which thus appears preserves all the ambiguity of real houses.’* With this, the key idea of this image theory is clearly formulated: the image is considered a technique for producing a special kind of objectivity; it is not about appearance, but rather about the production of being; with pictures things are fabricated that are – in contrast to normal things – imaginary things, because they are not subject to the laws of physics: for with images, and in fact only with images, a human being can see things and processes that are physically impossible. It is clear from just the simple fact that things visible in an image do not age. An object that does not age does not exist in the world except in images. One can only imagine such an object, or encounter it as a fantasy object presented in an image. The Visibility of the Image is concerned with a way of thinking about images that does not make use of semiotics. This follows necessarily from the intention to defend the possibility of asemantic images. Still, as I said, this drawing of boundaries within the book does not lead to using of the concept of image theory as a replacement, and this for one simple reason:  for me it was obvious that not only the historical theories introduced here but also the systematic perspectives belonged in philosophical aesthetics. This obviousness has since come to need explanation. For a turn towards the designation ‘image theory’ also involves a turn – in part especially forceful in just this respect – away from philosophical aesthetics. It seems to me that most contemporary image theorists, such as Klaus Rehkämper, understand themselves explicitly and emphatically not to be aestheticians. This distancing of image theory from aesthetics is not necessary, however, for unlike the case of semiotics, in which there are substantial named reasons why image theory cannot be detached, there seem to be no such reasons in aesthetics at all. The argument that is given for the distancing goes: philosophical aesthetics is the science of perception and most particularly of beauty and of art, just not the science of the image. But exactly

* Jean-Paul Sartre, What Is Literature? (1949), trans. Bernard Frechtman, New  York:  Philosophical Library, pp. 9 and 10.

xviii

Foreword to the New Edition (2008)

with respect to the history of formal aesthetics the argument is hardly persuasive. For here, under the title ‘aesthetics’, image theory in its contemporary sense was pursued  – I  remain committed to this understanding of aesthetics’ competence in my systematic considerations as well, which is the reason the book’s subtitle is History and Perspectives of Formal Aesthetics, rather than History of Formal Aesthetics and Perspectives of Formal Image Theory. One of the places where I speak about the theory of the image is a footnote, in which I look into the extent to which the themes of image theory formed part of formal aesthetics’ concept of the aesthetic; the contents of this footnote would now surely be better-placed in the text itself: ‘The question of whether something is a work of art seemed secondary to theoreticians of formal aesthetics. For this reason, this book presents a history of formal aesthetics with the intention of representing a theory of the image in all its material forms of appearance. So it is worth keeping in mind: not every image is a work of art, nor is every work of art an image. What is said about images need not hold for every work of art, and what is said about works of art need not be valid for every image’ (pp. 40–41). The turn to image theory at that time went hand in hand with a turn away from aesthetics, a compensatory shift that probably can no longer be reversed – nor does it need to be reversed. But we should not forget where the important roots of contemporary image theory lie: in formal aesthetics! With the subsequent development of image theory in the background, the new edition of The Visibility of the Image can be linked to an intention I did not have at the beginning because it seem too obvious, namely to show that aesthetics is one of the classical locations of image theory. Philosophical aesthetics has no reason not to feel the discussion of image theory to be within its remit. On the contrary: just as art historians rightly point out that there is a long tradition of serious thought about images in their discipline, so can aestheticians refer to an equally long tradition of image-theoretical reflection: The history of formal aesthetics is the best example. L.W. Sendenhorst, October 2007

Introduction

Hardly any other area of philosophy raises such diverse expectations as aesthetics. Extremely heterogeneous phenomena are debated under the heading ‘aesthetics’. It has not been possible to define it exclusively as a theory of beauty or high art for a long time. And even the original Greek understanding of aesthetics as the study of perception is inadequate to embrace the entire spectrum of contents currently under consideration in this field. To try to define the object of philosophical aesthetics is to run into an apparently unavoidable tautology: aesthetics is the discipline concerned with the aesthetic. In fact the concept of ‘aesthetic’ is being used more and more often not only in theoretical contexts, but for the characterization of real objects. People speak with great assurance of aesthetic experience, aesthetic objects and even of the aesthetics of things. Aesthetics is such a broad field because there are aesthetic aspects to be found in not only art and nature, but in people’s consciousness and self-understanding and in ethical and theoretical claims as well. The term ‘aesthetic’ in no way refers to the same quality in each of these contexts, however: it is not uncommon for talk about the aesthetic to function as another formulation for stylish elegance, for the appearance of presence, for attention directed to the act of perception, for the sensual presence of sense, and often just for the perception of something. It is impossible to avoid the conclusion that the spectrum of meaning is wide and vague. But to think that such a multiplicity of meanings is unanimously regretted would be an error. Even a passing glance at recent contributions to philosophical aesthetics shows that two evaluations of the content stand intractably opposed to one another. On the one hand, there are those who find the current situation in aesthetics completely unacceptable because the term itself has lost so much of its focus, specificity, its very meaning through inflationary use. From this point of view, aesthetics urgently needs to be realigned to its conceptual traditions, that is, to

2

The Visibility of the Image

be committed to a specific task and to treat only excellent phenomena as aesthetic objects: for example beauty, judgements of taste, the experience of nature or art. In this orientation, the view is often taken that because the potential of modernism’s great classical aesthetic concepts has not been exhausted, they should serve as guiding examples. From another orientation comes the assessment ordinarily characterized as postmodern. In accordance with it, the very breadth of the concept aesthetics offers an opportunity for future research: for semantic ambiguity, as the central argument goes, need not be equivalent to uselessness. On the contrary: if the breadth of the concept were taken into account, aesthetics would have a position at the foundation of the sciences and humanities that it has never had before. From this standpoint, any narrowing of the field of aesthetics to the study of special aesthetic phenomena in the modern sense is an unjust and unjustified expansion of one element from the broad spectrum of aesthetics into its overarching theme, keeping aesthetics from its current task of describing the contemporary function of aesthetic principles. The dispute about the actual meaning of the aesthetic is significant: not only is it a clear demonstration of how internally divided contemporary philosophical aesthetics is with respect to the way it understands itself; it shows at least equally well where there is unspoken agreement. The agreement particularly concerns the expectation of what an engagement with the history of aesthetics should do now, for what reason and in what forms inherited aesthetics have current relevance. In both cases, the history of aesthetics is regarded as the development of theories with diverse tasks and methods, with which one should be familiar so as to base one’s own work on the current state of research, to avoid needlessly repeating what has been known for a long time, and not least of all, to provide historical justification for one’s own approach. Now any of these reasons would no doubt be persuasive independently and would be enough to support further work in the history of aesthetics. But in light of these expectations alone, one important dimension of philosophical aesthetics goes unnoticed. Philosophical aesthetics has reflected theoretically not only current aesthetic phenomena, whatever they may be, exactly, but it has also, through conceptualization, affected actual events. We should be aware that more than a few of the aesthetic positions that have come down to us sought to be more than descriptions of current realities. Philosophical aestheticians worked in explicit and implicit expectation of setting out the foundations for future developments in the fields of art, society and culture. Many aesthetic theories are decidedly utopian projects. That extends from Friedrich Schiller’s design for an aesthetic

Introduction

3

state to Kurt Schwitters’s visions of a Merzwelt [Merzworld]. Both are exemplary cases of aestheticians wanting not primarily to describe something, but rather to create the conceptual conditions under which aesthetic projects first become communicable, and then should become historic realities. Taking this literally fundamental dimension of aesthetics into account means that in addition to the reasons already given for taking up the history of aesthetics, at least one more can be added: the history of aesthetics is not only relevant for learning the strengths and weaknesses of those aesthetic concepts already worked out, but very particularly for discovering the intellectual foundations on which aesthetic phenomena of the present rest. This approach to the history of philosophy proves to be especially useful when philosophical means are used to focus on the contemporary world of images, as is the case for the present work. The image belongs to those aesthetic phenomena that have undergone a fast and radical development in this century. New forms of images have appeared both inside and outside the visual arts. One thinks of abstract images, different from all earlier images in that they shows no object at all, or of digital images, which permit an unprecedented manipulation of the depicted object as it is being observed. Now these are in fact two very different pictorial forms, yet one principal content can nevertheless be recognized equally well in each of them: the discovery of new technologies for producing images does not in itself explain why a new pictorial form comes into being. Abstract images needed no technical invention at all, for the abstract image works with the traditional means of the easel picture. This does not apply in the same sense to the digital image, since its genesis is bound up with the earlier development of computer technology. But even here, new technology in itself does not sufficiently explain how digital images are possible. We need to be aware that even a new technology initially presents nothing more than possibilities – these possibilities still need to be used in order for genuinely innovative images to result from a new medium. To put it another way: images, works of art in particular, come to be on the basis of a particular conception of the image. Someone who thinks an image can only be an image if it is possible to recognize an object on it will hardly be in a position to make use of available technical possibilities to produce an abstract image. Someone who thinks a film must tell a story will not make a video clip using computer animation. So we can say technical possibilities can have an impact on the production of new image forms only if the pictorial understanding that in a logical sense permits it is already in place. Philosophical aesthetics affects the production of images by establishing the conceptual conditions in which the new images become thinkable.

4

The Visibility of the Image

Given this background, it becomes clear that the revolutions in the world of images in the twentieth century present a challenge to contemporary philosophical aesthetics. Of course it is an important topic in any case, one on which the history of philosophy confers special authority among the many broad and narrow understandings of aesthetics. But as long as one takes this route in his or her effort to advance contemporary aesthetics, he or she will try to bring an initiative based on the history of philosophy to bear on contemporary phenomena. One then still faces the problem that what is significant for the history of philosophy is not necessarily significant for the development of images, and that a certain historical arbitrariness therefore always remains in the choice of method. This can be avoided by looking at the image with the aesthetic values of the Zeitgeist in which the image could develop in the first place. There is an inner compulsion in a development, and it can be understood if it is possible to refer it back to a project that prepared the development theoretically. In turning to contemporary philosophical aesthetics with this expectation, one automatically turns to the history of philosophical aesthetics as well, but this time not to it alone, in order to adopt a suitable approach. Rather one goes further, to ground the development of the image itself in aesthetic argumentation. So the image is reflected in an aesthetic theoretically by showing which aesthetic is already reflected in the thing itself. Someone who looks at an image solely to inquire about the appearance of something hardly needs to justify his action philosophically. If we want to know how something looked, looks or could look, it is obvious that we will refer to images. For a long time, depictions have proven to be an excellent tool, informing us more quickly and more precisely than a thousand words about things and events in the visible world. Images show sights and insights that are not accessible to the naked eye, and that no communication in language can convey. Without images – and this is a commonplace – human beings would know less. The situation changes, however as soon as we take into account that images are not completely taken up with their capacity for depiction. Although it is confusing to put the image’s special capacity for visual communication in question, it is important to remember that images are neither made nor viewed exclusively for information about objects. One of the noteworthy phenomena about dealing with images is, rather, that they can be of high quality and worth looking at even if the depicted events are trivial or banal. A visit to a visual art museum can, like an evening of television, furnish ample evidence that the attraction of images need not be bound up with objective information. Cézanne’s apples do

Introduction

5

not attempt to clarify information or narrate events any more than a video clip on MTV does. So what do they show? The shared intention of the studies presented here of the visibility of the image is the reconstruction of a pictorial understanding that allows for images not to be used as signs for things that are absent. It tries to answer the question of what one can see in an image when one is not seeing depicted objects. When images are viewed, even if their content is of no interest, their mimetic status can no longer be taken for granted, as is always the case when images are serving informative purposes only. Philosophical aesthetics is the quarter from which we may expect help in understanding what images can do beyond simply depicting. It seems clear that from this standpoint abstract images play a key role. The abstract image is not a sign for an object because it does not even depict an object – still, it is an image. And yet not only in art, but in many popular pictorial forms as well – numerous video games come to mind – any relationship between what is visible in the image and an extant or fictive reality is either irrelevant or not given in the first place. These studies rest on a sense that images in the twentieth century, having been emancipated from the task of representation, are increasingly made and viewed for their visibility alone. Hence the question: when and where did the pictorial understanding develop that today makes it seem so natural to use images without any view towards objective information? The answer, and with it the main historical thesis goes: in formal aesthetics. The theses of formal aesthetics are to be reconstructed to show that in them, since the middle of the last century, ideas were being discussed that lend themselves to interpretation as the ground on which recent art and new media built their engagement with images. If, along the way, an orientation takes centre stage that would otherwise hardly command any attention at all at this point, it can be taken as an indication that in philosophical aesthetics as a whole, it was not held to be too important whether the approach being discussed and defended would endure in the immanent history of philosophy, or be meaningful for the realities with which aesthetics is concerned. Formal aesthetics developed in the nineteenth century in the school of the philosopher Johann Friedrich Herbart (1776–1841), marking, from a contemporary standpoint, a fundamental turning point in the history of aesthetics. It represents one of the first concepts with which philosophical aesthetics sought to free itself from the metaphysical mooring that had until then been a given. It belongs to a broader upheaval that operated under such slogans as ‘down with speculative aesthetics’ (Hettner) or ‘aesthetics from below’ (Fechner), and that

6

The Visibility of the Image

developed alternatives to philosophical aesthetics that took extant philosophies, rather than art works, as the starting point for statements about art. The shared goal is the work of a ‘general art history’ with a positivist orientation. In this context, aesthetics meant that one should respond to the perceptible qualities of aesthetic objects, rather than projecting philosophical theories on to them. Instead of using aesthetic phenomena to plug gaps in a philosophical system that was already in place, the objects themselves were to become the theme. The whole movement – and this is the source of its lasting significance – introduces analyses of images and of art that are genuinely phenomenological. We can speak of the beginning of modern art history. The purely immanent approach of formal aesthetics inevitably gives rise to an explicit double opposition; the programme was actually to break with the two great theories of philosophical aesthetics that prevailed in the nineteenth century: in opposition both to Kant’s analysis of aesthetic judgement as well as to Hegel’s linking of art to intellectual ideals, the call to go ‘back to the things themselves’ develops – and that also means: back to the visible. The history of formal aesthetics is a history of the investigation of the visibility of the image. All formal aestheticians share the view that an image is an object, an artefact whose diverse effects are achieved solely by covering a surface with visible forms. These visible forms on the surface of the image are the exclusive theme of formal aesthetics. The image is described as an object that is distinguished from other things as well as from other signs through its visibility. For in order to explain that an image can show more than an object, and is itself more than just an object, then it really is appropriate to research visibility. The visibility of an image represents a phenomenon sui generis. It is set apart in principle from the usual view of something because it is not bound up with the presence of that something. The visibility of an object being looked at in the world demands the presence of that object: one can only see what is there. But there is an exception to this rule on the surface of the image. Images isolate. In an image, the visibility of something is separated from its presence. Images are dematerializations that transform things into pure visibility. In a photograph of Peter, one does not see Peter himself, but only certain forms that are more or less similar to him. Peter’s visibility has been detached from his existence in this image, which is why what is depicted cannot be tasted or smelt, but only ever seen. This is significant for images: in order to be an image, an image must show something on its surface that is not there itself. Every image is a visible contradiction between presence and absence. For this reason, it is only on picture surfaces that visibility can be found without the ballast of some dependent substance: a photograph

Introduction

7

of Mount Everest is not heavy, and an image of the North Sea is not wet. Under these circumstances, as trivial as they are fundamental, the main focus turns to the question of what an image can do beyond depicting objects: if the objective content is not of interest, the visible surface of the image itself is. It is worth the effort to reconstruct the theory of the visibility of the image in its development from the non-speculative aesthetic movement of the nineteenth century to the phenomenology of the twentieth. Starting from Herbartianism, one actually finds a series of philosophies that are systematically relevant from the standpoint of the way they frame their inquiries, because they try to think back from the picture surface. The overarching purpose necessarily entails a commitment to concentrate on the reconstruction of those arguments that in hindsight appear to be the principal elements of a common project, to use images for their visibility. Since we have explicitly chosen to reconstruct not the history of aesthetics itself, but a particular reasoning from the history of aesthetics, the work of formal aestheticians will not be considered in its full breadth; we will not be following all of the tracks that lead out from them. From the many tracks that could be followed in the history of aesthetics, those will be selected that seem particularly relevant to the modern world of images. With reference to selected historical studies, each of the six chapters presents the genesis and significance of one main idea in formal aesthetics. The first chapter examines the issue of what understanding of a work underpins formal aesthetics. The Viennese philosopher Robert Zimmermann (1824– 1898) took up this problem. As a student of Herbart, he is to be credited with having brought his teacher’s sketchy programme of formal aesthetics into a consistent, systematic form. Zimmermann furnished not only the concept ‘formal aesthetics’, but also a clear idea of the discipline to which aesthetics would need to adhere, once it was free of metaphysical systems. Zimmermann designed formal aesthetics in explicit analogy to formal logic. Logic provides an exemplary demonstration of a purely syntactic way of using signs, that is, without regard to objective content. The way Zimmermann applied this procedure to aesthetics is to be reconstructed here in detail. It becomes clear that Zimmermann’s philosophical obscurity stems from his thinking that philosophical aesthetics needs to explain what beauty is. In fact formal aesthetics starts with a philosopher typical of a transitional period: in the form of his inquiry, Zimmermann is firmly bound to the eighteenth century – he is looking for the objective qualities of beauty. But in his concept of a work he anticipates twentieth-century structuralist thought – he looks only at visible relations on the surface. In the turn away from the question of beauty, Zimmermann, and with him his noteworthy Allgemeine Ästhetik

8

The Visibility of the Image

als Formwissenschaft [General Aesthetics as a Science of Form] of 1865, were forgotten. But Zimmermann need not be read as a theoretician of beauty. His writings have an unexpected currency – especially in light of recent debate about how the work of art is to be understood – because they can be grasped as an effort to outline a non-idealistic concept of form. In fact the image is an object of reflection on the grounds of its form alone in formal aesthetics. Zimmermann is not trying to describe the concrete forms of particular works, as in art history, but rather to describe the logical principles of pictorial form as such. With this idea, Zimmermann set a course that leads beyond his own solution. Zimmermann’s own student, the Viennese art theoretician Alois Riegl (1858–1905), went on to develop aesthetics on the model of formal logic. This helps to explain why philosophy lost sight of formal aesthetics:  the first formal observations of pictorial surfaces occur in the context of the founding of art history. The second chapter interprets Riegl’s theory of style as a further response to Zimmermann’s call for an aesthetics oriented towards formal logic. From this perspective it becomes clear that Riegl’s formal aesthetics supplements the relational logic that arose at the same time. The concerns of relational logic substantially developed by August De Morgan and Charles Sanders Peirce are analogous to those of formal aesthetics: the preparation of instruments for describing structural formations. Both disciplines are about specifying the formal qualities of relationships. But the categories of formal logic are not sufficient for the special purpose of describing a pictorial surface as an immanent relational structure. The traditional means of relational logic, for example categories such as ‘transitive’ and ‘reflexive’, cannot cope formally with the infrastructure of a pictorial surface. The transitional categories Riegl developed, such as ‘optical’ versus ‘painterly’ or ‘haptic versus ‘linear’, refine formal logic for aesthetic purposes, and so lay the foundation for formal aesthetics’ continuing engagement with relational logic. The third chapter follows subsequent work on the relational logic of the pictorial surface. The writings of the art theoretician Heinrich Wölfflin (1864–1945) necessarily lie at the heart of the matter. It is particularly the case for his famous book Principles of Art History (1915) which brought an entirely new depth to Riegl’s structure-theoretical understanding of style, and enriched this understanding by several new categories for the formal description of immanent pictorial relationships. Wölfflin’s thought still marks a turning point in the ways two central questions in formal aesthetics are answered. First, what logical dependencies exist between the relational qualities of a pictorial form? And second, how are the

Introduction

9

logical relational qualities of the image related to human perception? The remarkable thing is that Wölfflin gives one answer to both questions: the regularities of immanent pictorial relationships correspond to forms of human perception. In this way, Wölfflin brought about a fundamental change in the way formal aesthetics understands itself. For by undermining the difference between the form of depiction and the form of perception, he subverted the opposition between aesthetics as a theory of art and aisthetics as a theory of the senses. Because Wölfflin was using the image to research perception, formal aesthetics comes to serve aisthetics. The surface of the image lets us see structural connections that can be grasped as principles of vision. From this point of view, Wölfflin makes the image a unique instrument of cognition by virtue of its form. From just this strong observation about form one can see that the form of an image is not just an ornamental structure. Through its form, the image permits us to grasp one aspect of our observation, one that is independent of the observed object because it is entirely conditional. With this, the relationship between making visible and becoming visible through observation becomes the new theme of formal aesthetics. Among the central tasks of this chapter is to foreground and discuss Wölfflin’s more than terminological reliance on Kant’s concept of the form of intuition. Only in comparison to Kant can we describe the typically neo-Kantian development of transcendental aesthetics through formal aesthetics to a theory of – as Wölfflin puts it – ‘ocular conditions’. Wölfflin’s art historical principles develop a logic of ways of seeing that is needed and called upon just when consciousness exhibits a pictorial structural coherence. Wölfflin made Kant’s transcendental aesthetics concrete, not least by abandoning the idea of a transcendental subject. In historical perspective, the step his formal aesthetics makes towards an understanding of consciousness has a significance for the continuing development of phenomenology that is only now being systematically examined. Abandoning any purely intentional understanding of human consciousness, Ferdinand Fellmann describes consciousness as a medium whose functions and conditions at any particular moment can be grasped only by way of an image. His call to use an image to grasp, through form, something that cannot be described objectively because of its conditionality and affectivity, forms the hermeneutic background for this work on the history of formal aesthetics. The fourth chapter asks whether the formal observation of an image must always be the observation of a way of seeing. With the possibility of using an image as a cognitive instrument to recognize the conditions of perception, attention turns to the infrastructure of the picture surface. But once attention

10

The Visibility of the Image

is focussed the surface, the initial motivation can disappear, and the surface can also be viewed without hermeneutic interest. The development of the image in the twentieth century, driven by art and new media, challenges us to investigate the problem of what happens to a pictorial surface when it is free from the need to depict a way of seeing as well. The basic interests and expectations of formal aesthetics, the paradigms on which it draws for its arguments, can change: from a way of seeing to visibility. This decisive step can be reconstructed in the writings of the Saxon philosopher Konrad Fiedler (1841–1895). Although his work precedes Wölfflin’s, the formal aesthetic he outlined goes beyond an orientation to a way of seeing. Wölfflin shaped the neo-Kantian understanding of an image into a logic of ways of seeing; Fiedler in fact substantially developed the same idea, but in the end also aspired to overcome it. With Fiedler it is possible to demonstrate that the turn to a way of seeing is only a first step in the emancipation of the pictorial surface; he starts to make the surface absolute, but does not complete the process. Of course an image of Turner’s not of interest for the ships it depicts, but for the way the ships are seen. In art, when one is interested in a way of seeing, attention is already focussed on the surface of the image. This is where the way of seeing is constructed. One attends to the style of an image because it shows how something can be visible. A  conscious disregard of the depicted object is not a misuse of the image in such a case, because such a use is already implicit in it. A meaningful viewing of a Turner image is achieved when it is not ships, but an order of the visible that can be seen. But the possibility of using images for their sheer, pure visibility opens only when an image is viewed neither for its depicted objects nor for its way of seeing. The most radical kind of formal pictorial understanding permits an image to consist of its unique characteristics, its visibility alone. Inevitably, the question will be: to what images does this formal aesthetic apply? What images are viewed meaningfully when they are viewed for their visibility alone? Unlike Wölfflin, who rightly turned to the traditional easel picture with his logic of ways of seeing, this thesis about looking at the image for its visibility seems especially suited to making the new pictorial forms of the twentieth century comprehensible. With this idea as a guide, a path can be constructed that leads from avantgarde experiments at the beginning of the century – especially Suprematism and collage – through the theory of silent film and on to modern video clips. The concern at all points is with pictorial experiments in which a formal aesthetic point of view is explicitly reflected. Fiedler’s approach is elaborated to differentiate among different types of visibility in images. The pure visibility of images is conditioned by medium. The rigid visibility of an easel picture is different

Introduction

11

from the dynamic visibility made possible by film. Yet only with digital image processing does a form of pure visibility become available that can be called an independent entity  – Fiedler speaks of a ‘form of being’  – because it permits manipulation and, in the case of simulation, even interaction. Without moving materials around, without danger or force, sheer visibility is available on screen and eventually takes on contains qualities that are designed not to be visible, qualities that video games and computer simulations exploit. Visibility begins to exhibit behaviour and to enter into relationships of exchange with viewers, who automatically become users. The pictorial surface is transformed, on monitors, into a user surface. These qualitative leaps in the development of new pictorial forms can be clearly traced by attending to their visibility. When the interpretation of an image, in the sense of formal aesthetics, is internalized through an image, pure visibility takes on a level of autonomy unlike that of earlier images, one that seems to characterize images of this century in particular because it applies to both art and to new media. In both cases, it needs to be shown that the effort to make visibility unconditional ends at exactly the point where the image is no longer a sign for something, but is made and viewed as an object sui generis: as an object, then, characterized by its being nothing more than visible. This development introduces a change in the way an image is the understood to be produced, the effects of which become increasingly noticeable and oppressive. From the standpoint of a way of seeing, the production of an image that is not primarily concerned with simple depiction of a visible reality is one of the traditional tasks of visual art, one that can be associated with artistic truth claims. But from the standpoint of visibility, the possibility of speaking meaningfully about a formal truth vanishes; the image becomes a designed thing. Instead of an interpretation of visible reality, new pictorial forms in this century generate visibility alone, and with it an enrichment of visible reality with virtual reality. These new forms cannot be either false or true, because they simply are, without referring to anything. In this chapter, the constructions of virtual reality, culminating in cyberspace, are treated as technical transformations of an understanding of pictorial visibility anticipated in formal aesthetics. The fifth chapter pursues a philosophical analysis of the method that underpins the formal observation of an image. In formal aesthetics, the image, which consists of a multiplicity of aspects and is implicated in a multiplicity of contexts, is reduced to one surface. The really remarkable thing is that this reduction is not considered a loss of the image’s multiplicity – as one would first think – but a gain. In order to be able to understand the reduction immanent in the study of

12

The Visibility of the Image

visibility, it is necessary to examine the relationship between formal aesthetics and phenomenology. The writings of the French phenomenologist Maurice MerleauPonty (1908–1961) examine and extend the connections between the problems of reduction and visibility. His late essays in particular may be considered a further development of the work of formal aesthetics, because they show clearly how formal aesthetics always understood itself as a form of phenomenology avant la lettre. The phenomenological idea of the ‘epoché’, a deliberate refusal of relationships with objects, is the principle of the formal observation of images. MerleauPonty’s interpretation of reduction and pictorial visibility takes us back to the question of whether and how there can be pictorial forms that sensually reflect, in the images themselves, the formal as well as phenomenological ways they should be approached. Are there images that bear witness to having bracketed the world out? Following on from the types of images specified in the previous chapter, this requires an examination of images in which no object is visible at all. This is the case for an abstract image. The abstract image can no longer be observed in any way but the one formal aesthetics demands: there is no object to see. Therefore the abstract image is to be interpreted here, in connection with Merleau-Ponty, as a realized form of phenomenological reduction by means of painting. The sixth chapter turns to the semiotic status of the pictorial surface. From the standpoint of the theory of signs, the conclusions of formal aesthetics must have a semiotic foundation. The key question is, Is an image that does not refer to an object a sign, and if it is, in what sense? The abstract image can be understood as a sign only if we are in a position to recognize a type of sign that describes no object, either extant or fictive, which can specifically be a sign without any designated object. The semiotics of the American Charles William Morris (1901– 1979) is particularly concerned with this problem. The intention in turning to these writings is to represent semiotic aesthetics – at least at the beginning – as a variation of formal aesthetics using other means. Morris suggests a comparison between the form of the abstract image and the language of mathematics or logic. Zimmermann’s initial intention, to orient formal aesthetics to the methods of formal logic, remains in evidence here, in Morris’s comparison between the semiotic status of abstract images and algebraic formulae. But Morris’s theory of signs does more than help to give a semiotic description of the non-objective image in its traditional form as an easel picture. It goes on to develop a conceptual apparatus with which to reach a semiotic understanding of more recent types of play with non-objective imagery. Just as Morris, on the sign-theory side, charts a path from formator to formative discourse, there is a further discursive development for the abstract image as

Introduction

13

well. Morris encouraged, with good reason, a search for pictorial forms that can be described, in semiotic terms, as formative discourse. These have to be image sequences, for discourse always has a temporal dimension. In fact Morris’s concept of formative discourse can be used to describe the relatively recent phenomena of extremely fast image sequences. Surfing through channels on television, driving an automobile through an image-rich world of advertisements, a person sees ephemeral images that simply flit across the field of vision. The video clip demonstrates what happens to images in a transport of speed, and media studies describe a tendency for faster and faster image sequences to shape recent film, especially television production. Looking at this tendency from the point at which it is aimed – a target neither achieved nor even desired – objective contents disappear, and image sequences appear that take on an ambivalent semiotic status. It is a condition in which objective meaning is only suggested, not achieved, in which pure visibility is presented not as a real sign for something, but as a possible sign for signs. From a semiotic point of view, the totalizing of visibility puts the medium in a condition Hans Magnus Enzensberger described as a ‘null medium’. These studies of the logic of formal aesthetics serve to articulate a theory that led the step-by-step emancipation of pure visibility in the development of the image. The theory of visibility is understood to be a contribution to the phenomenology of medial worlds in which images are the dominant phenomena. For more and more people, more and more of what is held to be real comes from the viewing of images. The situation inevitably calls attention to the image as one of the factors that shape contemporary forms of life. To speak of a flood of images is anything but an original discovery. There can hardly be any argument that images contribute substantially to making the world a global village, in that the most distant events – in part simultaneous – are familiar, as if they had happened just around the corner. But in assessing this process, the following thought experiment is helpful: suppose there are two people who live in comparable environments and who have access to the same information at the same speed. The only difference is that in one world, images are used for information, and in the other they are not. Although at present it is difficult to believe that there would ever be non-visual media that could transmit information as well as images do, this thought experiment shows that even without a difference in transmitted knowledge, the world of images is richer by one singular phenomenon. Images expand reality in a way that is independent of any message, because their visibility is always more fundamental than their legibility. Information transmitted through images is

14

The Visibility of the Image

more than the information alone. They still always have another aspect that cannot be replaced by signs of the same value. For only with an image is the legibility of a sign bound up with its pure visibility. No sign that is not itself an image can substitute for this phenomenon. The phenomenon of pure visibility – in work on it as well as play with it – enters into human reality only through images. For this reason, a world without images would be poorer even apart from the loss of knowledge or insight:  one could see only what really is there, and everything that is not there would be condemned to invisibility. Visibility would be inseparably bound to the hard and heavy world. But since there are images, it is less and less often the case.

1

The Beginnings of Formal Aesthetics: Robert Zimmermann (1824–1898)

1.1 Formal logic as a model for formal aesthetics Giving up the work and contemplation of the work An increasing number of philosophical aestheticians deliberately avoid saying anything about the aesthetic object. For quite a few contemporary aestheticians, the aesthetic object is irrelevant. This characterization applies to the aesthetics of reception and to analytic aesthetics equally, if not in the same way. Both tendencies can serve as examples of the way aesthetic objects are discussed as ‘substitutes’. The work in the traditional sense, as an object characterized by special visible qualities, is deliberately circumvented. The aesthetics of reception turns away from the aesthetic object by concerning itself exclusively with the effect the aesthetic object has on the subject. The aesthetic object is defined by the subject’s response to it. It is, as Hans Robert Jauß emphasizes in Aesthetic Experience and Literary Hermeneutics, ‘the convergence of work and effect that is the starting point for German aesthetics of reception’ (tr) (p. 63). Even a brief glance at the movement’s key text confirms that it supports ‘the relinquishing of an aesthetics of the work’ (tr) (ibid.). The aesthetics of reception is not concerned with art objects, but rather with aesthetic experience in association with them. It describes acts of consciousness, and in this way transforms philosophical aesthetics into a subdiscipline of the theory of consciousness.1 In analytical aesthetics, the situation is not different in principle  – at least not if we keep this post-war movement’s original intention in mind.2 In this context, language analytic aesthetics is concerned with so-called meta-aesthetic problems rather than with works. This is documented with particular clarity

16

The Visibility of the Image

in the writings of George Dickie, a co-founder and key exponent of language analytic aesthetics. According to Dickie, ‘aesthetics (at least philosophical aesthetics) is concerned only with the language and concepts which are used to describe and evaluate works of art’.3 Aesthetics accordingly becomes a special case of language philosophy. The insights of a well-developed language philosophy are brought to bear on the language spoken in aesthetic reflection on art. So aesthetics becomes a reflection on the language of other aestheticians, which is to say meta-aesthetics. Contemporary aesthetics’ turn away from the object is understandable when it is seen as a reaction to the art of the avant-garde in this century. In order for a theory of art to justify its relevance to the present, it is increasingly expected to account for the avant-garde. Franz Koppe describes an ordinarily unspoken, accepted background of contemporary aesthetic discussion:  ‘If you discuss a theory of art today with people who are familiar with what is currently happening in art, you can be sure that the theory, whatever its source, will be tested, sooner rather than later, against the contemporary avant-garde. More exactly, by whether a particular conception of art accounts not only for the traditional inventory, but also, in fact above all for the oppositional avant-garde’s break with tradition in modernity’(tr).4 Exactly this break with tradition pertains to the understanding of a work, however. One of the hallmarks of the avant-garde is a programmatic destruction of works. The many ready-mades since Duchamp show, in a particularly crass way, that parts of contemporary art cannot be considered works in a traditional sense.5 The art of the avant-garde undermines the visible difference between an ordinary object and an aesthetic object by dispensing with composition and design, form and style.6 Parts of the so-called postmodern art of the present take this project to extremes, and completely abandon the idea that art needs a perceptible materialization in formal structures.7 With this background, it is understandable that reception aesthetics has turned to aesthetic experience. It is founded – as is analytic philosophy’s turn to language – on the following idea: if art produces no works, then aesthetics, too, must get along without a specific understanding of a work. This is the argument Rüdiger Bubner used in ‘Über einige Bedingungen gegenwärtiger Ästhetik’ [On Some Conditions of Contemporary Aesthetics] of 1973, in any case, to defend the project of a reception aesthetics based on Kant:  ‘So aesthetic conceptions that must work, unchanged, with the traditional category of the work, or that just add up to an emphatic confirmation of the concept of the work, are the least suited to contemporary art [. . ..] Modern art in particular has let us see that philosophical aesthetics must appeal purely to aesthetic experience itself if

The Beginnings of Formal Aesthetics

17

it does not want to completely block access to the ways art has been manifesting itself for some time’ (tr).8 Bubner’s idea is persuasive. Theories of aesthetic experience turn out to be best suited to an art for which visibility is not important, which may, in the most extreme cases, exist by declaration alone – but this is also the case for analytic aestheticians who argue in a similar way. This is the field of art that conforms to those aesthetics that take the view, in essence: ‘The aesthetic is something that may not finally be determined by looking at the object at all, but must rather be determined by observing what happens inside us. [. . .] This lets us say at least that the aesthetic does not constitute an area with ontologically specifiable qualities, but rather that it depends on an attitude that subjects are in principle capable of having with respect to objects’ (tr).* This is the way Birgit Recki supports a Kantian approach to the artistic situation at present in Wie ästhetisch ist die moderne Kunst?’ [How Aesthetic Is Modern Art?] of 1990 (pp. 107 and 109). The ways in which the avantgarde changed the concept of the work therefore do not, for her, have any bearing on the question of what is unique about aesthetics: ‘Modern art’, her thesis goes, ‘is always as aesthetic as we ourselves let it be – and for this reason is neither more nor less aesthetic than the art of earlier epochs’ (ibid., p. 112). In this evaluation, the approaches of reception aesthetics and languageanalysis come together. The latter approach, too, is suitable for any form of work, because it contains a statement of the characteristics of a work. Nelson Goodman’s famous essay ‘When Is Art?’ (1977) is typical in this respect. The title is a formulation of the question Goodman thinks should replace the traditional question ‘What is art?’ With the new question, Goodman is expressing, in a different way, the view that objects are only aesthetic objects as long as we see them that way. The aesthetic depends entirely on the momentary attitude of a subject or the current recognition of specific cultural institutions: ‘. . . .just as an object may be a symbol [. . .] at certain times and under certain circumstances, and not at others, so an object may be a work of art at some times and not at others. [. . .] The stone is normally no work of art while in the driveway, but may be so when on display in an art museum. [. . .] On the other hand, a Rembrandt painting may cease to function as a work of art . . .’ (p. 67). This thesis of aesthetics’ dependency on the situation can be pushed still further: Among Goodman’s followers, there is controversy about the meaning of the visible formal structure, whether the way an object is made can be set aside, not only for the question whether an object is a work of art or not, but also for the much more basic * Unless otherwise noted, italics in quoted material indicate emphasis in the original.

18

The Visibility of the Image

question of whether an object is an image as such, which does not need to be an artwork. Drawing on language analytic considerations, the appearance of image is declared to be a secondary consideration in deciding whether it is an image. It says something about contemporary philosophical aesthetics that Oliver R. Scholz can conclude, in his account of recent image theory: ‘The critical point is not the way the objects are designed’(tr).9

The trend in non-speculative aesthetics in the nineteenth century That which is held to be an advantage in dealing with difficult avant-garde art by reception aesthetics and analytic aesthetics can turn out to be a disadvantage if all aesthetic objects are treated in the same way with just the one set of tools, perhaps ultimately suitable to a ready-made. The proposal to dispense with the category of the work altogether, which can be referred back to practices within the avant-garde movement, becomes unsatisfactory when art appears in works. Neither the Kantian nor the analytical approach is able to understand what is unique about aesthetic objects whose particular design stands out and which continue to be aesthetic works despite all the destruction of works. The idea that a group of objects could be an object of aesthetics on the basis of their particular form of visibility hardly seems to be getting any attention any more. An orientation to the avant-garde fails to take into account the underlying fact that many aesthetic objects are trying to be some particular thing through their form, that they were made to be seen, that they serve the sole purpose of trying to show something. The elevation of the avant-garde to the standard for the currency of an aesthetic has the effect of putting the philosophical observation of formal properties in the background, although there will always be aesthetic phenomena that are unique on the basis of their form.* It is possible to treat a painting of Rembrandt’s, a collage of Schwitters’s and a video clip as if their aesthetic qualities were grounded in the same structures  – whether language analytic or consciousness theoretical – as Duchamp’s urinal. But this does not take into account the special quality of images, that even if they are not works of art, they still have aesthetic value on the basis of their visibility. Even if everyone * Peter Bürger completes this argument in Probleme gegenwärtiger Ästhetik [Problems in Contemporary Aesthetics] with three additional ‘objections that can be raised against the effort to develop a contemporary conception of aesthetics from avant-garde movements’ (tr) (p. 201). The key objection goes, ‘For if today one can speak legitimately only of aesthetic experience, but no longer of works of art, it also means that no contemporary artistic objectivation having the character of a work (whatever the type of work it might be) would match the most advanced level of aesthetic consciousness. In other words, the thesis implies a negative judgment of the whole of contemporary aesthetic production, insofar as it does not lie within the context of the avant-garde Happening’(tr) (ibid., p. 204).

The Beginnings of Formal Aesthetics

19

now knows that an object does not drift into an art museum on the basis of its formal qualities, that which is visible in an image and in art remains a theme in philosophical aesthetics, one that does not disappear just because some forms of contemporary art developed into art without works. The elements in contemporary philosophical aesthetics just addressed must seem unattractive to anyone interested in a philosophy of the visible qualities of images. On the other hand, they cast a positive light on movements in nineteenth-century aesthetics that are usually undervalued today. Anyone who has an understanding of objects and a decidedly phenomenological approach will be in fundamental agreement with last century’s so-called non-speculative aesthetics in at least in these respects. This movement carries a discussion of possible ways philosophical aesthetics’ turn to the object could look. In light of the situation just described, it is an inquiry with current relevance, and as such prompts a fresh look at this movement. Non-speculative aesthetics in the second half of the nineteenth century expresses an opposition to German idealism. By mid-century at the latest, there was a reorientation in aesthetics, as in philosophy as a whole, resting on the hope that by taking over the inductive methods of the natural sciences, aesthetics could achieve an unprecedented precision. A mode of observation staying as close as possible to the particularities of the object and going into great detail would displace the universalizing systematics of the early nineteenth century. ‘Precision’ is the key concept of an aesthetic trend that supports an empirical approach to aesthetics, and that draws on the methods of various sciences as a model for doing so. With this, the movement was reacting to an increasingly obvious and unsettling discrepancy between the precise achievements of the natural sciences on one side and stagnating philosophical theories on the other. The short formula for the thinking of this aesthetic movement, which considers itself non-speculative, is the fewer the philosophical assumptions, the more rigorous the knowledge. In short, in this movement there was unanimous support for the view that Konrad Fiedler (1841–1895) put so succinctly in his first text, ‘Über die Beurteilung von Werken der bildenden Kunst’ [On Judging Works of Visual Art] of 1876: ‘We will grasp the possibility of the greatest advances in this knowledge without philosophical reflections’ (tr) (p. 17). This sentence expresses the expectations of a whole generation of aestheticians. It represents the expression of an anti-idealistic turn in aesthetics for which there is evidence in many places.10 One gets both an very early and a very representative impression of the attitude that was new at the time in the opening passage from Eduard Hanslick’s (1825–1904) programmatic text Vom Musikalisch-Schönen. Ein Beitrag zur

20

The Visibility of the Image

Revision der Ästhetik der Tonkunst [On the Beautiful in Music. A Contribution to a Revised Aesthetics of Musical Art] of 1854. There he writes: ‘This objective movement [by which Hanslick means the anti-idealistic trend in philosophy as a whole] could not forego an engagement in the study of the beautiful as well. The philosophical treatment of aesthetics, an attempt to approach the essence of the beautiful in a metaphysical way and to expose its vital elements, is a more recent development. Now if a shift in the discipline should extend to the treatment of aesthetic questions as well, replacing the metaphysical principle with a kind of observation related to inductive methods of the natural sciences, and gaining a powerful influence and at least temporary dominance’ (tr) (p. 1) – ‘only then could one hope that aesthetics would have nothing to fear from the trial by fire of empiricism’ (tr) (p. 28) – in this way, the meaning of Hanslick’s thought can be resolved with a single quotation from Hermann Hettner’s (1821–1854) ‘Gegen die spekulative Ästhetik’ [Against Speculative Aesthetics] of 1845, an essay equally rousing in character. Today, the psychological aesthetic of Gustav Theodor Fechner (1801–1887) is the best-known version of an aesthetic from the non-speculative aesthetics movement. In fact psychological aesthetics can be seen as a prototype of nonspeculative approach, for it shows the movement’s distinguishing feature with great clarity: aesthetics is detached from philosophy. This result is unavoidable if aesthetics is made fully empirical. Fechner’s aesthetics provides an example of this. He leaves no doubt that he intends to transform the basic questions of aesthetics into empirical problems, so that they can then be answered using the experimental methods recently introduced into psychology. In Zur experimentellen Ästhetik [On Experimental Aesthetics] of 1871, the great speculative systems are replaced with the exact data of empirical research. With this, a pattern of thought comes into view, one that is very clear in Fechner, but that implicitly informs aesthetics in the second half of the century to an extent that should not be underestimated. Fechner’s ‘aesthetics from below’, from Vorschule der Ästhetik [Preschool for Aesthetics] has established itself as the name for this pattern of thought. In the search for a science to serve as guide and model for non-speculative aesthetics, hardly any discipline is overlooked.11 In his great, widely read Philosophy of Art (second edition, 1873; two volumes), Hippolyte Taine emphatically defended the view that aesthetics is ‘itself a species of botany, applied not to plants, but to the works of man. By virtue of this, it keeps pace with the general movement of the day, which now affiliates the moral sciences with the natural sciences, and which, giving to the first the principles, precautions and direction of the second, gives them the same stability, and assures them the same progress’

The Beginnings of Formal Aesthetics

21

(p. 38).12 On the other hand, Georg Hirth, in Aufgaben der Kunstphysiologie [The Responsibilities of a Physiology of Art] of 1891  – along with Grant Allen in Physiological Aesthetics (1877) and Francis Galton in Hereditary Genius (1869) – looks to physiology for the experimental methods that will provide precise answers to aesthetic questions – an idea defended even by Nietzsche in his late work.13 The view that problems of form can be seamlessly extracted from social causes, a view amenable to H. Taine, is represented implicitly in the art criticism of the writer and theoretician Charles-Augustin Sainte-Beuve, and explicitly in Die Kunst als soziologisches Phänomen [Art as a Sociological Phenomenon] of 1888, a text from the estate of the philosopher Jean-Marie Guyau. Conversely, Ernst Grosse’s view in his book Die Anfänge der Kunst [The Beginnings of Art] of 1894 is that aesthetics should be pursued as a form of ethnology, and Caesare Lombroso, in Genie und Irrsinn [Genius and Madness] of 1877 declares medical psychiatry to be the model science for a future aesthetics.

Robert Zimmermann’s forgotten programme The project of the Viennese aesthetician Robert Zimmermann (1824–1898) is among the initiatives made within framework of non-speculative aesthetics that are almost unknown today. Zimmermann figured prominently in the founding of the anti-idealistic reorientation of aesthetics through his essay, widely acclaimed at the time, ‘Die spekulative Ästhetik und die Kritik’ [Speculative Aesthetics and Criticism] of 1854.14 His alternative suggestion for speculative aesthetics can be reduced to the following formula: aesthetics will reach the desired level of precision when it orients itself to formal logic. Zimmermann’s statement of purpose reads, ‘to the extent aesthetics is a science of form, it coincides with logic as a science of form’(tr). This is the way Zimmermann formulated his programme in 1865 in his comprehensive, systematic principal work titled Allgemeine Ästhetik als Formwissenschaft [General Aesthetics as a Science of Form] (§80). Formal logic certainly has the same capacity as the natural sciences to provide a model of desirable precision. Zimmermann’s primary aesthetic concerns are to this extent in fundamental accord with the hope that by means of an empirical approach, aesthetics would become precise. His programme is – as one can in turn read from an essay title – typical for the ‘Reform der Ästhetik als exakter Wissenschaft’ [Reform of Aesthetics as an Exact Science] of 1862. Yet because Zimmermann does not single out an empirical discipline as his model – as is usual in the movement – he has a special position within the non-speculative aesthetic trend that is worth noting. An understanding

22

The Visibility of the Image

of Zimmermann’s aesthetics requires awareness that formal logic is not an empirical theory that creates knowledge from experiments. With formal logic as a model, aesthetics could never – as in the case of Fechner – get to the point of becoming an empirical discipline. On the contrary, formal logic is an a priori discipline, and as a result, Zimmermann’s own guiding concept forces him to shape his aesthetic accordingly. He himself expressly acknowledges it: ‘aesthetics [. . .] is therefore not an empirical, but rather an a priori science’ (tr) (Formwissenschaft, §76). Even this cursory look at the basic theses of Robert Zimmermann shows how clearly he stands out within non-speculative aesthetics. Zimmermann takes up an exceptional position. When the scientific euphoria of the second half of the nineteenth century dies down, and with it the belief in the possibility that philosophical aesthetics could be made empirical and resolved, that position becomes noteworthy. If a promising approach is developed within non-speculative aesthetics, it is Zimmermann’s. He does not believe in the possibility of translating philosophical problems smoothly into empirical inquiries. From today’s standpoint, Zimmermann’s aesthetic, often dismissed as a curiosity, appears distinctly progressive. For it responds in an anticipatory way to problems with making aesthetics empirical, for example with psychologism, which didn’t actually receive very widespread attention until the beginning of the twentieth century.15 The attraction of Zimmermann’s aesthetic is something almost contradictory. Although Zimmermann basically stood for a non-speculative aesthetic, he nevertheless does not talk about any ‘aesthetic from below’, if we take the metaphor to mean a connection to experimental results. He wants to use logical precision not to discuss individual images, but to talk about the logical qualities of works as such; he is concerned with a ‘general science of art’ (tr).16 By this Zimmermann means the prima facie, seemingly paradoxical ambition to unite apriorism with the analysis of works. Zimmermann’s steps in working this programme out are worth retracing.

1.2 The programme: A structural theory of the picture surface Formalism and Herbartianism Robert Zimmermann should be considered the primary exponent of aesthetic formalism. He took the view that the form of an object alone is responsible for

The Beginnings of Formal Aesthetics

23

its aesthetic qualities. The founding premise of formalism is that in an aesthetic theory, the content of aesthetic objects can be excluded as a matter of principle, because content is aesthetically indifferent. From this point of view, aesthetics is concerned only with the particular way something is made, only with the way it looks. These theses cannot be traced back to Zimmermann alone, nor are they new in the nineteenth century. Formalism rather counts among the basic aesthetic positions that can be traced, at least through their implicit variations, back to antiquity.17 But it is no coincidence that formalism acquired its systematic fittings in the nineteenth century – in the context of a movement opposed to idealistic philosophies, a reflection on basic formalist ideas was almost inevitable, since these were formulated in clear opposition to the idealistic understanding of artistic beauty.18 This was the case for the philosopher Johann Friedrich Herbart (1776–1841), particularly for his students. Herbart himself neglected to state his formal aesthetics explicitly; in his work, there are only short passages on aesthetic questions, and they are distributed throughout his entire philosophical work.19 Even today the term ‘Herbartianism’ designates formalism in aesthetics because a series of students took it upon themselves to work through and defend Herbart’s fragmentary theory; this applies to Friedrich Conrad Griepenkerl (1792–1849), Georg Eduard Bobrik (1802–1870), Otto Flügel (1842–1914) and most particularly to Robert Zimmermann.20 Zimmermann’s philosophical life work is marked by an increasingly strong identification with Herbart’s ideas. His early publications discuss Herbart’s theoretical philosophy, but what is at first an equally strong presence, that of the logician Bernard Bolzano, technically his instructor in philosophy, diminishes steadily.* In his aesthetics, Zimmermann finally comes to explicitly represent Herbart’s aesthetic views. He emphasizes it right from the first pages: Zimmermann understands his Allgemeine Ästhetik als Formwissenschaft of 1865 as the missing ‘systematic elaboration of aesthetics from a Herbartian point of view’ (tr) (p. 5). * Bolzano and Zimmermann had an informal teacher-student relationship. It arose from a close friendship between Bolzano and Johann August Zimmermann, Robert’s father. Cf. Ed. Winter, Bernard Bolzano und sein Kreis [Bernard Bolzano and his Circle]. It may have been decisive for Robert Zimmermann’s intellectual. He was able to pursue and even resolve this position by development that Bolzano passed along to him a strong fundamental rejection of Kant’s as well as of Hegel’s philosophy drawing closer to Herbart’s philosophy and by developing a purely formal aesthetic. Bolzano’s ‘theory of science’ further acquainted Zimmermann with a formally very advanced version of logic. Zimmermann even developed a short version of Bolzano’s logic for use in preparatory schools. On the collaboration of Bolzano and R.  Zimmermann in the field of formal logic, see the Introduction for ‘Robert Zimmermanns philosophische Propädeutik und die Vorlagen aus der Wissenschaftslehre Bernard Bolzanos’, ed. Eduard Winter [Robert Zimmermann’s Philosophical Propaedeutic and Its Antecedents in the Scientific Theory of Bernard Bolzano].

24

The Visibility of the Image

Formalism versus idealism The opposition between a Herbartian and an idealistic aesthetic crystallizes around the question of the way the relationship between form and content in an aesthetic object can be described. It is therefore concerned with what may be the most frequently discussed question in aesthetics of the second half of the century.21 Hardly any aesthetician can avoid taking a position on the relationship between form and content in works of art. In this discussion, which even today can be assessed only with difficulty, the various idealistic positions appear far from unanimous, but they do coincide on one key point. For idealism, the beauty of a form is based on the content expressed in that form, that is, on a relationship that extends beyond the work, and not on a relation immanent to the work. An idealistic understanding of beauty is bound up with the meaning, the content of the work. This view runs like a red thread through the most diverse variants of idealistic aesthetics, and can be documented in innumerable places. Hegel’s statement in his posthumously published Aesthetics of 1835 is as exemplary as it is explicit, ‘We called the beautiful the Idea of the beautiful. [. . .] Therefore the beautiful is characterized as the pure appearance of the Idea to sense’ (pp. 106 and 111). Even Schopenhauer, whose idealistic philosophy differs sharply from that of Hegel in other respects, leaves this basic idea untouched in The World as Will and Idea of 1819: the principle ‘which makes it possible to express the beautiful, concerns not the form but the content of phenomena, not the how but the what of the phenomenon’ (§45, p. 287). Aesthetic formalism advances exactly the opposite view. For Herbartianism, the beautiful is an attribute of the form itself, of the ‘how’. The perceptible immanent relations on the surface of the object alone are responsible for the quality and beauty of an aesthetic object. Beauty depends on how the inner relationships of the parts are arranged with respect to one another, how the object is composed and structured. So for Herbartianism, beauty is a feature of the interior structure; today we would speak of a syntactic understanding of beauty. But we must take care because although the formalist side of this argument accused the idealist side of considering the form of the object to be unimportant, this is not the case. Such a radical orientation to content cannot be attributed to any historically significant idealist aesthetic. An aesthetic of pure content or subject matter is problematic in any case because the perceptible appearance of contents always depends on some formal configuration that makes the content visible. This has by no means escaped idealist aestheticians’ notice. If, in idealist aesthetics, beauty is seen in the meaning of a work, it is still about a visible

The Beginnings of Formal Aesthetics

25

appearance of this meaning – whether it is the idea of the beautiful in Hegel or the of the will in Schopenhauer, both must become form in order to be beautiful. The relationship of form and content is therefore grasped as a dialectical relationship in idealistic aesthetics. In order to be content, however, the content depends on its opposite; there is no pictorial appearance of contents without pictorial form. Form and content are the two inseparable sides of a coin. This is important in distinguishing between formalist and idealistic positions in the question of form. According to the formalist view, the problem with the idealist view is not at all that form gets insufficient attention. What troubles the formal point of view about idealism concerns the insurmountable independence of form with respect to objective content. The discussion of beauty merely serves as a means of demonstrating this independence of form. For formalism, idealist aesthetics fail to recognize and to appropriately acknowledge the autonomous aspects of form, which are always there, despite its use for all kinds of purposes. Formalist aestheticians did not deny the relationship between form and content, however often one still hears it.22 The counterexamples are too obvious:  if we want to depict a chessboard, the square fields may not appear round. The way an image of something appears depends on the thing that is depicted. Yet the content does not determine the form of an aesthetic object completely, not in all its aspects, which is just what it comes down to for formalism. This partial independence can be recognized, as Zimmermann points out, by taking beauty into consideration. For if a form were to be completely determined by content, then any image of an object that had ever been depicted as beautiful would have to be beautiful. This is not the case, however. The same object can be equally recognizable in an image that is either beautiful or ugly. What formalism opposes is that despite all the dialectical recognition of the importance of form in idealist aesthetics, the visible exterior is clearly undervalued, since this exterior supposedly depends entirely on the purposes being served. It is just a function and has no independent existence. Especially in Hegel, one can see that form, for him, is understood only as a non-autonomous moment of the real, as that which permits the content to appear. It is the means to an end, and so stands in a functional relationship, as Hegel goes on to say explicitly: ‘by a definite content the form appropriate to it is also made definite’ (Aesthetics, p.  13). With this, the priorities are clearly set:  formal qualities do not proceed from making as such, but rather from the appropriateness of form to the idea that is realized in the making. Form should not emphasize its independence with respect to contents, but should be fully given over to the purpose

26

The Visibility of the Image

of depicting contents. From the idealistic point of view, the best form is based entirely on the purpose. This is exactly what Zimmermann finds impossible. No level of suitability can guarantee that a form is beautiful. Any deliberately constructed form has unique qualities that are not determined by this purpose or content, despite that form serving a purpose or specifying content. Beauty is an example of such a quality for Zimmermann. In the background, he keeps a simple idea that any purpose can be served by multiple forms, of which only a few are beautiful, which is why it is beauty that demonstrates the multiplicity of appropriate forms, beautiful and not. In this way, beauty serves to mark out a freedom of form with respect to purpose. It shows that a form, despite its functional engagement, also has an aspect that remains indeterminate. When it comes to beauty, forms are independent of content. One might also say: the problem of beauty enables Zimmermann to identify an autonomous aspect of forms.

Formal aesthetics: The observation of the visible form If, from a historical standpoint, Herbartianism’s concept of form sets up the opposition to idealism, from the standpoint of systems it sets up an analogy to the concept of form in formal logic. Formal logic is an independent discipline because logical form is an autonomous phenomenon whose validity can be described independently of content. In this respect, formal logic handles forms in an exemplary way, which Zimmermann wants to establish in aesthetics as well. Formal logic is exclusively concerned with structures that can be declared logical independently of content. The validity of the syllogism ‘Socrates is a human being, and every human being is mortal, therefore Socrates is mortal’ is a formal truth on which the content of the sentences has no bearing. For this reason, logical forms can be declared logically true or valid in logical calculations without any content. The content has no power to alter these formal insights or even to make them invalid. Even the syllogism ‘Socrates is a dog, dogs have five legs, so Socrates has five legs’ is formally correct. Zimmermann takes this treatment of forms in logic as a model, except that rather than the logic, he wants to describe the aesthetic qualities of forms, which have principles independent of content. His aesthetic rests on the view that forms in themselves have logical and aesthetic qualities. As disciplines concerned with forms, logic, like aesthetics, should therefore study forms as such, without taking functional content into consideration. Zimmerman’s primary interest is in defending this claim to analogy. He therefore does not tire of asserting, ‘We keep running up

The Beginnings of Formal Aesthetics

27

against the parallel [. . .] between aesthetics as one science of form, and logic as another science of form’ (Formwissenschaft, §975). In looking at Zimmermann’s project from this purely systematic perspective, it becomes clear that he is trying to grasp the aesthetic autonomy of form, as distinct from everything extra-aesthetic, by transferring the concept of form through which the autonomy of the logical is assured in formal logic. One might also say that Zimmerman wants to carry over, into aesthetics, the positive character logic has in formalism. For this reason it seems useful as well as natural to designate Zimmermann’s programme in analogy to formal logic as formal aesthetics and not as formalism  – which is what at first happened with Otto Flügel in Über den formalen Charakter des Ästhetik [On the Formal Character of Aesthetics] of 1864, as well as with Zimmermann himself in his essay ‘Über Lotzes Kritik der formalistischen Ästhetik’ [On Lotze’s Critique of Formal Aesthetics] of 1868.* Zimmermann’s orientation to formal logic makes it clear that the antagonism between formal aesthetics and idealism goes back to each aesthetic having discovered something essential in the other. For one, the essential thing is the surface appearance itself; for the other it is what lies beneath the surface. The inevitable result of this disparity in evaluation is that formal aesthetics and idealism promote diametrically opposed aesthetic concepts. Idealism sets out an aesthetic of transcendence, and formalism an aesthetic of immanence; here an essentialist search for the ideal and essential in aesthetics, there a positivist adherence to the structures of the surface; here the aesthetic form is bound to the unity of a hidden idea, there the aesthetic form is opened up into a multiplicity of visible relationships. Idealism tries to think form in its dependence on content; formalism, by contrast, understands by form exactly those aspects that are not determined by content. Only through such contrasts in argumentative strategy does it become possible to understand the essential intention of formalism. Of course Zimmermann’s formal aesthetics was still inhibited by a sense of

* The concept ‘formal aesthetics’ actually has the advantage over ‘formalism’ first, in emphasizing the analogy to formal logic, and second, in dispelling the negative aftertaste of the concept of formalism. This is why, by 1868, it was already natural for Hermann Lotze, in Geschichte der Ästhetik in Deutschland [The History of Aesthetics in Germany], to refer to Herbartianism as ‘formal aesthetics’ (p. 246). Heinrich Wölfflin used the term ‘formal aesthetics’ in his dissertation Prologemena zu einer Psychologie der Architektur [Prolegomena to a Psychology of Architecture] of 1886 (p. 21). The term is in use at present in P. Gold, Darstellung und Abstraktion. Aporien formaler Ästhetik [Depiction and Abstraction. Aporias in Formal Aesthetics] of 1991, and B. Dörflinger in Die Realität des Schönen in Kants Theorie rein ästhetischer Urteilskraft. Zur Gegenstandsbedeutung subjektiver und formaler Ästhetik [The Reality of Beauty in Kant’s Theory of Purely Aesthetic Judgement. On the Objective Meaning of Subjective and Formal Aesthetics] of 1988.

28

The Visibility of the Image

obligation to explain what beauty is. But stepping back from what came with the territory, we can see that quite apart from the problem of beauty, this is about a change in perspective in the observation of a work, taking a lesson from formal logic: a voluntary focus on form means a liberation from speculative ballast and superfluous hypotheses. Formal aesthetics grasps the aesthetic object purely as a structural entity, introducing into aesthetics a phenomenological-positivist view that rules out any other deep, ‘underlying’ dimension. Zimmermann’s formal aesthetics establishes a philosophy of the aesthetic surface. Zimmermann correctly anticipated the effect his aesthetic would have on the idealistic point of view: ‘Anyone who takes form to be a lifeless earthen vessel, containing the supernatural content that warms and illuminates it from within can, in fact must recoil from the first effort to locate the beautiful in the form alone, to retain the shell that seems to “drive out” the spirit’ (tr) (Formwissenschaft, p. VIf). In this formulation, too, Zimmermann draws subtle parallels between logic and aesthetics. Possible objections to his approach invoke traditional objections to formal logic. By putting ‘drive out’ in quotation marks, Zimmermann makes reference to Goethe’s idealistic critique of formal logic in the scene in the study in Faust (1808). There, Mephistopheles accuses the formal logicians of ‘. . . driving the spirit out of the parts’ (p. 199). Zimmermann is not treating this critique as any cogent argument against formal logic or formal aesthetics, but on the contrary as an expression of false expectation. He parries anticipated objections to his programme, having expected them because he knows them as the usual objections to formal logic. The decisive thing is above all his argumentative strategy: he does not refute the objection to looking at form, but rather turns the objection into its opposite; he turns it into praise. Purely formal observation of images does not drive the spirit out, but rather discovers the spirit in an aesthetic object, just not where it was expected, for we identify it with the form. To put it in another way, because beauty is wholly grounded in form, no spirit  – whatever that may mean  – will be driven out if the aesthetic analysis concentrates on forms. In keeping with Goethe, Zimmermann’s thesis notes that the spirit of beauty is form, an idea Goethe would actually have been able to support, and in fact himself advances in Wilhelm Meister’s Journeyman Years of 1829: ‘Do not look for anything behind the phenomena; they themselves are the lesson’ (p. 308). This matches Zimmermann’s general concern exactly: the surface should become the essential thing, and serve exactly the function traditionally served by ideas, contents or substances. So it is once again clear that formal aesthetics does not break with pattern itself of evaluating something as essential. Only in an aesthetic object, it values as essential exactly that which previously

The Beginnings of Formal Aesthetics

29

counted as the exact opposite of essential:  the surface structure. Put another way: the most superficial becomes, paradoxically, the very core. This change in attitude gives formal aesthetics a strong position in the history of ideas, for the consequences of revaluing the surface are clear: anyone who stays at a surface understood in this way must not be superficial in his aesthetics of surface. Such reversals are more familiar today than they were in Zimmermann’s times:  ‘nothing is concealed’, Wittgenstein writes in Philosophical Investigations (1953), ‘nothing is hidden’ (p. 135).23 In fact one gets the impression from reading Zimmermann’s Allgemeine Ästhetik als Formwissenschaft [General Aesthetics as a Science of Form] that in his defence of so-called empty forms he anticipated an anti-essentialist position that is as familiar from analytic philosophy24 as it is from recent twentieth-century phenomenology:25 ‘If some want to claim that the objects that are simply forms should be dismissed as empty, they would be unaware that the concepts of such a science that apply to such objects cannot be taken as empty. Despite the objects of the concepts being ‘empty’ forms, the discipline itself would not be empty. It would be a science dealing with content-rich concepts’ (tr) (§11).

The relational concept of form in Herbartianism ‘Relation’, possibly the most important basic concept in Herbartianism, also needs to be seen in the context of these changes in perspective from an analysis of content to one of form. By construing empty forms as immanent relations, it systematically thought out the appreciation of the surface, a guiding idea for formalism. We will not fully grasp the Herbartian formal perspective if we restrict ourselves to showing that formalists took the aesthetic object to be a formal structure. Formal observation is only the first step in an energetic effort to resolve the aesthetic object into a structure of relationships; in Herbartianism, form does not yet constitute the endpoint of the formal reduction. Herbart and Zimmermann do not regard forms in a gestalt-psychological way, as complete unities or as organically self-contained forms, but rather, in a second step, as set of relations.26 With this we come to the idea fundamental to all of Herbartianism:  Relationships within forms are, from an aesthetic standpoint, the critical ones for forms. This can already be found in Herbart himself: ‘Aesthetic judgements may only be passed on relationships; and the test of their accuracy must be that the value of the relationships disappears as soon as the parts are separated; conversely, [they] are reinstated when the context is restored’ (tr).27 One can actually say: Herbartianism can be recognized by the way it treats ‘form as made up of aesthetic relations’, (tr) as Zimmermann put it right away in the

30

The Visibility of the Image

introduction to Formwissenschaft (p. vii). Herbartians identify form with the inner relations of form – and this is meant to apply to later proponents as well, who developed Herbartianism further in fundamental ways.* For every form makes differentiations and sets diverse elements into relationships with one another. This is why forms can be understood as relationships. Once again, Otto Flügel notes this central point of the Herbartian concept of aesthetics with all the clarity one could hope for – formal aesthetics is based on ‘identifying relationship with form’ (tr).28 In this way, the goals of the Herbartian approach become increasingly clear: formal aesthetics concentrates solely on the immanent relationships that the parts of an image have to one another on the surface; neither the composition as a whole, the organizing principles or the arrangement of the parts on the surface is of interest to the formal aesthetician; it is rather the relationships between the composed parts on the pictorial surface. The concern of formal aesthetics is just the perceptible relationships in the syntax of the work, the planimetric infrastructure. Form is not a vessel offering depth, but a network, just ‘outline and colour on a plane or in space’ (tr), as it was expressed by the second generation of Herbartians, the most important of whom was Zimmermann’s student, Alois Riegl.29 He, too, would defend, as the ‘main theorem’ of the principle he called his formal aesthetic, ‘first, that an aesthetic judgement can be made only about relationships, never about anything that is presumed to be simple’ (tr).30 With this last step in the argument, the identification of form with immanent relations, Zimmermann presents an alternative to idealistic analyses of works. In positioning Herbart’s aesthetic historically, he emphasizes Herbart’s relational way of looking as having introducing a pattern of thinking into aesthetics that revolutionizes scientific theory at the same time. The reduction of the aesthetic object to the structure of the surface corresponds to a development in the history of ideas for which Ernst Cassirer (1874–1945) coined the phrase ‘from the concept of substance to the concept of function’. This is to say that research in the natural sciences in the nineteenth century stops trying to explain accidental changes with reference to an underlying substance, and tries instead to get  along with structures, relationships and functions. This is actually reliable: in all its guises, * J. W. Nahlowsky is fully justified in objecting, as early as 1863 in his ‘Ästhetisch-kritische Streifzüge’ [Aesthetic-Critical Wanderings], that the Herbartian concept of form does not coincide with the usual use of language: ‘Every form contains within itself certain simple relationships between similar parts; but these simple relationships do not constitute a form in the true sense, rather they are parts of a form. The actual form first arises in the binding of the individual relationships into a complete whole’ (tr) (p. 414). The language problem can be solved by using the term ‘gestalt’ to refer to what Nahlowsky here calls a form. Because of their relational concept of form, formal aestheticians did not in fact concern themselves with gestalts.

The Beginnings of Formal Aesthetics

31

formal thinking always tries to recognize a principle in the accidental. The way things relate to one another is not explained by way of a unifying entity. Rather the independence of the relata loses importance in favour of the very ways and means of being together. The constancy and invariability of laws with which relationships are grasped take over those functions once served by substance. ‘The identity toward which thought progressively tends’, Cassirer writes in Substance and Function and Einstein’s Theory of Relativity of 1910, ‘is not the identity of final, substantial things, but the identity of functional orders and correlations’ (p. 324). With this Cassirer astutely notes a turning point in nineteenth-century intellectual history that applies to Zimmermann’s aesthetic as well: it is the expression of a liberation from substantialism in the field of the philosophical observation of works. It sounds like Cassirer, but it is in fact Zimmermann who concluded, as early as 1858, ‘It is the same basic idea that takes both our theoretical and our aesthetic awareness back to simple unison, to objective forms, and leaves aside the objective something that can be found in the palpable parts of the unison as theoretically unrecognizable or aesthetically irrelevant. Herbartian aesthetics can only be purely formal; the objects of judgements of taste can only be relationships, forms’ (tr) (Geschichte der Ästhetik, [History of Aesthetics] p. 768).

1.3 Perspectives and problems in Herbartianism Preliminary remarks From a contemporary perspective, Robert Zimmermann’s aesthetics gives the impression of Janus: one face looks into the twentieth century while the other into the eighteenth. Zimmermann’s aesthetics is a transitional theory. It combines ideas that point towards the future with inquiries and hopes long since out of date. This ambivalence deserves to be regarded as a fair judgement of the beginnings of formal aesthetics. The resolution of the aesthetic object into a mere structure of relations should be regarded as the aspect that points towards the future; the defence of an objective concept of beauty appears to regress back to a state of knowledge prior to Kant’s Critique of the Power of Judgement (1790).

Perspective: A non-idealistic concept of the work Zimmermann’s proposal for a relational way of looking at aesthetic objects, disregarding content, has systematic significance, not least because art grew

32

The Visibility of the Image

closer to his formalist theses in the twentieth century. Much of the abstract art of classical modernism even appears to be an explicit artistic transposition of Herbartianism. The theoretical writings of Kurt Schwitters (1887–1948) document this with particular clarity. They leave no doubt that rigorously formalist views figure in the development of the abstract image and especially of abstract collage at the beginning of the century. We can observe this in one inconspicuous concept:  for Schwitters, the critical category in a theory of abstract images is the concept of indifference.31 Indifference is used to describe the way form is related to content and materials in a collage. ‘It is a matter of indifference whether the form depicts something or not’ (tr).32 Like Herbart and Zimmermann, he does not deny a relationship between form and content, but rather declares it to be aesthetically insignificant. The same holds for the material that is used to realize the gestalt: ‘The material is as insignificant as I am myself ’ (tr).33 Very similar characterizations of the relationship of material and content to form can in fact be found in Zimmermann’s Formwissenschaft – more than fifty years earlier: ‘There can be no question whether they [the forms] suit the material; because they are indifferent to the material, they suit anything. It is superfluous to ask whether the form is capable of transfiguring even indifference; since any material, whatever it may be, is aesthetically indifferent, form has no choice but to lend its lustre to matters of indifference’ (tr) (§73). Such statements of Zimmermann’s clarify the extent to which collage corresponded to the Herbartian concept of a work; the idea could even be pushed to the point of maintaining that in its choice of rubbish, collage almost literally ‘lend its lustre to matters of indifference’. But such speculation aside, collage must be interpreted as an aesthetic engagement with art in the medium of art, whose visible result is backed up by Herbartian views – and it is not just Schwitters’s writings that confirm it: ‘Forget things’, Georges Braque, too, proposes, ‘Look only at the relationships’ (tr).34 But further work on the reciprocity between formal work interpretation in Herbartianism one hand and formal work production in classical modernism on the other would be purely illustrative if there were no systematic consequences for one of the two sides. In this case the consequences bear on the construction of theory. The predominant insight in philosophical aesthetics after the Second World War was that purely visible form had become independent of content and material, making it impossible to continue to work with idealistic categories in the philosophical analysis of works. An image that exists for its pure visibility cannot be described using the categories of an idealistic aesthetic; think of the

The Beginnings of Formal Aesthetics

33

independence of the surface visibility in abstract collage, or even more clearly, in a video clip. Theodor W. Adorno, in his Philosophy of New Music of 1949, may have been the first to identify this problem and to present it as a challenge to this area of aesthetics in the future: ‘The liquidation of art – of the closed art work – becomes an aesthetic problem, and the increasing neutralization of the material brings with it the renunciation of identity of content and appearance which brings these traditional ideas of art to an end’ (p. 97). Adorno’s ideas can be put differently: a formal aesthetic can underpin the production of works as well. To the extent that images approach formal aesthetics’ understanding of works, that is, that they themselves reflect it, they distance themselves from an idealistic understanding of works. In idealist aesthetics, a work must be the apparent form of an invisible truth; there must be an identity between the content and the appearance of a work. For this reason, any idealistic aesthetic must have the traditional understanding of the work at its centre as an essential category. For such an understanding of the work, the unity of content and appearance recurs, for all parts serve a purpose, the appearance of an idea. The form’s relationship to the content is like that of accidents to substance, which is how there can be metaphorical talk of substantialism or essentialism in the idealistic understanding of works: the idealist aesthetic binds form to a truth, to content. The work in this way becomes the ontological carrier of the content, for the idea must be realized in forms having an external existence. In an exemplary way, Heidegger brings this understanding of the work to a definition of the idealistic conception of art as such: ‘Art is the setting-itself-to-work of truth’ (p. 19).35 With abstract collage, a development of the image begins that casts doubt on this idealist understanding of the work through the visible means of art. The form becomes independent and autonomous with respect to contents and materials. The purpose of the work is not the depiction of content, but the production of a planimetric infrastructure. A collage does not serve the making-visible of an absent idea, but the pure visibility of the present form. As long as the form of a work is taken to be the way an idea looks, it is impossible to do justice to a work that is purely a structure of relationships, with no unifying idea. This is why idealistic aesthetics increasingly seemed problematic in principle for theoretical reflections on the new pictorial forms of the twentieth century. There seems to be agreement, even among theoreticians otherwise at odds with one another, that the consideration of abstract works ultimately leads Zur Kritik der idealistischen Ästhetik [Towards a Critique of Idealistic Aesthetics] – the relevant title of the book by Peter Bürger published in 1983.

34

The Visibility of the Image

Responses to the limits of idealistic aesthetics must vary; there are at least two ways. There is, first, the possibility that was there from the beginning, of completely abandoning the analysis of the work and researching either the aesthetic experience or the language instead. Or a non-idealist concept of the work might be constructed – one that would be in a position to theoretically support the development of new pictorial forms as well. This is the route Peter Bürger proposed in claiming that ‘a non-idealistic concept of the work would be, among other things, one capable of thinking of form and content separately without making a negative aesthetic evaluation at the same time’ (tr).36 – such an attempt corresponds to the goals of Robert Zimmermann’s aesthetic. So the circle closes between recent discussions of the work and the programme of formal aesthetics in the nineteenth century. The critique of idealistic aesthetics raises challenges that enable us to read a largely overlooked trend in nineteenth-century aesthetics as a timely contribution to the contemporary discussion. The understanding of the work represented in Zimmermann’s aesthetics can serve as a model for the attempt to turn the split between form and content into something positive – a split that was always valued positively in logic. From this standpoint, Zimmermann’s aesthetics, often dismissed as antiquated, appear in a progressive light. Formal aesthetics does arise within a paradigm that takes the concern of philosophical aesthetics to be the presentation of a persuasive theory of beauty; but it did not actually achieve a persuasive theory of beauty. The noteworthy aspect of Zimmermann’s aesthetic is the idea of reinforcing a subtle passageway through the question of the work: between the idealist view of an aesthetic object as a manifestation of truth and its aesthetic absorption as just the occasion for a subjective encounter, there is a possibility of understanding the aesthetic object as a relational structure. The work is not grasped as the apparent form of an absent object, nor is there any denial or levelling of the difference between an aesthetic and non-aesthetic object. Zimmermann proposes that an aesthetic work is a structure defined by its immanent relations, and formal aesthetics is a structural theory of these surface relations. In anticipation of the structural approach, formal aesthetics turns immanent relations into the essential feature of a work. A double opposition shapes formal aesthetics: it rejects the Kantian conclusion, which also informs analytic aesthetics, that any attraction at all can function as an aesthetic object, but simultaneously rejects idealism’s demand that an aesthetic object make content visible. Kant’s analyses of aesthetic judgement do in fact get  along without substantial and normative statements about the object of judgement,

The Beginnings of Formal Aesthetics

35

but here the aesthetic of the object changes to the subjectivity of the recipient  – thereby undergoing exactly the same change that Herbart wants to reverse. And yet it is exactly because it demands so much that Zimmermann’s programme goes wrong nevertheless. With his understanding of a work, Zimmermann in fact sets out a programme worth considering, but is himself unable to resolve it into a persuasive form; it is not rare for a plan and its fulfilment to part company, not rare for an idea to come to fruition first among students. But before going into that, it is appropriate for historical reasons to consider the second face of the Janus, the one that looks back to eighteenthcentury ‘Herbartianism’.

The problem of beginnings: The objectivity of beauty The early formal aesthetics of Herbart and Zimmermann suffer from the same problem in that they try to answer a question that cannot be answered by means of logic. The relational observation of aesthetic objects is developed so as ‘to determine, in an exact way, what is beauty is’ (tr).37 Its aesthetic is normative, and it turns to the work because ‘what is beautiful should be objective or matterof-fact’ (tr).38 The traditions of eighteenth-century empirical aesthetics make themselves clearly felt. Here Herbart and Zimmermann share the basic assumption that beauty is an ontological quality.39 One could even say that Herbart and Zimmermann bring this tradition to a definitive conclusion, for they declare the pleasure-experiencing subject to be unimportant for the evaluation of beauty. Rather they contend that ‘aesthetic judgement, being objective, has a theoretically recognizable object’ (tr).40 As a result, for Herbart and Zimmermann, the beauty of something can be judged even if it has not been perceived. They do not shy away from any of the consequences they face as a result of this assumption. Beauty is supposed to be a quality that is present if one knows that the object meets certain criteria. These criteria for beauty ‘are universal, and are the same for the disembodied intellect as they are for us sensible human beings’ (tr).41 – ‘and this, in fact, as in any time, so too under any accompanying circumstances and in all connections and integrations’ (tr).42 In short, Herbart and Zimmermann refine their understanding of beauty in keeping with the thesis ‘no real beauty is actually sensual’ (tr).43 The analysis of immanent work relations needs to be seen against this background. According to Zimmermann, it is to be the means with which it becomes possible to discover ‘aesthetic ur-relationships’, (tr)44 which are necessarily beautiful. Herbart as well as Zimmermann believes that these are the

36

The Visibility of the Image

smallest components of the beautiful, ‘in which absolute satisfaction lies’(tr) (Formwissenschaft, p.  iv). If one knows these proportions, one knows which object is beautiful without looking, for it is only as a result of these proportions being present that ‘any material, if it is even capable of taking form at all, that is, if it is homogeneous, either pleases or displeases’ (tr) (ibid., §76). Although the very idea that beauty is an objective quality is more than doubtful, and so the search for objective characteristics of beauty rests on uncertain ground from the start, we should note that the real problem with Zimmermann is an overestimation of logic. If Zimmermann had proposed to research beauty using, say, the methods of perception psychology, we could readily have attested to a practical meaning in the project. His study of form would then be a kind of guide to good proportions – but certainly no philosophical theory of beautiful form. But that is exactly what Zimmermann aspires to, which is his problem. Zimmermann is not interested in showing, empirically, that the golden mean, for example, is a balanced relationship, but rather believes he can recognize forms that are necessarily beautiful just by thinking, by pure logic: ‘in whatever forms a thing pleases or displeases, whatever that thing may be, it is neither the eye nor the ear nor even experience that is capable of deciding, but thinking alone’ (tr) (ibid., §75). One can see from the quotation: Zimmermann’s goal is a logical calculus of beauty. He wants to turn beauty into a calculable topic in a kind of mathematics or logic. At the end of his aesthetic there is to be a limited number of forms, the content of which is open to any interpretation at all. Complex aesthetic phenomena can be made from, or alternatively, referred back to these forms.

The danger of logicism If we join Wilhelm Wundt (1832–1920) in using ‘logicism’ to designate an effort to use logical methods to solve problems that fundamentally cannot be solved by logical means, then Zimmermann’s aesthetics is an example of logicism.45 From a historical standpoint, it forms a counterpart to Fechner’s psychologism. Zimmermann ignored the fact that knowledge of the beauty of something requires concrete observation, and so is only attainable by empirical means.46 He further denied that the attitude of the person judging plays a crucial role in the judgement of beauty. The question of beauty cannot be answered without taking the subject into consideration. In this sense, his defence of an objective concept of beauty relapses to a point before the insights of the Critique

The Beginnings of Formal Aesthetics

37

of the Power of Judgement. Finally, the whole argument rests on the tenacious dispute of a basic fact, as Stephan Nachtsheim has already pointed out: ‘As true as it is that certain structures can be transposed into qualitatively very different elements (although different within limits), it is on the other hand not true that the suitability of the elements for the form is indifferent, that the form is only a structure of relations whose relata can be exchanged at will’ (tr).47 But Zimmermann can make no concession here; he cannot admit even the smallest influence of material on the beauty of the object, since a formal aesthetic ‘would be impossible if the material were not indifferent to the form’ (tr) (Formwissenschaft, §74). The reflections on Zimmermann show that for the formal approach, logicism presents a problem in principle. In Darstellung und Abstraktion [Depiction and Abstraction] (1991), Peter Gold was able to deduce that any formal aesthetic lands in an aporia if logic ‘is made to serve as a decisive principle of beauty’ (tr) (p.  47). In fact we must confirm that formal aesthetics is not suited to answering the question of beauty, for among its basic assumptions is one that ‘any appeal to sensuality is discarded as inadequate to beauty’ (ibid.). The visible form, which any formal aesthetic has to take as an anti-idealistically promising starting point, finally returns to irrelevance at Zimmermann’s hand, against his own intention. Since it is possible to read Zimmermann’s title Allgemeine Ästhetik als Formwissenschaft [General Aesthetics as a Science of Form] as ‘aesthetics as logic’, it can also be read as the interesting paradox ‘aesthetics without aesthesis’. The basic aesthetic forms are not associated with perception, either for Herbart or for Zimmermann. They are defined in such a way that they can satisfy or dissatisfy without having to be observed. Visible forms mutate into invisible ideas. This also explains how the first part of Friedrich Conrad Griepenkerl’s Lehrbuch der Ästhetik [Textbook of Aesthetics] of 1826 could be called ‘The Theory of Ideas’, remarkable for formal aesthetics. But the basic aesthetic forms correspond to an ‘idea of beauty’. This turns formalism into its opposite. When the sensually beautiful turns out to be beautiful only on the grounds of relationships that are not sensual, Zimmermann turns the beautiful into an imitative appearance of intellectual ideas, and the artist into a Platonic seeker after ideas:  ‘Even for the artist, the beautiful is something given, not something made by him’ (tr) (Geschichte der Ästhetik, p. 785). One could even claim that for Zimmermann, beauty is grasped as the depiction of an idea of form: ‘What presents itself to aesthetic judgement as pleasing or displeasing can do so only

38

The Visibility of the Image

because its forms are reproductions of the aesthetic’ (tr) (Formwissenschaft, §77). At the end of Zimmermann’s line of argument are idealistic conceptions that are just the opposite of those at the point of departure.48 And that raises the question of how Herbartianism, as it develops after Zimmermann, frees itself from objections that were initially justified, so as to unfold its own idea of a theory of the visible work.

2

Formal Aesthetics and Relational Logic:  Alois Riegl (1858–1905)

2.1 Transitions on the pictorial surface Preliminary remarks In light of the aporias that entangle formal aesthetics as a logical theory of the objectively beautiful, it is not surprising that formal aestheticians steer clear of the question of beauty as they continue to pursue their goals. The strengths of formal aesthetics do in fact lie at another level: relational observation’s potential is to be sought not in the normative, but in the descriptive. Yet in illustrating this, we get no proper support from Robert Zimmermann. It is rather his student Alois Riegl, the Viennese art historian (1858–1905), to whom one can turn to discover what is to be achieved through relational observation of the work.* Riegl transforms the formal aesthetics of early Herbartianism into a philosophy of style, and so becomes a co-founder of the Vienna School, which ‘remained the last bastion of Herbartianism into the last third of the past century’.1 For systematic as well as historic reasons, it seems advisable to follow further developments in formal aesthetics through Riegl.

* References for understanding the development from Zimmermann to Riegl can be found in L. Venturi, History of Art Criticism, pp. 271–288. To date, matters relating to this relationship have otherwise been confined to short footnotes. Part of the responsibility for this must surely belong to Max Dvorák’s appraisal of the student-teacher relationship: ‘How could Zimmermann’s unproductive variations on an already antiquated Herbartian philosophy [. . .] have satisfied a progressive intellect? If any trace of this teaching can be noted in Riegl’s writing, it is as a direct negation of its theories and methods’ (tr) (‘Alois Riegl’, p. 280). Lorenz Dittmann, who has further provided good critical insight into the discussion of stylistic and structural categories within formal aesthetics, once rightly commented on this assessment: ‘Dvořák was wrong there’ (tr) (Stil, Symbol, Struktur [Style, Symbol, Structure], p. 39).

40

The Visibility of the Image

‘Style’ instead of ‘beauty’ Riegl’s call to be one of the founders of the discipline of art history came in no small part through his largely unprecedented way of holding the viewing of art separate from questions of value or beauty.2 In the second half of the nineteenth century, the majority of aestheticians no longer considered beauty to be an essential feature of art; this was particularly the case for Riegl. One could even say that he tended towards an ‘elimination of the concept of beauty’.3 For Riegl, aestheticians who try to explain what is beautiful and what is ugly, what is high and what is low art, are pursuing idle questions. He was bored with the endless debates about the rationalization of beauty in which his teacher had participated so energetically, and advanced the almost defiant antithesis:  ‘Everything that exists is beautiful’ (tr) – although the exhortation might be completed in keeping with his thinking as, not everything that exists has style.4 The substitution of questions of style for questions of beauty, which Riegl had already advocated in his 1893 book, marks the first critical phase in the continuing development of formal aesthetics after Zimmermann; it marks a new topic. For Riegl, the immanent relations of an aesthetic object do not determine whether the object is beautiful or ugly, but rather what its style is. From this point on, then, this is what is to be analysed by means of Herbartian observation techniques. Riegl retains Herbartianism’s basic insight, that what is aesthetically critical in a form is its immanent relations.5 But Riegl also recognizes that this understanding of form only becomes meaningful if another problem is presented. He specified this problem: it is the transition of forms, between parts of the surface. Riegl brings formal aesthetics in exclusively to investigate the ‘connection among all objects represented in a picture’ – as he writes in Spätrömische Kunstindustrie [Late Roman Art Industry] of 1901 (p. 12). The whole gestalt of forms, the composition of forms, is to be bracketed out. The style of something can only be described, for Riegl, through the ‘relations of the parts between one another and between the whole’ (ibid., p. 58). The meaning of this idea becomes especially apparent in its application to images.*

* Riegl himself drew his formal insights not so much from images as from utilitarian objects and ornaments, specifically from the ‘late Roman art industry’, which, in the conventional art historical view of the time, had no artistic value at all. From later essays (to be examined later), it becomes clear that Riegl’s considerations are most definitely intended for images. The choice of a comic image to illustrate the difference in the aesthetic quality of immanent relations in what follows here may well be appropriate to Riegl, for whom the formal modes of observation and with it the history of art was not a theory of high art. The question of whether something is a work of art seemed secondary to theoreticians of formal aesthetics. For this reason, this book presents a history of formal aesthetics with the intention of representing a theory of the image in all its material forms of appearance. So

Formal Aesthetics and Relational Logic

41

Although external factors largely determine an image, it retains possibilities for variation in the transitions in the process of becoming visible. Even if two images consist of the same material and depict the same object from the same perspective, they are visually distinguishable in their immanent relations. The syntactic structure of the surface is not fully established in the semantic relationship of one part of the image to a depicted object or part of an object that lies outside the image, for it is unthinkable that an image would just depict an object. The objects depicted and the perspective chosen do in fact determine the forms on the pictorial surface. In moving around an object with a film camera, steadily changing the perspective on the object, the forms on the surface of the screen change steadily. But this aspect of the form, which can be called the variation of gestalt or of viewpoint, is not of interest to formal aestheticians. They direct their attention to formal possibilities within a stable point of view. This relates to transitions. The immanent relations in an image can be more similar in images of different content than in images with the same content, which is particularly clear when two images with the same content are held side by side: the identity of the object helps to see the variation in its forms of appearance. The pictorial examples reproduced as Figures 1 and 2, from the Belgian comic draughtsman Hergé (1907–1983) and from the English painter William Turner (1775–1851), respectively, show a comparable object from a nearly comparable perspective: a profile view of a travelling ship. There are objective differences, for example in the weather shown. But these differences can be set aside, for the essential thing is the planimetric infrastructure of these images is completely different. They construct the visibility of comparable views of a comparable thing in different ways. From a formal point of view, the differences in composition, the size of the ship, the lighting and the viewing angle are not significant to the aesthetic differences of these images. The constructed views are different not primarily in their being different views, but in constructing the same view in different ways.* The transitions in the images are different: in one case they are painterly, in the other haptic.

it is worth keeping in mind that not every image is a work of art, nor is every work of art an image. What is said about images need not hold for every work of art, and what is said about works of art need not be valid for every image. * In the twentieth century, Roman Ingarden (1893–1970) repositioned this idea at the centre of his phenomenological aesthetic. He writes, in a very similar vein, ‘One and the same object, for example, a material thing, such as a tree, a table or a chair – presented in the same visual properties with respect to its form, color and lighting, and seen from the same side – can be brought to appearance in aspects reconstructed in different ways. But it is not a matter of those differences between aspects that result when we perceive one and the same thing from the same side, but from different distances (thus with a different visual angle), with either the same or changed lighting. For then we experience

42

The Visibility of the Image

Painterly and haptic The most important basic so-called art historical principles are painterly and haptic. They refer to visible qualities of a transition of forms. The connection of things in an image – for example, the relation between the ship and the background, or that between the sky and the water  – is achieved haptically with Hergé; it would be comparable to the way Dürer or Ingres would have painted the picture. Turner, on the other hand  – like Rembrandt, Renoir, and many others – connects the object to his forms in a painterly way. That is to say, with painterly transitional relations, the relata keep visibly flowing into one another. The relationships therefore appear to be ephemeral, indistinct and analoguous. A painterly form has only transitions that are ‘as much one thing as another’. With painterly relational structures in images, visual inspection alone cannot order each transitional area to one of the relata that are separated by these transitions. One cannot see the exact place where one part of a form ends and a neighbouring one begins. The shapes and figures on the pictorial surface are bound into a visual unity with their surroundings. For haptic structures, exactly the reverse is the case. A relation is haptic when the relata are independent. The forms on the surface are figures set apart from their environment, figures whose beginning and end can be seen exactly. The relationship between the parts of the form is discrete, isolating and digital. In this case, the relata are singular, independent and sharply delineated with respect to one another; one could even say that every point in a transition from one shape [gestalt] to the next belongs to either one or the other. A contour line marks the ‘no-man’s-land’ between the fronts with maximum precision.6 It may be clear that both concepts, painterly and haptic, are metaphors. Painterly does not designate a quality of painting, nor does haptic designate one of touch. Rather a relation is painterly exactly when the formal relationships among the relata are as if they had been painted, even if they have been realized in a completely different medium; obviously there are painterly photographs. The same holds for the haptic. This metaphor proposes that a relation can, formally, be such that it is as if it could be touched. The relations in the image are taken to be plastically ‘graspable’; there is a definite, mathematically comprehensible

different aspects of the same thing. Rather, it is a matter of different ways of constructing one and the same aspect; these different ways of construction thus bring to appearance the same objectual properties, with the same Objective lighting conditions and subjective capabilities of perception, in the same arrangement and in the same foreshortening. In spite of this “sameness”, the ways of the aspect’s reconstruction in painting can distinguish themselves to a great extent from one another’ (Ontology, p. 61).

Formal Aesthetics and Relational Logic

43

place where the object ends and the environment begins, as there would be for an object in space. The metaphor of the haptic is well chosen. The forms in haptic representations actually can be interpreted in such a way as to symbolize values and knowledge that only a sense of touch can convey. It then follows that we should speak of optical images in connection with painterly images; as for example in Adolf Hildebrand’s (1847–1921) well-known text Das Problem der Form in der bildenden Kunst of 1893.7 The basic conceptual opposition ‘optical-haptic’ or, as Riegl usually says, ‘optical-tactile’, makes terminological sense because it employs a coherent metaphor for the senses. Talk about an optical representation signals that the transitions from one part of an image to another is conceived in such a way that the producer uses just the sense values and information that an eye can perceive, that cannot be grasped: that is, light, colour and shadow.* The orientation to light is prominent in painterly images, because this kind of depiction sets out to bring the visible relata into unity; the image refers to what all relata have in common, to light and colour. Limiting a representation to the pure reproduction of the appearance of colour therefore necessarily results in a painterly representation, in which the relata are visible in more unified than divided ways. The content in a haptic representation, correspondingly, presents itself in just the opposite way. Its pictorial surface has only relata that are divided in such a way as to make the beginning and the edge of something perceptible by touch. The division can be indicated by means of a line, which is why Heinrich Wölfflin (1864–1945), the author of Principles of Art History (1915), which fundamentally advanced formal aesthetics in Riegl’s sense, suggested the concept of linearity for haptic depiction. This basic conceptualization has the advantage of clarifying, in language, that only a contour line can show a sharp and precise transition between forms (Wölfflin’s terminology as well as his thought corresponds to Hergé’s reference to his style as ligne claire8). A haptic representation must work with lines and is in this sense related to a drawing – although there are also painterly drawings, one example that comes to mind is Rembrandt.

* Sculpture and architecture can certainly be painterly as well, namely when they engage shadows and light in making transitions. In a sculpture, the pupil of a human eye can be drilled in: in this case the eye is reproduced in a painterly way, for the representation is making something visible that cannot be felt. If an artist represents the pupil with three drill holes – as one finds in the work of Bernini – he heightens the painterly aspect of the sculpture further by showing that he is concerned only with the production of a diffuse shadow in this position, and not with the depiction of the round form of the pupil. Cf. Ph. Schweinfurth, Über den Begriff des Malerischen in der Plastik [On the Concept of the Painterly in Sculpture].

44

The Visibility of the Image

But the reverse situation can be imagined only with difficulty. Mathematical constructions cannot be painted, only drawn. A representation of reality that can be construed as scientific, that is based on the measureable, ‘objective’ object, is possible only with linear images. Conversely, images that support technical construction and exact calculation must be linear relational structures. For a technical drawing is about something, not about the way something appears. The painterly representation, on the other hand, makes an impressionistic representation of reality possible, one focussed on the subjective and optical appearance of the object. So the formal differences between painterly and linear correspond to different interests in the object, which for Wölfflin are the essential critical criteria for representation forms: ‘We need to go back to the basic difference between linear and painterly depiction, that which was already recognized in antiquity: the former presents things as they are, the latter as they appear to be. This definition sounds somewhat coarse and will be almost unbearable to philosophical ears. Is not everything appearance? And what sense is there in wanting to speak of a depiction of things “as they are”? These concepts nevertheless have their perpetual right when it comes to art. There is one style that, being objectively inclined, grasps things according to their solid, palpable condition and wants to assert them as such, and in contrast there is another style that, being more subjectively inclined, bases its representation on that image in which visibility really appears to the eye and that often bears so little resemblance to how we imagine the actual shape of things to be’ (Principles, p. 102).9 In fact there is less difference between the painterly and linear if it is interpreted ‘sensually’ as optical or haptic, and not only in that transitions are continuous in one and discrete in the other. If we take painterly representation to be optical, and a linear one to be haptic, this leads to a restriction in the processes of depicting various kinds of information. Certain visible phenomena cannot be depicted at all in a strictly haptic image – if the metaphor can be taken literally. In this context, Hergé’s representation is almost a prime example of an image that consists entirely of tactile values: shadows and clouds do not occur, and although the trawler is travelling at full speed, no exhaust fumes, no smoke rises from the chimney. This is not an oversight, but the internal consistency of an image showing only those indicators that can be grasped: shadows, vapour and clouds then do not exist. Even the colours are then used as if the object is not seen. Hergé’s world is a world of the blind made visible. Nothing in his images appears in the colourful way it appears in the world. Colour is used in a purely

Formal Aesthetics and Relational Logic

45

conceptual way, as if a painter who could not see had asked someone who could see what colour the object had, and had received only the answer: ‘sky is blue’. As a result, the sky in the image is just a blue surface. This blind way of using of colour becomes significant if the person being asked had answered that the object is plaid. For then the squares cannot be painted as they would be seen. Rather the figure, graspable and grasped within contour lines, is filled in with the pattern, flat, with no indication of space. There are many examples in Hergé’s work; the stylistically perfect representation of Captain Haddock’s plaid sakkos in The Adventures of Tintin: The Seven Crystal Balls of 1943 comes to mind. Turner is no less consistent in this respect, and so his style sets a different limit to what can be represented. With Turner, the smoke from the steamer is visible, almost too clearly visible, but cannot be distinguished from the ship’s metal hull, in its materiality and solidity; seen purely optically – seen, one should say more exactly, from a distance, the soft smoke and the hard steel are, as Turner presents them, indistinguishably black.

Limits to ways of representing From what has just been said, it is clear that art historical principles do not designate any firm characteristics. Both optical and painterly are limit values that are only ever approximately attainable in a concrete representation – but for logical, as well as for practical reasons, as the art historian Edgar Wind emphasized in his essay ‘Zur Systematik der künstlerischen Probleme’ [On the Classification of Artistic Problems] of 1925: ‘The purely optical, that has nothing of the haptic, that is, no formal boundaries, is as completely amorphous as light itself ’ (tr) (p. 449). Turner’s image itself lets us anticipate this last step towards complete dissolution of the image in coloured patches that flow into one another. It is an extremely painterly representation, and a short step would be enough make it completely abstract.10 It is not different with an extremely haptic representation. Both forms of representation are, at their extremes, equally close to abstraction, if not in the same way. Wind writes, aptly, ‘The purely haptic, the formal, that lacks any optical specificity is completely abstract, a geometric figure’ (tr) (ibid.). The haptic image consists entirely of hard external boundaries of a form being made visible; the painterly representation, by contrast, consists entirely of internal structures. Yet the haptic image’s conception of the visibility of contours leads, in the extreme case, to a result very similar to that of the painterly image: that is, the

46

The Visibility of the Image

dissolution of the image into meaningless patches of colour, in this case into purely monochrome patches. The larger the unity that is represented by tactile means, the larger the patches of uniform colour; the more comprehensive the contour line is, the larger the shape [gestalt] it encloses. The haptic, too, presents a limit value for imagery. Hergé’s representation of the sky gives an indication of such an abstract limit value; there, the sky is a purely monochrome surface and so only conditionally a visual representation of the sky. In any case, if one were to cut this sky out of the image, it would not be recognizable as a part of the image that represents the sky, although this is entirely possible with images that are stylistically less extreme. With Hergé we get only a flat blue clipping. Susanne K.  Langer (1895–1985), in her Philosophy in a New Key of 1942, pointed out earlier that this is the case for any part of an image: ‘The areas of light and shade that constitute a portrait, a photograph for instance, have no significance by themselves. In isolation we would consider them simply blotches’ (p. 94). This is undoubtedly an accurate conclusion. But we should add, for completeness, that there is a relational rule governing the size of these areas: the more extreme a style is in its way of constructing painterly or linear transitions on the surface of an image, the larger the areas will be that in isolation are no longer recognizable as part of the image. This makes it clear that the painterly and the linear provide, in addition to a means of describing empirical characteristics of a pictorial surface, logical limit values that may be sought but that can never be finally attained if the image is to still show anything at all. Riegl’s theory of aesthetic transition clearly exceeds an interest in real relations in real works and aims at an inquiry about principles. He pursues the idea that visible possibilities for variations available to an image through ‘shape and color on the plane and in space’ (Late Roman Art Industry, p. 9) are in fact infinite, but may be limited to a few logically specifiable extreme values. In this way Riegl steers formal aesthetics away from the question of beauty towards that of style, and understands this as the special task of describing and delimiting the area of uncertainty that is available to processes of representation. For him, the theory of style is not a theory of art historical epochs but a transcendental theory about the possibilities of making something visible. From a philosophical standpoint, his aesthetic takes up the question: What are the structural elements in a representation that are in fact in a representation, but that do not themselves represent anything? It is worth describing this step from the actual to the logical, from real surface relations to their thinkable possibilities more closely.

Formal Aesthetics and Relational Logic

47

2.2 Kunstwollen (the will to art): Making unlike things the same The double appearance of all things in nature In order to understand the significance of a pair of basic art historical principles, it is important to recognize that the distinction between haptic and painterly transitions applies to no specific pictorial medium. The principles are concerned with formal characteristics that can ultimately only be grasped paradoxically. This is about differentiations that are, on the one hand, present only if a relation is represented in such a way as to be visible in the first place, differentiations that are, on the other hand, presumed to be independent of a particular medium of representation. Riegl describes the possibilities of form medially, but without thinking of a specific medium. This perspective makes his investigations of works relate to the image at the level of principle. Riegl’s concerns have become easier to understand today, for in the philosophy of the Frenchman Michel Foucault (1926–1984), a comparable project has found great acclaim. With his famous concept of discourse, Foucault opened up that aspect of the process of stating something that art historical principles describe for the process of making something visible. The parallel can be quickly formulated: discourse makes speech possible for Foucault, as style makes becoming visible possible for Riegl – both are transcendental categories. Discourse turns every statement into more than a mere statement with a particular content. Foucault’s programmatic challenge, in The Archaeology of Knowledge of 1969, to describe ‘The Formation of Enunciative Modalities’ (p. 55) in fact corresponds to the formal aestheticians’ call to describe the stylistic formation of pictorial modalities. Foucault even confirms this in an analogous way: ‘Of course, discourses are composed of signs; but what they do is more than use these signs to designate things. It is this “more” that renders them irreducible to the language (langue) and to speech. It is this “more” that we must reveal and describe’ (ibid., p. 54). The same holds for formal aesthetics. It, too, sets out to describe this ‘more’ in images. It no longer seems remarkable that Foucault and Riegl further agree that it is the immanent relations that determine the formation of a discourse: ‘But what properly belongs to a discursive formation . . . is the way in which these different elements are related to one another . . . It is this group of relations that constitutes a system of conceptual formation’ (ibid., p. 66). These thoughts can be applied to images. This bundle of relationships constitutes a formation visible within a system; with this we come to an understanding of the Herbartians’ concept of a work.

48

The Visibility of the Image

Both Riegl and Foucault are in fact trying to reach generally valid, logical principles by way of relational description of a single, individual case – whether of discourse or of the image – which can itself be grasped as discourse according to Foucault. This fundamental claim within Riegl’s formal analysis of style nevertheless needs firmer support. This can be found in his philosophically decisive essay ‘Naturwerk und Kunstwerk’ [Work of Nature and the Work of Art] of 1901. Here he develops the idea that in pictorial representation – in whatever medium it may occur – it is inevitable for apriori reasons that the relations represented take on visible qualities that they would not have had if the content of the representation had been formulated conceptually. Riegl describes the production of an image as a process that always presents the producer with problems that he can resolve only through a deliberate determination. Without decision, no image can be created. The production of a visible depiction of an absent object is like a kind of inquisition. An answer must be found to the problem Riegl calls the ‘double appearance of all things in nature’(tr) (p. 67): ‘Natural objects reveal themselves to the human sensorium as isolated figures, but also as bound [. . .] into an infinite whole with the universe. They have limiting edges, but flow more or less smoothly into their environment’ (tr) (ibid., p. 60). There is an inexact condition, like a visual puzzle, ‘between individual self-containment on the one hand, and dissolution into the environment on the other’ (tr) (ibid., p. 67). Natural objects provide no information about how their transitions should or must be seen, and for Riegl they are stylistically neutral: ‘Both tendencies have been there from the beginning’ (tr) (ibid., p. 61). One could say that for Riegl the exact form of nature is largely indistinct. He discovers an idea that has been defended since, particularly by the phenomenologist Maurice Merleau-Ponty in his essay ‘Eye and Mind’ of 1961. Painters have always known, as Merleau-Ponty argues, much as Riegl does, ‘that there are no lines visible in themselves, that neither the contour of the apple nor the border between field and meadow is in this place or that, that they are always on the near or the far side of the point we look at. They are always between or behind whatever we fix our eyes upon’ (‘Eye and Mind’, p. 183).11 In fact, Riegl starts  – as does Merleau-Ponty  – from a polymorphous state of being, which is the reason a realistic depiction of nature is internally contradictory. Nature does not have one form that is to be captured. The real can be visible in multiple ways that are equally realistic. The polymorphous character of nature, its indeterminacy, makes a multiplicity of realistic images possible – as Riegl sees exactly: ‘each style of art strives for a true representation of nature and nothing else and each has indeed its own perception of nature in that he views a

Formal Aesthetics and Relational Logic

49

very particular phenomenon of it (tactile or optical, Nahsicht, Normalsicht, or Fernsicht)’ (Art Industry, p. 226, n.117). Yet here Riegl’s real interests make themselves felt:  this polymorphism of identical things is subject to firm, logically conceivable constraints. Extreme forms in which the indeterminate condition of an object can be made visible can be grasped with pure logic. Transitional forms can therefore be approached using a different line of argument. ‘Two extremes are thinkable in this context: on the one hand, the greatest isolation of individual natural objects with respect to all others, and on the other hand the strongest connection among the same things’ (tr) (‘Naturwerk’, p. 60). Riegl’s word ‘thinkable’ in the last quotation is especially significant, for it defines his aesthetic understanding. ‘Thinkable’ confirms the aprioristic claim of formal aesthetics, a distinguishing feature of this development since Zimmermann. Riegl, like his teacher Zimmermann, insisted that for aesthetics ‘thinking alone has to decide’ (Formwissenschaft, §75). It is this basic self-understanding that came from Zimmermann’s programme and was sustained in Riegl’s art theory, although in his case with the result that it is problematic to address Riegl as an art historian, at least if we understand art history in the usual way, as an empirical discipline that is concerned with specific works in time and space. For art history, the relevant question is not what is ‘thinkable’, but what is historically real. Riegl’s theory aims at a level different from that of the art historian. Empirical art history becomes, as Zimmermann claims, a description of works as such, that is a general science of art. That means, as Ernst Cassirer rightly saw, ‘The individual phenomena are meant to be nothing more than the paradigmatic illustrations of this difference [between linear and painterly]; in no way do they aim to ground them as such.’12 Conversely, the principles prescribe nothing about individual appearances, either. Riegl does not presume to anticipate the concrete way something has been made through formal logic. In contrast to Zimmermann, Riegl’s aesthetics are not normative. ‘The conceptual pair [. . .] (optical and haptic values) refers to a region of the visible that we could call the level of elementary values:  it designates those values that must be brought into balance in order for a visibly formed unity (“figure”) to come into being at all’ (tr).13 This formulates the intention underpinning Riegl’s theory of style: the search for an apriori theory of how artificial visibility comes about. Formal aesthetics is concerned not with empirical, but with logical possibilities that become available when a material medium is selected for the generation of forms. Art historical principles do not describe ‘the ways and means artistic problems are solved, but rather how they

50

The Visibility of the Image

are posed: rightly understood, they are anything but labels that can somehow be attached to concrete objects. Rather their essential antithesis indicates not a difference in style appearing between two observable phenomena within the world of appearances, but to a polarity outside the world of appearances between two theoretically definable principles. [. . .] As surely as the art historical principles must appear only in the form of absolute antitheses, then, they are just as surely unconcerned with “characterizing” works of art themselves – and as surely as the art historical principles of characterization are exclusively directed toward art works themselves, they just as surely do not appear in absolute oppositions, but in a smooth gradation: the poles in the one case indicate a polarity established beforehand that will not appear as such – in the other case there has been a compensation between the poles, for which there are not two, but infinitely many different possibilities’ (tr) (ibid., 53f.). In light of this concern, we can understand the reasons Riegl’s reflections on style are not bound up with a description of phenomena, such as those associated with such concepts as ‘expressionism’, ‘Baroque’ or ‘Renaissance’. Riegl’s aesthetics are not concerned with any given styles, but rather with their logical requirements, with the conditions of possibility of a style, one might say. Riegl’s theory of art is ‘transcendental-art theoretical’ (tr) (ibid., p. 65), because he understands aesthetics – as he learnt from his teacher – to be a ‘theoreticalaprioristic discipline’ (tr).14 With Riegl, Herbartianism’s programme of turning aesthetics into an aprioristic science is achieved, although not in the form Zimmermann had first thought.* In the development of formal aesthetics, the turn away from beauty and towards style leads to the discovery that there can be no artistic formulation without decisionism. Any form, by virtue of being a visible form, presents a resolution to problems that can be logically specified, but that cannot be logically resolved. Their resolution requires a determination. This is the reason Riegl sees every form as the expression of a principle he designates a ‘will to art’. The concept makes reference to one of the important philosophical roots of his theory.

* This may also be the reason Zimmermann’s aesthetics has hardly any following today: more than a few theories sustain interest because students have shown what can be made of them. Zimmermann would surely be better known in philosophy, then, if his approach had been transformed into a theory of visibility. But in a sense Riegl, with the programme of non-speculative aesthetics, really did bracket aesthetics out of philosophy and present it as an independent science. Riegl transforms Zimmermann’s formal aesthetics into a general science of art – with the result that it drops out of philosophers’ field of vision and precipitates the widespread but false view that formal aesthetics both flourished and ended with Zimmermann. It is not the case. Zimmermann’s thought is only the beginning of the history of formal aesthetics.

Formal Aesthetics and Relational Logic

51

Visibility and Kunstwollen (the will to art) Riegl’s reflections, and with them the underlying thinking of formal aesthetics as such, arise against the intellectual historical background of the philosophy of Arthur Schopenhauer (1788–1860). One might even say that this was where the development took place. Schopenhauer introduces the concept of visibility to philosophical and art theoretical discussion in the second book of The World as Will and Idea of 1819. But his lasting, systematic achievement is not only to have, with this concept, given philosophy a topic that is still current today, but also in having recognized the connection between will and visibility. For Schopenhauer, ‘will’ by no means designates only the human capacity and freedom to make decisions. For him, will, in addition to being a principle, can be taken to underpin everything that exists, because no object ultimately provides, of itself, a complete, rational justification for its existence. ‘This that withholds itself from investigation’ (Will and Idea, §24, p.  157) is what Schopenhauer designates as will: ‘For in everything in nature there is something of which no ground can ever be assigned, of which no explanation is possible, and no ulterior cause is to be sought’ (ibid., p. 161). With this insight into the fundamental indeterminacy of everything, it is only reasonable that for Schopenhauer the process of visibility, too, should consist of essentially two components: the first component can be explained according to the law of causation, and the second, which is not determined by causes, can be understood only as manifestations of a principle of the will. The first component comprises factors such as the material and the content of an image, as well as the specific purpose it is meant to serve. The second component includes the form. This means no visible form is causally or functionally determined to the extent that it could only look the way it looks. Schopenhauer positions this formulation prominently: ‘Only the appearance, the becoming visible, in this place, at this time, is brought about by the cause and is so far dependent on it, but not the whole of the phenomenon nor its inner nature. This is the will itself, to which the principle of sufficient reason has not application and which is therefore groundless’ (ibid., p. 179). This idea persists in formal aesthetics as a basic idea that is formulated again and again in various ways. To put it pointedly, it is as if Schopenhauer were speaking when Panofsky writes, ‘It is in the nature of an artwork to have the double quality of being on one hand determined de facto through temporal and spatial conditions, and, on the other hand, ideally, of constituting the timeless and complete solution of problems set a priori’ (tr).15

52

The Visibility of the Image

Formal aesthetics got its resistance to any sort of causal explanation from Schopenhauer. Formal aesthetics is also inherently anti-psychological as well as anti-materialistic. With respect to Riegl, this becomes especially clear in his explicit opposition to Gottfried Semper’s theory of style. His entire theory is based on the view that a visible form cannot be fully explained and calculated either through psychological reflections on the production process or through physical reflections on the medium. In depiction, something autonomous is always left to specify, something he calls Kunstwollen in deference to Schopenhauer, and whose manifestations he binds firmly to the aesthetic qualities of immanent relations: ‘Human beings do not bring anything to the natural object that is to be reproduced, but only emphasize the features that isolate or connect the elements and at the same time suppress the others, depending on whether the Kunstwollen is oriented toward the appearance of the isolated individual figure or toward that of its connection to its surroundings’ (tr) (‘Naturwerk’, p. 61). In contrast to idealism, the aesthetic object appears as a visible set of relationships imbued with decisions, rather than as a manifestation of an intellectual ideal. Artificial forms are therefore always the expression of an inexplicable will, an idea that Schopenhauer, too, formulates: ‘If the whole world as idea is only the visibility of the will, the work of art is to render this visibility more distinct’ (Will and Idea, §52, p. 345). It might also be said that art shows what can be willed when the visibility of things is at issue. In this way it becomes a visible expression of a principle that cannot itself be specified: ‘There can be only a metaphysical guess about how the aesthetic drive to see natural objects reproduced in works of art as either emphasizing or suppressing either the isolating or connecting features is determined, a guess that an art historian must resist as a matter of principle’ (tr) (‘Naturwerk’, p. 63).16 To whatever extent the content of a depiction may determine its form, a picture of Peter must still make Peter recognizable in its forms. No content and no medium can fully determine the process of making something visible. The process of giving something a form is never free of will, randomness and contingency.* Through wilful decisions, an unavoidable indeterminacy, that is, an * Schopenhauer’s principle, that visibility has two bases of determination, recurs in the work of Heinrich Wölfflin as well. He transforms this idea into his theory of the ‘double root of style’ (Principles, p. 83). The same considerations appear again here: forms are determined by causes that can be scientifically examined, as well as by initial conditions that can be logically described. With the help of psychology, it is possible to examine the artist’s state of mind that has produced this specific expression; the material causes of its coming about can be followed empirically. However, the conditions of possibility of expressing something in a form at all are logically constrained. As a result, any representation in art not only depicts an object, but also always exemplifies the language that has been chosen for the depiction. Wölfflin actually expands his thoughts about the principles

Formal Aesthetics and Relational Logic

53

explanatory gap in coherent rationalization, is bridged, and in this way, indeterminacy is converted into definition, which is to say, form. Such decisions, inscribed in the process of formulation, can also be seen as Erich Rothacker (1888–1965) does, as the dogmatism immanent in all cultural phenomena; decisionism is always a performance of dogmatism. Yet in the process of cultural development – and images are part of this – dogmatism is not only a dubious, irrational vernacular, but also a principle, anthropological and transcendental in equal measure, that makes visual cultural phenomena possible: form can only come about through dogmatic decision. Rothacker did not neglect to emphasize that his concept of dogmatism exactly fulfils the function Wölfflin – although he might also have designated Riegl  – ascribes to the concept of style. In this sense, the opposition of ‘linear’ and ‘painterly’ means, ‘There are just two possibilities. But in active life, a painter, etc., must know what he concretely wants, and then he develops a style that can only be explained dogmatically’ (tr).17 Rothacker calls it ‘painter, etc.’, and it pinpoints the issue. Rothacker’s dogmatism and Schopenhauer’s will are immanent not only in every image, but in every fabricated form that serves a purpose: there are always multiple possibilities for the way the form of something that fulfils a purpose can look. Style, one might say by way of generalizing the observations presented here, is life’s answer to the confrontation with unavoidable indeterminacy. In every artifact there is a will that is responsible for a part looking as it does. ‘Sensible’ reasons (price, purpose, machines, materials, etc.), for example, can never completely account for the form of clothing  – some decision is always left over that turns any piece of clothing, by way of its form, into the visible expression of a will to this form, to the expression of a language.* For if there is no final justification for one of the possible ways of giving form, then one must turn to style, which in turn is itself nothing other than a manifestation of will and dogmatism. This idea runs like a red thread from Schopenhauer through by identifying them as languages. The basic principles describe various languages for making something visible, which are the conditions under which something ‘can be said to be’ visible at all: ‘the painterly and linear are like two different languages in which one can say virtually anything’ (ibid., p. 93). * For Leibniz, this was actually the difference between artifacts and living things. For him, living things are the only structures whose forms are entirely determined by purpose. In this context, by 1714 in his Monadology, Leibniz had already clearly described indeterminacy in the developments of artificial forms. ‘Because a man-made machine isn’t a machine in every one of its parts. For example a cog on a brass wheel has parts or fragments which to us are no longer anything artificial, and bear no signs of their relation to the intended use of the wheel, signs that would mark them out as parts of a machine. But Nature’s machines  – living bodies, that is, are machines even in their smallest parts, down to infinity. That is what makes the difference between nature and artifice, that is between divine artifice and our artifice’ (§64).

54

The Visibility of the Image

Riegl and Wölfflin to Rothacker, through their transcendental observations of the conditions of possibility for visibility as such. They come to agreement about each artificial form being the expression of a non-rational principle, simply by virtue of having become visible at all.18 There is no avoiding dogmatism in the visible, unless one abandons the visible in favour of a conceptual medium. The statement ‘a sailing ship on the open sea’ reproduces the objective content of the images of Hergé and Turner without taking a position regarding the stylistic qualities of the transitions between the ship and space. Here we can see that concepts escape the stylistic demands of images. Conversely, we see that images cannot depict an object without a style. Style is not something added on, that could also be left out. There is no image with a lot of style or none at all, because nothing can be made visible without the will. Style is the principle that resolves the inevitable indeterminacies about making something visible. The extraordinary thing about this principle is its own visibility. The aesthetic quality of the relations on a pictorial surface is a visible phenomenological characteristic. This becomes clear if we follow up on Ernst Cassirer’s suggestion: ‘The result of our logical analysis of the concepts of style assumes its full significance only when we compare it with the result of the phenomenological analysis. What emerges is not only a parallelism but a genuine reciprocal determination’ (p. 73).19

Phenomenology of relations Kunstwollen, Riegl’s key idea, manifests itself, he writes, in the way ‘the plane relations  – perceivable in height and width’ are built up (Art Industry, p.  59). Riegl takes the view that the Kunstwollen achieves visible expression in the style of the work. With that he makes the assumption – which he himself considers to be unproblematic – that the relations of a work are a perceptible phenomenon, rather than the product of interpretation. Riegl is actually of the opinion that an aesthetic object appears ‘directly to sense perception as a self-contained unity’ (tr) (‘Naturwerk’, p. 61), that is, that the relations between the forms can be seen just as well as the figures and gestalten. Riegl’s reference to ‘perceivable plane relations’ is not gratuitous. It is crucial, for it indicates that Riegl has a phenomenological understanding of relations. At least phenomenologists typically take the direct visibility of relations as a starting point. One finds the phenomenological understanding of relations set out with exceptional clarity in the work of the Münster philosopher Alfred Brunswig (1877–1927), a phenomenologist almost completely unknown today. In his book

Formal Aesthetics and Relational Logic

55

Das Vergleichen und die Relationserkenntnis [Comparison and the Recognition of Relationships], published in 1910, Brunswig gives a comprehensive phenomenological analysis of the ‘direct perception of relationships’ (tr) (p. 14), summarizing the results as follows:  ‘Impartial phenomenological analysis shows, conversely, that forms are directly perceptible objective objects, and that grasping them is largely independent of grasping elements of the formed whole’ (tr) (ibid., p. 177). Even diverse ways of making transitions on the pictorial surface are a directly observable quality. Edmund Husserl (1850–1938) himself emphasized, in Erfahrung und Urteil [Experience and Judgment] of 1939: An ‘awareness of transgression as something discreet must be sharply distinguished from an awareness of continuous transgression’ (tr) (p. 179). Both forms of transition ‘are therefore different kinds of observable unity’ (tr) (p. 173). Whether a transition is painterly or linear can be seen, as can the condition of its being red or blue. Both are equally original. This is why Husserl speaks of the ‘comprehension of relationship and its basis in passivity’ (tr) (p. 171).20 As parallel as Riegl’s views are to phenomenology, it would be wrong to interpret them as a firm anticipation. Rather formal aesthetics has recourse, as does phenomenology itself, to a classical view of English empiricism that was being rediscovered by philosophers in many places at the end of the nineteenth century, Kant’s thesis of consciousness of relations being based on an act of intellectual synthesis having stood almost unchallenged among German speakers until then.21 But formal aesthetics had a purpose in turning back. The idea of direct perception of formal transitions really sets up just one more step in a systematic argument, namely the idea of the visibility of a pre-conceptual rationality.

Visibility as pre-conceptual rationality The significance of the thesis of direct visibility of relations to images becomes clear when it is applied to images. There it means that the Kunstwollen’s decision to bind things into a unity or differentiate them through transitions can be seen by observing the image, with no further process of reflection. It can be seen in the image whether a surface has a painterly internal structure or is internally monochrome, without visible relations. This in turn means, however, that one can speak of pre-conceptual acts being visible on the surface of an image. For this argumentative step, the phenomenological thoughts of the direct perception of relations must be linked to the classical definition of the concept Friedrich Nietzsche (1844–1900) gives in his posthumously published work ‘On Truth and Lying in a Non-Moral Sense’ of 1873. There he writes, ‘Every concept comes into

56

The Visibility of the Image

being by making equivalent that which is non-equivalent. Just as it is certain that no leaf is ever exactly the same as any other leaf, it is equally certain that the concept ‘leaf ’ is formed by dropping these individual differences arbitrarily’ (p. 145). This in fact characterizes the essential thing about a conceptual achievement:  concepts put objects together while ignoring their individual features. Because different things are considered the same – and every object is different from every other as a matter of principle  – the possibility arises of introducing one common linguistic expression for these more or less forcibly equalized things. This is the reason Nietzsche rightly noted that concepts are based on an ‘equalization of unequal things’ – and not only concepts, but also forms on pictorial surfaces. The intellectual action of making unlike things equal is inherent in every pictorial representation of objects by means of visible forms. The construction of concepts and the construction of forms are based, for Nietzsche, on one and the same intellectual principle: ‘Like form, a concept is produced by overlooking what is individual and real’ (ibid., p. 145). On the surface of an image, a form either combines two things into one or differentiates between two things; it makes something the same or sets it apart. In short, to make something visible is inevitably to produce identities out of similarities, and to create differences in between identities. This intellectual difference in the aesthetic process of making something visible is the basis for the fundamental difference between painterly and linear forms. Painterly forms bring unlike things together into one; Turner combines the smoke and the hull of the ship into one visible unity. Linear forms, on the other hand, differentiate; Hergé makes the ship and the background into two things that are visibly distinct. Yet the variations of light in the sky that Turner carefully distinguishes are reduced to a single colour by Hergé.22 By means of varying styles of depiction, different things are made visibly the same or visibly different. What this conceptlike capacity achieves is – based the phenomenological insight into the direct visibility of relations – immediately visible in the image. Diverse styles therefore turn out to be the products of diverse thinking. So one can say that images, in their visible, immanent relations, ‘tend toward concepts’ (tr) as Gottfried Boehm so aptly put it.23 Images initiate a conceptual equalization of unlike things by making sameness visible in diversity, and conversely by making difference visible in sameness. They show what can be the same and what can be different, and in doing so, make a pre-conceptual move visible. This is why Nietzsche saw no opposition between logic and aesthetics; they are two interlocked phenomena. For him, logic is as artistic as the artistic is logical.24

Formal Aesthetics and Relational Logic

57

Variations in style specify variations in thinking, and in fact thinking that can readily be compared to a corresponding conceptual rationality. A clear, linear style of depiction is informed by a rational energy, of the same type as that which produces scientific concepts. In an image of Dürer’s as in a mathematical proof, unlike things are made the same in such a way that there is no room for play, no moment of doubt, no blurriness. Only either-or differentiations are admissible. In their rationality they are allied to style. The range of elements to which a scientific concept refers has a linear boundary, while in other contexts concepts defined in an open, ‘painterly’ way are appropriately and productively applied. Here we see that Riegl’s typology of visible, immanent relations between parts of an image can be carried over to the invisible relations between concepts, so as to classify scientific thinking as haptic thinking. Hermann Nohl (1879–1960) was the first to articulate this idea at the beginning of this century. In his study Stil und Weltanschauung [Style and Weltanschauung] of 1920, he describes ‘which typical designs of the visible world may be distinguished and how they correspond to the typical philosophical understanding of reality’(tr) (p. 23).25 From this point of view we see even more clearly that Riegl’s concerns go far beyond those of an art historian. The basic principles he set forth applies not only to visible artefacts, but also to all representations of relationships in and to the world.26 Painterly and linear are different types of rationality immediately visible on a pictorial surface.

2.3 Intensional and extensional relational logic Preliminary remarks The assertion that art historical principles are logical categories is inexact inasmuch as the word ‘logical’ is ambiguous. By comparing formal aesthetics to relational logic, which also developed in the second half of the nineteenth century, we can clarify the sense in which art historical principles can be called logical categories with precision, and in which respect they differ from traditional logical categories.

Relational logic and its need for completion Relational logic is a subdiscipline of formal logic, which arose as logic was developing an algebraic footing.27 In Substance and Function and Einstein’s Theory of

58

The Visibility of the Image

Relativity of 1910, Ernst Cassirer shows how, as the natural sciences divested themselves of concepts of substance, traditional Aristotelian logic became inadequate. Aristotelian logic is not in a position to describe immanent relations in structural forms. When it comes to stating the logical characteristics of relations, it fails, and ‘the Aristotelian logic, in its general principles, is a true expression and mirror of the Aristotelian metaphysics’ (p.  4). That is to say, Aristotelian logic treats relations as characteristics of a substance. Relations have a distinctly subordinate position to substance, not to mention that relations could never become a category that would function as an alternative to the concept of substance. Within the framework of Aristotle’s view of ontology, a logic that could engage with the modern sciences would be out of the question. Hence Cassirer’s view that ‘exact science had here reached questions for which there existed no precise correlate in the traditional language of formal logic’ (ibid., preface, p. iii).28 Relational logic may be interpreted as a response to this situation. It develops the missing logical instrumentation required to describe phenomena without using the categories of substance and accident. For there to be a purely structural description of formal structures – and relational logic is a form of structuralism29 – the logical characteristics of relationships had to be defined unambiguously, a relational calculus worked out for describing structures within relational complexes with mathematical precision. The task fell to relational logic. This mathematical foundation for a structural mode of observation is substantially developed in the works of August De Morgan (1806–1871), Ernst Schröder (1841–1902) and Charles Sanders Peirce (1839–1914),30 who establish the premises that have retained their validity. The key relational logical categories in this model are the concepts of ‘transitivity’, ‘symmetry’ and ‘reflexivity’. They typify purely formal characteristics of relations. A relation is transitive if, for a, b and c, it is given that when ‘aRb’ and bRc’, this also always also implies ‘aRc’ (‘aRb’ indicates that the relation R is given between a and b). An example of transitivity is the relation of parallelism: if line a is parallel to line b, and line b is parallel to line c, then line a is also parallel to line c. A relation is symmetrical if the relata are interchangeable, if ‘aRb’ also makes ‘bRa’ possible: if, for example a is as old as b, then b is also as old as a. A relation is reflexive if the relata could be the same, if ‘aRa’ is a thinkable relationship: the relation between a murderer and the victim is a good example of reflexivity, because a murder can also be a suicide.31 Since relational logic provides the formal tools for the logical description of complex relational structures, there is no immediate obstacle to using these tools

Formal Aesthetics and Relational Logic

59

on aesthetic relational structures. Why should we not also ask about the relational logical qualities of the connections among things depicted in an image? It may seem unusual to submit an aesthetic object to relational logical classification. But it is a good way of showing how formal aesthetics is related to relational logic. Think back on the examples given above, on the images by Hergé and Turner. We can see that relational logical differentiation does apply to the aesthetic relations in both images – we also see, however, that they are insufficient for aesthetic relations. The following reflections make this clearer: If we apply the categories of relational logic to the figure-ground relation, it will first be transformed into the conceptual form ‘aRb’. ‘aRb’ means: the ship a is located in front of the background b.  Then, using the insights from formal aesthetics, we identify this relation R as ‘asymmetrical’, for the relation does not permit the order of the relata to be changed; the statement ‘the ship is the background of the sky’ is false. Another relational logical characteristic of this relationship is its intransitivity. This is to say: if someone is depicted in front of the hull of the ship, and this ship in turn is located in front of a background of sky and water, then this background is not a background for the person, because there no transition between person and sky. A figure-ground relationship is not reflexive, either, because no figure can function as a background for itself. With that, the most important formal characteristics of this relation are covered from the standpoint of logic. So a relational logical observation of two images that are identical in terms of content and composition gives the following result:  the structure of these depictions is the same. Hence it becomes clear that the structures responsible for style cannot be grasped by means of relational logic. The tools are too crude. Formal differences determined by style simply do not register, they fall through the filter; for relational logic, the relation ‘aRb’ in the depiction by Turner is formally identical to ‘aRb’ in the depiction by Hergé – as it would be identical to the relation in any representation at all. An aesthetician cannot accept this. Stylistically different representations are always – as Wölfflin explicitly says – ‘a completely different structural system’ (Principles, p.  310). The aesthetics of art historical principle can be read as a response to this situation. One who is not prepared to interpret the two images under consideration here as structurally identical has the task of improving relational logic. What is formally the same and formally different depends on the differentiating tools that are available. Riegl therefore sharpens relational logic’s potential for differentiation to meet the specific demands of pictorial representation. Relational logically identical relationships can be differentiated more subtly with art historical principles. This is because

60

The Visibility of the Image

Riegl takes the style of a structural relationship to be an inescapable quality of any relational structure. The relation ‘aRb(Turner)’  – the notation intended to mean ‘with Turner’  – would be asymmetrical, intransitive, irreflexive, painterly. Conversely, ‘aRb(Hergé)’ would have the logical characteristics: asymmetrical, intransitive, irreflexive, linear. Against the backdrop of a changed conception of logic in the second half of the century, Riegl’s introduction of art historical principles was as obvious a consequence as it was a necessary one. The need for completion is immediately noticeable, because the specific formal characteristics of an aesthetic object cannot be grasped using relational logical categories; to speak in this way is to completely miss what is specifically aesthetic. Then the question arises of how this can be, and exactly what ‘specifically aesthetic’ is. For this cannot be overlooked: for one thing, relational logic is not doing anything different from what Riegl does with the art historical principles. In both theories, possible formal characteristics of relations are specified. In both cases a set of tools are developed for describing relational structures. But why, finally, does relational logic ignore or overlook stylistic differences in structure? The key question for the relationship between formal aesthetics and relational logic goes: What is the difference between establishing that a relation is transitive, and establishing that it is painterly?

Sense and reference in images In order to recognize the difference between art historical and relational logical principles, it is advisable to bring the fundamental difference between concepts and images up to date. It can be done with reference to a fundamental distinction in modern semiotics that Gottlob Frege (1848–1945) undertook to make in his essay ‘On Sense and Reference’ of 1892. For Frege, there are ‘three levels of difference’ in signs (p. 213). A sign can set itself apart from another sign in three ways: ‘The difference may concern at most the conceptions, or the sense but not the referent, or, finally, the referent as well. The difference lies either in the sense only, or in the reference but not in the meaning, or finally in the meaning as well’ (ibid.). The first possibility for differentiating between two signs consists of two signs referring to two different objects. Then the meaning of this sign, in Frege’s sense, is variable; for him, the meaning corresponds to the extension of the sign. But two signs with an identical meaning can also differ from one another, in their sense, in fact, by which Frege understands the – as it is often said today – intension of a sign; this is the second possibility of a difference between signs. Signs

Formal Aesthetics and Relational Logic

61

may refer to the same object, but do it in different ways. Signs that present the object differently distinguish themselves in sense by calling attention to different characteristics of the object. The way of giving the same meaning is different between ‘morning star’ and ‘evening star’  – to draw on a famous example of Frege’s – although the meaning, which is to say the star that is meant, is identical. For Frege there is a third possibility, that signs distinguish themselves through the sort of notion their users have of them, although their sense and their reference are identical. Although signs may have identical sense and reference, different people will nevertheless associate them with various notions. This is, however, a purely subjective difference in signs and their effect, which cannot be grasped conceptually. With this outline in place, it is possible to regard stylistic difference as differences in the intension of the pictorial sign. For the concept of intension must – as Gottfried Gabriel already confirmed – ‘reach far enough to include all nuances of content’ (tr).32 A depiction of the same object by Hergé and Turner has the same extension, but depicts the object differently, so that the intension of these pictorial signs is not identical. Frege’s scheme is applicable to all signs – not only conceptual signs. The difference in sense with respect to two stylistically different images is a special kind of sense difference, however, that cannot have a concept. It therefore is advisable, as Gottfried Boehm, too, suggested, to speak of a specific ‘pictorial sense’ that he too associated with the quality of the immanent relations: ‘Images always contain more potential for connecting their individual elements than is required to read only their “content” ’ (tr).33 With that, a substantial difference between concept and images is exposed. Images distinguish themselves from concepts in enabling a wider spectrum of ways in which meaning may be given. We need to recognize that the spatial perspective in which an object can be depicted admits infinitely many pictorial descriptions of one and the same object, but that beyond this within it is possible to undertake another infinity of differentiations in the infrastructure within each of these perspectives. This two-tiered structure of pictorial intension has been described by Hans Jonas (1903–1993) in The Phenomenon of Life: Toward a Philosophical Biology of 1961: ‘There are many, equally recognizable, visual shapes to the same object, as a result of relative position and perspective: its “aspects”; each of these enjoys an independence from the variation of size due to distance; and independence from variations of color and brightness due to conditions of light; an independence from the completeness of detail, which can merge and disappear in the simultaneous wholeness of an object’s view. Through all these variations of sense the form remains identifiable and continuously represents

62

The Visibility of the Image

the same thing’ (p. 162). This is the first step towards chancing the intension of a pictorial sign. One shows the same object from different spatial positions. In this way, the same object always takes a different gestalt in the image. But the decisive thing is, as Jonas continues, that ‘through all these variations of sense the form remains identifiable and continuously represents the same thing’ (ibid.) This second form of the ‘sense variations’ is exactly what constitutes a specific pictorial sense that is not given to the concept. Frege’s example should clarify it:  because the concept of ‘morning star’ as well as ‘evening star’ can refer to Venus, the extension of this sign is identical, despite the difference in intension. But at the moment aesthetic phenomena are taken into consideration, things become more problematic. In a pictorial medium, it is possible, keeping to one intension, to attempt to differentiate a kind of ‘second’ intension. This is the case when various artists produce images of the evening star. It would even be the case if the same star were merely photographed using different lenses. This is exactly what Frege overlooks in an example he uses to explain sense and reference: ‘Somebody observes the moon through a telescope. I compare the moon itself to the referent:  it is the object of the observation, mediated by the real image projected by the object glass in the interior of the telescope, and by the retinal image of the observer. The former I compare to the sense, the latter to the conception or experience. The image in the telescope is indeed one-sided and dependent of the standpoint of observation; but it is still objective inasmuch as it can be used by several observers’ (‘Sense and Reference’, p. 213). According to this comparison, sense corresponds only to a perspective conditioned by location. But this is insufficient. As Frege correctly sees, the ‘real image projected by the object glass’ is always a projected image, which means, exactly for this reason, it can be projected in any perspective in different ways, which is to say it can appear in different perspectives in very different ways. There is an indeterminacy in polymorphous nature that permits a multiplicity of images without a change in viewpoint. It is worth remembering that even lenses have specific depictive characteristics, which could no doubt be exchanged for others, but never eliminated. Promotional brochures for lenses and telescopes normally include an image showing how the optical system in question depicts an object from a specific perspective, and this for good reason. We could say then that these images show the manner in which an object is given with a lens. In short, they show sense. The possibilities for variation within a given perspective proliferate if the process of depiction is subject to artistic considerations. Still, even here the main idea remains in place:  The style of an image can be recognized as a form of

Formal Aesthetics and Relational Logic

63

intension all its own, one that permits differentiations in access to an object that are not given for a concept if that concept is grasped as a mathematical function. To realize comparable stylistic differentiation on a conceptual level, we must switch to metaphorical or poetic language. Frege was fully aware of the special form of stylistic sense in poetry, for he writes:  ‘To the possible differences here belong also the coloring and shading which poetic eloquence seeks to give the sense’ (ibid., p. 213). But Frege takes the view that these possibilities for differentiation in the way an object is artistically mediated are not objective, that is, not to be found in the sign. According to Frege, there are no features of the work that account of the differences in intension determined by style; for him, style is a subjective projection of the receiver: ‘Such coloring and shading are not objective, and must be evoked by each hearer or reader according to the hints of the poet or speaker’ (ibid.). Frege speaks only metaphorically of ‘coloration’, but in doing so he aligns stylistic differences with irrational and subjective variations in imagination.34 He appears not to notice that by saying that these variations in imagination follow the ‘wave of the poet’ he is contradicting himself: a poet – like a painter – can only wave by means of his work, that is through objective nuances in the sign. Frege’s coloration manifests itself in the image as visible style.

Types of relational logic In clarifying the initial problem, namely the relationship of art historical principles to relation logical classification of relationship, the semiotic distinction between concept and image proves helpful. According to Riegl, stylistic differences appear as variations in the formal characteristics of relations; the observable transitions vary. For Riegl, stylistic differences are definitely objective, grounded in the relational differences in the work. These cannot be grasped through relational logic, however, because it is oriented exclusively to a conceptual medium which is free of images’ stylistic constraints. That which is a liberation for the one is a loss for the other. An aesthetician simply passes over the structural differences in relations determined through observation. Relational logic assumes that by formalizing a relation to the term ‘aRb’, no significant characteristic is lost. This is only the case as long as we remain in the realm of conceptual languages and scientific contexts, however; these are, as language analytic philosophy says, non-intensional contexts. An English and a German statement can therefore be replaced and translated as ‘aRb’, but a pictorial representation of this relationship cannot be – it lies in an intensional

64

The Visibility of the Image

context, which is to say that no extensional equivalent sign can substitute for this representation. We can conclude from this that the formalizations that have been so successful in logic offer no appropriate access to aesthetic phenomenon, because formalization obliterates crucial aesthetic structural characteristics. But Riegl  – followed by Wölfflin  – draws a different conclusion; for him Zimmermann’s idea of positioning formal logic as a model is preserved. Riegl’s distinctive achievement is not to turn against a formal logical mode of observation in aesthetics, but rather to grasp the problem as an occasion to improve the formalism of logic in keeping with the special demands of aesthetics. To this end, Riegl supplements relational logic by introducing an intensional typology: art historical principles sort relations into types according to their various ways of being aesthetically given. The principles establish types of structures that carry meaning, but that have no objective meaning in themselves. Art historical principles expose the very structural qualities that are destroyed by formal logic. Whatever the object of an image, its reference, its meaning, its denotation, none of it matters to typing according to art historical principles. This result initiates a clarification of the relationship between relational logic and formal aesthetics: the mode of intensional observation Riegl developed specifically for images overturned relational logic’s way of going about classification. Relational logic operates extensionally, as its co-founder Charles Sanders Peirce made unmistakably clear. Relational logical characteristics are specified when the relations are grasped as a class of pairs, or when more than two objects are related to one another, as a class of triplets, quadruplets, and so on. Stated as a generalization: extensionally, a relation is the class of ordered n-tuplets. There is no further consideration of way we relate to these n-tuplets. The beginning of Peirce’s text ‘The Logic of Relatives’ of 1883 is typical for this extensional conception of relational logic: ‘A dual relative term, such as ‘lover’, ‘benefactor’, ‘servant’, is a common name signifying a pair of objects. Of the two members of the pair, a determinate one is generally the first, and the other the second; so that if the order is reversed, the pair is not considered as remaining the same. Let A, B, C, D., etc., be all the individual objects in the universe; then all the individual pairs may be arrayed in a block, thus: A:A B:A C:A D:A etc.

A:B B:B C:B D:B etc.

A:C B:C C:C D:C etc.

A:D B:D C:D D:D etc.

etc. etc. etc. etc. etc.

‘A general relative may be conceived as a logical aggregate of a number of such individual relatives’ (p. 195).

Formal Aesthetics and Relational Logic

65

With respect to this difference – relational logic undertakes an extensional classification and theories of art historical principle undertake an intensional classification of relations – the main idea of formal aesthetics may be formulated as follows: Relations that are the same for a formal logician can vary for an aesthetician, because unlike the logician, the aesthetician does not abstract from the way something is visibly given. In extensional observations, it does not matter whether one is concerned with an image or a concept, for what is at issue is not the medium, but the reference. This is why categorizing an aesthetic object by means of relational logic never seems to work, for what is specifically aesthetic lies not in the reference, but in the concrete forms of an object, in its transitions, in the ways and means its relations convey content. With this we can answer the questions with which we began, about the sense in which art historical principles can be considered as logical categories. With his aesthetics, Riegl exposes the structures that formal logic stopped short of grasping, but for which the effort to make relation logical distinctions remains meaningful. These formal differences are not relevant as long as logic is exclusively oriented to conceptual language. There we do not encounter stylistic types of relations. But as soon as the observation comes to include the pictorial way in which relations are given, a field of new logical differentiation opens. The theory of art historical principles is an extension of relational logic into the realm of aesthetics.

The aesthetic grounding of relational logic Art historical principles subvert the opposition between logic and aesthetics by being equally concerned with aesthetic and logical differences. There are grounds for both ways of reading. That there are aesthetic differences between a painting by Hergé and one by Turner is supported by the idea that the infrastructure in each case is perceptible; the images have different styles. That we are concerned with a logical difference is supported by the idea that the main possibilities the artists had for depiction were grasped a priori; the images show different ways of thinking. It was, once again, Erwin Panofsky who recognized this double, logical-aesthetic character of the art historical principles, maintaining that they ‘first, possess apriori validity’ and ‘second, apply not to unobservable, but to observable things’ (tr).35 And it was not only from the art theoretical side that this double character was noticed. Charles Sanders Peirce, too, assumed the identity of logicalaesthetic aspects in relation logical principles. For Peirce, relational logic is not only one subfield among others within formal logic; relational logic had a special

66

The Visibility of the Image

position for him, which he described in ‘The Logic of Relatives’ of 1897: ‘Now in studying the logic of relatives we must sedulously avoid the error of regarding it as a highly specialized doctrine. It is, on the contrary, nothing but formal logic generalized to the very tip-top’ (p. 299). This implies that for Peirce relational logic is engaged with the formal principles of logical thinking as such. Any form of rational and logical thought is built up from relationships. Relational logic is a logic that works meta-logically, that is, with existing logical forms. The relational logician Wilhelm Burkamp (1879–1939) of Rostock, now unjustly fallen into obscurity, put this idea at the centre of his reflections: ‘We can order relationships that are specifically logical among [. . .] kinds of relationships. The implication is a relation, which is as a rule an asymmetrical relation, whose reflexivity is right for any relatum; the disjunction is an intransitive, symmetrical relation, whose reflexivity is right only for a true relatum etc. [. . .] So the whole of formal logic has a relation logical character, both in its specifically logical concepts as well as in its specifically logical relationships’ (tr).36 Relational logic’s reason for taking a special position becomes clear in light of the claim that it is meta-logical:  it is a formal theory about the formal conditions of possibility for logic. It sets out to describe, by logical means, which formal structures comprise formal logic. Even De Morgan studied the relations between subject and predicate in a syllogism, which lets us see that from the start of the development of relational logic these currents, like Herbartianism, rest on the idea: it is the relations in forms that matter – whether they are logical or aesthetic.37 Yet for Peirce relational logic’s metalogical character is not the only reason for its special position. He himself sees that the reduction of logical form to its immanent relations in logic puts a phenomenon at issue that has an aesthetic, which is to say here a perceptible character. According to Peirce, an extremely generalized logic suggests a bridge to the aesthetic, which he even cast as a relationship of dependency:  ‘logic needs the help of esthetics’38 By seeing variations of relational logic in any form of logic, he sets up the idea with which he tries to give the whole of logic a foundation in aesthetics. For Peirce, logic gets help from aesthetics, for relational logic deals with observable phenomena. It is especially clear in the relation logical category of symmetry: it describes a phenomenon that is as logical as it is aesthetic. This is, for Peirce, what accounts for relational logic’s special, double position:  it takes on not only meta-logical but also proto-logical functions. On the one hand, Peirce reduces complex forms of logical thinking to  – as Wilhelm Dilthey would express it  – ‘elementary

Formal Aesthetics and Relational Logic

67

logical operators’ (tr).39 On the other hand, he tries to give the immediate, intuitive visibility of logic an aesthetic foundation in observation. This is the help that logic needs from aesthetics.40 With this, the relationship of relational logic to formal aesthetics crystallizes further into a mutually supplementary relationship.41 In both disciplines it comes to a subversion of the opposition between logic and aesthetics, and with it to a convergence in many aspects. Relational aesthetics faces the challenge of basing its categories entirely on logical differences, and relational logic considers its categories to be based in observation. This does not mean that a fundamental difference cannot retained in the complementary relationship. Yet the mutually supplementary relationship lets formal aesthetics and relational logic appear as two sides of a coin: in art – we can read Riegl in this way – there are logical differences to be seen. In logic – we can read Peirce in this way – there are aesthetic differences we can think.

3

The Logic of Ways of Seeing: Heinrich Wölfflin (1864–1945)

3.1 The relational logic of an image Preliminary remarks Ascertaining the characteristics that are specific to relations, such as transitivity, symmetry or reflexivity, is just the first part of what a modern relational logic has to do. The logical characteristics of relations are ultimately meant for a more far-reaching purpose, which Günther Patzig formulated as follows: ‘A relational logic is responsible for determining which structures are capable of bringing diverse forms of relations together, and for developing arguments that permit us to draw other relations and characteristics of the relata from the specific relations that lie before us’ (tr).1 Relational logic first comes into its own when it is describing the logical coherence among several relations. That is, the system of categories of logical relational characteristics serves to ground a second step, the development of theorems about relationships. ‘Theorems about relations’ is, in any case, the way Rudolf Carnap, in his Einführung in die symbolische Logik [Introduction to Symbolic Logic] of 1954, designated a possible way to draw, from certain formal characteristics, a conclusion about a relation to other formal characteristics. The following dependencies, for example, are valid between relations: 1. Transitive, symmetrical relationships are reflexive. 2. Asymmetrical relations are irreflexive. 3. Among transitive relations, the asymmetrical ones are irreflexive, and vice versa.2 If the comparison between formal aesthetics and relational logic in the last chapter concluded that both disciplines are concerned to the same extent, if not in the

70

The Visibility of the Image

same way, with the formal characteristics of relations, the question arises whether the second aspect of relational logic might also have its counterpart in formal aesthetics. Stated concretely, the question goes: Are there logical theorems about the mutual dependencies of aesthetic relational characteristics in formal aesthetics as well? Is it possible to logically deduce, from just the knowledge that the quality of a transition in a representation’s immanent relation is linear or rather painterly, other formal characteristics of the surface infrastructure? Heinrich Wölfflin’s study Principles of Art History: The Problem of the Development of Style in Early Modern Art of 1915 appears to answer just this question. Therefore we can, with Wölfflin’s help, try to develop the parallels Riegl introduced between formal aesthetics and relational logic. Perhaps more than any other aesthetician, Wölfflin focussed on the question of the logical force of the painterly and on all aspects of ‘pictorial form’.3 With this concept, Wölfflin turns to a problem known also from Ludwig Wittgenstein’s Tractatus logico-philosophicus (1921–1922). Both start from a relational concept of the image: ‘What constitutes a picture is that its elements are related to one another in a determinate way’ (p. 10). But for Wittgenstein this does not imply a description of the empirical structures between elements of an image in specific cases. For him, as for Wölfflin, the concern is with logical possibilities, the possibilities in principle for relationships between parts of an image – and it is exactly these possibilities that Wölfflin calls ‘pictorial form’ and Wittgenstein calls ‘representational form’: ‘Let us call this connexion of its elements the structure of the picture, and let us call the possibility of this structure the pictorial form of the picture’ (ibid.).4 In order to determine the pictorial form or the representational form, Wölfflin expanded the system of art historical principles with four additional conceptual pairs. These are plane – recession, closed – open form, multiplicity – unity, and clearness – unclearness. The following content needs to be linked to these concepts.

Plane – recession With the conceptual pair ‘plane – recession’ Wölfflin is once again concerned with a relational characteristic of an image, specifically ‘which can be arranged next to or behind one another’ (Principles, p. 169). There are two extremes in the way the spatial relation between two objects can be reproduced in a pictorial representation: things can be positioned near one another on a plane or one behind the other in space.5 Of course these extremes allow for countless transitional forms – as do linear and painterly; any angle of oblique-diagonal ordering is thinkable. But at ‘a point where the contents of the picture can no longer be grasped as planar

The Logic of Ways of Seeing

71

sections, [there] the nerve center has shifted to the relation between front and rear parts’ (p. 157). This is the crucial point in Wölfflin’s argument: no pictorial depiction of two things is thinkable unless the two things are related in some way within the spectrum of spatial possibilities, between being next to one another (i.e. on a plane) and one being behind the other (i.e. in recession). This is logically impossible. It becomes clear, then, that we are dealing with a characteristic of pictorial form that is recognizable a priori: space is a form of representation.*

The limits of pictorial abstraction Wölfflin’s conceptual pair ‘plane – recession’ again emphasizes the basic terms of art historical principles. The principles are not concepts for describing empirical characteristics, supporting a stylistic account of specific historical works. What is philosophically significant about them is that they expose the a priori formal characteristics of a representation. We are dealing with constraints a depiction must fulfil, for logical reasons, if it is to depict anything. This is the case for the first conceptual pair, painterly and linear: a form can only be visible if the transitions take on a value between the painterly and the linear. Any work of art is, accordingly, a unique resolution between opposites that are recognizable a priori. A depiction can nevertheless make two things visible only if the things can be ordered between ‘recession’ and ‘plane’. We can know this about any depiction without having to see it. It is a purely formal-logical knowledge of the logic of pictorial representation. From these reflections, it becomes clear that the art historical principles define those aspects of pictorial representation that pictorial representation cannot disregard. Formal aesthetics rest on the belief that images can abstract many things in representation – but not everything. What is logically unique about an image is not so much its capacity to abstract in the process of representation, as those characteristics from which it cannot abstract. It is possible to denote an object in a pictorial representation without that pictorial description giving any information about the size, colour or materiality of the depicted object. But in an image, it is impossible to denote two objects in relation to one another at all without making a specific spatial order visible. This is a basic difference between images and conceptual language. Within a system of conceptual symbols, there is no difficulty in remaining spatially neutral in relation to two objects: ‘Stan and

* At this point, a reader familiar with Kant’s philosophy may already have understood why it is necessary, in what follows, to compare Wölfflin’s theory with Kant’s transcendental aesthetics as well.

72

The Visibility of the Image

Oli are over there!’ With an image, on the other hand, it is clear a priori that this is impossible. Any image of Stan and Oli depicts a specific spatial relationship. It follows from these reflections: images are fundamentally more restricted than concepts in their capacity to abstract. There is nothing that cannot be abstracted in conceptual language; this is why there are no principles of language. In pictorial language, however, there are several things that cannot be abstracted; this is why there are art historical principles whose completeness cannot be confirmed. Wölfflin himself considers it entirely possible that his system of art historical categories could be expanded. A conceptual pair of pictorial categories is always indicated when it can be used to describe a kernel of pictorial depiction that cannot be abstracted. The kernel is related to the intensionality of the pictorial sign, that is, to the way the image arranges a reference to something. The art historical principles set out the characteristics that we know, a priori, will be present in any pictorial description. We could say that Wölfflin, with his conceptual pair ‘plane’ and ‘recession’, specified a logical, intensional quality of a pictorial reference: ‘then here, too, we shall obtain two representational types as different from one another as the linear and painterly styles’ (p. 157).

Closed form – open form The same holds true for the second conceptual pair that Wölfflin introduced: closed form and open form.6 Wölfflin is dissatisfied with the terms, but does not want to replace them with others, ‘because their generality describes the phenomenon better than tectonic and atectonic and they are more accurate than the roughly synonymous strict and free, regular and irregular, and so on’ (p. 204). With this sentence, Wölfflin is implying that the forms of an image always stand in some relation to the central axis of the depiction: that is, to the symmetry of the image. For this conceptual pair too, then, an aesthetic object is described in terms of a kind of relational grid. Open form is recognizable in that ‘pure symmetries disappear’ (ibid., p. 205). As a result, the aesthetic object does not appear to have been so rigorously thought through. On the contrary, the tectonic pictorial form is based on a regular, symmetrical ordering of pictorial parts. ‘In mechanics this contrast is referred to in terms of stable of labile equilibriums’ (p. 125). In consideration of the symmetrical-asymmetrical, we are in fact concerned with two relational logical possibilities for any form of image. The content of a representation can be conveyed in such a way that the image either is or is not oriented to a central axis – whether this be vertical or horizontal. It should be noted, in any case, that there are always more asymmetrical than symmetrical possibilities for

The Logic of Ways of Seeing

73

putting the parts of an image in order. This is the reason Wölfflin points out that the closed-symmetrical formulation creates the impression of having been deliberate. One can only agree: according to the laws of probability, a symmetrical organization of pictorial parts would occur far more frequently if the separate elements were randomly distributed: ‘Ultimately it is not about the verticals and horizontals, the frontal views and profiles, tectonics and atectonics, but rather whether the visibility of the figure, of the whole image, seems intentional or not’ (p. 206). With this Wölfflin arrives at the real meaning of ‘closed’ and ‘open’: There are two forms of representation that differ from one another in that in the closed form, the content is presented as if all relations of the parts to one another had been calculated; in the open form, on the other hand, the content is depicted as if the ordering of the parts had been left to chance. The closed form is the one in which the relations of the parts to one another can be reduced to a concept: with this pictorial form, we can say that the parts are symmetrical to one another, the parts frame in a triangle, the parts form a square, or similar things. Language can describe the composition in terms of shape. With the open form, conversely, the forms of an aesthetic object do not relate to one another in any conceptually graspable way; as a result, the composition is less prominent, or at least not so rigorous. With this situation in mind, Christiane Schmitz aptly finds that ‘in this apparently paradoxical reversal, a work would be “closed” just when its principles of construction are openly available, and conversely “open” when the availability is closed: closed form correlates with open formation, closed formation with open form’ (tr).7

Multiplicity – unity The third pair of art historical concepts Wölfflin introduced is called multiplicity and unity. Again it is about categories for describing the immanent relations in pictorial syntax. This time we are concerned, as Wölfflin already expressly says in ‘Das Problem des Stils in der bildenden Kunst’ [The Problem of Style in Visual Art], a talk given in 1911, with ‘the way in which the parts relate to the whole’ (tr) (p. 576). Since Wölfflin is convinced that ‘two different forms of artistic unity’ (tr) are thinkable (p. 577), even the opposition between ‘multiplicity’ and ‘unity’ is actually inexact. ‘Multiplicity versus unity’ is a shortening of ‘Multiple Unity and Unified Unity’ (Principles, p. 234). A multiplicity of parts is given if each individual figure can be isolated, if the forms that relate to one another are separate, self-contained shapes and if they do not blend into an amorphous whole: ‘The whole comprises a system of independent parts’ (p. 310). In a unified unity, conversely, the parts of the representation may be ‘conceived only as a unity’ (tr) (‘Problem des Stils’, p. 577).

74

The Visibility of the Image

With this pair of concepts, Wölfflin is once again concerned with a phenomenological description of pictorial relations. With the categories ‘multiplicity – unity’, he is making the same distinction Edmund Husserl takes up in the third Logical Investigations of 1901 with the title ‘On the Theory of Wholes and Parts.’ There, Husserl divides the parts that make up a whole into dependent and independent objects: ‘Contents of the former sort can only be conceived as parts of more comprehensive wholes, whereas the latter appear possible, even if nothing whatever exists beside them, nothing therefore bound up with them to form a whole Contents of the first sort are thinkable only as parts of a comprehensive whole’ (Vol. 2, p. 439). If the parts are dependent, the whole is unified, and if the parts are independent, the whole is multiple. The criterion Husserl uses to recognize dependent and independent image forms as such is worth noting, and particularly applicable to images: It is the ‘inseparability of non-independent parts’ (ibid., p. 439). Conversely, an independent part is identifiable, for Husserl, by being ‘separably presentable’ (ibid., p.  439, italics in original). In fact this phenomenological difference in style is shown clearly in the pictorial examples introduced above, by Turner and Hergé. With Hergé, the ship can be cut out of the picture without difficulty and the part then recognized as a ship independently. The immanent relations have the quality of ‘wholes which are broken up, or could be broken up, into pieces – in their case talk of members or of articulated structure alone comes natural. The parts are here not merely disjoined from each other, but relatively independent, they have the character of mutually-put-together pieces’ (p. 437, italics in original). With Turner, conversely, it would first be difficult to detach parts – the exact beginning of an individual form cannot be found – and second it would bring no recognizable result. A  ship cut from Turner’s picture would be just an unclear daub of colour. The conceptual pair ‘multiplicity and unity’ is closely related to the last of Wölfflin’s conceptual pairs, ‘clearness and unclearness’.8

Clearness – unclearness Like all the pairs of principles, the pair ‘clearness and unclearness’ is not meant to be evaluative, but purely descriptive. It describes the difference that relations between two forms can make from an ‘acme of clarity’ to something that ‘retains some indeterminateness’ (Principles, pp.  198–199). In a clear image, the parts can be established as elements, which is impossible in an unclear image because fluid transitions cause the formal elements to merge.

The Logic of Ways of Seeing

75

Relational logical rules for images What is philosophically critical in Wölfflin’s five-paired system of art historical principles is the coherence among them. This is already indicated in the last two pairs of concepts. We see immediately that multiplicity in design will necessarily go hand in hand with clarity in form. Nevertheless, Wölfflin himself was never as clear with regard to the manner of the principles’ coherence as one might have wished. The first explicit inquiry was undertaken in the context of research on Wölfflin. In his research on ‘coherence with respect to Wölfflin’s reflections’, Meinhold Lurz comes to the conclusion: ‘What mattered to Wölfflin was that if a concept on one side of his conceptual pair applies to an art work, the same side of all the others should apply to it as well. There should be no instance of a concept’s opposite side suddenly intervening. If, for example, an image is painterly, it cannot be clear, and if it has an open form it cannot give the effect of multiplicity’ (tr).9 This does actually match Wölfflin’s intention, as indicated in the following: ‘The linear-plastic category is as closely associated with the compact strata of space in the planar style as the tectonic-closed category is naturally related to the independence of parts and consistent clarity. But imperfect clarity of form and the effect of unity among depreciated individual parts will combine of their own accord with the flowing, atectonic category, and are best accommodated in the realm of impressionistic, painterly apprehension’ (p. 306). With this conclusion we can confirm the structural affinity to theorems of relational logic that we suspected at the beginning. With Wölfflin, the parallels between formal aesthetics and relational logic are taken a step further. He wants to find those ‘theorems about relations’ that would make it possible, on the basis of the formal transitional quality of a relation being painterly or linear, to come to a conclusion about the presence of other formal qualities of the infrastructure; just as it is possible to conclude from the relation being asymmetric that it is also irreflexive. The strength of Wölfflin’s understanding of his aesthetics as a kind of formal logic becomes clear when the coherence of the principles are brought to bear on two formulae of relational logic: 1. Any representation with linear transition is, in its syntactic relationship, planar, closed, multiple and clear. 2. Any representation with painterly transition is, in its syntactic relations, recessive, open, unified and unclear.10 In bringing Wölfflin’s theory to bear on these two statements, the key problem abruptly appears: Why can there be no instance of, as Meinhold Lurz put

76

The Visibility of the Image

it above, ‘a concept’s opposite side suddenly intervening’ (tr)? Here the answer must be: for logical reasons – only then does Wölfflin’s project take on not only art historical, but also philosophical importance. If the correlation between a principle (such as ‘linear’) and the other principles on the same side (such as ‘clear’, etc.) is historically specific to Renaissance representations, then it is a purely contingent correlation that could be thought differently and so could not be a logical one. But this is exactly Wölfflin’s target, and this is exactly the way we should understand the metaphors of ‘naturally related’ and ‘combine of their own accord’ used in the last quotation: The relational qualities of an image have a logical coherence. Although Wölfflin, as an art historian, makes a specialty of historical styles, his reflections are directed towards a pictorial logic. His insights develop from historical examples, but apply to the constraints, in principle, of ‘pictorial form’. They appear to be historically determined because they are logically necessary. In his essay ‘Norm and Form’ of 1963, Ernst H. Gombrich made explicit reference to it: ‘But what strikes one about these co-ordinates is that they are not independent, either logically or historically’ (p.  94). Wölfflin extends the idea Herbart and Zimmermann introduced into aesthetics, that aesthetics can be pursued as an a priori conceptual science. Empirical and historical contexts do not matter here, as Wölfflin himself writes, ‘since we are only interested in explaining concepts’ (Principles, p. 45). For an art historian to make such a statement is completely unbelievable. It shows how forcefully logic governs the theory of art historical principles.* It remains to discuss the validity of the theorems Wölfflin formulated. The logical dependence of a linear or painterly transitional quality is easily deduced for the last two principles: Only in the presence of hard transitions is it possible to give a representation of something that is clear, that is, in which there are no indeterminate places. Multiplicity, too can be deduced logically: Only when the parts of a representation are delimited in a clear and linear way can there be a * The rigorous logicity of the pairs of art historical principles  – whether Riegl’s or Wölfflin’s  – is not only systematically but also historically critical, for it indicates the defeat of psychologically grounded principles, which came to a peak with Nietzsche’s ‘Apollonian’ and ‘Dionysian’. More than a few of Wölfflin’s contemporaries did not see this logical kind of justification as any justification at all. The following passage from Oskar Wulff, for example, is characteristic: ‘Only where are the concepts supposed to have gained their universality? […] Such a claim can be defended with only two means of proof: through the discovery of the same forms of intuition in a style-historical parallel, that is, through comparative observation, or by tracing it back to its psychological roots. Wölfflin brings none of this to bear’ (tr) (‘Kritische Erörterungen zur Prinzipienlehre der Kunstwissenschaft’ [Critical Considerations of the Theory of Art Historical Principles], part 1, p. 8). The choice of two ways Wulff offers is incomplete: in addition to the historical and the psychological ways to ground principles, the logical enters with formal aesthetics. This is the reason formal aesthetics since Riegl and Wölfflin is as much an expression of anti-psychologism as of anti-historicism, as phenomenology is for Husserl.

The Logic of Ways of Seeing

77

pictorial surface with a multiplicity of independent figures. Conversely, a painterly quality of transitions leads logically to a more fundamental unclearness. ‘The archenemy of the painterly is the isolation of individual form’ (p. 148). A painterly quality of transition directed towards connection and not towards isolation of the individual forms will in principle produce a unification of the pictorial elements. This logical correlation of transitional qualities and independence of the parts was also introduced by Husserl as an explicit theorem in his Logical Investigations of the relations between parts and the whole:  ‘One may affirm that: two contemporaneous sensuous concreta necessarily form an ‘undifferentiated whole’ if all the immediately constitutive “moments” of the one pass unbrokenly over into corresponding constitutive “moments” of the other’ (p. 450. Italics in original). The situation is similar with the conceptual pair ‘closed – open’. A mode of representation giving the impression that parts of the image are in a closed relationship of dependency must be a linear and clear form of representation, since this is the only way tectonic structures can be made visible. With an extremely painterly style, no symmetry can be established at all, for one cannot determine exactly where the middle of this transition would be: this middle would not single itself out in the form of a visible line. The only pair of concepts for which the dependency of the one concept cannot be logically deduced from the other concept on the same side is ‘plane  – recession’. Wölfflin’s theorem is hasty in this regard. For it is entirely possible to think a representation in which all parts are organized absolutely beside one another on a plane, but in which the transitions are nevertheless painterly and the overall impression unified and unclear. The fact that it is possible to think of such a case suffices as an argument against purely logical coherence. Still, we need to add that although it is not possible to deduce planarity from the linearity of a representation, it is possible to deduce dependency. Linear form in transitions tends towards a planar form of organization, because the overall formal impression enables us to see that the image contains only haptic information. The placement of objects behind one another in a representation leads to things on the horizon becoming smaller, due to perspectival foreshortening. A situation that can only be seen, but not touched, must be represented in this way. A  linear image is the representation of a tactile reality. It follows that it will have to avoid emphasizing optical foreshortening – which is why it tends towards a planar organization. ‘And if it seems as though the recessional style does not necessarily belong to this family, one can point to the fact that its recessional tensions are built exclusively upon optical effects that only have any significance for the eye, not for the sense of plasticity’ (p. 306).

78

The Visibility of the Image

Pairs of art historical principles as computer controls In characterizing the ways and means planarity and linearity correlate in images, one reaches a point that is relevant to the reciprocal logical dependency of the art historical principles as a whole. For in one key aspect, the relational logical dependencies within one form of image differ from those generated in relational logic. The reason is that aesthetic characteristics such as painterly, multiple, and so on can have visible gradations. Qualities such as transitivity and reflexivity, on the other hand, are either there or not; there are no gradations. In tracing the formal logical-aesthetic dependencies between various relational qualities in an image, the dependencies carry only imaginatively idealized, extreme values: it is in fact impossible for an extremely painterly representation to be a multiple representation, and impossible for an extremely clear representation to be a painterly one. But it is entirely possible for an image that is painterly to some extent to still clearly show multiplicity – Renoir’s images are exemplary in this respect. This dispels the worry that if the principles on one side determine the other principles on the same side, there would be just two types of image. When the relational features of the pictorial parts do not lend themselves to extreme values, a space of in-between, of play opens, which permits infinitely many forms of images. If this were not the case, the differentiated combinations of relational qualities that the art historical principles describe could not exist. Furthermore, a change in one relational quality would necessarily change every other relational quality in equal measure – as if transmitted through a gear mechanism. But in their middle values, the reciprocal dependencies of the aesthetic relational qualities are not so strict, as can readily be seen with computer-assisted image processing. The art historical principles are an answer to the question: how can the form of an image be changed if the reference is supposed to remain unchanged? Computer-assisted image processing asks the same question once again. For here the logical dependencies Wölfflin described in an image return in the form of controls. ‘How can the form of an image be changed?’ becomes a question whose answer is expressed as a control. Even a normal television has a control with which just one quality of the immanent relations in the image can be gradually changed: the contrast control. When the image processing is computer-assisted, it becomes possible to manipulate every surface quality of the image with a control. The computer transforms specifically the infrastructure of the image, the very aspect of the image Wölfflin’s art historical principles describe. In computer-assisted image

The Logic of Ways of Seeing

79

processing, the spectrum defined by any one art historical conceptual pair can be paced off with no gradations by moving a control. In a sense, Wölfflin’s theory can even handle the so-called morphing on the screen, something he himself could not yet have even considered: One can feed the image by Turner and the one by Hergé into the computer and give it a command to calculate an indeterminately long series of images that transform these two styles into one other. The correlation between the art historical principles and digital imaging becomes still more fundamental when we consider that two modes are generally recognized in computer-generated images – that is, those that are not only manipulated, but actually produced in the computer: so-called raster graphics and so-called vector graphics. Before a mark can be made on a screen, the user must decide which mode he will use for the drawing. This decision is unavoidable. The thesis of formal aesthetics, that the choice of a pictorial language precedes, in a logical sense, each representational process, appears in digital image processing as an option of painterly or linear that really does precede the process of representation: The raster uses the painterly and the vector image the linear as pictorial language. So it is not surprising that users’ manuals for computer drawing programmes have returned to precisely those comparisons of images that are familiar from the texts of formal aesthetics. The manual for the programme Adobe Illustrator 6.0, for example, compares a bicycle in the painterly pixel mode with one in a linear vector mode (see Figure 3) – just as Wölfflin compares nudes by Dürer and Rembrandt. In didactic hindsight, the example from the manual actually goes beyond Wölfflin’s comparisons in Principles of Art History. The goal Wölfflin pursues with his theory alone, of directing the attention of the formal aesthetician to the immanent relations in the image, is pursued visually as well in the users’ manual. Using two levels of enlargement of a selected detail, it directs attention to the exact point where the formal differences between the images arise:  namely the transitions. Such an image would need no changes to satisfy Wölfflin’s Principles of Art History; here, too, the principles would fulfil the purpose for which they were made, namely to facilitate access to the formal observation of images by showing, exactly, what formal aesthetics is observing in the image. But before we push the parallels too far, we must also note that Wölfflin did not have the images he compared and put under the magnifier of relational analysis specially prepared, although it would have been no problem to have suitable illustrations made. But this is exactly what is crucial about Wölfflin’s comparisons: he demonstrates them on works of visual art. In this way, the works in particular and art in general acquire an epistemological function. Because Wölfflin,

80

The Visibility of the Image

with his many famous confrontations between Renaissance and Baroque images, exposed a dimension in works of art that today, with computer-generated images, has become a matter of setting the controls, one can see in retrospect the purpose formal art theory and visual art served in the development of new pictorial forms. A pictorial understanding was worked out which, in an elementary sense, prepared the way for digital image processing. The quintessence of Wölfflin’s theory is that art shows and formal aesthetics thinks the possibilities an image has for depicting an object. Since digital image processing sets out to be a universal medium, offering all representational possibilities as available options, one can say that knowing the possibilities for representation is a logical prerequisite for the conception of digital image processing. Only someone familiar with the possible ways images can show things could design a programme that offers these representational possibilities. This is the reason visual art and formal aesthetics appear, from a contemporary point of view, to lay groundwork that make the subsequent development of digital computer graphics conceivable. Building on the basic difference between the raster- and vector modes, the relational logical aspects of an image that Wölfflin grasped with his other principles can also be adjusted using supplementary controls. The level of openness and gradations of depth can be changed for an individual image in any pictorial language. It is even possible to create an image, in whatever pictorial mode one chooses, that approaches the style of an image that would, from a relational logical standpoint, be closer to the opposite mode. For in each mode, the transition from one pictorial part to another can be marked with a line, but can also dispense with line altogether, or can be softened into continuity. The contrast can be heightened in such a way as to produce two visible parts from a unity; it can also be reduced to the point where two parts blend into one form. In computerassisted image processing on a monitor, that which form compounds into a unity in an image is dynamic. Any point in the object to be depicted can furnish grounds for a visible differentiation in the form of a transition, and conversely, every differentiation in a form can be suppressed. Internal differentiations on a surface can be gradually made less or more visible. So making non-equivalent things equivalent and making differentiations in identical things becomes of question of adjustment [Einstellung] not – as Nietzsche would have it – in the attitude of a person, but in the setting of a control. Depending on the Einstellung, the tectonic structure of an image can be systematized or dispersed. For example if a face is represented on the monitor, the fine asymmetries found in any face can be gradually removed or enhanced. And the image continues to be a recognizable representation of one and the same

The Logic of Ways of Seeing

81

person. Depending on the setting of a control, there will be a higher or lower incidence of exact symmetries and relations between forms that disclose geometric figures, for example squares, triangles or circles. The same manoeuvrable pictorial dynamics apply to the gradation of parts in space: the representation of an object on the computer screen permits itself to be shunted from planar to recessional ordering. If the control is no longer operating on the pictorial form as a whole, the pictorial possibilities become absolutely unlimited. Any details of the image may be arbitrarily defined as unities, whose relational structures can then be manipulated separately – each with separate controls as the need arises. In this way, an object can, according to its position in space, take on, say, different transitions, degrees of clarity and internal differentiations. It is not unusual for things in the background to be depicted in a more painterly way than things in the foreground. But this is only one possible way in which the manner of manipulation can change according to position. The image can be divided into infinitely many sections, all independently transformable. This brings us to the special kind of logical dependency in the relational qualities of images as such. Merely adjusting the contrast control produces a change in multiplicity and unity. High contrast renders fine internal differentiations invisible, that is, we get many surfaces that are in themselves monochrome. But if the contrast control is at zero, it is logically impossible for any multiplicity to be visible at all, because no differentiating contrast is given. The logical impossibility of uniting extreme multiplicity with extremely low contrast appears on the computer screen in the form of a pictorial disruption. Controls set at opposite extremes produce signal noise. But as long as the controls are set at middle values, there is unlimited scope for play with pictorial form. A change in one aesthetic relational quality does not correspond to a proportional change in the others. One control is not directly linked to the effects of the others. Rather the other qualities adjust – belatedly, so to speak – only in extreme changes. This gives rise once again to indeterminacies within the reciprocal dependencies of relational qualities in pictorial form. This means that although combinations of relational qualities are logically determined at their extremes, there is a possibility of intentional choice of at middle values. Even if a particular mode has been selected, the way that mode is used makes it possible to interpret the basic decision in many ways. So images that are comparable with respect to their transitions may still vary in terms of being closed and open. The relational logic of pictorial form is a logic of limit values for a free space, and as such typical for logics of the indeterminate. What is indeterminate in pictorial form cannot and should not be completely carried over into the determinate. This also holds

82

The Visibility of the Image

for the immanent dependencies in the infrastructure. In every pictorial form there is a logically indeterminate remainder, even with respect to the constellation of its various relational characteristics. Within this field of play with middle values, there are aesthetic differences in the effects produced depending on which control one is using. It shows that in the middle range, the controls do not assert themselves so rigorously, that changes made by one control have the same effect as those made by another. The changes only ‘cut’ later. This is the logical space of play that supports the stylistic plurality of pictorial representation.

Principles of colour relations: Colour contrast – colour convergence If one thing stands out about Wölfflin’s aesthetics – and it becomes especially clear in the context of controls – it is that the art historical principles are not used to investigate the colour of an aesthetic object.* This is in fact more than a little surprising, since colour is widely understood to be an essential formal attribute. In everyday language, at least, the difference between an image painted in gaudy colours or in subdued pastel tones would be viewed as a formal one. One and the same object can, in fact, be visually depicted in one and the same perspective with markedly different colouration. This supports the contention that with colour, we are dealing a formal aspect, and not with the content of the image. Rococo and Baroque images can sometimes be distinguished only on the basis of their colour. So there is a question about why colour was bracketed out of the relational logical system of Wölfflin’s art historical principles. The answer to this question is as simple as it is telling. For Wölfflin, colour is not a formal quality of an image. It is not for technical reasons alone that the visual examples in Principles of Art History are reproduced in black and white. Colour is unimportant as a logical consequence of Wölfflin’s concept of form. Wöllflin’s understanding of form is that of Herbartianism; for him, form is the same as relation. For Wölfflin, as for Herbart and Zimmermann, formal qualities are exclusively characteristics of the infrastructure. The consequence is that a formal quality can be described only using relational concepts. A monovalent predicate is not, from a Herbartian standpoint, concerned with anything formal at all. The predicate ‘have-a-colour’ is a monovalent predicate. Having a colour

* Even the art historian and colour theorist Erwin Strauss, who studied under Wölfflin, objected that in implicit in Wölfflin’s aesthetics is a dubious proposal not to talk about colour. He reports this from a conversation: ‘Wölfflin thinks that it is beyond the competence of an art historian to speak of colour’ (tr) (Koloritgeschichtliche Untersuchungen zur Malerei seit Giotto und andere Studien [Investigations in the History of Atmosphere in Painting since Giotto and Other Studies], p. 9).

The Logic of Ways of Seeing

83

is not a quality of a relation, but at most a quality of the relata in a relation. It follows, then, that Wölfflin did not pursue colour in his art historical principles, for the principles were meant exclusively for the understanding of characteristics of immanent pictorial relations. The colours of the ‘patches’ that appear in such immanent relationships on a pictorial surface are inconsequential for the aesthetic quality of this relationship: ‘And here it is of no consequence whether these patches speak as color or as areas of light and dark’ (p. 100). We must interpret this to mean that for Wölfflin, colour does not take part in way the form is made, but rather fills the form in, in an aesthetically unimportant way. Colour is the antithesis of form; colour belongs to the mimetic content of an image. That is, the particular colour in which something is reproduced is not determined by the pictorial language, but by the object depicted. Even if it seems far-fetched at first glance, Wölfflin’s rejection of colour as an aspect of form is based on an impressionistic understanding of colour after all. Impressionism had a well-founded theory of colour at its disposal, as Max Imdahl showed in his pertinent study Farbe [Colour] of 1987. Its key feature is the ‘de-conceptualization of vision, which itself rest on an absolutization of colour vision’ (tr) (p. 26). The impressionist image appears as a liberation from the logic of the image. The purely painterly representation is not meant to be a way of representing, but to free the image from any way of representing in pursuit of an immediate vision of things, with no conceptual preparation, no calculation. Impressionism is defined by the belief that there is  – as the art theorist John Ruskin had claimed – an ‘innocent eye’ and that the task of painting comprises a ‘vision that sees colour alone’ (ibid., p. 24). Max Raphael (1889–1952), too, the philosopher of art so critical to these frameworks, confirms these views of impressionism with his study Von Monet zu Picasso [From Monet to Picasso] of 1913:  ‘Everything that was scaffolding and as such a transmitter of intellectual stimulus was taboo; one stuck with the accidental’ (tr) (p. 98). But art historical principles are meant to describe and conceptually grasp exactly this ‘scaffolding’ of pictorial depiction, an expression for the intellectual prerequisites of pictorial depiction. So this makes it clear: With his principles, Wölfflin addressed those qualities of the image that the Impressionists were trying to overcome by making an image from colour alone, without form. Despite all the differences in the implications of the pictorial concepts, there is still a common understanding of colour in the background. For Wölfflin and for the theory of Impressionism, colour – as Raphael said – is something ‘accidental’. The difference is that Wölfflin is trying to purge the image of accidents by means

84

The Visibility of the Image

of the principles, and the Impressionists, conversely, are trying, in their works, to reduce the image to the purely accidental and ephemeral. But as we can quickly confirm, the opposition is asymmetrical. With his theory, Wölfflin was claiming to be able to describe the language of any image, including that of an Impressionist image. From the standpoint of the theory of art historical principles, the theoretical claims implicit in Impressionism appear to have failed.* It is impossible to make an image that escapes pictorial logic. Impressionist painting holds tight. In its works, it remains fixed in a pictorial understanding according to which an image is supposed to interpret the appearance of visible reality. The representation occurs in a pictorial language that itself in turn becomes the real purpose of the representation. It is painterly language that Impressionists use, and expose. But the crucial thing is painterliness is an art language that can be realized independently of any particular kind of colour. ‘Painterly and colorful are two quite different things’, Wölfflin insists (Principles, p. 132). This is the reason the painterly image form is not, for him, the liberation of the image from all pictorial language, but rather the realization of an interpretation of visible reality. Still one wonders whether the view that prevailed in the second half of the nineteenth century, that colour was the opposite of form, is tenable.11 One of the notable things about Wölfflin is that he undogmatically points out matters that tend to refute his own position. The next part of the quotation makes this clear: ‘Painterly and coloured are two completely different things, but there is painterly and non-painterly colour.’ Apparently Wölfflin sees that the colour in an image, too, determines what language the image speaks; and in fact colour is never completely neutral in terms of structure. The colour of the relata among transitions, too, determines the aesthetic quality of a transition. Colour is a factor that affects the image structurally. In this respect, there was a basic development in the way colour was understood after Wölfflin, which Heinz Paetzold clarified in the following way: ‘Colour should not be considered something self-contained, but always a relational phenomenon’ (tr).12 So a painterly transitional quality is determined not only by the breadth of the segments that flow continuously together, that lie between the relata of the transition, but also by the colour tonality of the relata.

* This theoretical failure is not necessarily significant for the practice of art. Imdahl rightly points out that the belief in an innocent eye can still define the self-understanding of a direction in painting, even when, as we now know, that it is, as E. H. Gombrich says, a pure myth. We must in general take note: However obsolete a theory may be from a philosophical perspective, it can nevertheless facilitate noteworthy works of art.

The Logic of Ways of Seeing

85

For example it is considerably easier to see a continuous transition between colours that are not complementary than to see one between colours that are. Complementary colours cannot flow together in terms of colour at all, because they are defined exactly as colours between which there is no coloured, only a grey colour transition. The linearity of even a sharp, discrete juxtaposition of surfaces can be suppressed or heighted through colour contrasts. Colour contrast is a relational quality determined by colour.* ‘Having a complementary colour’, for example, is a divalent predicate for a colour contrast, for a colour is a complementary colour only for another colour. So this predicate does have the aesthetic features of a visible relation, something formal, we could also say in the Herbartian sense. This predicate applies to structural characteristics and not to the way the form is filled in. If colour contrasts really share responsibility for the quality of immanent pictorial relations, the question arises, one that Wölfflin could only touch upon, of whether colour should not be among the principles after all. Here again Wölfflin indicates a direction he did not follow: ‘Even the coloration of the world itself is not fixed; it can be interpreted one way or another’ (Principles, p. 135). The colour used in an image is not completely determined by the object depicted; here, too, there is an indeterminacy that a Kunstwollen can engage. So it always comes down to a decision about the light in which to reproduce the colour of an object. Whether a shadow is permitted to change the local colour or just to make it darker is a question that can be resolved only by choice. In processes of depicting, there are ways of seeing the colour of an object. The colour of a given formal element in an image can be interpreted. Just as the qualities of transition, the unity, the spatiality, the coherence and clarity can be transformed detached from a referent object that is unchanged, Wölfflin also sees that ‘as with line . . . color here also takes an a life detached from its objects’ (ibid., p. 135). If this emancipation of colour is given, and if Kunstwollen determines colour, it seems that looking for a conceptual pair for colour would be worth the effort after all. Here, again, it is helpful to refer to computer-assisted image processing. The comparison between art historical principles and controls for computer-assisted image processing can be turned the other way: starting from Wölfflin, one can recognize in the monitor controls a possible way of technically transposing his * The most important colour contrasts are:1. the so-called polar contrast between all primary colours (red:  blue, blue:  yellow, yellow:  red), 2.  the so-called soft contrast between all secondary colours (orange: green, green: violet, violet: orange) and 3. The so-called complementary contrast between a primary colour and one particular secondary colour – namely the one at the opposite point on the colour wheel (red: green, blue: orange, yellow: violet). Cf. H. Küppers, Die Logik der Farbe [The Logic of Colour], and E. Marx, Die Farbkontraste [Colour Contrasts].

86

The Visibility of the Image

pairs of principles. But is it also possible to start from thinkable controls, and then ask whether they correspond to any pair of principles. The first control that comes to mind in this context is the colour control. Yet the colour control does not change the structure of an image, at least not the form as it appears on television monitors. It is easy to imagine a slightly modified colour control, however, that would change the colour of an image relationally. This would be the case for a control for colour contrast. Such a control would, according to the setting, produce a convergence of the colour tones at one extreme, and a contrast in the colour tones at the other extreme.13 The image is transformed so that identical colour tones in various parts of the image would be changed in different ways, so that from a relational standpoint, the same change for the entire image would produce more or less colour contrast. The criterion that controls the way the colour is changed in a given place would not, then, be the colour at that place, as it is for the colour control in a television. There the change is determined by the information in one specific place. The criterion for change in colour contrast is one element’s relationship to its surroundings. So depending on the way the control is set, the computer must look for a way the colour relationships between the relata can be changed so as to heighten the colour contrast or make the colours converge. The more extreme the setting, the more potential solutions there will be that ignore local colour completely. The lower the colour contrast realized in the image, the more painterly it will be; complete convergence, however, brings a monochrome destruction of the image. Another pair of conceptual principles can be drawn from the extreme positions of the colour contrast control: colour contrast versus colour convergence.

3.2 Formal and transcendental aesthetics Preliminary remarks In order to pursue the philosophy of art historical principles further, we need to examine Wölfflin’s relationship to Kant’s philosophy. The concern is not only to note the systematic achievements of formal aesthetics. Historically, too, the decisive next step in the development of formal aesthetics occurs in a discussion of the theory Kant formulated. Wölfflin considers his own relational logic of the image to be a supplement to Kant. Still, and this may seem surprising at first glance, the issues were not debated in reference to Kant’s aesthetic as such, to

The Logic of Ways of Seeing

87

Critique of the Power of Judgement of 1790, but rather referred to Kant’s epistemology in the Critique of Pure Reason of 1781 (CPR). It is typical of aestheticians who consider themselves philosophers of the aesthetic object to turn to Kant’s theoretical philosophy. For an aesthetics oriented towards works, which includes formal aesthetics, the analysis of aesthetic judgement Kant provided offers no points of access; the subject matter is too diverse: one line of thought concerns itself with objects, another with validity claims for judgements of taste – there is no overlap. But as soon as Kant’s epistemology is taken into account, the situation changes. The principles can be understood as supplementing particularly the ‘transcendental aesthetics’ – Kant’s first lesson in the Critique of Pure Reason.

The identity of representational forms and forms of intuition Wölfflin’s neo-Kantian thesis goes: ‘One can treat them [the art historical principles] as forms of representation or as forms of perception [which can be called forms of intuition or Anschauungsform too]: nature is seen in these forms and it is in these forms that art represents its content’ (p. 98). With this claim, Wölfflin fundamentally extends the scope of formal aesthetics. From the visible forms in which images depict an object, that is, representational forms as such, Wölfflin draws conclusions about the invisible forms in which human beings see reality, that is, in which they see. In this respect Wölfflin is clear: for him, Velásquez did not simply represent the world in a painterly way: ‘but Velásquez saw them in such a painterly way’ (p. 108). That is to say that in his paintings, Velázquez formulated a statement about his own ways and means of seeing: ‘Velasquez had such an eye, one attuned to appearance’ (p. 127). With Wölfflin, the issues in formal aesthetics become more complex. He proposes an interrelationship between perception and representation, and so ushers in a new phase in the history of formal aesthetics. Its basic idea goes: The way a human being sees things, his perception of the visible world is, like a pictorial representation, a medium that models the visibility of something – but with the difference, that pictorial representation is a visible medium and perception an invisible medium. What in perception becomes visible invisibly, in consciousness, occurs visibly in pictorial representation, made visible on the pictorial surface. The externally visible representation in a material picture therefore has a kind of visibility advantage over perception, which is an immaterial representation in consciousness; the picture has a double visibility: And Wölfflin uses this very visibility advantage methodologically to investigate perception. He assumes one typically phenomenological idea. ‘The mystery of visibility’, Bernard

88

The Visibility of the Image

Waldenfels writes, can in the end only be researched ‘because the process that makes something visible is itself generated from the visible, and because the image in which something becomes visible itself steps into the visible’ (tr).14 This is exactly the reason Wölfflin transfers the relational logic of pictorial representational methods over to perception, identifying forms of representation with forms of intuition. The claim of his logic becomes more comprehensive; it is a logic of seeing, not only of painting. In this way, the concept of representational form or pictorial form takes on a new dimension. It refers not only to possibilities for material depiction, but to ways of seeing as such, which for Wölfflin means ‘a specific conception of visibility’ (p. 134). Comparisons between image and eye are usually regarded with scepticism today. But before we criticize Wölfflin, we must see exactly what he was trying to do. For he was not contending that human perceptions were images at all; of course it is completely absurd for an eidolon to appear via perception in consciousness, as Leucippus, Democritus and Epicurus imagined it in antique philosophy. Yet the substantive incomparability between material images and perceptions should not lead us to overlook the benefits of a structural comparison. For in light of the invisibility of the perceptual process of becoming visible, the visible image offers the only possible way of gaining insight into the medially determined structures of perception. Even before knowing the details of Wölfflin’s reflections, it has to be clear that this is not about a material interpretation of perception as ‘images in the head’, but concerns contemporary thinking about how to make methodological use of the ‘relation between becoming visible in perception and making visible in visual art’ (tr).15 The structural laws of making something visible on the pictorial surface are used to get a look at the invisible organization of a perceptual process. This is a turning point in the history of formal aesthetics. If formal aesthetics before Wölfflin was simply the observation of works, he did not abandon the effort; rather he made it serve a purpose: The relational observation of the work is associated with goals that had been foreign to formal aesthetics until then. One can also say: art is treated as a mode of episteme, for a relational logic of perception is to be derived from the relational logic of the image. Wölfflin broadened the understanding of ‘aesthetic’ in the formal aesthetic movement to the meaning one associates with the original Greek concept of aesthesis. As paradoxical as it may seem at first glance, formal aesthetics is a theory of perception for Wölfflin, despite its engagement with works of art. This is what is so particularly attractive about his aesthetic understanding. Wölfflin identified the theory of art with the theory of perception  – that is, aesthetics with

The Logic of Ways of Seeing

89

aisthetic  – by proposing art as a means of studying the structures of perception. One can say: Wölfflin understands aisthetics as the task of aesthetics. Very early on he gives a ground-breaking response to an issue that should, according to Heinz Paetzold, be declared the central question of an Ästhetik der neueren Moderne [Aesthetics of Recent Modernity]: ‘How can a person think methodically about a theory of the senses enmeshed with aesthetics?’ (tr) (p. 20). It is a late confirmation of formal aesthetics to have its key idea defended afresh today: ‘The arts show what it means to have experiences in the medium of the senses’ (tr) (ibid).*

The relational structure of perception Wölfflin achieves this objective of expanding the formal aesthetics of works into a theory of perception by orienting himself to both the content and the terminology of Kant’s transcendental aesthetics. With this theory Kant, too, outlines a theory of perception in the original sense of aeisthetics. He leaves no doubt about this: ‘I call a science of all principles of apriori sensibility the transcendental aesthetic’ (CPR, p. 173). The basic idea of transcendental aesthetics is that perception and passive mirroring should be recognized as two phenomena that are incomparable in principle. Kant categorically excludes copy theory of any sort from perception. Observations of perception are determined by principles that are established not through a visible object, but rather through the * The decisive point in Wölfflin’s thinking, then, is not about erasing the difference between the concepts ‘aesthetic’ and ‘aisthetic’ or even saying that the philosophical disciplines aesthetics and aisthetics cannot be distinguished. Here there is a relatively simple difference: Aisthetics has nothing whatever to do with human perception; it is a theory of the senses. Aesthetics, on the other hand, studies just those phenomena that are related to art issues or to questions of beauty. So aesthetics is not necessarily directly concerned with art at all, although in aesthetic issues there is always a connection to question of art. (On the conceptual difference between ‘aesthetics’ and ‘aisthetics’ see M. Seel, ‘Ästhetik und Aisthetik’ [Aesthetics and Aisthetics]) But that which can be clearly distinguished in conceptual terms can be objectively bound together – one such relationship is familiar, for example, from the disciplines of physiology and psychology. So aesthetics is concerned with, among other things, so-called aesthetic perception, that is, the special perception of special things such as works of art or the beauties of nature. To this extent, aesthetics is sometimes a branch of aisthetics; there are many fluid transitions between aesthetic and aisthetic issues. (On the intertwining of aesthetic and aesthetic inquiries see W. Welsch, ‘Erweiterungen der Ästhetik’ [Extensions of Aesthetics]). It is therefore appropriate to redouble precautions in using the terms ‘aesthetic’ and ‘aisthetic’: On the one hand, the traditional conceptual difference between ‘aesthetic’ and ‘aisthetic’ should not be lost, on the other hand this conceptual differentiation between two disciplines should not cause us to overlook the objective penetration of issues of perception into problems in representation and vice versa – as we conceptually distinguish between the disciplines of physiology and psychology, yet still can see how their subject matter is linked. It is pointless to try to decide whether the investigation of the interdependence of perception and art to be a topic in aesthetics or in aisthetics. Discussion of this matter could be advanced considerably by suppressing the use of the concept of aesthetics and, in those places where it is meant, speaking instead of the ‘theory of the senses’ or ‘the theory of art’ respectively.

90

The Visibility of the Image

forms of intuition themselves. In Kant, it goes:  ‘The undetermined object of an empirical observation is called an appearance. I call that in the appearance which corresponds to sensation its matter, but that which allows the manifold of appearance to be ordered in certain relations I call the form of appearance. Since that within which the sensations can alone be ordered and placed in a certain form cannot itself be in turn a sensation, the matter of all appearance is only given to us a posteriori, but its form must all lie ready for it in the mind a priori, and can therefore be considered separately from all sensation’ (ibid., B34, pp. 172–173). With the concept of the form of intuition, then, Wölfflin is reaching back to the central term of Kant’s transcendental aesthetics, and he allies himself with Kant’s basic thinking in terms of content as well: ‘visual perception is not a mirror’ (p.  305). The inevitable phenomenality of the world is borne out in such statements  – Wölfflin puts ‘the world’ in quotation marks for a reason (Principles, p. 319). For he agrees with Kant that reality cannot be grasped as it actually is through perception, but only in forms that come from the subject. Reality as one massive static pole, to which we refer by way of perception or pictorial representation, evades visibility because even in perception – before there has even been any conceptual interpretation – it is reasonable to make a distinction between the way something looks and the way it is, the appearance and the thing in itself. The external world, which resists and even obstructs actions, is accessible to visual perception only in a mediated, which is to say a medial way. Human sensibility is not in a position to overcome the phenomenality of reality and arrive at the thing in itself. The aesthetic writing of Konrad Fiedler, in particular, set these ideas of Kant’s at the centre of a neo-Kantian aesthetic, and in this respect were surely part of Wölfflin’s intellectual background,16 as we can see immediately from the following quotation: ‘The decisive turning point for the mind in search of knowledge comes at that moment when facts, apparently endowed with perfect reality, reveal themselves in deep reflection to be deceptive appearances, where one sees that the human capacity for insight is not confronted by a completely detached external world, like a mirror with respect to the object whose image appears in it, but rather that the so-called the external world is the forever changing, constantly renewing result of an intellectual process’ (tr).17 In short, because generating perceptions is a hidden formative activity, Kant considers it necessary, as Wölfflin does, to specify forms of intuition. For, as Wölfflin writes, with reference to Kant, ‘the observation of nature remains an empty concept if one is unaware of the forms through which that observation is made’ (Principles, p. 309f.).

The Logic of Ways of Seeing

91

There is still more common ground with respect to understandings of the form of intuition. Neither Kant nor Wölfflin understands these forms that organize and facilitate perception as specific figures; nor are the forms empty vessels into which one tosses the stuff of sensation, as it were, thereby giving it a shape. When Kant speaks of the ‘form of intuition’ (CPR, B38, p. 174), he, like the formal aestheticians of Herbartianism, means only relational conjunctions, organizational structures.18 Form is just ‘that which allows the manifold of appearance to be ordered in certain relations’ (CPR, B34, p. 173). This gives us a basic idea to keep in mind, common to formal and transcendental aesthetics: as something is being seen, what is perceived takes on relations that were not initially given, but rather that arise solely from the medium of perception. This subjective process of formulation is comparable to a pair of glasses through which the world is seen – except that unlike sunglasses, these do not colour the world, but rather relationally structure it. This is what Wölfflin means when he writes ‘visibility crystallizes for the eye in certain forms’ (p. 310). Clearly these forms need to be defined; here, too, Kant is still heading in the same direction as Wölfflin.

Space as a form of intuition For Kant, there are two subjective forms of intuition:  the constraints of the senses for Kant are space and time. This is to say that everything that is given in perception is to be found in spatiotemporal relations. A visible object always has extension, and several objects have relations of being near, above, behind, or after one another. These relations are of a perceptible kind – although they tell us nothing about the content of a perception, but rather only about the ways the things in the perception appear. For Georg Mohr, the forms of intuition describe ‘constraints unique to receptivity’ (tr) in perception.19 This is a convincing interpretation in that it illuminates Kant’s medial conception of the capacity of perception. Unique conditions of receptivity are medial conditions: space and time are the inevitable media in which perceptions are made. Just as the colour of objects cannot be depicted using black and white film, so the human capacity to perceive allows for no visibility of space- or timeless things, or any fourth dimension. The medial conditions of possibility are not given in either case. Clearly space as a form of intuition has high priority in the description of the mediality of visual perception. In the Critique of Pure Reason, space is ‘the form of all appearances of outer sense, that is, the subjective condition of sensibility, under which alone outer intuition is possible for us’ (CPR, B42, p. 177). Time, however, is for Kant the form of intuition that makes shifting ideas, feelings or

92

The Visibility of the Image

representations – even representations of space possible in the empirical subject himself. But the crucial thesis with respect to space notes, ‘Space is not a empirical concept that has been drawn from outer experience’ (ibid., B38, 174). Kant makes several arguments for the a priori character of space as a form intuition.20 In fact there is supporting evidence in that we cannot imagine there being no space, although we can very easily imagine an empty space. If space were an empirical property of an object, we would be able to imaginatively abstract from this property; we could imagine an object without spatial extension. But this is exactly what is impossible in principle. For Kant, space is not something that can be abstracted from perception, and so it is not something abstracted at all: ‘We cannot, for example, imagine spatial and non-spatial elephants in the way in which we can imagine elephants which are grey and elephants which are not’ – is the way Stephen Körner explained Kant’s argument.21 There continues to be a structural affinity between formal and transcendental aesthetics on this point, for the art historical principles, too, describe the limits of abstraction in pictorial representations. The art historical principles name characteristics that are known a priori to pertain to the visible. We can no more imagine an elephant that does not contrast with its environment than we can image an elephant without space. Without immanent contrasts there can be no visibility of anything. Wölfflin emphasizes this even in his dissertation ‘Prolegomena zu einer Psychologie der Architektur’ [Prolegomena to a Psychology of Architecture]:  ‘It is a conditio sine qua non that every thing, in order to be distinct, must set boundaries with respect to its surroundings’ (tr) (p.  25).22 The same argument Kant gave for the apriority of space applies here: The quality of the transition cannot be abstracted from experience, for the form would not be visible at all without a quality from the spectrum between linear and painterly, and so the representation would not be a representation. Having a quality of transition is for Wölfflin as space and time are for Kant, ‘the a priori formal condition all appearances in general’ (CPR, B50, p. 180). When, with this in the background, we consider that Wölfflin’s formal aesthetics set out to be a supplement, a neo-Kantian variant of transcendental aesthetics, it appears logically necessary for one of the pairs of principles to recognize Kant’s forms of spatial observation. This happens in the conceptual pair ‘plane –recession’. ‘Space’ is the overarching concept for the boundaries indicated by ‘plane’ and ‘recession’. In order to perceive something, as to depict something, the parts of the visible must have spatial relationships to one another; that is, it is logically necessary for the relationships to lie somewhere between the extremes of one being plainly adjacent to the other, and one being plainly recessional,

The Logic of Ways of Seeing

93

behind the other. The notion that everything visible is spatially ordered cannot be derived from the visible, because the visible itself only becomes visible by means of these forms of intuition. So we can see that in analysing the structures of pictorial representation as it applies to the idea of space, Wölfflin takes a different route to the same conclusion reached by Kant – although at this point the structural affinity between Kant’s and Wölfflin’s theories of forms of intuition comes to an end.

3.3 The conditionality of perception Differences in interest The reasons Kant and Wölfflin have to go their separate ways becomes clear when we reflect on their intentions. The interest that attracted transcendental aesthetics to forms of perception is different from any formal aesthetics could call its own. The difference in names is suggestive in itself: a transcendental theory is per definitionem concerned with justifications, while a formal theory is concerned with descriptions. As transcendental philosophy, the Critique of Pure Reason sets out to define the conditions of possibility for scientific knowledge, and transcendental aesthetics, as part of the project, is obliged to fit within the general framework. Returning, difficulties notwithstanding, to Wölfflin’s metaphor of ‘glasses’ mentioned above, we can say that transcendental aesthetics is about a pair of glasses we wear whenever we look at the world, glasses that make mathematical insights applicable a priori to all visible objects. The strategy for proving this is based on the following idea: Mathematical laws that apply to perception in its pure form must apply equally to all things in this form  – which all perceived things are. From Kant’s transcendental claim we can conclude that his forms of intuition are general, static and ahistorical. Although Kant always took perception to be a medium that takes its formative effect in the process of making something visible, he saw no possibilities for variations in this formative process; The medium stays the same and has no individual features. For Kant, the space-glasses through which one sees the world first, cannot be removed, and second, cannot be changed. This is essential for Kant’s understanding of the forms of intuition. For him it is the only way to explain why the laws of geometry do not change. Perception is in fact made, but as far as its formal character goes, always in the same way. The result is that this formation can be taken as empirical reality, for

94

The Visibility of the Image

it can neither change nor be suspended. Kant declared it in the famous passage in Critique of Pure Reason: ‘Our expositions accordingly teach the reality [. . .] of space in light of everything that can come before us externally as an object, but at the same time the ideality of space in regard to things when they are considered in themselves through reason, i.e., without taking account of the constitution of our sensibility. We therefore assert the empirical reality of space’ (CPR, B44, p. 177). Formal aesthetics has a different understanding of forms of intuition. It considers forms of intuition to be individual, dynamic and historic. Wölfflin leaves no doubt about it: ‘In other words, the content of the world is not crystallized into some unchanging form for visual perception’ (p. 305). With this it immediately becomes clear that the efforts of transcendental philosophy to reach the ultimate ground of knowledge are alien to formal aesthetics. Rather than a particular way of seeing, its interest lies in the multiplicity of possible ways of seeing, ways in which the world can be seen; so, too, then, in perspectives that are completely unsuitable for scientific justification. For Wölfflin, the way of seeing the world that permits scientific description is one way of seeing, among many others – an important one, certainly, but still not the only one.

Living mirrors The interest in the plurality and dynamics of observational forms is especially clear at that point in Wölfflin’s argument where he explains his ‘real’ reason for resisting the idea of likening pictorial representation and a perception to a mirror. That a forming underpins the view of something in a pictorial representation and in a perception is just one thing that argues against the mirror metaphor – and actually not an important one: Mirror reflections, too, can easily present things with distorted relations. A  curved mirror, for example, distorts the infrastructure of the visible; a concave mirror makes everything appear wider than it is. In the nineteenth century, a highly polished black surface was called a black mirror or ‘Claude Lorraine’s mirror’, because it gave visible reality the kind of appearance that was familiar from the artist’s paintings.23 Mirrors can change the immanent relations of the visible in the most diverse ways; in this respect they are entirely comparable to pictorial representation.24 So there must be another argument against the mirror comparison. Wölfflin pins it down: ‘And if it has been compared to a mirror that reflects the changing picture of “the world”, then this analogy is doubly misleading: comparing the creative labor of art to a reflection is not a good analogy. If we are to permit the expression at all,

The Logic of Ways of Seeing

95

we should have to bear in mind that the structure of the mirror itself has always been subject to change’ (Principles, p. 319). Wölfflin’s idea is clear: The process of representation is comparable to mirroring only if the material that constitutes the mirror is changeable. There is an idea that Schiller formulated in his famous poem ‘The Artists’ of 1798 that needs to be taken seriously: ‘Till from the image on the water glassed / The likeness rose – and Painting grew at last! (‘The Artists’, p. 76). In fact a rigid glass mirror does suggest that the structures in which the visible takes shape are stable. A glass mirror has no dynamic representational grammar, but even in the mirror image in the waves, the order of the visible begins to shift. For Wölfflin, the really important difference between a mirror and the way human perception works is that the glass (the material of conventional mirrors) is fixed. He cannot grasp ‘representational grammar’ if he starts by thinking the mediality of perception is always the same: ‘visual perception is not a mirror that always remains the same; it is a living faculty of perception’ (Principles, p. 305). Up to the first comma, this sentence of Wölfflin’s might have been quoted above to establish parallels between Kant and Wölfflin; after the comma the differences begin. Although their basic positions leading to a rejection of the comparison between perception and a passive reflection are the same, Wölfflin’s understanding of perception still differs fundamentally from Kant’s. According to Kant, too, perception is determined by form, but it still is no ‘lively observational force’, that is, it is not the observational force of a biological entity in a dynamic interactive relationship to its environment. Here we encounter a distance between Kant and Wölfflin, the latter initiating a tradition completely foreign to Kant: The tradition that goes back to Nikolaus von Kues, of perception as a living mirror.25 The metaphor of a living mirror is used to convey the idea of the immanent dynamics of observation. The individuality of a living, embodied human being, with his own special, changeable, situation-specific characteristics, impairs ideal constructions of perceptual function, so that only distorted variants ever become real. The world is not visible to human beings in just one way that way that can further be scientifically constructed. Even Leibniz – in a letter to Nicolas François Remond – emphasized that it makes no sense to assume that all human beings have the same modalities of perception: ‘The perceptions of beings can be simultaneously distinct in regard to only a few things, after all, they are more significantly shaped by the positioning, or viewpoint, so to speak, of the mirror, so that one and the same universe is reproduced in infinitely varied ways by as many living mirrors, each depicting it in his own way’ (tr).26

96

The Visibility of the Image

This is what lies behind the neo-Kantian theory of art historical principles. It sets out to determine the logical limits of the polymorphism of visible worlds. Here, formal aesthetics is assigning value to an idea that is generally considered awkward from the standpoint of scientific theory. It is worth noting, in any case, that in his The New Organon [Novum Organum] of 1620, Francis Bacon describes scientific activity as an effort to make individual perception resemble a fixed and flat mirror. For Bacon, exact science begins with the death-knell of the living mirror: ‘The assertion that the human senses are the measure of things is false; to the contrary, all perceptions, both of sense and mind, are relative to man, not to the universe. The human understanding is like an uneven mirror receiving rays from things and merging its own nature with the nature of things, which thus distorts and corrupts it. [. . .] But as men’s minds have been occupied in so many strange ways that they have no even, polished surface available to receive the true rays of things, it is essential for us to realise that we need to find a remedy for this too. [. . .] just as an uneven mirror alters the rays of things from their proper shape and figure, so also the mind, when it is affected by things through the senses, does not faithfully preserve them, but inserts and mingles its own nature with the nature of things as it forms and devises its own notions’ (pp. 41 and 18–19). A description of the same state of affairs may be evaluated in two opposing ways. For Bacon, the biological organization of perception ‘distorts and corrupts’ ideal scientific vision. For Wölfflin, the same inevitable distortion of a single, one-to-one depiction in processes of visualization opens the possibility for art to speak of a living human being’s powers of comprehension. In this way human visual perception is freed from its passive role of delivering, neutrally at best, the mere materials for further cognitive processing. It escapes, and acquires a rationality of its own. Fiedler’s neo-Kantianism once again provides support for Wölfflin’s argument in this regard. Among the fundamental achievements of Fiedler’s aesthetic, in any case, is a description of sense perception as a spontaneous faculty, which not only passively delivers material to the understanding, but which constitutes a complete form of rational activity in itself.27 The duality of sense perception and intellectual conceptualization disappears with Fiedler, since ‘in every sensual perception there already is mental activity’ (tr).28 This ‘decisive transformation’, which Fiedler made with Kant, sustains Wölfflin’s concept of perception.29 So it follows that there are two forms of perception in Wölfflin that are presented purely as categories of understanding with Kant: unity and multiplicity. For Wölfflin, an observation without unities or multiplicities is as unimaginable as a perception without any spatial ordering of parts – the same holds for any

The Logic of Ways of Seeing

97

image. Unity does not depend on an act of conceptualization, but is achieved by sense perception itself. In these forms of intuition, Wölfflin shares the view that the founder of gestalt psychology Christian v.  Ehrenfels presented in his epochal essay ‘Über “Gestaltsqualitäten” ’ [On Qualities of Gestalt] (1890) ‘that the conception of space- and sound gestalten comes about without our involvement, without any intellectual act being specially directed toward them’ (tr) (p. 14)30 The smallest elements of perception are, accordingly, not free atoms of perception, but unities and multiplicities of unities.31 Forms of intuition are in this sense already forms of thinking; they describe the immanent rationality of an perception and confirm the gestalt psychologist Rudolf Arnheim’s succinct formulation: ‘Visual perception is visual thinking.’32

The conditions of the eye Although Wölfflin transformed two of Kant’s categories of understanding into forms of intuition, and so gave Fiedler’s ideas about the intellectual basis of all perception a solid grounding, this is still not the primary interest he was pursuing with his theory of forms of intuition. Wölfflin’s reflections partially overlap with gestalt psychology, but this common ground was not his actual intention. This rather comes into view when we notice that Wölfflin’s concept of forms of intuition consists exclusively of polar oppositions. For Wölfflin, ‘the’ form of intuition or ‘the’ form of observation do not exist, as he stated clearly – further on in the glasses-metaphor:  ‘There are no eyeglasses that work for everyone’ (Principles, p.  323). But there are limits to deformability, limits of possible orders of visible. By ordering his forms of intuition as a spectrum, Wölfflin is describing the possibilities between which every visible gestalt conceived by living human beings can oscillate. This confirms Andreas Eckl’s interpretation of formal aesthetics as well: We need to ‘understand Wölfflin’s principles as further conceptual differentiation of this ‘transcendental aesthetics’. The conditions of possibility for ‘forms of objects of the senses’ were grasped conceptually in terms of a system, and in fact in such a way that due to the possibilities of variation, the polar boundaries of the maximum perceptual variations are designated’ (tr).33 So Wölfflin was in no way trying to turn the account of possible forms of intuition into a Sisyphean task, but to rein it in through some key data, recognizable a priori. ‘The poverty of language takes its revenge here. One would need a thousand words to give every transition a name. It is always a case of relative judgments: in comparison with one style, another may be called painterly’ (p. 112).

98

The Visibility of the Image

Wölfflin’s relationship to Kant keeps becoming clearer: Their theories of forms of intuition do not stand in opposition to one another; rather Wölfflin’s more penetrating interest turned to a phenomenon of perception that had remained outside Kant’s reflections: to the unique formal conditions that spatial observation could produce in the empirical life of a person. He was concerned with possibilities of variation beyond those that had seemed invariable to Kant. The subject matter of Wölfflin’s formal aesthetics is – as he said himself – the ‘states of the eye’ (ibid., p. 98). With the concept of conditions, an aspect of a perception is being described that can change without the perception ceasing to be the perception of a particular object. And it is exactly in this unintentional respect that perceptions are at their most dynamic and individual. By now we can see that Wölfflin’s recovery of Kant’s concept of forms of intuition had a purely methodological intention, as was usually the case in neo-Kantianism. His intentions were his own, quite detached from Kant’s. It is possible to reduce the difference between the concepts of forms of intuition in Kant and Wölfflin to a formula: The conditions of Kantian forms of spatial intuition are Wölfflin’s forms of intuition. It is crucial that conditions can be of a bodily as well as mental sort. The concept of condition undermines the body-mind opposition, and it is exactly in this way that Wölfflin’s theory of forms of intuition acquires a specifically neo-Kantian perspective that was never anticipated in Kant: When we consider conditions of perception, we assume that physical and mental components participate equally in the process of perception. It goes to the heart of Wölfflinian aesthetics when Gottfried Boehm confirms:  ‘So Wölfflin tried to grasp the psycho-philological (anthropological) organization of human beings as a new a priori.’34 Conditions include passing configurations as well as long-term dispositions. Both can fundamentally affect and change the quality of a perception to the same extent. Interests, moods, emotional states, illnesses (psychological or physical), deliberate changes of mind or fixed traits of character, all contribute to a perception being not just an perception of something, but always the perception of something under the conditions of a particular moment.35 Drugs have an especially marked effect on the formal modality of perception. Aldous Huxley gave a detailed description of perception on a mescaline high in the report that has since become a classic namely The Doors of Perception of 1954. But the situation need not be extreme for a perception to take on conditions, rather a condition is always given, because there is no situation without a corresponding kind of state of mind. Visual perceptions change their internal constitution continually in their interactive play with the perceivers’ surroundings.36 We know that the world looks different in dangerous situations than it does in

The Logic of Ways of Seeing

99

moments of contemplation. Some knowledge of a thing also makes that thing look different, raising concern and lending emphasis. A connoisseur sees an object differently from a layman. The same thing holds for cultural influences.37 It has long been known in psychology and physiology that seeing involves acts of selection and preference that change according to attitude, interests and affect. By 1887, without knowing the results of modern research in perception, Fiedler had claimed, ‘Anyone who sees in perceptual representation just the intellectual mirror image of something present to the senses should be taught about the endlessly complicated psychophysical events that underpin ‘the design of a perception’ (tr).38 The formulation ‘the design of a perception’ in fact precisely defines the subject of Wölfflin’s aesthetics. Wölfflin is concerned with a logic of possibilities for giving form to perceptions, and from a contemporary perspective that means, he makes ‘the way free for the development of a medial theory of consciousness, one that measures meaning not solely with reference to objects, but also and primarily by the way they are given in conditions of consciousness’(tr).39 For Wölfflin, ‘the design of a perception’ comes about through what he metaphorically calls the ‘condition of the eye’. This closes the circle from his concept of perception to his understanding of style and image. For Wölfflin’s concept of style is itself concerned in turn with nothing other than  – Erich Rothacker saw this in his review of Principles of Art History – ‘understanding the condition of the image’ (tr) (p. 170). We can therefore say, just as the style of an image determines the condition of its pictorial surface, so does the condition of the eye inform the style of a perception. Both stylistic phenomena adhere to the same relational logic.

Interests of the philosophy of life To really get at the difference between Wölfflin’s and Kant’s theories of observational forms, we would have to say, they are dealing with different subjects. Wölfflin is concerned with an embodied subject, whose vision can never be suitably described without reference to this embodiment. It is only on the basis of this assumption that there would be any possibility of writing a history of perception, of its life and metamorphoses.40 Wölfflin has this provocative objection to Kant: ‘Seeing involves the entire person’ (tr).41 Banalities come into it as well: a transcendental subject cannot be short-sighted – a person certainly can be. A transcendental subject cannot get drunk, but forms of intuition blur for drunken human beings all the same. Wölfflin ties the idea of forms of intuition introduced by Kant to an anti-Kantian understanding of the subject. Wölfflin describes the conditions of possibility for perception by a living, embodied

100

The Visibility of the Image

human being, for whom perception depends on a unity made up of psychic and organic components in equal measure.42 The theory of forms of intuition he is developing conceives of a subject that rises above the division between body and mind. This very turning away from the purely transcendental subject can be placed in the tradition of the philosophy of life. In his On the Aesthetic Education of Man:  In a Series of Letters (1795), Friedrich Schiller was critical of Kant’s work for not having taken the inevitability of individuality in aesthetic perception into account: ‘For man is not just Person pure and simple, but Person situated in a particular Condition. Every Condition, however, every determinate existence, has its origins in time; and so man, as a phenomenal being, must also have a beginning, although the pure Intelligence within him is eternal’ (Eleventh Letter, p. 75). Judgements of this kind led to an increase in the number of thinkers to whom the transcendental subject appears as it does to Schiller: More and more often one reads – even as early as 1816 in Herbart’s A Text-Book in Psychology, for example – the claim that ‘the attention must be directed toward changing conditions’ (p. 2). Overall, the development is inversely proportional:  As the conditionality of human beings gains attention, appreciation of Kant’s transcendental philosophy steadily declines. With Schopenhauer, this tendency is so far progressed that Kant’s philosophy appears to him as a theory of ‘a winged Cherub without a body’ (p. 129).43 It is not surprising to find this cynical critique in Schopenhauer. His thinking cuts deeply into nineteenth-century intellectual history. Along with Friedrich Nietzsche, he is the central protagonist of a philosophy of life. He outlines an understanding of subjectivity best-known through its characterization in Wilhelm Dilthey’s ‘Introduction to the Human Sciences’ (1883): ‘The veins of the perceiving subject as constructed by Lock, Hume and Kant carry not real blood, but the diluted juice of reason as a mere act of thinking’ (XVIII, p. 50).* * Here we should note a typical discrepancy between two disciplines. In art history, Wölfflin is simply presented as an art historian who was among the most famous students of Dilthey’s. In ‘Reinterpreting Wölfflin’, J. Hart outlines what was in fact a systematic relationship between Wölfflin and Dilthey. In philosophy, hardly anyone notices that one of the most important art historians of the twentieth century understood himself to be a student of Dilthey’s; Wölfflin never studied art history, either; he studied philosophy. (So the situation resembles the case of Zimmermann and Riegl.) The bare facts are as follows: Wölfflin studied philosophy in Berlin with Dilthey for two semesters from 1885, and in the winter semester of 1885–1886 joined the seminar ‘Logic and Epistemology Theory’. This is where his first outlines of an aesthetic were developed and presented. Wölfflin’s doctorate was planned with Dilthey, but actually took place with Johannes Volkelt in Munich for reasons that are not entirely clear. Nor should we forget that Wölfflin was Dilthey’s colleague at the Humboldt University in Berlin from 1901 until Dilthey’s death in 1911. The monograph Heinrich Wölfflin, by M. Lurz, is helpful with details about the biography and the intellectual development in Wölfflin’s work. See also the dissertation Heinrich Wölfflin: An Intellectual Biography, in this regard especially the sections ‘Berlin and Dilthey’, pp. 73–90, and ‘Evolution of the Dissertation’, pp. 90–95.

The Logic of Ways of Seeing

101

One could almost take it for granted that from this standpoint, the special conditionality of perception would have to be identified as the topic of a modified transcendental philosophy. This is the case with Dilthey:  ‘The sensually perceptible also contains, even apart from the infinite variability of its contents, differences in the manner in which the contents are present for me.’44 These differences need to be described, and this in fact  – as Wölfflin in turn could learn from his teacher Dilthey – by means of a structural theory of ‘immanent relationships’ and ‘internal relationships’ (tr) (ibid). Since it is only the quality of an internal structure that is of interest in a formal consideration, it does not matter which causes are responsible for the differences in the structures. This is a basic idea: it is impossible to distinguish between important and unimportant factors that affect conditionality. Everything that has an influence on a condition is equally important, just because it has an influence – even if the condition is determined by someone’s culturally absolutely meaningless exhaustion, as in Ludwig Klages elaborated in ‘Vom Wesen des Rhythmus’ [On the Nature of Rhythm] of 1934. Once it has been acknowledged that there is no perception without conditions, even exhaustion must be taken into account: ‘The appearance of the table [. . .] changes constantly: it changes with the direction from which I see it, with the distance, illumination, it even changes with the conditions of my person, since I see it differently fully rested than I do at moments of disabling exhaustion. It is never exactly the same for two people, because it is unthinkable that two people would feel impressions that were identical in kind (qualitatively). [. . .] So the world of appearances is in a continual state of change and flight’ (tr) (p. 504f.). In short, the illusion of the subject as a clear mirror is foreign to both movements  – that of the philosophy of life and that of formal aesthetics. But this would not be especially noteworthy in itself if the formal aesthetics of Wölfflin were not conceived as a neo-Kantian aesthetic. In fact one can see from Wölfflin that the neo-Kantian aestheticians who attach themselves to the Critique of Pure Reason clearly distance themselves from Kant in regard to their understanding of the subject – and this from the very beginning.45 At least there are formulations that call for an aesthetic in Wölfflin’s sense even in the founding documents of neo-Kantianism, in Otto Liebmann’s (1840–1912) treatise Über den objektiven Anblick [On the Objective View] (1869): ‘Now to our problem! How do we see objects? Let us take a living, healthy human being – not a statue – as a given. Say he has opened both eyes, and it is day’ (tr) (p. 67).46 Formal aesthetics is, from a historical standpoint, a reaction and an answer to a question posed right at the beginning of neo-Kantianism: ‘How do we see objects?’ ‘We’ are not those

102

The Visibility of the Image

transcendental subjects undoubtedly meant by ‘statues’, but human beings who are alive and bound up with history: ‘The formal theory of art is the systematic effort to historicize transcendental subjectivity’ (tr).47

Aesthesiology The orientation of Wölfflin’s formal aesthetics towards the philosophy of life means that his continuing development of the theory of forms of intuition cannot be, as it is in Kant, part of a Critique of Pure Reason. If Wölfflin’s theory of forms of intuition is part of a modified transcendental philosophy, then it is also part of an ‘anthropology of the senses’ as the concept was introduced in 1923 by the neo-Kantian Helmuth Plessner (1892–1985) in ‘Die Einheit der Sinne’ [The Unity of the Senses]. Plessner’s goals correspond to Wölfflin’s, for he, too, is working out a philosophy ‘that relies on Kant, but only for its way putting questions, being opposed to Kantian philosophy in its inclinations and results’ (tr) (p. 18) He calls this philosophy ‘aesthesiology’. With the terminology, he makes a reasonable suggestion for a way the connection between logic and aesthetics sought in Herbartianism might be expressed in language. But he furthermore drew a clear picture of the way aesthesiological descriptions of perceptions would have to look: in aesthesiology, immanent structures of observation are interpreted as ‘the fusion of several kinds of perceptions and several kinds of comprehension’ (tr) (ibid., p. 162). This actually offers a possibility of visually describing the influence of conditionality on perception. To say it with Wölfflin’s glasses-metaphor: we wear not just one pair of glasses, but in fact several. Conditionality is a formation that works as if there were additional filters even before the Kantian spatial-glasses, filters that then, consolidated, determine the structures of perception. With this image of multiple glasses we gain access to an explanatory model that turns up again in various places among Wölfflin’s followers. The FinnishGerman philosopher Hermann Friedmann, acknowledged by Plessner alone in the end, but entirely forgotten today, raises the question in this context in Die Welt der Formen [The World of Forms] of 1925, ‘whether we might still discover specific a priori organized relationships in the world of sensibilities itself, to which transcendental philosophy has no far not extended’ (tr) (p.  39).48 With these additional a priori organized relationships Friedmann is thinking, in sympathy with Wölfflin, of the art historical principles. He considers ‘progress in transcendental philosophy to be possible’ (tr) (ibid., p. 40), if the art historical principles are always interpreted as the description of a ‘subform’ of the ‘main form’ space

The Logic of Ways of Seeing

103

(ibid., p. 41).* For the subforms, too, that is, the stylizations embedded in every perception, have an a priori character. But it is of a kind different from the one to which Kant laid claim. It namely concerns the fact that an immanent stylization can change, but cannot disappear. Here we can see that in formal aesthetics, the ephemeral, in its ephemerality becomes a kind of fundamentum inconcussum. Seen as a whole, the changeability of human beings, a condition of living, is an unchangeable certainty. To put it in another way, the idea goes: the subforms of perception are as inevitable as the main forms; as soon as one thing is seen next to another, this happens in an aesthetically mediated form. For Friedmann, every effort that tries to grasp the ‘main form’ space without a specific subform – on its own without conditions, so to speak – is doomed to failure. Any project of describing the main forms independently ends with ‘the main forms becoming so empty, that they finally are not forms any more’ (tr) (ibid., p. 41). In short, there is no such thing as a form of spatial perception in itself. Even a form of spatial observation appears only in particular and historical circumstances.

The emancipation of purposeless perception From the perspectives presented here, the mistrust with which transcendental aesthetics is met in formal aesthetics is understandable. From the standpoint of formal aesthetics, Kant’s theory appears to be an attempt, doomed to failure, to describe human spatial perception without describing a particular phenomenological style. All Kant himself says about the kind of infrastructure in his form of spatial intuition is, ‘All things are next to one another in space’ (CPR, B43, p. 177). That is undoubtedly correct, but also says very little, in light of the many aesthetic possibilities known from images about ways things can be near one another in space. Kant’s reflections remain unsatisfying in two respects. On the one hand there are – as Plessner says – ‘spaces in every style’ (tr),49 while on the other, Kant’s descriptions of space are hardly neutral with respect to the stylistic possibilities for things being near one another in space. A very clear and firm conception of the ‘how’ of being close to one other of is implicit in Kant. It appears obvious to Kant that things-being-near-one-another means a discrete and clear things-being-near-one-another.50 Kant’s understanding of space as a form of intuition mediates the visible as a representation in which the transitions are sharply delineated, there are many parts, and each place is clear and distinct. * The concept of ‘subform’ is in accord with ideas developed above in connection with the use of Frege’s distinction between sense and reference in images, that style can be understood as a second intensional differentiation.

104

The Visibility of the Image

Even an unclear and blurred object would appear in this form as clear and not blurred, because it could be clearly recognized as a blurred object; this is familiar from a sharply focussed photograph of a diffuse cloud. The very ambiguities that would prevent such recognition are not to be found in Kant’s forms of intuition. It resembles a system of mathematical coordinates. There is nothing about fuzzy horizons, essential for human observation; there is no sharp focus or any blurriness in the distance. The infrastructure has no weighting or particularity. Each point is of equal value in a grid structure. Had Kant wanted to represent his understanding of the form of intuition, Dürer’s images would have been helpful to him. Kant’s unannounced style of his forms of intuition is grounded in the purpose he expects perception to serve:  It must make everyday life possible, and this includes scientific investigation of the world. What Wölfflin saw applies to Kant as well: ‘The great opposition between linear and painterly styles corresponds to a fundamentally different interest in the world’ (p. 109) – and Kant’s interest is clear. He sets out to explain the calculability of the natural world and not to give a phenomenological description of an emancipated observation. This is why each point in the space of his form of perception has to be a clear point on a screen. Stefan Majetschak examines this detail in Kant closely in his essay ‘Welt als Begriff und Welt als Kunst’ [World as Concept and World as Art]. Kant’s reflections in transcendental aesthetics do not address ‘perception as perception, but arrange the given “to serve judgement” ’ (tr) (p. 279). Kant’s approach does not permit a transition from one part to another to draw from an inexact, impressionistic transitional realm, from this-as-well-as-that. Form needs to inhibit this, and it does so by means of its implicit style: ‘One who looks scientifically at a representation of perception will not reach clarity about its perceptible condition to the extent that he transforms everything into a concept, and from the point where he begins the examination, he is no longer dealing with the representation of perception, but with the concept of it’ (tr).51 Although Kant applies the concept ‘Anschauung’ to all sense perception  – hence, tactile and acoustic as well – and so gives a first impression of addressing all sense perceptions as visual perceptions, the situation is closer to the reverse. A stylistic interpretation of his understandings of perception makes it clear that Kant treats the visual world as a tactile world: ‘The activity of seeing follows a model of touching that makes use of a virtual stick’ (tr).52 Here, the tradition of Cartesianism lives on, as the French phenomenologist Maurice Merleau-Ponty came to understand in his study ‘The Eye and the Mind’ of 1961: ‘The Cartesian concept of vision is modelled after the sense of touch’ (p.  170). This is not

The Logic of Ways of Seeing

105

remarkable: For knowledge of a form that can be calculated comes only through the sense of touch.** But this technically useful way of looking at of the visible world is constructed as well.*** Obviously it is not a disadvantage from a scientific standpoint, since to decide the success of actions and techniques, one need not know whether the visible world has ever been seen by a human being as it is projected in the construction. If the world is to be calculated mathematically, it is not – nor should it be – seen bodily, but is rather constructed in a style. This constructed quality and with it the artificiality of technically serviceable vision only becomes noticeable as such when other styles of visibility, from art, assert their right to show the world. For a self-reflection on one’s own style – as Adolf Hildebrand says – ‘will never be carried out and followed through in natural science, because singling such a thing out only has meaning for artistic activity’.53 Once the immanent style of scientific vision has been reflected aesthetically, the status of the sort of undertaking Kant imagined in the Critique of Pure Reason changes, in fact in a way that Ernst Cassirer pinpointed with all the clarity one could wish in The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms [1923]: ‘Thus the critique of reason becomes the critique of culture’ (p.  80). The following idea is a cornerstone of neo-Kantianism:  Once we recognize that a scientifically useful and calculable way of seeing is the way people see under particular, certainly special, but still not immutable conditions, it becomes necessary to expand the structure of transcendental philosophy: ‘Along with the pure function of cognition we must seek to understand the function of linguistic thinking, the function of mythical and religious thinking, and the function of artistic perception, in such a way as to disclose how in all of them there is attained an entirely determinate formation, not exactly of the world, but rather making for the world, for an objective, meaningful context and an objective unity that can be apprehended as such. [. . .] As long as philosophical thought limits itself to analysis of pure cognition, the naïve-realistic view of the world cannot be wholly discredited’ (ibid., pp. 79–80). ** An idea that can in turn be found analysed with particular clarity in Konrad Fiedler: ‘The more precise we want our knowledge to be, however, the less we rely on our sense of vision, and the more we rely on the sense of touch; and when we speak of the form of an object in the truest sense, we are no longer speaking about the participation of vision at all, but rather referring to the tangible, measureable, calculable form. This becomes our standard for the accuracy of vision, and we ask ourselves whether we see the form as it behaves in tactile, graspable reality; should this be the case, we are convinced that we have an accurate and complete visual representation of the form of the object’ (tr) (‘Über den Ursprung der künstlerischen Tätigkeit’ [The Origin of Artistic Activity], p. 148. *** Hegel had already formulated this objection to Kant in the Phenomenology of Spirit, 1977 [1807]:  ‘The actual is not something spatial, as it is regarded in mathematics; with non-actual things like the objects of mathematics, neither concrete sense-intuition nor philosophy has the least concern’ (p. 26).

106

The Visibility of the Image

It is as if he had been familiar with these sentences, so definitely is Wölfflin’s formal aesthetics a continuation of formal aesthetics after the loss of scientific ordering structures’ priority – with one subtle difference: Instead of describing structures in which the world is seen to be calculated, formal aesthetics describes structures in which the world can be seen. It is interested less in realities than in possibilities: ‘Just as one can make out all kinds of words in the tolling of bells, so the visual world can be laid out in a number of different ways, and no one can say that one of them is truer than the others’ (p. 111).54 For Wölfflin as for Cassirer, modes of perception beyond pragmatic demands are of equal value in principle: ‘A purely optical perception of the world is one possibility, but nothing more’ (p. 111). If perception frees itself from all services and purposes, then the criterion for better or worse ways of seeing disappears, then the role of evaluation and use value of ways of seeing is taken over by purely formal work on its immanent logic. This freedom is not the least of what sustains art: something is shown in order to show that this, too, is a way of showing.

4

From the Way of Seeing to Visibility:  Konrad Fiedler (1841–1895)

4.1 The paradigms of formal aesthetics Preliminary remarks Formal aesthetics, and this applies to all its versions, is concerned per definitionem exclusively with the way an aesthetic object is made. This kind of aesthetic reflection can, however, have diverse motivations and be bound up with very different goals. The impulses and expectations that lead someone to contend that the content of an image is unimportant have changed several times in the history of formal aesthetics, not continuously, but in phases of shared interests and underlying perspectives. It is therefore appropriate to identify paradigms for the formal consideration of the image. The aesthetic writing of the Saxon philosopher Konrad Fiedler (1841–1895) achieves this in a way that remains exemplary today. Anyone wishing to explain the meaning of a formal pictorial observation should take his work as a guide. Fiedler differs from both the early Herbartians and the theoreticians of art historical principles in that he does not establish any concrete categories or legitimate rules of form. Fiedler’s reflections are rather at a meta-level. He wants to illuminate the basis, the limits, and perspectives of the formal approach. There is, finally, a question guiding his reflections that asserts itself even now in regard to ordinary engagement with mass media, especially television images: Why do people look at images even if their contents are considered unimportant or even banal? By stating the inquiry in this way, it becomes clear that for Fiedler, the formal observation of an aesthetic object is by no means obvious, but rather urgently needs justification. If you look at an image in order to learn something about the way an object looks, you will hardly need any further justification for such an

108

The Visibility of the Image

encounter with the image. Images long since established themselves as a medium that is usually faster and more precise than any other medium at giving information about objective matters of fact: A brief look at an image says more than a thousand words. But it is exactly this obvious use of images that formal observation disables, deliberately rendering it meaningless. So there must be some other impetus that explains how pictorial observation can elevate the infrastructure of the pictorial surface to the sole concern of an aesthetic: how can an aesthetic treat the surface of an image as an absolute, on what grounds is it permissible? At various places in his work, Fiedler discusses three possible answers to this question. By fitting these places together, we find three fundamental beliefs and two changes in belief, that is, the work undertakes two paradigm changes in the development of formal aesthetics.

From beauty to a way of seeing The first paradigm of formal aesthetic can be quickly defined. Herbart and Zimmermann turn to the surface structure of aesthetic works – as we saw here in Chapter 1 – because they believe that ‘the elements of beauty can only be found in form and relationships’ (tr).1 Fiedler formulates Zimmermann’s concerns accordingly. For him, this kind of formal aesthetic stands for a paradigm of beauty. Formal analysis serves the investigation of beauty. The immanent relations in a work are meant to support an objective concept of beauty. The content of an image may be disregarded, because it makes no difference to the beauty or ugliness of the image. This kind of formal aesthetics is often rightly considered aestheticism. The first paradigm change in the logic of formal aesthetics’ internal development – traced here in Chapters 2 and 3 – can be stated as follows: Instead of identifying form with beauty, it equates form with content; so for formal aesthetics, beautiful form turns into symbolic form. This fundamentally new orientation is described in Fiedler’s papers. In the history of formal aesthetics, form never ceases to be an absolute; all that changes is the phenomena bound up with this form-made-absolute. This is the reason Fiedler is able to simultaneously defend and criticize Zimmermann’s relational approach: The beginnings of formalism ‘seem to rest on a rather one-sided conception of aesthetic pleasure [. . .] which does not recognize that the content as well as the form has an aesthetic value [. . .] Nevertheless’, Fiedler continues, ‘one feels drawn to the formal aestheticians in one respect. [. . .] The essential artistic value of the form consists of the insight conveyed and brought to expression through the form. The real artistic content of the artwork therefore lies in the form’ (tr) (ibid., pp. 22 and 23).

From the Way of Seeing to Visibility

109

To regard the form as the actual content – that is the central theme of Fiedler’s first book, On Judging Works of Art, which appeared in 1876. In this essay he develops a typical neo-Kantian perspective for formal aesthetics: ‘In a work of art the Gestalt-forming activity finds its way to an externalized completion. The substance of such a work is nothing else than the Gestalt-formation itself ’ (p.  56). Later philosophers of art historical principles are merely fleshing this idea out in the end. They are representing the paradigms of symbolic form that Fiedler introduced to formal aesthetics. Art historical principles are not grounded in the same way, but are grounded to the same extent on an understanding of symbolic form.2 For Riegl, form is by no means simply aesthetic surface decoration that may be beautiful or ugly, but rather the symbolic expression of a unique and historical Kunstwollen.3 This was the case for Wölfflin as well: Form as such is a depiction of forms of intuition and modalities of perception. Clearly Riegl and Wölfflin differ in regard to their views of what pictorial form as form exemplifies – Wölfflin replaces Kunstwollen with forms of intuition; yet this difference plays itself out on shared ground, for formal aesthetics does not provide grounds for opposing to semiotic understanding of the image in either case. Emil Utitz confirmed this as well in an essay of 1929 that remains pivotal today, ‘Über Grundbegriffe der Kunstwissenschaft’ [On the Principles of Art History]: The principles pursue a ‘systematic unification of meaning and form. [. . .] art history becomes intellectual history, without abandoning the analysis of form in any way; for this intellectuality is revealed only in forms’ (tr) (p. 42f.).4 Wölfflin’s formal analyses of art typify and represent the paradigm of symbolic form to the extent that they provide an extremely detailed elaboration of neo-Kantian perspectivist thought that can hardly be found anywhere else. His aesthetic seems to make an idea described by Fiedler concrete, to interpret pictorial form as a cognitive instrument. The content of symbolic form is clear to Wölfflin: perspectives and viewpoints; he himself speak in the terminology of the philosophy of life, of the ‘conditions of the eye’. In this way Utitz’s vague concept of ‘intellectuality’ is made concrete and specific in the neo-Kantian sense. This is just one possibility, however. There is undoubtedly a plethora of non-objective data that could be represented in the form of an image. The expression of moods, feelings and emotions occurs largely in the form of images. But Wölfflin shaped the paradigm of symbolic form exclusively into a theory of ways of seeing. The presupposition of his formal aesthetic states that the image refers, by means of its pictorial form, to modalities of perception. The paradigm of symbolic form, too, is a paradigm of a way of seeing.

110

The Visibility of the Image

With the shift from a paradigm of beauty to a paradigm of a way of seeing, fine art becomes cognitive art, and formal aesthetics enters into the tradition of the founder of aesthetics Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten.5 This was the way to refute the widespread view that formal consideration of an image can deliver no recognition of content beyond what is immanent in the image. Wölfflin’s aesthetic yields exemplary analyses of solely the form of work, but nevertheless opens a perspective beyond what is strictly immanent in the work, for form as form contains – as Max Bense would put it – ‘Formmitteilung’ [communication through form] (tr).6 In the opposition frequently constructed between formal and semiotic understandings of the image, especially in recent language analytic philosophy, no account is taken of a level of meaning available to the image which coincides with the image’s form. For the paradigm of symbolic form, it is necessary to describe, in addition to the objective meaning, another meaning that one can only get by looking at the image formally. It takes just one example to show that the paradigm of a way of seeing is taken for granted in viewing images more often than one would immediately assume. That form becomes content, that an image shows how it shows, is by no means a trait specific to works of art.

The depiction of a way of seeing In a magazine article about the dangers of visual impairment in road traffic, there is an illustration by Reinhard Schmid that is reproduced in this book as Figure 4. We are dealing with an image of great formal complexity. In the foreground, spanning the whole horizontal axis, is a special pair of glasses that opticians use for refractions, that is, to determine the degree of short- or far-sightedness. In the upper right we see a hand drawing a glass lens out these glasses’ special holder. Behind the glasses we see a street scene with two rows of cars seen from the back. What is significant about this image is not the depicted objects at all; these are banal. The photograph is notable because it is a good example of a type of image in which however completely we can conceptually grasp and count up the depicted things, we still cannot grasp the image’s actual content. For the intended meaning of this illustration apparently lies at a non-objective level. The image is not primarily about the depiction of objects, but about the depiction of two different ways of seeing: About the way a near-sighted person sees things without glasses on the one hand, and about the way he sees them with glasses on the other. The image is about the physiologically conditioned modalities of visual perception. The whole street scene is reproduced in a fuzziness that corresponds to a near-sighted person’s vision. The only clear, ‘normal’ view comes

From the Way of Seeing to Visibility

111

through the left lens of the glasses. The glasses’ frame itself is reproduced in high definition as well, for it is located so far in the foreground that the distortions of near-sightedness are not yet noticeable. This image is helpful for the present inquiry inasmuch as we can readily see from it how an image can be a sign with two fundamentally different meanings: In different ways, but to the same extent, the photograph refers to automobiles and to one way of seeing, namely near-sightedness. So we can say that the image has both an objective and a non-objective meaning: It depicts things, on the one hand, and near-sighted vision on the other. The two meanings of an image, the objective one and the non-objective one, may be complementary, but are logically completely independent of one another. In this example, there is an associative relationship: the objective refraction glasses are appropriate for the visual fault of near-sightedness. But in principle, a depicted object in an image that refers to a way of seeing merely stands for objects as such. It is appropriate to the content of the article that a street scene is depicted. But any other object could have been shown to depict nearsightedness. For the crucial thing is that the choice of particular objects does not affect the depiction of ways of seeing. Rather it is the quality of the immanent pictorial relations in the depiction of these objects, that is, the form in the Herbartian sense. In this sense, the pictorial example actually consists of two images: the depiction of near-sightedness by means of fuzzy transitions in the parts of the form, and the round image in a rectangular image, delineated by the frame of the glasses, that normal vision depicts with exact transitions. The image was made by montaging three photographs: the glasses, the street scene ‘sharp‘, and the street scene ‘fuzzy’ were photographed separately and then collaged, supporting the idea that in this image, we are dealing with several images in one. The logical purpose of this pictorial example should be clear: a purely formal observation can reveal a non-objective pictorial content. Although a viewer may be concerned solely with the quality of the immanent pictorial relations, he reads a symbol all the same and gains an insight into a near-sighted person’s way of seeing. One could also say: The illustration shows why Wölfflin introduced works of visual art. Neo-Kantian perspectivism in aesthetics represents an attempt to make formal and cognitive interests converge. This is achieved by applying the idea that the infrastructure of an image can correspond to the infrastructure of a perception even for works of visual art. Art takes on a special cognitive obligation. In the end, the paradigm of the way of seeing carries over into art an idea that is elsewhere deemed obvious without much discussion. For the paradigm of the way of seeing turns works of art into unintended illustrations

112

The Visibility of the Image

for an unwritten book on the optics or psychology of rare modulations in perception or even of eye diseases. So behind this paradigm lies an understanding that is also found in recent phenomenology, that an artist’s studio is nothing other than a ‘kind of vision laboratory’ (tr).7 One could also say: The artist is understood as a psychologist of perception by other means. In the context of perception psychology, images are often produced and used for observational cognition on the grounds of their non-objective level of meaning.8 The phenomenon of so-called adaptive filtering is discussed exclusively using images with this cognitive function. With this background, one can say that for neo-Kantians, art appears as the depiction of adaptive filters, that is, of the interpretational achievements inherent in visual processes – and in fact very much as the depiction of filters that are currently being rediscovered in perceptual psychology. In the relevant research of Ingo Rentschler, ‘non-linear’ and ‘linear filter functions’ again assume a key role in the internal structure of perception, giving Wölfflin’s theory a late confirmation. The concept of a filter is increasingly replacing Wölfflin’s neo-Kantian concept of the form of intuition, just as, conversely, attempts are made to reconstruct formal stylizations in art through combinations of filters.9

The invention of ways of seeing In this context we should be aware that it is exceptionally rare for the depiction of a mode of perception that can be explained psychologically or physiologically to be recognized as an artistic achievement. On the contrary, we are more likely to consider it an instance of good illustration – as in the example given above.* ‘Art’, on the other hand, as Martin Seel emphasizes, ‘invents depictions

* Note further, however, that the vision of a near-sighted person is not so banal as it might appear at first ‘glance’. The work of Gerhard Richter in particular demonstrates the artistic possibilities available in blurred vision. In his early novel King, Queen, Knave (1928), Vladimir Nabokov examined vision under conditions of near-sightedness in detail, by making his main character Franz step on his glasses and then sending him on a journey through Berlin: ‘At last Franz overcame all the blotches and banks of fog, located his hat, recoiled from the embrace of the clowning mirror and made for the door. Only his face remained bare. Having negotiated the stairs, where an angel was singing as she polished the banisters, he showed the desk clerk the address on the priceless card and was told what bus to take and where to wait for it. He hesitated for a moment, tempted by the magic and majestic possibility of a taxi. He rejected it not only because of the cost but because his potential employer might take him for a spendthrift if he arrived in state. Once in the street he was engulfed in streaming radiance. Outlines did not exist, colors had no substance. Like a woman’s wispy dress that has slipped off its hanger, the city shimmered and fell in fantastic folds, not held up by anything, a discarnate iridescence limply suspended in the azure autumnal air. Beyond the nacreous desert of the square, across which a car sped now and then with a new metropolitan trumpeting, great pink edifices loomed, and suddenly a sunbeam, a gleam of glass, would stab him painfully in the pupil’ (p. 53f.).

From the Way of Seeing to Visibility

113

of ways of seeing the world’ (tr).10 This rightly reminds us that the infrastructure of a work does not need to be the representation of a reality seen with particular eyes. The infrastructure can result from trying to construct the depiction of something independently of seeing of that thing. It would be completely beside the point, for example, to verify that Giotto’s images really reproduce the way he or someone else saw the world. Still, this argument keeps reappearing: The special, somewhat painterly sfumato in the Leonardo’s images is attributed to the Renaissance painter’s near-sightedness; El Greco’s vertically attenuated style is actually explained through astigmatism with some frequency, and Monet’s late work is interpreted as the manifestation of a particular form of cataract.11 But although there will never be any means of monitoring the structural correspondence between eye and image that is being asserted here, the absence of any such monitoring unimportant. The images of Giotto, Leonardo, El Greco or Monet do not show how they, as historically unique people, saw the world, but rather inform us about how something can be seen.12 Yet images that reproduce no specific, experienced vision can, conversely, have an effect on vision. When we are inquiring into the possibilities of making something visible by means of an image, we are, finally, concerned not only to compile representations of ways of seeing, but further with constructing and isolating visibility. This matches one of Fiedler’s a central ideas in his text ‘Über den Ursprung der künstlerischen Tätigkeit’ [On the Origin of Artistic Activity] of 1887. The responsibilities of art that go beyond illustration include ‘the development and formulation of designs in which reality is represented exclusively to the degree it can be a visible reality’ (p. 153) – and there is, according to Fiedler, an acute ‘artistic need’ for this: ‘Anyone who really looks inside himself for it can discover for himself how inexact, incomplete, meagre the visibility is of which we are possessed’ (tr) (p. 155). In projecting a pure visibility, art takes on a transcendental function: It simulates schematic planes that make it possible to see an object. The form of an image becomes a scheme of perception by means of its relations. No one can get along without these planes that are drawn, for Fiedler, by artists: ‘Even the least of us must produce his world according to its visible form.’ (tr).13 It is almost a commonplace when Schopenhauer says: ‘The artist lets us see the world through his eyes’14 – but what does it mean? Just as an architectural drawing, the objective side of a correspondence, can give a sense that the projected structure will built exactly as it is drawn, projected visibilities can, with the immanent relations of their infrastructure, serve as ‘directions for seeing’,15 as Wilhelm Dilthey aptly puts it, as blueprints for conditions that – as Fiedler

114

The Visibility of the Image

puts it – ‘transform the mirror image of the world in people’s heads’ (tr).16 So art takes on the task of making and teaching new ways of seeing: ‘All progress consists of expanding knowledge. Applied to the visual arts, progress consists of depicting a new, inventive understanding of nature’ (tr) (ibid.). So it would be a complete misunderstanding of Fiedler’s and Wölfflin’s medial theory of perception to interpret it as an ontological statement about the way perceptions exist. The stuff of perception is not known, and there is no intention of introducing an entity into consciousness when perceptions are explicated as a visual medium. Formal aesthetics’ pictorial concept is meant only as a tool for grasping something that cannot be described intentionally because it is the condition of intentionality. By means of visible immanent relations in images, people gain access to the invisible conditions of seeing. Formal aesthetics is trying, as Fiedler put it, ‘to gain an insight into the condition in which our visible world finds itself ’ (tr) (‘Ursprung’, p. 154).17 The infrastructure of an image gives an insight into the syntax of seeing, into the human condition: ‘Someone with van Gogh’s images in mind‘, as Ferdinand Fellmann describes this phenomenon, ‘will see the landscapes of Provence differently from someone who does not have this model. He will discover qualities in the landscape that make themselves available to him only because they have been seen as an image (“as painted”). In this sense even objective perceptions are engaged and suffused with the images that constitute the independent dimension of meaning in conditioned consciousness’ (tr).18 If we take it into account that there are aesthetic structural qualities even in visual perceptions, then the concept of an image will always be an irreplaceable category in theories of consciousness and of perception.19 In recent phenomenology, this necessity has been repeatedly emphasized: ‘Typical stylistic structures are already inscribed in our experiential world.’20 Only in images can we see the stylistic structures that comprise the immaterial pictorial quality of perception, and exactly because of this pictorial quality, perception cannot be taken to be a passive copy. It is ‘the realization that there is a level of meaning in consciousness that coincides not with objects, but with forms of representation’ (tr).21 But these phenomenological arguments for comparability between image and eye seem to have been overlooked from the language analytic side. When the objection is raised that it is unnecessary to treat human perceptions as images,22 we need to insist on knowing exactly which phenomenon is to be explained with reference to a pictorial analogy. What is at stake in defending of the concept of the image as an irreplaceable category for phenomena of consciousness is not – as the critics usually assert – about

From the Way of Seeing to Visibility

115

why a perception is always an intentional representation of something, but only about the conditional structural qualities of this representation that exists independently of its intentionality. In short, it is not about whether it is possible to explain how people can make things circle about in their minds without assuming mental images, but whether it is possible to understand how something can be visible to a person in different ways, depending on conditions, without resorting to images  – the former may be possible, the latter must be doubted. Only an image can show what it means to have an experience in the medium of human senses.

From a way of seeing to pure visibility Taking the cognitive background of Wölfflin’s formal aesthetics into account, it becomes clear that for him the formal consideration of an image does not lead to any overcoming of the content, but in fact only to a change of object. Wölfflin is researching art historical works out of an interest in content using formal methods. The detailed investigations of Norbert Schmitz confirm it: ‘With this, then, the object of the image was no longer nature as something independent of that image, but our human perception’ (tr).23 Now if the goal of formal aesthetics is, as it claims, to leave the content of an image aside and to overpower it, and if in addition the form is, with the paradigm of the way of seeing, elevated to the actual content of the image, then the paradigm of the way of seeing cannot possibly be the conclusion of the internal logic of formal aesthetics, but only a first step in the direction of a still more radical victory over content – even over the subjective conditions of the eyes. Wölfflin’s aesthetics fleshes out an insight typical of Fielder, that the form of a work of art is its own content – with Fiedler this is not the last word, however. Fiedler takes the insight into form as symbolizing condition as a kind of intermediate result in his reflections, which he himself did not work out in nearly so extensive and detailed a way as Wölfflin did. We do not do justice to Konrad Fiedler’s contribution to the development of a purely formal understanding of the image if we read him solely as the philosopher who described the identity of formal and cognitive interests in art, and so the paradigm of an aesthetics of ways of seeing. There is no doubt that he furnished the critical antecedents on which Wölfflin’s theory of forms of intuition is built, but in his later major work in aesthetics, ‘Über den Ursprung der künstlerischen Tätigkeit’ [On the Origin of Artistic Activity] of 1887, the early paradigm shift from beauty to way of seeing is just the first step in the logical internal development of formal aesthetics,

116

The Visibility of the Image

followed as compellingly by a second conquest. This occurs with the concept of visibility – which is central to this text, in fact only to this text. After starting his argument by recounting afresh his view of art as perceptible cognition, two final chapters outline a perspective, so far largely neglected, that goes much further towards a purely formal understanding of the image: The main idea goes thus: from a way of seeing to pure visibility. Fiedler begins his account of this very modern perspective by stepping back in the same way from both the relevance of sensual beauty and from perceptible cognition for works of art: ‘Almost all the claims that tend to be made for any art practice can be aligned, if in a somewhat indefinite way, under one of two headings: the claim is either that the art has a sensual value or that it has a reference value’ (tr) (‘Ursprung’, p. 189). This statement addresses the first two paradigms of formal aesthetics: Herbart and Zimmermann clearly claim that art should be perceived to be beautiful, and Wölfflin clearly demands reference, that is, a relationship of the pictorial form to the perception. Fiedler himself will not accept, after all, that it is essential for images to be demonstrably beautiful or meaningful, as they often are, or particularly why works of visual art should or even must be subservient to these functions. His scepticism rests on the view: ‘These do not require such complicated activities as those that give rise to artistic achievements’ (tr) (ibid.). For beauty, the statement is quickly appreciated, because there are two reasons why it is not surprising to a contemporary reader, in the context of this discussion, that the relevance of beauty to works of art is not accepted. First, the view had already been attributed to Fiedler many times,24 and second, at the end of the nineteenth century, since the appearance of Karl Rosenkranz’s Ästhetik des Hässlichen [The Aesthetics of Ugliness] (1853), art and art theory was turning away from an orientation towards beauty with increasing frequency. Yet for Fiedler to also assert a liberation of visible form from cognitive tasks seems in nearly diametrical opposition to the usual understanding of Fiedler, if we understand him primarily as a neo-Kantian theoretician who interprets art as a cognitive achievement complementary to science. But his formulations speak for themselves: ‘Only when we have come to be so at ease with art can we acknowledge an indebtedness to it that is actually completely different from anything sought by our scientific [sic!], desiring, aesthetically sensitive nature’ (tr) (‘Ursprung’, p. 218). Fiedler opposes all art’s obligations, including the obligation to contribute to that which is ‘sought by our scientific . . . nature’. An understanding of art as autonomous is incompatible with reducing art to an instrument for advancing the culture of seeing. Reducing art to cultural progress is incompatible with an

From the Way of Seeing to Visibility

117

understanding of art as autonomous. ‘Here, at the end of our research, we realize just the opposite, that because we have tried to clear the haze within us that had been hiding the secret meaning of artistic activity, we must now also free ourselves from the prejudice that the value of this activity is to be sought in effects that are beneficial in completely different realms of existence’(tr) (ibid.). We can also say that perspectivism is too narrow a perspective for the many possible forms of an image. It does not necessarily matter to every image how the perceptual apparatus functions, which way of seeing is depicted with the infrastructure, or how seeing can be taught and learnt. What neo-Kantianism is doing, rather, is issuing a normative prescription: to compel art to conform to ways of seeing, perspectives, forms of presentation, styles, modalities of perception – or however one wants to understand form interpreted as content. In terms of formal aesthetics’ historical development, this means to demand perceptible knowledge from art is as normative as it is to demand beauty. Just as we may object that Zimmermann thought of art only as beautiful art, we may object that Wölfflin refers to pictorial form only as a depiction of forms of intuition. To the same extent, if not in the same way, art is made to serve a purpose in both cases: Immanent relations have to satisfy requirements, first, for beauty, and then for the history of vision. But for Fiedler both the feeling an image elicits and the knowledge an image displays are only given in the image in a mediated sense, hence through associated interests and interpretations. This means, concretely: Only through perspectivist thought in neo-Kantianism or, in contemporary terms, the phenomenological orientation to perception, does any image become a representation of an order of the visible. It is not immediately visible; it is not the most striking feature of an encounter with an image. In Fiedler’s view, these interpretations therefore do not do justice to the most important principle of a purely formal consideration of an image, which tries to get beyond any mediation: ‘What we gain indirectly by way of heightened sensation from this world of constructs is, as we know, a secondary gain, in fact also brought to life through artistic work, but not to be regarded as the crucial powers there, where the work of image-making appears undisguised’ (tr) (ibid., p. 207). The structures of the argument reappear in historical perspective as well: Fiedler is arguing here against epistemological formalism, for which images are the reflections of perspectives, using the same argument that Wölfflin’s neoKantian formalism uses against idealistic aesthetics of content. Wölfflin emphasizes any number of times that the objective content of an image is a trivial side issue as far as the depiction of the eye’s conditions is concerned. Yet Fiedler – despite working historically earlier than Wölfflin – took the next step leading

118

The Visibility of the Image

logically beyond Wölfflin: That is, from a formal standpoint, it is equally beside the point for an image to depict a way of seeing through its immanent relations as it is for the form of the image to depict an object. Both are forms of reference: the one refers to a subjective internal condition and the other to objective, external things. An exact description of the neo-Kantian understanding of form raises the idea of a doubled formalization:  the form of image need not represent either a way of seeing objects or the ways subjects see. That the depicted object is unimportant to the formal consideration of images forms the basis for all formal aesthetics that are concerned solely with pictorial syntax in the Herbartian sense. But the possibility that the conditionality shown in an image can also be declared unimportant led Fiedler, who is often too closely aligned with neoKantianism, to overcome neo-Kantian perspectivism. Of course this does not mean that the viewer of the image, that is, the recipient, disappears. Fiedler does not want to even engage with the metaphysical-ontological question of whether there can be a pictorial existence without an interpreting pictorial consciousness: ‘We rightly affirm that it is only with our own existence that that is given which we are able to say is present. But as we have seen, this does not say very much’ (tr) (ibid., p. 185). Fiedler wants a formalization that considers the subjectivity and conditionality, the will-to-art and to form that flow into a representation to be formally unimportant. The surface of an image can be as independent of the eye’s perceptual organization as it is of objects, and this just when the conditions that are becoming visible, whose inner relational logic Wölfflin was able to expose, is itself once again recognized as a kind of substance and content. The relational logic of the image cannot be autonomous for Wölfflin because it is representationally related to the syntax of perception,25 because it formalizes by merely exchanging the content. Fiedler conversely developed a concept of the image in which pictorial forms are free from the functions of both beauty and cognition. Which does not necessarily mean that the forms of an image may not be beautiful or that they may not convey knowledge. For Fiedler’s perspective, it is irrelevant whether they are or do this. Fiedler’s approach emerges from these considerations: His aesthetics should be read as the idea, which he himself still considered utopian, to develop a type of image free of both purposes and letting the pictorial surface be the whole of the image. His aesthetic raises the questions: What remains of an image at the end of such a radically formal viewing? In a formal perspective, what remains an image at all? How do the syntactic structures of an image differ from those of an ornament or wallpaper? What must the forms of an image do to be the forms

From the Way of Seeing to Visibility

119

of an image and not those of some other sort of object? Fiedler’s answer to these questions goes: ‘that something is produced that seems to be there for its visibility alone’ (tr) (‘Ursprung’, p. 209). The importance of this statement for the history of formal aesthetics can hardly be overestimated. Fiedler is formulating a proposal for a third solution to the problem every formal aesthetician ultimately asks himself: Why do people go on looking at images – the introductory question – when the contents are no longer interesting? For their beauty, was Herbart’s and Zimmermann’s answer. For their way of seeing, according to Wölfflin. And when art is as unpersuasive as a mode of beauty as it is as a mode of perception, then – Fiedler says – images can and should be viewed for their pure visibility alone: Images are ‘designs of visibility’ (tr) (‘Sichtbarkeitsgestaltungen’) (ibid., 188). This is the basic theory of formal aesthetics in paradigms of visibility. In the first paradigm change, the fine arts became the perceptual arts; these in turn become – almost tautologically – the ‘visible arts’. Benedetto Croce (1866– 1952) uses this term in the essay ‘Theorie der Kunst als reiner Sichtbarkeit’ [Theory of Art as Pure Visibility] (1911). With this formulation, Croce pinpointed the way Fiedler’s aesthetics had transformed the concept of the visual arts. Croce clearly identified which categories of traditional aesthetics needed to be replaced by Fiedler’s concept of visibility: ‘The principle of art is henceforth neither beauty nor concept nor mimesis, nor even feeling, but rather visibility’ (tr) (p. 194). In the most radical kind of formal observation of an image, that is, one without regard for any purpose, it is visibility alone that cannot be ignored. It makes no difference what an image achieves, what purpose it serves or what reasoning underpins it, formally, it is its unique kind of visibility that accounts for an image being an image.

Pure visibility versus dependent visibility Visibility is a characteristic of many objects. It is the possibility of being seen. Every material object offers human beings this kind of contact under certain conditions. So at first glance it appears odd to try to understand visibility as a characteristic found only in images; nor is this the thesis. To do justice to Fiedler’s theory, we must identify and compare two forms of visibility. There are crucial differences ‘between the richness of visibility we call nature and the designed visibility that comes before our eyes through artistic activity’ (tr) (‘Ursprung’, p. 188). We should even emphasize that it ‘comes before our eyes only through artistic activity’. The pure form of visibility is attainable only through an

120

The Visibility of the Image

image: ‘This activity is in fact essential when we are concerned with producing a pure expression of the visibility of a phenomenon’ (tr) (ibid., p. 189). For an object to be an image, it is accordingly not enough for this thing to be visible. Pictorial existence demands that the image produce a form of visibility that differs from the visibility of ‘normal’ objects in that it is not the visibility of something one sees, as paradoxical as it may sound. We need not shy away from this as a definition of an image: images are objects on which we can see something that is not present at the place where the image as object is located. The existence of an image is as much a presence of something absent as it is an absence of something present; no object can be an image of itself. As similar as one egg may be to another, one egg will never become the image of another, because the ‘depicted’ egg is itself an egg. This unity of visibility inevitably breaks an image up, destroys it and leads to a contradiction: The visibility of the pictorial surface contradicts the visibility of the thing that is present. Every image is obliged to elevate its surface to a self-sufficient phenomenon, that is, to construct a difference between the pictorial surface and the pictorial material. One can also say that images come about through a process of isolation; the visibility of something is presented separately, uncoupled and isolated from the substantial presence of that thing: ‘Only through this activity does the visibility of a visible thing break free of the thing and become a free, independent entity’ (tr) (ibid., p. 192). Pure visibility takes the substance away from the visibility of something. It is not bound up with any object, and does not make reference to the presence of any entity. To speak phenomenologically, pure visibility has no intentionality, which is to say it is not the visibility of something. It is a special form sui generis that is realized only in images, and whose qualities are appreciated only by recognizing ‘how dependent and restricted the visibility of nature is as long as it is constituted only in perceptions or in an internal representation process’ (tr) (ibid., p. 191). The restricted or dependent visibility of nature is the opposite of pure visibility. Direct perception of something reveals a world in which the visibility is only ever the visibility of an outer skin, a surface to which an object is given. With an object, the surface has no independent life. In nature, the visible surface is a functioning husk. From whatever perspective nature is seen, visibility cannot be separated from the object: ‘The eye can only show us objects among whose complicated sensual properties visibility is just one aspect’ (tr) (ibid., p. 189). This intentionality of visibility is not grounded in the intentional structure of perception; one looks at images with the same eyes. There is a different

From the Way of Seeing to Visibility

121

reason:  Visual perception outside of images is supplemented by other senses. Any non-pictorial object offers perceptual possibilities to the other senses as well. Dependent visibility can be revealed as the husk of something present that is invisible, because there are many ways of getting behind the visible surface – it is usually very easy. Visible things can also be smelt, tasted and felt. It is possible to perform actions with them, and to be hindered in one’s activity, and to be brought to the limits of what is possible. These are the ways we can be sure that visibility is only one characteristic of one and the same ‘substance’ that can be perceived through other characteristics too. ‘So we are not immediately lead by experiences of the eyes into an exclusive realm of visibility’ (tr) (ibid., p. 190). To formulate it in another way: When we see an object, this object is not completely given over to its visibility; it is more than just visible. One sees a package that cannot be undone just by looking at it. ‘In visual perception and representation as such, there is so far no means of gaining what the autonomy of the visibility of something would show us’ (tr) (ibid., p. 189). Things are different with an image. ‘We make something that shows us the visibility of an object, and in doing so, we bring forth something new, something different from what was there earlier through our visual faculties’ (tr) (ibid., p. 162). If an image shows an object, visibility coincides with the whole reality, for in any image, visibility is everything that is given about an object; in depiction – and in fact only in pictorial depiction – object and visibility are identical: the objects of the image have no substance, they are phantoms. By means of an image, reality acquires a skin:  However heavy the object one sees in an image: It is not heavy – and an image of the North Sea is not wet, and an image of the sun is not warm. There is just one access to the reality of the image: looking at it. The world depicted in an image corresponds to the artistic world of a person who can only see – but who otherwise cannot hear, smell, taste, touch or locate his position. This person is furthermore incapable of action. The world of images is one-sided and reduced to the visual: Objects cannot be touched or smelt, heard or even used. By disengaging the world from of its usual availability to be heard, smelt, tasted, touched and used, the image disempowers ‘reality, that sets firm limits on the deeds and desires of human beings’ (tr) (ibid., p. 101). This comes close to formulating one task every image must ultimately accomplish, namely ‘to extract the form in which visible nature appears to us from obscurity and to give it clear expression’ (tr) (ibid., p. 193). The result of this de-substantiation, deprivation of force and disentangling of the obscurity given in the visibility of the image is not, as one might perhaps think, an irreversible destruction of reality. On the contrary, pictorial reality sui

122

The Visibility of the Image

generis is first constituted through images’ destructive measures. The iconoclastic controversy is immanent to the image.26 Fiedler clearly develops the typical expressionist two-step on the constitution of pictorial reality, which has been analysed in detail under the concept of de-realizing materialization.27 ‘By reducing the whole substance of real existence to the ephemeral stuff of perception and the representations of a single sense, we lose the ground of the real world under our feet’ (tr) (‘Ursprung’, p. 190). Yet this very destructive disempowering of all the non-visual senses transforms itself into a constructive move and ‘puts another form of being in its place’ (tr) (ibid., p. 189). This may be Fiedler’s main thesis: the pure visibility of the image is an independent ‘form of being’ – and not a form of appearance dependent on being. Pure visibility is given when visibility itself emerges as an entity, and no longer as the appearance of an entity. The formal study of images culminates in an ontological insight. The image has a special ontological status solely on the grounds of being an image:  we get to see visibility itself. For Fiedler, images are not a world of their own on the basis of their pictorially immanent interpretation of visible reality – as one often hears today – but on the basis of visibility’s isolation into an independent entity without substance. This understanding of the image does not depend on the possibility that a process of interpretation can be involved in the process of isolation. An image constitutes an autonomous reality not by means of an interpretation of the visible world conditioned by a way of seeing, but by visibility splitting away and becoming absolute to a material without substance. The producer of an image is meant to ‘to isolate the visibility of a thing in such a way that the idea of an object through which the visibility appears disappears completely, and visibility turns into an autonomous form of being’ (tr) (ibid., p. 191). With these thoughts, Fiedler is developing an alternative to neo-Kantian perspectivism’s idea of pictorial worldmaking. For perspectivist thinking, each perspective discloses its own reality, because there is no reality outside a perspective. With Fiedler, on the other hand, the image does not disclose an absent world, but builds up a present world sui generis, because the reality that can only be seen in this medium possesses ontological characteristics that are not to be found anywhere else. As long as we treat the image as the reproduction of a perception, we will fail to recognize its real nature, especially that of art: ‘In realizing that the pure and clear visible form of things is closed off from the human mind as long as the visible is grasped only in terms of direct or reproduced and associated perceptions, we come to the other insight that artistic activity is required in order to even approach the visible form of nature at all’ (tr) (ibid., p. 193f.). There

From the Way of Seeing to Visibility

123

is no contradiction at all between this special ontological status and the status of image itself as an object in space and time. The pure visibility in the image is – as Fiedler emphasizes – bound to the visibility of an image carrier. Fiedler knows very well that ‘for this to be possible, however, a material is required which is itself visible, and through whose manipulation it becomes possible to actually produce that construction of visibility’ (tr) (ibid., p. 192). But this visibility of the pictorial material, which obviously can be smelt and felt as well, must be overcome in the image-making process, which is the reason one principle of imagery can be relied upon: Pure visibility arises only if the image is capable of making its constituent material invisible.28 ‘The material’, Fiedler writes, anticipating the idea now familiar from phenomenology, ‘is in a sense forced to betray itself, inasmuch as it is made to serve the purpose of giving expression to such an immaterial construction as the ways things present themselves to vision’ (tr) (ibid., p. 192). Only by destroying material visibility ‘can that world of art arise in which the visibility of things manifests itself in the arrangement of pure form constructions [Formgebilde]’ (tr) (ibid., p. 193).

Pure visibility and ornament Fiedler’s last formulation namely ‘the arrangement of pure form constructions’ asks for further definition. Just as one can describe a difference between the pure visibility of an image and the dependent visibility of an object, so must one set pure visibility apart from the visibility of an ornament – even if Fiedler did not work out the distinction himself. But exactly because ornaments generally qualify as purely formal constructions, they raise a question about why they should not be considered prototypical of the pure form of visibility, or more precisely, why formal aesthetics does not consider ornaments to be images. An ornament, too, is made just to be seen, but the visibility of ornaments does not attain the status of an autonomous pictorial surface; it always remains a husk of visibility. An ornament is always an enclosing and embellishing something. Without such a substrate, one could say, affixation, an ornament is unthinkable. In his studies relevant to the issue, Hans Sedlmayr (1896–1984) shed light on the issue: ‘The real cause of ornament’s death is roughly this. It is the very essence of the ornament that its character, both as to shape and colour, grows naturally out of the body that carries it, be that body a piece of architecture, a utensil of some kind, or, to give the earliest instance, the human form itself. But what remote justification for its existence can there be, when that same body, striving for a supposed purity, rejects for that very reason the very idea of an ornament?

124

The Visibility of the Image

The ornament is indeed the only category of art which cannot possibly achieve autonomy – and so the ornament dies’ (Art in Crisis, p. 91f.).29 The autonomy of visibility is essential for the pure visibility of the image. Only as autonomous visibility does visibility become pictorial visibility, and in this way become a form of being. Only if visibility can free itself from the carrier is the image capable of showing something that is not present. So the pure visibility of an image can be clearly distinguished from that of an ornament: while looking at an ornament, one is seeing the surface of an object that is present, whereas while looking at an image, one is not seeing marked wallpaper. This differentiation of image from ornament is of current interest in particular because it contradicts the widespread language analytic view that image and ornament can be distinguished only through semiotics. According to the language analytic persuasion represented by Danto and Goodman, an image is always a sign that stands for something else. An ornament, on the other hand, is an asemiotic decoration that has no semiotic character. The image becomes an image only on the basis of its interpretation as a sign. Without this semiotic interpretation by a user, an image would not be recognizable as an image. In this view, an image can be distinguished from ‘normal’ objects that are not images only by means of a semiotic interpretation.30 In this respect, Fiedler’s reflections are refreshingly non-judgemental. Formal aesthetics’ position presents a welcome alternative to the view, hardly challenged today, that any sort of imagery has a semiotic character. Fiedler pursues the idea of tracing a formal difference between image and ornament that is not semiotic. This is Fiedler’s unique achievement. His thinking necessarily leads to the insight:  Images and ornaments are phenomenologically different phenomena. Visibility appears as an autonomous form of being only in an image. Only in an image can we see something that is not present where we are looking. That does not mean that this pure visibility that is seen when one sees an image is not normally also used as a sign for absent things. Any form of being can be used as a sign. The formal approach opens the possibility of having images in which pure visibility is present without trying to be a sign for something else. Images remain images, even if meaning of any kind is deemed unimportant, that is, if the images are viewed formally. That an image can also be a sign is the product of a subsequent use of pure visibility as a sign for that to which it bears some similarity. Yet not everything that resembles something else is therefore already a pictorial sign for this other thing. This belongs to the basic insights that Fiedler was able to work out by identifying pure visibility above all as a semiotically neutral form of being. The pure

From the Way of Seeing to Visibility

125

visibility of an image can be, but need not be a sign. For something that exists, it is no more necessary to have a semiotic quality than it is to be beautiful or to have cognitive qualities. Any object can be declared a sign and still remain, as a perceptible phenomenon, the same object, even if it does not serve a semiotic function. In an image, a thing remains visible even if this depicted thing has no semantic relation to anything else. In an image, a thing goes on being similar to something absent even if the image is not considered a sign for that to which it is similar. Visibility is more basic than legibility, as we can tell even from animals who, although they presumably cannot read, can still see something materially absent in images. This is exactly what Fiedler recognized: Images continue to be pure visibility even though the pure visibility may not refer to anything. Even if images actually always can be and perhaps even always are interpreted as signs, the semiotic character still cannot be essential for the image from a logical perspective, since Fiedler’s thinking admits the possibility of images that are not symbols. This would be the case for images that ‘are created just for their visibility’s sake’ (tr) (‘Ursprung’, p. 194). The ‘just’ here means ‘solely’. With this, Fiedler is saying: ‘so art seems to be denied any and all meaning’ (tr) (ibid., p. 217). Fiedler’s aesthetics ends in the idea of an asemiotic image that neither refers to an object nor shows any condition, but constitutes and designs a pure form of visibility. He understands the image as creating pure visibility. In this respect his aesthetics challenge the artist to find a pictorial form in keeping the maxim: Stop trying to interpret visible reality in the production of an image, and try instead to understand the creation of an image as the building of an object in which visibility becomes an independent form of being! The change in paradigm from a way of seeing to visibility is bound up with a change in the concept of artistic activity. The artist is no longer to make secondary constructions that take visible reality into account, but to enrich visible reality by a phenomenon sui generis that is only visible and that does not occur without artistic activity. The question arises, are there images grounded in Fiedler’s aesthetics?

4.2 Images produced technically: ‘For their visibility’s sake alone’ Preliminary remarks With Fiedler, the internal logic of development in the history of formal aesthetics reaches its most radical configuration. It was not unusual for him to use the images of his friend Hans von Marées as examples of his thinking. This is

126

The Visibility of the Image

unpersuasive. If images of this sort serve his theory of pure visibility adequately, any traditional artwork at all might be pressed into service. But it only matters as long as we are looking for pictorial examples to show the ‘development of the visual process’ (tr) (‘Ursprung’, p. 168). Actually we hear again and again the view that ‘every image embodies a way of seeing’.31 This is right only in a very particular sense, however: An image can only ever depict an object in a way of seeing, so it follows that any image can present a style of making visible. But things do not always go as far as this shift of meaning. One hardly looks at holiday snaps for their surface infrastructure; in an illustrated users’ manual, it is not the view but the objective information that is of interest. Even Wölfflin’s intention to construe the history of painting as an illustration of the history of looking is a very biased view of the multiple functions of visual art – but it is nevertheless a view that at least applies to many works: visual art has traditionally always been associated with an interest in finding out about perspectives, perceptual and representational possibilities. But Fiedler’s idea of grasping the image as a design of visibility appears to have become a concern of art only in the twentieth century. One might object at this point that according to Fiedler’s own understanding, every image must isolate visibility to a pure form. That is correct. Yet this formal description does not do justice to every image, does not account entirely for it. Crucial questions are: Which images are produced solely and exclusively for the sake of their pure visibility? Of which image can we claim that the surface of the image is the whole image? When do images stop being signs for a visible reality and instead become, themselves, an only-visible reality?

Avant-garde experiments with pure visibility The first attempt in the history of art to create an image purely for the sake of its visibility can be found in the painting of Kasimir Malevich (1879–1935). Malevich characterized his programme as Suprematism, to reflect the essence of the image in the image itself, which is to say, to make it visible.32 Malevich’s great significance for twentieth-century art goes back to his claim to make images concerned with a sensible self-reflection of the image, an aesthetic theory of the image. The interest in perception is delayed with Malevich. In Suprematism the artist investigates neither objects nor ways of seeing, but the image itself, by means of the image. The image serves a function that can be served only by an image and so is essential for an image at exactly the moment it initiates a visibility that is not the visibility of something. In order to show this, an image must

From the Way of Seeing to Visibility

127

relinquish representation and be thinkable as pure monochrome. Any sense of having content then disappears from the image; the image is nothing other than visibility. Monochrome painting is one of Suprematism’s forms of fulfilment, that is, of painting for the sake of pure visibility alone. The painting and theory of Suprematism is as programmatic as the monochrome image is constricting of artistic fantasy. The monochrome image suffers from its exclusion of any leeway for play with various forms and styles. So we really cannot speak of a ‘design of visibility’ as Fiedler claimed: For the essential thing about being monochrome is that nothing is designed. Monochrome painting cannot get past its status as an intellectual experiment – which is no small achievement. It is an esoteric and typically avant-garde phenomenon. We can therefore also say that Malevich did not so much realize Fiedler’s programme as reform and extend it. In this respect he is an important intermediary. Rather than Fiedler, it is Suprematist painting that continues to challenge more than a few artists. The idea is to reach the goal by other means; to look for more formally complex forms of realization that do not equate pure visibility with pure colouration of a surface. ‘Since Malevich celebrated the life of the pictorial surface as such, painting has responded by structuring visibility as such [. . .] For a long time it was unclear how Malevich’s vast range of non-objectivity could be realized beyond the white canvas’(tr).33 It did not take quite as long as Norbert Bolz thinks it did, at least not if we take into account another experiment on the theme of pure visibility: collage. Collage, too, is an answer to the question of how the surface of an image can be made absolute. The theoretical writing of Kurt Schwitters provides particularly clear documentation of this. The goal of a collage is to realize a complete ‘Entformelung’ (de-formulation) and ‘Entmaterializierung’ (de-materialization) of all the materials that are being turned into elements of pure form and colour in this way.34 The significance and the meaning of an image are to be destroyed so that an image can be created that is exclusively a structured colour surface. One might object that with collage we are concerned with the creation of ornaments. But this is not the case. Collage’s objectives can be met only by means of images. For collage, too, is trying to make something visible on an object that is not present in the place the collage is located. The design is meant to make the material fact that a collage consists of slips, shreds and rubbish as invisible as the fact that in an easel painting one is looking at oil and canvas. The design is required to build up an independent surface. Collage is trying to be something for the eye that it is not, seen objectively. But only an image can accomplish this. An objective image is concerned to produce the visibility of something absent; collage is

128

The Visibility of the Image

trying to produce a pure visibility of colour and light. That which Fiedler calls the isolation of visibility therefore corresponds exactly to Schwitters’s concept of de-materialization:  collage takes materiality away from the material that is present and so isolates visibility as such. For this reason a collage is not an ornament, but an instance of light and colour becoming independent – as does the monochrome image. In fact collage is the paradoxical effort to make a monochrome image without that image being monochrome. Schwitters understands his work overall as ‘preliminary sketches’. He himself did not believe that collage – or visual art as such – can do more than experiment with the theme of pure visibility. This self-assessment, which applies to Malevich as well, is based on both artists’ commitment to the idea of the classical, original easel painting. Both uphold the tradition of painting and try to achieve something using a medium in which it is hardly possible. The work of making a pictorial surface absolute is therefore taken forward, systematically as well as historically, in reflections in a new medium: in the theory of film. It was recognized very early that certain forms of film permit the pictorial understanding of Fiedler, Malevich and Schwitters to be realized.

From silent film to video clip Visible Man and the Spirit of Film, by the Vienna- and Berlin-based aesthetician Béla Balázs (1884–1949), appeared in 1924. In the development of formal aesthetics, on its way from a way of seeing to visibility, this book is a milestone – although it can very easily be misunderstood. Due to an unfortunate writing style, one quickly gets the impression that Balázs is writing about films as they are seen in the cinema. But from this perspective the book can be taken only as a curiosity. The claims would be for the most part inapplicable, for hardly a single well-known film would bear them out, for example the claim that ‘a good film does not have any “content” as such [. . .] It no more has content that does a painting, a piece of music – or indeed a facial expression’ (Visible Man, p. 19). As description, these sentences are false: There are infinitely many films that have clearly definable contents and that leave no doubt about telling a story. Balázs’s Visible Man belongs among typical twentiethcentury utopias concerning ‘pure visuality’ (p.  21), along with Suprematism and Merz theory. ‘Film’, Balázs suggests, ‘is a surface art’ (p. 19). It would be in a position to create an independent ‘surface of visibility’ (p. 20), ‘Since the film is two-dimensional, with nothing “behind” the image surface, and no “hidden meaning” ’ (p. 20).

From the Way of Seeing to Visibility

129

Balázs describes a film of the future. He takes silent film as the starting point. It bothers him, obviously, that such a film tells a story, and the audience hears music rather than speech. Yet Balázs can imagine that it does not have to be this way. His thoughts arrive at the view: Only with a kind of inversion of the silent film will the artist be in the position to make images for their visibility alone: ‘I expect much more from the reverse procedure, one that to my knowledge has never been attempted. I am thinking of the filming of pieces of music. The visions, even irrational ones, that unfold before our mind’s eye when we listen to music could be made to pass before us on film. Who knows, perhaps this will develop into an entirely novel branch of art?’ (p. 79). Could the video clip be anticipated with any greater precision? The video clip, which first appeared in the 1970s, is clearly recognized here, in 1924, and predicted as a visible reflection of the principles of formal aesthetics. Balázs saw film developing inevitably in the direction of this pictorial form, once it had stopped carrying contents and was trying instead to let the possibilities of the medium present themselves. In a clip, images appear in a way that rules out the possibility of viewing for anything but their visibility. Through the development of modern media, the formal aesthetics of pure visibility has retroactively become an exact phenomenology. It is little short of astonishing how accurately formal aesthetics can be read when we are thinking of clips. This applies to Fiedler and Schwitters just as it does to Balázs.

The video clip Video clips are filmed collages.* They consist of a flickering of images made using the most diverse techniques (film, photography, video, animation) and montaged together in such a way as to have equal value. The key feature of a clip is the fast cutting and quick movement of the parts in a shot. No image can be read as representation – there is not enough time. It is not unusual for a shot to last a fraction of a second. Everything that appears is only an indication, and usually shown only in part. No story is told, nor can the image serve as the representation of a way of seeing. Balázs’s claim is valid: A clip has no content at all, and even if the separate images in the collage show entirely recognizable objects, these are * We need to be aware that the term ‘video clip’ does not refer to every film that illustrates a piece of music, but rather only to the extremely fast montage style of films that were developed in connection with music, and actually achieved their purest form in this connection, but that in principle can also be used when no music is being filmed. In the chapter ‘Videoclips’ in Leben in künstlichen Welten [Life in Artificial Worlds], H. Buddemeier gives a detailed description of the conception of a typical video clip.

130

The Visibility of the Image

completely entformelt and entmaterializiert in Schwitters’s sense. We could say that clips are the best Merz art. At a certain speed, any image is ‘vermerzed’ – which means it becomes a work of Merz art. The image is emptied of meaning and becomes a piece in an optical kaleidoscope. In the most extreme versions, the image sequences in a clip approach sheer monotone noise. You almost get an impression of monochromy again, because the possibilities for perceiving and understanding are overburdened, deliberately and without restraint. Clips have one thing in common with monochrome painting, at least with gigantic American colour field painting, which must be seen, its makers insist, from a short enough distance that the viewer is overwhelmed by its size. With a clip, too, one is overwhelmed by the speed, but also by the extreme close-up and fragmentation that was already at the heart of Balázs’s filmic vision. Objectivities are dissolved in pure abstractions, deformed or drawn into the surrealistic. Every part of a clip serves, in the play of light, to degrade the other parts of the clip, including itself, to purely aesthetic elements of form. Even human beings are subject to this principle: ‘True theatre actors‘, Balázs writes, ‘are accustomed to representing the most varied characters, and can only rarely be used in film.’35 With a clip we must accept it: The players are not actors or performers, but puppets or models. In summary, a clip is constructed for the purpose of setting the pictorial surface into as sophisticated and unfamiliar a dynamic as possible, so as to isolate pure visibility as the only perceptible aspect of the image. Visibility itself becomes visible. We always see just the possibility of seeing something, but never more, because no possibility becomes reality. Through images, the video clip shows how the surface of an image can become the whole of the image. The image says nothing of either real things or of subjective conditions, but rather is the pure self-representation of the possibilities of a medium. In this way the step from a way of seeing to pure visibility is itself aesthetic, that is to say, it is reflected in a sensible way in the image. The enlightened and scientific interest of the traditional easel picture, the interest in showing people how visible reality looks, has given way to a free play with pure visibility. The mannered quality of many clips comes from deliberately representing this will to be formal artificially. What it possible is shown, and this is shown because it is possible. The image has interiorized the surface-as-absolute, described in formal aesthetics, and makes a show of it. In the clip, the image has freed itself from its older residues, from being taken into service, from masquerading; it has thrown off categories such as information and responsibility and has come into its own. It would be unproductive to try to see, in a video clip, the complementary relationship between art and science that has so often defined Western art. In

From the Way of Seeing to Visibility

131

a video clip, the site of the struggle for perceivable knowledge is occupied  – whether one defends or regrets it – by the optical effect, which is presented for its visibility alone. It is about exhibiting the view that an image is nothing but pure visibility; there is nothing to understand, and accordingly few hermeneutic starting points.36 The clip serves a pictorial medium’s playful self-representation. If there is a dimension of meaning in clips at all, then only the medial selfreflection described by Marshall McLuhan: the medium is the message.

Four forms of pure visibility: The easel picture, the film, the digital image and the simulation As impressive as the emancipation of video clip’s pure visibility may be, a clip remains a film, and because of film’s medial limitations, it is by no means the endpoint in the development of an independent, pure visibility. A typology of the various forms of pure visibility in images helps to recognize this. In his short discussion of Balázs’s Visible Man of 1925, Robert Musil laid a possible foundation for such a typology by separating the pure visibility of the easel picture from that of the film. He writes, ‘Above all – any argument that film is an art might be paradoxically extended in this way – what speaks in its favour is its degenerate existence as an event reduced to moving shadows that nevertheless produces an illusion of life. For every art is such dissociation. Mute as a fish and pale as the subterranean, film floats in a pond of the only-visible [nursichtbar]; but painting is mute and fixed’ (tr).37 Musil’s understanding of art corresponds exactly to Fiedler’s: Every art consists of the dissociation of the only-visible, the shadowlike, to a separate form of being; Fiedler calls this the isolation of visibility. But this dissociation goes on – as Musil sees – to diverse versions of pure, pictorial visibility. Through the medium from which it is dissociated, isolated visibility retains medium-specific characteristics; neither the style in which the medium was used nor the representational content has any influence on this purely formal logic. Musil distinguishes the easel picture’s fixed pure visibility from film’s moving pure visibility. In a painting of a fish, the only-visible fish is rigid; it is caught and frozen in place in a moment. In film, however, it can move and swim. So there are two fundamentally different versions of pure visibility: the static and the dynamic. Musil’s bipartite division is no longer adequate for the most recent media. Since the development of film, there are two more ways an only-visible fish can swim about; Musil was unable to even imagine them. Like most theoreticians of the twentieth century, Musil was so deeply fascinated by film that it seemed to him to have completely emancipated pure visibility from its fixity. A film is,

132

The Visibility of the Image

quite apart from its way of seeing and its content – a more natural medium per se than the easel picture – because the world’s dynamics can be adjusted. But in his enthusiasm, he does not appreciate that in a film, even fish are caught and in fact still fixed. It is clear: A fish in a film moves, but the movement is set; the movement is linear and one-dimensional. The fish swims from point a to point b, and even if one has not yet seen the film, this line is already determined by the medium, in fact as a matter of principle. In the medium of film there is just one dynamic, which is firmly established before the film is seen. The movements in the film run from the roll, like the film material, in a fixed order. Seen as a whole, then, the dynamics in film are just as inactive and fixed as the visibility of an easel picture. If the fish is to swim in another way, another film must be made, just as another image must be painted if an object is to be seen in another position. This unites film with the easel picture: both are able to show only what is planned and previewed. The fish in a film will never break away to take a different turn around Musil’s pond of only-visibility. The limits of possibilities for movement in film become increasingly clear the more pure visibility takes on an independent form of being, the greater the drive towards a convergence between pure visibility and a visibility known through real objects. A  fish in a pond of the only-visible does not move in the same way as one in a real pond. This does not mean that the camera is depicting it through a way of seeing, that the movement of the filmed fish may appear different from that of the real one. The typology of pure visibility does not extend to the manner in which something appears; this is the content of the art historical principles. We should rather keep in mind that the pure visibility of a film differs from the visibility of the thing represented in that a person cannot intervene in the filmic visibility, but most definitely can dramatically change the visibility of the thing – not always for the better. The film enables us to imitate dynamic objects, but not to manipulate visibility. This opens an unbridgeable gap between the filmic form of pure visibility and the intentional form of the dependent visibility of real things. Pure visibility cannot become a perfect reality in film, because in it, no one can intervene in film’s only-visible reality. One is condemned to look on at the most horrible assassinations without taking any action. All the while we consider it obvious that one can deal with reality: One need only smash something to see that although our power to change visibility is in fact diminished, it is still there. Yet there is no way of getting hold of pure visibility in either an easel picture or in a film. One can destroy a painting, but not the represented object. To stay with Musil’s example, the fish cannot change the direction in which it is swimming.

From the Way of Seeing to Visibility

133

With this in the background, even the video clip has a conservative position in the development of the image. The viewer regards pure visibility as it becomes visible in a clip just as passively as in an Old Master. This contradicts Fiedler’s claim that visibility becomes a form of being. If something is to be a form of being, it means, an entity that exists for itself, then a person must be able to enter into an exchange with it. One of the qualities of what we call an ‘entity’ is that that a person can do something with it, even if he cannot always do what he wants. Its pure visibility being inaccessible, a clip remains a traditional, onedimensional film, which becomes particularly striking when film is confronted with the possibilities of digital image processing. Computerized digital image processing supports a third type of pictorial visibility: manipulable pure visibility. In this technology, the image is dispersed on a screen in points of light, so-called pixels, under conditions controlled by a computer.38 The image is a dot matrix surface, for which the computer calculates which point is illuminated in what way when. It is not a problem for this screen technology to make the only-visible fish swim in any direction imaginable. The fish swims on the screen as in any film, but, as in a real pond, where it swims is not determined beforehand any more. Rather the direction may be made dependent on the most diverse conditions by means of the computer. A viewer of the fish can, for example, use keys and controls to make the fish swim in any direction he likes. In the digital image, computer-supported processing makes pure visibility usable. The pictorial surface becomes – as computer terminology rightly calls it – a user interface. This marks a crucial difference between the digital image and the easel picture along with film: The viewer can for the first time enter into pure visibility and have an effect on it. With so-called Computer Aided Design (CAD) a house can be turned and used at will. On screen, it is possible to walk across rooms, smash cups, construct parts of airplanes and assemble airplanes from parts already constructed. Digital images permit a modelling with pure visibility without having to account for or attend to the ballast of substance, which this thing’s visibility has outside the image.39 With the development of digital image processing, a functional substitution has occurred: Pure visibility becomes what oil paint is to the easel picture. One does not paint with pigment, but directly with immaterial visibility. In comparison with nature, the pure visibility of the image in CAD is lighter, faster, more precise, and can be accessed and manipulated with no danger at all. Here we are shown ‘what the visibility of things’, as Fiedler wrote, ‘cannot be as long as it adheres nature’ (tr) (‘Ursprung’, p. 192). This is due entirely to pure visibility being no

134

The Visibility of the Image

more than a dense syntactic structure that can be transformed in isolation by means of a computer on a screen. One can also say that the computer treats the image exactly as formal aesthetics had previously demonstrated in theory: as a surface-deep design of visibility. When a pure form of visibility becomes manipulable through digital image media, we have taken a step in the direction of the development Fiedler conceived as the development of pure visibility into an independent form of being. Developments in image production technology gradually catch up with formal aesthetics’ theoretical outline. Pictorial visibility is significantly enriched at each step in the development of the easel picture through film to the digital image. The step from the fixed dynamics of film to the open dynamics of the pictorial screen should be understood as a heightening of naturalism supported by the medium. Only we must abandon the idea that naturalism in the development of media has anything to do with a particular way of seeing, a certain style of representation. Naturalism, as it expands in the development of media, is an increasingly more accurate imitation of the visibility of something in the absence of that thing. The steps from the easel picture through film to the digital image resemble the steps made by pure visibility of the image towards the dependent visibility of something. So we can already see the goal of this development: ‘The visibility of things manifests itself in the arrangement of pure form constructions [Formgebilde]’ (tr) (ibid., p. 193). The step from film’s pure visibility in motion to digital image processing’s pure visibility in manipulation is not the final step in the development of the formal image. Manipulable visibility approaches dependent visibility in yet another of its aspects. Musil’s example can again shed light on this latter type of visibility: in the digital image, the fish swims in the only-visible pond in a direction that can be chosen at will – but it always swims in just this chosen direction, in a line fixed through external parameters; it does not choose its direction, it has no will and no desires – nor could it have, being nothing more than a packet of light. The digital image acknowledges only a fish without qualities, which does not appear in nature. Visibility in nature does underpin possibilities for change, yet such changes meet anticipated and unforeseen reactions, run into obstacles and wind up at the edges of what is possible. Visibility outside digital image processing is anything but at our ready disposal. For pure pictorial visibility to be converging in yet another way would therefore mean that what appears in the specifications as full accessibility must again be restricted, that artificial limits must again be deliberately set on unlimited manipulability. Manipulable pure visibility is surpassed by interactive pure visibility.

From the Way of Seeing to Visibility

135

Interaction with pure visibility is realized in computer-supported simulation; Although it, too, processes the image digitally, it represents a step beyond digital image processing in itself.40 Imagine a computer simulation of a fish in a pond. The only-visible fish behaves as if it were a real fish, as if it had other-than-visible qualities as well. It is in fact possible to chase it in various directions, although still within limits. It is possible to lure it with bait. This is the essential difference between simulation and non-interactive digital image processing. A digitized fish can swim at any speed. In becoming a simulated fish, which is also always a digitized fish, it enters into a relation of exchange with the one who has changed it. Not only does the user affect the image, but the image also responds to what the user is doing with pure visibility. Despite being completely without substance, the visibility of a simulation behaves as if it had physical and psychic qualities. In simulation, visibility, de-substantiated through the appearance of images, goes on to acquire artificial substance, to take on patterns of behaviour, resistances and desires. The de-substantiation achieved appears to reverse itself. The appearance rises to a higher power, and in this way paradoxically becomes a form of being. The only-visible fish becomes a fish with qualities. It could look as if it could become autonomous and eat a smaller fish – also only-visible – swimming in the vicinity. Put near a bigger one, it could be eaten – this interaction between user and image is familiar from countless videogames. In fact most videogames are prime examples of the interactive form of pure visibility. They rely on playing with pure visibility as if it were an object that can be grasped and used; that is real. The interaction turns appearance into a special sort of object: into an only-visible thing. The step from the digital image to simulation is comparable to the jump from film to the digital image. In both cases, a new form of visibility becomes possible that no earlier medium was able to achieve. Interactive simulation is developing in increasingly diverse contexts: a new airplane is no longer constructed at a terminal with CAD alone. This is still a procedure used exclusively in digital image processing. The airplane is also flown experimentally on the screen. The latter is, furthermore, a procedure based on feedback between user and image. From the standpoint of formal aesthetics, these techniques show two fundamentally different types of visibility. Imagine an image of an airplane that a viewer can control at will. As long a pure visibility offers no resistance, no change will cause the image to react. Here, any old crate can fly at supersonic speeds, which could never actually happen in the construction of an airplane. The step from digital image to simulation has been taken when pure visibility has taken on a life and behavioural pattern of its own. That is, when the airplane in the

136

The Visibility of the Image

realm of the supersonic falls apart on screen, or just cannot accelerate to that point in the first place. Still, the behaviour of pure visibility as determined by the computer need not correspond to the way it behaves in any reality familiar to human beings. Airplanes can be flown in simulation in multiple realities and conditions that exist only on the screen: This is the step that turns pure visibility into a virtual reality. The physics that describes the laws of non-simulated nature turns into a special physics that describes only the laws of a particular reality. Fiedler’s theory of the development of pure visibility into an independent form of being is transformed into a computer-supported simulation. It is a demonstration of what Fiedler anticipated: ‘From the very object we could not separate from its tactility, we manage to more or less separate visibility as something independent’ (tr) (‘Ursprung’, p 161). As a typology of pure visibility we can confirm: Any image produces a pure form of visibility. Four types appear depending on medium: 1. 2. 3. 4.

the fixed pure visibility of the easel picture, the moving pure visibility of the film, the manipulable pure visibility of the digital image and the interactive pure visibility of the computer simulation.

The intermediate position of photography Photography takes up an intermediate position within the typological system of pure visibility, and a facilitating position in the logic of formal aesthetics’ development. On the one hand, photography’s visibility is as fixed and unmoving as that of any easel picture. Photography was and still is a traditional pictorial medium with which originals are created. Even if this use may be rare, or becoming rare, it should not be judged impossible. On the other hand, photography allows an access to fixed visibility that no easel picture could achieve. The speed and ease with which a photograph is produced, and especially its unlimited reproducibility, support an independent engagement with pure visibility in which the object of the image is as unimportant as the image’s way of seeing. There is no longer any concern about either the depicted object or the way of seeing in any process of reproduction. Neither the ‘what’ nor the ‘how’ is of any interest, since the reproduction does not set out to interpret pure visibility by means of a subjective way of seeing, but simply to duplicate. With the reproduction of an image, the issue is not to produce an image about an image, but to multiply the same image. The reproducibility of photography makes the

From the Way of Seeing to Visibility

137

visibility of any image accessible and independent. This accounts for the special position of photography: it replicates the isolated and fixed pure visibility of an image – including that of an easel picture. Photography, as Walter Benjamin famously pointed out in the essay ‘The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction’ (1936), changes the aesthetic status of the original, in a sense retroactively, without changing the work one bit. By reproducing an easel picture, the pure visibility of the original is released from its tie to a unique image carrier and so to a place. Through photographic reproduction, pure visibility, which is generated subjectively for an original painting and attached to a single support, can be available in unlimited quantities, in the most varied places at the same time. From the standpoint of formal aesthetics, the destruction of an aura, which Benjamin described in detail, is the result of an alienation in purpose: original images, produced for the representation of ways of seeing, are reproduced for their visibility alone. This is the reason a reproduction affects those schooled on the original as alien and in a sense empty. Reproduction works against the intention of more than a few images. The perception of a visible world is the basis of a painted easel picture. But the mode of perception plays no part in the process of reproduction. In replicating images, the single image automatically becomes a purely superficial design. For reproduction processes do not treat images as signs for objects or for ways of seeing, but as purely formal designs of visibility. In the process of reproduction, it is impossible to tell whether what is being reproduced is a pattern or an image. Reproduction’s tendency to give preference to a superficial treatment of an image is reinforced by the mass of everyday images. Only through reproduction techniques has it become possible for people to live in an environment in which vast numbers of images rush through one’s field of vision at a speed reminiscent of a video clip. And if it was always the case that not every image was viewed for its meaning, mass-distributed reproductions lead to more images being used solely as designs of visibility. Photography is the medium suitable for images that one flicks past, that are seen only in passing. With the invention of photography, the technique was found that made it possible to mechanically isolate and multiply the visibility of something quickly. When photography serves to depict its own medium, what it renders visible is no longer ways of seeing, but rather pure visibility. This is not to say that there are no photographs available for hermeneutic consideration. Photography is open to various uses. It negotiates between the easel picture and the digital image by enabling an image to function purely as a

138

The Visibility of the Image

design of visibility. Photography makes it possible for classical images to appear in contexts that would be completely inaccessible to them if only the original was available. The process of mass reproduction leaves only a decorative visibility behind, even of those images that exemplify a notable way of seeing. Think of the Sistine Madonna’s angels:  It would be completely pointless to continue to regard Rafael’s masterpiece reproduced on a T-shirt or a napkin as a contribution to the perceptual psychology of the way human vision is organized. The original once had this function, among others, which can be destroyed by reproduction. On the T-shirt, there is no role for an engagement with a way of seeing. Rafael’s contribution to the development of a Renaissance perspective turns, nolens volens, into a fashion statement, a play with pure visibility. In a way very different from any he imagined, this way of engaging with images, brought about through photography, responds to Fiedler’s call for an understanding of the image as simply a ‘design of visibility’.

The will to media Photography’s intermediate position confirms the basic thinking behind the typology of pure visibility: The only-visible splits away into forms that are not products of artistic activity, but the inventions of new media. Reproducibility is the first step in a technical development towards a medium that puts pure visibility at our disposal. To put it metaphorically: Photography would really prefer to be a digital image, to offer access to pure visibility while it is being viewed. But not even with the most sophisticated improvements can photography achieve this. The step can be made only with the leap into another medium, into digital image processing. On an easel picture, even the most virtuoso artist cannot create an interactive communication with pure visibility, something which any videogame achieves with ease. So the choice of medium takes on a meaning. Before there is any content, it implies a choice of a particular form of pure visibility. This leads to a situation Riegl and Wölfflin could not have fully grasped, and to which they did not fully respond: Since there have been media that are qualitatively varied with respect to visibility, a will to medium has preceded the will to art. It is a matter of deciding which medium to use to depict something. Riegl and Wölfflin considered the pictorial medium to be formally unimportant, since from a formal perspective, the pictorial media they saw offered the same type of pure visibility: The formal qualities of pure visibility do not change depending on whether one makes a print, an oil painting or a watercolour. Exactly this idea is key

From the Way of Seeing to Visibility

139

to the art historical principles: The question of whether something is represented in a painterly or haptic way is not a question of pictorial medium, but of the will to art, that is, of the stylistic use of whichever medium. Any medium is stylistically indeterminate, and so may be used in a painterly or linear form. This is the reason Riegl and Wölfflin could explain that the forms of ways of seeing cannot be defined, either in terms of aesthetic content or in terms of materials. But they did not notice that the forms of visibility are determined by the medium, because they did not consider any alternatives to the fixed visibility of the easel picture. The choices of formal possibilities in the representation process have become more complex. For Riegl and Wölfflin, the one insurmountable question in the process of depiction is whether an object is depicted in a painterly or a linear way. Today, the question of whether an object is depicted in a fixed, moving, manipulable or interactive way is unavoidable as well. To this extent, the types of pure visibility are categories that apply to one of the levels of the art historical principles. Someone producing an image today – whatever it may look like – has had to decide that pure visibility should, for example, be fixed. In everyday life, it is usually just the question of the form of visibility that arises, not the form of representational optics: Shall I take a photograph or make a video? This decision is normally determined by the image’s eventual use. The classical easel picture is and remains unsurpassed as the medium for the question of the way of seeing, the ‘how’ of visibility. Only in the easel picture is visibility locked in, so that one can concentrate on how it looks. For this reason, the easel picture will continue to be one artistic medium among others. As long as human beings want to know how their visible reality looks and can be arranged, they will not be able to avoid using images as cognitive instruments. Only in a still image are the dynamics of the subjective conditions brought to a halt, and one instant, a moment in a development, held fast. This is the way a viewer can engage with one and the same object in an otherwise dizzying multiplicity of appearances. The ways human beings see become communicable and comprehensible. It is very different with film, which can in fact also be used for the representation of momentary conditions and coincidences, but without exhausting its medial possibilities. Unlike a still image, the medium of film permits the development of conditions and matters of fact to be traced. Film is particularly suited to situations in which the logic and necessity of a chain of events needs to be visible. For it is a condition of film that movement occurs in a predetermined form, and this corresponds to the inevitability of developments. In an interactive video game, there is no predictable development.

140

The Visibility of the Image

When interest shifts from the analysis of a way of seeing and the inevitability of developments to the availability and manipulability of visibility, we come back to digital image processing. With electronic image processing, the traditional task of the easel picture, namely to interpret visible reality, loses its monopoly on image-making activity. Along with interpreting visible reality by means of an image comes the surpassing of the interpretation of visible reality by means of an image. Obviously even a computer screen can reproduce an Old Master. A computer can also be used to paint a traditional picture. But computers used in such ways do not exploit the possibilities that open with the advent of digital image processing. It would be like photographing with a film camera – which is actually possible! The specific possibilities of digital image processing lie in the construction and modulation of an object in the visible alone. When the digital medium is used for this, the purpose to which it is suited, the will to understand the way the visible is ordered is displaces by a will to possess and take of control of the visible. This is a shift that ushers in a shift from the hermeneutics of the image to the pragmatics of the image. The meaning of the way of seeing is abandoned, which is the reason most computer images are very unrefined and crude stylistically as well. They present no object for hermeneutics, because there is no interpretation of visible reality to understand in a digital image. Rather than understanding the image, the viewer is meant to use the image; to him, pure visibility is a model without mass.41 Digital image processing turns pure visibility into a new ‘immaterial material’, with which the user shapes, models and constructs on screen as he once could with clay or plaster outside the image. Digital image processing is made to treat pictorial appearance as a form of being. In comparison with non-interactive digital image processing, interactive simulation is paradoxically as much a step forward as a step back. On the one hand, computer simulation makes it possible to use and manipulate pure visibility, which corresponds still more exactly to the use and manipulation of the depicted thing in reality. In simulation, pure visibility begins to behave like dependent visibility or, more exactly, a dependent visibility. But on the other hand, the step from freely available digital visibility processing to simulation is also puts a restriction on the possibilities and freedoms obtained. In simulation, things can no longer be handled as one wishes, but only as the simulated reality permits. A reality principle governs simulation, even if it is not the principle that governs matters outside simulation. This special mixture of restriction and accessibility, of prescription and freedom through pure visibility of simulation is the basis of virtual reality.

From the Way of Seeing to Visibility

141

Virtual reality and cyberspace There are two forms of computer-supported simulation:  the recognizable and the unrecognizable. A  simulation that occurs on the screen is recognizable, because the viewer sees that the simulation concerns an image. An example of this kind of simulation was given above with the airplane that can be test-flown on screen. The only-visible airplane, even if it is just a simplified line drawing, can be recognized as such by the viewer during the simulation without difficulty. The viewer looks from the outside at the image of an airplane in flight, which is simulating its behaviour by means of symbolic language; schematically depicted flames could mean, for example, that the overworked engine had exploded. Screen simulation can also provide views into and from the cockpit. There is a view of a schematically depicted dashboard and one given through the windscreen as well. As perfectly as we see what we would see on the instrument panel and through the window during the flight, in this kind of simulation we see what we see, always as a depiction. There is no danger of confusion. This very thing changes when the simulation is no longer recognizable as such. The phenomenon of a simulation that is not recognizable has, in turn, two forms: as special and as general simulation. A flight simulator, for example, is a special simulator. With this computer-governed machine, it is possible to interact with a machine in an unrecognizable form. From inside the simulator cabin, it is no longer possible to distinguish the cabin from the cockpit of an airplane. Pure visibility is joined by ever-improving pure audibility, tactility, smellability, usability. In artificial form, visibility’s disentanglement is reversed. One can practice the flight of a machine in simulation because the point of contact between computer and the user of the image, the so-called interface, is considered part of the image. Care is taken to see that interaction with the computer from the outside resembles interaction with an airplane.42 General unrecognizable simulation is the last step towards the development of perfect, independent pure visibility. The much-discussed concept of ‘cyberspace’ stands for this phenomenon. Cyberspace technology is concerned with a machine to simulate any situation, that is, with universal simulation technology.43 This is achieved by providing the senses with impressions so apparently real that they are perceived to be perceptions of a physically extant reality. The illusion is achieved by confronting people directly with deceptive sensory stimuli. At the current stage, the viewer of the image still wears data goggles: Images are not seen from a certain distance, as with a television, but projected at a range of just a few centimetres directly into the eye, realizing for the first time an image

142

The Visibility of the Image

form in which the viewer can perceive no frame. It is often rightly said that cyberspace realizes the idea of the panoramic image through other technical possibilities. The interface between computer and user becomes invisible, and with this, the pure visibility of the image becomes absolute. The image is no longer in conflict with a non-pictorial environment that lies beyond the image, because no such environment exists. The image is no longer recognizable as an image; it is the rare case of pure visibility no longer recognizable as a pictorial effect. An only-visible view of a spatial situation is projected directly into the eyes of the viewer. When he moves his head, the collimation shifts in exactly the same way as sensual impressions would if the viewer had moved himself or his head in material reality. Cyberspace is a 360-degree simulation. This is possible because the data goggles are fitted with sensors that report every head movement and change in the line of sight to a calculator, which uses the data to transform pure visibility. This cybernetic feedback can be applied to other senses: Sounds can be simulated with a data helmet, tactile sensations with data gloves, and so on to full data suits. It is clear that the development of cyberspace technology is trying to get at human nerves directly through implants, passing over glasses and gloves. The interface can also be constructed as a socket in the back of the head. Through the electronic stimulation of nerves, something onlyvisible can be produced without any material support being there at all. Imagery is completely dematerialized.* The effect of cyberspace is obvious. A  visible world comes into being that has no materiality, not even that of an image carrier. The viewer not only sees, but moves about in this only-visible world. The pictorial surface becomes the

* At this point, however, we also need to point out that any unrecognizable simulation has limits in principle, limits which cannot be exceeded even in cyberspace. External human senses can all be simulated – at least their simulation is thinkable. Visibility and audibility, tactility, and so on, can be produced without producing the object. But for interior senses and for physiological human needs, a simulation is not practically, but logically impossible, because the simulacrum must take on substantial qualities in order to be a simulacrum. It is meaningful to speak about a simulation only as long as there is an external standpoint from which we can tell that the simulation is not reality. With a flight simulator, this is the view from the outside into the cabin. By walking out of the cabin or taking off the data helmet and data gloves, we can tell that what we had taken earlier to be actual reality was an artificially produced simulation; in fact we have not flown somewhere else in the airplane. In speaking of an unrecognizable simulation, we are referring to the user’s perspective; a simulation in principal, unrecognizable even from the outside, could not and would not need to be designated a simulation, because it would be indistinguishable from reality. One human phenomenon that cannot in principle be simulated because there is no external perspective to make the simulation recognizable as such is nourishment. Even with the simulation of a long-haul flight, any flight simulator reaches a limit. Even the steward serving coffee can be, say, an actor or a contrived robot. But coffee, as artificial as it might be, is still coffee: Artificial food is probably bad food, but still food. But rather than being a bad airplane, a flight simulator is no airplane at all. However perfect cyberspace technology becomes, there will be no virtual food and no virtual air.

From the Way of Seeing to Visibility

143

person’s only environment. He is transported into the space of pure visibility; he can move about freely in it and investigate it in the same way he learnt to investigate visible reality outside simulation. He can grasp a depicted object that is only visible because the computer provides the tactile stimuli that constitute grasping. Virtual reality can be filled with any imaginable objects, including other people – real as well as fictional people.44 No meaningful distinction exists for cyberspace technology between putting an object into the virtual space and letting another person enter – on the contrary: Only then does the technology reveal its peculiarity. Cyberspace is a world of zombies, with only the husks of people; the skin of reality. The dead can live here, without really living, and the living die here without really being dead. This is exactly what is meant when Fiedler says that appearance will turn into a form of being. It is a credit to Fiedler’s imaginative powers that he saw so early how his programme of the only-visible becoming independent would have to end and how it today has ended: with a ‘ghost of reality’ (tr)45 – cyberspace is nothing other than this: a phantom of visibility. When ‘the formal relationships of an art suddenly emerge in isolation’,46 we are faced with a – and Musil saw this even in film – ‘fundamentally strange splitting off [of visibility] from the fullness of life’ (tr) (ibid., p.  1139):  with a ‘mad world’ (tr) (ibid., p. 1140). This mad flaying of the world has its beginnings in any image; it ends in cyberspace, with pure visibility becoming completely absolute. Pure visibility, an aspect of any image, becomes the whole, and so takes the image to its own limit.

Non-symbolic communication Cyberspace is philosophically significant as the apparent discovery of a form of image that cannot be meaningfully discussed as a sign. Fiedler’s aesthetics accomplished preliminary work on this point, too, by giving not a semiotic, but a phenomenological definition of the image as a special form of visibility. This is not at all to suggest that images do not often function as signs for something absent – only that they do not have to! Images can set their semiotic character aside without ceasing to be images. In this respect cyberspace is the experimentum crucis: Here the image abandons its semiotic character without giving up its support of pictorial communication. The development of cyberspace is, in fact, bound up with this goal: non-symbolic communication. Someone asks, ‘Who is Peter?’ This question can be answered in many ways. Peter can be described verbally; or a photograph of Peter might be shown. Both would clearly be symbolic modes of response. We would have a non-symbolic

144

The Visibility of the Image

answer to the question if someone just pointed to Peter and perhaps also said, ‘That’s Peter!’ Of course the sentence ‘That’s Peter!’ has a symbolic nature. But the sentence is not in itself the answer to the question. It only refers to the answer, and that answer is not a symbol of Peter, but Peter himself. From a semiotic standpoint, the situation does not change if the answer is given while Peter is appearing in cyberspace as a ‘ghost’. We can see from this simple example that cyberspace opens a non-symbolic communication – and this in fact programmatically. Jaron Lanier, inventor of the most important technologies needed to realize cyberspace, confirmed this idea as the goal he set in the development of virtual realities in an interview for The Whole Earth Review in 1989: ‘There is an idea I’m very interested in called post-symbolic communication. This means that . . . you really don’t need to describe the world any more because you can simply make any contingency’ (p. 118). Because in cyberspace visible reality is performed rather than described, cyberspace is produced not through an act of depiction, but a process of imitation. We should be aware that the development from easel picture to simulation is linked to a shift in the principle of mimesis. Simulation does not attempt to interpret visible reality, but to isolate the visibility of something in order to present it.47 One might object that for exactly this reason, a simulation is not an image at all. But this objection is based on the assumption that an image must always be a sign, always an interpretive depiction. But if we take into account that cyberspace only isolates an aspect that is also present as part of a depiction, then cyberspace can also be considered a form of imagery. An image interprets and isolates visibility. If we consider the act of semiotic interpretation to be the essential thing, then cyberspace is not an image; if we conversely take phenomenological, pure visibility to be the essential quality of any image, then cyberspace is an image, and in fact an image that consists entirely of pictorial surface. One could also say: simulation continues to be an image because it produces what only images can produce: pure visibility. The development of digital image processing is in any case based on a realization of the autonomy of visibility. This substantiates the understanding of the image that Fielder thought out beforehand: It is possible to construct pure visibility without necessarily having to create a sign. Images that can be read as signs for a way of seeing can also be regarded as constructions of pure visibility.* * This understanding can be expanded further. Boris Groys makes an effort to do this in his essay ‘Die Erzeugung der Sichtbarkeit’ [The Production of Visibility] (1995). He regards all of art from this standpoint: ‘Art is by its nature the making of visibility: The work of art as such is made to be seen’ (tr). But Groys further believes that art can only produce visibility by making something new. Only the new rises above what is already and so makes itself visible. The old, on the other hand, melts into the art historical

From the Way of Seeing to Visibility

145

No image has to be understood as an interpretation; to take an image to be an interpretation is itself an interpretation. By grasping pure visibility as a form of being and not as appearance, Fiedler anticipated the essence of digital image processing and was the first to have the idea of a non-symbolic communication through images. When pure visibility becomes a form of being, the viewer no longer sees a sign with an objective reference, but a special form of visible reality. Visibility’s independence is necessarily bound up with a loss of semiotic qualities. What cyberspace achieves is inherent in any image, and starts to be comprehensible with CAD. Here, visibility is already treated as material that is not more than it is: visibility. We have become accustomed to the idea that the depicted object of an artwork may not be important. Who looks at Cézanne’s apples to see apples? Many images in art are viewed for their style alone. But this formal observation is inadequate for the new pictorial forms of the twentieth century. Particularly in recent developments in the image, one finds a sensual reflection of the step from a way of seeing to visibility. The visible style of a digital image is formally as unimportant as visible apples are to an image of Cézanne’s.

4.3 The disappearance of artistic claims to truth Preliminary remarks In the short essay ‘Moderner Naturalismus und künstlerische Wahrheit’ [Modern Naturalism and Artistic Truth] of 1881, Konrad Fiedler raises the question of

background and remains indistinguishable from it. Groys therefore identifies the artistic production of visibility with the production of something new: ‘Visibility or presence is not a characteristic of an object under consideration as such, but the effect of a relation between this object and its background. Even if we are permitted to see everything that is, there is still a space for innovation, for through innovation new visibilities are produced. [. . .] For visibility that is to be achieved through innovation is, as I said, the effect of a relation between the work of art and its context. In order to produce visibility, it is not absolutely necessary to put a new object of consideration into a normative context, we can also situate a familiar object in a new context’ (tr) (ibid.). The result is that through these interpretations, art forms that would otherwise be very difficult to tie in to this approach are taken to be the production of visibility: Object-Art. For Groys, even ready-mades and installations are attempts to produce visibility, because they create something new in the context of art history. However this is not achieved through a new design of something, as is traditional in art, but only through the design and use of contexts in which a common object is placed. For Groys, the production of visibility in the avant-garde of this century has increasingly moved away from the object and towards work on contexts: What takes shape is not the work of art, but its context. But as persuasive as this understanding of object-art as the production of visibility is, we still need to attend to the phenomenological difference between the visibility of a ready-made as an innovation with respect to the background of art history, and the pure visibility of an image. In a ready-made, the visible object remains materially present and is not pure visibility. So we should consider whether ‘visibility’ produced through contexts and innovation would not be better characterized with the term ‘conspicuousness’.

146

The Visibility of the Image

‘what truth may be in an artistic sense’ (tr) (p. 97). Asking the question is in itself remarkable. One often hears the view expressed that truth claims must be ruled out of a formal understanding of art. This is correct insofar as formal aestheticians do in fact refute concepts in which art, and art alone, is said to open access to a higher, metaphysical form of truth. But it is not true that formal aesthetics is therefore obliged to take the view that the concept of truth does not apply to images at all. Fiedler’s own account of the artistic concept of truth has the disadvantage of being most clear about what artistic truth should not be, namely a naturalistic description of reality. It is nevertheless appropriate to examine how a claim to artistic truth is understood within a formal approach to an image, and how this is affected by the conceptual shift – from an image as a representation of a way of seeing to an image as a design of visibility. We will confirm that the shift from a way of seeing to visibility manifests itself as a disappearance of artistic truth claims, and in this way, by means of a investigating a detail, use the problem of truth to confirm the development under discussion here.

Problems of pictorial truth Language analytical philosophers often raise the issue of whether it is possible for an image to be true at all. Images are said not to assert anything, and only assertions can have the quality of being true or false. It is actually right that an image showing Peter in front of the cathedral in Florence is not identical with the statement: ‘Peter is in Florence.’ For even an image that only depicts one object always depicts infinitely many matters of fact; each depiction of an object offers a vast amount of information about the relationships of the parts of the objects to one another. An image of Peter shows how he holds his arms, how he holds his head. In short, it reproduces the relationship of every depicted part to every other depicted part. In a photograph of Peter in Florence, it may also be possible to see that that the sky is blue, that there are many tourists and doves there. It is not unusual for this fundamental ambiguity of images to be an advantage, for example should one wish to reconstruct a house. This can always be better achieved with an image than with a verbal description of the house,*

* Another difference between images and statements can be mentioned here:  images and conceptual language differ in that in an image there is the possibility that something can be accidentally described, without anyone having been involved; this is excluded from spoken or written language. Accidental description in images did first become possible with photography, but right away one finds countless examples of things going on the background of an image that are there purely by accident, and that no one intended to depict. This sets images made using photographic technologies,

From the Way of Seeing to Visibility

147

even if the house appears in the image by accident. Infinitely many matters of fact are reproduced in any image, each in need of a unique statement: an image says more than a thousand words. An advantage can be a disadvantage in other contexts: an image always shows more than a thousand words say – but it never says a sentence. The existence of any particular matter of fact cannot be asserted by means of an image. It is impossible to set up an image that reproduces only the fact that ‘Peter is in Florence’. And we have not even asked whether an image could negate a matter of fact, or locate it in the past or future. No image can depict what something is not. Only conceptual statements can perform these acts of abstraction, and this can be used to mark an important difference: The image can neither restrict itself to the depiction of a one matter of fact nor assert its existence. But since the question of truth can only be posed meaningfully for an asserted matter of fact, we must either stop talking about the truth of an image – the option is supported by most scientific theorists – or take another meaning from it – this option is defended by most aestheticians. Our daily dealings with images show how this ‘other meaning’ can look.48

Adaequatio imagines ad rem perceptam Despite the essential difference between images and statements, we may ask whether a matter of fact that is not asserted, but still depicted, coincides with something we see. If we are looking at an image of Peter in Florence, it is reasonable to confront the image with questions about whether he was there, whether the weather really was pleasant, whether he really was wearing that jacket, and so on With regard to any matter of fact, it is possible in principle to ask whether the image is true or false, and possibly to answer on the basis of the image. This is a common practice: on seeing an image of a flying saucer, one asks whether this is a true image – and everyone knows what is meant in a familiar and contextual sense by this truth. Hundreds of researchers are engaged every day with the discussion of the truth of images in this sense. As Nelson Goodman was able to put it in his essay ‘On Rightness of Rendering’, not only the truth of a statement but also the truth of images is a function of the right match. An engagement that is not more closely defined by the images themselves leads to a sign including film and video, apart from all other kinds of images. There is no purely accidental object in a painted image; there is always a painter that wanted to paint it in. Even if he wanted to paint something that was supposed to be in that place accidentally, he intends to paint it. For this reason, the recognition of the photographic image as art essentially depends on whether accident is to be accepted as an artistic element. The Dadaists were, as we know, the first to make the claim, and they in turn did not defend photography as an art form for nothing.

148

The Visibility of the Image

being interpreted as matching: if this is the case, then it is true. ‘The truth of statements and the accuracy of descriptions [. . .] is primarily a matter of fit: fit to what is referred to in one way or another, or to other renderings, or to modes and manners of organization’ (p.  138). Unlike Heidegger, Goodman does not seem to want to refute the interpretation of ‘truth as accuracy’, but rather sees it as opening a perspective, of replacing generally speculative talk about ‘truth’ with sober talk about the ‘rightness of fit’ (p. 132): ‘Rather than attempting to subsume descriptive and representational rightness under the truth, we shall do better, I think, to subsume truth along with these under the general notion of rightness of fit’ (p. 132). With respect to these reflections, it has been rightly pointed out that ‘with Goodman, the final decision about what is right becomes the burden of practice’ (tr).49 What fits depends on how one engages with the object to which the question is being put. One’s engagement with an image is not determined by the image itself, but brought in through contexts, interests and prior knowledge. Only a specific practice provides the framework in which something fits something. The concept of accuracy is grounded in a way of living and interacting. It is not necessarily an argument against the use of the concept or accuracy, but it is an exact description of the conditions under which the concept can be used. Even non-objective information about an image, for example the way of seeing, can match. Even for the non-objective information in images there are conventional forms, within which it is by no means arbitrary or relative to confirm that the image matches. A blurry photograph does not say: ‘A short-sighted person’s vision has qualities exemplified in the relations in this image.’ This information is only gained through an interpretation of the image. The practice consists of asking whether the immanent relations in an image correspond to a particular kind of seeing, whether the image as a whole corresponds, on the basis of the way it is made, to a situation as it is seen at a particular moment, under particular conditions. This interpretation does not demand that every part of the image correspond to a part of the object. It is rather about an agreement between the infrastructure of the pictorial surface and the infrastructure of a perceptual syntax. Assuming that works of art are obliged to research perceptual conditions, it is reasonable to regard this structural correspondence between the image and something seen as a kind of artistic truth: adequatio imagines ad rem perceptam.50 The claim of adequatio, which a phenomenon needs in order to be capable of being true in the first place, is not made by any image in itself, but is drawn in through an engagement

From the Way of Seeing to Visibility

149

with the viewer that the image does not specify any more closely. In this sense of truth, many impressionist images show very well, for example, the way in which visible reality appears to human beings when they perceive it in a state of a radical transience and ephemerality. From this example, one also sees that the formal concept of artistic truth is an unpretentious category: It is the accuracy of nonobjective information. This understanding of truth therefore presupposes that any image is to be understood as information and not as expression.

Information instead of expression For Wölfflin, the immanent relations in an artistic image necessarily follow from a particular way of seeing. For him, an artist’s images are always made in the way the artist would have been seeing. The artist’s optical conditions are inevitably recorded in the form of an artistic works. A work of art is, for Wölfflin, always the expression of a particular mode of perception. So for him, the question of truth does not arise. His starting point is, in fact, that the forms of Renaissance and Baroque art were not visual possibilities, but rather the logical result and so the expression of the way people saw at that time; his aesthetic makes a decidedly historical claim. This has already been quoted above: ‘Velasquez saw them [the objects he painted] in such a painterly way’ (Principles, p.  108). Wölfflin does not mean this metaphorically at all. He very clearly takes the view that people at a particular time would not have been able to see in any other way than is shown in the images of the artists of this time, and accordingly he wants to reconstruct the teleological history of vision using visual art. Wölfflin’s historical claims for formal aesthetics have been criticized often and with justification51 – but recently have also being defended in a modified form.52 His thesis, that there are epochal, immutably firm forms of intuition at specific times, and that they determine the style of all artists of these epochs, cannot be defended empirically, and is logically as absurd as the view that only a short-sighted person could make a blurry image. The images of the Renaissance and the Baroque inform us about various ways of seeing. But they do not tell us who and when, to say nothing of whether an entire generation saw in this way – at least not without making some additional purely hypothetical and idealistic assumptions. For the non-objective and the objective content of an image can be equally fictional. Even a person with normal vision can make blurry photographs. We therefore need to treat the non-objective content depicted in an image in the same way as we treat the objective content: not as a reproduced copy of something, but as a deliberately produced depiction of the form of intuition.53

150

The Visibility of the Image

Today, the research of Ernst H. Gombrich, from his famous collection The Image and the Eye. Further Studies in the Psychology of Pictorial Representation of 1982, provides an almost ideal example of treating the non-objective meaning of images in this latter sense. His understanding of the relationship between image and eye, that is between representation and perception is, from a philosophical standpoint, a great advance over Wölfflin’s because he gets free of all speculative assumptions and retains only the portion of Wölfflin’s reflections that argue as information theory does. He repeatedly rejects the assumption that the expression of an age is to be seen in a style.54 For Gombrich, the immanent relations in an image are not necessarily the expression of, but only information about possible ways of seeing.55 He is concerned ‘. . . to scrutinize painting by great masters for the amount of information embodied in their pictures’.56 Yet the accuracy of the non-objective information in images is no more taken for granted than that of the objective information. Gombrich rather works the truth out by comparing structures in the image. In this way he inquires of a great number of very diverse images, for example, whether they correctly reproduce the ambiguity of perception at the edges of an image – whether they match. If the quality of the immanent structures does not correspond, the image is rejected as an inaccurate representation of the structural coherence under investigation. To this end, he draws a comparison between the quality of their immanent relations and the syntax of perception. The result of this search for correspondence, that is, the search for truth, is, for example, that he rejects as false the obvious solution of an image that is simply blurred at its edges: ‘Our photographer Gombrich writes, ‘resorted to the expedient of covering part of his lens with vaseline to get partial blurring of the field, but the results only demonstrate the futility of this device’ (p. 267). It is clear, even from the problems that arise in the pictorial knowledge of ambiguity at the edges of perception, that changes of the condition of the eye, still trivial in the case of short-sightedness, can become an undertaking as complex as it is subtle. It sets a task that is at once a challenge to the sciences of perceptual psychology and to the visual arts. This is formal aesthetics’ main idea within the paradigm of a way of seeing; art and science are not in opposition, but mutually complete one another because in researching visible reality, both make claims to truth: ‘The artistic drive is a drive for knowledge, artistic activity engages the capacity for knowledge, the artistic result is the resulting knowledge’.57

From the Way of Seeing to Visibility

151

Artistic truth as surface coherence It has already been pointed out above that if we see the representational means of artistic images exclusively in a representational relationship to concrete forms of human observation, we will have an insufficient understanding of what an image can do and particularly of what an artistic image sets out to do. Pictorial depiction can free itself from a human way of seeing, and it is characteristic of many works of art to want to be more than an illustrative representation of modalities of perception available to psychological and physiological investigation. It is not unusual in art for the concrete ways people see to be completely unimportant; just as the depicted object can become unimportant. Cubism furnishes many examples of images reproducing not a way of seeing, but forms in which the pure visibility of something can be constructed. It would be absurd to interpret such construction as the condition of the eye, in Wölfflin’s sense. There is an asymmetrical relationship between perception and depiction: there are more possibilities for depicting an object than there are for seeing it. The visibility of something can be constructed in an image without any intention that the construction should represent the way people see this thing. This, the image’s very emancipation from simply illustrating a way of seeing to inventing visibilities, leads to the question of the criteria that can still be used to test truth claims. For an artistic image, which we assume ‘enriches the world by a new kind of perception’ (tr)58 it is impossible in principle to compare the image with a perceptual syntax. For it is exactly per definitionem a new, a constructed type of observation, for which there is no prior example, to which this sketch must stand in depictive correspondence. How can we still speak of artistic truth? Although its title does not exactly give the impression of its being a contribution to the development of the formal observation of images, particularly to the question of artistic truth, the book by the Berlin philosopher Georg Simmel (1858–1918) that appeared in 1900, The Philosophy of Money does this nevertheless.59 A view is defended here that artistic truth is a quality of the relations of the parts of an image to one another. The crucial passage in this respect goes: ‘In what is called the “truth” of a work of art, the mutual relationship of its elements as against its relationship to the object that it depicts is also probably much more significant than is usually acknowledged [. . .] Truth is therefore also a relative concept in the particular context of art. It is realized as a relationship between the elements of a work of art, and not as an exact correspondence between the elements and an external object which constitutes the absolute norm’ (p. 106f.).

152

The Visibility of the Image

Simmel takes the only logical route: The truth of an artwork has to be definable on the basis of the surface syntax alone. One speaks of artistic truth when a special form of the ‘phenomenon of relations’ (p. 107) is given. It is the surface coherence of an image. Simmel even explicitly rejects the view that the criterion for the truth of an artwork would be that a correspondence or correlation is given between the image and the represented object. This kind of relation, he says, applies only to “truth” in the ordinary and substantial sense’ (ibid., p. 107). Here Simmel and Fiedler are in agreement: ‘The creation of inventories of the world’ (tr)60 is not a valid criterion for artistic truth. But even if no correspondence can be established between the representation of a way of seeing as a whole and the structures of a perception, unified coherence is still a truth criterion for an artistic depiction. This way of reading renders the question of an object’s claim to artistic truth identical with the question of its aesthetic success. For the formal observation of images, the question of artistic truth coincides with the question of stylistic coherence. In this way, the perfecting of a style becomes a criterion of artistic truth. For this reason it is not remarkable that Simmel was often accused of aestheticism. A way of seeing is declared true when it is found to be coherent. So, according to Simmel, ‘we can get no impression of either truth or falsehood from single elements in works of fine art or of literature; in isolation they stand outside these categories. Or looking at the matter from the other side: the artist is free as regards initial elements from which the work of art emerges; only after he has chosen a character, a style, an element to colour and form, an atmosphere, do the other parts become predetermined. They have now to meet the expectations aroused by the first step, which may be fantastic, arbitrary and unreal. So long as the elaboration is harmonious and consistent, the whole will produce an impression of “inner truth”, whether or not an individual part corresponds to outward reality and satisfies the claim to “truth” in the ordinary and substantial sense. Truth in a work of art means that as a whole it keeps the promise which one part has, as it were, voluntarily offered us. It may be any one part, since the mutual correspondence of the parts gives the quality of truth to each of them’ (p. 107). This interpretation of artistic truth comes to an ambivalent conclusion: on the one hand, this concept certainly resonates with the basic approach of formal aesthetics and understands artistic truth as a syntactic trait of the pictorial surface. But according to Simmel’s concept, the question of the artistic truth of a work is the same as the question about its aesthetic coherence, its stylistic selfsufficiency and internal relational harmony. This understanding of truth presents

From the Way of Seeing to Visibility

153

another problem: When is the coherence of the pictorial surface given? How can this be established? What Simmel introduces as the criterion of aesthetic truth corresponds to the criterion with which the aesthetic quality of artworks is traditionally judged. But whether the whole work really ‘keeps the promise which one part has, as it were, voluntarily offered us’ (p. 107), as Simmel put it in the last quotation, ultimately remains a question whose answer is as contentious as the question of an object’s aesthetic quality is speculative. In short, we need to see whether another criterion for artistic truth can be found. Contemporary aesthetics provides crucial suggestions in this regard.

Artistic truth as rhetorical success The reception of the idea that works of art follow the invention of ways of seeing has taken many forms in recent aesthetics. A predominant understanding is that it is not enough for a work of art just to represent a way of seeing. If this is the case, no specific difference from a non-artistic representation has yet been established. The image of short-sightedness used earlier also presents a way of seeing. Any pictorial representation can finally be seen this way, as if it showed a way of seeing. For Arthur C. Danto, the situation produces the following relationship between a work of art and something that is not a work of art: ‘Any representation not an artwork can be matched by one that is one, the difference lying in the fact that the artwork uses the way the nonartwork presents its content to make a point about how that content is presented.’61 The symbolic dimension of artistic practice does not suffice to establish a specific artistic form of truth. In addition to the symbolic dimension of artistic form production, a pragmatic concern must be added, one could even say a didactic concern. We demand from an art work whose form symbolizes a way of seeing, as we do not from an illustration of the way of seeing, that this way of seeing be shared with the viewer in a way that changes his way of seeing things. And this is a process of which we can ask, as we can of any pragmatic process, whether it functions or not, in short: whether it is successful. The artistic truth of images is decided by way of the success of a message on a non-objective level of meaning. Art appears as an attack on the viewer’s own mental condition; for this must be changed, should he see the world as it is represented. Even Nelson Goodman, from his language analytic perspective, emphasizes – surprisingly – this pragmatic challenge: ‘What counts as success in achieving accord depends upon what our habits, progressively modified in the face of new encounters and new proposals, adopt as projectable kinds [. . .] A  Mondrian design is right if

154

The Visibility of the Image

projectable as effective in seeing a world’.62 If we start from the idea that the investigation of ways of seeing in art coincides with a genuine rhetorical concern, it becomes possible to describe a concept of artistic truth. It is not enough for works of art to represent the world in some way. Beyond this way of seeing, they must also cause the viewer to see the world with a changed perspective – changed as much as possible in the suggested way: Art – as Danto predictably emphasizes – ‘He must in some marvellous way engage the mind and make it move into the state he intends it to be in. He is not dealing with automata or mere rational beings.’63 The rhetorical-pragmatic dimension is valid only inasmuch as it functions or does not function. Works of art are valid in a way that is fundamentally different way from the way statements are valid for their truth. We cannot justify the validity of art as we would, say, the validity of propositions or actions, it is rather a success in shaping a reality. With the formulation ‘truth of art’ it becomes possible to describe the function of disclosing a world, that is, its capacity to represent and interpret reality in such a way as to also be a way for others. ‘The truth of art’, as Martin Seel formulated it, ‘is the validity of world disclosure’(tr).64 The question is what the validity of world disclosure is. Wilhelm Dilthey rightly pointed out in this regard that for a pragmatic understanding of artistic validity, these are purely ‘questions of influence and power’,65 the principle of which is that a powerful man ‘compels men to see with his eyes’ (ibid, p. 209). In fact the impact of a way of seeing is a criterion that can decide whether to ascribe artistic validity to a work or not.

The missing possibility of being true The pragmatic reading of artistic truth opens a middle way: On the one hand, elaborate speculative claims that some higher form of metaphysical truth is to be found in art are rejected. On the other hand, specific artistic concepts of truth are defended as meaningful. ‘Its truth’, as Fellmann summarized the formal-pragmatic understanding of art, ‘is a function of the capacity to generate regulated vision, and so to inculcate a particular way of seeing’ (tr).66 To put it in another way, we can speak of artistic truth only if art is taken to be the representation of a way of seeing. If art surpasses this function, talk about artistic truth becomes superfluous. The phenomenon of artistic truth is bound to the paradigm of the way of seeing, that is, to images that reflect their way of seeing sensually.

From the Way of Seeing to Visibility

155

But even these last claims to truth disappear when no interpretation of visible reality is to be seen in an image at all, only autonomous designs of visibility. It is not on the basis of the image itself that we affirm or deny an image’s truth claims, but rather on a prior decision to consider the image as representing a way of seeing or as a design of visibility. The interpretation of an image as the representation of a way of seeing arises from a particular understanding of art, without which the question of artistic truth would not arise. When pure visibility has become an independent form of being, this interpretation has reached its limits. The question of artistic truth then becomes as absurd as it would be if directed at an ordinary object. In the case of a video clip, or of a computer animation, or of cyberspace, it is impossible to assume formal, artistic truth: All are beyond a way of seeing, if not in the same way, then to the same extent, and so the conditions for claiming artistic truth are not given. As the way of seeing recedes, so do claims to artistic truth. The emancipation of pure visibility is  – leaving the development of technical media aside  – the result of a willingness to consider artistic truth claims to be unimportant. For the relationship between artistic truth and pure visibility is inversely proportional: As interest in understanding the image as an original work of art dwindles, interest in the image as a structure of pure visibility, that is, as a design achievement, expands. Unlike an artistic achievement in the traditional sense, this does not interpret visible reality, but only – and this ‘only’ is no judgement – to equip it with new visible things. An image that exists only because of its visibility – and depending on one’s point of view this will be regretted as intellectual impoverishment or defended it as an emancipation from unjustified demands – does not claim to be more than can be seen, although more can be seen than is really present.

5

Phenomenological Reduction and Pictorial Abstraction: Maurice Merleau-Ponty (1908–1961)

5.1 Formal aesthetics and reduction Preliminary remarks The intention of formal aesthetics becomes accessible to us only if we recognize the procedure that defines it, namely the reduction of the aesthetic object in its complexity, as a productive philosophical method. Whether the formal observation of an image serves to affirm beauty, trace the logic of a way of seeing, or isolate autonomous visibility, the image is consciously reduced to its infrastructure in each case, and many other aspects of the image – say, the social, art historical or iconological dimensions – are excluded, every formalism is associated with a reduction. Yet it is remarkable that in the writings of formal aesthetics, methodological self-reflection is not centred on the concept of reduction. It is not rare to even get the impression – it is especially the case for Wölfflin – that to concentrate on form is understood to be completely obvious and normal:  as though there were no other way to interact with images, as though people see only a planimetric network of relations in images. One misses a critical awareness of the method, the unspoken assumptions on which formal observation is based. For this reason it is appropriate to illuminate the formal approach form a specifically phenomenological perspective, and in this way to complete its self-understanding. For if there is one philosophy that has discussed the possibilities and the functions of reduction as a philosophical method, then it is the phenomenology founded by Edmund Husserl. This is clear from even a short review of Husserl’s point of view.

158

The Visibility of the Image

Phenomenological reduction For Edmund Husserl, it is characteristic of both scientific and everyday interaction with the world that this world be preconceived as, and assumed to be, real and present. In what he calls the ‘natural attitude’, we are conscious of the world as a present reality.1 This consciousness of reality is the starting point for phenomenological argumentation. In this respect, it shares in the principle of inescapable phenomenality, that is, the view that reality is only ever the intentional content of consciousness. Yet this phenomenal character of reality is not itself in turn the content of consciousness. It is actually that characteristic of natural consciousness to be directed towards something in a way that covers up the quality that the things being taken to be real are things for consciousness. Husserl’s concept of the natural attitude makes reference to something being given in consciousness in such a way that no attention is drawn to the mediation. This dimming out is the norm, the preconceived, self-activating ground of any lived life, requiring no supplementary effort: Without some deliberate effort to change the natural attitude, consciousness is in things. This ‘being-directedtowards-something’, crucial to any intentional structure, therefore constitutes the theme of phenomenology, in particular the theory of reduction. The principle of phenomenological reduction consists of artificially abandoning the natural attitude so as to gain a new perspective on the object. Belief in the existence of an external world, often dismissed as naïve, is rendered inoperative by means of an attitude known as epoché. Epoché is, as Husserl defines it in the Ideas of 1913, the ‘bracketing out’ [Einklammerung] or ‘suppression’ [Ausschaltung] of a belief in existence: ‘We put out of action the general positing that belongs to the essence of the natural attitude’ (§32, p. 61). This, the phenomenologist’s willed disposition, requires a deliberate and extraordinary act.2 Maintaining the epoché, too, demands continuous effort, which is one of the reasons it is not unusual for this attitude to become problematic: ‘The source of all such difficulties lies in the unnatural direction of intuition and thought which phenomenological analysis requires.’3 If Husserl’s concept of epoché at first glance recalls Descartes’s concept of methodical doubt, the formulation ‘for phenomenological analysis’ marks the crucial difference. Husserl is not attempting to overcome the state of epoché by means of phenomenological analysis, but rather to work out from this state. With Descartes, on the other hand, methodical doubt is there to be overcome. In his meditations, Descartes even deliberately adopts the position of a radical sceptic, and doubts the validity of every belief in existence; but the goal of this doubt consists in finding a foundation on which to

Phenomenological Reduction and Pictorial Abstraction

159

build an assertion of existence. Descartes wants to leave the pure immanence of consciousness behind – and to do it as quickly as possible. But Husserl’s goal in bracketing out natural belief in the existence of the world is to stop focusing on what a recognized object is, and concentrate instead on how it is given, that is, to allow structures of consciousness to show themselves and become potential objects of phenomenological description. Phenomenology’s claim to be able to see entities as they have never been seen before therefore depends on the success of the epoché. Epoché can ‘turn one’s regard to the phenomenological field’ – (Ideas, §60, p. 139) just as a gestalt can suddenly change: The look can turn back from consciousness’s object of reference to acts of consciousness themselves, so that in the artificial attitude, the real theme of phenomenology can come into view: the immanent structures of consciousness.

The image as the object of phenomenological reduction After even this short paraphrase of Husserl’s idea of phenomenological reduction, it is easy to interpret formal aesthetics as implementing a phenomenological reduction for a different object. Husserl calls for a reduction of what is immediately given to consciousness. Formal aesthetics is concerned, conversely, with the image. Yet the two phenomena are related in their intentional character. For it is not only objective consciousness that is an intentional consciousness of something; an objective image, too, is an image of something, and so disposes over an intentional character. The parallels between image and consciousness extend further in their common medial transparency. Consciousness is not alone in giving something and as it does, then disappearing into the background as the giving medium. The image, too, shows an object; that is, it produces consciousness, without drawing attention to itself as a material object. This idea, having by now become almost a commonplace as ‘the transparency of the image’, is among the classical phenomenological insights. It is clear where these parallels between image and consciousness lead: The observation of an image, too, involves a natural attitude, or as Husserl says in his lecture ‘Phantasy and Image Consciousness’ of 1904–1905: ‘In normal contemplation of the picture I live in the image consciousness. In that case, I focus my attention on something entirely different’ (p. 48). We have a normal observation of an image when the viewer is looking at the image not in order to see the material object that is present, the canvas or the paper, but rather the absent, depicted object, the so-called image object. A person looking at an image without interest, as is normally the case in looking through an album of photographs, is

160

The Visibility of the Image

observing an absent world – but still a world and not a piece of paper. This does not mean that the image cannot also be viewed as a material object. Any image is visible in two aspects: as something that depicts and as something depicted.* Landscapes of kilometres unfold on a piece of paper of a few square centimetres; both aspects can be observed. But an image is considered a depiction of something in the sense under discussion here only if we are looking not at, but through the surface of the image.4 Because of its intentional character, an image is an object that allows a phenomenological reduction to be carried out. An artificial attitude can be taken towards even an image, in the hope of in this way discovering aspects whose character it is to be overlooked in normal pictorial observation. Although the suitability of images for reduction seems so clear, Husserl himself never suggested or implemented it. In this respect, the studies of the Frenchman Maurice Merleau-Ponty (1908–1961) are ground-breaking. Especially in his late essays, Merleau-Ponty explained in detail that not only the image, but also every linguistic phenomenon should be submitted to a phenomenological reduction, since medial self-denial is characteristic of any linguistic message. In The Prose of the World, which Merleau-Ponty wrote in the early 1950s and which was published in 1969, it says, ‘When someone [. . .] succeeds in expressing himself, the signs are immediately forgotten; all that remains is the meaning. The perfection of language lies in its capacity to pass unnoticed’ (p. 10). Merleau-Ponty himself confirms the structural affinity of language to consciousness – in principle in this context – by emphasizing that the intentional orientation of an image, ‘just as perception takes us to things themselves’ (ibid., p. 14). His conclusion from this analogy is clear:  ‘If we want to understand language in its original mode of signifying, we shall have to pretend never to have spoken. We must perform

* This double visibility – as Husserl shows in his image lecture – is in a relationship of mutual antagonism, and it is just this that accounts for the special way things are given in pictorial depiction: ‘The appearance belonging to the image object is distinguished in one point from the normal perceptual appearance. This is an essential point that makes it impossible for us to view the appearance belonging to the image object as a normal perception: It bears within itself the characteristic of unreality, of conflict with the actual present. The perception of the surroundings, the perception in which the actual present becomes constituted for us, continues on through the frame and then signifies “printed paper” or “painted canvas” ’ (p. 51). ‘And yet it belongs to these apprehension contents: in short, there is conflict. But in a peculiar way. The image object does triumph, insofar as it comes to appearance. The apprehension contents are permeated by the image-object apprehension; they fuse into the unity of the appearance. But the other apprehension is still there; it has its normal, stable, connection with the appearance of the surroundings. Perception gives the characteristic of present reality. The surroundings are real surroundings; the paper, too, is something actually present. The image appears, but it conflicts with what is actually present. It is therefore merely an ‘image’; however much it appears, it is a nothing [ein Nichts]’ (Phantasy, Image Consciousness, and Memory, 1898– 1925, p. 50).

Phenomenological Reduction and Pictorial Abstraction

161

a reduction upon language, without which it would still be hidden from our view – leading us back to what signifies. We should look at language the way deaf people look at those who are speaking. We should compare the art of language with other arts of expression which do not have recourse to language and try to see language as one of those mute arts’ (ibid., p. 46). Against this background, we can understand how a purely formal observation of the image is justified. It is not about treating the image as an ornament, but about the effort to describe, by bracketing out the relationship to the referent, aspects of the image that are not the subject of attention. We should not overlook Fiedler’s call, even before Husserl, ‘to grasp that seeing as such can come into its own only when every relationship to any objectivity that is in any sense perceptible has disappeared from it’ (tr).5 Yet what formed the core of his writings was not, as it was for Husserl, the elaboration of this methodological challenge, but rather the implementation of this method, the description of what one sees when one is not looking at the referent of an image. This applies equally to Wölfflin’s theory of art historical principles. If Wölfflin observes an image ‘naively’, that is, without reflecting on the attitude that is conditioning his observation, then it is certainly a phenomenological naivety in observing images: bracketing out the relationship to the referent. It is characteristic of the formal approach to describe the image from an unnatural attitude. For normally we see an image not as just a system of immanent relations, but as a representation of contents. Epoché is meant to alter this seeing so that we can better understand the image as a medium that constructs meaning. By means of the epoché, the place where the meaning of the image is generated, namely the surface of the image, is observed – or better, becomes observable.

The surface of the image From a phenomenological perspective, the surface of an image is in fact a special problem. We must be aware that it is as much an aspect of the material depicting as it of what is immaterially depicted. For on the one hand, the pictorial surface is the ‘touchable’ outer edge of a physical object. Familiar methods of describing material characteristics may be used to describe it. So to point out that something is painted canvas or printed paper is undoubtedly to give one kind of description of a pictorial surface; using scientific methods, such surface details can be made specific. But such descriptions sidestep the essential issue, that the object of description is a representation, which it to say that it has an intentional structure. We must therefore also be aware that the pictorial surface

162

The Visibility of the Image

is the place where the immaterial representation of something absent appears. The reverse side of an image is not a pictorial surface, even though it is materially bound to the front side. Here we can already see how a pictorial surface resists a scientific approach. No physical examination, however rigorous, can come to the conclusion that a painted surface is the surface of an image and not that of a painted object. Only if an object is examined as a representation of something can we be sure that we are looking at a pictorial surface, or, to put it more exactly: that we are seeing through, overlooking the pictorial surface in its materiality; this pictorial surface has no reverse side. It is a phenomenon that is not visible, but rather must be made visible, and in fact made visible after it has been seen through. The infrastructure of an image belongs to the terrain Husserl calls ‘the invisible’.6 It can be described, just as the lenses can be described, in two ways. There seems to be a difference between describing a lens from a physical perspective, pointing out that it is round and that it has a pronounced curvature, and drawing attention to it by trying to describe it while looking through it. That is typical of phenomenology. The phrase ‘to the things themselves’ insists not on a scientific turn in philosophy, but rather always on a description of things as they are given for a subject: as they are if they are a phenomenon.* To meet the requirement, a lens would have to be looked through, even if no relevance has been established to the object being viewed. One can also say that the qualities that phenomenology wants to describe must first be turned into visible phenomena by means of a reduction. It is problematical to do this with an image, for an image resists superficial observation. It takes artificial effort to observe it formally. Jean-Paul Sartre (1905–1980) described this with all desirable clarity

* In the area of aesthetics, the positioning of this phenomenological phrase has introduced a turn back towards the aesthetic object, which, from a contemporary standpoint, looks like a new version of the programme proposed by Herbart and Zimmermann. In phenomenological aesthetics, one finds the same resistance to anchoring philosophical aesthetics in metaphysical systems that is characteristic of the beginnings of formal aesthetics. Both aesthetics arise from the same position with respect to speculative philosophy. We can see this clearly in the first sentences of Donald Brinkmann’s book Natur und Kunst. Zur Phänomenologie des ästhetischen Gegenstandes [Nature and Art. On the Phenomenology of the Aesthetic Object] of 1938; except for the mention of Husserl, they could be Zimmermann’s: ‘With respect to all traditional constructive “theories”, the phenomenological aesthetic proposed here adopts Husserl’s call “to the things” in the form of “back to the aesthetic object”. Far from retaining traditional constructive aestheticians’ concern with resolving or explaining or understanding the mystery of the aesthetic object, a critical phenomenological aesthetic is content to rediscover, under all the constructive accessories, the object in its qualitative being, and so to present it in its full mystery and contradiction for the first time. In other words, it sets out to restore to aesthetics its object, which it had lost through systematic bias over time, and to point out the way this recovery of the object can be achieved’ (S. V.). In light of this fundamental agreement in position, is it not surprising that Brinkmann further confirms the idea defended in this chapter: ‘Wölfflin’s theory [has] [. . .] the greatest significance for a phenomenology of aesthetic objects’ (ibid., p. 141).

Phenomenological Reduction and Pictorial Abstraction

163

in his phenomenological study The Imaginary (1940): ‘A picture spontaneously offers itself in relief to the imaging consciousness, and the perceptual consciousness would have great difficulty seeing it as flat’ (p. 50). Formal aesthetics is the attempt to see the image as a surface, so as to turn the surface of an image into a phenomenon. It is concerned with a process of aestheticizing, that is, of sensitizing to the an-aesthetic aspects of an image. The concept of the an-aesthetic, much-discussed at present, corresponds to the actual status of formal aesthetics. The goal is an inversion of the image’s immanent relation of aesthetic to an-aesthetic.* The power of the image to draw the look through the surface to what is represented is artificially disempowered through epoché, so that it can, after the look has come to rest on what is represented, resurface from the depths, so to speak, not directly from the front, but from behind, to the surface. This detour – to the represented thing and back to the surface – is necessary; for the formal observation of an image out from the epoché leads to a way of looking at the image that is different from what would be produced in a crude-formal way of looking that no longer takes what is represented into account at all. This last would reduce the image to an ornament or just a pattern, but formal aesthetics – because it brackets out, rather than ignoring the semantic dimension – treats the image as an empty syntactic structure, like a mathematical formula. A person engaged in this kind of formal observation knows that what it is describing is an aspect of an image, that the surface not only possesses decorative qualities, but also displays a pictorial language suitable for making an absent object visible. So it produces, by means of the epoché, an artificial look at the image that opens the narrow path between a description of * Wolfgang Welsch speaks of an ‘aesthetic-anaesthetic relation in every mode of perception’ within the phenomenological tradition (Ästhetisches Denken [Aesthetic Thinking]), p.  33. This refers to the presumed contents: ‘One sees visible objects, not seeing or visibility. Actual perception is related to objects, pushes forward, and is efficient for this very reason. Of course this means that a kind of anaesthetic is inscribed in perception itself. Its own specificity  – its schemata and character, including the limitations they entail – remains curiously hidden from it’ (ibid., p. 33f.). In applying this – for now terminological – suggestion to formal aesthetics, the implications are clear: An almost paradoxical situation arises. In phenomenological considerations, medial communication is not theorized to the same extent as is the perception of objects or images. In viewing an image, the stylistic structures are unthematic, that is, for Welsch they are not aesthetic, if the concept ‘aesthetic’ is understood in the original Greek sense of ‘perceived’ — but formal aesthetics is concerned with these very aspects: Formal aesthetics is, in the contemporary understanding, an anaesthetics. Formal aesthetics is concerned with the object of contemporary anaesthetics: The schemata and character of a perception Welsch is referring to correspond to the theme of formal aesthetics, which is to say anaesthetics. This makes it clear that the demand for an anaesthetics is not merely terminological. ‘Anaesthetics’ is meant to express the possibility that the unthematized reverse side, the anaesthetic aspects could be more relevant than the visible ones. ‘To put it briefly, anaesthetics has to do with the reverse side of aesthetics’ (tr) (p. 10). In fact Wölfflin’s results from the example of stylistic phenomena confirm Welsch’s programmatically formulated hope that turning to anaesthetics will serve to clarify aesthetics.

164

The Visibility of the Image

the work that is materialistic – directed solely towards the physical work – and one that is idealistic – directed solely towards the content: ‘In the last analysis, phenomenology is neither a materialism nor a philosophy of mind. Its proper work is to unveil the pre-theoretical layer on which both of these idealizations find their relative justification and are gone beyond.7 If we keep in mind that the pictorial examples from Wölfflin’s Principles of Art History would serve their argumentative function equally well if they were reproduced upside down, we have a clear instance of what Husserl described as a truly unnatural way of looking. Qualities of style are purely phenomenological qualities of a pictorial surface, for they are completely inaccessible to the natural sciences; style cannot be measured. This becomes clear even in the relational qualities that finally constitute style, for example the painterly and the linear. Every visible transition from one form to another is painterly if we can just get close enough, with the aid of a microscope, and every transition appears linear if we are only far enough away. We can see the quality of a pictorial surface only by looking at it from the same distance needed to see the represented object properly. For this reason Merleau-Ponty, too, stresses the importance of the correct distance. For we can only understand it phenomenologically: ‘Anyone observing the painter too closely, with his nose on the brush, would see only the reverse side of his work. The other side is this thin stroke of black, the place is the great sun spot that he begins to circumscribe’ (Prose, p. 44). The right distance must be maintained, but it does not matter which way the image is hung. From this we can see that the an-aesthetic structural qualities of an image do in fact depend on content, but not one concrete content. The formalization of an image changes the status of the content:  Specific content becomes unspecific. The painterly, planar, unified, clear and a-tectonic structural quality of an image seen upside down is no longer recognizable, or not so clearly recognizable as it is in one that is hanging correctly. In fact if the images in Wölfflin’s Principles of Art History really were turned upside down, it would ease the demands the formal mode of viewing makes on the viewer.* The artificial, that is to say phenomenological view of images in Wölfflin’s argument would then become clear more quickly. Wölfflin’s doctoral supervisor, Johannes Volkelt, was correct in supposing that ‘the attitude of an aesthetician in Herbart’s sense is phenomenological’ (tr).8 * This method is actually very widely used in graphology. There, texts are turned upside down during formal analysis, so that the viewer does not become a reader.

Phenomenological Reduction and Pictorial Abstraction

165

5.2 Visibility as quiddity The problem of phenomenological reduction That the idea of a phenomenological reduction can be applied to an image is significant for the way phenomenology is understood in principle, in whatever way phenomenology in principle is practiced. At first glance, one could get the idea from formal aesthetics that an image is just one more possible object that can be examined using phenomenological instruments. But this interpretation quickly reaches its limits. It does not take the objective connection between aesthetics and phenomenology into account. In contrast to the epoché during the viewing of an image, Husserl’s concept of a reduction of what is immediately given to consciousness is fundamentally difficult. With this in mind, the role of the image as an object of phenomenological observation changes abruptly. If Husserl’s original idea of phenomenological reduction is tangled up in aporias, it means that the idea of an epoché as such is meaningful only for the observation of an image. Husserl himself leaves no doubt that the reduction should turn the phenomenologist’s attention to the subject: ‘If I put myself above all this life and refrain from doing any believing that takes “the world” straightforwardly as existing – if I direct my attention to this life itself, as consciousness of “the” world, I thereby acquire myself as the pure ego, with the pure stream of my cogitationes.’9 By disabling natural belief in the world by means of the epoché, the subject Husserl calls transcendent or pure is supposed to appear to the phenomenologist. The reason for referring to the subject in this way lies in phenomenology’s claim: Reduction is not to be understood as a psychology of the empirical and therefore always individual subject, rather it sets out, in its eidetic vision, to experience the possibilities of consciousness in principle. Following his transcendental turn in the Ideas of 1913, Husserl also pursued his programme of categorical knowledge into the subject. He extends the eidetic of external objects, that is, seeing the general in the particular, with an eidetic of internal experience, that is, a seeing of transcendental principles. The explicit goal of phenomenological reduction is to draw principles of consciousness out of empirical consciousness. The crucial thing about phenomenological reduction is that its results should take a form of universal validity by originary intuition, setting it apart from conceptual abstraction. Husserl believes that fundamental principles can be observed in consciousness. To turn one’s attention from the content of consciousness to acts of consciousness – from noemata to noesen – is not to be understood as a psychologism,

166

The Visibility of the Image

which attempts to explain the objectivity of the world from empirical contents, but rather as a new instance of transcendental philosophy that does not deduce, as Kant does, the logical conditions of possibility, but rather itself becomes the object of a transcendental experience. It is about seeing the general in the particular, not only in an eidetic variation of objects (as it is even in the Logical Investigations) but with consciousness itself. In the epoché, the reality judged to be real in the natural attitude is to develop from possibilities of acts of consciousness experienced. Husserl’s students in Göttingen rightly found it difficult to reconcile the turn to transcendental philosophy with phenomenology’s original impetus to focus on the things themselves. Phenomenological reduction further seeks to describe and make evident the real world in its consciousnessconstituting processes more or less from the inside – not to construct it. As understandable as Husserl’s ambitious expectations for reduction are, the practice remains ambiguous. If the direct experience of an object undergoes reduction, the reduction changes the objective experience in a way that comes out as a judgement of the experience, as a purely subjective experience that manifests itself in the perceptual judgment. Through the epoché, the observation ‘The book is red’ turns into ‘I see red and interpret this as a book’. But this change in position does not afford greater insight into the state of affairs that is the content of the object, nor does it open on to a conception of transcendental subjectivity. The problems with reduction as the eidetic vision of a pure ego are of a fundamental kind: The laws governing the way experience is constructed cannot become an object of experience, for no phenomenologist has the skill to disable himself as a real subject of assertion. At best, the reduction concludes with a statement about what an empirical consciousness experiences at one moment. But this is insufficient, since what a reduction is supposed to make clearly accessible is not an empirical experience, but rather subjective rules governing the formation of experience, cleansed of all individuality and subjectivity. The problem is, and MerleauPonty proposed to challenge Husserl about it as early as 1945 in Phenomenology of Perception, that one’s own subjectivity is unavoidable: ‘The most important lesson which the reduction teaches us is the impossibility of a complete reduction. This is why Husserl is constantly reexamining the possibility of the reduction. If we were absolute mind, the reduction would present no problem’ (p. xiv). For if reduction leads to an awareness of the existence of the empirical subject, then the problem of achieving a complete reduction shifts over to the question about switching off the reality of the empirical subject. But this is logically impossible. As radical as reduction may be, there will still be psychological assertions about empirical subjects – assertions formulated in the natural attitude, that is, in a belief

Phenomenological Reduction and Pictorial Abstraction

167

in the existence of the ego in question. And how could it be otherwise? For the self, whose existence must be ignored by the phenomenologist in the eidetic vision of transcendental acts, is identical to the phenomenologist’s self. Belief in one’s own existence cannot be disabled or bracketed out, because existence is always part of self-consciousness: cogito ergo sum. The theory of reduction must therefore end in the aporia: ‘No one knows what “my pure consciousness” really means. For as long as consciousness is mine, that is, empirical, it is not pure, and if a consciousness is pure, that is, “consciousness as such”, then it is not empirical. This is the dilemma of transcendental phenomenology. It does not strive for introspection. That would be psychology, which would undermine the validity claims to which phenomenology holds firmly. All the same, phenomenology remains oriented to the subjective side of active cognition. How is it possible? Subjectivity without subjectivism – that is the unresolved mystery of the reduction’ (tr).10

Between subject and object: The pictorial surface These problems with reduction of direct consciousness of an object ask for the reason it is the possible, through epoché, to reduce the image during viewing. Is representation significantly different from perception in terms of its suitability to be an object of phenomenological reduction? Representations, whether texts or images, are particularly suitable for phenomenological reduction. The reason is that with them, epoché does not focus attention entirely on the subject of the observation, but rather permits some consideration of an aspect of the work that is not thematic. Phenomenological reduction avoids subjectivism exactly when it – like hermeneutics – deals exclusively with mediated experience, because here, after the reduction, an awareness of the instance of mediation persists. With an image, the phenomenologist is with the image even after the reduction. The epoché does not lead the receiver of the image to an aesthetic of reception, an awareness of aesthetic experience, but rather to awareness at another level that mediates between him and what is represented: the pictorial surface. The surface of the image is a phenomenon that is positioned between the object and the subject as the image is being perceived, and so affords the possibility of stopping, in the process of reduction, before stepping back into in pure subjectivity. The basis for this is that to bracket out what is represented while viewing a representation can only ever be to complete the process, given by the image itself, of de-realization of what is represented. When an image is submitted to a phenomenological reduction, it is an attempt to see the image itself as a form of reduction, which is to say, as de-realization.

168

The Visibility of the Image

Fiedler’s theory of pure, pictorial visibility does not propose anything different. To represent reality means to ‘reduce’ reality to its pure visibility. His aesthetic, seen in this way, performs a phenomenological reduction of the image to the extent it characterizes the de-substantiation of visibility that is immanent in an image as pure visibility. In ‘Eye and Mind’ (1961), Merleau-Ponty can only repeat Fiedler’s main idea about images: ‘They present the object by its outside, or its envelope’ (p. 172). The reason is clear: ‘to make us see the visible’ (ibid., p. 166). We must understand the call for a phenomenological reduction of pictorial consciousness as the theoretical reflection of a de-realization already achieved in artistic practice. From this perspective we can understand why it was almost inevitable that the epoché would reveal its strengths in formal aesthetics. Only in an image can reduction expose a phenomenon that cannot be grasped materially or idealistically: This is style – and here once again Merleau-Ponty’s view coincides with formal aesthetics, particularly with Wölfflin’s.11 As the formalists emphasized again and again, the form visible on the surface, the infrastructure of an image, is misunderstood if it is considered to be just an ornamental pattern. MerleauPonty’s response to formalism is telling in this respect. He, too, worked with a widespread but unfounded concept of formalism, and wrote, very aptly:  ‘It is certainly correct to condemn formalism, but it is usually forgotten that formalism’s error is not that it overestimates form but that it esteems form so little that it abstracts it from meaning’ (Prose, p. 89). At least the writings of Fiedler and Wölfflin are enough to show that the theories worked out in formal aesthetics are completely in accord with phenomenology: They, too, describe style as the product of a transcendental reduction and so as the condition of possibility of using an image to refer to something outside the image.12 In this respect, too, all that was left for Merleau-Ponty to do was to condense the formal understanding of style into a short phrase: ‘Style is what makes all signification possible’ (Prose, p. 58). So the image fulfils even Husserl’s transcendental philosophical expectations for phenomenological reduction. By looking away from the ‘what’ in an image, we come to see the structures that make it possible for an image to have meaning.

Intra-ontology If we ask what we can conclude from the knowledge that unlike the reduction of perception, the reduction of an image works, two alternatives present themselves: On the one had, the suitability of images for phenomenological reduction can be used as an argument for restricting phenomenology to the treatment of

Phenomenological Reduction and Pictorial Abstraction

169

these objects. The critique of Husserl’s idea that it is possible to submit things immediately given to consciousness to reduction would then go: Reduction can only ever be implemented with what is represented, for there it is inherent in the object. The unattractive consequence of this alternative is that phenomenology, as a method exclusive to aesthetics, would languish. Alternatively, there is the possibility of understanding the suitability of images to phenomenological reduction as a need to change Husserl’s understanding of phenomenology as shaped by his concept of reduction, and to develop it further in an aesthetic sense. That is, we could take, from images’ suitability to phenomenological reduction, the idea of conceiving of phenomenology as aesthetic theory. This seems to be the way Merleau-Ponty wants to go. Merleau-Ponty addresses his relationship to Husserl’s theory of reduction in detail in the essay ‘The Philosopher and His Shadow’, which appeared in 1959. The main idea in this essay is given in the title. Only it would be very inadequately understood if one were to read it as just a modest biographical indication that Merleau-Ponty does not find his connection to Husserl to be very substantial. The concept of the shadow is meant to guide the reinterpretation of idea of phenomenological reduction. This becomes clear when we recall Merleau-Ponty’s objections to Husserl’s concept of reduction. Merleau-Ponty doubts the existence of the ‘singular beings’ (p. 165) that Husserl set out to find in a transcendental experience by means of a reduction. He writes critically of Husserl’s theories of reduction: ‘They look deeper down for the fundamental’ (ibid., p. 163). This is a valid objection. Husserl does in fact try to disclose, by means of reduction, a realm of knowledge he himself calls ‘ideas’, and in doing so recalls Plato. Reduction is said to make it possible to experience a reality that grounds visible reality like an essence. This is where Merleau-Ponty begins his development of phenomenology. He relocates the goal of phenomenological reduction: from a vision of ideas to a vision of a shadow. Rather than looking at ideas themselves, a philosopher looks at that which proceeds from the ideas: their visible shadows. Phenomenology is not to leave Plato’s cave, but to be this cave’s philosophy. In Merleau-Ponty, ‘shadow’ can be read as the metaphorical conception of that which he, in contrast to Husserl, expects to disclose from the reduction. Shadows always remain bound to the presence of the objects of which they are shadows, and are in this way distinguished from traces. They cannot get free of things. With a shadow, one can always be certain, to this extent, of seeing something between an object and a subject. Shadows only exist within this tension. They are the insubstantial phenomena that exist only between something’s being-in-itself and a subject’s being-for-itself.

170

The Visibility of the Image

It is often inconspicuous words that show the concerns of a philosophy. The frequency with which ‘between’ becomes central in Merleau-Ponty’s writing is noticeable, and stylistically emphasizes his phenomenological concern with transitional areas. In this respect, the reduction of the image serves as a model of an aesthetically transformed phenomenological reduction. Since reduction of the image reveals the pictorial surface as a phenomenon lying between the ideal represented content and the observer looking on, the reduction of the direct awareness of the object cannot end in the subject, but must contend with the phenomenon that mediates between subject and object. The late phenomenology of Merleau-Ponty is – cum grano salis – wholly taken up with an inquiry into such – as he himself says – ‘hinges of being’13 between the objective and the subjective: ‘There is undeniably something between transcendent Nature, naturalism’s being in itself, and the immanence of mind, its acts, and its noema. It is into this interval that we must try to advance’ (ibid., p. 166).’14 When, in light of this programmatic challenge, we recall Husserl’s view – ‘In so far as their respective senses are concerned, a veritable abyss yawns between consciousness and reality’ (Ideas, p.  111)  – the difference between these two thinkers seems substantial. With Husserl, the disabling of a belief in the objective world can only lead to the subjective, since he does not know or does not identify any intermediate phenomena. Merleau-Ponty, by contrast, schooled in the observation of the image, takes hold of reduction as the very method with which to recognize an unrecognized reality between subject and object – or better said: a reality that is subjective and objective to the same extent. In this Merleau-Ponty actually accounts for just one of Husserl’s original ideas, one he thinks Husserl himself did not take into account systematically enough through the course of his development. It is the idea that for phenomenology, the essence of a thing cannot be something that lies behind the appearance, but a phenomenon that shows itself in the appearance. It is characteristic of Merleau-Ponty’s style to designate the subject of his fragmentary posthumous text The Visible and the Invisible, which appeared in the years 1959 and 1960, as ‘intra-ontologie’ (p. 225). Phenomenology – one could speak of a new form of ontology – is to investigate realities that subvert the subject-object duality. Merleau-Ponty finds two great topics for his intra-ontology:  visibility and the body. Both phenomena are, for MerleauPonty, an answer to the question of what bridges the duality of consciousness and being. Visibility is always the visibility of an object for a subject; the body is the physicality of a subject. In the natural attitude, neither comes to mind. Life is

Phenomenological Reduction and Pictorial Abstraction

171

normally lived in things to such an extent that neither the visibility of things nor the body is experienced as an issue. It is astonishing how little we know of the way something looks if we live and deal with that thing undisturbed. Only by bracketing reality out, and so always and in fact primarily putting an end to all pragmatic living of life, does one get a view of the pure visibility of a thing and of one’s own body. And there are further structural affinities between the body and visibility. For the body itself has an inner constitution of visibility, that is, it is always a body that sees as much as it is seen. For Merleau-Ponty, the visibility of the world is – and this is reminiscent of Schopenhauer – the world’s physicality:  ‘From now on the body stands for things themselves being visible and becoming visible’(tr).15 These reflections show, for Merleau-Ponty, that visibility is more than the effort to provide phenomenology with a new topic of study, supplementing others. The turn to visibility expresses an understanding of phenomenology that has been modified in response to Husserl, distancing itself from eidetic vision, although Merleau-Ponty has no intention of leaving the reduction behind. For him, visibility rather becomes the new phenomenological quiddity of reality: ‘The world is what we see’ (The Visible and the Invisible, p. 3).16 Phenomenology therefore has to investigate what I  perceive. For Merleau-Ponty, phenomenology is the same as the theory of visibility. So from a historical point of view, the phenomenological discussion fifty years after Fiedler approaches one of his basic ideas: If an object loses its reality, which is to say that it is undergoing phenomenological analysis, nothing will remain of it but its pure visibility. Visibility is the genuine topic of phenomenology, just as formal aesthetics is, conversely, phenomenology avant la lettre.

5.3 The abstract image Preliminary remarks In committing phenomenology to an inquiry into visibility, Merleau-Ponty brought it closer to the practice of art than it had ever been before. For MerleauPonty, phenomenology addresses the same issues as painting: ‘In whatever civilization it is born, from whatever beliefs, motives or thoughts, no matter what ceremonies surround it – and even when it appears devoted to something else – from Lascaux to our time, pure or impure, figurative or not, painting celebrates no other enigma but that of visibility.’17 In light of phenomenology’s and painting’s

172

The Visibility of the Image

shared subject matter, the question arises  – in particular after Merleau-Ponty located phenomenology so clearly in relation to the image – whether painting conversely adopts phenomenological considerations of its own, that is, whether such considerations can be reflected in paintings. Merleau-Ponty may not have examined this problematic with perfect clarity, but his desire to have understood as a phenomenological reduction says a great deal:  ‘With what is abstract art concerned, if not with a certain way of rejecting or denying the world?’ (tr) (La Prose du Monde, p. 89).* The step towards giving up objective content altogether, taken by artists such as Henry van de Velde, Adolf Hölzel, Wassily Kandinsky at the beginning of the twentieth century, presumes a pictorial understanding that could make such a step even thinkable.18 It is worth the effort to base the development of the abstract image in genuinely phenomenological argumentation, although without referring to specific artists, as in art history. The point is to show that it is possible and obvious to step from a phenomenological understanding of an image to an abstract image. At issue is an abstract image that presumes not to imitate any visible reality. An abstract image is of special interest to formal image theory only if one takes strictly the absence of reference to any real or fictional object as a starting point. For an image that does not resemble any object, that does not isolate the visibility of any object, raises the question of how it is an image at all.

The sacrifice of objects Although fish are not among the most significant themes in the visual arts, images of fish make extraordinarily good examples for explicating formal differences among types of images. In the last chapter, four types of pure visibility were identified in this way following on from Robert Musil’s example of a fish in a pond of only-visibility: the easel picture, fixed; the film, dynamic; the digital image, manipulable; simulation, presenting an interactive fish. From MerleauPonty’s phenomenological perspective, this model cannot yet be complete. This division does not include the pictorial type of pure visibility in which the fish swims out the picture entirely. For Merleau-Ponty, this is exactly what happens with an abstract image: ‘But the painter throws away the fish and keeps the net’ (Prose, p. 47). * This question did not appear in the English translation (Heinemann, 1974) and has been translated from the French.

Phenomenological Reduction and Pictorial Abstraction

173

As is often the case with Merleau-Ponty, an understanding of his reflections on this point depends on a metaphor. In what respect can an abstract image be understood as a leftover net? And there are further difficulties in understanding this statement, for it is not enough to clarify the purely metaphorical meaning of ‘net’: It is rather the particularity of the subtle formulation ‘keeps the net’ that simultaneously gives, by means of ambiguity, two different but complementary answers to the question of what an abstract image is, two answers that add up to one answer. In order to understand what is left over for Merleau-Ponty when there is no longer any recognizable object, the word ‘net’ must be read equally as a concept and as a metaphor. If we take ‘net’ to be a concept, an image’s refusal to depict something leads to a net of immanent relations, to a planimetric infrastructure. For an objective image is, for Merleau-Ponty, ‘all run through and intertwined on the surface by a network of vectors and a clustering of the lines of force to their roots’ (Prose, p. 47). This depth is exactly what is abandoned in an abstract image, for it is in the nature of an abstract image not to refer to any object beyond the image. In an abstract image, one no long looks through the surface, whether this be a window or a filter, at a visible world. But exactly this rejection of reference confronts abstract art with a problem: on the one hand, there should be an image without depth, having no objective meaning, while on the other hand, the result has to be distinguishable from a simple pattern. An abstract image is a pure net of relations, but it should not be just a net, as is familiar from wallpaper. So the problem of the abstract image corresponds to the problem of formal aesthetics. The origin of the abstract image can be traced in the theory of art as well as in the practice of art; theory and practice are complementary.19 Both theory and practice want to get beyond the objective content of an image without destroying the image in its image-ness in the process. There is an experimentum crucis in formal aesthetics: Justification of aesthetic formalism, whether of the theoretical or practical sort, depends on the capacity to differentiate between ornament and abstraction. Now we can understand the real meaning phenomenology has for formalism. Formal aesthetics can get help from phenomenology in distinguishing ornament from abstraction. For phenomenology shows that reduction does not necessarily destroy the sense of something, but can, on the contrary, bring sense to light that was not thematized. We can understand this by reading the word ‘net’ as a metaphor. The metaphorical meaning of ‘net’ is firmly established through a ‘maritime’ context – ‘But the painter throws away the fish and keeps the net’: the net is the means of catching the fish. This says – using net as a metaphor for means – that

174

The Visibility of the Image

abstract artists throw away the contents, instead retaining the means with which they were able to hold the fish in a fish-image, and making this means the only aspect of the image. How are we to conceive of such an image which shows the means one could use to catch a fish? Merleau-Ponty is not thinking of, say, an image of a fishnet. What are the means with which a depicted fish is pictorially caught? Can there be an image of a fish in which no fish can be seen? For Merleau-Ponty, the answer is clear. Style is the means with which reference can be developed in an image. Without designing a surface in a particular way, no object can be depicted. Abstraction is, within the image, a turning away from the object, and at the same time the image’s turning ‘to itself ’, in fact to those pictorial methods available for catching something in an image. This is nothing other than the design of a surface with visible forms. Abstraction is a form of pictorial self-reflection on this process. The only means available to a painter for catching a fish in an image consists of covering an object with a net of relations, that is, creating a visibly structured surface. Such a network, which is more than an ornament because it has come from a reduction of the objective image, can be called an abstract image. So abstraction appears as a phenomenological reduction enacted by means of an image. What abstraction and phenomenological reduction have in common is that by artificially giving the object up, the surface of the image is isolated and made into the sole visible aspect of the image. By turning the look away from the object, reduction is trying to get a look at the surface. The same holds for abstraction: By abandoning the objective matter of an objective image, it tries to draw attention to some aspect of that image that was not at issue. Merleau-Ponty calls this the ‘holocaust’ of objects’ (Prose, p. 63). The object is abandoned in the interests of perceptual enhancement at another level. Even Husserl said of reduction, ‘Strictly speaking we have not lost anything’ (Ideas, p. 113). Through the loss of the fish, we get a look at the fishing net, which for an abstract image is really only a network of relations. The abstract image is, from a genetic perspective, an image. It must be derived from an objective image. This happens by reading the abstract image as a demonstration of forms that can also be used to make an objective image. The source of the meaning of an image lies in visible differentiation and visible identification, the creation of transitions and contrasts, of unities and multiplicities on the surface of an object: ‘If we really want to understand the origin of signification – and unless we do, we shall not understand any other creation or any other culture, for we shall fall back upon the supposition of an intelligible world in which everything is signified in advance  – we must give up every signification that is already institutionalized and return to the starting point of a nonsignifying

Phenomenological Reduction and Pictorial Abstraction

175

world’ (Prose, p. 58). It is clear from this quotation that Merleau-Ponty had no need to distinguish between art and phenomenology. This statement applies equally to the phenomenologist’s activity, which is a process of reduction, and to the artist’s activity, which is a process of abstraction. Both pursue a transcendental inquiry, that is, they try to make visible the conditions under which an image can represent something. It is about a reflection on the way images come into being. From this standpoint, abstract images are a form of meta-imagery, since they make even reflections about the image visible as an image. This concern is not entirely without precedent. The abstract image can be understood as a development of the ideas Friedrich Schlegel was calling ‘transcendental poetry’ as early as 1798 in the Athenäums-Fragmenten [Fragments from the Athenaeum].20 This programmatic concept marks the beginning of art works’ claim to make the conditions of their own possibility visible, thereby reflecting themselves in their visibility. This entails – unavoidably, a programme of transcendental images – an intersection between art’s and phenomenology’s interests in cognition, between practice and theory. The difference lies in the means: In art, visibility is achieved by means of visible works, in phenomenology it is attained by means of a changed attitude to the original intuition. Art and phenomenology approach one another in two steps. It has already been rightly noted that art and phenomenology pursue common interests, whether in disclosing authentic reality in an expressionistic sense, or in resolving the mystery of visibility.21 But this is ultimately just their first step towards reciprocal completion. They really draw closer when the phenomenological attitude is reflected sensually as an aspect of an image, so that art is working towards an aesthetic fulfilment of phenomenological ideas: In this way, art is made complete as phenomenology, and reciprocally, phenomenology is made complete as aesthetic theory.22

The abstract image: Part of an absent whole Summarizing the phenomenological train of thought, we can confirm that an abstract image is unique in that it may be viewed in the natural attitude in the same way an objective image is viewed from the epoché. With an abstract image, there is no need to bracket out the relationship to the object and with it the unnatural aspect of formal observation. The abstract image shows a viewer in a normal attitude what an objective image can show a viewer orientated artificially. In this respect an abstract image serves, on the one hand, as relief: It is not in the subject, but in the work that the epoché required for formal observation

176

The Visibility of the Image

occurs.23 This means, on the contrary, that an abstract image is seen as an image – and not as a pattern – only if it is received and interpreted as just such relief, as – as Wölfflin says – ‘the pleasure of seeing redeemed from the worry of ordinary looking’ (tr).24 A further consequence is that an abstract image always remains a dependent secondary phenomenon, a supplemental relief with regard to an objective image. For an abstract image can only avoid being an ornament by standing in some conceivable relation to an objective image. This concerns not an empirical but a logical relationship between abstraction and objectivity, one that is asymmetrical: abstract images are unthinkable without the supposition of objective images, but objective images can readily be thought without abstract images. The relationship is asymmetrical because an objective image, too, possesses the qualities that isolate and absolutize an abstract image. In every objective image, an abstract image is inscribed as an unthematized part that lies outside the subject matter. Merleau-Ponty is right to think thus:  ‘The classics were also already painters in the modern sense’ (Prose, p. 70). From a phenomenological point of view, the abstract image is conceived as the whole of what is a part-aspect of the objective image. This becomes especially clear when we take Roman Ingarden’s phenomenology of the image into account: ‘I do . . . want to call attention to the fact that a, so to speak, non-presentational picture enters into the structure of every presentational picture as an indispensable component of it, and that the artistic or aesthetic value of the whole picture depends in an essential way on the artistic value of this.’25 Here, the difference between an abstract image and a pattern is again noted: The abstract image means to be an isolation of a constituent part of an objective image – even if it looks like an ornament. It presents the forms from which it is uniquely made as the infrastructure of an absent objective image. Yet if a part appears as a whole, a symbolization takes place, to which the semiotic principle of abstraction would apply: The goal of an abstract image is to free immanent pictorial relations to be the whole, that is, to symbolize according to the pars-pro-toto principle. The abstract image is not a sign for an object, but – as will be examined in the next chapter – only a possible sign that is not completely realized. It is a sign for another sign, an image about the way an objective image could be structured. Instead of real fish, only a net is painted, with which possible fish could possibly be caught. Instead of describing an objective reality, which could also be fictional, but which is a reality nevertheless, the abstract image describes possible ways reality could be represented and experienced. One can also say, instead of representing an object through a way of seeing – what an objective image does – the abstract image tries to make just a way of seeing visible, without the object.

Phenomenological Reduction and Pictorial Abstraction

177

There are graduated steps along to way to lending a way of seeing visibility. It begins with the representation of objects that obviously could not be the purpose of the image: It is odd to think that Cézanne wanted to indicate apples. If we look formally at the representational form used in an objective image, the object in this image transforms itself into an example of the experience of objects as such, which  – as Merleau-Ponty noted  – ‘may be banal’ (Prose, p.  46f.). The abstract image is the endpoint of the formal isolation of the way of seeing to the sole intention of an image, which is in fact associated with a qualitative leap. For only in abstraction does the way of seeing coincide with visibility. In an objective image, a way of seeing is shown by using this way to seeing to present an object. The interpretation of visible reality manifests itself in the quality of the immanent relations and determines the style of the image, which makes different things the same of differentiates among things that are the same: ‘For each painter, style is a system of equivalences he builds for himself for this work of manifestation’ (ibid., p. 61). In this sense the origin of the abstract image is based on the discovery that it is possible to create a system of equivalents without representing things. For an image does not need to show an object in order to represent a way of seeing in itself. An abstract image, too, can show how unities are formed, how transitions are understood. In an abstract image, visible reality does disappear, but the interpretation of visible reality does not; on the contrary, interpretation becomes the only thing that is visible.26 As Egon von Rüden describes the process of abstraction, the pictorial surface ‘becomes the basis for a purely immanentistic understanding of the image that is identical with a formalist conception of style, that strives for style as style, that is, for an abstract self-representation of style as a durable artistic principle, purged of all objects’ (tr).27 So for an objective image, an abstract image, identical in style, is always thinkable, and conversely for an abstract image, an objective one. For Merleau-Ponty, Vermeer’s images have non-objective pendants in which retain only ‘the “Vermeer structure” ’ (Prose, p. 70). It concerns an image that ‘observes the system of equivalences’ (ibid., p.  70). It would be an abstract image that could not be distinguished structurally from one of Vermeer’s images, because it ‘speaks the language of Vermeer’ (ibid., p. 70). This does not apply to an ornament. This does not mean that an abstract image could not appear as a pattern due to the viewer’s incapacity – whether the reasons for it lie in him or in the work – to recognize the forms on the surface as the syntax of a pictorial language. Abstract images demand migration to another phenomenological level: One who sees something other than forms in an abstract image will fail, as will one who sees just forms.

6

From the Formula to Formative Discourse: Charles William Morris (1901–1979)

6.1 Images about images Preliminary remarks Formal and phenomenological reflections on the abstract image eventually run into semiotic difficulties. Because formal and phenomenological aesthetics take an abstract image to be the expansion of one partial aspect of an objective image into the whole image, the abstract image stands in a relationship to thinkable objective images. An abstract image differs from an ornament only on the basis of its relationship to a possible objective image. Unlike an ornament, the abstract image is a unique kind of sign. According to Merleau-Ponty, the infrastructure of an abstract image is not just a simple patterning, but the net, the pictorial means with which objects might have been caught; one could also say: the infrastructure of an abstract image is the syntax of a possible pictorial sign. But the question is how the relationship of abstract to objective image can be described semiotically. What sort of sign are we dealing with in an image that withholds interpretation of content and leaves it at syntax? In order to proceed, formal aesthetics needs a semiotic foundation.

Images of ways of seeing: The ‘how’ becomes ‘what’ A sign is an object that stands for something else and that therefore refers to this other thing: aliquod, quo stat pro aliquot is the classical definition of a sign. Tying this definition to the results of formal pictorial analysis, an image can

180

The Visibility of the Image

function doubly as an iconic sign, that is – according to Peirce – as a sign that resembles what it denotes. The image can – as was established at the beginning of Chapter 4 – possess an objective and a non-objective meaning, that is, it can stand for objects and for ways of seeing, not in the same way, but in equally pictorial ways. This iconic doubling of meaning arises because the image, in its representation, resembles an object, but in its infrastructure, it resembles a condition of perception. The two possible meanings of the image are closely related. The non-objective meaning of an image corresponds to the ways and means, to how an image refers to an object, or, stated semiotically:  That to which an image refers in its non-objective meaning is the sense of the pictorial sign. The sense – this is Frege’s term for the denoted object’s way of being given  – becomes the non-objective reference in aesthetic contexts. This can also be formulated more simply: If an image refers to a way of seeing, the ‘How the image refers to the object’ becomes ‘What the image shows’.1 Chapter  4 explained how the early Fiedler demanded that this shift in meaning be present in works of visual art, insisting that ‘the substance of such a work is nothing else than the Gestalt-formation itself ’ (On Judging Works of Art p. 56). But the ‘how’ does not become a new ‘what’ just by being there. It only comes to a new act of symbolization if the image not only possesses a particular way of showing, but further symbolizes this way of making visible as two possibilities: first as a possible human form of intuition, and again as a possible form of representation for other images; for this reason the terms form of intuition and form of representational coincide. If this is the case, the visible form of the image stands in for something else that is invisible, and so is a genuine sign. The abstract image is – in light of the phenomenological perspectives presented in the last chapter – no exception in this respect, but rather a radicalization of the non-objective possibilities for symbolization that lie within any objective image. If the objective image is a sign with a double meaning, the abstract image is just a simple sign: It has only a non-objective meaning. The abstract image only shows a way of seeing the world, without presenting an object in this way of seeing; the ‘how’ of an image has become the only existing ‘what’, one can also say: the way of seeing coincides with the visible.2

The problem: How does the ‘how’ become the ‘what’? From a formal standpoint, it is convincing that an image elevates its own ‘how’ to content; this description undoubtedly addresses the concerns of the greater part of visual art historically as well.3 But this description is semiotically doubtful. If

From the Formula to Formative Discourse

181

the meaning of images is to show how they show what they show, the question arises, How do images show how they show what they show? The question is not sophistic; it concerns a fundamental problem in formal aesthetics. Martin Seel rightly points out a serious difficulty in the formal interpretation of images:  ‘The work of art accordingly presents a form in which it presents its contents. This formula emphasizes above all the aspects of art works that show techniques. But the formalistic explanation remains conspicuously empty because it always puts the work of art into a meta-position with respect to what is at issue, whatever it may offer. If the way a work of art offers things means that its own technique is presented, it follows that this technique, too, is in turn something which is offered by the work of art, with the consequence that this can be offered in one way or another. We land in a regress’ (tr).4 Concretely, the problem consists of the following: If a blurry image depicts the perceptual modalities of a short-sighted person, then the represented form of intuition is the non-objective meaning of the image, of which it could be justifiably asked: How does the blurry image refer to this way of seeing? The questions proliferate. If an image is a double sign in the sense discussed above, it must be possible to distinguish the principal aspects of each of them: sense and meaning. Or to ask in another way: If a blurry image represents the vision of a short-sighted person, is that short-sighted vision represented in a particular style, as an object in an image is always represented in a particular style? The same holds for abstract images: How does an abstract image symbolize a way of seeing without itself using a way of seeing to show the way of seeing? A fundamental difficulty lies behind these questions: Are images that symbolize a way of seeing metalinguistic signs? A metalinguistic sign is a sign that refers to another sign. At first glance this seems to be the case for images, since they show a way of seeing given in other images. The way of seeing an image uses to represent something corresponds to that which can be called a pictorial language. It follows that an image about pictorial language – even about its own – is a sign about a language, and that it is, in turn, a metalinguistic sign. So one can say that art that claims to discover ways of seeing discovers languages of representation and languages of perception. From a semiotic standpoint, such art consists, as the title of a relevant anthology on semiotic aesthetics subtly puts it, of signs of signs about signs Zeichen von Zeichen für Zeichen [Signs for Signs about Signs].5 This is to say that works of art are signs that refer to the language of signs so as to make new signs in this language possible. The problem with this interpretational approach is that meta-languages, too, use languages. If, in keeping with Max Bense, we call images signs for

182

The Visibility of the Image

signs about signs, we unavoidably confront the question of which language we should use if we want to represent, by means of an image, how images show what they show. The obvious and by no means trivial answer goes, we use established pictorial languages. With established pictorial languages, images can be used to make meta-structural images that examine ways and means of showing.

Meta-images: Structural drawings, x-rays and gallery images In keeping with Arnold Gehlen’s aesthetics, but with Kant’s as well, images of visual art are taken to be ‘images about images’ and are interpreted using that formula.6 If we take this definition seriously, the way of referring to the ‘how’ of another image is itself a process that could be called ‘depicting’. But this is not persuasive in two respects. First, abstract images would no longer be abstract images, for they would have an object to which they would refer, namely other images. Second, images that are very obviously about other images barely resemble images that show how they show what they show. Images that indisputably qualify as ‘images of images’ include, for example, structural drawings. In order to represent compositional patterns and so-called lines of force, art historians use structural drawings, showing the significant features through the formal construction of an image. Max Imdahl in Germany and Erle Loran in America are known for producing such images about images.7 Their drawings really are images about images, for the objective meaning and the stylistic means of making reference to this objective meaning can be separated without difficulty. They are images of images in the same sense a landscape is an image of a landscape. It would be only logical to call them ‘picture-pictures’. Structural drawings are semiotically comparable to x-rays of an image, also often used by art historians.8 In both cases, the image of another image is produced, and in both bases this happens in a way that makes immanent pictorial structures visible. X-ray as well as thermal- or infrared images make it possible to see pictorial structures that can no longer be seen by the light of day; structural drawings, conversely, show structures that are ordinarily overlooked. So in a certain sense structural drawings are a kind of compositional x-ray; what we see through is not the support, but the phenomenological opacity of the image. The same holds for gallery and studio images. These usually show a flood of images in the spaces of an artist, art dealer or museum. Here, too, what are

From the Formula to Formative Discourse

183

produced are images about images in the strict semiotic sense. These images show especially clearly that images about images represent the depicted images in a particular style. To state it formally, in the depicting image and the depicted image we are concerned with a system of relationships that does not possess the same aesthetic structural qualities. The image is reproduced as seen through a way of seeing, and it has to be this way for the depicting image to be an independent image at all. If the depicting image had the same structural qualities as the depicted image, it would be a copy. A copy with style is an inherent contradiction. On the contrary: With a perfect copy of an image, perfect transparency – the image and what it denotes cannot be visually distinguished – comes at the cost of losing stylization. It is therefore only conditionally justified to go on speaking of images about images in the context of perfect copies. The concept of pictorial imitation is more appropriate.9 For imitation is unique in not interpreting the object in its visibility, but rather imitating it in its materiality, in its plastic form. But pictorial imitation is a limit case that does not occur among images about images. Here the structural qualities of the depicted image are transformed in the process of depiction, which is why the same images in different gallery images appear widely to vary widely in style. With this, these images about images confirm what was to be expected semiotically:  When images refer to other images, they do so in a particular style. Images about images have sense and meaning. An x-ray picture and a structural drawing, if they refer to the same image, have the same reference with differing sense.* This also holds from one structural drawing to another, for they can work through the distinguishing marks of an image’s style in varying ways. By attempting to represent an image’s way of representing by means of a structural drawing, the way of representing itself is made visible in a particular type of pictorial representation. This is not a problem as long as one realizes that if images about images become, in turn, the objects of an image, an infinite regress will result. Structural drawings of structural drawings can certainly be made: images about images about images. But we will not get to an abstract image by this route. We cannot describe the semiotic status of non-objective images appropriately if we think of them as images about images.

* The problem does arise at this point that one sometimes does not know what the same image is. X-ray images of other images let us see not only invisible structures of images whose surface can be seen, but more usually completely different images, even those of another painter. An x-ray can also actually be an image about an image, but not an image about the visible image to which a structural drawing would refer. In this case the meaning would not be identical.

184

The Visibility of the Image

6.2 Images as formulae Designation without denotation Although we cannot comprehend the semiotic character of abstract images by treating them as images about images, we can learn from the problems associated with this explanatory effort. We will be able to characterize an abstract image semiotically only if we abandon the view that a sign has exactly two possibilities for making references:  either to objects or to other signs. As long as we accept these premises, the abstract image must be assigned to one of the two possibilities in order to qualify as a sign. If, on the other hand, we want to subvert this dualism and describe the abstract image as a sign that refers neither to objects nor to other signs, then it is helpful to turn to the semiotics of the American philosopher Charles William Morris (1901–1979). Not least among the distinguishing features of Morris’s semiotics is that the phenomenon of designation, as he himself says explicitly in his main work Signs, Language and Behavior of 1946, ‘does not restrict the alternatives for mathematics to either designating the world or designating signs, for formative-informative discourse does neither’ (Signs, Chapter VI, n.  ‘L’., p.  271).* This foundation already supports the early essay ‘Esthetics and the Theory of Signs’ of 1939, in which Morris in a sense picks up on Robert Zimmermann’s original thought, namely that logic and aesthetics ‘have long been felt as related’ (‘Esthetics’, p. 131).* His intention is very clear: He wants to show that there are ‘distinctive kinds of signs’ (Signs, p. 161) that ‘do not designate either the world or language’ (ibid., p. 170). Of course this type of sign must be of special interest for the theory of the abstract image, as Morris himself confirmed. It can forestall what Morris

* As soon as discussion turns to semiotics, terminological problems inevitably arise. This is particularly true when we are concerned with authors of varying backgrounds and from different times as well. In order to avoid misunderstandings, let us say here explicitly how the terminology of the authors under consideration here is used: The concepts ‘denotation’ (Morris), ‘Bedeutung/meaning’ (Frege) and ‘extension’ (Carnap) are considered the same. As is usual in analytical philosophy after Goodman, no distinction is made between the use of ‘symbol’ and ‘sign’. These identifications are widely established in contemporary semiotic aesthetics, which does not rule out the possibility of and need for differentiation in other discussions. * In Morris’s work it is particularly clear that semiotic aesthetics does not necessarily have to be opposed to formalism. A study of a work that is restricted to the form can conclude that the form of the work is, as a form, a sign, and so a potential object of semiotic analysis. For this reason, the self-assessment of many semiotic aestheticians should be corrected, and this specifically as Walther Ch. Zimmerli explained: Rather than being a movement resistant to formal aesthetics, the ‘semiotic turn’ in twentieth-century aesthetics was rather first instigated by ‘functionalism, formalism and structuralism’ (tr) (Die ästhetisch-semiotische Relation und das Problem einer philosophischen Literaturästhetik [The Aesthetic-Semiotic Relation and the Problem of a Philosophical Literary Aesthetics], p. 180).

From the Formula to Formative Discourse

185

does not want on any account, namely for images without objective content to be classed as asemantic things. Morris supports the thesis, actually still widespread, that every ‘work of art is conceived a sign’ (‘Esthetics’, p. 131). There is no problem maintaining this view with most art objects. The problematically uncertain case is the abstract image, or music, which is not under discussion here. But Morris takes up exactly this problem. He wants to try ‘to confirm the sign status of the art work’ (ibid., p. 137), for his view is that even if ‘no denotatum [. . .] can be found, the work of art can still be considered a sign (ibid., p. 140). For Morris, the rejection of objective content is not necessarily associated with the loss of status as a sign. For, as Morris’s thesis goes: ‘There can be designation without denotation’ (ibid.). A designation is a ‘description of the conditions which something must fulfil to be a denotatum of the sign’ (Signs, p. 20). It is actually not difficult to imagine that while ‘every sign has a designatum, not every sign has a denotatum’ (Foundations, p.  83). The best-known examples of this are fictional signs. The sign ‘unicorn’ specifies a ‘kind of object’ (ibid.) that is, this sign has a designatum, but refers to no denotatum. Abstract images are not fictional images, however. The difference is obvious. A fiction describes a kind of object, and the fictive lies in there being no object of this kind. With a fiction, one knows perfectly well which object would be a denotatum of the sign if one existed – but it is different for an abstract image. There, no object of any kind is described. So one should differentiate between saying an abstract image or a fictional image has no denotatum; both have no denotatum in different ways. A fictional sign has a nonexistent denotatum. Fictions, as Morris aptly puts is, are ‘signs which . . . have null denotation’ (ibid., p. 103). Yet an abstract image is not a null-denotation, for it has neither an existent nor a non-existent denotatum.10 What describes an abstract image comes before the description of an object. Abstract images are characterized by not describing any kind of object, but rather a way – available to all kinds of objects – that objects could become stylistically visible. This is a difference, because the various ways objects can be are, in turn, related to many kinds of objects; they constitute a pre-objective problem. The central question therefore goes: How can designation be conceived semiotically for abstract images? Morris suggests that ‘a comparison of abstract art to mathematics may be clarifying at this point’.11 The formal language of mathematics is a semiotic phenomenon for Morris, possessing the same semiotic characteristics found in abstract images – including the problems, namely the refusal of an objective meaning: ‘At first sight this thesis might seem to lend support to the view that such art has no semantical

186

The Visibility of the Image

dimension, since a mathematical system is commonly regarded as purely formal or syntactical’ (ibid.). But for Morris, this negative assessment does not last. For him, the language of mathematics is finally no more an asemantic phenomenon – it would then be no language at all – than abstract art is. We have only to get past the first impression. Then the typical signs of a purely formal language show what they are:  formulae. ‘The mathematical terms mentioned are commonly regarded as signs added to the language so that certain operations, otherwise impossible in certain cases, are always possible, and certain formulas, otherwise needing qualifications, can be stated in their full generality’ (Foundations, p. 106). For Morris, it really is ‘one of the most difficult topics in semiotics:  the interpretation of what are often called ‘logical signs’ or ‘formal signs’ or ‘syncategorematic signs’ (Signs, p.  86). Morris emphasizes again and again that the critical question is whether these unusual signs ‘can actually be regarded as signs’ (ibid.), ‘whether formators are signs, whether and what they signify’ (ibid., p. 154).*

The formula: A special case of designation without denotation For Morris, the semiotic problems of abstract art are semiotic problems of formulae or, as he himself usually put it, of ‘formators’, or more exactly, ‘formative ascriptors’. A formal statement of the type ‘a + b = c’ actually does not describe an object and makes an interpretation of content impossible. Formators are a special class of sign. Their opposite are so-called ‘lexicative signs or lexicators’ (Signs, p. 153). For Morris, these are signs whose meaning can be given, can be found in a lexicon. This cannot be the case for formators. A formator ‘does not lexicatively signify with respect to things other than signs. Nor with respect to signs. [. . .] The question then is legitimate whether formators are signs at all in the sense in which lexicators are signs’ (ibid., p.  157). One sees that with the concept of the formator, Morris is trying to subvert the division of signs into objective signs and meta-signs, without challenging semiotic status: ‘And even the finally formalized structure has a semantical character [. . .] the mathematical system designates the class of structures similar to itself and denotes any

* At this point it may be added that Morris did not distance himself from his comparison of abstract art with the formal language of mathematics. On the contrary, in his later writings Morris repeatedly discusses even his early essay ‘Esthetics and the Theory of Signs’ very critically, but as far the problems addressed here concerning the semiotic character of a work of art that does not denote anything, Morris was still saying, in 1964: ‘This problem arises in another form in the analysis of analytic formative ascriptors in symbolic logic and mathematics’ (Signification and Significance, p. 69, n.6).

From the Formula to Formative Discourse

187

structure which in fact is so similar – though in fact there may be no denotatum other than the sign vehicles of the system itself ’ (‘Esthetics’, p. 141). The central idea is formulated here:  Formators do not designate things or signs, but rather symbolize their own structure as a possible structure for other signs. They are signs for a purely formal contact with realities. In a certain sense, formators are not complete signs, because they refer to nothing. They have the character of a sign only inasmuch as they describe the form of a possible sign. To this extent, formulae are always signs for other ‘complete’ signs with sense and reference – but also self-reflexive. A particular structure is presented as the structure of a possible statement, a possible description  – or with an abstract image, as the syntactic structure, the stylistic form of a possible objective image. The self-reflexive turning of formulae and abstract images towards their own structure is always just a turning towards one realization of this structure among many. This is how the essential semantic ambiguity of the formula comes about. The part-to-whole relation described by phenomenology between abstract and objective images returns at this point: The formula itself is part of that which it symbolizes as whole. It possesses, in itself, the qualities of the class of structures to which it refers. Nelson Goodman would call the mode of symbolization of formative ascriptors an exemplification:  ‘Exemplification is the relationship between a sample and what it refers to.’12 Goodman rightly points out further that exemplification, ‘although encountered here rather incidentally in the course of the inquiry into expression, and seldom given much attention, [. . .] is an important and widely used mode of symbolization in and out of the arts’ (ibid., p. 52). Goodman’s concept of exemplification is heading in the same direction as Morris’s concept of the formula. Like the formula, the probe is a sign turned on itself, for an object becomes a probe by being considered representative of a class of objects to which it belongs. Once again with a probe, the relation between sign and meaning is that of part-to-whole.13 The principle that defines the formula also applies to the probe: ‘Exemplification is possession plus reference.’14 The formula, too, not only has its own structural characteristics, but shows them as the contents of a selfreferential symbol. Formulae and abstract images cease to be ornaments only if we perceive the difference between possession and reference to possession. Even Morris emphasizes this by noting that ‘in the work of art the sign vehicle is [. . .] one of its own denotata, but in esthetic perception it must be realized as such, i.e., the two must not be confused’ (‘Esthetics’, p. 137). This is an implicit recognition that a fictional formula is as unthinkable as a fictional way of seeing. Only the objective content of an image can be fictional. But the existence

188

The Visibility of the Image

of a represented way of seeing is always proven by the representing image itself. For the image itself is evidence that at least one of the symbolized structures exists: There can be no probe of something that does not exist.

Formulae and horizon consciousness A formula is unique in its semantic indeterminacy. Formulae are neither meaningless, nor do they have any firm meaning; Ernst Cassirer would, in the tradition of Kant, speak of formulae in terms of ‘pure meaning’.15 A formula sets up an objective sign with an objective description, without itself being this denotation. The formula is only the form prepared for a possible sign with meaning: ‘a + b = c’ can become ‘1 apple plus 1 apple equals 2 apples’. The objects in the structure are not definite, which does not mean that no definite structure is being described. In fact, it is essential that the structure can remain the same even when the relata change. In structures, relationships take priority over what is related. So the relata in structures can change in appearance and reference while the structure stays exactly the same. If we compare this semiotic mode of a ‘mathematical formula that is what it represents’16 with the semiotic structure of an abstract image, it becomes clear that in both cases a meaningfulness is given that Husserl outlines with the term ‘horizon’. Husserl was particularly distinct about this concept in Cartesian Meditations of 1931. There he attempts to use the concept of horizon to describe an open relationship to an object, one in which, paradoxically, there is no particular object, but into which some particular object can be introduced at any time. ‘Horizons’, he says, ‘are “predeterminate” potentialities’ (p.  45). Horizon consciousness is determined consciousness of an as yet indeterminate object. For Husserl, the essential thing about this kind of sensefulness is what is left over from ‘further determinings (which perhaps never take place)’ (ibid., p. 45). The structural affinity to abstract images is obvious: They, too, are related to an object without yet being related to a specific object. They set up the reference by referring to a schema into which an object can fit. They make reference to an object possible by establishing the way the referential object will be. Formulae, as much as representations of ways of seeing, are potential carriers of meaning that can, like a horizon, be transformed into the state of current meaning, that can be, as Husserl says, ‘filled’. But this ‘filling’ necessarily alters the logical status of the reference. To explicate the indeterminacy of the horizon thematically ‘means to transform the formal, perpetually open apriority of the horizon into a series of material (predicative) assertions’.17

From the Formula to Formative Discourse

189

This much can be claimed for formulae as well as for abstract art: As a formula stops being semantically indeterminate and becomes semantically explicit, an algebraic formula becomes an arithmetic one, ‘a + b = c’ becomes, for example ‘1 apple plus 1 apple equals 2 apples’.18 One of Morris’s subtle insights was to notice, again here, the structural affinity between the formal language of mathematics and the formal images of abstract art: ‘Abstract art has a relation to the total language of art similar to the relation of mathematics to the total language of science’ (‘Esthetics’, p.  140). That is, from a semiotic view of its infrastructure, abstract art is related to objective art as algebra is to arithmetic. The central idea is that formal languages or formal images make it possible to recognize the immanent relations of referential statements or objective images:  ‘For it is by formative ascriptors that we see certain interrelationships between our lexicative ascriptors’ (Signs, p. 170). From the standpoint of this structural affinity, objective images appear in a different light. Any arithmetic statement can be treated as an algebraic formula:  Formators can ‘have a lexicative component’ (ibid., p.  161). So from a semiotic perspective, we can understand what the formal-phenomenological concept of abstract image is claiming. In calculating apples, it is possible ignore the meaning of the relata in the syntactic relations, and so to view the arithmetic calculation as one state of a formula only, that is, as a relational structure only. The expression ‘1 apple’ is declared a meaningless sign and we get a purely syntactic formula. This exact semiotic transformation takes place when an objective image is taken to be a sign for a way of seeing. It is not important whether the relata of a formula are independently meaningful or not: ‘The x’s and y’s and p’s and q’s of formulas may be ambiguous lexicators (signifying whatever is signified by the members of a certain set of signs) and yet as establishing relations between signs in a sign combination [. . .] they may be formators of the type to be called connectors’ (Signs, Chapter VI, note ‘D’ p. 269). The question of how the ‘how’ gets to be ‘what’ in an image can be answered by comparison with formulae. If an objective image is used as a probe into its infrastructure, then no one refers meta-linguistically to a way of seeing, but rather transforms a sign with a specific, determined meaning into a sign with an indeterminate meaning. That is, a part of the image is taken to be the whole, and from the specific, determined intentionality of the image comes an indeterminate horizon. This change can occur without there being the slightest change in the sign’s appearance: The transformation is the result of taking the pictorial sign as a formal probe for its own structure. In this sense, the abstract image can be interpreted, to use a concept from modern linguistics, as an imitation formula.

190

The Visibility of the Image

The image as an imitation formula In comparison to the theory of visual art, the representation of languages by means of languages in linguistics has been more fully researched. The results of research into so-called imitation formulae19 apply to the audibility of spoken languages, but can also be transposed to the visibility of pictorial languages. Just as an image can represent a pictorial language by means of its visible, immanent relations, so, too, can a word do it by means of its audible immanent relations. Just as there are abstract images whose non-objective meaning lies in the form, there is poetry as pure sound painting. And just as there are images outside of art that represent ways of seeing by means of their relations, illustrations, for example, there are also words outside poetry that do not mean languages, but rather imitate: ‘Rhabarber’ is an example of this. ‘Rhabarber’ is an imitation formula used in the theatre as an acoustic representation of mumbling. The actors who want to imitate the language just say ‘Rhabarber, rhabarber, rhabarber’ or in England ‘rhubarb, rhubarb, rhubarb’. Miorita Ulrich says of this: ‘Imitation formulae of the type rhabarber, rhubarb are not names as such, they do not mean “to speak in general, to talk” (not “to speak incomprehensibly” either) nor do they designate one or another form of speaking: They represent speaking (talking), they are the depiction of speaking, or more specifically of talking. Still more: They have no single-language meaning at all, neither a lexical nor a categorical nor a syntactic one (Rhabarber is neither the substantive in the formula Rhabarber, Rhabarber nor anything like the “subject” of a sentence): Only in certain communities do they have a traditional text function. They do in fact coincide materially [in this example] with a word in a language that means something: Rhubarb is the single language name for a plant, Barbara is a personal name. [. . .] These meanings are suspended, however, when the function is “imitation of speaking”: The only thing that continues to matter is the suitability of these forms, on the basis of their phonetic construction, to function as instruments of imitation, to give the listener the impression of speaking, of talking whose meaning cannot be pinned down or identified in a single language. Here, a fragment of (material) language, as a thing, serves a function that is not actually “linguistic”, which means not actually for reference, but as the depiction of a “reality” which is once again language’ (tr).20 In this semiotic sense, an image can be an imitation formula as well – even an image that was not meant to be. Any image, however ordinary, can be a formula for the kind of making-things-visible that the image itself possesses. For Fiedler, art is nothing other than an ‘inherited system of formulae’(tr).21 With

From the Formula to Formative Discourse

191

this we have come to the point where semiotic reflections and Fiedler’s formal description complete one another. It seems entirely logical that in Fiedler’s posthumous-published writing ‘Wirklichkeit und Kunst’ [Reality and Art], the key term for characterizing art is ‘formula’.22 This quality of formulae can be transferred to perception, which then itself becomes a formula. To put it another way, to Fiedler, Wölfflin’s forms of intuition are called ‘formulae’, which is semiotically exactly right. A form of intuition is a formula: ‘It is as if the eye is in possession of a great treasure of formulae, to which it refers the impressions it receives, so forming a visual image that is satisfactory and satisfying only to the extent the impressions have been fully absorbed into those formulae’(tr) (ibid., p. 157).

6.3 The formative discourse of fast image sequences The formative discourse of formal logic and mathematics The comparison Morris set up in the essay ‘Esthetics and the Theory of Signs’ of 1939 between non-objective images and the formal language of mathematics breaks off one-sidedly in the book Signs, Language and Behavior of 1946. Only the semiotic structure of the language of mathematics is pursued further. But the parallels to abstract image forms are not extended. This opens the possibility of completing Morris’s original comparison in this respect. Morris rightly points out that for the language of mathematics, a description of independent kinds of signs that occur is not enough. For a language, it is not only typical to work with specific signs. The same signs can be used in very diverse ways. More complex linguistic phenomena are therefore defined not only through the formal characteristics of their building blocks, but also through forms of engagement with the signs, through linguistic practice. Therefore the concept of the formula or the formator is no longer enough for Morris to describe the language of mathematics semiotically. He introduces the concept of formative discourse. The concept of discourse develops into a key concept for Morris, although his use of it is purely technical. A discourse is a special way of interacting with signs for specific purposes. In contrast to a single sign, discourse is a procedure, a process, and always has a temporal duration and dynamic. With this, Morris is emphasizing that the use of signs leads to semiotically different structures. Although a religious text may use the same signs, that is, make use of the same concepts as a scientific one, there is a semiotic difference between them: ‘Such

192

The Visibility of the Image

specializations of language will be called types of discourse. Books, for example, are classified as scientific, mathematical, poetic, religious, and the like’ (Signs, p. 123). From Morris’s comprehensive system of discursive types, it is formative discourse that is relevant for formal aesthetics. The language of mathematics and logic functions for Morris as the prime example of a formative discourse. According to his semiotics, ‘logico-mathematical discourse is [. . .] a type of formative discourse’ (ibid., pp. 178–179). This type of discourse is characterized as one ‘in which formative ascriptors are dominant’ (ibid., p.  168); of course many formulae are used in mathematics. Yet in addition to the frequency of this specific type of sign, there is a use of the sign that is at least as specific – a use for which it does not even seem to matter too much whether we are working with formators or lexicators. In formative discourse, the meaning of signs can also become unimportant through use. A  formative discourse must therefore not consist entirely of formators. For Morris, the following syllogism is typical of a formative discourse:  ‘ “If men are animals, and animals are mortal, then men are mortal” may be taken as an instance of the kind of discourse we have in mind. Tested in terms of our preceding distinctions and methods, this compound ascriptor is formative and analytic in English, regardless of whether the component ascriptors are formative or lexicative’ (ibid., p. 169). This syllogism could also appear in a scientific discourse, for example in a biology book, but there it would have another meaning. In formative discourse, the meaning that is there becomes irrelevant. It is not important whether the syllogism is written with concepts or with variables having no content: ‘If A B and B C are, then A C are.’ Signs are used in a formative discourse in such a way that lexicators can be used as well, although the argument is formal only. When we consider the description of logical-mathematical discourse and remember the comparison of the languages of mathematics and of abstract art Morris himself began, the question inevitably arises whether the step from formator to a formative discourse for images could not be traced. Are there images that are semiotically related to an abstract image as imitation formula in the same way formative discourse is related to the formator? One gets the impression that Morris himself was calling for work on this question. He at least left no doubt that in his view even non-conceptual signs could constitute discourse. The arts ‘may then signify in any of the modes of signifying. And since they can be put to various uses, they can illustrate in various degrees all of the types of discourse which have been distinguished’ (ibid., p. 194). Still the question remains open: What images create a formative discourse?

From the Formula to Formative Discourse

193

Morris himself seems to want to avoid this very question, although his argument almost forces him to pursue the comparison he began in his early writing. He also notices what he would have to specify in order to work through his parallels: a further development of the abstract image to the point of possessing a discursive character of its own. But his indications remain unsatisfying. On the one hand, we get the impression that there is no doubt about the existence of formative discourse in art as well; there is really no need to mention it, since everyone knows about it: ‘Finally, the arts may signify formatively: not only may they include formators but they may in subtle ways link signified properties as both pertaining to a given object and as not pertaining, and thus at least approximate the formative ascriptors of speech and writing’ (ibid., p. 194). On the other hand, he makes the possibility of using formators for formative discourse in images relative: ‘Formators are clumsily handled in other media than speech or writing’ (ibid., p. 195). In short, Morris appears to suspect that there will be a type of image that could be described as formative discourse; but he either does not know or cannot find it, although he himself insists that semiotic research on images should not be constrained to the high arts: ‘An age in which printing, photography, painting, film and television have an important place will call for a semiotic which has not neglected the visual sign’ (ibid., p. 190).

From the imitation formula to the video clip In the next-to-last investigation (Chapter 4), we saw that video clips are to be counted among the pictorial forms that reflect the descriptions and expectations of formal aesthetics. In light of Morris’s thoughts on the possibility of a formative discourse in the arts, it seems appropriate to turn again to video clips, for in them, the two main characteristics of a formative discourse can be quickly established: Clips are, first, discursive in an original sense, namely as the discurrere of a sequence of images in motion. This applies to any film, of course, but film does not share the second indication. Clips tell no story and explain no matters of fact. The staccato-like change in angle, the deliberate testing of the viewer through speed and scale make it impossible to see a fast sequence of images as the representation of content, or to somehow read it as a sign in the way that is familiar from narrative film. The collage principle has the effect of reducing the sequence of images to their pure visibility. But, and this is crucial, this formalization nevertheless does not end in a kaleidoscopic play of light; the fundamental semiotic structural affinity between the clip and the abstract image lies just here – in its idiosyncratic semiotic status. Neither pictorial form constructs signs

194

The Visibility of the Image

with reference to things outside the image. Rather the image enters a state, as changeable as it is ambivalent, of having the capacity to be only a possible sign, without acting on the possibility. This happens by two different routes. The abstract image is not permitted any recognizable similarity to an object, so as to be certain not to be read as a sign for that object. If an image has no similarity to any objective quality at all, it cannot be taken as an iconic sign of this object – rather at most as an arbitrary one. With this in the background, abstraction becomes the effort to defend the image from being interpreted as a sign for an absent object. In an abstract image, the independence of pure visibility becomes clear, for it cannot be interpreted as a sign for an absent object. The abstract image refuses the use of images that otherwise seem to be so obvious: an image that shows Peter is also a sign for Peter. With the abstract image, it becomes clear that there are two steps here. An image that shows Peter can in fact be interpreted as a sign for Peter – but it does not have to be. Pure visibility is more fundamental than legibility. It is possible, often even very obvious to take an image to be a sign in the usual way, but it is not at all necessary. For not everything that in some way resembles something else is therefore a sign of that other thing. An image is, above all, the visibility of something without the presence of that thing. But this does not mean that pure visibility is a sign for the thing as well. It only becomes this through interpretation as a sign. But the image would remain an image without this interpretation, as can be seen in the abstract image, which cannot be interpreted as a sign of anything at all, and remains an image. This means, to sum up, that for easel pictures, the only way of making an abstract image is to reject mimesis. This is not the case for image sequences. With respect to possibilities for abstraction, electronic media are richer than easel pictures and photographs. In addition of dissimilarity, they have speed at their disposal as an alternative way of switching off the objective interpretation of the image. The principle is simple: The image is shown so briefly that the represented object cannot be recognized. This is not possible with an easel picture. In fact it is characteristic of an easel picture to freeze the depicted object and so present it for an extended, even contemplative observation. In this respect, image sequences make the transition between an objective image and a purely abstract image fluid. Image sequences can indicate an object only in passing, by letting it rush by. One recognizes only what kind of object was to be seen, but not which object it actually was. One recognizes human beings, for example, but not specific people. Because of the speed, the images can no longer be taken to be signs for particular objects. The reduction of the image to formulae

From the Formula to Formative Discourse

195

is not achieved here through the style of the images, but through the discourse in which the images are located. Of course we know from easel pictures that an object can be painted in such a way that its particularity remains unrecognizable. There are images that show no actual people, only schematic human beings. In an easel picture, this is done through the stylistic transformation of a possible person. The image interprets the appearance of a person in such a way that no specific person can be recognized. This stylistic schematization is available for single images in an image sequence as well. Like a collage, a clip can use images in diverse styles as building blocks. But the stylistic schematization does not reach the foreground; it does not become the dominant means, for unlike the easel picture, the image sequence has the further possibility of destroying the relationship to a concrete object by showing the object temporarily. Speed is the preferred means of transforming the specific determined meaning of the individual images into a reference to something indeterminate. The single images in a clip are no longer signs, but only possible signs. They could be iconic signs if only they could be seen for longer. Even if the single images show an object, then, they are still not signs for these objects: ‘Formative ascriptors are not lexicative even though they contain lexicators, because they do not designate, appraise or prescribe’ (ibid., p. 166). This is exactly the case with a clip:  The single images lose their relationship to the world in formative discourse, although a similarity with it is preserved; Representational images turn into play with pure visibility.* Ideally, a clip gives no sequence of depictions of specific things, but an unspecific indication of things.23 The state that is sought, into which the sequence is to take the meaning of the single images, is bound up with rushing by. A clip has no beginning and no end; it is a series that can continue endlessly, that lives from the change of images and that is actually there only for it. A slow clip is not a clip at all. Only haste prevents definitive objective meaning from coming through, and with it a relationship to specific objects being built up. The

* Semiotic parallels between video clips and graffiti can be seen here as well. With a graffito such as Jean Baudrillard’s famous example ‘Kool Killer’, words become empty formulae and continue to be at most signs for signs. To this extent, a formal emancipation of concepts’ visibility is taking place, as it was anticipated in the sound painting of avant-garde poetry: ‘For SUPERBEE SPIX COLA 139 KOOL GUY CRASY CROSS 1 36 means nothing, it is not even a proper name, but rather a symbolic matriculation number whose function is to derail the common system of designations, [. . .] Invincible due to their own poverty, they resist every interpretation and every connotation, no longer denoting anyone or anything. In this way, with neither connotation nor denotation, they escape the principle of signification and, as empty signifiers, erupt into the sphere of the full signs of the city, dissolving it on contact. [. . .] This was precisely because graffiti has no content and no message: this emptiness gives it its strength’ (‘Kool Killer’, pp. 78, 79f. and 80).

196

The Visibility of the Image

principle of the clip is that of time being short, which contributes to the production of a labile intermediate state. The viewer gets no time to take the image in as a representation of something. The idea is to allow just as much time as it takes to see that if there were enough time it would be possible to see content – this possibility is not to be used, however, only to be seen as a possibility. This is the way the equally ambivalent and unstable semiotic condition of a purely formative discourse is constituted. There is no completed reference at hand, only pretence. An intentional structure of a reference is prepared, but not realized; it remains indeterminate: ‘the screen becoming suddenly a last horizon of visibility’.24 The clip goes beyond the abstract image. It surpasses even the character of the abstract image as an imitation formula. The static formator becomes a formative discourse which once again grasps the sequence of signs itself not in terms of content, but in purely formal terms. A  formative discourse does not develop a story, but attempts to protect the pure visibility of images from interpretation through content – at least as long as the images are running. Stopping a clip would change the semiotic status of the visible, allowing the artificiality of the visible to burst in. Pausing a clip is semiotically comparable to filling the algebraic formula ‘a + b = c’ with content, letting it become ‘1 apple plus 1 apple equals 2 apples’. Stopping a clip produces specific determinacy. The formative discourse of the speeding image sequence, the formal play with pure visibility, turns into one single still image with style and reference.

Internalized schedulelessness If we recognize the clip as an extreme form of a tendency that can be observed in television, reflections on the formative discourse of fast image sequences take on special meaning. Of course no emptying or formalization of content takes place just by projecting a normal image on the screen of a television; a monitor can reproduce any Old Master. New media can in general be used for the same purposes that older media could have achieved. But it is unconvincing to research television with the idea that films can be viewed on it. This is not a quality specific to the use of the monitor in producing images. The novelty is that by projecting the images on screens, it becomes possible to change programmes – to zap. Only with the development of monitors did it become possible to jump back and forth between images and films by pressing a button – that is, if we ignore the suggestion, however right it may be, that we could also produce a clip by roller-skating through a museum. Formative discourses as described here arise in zapping: image sequences without beginning

From the Formula to Formative Discourse

197

or end, without a schedule. The images are viewed not as real signs, but as potential signs, without getting to the point of the possible becoming real. Jumping between the programmes makes any one channel obsolete. No one knows which sequence of images he will see. Television has a uniquely paradoxical character: because it offers many programmes, it also offers the possibility of watching without a programme. The viewer himself produces a video clip according to the following principle:  Before content or a statement becomes recognizable, it is right to switch over, because although we can use the television to view content, this does not exploit the specific possibility it offers for schedulelessness. Images that are made specifically for monitors can respond to the possibilities of electronic image processing. An image sequence for television will try to ward off the danger of being switched off by switching over. This is possible when the destruction of the programme through zapping in turn becomes the programme. When numerous contemporary investigations in media studies conclude ‘that the surface changes constantly, and is furthermore presented in such an unfamiliar and clever way as to arouse intense interest’ (tr),25 formal aesthetics takes the view that the tendency of electronic image processing towards purely formative discourse lies in the logic of the medium. The principle of the clip, ‘that the viewer should not get enough time to completely grasp the images’ (tr) (ibid.), is noticeable even in broadcasts that make explicit claims to being informative. As soon as we have adopted the premise that television, too, reflects the formal possibilities of electronic image processing – which need not be the case at all, for films can be shown and reports made on television as well – then formative discourses inevitably arise that react to having no schedule by internalizing an absence of schedule. In this way the ‘missing half-second’ becomes a phenomenon that increasingly characterizes mass media.* Electronic image processing can make visibility absolute and treat it as a material. It further supports that which also is actually new in new media, the use

* It is worth noting that the tendency to understand image sequences in terms of clips can be demonstrated even in broadcasts that are incompatible with rapid sequencing because they have the express intention of transferring information. But even news broadcasts are defined by the possibilities of new media; see H. Sturm, ‘Wahrnehmung und Fernsehen: Die fehlende Halbsekunde’ [Perception and Television: The Missing Half-Second], and the chapter ‘News in Electronic Media’, pp. 31–61, in H. Buddemeier, Leben in künstlichen Welten [Life in Artificial Worlds]. With such media research in the background, one gets the impression that human beings are more attracted to exploiting the possibilities of a medium than they are to making use of the medium’s mandate to inform. That is, formal aesthetics leads us to the question of why media are not used for informative functions to the extent they could be, why human beings are so fascinated with total visibility. The question exceeds the programme of formal aesthetics, however. Norbert Bolz, too, noted this critical point and made this reference to it: ‘Here an aesthetics of communication would need an anthropological foundation’ (tr) (Chaos und Simulation [Chaos and Simulation], p. 123).

198

The Visibility of the Image

of pictorial visibility as a purely formative discourse. Electronic image processing sets pure visibility into a dynamic that is not a function of a representation or of a course of events, but a modelling with possible signs, bracketing out their character as signs so that it need not be taken into account. In Computer Aided Design (CAD), pure visibility enters into a formative discourse. It changes, visible things are twisted and turned, but the sum of the changes occurs without any link to a denotatum. As the processes of change are underway, the substance, the reference is not dragged along:  not signs, but only pure visibility is being manipulated. As in modelling clay, no signs are deformed, rather something is produced that can be a sign. Reference again becomes relevant to electronic image processing of pure visibility only if the process, the discourse, stops, so that at the end of the transformation there is an image whose visibility can again be interpreted as a figurative representation of something. During the transformation, interpretation as a sign is set aside, so that even if the image shows an object, it is not a sign of this object. This is familiar to the concept in algebra: In algebraic calculation too, one cannot know whether or what ‘a’ means. As in calculation, so too on the screen of CAD, a purely formative discourse is underway during the transformation.

The question of medial status Against this background of constant danger that electronic image processing will become formative discourse, it becomes understandable that assessments of television’s quality as a medium of information can vary so markedly. A medium is a means for transporting information. In this sense, electronic image processing on monitors can be used as a medium of information. From this perspective, television is a medium in the classical sense. Supporting this view is a process that can hardly be denied, that television images can transmit knowledge of matters of fact. By means of the transmission of images, one gets insights into events that one never actually saw. The distance between events on earth  – in space as well as in time – diminishes, and the world shrinks increasingly into a – as Marshall McLuhan described it in the 1960s – ‘global village’, where everyone is informed, or more exactly, can be informed, about everything.26 Live broadcast makes it possible, through electronic image processing, to view of events around the world all at once. From the standpoint of information theory, television is the fastest medium for visual matters of fact. It seems that fast image sequences are incompatible with the medial requirements of electronic image transmission. The speed of images has the effect of

From the Formula to Formative Discourse

199

making pure visibility so absolute, so independent that it is no longer viewed as a sign for something absent and therefore as information, but rather for its syntax as formative discourse. This is most apparent in the most extreme case of the clip, but starts earlier. It amounts to a kind of revolt of the image as pure visibility. In zapping, no distinction is made between a newscast and a feature film: with respect to their pure visibility, they become equal. So one can get the impression that at least for fast image sequences – whether self-made or preexisting – the far more radical media theoretician Günther Anders’s view of television as a whole is right: it is not a medium. In the study Die Welt als Phantom und Matrize. Philosophische Betrachtungen über Rundfunk und Fernsehen [The World as Phantom and Matrix. Philosophical Observations on Radio and Television], which was already in print in 1956, Günther Anders (1902–1992), a Viennese student of Husserl, presented the view that television images are not representations, but phantoms. The thesis is currently enjoying renewed interest as it is further developed by the French theoretician of postmodernism Jean Baudrillard – the development consists primarily in bending Anders’s critical position into an affirmative stance. Baudrillard speaks of simulations rather than phantoms, but with respect to the assessment of electronic transmission of pure visibility, both take the view ‘that we cannot answer the question whether we should address ourselves to it as present or absent, as real or pictorial [. . .] For phantoms are nothing but forms that present themselves as things’ (tr).27 The provocative quintessence of the simulation-theoretical point of view goes: On the monitor, visibility becomes so independent and unmanageable that it is taken for reality. The images presumably taken to be informative representations change their ontological status and mutate into a substitute for reality: They begin ‘to be not the depiction of reality, but reality itself ’ (tr) (ibid., p. 168). The argument inevitably leads to a denial of television’s right to be a medium. It must be taken seriously. The modern view finds, even in electronic image processing, the continuing possibility of a supplementary instrument of enlightenment for the liberation of human beings from illusions and false opinions; the postmodern view that sees television as a simulating replacement for reality and welcomes it as an apparent liberation from harsh reality: the argument between the two is not about whether electronic image processing is a bad or a badly used medium, but about the far more fundamental problem of whether it is a medium at all. This is the unequivocal postmodern point of view: ‘Television is not a medium, it is reality!’ (tr).28 At first glance, this thesis seems compatible with the fact that fast image sequences make the objective meaning of single images inaccessible, and can

200

The Visibility of the Image

be viewed as a whole just for the sake of their pure visibility, as a simulation. But taking fast images up into postmodern simulation theory in this way does not take their semiotic uniqueness as formative discourse into account. In recognizing how fast image sequences achieve the formulaic quality of the abstract image by other means, it becomes clear why the question of its medial status is so difficult to answer. Are abstract images a medium? Images are a medium – yet in formative discourse the image enters into a state in which the meaning is no longer firm, but given only as a possibility. From fast image sequences it becomes clear that in the argument between modern and postmodern authors about the medial status of television, a third, more subtle position is usually overlooked: The formal qualities of fast image sequences suggest Hans Magnus Enzensberger’s view: Television is developing into a null-medium.

The null-medium Hans Magnus Enzensberger introduces the concept of the null-medium in his eponymous essay of 1988. With it, he presents an interpretation of television that best suits the formulaic quality of fast image sequences. If a viewer not only uses, but further exploits television for its possibilities of exaggerated dynamics, he moves ‘energetically toward a state that could be called schedulelessness. In pursuit of this goal, he uses all the available buttons on his remote control like a virtuoso. [. . .] The new media are new in that they no longer rely on programmes. They achieve their true purpose to the extent they approach the state of a nullmedium. [. . .] Visual technologies, television above all, are the first to be in a position to really get rid of the burden of speech and to liquidate everything that once was called programme, meaning, “content”. [. . .] Not the weakness, but the strength of television lies in the null-setting. It constitutes the use value. One turns the device on in order to switch off ’ (tr) (pp. 93, 95f. and 101). Fast discourses transform the medium in which they occur into an extraordinary state. It is a situation in which no information is delivered, although only that is done which normally delivers information in this medium: images are shown. This is the advantage of the concept of the null-medium. Television is not denied any possibility of being a medium. But there is a description of conditions in which it is not used as a medium. How widespread this state may actually be is not important to a semiotic description. Mathematical formulae are prototypical for null-media. They have no specific content  – ‘a + b  =  c’ has no referent  – but content can nevertheless be entered into the formula. The idea of the null-medium also closes the circle to

From the Formula to Formative Discourse

201

Merleau-Ponty’s description of the painter who throws the fish away to keep the net closed: The empty net is a metaphor for the null-medium. A null-medium is a form in which an objective sense is pre-arranged. Any image, viewed formally, can enter into this state, now emptied of sense, and with increasing speed the pressure to do so increases. Lack of time makes the surface unavoidable. The inevitable result is that the pictorial surface is valued more highly, making the image subject to principles of design. Abstract art marked the endpoint of formal observation from the side of the work. It described a goal that fast image sequences, too, strive to achieve by other means: ‘Without the heroic pioneering achievements of modern art, null-media could not be imagined. [. . .] From Kandinsky to action painting, from Constructivism to the depths of Op Art and computer graphics, artists have done what they could to purge their works of any “meaning”. To the extent they have achieved such minimization, they qualify fully as forerunners of the null-media’ (tr) (Nullmedium, p. 97). From abstract art, the overall pattern becomes clear: null-media are not new media that ally themselves with those that are already established. The discovery of null-media is a discovery of formal uses of existing media; any medium can approach the state of a null-medium. Abstraction is a way to the null-medium for an easel picture, for the screen it is the fast image sequence. But what the two have in common is their position on visibility. In both cases, a production of visibility replaces the representation and interpretation of a visible reality. This is an underlying context: As soon as a pictorial medium is used for its visibility alone, it necessarily becomes a null-medium. Access to images for their visibility alone can be achieved only when one looks to images for enrichment not of an informative, but of a purely phenomenological kind: When we do not want to know something, but rather to see something. Images enrich human reality by making absent things visible. The use of the image as a sign logically comes later, for the visibility of the image is more fundamental than its legibility. By making it difficult, if not impossible to use the image as a sign, the null-medium exploits as much as it exhibits the pre-eminence of visibility: Hardly any other phenomenon demonstrates so clearly as extremely fast image sequences, explicitly setting out to overwhelm the reading viewer, that images, if they do not inform about objects, remain images. The legibility of the image as a sign retreats into the background – as the image forces it to do – and remains present there only as a possibility. Fast image sequences confirm the assumption that the development of new pictorial forms reflects the pictorial understanding of formal aesthetics. The image in the twentieth century, in art and in new media, appears as a perceptible reflection of its own foundation: its visibility.

Notes Chapter 1 1 For an overview of the discussion of this concept of aesthetics see Kolloquium Kunst und Philosophie 1. Das Kunstwerk [The Colloquium Art and Philosophy 1. The Work of Art], edited by W. Oelmüller. 2 The beginnings of analytical aesthetics mentioned here are given in detail in K. Lüdeking, Analytische Philosophie der Kunst [Analytic Philosophy of Art]. 3 G. Dickie, ‘Is Psychology Relevant to Aesthetics?’, p. 324. 4 F. Koppe, Grundbegriffe der Ästhetik [Principles of Aesthetics], p. 170. On the role of the avant-garde as a testing ground for an aesthetic’s current relevance, cf. L. Wiesing, ‘La situazione attuale dell’estetica in Germania’. 5 The traditional understanding of a work is presented in W. Thierse, ‘Das Ganze ist aber das, was Anfang, Mitte und Ende hat’ [But the Whole Is That Which Has a Beginning, Middle and End]. 6 Cf. the destruction of the concept of a work by the avant-garde P. Bürger, Theory of the Avant-Garde. The Kolloquium Kunst und Philosophie 3. Ästhetische Erfahrung [The Colloquium Art and Philosophy 3. The Work of Art] edited by W. Oelmüller, which offers a look at the vast literature on problems in the destruction of the work. 7 See J.-F. Lyotard, Immaterialität und Postmoderne. 8 Another example of the programmatic renewal of a Kantian approach on the basis of the destruction of the work ushered in by Duchamp is the study Kant after Duchamp by Th. de Duve. 9 O. R. Scholz, Bild, Darstellung, Zeichen [Image, Depiction, Sign], p. 137. 10 The relevant comprehensive overview of diverse efforts to develop an antiidealistic philosophy of art appears in A. Halder, Kunst und Kult [Art and Cult] and St. Nachtsheim, Kunstphilosophie und empirische Kunstforschung 1870–1920 [Philosophy of Art and the Empirical Investigation of Art]. Also helpful and noteworthy is the outline, in print by 1930, Die Philosophie der Kunstgeschichte in der Gegenwart [The Philosophy of Contemporary Art History] by W. Passarge. 11 See E. Gilbert and H. Kuhn, ‘Esthetics in the Age of Science’, pp. 524–549 in A History of Esthetics. 12 For the rarely sufficiently acknowledged significance of Taine’s aesthetics, see E. Cassirer, Zur Logik der Kulturwissenschaften [The Logic of the Cultural Sciences], pp. 78–86. Taine’s role in anticipating the phenomenology of the image

204

13 14 15

16

17

18

19

20

21

Notes

is presented in L. Wiesing, ‘Phänomenologie des Bildes nach Husserl und Sartre’ [Phenomenology of the Image after Husserl and Sartre], pp. 265–269. Cf. V. Gerhardt, ‘Von der ästhetischen Metaphysik zur Physiologie der Kunst’ [From Aesthetic Metaphysics to the Physiology of Art]. S. Barrach’s book Über spekulative Ästhetik und Kritik [On Speculative Aesthetics and Criticism], a reaction to Zimmermann’s essay, appeared in the same year. The history of the distancing of empirically-psychologically oriented aesthetics in the first half of the twentieth century is traced in detail in the Geschichte der psychologischen Ästhetik [History of Psychological Aesthetics] by Ch. G. Allesch, especially in Chapter 23, ‘Die psychologische Aesthetik und ihre Gegner’[Psychological Aesthetics and Its Enemies], pp. 396–425. The concept of a ‘general study of art’, so central to the philosophy of art in the early twentieth century, actually first occurs in R. Zimmermann’s essay ‘Zur Reform der Ästhetik als exakter Wissenschaft’ [On the Reform of Aesthetics as an Exact Science] of 1862 (p. 227). A precise account of the history and theory of this concept can be found in W. Henckmann, ‘Probleme der allgemeinen Kunstwissenschaft’ [Problems of a General Theory of Art]. A brief overview of the history of formalism is found in O. Hostinsky, Herbarts Äesthetik in ihren grundlegenden Teilen quellenmäßig dargestellt und erläutert [Herbart’s Aesthetics Presented in Its Essential Parts by Source], pp. 98–107. In addition, Zimmermann himself continually calls attention to formalist thinking in his Geschichte der Ästhetik als philosophischer Wissenschaft [Aesthetics as Philosophical Science] of 1858, and to this extent writes what is still the essential history of aesthetics – obviously only up to the nineteenth century. This Geschichte der Ästhetik [History of Aesthetics] corresponds to the first part of the two-volume work, also called Ästhetik [Aesthetics], whose second part is in turn identical to Zimmermann’s Allgemeine Ästhetik als Formwissenschaft. Zimmermann’s path and position within the anti-metaphysical movement of the nineteenth century is given in R. Bauer, Der Idealismus und seine Gegner in Österreich [Idealism and Its Enemies in Austria], pp. 71–76. An annotated collection of these places can be found in a work cited above, O. Hostinsky’s Herbarts Ästhetik in ihen grundlegendedn Teilen quellenmäßig dargestellt und erläutert. Herbarts Äesthetik [Herbart’s Aesthetics], a dissertation by A. Ziechner of 1908, remains the most comprehensive account of his theory. The aestheticians Griepenkerl, Bobrik and Flügel have largely fallen into oblivion. The dissertations Bobriks Äesthetik [Bobrik’s Aesthetics] by E. Fiebig and Ästhetik und Wissenschaft [Aesthetics and Science] by E. Krämer are helpful for Bobrik. For Flügel, see K. Hemprich, Otto Flügels Leben und Schriften [Otto Flügel’s Life and Writing]. A good additional overview of the dispute can be found in K. S. Laurila, Ästhetische Streitfrcagen [Aesthetic Controversies], in the chapter ‘Der Streit um Form und

Notes

22

23 24

25

26

27 28 29

30

31 32 33 34

205

Inhalt in der Ästhetik’ [The Argument about Form and Content in Aesthetics], pp. 227–365. Also, cf. L. -O. Åhlberg, Form and Content Revisited. For an example see F. Th. Vischer’s contribution, Über das Verhältnis von Form und Inhalt in der Kunst [On the Relationship between Form and Content in Art] of 1858. The essay ‘Logik in Literatur’ [Logic in Literature] by G. Gabriel examines Goethe’s ‘holistic’ critique of logic. Cf. N. Malcolm, Nothing Is hidden, and the chapter ‘Der Angriff auf den Essentialismus’ [The Attack on Essentialism] in G. Pitcher, Die Philosophie Wittgensteins [Wittgenstein’s Philosophy], pp. 251–264. This is particularly the case in V. Flusser’s Lob der Oberflächlichkeit. Für eine Phänomenologie der Medien [In Praise of Superficiality. Towards a Phenomenology of Media]. The difference between the concept of form, or better of gestalt in gestalt psychology and the concept of form in Herbartianism has been examined in detail by Alois Höfler in ‘Gestalt und Beziehung – Gestalt und Anschauung’ [Gestalt and Relationship – Gestalt and Intuition] of 1912, although without taking Herbart into consideration: ‘Gestalt is not relationship, that is, Gestalt cannot be completely dissolved into relationships, association, relations’ (tr) (p. 162). Since this is exactly what Herbart and Zimmermann want to do, however, to resolve Gestalten into relations, their concerns do not correspond to those of gestalt psychology on this point. J. F. Herbart, Analytische Beleuchtung des Naturrechts und der Moral [Analytic Illumination of Natural Law and Morals], p. 217. O. Flügel, Über den formalen Charakter der Ästhetik [On the Formal Character of Aesthetics], p. 350. From this perspective, it becomes understandable that Zimmermann, with Riegl – whose further developments of Herbartianism will be discussed in the next chapter – should figure among the fathers of modern structural art history. A short essay of 1937 by L. Venturi, Robert Zimmermann et les origins de la Science de l’art, which takes up this theme, may be the only publication in this century to concern itself especially and exclusively with Zimmermann. J. F. Herbart, Allgemeine Metaphysik, nebst den Anfängen der philosophischen Naturlehre. 1. historisch-kritischer Teil [General Metaphysics, with the Beginnings of the Philosophical Study of Nature. 1. Critical-historical Section], p. 381. On the meaning of the concept of indifference for Schwitters’s aesthetic theory, cf. L. Wiesing, Stil statt Wahrheit [Style Instead of Truth], pp. 28–49. K. Schwitters, ‘Tragödie’ [Tragedy], pp. 99. K. Schwitters, ‘Merz’, p. 76. G. Braque, Der Tag und die Nacht [Day and Night], pp. 41. The formalist background of abstract art is presented in detail in W. Hofmann’s text, Grundlagen der modernen Kunst [Foundations of Modern Art] which has since become a classic.

206

Notes

35 M. Heidegger, ‘The Origin of the Work of Art’, p. 63. 36 P. Bürger, Zur Kritik der idealistischen Ästhetik, p. 89. 37 R. Zimmermann, ‘Zur Reform der Ästhetik als exakter Wissenschaft’ [On the Reform of Aesthetics as an Exact Science], pp. 226. 38 J. F. Herbart, A Text-Book in Psychology, p. 129. 39 We need to be aware, however, that the development of objectivism in Zimmermann’s concept of beauty was also encouraged in the views of his teacher, B. Bolzano, who presented them in ‘Über den Begriff des Schönen’ [On the Concept of the Beautiful] of 1843. 40 J. F. Herbart, Kurze Enzyklopädie der Philosophie aus praktischen Gesichtpunkten entworfen [A Short Encyclopaedia of Philosophy in Practical Terms], pp. 371. 41 J. F. Herbart, Psychologie als Wissenschaft, neu gegründet auf Erfahrung, Metaphysik und Mathematik. Analytischer Teil. [Psychology as Science, Newly Based on Experience, Metaphysics and Mathematics. Analytic Section], pp. 94. 42 J. F. Herbart, Allgemeine praktische Philosophie [General Practical Philosophy], pp. 27. 43 J. F. Herbart, A Text-Book in Psychology, p. 49. 44 R. Zimmermann, ‘Über Lotzes Kritik der formalistischen Ästhetik’ [On Lotze’s Criticism of Formalist Aesthetics], p. 376. 45 See W. Wundt, ‘Psychologismus und Logizismus’ [Psychologism and Logicism]. 46 The logician and aesthetician Georg Neudecker (1850–unknown) already identified this as the central problem of early Herbartianism in his Studien zur Geschichte der deutschen Ästhetik seit Kant [Studies in the History of German Aesthetics since Kant] of 1878. ‘The task given [through Herbart] to aesthetics could in fact be accomplished only by observation and experience, in short empiricism, which is also the only source from which Zimmermann quietly draws his pleasing forms’ (tr) (p. 90). H. Lotze, in his Geschichte der Ästhetik in Deutschland [History of Aesthetics in Germany], evaluated the problem of early Herbartianism in a very similar way: it wants to answer of question of beauty with logical means, but ‘it can, by its very nature, only be answered the experimental way’ (tr) (p. 245). In fact the evaluation runs like a scarlet thread through discussions of Herbart and Zimmermann. Again and again it is said of their project: ‘certainly as empirical, but not as apriori aesthetics’ (O. Hostinsky, Herbarts Äesthetik in ihren grundlegenden Teilen quellenmäßig dargestellt und erläutert [Aesthetics Presented and Explained in Its Basic Parts Through Sources], pp. 92). 47 S. Nachtsheim, Kunstphilosophie und empirische Kunstforschung [Philosophy of Art and the Empirical Study of Art], pp. 72f. 48 Hermann Lotze has done more than anyone else to establish this unintended yet implicitly present self-contradiction in the first phases of formal aesthetics: ‘But formal aesthetics still works primarily with the materials it inherited from the large and lively, often misguided, but here unfairly underestimated efforts of idealist aesthetics’ (tr) (p. 246).

Notes

207

Chapter 2 1 J. von Schlosser, Die Wiener Schule der Kunstgeschichte [The Vienna School of Art History], p. 149. 2 On the life and work of Riegl, cf. the comprehensive monograph Studi su Alois Riegl by S. Scarocchia. Riegl’s significance for the formation of modern art history is presented by H. Köhler, Strukturale Bildlichkeit [Structural Pictoriality], and W. Sauerländer, ‘Alois Riegl und die Entstehung der autonomen Kunstgeschichte am Fin de Siècle’ [Alois Riegl and the Rise of Modern Art History at the Fin de siècle]. 3 D. Frey, ‘Probleme einer Geschichte der Kunstwissenschaft’ [Problems in History for Science Art], p. 31. 4 See W. Kemp, Alois Riegl; this is the also the source of the last quotation from Riegl’s unpublished estate (p. 45). 5 Ernst H. Gombrich confirms this in a remote place: ‘Riegl looked to Herbart’s formal aesthetics, which prevailed the time and which Zimmermann no doubt conveyed to him in Vienna, for the methodological equipment of his first major work’ (‘Rezension von “J. Bodonyi: Entstehung und Bedeutung des Goldgrundes in der spätantiken Bildkomposition” ’ [Origin and Significance of the Gold Ground in Late Antique Pictorial Composition], p. 66) 6 W. Passarge goes on to provides a very suggestive overview of the history of diverse theories of basic art historical principles stemming from Riegl in the chapter ‘Kunstgeschichte als Formgeschichte und das Problem der Grundbegriffe’ [Art History as a History of Form and the Problem of Principles] in Die Philosophie der Kunstgeschichte in der Gegenwart [The Philosophy of Contemporary Art History], pp. 16–36; for more on the issue, see Th. Zaunschirm, Systeme der Kunstgeschichte [Systems of Art History]. The studies Zur Frage nach dem Malerischen [On the Question of the Painterly] by A. Schmarsow and ‘Plastisch und Malerisch’ [Plastic and Painterly] by W. Thomae are helpful from a systematic standpoint. A. Hauser attempts to align particularly the theories of Riegl and Wölfflin within an intellectual history in the chapter ‘Geschichtsphilosophie der Kunst: “Kunstgeschichte ohne Namen” ’ [Philosophy of the History of Art: ‘Art History without Names’], pp. 127–306 in Philosophie der Kunstgeschichte [Philosophy of Art History]. From a philosophical perspective, the interpretation ‘Über Grundbegriffe der Kunstwissenschaft’ [On Principles of Art History] by E. Utitz is noteworthy. G. Kaschnitz-Weinberg’s contribution to this discussion is presented by M. M. Roß, Künstlerische Struktur und Strukturontologie [Artistic Structure and Ontology of Structure]. 7 A. Hildebrand, The Problem of Form, 131. 8 See B. Peeters, Hergé, p. 22f.

208

Notes

9 The difference between haptic and painterly corresponds to the opposition between the ‘form of being’ [‘Daseinsform’] and ‘form of effect’ [‘Wirkungsform’] in Adolph Hildebrand’s The Problem of Form in the Visual Arts of 1893: ‘The idea of the “form of being” relates to the object itself [. . .] the idea of the “form of effect”, conversely, relates to the optical image of the object’ (p. 131). With his opposition between the form of being and the form of effect, Hildebrand departs in one essential point from the position formal aestheticians take of art historical principles. Hildebrand is not primarily concerned with a logical description of the pictorial form, but with criteria for artistic quality. For him, the optically farsighted mode of depiction is a mark of quality. For more details on this and on Hildebrand’s view of Riegl, see M. Imdahl, ‘Marées, Fiedler, Hildebrand, Riegl, Cézanne’, p. 174ff. 10 See the comparison between Turner and Mark Rothko in M. Bockemühl, J. M. W. Turner, pp. 29–47. 11 This key idea of Merleau-Ponty’s can be compared to B. Waldenfels study ‘Das Zerspringen des Seins’ [The Shattering of Being]. 12 E. Cassirer, The Logic of the Cultural Sciences, p. 61. 13 E. Panofsky, ‘Über das Verhältnis der Kunstgeschichte zur Kunsttheorie’ [On the Relationship of Art History to Art Theory], p. 51. 14 H. Sedlmayr, ‘Kunstgeschichte als Stilgeschichte’ [Art History as a History of Style], p. 22. Sedlmayr also examines Riegl’s distinction between ‘external stylistic character’ and the ‘principle of style’ in this context. These two concepts do in fact clearly explain how his thinking relates to familiar concepts of style. ‘Expressionism’ can definitely be used as a stylistic category according to Riegl. He is in a position to morphologically summarize the external stylistic character of a great many forms. The art historical principles, on the other hand, refer to the conditions of possibility for an external stylistic character, and to this extent present a transcendental stylistic principle. 15 E. Panofsky, ‘Über das Verhältnis der Kunstgeschichte zur Kunsttheorie’ [On the Relationship of Art History to Art Theory], p. 67. By 1920, in the essay ‘Der Begriff des Kunstwollens’ [The Concept of Kunstwollen], Panofsky had already given the interpretation of Kunstwollen that prevails today. 16 The expression ‘drive’, which Riegl uses often, not just in this quotation, is a concept Schopenhauer typically uses in describing his understanding of the will. For him, will is ‘merely a blind, incessant impulse’ (Will and Idea, §54, p. 354). For him, the optically farsighted mode of depiction is a mark of quality. This is not an altogether unimportant conceptualization. It provides terminological clarity that in formal aesthetics, Kunstwollen is not understood as a rational decision at all. This is sometimes overlooked in the reception of formalism. P. Bürger writes, for example, ‘In other words: formalists are concerned to reconstruct the process of artistic creation as a rational choice between possible alternatives’

Notes

17

18

19 20

21

22 23 24

25

209

(Vermittlung – Rezeption – Funktion, [Transmission – Reception – Function], p. 96) It is correct: Formalists are concerned to describe a choice between possible alternatives, and these alternatives can in fact be rationally determined; but in the production of art, in a formal understanding, the choice itself need not in turn be rationally grounded, but rather may result from an irrational drive. E. Rothacker, Die dogmatische Denkform in den Geisteswissenschaften und das Problem des Historismus [The Dogmatic Way of Thinking in the Humanities and the Problem of Historicism], p. 20. If we call this non-rational principle ‘life’, we come to understand why Riegl’s theory of Kunstwollen has been justifiably identified in many quarters as vitalism. Cf. W. Sauerländer, ‘Alois Riegl und die Entstehung der autonomen Kunstgeschichte am Fin de Siècle’, pp. 133–137. E. Cassirer, The Logic of the Cultural Sciences, p. 73. This is also emphasized in the research of S. Scarrocchia, Studi su Alois Riegl, here particularly in the chapter ‘Riegl e l’arte contemporanea. Contributo alla fenomenologia degli stili’, pp. 189–208. The idea of the direct observation of relationships can also be found in Alexius Meinong, Carl Stumpf and William James; cf. H. Höffding, Der Relationsbegriff [The Concept of Relation], pp. 14–30. Brunswig acknowledges the originality of his viewers carefully when he writes: ‘There is a fairly general recognition, that a piece of psychic reality is currently being rediscovered’ (Das Vergleichen und die Relationserkenntnis [Comparison and the Recognition of Relation], p. 3). In fact by 1739, David Hume had already described the direct visibility of relations with great clarity in Treatise of Human Nature: ‘Relations are discoverable at first sight, and fall more properly under the province of intuition than demonstration’ (p. 70). In this context, see also R. Jochims, Visuelle Identität [Visual Identity]. G. Boehm, Sehen [Seeing], p. 52 In his essay ‘Logik und Ästhetik’ [Logic and Aesthetics], G. Abel examines this internal interlocking of logic and aesthetics in Nietzsche more closely, and positions it in the wider context of perspectivism and interpretation philosophy. See also in this regard Die Weltanschauungen der Malerei [The Weltanschauung of Painting] by H. Nohl. According to Nohl, this idea that one might characterize formal styles in the history of thought, in their diversity, as one does in formal aesthetics, using relational concepts, particularly Riegl’s basic principles – was taken up primarily from Karl Mannheim ‘Beiträge zur Theorie der WeltanschauungsInterpretation’ [Contributions to the Theory of Weltanschauung Interpretation]. His programme of a sociology of knowledge was developed explicitly through the application of Riegl’s idea to the description of structural differences in world views. In ‘Science as Art’, Paul Feyerabend defended the more radical view that by applying Riegl’s principles to scientific discourse, discourse might be resolved into purely

210

26

27

28

29 30 31

32 33 34

Notes aesthetic phenomena that distinguish themselves from one another through style alone, and that the truth of statements must therefore be understood in such a way that their ‘trust is what the style of thought says truth is to be’ (p. 46). It is possible to interpret the variety of representations of relationships to the world in a realistic way. In this case it would no longer be a worldly image, no longer a theoretical representations, an image or artefact that is discussed as haptic or painterly, but the world depicted in these things. So different ontologies correspond to haptic and painterly: a ‘discreet ontology’ and an ‘indiscreet ontology’ – without this necessarily being meant in a substantialistic sense. In contemporary discussions of indiscreet ontology there are in fact remarkable views of the way Riegl’s main ideas can be defended with ontological methods. This is especially clear in W. Hogrebe’s essay ‘Eindeutigkeit and Vieldeutigkeit’ [Clarity and Ambiguity]. In A History of Formal Logic, J. M. Bochenski gives a succinct overview of the history of relational logic. See also E. Paisseran, La Logique des relations et son histoire. Cf. on the Aristotelian concept of relations ‘An Historical Sketch of the Problem of Relations’ by D. S. Mackay, ‘The Concept of Relation: Some Observations on Its History’ by J. R. Weinberg, as well as the chapter: ‘Die Geschichte des Relationsbegriffs’ [The History of the Concept of Relation] in H. Höffding, Der Relationsbegriff [The Concept of Relation] S. 1–13. On A. N. Whitehead’s defeat of the Aristotelian concept of relations, see G. Böhme, ‘Whiteheads Abkehr von der Substanzmetaphysik. Substanz und Relation’ [Whitehead’s Renunciation of the Metaphysics of Substance. Substance and Relation]. This is the conclusion of F. Patzig’s research in ‘Der Strukturalismus und seine Grenzen’ [Structuralism and Its Limits]. D. D. Merill gives an introduction especially to the relational logicians De Morgan and Peirce, ‘DeMorgan, Peirce and the Logic of Relations’. In this context, see the chapter ‘Verschiedene Arten von Relationen’ [Various Kinds of Relations] in R. Carnap, Einführung in die Symbolische Logik [Introduction to Symbolic Logic] pp. 104–109. G. Gabriel, Fiktion und Wahrheit [Fiction and Truth], p. 15. G. Boehm, ‘Bildsinn und Sinnesorgane’ [Pictorial Meaning and Sense Organs], p. 125. The effort to make use of Frege’s conceptual tools for a semantic description of art works goes back in no small measure to the works of Gottfried Gabriel, and can already be found developed in the text mentioned earlier, Fiktion und Wahrheit [Fiction and Truth]: particularly worth noting here is the appendix, a re-working of an essay that appeared as early as 1970, ‘Frege über semantische Eigenschaften der Dichtung’ [Frege on the Semantic Characteristic of Poetry]. Gabriel examines Frege’s

Notes

35 36 37 38

39

40

41

211

own ‘poetry’, that is, his own use of metaphor in the distinction between sense and meaning, in the essay ‘Der Logiker als Metaphoriker’ [The Logician as MetaphorMaker]. In Fiktion und Diktion, G. Genette shows that the distinction between sense and meaning can be used to define the style of literary texts. The suggestion that Frege’s metaphor of coloration be interpreted as a description of style can be found in A. C. Danto, The Transfiguration of the Commonplace, pp. 249–251. E. Panofsky, ‘Über das Verhältnis der Kunstgeschichte zur Kunsttheorie’ [On the Relationship of Art History to Art Theory], p. 141. W. Burkamp, Begriff und Beziehung [Concept and Relationship], p. 59. See also Burkamp’s Logik [Logic]. This is presented in detail in D. D. Merrill’s Augustus DeMorgan and the Logic of Relations. C. S. Peirce, ‘Why Study Logic?’ p. 115. Cf. Th. A. Schulz, Panorama der Ästhetik von Charles Sanders Peirce [Panorama of the Aesthetics of Charles Sanders Peirce]; C. M. Smith, The Aesthetics of Charles S. Peirce’; M. O. Hocutt, ‘Logical Foundations of Peirce’s Aesthetics’. W. Dilthey, Studien zur Grundlegung der Geisteswissenschaften, p. 28. On Dilthey’s grounding of logic in aesthetics, see F. Fellmann, Symbolischer Pragmatismus [Symbolic Pragmatism], pp. 109–143. Cf. K.-O. Apel, Der Denkweg von Charles Sanders Peirce [Charles Sanders Peirce’s Intellectual Journey], S. 175ff. Apel works through the aesthetic basis for Peirce’s theory of relations, and further associates it with Husserl’s theory of intuitive insight. The justification for this kind of reading is further confirmed in the detailed study ‘Peirce’s Esthetics’, by V. Kent. In fact the phenomenological idea of an ‘eidetic as protologic’ seems to lend itself readily to an association with Peirce’s proto-logical function of aesthetics. This becomes clear by holding to an aesthetic way of reading phenomenology, as F. Fellmann has proposed in Phänomenologie als ästhetische Theorie [Phenomenology as Aesthetic Theory]. A discussion the goes into this idea of the complementary relationships between logic and aesthetics more deeply can be found in G. Gabriel’s ‘Erkenntnis in Wissenschaft, Philosophie und Dichtung’ [Knowledge in Science, Philosophy and Poetry].

Chapter 3 1 G. Patzig, Relation [Relation], p. 1231. 2 See R. Carnap, Einführung in die Symbolische Logik [Introduction to Symbolic Logic], pp. 106–109. 3 On the concept of pictorial form, see further in H. Wölfflin, ‘The New Pictorial Form’, pp. 251–286 in Classical Art.

212

Notes

4 In the introductory essay ‘Zum geschichtlichen Ort’ [On Historical Locality], pp. 13–54 in Wittgensteins Kristall [Wittgenstein’s Crystal], Cl.-A. Scheier shows not only that Wölfflin’s concept of pictorial form can be compared with Wittgenstein’s understanding of the image, but also conversely, that we can be assume Wittgenstein had a solid art historical background. 5 An idea that can be found as early as 1893 in Das Problem der Form in der Bildenden Kunst [The Problem of Form in the Visual Arts] by Adolph Hildebrand (in Chapter 4, ‘Flächen- und Tiefenvorstellung’ [Conceptions of Surface and Depth], pp. 39–57). 6 On the difficulties with this pair of concepts, see W. Marx’s essay ‘Offene und geschlossenen Form’ [Open and Closed Form]. 7 Ch. Schmitz, ‘Wölfflin und die Literatur’ [Wölfflin and Literature], p. 64 8 M. Podro has investigated the problem of the unity and complexity of art works in ‘A Sense of Complexity in the Visual Arts’, and has done so by making an explicit reference to Herbart’s understanding of form, which is noteworthy. 9 M. Lurz, Heinrich Wölfflin, p. 186. Lurz’s portrayal of Wölfflin is not only central for the interlinking of the principles, but also can be taken to be the main monograph on Wölfflin’s work as a whole; there is, in addition, a comprehensive bibliography of the vast Wölfflin literature. A. Hauser, in ‘Grundbegriffliches zu Wölfflins “Kunstgeschichtlichen Grundbegriffen” ’ [Principles of Wölfflin’s Art Historical Principles] does provide another equally noteworthy riposte to Lurz’s view of Wölfflin, however, proposing that Wölfflin’s work is based on a psychologicalempathic theory. 10 A comparably formulaic representation of Wölfflin’s conclusions can be found as early as 1915, in M. Hamburger Das Form-Problem in der neueren deutschen Ästhetik und Kunsttheorie [The Problem of Form in Recent German Aesthetics and Art Theory]. It says there, aptly, ‘To summarize this way of regarding form, we can conclude: the linear art work is at the same time planar, closed, clear in its coordinated parts. The painterly work is recessive, in its open form, and, through the subordination of parts, deliberately unclear’ (tr) (p. 150). 11 In Kant’s Critique of the Power of Judgement (1790), too, colour is consistently treated as the opposite of form. Only the relational structure of a form belongs ‘to the form; because there it is possible to abstract from the qualities of any perception (whether, and which colour, or whether and which tone it may be)’ (A 40). 12 H. Paetzold, Ästhetik der neueren Moderne [Aesthetics of Recent Modernity], p. 50. 13 The juxtaposition of the concepts ‘convergence’ versus ‘contrast’ is located in Joh Pawlik, Praxis der Farbe [The Practice of Colour], pp. 41–47. 14 B. Waldenfels, ‘Ordnungen des Sichtbaren’[Orders of the Visible], p. 334. For a more semiotically oriented discussion of the connection between image and perception,

Notes

15 16

17 18

19 20 21 22

23

24

25

213

see also the conference papers Vision and Visuality, edited by H. Foster and N. Bryson, Vision and Painting. B. Waldenfels, ‘Ordnungen des Sichtbaren’ [Orders of the Visible], p. 234. On this point see J. Hart, Heinrich Wölfflin: An Intellectual Biography, the section ‘The Influence of Fiedler and Kant’, pp. 424–426. The strong presence of neoKantian thinking in the intellectual life around the turn of the century should not be underestimated: cf. Th. E. Willey, Back to Kant. Specifically regarding Wölfflin, we know from unpublished posthumous sources that he studied the work of the most important proponents of neo-Kantianism in detail: he knew the writing of Ed Zeller, F. A. Lange, F. Paulsen, O. Liebmann, A. Riehl and W. Windelband: cf. on this point J. Hart, ‘Reinterpreting Wölfflin’. K. Fiedler, ‘Moderner Naturalismus und künstlerische Wahrheit’ [Modern Naturalism and Artistic Truth], p. 103. Johann Heinrich Lambert, too, emphasizes this relational understanding in a ‘Brief an Kant vom 3. Feb. 1766’ [Letter to Kant of 3 February 1766]: ‘Since form arises entirely from relational concepts, it specifies simple conceptual relationships, no others’ (p. 65). The connection between the concepts of form and relation in Kant is presented in detail in the study Relation und Funktion [Relation and Function] by P. Schultheiss. On the concept of form in the Critique of Pure Reason, see H. Graubner, Form und Wesen [Form and Essence]. G.Mohr, Das sinnliche Ich [The Sensual Self], p. 91. Cf. P. Rohs, Transzendental Ästhetik [Transcendental Aesthetics]. St. Körner, Kant, pp. 34–35. This quotation from Wölfflin lies at the core of A. Hauser’s very concise account of Wölfflin’s theory, ‘Grundbegriffliches zu Wölfflins “Kunstgeschichtlichen Grundbegriffen” ’[Principles of Wölfflin’s ‘Principles of Art History’]. On the black mirror, cf. the catalogue Sehsucht [The Longing to See], published by the Art- and Exhibition Gallery of the German Federal Republic, p. 113. There is basic material about how well the comparison between image and mirror works in the essay ‘Spieglein, Spieglein an der Wand . . .’ [Mirror, mirror, on the Wall . . .] by J. Kulenkampff. In his essay ‘Mirrors’ of 1984, U. Eco, too, supported this view from a semiotic perspective. Eco comes to the conclusion that a pictorial representation is not comparable to a mirror, because pictorial representations are signs, whereas mirror images are not. But he finds that distorting mirrors undermine the opposition, for because they structurally transform the visible, it is possible to detect in them ‘the beginning of semiosis’ (p. 218). On the theory and history of this metaphor, see R. Konersmann, Lebendige Spiegel [Living Mirror].

214

Notes

26 G. W. Leibniz, ‘Aus den Briefen von Leibniz an Remond’ [From Leibniz’s Letters to Remond], p. 471. 27 On the history of the development of an understanding of perception from Kant to the neo-Kantians of formal aesthetics, cf. M. Podro, The Manifold in Perception. 28 K. Fiedler, Moderner Naturalismus und künstlerische Wahrheit [Modern Naturalism and Artistic Truth], p. 107. 29 G. Boehm, ‘Einleitung zu “Konrad Fiedler: Schriften zur Kunst I” ’ [Introduction to ‘Konrad Fiedler: Writings on Art I’], p. XLIX. In Gottfried Boehm’s account of ‘Fiedler’s interpretation of Kant’ (pp. XLVII–LII), the idea of a reinterpretation is central, as in the quotation. In fact this very probably matches Fiedler’s own understanding – as well as Wölfflin’s. As far as one can tell from the texts, both start from the perspective on Kant that was usual in the nineteenth-century, namely that Kant understands perception to be a process in which a form of intuition is in fact inscribed, but which does not take on a structuring through fantasy, produced in the imagination. But this understanding of Kant has been qualified frequently; cf. P. F. Strawson, ‘Imagination and Perception’. This interpretation of Kant centres on a footnote from the first edition of the Critique of Pure Reason. There, Kant notes that ‘the imagination is a necessary ingredient of perception itself ’ (A120, p. 239). That would mean that Kant, too, was unable to conceive of perception without immanent acts of fantasy. Yet it is difficult to know how firmly to place this footnote, which no longer appeared in the second edition of the Critique of Pure Reason, at the centre. As the starting point for Kant’s understanding of perception, it would necessarily change our picture of Fiedler: The ‘decisive reinterpretation’ (Boehm) then becomes an equally persuasive relationship of continuation, as it has been developed by Stefan Majetschak: ‘Exactly when Kant’s analysis applies, that we can count on the power of imagination having a constitutive function in any awareness of perceptible forms, we can say, with Fiedler, that the “fantasy of an artist [. . .] is basically nothing other than the power of imagination we all need to some extent in order to possess the world as a visible appearance” ’ (tr) (Bd.1, p. 31). (St. Majetschak, ‘Die Überwindung der Schönheit’ [The Conquest of Beauty], p. 60). 30 In considering that the critical basic ideas of Wölfflin’s later theory of art historical principles were already set out in Wölfflin’s dissertation ‘Prolegomena zu einer Psychologie der Architektur’ [Prolegomena to a Psychology of Architecture] of 1886, it is not surprising that Wölfflin was credited as a precursor even of gestalt theory; see F. Sander, ‘Gestaltpsychologie und Kunsttheorie’ [Gestalt Psychology and Art Theory]. Further systematic connections of Fiedler’s and Wölfflin’s theories of visibility to gestalt theory and in particular their common effect on abstract art of the early twentieth century are traced in W. Hofmann, ‘Studien zur Kunsttheorie des 20. Jahrhunderts’ [Studies on the Art Theory of the 20th Century].

Notes

215

31 ‘ “Seeing” ’ for instance, is not a passive process, by which meaningless impressions are stored up for the use of an organizing mind, which construes forms out of these amorphous data to suit its own purposes. “Seeing” is itself a process of formulation; our understanding of the visible world begins in the eye’ (S. K. Langer, Philosophy in a New Key, p. 90). 32 R. Arnheim, Visual Thinking, p. 14. 33 A. Eckl, ‘Zum Problem der kategorialen Funktion von Wölfflins “Kunstgeschichtlichen Grundbegriffen” ’ [On the Problem of Categorical Function in Wölfflin’s Art Historical Principles], p. 40. The interpretation of Wölfflin presented so concisely in this essay is examined more fully in Eckl’s book Kategorien der Anschauung [Categories of Perception]. 34 G. Boehm, Einleitung zu ‘Konrad Fiedler: Schriften zur Kunst 1’ [Introduction to ‘Konrad Fiedler: Writings on Art 1], p. XCI. 35 More precise observations about the relativity of seeing can be found in N. Goodman, The Structure of Appearance. 36 In The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception J. J. Gibson explicitly examines visual perception as a function of the perceiver’s environment. The ecological theory of perception provides concrete psychological results to support theses that are defended in philosophy at the level of principle through so-called interpretationism. Every perception process is an interpretation process according to this view, so that the environment determines the type of an internal interpretation. One could also say that since an observation is always determined by the environment, there is always a condition to its being understood. The chapter ‘Wahrnehmen und Interpretieren’ [Perceiving and Interpreting], pp. 110–131, in H. Lenk, Interpretationskonstruckte [Interpretational Constructs] is relevant here. 37 See M. H. Segall, D. T. Campbell and M. J. Herskovits, The Influence of Culture on Visual Perception, and Th. Kleinspehn, Der flüchtige Blick [The Fleeting Glance]. 38 K. Fiedler, ‘Über den Ursprung der künstlerischen Tätigkeit’ [The Origin of Artistic Activity], p. 130. 39 F. Fellmann, Symbolischer Pragmatismus [Symbolic Pragmatism], p. 34. 40 The most recent attempt so far to describe concrete spatial and also temporal formations can be found in Metamorphosen von Raum und Zeit [Transformations of Space and Time] by M. Burckhardt. Burckhardt’s insights lie directly the tradition of formal aesthetics: they read as an explicit continuation of this project. Yet it seems the recent histories of vision are generally marked by disinterest in any history of their own. This is also the case for the text of Th. Kleinspehn, mentioned earlier, Der flüchtige Blick [The Fleeting Glance]. In his very concise overview of recent attempts to understand the ways culture and technology has transformed vision, Wolfgang Kemp rightly arrived at the following generalization: ‘A common feature of these studies is a lack of awareness of the historicity of the approach.

216

41 42

43

44 45

46 47 48

Notes They lack a call and productive response to a life work structured entirely in this direction, making it all the more surprising, as Walter Benjamin, the everpresent mediator between a relatively narrow art history and a general cultural criticism, did not refrain from pointing out. I think of Alois Riegl, who [. . .] tested the possibilities for “a history of the eye” – a history of the eye being the corresponding formulation of the great competitor Heinrich Wölfflin, who, like Riegl, saw the history of vision as “the most elementary task of a history of art” ’ (tr) (‘Augengeschichten und skopische Regime’) [Histories of the Eye and Scopic Regimes]), p. 1164. H. Wölfflin, In eigener Sache [In My Own Affairs], p. 17. It is therefore entirely appropriate that Hermann Schmitz should assign Wölfflin a key position in his text ‘Der Leib im Spiegel der Kunst’ [The Body in the Mirror of Art] (1966): ‘Among the leading historians and theoreticians of art, Wölfflin seems to be the only one to have suspected, and even sometimes to even have clearly seen the definitive significance of bodily existence for the formation of artistic style’ (tr) (p. 257f.). In fact the interpretation of the concept of condition in Wölfflin has also shown that Schmitz’s assertion is valid not ‘for the young Wölfflin’ alone (ibid., p. 258), as he himself thought. Wölfflin did in fact defend the thesis especially clearly in his dissertation ‘Prolegomena zu einer Psychologie der Architektur’ [Prolegomena to a Psychology of Architecture] (p. 21). But this does not conflict with the later theory of art historical principles. A. Schopenhauer, The World as Will and Idea §18, p. 142. On the way Schopenhauer’s thinking related to the body see F. Esser, Die Funktion des Leibes in der Philosophie Schopenhauers [The Function of the Body in Schopenhauer’s Philosophy]. W. Dilthey, ‘Studien zur Grundlegung der Geisteswissenschaften’ [Studies on the Foundations of the Human Sciences], p. 33. From a certain perspective, Kant himself sets up the development of neoKantianism towards a historical subject. The Critique of Pure Reason ends, in any case, with very short fourth main section of the theory of transcendental method, with the title: ‘The History of Pure Reason’. Yet Kant himself confirmed that this heading is only a plan at this point: ‘This title stands here only to designate a place that is left open in the system and must be filled in the future (B880, p. 702). On Liebmann, see H. -L. Ollig, Der Neo-Kantianismus [Neo-Kantianism], pp. 9–15. A. Halder, Kunst und Kult [Art and Cult], p. 29. There is more detailed information about Friedmann’s philosophy in F. Kuntze, Der morphologische Idealismus [Morphological Idealism], and W. Hofmann, ‘Studien zur Kunsttheorie des 20. Jahrhunderts’ [Studies of 20th-Century Art Theory], pp. 149–152.

Notes

217

49 H. Plessner, ‘Die Einheit der Sinne’ [The Unity of the Senses], p. 81. 50 Spatial infrastructure according to Kant has been described with the instrumentation of relational logic in The Shape of Space by G. Nerlich; see in particular the chapter ‘Space and Systems of Relations’, pp. 5–28. 51 K. Fiedler, ‘Aphorismen’ [Aphorisms], p. 60. 52 G. Boehm, ‘Die Wiederkehr der Bilder’ [The Return of Images], p. 19. 53 A. Hildebrand, Das Problem der Form [The Problem of Form], p. 120. 54 It must be noted again here that the relativism of ways of seeing in formal aesthetics – with Fiedler as well as with Wölfflin – is based on a fundamental exclusion of practical demands, and so is concerned with the autonomous artistic look. Perception can only be emancipated if it has no purposes to serve. Fiedler definitely did point out that reality, which on the one hand ‘remains to the observation a continually changing, ephemeral play’, and on the other hand, ‘sets firm limits to human deeds and desires’ (tr) (Moderner Naturalismus und künstlerische Wahrheit [Modern Naturalism and Artistic Truth], p. 101). Nor were there any doubts at all in formal aesthetics about the argument against the relativism of ways of seeing presented with exceptional clarity by the Realist Georg Christoph Lichtenberg, namely ‘that human beings do not have the power to model the world as they wish, but do have to power to grind lenses through which it can be made to appear almost as they wish’ (‘Amintors Morgenandacht’ [Amintor’s Morning Devotion], p. 295). On the pragmatic limits of relativist positions, see F. Fellmann, Interpretationimus und symbolischer Pragmatismus [Interpretationism and Symbolic Pragmatism].

Chapter 4 1 K. Fiedler, ‘Aphorismen’ [Aphorisms], p. 21. 2 This is also confirmed in G. Pochat, Der Symbolbegriff in der Ästhetik und Kunstwissenschaft [The Concept of the Symbol in Aesthetics and Art History], pp. 69–76. 3 The research of Margaret Iverson on the semiotic dimension of Kunstwollen is helpful in this regard. She comes to the conclusion: ‘I have tried to show that this attention to form – the artifice of art – does not imply a disregard for meaning. On the contrary, it multiplies meanings. [. . .] This is the lesson of modernism: visual signs have a power of their own which is independent of the relationship to things’ (‘Style as Structure’, p. 71). 4 In this context it is also worth noting that a bridge from German to Russian formalism, as represented by Boris Eichenbaum, Roman Jakobson, Viktor Schklovsky and Yuri Tynyanov, might be thrashed out around this idea of

218

5

6 7

8

9

Notes

Fiedler’s. Russian formalism, too, although it is primarily a theory of literature and not a theory of visibility as formal aesthetics is, sees its task in an ‘analysis of form understood as content’– at least in Boris Eichenbaum’s ‘Die Theorie der formalen Methode’ [The Theory of the Formal Method] of 1925 (p. 21). The accompanying explanations concur with the argumentation from formal aesthetics as well: ‘A new meaning was now read from the form itself; it no longer registered as something external to the work, but as something concrete-dynamic that has content in itself, without any correlations. It amounted to a decisive criticism of the views of the Symbolists, who were looking behind and through the form for “content”. Hand in hand with this criticism went the conquering of “aestheticism”, the preference for individual components of the form, very consciously separated from “content” ’ (tr) (ibid., 20f.). Cf. A. A. Hansen-Löve, Der Russiche Formalismus [Russian Formalism], and V. Ehrlich, Russischer Formalismus [Russian Formalism]. Cf. U. Franke, Kunst als Erkenntnis [Art as Cognition], and G. Gabriel, ‘Erkenntnis in Wissenschaft, Philosophie und Dichtung’ [Cognition in Science, Philosophy and Poetry]. In Baumgarten we actually have the central aesthetician of the eighteenth century who, with his complementary understanding of logic and aesthetics, is in agreement in principle with Herbartianism’s programme of formal aesthetics. But this agreement in principle between Herbartianism and the original idea of an aesthetic discipline should not lead us on to suppose that Baumgarten was quick to distance himself from the Herbartians’ purely formal way of working in the way he imagined the realization of his programme. For Baumgarten, cognitive achievement specific to art is bound up with the contents of artworks. This is the reason Baumgarten’s aesthetics is carried further in the nineteenth century, if at all, in idealism and not in formal aesthetics. This is confirmed in H. Paetzold’s detailed history of Baumgarten’s influence Ästhetik des deutschen Idealismus [Aesthetics of German Idealism]. M. Bense, Aesthetica [Aesthetica], p. 49. B. Waldenfels, ‘Ordnungen des Sichtbaren’ [Orders of the Visible], p. 251. On understanding the idea of the artist’s studio as a scientist’s laboratory, see also N. Schmitz, Kunst und Wissenschaft im Zeichen der Moderne [Art and Science under the Sign of the Modern], pp. 153–166. In The Perception of the Visual World, James J. Gibson somewhat unconventionally uses an image fuzzy at the edges to represent the vision of children. Photographs serving this semiotic function are especially numerous in H. Haken and M. HakenKrell, Erfolgsgeheimnisse der Wahrnehmung [Secrets of Perceptual Success]. See I. Rentschler, ‘Weltbilder der Kunst – Erscheinungsformen der Wirklichkeit’ [World Views of Art – Forms of Reality’s Appearance].

Notes

219

10 M. Seel, Kunst, Wahrheit, Welterschließung [Art, Truth, Worldmaking], p. 44. Expressed in this essay especially concisely, the idea is examined in greater detail in Die Kunst der Entzweiung [The Art of Rupture]. 11 In The World through Blunted Sight. An Inquiry into the Influence of Defective Vision on Art and Character, the English ophthalmologist Patrick Trevor-Roper has, with impressive results, advanced the view that the visible world of art is for the most part the result of defective vision; see especially the chapter ‘The Unfocussed Image’, pp. 17–63. For G. Boehm, such naturalistic accounts serve as evidence that a basic hermeneutic understanding of the image has been lost. He rightly points out ‘just because vision has a natural basis is no reason to suppose that the viewer is entirely dependent on it’(Sehen [Seeing], p. 57). 12 E. H. Gombrich, in Zwischen Landkarte und Spiegelbild [Between Map and Mirror Image] further undermines this view. 13 K. Fiedler, On Judging Works of Visual Art, The stylistic colouration of perception is, accordingly, unavoidable. As a result, there are two possible reactions to it: One can try to understand the stylistic structures that are there, that is, to describe, in a metalinguistic move, the language of the perception in a conceptual language; or one lets himself be involved in an interaction between image and perception, that is, one tries to change his view. The first way corresponds to the programme of a hermeneutics of the image. Its goal is to develop conceptual categories that make the non-objective meaning of the images linguistically describable, and so make it possible to understand the conditionality of ways of seeing, a conditionality based on their immanent pictorial logic. The hermeneutics of images will not be pursued further here. Gottfried Boehm, in ‘Zu einer Hermeneutik des Bildes’ [On a Hermeneutics of Images], has traced its goals and its exact provenance from Fiedler’s demand for a logic of the image. At least equally plausible is the route taken by J. Hart, in ‘Reinterpreting Wölfflin’, from Wölfflin’s aesthetics to a hermeneutics of the image. 14 A. Schopenhauer, The World as Will and Idea, Vol. I, §37, p. 252. 15 W. Dilthey, ‘Contributions to the Study of Individuality’, p. 247. On the ‘crossfertilization of Dilthey’s and Wölfflin’s insights’, see also E. Utitz, Über Grundbegriffe der Kunstwissenschaft [On the Principles of Art History], p. 39. 16 K. Fiedler, ‘Aphorismen’ [Aphorisms], p. 42. 17 This idea that images, particularly in art, say less about objects than they do about conditions, is supported phenomenologically and semiotically in F. Fellmann, ‘Wovon sprechen die Bilder?’ [What Do Images Speak About?]. 18 F. Fellmann, Symbolischer Pragmatismus [Symbolic Pragmatism], p. 133. On the pictorial character of landscape perceptions, cf. M. Smuda, ‘Natur als ästhetischer Gegenstand und als Gegenstand der Ästhetik’ [Nature as an Aesthetic Object and as the Object of Aesthetics].

220

Notes

19 In his study Mental Imagery, Mark Rollins confirms this view: cf. especially the sections ‘Images as Structured Configurations’, pp. 72–81, and ‘Picture Perception and Mental Imagery’, pp. 99–108. It is astonishing how closely Rollins’s arguments resemble those of the formal aestheticians. One finds Rollins unfolding and persuasively defending the basic ideas of Fiedler and Wölfflin freshly against the background of recent findings in cognitive science. So he, too, begins by asserting: ‘It is crucial that it be possible for different series of images to represent the same content; for it is only in that way that the same visual process type can be said to admit of multiple realizations’ (ibid., p. 84). The reasoning from this inner flexibility of ‘ “images” lies in the same tradition: In order to describe perceptions, it is necessary to assume a “perceptual style” ’ (ibid., p. 94). According to Rollins, every perception is imprinted with what he calls ‘ “pictorial attitudes”, which have as their content a certain perceptual organization or way of seeing the world’ (ibid, p. 96). This way of seeing determines a form of intuition or, to be more precise with respect to the concept of form: ‘not just form but relation among form’ (ibid., p. 91). A noteworthy clarification of this understanding of internal images can be found in K. Sachs-Hombach, ‘Piktoriale Einstellungen’ [Pictorial Attitudes]. 20 B. Waldenfels, ‘Das Rätsel der Sichtbarkeit’ [The Mystery of Visibility], p. 335. Also noteworthy in this context is Henri Focillon, who does not yet figure in the history of phenomenology’s development, particularly in France, despite having worked out very comparable ideas as early as 1934 in his book The Life of Forms in Art: ‘Human consciousness is in perpetual pursuit of a language and a style. To assume consciousness is at once to assume form. Even at levels far below the zone of definition and clarity, forms, measures and relationship exist. The chief characteristic of the mind is to be constantly describing itself. The mind is a design that is in a state of ceaseless flux, of ceaseless weaving and then unweaving, and its activity, in this sense is an artistic activity’ (p. 118). It would be worth the effort to find out to what extent Focillon acted as intermediary between formal aestheticians such as Fiedler and Wölfflin on the one hand and Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenology on the other. For as the latter put it: ‘Perception already stylizes’ (The Prose of the World, p. 59). This passage alone is evidence of a basic structural affinity. 21 F. Fellmann, Symbolischer Pragmatismus [Symbolic Pragmatism], p. 70. 22 On these topics, see the essay by O. R. Scholz, ‘Bilder im Geiste?’ [Images in Minds?]. 23 N. Schmitz, Kunst und Wissenschaft im Zeichen der Moderne [Art and Science under the Sign of the Modern], p. 60. 24 See St. Majetschak, ‘Die Überwindung der Schönheit’ [The Conquest of Beauty]. 25 The concept of perceptual syntax appears as early as M. Mearleau-Ponty’s Phenomenology of 1945. 26 Cf. G. Boehm, ‘Die Bilderfrage’ [The Problem of Images].

Notes

221

27 See F. Fellmann, Phänomenologie und Expressionismus [Phenomenology and Expressionism], pp. 44–56 and 66–71. 28 Cf. Transparence et Opacité by Ph. Junod. 29 H. Sedlmayr, Art in Crisis, p. 91f. 30 Oliver R. Scholz exemplifies the language analytic point of view: ‘Whether something is an image or not depends not so much on how the thing is constituted as above all on which semiotic system is serving as the framework for the interpretation. Strictly speaking, one should not ask what an image is, or which things are images as such, but rather when, or under what conditions something is an image, when something is functioning within a pictorial system’ (tr) (Bild, Darstellung, Zeichen [Image, Representation, Sign], p. 83). 31 J. Berger, Ways of Seeing, p. 2. 32 See in this regard K. Malevitch’s own text, Suprematismus [Suprematism], and also in regard to his understanding of images the texts from the anthology Nach der Destruktion des ästhetischen Scheins [After the Destruction of Aesthetic Appearance], edited by H. M. Bachmayer, D. Kamper and F. Rötzer. 33 N. Bolz, Am Ende der Gutenberg-Galaxis [At the End of the Gutenberg Galaxy], p. 149. 34 See Wiesing, Stil statt Wahrheit [Style Instead of Truth], pp. 101–115. 35 B. Balázs, Visible Man, p. 27. 36 The thesis is also found in H. U. Gumbrecht, ‘Wahrnehmung vs. Erfahrung oder Die schnellen Bilder und ihre Interpretationsresistenz’ [Perception vs. Experience, or Rapid Imagery and Its Resistance to Interpretation]. 37 R. Musil, ‘Ansätze zu neuer Ästhetik’ [Approaches to Recent Aesthetics], p. 1138f. 38 See H. van den Boom, Digitale Ästhetik [Digital Aesthetics], and J. Deken, Computerbilder [Computer Images]. 39 For Vilém Flusser, this is the reason that ‘a visionary power is expressed in these surfaces that would never have been possible before the invention of keys (Into the Universe of Technical Images, p. 32). At first glance it may seem a surprising characterization. There was never any substance or danger about changing things in one’s imagination. But if we start from the idea that ‘technical images are envisioned surfaces’ (ibid., p. 33), Flusser’s thesis in fact becomes persuasive: if we interpret the image itself as one way imagination may be enacted, then the technical image opens unsuspected imaginative possibilities, and conversely technical images offer the theory of consciousness the possibility of thinking of the power of imagination as a form of virtual imagery. This suggestion – the pendant to Flusser’s approach, so to speak – can be found in F. Fellmann, Einbildungskraft as virtuelle Bildlichkeit [Imaginative Power as Virtual Imagery]. 40 The relevant account of possibilities for interaction between a human being and an image can be found in M. W. Krueger, Artificial Reality II.

222

Notes

41 See H. van den Boom, ‘Vom Modell zur Simulation’ [From Model to Simulation]. 42 On so-called interface design, see the essay collection The Art of Human-Computer, edited by B. Laurel. 43 An extensive overview of the developments, possibilities and assessment of cyberspace technology can be found in H. Rheingold’s report Virtuelle Welten [Virtual Worlds], as well as in the anthology Cyberspace, edited by F. Rötzer and P. Weibel. 44 ‘The world of numerical simulation is neither real nor imaginary, it presents another category: The virtual exists without really existing’ (tr) (Ed Couchot, ‘Die Spiele des Realen und des Virtuellen’ [Games of the Real and Virtual], p. 350. 45 K. Fiedler, Moderner Naturalismus und künstlerische Wahrheit [Modern Naturalism and Artistic Truth], p. 101. The dimension of cyberspace that is ghostly in best sense of the term is interpreted in K. Lüdeking, ‘Die Vergangenheit des Körpers’ [The Body’s Past]. 46 R. Musil, ‘Ansätze zu neuer Ästhetik’ [Approaches to Recent Aesthetics], p. 1140. 47 The goal of not understanding an image to be an interpretation was one of the visions linked to photography in classical modernism. The name of the photographer Edward Weston (1886–1958), for example, is firmly attached to the idea of ‘presentation instead of interpretation’. Today one gets the impression that photography raised expectations that could be met only by digital image processing. This background supports a fresh reading of early programs of photography, such as Weston’s call for presentation instead of interpretation. 48 Gottfried Gabriel describes a noteworthy attempt to mediate between scientifictheoretical and aesthetic routes. In the discussion of the relationships between ‘art and truth’ in ‘Erkenntnis in Wissenschaft, Philosophie und Dichtung’ [Cognition in Science, Philosophy and Poetry] he, too, comes to the conclusion: ‘So it seems that we are under pressure to introduce a completely different concept of truth, namely one that is non-propositional’ (tr) (p. 214). Yet his no doubt realistic estimate of the effect of this route prevents him from taking a thinkable theoretical route, ‘But this alternative offers no way out, at least none that could be accepted from a scientific theoretical standpoint’ (tr) (ibid.). He therefore outlines an alternative concept that ‘could satisfy all sides’. ‘This possibility consists of recognizing the propositional concept of truth as the only concept of truth, but extending the concept of cognition beyond the propositional concept of truth. This then means watching out for potentially non-propositional insights rather than for non-propositional truths’ (ibid.). 49 G. Gamm, Flucht aus der Kategorie [Escape from Categories], p. 329. See G. Abel, Interpretationswelten [Interpretation Worlds], pp. 300–314, for more about the fitting function’s inevitable dependence on practice and interpretation.

Notes

223

50 B. Waldenfels chose this formulation, which draws on the famous definition ‘veritas est adequatio rei et inerlectus’, in ‘Das Zerspringen des Seins’ [The Shattering of Being] (p. 149). 51 Cf. here the essay that remains today the most persuasive criticism, the young E. Panofsky’s ‘Das Problem des Stils in der bildenden Kunst’ [The Problem of Style in Visual Art]. On the other hand, A. Eckl rightly emphasizes that these criticisms lose their force when Wölfflin is read, against his own intention, in a strictly neoKantian, a-historic way: ‘If the Principles are understood to be the result of an analysis of the conditions of possibility for aesthetic perception, the periodicity of the stylistic development becomes contingent, rather than constitutive of Wölfflin’s theory’ (tr) (‘Zum Problem der kategorialen Funktion von Wölfflins “Kunstgeschichtlichen Grundbegriffen” ’ [On the Problem of Categorical Function of Wölfflin’s Art Historical Principles], p. 35. 52 The aesthetics of the American George Kubler is especially typical of this, as the following quotation shows: ‘The “history of things” is intended to reunite ideas and objects under the rubric of visual form: the term includes both artefacts and works of art, both replicas and unique examples, both tools and expressions – in short all materials worked by human hands under the guidance of connected developed in temporal sequence. From all these things a shape in time emerges. A visible portrait of the collective identity, whether tribe, class or nation, comes into being’ (The Shape of Time, p. 8). 53 A very similar argument appears in Hegel’s criticism of physiognomy from the Phenomenology of Spirit of 1807. It warns against interpreting facial characteristics as causal expressions of internal states and traits of character. These are only sign-based expressions, and only information that can therefore be true and false: ‘It is therefore no doubt an expression, but at the same time only in the sense of a sign, so that to the content expressed the peculiar nature of that by which it is expressed is completely indifferent. The inner in thus appearing is doubtless an invisible made visible, but without being itself united to this appearance’ (p. 111). 54 This is especially clear in Gombrich’s essay ‘Styles of Art and Styles of Life’. 55 On the relationship of information to image see H. D. Zimmer, Sprache und Bildwahrnehmung [Language and the Perception of Images]. 56 E. H. Gombrich, ‘Standards of Truth’, p. 266. 57 K. Fiedler, ‘Über die Beurteilung von Werken der bildenden Kunst’ [Evaluating Works of Visual Art], S. 57. 58 K. Fiedler, ‘Aphorismen’ [Aphorisms], p. 43 59 If we see this book as the one in which Simmel began to outline what later became his formal sociology, it seems almost obvious that formal analyses of art would also

224

60 61 62

63 64 65 66

Notes appear here and there in it. On the concept of formal sociology, see Chapter 3 in Simmel’s Grundfragen der Soziologie [Fundamental Questions in Sociology]. K. Fiedler, Moderner Naturalismus und künstlerische Wahrheit [Modern Naturalism and Artistic Truth], p. 99. A. C. Danto, The Transfiguration of the Commonplace, p. 146. N. Goodman, ‘On Rightness of Rendering’, p. 137. Goodman seems to want to make the question of the criterion for accuracy in art an exception to relativism found elsewhere in his writings. This is especially clear the Revisions he made with Catherine Z. Elgin of her theories in 1988. On the one hand, it represents relativism with respect to the view that a general criterion for accuracy might be found: ‘No philosophical pronouncement can provide a general criterion or rules for determining rightness’ (p. 158). But on the other hand, there is very definitely a suggestion for a possible criterion of accuracy specifically for works of visual art: it is success in changing a way of seeing, the function of sharing a mode of perception. At least the following sentences seem to repeat Dilthey’s view exactly: ‘A work is right to the extent that the markers it exemplifies can be projected to enhance our understanding of the work itself and of other aspects of our experience. Successful works transform perception and transfigure its objects by bringing us to recognize to aspects, objects and order that we would once have underrated or overlooked’ (ibid., p. 22). A. C. Danto, The Transfiguration of the Commonplace, p. 169. M. Seel, Kunst, Wahrheit, Welterschließung [Art, Truth, World Disclosure], p. 50 W. Dilthey, ‘The Three Epochs of Modern Aesthetics and Its Present Task’, p. 209. F. Fellmann, Symbolischer Pragmatismus [Symbolic Pragmatism], p. 194.

Chapter 5 1 See Ed Husserl, Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy. In this context see especially §30, ‘The General Theory of the Natural Attitude’, p. 56. 2 On the concept of epoché in Husserl, compare with The Problem of Epoché in the Philosophy of Edmund Husserl by E. Ströker. 3 Ed Husserl, ‘Investigation III: On the Theory of Wholes and Parts’, p. 170. 4 Cf. L. Wiesing, ‘Phänomenologie des Bildes nach Husserl und Sartre’ [Phenomenology of the Image after Husserl and Sartre]. 5 K. Fiedler, ‘Über den Ursprung der künstlerischen Tätigkeit’ [On the Origin of Artistic Activity], p. 153. 6 Ed Husserl, Cartesianische Meditationen [Cartesian Meditations], S. 50. 7 M. Merleau-Ponty, ‘The Philosopher and His Shadow’, p. 165.

Notes

225

8 J. Volkelt, ‘Objektive Ästhetik’ [Objective Aesthetics], p. 401. In light of the way formal analyses assumed phenomenological analysis – already noted in the previous chapter – one can only endorse E. Holenstein’s contemporary call for a systematic ‘reintegration of formal and structural analyses in phenomenology’ (E. Holenstein, Linguisik, Semiotik, Hermeneutik, [Linguistics, Semiotics, Hermeneutics], p. 9). The route Holenstein suggests for such reintegration is, however, oriented primarily towards the work of the Prague philosopher Roman Jakobson. See E. Holenstein, Roman Jakobson’s phänomenologischer Strukturalismus [Roman Jakobson’s Phenomenological Structuralism]. Jakobson’s work really is a prime example of an integration of formal and phenomenological thinking, in which his understanding of formalism lies in the Russian, rather than in the Herbartian tradition. In this respect two traditions in the integration of formal and phenomenological thinking should be distinguished. 9 Ed Husserl, Cartesianische Meditationen [Cartesian Meditations], p. 21. 10 F. Fellmann, Phänomenologie als ästhetische Theorie [Phenomenology as Aesthetic Theory], p. 127. 11 Cf. also L. Singer, ‘Merleau-Ponty on the Concept of Style’. 12 The art historian Hermann Beenken in particular worked this aspect of formal aesthestics in the essay ‘Konsequenzen und Aufgaben der Stilanalyse’[Implications and Tasks of Stylistic Analysis] of 1925. Beenken, who earned his doctoral degree under Wölfflin in Munich in 1920, was the first to call attention to the complementary relationship between Wölfflin and Husserl. He says, ‘What remains most comparable [to Wölfflin’s stylistic analysis] is phenomenological analysis as it was developed by Husserl and his circle for philosophical work. For there, too, in the area of, say, assertions in the realm of mental events, one is not content with an investigation of the factual, as it is done in psychology, it being a science of experience; rather phenomena are “transcendentally cleansed” by means of peculiar “reductions”, so that the statements are the statements of ideas, not statements of matters-of-fact. Stylistic analysis too, although it always starts from things given in experience, is aimed at “transcendentally cleansed phenomena”, and the principles it seeks are not, in the first instance, those of real matters-of-fact, but of essential principles, and so of ideal nature’ (‘Konsequenzen und Aufgaben der Stilanalyse’ [Implications and Tasks of Stylistic Analysis], p. 417f.). 13 M. Merleau-Ponty, The Visible and the Invisible, p. 236 14 M. Merleau-Ponty, ‘The Philosopher and His Shadow’, p. 166. 15 B. Waldenfels, Phänomenologie in Frankreich [Phenomenology in France], p. 200. 16 M. Merleau-Ponty, The Visible and the Invisible, p. 3. 17 M. Merleau-Ponty, ‘Eye and Mind’, pp. 165–166. 18 See O. Stelzer, Die Vorgeschichte der abstrakten Kunst [The Prehistory of Abstract Art].

226

Notes

19 The way theory and practice complement one another at the beginning of the century has been repeatedly noted. Here is Werner Hofmann’s view of aesthetics from Wölfflin to Sedlmayr: ‘One can come to this way of seeing only if one has learned, through engagement with the abstract painting of our time, to look into formal relationships without objects’ (Gespräche mit dem Sichtbaren [Conversations with the Visible], Part 2, p. 580). In the study Kunst und Wissenschaft im Zeichen der Moderne [Art and Science under the Sign of the Modern], N. Schmitz presents a pertinent account of the relationship between Wölfflin’s art theory and the origin of abstract images, which can be especially persuasively drawn as a comparison with the work of Adolph Hölzel. 20 F. Schlegel, Schriften zur Literatur [Writings on Literature], Frag. 238, p. 50. According to Franz Gniffke, ‘Transcendental Poetry’ is the name ‘for an art that has become critical in the Kantian sense, because it reflects conditions of its objective depiction that had never become visible before. That means that the process of the painter’s reflection goes back – more than on his own representation in a self-portrait or the representation of such things as the situation of the painter in the studio – into the invisible conditions for making them visible’ (‘Bilder über Bilder’ [Images about Images], p. 208). The transcendental thinking of Kant and particularly of neo-Kantianism was actually read in detail by the fathers of abstract art, and undoubtedly had a decisive effect on the intellectual framework of their works, as D. H. Kahnweiler was able to emphasize in an exemplary way through the example of the emergence of Cubism with Juan Gris; see D. -H. Kahnweiler, Juan Gris. 21 See F. Fellmann, Phänomenologie und Expressionismus [Phenomenology and Expressionism], and H. R. Sepp, ‘Annäherungen an die Wirklichkeit’ [Approaches to Reality]. 22 F. Fellmann elaborates this idea in Phänomenologie als ästhetische Theorie [Phenomenology as Aesthetic Theory]. Largely neglected ideas about the image as an artistic means of pursuing phenomenological interests appear very early in the work of Husserl’s student, the Freiburger Fritz Kaufmann; see especially Kaufmann’s 1940 study ‘Kunst und Phänomenologie’ [Art and Phenomenology]. 23 From this point of view, it seems obvious that only in the abstract image did the art historical principles find an object adequate to their theses. This reading of formal aesthetics would argue roughly as follows: Formal pictorial analysis in Wölfflin is directed at the wrong object. The purely relational view should be directed towards purely abstract images from the start, for only in this way is no tension generated; in this way no reduction to form is necessary, for the abstract image already does what formal aesthetics tries to do more or less forcefully with an objective image: to make a pure network of immanent relations. A. Eckl gives exemplary evidence that the results of Wölfflin’s theory of art historical principles really can be profitably used to

Notes

24 25 26 27

227

interpret an abstract composition in ‘Zum Problem der kategorialen Funktion von Wölfflins “Kunstgeschichtlichen Grundbegriffen” ’ [On the Problem of Categorical Function of Wölfflin’s Art Historical Principles], pp. 44–52. H. Wölfflin, ‘Adolf von Hildebrand’, p. 92. R. Ingarden, The Ontology of the Work of Art, p. 214. Cf. also R. Ingarden, ‘Über die sogenannte “abstrakte” Malerei’ [On So-Called ‘Abstract’ Painting]. Cf. G. Boehm, Abstraktion und Realität [Abstraction and Reality]. E. von Rüden, van de Velde – Kandinsky – Hölzel, p. 45.

Chapter 6 1 Cf. E. H. Gombrich, ‘The “What” and the “How” ’. 2 To return to Frege’s view, in an abstract image we are dealing with a sign that has sense, but no meaning. In a footnote to ‘Sense and Reference’, Frege himself proposed ‘it would be desirable to have a special term for signs having only sense’ (p. 216). He suggests naming them ‘representations’ (ibid.). This is a very capricious suggestion, for in following it, concepts such as ‘unicorn’ would be representations, on the one hand, and on the other, representations that depict extant things would be no longer be representations. As will be examined more fully in what follows, what Frege calls a representation would better be called a fictional sign. 3 Cf. W. Hofmann, Von der Nachahmung zur Wirklichkeit [From Imitation to Reality]. 4 M. Seel, Kunst, Wahrheit, Welterschließung’ [Art, Truth, World Disclosure], p. 62. 5 The reference is to the Festschrift Zeichen von Zeichen für Zeichen [Signs for Signs about Signs], edited by E. Walther and U. Bayer. 6 Cf. A. Gehlen, Zeit-Bilder [Time Images]. See F. Gniffke, ‘Bilder über Bilder’ [Images about Images]. 7 For examples, see M. Imdahl, Giotto Arenafresken, and E. Loran, Cézanne’s Composition. On the current discussion of art historical structural drawings and specifically on the difference between their conception of ways of seeing and that of works of art, cf. F. Koppe, ‘Kunst als entäußerte Weise, die Welt zu sehen’ [Art as an Externalized Way of Seeing the World]. 8 So-called computer-generated cartoons can also be mentioned in this context. These are technically generated images about images of a particular kind, specifically drawings that are produced from photographs by means of a computer. Cf. the essay ‘Computer-Generated Cartoons’ by D. Pearson, E. Hanna and K. Martinez. 9 Husserl speaks of ‘adequate images’. For him, this is a special form of ‘multifaceted pictoriality’ [‘mehrfältigen Bildlichkeit’]. This is Husserl’s

228

10

11

12 13

14 15

Notes extraordinary name for all types of image-depicting images, from an essay of 1905 among his posthumous papers. But more detailed explanations remain very sketchy. On adequate images he says: ‘An adequate image; that is, in the case of images of images, an image that is a perfect copy of the original image such that the image apprehension could no longer feel any duality at all and therefore image apprehension could no longer occur [. . .] In the case of paintings: The images of paintings can be adequate if, say, the image intends to be the image only of the plastic form’ (Phantasy, Image Consciousness and Memory, Appendix IX, p. 189). In this context, reference is made expressly to G. Gabriel’s pertinent research, which persuasively shows why one need not assume the ontological existence of fictional objects in order to describe fictional signs. Fictional objects can be grasped as pure sense structures (intensions). In this regard, see G. Gabriel’s essay ‘Sachen gibt’s, die gibt’s gar nicht’ [There Are Things That Don’t Exist] as well as his chapter ‘Semantische Grundbegriffe und die Definition des Terminus “fiktionale Rede” ’ [Semantic Principles and the Definition of the Term ‘Fictional Speech’] in Fiktion und Wahrheit [Fiction and Truth], pp. 14–32. Ch. W. Morris, ‘Esthetics and the Theory of Signs’, p. 140. Morris’s comparison also matches the self-conception of many abstract artists, as is clear in O. Stelzer, Die Vorgeschichte der abstrakten Kunst [The Prehistory of Abstract Art], especially in the chapter ‘Kunst und Mathematik’ [Art and Mathematics], pp. 24–28. Max Bense, who has made use of Morris’s insights at many points in his aesthetics, points out the semiotic parallels between formal communication in art and mathematics as well. He confirms, ‘There are “formal communications” that appear here as the bearers of aesthetic characteristics. With them, artistic results move into the area of mathematical phenomena’ (tr) (Aesthetica, p. 49). N. Goodman, Languages of Art, p. 53, n.5. In the essay ‘Die Rolle von Probe und Etikett in Goodmans Theorie des Exemplifikation’ [The Role of the Probe and Label in Goodman’s Theory of Exemplification], D. Gerhardus has worked through the part-to-whole relation and interpreted it more closely. N. Goodman, Languages of Art, p. 53. Cassirer does in fact give a description of a symbolic function – as Ernst Wolfgang Orth worked out in his essay ‘Lektüre und geistiger Bildraum’ [Readings and Mental Pictorial Space] – specific to ‘formal contact with realities resulting in substantial loss of bearings’ (tr) (p. 186). By 1927, Cassirer was already making a semiotic distinction between the ‘expression’ [Ausdruck] and the ‘representation’ [Darstellung] of ‘pure meaning’ [reine Bedeutung]; See E. Cassirer, ‘Das Symbolproblem und seine Stellung im System der Philosophie’, [The Problem of the Symbol and Its Position in the System of Philosophy], pp. 88–89 and 90–91 and 8–10. In fact Cassirer’s concept of pure meaning already contains the idea of a

Notes

16

17

18 19

20 21

22 23 24 25 26 27 28

229

semiotic comparison between abstract, aesthetic phenomena and the language of mathematics in Morris’s concept of the formator. For – as Orth, too, demonstrates – Morris’s prime examples of pure meaning embrace ‘mathematical calculation – but also that which he calls style’ (tr) (‘Lektüre und geistiger Bildraum’ [Readings and Mental Pictorial Space]), p. 186. This apt phrase appears in the introduction to Ch. L. Hart Nibbrig’s Zum Drum und Dran einer Fragestellung [On the Ins and Outs of an Inquiry] in a short parallelization of mathematical formulae with music, p. 12. G. Gamm, Flucht aus der Kategorie [Escape from Categories], p. 109. Cf. also G. Gabriel, Fiktion und Wahrheit [Fiction and Truth] the chapter: ‘Von der Semantik zur Ästhetik’ [From Semantics to Aesthetics], pp. 99–111. Cf. also F. Kambartel, ‘Formales und Inhaltliches Sprechen’ [Speech: Form and Content]. The concept of ‘imitation formula’ was introduced by Miorita Ulrich. See the essays ‘Bread-and-butter, Bread-and-butter’ and ‘Sprachnachahmung, Nachahmung von Sprache und Übersetzung’ [Linguistic Imitation, Imitation of Language and Translation]. M. Ulrich, ‘Bread-and-butter, Bread-and-butter’, p. 269. K. Fiedler, ‘Wirklichkeit und Kunst’ [Reality and Art], p. 125. In a comparable way, Aby Warburg (1866–1929) also interprets art as an inherited system of formulae. Warburg was not interested in formulae for visibility manifest in art, however, but in formulae for pathos, on what he called ‘pathos formulae’ (See A. M. Warburg, Ausgewählte Schriften und Würdigungen [Selected Writings and Criticism], pp. 125 ff. and 153 ff.). But as far as the implicit semiotic evaluation of art is concerned, Warburg’s interpretive direction is in line with Fiedler’s – which is the one Morris articulated. In his interpretation of the pathos formula in ‘Von Warburg ausgehend’ [Starting with Warburg], Hans Ulrich Reck returns to the structural affinity between formulae and Husserl’s concept of horizon and speaks trenchantly of the formula as a ‘horizon of expectation’ (p. 208). K. Fiedler, ‘Wirklichkeit und Kunst’ [Reality and Art], pp. 124, 125, 126, 128, 157, 158, 160 and 162. Cf. P. Weibel, Musik-Videos’ [Music Videos]. P. Virilio, ‘The Illusions of Zero Time’, p. 30. H. Buddemeier, Leben in künstlichen Welten [Life in Artificial Worlds], p. 46. See M. McLuhan, Understanding Media: The Extensions of Man. G. Anders, Die Welt als Phantom und Matrize [The World as Phantom and Matrix], pp. 142 and 170. V. Anding, ‘TV-Trilogie’ [TV Trilogy], p. 17.

Bibliography Abel, Günter (1993) Interpretationswelten. Gegenwartsphilosophie jenseits von Essentialismus und Relativismus, Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp. Abel, Günter (1987) ‘Logik und Ästhetik’, 112–148 in Nietzsche-Studien, Vol. 16. Adorno, Theodor W. (2006) Philosophy of New Music, trans. Robert Hullot-Kentor, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Åhlberg, L.-O. (1991) ‘Form and Content Revisited’, 9–26 in Filozofski Vestnik, Vol. 1. Allen, Grant (1977) [1877] Physiological Aesthetics, New York: Garland. Allesch, Christian Gerd (1994) Geschichte der psychologischen Ästhetik. Untersuchungen zur historischen Entwicklung eines psychologischen Verständnisses ästhetischer Phänomene, Göttingen: Hogrefe. Anders, Günther (1994) [1956] ‘Die Welt als Phantom und Matrize’, 97–212 in Die Antiquiertheit des Menschen, Vol. 1, Über die Seele im Zeitalter der zweiten industriellen Revolution, Munich: C.H. Beck. Anding, Volker (1986) ‘TV-Trilogie’, 17–20 in Video in Kunst und Alltag. Vom kommerziellen zum kulturellen Videoclip, eds. Veruschka and Gabor Bódy, Cologne: DuMont. Apel, Karl–Otto (1975) Der Denkweg von Charles Sanders Peirce, Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp. Arnheim, Rudolph (1969) Visual Thinking, Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press. Bachmayer, Hans Matthäus, Kamper, Dietmar and Rötzer, Florian (1992) Nach der Destruktion des ästhetischen Scheins. Van Gogh – Malewitsch – Duchamp, Munich: Boer. Bacon, Francis (2000) [1620] The New Organon, New York: Cambridge University Press. Balázs, Béla (2010) [1924] ‘Visible Man’, 1–90 in Early Film Theory: Visible Man or the Culture of Film, trans. Rodney Livingstone, New York: Berghahn Books. Barrach, Siegmund (1854) Über spekulative Ästhetik und Kritik, Vienna: Tendler. Baudrillard, Jean (1993) ‘Kool Killer, or the Insurrection of Signs’, 76–83 in Symbolic Exchange and Death, trans. Iain Hamilton Grant, London: Sage. Bauer, Roger (1966) Der Idealismus und seine Gegner in Österreich, Heidelberg: Winter. Beenken, Hermann (1925) ‘Konsequenzen und Aufgaben der Stilanalyse’, 417–437 in Zeitschrift für Ästhetik und allgemeine Kunstwissenschaft, Vol. 18. Benjamin, Walter (1969) [1936] ‘The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction’, 217–252 in Illuminations, trans. Harry Zohn, New York: Schocken.

232

Bibliography

Bense, Max (1982) [1965] Aesthetica. Einführung in die neue Aesthetik, Baden-Baden: Agis. Berger, John (1972) Ways of Seeing, London: Penguin. Bochenski, Joseph M. A. (1961) A History of Formal Logic. Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press. Bockemühl, Michael (1991) J. M. W. Turner. Die Welt des Lichtes und der Farbe, Cologne: Taschen. Boehm, Gottfried (1990) ‘Abstraktion und Realität. Zum Verhältnis von Kunst und Kunstphilosophie in der Moderne’, 225–237 in Philosophisches Jahrbuch, Vol. 97. Boehm, Gottfried (1980) ‘Bildsinn und Sinnesorgane’, 118–132 in Neue Hefte für Philosophie, Vol. 18/19. Boehm, Gottfried (1994) ‘Die Bilderfrage’, 325–343 in Was ist ein Bild?, Munich: Wilhelm Fink. Boehm, Gottfried (1994) ‘Die Wiederkehr der Bilder’, 11–38 in Was ist ein Bild?, München: Wilhelm Fink. Boehm, Gottfried (1991) ‘Einleitung zu “Konrad Fiedler: Schriften zur Kunst I” ’, XLV–XLCVII, Munich: Wilhelm Fink. Boehm, Gottfried (1992) ‘Sehen. Hermeneutische Reflexionen’, 50–67 in Internationale Zeitschrift für Philosophie, Vol. 1. Boehm, Gottfried (1978) ‘Zu einer Hermeneutik des Bildes’, 444–472 in Die Hermeneutik und die Wissenschaften, Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp. Böhme, Gernot (1970) ‘Whiteheads Abkehr von der Substanzmetaphysik. Substanz und Relation’, 548–553 in Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung, Vol. 24. Bolz, Norbert (1993) Am Ende der Gutenberg-Galaxis. Die neuen Kommunikationsverhältnisse, Munich: Wilhelm Fink. Bolz, Norbert (1992) Chaos und Simulation, Munich: Wilhelm Fink. Bolzano, Bernard (1972) [1843] ‘Über den Begriff des Schönen. Eine philosophische Abhandlung’, 1–118 in Untersuchungen zur Grundlegung der Ästhetik, ed. Dietfried Gerhardus, Frankfurt a.M.: Athenäum. Boom, Holger van den (1987) Digitale Ästhetik. Zu einer Bildungstheorie des Computers, Stuttgart: Metzler. Boom, Holger van den (1988) ‘Vom Modell zur Simulation. Die Zukunft des Designprozesses’, 13–40 in Simulation und Wirklichkeit, Cologne: DuMont. Braque, Georges (1953) Der Tag und die Nacht. Aus den Aufzeichnungen 1917–1952, Zurich: Die Arche. Brinkmann, Donald (1938) Natur und Kunst. Zur Phänomenologie des ästhetischen Gegenstandes, Zurich and Leipzig: Rascher. Brunswig, Alfred (1910) Das Vergleichen und die Relationserkenntnis, Leipzig and Berlin: Teubner. Bryson, Norman (1983) Vision and Painting. The Logic of the Gaze, New Haven and London: Yale University Press.

Bibliography

233

Bubner, Rüdiger (1989) [1973] ‘Über einige Bedingungen gegenwärtiger Ästhetik’, 9–51 in Ästhetische Erfahrung, Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp. Buddemeier, Heinz (1993) Leben in künstlichen Welten. Cyberspace, Videoclips und das tägliche Fernsehen, Stuttgart: Urachhaus. Burckhardt, Martin (1994) Metamorphosen von Raum und Zeit. Eine Geschichte der Wahrnehmung, Frankfurt and New York: Campus. Bürger, Peter (1981) ‘Probleme gegenwärtiger Ästhetik’, 200–244 in Kolloquium Kunst und Philosophie 1. Ästhetische Erfahrung, ed. Willi Oelmüller, Paderborn, Munich, Vienna and Zurich: UTB. Bürger, Peter (1984) [1974] Theory of the Avant-Garde, trans. Michael Shaw, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Bürger, Peter (1979) Vermittlung – Rezeption – Funktion. Ästhetische Theorie und Methodologie der Literaturwissenschaft, Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp. Bürger, Peter (1983) Zur Kritik der idealistischen Ästhetik, Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp. Burkamp, Wilhelm (1927) Begriff und Beziehung. Studien zur Grundlegung der Logik, Leipzig: Meiner. Burkamp, Wilhelm (1932) Logik, Berlin: Mittler & Sohn. Carnap, Rudolf (1954) Einführung in die symbolische Logik, Vienna: Springer. Cassirer, Ernst (1985) [1927] ‘Das Symbolproblem und seine Stellung im System der Philosophie’, 1–21 in Symbol, Technik, Sprache. Aufsätze aus den Jahren 1927–1933, Hamburg: Meiner. Cassirer, Ernst (2000) [1942] The Logic of the Cultural Sciences, trans. Steve G. Lofts, New Haven and London: Yale University Press. Cassirer, Ernst (1953) [1923] The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms, Vol. 1: Language, trans. Ralph Manheim, New Haven: Yale University Press. Cassirer, Ernst (1953) [1910] Substance and Function and Einstein’s Theory of Relativity, trans. William Curtis Swabey and Marie Collins Swabey, New York: Dover Publications. Couchot, Edmond (1991) ‘Die Spiele des Realen und des Virtuellen’, 346–355 in Digitaler Schein. Ästhetik der elektronischen Medien, Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp. Croce, Benedetto (1929) [1911] ‘Die Theorie der Kunst als reiner Sichtbarkeit’, 191–205 in Kleine Schriften zur Ästhetik in zwei Bänden, Vol. 2, Tübingen: Mohr (Siebeck). Danto, Arthur C. (1981) The Transfiguration of the Commonplace: A Philosophy of Art, Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Deken, Joseph (1984) [1983] Computerbilder. Kreativität und Technik, Basel: Birkhäuser. Dickie, George (1968) ‘Is Psychology Relevant to Aesthetics?’ 321–335 in Contemporary Studies in Aesthetics, ed. F. J. Coleman, New York: McGraw-Hill . Dilthey, Wilhelm (1934) [1895/96] ‘Beiträge zum Studium der Individualität’, 241–316 in Gesammelte Schriften, Vol. 5, Stuttgart and Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht. Dilthey, Wilhelm (1989) [1883] ‘Introduction to the Human Sciences’, in Selected Works, Vol. 1, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

234

Bibliography

Dilthey, Wilhelm (1942) [1910] ‘Studien zur Grundlegung der Geisteswissenschaften’, 3–75 in Gesammelte Schriften, Vol. 7, Leipzig and Berlin: Teubner. Dilthey, Wilhelm (1985) [1892] ‘The Three Epochs of Modern Aesthetics and Its Present Task’, 175–222 in Wilhelm Dilthey Selected Works, Vol. 5, Princeton: Princeton University Press. Dittmann, Lorenz (1967) Stil, Symbol, Struktur. Studien zu Kategorien der Kunstgeschichte, Munich: Wilhelm Fink. Dörflinger, Bernd (1988) Die Realität des Schönen in Kants Theorie rein ästhetischer Urteilskraft. Zur Gegenstandsbedeutung subjektiver und formaler Ästhetik, Bonn: Bouvier. Duve, Thierry (1996) [1989] Kant after Duchamp, Cambridge: MIT Press. Dvořák, Max (1929) [1905] ‘Alois Riegl’, 279–298 in Gesammelte Aufsätze zur Kunstgeschichte, eds. Karl Maria Swoboda and Johannes Wilde, München: Piper. Eckl, Andreas (1995) Kategorien der Anschauung. Zur transzendentalphilosophischen Bedeutung von Heinrich Wölfflins ‘Kunstgeschichtlichen Grundbegriffen’, Munich: Wilhelm Fink. Eckl, Andreas (1993) ‘Zum Problem der kategorialen Funktion von Wölfflins “Kunstgeschichtlichen Grundbegriffen”. Erläuterungen an einem Beispiel ihrer Anwendung’, 29–52 in Zeitschrift für Ästhetik und allgemeine Kunstwissenschaft, Vol.38. Eco, Umberto (1986) [1985] ‘Mirrors’, 202–226 in Semiotics and the Philosophy of Language, Bloomington: University of Indiana Press. Ehrenfels, Christian von (1967) [1890] ‘Über “Gestaltqualitäten” ’, 11–43 in Gestalthaftes Sehen. Ergebnisse und Aufgaben der Morphologie, ed. Ferdinand Weinhandl, Darmstadt: WBG. Ehrlich, Victor (1983) Russischer Formalismus, Munich: Hanser. Eichenbaum, Boris (1965) [1925] ‘Die Theorie der formalen Methode’, 7–52 in Aufsätze zur Theorie und Geschichte der Literatur, ed. Alexander Kaempfe, Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp. Enzensberger, Hans Magnus (1989) [1988] ‘Das Nullmedium oder Warum alle Klagen über das Fernsehen gegenstandslos sind’, 89–103 in Mittelmaß und Wahn. Gesammelte Zerstreuungen, Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp. Esser, Franziska (1991) Die Funktion des Leibes in der Philosophie Schopenhauers, Dissertation, Münster. Fechner, Gustav Theodor (1978) [1876] Vorschule der Ästhetik and Zur experimentellen Ästhetik [1871], Hildesheim and New York: Olms. Fellmann, Ferdinand (1995) ‘Einbildungskraft und virtuelle Bildlichkeit’, 264–272 in Weltbilder-Bilderwelten. Computergestützte Visionen, Interface 2, ed. Klaus Peter Dencker, Hamburg: Hans-Bredow-Institut für Rundfunk and Fernsehen. Fellmann, Ferdinand (1990) ‘Interpretationismus und symbolischer Pragmatismus’, 51– 59 in Allgemeine Zeitschrift für Philosophie, Vol. 15.

Bibliography

235

Fellmann, Ferdinand (1989) Phänomenologie als ästhetische Theorie, Freiburg and Munich: Alber. Fellmann, Ferdinand (1982) Phänomenologie und Expressionismus, Freiberg and Munich: Alber. Fellmann, Ferdinand (1991) Symbolischer Pragmatismus. Hermeneutik nach Dilthey, Reinbek bei Hamburg: Rowohlt. Fellmann, Ferdinand (1996) ‘Wovon sprechen die Bilder? Aspekte der Bild-Semantik’, 143–155 in Bild und Reflexion. Paradigmen und Perspektiven gegenwärtiger Ästhetik, eds. Birgit Recki and Lambert Wiesing, Munich: Wilhelm Fink. Feyerabend, Paul (1984) ‘Science as Art: a Discussion of Riegl’s Theory of Art and an Attempt to Apply It to the Sciences’, 16–46 in Art & Text, Vols. 12 and 13. Fiebig, Ernst (1930) Bobriks Ästhetik. Beiträge zur Lehre des ästhetischen Formalismus, Dissertation, Bonn. Fiedler, Konrad (1991) [without Year] ‘Aphorismen’, 7–105 in Schriften zur Kunst, Vol. 2, ed. Gottfried Boehm, Munich: Wilhelm Fink. Fiedler, Konrad (1991) [1881] ‘Moderner Naturalismus und künstlerische Wahrheit’, 81–110 in Schriften zur Kunst, Vol. 1, ed. Gottfried Boehm, Munich: Wilhelm Fink. Fiedler, Konrad (1949) [1876] On Judging Works of Visual Art, trans. Henry SchaeferSimmern and Fulmer Mood, Berkeley: University of California Press, Fiedler, Konrad (1991) [1887] ‘Über den Ursprung der künstlerischen Tätigkeit’, 111– 220 in Schriften zur Kunst, Vol. 1, ed. Gottfried Boehm, Munich: Wilhelm Fink. Fiedler, Konrad (1991) [without Year] ‘Wirklichkeit und Kunst. Drei Bruchstücke’, 107– 193 in Schriften zur Kunst, Vol. 2, ed. Gottfried Boehm, Munich: Wilhelm Fink. Flügel, Otto (1864) ‘Über den formalen Charakter der Ästhetik’, 349–370 in Zeitschrift für exakte Philosophie, Vol. 4. Flusser, Vilém (2011) Into the Universe of Technical Images, trans. Nancy Ann Roth, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Flusser, Vilém (1993) Lob der Oberflächlichkeit. Für eine Phänomenologie der Medien, ed. Stefan Bollmann, Bensheim and Düsseldorf: Bollmann. Focillon, Henri (1989) [1934] The Life of Forms in Art, New York: Zone Books. Foster, Hal (1988) Vision and Visuality, Seattle: Bay Press. Foucault, Michel (2002) [1969] The Archaeology of Knowledge, trans. Alan M. Sheridan Smith, London and New York: Routledge Classics. Franke, Ursula (1972) Kunst als Erkenntnis. Die Rolle der Sinnlichkeit in der Ästhetik des Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten, Wiesbaden: Steiner. Frege, Gottlob (1948) [1892] ‘Sense and Reference’, 209–230 in The Philosophical Review, Vol. 57. Frey, Dagobert (1946) Kunstwissenschaftliche Grundfragen. Prolegomena zu einer Kunstphilosophie, Vienna: Steiner. Frey, Dagobert (1958) ‘Probleme einer Geschichte der Kunstwissenschaft’, 1–37 in Deutsche Vierteljahresschrift für Literaturwissenschaft und Geistesgeschichte, Vol. 32.

236

Bibliography

Friedmann, Hermann (1930) [1925] Die Welt der Formen. System eines morphologischen Idealismus, Munich: C.H. Beck. Gabriel, Gottfried (1991) ‘Der Logiker als Metaphoriker. Freges philosophische Rhetorik’, 65–88 in Zwischen Logik und Literatur. Erkenntnisformen von Dichtung, Philosophie und Wissenschaft, Stuttgart: Metzler. Gabriel, Gottfried (1991) ‘Erkenntnis in Wissenschaft, Philosophie und Dichtung. Argumente für einen komplementären Pluralismus’, 202–224 in Zwischen Logik und Literatur. Erkenntnisformen von Dichtung, Philosophie und Wissenschaft, Stuttgart: Metzler. Gabriel, Gottfried (1975) Fiktion und Wahrheit. Eine semantische Theorie der Literatur, Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Frommann und Holzboog. Gabriel, Gottfried (1996) ‘Logik in Literatur. Über logisches und analogisches Denken’, 109–133 in Philosophie in Literatur, eds. Christiane Schildknecht and Dieter Teichert, Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp. Gabriel, Gottfried (1991) [1987] ‘ “Sachen gibt’s, die gibt’s gar nicht”, Sind literarische Figuren fiktive Gegenstände?’, 133–146 in Zwischen Logik und Literatur. Erkenntnisformen von Dichtung, Philosophie und Wissenschaft, Stuttgart: Metzler. Galton, Francis (1962) [1869] Hereditary Genius. An Inquiry into Its Laws and Consequences, London, Cleveland and New York: Meridian. Gamm, Gerhard (1994) Flucht aus der Kategorie. Die Positivierung des Unbestimmten als Ausgang der Moderne, Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp. Gehlen, Arnold (1986) [1960] Zeit-Bilder. Zur Soziologie und Ästhetik der modernen Malerei, Frankfurt a.M. and Bonn: Klostermann. Genette, Gérard (1992) [1991] Fiktion und Diktion, Munich: Wilhelm Fink. Gerhardt, Volker (1984) ‘Von der ästhetischen Metaphysik zur Physiologie der Kunst’, 374–393 in Nietzsche-Studien, Vol. 13. Gerhardus, Dietfried (1994) ‘Die Rolle von Probe und Etikett in Goodmans Theorie der Exemplifikation’, 882–891 in Analyomen 1. Proceedings of the 1st Conference ‘Perspectives in Analytical Philosophy, eds. Georg Meggle and Ursula Wessels, Berlin and New York: De Gruyter. Gibson, James J. (1979) The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception, Boston: Houghton Mifflin. Gibson, James J. (1950) The Perception of the Visual World, Boston: Houghton Mifflin. Gilbert, Katherine Everett and Kuhn, Helmut (1954) A History of Esthetics, Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Gniffke, Franz (1990) ‘Bilder über Bilder. Ansätze einer Theorie moderner Malerei bei Kant’, 183–211 in Wozu Bilder im Christentum? Beiträge zur theologischen Kunsttheorie, ed. Alex Stock, St. Ottilien: EOS-Verlag. Goethe, Johann Wolfgang von (1961) [1808] Faust, trans. Walter Kaufmann, New York: Anchor Books. Goethe, Johann Wolfgang von (1989) [1829] ‘Wilhelm Meister’s Journeyman Years’, in Goethe: The Collected Works, Vol. 10, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Bibliography

237

Gold, Peter (1991) Darstellung und Abstraktion. Aporien formaler Ästhetik, Frankfurt a.M.: Hain. Gombrich, Ernst H. (1982) ‘Mirror and Map: Theories of Pictorial Representation’, 172–214 in The Image and the Eye: New Studies in the Psychology of Pictorial Representation, Oxford: Phaidon. Gombrich, Ernst H. (1966) [1963] ‘Norm and Form. The Stylistic Categories of Art History and their Origins in Renaissance Ideals’, 81–98 in Norm and Form. Studies in the Art of the Renaissance, London: Phaidon. Gombrich, Ernst H. (1932/33) ‘Rezension von “J. Bodonyi: Entstehung und Bedeutung des Goldgrundes in der spätantiken Bildkomposition” ’, 65–76 in Kritische Berichte zur kunstgeschichtlichen Literatur, Vol. 5. Gombrich, Ernst H. (1982) ‘Standards of Truth: The Arrested Image and the Moving Eye’, 244–277 in New Studies in the Psychology of Representation, Oxford: Phaidon. Gombrich, Ernst H. (1991) ‘Styles of Art and Styles of Life’, 9–22 in Kunst & Museumjournaal, Vol. 3. Gombrich, Ernst H. (1972) ‘The “What” and the “How”, Perspective Representation and the Phenomenal World’, 129–149 in Logic and Art: Essays in Honor of Nelson Goodman, eds. Richard S. Rudner and Israel Scheffler, Indianapolis and New York: Ridgeview. Goodman, Nelson (1968) Languages of Art: An Approach to a Theory of Symbols, Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill. Goodman, Nelson (1978) ‘On Rightness of Rendering’, 109–140 in Ways of Worldmaking, Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing. Goodman, Nelson (1966) [1951] The Structure of Appearance, Indianapolis, New York and Kansas City: Bobbs-Merrill. Goodman, Nelson (1978) ‘When Is Art?’ 57–70 in Ways of Worldmaking, Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing. Goodman, Nelson and Catherine Z. Elgin (1988) Reconceptions in Philosophy and Other Arts and Sciences, Indianapolis and Cambridge, Hackett. Graubner, Hans (1972) Form und Wesen. Ein Beitrag zur Deutung des Formbegriffs in Kants Kritik der reinen Vernunft, Kantstudien Ergänzungshefte, Bonn: Bouvier. Griepenkerl, Friedrich Konrad (1826) Lehrbuch der Ästhetik, Braunschweig: Vieweg. Grosse, Ernst (1894) Die Anfänge der Kunst, Freiburg and Leipzig: Mohr. Groys, Boris (1995) ‘Die Erzeugung der Sichtbarkeit’, in Frankfurter Allgemeine Zeitung, No. 24. Gumbrecht, Hans U. (1996) ‘Wahrnehmung vs. Erfahrung oder Die schnellen Bilder und ihre Interpretationsresistenz’, 156–175 in Bild und Reflexion. Paradigmen und Perspektiven gegenwärtiger Ästhetik, eds. Birgit Recki and Lambert Wiesing, Munich: Wilhelm Fink. Guyau, Jean-Marie (1912) [1888] Die Kunst als soziologisches Phänomen, Leipzig: Klinkhardt. Haken, Hermann and Haken-Krell, Maria (1992) Erfolgsgeheimnisse der Wahrnehmung. Synergetik als Schlüssel zum Gehirn, Stuttgart: Deutsche Verlags-Anstalt.

238

Bibliography

Halder, Alois (1964) Kunst und Kult. Zur Ästhetik und Philosophie der Kunst in der Wende vom 19. zum 20. Jahrhundert, Freiburg: Alber. Hamburger, Margarete (1973) [1915] Das Form-Problem in der neueren deutschen Ästhetik und Kunsttheorie, Nendeln/Liechtenstein: Kraus Reprint. Hansen-Löve, Aage Ansgar (1978) Der Russische Formalismus. Methodologische Rekonstruktion seiner Entwicklung aus dem Prinzip der Verfremdung, Vienna: Verlag der Österreichischen Akademie der Wissenschaften. Hanslick, Eduard (1965) [1854] Vom Musikalisch-Schönen. Ein Beitrag zur Revision der Ästhetik der Tonkunst, Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft. Hart, Joan (1981) Heinrich Wölfflin: An Intellectual Biography, Berkeley: University of California Press. Hart, Joan (1982) ‘Reinterpreting Wölfflin. Neo-Kantianism and Hermeneutics’, 292– 300 in Art Journal, Vol. 42. Hart Nibbrig, Christiaan L. (1994) ‘Zum Drum und Dran einer Fragestellung. Ein Vorgeschmack’, 7–14 in Was heißt ‘Darstellen’?, Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp. Hauser, Arnold (1986) ‘Grundbegriffliches zu Wölfflins “Kunstgeschichtlichen Grundbegriffen” ’, 39–53 in Beiträge zu Kunst und Kunstgeschichte um 1900, Zurich: Jahrbuch des Schweizerischen Instituts für Kunstwissenschaft 1984–1986. Hauser, Arnold (1958) Philosophie der Kunstgeschichte, Munich: C.H. Beck. Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich (1975) [1835] Aesthetics. Lectures on Fine Art, Vol. 1, trans. T. M. Knox, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich (1979) [1807] Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. A. V. Miller, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Heidegger, Martin (2002) [1935/36] ‘The Origin of the Work of Art’ in Off the Beaten Track, trans. Julian Young and Kenneth Haynes, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hemprich, Karl (1908) Otto Flügels Leben und Schriften, Langensalza: Beyer & Söhne. Henckmann, Wolfhart (1985) ‘Probleme der allgemeinen Kunstwissenschaft’, 273–334 in Kategorien und Methoden der deutschen Kunstgeschichte 1900–1930, eds. Oskar Bätschmann and Lorenz Dittmann, Stuttgart: Steiner. Herbart, Johann Friedrich (1851) [1828] Allgemeine Metaphysik, nebst den Anfängen der philosophischen Naturlehre. 1. historisch-kritischer Teil, 49–514 in Sämtliche Werke, Vol. 3, ed. Gustav Hartenstein, Leipzig: L. Voss. Herbart, Johann Friedrich (1851) [1808] Allgemeine praktische Philosophie, 1–212 in Sämtliche Werke, Vol. 8, ed. Gustav Hartenstein, Leipzig: L. Voss. Herbart, Johann Friedrich (1851) [1836] Analytische Beleuchtung des Naturrechts und der Moral, pp. 214–405 in Sämtliche Werke, Vol. 8, ed. Gustav Hartenstein, Leipzig: L. Voss. Herbart, Johann Friedrich (1850) [1831] Kurze Enzyklopadie der Philosophie aus praktischen Gesichtspunkten entworfen in Sämtliche Werke, Vol. 2, ed. Gustav Hartenstein, Leipzig: L. Voss.

Bibliography

239

Herbart, Johann Friedrich (1850) [1813] Lehrbuch zur Einleitung in die Philosophie, 1–360 in Sämtliche Werke, Vol. 1, ed. Gustav Hartenstein, Leipzig: L. Voss. Herbart, Johann Friedrich (1850) [1825] Psychologie als Wissenschaft, neu gegrundet auf Erfahrung, Metaphysik und Mathematik. 2. Analytischer Teil, in Sämtliche Werke, Vol. 6, ed. Gustav Hartenstein, Leipzig: L. Voss. Herbart, Johann Friedrich (1896) [1816] A Text-Book in Psychology, trans. Margaret K. Smith, New York: D. Appleton and Co. Hergé (1975) [1943] The Adventures of Tintin: The Seven Crystal Balls, London: Little Brown for Young Readers. Hettner, Hermann Julius Theodor (1959) [1845] ‘Gegen die speculative Äesthetik’, 17–49 in Schriften Zur Literatur, Berlin: Aufbau-Verlag. Hildebrand, Adolf von (1907) [1893] The Problem of Form in Painting and Sculpture, New York: G. E. Stechert & Co.. Hirth, Georg (1891) Aufgaben der Kunstphysiologie, Munich: G. Hirth. Hocutt, Max Oliver (1962/63) ‘Logical Foundations of Peirce’s Aesthetics’, 157–166 in The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 21. Høffding, Harald (1922) Der Relationsbegriff. Eine erkenntnistheoretische Untersuchung, Leipzig: Reisland. Höfler, Alois (1912) ‘Gestalt und Beziehung – Gestalt und Anschauung’, 161–228 in Zeitschrift für Psychologie und Physiologie der Sinnesorgane, Vol. 60. Hofmann, Werner (1961) ‘Gespräche mit dem Sichtbaren. Die Wege der modernen Kunstwissenschaft, Part 1, 473–482 in Merkur, Vol. 159, Part 2, 576–586 in Vol. 160. Hofmann, Werner (1966) Grundlagen der modernen Kunst, Stuttgart: Kröner. Hofmann, Werner (1955) ‘Studien zur Kunsttheorie des 20. Jahrhunderts’, 136–156 in Zeitschrift für Kunstgeschichte, Vol. 18. Hofmann, Werner (1970) [1969] Von der Nachahmung zur Wirklichkeit. Die schöpferische Befreiung der Kunst 1890–1917, Cologne: DuMont. Hogrebe, Wolfram (1990) ‘Eindeutigkeit und Vieldeutigkeit. Vorzüge einer indiskreten Ontologie’, 217–232 in Einheit und Vielheit. XIV. Deutscher Kongreß für Philosophie, ed. Odo Marquard, Hamburg: Meiner. Holenstein, Elmar (1976) Linguistik, Semiotik, Hermeneutic. Plädoyers für eine strukturale Phänomenologie, Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp. Holenstein, Elmar (1975) Roman Jakobson’s phänomenologischer Strukturalismus, Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp. Hostinsky, Otakar (1891) Herbarts Ästhetik in ihren grundlegenden Teilen quellenmäßig dargestellt und erläutert, Hamburg and Leipzig: L. Voss. Hume, David (1960) [1738–40] A Treatise of Human Nature, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Husserl, Edmund (1965) [1931] Cartesian Meditations, trans. Dorion Cairns, The Hague: Nijhoff. Husserl, Edmund (1985) [1939] Erfahrung und Urteil. Untersuchungen zur Genealogie der Logik, ed. Ludwig Landgrebe, Hamburg: Meiner.

240

Bibliography

Husserl, Edmund (1982) [1913] Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy, The Hague: Nijhoff. Husserl, Edmund (1970) [1900 and 1901] Logical Investigations, trans. John Niemeyer Findlay, London and York: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Husserl, Edmund (2005) Phantasy, Image Consciousness, and Memory, 1898–1925, trans. John B. Brough Dordrecht: Springer. Huxley, Aldous (2004) [1954] The Doors of Perception and Heaven and Hell, New York: Perennial Classics. Imdahl, Max (1987) Farbe. Kunsttheoretische Reflexionen in Frankreich, Munich: Wilhelm Fink. Imdahl, Max (1980) Giotto Arenafresken. Ikonographie, Ikonologie, Ikonik, Munich: Wilhelm Fink. Imdahl, Max (1963) ‘Marées, Fiedler, Hildebrand, Riegl, Cézanne’, 142–195 in Literatur und Gesellschaft vom Neunzehnten ins zwanzigste Jahrhundert, ed. Hans Joachim Schrimpf, Bonn: Bouvier. Ingarden, Roman (1989) [1962] Ontology of the Work of Art: The Musical Work, The Picture, The Architectural Work, The Film, trans. Raymond Meyer with John T. Goldthwait, Athens: Ohio University Press. Ingarden, Roman (1969) ‘Über die sogenannte “abstrakte” Malerei’, 51–76 in Erlebnis, Kunstwerk und Wert. Vorträge zur Ästhetik 1937–1967, Tübingen: Niemeyer. Iversen, Margaret (1979) ‘Style as Structure. Alois Riegl’s Historiography’, 62–72 in Art History, Vol. 2. Jauß, Hans Robert (1991) Ästhetische Erfahrung und literarische Hermeneutik, Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp. Jochims, Reimer (1975) Visuelle Identität. Konzeptionelle Malerei von Piero Della Francesca bis zur Gegenwart, Frankfurt a. M.: Insel. Jonas, Hans (2001) [1966] The Phenomenon of Life: Toward a Philosophical Biology, Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press. Junod, Philippe (1976) Transparence et Opacité: Essai Sur les Fondements théoriques de L’art Moderne: Pour une nouvelle Lecture de Konrad Fiedler Collection Histoire et Théorie de L’art. Lausanne: Éditions L’Age d’homme. Kahnweiler, Daniel-Hengy (1968) [1946] Juan Gris. Leben und Werk, Stuttgart: Gerd Hatje. Kambartel, Friedrich (1967) ‘Formales und Inhaltliches Sprechen’, 293–312 in Das Problem der Sprache.VIII. Deutscher Kongress für Philosophie, ed. Hans-Georg Gadamer, Munich: Wilhem Fink. Kant, Immanuel (2000) [1790] Critique of the Power of Judgement, trans. Paul Guyer and Eric Matthews, New York: Cambridge University Press. Kant, Immanuel (1998) [1781/87] Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kaufmann, Fritz (1960) [1940] ‘Kunst und Phänomenologie’, 195–208 in Das Reich des Schönen. Bausteine zu einer Philosophie der Kunst, Stuttgart: Kohlhammer.

Bibliography

241

Kemp, Wolfgang (1990) ‘Alois Riegl’, 36–60 in Altmeister moderner Kunstgeschichte, ed. Heinrich Dilly, Berlin: Reimer. Kemp, Wolfgang (1991) ‘Augengeschichten und skopische Regime. Alois Riegls Schrift “Das Holländische Gruppenporträt” ’, 1162–1169 in Merkur, No. 513. Kent, Beverly (1976) ‘Peirce’s Esthetics. A New Look’, 263–283 in Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, Vol. 12. Klages, Ludwig (1974) [1934] ‘Vom Wesen des Rhythmus’, 504–551 in Sämtliche Werke Vol. 3. Philosophische Studien, ed. Ernst Frauchiger et al., Bonn: Bouvier. Kleinspehn, Thomas (1991) Der flüchtige Blick. Sehen und Identität in der Kultur der Neuzeit, Reinbek bei Hamburg: Rowohlt. Köhler, Herbert (1984) Strukturale Bildlichkeit. Studien zum Begriff der Struktur in der Kunstgeschichte, Munich: Mäander. Konersmann, Ralf (1991) Lebendige Spiegel. Die Metapher des Subjekts, Frankfurt a.M.: Fischer. Koppe, Franz (1983) Grundbegriffe der Ästhetik, Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp. Koppe, Franz (1991) ‘Kunst als entäußerte Weise, die Welt zu sehen. Zu Nelson Goodman und Arthur C. Danto in weitergehender Absicht’, 81–103 in Perspektiven der Kunstphilosophie. Texte und Diskussionen, ed. Franz Koppe, Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp. Körner, Stephan (1990) [1955] Kant, London: Penguin. Krämer, Erwin (1940) Ästhetik und Wissenschaft. Ein Grundproblem Eduard Bobriks, Königsberg: Volz & Co. Krueger, Myron W. (1990) Artificial Reality II, New York and Bonn: Addison Wesley. Kubler, George (2008) [1962] The Shape of Time. Remarks on the History of Things, New Haven: Yale University Press. Kulenkampff, Jens (1996) ‘Spieglein, Spieglein an der Wand…’, 270–293 in Bild und Reflexion. Paradigmen und Perspektiven gegenwärtiger Ästhetik, eds. Birgit Recki and Lambert Wiesing, Munich: Wilhelm Fink. Kunst- und Ausstellungshalle der Bundesrepublik Deutschland (1999) Sehsucht. Das Panorama als Massenunterhaltung des 19. Jahrhunderts, Basel: Stroemfeld/ Roter Stern. Kuntze, Friedrich (1929) Der morphologische Idealismus: Seine Grundlagen und seine Bedeutung, Munich: C.H. Beck. Küppers, Harald (1976) Die Logik der Farbe. Theoretische Grundlagen der Farbenlehre, Munich: Callwey. Lambert, Johann Heinrich (1922) ‘Brief an Kant vom 3. Feb. 1766’, 62–67 in Kants gesammelte Schriften, Vol. 10, ed. Preußische Akademie der Wissenschaften, Berlin and Leipzig: De Gruyter. Langer, Susan (1990) [1942] Philosophy in a New Key: A Study in the Symbolism of Reason, Rite, and Art, Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. Lanier, Jaron (1989) ‘Virtual Reality: An Interview with Jaron Lanier’, 108–119 in The Whole Earth Review.

242

Bibliography

Laurel, Brenda (1990) The Art of Human-Computer. Interface Design, New York: Addison Wesley. Laurila, Kaarle Sanfrid (1944) Ästhetische Streitfragen, Helsinki: Akateeminen Kirjakauppa. Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm (1966) [1714–16] ‘Aus den Briefen von Leibniz an Remond’, 457–477 in Hauptschriften zur Grundlegung der Philosophie, Vol. 2, ed. Ernst Cassirer, Hamburg: Meiner. Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm (1898) [1714] The Monadology, trans. Robert Latta, Oxford: Clarendon. Lenk, Hans (1993) Interpretationskonstrukte. Zur Kritik der interpretatorischen Vernunft, Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp. Lichtenberg, Georg Christoph (1982) [1791] ‘Amintors Morgenandacht’, 292–295 in Werke in einem Band, ed. Hans Friederici, Berlin and Weimar: Aufbau-Verlag. Liebmann, Otto (1869) Über den objektiven Anblick. Eine kritische Abhandlung, Stuttgart: Teubner. Lombroso, Cesare (1877) Genie und Irrsinn, Leipzig: Reclam. Loran, Erle (1963) [1943] Cézanne’s Composition. Analysis of his Form with Diagrams and Photographs of his Motifs, Berkley and Los Angeles: University of California Press. Lotze, Hermann (1913) [1868] Geschichte der Ästhetik in Deutschland, Leipzig: Meiner. Lüdeking, Karlheinz (1988) Analytische Philosophie der Kunst, Frankfurt a.M.: Athenäum. Lüdeking, Karlheinz (1996) ‘Die Vergangenheit des Körpers’, 216–227 in Kunstforum International, Vol. 132. Lurz, Meinhold (1981) Heinrich Wölfflin. Biographie einer Kunsttheorie, Worms: Wernersche Verlagsgesellschaft. Lyotard, Jean-Francois (1985) Immaterialität und Postmoderne, Berlin: Merve. Mackay, Donald S. (1930) ‘An Historical Sketch of the Problem of Relations’, 3–34 in Studies in the Problem of Relations, eds. G. P. Adams, J. Loewenberg and St. C. Pepper, Berkley: University of California Press. Majetschak, Stefan (1993) ‘Die Überwindung der Schönheit’, 55–69 in Allgemeine Zeitschrift für Philosophie, Vol. 18. Majetschak, Stefan (1989) ‘Welt als Begriff und Welt als Kunst. Zur Einschätzung der theoretischen Leistungsfähigkeit des Ästhetischen bei Kant und Konrad Fiedler’, 276–293 in Philosophisches Jahrbuch, Vol. 96. Malcolm, Norman (1986) Nothing is hidden. Wittgenstein’s Criticism of his Early Thought, Oxford: Blackwell. Malewitsch, Kasimir (1989) [1922] ‘Suprematismus. Die gegenstandslose Welt’, 35–212 in Suprematismus. Die gegenstandslose Welt, ed. Werner Haftmann, Cologne: DuMont. Mannheim, Karl (1923) [1921/22] ‘Beiträge zur Theorie der WeltanschauungsInterpretation’, 236–274 in Jahrbuch für Kunstgeschichte, Vol. 1, Vienna: Böhlau. Marx, Ellen (1973) Die Farbkontraste, Ravensburg: Maier.

Bibliography

243

Marx, Wolfgang (1983) ‘Offene und geschlossene Form. Überlegungen zu einem Kardinalproblem der Ästhetik’, 65–79 in Kunst und Kunstforschung. Beiträge zur Ästhetik, ed. Gerdt Wolandt, Bonn: Bouvier. McLuhan, Marshall (1964) Understanding Media: The Extensions of Man, New York: Routledge. Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (1984) [1969] Die Prosa der Welt, trans. Regula Giuliani, Munich: Wilhelm Fink. Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (1964) ‘Eye and Mind’, 159–190 in The Primacy of Perception, trans. William Cobb, Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press. Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (1969) La Prose du Monde, ed. Claude Lefort, Paris: Gallimard. Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (1962) [1945] Phenomenology of Perception, trans. Colin Smith, London: Routledge. Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (1964) [1959] ‘The Philosopher and His Shadow’, 159–181 in Signs, trans. Richard C. McCleary, Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press. Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (1974) [1969] The Prose of the World, trans. John O’Neill, London: Heinemann. Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (1968) [1964] trans. Claude Lefort, The Visible and the Invisible, Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press. Merrill, Daniel D. (1990) Augustus DeMorgan and the Logic of Relations, Dordrecht, Boston and London: Springer. Merrill, Daniel D. (1978) ‘DeMorgan, Peirce and the Logic of Relations’, 247–284 in Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, Vol. 14. Metzger, Wolfgang (2006) Laws of Seeing, Cambridge: MIT Press. Mohr, Georg (1991) Das sinnliche Ich. Innerer Sinn und Bewußtsein bei Kant, Frankfurt a.M.: Königshausen & Neumann. Morris, Charles William (1939) ‘Esthetics and the Theory of Signs’, 131–150 in Journal of Unified Science Vol. 8. Morris, Charles William (1938) ‘Foundations of the Theory of Signs’, 77–138 in International Encyclopedia of Unified Science, Vol. 1. Morris, Charles William (1964) Signification and Significance, Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press. Morris, Charles William (1946) Signs, Language and Behavior, New York: Prentice-Hall. Musil, Robert (1978) ‘Ansätze zu neuer Ästhetik’, 1137–1154 in Gesammelte Werke, Vol. 2, ed. Adolf Frisé, Reinbek bei Hamburg: Rowohlt. Nabokov, Vladimir (1989) [1928] King, Queen, Knave, New York: Vintage Books. Nachtsheim, Stephan (1984) Kunstphilosophie und empirische Kunstforschung 1870– 1920, Berlin: Gebr. Mann. Nahlowsky, Joseph Wilhelm (1863) ‘Ästhetisch-kritische Streifzüge’, 384–440 in Zeitschrift für exakte Philosophie, Vol. 3. Nerlich, Graham (1976) The Shape of Space, London, New York, Melbourne and Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

244

Bibliography

Neudecker, Georg (1878) Studien zur Geschichte der deutschen Ästhetik seit Kant, Würzburg: Stahel. Nietzsche, Friedrich (1999) [1873] ‘On Truth and Lying in a Non-Moral Sense’, in The Birth of Tragedy and Other Writings, ed. Raymond Guess and Ronald Speirs, trans. Ronald Speirs, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Nohl, Herman (1908) Die Weltanschauungen der Malerei, Jena: Eugen Diederichs. Nohl, Herman (1920) Stil und Weltanschauung, Jena: Eugen Diederichs. Oelmüller, Willi, ed. (1981) Kolloquium 1: Ästhetische Erfahrungen, Paderborn: Schöningh. Oelmüller, Willi, ed. (1983) Kolloquium 3: Das Kunstwerk, Paderborn: Schöningh. Ollig, Hans-Ludwig (1979) Der Neukantianismus, Stuttgart: Metzler. Orth, Ernst W. (1996) ‘Lektüre und geistiger Bildraum’, 180–192 in Bild und Reflexion. Paradigmen und Perspektiven gegenwärtiger Ästhetik, eds. Birgit Recki and Lambert Wiesing, Munich: Wilhelm Fink. Paetzold, Heinz (1983) Ästhetik des deutschen Idealismus. Zur Idee ästhetischer Rationalität bei Baumgarten, Kant, Schelling, Hegel und Schopenhauer, Wiesbaden: Steiner. Paetzold, Heinz (1990) Ästhetik der neueren Moderne. Sinnlichkeit und Reflexion in der konzeptionellen Kunst der Gegenwart, Stuttgart: Steiner. Paisseran, Etienne (1973) La Logique des relations et son histoire, Dissertation, Université de Fribourg. Panofsky, Ernst (1992) ‘Das Problem des Stils in der bildenden Kunst’, 19–27 in Aufsätze zu Grundfragen der Kunstwissenschaft, eds. Hariolf Oberer and Egon Verheyen, Berlin: Spiess. Panofsky, Ernst (1992) [1920] ‘Der Begriff des Kunstwollens’, 29–43 in Aufsätze zu Grundfragen der Kunstwissenschaft, eds. Hariolf Oberer and Egon Verheyen, Berlin: Spiess. Panofsky, Ernst (1992) [1925] ‘Über das Verhältnis der Kunstgeschichte zur Kunsttheorie’, 49–75 in Aufsätze zu Grundfragen der Kunstwissenschaft, eds. Hariolf Oberer and Egon Verheyen, Berlin: Spiess. Passarge, Walter (1930) Die Philosophie der Kunstgeschichte in der Gegenwart, Berlin: Junker und Dünnhaupt. Patzig, Günther (1981) ‘Der Strukturalismus und seine Grenzen’, 101–125 in Sprache und Logik, Göttingen: Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht. Patzig, Günther (1973) ‘Relation’, 1220–1231 in Handbuch Philosophischer Grundbegriffe, eds. Hermann Krings, Hans Michael Baumgartner and Christoph Wild,Vol. 2, Munich: Kösel. Pawlik, Johannes (1981) Praxis der Farbe. Bildnerische Gestaltung, Cologne: DuMont. Pearson, Don, Hanna, Elias and Martinez, Kirk (1990) ‘Computer-generated cartoons’, 46–60 in Images and Understanding, ed. Horace Barlow, Colin Blakemore and Miranda Weston-Smith, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Peeters, Benoit (1983) Hergé. Ein Leben für die Comics, Reinbek bei Hamburg: Rowohlt.

Bibliography

245

Peirce, Charles Sanders (1933) [1897] ‘The Logic of Relatives’, 288–345 in Collected Papers Vol. 3, eds. Ch. Hartshorne and Paul Weiss, Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Peirce, Charles Sanders (1932) [1902] ‘Why Study Logic?’, in Collected Papers, Vol. 2, eds. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss, Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Pitcher, Georg (1967) [1964] Die Philosophie Wittgensteins, Freiburg and Munich: Alber. Plessner, Helmuth (1980) [1923] ‘Die Einheit der Sinne. Grundlinien einer Ästhesiologie des Geistes’, 7–315 in Gesammelte Schriften, Vol. 3, eds. Günther Dux, Odo Marquard and Elisabeth Ströker, Frankfurt a.M: Suhrkamp. Pochat, Götz (1983) Der Symbolbegriff in der Ästhetik und Kunstwissenschaft, Cologne: DuMont. Podro, Michael (1972) The Manifold in Perception. Theories of Art from Kant to Hildebrand, Oxford: Clarendon. Podro, Michael (1962/63) ‘A Sense of Complexity in the Visual Arts’, 83–98 in Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Vol. 63. Raphael, Max (1989) [1913] Von Monet zu Picasso. Grundzüge einer Ästhetik und Entwicklung der modernen Malerei, ed. Klaus Binder, Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp. Reck, Hans Ulrich (1991) ‘Von Warburg ausgehend. Bildmysterien und Diskursordnung’, 198–213 in Kunstforum International, Vol. 114. Recki, Birgit (1990) ‘Wie ästhetisch ist die moderne Kunst?’, 93–120 in Sehen und Denken. Philosophische Betrachtungen zur modernen Skulptur, ed. Volker Gerhardt, Münster: Kleinheinrich. Rentschler, Ingo (1990) ‘Weltbilder der Kunst – Erscheinungsformen der Wirklichkeit’, 115–134 in Geist und Natur. Über den Widerspruch zwischen naturwissenschaftlicher Erkenntnis und philosophischer Welterfahrung, eds. Hans-Peter Dürr and Walther Ch. Zimmerli, Bern: Scherz. Rheingold, Howard (1992) [1991] Virtuelle Welten. Reisen im Cyberspace, Reinbek bei Hamburg: Rowohlt. Riegl, Alois (1984) [1901] Late Roman Art Industry, trans. Rolf Winkes, Rome: Giorgio Bretschneider Riegl, Alois (1929) [1901] ‘Naturwerk und Kunstwerk’, 51–70 in Gesammelte Aufsätze, ed. Hans Sedlmayr, Augsburg and Vienna: Benno Filser. Riegl, Alois (1993) [1893] Problems of Style: foundations for a History of Ornament, Princeton: Princeton University Press. Roß, Martin M. (1990) Künstlerische Struktur und Strukturontologie, Munich: F. Pfeil. Rohs, Peter (1973) Transzendentale Ästhetik, Meisenheim a.G.: Hain. Rollins, Mark (1989) Mental Imagery. On the Limits of Cognitive Science, New Haven and London: Yale University Press. Rosenkranz, Karl (1900) [1853] Ästhetik des Hässlichen, Leipzig: Reclam. Rothacker, Erich (1954) Die dogmatische Denkform in den Geisteswissenschaften und das Problem des Historismus, Mainz and Wiesbaden: Akademie der Wissenschaften und der Literatur.

246

Bibliography

Rothacker, Erich (1919) ‘Rezension von “Heinrich Wölfflin: Kunstgeschichtliche Grundbegriffe” ’, 168–186 in Repertorium für Kunstwissenschaft, Vol. 41. Rötzer, Florian and Weibel, Peter (1993) Cyberspace, Munich: Boer. Rüden, Egon von (1971) van de Velde – Kandinsky – Hölzel. Typologische Studien zur Entstehung der gegenstandslosen Malerei, Wuppertal, Ratingen and Kastellaun: Henn Verlag. Sachs-Hombach, Klaus (1995) ‘Piktoriale Einstellungen’, 195–211 in Bilder im Geiste. Zur kognitiven und erkenntnistheoretischen Funktion piktorialer Repräsentationen, Amsterdam and Atlanta: Rodopi. Sander, Friedrich (1932) ‘Gestaltpsychologie und Kunsttheorie’, 319–346 in Neue Psychologische Studien, Vol. 4. Sartre, Jean-Paul (2004) [1940] The Imaginary: A Phenomenological Psychology of the Imagination, trans. Jonathan Webber, London and New York: Routledge. Sartre, Jean-Paul (1949) [1948] What Is Literature? trans. Bernard Frechtman, New York: Philosophical Library. Sauerländer, Willibald (1977) ‘Alois Riegl und die Entstehung der autonomen Kunstgeschichte am Fin de Siècle’, 125–139 in Fin de Siècle. Zur Literatur und Kunst der Jahrhundertwende, ed. R. Bauer, Frankfurt a.M.: Klostermann. Scarrocchia, Sandro (1986) Studi su Alois Riegl, Bologna: Nuova Alfa. Scheier, Claus-Arthur (1991) Wittgensteins Kristall, Freiburg and Munich: Alber. Schiller, Friedrich (1870) [1798] ‘The Artists’, 72–79 in Schiller’s Complete Works, trans. Charles J. Hempel, Vol. 1, Philadelphia: L. Kohler. Schiller, Friedrich (1967) [1795] On the Aesthetic Education of Man In a Series of Letters, eds. and trans. Elizabeth M. Wilkinson and L. A. Willoughby, Oxford: The Clarendon Press. Schlegel, Friedrich (1972) [1798] Athenäums-Fragmente, Munich: dtv. Schlosser, Julius von (1934) ‘Die Wiener Schule der Kunstgeschichte. Rückblich auf ein Säkulum deutscher Gelehrtenarbeit in Österreich’, 142–228 in Mitteilungen des Österreichischen Instituts fur Geschichtsforschung, Supplemental Volume 13. Schmarsow, August (1896) Zur Frage nach dem Malerischen. Sein Grundbegriff und seine Entwicklung, Leipzig: Hirzel. Schmitz, Christiane (1993) ‘Wölfflin und die Literatur’, 53–82 in Zeitschrift für Ästhetik und allgemeine Kunstwissenschaft, Vol. 38. Schmitz, Hermann (1987) [1966] ‘Der Leib im Spiegel der Kunst’, in System der Philosophie, Vol. 2, Part 2, Bonn: Bouvier. Schmitz, Norbert (1993) Kunst und Wissenschaft im Zeichen der Moderne. Exemplarische Studien zum Verhältnis von klassischer Avantgarde und zeitgenössischer Kunstgeschichte in Deutschland: Hölzel, Wölfflin, Kandinsky, Dvořák, Bonn: VDG. Scholz, Oliver R. (1991) Bild, Darstellung, Zeichen, Freiburg and Munich: Alber. Scholz, Oliver R. (1995) ‘Bilder im Geiste? Das Standardmodell, sein Scheitern und ein Gegenvorschlag’, 39–61 in Bilder im Geiste. Zur kognitiven und

Bibliography

247

erkenntnistheoretischen Funktion piktorialer Repräsentationen, ed. Klaus SachsHombach, Amsterdam and Atlanta: Rodopi. Schopenhauer, Arthur (1883) [1819] The World as Will and Idea, trans. Jill Berman, London: Kegan Paul, 1907–1909. Schulthess, Peter (1981) Relation und Funktion. Eine systematische und entwicklungsgeschichtliche Untersuchung zur theoretischen Philosophie Kants, Berlin and New York: De Gruyter. Schulz, Theodore A. (1961) Panorama der Ästhetik von Charles Sanders Peirce, Stuttgart: Mayer. Schweinfurth, Philipp (1910) Über den Begriff des Malerischen in der Plastik, Straßburg: Heitz & Mündel. Schwitters, Kurt (1981) [1920] ‘Merz’, 74–82 in Das literarische Werk, Vol. 5, ed. Friedhelm Lach, Cologne: DuMont. Schwitters, Kurt (1981) [1922] ‘Tragödie. Tran No. 22’, 97–104 in Das literarische Werk, Vol. 5, ed. Friedhelm Lach, Cologne: DuMont. Sedlmayr, Hans (2007) [1948] Art in Crisis: The Lost Center, trans. Brian Battershaw, New Brunswick and London: Transaction. Sedlmayr, Hans (1958) ‘Kunstgeschichte als Stilgeschichte. Die Quintessenz der Lehren Riegls’, 14–34 in Kunst und Wahrheit. Zur Theorie und Methode der Kunstgeschichte, Hamburg: Rowohlt. Seel, Martin (1996) ‘Ästhetik und Aisthetik. Über einige Besonderheiten ästhetischer Wahrnehmung’, 17–38 in Bild und Reflexion. Paradigmen und Perspektiven gegenwärtiger Ästhetik, eds. Birgit Recki and Lambert Wiesing, Munich: Wilhelm Fink. Seel, Martin (1985) Die Kunst der Entzweiung. Zum Begriff der ästhetischen Rationalität, Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp. Seel, Martin (1991) ‘Kunst, Wahrheit, Welterschließung’, 36–80 in Perspektiven der Kunstphilosophie. Texte und Diskussionen, ed. Franz Koppe, Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp. Segall, Marshall H., Campbell, Donald T. and Herskovits, Melville J. (1966) The Influence of Culture on Visual Perception, Indianapolis, New York and Kansas City: Bobbs-Merrill. Sepp, Hans R. (1988) ‘Annäherungen an die Wirklichkeit. Phänomenologie and Malerei nach 1900’, 77–93 in Edmund Husserl und die Phänomenologische Bewegung, ed. Hans R. Sepp, Freiburg and Munich: Alber. Simmel, Georg (1970) [1917] Grundfragen der Soziologie, Berlin: De Gruyter. Simmel, Georg (2004) [1900] The Philosophy of Money, London and New York: Routledge. Singer, Linda (1981) ‘Merleau-Ponty on the Concept of Style’, 153–163 in Man and World, Vol. 14. Smith, C. M. (1972) ‘The Aesthetics of Charles S. Peirce’, 21–29 in The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 31.

248

Bibliography

Smuda, Manfred (1986) ‘Natur als ästhetischer Gegenstand und als Gegenstand der Ästhetik. Zur Konstitution von Landschaft’, 44–69 in Landschaft, ed. Manfred Smuda, Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp. Stelzer, Otto (1964) Die Vorgeschichte der abstrakten Kunst. Denkmodelle und Vorbilder, Munich: Piper. Strauss, Ernst (1983) Koloritgeschichtliche Untersuchungen zur Malerei seit Giotto und andere Studien, Munich and Berlin: Deutscher Kunstverlag. Strawson, Peter F. (1974) ‘Imagination and Perception’, 45–65 in Freedom and Resentment and Other Essays, London and New York: Routledge. Ströker, Elisabeth (1971) ‘Das Problem der Epoché in der Philosophie Edmund Husserls, 175–185 in Analecta Husserliana, Vol. 1, ed. Anna-Teresa Tymieniecka, Dordrecht: D Reidel. Sturm, Hertha (1984) ‘Wahrnehmung und Fernsehen: Die fehlende Halbsekunde’, 58–65 in Media-Perspektiven, Vol. 1. Taine, Hippolyte (1873) [1865] Philosophy of Art, trans. John Durand, New York: Holt and Williams. Thierse, Wolfgang (1990) ‘Das Ganze aber ist das, was Anfang, Mitte und Ende hat. Problemgeschichtliche Beobachtungen zur Geschichte des Werkbegriffs’, 378–414 in Ästhetische Grundbegriffe. Studien zu einem historischen Wörterbuch, eds. Karlheinz Barck, Martin Fontius und Wolfgang Thierse, Berlin: Metzler. Thomae, Walter (1926) ‘Plastisch und Malerisch’, in Zeitschrift für Ästhetik und allgemeine Kunstwissenschaft, Vol. 20. Trevor-Roper, Patrick (1988) [1970] The World Through Blunted Sight. An Inquiry into the Influence of Defective Vision on Art and Character, London: Bobbs-Merrill. Ulrich, Miorita (1988) ‘Bread-and-butter, Bread-and-butter’. Zur Nachahmung des Sprechens’,260–283 in Poetica. Zeitschrift für Sprach- und Literaturwissenschaft, Vol. 20. Ulrich, Miorita (1989/90) ‘Sprachnachahmung, Nachahmung von Sprache und Übersetzung’, 100–122 in Fremdsprachen und Hochschule, Vol. 27/28. Utitz, Emil (1929) ‘Über Grundbegriffe der Kunstwissenschaft’, 6–69 in Kant-Studien, Vol. 34. Venturi, Lionello (1964) ‘Art Criticism and Pure Visibility’, 271–298 in History of Art Criticism, trans. from Charles Marriott, New York: Dutton. Venturi, Lionello (1964) History of Art Criticism, trans. Charles Marriot, New York: Dutton. Venturi, Lionello (1937) ‘Robert Zimmermann et les origins de la Science de l’Art, 35–38 in II. Congrès International d’Esthétique et de Science de l’Art, ed. Raymond Bayer, Paris, Vol. 2. Virilio, Paul (2013) [2000] ‘The Illusions of Zero Time’, 28–36 in Virilio and Visual Culture: (Critical Connections), eds. John Armitage and Ryan Bishop, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. Vischer, Friedrich Theodor (1858) Über das Verhältnis von Form und Inhalt in der Kunst, Zurich: Meyer & Zeller.

Bibliography

249

Volkelt, Johannes (1917) ‘Objektive Ästhetik’, 385–424 in Zeitschrift für Ästhetik und allgemeine Kunstwissenschaft, Vol. 12. Waldenfels, Bernhard (1989) ‘Das Rätsel der Sichtbarkeit. Kunstphänomenologische Betrachtungen im Hinblick auf den Status der modernen Malerei’, 331–341 in Kunstforum International, Vol. 100. Waldenfels, Bernhard (1986) ‘Das Zerspringen des Seins. Ontologische Auslegung der Erfahrung am Leitfaden der Malerei’, 144–161 in Leibhaftige Vernunft. Spuren von Merleau-Pontys Denken, eds. Alexandre Métreaux and Bernhard Waldenfels, Munich: Wilhelm Fink Waldenfels, Bernhard (1994) ‘Ordnungen des Sichtbaren’, 233–252 in Was ist ein Bild?, ed. Gottfried Boehm, Munich: Wilhelm Fink. Waldenfels, Bernhard (1987) Phänomenologie in Frankreich, Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp. Walther, Elisabeth and Bayer, Udo, eds. (1990) Zeichen von Zeichen für Zeichen. Festschrift für Max Bense, Stuttgart: Agis. Warburg, Aby M. (1980) Ausgewählte Schriften und Würdigungen, ed. Dieter Wuttke, Baden-Baden: Koerner. Weibel, Peter (1986) ‘Musik-Videos. Von Vaudeville bis Videoville’, 24–41 in Video in Kunst und Alltag. Vom kommerziellen zum kulturellen Videoclip, eds. Veruschka Bódy and Gabor Bódy, Cologne: DuMont. Weinberg, Julius R. (1965) ‘The Concept of Relation: Some Observations on Its History’, 61–119 in Abstraction, Relation, and Induction. Three Essays in the History of Thought, Madison: University of Wisconsin Press. Welsch, Wolfgang (1990) Ästhetisches Denken, Stuttgart: Reclam. Welsch, Wolfgang (1996) ‘Erweiterungen der Ästhetik. Eine Replik’, 39–67 in Bild und Reflexion. Paradigmen und Perspektiven gegenwärtiger Ästhetik, ed. Birgit Recki and Lambert Wiesing, Munich: Wilhelm Fink. Weston, Edward (1979) [1924/25] ‘Präsentation statt Interpretation’, 66–70 in Theorie der Fotografie, Vol. 2, ed. Wolfgang Kemp, Munich: Shirmer/Mosel. Wiesing, Lambert (1991) ‘La situazione attuale dell’estetica in Germania’, 241–248 in Le Grandi Correnti dell’estetica Novecentesca, ed. Grazia Marchiano, Milano: Guerini Studio. Wiesing, Lambert (1995) ‘Phänomenologie des Bildes nach Husserl und Sartre’, 255– 281 in Phänomenologische Forschungen, Vol. 30. Wiesing, Lambert (1991) Stil statt Wahrheit. Kurt Schwitters und Ludwig Wittgenstein über ästhetische Lebensformen, Munich: Wilhelm Fink. Willey, Thomas E. (1978) Back to Kant. The Revival of Kantianism in German Social and Historical Thought 1860–1914, Detroit: UMI. Wind, Edgar (1925) ‘Zur Systematik der künstlerischen Probleme’, 438–486 in Zeitschrift für Ästhetik und allgemeine Kunstwissenschaft, Vol. 18. Winter, Eduard (1967) ‘Bernard Bolzano und sein Kreis’, 7–28 in Bernard Bolzano. Ein Denker und Erzieher im österreichischen Vormärz, ed. Eduard Winter, Vienna: Böhlaus

250

Bibliography

Winter, Eduard (1975) Introduction to ‘Robert Zimmermanns philosophische Propädeutik und die Vorlagen aus der Wissenschaftslehre Bernard Bolzanos. Eine Dokumentation zur Geschichte des Denkens und der Erziehung in der Donaumonarchie’, 7–36, ed. Eduard Winter, Vienna: Österreichische Akademie der Wissenschaften Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1967) Philosophical Investigations, trans. G. E. M. Anscombe, Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Wittgenstein, Ludwig (2002) Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, trans. D. F. Pears and B. F. McGuiness, London and New York: Routledge. Wölfflin, Heinrich (1946) [1918] ‘Adolf von Hildebrand. Zu seinem 70. Geburtstag am 6. Oktober’, 89–99 in Kleine Schriften (1886–1933), ed. Joseph Gantner, Basel: Schwabe. Wölfflin, Heinrich (1912) ‘Das Problem des Stils in der bildenden Kunst’, 572–578 in Sitzungsberichte der Königlich Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften: Berlin: Verlag der Akademie der Wissenschaften. Wölfflin, Heinrich (1953) [1899] Die klassische Kunst. Eine Einführung in die italienische Renaissance, Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft. Wölfflin, Heinrich (1960) [1933] ‘Eine Revision als Nachwort’, 274–280 in Kunstgeschichtliche Grundbegriffe. Das Problem der Stilentwicklung in der neueren Kunst, Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft. Wölfflin, Heinrich (1941) [1920] ‘In eigener Sache. Zur Rechtfertigung meiner “Kunstgeschichtlichen Grundbegriffe” ’, 15–18 in Gedanken zur Kunstgeschichte. Gedrucktes und Ungedrucktes, Basel: Schwabe. Wölfflin, Heinrich (2015) [1915] Principles of Art History: The Problem of the Development of Style in Early Modern Art, trans. Jonathan Blower, Los Angeles: Getty Publications. Wölfflin, Heinrich (1946) [1886] ‘Prolegomena zu einer Psychologie der Architektur’, in Kleine Schriften (1886–1933), ed. Joseph Gantner, Basel: B. Schwabe & Co. Wulff, Oskar (1917) ‘Kritische Erörterungen zur Prinzipienlehre der Kunstwissenschaft’, Part 1, 1–34 in Zeitschrift für Ästhetik und allgemeine Kunstwissenschaft, Vol. 12. Wundt, Wilhelm (1910) ‘Psychologismus und Logizismus’, 511–634 in Kleine Schriften in drei Bänden, Vol. 1, Leipzig: Engelmann. Zaunschirm, Thomas (1975) Systeme der Kunstgeschichte, Vienna: Verband der Wissenschaftlichen Gesellschaften Österreichs. Ziechner, Alfred (1908) Herbarts Ästhetik, Leipzig: Frankenstein & Wagner. Zimmer, Hubert D. (1983) Sprache und Bildwahrnehmung. Die Repräsentation sprachlicher und visueller Informationen und deren Interaktion in der Wahrnehmung, Frankfurt a.M.: Haag & Heerchen. Zimmerli, Walther Ch. (1984) ‘Die ästhetisch-semiotische Relation und das Problem einer philosophischen Literaturästhetik’, 173–189 in Studia Philosophica, Vol. 43. Zimmermann, Jörg (1980) Sprachanalytische Ästhetik. Ein Überblick, Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Frommann-Holzboog.

Bibliography

251

Zimmermann, Robert (1973) [1865] Allgemeine Ästhetik als Formwissenschaft, Hildesheim and New York: Olms. Zimmermann, Robert (1854) ‘Die spekulative Ästhetik und die Kritik’, 37–40 in Blätter für Literatur und Kunst, No. 6. Zimmermann, Robert (1973) [1858] Geschichte der Ästhetik als philosophischer Wissenschaft, Hildesheim and New York: Olms. Zimmermann, Robert (1870) [1868] ‘Über Lotzes Kritik der formalistischen Ästhetik’, 370–383 in Studien und Kritiken zur Philosophie und Ästhetik, Vol. 1, Vienna: Braumüller. Zimmermann, Robert (1870) [1862] ‘Zur Reform der Ästhetik als exakter Wissenschaft’, 223–265 in Studien und Kritiken zur Philosophie und Ästhetik, Vol. 1, Vienna: Braumüller.

Index abstraction, pictorial as defence against interpretation as sign of absent object 194 difference from conceptual abstraction 165 limits of 71–2, 92, 147 as phenomenological reduction 174, 175 possibilities for in various media 194 Adorno, Theodor W. 33 aesthesiology 102–3 aesthesis 37, 88, 89 see also perception aesthetics, formal art as disclosure of (Wõlfflin) 80 beauty and 34, 37, 39, 50 causal explanation rejected by 51–2 computer manual text, similarity to 78–9 consciousness, means of studying 9, 114, 159 formal logic, analogous to 7, 8, 27, 65–70, 75 formative discourse’s relevance to 47, 102 as groundwork for digital image technology 80, 134 Herbart’s 23, 30 idealism rejected by xviii, 6, 8, 27–8, 30, 33, 52 image as object of reflection in 8 intentional character of 159 paradigms of (Fiedler) 10, 107–19 as phenomenology 12, 171 possibilities as primary concern of 106 reduction of the image in 11, 157, 159 relational logic, parallels to 57–67 semiotic aesthetics as variation of 12 style as object of 40 surface infrastructure as concern of 30 transcendental aesthetics rejected by 6, 9, 86–9, 93–4, 103 twentieth-century image forms grounding in xvii–xviii, 5, 11, 129

visibility as exclusive theme of 6 Zimmermann as beginning of 50 aisthetics 9, 88–9 Allen, Grant 21 Anders, Günther xiv, 199 Arnheim, Rudolph 97 art avant-garde 16, 18, 127, 195 film as 131 formative discourse in 193 modern and postmodern 16 science and 130, 150 theory of x, xv, 10, 16 as visibility, making of 144–5 will to 138–9 see also Kunstwollen art history x–xi, 6, 8, 40, 49, 100, 109, 145, 172 Bacon, Francis 96 Balázs, Béla 128–31 Baudrillard, Jean 199 Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb 110, 218 beauty 2, 34, 37, 46, 50, 89, 108 Beenken, H. 225 Benjamin, Walter 137, 216 Bense, Max 110, 181–2 Bildtheorie ix–xi Bildwissenschaft see visual culture Bobrik, Georg Eduard 23, 204 Boehm, Gottfried xi, 56, 61, 98, 209, 210, 214, 215, 217, 219, 220, 227 Bolz, Norbert 127, 197, 221 Bolzano, Bernard 23 Braque, Georges 32 Brinkmann, Donald 162 Brunswig, Alfred 54–5, 209 Bubner, Rüdiger 16–17 Buddemeier, Heinz 129, 197, 229 Bürger, Peter 18, 33, 34, 203 Burkamp, Wilhelm 66, 211

254

Index

Carnap, Rudolf 69, 184, 210, 211 Cassirer, Ernst 30–1, 49, 57–8, 105, 106, 188, 203, 208, 209, 228 Cézanne, Paul 4, 145, 177 collage xvi, 10, 32, 33, 127–8, 129, 193 colour 82–6 Computer Aided Design (CAD) 133, 135, 145, 198 consciousness forms of representation in 114 image in 88, 114 images in the study of 9 intentional content of 158 as object of phenomenological reduction 159, 165–6, 168 copy 89, 183 Croce, Benedetto xiv, 119 cubism 151 cyberspace 11, 141–4, 155 Dada 147 Danto, Arthur 124, 153, 154, 211, 224 De Morgan, August 8, 58, 66 decisionism 50, 53 Democritus 88 Descartes, René 158–9 Dickie George 16, 203 Dilthey, Wilhelm 66, 100, 101, 113, 154, 216, 224 discourse, formative 12, 191 formal aesthetics’ relevance to 192 Dittmann, Lorenz 39 Dõrflinger, Bernard 27 drawing, structural 182 Dürer, Albrecht 42, 57, 79, 104 Dvorák, Max 39 easel picture 12, 131, 139, 144 Eckl, Andreas 97, 215, 223, 226 Ehrenfels, Christian v. 97 eidolon 88 Einstellung 80 Enzensberger, Hans Magnus 13, 200 Epicurus 88 epoché 12, 158–9, 163, 165, 167 see also reduction Fechner, Gustav Theodor 5, 20, 22, 36 Fellmann, Ferdinand 9, 114, 154, 211, 215, 217

Fiedler, Konrad xiv, 10, 11, 19, 90, 96, 97, 105, 107–56, 168, 180 film 131–4, 139 Flügel, Otto 23, 27, 30, 204, 205 Flusser, Vilem 221 formator (Morris) 12, 186–97, 189, 191–3, 196, 229 forms of intuition (Kant) 9, 90 as determinants of style (Wõlfflin) 149 formal aesthetics’ understanding of 93–7 as polar opposites (Wõlfflin) 97 formal aesthetics see aesthetics, formal formula 188–91 imitation 192 Foucault, Michel 47–8 Frege, Gottlob 60–3, 103, 180, 184 Friedmann, Hermann 102, 103, 216, 236 fundamentum inconcussum, ephemerality as 103 Gabriel, Gottfried 61, 205, 210, 211, 218, 222, 228, 229 Galton, Francis 21 Gehlen, Arnold 182, 227 Goethe, Johannes Wolfgang von 28 Gogh, Vincent van 114 Gold, Peter 27, 37, 219, 223, 237 Gombrich, Ernst H. 76, 84, 150, 207, 223, 227 Goodman, Nelson xiii, 17, 124, 147–8, 153, 184, 187, 215, 224, 228 graphology 164 Griepenkerl, Friedrich Conrad 23, 37, 204 Grosse, Ernst 21 Groys, Boris 144–5 Guyau, Jean-Marie 21 Hanslick, Eduard 19 Hart, Joan 100, 213, 219 Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 6, 24, 25, 79, 105 Heidegger, Martin 33, 148, 206 Herbart, Johann Friedrich 5, 7, 23, 35, 76, 100, 161, 164 Herbartianism 35, 39, 40, 66, 91, 102, 107, 111 Hergé 41, 43, 44, 45–6, 54, 56, 59, 65, 74 Hettner, Hermann 5, 20 Hildebrand, Adolf 43, 105

Index Hirth, Georg 21 Hölzel, Adolf 172 horizon 188 Husserl, Edmund 55, 74, 77, 157–74 image abstract 171–7 as cognitive instrument 9 compared to algebraic formula 12 as imitation formula 189–91, 192, 196 infra-red 182 as phenomenological reduction 12, 172–7, 179, 180, 183, 184, 185 sense and reference in the 60–3 as sign 12 theory of the ix–xviii, 18, 40, 126, 172 x-ray 182, 183 see also Bildtheorie image sequences 13 Imdahl, Max 83, 84, 182, 208, 227 Ingarden, Roman 41, 176, 227 Ingres, Jean-Auguste-Dominique 42 intuition, form of (Kant) see forms of intuition Jauß, Hans Robert 15 Jonas, Hans 61, 62

255

logicism 36 Lombroso, Caesare 21 Loran, Erle 182 Lotze, Hermann 27 Lurz, Meinhold 75, 100 Majetschak, Stefan 104 Malevich, Kasimir 126–7, 128 Marées, Hans v. 125 Marx, Ellen 85 McLuhan, Marshall 131 Merleau-Ponty, Maurice 12, 47, 104–5, 157–77, 179, 224, 225 Merz 3, 128, 130 mirror, living 94–5, 99, 101 Mohr, Georg 91 Mondrian, Piet 153–4 Morris, Charles William 12, 179–202 MTV 5 Musil, Robert xiv, 131, 143, 172 Nachtsheim, Stephan 37 Nietzsche, Friedrich 21, 55–6, 80, 100 noemata 165 noesen 165 Nohl, Hermann 57, 209 null-medium 13, 200–1 ornament, visibility and 123–5, 176

Kandinsky, Wassily 172 Kant 6, 9, 34, 36–7, 55, 71, 86–7 form of intuition in 90–4, 97–9, 100, 102–4, 105, 182 transcendental aesthetic of 89, 93 Klages, Ludwig 101 Koppe, Franz 16 Körner, Stephen 92 Kues, Nikolaus von 95 Kunstwollen 51, 52, 109 Küppers, Harald 85 Langer, Susanne K. 46 Lanier, Jaron 144 Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm 95 Liebmann, Otto 101, 213, 216 logic aesthetics of (Zimmermann) 37 Artistotelian 58 relational 8, 58, 89 of ways of seeing (Wõlfflin) 10

Paetzold, Heinz 84, 89, 212 Panofsky, Erwin 51, 65, 208, 211 Patzig, Günther 69, 211 Peirce, Charles Sanders 8, 58, 64, 65–7, 180, 210, 211 perception conditionality of 97–8, 99, 101, 102, 199 in contrast to mirroring 89–90 design of a 99 as mental activity (Fiedler) 96 relational structure of 89 unity and multiplicity as forms of (Wõlfflin) 96 philosophy aesthetics and the history of 4–5 analytic 110, 124, 192 formal aesthetics’ obscurity in 4 of language 16 transcendental 93, 94, 100, 102, 105, 166 photography 136–8, 147, 150

256

Index

Plato ix–x, 37, 169 Plessner, Helmuth 102, 103, 217 principles, art historical (Wõlfflin) 9, 45, 47, 49–50 absence of colour relations from 82–5 as computer controls 78–86 irrelevance of medium to 139 as logical categories 57, 59, 60, 63–5, 70–2, 75–6 as supplement to transcendental aesthetics 87, 92, 96, 102 psychologism 36 Raphael, Max 83 Raphael Sanzio 137 raster graphics 79 ready-made 16, 18 Recki, Birgit 17 reduction xv, 11–12, 29, 30, 66, 157–62, 165–77, 194, 226 Rehkämper, Klaus xvii Rembrandt van Rijn 17, 18, 79 Renoir, Auguste 42, 78 reproduction 137, 139 Riegl, Alois 8, 39–68, 138, 139 Rothacker, Erich 53, 54, 99 Ruskin, John 83 Sainte-Beuve, Charles-Augustin 21 Sartre, Jean-Paul xvi, 162–3 Schiller, Friedrich 3, 95, 100 Schlegel, Friedrich 175 Schmid, Reinhard 110 Schmitz, Christiane 73, 212 Schmitz, Norbert 115, 218, 220, 226 Scholz, Oliver R. 18, 203 Schopenhauer, Arthusr 24, 25, 51–2, 53, 100, 113, 171, 208, 216, 219 Schröder, Ernst 58 Schweinfurth, Cf. Ph. 43 Schwitters, Kurt 3, 18, 32, 127–8 sculpture 43, 107 Sedlmayr, Hans 123, 208, 221, 226 Seel, Martin 22, 89, 112, 154, 181, 219, 224 semiotics xiii, xvii, 12, 60, 125, 184–6 Semper, Gottfried 52 signs images as potential xii–xiii, 197, 198 sequence of 196 theory of xiii, 12

Simmel, Georg 151–3 simulation (digital) 11, 135–6, 140, 141–2, 143, 144, 172, 197 style 8, 39–40, 44, 46, 48, 50, 53, 99, 103, 105, 168 compared to phenomenological analysis 54 of forms of intuition 103–4 Frege’s view of 63, 103 qualitative immeasurability of 164 as resolution of indeterminacy 54 Riegl’s theory of 49–50 Semper’s theory of 52 as system of equivalences 177, 183 variations in, as variations in thinking 57 subject concept of for Wõlfflin and Kant 99 transcendental 100, 165–6 Suprematism 10, 126–7, 128 surface, pictorial emancipation of 10, 123, 128 infrastructure of 108, 148, 152 materiality of 161–2 relational logic of 8, 30, 39–47, 54, 57 semiotic status of 12 between subject and object 167, 170 as user interface 11, 113, 142–3 valuing of 201 as whole of image 118, 144 symbolic form 108 paradigm of 109, 110 Taine, Hippolyte 20 Turner, William 10, 41, 45, 54, 56, 59–60, 65, 74, 79 Utitz, Emil 109 vector graphics 79 Velásquez, Diego 87, 149 Velde, Henry van de 172 video clip 10, 13, 18, 129–31, 133, 137 videogames 135, 139 Vienna School 39 virtual reality 11, 140–3 visibility conditions of 114 design of 126, 127, 134, 138, 146, 155 four types of 131–6

Index paradigm of 119–25 pictorial 11, 12 pure xiii, 11, 115–55, 168, 171, 172, 183, 193, 194, 196–200 styles of 105 as topic of phenomenology 171 visual culture x–xii Volkelt, Johannes 100, 164 Waldenfels, Bernard 87–8 ways of seeing, multiple possibilities for 94, 105 paradigm of 110–15 Welsch, Wolfgang 89, 163

257

Wind, Edward 45 Winter, Eduard 23 Wittgenstein, Ludwig 29, 70, 212 Wölfflin, Heinrich 8–10, 27, 43, 44, 52, 59, 69–106, 109, 111, 112, 114–19, 126, 138, 139, 149–51, 157, 161, 162, 164, 168, 176, 191, 207, 211–20, 223–7 Wundt, Wilhelm 36, 206 Zimmerli, Walther Ch. 184 Zimmerman, Robert 7–8, 15–38, 76, 82, 100, 108, 116, 117, 161, 162, 204, 205, 206, 207

Figure 1 Hergé. Image of the ship Sirius from the comic series Tintin, Red Rackham’s Treasure, 1944.

Figure 2 J. M. W. Turner, Staffa, oil on canvas, 1832.

Figure 3 Vector and Raster (pixels). Illustration from the manual for Adobe Illustrator 6.0, Adobe Systems Incorporated, 1995.

Figure 4 Illustration from auto motor und sport, 1993.