148 98 31MB
English Pages 473 [485] Year 2019
The Age of Criticism The Late Renaissance
in Italy
By Baxter Hathaway DEPARTMENT OF ENGLISH CORNELL UNIVERSITY
CORNELL UNIVERSITY PRESS ITHACA,
NEW YORK
THE AGE OF The Late
CRITICISM
Renaissance in Italy
'
This work has been brought to publication with the assistance of a grant
from the Ford Foundation.
©1962 by
Cornell University
CORNELL UNIVERSITY PRESS
First published 1962
Library of Congress Catalog Card Number: 62-8488
PRINTED IN THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA
BY VAIL-BALLOU
PRESS, INC.
Preface
ALL
theory
gray, as
is
Goethe
said,
which human beings must acquire either
our
own
but
if
if
its
gray ness
a toleration.
practical business, to
sionately, or the picture
which
but
something for
is
What
is
not theory
which our egos commit us
pas-
of concrete experiences moving past
show
is
us,
they are illuminations of gray theory are colorful enough
outside the bounds of theory are chaotic and often meaningless.
More than
in
most ages the
literary critics of the Renaissance
committed to pure theory, and,
like
our
own
were
age, the sixteenth century
has often disparagingly been referred to as “an age of criticism.”
Those
who
domi-
disparage ages in
which the power of
nant or strong usually claim that
much
critical speculation is
theorizing dries up the flow of
who assert, with how to dance. If it is
creative impulses; but they have their opponents
Pope, that grace of motion comes from learning true that sixteenth-century Italy
velopment of
literary criticism
was pre-eminently
and
if
poetry, the fact that Ariosto and Tasso poets
—lived
away.
It is
in that stifling
conceded that
a stage for the de-
criticism thwarts the creation of
—two of the four greatest
Italian
atmosphere must somehow be explained
literary Italy turned to
theory later than the
which Ariosto flourished and that Tasso’s some of the faults which critics of criticism attribute
early part of the century in
poetry exhibits
to the effects of criticism.
by means of attainment.
it,
A
The
best defense of criticism
is
to assert that
in the long run, cultures reach higher general levels of
tradition of artistic
development can hardly
exist
with-
out some continuity of consciousness of what the development implies. Criticism
is
the armature. In literary history a large percentage of the
significant literary theorists turn out to
have been poets, playwrights,
v
Preface and
novelists,
even though some
may wish
to define aesthetic specula-
tion as a branch of philosophy. Philosophical theory is
and
especially gray,
life is
not worth
was
Plato
if
the theory that
is
right in saying that the
living, the life that
worth
is
living
unexamined
in part at least,
is,
gray.
Sixty-some years ago
was the one who had importance of the his
J.
E. Spingarn could rightfully claim that he
called the attention of the world’s scholars to the
Italian literary critics of the sixteenth century,
claim has been acknowledged in the intervening years
Saintsbury, Ciro Trabalza, Giuseppe Toffanin, and the
who
have dealt more briefly with
in spite of the high
this
segment of
by George
many
others
literary history.
honor formally granted them, those
and
But
Italian critics
have remained for the most part unread in the English-speaking world, either because their
books are hard to come by or because the languages
which they wrote have posed obstacles to the readers with the greatest interest in their ideas. And, above all, many who have given lip
in
service to the importance of Italian criticism have attempted to treat
own
the history of criticism as the history of the criticism of their tions,
pale reflections and derivations. Professor Allan steps to correct this situation
by
H. Gilbert took great from the
liberally translating passages
Renaissance Italians in his Literary Criticism Plato to ,
But the whole
As
na-
ignoring the substantive object while concerning themselves with
field
even
now
Dry den
(1940).
has scarcely been scratched.
book
the reader will immediately perceive, the attempt in this
to deal with the complexities of the criticism of the period
1540 and 1613
by means of
is
between
“histories” of five of the ideas particularly
important for the understanding of the literary aesthetics of the Ren-
This
aissance.
is
an act of sinking depth shafts into the area rather than
of trying to strip-mine the whole.
proach
will, I fear,
The shortcomings
be apparent. There
distorted in being abstracted
from
its
is
of such an ap-
danger always that an idea
context. In
any
critical
is
system
concepts are entangled one with another, and to deal with the evolution of several ideas separately entails
much
repetition or
demands of the
reader that he reassemble parts of idea clusters that have been scattered
widely. But there are also advantages in this approach. critic
specific
arguments or doctrines even
eral attractions or repulsions. is
When
one
responds to another or builds upon another’s work, he turns to
to put
To
he
is
motivated by vague, gen-
look at the history of a significant idea
any expression of opinion vi
if
in a context quite possibly as
im-
Preface portant as the context of the writer’s system from which lifted.
Our
general familiarity with the
make apology unnecessary. Since this book is aimed speaking world,
what
available
I
have used should
at the interested reader in the English-
have surrendered some scholarly amenities to make
I
clearly has not been sufficiently available.
that the kind of translation
I
am aware
I
is always to some degree falsifisome modicum of interpretation of the
engage in
cation since translation involves text. I
method
bodily
it is
quake on remembering that Saintsbury attributed great impor-
word “transport” in describing the ofwhen Minturno’s word was simply movere “to move,”
tance to Minturno’s use of the fices
as
of poetry,
commonplace
my
in his time as
nights.
I
cannot hope that
To
share of them.
H.
I
necessarily
worthy of mention. The Latin
Theory
realized that
impossible to cover
is
with
one of
its
these.
many
are
especially
meanings, ren-
To make
the meaning
must be distinguished from
species
“image,” or “phantom,” use of a
Three
difficulties.
species,
dered here often as “appearance,”
which
it
I
in the vocabularies of the sixteenth-
present particular
clear in passages in
make
game
chose to be as serviceable as possible.
words used frequently
critics
like
engage in translation
B. Charlton did in his Castelvetro's
would
the area satisfactorily, and
Certain
it is slips
have succeeded in avoiding making
I
of course, ideal; but early in the
is,
printing parallel passages
century
find; for
print original passages alongside English trans-
lations or paraphrases, as
of Poetry,
one could
who must
keep the historian of ideas
this that
awake
term
a
less
common
equivalent
is
“sight,”
sometimes
necessary. Likewise, the Renaissance Italian costumi cannot uniformly
be translated
by any
single
expresses the meaning;
word; sometimes “character” adequately
more often
the significance
is
“individual traits
of character,” “usages,” “manners,” or “manifestation of custom.” Al-
though
I
have not tried to be consistent in translating
most often presented ( fabula ,
lating
it
fable)
are not
is
a
all
it
this
word,
as “character traits.” Finally, the
word
booby
I
have
favola
and the dangers encountered in transof our making, for the Renaissance critics often used trap,
uncertainly and were even more confused by the Greek mythos, which they took to be its equivalent. By favola the Renaissance Italians generally meant simply “plot” or “structure,” but often in the same it
breath they
made
reference to the “fables” of Aesop as
were the same. Here
I
have frequently
left the
if
the
meaning
reader the task of de-
termining the range of denotations by using the direct cognate “fable.” vii
Preface Since the ideas that are traced out here are those that provide the philosophical bases for criticism
—the those
critics
more
to say, are items of pure theory
is
casts of
mind play
larger roles than
The
consistently concerned with techniques.
however, of the Renaissance
and
—that
with philosophical
great virtue,
was their ability to comprehend which the critics of the twenty
critics
utilize the Poetics of Aristotle,
centuries that preceded had apparently been unable to do.
they had to be concerned with the philosophy of
segment of history some of the great
studies of this
Any
To
do
it
literature. In previous critical theorists of
the period have been
slighted.
of the Renaissance,
not of the whole modern world, should include
if
list
Sperone Speroni, Robortelli, Francesco
of the great critical theorists
Ludovico Castelvetro,
Patrizi,
Tasso, Giacopo Mazzoni, Francesco Buonamici, and Paolo Beni, but of these only Tasso and Castelvetro have received the attention they de-
no other reason, Professor Gilbert’s Literary Criticism
serve. If for
Plato to
Dry den
,
has been an invaluable aid to the understanding of the
history of criticism because of the translations
it
contains of passages
from Mazzoni.
My
labors in gathering the materials for this study
greatly
by easy
were lightened
access to the riches of the Willard Fiske collections of
Petrarch and Dante works in the Cornell University Library, and
wish to express particularly over the period of at Cornell. I
am
many
my
years
gratitude for the assistance rendered
by
the Rare
Book Department
also indebted to the kindness
I
me
librarians
and co-operation of the
Emmanuele in Rome and of the Marciana in Venice. I have been twice aided by grants from the Faculty Research Grants Committee and twice by the English Department Grant-in- Aid Fund of Cornell University. A year in Italy on a Fulstaffs
of the Biblioteca Vittorio
bright grant and the co-operation of the Fulbright Commission in
Rome were the
likewise of great value to me.
Department of
Classics at Cornell
patience the innumerable questions
to
make amends
for
the
all
may show
my
debted to Professor Joseph A. Mazzeo.
that
ignorance.
To
I
many
a
very pleasant summer
at
Ca
must
similarly in-
the neighborly proximity I
owe not only
Savio, near Venice, but also
helpful hints, elucidations, and illuminations. viii
I
have not asked
am
I
of Professor G. F. Folena of the University of Padua
memories of
members of
have put to them, though
I
hasten to say that the following text
them enough
Almost
have answered with unflagging
I
wish to thank
Preface
M. Durling
Professors Mario A. Levi and Robert
for their kindness in
reading large parts of the manuscript. I
am
indebted to
his translations
Andrew Bongiorno
Commentary on
“Castelvetro’s
for permission to quote
from
of Castelvetro in his unpublished doctoral dissertation,
versity, 1935); to
the Poetics of Aristotle” (Cornell Uni-
Allan H. Gilbert for use of
Criticism, Plato to
his text
or translations of
Minturno, and Mazzoni, from Literary
Sidney, Aristotle’s Poetics
Dry den,
cited
by permission
of the
Wayne
State
University Press, Detroit, Michigan, U.S.A.; to Ruth Kelso and the University of
Illinois Press
Navagero (University of vol. IX, no. 3;
for use of her translations of Fracastoro in
Illinois
Urbana, 1924); and to
sion to quote a passage
which appeared
Language and Literature, the Kenyon Review for permis-
Studies in
from Lionel
Trilling’s
“Freud and Literature”
in its Spring, 1941, issue.
B. Ithaca,
May
New
York
1961
IX
H.
Contents
v
Preface
One
Part
:
Poetry
1
The Theory
2
Patrizi’s
as Imitation
of Imitation in the Renaissance
3
Instruments, Subjects, and
4
Were Empedocles and
5
Is
6
Are prose
7
Imitation as Idol
Fart
3
Attack on Mimesis
9
Modes
of Imitation
23
Lucretius poets?
65
poetic imitation limited to imitation of action?
Two:
8
What
9
a
fictions
8
poems?
Making and
87 Particularization
1
1
Universals and Particulars
world should be and what
129
it is
Tasso’s Perfect Exemplars
144
10
Truth and Reality
159
11
Universality as Unity
167
12
Penumbral Ideas
17
13
The Grandeur
189
Part Three:
A
of Generality
Purgation of Passiotis
A New
14
Catharsis:
15
Robortelli and
16
The Development
Implement
205
Maggi
214
of the Opposition
225 xi
Contents Consolidations
239
18
Moving by Pathos or Ethos
264
19
Syntheses
274
20
Omnibus Purgations
291
17
The
Part Four:
Poetic Imagination
21
The
22
Speroni and Tomitano
23
Girolamo Fracastoro
316
24
Paduans and Aristotelians
329
25
Platonism, Love, Beauty, and Florence
341
26
Mazzoni’s Immediate Predecessors
349
27
Mazzoni and Bulgarini
355
28
Mazzoni on Dreams
29
Tasso’s
Revival of Classical Ideas
Part Five: 30
Platonists
Poet's
310
375
Magic Realism
The
303
390
Art and the Poet's Furor
and Aristotelians
399
Patrizi’s Synthesis
4
32
Christians and Aristotelians
421
33
The Four Furors and
431
34
True wit
3
1
Index
is
the Music of the Spheres
nature to advantage dress’d
1
437 46
Xll
Part One
POETRY AS IMITATION
'
\
1
The Theory
of Imitation
in the Renaissance
SOME
our day
themselves Aristotelians;
it
cannot, therefore, be assumed that the theory of poetry as imitation
is
a
dead
literary critics in
still call
thing. Literary creation in the past century
characterized both
by
realism, especially in the novel,
result
On
a half has
been
and by expres-
would of emphasis upon “holding the mirror up to
sionism, especially in poetry.
seem to be the
and
the surface, realistic literature
upon the theory of poetry as imitation; and expressionistic literature would seem to be the result of emphasis on theories that stress not a faithful rendition of what lies outside the human mind but created art objects that are responsive only to what comes into being in the poet’s soul. M. H. Abrams, in The Mirror and the Lamp has amply demonstrated the shift in “constitutive” metaphors by which the expressionistic “lamp” critics of the Romantic period supplanted or nature,” that
is,
,
overthrew the “mirror”
critics of the
Renaissance or Neoclassic period.
In the mid-twentieth century, mirror theories of art have very poor social standing,
and
it
has long been customary to berate the critics
of the Italian cinquecento for falling prey to theories of poetry as mirrorings.
Mimetic and mirror theories of
art
are not,
however,
precisely identical, and before the Renaissance critics are summarily dismissed, there should be a clear understanding
the broad problem most occupied
The
on what aspects of
them and why.
twentieth-century Aristotelian usually does battle for art
imitation not because he puts a high value
on
as
faithful representations
The Age
of Criticism
of external nature in poetry or painting but because he needs to dis-
communicated by
tinguish the nature of the thing
from
a
work
of fine art
must be
abstract, philosophic, or scientific expression. Since it
conceded that not every poem, novel, or play possessing the
qualities
of fine art unmistakably imitates something, the concept of imitation
and no doubt must,
can,
if it is
to be
embraced
at
all,
be extended
which an organization of relative concreteness expresses or embodies a set of more general relations. If this much to cover
all
instances in
granted, the concept of imitation can
be useful in defining
latitude
is
what
central to poetic discourse, in contradistinction to other kinds
is
still
of discourse.
For
instance, in reading
difficulty, it
the
poem
is
By
is.
most poems that offer some obscurity or
perhaps well to determine
first
what the
“situation” of
I mean what concrete action is being preWhat, in other words, even for a lyric poem, is its in “Dover Beach” the situation is of a man asking a
“situation”
sented or imitated.
mise en scene (as
woman
come
to
to a
window
overlooking the Channel so that he can
project onto the scene below his
comments
to her about love and
darkness in the appearances and realities of the world)? In a dramatic
monologue the
situation
is
usually obvious. Likewise the situation
usually obvious in a Shakespeare sonnet.
A
is
simple extension of prin-
ciple can lead to understanding of the nature of the shifting situation in Eliot’s
“(x
A
-f-
“The Waste Land.” To
y) (x
+ y)
=x
-f-
poetic without
would seem
that
its it
may
by an image
+y
“A
the contrary, an assertion such as
2”
quite abstract and situationless.
is
man’s
first instinct is
to
sit
down”
is
have an ingredient of ironic wit that renders
being in any
way
imitative of a situation. So
cannot be said that imitation
element in poetry. In a pressed in
2xy
statement such as Shaw’s
similarly abstract but it
2
poem with
cluster in
is
it
an indispensable
highly abstract subject matter ex-
which the images
are unrelated except
connection with the abstract idea, the images are concrete but do not
comprise a situation, and in such a case “concreteness” seems to be a better term for the essential element in poetry than “imitation,” even
though “imitation” always implies concreteness but “concreteness” does not always imply sequential imitation.
Many without
poems, be
it
said,
with highly abstract subject matter and
a hint of landscape or external situation can nevertheless be
thought of
as imitative if the poet’s voice in the
presence of the poet speaking. This 4
is
poem
implies the
an aspect of the problem clearly
The Theory
of Imitation
recognized in the Renaissance and debated then.
“The Second Coming” may poem with a situation and consequently
be defended in
Yeats’s
a poet’s imitation of his
ment
own
as
poem such manner
this
as
as a
an imitation. Whether such
voice constitutes the central poetic ele-
“The Second Coming” or whether
in
A
that element
is
the total
imaginative conception or the use of such vivid means of concrete expression as the falcon image, the image of the slouching beast, or such
“The ceremony
uniqueness of expression as I
would be reluctant
is
Plato in the Republic a
On
to assert.
or mirror reproduction
of innocence
is
drowned”
the other hand, mere photographic
clearly not in itself necessarily poetic.
compared the
poet’s imitating of things to
mirror image. Renaissance scholars found in Aristotle mirror refer-
The
ences linked to imitations. the
phrase
Cicero:
the
comedy
is
vitae.
The
man
as imitation. In
a mirror”
a
mirror of custom, an image
metaphor was abundantly used
mirror late
question, unless asserting so is
life,
could find the same significance in Horace’s
throughout the middle and
ment “Poetry
mirror figure was
grammarian Donatus attributed to
“an imitation of
of truth.” Renaissance
exemplar
classical locus for the
fourth-century
Renaissance.
much
was
Of
implies in
can be
this there
any way that the
also little
state-
central in Renaissance theories of poetry
any theory of imitation more attention
is
paid to the
nature of the thing imitated than in any theory in which there
nothing “outside there” to which the expression advantage of mimetic theory
is
that
it
is
is
related, but the one
offers a basis, although quite
between poetry
as
one kind
done during the great burst of
aesthetic
possibly an incomplete one, for distinction
of discourse and other kinds.
The
literary theorizing
speculation in sixteenth-century Italy, and to a far lesser extent in
sixteenth-century France and England, bears a parental relation of
both father and mother to
all
theorizing done since then. Either six-
teenth-century theorizing contained oppositions often unresolved until later centuries, or the precarious
mating of ideas which occurred then
contained genes that did not become evident until later generations.
For sixteenth-century ophers turned their
Italy
was the time and place
full attention to
in contradistinction to the fifteenth
in
which
philos-
the nature of creative activity,
century
when
the Humanists
were
with passion for the study of the poetry of Greece and Rome, supposing it to be more important than philosophy, and to the followfilled
ing epochs beginning with Bacon, Descartes, Pascal, and
Locke when 5
The Age
of Criticism
philosophy meant something more like interest in mathematics, and the
life
scientific
method,
of reason. Historians of philosophy have
most completely ignored the philosophers of sixteenth-century
al-
Italy,
except for some recent signs of interest in the origins of scientific rationalism, as humanistic philosophy has had entific rationalism.
over
as if it did
no place
in histories of sci-
That part of the map is left blank or, rather, is sealed exist. The Romantic movement found philosophers
not
again devoting a significant part of their thinking to problems of aesthetics
—witness Kant, Schelling, Hegel, even John Stuart Mill—but
with insufficient force to overcome the bias of the preceding two centuries.
Even now, with
the sole exception of Pomponazzi, the only
sixteenth-century Italian philosophers the early scientific rationalists
who
—Telesio,
known
are extensively
are
Giordano Bruno, Campanella,
and Galileo. The vast philosophic compendia of Mazzoni and
Patrizi are
And even in histories of literary criticism it has more common to give lip service to the great importance of
virtually unobtainable.
been far
sixteenth-century speculation than to indulge in actual reading of the texts.
In strict justice to
what happened,
it
must be conceded that sixteenth-
century Italian literary criticism was more a re-creation than an original
what
creation. Subtract the attempts to understand
Cicero, Horace, and Quintilian had
meant
Plato, Aristotle,
in their literary criticism,
only a small heap of random original comments seems to be
and
The
left.
Renaissance philosophers attempted to pick up right where the Alexandrian commentators, grammarians, and rhetoricians had
having in their turn
as if the intervening
But they did not wish to stand
still.
of putting together a complete
completed
in antiquity,
left off,
chasms of centuries did not
They were
body of
well aware that the task
literary doctrine
had not been
and they addressed themselves to the job of put-
ting the pieces together and filling in the gaps. In this sense their
was both
original
and complicated, and they carried on
campaign for the better part of
a century.
Out
of the
the classical world, extant in the Renaissance, that critical
comments, only
literary theory.
One
a
many
were
work
continuous treatises of
repositories for
Aristotle’s Poetics provided a full system of
of the puzzling questions of
more was not made of
be-
exist.
all
time has been
why
Aristotle’s Poetics in classical times. If discovery
implies use, the sixteenth-century Italians can be said to have invented Aristotle’s Poetics certainly they
cism
a
were the
first
to
make
a literary criti-
going concern, in other than handmaiden status to rhetoric, 6
ethics,
The Theory
of Imitation
Thus, even though their main work was
religion, or philosophy.
dredging of the texts of antiquity for pertinent
complishment was far from
small.
They
not fully exist until they discovered
For the theory of clusively
a
citations, their net ac-
existed in a tradition that did
it.
imitation, the Renaissance writers relied almost ex-
on Plato and
Aristotle.
They were
by
upset
that side of Plato
that disparaged poetry as an imitation of an imitation, fully scanned the Republic
and they care-
and the dialogues for proof of the existence
of the other side of Plato that allowed the poet’s imitation to transcend the limitations of the world of particulars. In their attempts to under-
stand the subtleties of Aristotle’s theory of imitation they turned im-
mediately and regularly to Plato.
decade or so of the
after the first
The evidence is overpowering that, new critical theorizing, the curricula
of the schools and universities were systematized to ensure familiarity
on the part of
a large
number of
Aristotle bearing in particular
who
and Puritans
on poetry
as imitation.
had gleefully made use of
poetry were apparently defense of the poet’s Nevertheless,
students with the passages in Plato and
still
mode
if it is
make
the
of imitation a burning issue.
asked
why
Renaissance writers accepted so unilittle
interest in exploring the
possibility of other philosophic bases for poetry, all
Philistines
Plato’s disparagement of
present in sufficient numbers to
formly the doctrine of imitation and had that
The
it
must be remembered
antiquity had accepted the doctrine. In whatever authority they
turned to they found variations of the same doctrine. This uniformity in their heritage accounts also for their habit of not
going
much beyond
Plato and Aristotle in their search for relevant ideas.
For the mirror concept they could
also find
support in Horace and
Cicero^ (Donatus). Paolo Beni claimed that the three important classical authorities for doctrines of imitation in his
and Plutarch. writers
was
On
minor points of doctrine
utilized. Vettori, for instance,
Athenaeus on dancing
as a
mode
day were
Plato, Aristotle,
a variety of other classical
made
use of a passage in
of imitation. Mazzoni used Proclus as
authority in explaining the theory of imitation as proportion or similitude. Similar elaborations rhetoricians,
who
were garnered from an assortment of
in their classifications of tropes
classical
and figures of thought
had touched upon relationships comparable to that between imitations and things imitated. These same rhetoricians often also came near to exploring the nature of symbolic imitation; but Plato had already culti-
vated this territory in his handling of language as symbol. 7
It is
note-
The Age worthy
of Criticism
that Patrizi, in launching his revolutionary attack
theory of imitation, dealt
roughly with Plato
as
though he was customarily
as
on
al-
a professing Platonist.
Finally, the sixteenth-century writers
made
use of the classical
cations of kinds of reasoning in formulating their ideas, for rational or speech arts poetry
and rhetoric because of
Aristotle’s
with Aristotle,
was distinguished from
classifi-
among
the
dialectic, sophistic,
dependence on imitation. But the existence
its
of these supporting authorities merely confirmed them in their practice of relying primarily
upon the
ideas of Aristotle
and Plato.
Had
there
been no possibility of debate over moot points in Aristotle and Plato, speculation on the theory of imitation in the Renaissance might have
been far
The
extensive than
less
it
was.
Renaissance theorists did, in
fact,
handle a considerable number
of complex problems, some already extensively bruited in antiquity and
some
not.
imitation?
Can lyric or dithyrambic poetry legitimately be Of what is it an imitation? Does not the theory of
called an
imitation
apply better to prose fiction or to comedies and tragedies in prose than to poetry characterized in
by
verse?
imitation the distinguishing element
Is
poetry and not verse? Under what conditions can philosophic doc-
trine
be used in poetry
if
poetry
concepts out of place in poetry? poetic imitation, and to imitate his
own
which
is
the
is
concrete imitation? Are scientific
Is
poetic invention different
more important? Can
a
from
poet be said
voice or use himself as persona? All of these and
other questions were fought over, and the harvest of critical ideas that resulted It
was
a
bumper
one, even
the fruit
was not of high
quality.
bears repeating that one of the principal reasons for close scrutiny of
Renaissance critical activity intensely, is,
if all
is
that
it
was carried on over
and with consecutive development.
consequently,
less a
The corpus
a
long period,
of
its
product
matter of a few gems of prose style or surpassing
genius than of a rather plodding but intelligent effort to think through the questions that faced the age.
8
2
Patrizi’s
IN
Attack on Mimesis
1586, Franceso Patrizi, at that time the
pher
volumes of
showpiece Platonic philoso-
court and university of Ferrara, published the two separate
at the
his Poetica.
The second
of these,
La deca
disputata , contains
ten books illustrative of Patrizi’s forensic ability, the greater
which
consist of a slashing attack
imitation.
He
conducted
his
upon
number of
Aristotle’s theory of
poetry
as
argument with such gusto that the thinking
of an age normally uncritical of Aristotle
is
best revealed
by
this opposi-
tion to Aristotle, for Patrizi’s stand less reveals an unalterable opposition
between himself and the
which
extent to
by
rest of his
contemporaries than
it
indicates the
contemporaries were cramped within and hampered
his
was occasionally carmethod into hairsplitting and into trying to win his argument even if he went beyond common sense in doing so. La deca disputata however, is a document of real importance in the history of the confines of the Aristotelian dicta. Patrizi
away by
ried
his
,
literary criticism,
and
its
contents merit close analysis.
The attack upon Aristotle’s mimetic concept begins in dead earnest with Book III. Patrizi presented himself as one who followed scientific reason at
all
times,
whether
it
did or did not accord with authority.
He
claimed that Aristotle had presented his theory of imitation without
proof and even without adequate explanation. Quite to the contrary, he
“we have always been
said,
facts themselves
and
in the authority of sible,
was
inclined and accustomed to put beliefs in the
in the reasons inferred
anyone.” So
any truth that might reside
his
from the
program was to
in Aristotle’s idea,
facts rather than
ferret out,
and
his first
to eliminate equivocations hidden in the uses of the
tion” as Aristotle had defined
word
it.
9
if
pos-
attempt “imita-
The Age As
of Criticism
found
a result of his researches, Patrizi
six different
meanings of
imitation in Aristotle: (
1
nouns taken
all
)
by
Aristotle
as imitations of things,
from the Cratylus of
an interpretation borrowed
Plato, in
whether words should be thought of bols, signs, similars, images, figures,
which Plato had asked sym-
as imitators, imitations,
or declarations
(2) the rhetorical concept of enargeia (putting scenes concretely and
vividly before our eyes) extended to
mean
imitation
(3) the fable or plot of an action thought of as an imitation of an action (4) imitation consisting of the relation between an action presented on a stage
and
a real-life action
(5) an extension of the principle in 4 to include epic and dithyrambic
poetry
accompaniment
(6) a further extension including musical If these
meanings are ultimately
all
the same, Patrizi argued, Aristotle’s
was not equivocal. If it was equivocal, his thinking was diswas bothered by the fact that some of these meanings were more generic than others and that many did not make clear whether any kind of prose as well as verse could be thought of as imitation. One failure of Aristotle was therefore that he did not sufficiently definition
orderly. Patrizi
define or circumscribe his term. Patrizi next tested these different
meanings against
sertion that poetry imitates with words,
words and is
all
are imitations, he said, users of
words
The concept
harmony, and rhythm.
any use of words
is
are poets, but he thought
not what gives poetry
its
form and
Aristotle’s asIf all
then similarly imitation, it
self-evident that this
essence.
of enargeia Patrizi treated
more
“describing something in words in such a
way
He defined we not only
gently. that
it
as
hear
them but seem to see it as if it were present and in plain view.” He observed that Hermogenes had understood poetic imitation in this way, that “Longinus” (one of the few references to “On the Sublime” in the sixteenth century even though Robortelli had published a Latin translation in 1548) had exalted Homer on account of his depiction of images, and that Aristotle had suggested the same in praising Homer for his metaphors. Patrizi, speaking for himself, added that enargeia so
much
virtue that one of our
modern
writers has included
the four ‘properties’ (as he called them) of poetry
.
.
.
truly of
as
one of
the others being
prudence, variety, and suavity.” But Patrizi argued that 10
“is it
this quality in
Attack on Mimesis
Patrizi' s itself
makes
a
poet only
minor poet and pertains to the aspects of
a
poem that are not really vital. The modern writer to whom on one
was
Patrizi referred
1
who
enargeia with poetic
occasion at least practically identified
imagination
Castelvetro,
a
Patrizi said that this expositor of Aristotle often called
.
poetry a resemblance but never told precisely what he meant by re-
“The
semblance, although he did say, ing well
how
to resemble; that
mind with harmonized words
right thing in poetry
is
in
know-
to present clearly to the eyes of the
is,
that
which is far from us either because make us see it not otherwise than
of distance of place or of time and if it
were before our
, tion.’ 2 Patrizi still
eyes.
And
in
doing that poetry finds
found grounds for objecting,
he was predisposed to accept enargeia enargeia
is
not necessarily present in
the essential element in poetry,
poems where
as
important in poetry, that
parts of poems, so that
all
would follow
it
perfec-
its
in spite of the fact that
if it
were
that only those parts of
did exist could be called poetry. Furthermore, he
it
claimed, not even Aristotle asserted that enargeia should be present
everywhere
poem. Again,
in a
any vivid speaker or orator be classed
as a poet.
And
enargeia
if
who makes
is
the discriminating feature,
a picture
come
clear for us
must
again, since dramatic poetry brings us actors
who
are in front of our eyes, not as
in
for the transporting of distant objects to us; dramatic poets do not
it
need “words of evidence” there must be
two kinds of
the other perfecting
enargeia
is
it;
in
if
they are there, there
order for us to
Although
it is
see. So, Patrizi
no demand concluded,
poetic imitation, one giving poetry
its
but neither Plato nor Aristotle asserted
a perfecting kind of imitation,
kind that gives poetry
is
its
essential
we
form,
that. If
yet need to discover the
form.
a digression at this point to turn
from
Patrizi’s willing-
ness to identify enargeia usually thought of as a kind of rhetorical figure ,
or embellishment, with imitation,
it is
important to
call attention to
the
fact that several of the literary critics of sixteenth-century Italy dealt at
more or
less
length with enargeia and to
of Patrizi’s problem depends raised
by
insist that a full
upon understanding
these other treatments.
Some
understanding
the complex questions
of the outstanding treatments of
enargeia are to be found in Pigna, Giraldi Cinthio, Cavalcanti’s Retorica
Ludovico stotele
Castelvetro, Foetica d’Ari-
vulgarizzata
1576), pp. 366-373.
et
sposta
(Basilea,
2
Francesco Patrizi, Della poetica: La deca disputata (Ferrara, 1586), p. 64; Castelvetro, Poetica d’Aristotele, p. 601. 11
The Age
of Criticism
Muzio, Tasso, Mazzoni, and Beni
some
3 .
This concept
significance in Renaissance theorizing
also
played a role of
on imagination
4
and led to
speculation on the place of particularity or concretion in poetry sequently, an understanding of the importance of
its
functioning
comprehension of the true nature of Renaissance
to
5 .
is
poetry, the
poem
ness belongs to a
vital
critical theory.
perception that, however necessary vivid concreteness
Patrizi’s
Con-
is
in
more than provide vivid concretesecond-rate kind of poetry was an acute one. that does nothing
To prove that poetry should not be only, Patrizi used the genetic
and for which he had
laid the
confined to imitations of an action
method which was customary with him groundwork in his La deca istoriale by
showing that many of the prose writings of the period preceding Aristotle’s
He
Poetics contained fables and
said that if Aristotle
meant
his
many poems
in the third
by
this way it would poem and every poem
theory to apply in
follow that every fable should be considered a
would have
did not contain fables.
and he tried to prove by use of Plato’s distinctions book of the Republic between poetry and mythology and a fable,
the distinctions
made by Diodorus
Siculus
between poetry and other
kinds of writing in primitive times that this definition of poetry had no
standing outside of Aristotle. Patrizi indicated that fables could be com-
monly found among
writers of
all sorts:
historians, philosophers, dia-
logue writers, and writers of novelle. Patrizi
had an easy time with the fourth possible meaning of poetic
imitation, for
it
was
to
him unthinkable
that
all
kinds of poetry could
be represented on a stage; Aristotle himself had confessed to the impossibility of staging the pursuit of
Hector by Achilles around the
And, to the contrary, the Platonic dialogues and other kinds of writing, which are self-evidently not poetry, can be presented
walls of Troy.
3
See Giovan Batdsta Pigna,
/
romanzi
(Vinegia, 1554), pp. 49-51; Giovambattista Giraldi Cinthio, “Discorso intorno al
comporre de
i
romanzi,” in Discorsi
(Vinegia, 1554), pp. 56 (where, significantly, Giraldi suggests his immediate
authority was Vida for the idea that enargeia etry),
La
is
the essential element in po-
161-162; Bartolomeo Cavalcand,
ret orica
(Vinegia,
1559),
p.
296;
Girolamo Muzio Giustinopolitano, Deirarte poetica
1551), p. 79;
in
Rime
diverse (Vinegia,
Torquato Tasso, Discorsi 12
del
poema
eroico, in Opere, XII (Pisa,
Giacopo Mazzoni, Della Comedia di Dante ed. by Mauro Verdoni and Domenico Buccioli 1823), 126, 184;
difesa della
(Cesena,
1688),
II,
18-20; Paolo Beni,
Comparazione di Omero, Virigilio, e Torquato in Tasso, Opere, XXI (Pisa, 1828), 250; and Beni, In Aristotelis poetic am commentarii (Patavii, 1613), pp. 24, 57, 60, 92. 4
6
See infra, p. 333. See infra, p. 201.
Attack on Mimesis
Patrizi' s
on
may
a stage. Stage presentations
clearly be called imitations, but this
kind of imitation does not belong to If in epic
an imitator
when
he presented the speeches of
discourse but not an imitator
Homer
poetry.
all
poetry, Patrizi argued, Aristotle meant the poet to be called
when
was not
in a large part of Iliad
his characters in direct
own
he narrated in his a poet, for
person, then
according to
Patrizi’s
count there are 8474 verses of straight narration in the Iliad but only 7286 verses in direct discourse; thus Homer was a poet in only half of his
poem.
In his sixth usage of the term “imitation” Aristotle mistook musical
instruments for genres of poetry. Patrizi’s general conclusion then fol-
lowed that no one of these
six
meanings was adequate to
tation as the essential feature of
all
establish imi-
poetry.
In the fourth book Patrizi retraced his steps through the maze of these six
ways of
treating imitation, testing against the six definitions the oft-
repeated dictum that poetry
is
Patrizi claimed that Plutarch’s
“poetry
like
painting in being an imitation. is
speaking picture” [derived
a
by Plutarch from Simonides] and Horace’s ut Aristotle’s Plato’s
pictura poesis as well as
comparisons of poetry and painting, were
comment
all
derived from
Republic Book X, that the poet
in the
is
,
painter in presenting a variety of colors, using
but Patrizi then disposed of
his
words
own argument by
like the
instead of colors,
asserting that Plato’s
comparison was between words and colors, not between poetry and painting as imitations.
More
difficult it
was
to dispose of Plato’s comparisons of poets
painters as icon makers, even
though he reverted to
that in such cases the differentia classes, since sculptors,
casters also
make
do not exclude members of other
makers of pictures with
images,
effigies,
and
argument
his usual
and
icons.
wood
and bronze
inlays,
Mazzoni based
his
theory
of poetic imitation on Plato’s concept of poetry as ikonopoeia the same ,
matters that Patrizi reviewed at this point. Mazzoni’s Della difesa della
Comedia
di DaJite
tion of Patrizi’s
appeared in 1587, in the year following the publicadisputata. Both Patrizi and Mazzoni were moti-
La deca
vated in large measure by the desire to refute the Aristotelianized
Platonism of Tasso, and
were destined in Platonic first Patrizi
it is
to be the first
these two,
who
newly constituted
chair
curious to observe
two holders of
philosophy in the Sapienza at
and then Mazzoni, differed
the
Rome
in their
how
in the following decade,
handling of
Platonic doctrine.
H
this
item of
The Age
An
image, Patrizi
of Criticism
said, “is a certain figure that has a
blance to something,” whereas an effigy resembles person. Both are imitations, the one a poet can make both images and
less,
general resem-
a particular thing or
the other more.
effigies, like
true that
It is
any other icon maker, he
conceded, relying on Plato’s definition in the Sophist of an imitator
as a
maker of idols, on a statement in the third book of the Republic that “making oneself resemble someone else in voice or figure is imitating him whom one tries to resemble,” and on a similar statement in Book II of Laws. Plato as Patrizi understood him meant imitation clearly to be resemblancing. After identifying Plato’s icastic imitation
with effigy making, he determined that any true imitation
made by
resemblance, whether
and
that “if the poet imitates
imitation he should
and poetry should be
The
a
is
an imitator and
may
possibility of faithful
poetry
if
is
really an
maker of resemblances
become impatient with the slow the need of skipping ahead some
well
grinding out of his logic and feel distance in order to understand
a
be a
and added
6
resemblance.”
reader of Patrizi
tries to
a painter, sculptor, or poet,
make resemblances and be
( Sophist
why
he failed at
point to accept the
this
resemblancing of a picture originating in the poet’s
or painter’s mind, particularly
when he was
aware, as
many
of his
learned contemporaries were not, that Plato himself had described this
kind of imitation. But Patrizi refused to identify expression with imita-
He
tion.
said:
“Others
nection, that the poet
him, in the same
way
may
say to me, as Plato says in this same con-
makes manifest the example that he has within
that the painter imitates the example of something
either of nature or of art put before
exact a resemblance that nothing
having in
his
expresses
it
all
is
falsified,
his colors creates so
and likewise the poet,
mind the example which resembles nothing
with
not imitation, or to
him and with
his verses that others if it is
it;
And
as a painter
art or nature, so
it
is
is
common
his colors
resemble
can he also feign something that has
never existed in art or nature, but only in 6
can with
outside, yet so
but expression
not peculiar to the poet, since
writers and speakers.
something out of
seem to see
his
own
fantasy. Likewise,
it
For Plato’s treatment of the distincbetween icastic and fantastic imitation (which is very brief, in view of what the Renaissance critics made of
“appearance” of what does not actually But from the context in Plato it is apparent that he would have classed
Sophist 236. Icastic imitation presents a true likeness of an object or
tive
tion
it),
see
person. Fantastic imitation presents an
exist.
as fantastic a portrait that
since
surface.
the
actual
used perspec-
canvas
is
a
flat
Attack on Mimesis
Patrizi’ s
seems that
a
poet can both make a portrait that
is
what
similar to
exists
and can express those imaginations that he has conceived within himself, often corresponding to nothing in
is common to much turn away from
sion, Patrizi insisted,
Patrizi did not so
nature, or divinity.”
art, all
nature of poetry as he refused to
make
The term
equivalent of imitation.
to particular resemblance
—
kinds of
it
men
But expres-
7 .
the Romantic concept of the
the earmark of poetry and the
“imitation” he confined to reference
And
in effect to Plato’s icastic imitation.
how, he asked, can this resemblancing be done better with the use of words than by enargeia by putting before our eyes that which pertains to our ears. But again he said that this technique leads only to minor ,
poetry, takes into account only sections of poems, not wholes, and also
is
used by writers other than poets.
Turning
to conceptions of imitations primarily based
on particular
genres of poetry, he briefly entertained the notion that the kind of imitation found in
drama resided
comic masks and the
realities
between
in the relation
He
they represented.
tragic
and
objected to this
—
two grounds that masks are things whereas poetic imitation must pertain to words primarily and that even if this kind of resemblance could be said to give form and essence to dramatic poetry theory, however, on
it
could hardly be extended to apply to other kinds.
show
to
tive
that
then proceeded
poetry could not claim the support of Plato and Aristotle, since
Plato had specifically said that a poet imitates only hides his
own
different
words
own
his
He
any theory of imitation based primarily on epic or narra-
presence and Aristotle had in saying a poet
And,
person.
is
made
not imitating
when
he completely
the same assertion in
when
Patrizi added, in other kinds of
he
is
speaking in
poetry poets more
more obviously speak in their own person than in epic poetry. was at this point begging the question as it was framed by his contemporaries, for many literary theorists of his generation were ask-
often and Patrizi
ing
if
a lyric poet in the creation of the
poem could not be
imitating himself, to be speaking behind a
separating himself as a character in a life self. Patrizi,
who
claimed to be a
mask representing
poem from
rationalist,
said to
be
himself, in
his practical
or real-
was here using the
logic
of authority to refute the rationalistic theories of the authoritarians, so that the result had value only as a tactical maneuver.
Since in dealing with the theories of special genres he had lost sight of his testing of poetry against painting, Patrizi had to point out, in 7
Patrizi,
La deca
disputata, p. 91. 5
The Age moving
of Criticism
poem
to his final item (considering a
an imitation of an
as
making any of these
action or fable), the difficulty of
theories except
that of enargeia apply to both media. In the eighteenth century, especially in the school of
DuBos, the formula of ut pictura poesis was
re-
versed so that critics urged painters to try to give their pictures literary
by portraying such things as “The Slaughter of the Innocents” “The Assassination of Caesar.” But Patrizi denied the validity of this parallel. Not only did he suppose that merely a few kinds of poetry had fables
or
fables or concrete actions, but he also asked
an imitation. Insofar
how
a fable could
a fable was a fable simply by
as
its
be called
adherence to
would have to consist in the the resemblance between what the poet showed
necessity and probability, the resemblance probability, that
is,
in
and what should have happened. Is the fable then an imitation of the poem? Or is it the image or effigy that poetry makes? Patrizi was not stalling for time but was availing himself of the dilemma all literal interpreters of Plato have found themselves in, a dilemma caused by the ambiguity of Plato’s use of reality concepts in Patrizi
was face
to face with the
poetry and history.
He
his treatments of poetry.
commonplace
distinctions
between
argued that since Plato had banned poets
who
presented a false imitation of reality one can infer that epic poems are
not really poems unless they have true heroes to imitate, because an
an imitation of a
imitation of a false hero
is
to these discriminations
Homer was
side of imitation conceived as fable,
the fable bears tation, in
little
which
false reality,
not a poet. But arguing from the
one
led to conclude that
is
resemblance to the exemplar there
case there
is
and according
imitation
which
is
true poetic imi-
not imitation. Like
is
Mazzoni, Patrizi believed Plato had intended to define poetry tastic,
not
as icastic, imitation,
and
like Castelvetro
defenders of the romances he believed that
when
and
like
as fan-
some of the
many poems do
not even
bear the apparent resemblance to be found in fantastic imitation.
The
only possible conclusion, he decided, was that Homer, the greatest of poets,
was admired not for
or for not imitating at is
not the cause of
his
likes
and nobody
quite separate
On
from
his
poetry
is
not imitation and imitation
What can be said who do imitate exactly
(this
mediocre poets.
“real imitation but either for false imitation
So
poetry.”
for lesser poets. Poets poets,
all.
It
is
a
Homer
can be said
turn out to be minor
cheap authoritarian reference to Horace)
can be seen that Patrizi was keeping invention
imitation.
the basis of this line of argument, Patrizi 1
for
was
able to conclude
Patrizi that
if
poetry
and
imitation,
is
Attack on Mimesis
must be something of which
imitation there
this
s
something must not
tion
is
nothing more than history;
only in the poet’s mind.
exist
exemplar to be imitated must be true,
the external object
if false,
said,
must be the work of
any case the imitation of
it is
God,
either
history.
He
it
in-
is
included
Anything
description of any particulars in the objective world.
he
The
or both. If true, the imita-
false,
vented. Patrizi used a concept of history so broad that
true,
an
it is
that
is
nature, or man, and in
“when
claimed that
poets
make make images just as they are.” And showed that poetry cannot be made
describe the dawn, the setting of the sun, and night in verse, they history out of
it
because they
Aristotle, he
added smirkingly,
from
history.
Again
case,
not to
in his time
make
Patrizi
seems to have been arguing only to win
True,
sense.
this definition
his
of history was widespread
and allowed most writers to speak of natural history and
as history. Aristotle’s usage was much the was not enough that Patrizi tried not at all to understand the distinction between universal truth and particular truth that was common in his day and that constituted the dilemma in Plato; he was intent on eliminating the word “imitation” from the critic’s vocabulary even if the idea expressed by the word remained intact. He also caused himself trouble by refusing to consider the possibility that poetic ele-
even geographical description same. But
it
ments could be found
in prose fiction, in oratory, in history,
other kinds of writing. His real
enemy was
who
the critic
and
in
attempted to
limit poetry to icastic imitation, to portraiture of real-life particulars
in short, to rigid realism. Patrizi
was
like later
rejected the mimetic concept because
the mirroring of
it
Romantic
who
seemed to confine the poet to
what lay outside him rather than
express the images that had their origin within his real
theorists
him
to
mind. But
his
to allow
own
problem was one of defining terms.
Many
of the arguments that
fill
the remaining books of
La deca
disputata deal with specific problems to be treated later in this study as
V
separate aspects of the total question. In
Book
whether or not poetry can be written
Book VI he asked if He challenged in Book VII
plot
is
more
essential to
Aristotle’s assertion that in
Book VIII showed
Patrizi questioned
in prose. In
poetry than verse.
Empedocles was
that poetry can be
less a
poet than
made from
handled questions of harmony and rhythm, and Book
Homer
history.
X
and
Book IX
covered prob-
lems connected with modes of imitation. All of these questions bear important relations to the theory of imitation.
At
this point,
however, con-
The Age
of Criticism
cern need be only with the resounding statement he made at the
Book
conclusion of
VIII.
After contending for some pages with Castelvetro, Patrizi said that being a poet does not consist either in the subject matter used or in inventing or in not inventing poetic manner.”
He
it
“so
much
proper
as in treating it in the
proclaimed that here
the one universal and, true
is
conclusion that can be drawn concerning the subject matter of poetry
—“that the matters comprised by either science, 8
would show
Patrizi said that he
meant by “treated poetically,” but if he did do so, too tangential and unmarked for me to find them. in
his
printed works,
it
would seem
advocacy of enargeia and
or history can be
and for poems, provided that they are
suitable subjects for poetry
treated poetically.”
art,
in
his
Empedocles, that Empedocles was
If his
answer
be located in
to
much
what he
his explanations are
argument, during as
later
his
his
limited
defense of
Homer
a poet as
exists
because
mysteries and allegories provided a second level of meaning in the natural science of
Empedocles
much
poetically ran counter to
was nevertheless
far
well as in the narrative of
poet can treat
Patrizi’s belief that a it
as
from unique
Homer.
subjects provided that he does
all
of the thought of the Renaissance but in
its
time, as Professor
H.
B. Charlton
pointed out several decades ago. Scaliger had taken the line that everything can be used in poetry, for to him poetic qualities were matters of diction and the castoro,
who
form of poetry was
belonged in
spirit to
which poetry was primarily
its
metrical arrangement
if
only
it
can be adorned.”
Bruno
said, “I
10
day
against the Aristotelian formalists of his belief;
The
is
took an even
suitable for the
Giordano Bruno’s outburst is
a
famous instance of the
many kinds of and human inven-
say that there are and can be as
poets as there can be and are kinds of sentiments tions.” 11
contrary positions were of great diversity and represent
the subject matter of other sections of this work; some, however, 8
Ibid., p. 175.
9
J.
C. Scaliger, Poetices
(Lugduni,
1561),
p.
125.
libri
See
septem
H.
B.
vanni Aquilecchia
18
Nauger
ius, in
1555), p. 337.
p.
“Giordano Bruno, De gVheroici fuin Dialoghi italiani ed. by Gio-
55
Girolamo Fracastoro, Opera omnia (Venezia,
di
132.
rori,
-
came
See also Antonio Fusco, ha poetica Ludovico Castelvetro (Napoli, 1904),
Charlton, Castelvetro' s Theory of Poetry (Manchester, Eng., 1913), pp. 5310
Fra-
the pre-Aristotelian generation to
a matter of ornamentation,
stronger stand than Patrizi, saying that “everything poet’s matter,
9 .
959
-
,
(Firenze,
1957),
p.
Attack on Mimesis
Patrizi' s
When
close to coinciding with this stand.
Minturno, for instance,
said
that the poet can handle anything that can conveniently be put into verse, 12
tions
he seemingly anticipated
upon what was “convenient.”
that a poet puts that the fable exist
is
all his
but he really imposed limita-
Patrizi,
Just before saying this he remarked
force into inventing and soon afterward added
the most important part of a
poem and
poem can
that a
without characters but not without action. His stand on the ques-
was much
tion of imitation
closer to orthodox Aristotelianism than the
one statement taken out of context would suggest.
When
Tasso or
Castelvetro advised poets to be careful to choose the kinds of subject
matter that were
fit
for poetry or that
form of poetry, they
essential
were capable of receiving the
in effect closed the
door to heterodoxy. 13
When Giraldi Cinthio asserted that a romance writer can use under the sun their
as grist for his mill if
he
is
due measure and proper ornament “so that the
and well-composed body,”
14
everything
judicious and gives result
is
things
all
a regulated
he was making a localized remark about
one kind of poetry and probably did not have the same questions
mind
that
were plaguing
his rhetorical treatises,
Patrizi
and Bruno.
When
in
Robortelli, in one of
questioned the prohibition of the subject matter
of the arts and sciences to the poet, he was concerned only that the prohibition be relaxed to permit occasional references
imitation. 15
When,
by
poets to
he was orthodox in making poetry an
scientific or philosophic concepts;
attempted to prove that
in 1599, Alessandro Guarini
even doctrinal lyric poetry could be conceived
form of
as a
imitation,
the looseness of his definition of “imitation” allowed him to embrace a position not unlike Patrizi’s even
he approached
if
it
from quite an
opposite angle. Although poetry usually deals with invented subject matter,. Alessandro Guarini said,
must be of that kind that “bears
it
can handle true
ideas,
but the truth
which truth either receives such semblance from the poetic mode with which it somehow is masked (so to speak), so that it almost comes actually to lose its own form, or
it
has through
a universal falseness, ject, as
its
own
a
semblance of
nature
however) so that
its it
fable,
similarity
becomes
with the a
false
(with
proper poetic sub-
by saying rare, wonderful, and excellent things, and in short manner in which poets usually treat them even though
just in that
“Antonio Sebastiano Minturno, De poeta
(Venetiis,
Charlton, loc. 11
1559),
.
107.
See
“Giraldi Cinthio, “I romanzi,”
“Francesco Robortelli,
De
cit.
19
p. 26.
artificio
dicendi (Bononiae, 1567), pp. 7-8.
cit.
Charlton, loc
p.
The Age
of Criticism
they have happened just in his failure to separate
this
way.”
16
Where
Guarini faltered was in
well enough accounts of true facts in history from
statements of reputedly true doctrine. His recognition of the existence of the no-man’s-land between poetic substance and abstract doctrinal
substance was, however, penetrating for his century.
Not only was
Patrizi not entirely alone in his
few
cally treated, but also a
century in holding that
could be used in poetry
sorts of subject matters
all
if
they were poeti-
scattered writers, notably Scaliger and
Paolo Beni, joined him in stepping out of the closed ranks of those fully accepted the theory of poetry as imitation. It
Scaliger nor Beni
theory
made
as Patrizi did.
as consistent
Before
treatise
he
said,
“We
poetry in general.”
up
set
18
hear too
And
classes of religious
and moral and
scientific
poetry
all
17 ,
but later in
his
imitation being the basis of
grouping of poets by subject matter he
and philosophic poets, including subclasses of and thus room was made for
political poets,
poets such as Empedocles and Lucretius imitators
upon the
began with acceptance of
imitation
is
much about
in his
true that neither
or as complete an attack
Patrizi, Scaliger
the notion that the basis of
is
who
whom
he did not consider
19 .
Beni, following Patrizi in time,
was very much aware of
Patrizi’s line
of attack. Like Patrizi, he pointed out that Aristotle never really defined imitation,
and he charged Aristotle with having used synonyms for
imitation that confused the picture
more than they
clarified
it:
eikazein
(to liken), apeikazein , zoographein (to depict). Poets are eikonopoioi
(makers of images). Beni found also in Aristotle the concept of enargeia , or evidentia , that
is,
sense orators, historians, and
hypotyposis; but he believed that in this
anyone
else
who
brings either external or
internal characteristics of things before our eyes
he followed
Patrizi’s
reasoning closely.
is
an imitator. So
He went beyond
this
far,
point to
develop one of the most comprehensive treatments of mimetic theory of the late Renaissance, one that bears interpretations of trizi’s
attack
upon
Mazzoni than
more resemblance
to the Platonic
to the standard Aristotelian
line.
Pa-
the mimetic concept can be thought of as one of the
polar positions in the triangular tensions of Renaissance speculations on the question, Beni’s and Mazzoni’s Platonic interpretation representing 16
Alessandro Guarini, “Lezione
Accademia
nell’
Mantova sopra il sonetto, Doglia, che vaga donna di Monsignor della Casa,” in Giovanni della Casa, Opere (Venezia, 1728), .
I,
.
degl'Invaghiti
in
17
20
M.
18 19
Padelford, Select
T ranslatians
Scaliger’s Poetics (Yale Studies in
English,
.
351-352.
F.
from
XXVI; New
Ibid., p. 27. Ibid., p. 16.
York, 1905), p.
1.
VatrizJs Attack on Mimesis another, and the Aristotelian orthodox view the third.
No
one of these
should be thought to dominate completely the aesthetic speculation of the sixteenth century.
God is an
mind (“by
imitator, Beni said, in ‘‘realizing” the ideas in his
which term Nature is said to imitate God, and Art to imitate Nature”) 20 Although for most of the ranges of implication behind this idea Beni relied upon Plato’s Timaeus and Sophist as well as on Christian doctrine, he also tried to show that generally among the Peripatetics “imitation is a thing in the class of those
nouns that are called analogues
which can primarily be applied some analogy or proportion or parison
to
similitude or,
indeed, Cicero treats analogy).”
(as,
of distinctions, mostly on the relation of
tempted to show that as imitator
.
that
if
you
With
prefer,
by com-
a long, intricate play
God to the logos, Beni atGod could be thought of
in this sense that
and manifestations of them;
plete creations of
Godhead
stituted.
was
.
or Creator and that the same relationship prevailed between
Plato’s Ideas
of
it
.
one thing and then to another by
—
God
than
just as angels are
man is—man
representing merely vestiges
a kind of hierarchy of imitation as analogues
The same
force of imitation
is
more comcan be con-
not to be found in
all
things;
power of imitating. What is peculiar in this account of Beni’s is the way in which the subject matter is considered as an agent faculty having the power of imitating God or the more intelligible orders of things. To say that certain media have limitations not shared by others is one thing; to say, that
as
is
to say,
some
faculties
have greater and some
less
Beni did, that a variety of powers can be found in painting, poetry,
and sculpture
is
quite another.
follows from this interpretation that Beni
would find Aristotle’s theory of imitation unclear. He also said that from Plutarch’s idea poetry is like painting we cannot learn what we want to know. To the contrary, he thought Plato was clear but came to this conclusion only after deciding that Plato implied a distinction between simple and It
—
total imitation, the
kind of presentation
when
a
poet speaks in
his
own
person in the historian’s manner, as in lyric poems, being simple, and direct presentation of the speech of a character being dramatic or total.
So to Plato imitation meant portraying either the words or the characteristics of
someone. In the course of
term to
from “simple imitation”
shift
his discussion,
Beni allowed
his
to “simple narration,” the latter
term being the one usually thought of as representing Plato’s meaning; Beni’s broadening of it to allow such pieces of writing as Hesiod’s “Beni, In Aristotelis poeticam commentarii,
p. 57.
21
The Age
of Criticism
Works and Days and
Virgil’s
Georgies to have a place in the room of
imitations represented
more
wish to find Plato consistent and clear
a
than an agreement with his contemporaries.
He
believed that Aristotle
intended to follow Plato’s line of reasoning throughout but failed to express himself sufficiently.
The
extension of the mimetic principle to include a historian’s nar-
must have bothered Beni.
ration
He
provisionally decided that
when
a
poet narrated simply he differed from a historian only in using verse,
but after some floundering he attempted to
predicament by deliberately
work
himself out of his
utilizing the sense of imitation as a bor-
rowing from one’s predecessors. Whether the
distinction he
made
as a
this maneuver is an important one or not is unclear. It whole host of scattered observations in the critical literature of sixteenth-century Italy that did honor to the earnestness of the
consequence of is
typical of a
critical
endeavor of that time even
if
they led no place in particular.
Beni said that the historian can hardly avoid accepting the facts provided him by the best of his historian predecessors, but the poet differs
from him
in
having more liberty of at
least
choosing which of
cessors he will imitate. Virgil could create an original
his
prede-
work while
form and content, but Tacitus could not have done this. This difference in the obligations of historian and poet shows something about the different way in which they employ the broad concept stealing both
of mimesis. In a long passage that followed, Beni tried to justify Aristotle’s inconsistencies in
using the term “imitation”
range of the “analogue” concept
all
the
way from
by showing
the
the imitation of
former writers to the direct imitation of the speech and persons of
human
beings on a stage
21 .
This account of Beni’s explanation does not do Aristotelianism, for although one finds
full justice to his
him spending much time accus-
ing Aristotle of inconsistency and lack of clarity, he nevertheless im-
on which he put near the top any which we can hear the voice of a persona and
plied consistently a scale of imitations
poem
or part of
can sense,
as if
poem
in
with our eyes
particular people.
That
( enargeia ),
the gestures and actions of
sense of “being there”
was important
of understanding the concept of imitation in poetry.
began
his explanation as if
Ibid., pp. 62-63.
22
way
he were a follower of Patrizi, Beni did ac-
cept the theory of imitation as he chose to define 21
And
in his
although he
it.
3
Instruments, Subjects, and
Modes of Imitation
THE best entry to the complexities of the on poetic imitation can be found
Renaissance
critics’ attitudes
in tracing out the conflicting interpre-
tations of Aristotle’s classification of kinds of imitations to be
found
in
which was dependent upon differences in subject matter being imitated, differences in the modes of the imitation, and differences in the instruments used in the imitation. This was a text that the sixteenthcentury critics often expounded since the problems it dealt with were very real and present among them. At stake was contemporary writing
poetry,
as
well as the theory of imitation. If the theory of imitation did not
account for what went on in most of the kinds of poetry that their instincts
accepted
as poetry,
theory, even though all
it
they would look with suspicion upon the
had the authority of Aristotle
antiquity, for that matter
—behind
the defenders of mimetic theory pliable
enough
Some
to
account for
all
— and of Plato and
Patrizi has already
it.
were hard-pressed
to
make
shown
the facts.
of the questions pestering Beni were the important ones:
narration be called imitation?
that
the theory
What
is
Can
the instrument of imitation in
Does the narrative poet imitate when he speaks in his own voice? In what way can lyric poems be called imitations? In an-
narrative poetry?
swering these questions, the sixteenth-century
critics
found
Plato’s in-
consistency of statement as significant as Aristotle’s clarity, and the total
confusion can be simplified by using
Plato’s statements,
as a
bridge Mazzoni’s study of
which, paralleling Beni’s and coming twenty -six years 23
The Age
of Criticism
Summary
provided the foundation for Beni.
earlier,
of other parts of
Mazzoni’s theory of poetic imitation must wait until
Comedia
In his introduction to Della difesa della
between
after describing Plato’s distinction tion,
Mazzoni
Now
I
icastic
later.
1
Dante (1587),
di
and fantastic imita-
said:
add that poetry should be placed among the imitative subordinate to
this class of imitation, as a species
ginning to define poetry one can say
and very important
member
difficulty.
For
persons themselves
who
understanding of
full
poems can be of three
that
speak, as do
sorts, that
is,
comedy and
it
arts and, in
Hence on
But here
imitation.
it is
genus.
its
arises a
we
be-
new
should re-
either representing the
tragedy, or merely relating
the things in the person of the poet, as dithyrambic poetry usually does
and
as
is
done
in the first three
books of the Georgies of Virgil, or partly
narrating and partly introducing other speakers, as the Odyssey , and the Aeneid of Virgil. imitation
is
found
poem
in that sort of
sons as speakers. But
it
It
may
it
which
seems then that imitation
is
is
And
be clearly seen that
is
imitation in those
narrated through the
mouth
of
the genus containing only the poetry
that Aristotle called dramatic, and that imitation can
genus of narrative poetry.
seen in the Iliad and
are introduced other per-
does not appear that there
other sorts of poems in which something the poet.
Now
in
is
this difficulty
is
by no means be the
the greater because
it
ap-
pears to be founded on the reason immediately apparent and on the authority of Plato,
who
in the
beginning of the third book of the Republic says
clearly that dramatic poetry alone
nothing to do with imitation
is
imitative and that narrative poetry has
2 .
Plato called the genus of poetry “narration” instead of Aristotle’s “imitation,” first
Mazzoni
asserted, using Proclus’ interpretation, to
be found in the
chapter of his commentary on the Republic of the three species of ,
which is imitative, as in comedy and tragedy; (2) the narrative which is nonimitative, as in dithyrambic poems and in poems “that tell the history of men without prosopopoeia”; and (3) a mixture of the first two, as in Homer. Maznarration according to Plato: (1) the dramatic,
zoni called special attention to Proclus’ comparison of poetry and history, as did Beni later, in constituting narrative as the generic term.
History
is
presented. 1
narrative in Its
which the
direct discourse of characters
is
not
opposite, dramatic poetry, imitates.
Infra , pp. 51-52, 76-78, 85, 103,
1
18—
gan,
U.S.A.,
Literary
124. 3
Cited by permission of the Wayne State University Press, Detroit, Michi24
(New
from Allan H.
Criticism ,
York, 1940),
Plato p. 361.
to
Gilbert,
Dry den
Modes Then, by use of tion as a lever,
between
Plato’s distinction
Mazzoni constructed
poetic imitation implied
by
of Imitation
a
novel
icastic list
and fantastic imita-
of the four species of
Aristotle in his various uses of the term,
defining imitation generically as analogue and listing Aristotle’s four
(“which
species as (i) the dramatic-fantastic
necessarily contains
two
sorts of idols
that of the person represented.
The
an imitation because
is
and images. The
other
is
first
image
it
is
the false but verisimilar
image which the actor presents; since he does not represent the true but the verisimilar, he consequently represents the image and the simulacrum
of the truth”); (2) the dramatic-icastic,
which
gives the direct imitation
of a real person; (3) the narrative-fantastic imitation, “which always certainly presents the image and the simulacrum of the truth and can
have another
as well,
which
is
always found in narrative-icastic poetry”;
and (4) the narrative-icastic, “which ought to contain the idol and the in particularization.” 3 Mazzoni conceded that
image which consists Aristotle,
though he used the term “imitation”
in
all
of these senses,
thought some of them were more properly or completely imitations than others.
The term must be understood
Next, in spite of
his interpretation
suggesting that narration
is
to be relative.
of Plato’s handling of the problem
the genus, not imitation, Mazzoni attempted
to prove that Plato did not consistently intend to exclude narrative
the genus of imitation. Although,
denied that narrative poetry
is
from
Mazzoni argued, Plato sometimes
imitation, at other times he hinted that
narrative poetry should be thought of as less completely imitative than
dramatic poetry, and in the Sophist he identified narrative with imitation.
The
difference,
Mazzoni thought Plato meant,
is
between narrative
poetry which uses an instrument in order to imitate and dramatic poetry which imitates directly without instrument. Furthermore, Mazzoni pointed out that since fantastic narrative must represent the verisimilar or an idol or
simulacrum of truth Plato must have thought
of such narratives as imitations. Mazzoni had to use
preamble to
as
which
a poet should be identified as
to create images,
by
all
these arguments
his principal interpretation of imitation,
and he achieves
this
according to
an imitator primarily by
his ability
end by sharp particularization and
the use of enargeia. But this aspect of Mazzoni’s theorizing deserves
separate handling later, as one of the significant
of literary criticism in the Renaissance.
purposes
is
What
moments is
in the history
notable for present
the line of reasoning Mazzoni took to adjudicate between
Plato and Aristotle and to provide a broad definition for the concept of 3
Translations
by
Gilbert, loc.
cit.
25
The Age
of Criticism
would apply
to narrative
imitation so that
it
to dramatic. In
comparison with
distinction
and lyric poems
between imitation by means of instrument
drama
that without instrument in
is
as well as
enlargement of definition,
this
his
and
in narrative
of lesser importance.
When
Paolo
Beni said that only recently had the central problems concerning
mimetic theory been
enough
clarified
to be useful, he almost certainly
had Mazzoni in mind. Needless to say, a vast literature on the instruments, subject matters,
and modes of imitation had come into being between the early years of
Much
the utilization of the Poetics of Aristotle and 1587.
when
however, uncritical, and in the early speculation imitation had not been seriously challenged, lessly
made
or easily
that
came hard
many
been questioned. Since
after
many
of
it
was,
the principle of
statements were care-
some of the primary
had
tenets
of the mid-century scholars, such as
Robortelli, Maggi, and Vettori, could be counted
on
to
show an
in-
timate acquaintance with the texts of both Platonists and Peripatetics, the ultimate difference between their stands and those of Mazzoni and
Beni
is
revealed in the greater sorting and
terials at
hand for the
later writers
naivete of the earlier writers
Trissino,
who was
not,
all
was
in
all,
one of the really
is
greater
influential critics of
in his handling of the
beginning to give an expanded interpre-
tation of Aristotle’s division according to means, subject, said: “Just as all imitating
The
text of the Poetics.
from impressive
far
varieties of poetic imitation. In
which the ma-
to
often revealed whenever they stray far
is
from immediate interpretation of the the sixteenth century,
winnowing
had been subjected.
and mode, he
or counterfeiting [contrctfare] of other
done with shapes and words
men
(as Plato says) and, as Aristotle adds,
with colors, likewise, in attempting to counterfeit someone, you not only determine
hunchback
if
shape arfd form (that
his
he
is
a
hunchback, or make him
man, or assign him any other
and counterfeit
his
is,
trait
him the
give
a cripple
figure of a
or a cross-eyed
he has), but also you determine
speech and determine
his color; that
is,
in order to
man you make him white, and a Moor or Saracen is by making him black.” 4 All of this is simple-minded enough, and Trissino did not get much more profound in adding that
counterfeit a white
counterfeited
the three instruments or tools in poetic imitation are speech, correspond-
ing to words,
rhythm corresponding
* G. G. Trissino, Poetica, Bk. but written earlier), in Tutte
2
6
V
(1563,
!e
opere
to shapes,
and harmony corre-
(Verona, 1729),
II,
92-93.
Modes sponding to colors, even though
of Imitation
an afterthought he decided that
as
dance and song used in the theater are not in themselves to be confused with the poetic, so that in speaking of poetic imitations fine ourselves to
we
should con-
words and rhythms.
In discussing Aristotle’s division of imitations according to subject matter, Trissino did
make an
merely dividing mankind into either
moral
social or
that characters can be imitated as better than, the
they are at present, he remarked that than they were,
Montagna
distinctions he
found revealed
forms worse. In music,
fifes, flutes,
imitate worse.
as,
Vinci painted
or worse than
men
as better,
and
and the Padoane and Spingardo
organ music, and “sounds and songs
and similar songs imitate the better”; other kinds
Homer imitated
better,
Theocritus worse, Burchiello and
Berni worst; Petrarch and Dante better. This, Trissino said, difference
as better
The same
in dances, the Giojosi, Lioncelli,
men
call to battle
Da
classes in saying
same
worse, and Titian as they were.
as
Rosine forms showing
which
contemporary
interesting comparison with
and music. Supposing accurately that Aristotle was not
painting, dance,
is
also the
between comedy and tragedy. Trissino differed from many
of the critics of his time in keeping his eye steadily on the aesthetics of
Dante this
as well as
on the Poetics of
Aristotle,
point in his thinking, that Dante in his
and he was well aware,
De
at
vulgari eloquentia had
distributed poetic genres according to their correspondence with the
vegetable, animal, and rational souls of
responding to the vegetable soul
is
men
—
a division in
which cor-
the useful (useful pertaining to arms
and our safety; ergo war poetry); to the animal or sensible soul light
(Venus
—love poetry); to the rational soul are honor,
is
virtue,
de-
and
the regulated will. This system of Dante’s, Trissino affirmed, “is not truly different
from what we have determined following
arms, Venus, and the regulated will
all
pertain to virtuous and vicious
stemming from virtuous or vicious character
actions
that every reader of classical poetry
Aristotle,” for
knows
traits.
that there are
But he
said
more genres of
poetry than these three.
On
the crucial question of the
to offer
beyond
modes of imitation, Trissino had poems falling into each
a listing of the kinds of
gory. His three modes
show
Aristotle’s division already accepted
established: (i) elegies, odes, canzoni , ballades,
speaking in his
own
little
cate-
and
and so on show the poet
person; (2) comedies, tragedies, and eclogues are
dramatic representations; and (3) in heroic or epic poems the poet sometimes speaks himself and sometimes introduces characters speaking. Tris27
The Age
of Criticism 5
was unable
sino thus blithely cut the knot that Patrizi
For the
how
significant question of
to untie later.
a poet speaking in his
own
voice
could be said to imitate, Trissino had no real explanation, but clearly he considered stage representation as only one In
Book VI
common
of imitation.
Trissino stated that the heroic poet imitates
not by representation. In showing he found three
possibilities
mode
(3)
by
narrative,
imitations could be credible im-
lines of defense:
on the grounds
opinion, (2)
same thing, and
how
(i)
on the grounds of done the
that other poets have
on the grounds that these can present an exemplum
,
exemplum should be better than ordinary reality. Epic and romance writers both go beyond imitation of realistic traits, he afsince an
firmed, in order to provide exemplar Trissino thus did not conceive of imitation merely as a mirroring.
In his trail-blazing
more
commentary on
the Poetics Robortelli had
much
to say about the pleasures of imitating than of the kinds of imita-
tions.
He
did believe that a poet can rightfully be called an imitator
when he speaks in his own “What other end therefore to please
human
by means of
person. 7 In his introduction
of the poetic faculty do
we
when
said,
say exists than
representation, description, and imitation of
all
actions or emotions, of anything either animate or inanimate?”
he seems to be treating the concept of imitation cavalierly
broadly in making tion.”
he
He was
not,
cluded description terms,
it
found
in
it
a
term
parallel to “representation”
however, speaking loosely as
would seem
as
well as
and “descrip-
at this point, for
one of the kinds of imitation. In
8
he in-
this list of parallel
what can be covered by “repre-
that imitation applies particularly to
an epic poem, since dramatic imitation
is
sentation.”
Robortelli’s
found
most important contribution to mimetic theory can be under the general heading of
in his inclusion of “description”
imitation, for in his
commentary on
modes of
Aristotle’s classification of
imitation, he pointed out that the previous creators of Latin translations
of the text, Pazzi and Valla, had failed to understand the significance of
the verb enargein in literary criticism and had not associated
it
with the
“The meaning
is,
the poet
concept of enargeia. Robortelli’s statement imitates either
when
he shows
all
is:
as if acting
and manifestly or when
expressing those things the speech and actions of 5
6 7
Ibid., p. 96. Ibid., pp.
1
arte
13,
1
17.
Robortelli, In librum Aristotelis de
28
poetica
which
explicationes
1548), pp. 280-282. 8
Ibid., p. 2.
are imitated.” (Florentiae,
Modes
of Imitation
Not only
did he argue here that the concept of enargeia should be
identified
with Cicero’s evidentia
but
also in his use of the
words
exprimentes and evidenter he set the stage for the fuller treatment Beni
brought to the question sixty-five years
later 9 .
Robortelli was particularly concerned with the
be found in poems such acter like
Aeneid and Odyssey
Aeneas or Odysseus embarks upon
and in
tive
as the
his
mode
a
in
of imitation to
which
a char-
long retrospective narra-
narrative presents dialogue imitating the characters
introduced into the story, so that not only
is
the poet hidden but a
modes of imitation which the poet hands
character becomes imitator. In his classification of Robortelli consequently
over his whole
poem
made room
for a
mode
in
to a narrator other than himself. In his second class
he included poems narrated
by
the poet, including or not including
direct discourse of the characters. In the third class he included stage
representations, in totle,
which the poet professes nothing on his own. Arisfrom Plato’s Laws
Robortelli believed, took his classification
much
without
modification.
Vincenzo Maggi’s commentary on the Poetics, which appeared two years later than Robortelli’s but the differences of imitation
modes of poetic
ences of
was begun
among
imitation.
earlier,
put more
stress
upon
the various arts than on the differ-
Of particular interest is a protracted by means of rhythm. Maggi indi-
passage on the nature of imitation
rhythm as any kind of movement, not to was customary among later interpreters of Aristotle. In this way he could think of the metrical movements of a poetic line as a kind of imitation. Rhythm, he said, can imitate movement or anything that has motions by means of motions that bear corcated his willingness to define
limit
it
to dancing only as
respondent proportions to habits, actions, and emotions.
Working with
passages in Plato’s Timaeus, in Aristotle, and in Boethius, he developed
rhythm as the reducing of motions in us tempering by means of the imitated proportion. Into
the notion of the function of to a middle state, a this
context he brought a discussion of the rhythmical principles of con-
temporary
Italian poetry,
classical quantitative
pondering the effects of the changes from
rhythms to
stress
and building
his notions of Italian
metrics
upon what he could
him
Dante and Antonio da Tempo. In several of the Renaissance on metrics, it should be pointed out, the dependence of poetic
in
find immediately in Trissino
and through
treatises
meters upon dance steps was 9
Ibid.,
made
particularly evident, as
pp. 24-25. 29
would be
The Age true with us
if
we
customary meters “waltz” or “polka” or
called our
comments upon the
“rock-and-roll.” In his tions,
of Criticism
imitation of manners,
and actions by means of dancing, Maggi spent most of
defining mores , ethos pathos and so on. Like Robortelli, ,
,
his
emotime
Maggi was
especially concerned with the question of the pleasures of imitating. 10
Giovan Battista Pigna, less occupied with interpreting Aristotle, than were Robortelli and Maggi, produced statements about kinds of imitation that had some originality but no great value in an age largely dominated by Aristotelians. His classification of modes of imitation is not
clear.
The
three modes, he said, are: (i) imitating an object in the
in a different medium, as when a painter expresses a by means of colors and lines or a poet does it with words; (2) imitating qualities by like qualities, such as representing beautiful things by beautiful verses or ugly things by ugly verses; (3) imitating some-
same manner but horse
thing differing only in manner, as in the difference between epic poetry
and tragedy, both of which present poetic imitations of heroes. In tragedy characters are brought upon the stage speaking and acting,
how deeds are done and The more the total action is
while in epic poetry the poet narrates
presents
dialogues between the characters.
brought
before our eyes
( enargeia
but Pigna made no scholarly reference to
the rhetorical principle), the
Comedy and
tragedy
more
epic poetry can be said to imitate.
are, therefore, closer to real imitation,
poems recites dialogues, he by making his voice conform
but
when
the poet reading his
gives a lifelike rendition
of the character
to the character’s
ner. Since heroic verse has
man-
an unnatural ring in the mouths of most
characters, the writer of epic
poems should avoid
and should spend more time narrating.
It is
this
kind of imitating
for this reason that dramatic
fables are written in iambic verse since this verse
form
is
most
like prose
and, consequently, lifelike.
That Pigna thought of imitation as strict lifelikeness is shown also by opposing the demands of imitation and the marvelous in poetry.
his
Narrative poetry adds study and thought to imitation, and to reflect these additions poetry
must be more than
life size.
Exaggeration also
creates marvels for the sake of novelty. Since both marvels and imitation
are necessary in epic poetry, the poet
One
must compromise between them.
should be tempered by the other, Pigna
the same
way
10
as a
balance of humors
Vincenzo Maggi and Bartolommeo Lombardi, In Aristotelis librum de po3
°
is
etic a
much human body.
said, as in Virgil, in
necessary in the
communes
explanationes (Venetiis,
1550), pp. 42-49, 68-71.
Modes This need for compromise
parade of imitated speeches
is
by
the fact that a constant
boring, and, contrariwise, constant de-
and circumstances
character, dialogue imitation
character from another
11
It
.
problem of poetic imitation as
greater
is obfuscating, and the becomes tiresome. In the portrayal of manners or
scription of places, persons,
beauty that results
made
is
of Imitation
is
necessary in order to distinguish one
can be seen that Pigna’s handling of the as
is
much
practical application of theory
pure theory.
Sperone Speroni was even
a systematic literary theorist than
less
Pigna. His critical observations are scattered through so that
it is
easy to forget that he was one of the
first
many works
writers to give evi-
dence of close study of Aristotle’s Poetics. Even more importantly, Speroni was one of the
first
to use the ideas in the Poetics for other
purposes than simply to explain what Aristotle meant. In
his
Apologia
dei dialogic the long explanation of literary principles that he read to
the Inquisitors in
Rome
in order to clear himself of charges of
morality and unseemliness of behavior,
were
poetic imitation
made
all
im-
comments on the nature of Most of these comments
tangentially.
concerned dialogue writing rather than poetry, but Speroni strove to
how
consider dialogues as a genre of poetry. His argument reveals closely in the Renaissance the concept of imitation
was
tied to the
moral
question of the propriety of presenting evil as well as good characters, of showing the dramatic clash in the Oneness of true doctrine
Manyness
—the
At some dialogue in
opposed to presenting
same moral question
whom, by way
pervaded the works of Plato, from Fathers, the
as
that, in fact,
of the Church
Church had acquired its belligerent attitude toward poetry. length, Speroni made a distinction between the kind of which the author introduces himself as one of the characters
and peddles
— resembles epic poetry and history — and
doctrine to compliant interlocutors, as in Cicero
his
kind of dialogue, Speroni the kind of dialogue in
said,
which the author keeps himself hidden,
this
as in
Plato and Lucian, so that the characters decide questions in dramatic conflict, in is
comedy, for example. In the
to select only
what
is
notable and
first
kind, the aim of the author
worthy of
attention and to intro-
duce only ideas that do honor to the speaker. Although Speroni compared this
first
kind with epic poetry,
it
seerhs clear that he
tion. 11
This second kind, “being
Pigna, op.
cit.,
like
thought of
more exactly be called imitacomedy, which is a form of poetry,
the dramatic kind as something that could
pp. 15-16. 3i
The Age would,
like
return to
it,
its
of Criticism
share in poetic privileges.”
comedies
similarity to
comic and poetic matter without
.
.
A moment .
verse.”
later
he
“We
said:
imitation in the dialogue 12
The
is
implication was that
Cicero’s kind of dialogue can less easily be called poetry and therefore
can
less easily
be classed as imitation. Speroni did not, however, refuse
to call epic poetry imitation, for in his treatises
on Virgil he doubted
the possibility of calling Virgil’s Georgies an imitation, in contradistinction to the
Aeneid which, according to the firm tradition he followed, ,
was one.
certainly
He
things,
“Concerning the Aeneid
said:
although, in respect to
its
I
must explain that
by means of which
verses
it
imitates
characterizations of gods and men, the figures used in
its
the fables that in
poem and
many
places are scattered about in
it, it
it,
and
seems to be a
not because of these not a poem, in respect to the main fable
is
—which
is
There
no explanation of how he considered verse narrative
is
many
poem
the soul of a
imitation, but that he did so
—
it is
true history and nothing else.”
13
to be an
evident.
is
Benedetto Varchi, in one of
his
Lezzioni of 1553, gave a thumbnail if un-
sketch of a theory of imitation that followed Aristotle slavishly
To
critically.
Varchi,
meant “to represent.” Speroni
“to imitate”
stressed the constitution of the fable in his definition of poetry, but
Varchi stressed imitation. is
to imitate.
To
find
if
The
poet’s first
and principal
artifice,
he
said,
work is a poem you first see if it does you decide the best poet by deciding who imitators and all poems are imitations: epic,
a literary
or does not imitate. Similarly, imitates best. All poets are tragic, elegiac,
and
all
others.
The
three kinds and three kinds only.
differences
One
among
genres can be of
imitates either different things,
or with different things, or in a different manner. 14 If these doctrines of
Varchi’s were not Speroni’s, they were at least the doctrines that Varchi
imported into Florence from critics in the
his
contacts with the group of Aristotelian
Paduan Accademia degl’Infiammati, of which Speroni was
the central figure.
Alessandro Lionardi, a disciple of Speroni, presented in della inventione poetica (1554) conversations
his Dialogi
between Speroni and one
of the well-known Aristotelian philosophers of the generation preceding Speroni’s,
12
13
What
Sperone Speroni, “Apologia dei dia-
logi,” in
in
Marcantonio Genova.
Opere (Venezia,
Speroni,
Opere
,
II,
1740),
I,
275.
“Dialogo sopra Virgilio,” 200-201. 32
14
is
found
Benedetto
in Lionardi
Varchi,
renza, 1590), p. 580.
is
proto-
Lezzioni
(Fio-
Modes
dominated by rhetorical theory, but by a
largely
iVristotelianism,
of Imitation
rhetorical theory that had already been adjusted to the needs of poetry.
Invention, for instance,
was no longer the
orator’s searching out of the
facts
and figures to support
least,
the creation of about any kind of idea. Diligence and imitation
his case
but was, in poetic invention at
were the modes used by the poet
in arriving at knowledge through inshowed Speroni saying, is “following the effects of things and observing them well.” The poet has to know the nature of things in order to portray them and to create traits corresponding to them in respect to time and place. Speroni the Platonist then got off on the Platonic notion of speech as “an image and simulacrum of the mind.” Furthermore, he said Aristotle’s assertion that the fable, not verses, determines poetry shows that invention is more im-
vention. Imitation, Lionardi
portant than disposition and style, for in constructing his fable the poet’s
powers of inventing and imitating are
At
Genova,
a later point,
in
When
tested.
mere narrator
imitate, he should be called a
a writer does not
15 .
summarizing what Speroni had
said dur-
ing the previous day’s conversation, stated: “Poetry consists in imitation,
which
is
either of things or of persons,
and mind, in regard to their
A
and of
body
that pertains to
all
qualities, operations, conditions,
and
states.
poet should therefore studiously, diligently, and artfully represent
speech, actions, manners, and emotions, painting
with words
as a painter
that a historian as describing
is,
would with
like a poet,
colors.”
At
all as
this
well as he can
point Speroni said
an imitator since imitation can be defined
—supposing Speroni —one can see why,
anything or any action well (so that
and Lionardi’s Speroni to be one and the same person
on
in his later treatise
Aeneid
as
Virgil, he
had no trouble in thinking of the
an imitation). But Genova proceeded to distinctions between
poetry and history partly on the grounds that the poet does not simply is
concerned more
own
person than the
narrate everything as the historian does, “since he
with adornment and historian is.” 16
At
between imitation
less
with speaking in
still
later point,
troduces characters speaking he imitates, but voice
we
should
call the
said,
Alessandro Lionardi, Dialogi della inventione poetica (Venetia, 1554), pp. 1
when
he speaks in
kind of utterance “enunciation,” that
and simple narration. Plato, he 15
his
Genova explained his distinction and simple narration by saying that when a poet ina
divided imitations into
w lbid.,
pp. 50-51.
1-12.
33
his
own
is,
pure
two kinds
The Age (fantastic still
later
and
we
of Criticism
icastic?),
and Aristotle made the same
distinction. 17
But
learn that the three basic kinds of poetic imitation are the
the lyric, and the elegiac. Tragedy, comedy, and epic poetry are
satiric,
mixed forms. 18
Although G. to
P. Capriano, in his Della vera poetica (i 555),
make invention or
feigning of material a
seemed
more important earmark
of poetry than imitation in his general treatment of the subject, his treatise
opens with
a
chapter dealing with imitation. In
he
it
said: “All
comprehended by the intellect or can fall under one or another of the senses are in some mode or by some means imitable, the latter in the form in which the senses present them to us and the former not in the form in which they actually exist but in that in which we can imagine them when they are reduced to the senses, in
things that can either be
such instances
as angels, gods, spirits,
and
souls.
And
in this case, imita-
tion (leaving aside that other kind of imitation in things
by which
imitating themselves they attempt to perpetuate themselves)
representation of something things, since this imitation
is
simply a
by means of appearances, not
of true
not the appearance of the true but of the
feigned and simulated.” Capriano described imitative arts, one noble, the other ignoble.
two broad
The
statues
— of
smell,
and touch
sight
and hearing. The ignoble
—senses
classes of the
noble kind
nobler senses and more ample faculties
utilizes the
in
is
is
that
—poetry,
which
pictures,
arts are outlets for taste,
do not leave
that are ignoble because they
durable impressions, are by nature lower, and are incapable of convey-
They
ing teachings.
are
fit
“rather for the pleasure of the
for the proper delight of the mind.” Poetry art because
alone
it
the sensible.
It
is
is
body than
the supreme and absolute
fully capable of imitating
both the
follows that words are the best
intelligible
medium
and
of imitation,
give greater delight than other media, and can bear up under a variety of ornaments. Poetry
is
like
music in possessing rhythm or numbers. 19
Leaving aside for the time being the implications of these remarks
in
on the question whether philosophy or science in verse is imitation and therefore poetry, we can see that this broad approach to the definition of imitation not only leads to no real distinction between their bearing
the kind of imitation found in represented drama and that found in narrative poetry but even tion, if 17 18
indeed
it
Ibid., p. 76.
Ibid., pp. 79-80.
34
makes narrative poetry central
does not even
make
in the defini-
philosophic discourse central, since 19
Giovanni
Pietro
Capriano,
vera poetica (Vinegia, 1555),
sig.
Della
A3.
Modes
of Imitation
between words and the things the words imitate
the relationship
basis of the definition.
This
more Platonic than
is
showed, but Capriano was an important forerunner of such Segni, Patrizi,
is
the
Aristotelian, as Patrizi critics as
and Mazzoni.
was more concerned with the modes of
Pier Vettori, like Maggi,
mode
imitation found in the various arts than with distinctions of
within the art of
poetry alone. Relying upon what Athenaeus had said
about kinds of dances (thirteenth book of the Deipno sophists ), he tried to define imitation so that the kind of imitation used in
He was
be reflected in the definition.
dancing would
certain that epic, tragic, and
poetry could be said to imitate the mores and actions of men. cepted dancing as imitation but was
less
comic
He
ac-
certain that music could
properly be called imitative. Although he distinguished genres of poetry
according to the usual understanding of Aristotle’s division of mode, subject,
and instrument of imitation, he did
little
with
Vettori was
it.
very conscious of the notion that the concept of imitation should not be limited to direct or mirror transcriptions of reality but could apply to conventionalizations or correspondences in forms, filtered
projected
upon
a
medium,
as in
dancing or music.
He
through or
pointed out that
mores and actions can be imitated that dancers in their tated.
He
wished to substitute the term “imitated and expressed” for
any simple and the
word
in rhythms as well as emotions and movements can be said to reflect the thing imi-
literal
use of the
“imitation.” But although he gave
great latitude, he nevertheless doubted that elegies and lyric
poems could be
called
called imitations,
and he
it
word
poems
since he did not see
insisted that if
poetry
is
perforce
show
words or
they could be
to be called an imitation
must have characters doing things and not be
inactive or at leisure in
how
a static picture of
deeds. Dramatic poets, he said,
characters doing things, but the opportunity
other kinds of poets equally
is
men must
open to
20 .
Minturno brings us face to face with other problems. In dealing with Aristotle’s division of
men
poems according
to the subject matter imitated
the same as or better or worse than the
—Minturno was one of the
first
men we know
in
our age
to lead literary critics onto the stony
path followed by countless Neoclassical critics in the following two
mean the distinction to be opposed to low or vicious characters
centuries, for he asked if Aristotle did not
between princes and noblemen 20
Pier Vettori,
Commentarii
in
as pri-
mum librum Aristotelis de arte poetarum
(Florentiae,
1573), pp.
3,
18, 21.
35
5,
10,
13-14,
The Age
of Criticism
up three
usual lines in setting
He
parasites. 21
workmen, and
like farmers, shepherds,
followed more
poems: narrated, imitative, and
classes of
mixed. Since this classification was of poems, not of imitations,
would
it
seem that Minturno included tinder poetry many poems that were not imitations at his
all
either
or only partly imitations, but, in fact, he extended
concept of imitation to cover instances in which the poet can be said
to imitate himself speaking. Moreover, in the Latin
made
the point that imitation
De
poeta (1559), he not confined to dramatic poetry but is
is
any kind which by means of narration shows some surface aspect of the thing described. 22 Similarly, in Varte poetica (1564), he found
in
made by
speaking of the kind of imitation
said,
cannot say that he does not imitate
body or
poet addresses someone
a
leaves his character as poet
form of the
depicts well the
for in Petrarch
we 23
which does not
he makes
.
.
.
seem that he
it
and adopts or maintains another character,
can recognize two persons, one of the poet
narrates and the other of the lover
donna Laura.”
else,
we
“For
the passions of the mind, or reveals manners acceptably.
when
In fact,
who
lyric poets:
when
he directs
his
when he Ma-
speech to
His distinction between speech that imitates and that imitate thus rested either
on the notion of poetry’s
concreteness in depicting the particular surface of objective things or
on the
poet’s introduction of himself into his
with an individual’s dramatic subject matter that he
slant
toward or
poem
an individual
as
interest in the
nonconcrete
exposing. According to this distinction,
is
Long-
“The Psalm of Life” “The human soul is immortal,”
fellow could be considered to imitate himself in
when he
instead of saying nonconcretely,
said,
me not in mournful numbers/ Life is me involves us in the individuality of
“Tell
dream,” for the
Auden’s in
its
“Sir,
no man’s enemy
relation to the poet
It
by
its
the prayer
his
own
form used
is
dramatic
history and point of view, particu-
the use of “Sir” as a
should be clear from
faced one of
.
and to the abstract subject matter and implies
an individual speaker with larly illuminated
.
but an empty the speaker. In
all this
form of address for God.
that the theory of poetry as imitation
severest tests in the sixteenth-century criticism
question of whether
it
on the
could or could not embrace lyric poetry. In-
terpretations of imitation as “expression” or “description” could contain lyric poetry adequately. 21
Minturno,
Varte
Napoli, 1725), pp. 2-3.
36
Minturno was one of the
poetica
(1564;
however, to
first,
“Minturno, De poeta p. 48. 23 Varte poetica pp. 173— 175. ,
,
Modes
of Imitation
bring the question out into the open. In an age of Petrarchists, a theory of poetry excluding Petrarch
noted totle
that,
had
was doomed
to hard going.
Minturno
while Plato had called dithyrambic poems narrations, Aris-
them among
listed
imitations.
The
ancient grammarians, he
added, accounted for lyric poetry in the “mixed”
class.
In innumerable points of doctrine, Ludovico Castelvetro’s tary on Aristotle’s Poetics
development of
was
a
commen-
landmark or turning point
On
literary criticism in the sixteenth century.
had
ject of Aristotle’s classifications of kinds of imitation he
in the
the sub-
much
to
say that was subtle and important, even though here as elsewhere he infuriated his readers by his method as often as he enlightened them. The non- Aristotelians were angered by his close adherence to Aristotle’s
main
show
lines of
thought; the Aristotelians were angered
that in the
working out of the
by
his eagerness to
details Aristotle either
or did not say enough. His introduction to the subject Aristotelian; he said that the general
mode
of poetry
is
was wrong
was
strictly
imitation,
and
of imitations there are three genera: according to object, according to
medium, and according
more
differentia to
to manner.
show how
But he believed Aristotle needed
imitation in poetry corresponds to imita-
tion in painting and sculpture. Poetry, he said, its
object
medium
“men
as better
is
imitation having for
than they are, or worse, or as they are; for
language, rhythm, and harmony; and for
its
mode
its
narration
and drama.” His usual refinement upon Aristotle was not, however, long in following. Castelvetro said:
the
modes of poetry more
“And
precisely
yet Aristotle could have explained if
he had not used the example of
painting as his point of departure, and had used the following argument instead.
Poetry represents a possible action either by using words to
words and things to represent things, or by using words to words and things.” Castelvetro’s “words to represent words and things to represent things” is the imitation of life found in the stage presentation of dramatic poetry. “Words to represent both words and things” is narrative imitation. Castelvetro continued: “Of these two modes of representing an action, the first gives the more lifelike representation. We have an analogous phenomenon in painting, which reprerepresent
represent both
sents objects either
by
their natural colors or
by
light
and shade, the
second kind of representations being called by the Greeks
Monochromes, as regards their mode, are like narrative poetry, which uses only words to represent both words and things; and paintings in 37
The Age color, as regards their
of Criticism
mode
which
again, are like dramatic poetry,
uses
24
words to represent words, and things to represent things.” Genres of poetry should be determined by subject matter and by meter, Castelvetro said. He had a minor quarrel with Aristotle on this point, for he understood Aristotle to have said that kinds of poets are
determined by the kinds of subjects they treat rather than by diction or meter. Distinction on the basis of diction Castelvetro especially refused, since he claimed that a poet
not a poet
is
when
he uses nonpoetic diction.
Castelvetro carped at Aristotle also for not giving a precise
He
kinds of possible imitations.
list
of the
reasoned that since there are three ob-
worse), five media, and three modes,
jects of imitation (better, same,
even without compounding these Aristotle should have described eleven species of imitation.
By compounding them
he calculated that the largest
number of species would be ninety-five; but he decided that a number would be fifty-five species, since some of the items would not combine well with some of the others. He did not tell how he arrived at the number fifty-five. Addressing himself to questions that were creating more stir in his own day, he distinguished between modes of imitation in which speeches are summarized or paraphrased possible
more
realistic
and those with direct discourse and indirect imitation of the descriptive items of the situation. But
when
he came to constitute the three main
genres of poetic imitation, these idiosyncrasies did not prevent him from achieving a
that
list
he had defined in
was
in the
classes as narrative, dramatic, his similitudinary class
find
him saying
that
traditional. Instead of the
two kinds
poetry with painting, he
listed the
and similitudinary, without making clear
from the other two. When we the similitudinary kind uses words and things to
how
resemble words and things, fers
main
his paralleling
was
we
distinct
can be puzzled to determine
from the dramatic and can therefore be puzzled to
ing the Iliad as an example of the similitudinary kind. If to represent things” Castelvetro objects,
why
is
find
how him
by using
it
dif-
offer-
“things
meant that Homer gave descriptions of
the result not simply narrative? Furthermore, on the
same page Castelvetro claimed that one of the subclasses of the narrative
mode
actually belonged in the similitudinary category.
mode, he
said,
can be compared to chiaroscuro. In
“in expressing
words stored
in his
Andrew Bongiorno, “Castelvetro’s Commentary on the Poetics of Aris38
narrative
mode, the writer,
memory,” may follow one of
methods, two of which are direct and one 24
this
The
is
three
oblique:
totle” (unpublished thesis, Cornell
Uni-
versity, 1935), p. 31. See also pp. 22, 24.
Modes First direct kind
own
his
of Imitation
—the poet or the narrator used speaks throughout
in
person.
Oblique kind
—the action —the
Second direct kind verbatim.
It is this
is
presented in indirect discourse.
poet presents speeches of
characters
his
kind that belongs to the similitudinary category,
according to Castelvetro’s assertion. Aside from Castelvetro’s claim that the similitudinary kind uses words and things to resemble words and things, this is simply the usual 25 list of narrative, dramatic, and mixed kinds Tasso often followed the .
and sometimes
ideas of Castelvetro
objecting to them. But
all
clarified Castelvetro’s distinctions in
does not
come
clear
when Tasso
imitation should not be defined as a resemblance since
occur accidentally; imitation should be thought of
says that
some resemblances even
as a similitude
though only those similitudes that are intentionally created by study and
art should
tation
is
be called imitations. “I say,” remarked Tasso, “that imi-
and imitating
artful similitude,
and what does not
exist
the intention of resembling,
is
cannot be imitated or resembled.”
26
In Castel-
vetro’s interpretation of poetic imitation the outstanding feature latitude he gave to narrative, but he
than
many
of his contemporaries.
was
He
is
the
far less specific in this regard
argued that gnomic poetry could
legitimately be called poetry because wise sayings have affinities with
oracular sayings and so have something of the divine in sequently,
it
would seem
If Castelvetro’s basis
that for
him not
all
them
27
Con-
.
poetry was imitative.
of classification remains
somewhat confused, one his comments on the
can nevertheless feel the cogency of some of separate modes.
The
narrative
mode can be
subdivided, he said, in terms
of whether or not the poet slants his material.
viding
it is
Still
another
way
of di-
between universalized narrative and particu-
to distinguish
larized narrative. Universalized narrative concerns classes, species, or
wholes, whereas particularized narratives concern individuals or units.
This distinction would no doubt remain entirely unclear had Castelvetro not added that the Aeneid
is
a generalized narrative,
sey and Iliad are particularized. This distinction cal
one originating from distinctions of
Two, “Universal and
was primarily
style, as will
a rhetori-
be seen in Part
Particulars.”
In spite of the fact that
some of
Castelvetro’s
"’Ibid., pp. 87-97. 28
whereas the Odys-
Torquato Tasso, Del giadizio sovra
comments on
the nature
“ Gerusalemme di Torquato Tasso, Opere, XII, 302-303.
1
^Bongiorno, op.
cit ., p. 60.
39
in
The Age
of Criticism
mode have been
of the dramatic
cited as the first insistence
on the
unities of place
and time and hence the significant beginning of the
rigidities of the
Neoclassic attitudes toward drama and hence a prime
instance of his wrongheadedrifess, taken in context of the distinctions
between the narrative and the dramatic modes of
they seem to make rather good sense. said,
can move about
mode.
It
narrative
making of imitating,
dramatic mode, Castelvetro
time and space than can the narrative
less easily in
can represent only the
mode can more
The
and the audible, whereas the
visible
easily bring into play states of consciousness
and internal promptings. The dramatic mode
stirs
emotions more than
narrative but gives a simpler and less full-bodied account of the nature
of the events since some aspects of the action cannot be directly or fully
represented on a stage. This certain media such as
done
in
is
the kind of analysis of the limitations of
we make
today
when we
motion pictures that can be done only
in novels.
When Castelvetro said further that
sents actions as occurring in the time in
occur” and that for limited
by
this
decide what can be
less
well on the stage or
“the dramatic
mode
repre-
which they would naturally
comedy
reason the length of a
or tragedy
the comfort of the audience and “cannot represent
is
more
which it takes to what is simply imitative. The concept of poetic imitation held in the Renaissance was capable of extension to include expressive poems as well as poems that are content to mirror externals, but Castelvetro as well as some of the others was trapped by his own logic to assume that no special case had to be made for drama as direct imitation and that consequently the nature of drama was to imitate wholly and directly. For such reasons an expressive theater like that of Shakespeare came to be excluded from things than those
which can occur
present the drama,” he did,
it is
in the space of time
true, limit the
drama
to
—
—
the Neoclassic world.
On
the other hand, Castelvetro was led
to argue that the dramatic
mode must
by
the literalness of his
mind
present feigned or imaginary
events that could happen, presumably because
impossible to con-
it is
ceive of the staged event as an imitation of itself as a historical action.
Cicero delivering an oration of an oration delivered
is
not an imitation.
by Cicero would have
Castelvetro allowed the narrative
happened and what
is
in the
mode
to treat
A
stage presentation
to be imaginary.
But
both what has actually
realm of the possible; that
is
to say,
it
can
be either a rendition of actuality or a rendition of something feigned
which
is
made 4°
to look like actuality.
Who
can
tell
why
he did not see
Modes
of Imitation
the possibility of a stage rendering of actuality? But Castelvetro claimed
was due not to its tradition handed down by
that his restriction of the stage to imaginary actions inability to handle actual
happenings but to a
the Ancients. Passion plays are a violation of this principle.
Castelvetro gave
mode
metaphor later.
by
some
insight into the nature of his similitudinary
in asserting that the dramatic
The
is
to a simile
—
mode
to the similitudinary as a
is
remark Mazzoni was to repeat
a
similitudinary, Castelvetro continued,
narrative but
—a antiquity— and Heroides
is
works like Ovid’s supposedly written by famous women of
found separate and alone
series of letters
in
few years
a
usually accompanied
is
in
epigrams involving a speaker other than the poet.
Richardson’s Pamela or Clarissa he would no doubt have called similitudinary, or Browning’s dramatic monologues. the true similitudinary
He
said,
poem demands some words by
the scene for the simile
28 .
All in
all,
however, that
the author to set
Castelvetro claimed that there are
seven ways of representing speech: three simple and four compound. Precisely
cluded
what
among
these are he did not say, but they
his fifty-five
in-
kinds of imitation.
Although Castelvetro seemingly consented to imitation into three principal
the similitudinary
were probably
modes
— he did not,
—the
in his
imitation, patently indicate that
a division of poetic
dramatic, the narrative, and
main discussions of the modes of
narrative should be thought of as
all
Near the end of his commentary, in his discussion of Aristotle’s treatment of the modes of narrative in epic poetry, he showed more plainly his reluctance to consider as imitation narrative in which a poet speaks in his own person. The epic poet’s manner of introduc-
imitation.
ing characters to speak in direct discourse
but similitudinary, he
we
said.
When
is
words
have imitation (rassomigliare), but
not really representational
are represented with
we do
not have
this
resembling when words have to represent things. So he argued words cannot represent actions in some manner epic poetry imitation.
Following
this line
entation of characters
two modes, degree.
He
on
that is
if
not
is
truly imitative and that the other
the narrative and the similitudinary, are so only to a lesser
revealed his methods of defining in saying:
we
can say
instrument by means of which the action
is
that,
“Moreover,
comparatively, that
best imitated
imitative one, in contrast to those instruments Ibid.,
direct
of reasoning, he decided that only pres-
a stage
following this line of reasoning,
28
words
by means
is
the only
of which one
pp. 100-103. 4i
The Age imitates
less,
and that these
are not imitative;
from
is
which
in contrast to
they do not imitate of speech
was
this
latter in
comparison and
reasoning
we
in contrast to
it
can be secure in saying that
the only imitative instrument, in relation to dance and melody,
speech
it
of Criticism
is
can be called nonimitative instruments, since
it
as fully as
the most imitative mode,
also the
29
speech does.” it
Since the dramatic
follows that for Castelvetro
The same
only truly imitative one.
mode
relative principle he
applied to the distinctions between particularized and generalized narratives
He
and between biased and unbiased narratives.
more
the poet imitates
“For since
said:
fully in narrating the particularized material of
the action than the universalized,
it
follows that only the particularized
material of the action can be called imitable
we
if
consider
that Castelvetro considered
Homer more
alongside
it
The
of the universalized, which can be called nonimitable.”
result
was
an imitator than Virgil not
only because he introduced characters speaking more often and allotted
them longer speeches but
also because he particularized
more
in describ-
ing actions.
Even
poet an imitator, according to Castelvetro’s view, to
less is a
the extent that he introduces expository
comment upon
the material
supposedly being imitated. Castelvetro’s analysis was: “If the poet in that part of the epic in
which he
narrates only and recounts the action
and does not introduce characters speaking
not an imitator according
is
not a poet, what shall we say about which he neither narrates action nor introduces a character to speak but passes judgment on the things narrated, either blaming or praising them or deriving from them common utility or instructions about civil life or the good life? Surely no
to Aristotle a
and consequently
poet in that part of
other than that he
is
is
his epic in
not an imitator by reason of the mode, since he
—that any character among —or by reason of the material of the
does not introduce any character to speak those
who
intervene in the fable
fable, since that material
feeling of the poet
because of the
is
separate
toward the
mode
is,
from the
action.
Now
or of the material,
it
fable
if
he
is
and
arises
from the
not imitator either
follows that he
is
not
a
poet
any way.” By-products of adding judgments to narrative presentain Castelvetro’s view of things, were that we recognize the poet to be partisan and hence not to be trusted and that he makes him-
in
tions,
self hateful
to us
a certain pride 20
by adopting
a stance of superiority to us “in revealing
and confidence
in his
Castelvetro, Poetica d'Aristotele, pp.
42
own
544-545.
goodness
when
in putting
Modes aside the office of narrator
which was
of Imitation
rightfully his he takes
on the
office
of preacher and corrector of behavior out of reason, into which
error
Homer
never
falls
but Virgil on occasion does.” Since Castelvetro
broadly considered poetry an imitation of history,
it
was
characteristic
of him to apply the historian’s prohibition against bias to the poet.
Furthermore, since he believed that the pleasure of poetry comes
from our admiration for the poet’s artistry, there need be no surprise to find him advocating the writing of the more purely imitative largely
modes of poetry because he thought introducing characters to speak requires more skill and acuteness of wit than simple narration. Shall we say that Aristotle’s theory of imitation as it was described
by
was
Castelvetro
defined,
many
poems
that had passed as
and had even been thought of in the essence of poetry, if
from the
Most
territory.
relativists
With
ripe for Patrizi’s plucking?
kinds of
and defined
as imitations
the theory so
poems for
centuries
were denied participation
they were not indeed completely excluded
of the Aristotelians of Castelvetro’s time were
entities in
terms of centers of purity or intensity
with gradations receding into the periphery. But although Castelvetro
made some concessions to definitions of imitation based upon realization of particulars and upon creation of cognate structures, he did not compromise his literal conception enough to make it flexible. The result was that
Patrizi rejected
Another of the
entirely.
it
significant treatments of the range or
gamut of the
was that of the Florentine Agnolo Segni. His leading question, like that of Minturno, was whether or not the canzoni of Petrarch were true poems. He argued that we must take on
idea of poetic imitation
faith
and
as
axiomatic that the genus of poetry
this belief rests
on both the authority of
all
is
imitation,
inasmuch
as
major philosophers and
common
opinion. Since imitation extends to other arts than poetry, he
asked
we
if
could arrive at a sound answer about poetic imitation
merely by looking
most of
varieties
at its
his predecessors
in
poetry. This, Segni affirmed,
had held to be
possible, for
they believed
that poetic imitation had already been adequately defined: the poet u imitates when he in his narration speaks in another’s person and as
much
as possible
does everything to resemble him.” Segni thought these
predecessors believed that both Plato and Aristotle did not include a poet’s speaking in his this
was no doubt
right, since
it
own person among imitations, and
Plato’s
he responded:
and Aristotle’s view of mimesis, but
is
it
reduces the majestic expanse of poetry to a small ter43
The Age ritory?
According
of Criticism
to this traditional view,
wise and divine man, speaks in
when he shows
but
ing, then
on
this
poetry
is
own
his
a slave, a prostitute, a
revealed in
its
account.” If this view
lyric
made dithyrambic poetry out
is
many
who
is
a
not poetry,
is
a criminal speak-
and vaunted
glorified
correct, Segni continued,
is
poems
the poet,
madman, or
divinity and
have to stop calling Petrarch and
Dithyrambic and
“when
person the result
we
shall
other famous poets poets.
though Aristbtle
are not poetry, even
to be a species of poetry. So, he con-
cluded, this view of poetic imitation must be wrong.
Unlike
Patrizi,
Segni did not so
much
attack the theory of imita-
He
tion as the traditional interpretation of imitation. Aristotle’s theory
was derived from Plato and had
its full
show
Plato’s theory. Therefore, he decided that if he could
his point. It
images that
was
enough now
when
in
that Plato’s
traditional interpretation he
to Plato’s
view of the poet
terms must await the development of
idol
meaning
would have maker of idols or Segni turned. His explanation of poetic imitation on these
meaning went deeper than the
won
believed that
to note that Segni
as
this aspect of the theory. It
conceded that
he adopts the mask of someone
else,
a poet
that
is
is,
maker of an
a
“invests himself
with another’s person and speaks through him.” But he argued that poet can also make idols in speaking in
his
own
is
a
person.
Our problem in understanding Segni is one of separating from his whole system the particular aspects of his body of thought with which we are momentarily concerned. All imitation, he said, is done with some instrument: painters use figures and colors, sculptors sculpt, and dancers dance. Segni faced such questions as whether marble or chisel should
be called instrument of the sculptor and brush or design and color the instrument of the painter.
He
instrument of imitation,
say,
idol itself
— especially
I
voted against incidental is
tools:
“But the
either the material of the idol or the
the latter, because the idol
is
composed of its is composed with
form of the exemplar, and although it we do not mean instrument for the imitation but the Segni’s problem was complicated here by Aristotle’s having
material in the
an instrument, idol itself.”
distinguished between kinds of imitations
on the
basis of
both material
and instrument. Segni’s point was simply that the idol (which can be no more than words of any kind)
is
the instrument of the imitation
of the ideal exemplar and not the subject matter. In poetry the is
word
the instrument for the poet’s composing of the idol. This becomes
clear as Segni continues: “In this
manner
a thing
comes
in imitation j
44
Modes
of Imitation
to have three aspects: as instrument in respect to the artifice, as idol
and
in respect to the exemplar,
figure or
motion
—
also as
what
and
a figure in sculpture
it
is
in itself; that
motion
a
is,
in the dance.” 30
evident even from his handling of this one critical problem that
It is
Segni was one of the penetrating critical theorists of the sixteenth century. But his account of imitation as idol making had the one serious flaw, to be as
found among most
symbol, an imitation of
its
with Segni in mind, there
Platonists, that
any word became
in
it,
idea, and, as Patrizi objected, quite possibly
then no basis for distinguishing between
is
poetic imitation and other uses of speech. Segni tried to bypass this difficulty
without really resolving the oppositions by making the
dis-
He
said
tinction rest that,
on the difference between true and
false speech.
although Plato and Aristotle, caught in their
moment
of history,
had entertained the possibility of including dance and song
ments of poetry,
essential
its
disregarding
everyday,
into the true
and the
and Lucian are
instrument
Holy
names and words that are
effected
Segni
by means
we
call
by what
Plato,
speech
divided
true speech, Boccaccio
But
in false speech,
idols of true things, the
commonly known
is
summed up
is
as instru-
Now
idols of the
names according to both Plato and
Aristotle are forms of imitation.
is
Scripture
Concepts are imitations or
false speech.
things they stand for, so that
uses
clearly speech.
forms of speech,
practical
false.
is
which
likewise
communication
as fable.
his point in saying:
“Idols are therefore created
two ways, with
the false and with the true;
of speech in
the false ‘fable’ and the Greeks called
it
The
mythologia
kind of speech, he added, does not belong to poetry, for
this
true
is
the
province of history or science, the province of that which asserts what has happened or idols
with
what
is.
In consequence, the poet’s province
is
to
make
speech and with fables that are similar to the true
false
but not true. So Se^ni, in availing himself of standard Aristotelian tinctions in order to solve the relied heavily
Patrizi
upon
had Segni
in
the concept of fable, in a
mind
in setting
of the fable in order to knock It is
speaks in his 30
le
it
up
Agnolo
show how
own
Segni,
way
suggesting that
theory of imitation by means
a
down.
plain that in the distinction itself
Segni did not
dis-
problems of the instruments of imitation,
between true and
false
the poet can be called an imitator
person, or had not yet
Ragionamento sopra
shown how. For
1581), pp. 1-16.
cose pertinenti alia poetica (Fiorenza,
45
speech
when
he
this further
The Age
of Criticisvi
demonstration he needed a distinction between fabulous speech of ac-
which had
tion and fabulous speech of nonaction, both of
from true speech. Poetic
imitation, he said,
of images with false speech”; that
is, it is
to be distinct
“a particular composition
is
“mythology and
fable.”
Segni had another try at interpreting Aristotle and Plato in an
attempt to show that both believed that some imitators struments and some use themselves as instruments.
He
work with
found the
who
ence in instrument especially clear between the dancer
by using
who
in-
differ-
imitates
himself as imitative instrument and the painter or musician
uses instruments other than himself. Extending the dancer’s prin-
ciple,
the dancer does in imitating and in his
we find a bridge between what what the poet does when he imitates
Segni suggested that in orators
own
person, for orators often engage in incidental imitation.
Segni showed that the principle could be carried even further the real-life hypocrite as one
ment for
When
who borrows
his
own
person
by
citing
as instru-
imitation.
an actor or orator uses himself
as instrument,
Segni
said,
the imitator and the idol created are one and the same. This he believed
was the kind of imitation Plato outlined in the Sophist treating the sophist as the kind of imitator in whom two imitations are joined into one. The classification of modes of imitation that Segni arrived at with his complex argument was the standard one: a poet can narrate in his own person, introduce characters to speak, or mix the two modes. But his defense of the pure narrative mode demanded that the narrator be thought of as making an idol of himself. When a cast of characters is introduced to speak, as in Homer, the poet imitates with himself as instrument and idol together. The reader could well wish for more clarity when Segni tried to show that there is the same kind of imitation but slight difference in the use of instrument whenever a poet ,
speaks in his
own
person; but
of a full explanation.
He
what he
said that
gets
when
is
a brief statement instead
“the poet speaks in the
name
of the person he himself has introduced he then imitates with himself
and makes himself instrument and his
own name
idol of the exemplar;
and when
in
he imitates by means of himself, he imitates by himself
with different instruments. Plato says that when the poet speaks in another’s person he does to take our attention
the poet if
who
is
all
he can to make the poet not appear and
away from him,
the poet puts on the dress of 46
so that
we
can believe
it is
not
speaking but the one he has introduced and named. So
someone
else
and
in his
own
person
Modes
of Imitation
expresses the stranger and presents his appearance, in this case
own
he imitates with his
it
manifest that
is
person and in counterfeiting an-
other makes himself into an idol and an image of that other.”
who
putting on the dress of someone else applies to a poet
31
This
uses direct
discourse.
own voice, Segni repeated, is imitation He argued that when Plato said the poet
with
Narration in the poet’s a different instrument.
does
not imitate in narrating the doings of others he was obviously using the
term “imitation” in
means any kind of feigning of
false speech,
things can be of “immutable things, character
mind”
as
well as of actions.
a fable, since
argued that fable
a limited sense. Elsewhere, Segni
Thus
and the imitation of traits,
Petrarch’s poetry can be said to have
he conceives of himself
as a perfect lover to imitate
projects Laura as a lady of singular virtue.
The
was never
rendering of an ideal exemplar, the
was implicated here
as
much
as the
far
and
between
real situation
Petrarch and Laura was not what the imitation in the poems be. Since imitation to Segni
false
and passions of the
made
it
removed from the concrete problem of universality
critical
theory of imitation
32 .
False speech
or fable was for him speech that held up an image or icon for our
contemplation.
What
remains unclear
is
where the boundary
between abstract propositions expressed
line lies
as abstract propositions,
thus in the area of truth, and abstract propositions cast in the
and
form
of an idol because the poet as poet has a role to play in his utterance,
and thus operates
in the area of the false.
One can
see,
by keeping
in
mind how the Renaissance theorists justified the inclusion of lyric poems within imitations, that this doctrine was not unusual for the sixteenth century, both before and after Segni (especially in
and Mazzoni), but in Segni In including lyrics in disposing
To
his
among
imitations, Segni faced a serious
human
actions.
He saw
why
no reason
and thought cannot be subjects of imitation
way
Minturno
found subtle expression.
problem
of the further Aristotelian discrimination that poetry
an imitation of passions,
it
as
is
characters,
well as actions.
of thinking, Aristotle’s classification of the qualitative parts
of poetry into characters, passions, actions, and thought
( dianoia )
It seemed to him that Aristotle meant to refer only to dramatic imitations in specifying imitation of
implied the range of poetic imitations.
actions. Instead of conceiving that a poet treating himself as instru-
ment could make an action out of 31
Ibid.,
pp. 34-35.
his passions 82
or thoughts, Segni, to
Ibid., pp. 61-64.
47
The Age
whom
the
of Criticism
making of the
idol in false speech constituted imitation,
treated imitation of actions as only one of the parallel forms of imitation.
Although
poems have no
lyric
mores and human
action, he argued, but imitate
both Aristotle and Plato did make room
passions,
for lyric poetry in the province of poetry. Fable had to
the composition of a fake idol.
He
they
totle said that poets imitate things as as
mean
him
for
showed, further, that when Aristhey ought to be, or
are, as
they are said to be he made no restriction of imitation to actions.
Since Aristotle had set up in a series of preferences action, character,
and thought, he believed that Aristotle meant imitation of
was in
possible. In this
way
all
of these
Segni supported his contention that imitation
poetry consisted of the making of the
but verisimilar
false
idol.
Tasso’s aesthetic theory in general ran parallel to Segni’s, but con-
cerning matters pertaining to poetic imitation he was far
less explicit
than Segni, even though
his
it is
obvious that Patrizi created
Only
disputata with Tasso as his central antagonist.
an addendum to La deca disputata,
Gerusalemme
the quarrel over the
numbered by
is,
but Patrizi
liberata,
among
the contestants in that controversy
T rimer one,
the
strictly speaking, a
La deca
document in was usually
the leaders of
the opponents of Tasso. Tasso’s direct reply to Patrizi’s argument at the
end of Tasso’s
life
when
the
two of them, both
came
Rome
in
and
both near death, were cast together in a strange final friendship (Patrizi was buried in Tasso’s tomb) which indicated probably that they had more to share in their opposition in critical matters than they had in
common
with the
Tasso agreed, in
rest of the world. his
Del giudizio sovra
la
Gerusalemme
to Patrizi’s attempt to refute the theory of imitation, that possible to demonstrate with
any certainty what
Aristotle,
in response
was imor his comit
mentator Averroes, had meant by imitation. Tasso’s primary defense of Aristotle was a defense of the logic of equivocal definitions. protested: “I say then that
and some analogous,
some genera
are universal,
some
and of
as Patrizi himself affirms,
He
equivocal,
these, as
Am-
who
have
monius, Alexander of Aphrodisias, and other Peripatetics
explained the logic of Aristotle teach, the species participate equally in some, so that the genus
for another, or
first.”
is
not named any more for one species than
Such genera
are univocal, as in the classifications
of animals, for lions, horses, and elephants are
all
equally species, and
one no more than the others. In other genera, which are not truly equivocal, the genus 48
name
applies equally to
all
species but originated
Modes
of Imitation
with one species and then was extended to cover the others. Tasso said that the
genus “imitation”
that of the relativist.
of this kind. Thus, his position was
is
He meant
that the concept of imitation applies
most completely to dramatic or representative and was extended
originated,
by
tion used
later to narration
“which
epic poets,
own
poets always speak in their
midway
that point there
it
yet more imitation than the pure
is
narration of dithyrambic poets.” According to Tasso,
poets only
where
imitations,
and the kind of imitadithyrambic
But Tasso put dithyrambic
voice.
beyond
in the scale of imitations, for he said that
extension of the principle to any kind of writing
is
and speaking, since words (according to Plato
Phaednis) are
in the
symbols imitating their meanings, and, even further, the characters of letters
were formed by
imitation, as
Athenaeus indicated
in
Book
X
of the Deipno sophists?* Between Patrizi’s rationalism, to which a general
to
term seemed inappropriate
all
on
members of
its
and periphery choice
distinctions of centrality
both
sides
are battles
Even
were engaging
had relatively
poema
del
in
merely verbal
from the opposition between him and
,
he
flatly stated that all
well as sculpture, painting, and other
since
Patrizi,
Tasso
genera of poetry imitate,
arts,
and
and the painter can use the same subject matter
—the differentiation between the two
the thing imitated. Poetry, he said, In DelParte poetica
imitation
is
arts
is,
imitate the
cannot reside
made
kinds of
poems and
the early version of the Discorsi
,
Discorsi del
imitate are actions, its
its
modes
eroico , he
showed
pure narration
much with
as imitation that
35 .
36
But
in the Discorsi ,
33
Tasso, Del giudizio, in Opere, XII,
34
in
Tasso, Discorsi del
poema
eroico,
Tasso
the specific difficulties of conceiving
were worrying
his
contemporaries,
although, like Segni, he identified imitation with false speech.
300-301.
In the
that actions could include con-
templations, as “action of the intellect.”
did not involve himself
,
all
are narration and repre-
instruments are speech, song, and dance
poema
in
in verses, not
Tasso made clearer than he did in the revision that the things
sentation,
as
since the poet
that,
—that
same thing
.
difficult
to say about the kinds of imitation. In the Discorsi
little
eroico
in colors 34
is
battles. Nevertheless, these
being fought in literary criticism.
still
aside
did not apply clearly and distinctly
if it
group, and Tasso’s Aristotelian relativism based
35
He
Tasso, Discorsi delParte poetica
Opere, XII, 205. 30 See infra, pp. 74-75.
Opere, XII, 9-10.
49
re-
in
The Age marked:
“When
of Criticism
Aristotle says that poetry considers the universal
more
[than history], he teaches us in consequence the office of the other [the writer of history],
which
not to imitate, since imitation
but with the verisimilar.”
37
to narrate the particular, but this
is
is
not by
its
is
nature joined with the true
he added, that historians do on
It is true,
occasion imitate, or feign, orations, but in doing so they trespass upon the territory of the poet. Again, he said that poets pursue beauty in
two ways, by
narration and
tion; narration
lyric
poems
is
by
representation; both are forms of imita-
the province of epic poets
in creating his
38 .
Tasso largely ignored
theory of poetry, and most of
his
his
arguments
pertain primarily to epic poetry.
Since he needed to argue that heroic poets should base their fables
upon history, he chose to emphasize the poet’s need to select material upon which the form of a heroic poem can be best impressed. Instead of quoting Plotinus, whom he was obviously following, he cited the late Alexandrian Peripatetic Philoponus as saying that
it is
necessary
to consider not only the kind of subject but also the ability of the
matter to receive the forms.
Not only
material capable of receiving
all
but particularly
form of
it
does the poet have to select
ornament and perfection, Tasso
has to be able to receive the forms.
Wax
a seal better than either softer or harder materials.
ing statues marble imitation
is
is
better than
concerned,
verisimilitude
we
wood 39
by inventing
up
Here, so far
some of
as the
takes the
For maktheory of
about gaining
his scruples
actions as against gaining credence
ing the main action from history, fully face
.
are lost in
which
is
said,
by
tak-
not imitation. Tasso did not
to the problem.
Malatesta Porta, defender of Tasso but disciple generally of Afazzoni, deliberately confused imitation and invention, since for
him invention
and imitation were much the same. Since with Aristotle he believed that fable qualities of
the substance of poetry, he could say that the essential
is
poetry are to be found in the “mode and quality of inventing
and imitating.” According to Porta,
becomes
a writer dealing
a historian if he does not imitate
—
this
with human actions
means
does not invent. Although he said epic poetry, which
clearly is
if
he
narration,
from tragedy as imitation only in the mode and instrument of imitation, what he more specifically meant was that epic poetry should differs
be considered imitation because the poet mixes the speech of others 37
Discorsi del
poema
eroico in Opere,
39 39
XII, 23.
50
Ibid., p.
Ibid.,
17.
pp. 27-30.
Modes with
his narration in his
own
imitation and nonimitation.
40
voice; that
of Imitation is,
he creates a mixture of
Porta followed Mazzoni’s ideas on icastic
and fantastic imitation, especially because
this distinction
was important
to the question of the place of invention in poetry, but he overlooked,
or did not understand, Mazzoni’s subtler distinctions.
kinds of imitation he held himself
probe too Patrizi
down
questions of
to Tasso’s unwillingness to
far.
argued that Plato made imitation one of the specific varieties
made
of narration whereas Aristotle varieties of imitation
epic poetry that a poet
is
narration one of the specific
and that Aristotle never definitely affirmed that
borrowed from Plato the statement
imitation, since he
when
not an imitator
is
speaking in his
concluded that Plato’s meaning was unclear,
was primarily
we
choose
On
a
maker of
idols;
own
person. Patrizi
an imitator
in that to Plato
but Patrizi concluded that
should agree with Plato that imitation
is
we must
if
one form of
narration. 41
In the year following Patrizi’s difesa di
La deca
Dante appeared. In contrast
disputata, Mazzoni’s Della
to his classification of imitations
(dramatic-fantastic, dramatic-icastic, narrative-fantastic, and narrativeicastic),
already examined, and to his extensive and valuable
on imitation its
as idol
making and
comments
particularization, to be dealt
with
in
proper place, 42 Mazzoni had quite conventional things to say about
modes of poetic imitation. In this more conventional side of his nature, Mazzoni was, like Tasso, a relativist. There are, he said, three degrees of poetic imitation: (i) the dramatic, using no narrator; (2) the hybrid of dramatic and narrative
modes
as in epic poetry, less clearly imitative
than the dramatic; and (3) pure narration in the poet’s own person, a still tower degree of imitation although still to be called imitation, for otherwise Aristotle
would have been wrong
poetry imitative. 43 But Mazzoni wavered
as did
in calling
many
dithyrambic
of his contem-
poraries in regard to the nature of pure imitation.
Although he
poetic imitation a kind of class that can contain a
more and
partially reversed himself in the
was 40
Malatesta Porta,
sopra
dal'lnfarinato
Rossi, ovvero del
obbiezioni
Accademico
Gemsalemme
Tasso
II
alcune
in Tasso,
liberata di
Opere,
XX
fatte
41
Patrizi,
La deca
with
disputata, pp. 197—
198.
Crusca
42
Torquato
43
della
he
second volume of Della difesa (which
not, incidentally, published until 1688), in a passage dealing
Parere alia
called
a less,
See pp. 24-25 and 118-125. Mazzoni, Della difesa, I, 368-369.
(Pisa, 1828),
66-69. 5
1
The Age
of Criticism
whether or not a poet
imitating
is
when
he passes judgment upon
the events portrayed. Bulgarini had adopted Castelvetro’s position, to be Aristotle’s, in arguing that
believing
it
imitating
when he
Mazzoni answered
rative.
own it
voices, for
judgments
poems
his
own
said, that
voice,
an epic poet
when he
when
not imitating he can make
is
As
to classify as even a third-degree imitator?
he added, soon
he speaks for himself
affirmed that Piccolomini
after, that the
as
when he
was confused
of deeds and actions, not of words.
sists
not imitating
is
How then did he leave room for the maker of dithyrambic
44 .
this question,
when
that obviously epic poets often speak in their
they did not they would be dramatic poets. Although
if
must be granted, he
he speaks in
Dante was not properly
expressed his bias toward the characters of his nar-
can describe (that
is,
imitate) actions
what does not
poet
is
if
in
much
as
answer to an imitator
has a character speak, and he in insisting that imitation con-
The
historian,
and deeds.
Mazzoni argued,
What
the poet does
exist as if it did. Imitation of actions
is
imitation of external things, “but the imitation of a person speaking
is
is
to describe
an imitation of habits and the internal disposition revealed by means of
Mazzoni meant “words” by these “external signs,” how, with many of his contemporaries, he considered
external signs.”
and it
it is
plain
possible to say that a poet speaking in his
words
his
own
mean when he imitate?
the
What
two kinds
habits
and internal
own
dispositions; but
said that a poet speaking in his is
uncertain
is
person imitates with
what then did he
own
voice does not
where he drew a boundary line between two statements from being con-
of speech to keep the
tradictory.
Mazzoni then returned
to the question of the biased or partisan
writer whose passions color his portrayals or interfere with them. His point on this score was that the writer should not try to withhold his
judgment but should make
his
judgment
dispassionate.
A
poet should
man
of good will, but to be a man of good will he should be condemn the vicious and praise the virtuous. Poets, he claimed, must be even more judges of things than historians since they are under greater obligation to move their readers 45 What is to be seen in
be a
able to
.
tracing out Mazzoni’s line of thought
is
a crux never quite
to resolution in Renaissance aesthetics. Imitation
meant
brought
faithful rendi-
tion of the particulars, and finally full concretion implied recording
the nature of the perceiver as well as that of the thing perceived. 44
Ibid., II, 131-132.
52
45
Ibid., II,
140.
Modes But on the
of Imitation
level of abstract philosophic speech, bias
was
a distortion.
his
preliminary
arguments were more extensive than
Bulgarini’s
statement would indicate. His main thought was that a poet should present his narratives in such a
own mind
way
make up
that the reader can
He
about the significance of the actions.
his
consequently
thought Mazzoni was wrong for defending Dante’s speaking in
own
person and passing judgments upon his characters.
does
this,
he
said,
“the reader
is
When
his
a poet
deprived of the opportunity of reason-
ing about and judging the things narrated that the poet himself has
already judged, and
low opinion of
it
would seem
his reader’s wit,
that he
determine rightly by himself without
his aid.”
menting, the poet treats his material as asserted that of essay-like
all
shows that he has
poets Ariosto
if it
Furthermore, by com-
were
history. 46 Bulgarini
was the one who most provided
commentaries upon the significance of
his actions, especially
in the discourses preliminary to his cantos. Bulgarini
would be
liable to the
poetry
to praise
is
a rather
not thinking him likely to be able to
same charge were
and blame, not to
it
thought Petrarch
not that the function of lyric
imitate, so that the rule against
commentary should not be extended to Petrarch’s kind of poetry. Hieronymo Zoppio, one of the first writers to come to the defense of Dante and Mazzoni after the publication of Bulgarini’s Alcune con1583, retorted that Aristotle could not have rejected
siderazioni in
poetry in which poets were found speaking in their
he accepted lyric and elegiac poets
as poets.
He
own
voices since
remarked
that,
if
dialogue writers are truly, “as the learned say,” imitators, then Boethius
must be
a poet
and an imitator. Zoppio
also called attention to the fact
that Cicero had imitated himself in the Tusculan Disputations. This
usage of Cicero provided him the avenue to his
own
explanation, for
he did not want to stretch the concept of imitation to include poets speaking ex professo. Instead, in a manner like Minturno’s and Segni’s,
two selves, one which pair it is the poet Dante who imitates and the philosopher Dante who is imitated. 47 Zoppio repeated this notion in answering the question whether a poet can be said to imitate himself when he as poet passes judgment on the situation that he is he mulled over the possibility of splitting Dante into poet, one philosopher, of
445
Bellisario
Bulgarini,
Alcune
siderazioni sopraH discorso di
copo Mazzoni
(Siena,
1583),
con-
M. Giapp.
21,
47
Hieronymo Zoppio, Ragionamenti
in difesa di
Dante
et del Petrarca
logna, 1583), pp. 8-9.
24-25.
53
(Bo-
The Age imitating; that
he
is
is
of Criticism
which
to say, can he universalize about a situation in
supposedly a character? His dubious response was that the judg-
ment is made by the philosopher
self
and the imitation by the poet
Like Zoppio, Opazio Capponi objected to some of Bulgarini’s
self.
48
critical
doctrines. In his reply to Capponi, Bulgarini once again protested that
The
a poet should not imitate himself. like Segni,
subtle distinctions of writers
Mazzoni, or Zoppio apparently went over
his
head.
could comprehend only that a poet functions in a story either
He
as real-
actor or as narrator, not as an imitator of himself. Bulgarini then
life
added about
new
a
wrinkle to the problem in asserting that
his virtuous actions
that a poet’s account of his
and
if
the effect
own
happy for another
out his
critical
if
tells
about
actions can be taken as either true
as of truth the result will
is
reason, namely,
be called history,
of falsehoods the story will be patently incredible. 49
if
poet
he becomes guilty of vainglory or boasting. In
addition, his effects will not be
or false;
if a
he seems shameless to the reader and
his vicious actions
writings Bulgarini was to be
persistence, or stubbornness, in defending
Through-
commended more
for his
what he thought was the
Aristotelian position than for eagerness to think through the actual
problems that poets
He was
face.
a
man with
were, as he himself claimed, that he forced
blinders on. His virtues his
opponents to reveal
themselves fully in order to combat his arguments.
The
critical
war
was waged over Guarini’s here, for no one doubted that
that
need not detain us long,
11
a
pastor fido
tragicomedy
could be called an imitation. However, after a preamble in which he defined imitation broadly, Guarini presented his readers with a standard version of the
modes of
imitation.
Imitation,
he
said,
is
making
resemblance to truth. Everything in the world participates in one
a
way
or another in imitation, “commencing with the creation of the world
when
Maker produced it” in conformity with the divine mind ab eterno .” In creating man, the microcosm, God said, “Let man be made in our image and similitude.” Man has learned everything by imitation to live well, to gain happiness by trying to resemble God. When the sciences express the truth, they give imitations or pictures of what exists in the intellect, that is, of the forms of concepts by means of words. This was an iteration of the broad conthat Divine
Idea “in his
—
—
48 40
Ibid.,
pp. 52-53.
Bulgarini, Repliche alle risposte del
54
Sig.
Orazio Capponi (Siena, 158 5), pp.
73-74.
Modes
of Imitation
cept of imitation usually considered vaguely Platonic, although
form was
specific
Turning
its
distinctly Christian.
to the question of the species of poetic imitation, Guarini
explained that of the imitative arts only poetry uses speech and that the three species of poetic imitation derive
from the combining of
speech imitation with other kinds. His three kinds were: the poet does not intervene but represents actions in acters act out everything before
(2)
when
the poet narrates in his
(i)
which the char-
our eyes, not before our
own
when
intellects;
person and uses no “discourse”
and dithyrambic poetry; (3) when the poet mixes the dramatic and the narrative, as in epic poetry.
which
not
is
Homer,
own,
his
as in lyric
Virgil, Dante, Ariosto,
and Tasso were
all
users of this
mixed
form. Unlike some of his contemporaries, Guarini dismissed the notion that a dithyrambic or lyric poet can be considered an imitator to the
extent that he
on occasion introduces other speakers or because those
genres are capable of such introductions. This usage, he so rarely that
He
argued that lyric poets present
characters not in order to simulate the dramatic
in
use of the figure of prosopopoeia.
one ode of Horace’s in dialogue form but
did not
make Horace
The problem
occurs
should be considered merely accidental and not a
it
force materially affecting the species.
make
said,
a
He
mode but simply
to
allowed one exception
insisted that this aberration
dramatic poet. 50
of relating the ideas of the Pisan philosopher Fran-
cesco Buonamici to the history of the particular ideas being traced is
although Buonamici never strayed far from the Aris-
difficult, for,
totelian line, his Aristotelianism
was the expression of
a
profoundly
indoctrinated Peripatetic rather than a mere paraphrase of the Poetics.
He
had far more to say about the nature of imitation in general than
about the modes or varieties of poetic imitation. assertions
Poetry”
come
in his
—rather
second
— “On discourse
his
The
of his significant
the Essential Parts of
than in the third discourse, which
cerned with the question of imitation.
comes from
Many
is
directly con-
uniqueness of Buonamici
approaching the question of the essence of poetry from
the angle of the poet as “maker” rather than as “imitator.”
The
funda-
mental distinction for him was between “doing” and “making.” Singers
and dancers are “doers”; architects and poets' are “makers.” 50
G.
B.
Guarini,
poesia tragicomica
Compendio
della
d’ltalia,
LXI
(Bari,
1914), 220-222.
(1601), in Scrittori
55
The Age To
distinguish
separated
he
this,
from
it
of Criticism
poetry from some of the other arts that
we must
said,
(i) the creative arts,
merely use adornment
Buonamici
arts,
kosmetikai.
which make something new;
adorned,
is
A
he continued,
is
that
which
exists
do
arts:
(2) the arts that
use things already made; and (3) those by which something embellished, or beautified. This third kind is kosmetikai. classification,
To
think in terms of a three-part division of
different
between absolute
making (when an object such as a chair results from the work) and the kind of making which retains “some relation to a substantive thing, such
as painting, sculpture, music,
or dancing, since the
semblance of something.” Arts of
a
is
mimetic or imitative
arts.
this
Poetry, however,
them
in
not a pure mimetic art
is
but an art of a hybrid or complex kind. In terms of the tion, it creates in the
work
second kind are the true
first classifica-
invention of the fable and beautifies in dressing
the fable in verse; and in terms of the second classification
it
an
is
imitator, not absolute. “Poetry,” he said, “is therefore the art of fabling
which
in verse
Buonamici
creates and adorns and imitates the fact.”
revealed his interest in the current controversy over Dante in adding:
“Therefore, Dante, in writing in verse and fabling and in imitating,
is
necessarily a poet.”
As
good Aristotelian, Buonamici was a relativist, making distinctions on the basis of center and periphery, and claimed that his definition allowed leeway for poems to differ one from another. His central a
principle
is
in general
Not
all
that a poet should imitate and create fables in verse but
need conform only “more or
less” to this central principle.
kinds of whiteness, he said, are identical.
The
best poet
who conforms best to the central principle. 51 By relating poetry to painting, Buonamici showed how
is
the
one
of poetry differed from that of the other
arts.
The
the matter
architect, he said,
directly expresses his idea in building his house. In comparison, poets
and painters have double “ideas”: (1) the idea which, like the architect’s, finds its form in the created work and (2) the idea of the thing to
be represented, for the representing of which instruments are
required.
Thus poetry
represent to us, the
two ideas, one of the thing other the form and disposition that “has
give to the material, which, in fable that proceeds
my
opinion,
from the ordering of
it
wants to
it
means to
the constituting of the
is
its
parts,
and up to
point poetry does not differ from painting since the fable ^Francesco Buonamici, Discorsi poetici (Fiorenza, 56
is
1597), pp. 24-25.
this
like the
Modes and
design,
just as the design
a disposition of colors, so the fable
is
52 a disposition of the parts of the action.”
is
plot or structure
There was
critics
basing poetic imitation on the relation between the
and the raw-material mass of is
how
a vast literature
on the importance of fable — that —in poetry. We have encountered hints of doctrine
by the sixteenth-century
left is,
of Imitation
rarely connections
as the essential feature
real-life particulars.
composed
What
were made between the two
fable
surprising
is
ideas, imitation
of poetry and fable as the essential feature.
which the imitative arts were made to be one division of the “making” arts, the relation between fable, the thing made, and imitation, the limited kind of making, was closer than was generally the case. Although in his discourse which is directly concerned with imitation Buonamici based his definition of imitation upon some kind of In Buonamici’s system in
correspondence that
exists
between two things
—
a
broad definition
he extended the term to embrace the even broader concept of enargeia
he
as imitation. In imitation,
imitated; this thing
is
said,
there
first
has to be a thing to be
absolute and can exist without being imitated
or without an imitator. But an imitation cannot exist unless something is
imitated, just as a
name means nothing
Thus, imitation should be thought of
unless
it
names something.
as “a counterfeiting
and
before the eyes of the mind and of the head a thing that
something
like
by is
itself, it
as
else;
this
reference to exist the reader of a
Thus when
and cannot properly is
man sees the not know what he is
a stupid
picture of a hippopotamus on a canvas he will
This failure
which it poem must
nevertheless always refers us to something else of
an image.” For
at
held to be
is
and even though the imitating thing can stand
be able to identify the referent.
looking
a putting
treat the imitation as an imitation.
like the failure of the
man who, not knowing how
to
read, sees the shapes of the letters as things in themselves but does not see
what the shapes symbolize. Buonamici did
not, however,
demand
that the things imitated have real existence in the external world.
The
thing represented, he said, can be substantive either in nature or in the imagination. existing thing;
When
when
a
painter represents a man, he imitates an
he represents a chimera, he imitates an imagined
whence it would be no representation representing thing is given the same name as the thing repre-
one, “for otherwise there is
that the
sented and the picture 52
is
.
said to
.
.
be a chimera or a man, in
Ibid., p. 37.
57
much
the
The Age same way and
of Criticism
as colors are called
both what
spiritually in the eye, so that
exists materially in the wall
both wall and eye are
colored for the simple reason that the real either
form and quality
the same
as the spiritual,
and
is
said to be
or seems to be of
in fact the real
is
made
manifest to us through the spiritual.” In this process of imitation, the thing doing the representing
is
immediate, the thing represented
is
mediated. But Buonamici added, with Patrizi’s argument in mind, no doubt, that imitation should be thought of as an equivocal term. For instance, in painting
can apply either to a representation with colors
it
or to one with design. 53
Buonamici was concepts are
all
a latitudinarian in
between the imitation and the thing
relationship
he wanted excluded from poetry, at
arguing that colors, words, and
instruments the poet can use in achieving his desired
as poetry,
pure contemplation or speculation, he
by concepts tolerance
why
is
if
any use of concepts aiming ample room for imitation
left
human
the concepts concerned the
coupled with
his basic stress
he was not perturbed, as were
will. 54
upon enargeia
many
Although
imitated.
,
it
When
this
can be seen
of his contemporaries,
by
the necessity of distinguishing between narration and dramatic representation as imitations.
were the
The
questions he was most concerned about
relation of imitation to thought, the nature of the pleasure that
comes from imitating, and the overlap between imitating other writers and imitating the real world. Partial reference to the
arguments of Alessandro Guarini has
al-
ready been made. 55 In an academy lecture read in Mantua in 1599, Guarini the younger, following a line of reasoning that was substantially Segni’s, addressed himself directly to the question of
lyric
poem could be
said to be an imitation of
how
a
an action. Segni had
argued that lyrics are imitations but not imitations of action. 56 Alessandro Guarini
commenced
his
reasoning with the reminder that
many
great literati had affirmed that lyric poetry could not legitimately
be called poetry according to Aristotle’s definitions, since neither imitation nor action. But although he spent
showing that said to be
was
to
a lyric poet in imitating a
forming
show
a “fable,”
it
some
possesses effort in
sequence of passions could be
and hence an
action, his principal
aim
that the concept of imitation could be extended to cover
imitations of passions as well as actions. Guarini’s framing of the ques53 64
Ibid.,
pp. 40-41.
Ibid., pp. 50-51.
58
65
Supra,
50
See supra p. 49.
p. 20. ,
Modes tion differs
little
from
eighteenth century
who
as a passive, rather
of Imitation
Blackmore
that of Sir Richard
in the early
called attention to the possibility of using
than an active, hero. As
a stoic hero,
Job
Addison’s
was hardly a man of passion, but since he was things were done rather than a doer, his import for
Cato, of the same period, a character to
whom
literary criticism
was much the same.
Alessandro Guarini remarked that Aristotle’s failure to account fully for the kind of imitation to be found in lyric poetry can be explained
only by the incompleteness of the Poetics as to
the lacuna in Aristotle
fill
we
have
it
and added that
there can be an imitation of passions as well as of actions.
should be a kind showing “characters suffering since
human
affections are
no
how
incumbent upon us to show
it is
less
There
( pazienti ), so to speak,
imitable than
human
effects
and
which is the end of the art of poetry.” a good part of the kind of imitation to be of this kind: witness the passions of Dido in
imitable with that same delight
Actually, Guarini said,
found
in epic poetry
is
the Aeneid and in Ariosto (“the ,
new Homer
of our age”) the
many
examples of passages reflecting pathos rather than action. Guarini added: “I understand patient characters to be those who, while not
doing anything outwardly, suffer those passions in their minds of which the lyric poets in their poetic compositions undertake to create re-
semblances: anger,
joy, sorrow,
desperation,
love,
desire,
hope, fear, jealousy, disdain,
and any others similar to them. Elegies, odes,
epigrams, distichs, sestinas, canzoni madrigals, and sonnets are full of ,
such emotions.
When
poets express these passions and affections, do
they not succeed in imitating and feigning them in their most excellent
mode
of existence in a
these passions,
human mind? And while they
do they not form
invention of something that displayed in verses.”
But even
if
is
a lyric fable?
—a poetic fable being the
untrue but verisimilar, and verisimilarly
57
Guarini founded
passion and action as subjects for lyric poetry. Sonnets,
acting,
feign and imitate
he
upon the parallel between imitation, he left room for actions in his case
said, are also
capable of presenting characters
with the poet either representing himself
ing other characters to act. This
is
as acting or introduc-
the idea that his father had already
rejected, arguing that actions appear too rarely in lyric poetry to
be important. Guarini asked,
when 67
Is
not Laura a character introduced acting
in paradise she takes Petrarch
A. Guarini, op.
cit.,
by hand and
talks to
pp. 347-349.
59
him? The
The Age
of Criticism
greatest difficulty Guarini foresaw in this regard
was
in distinguishing
When
between descriptions of amorous passions and true
histories.
what we have
how do we
the difference
to deal with
not objective action,
is
tell
between feigned and true statement? Mazzoni had not Guarini’s answer was that, although
faced this question squarely.
amorous passions truly a
exist,
we
cannot for that reason suppose, that
poet cannot feign them. Guarini’s reliance upon the distinction be-
tween true and
false
speech
is
again reminiscent of Segni.
Paolo Beni’s In Aristotelis poeticam commentarii (1613), which on was a routine commentary following Aristotle’s text, was
the surface
in actuality
an exposition of one hundred of the chief
troversies of the sixteenth century.
critical
As might be expected,
con-
several of
these controversies dealt with problems connected with the theory of imitation. Certain resemblances existing lines
between
of attack have already been indicated.
length some of the controversies which are
58
Beni’s and Patrizi’s
But Beni
now
also treated at
the subject of concern.
Since his book served the dual purpose of reviewing current critical theories and interpreting Aristotle,
it
is
hard at times to distinguish
between comments serving one aim and those serving the
other. In
both, however, he directed his remarks to the main questions of
how
is to the definition of poetry and what employment of the concept in the various genres of poetry. Certainly, Beni said, however poetry is defined, there must be room in the definition for lyric poetry. In order to dissipate the confusion attending the whole problem of poetic imitation, Beni subdivided it into ten questions, some of them dealing with the interpretation of Aristotle and some with the burning issues of his own day: (1) Did Aristotle mean that the epic, tragic, comic, dithyrambic, auletic, and citharistic forms are genres of poetry or have a com-
central the concept of imitation
the variations are in the
mon
quality as imitations?
(2) If the auletic and citharistic forms are arts that are closely related to poetry,
why
did Aristotle not put in the same
related arts? Perhaps painting
list
other closely
and sculpture are more closely
lated to poetry than these as imitations, since painting
poetry and poetry (3) (4)
is
Supra, pp. 20-22.
60
mute
a speaking picture.
Why did Aristotle confuse poetry with music? Why did he parallel species of poetry and not the auletic and citharistic?
58
is
re-
the genus with
Modes
of Imitation
(6)
Why did he leave no room for lyric poetry? Why did he make imitation the essence of poetry?
(7)
What
(5)
mean by
did Aristotle
imitation? God’s creation
be an imitation, and nature to imitate God. In imitates
and imitators are
Aristotle called
Can we
(8)
uses of
all
identify the
who
all
words
this sense
is
said to
everyone
use words. Both Plato and
imitation.
dithyrambic poetry with lyric
ancient
poetry? Lyric poetry often seems not to imitate but to narrate like history
or philosophy or oratory. So,
(10) poetry are the same,
if
dithyrambic and lyric
was imitation only accidental with the
dithyrambic but necessary with comedy and tragedy?
Did the
(9)
auletic or citharistic
forms use imitation?
What
overlap existed between epic poetry and the mimes of Sophron and Xenarchus and the Socratic dialogues? Should
poems
dialogues be thought of as epic
Many
in prose?
of these questions, simple technicalities though they were
in the clarification of the
among
debated
meaning of
Aristotle’s text,
much
had been
the expositors of Aristotle, as Beni indicated. Beni
pointed out that Robortelli, Maggi, Vettori, and Castelvetro had
sumed
meant the
that Aristotle
auletic
and
citharistic to
all as-
be forms of
poetry and capable of imitation, but he chose to agree with Alessandro Piccolomini and Riccoboni,
Beni argued that
these
if
out speech and speech poetry, for classify
and
if
why
as the
distinguished
them from poetry.
were kinds of poems poetry could is
poetry can
poetry
who had
if
with-
exist
without words,
why
in
did the Peripatetics
product of the rational faculty using words,
did Plutarch call poetry a speaking picture?
called Tfiythologues
exist
one element not to be dispensed with
Why
are poets
they do not use words?
Beni acknowledged the fact that
it
is
hard to distinguish between
sung music and poetry, and he was troubled that Aristotle
in the
eighth book of the Politics seemed to treat poetry as one of the sub-
many ancient authors on the range of the showed how the words for “tragedy,” “comedy,”
divisions of music. Citing
species of music, he
and “epic” originally meant song; and he indicated that epic poems
were
originally
sung in public. But poetry to him meant words, not
music. So for him imitation in poetry meant something done with
words. In his thirteenth controversy, after asking
make mention of
why
Aristotle did not
certain obvious kinds of poetry such as epigrams, 61
The Age odes,
of Criticism
hymns, epithalamia,
satires,
eclogues, tragicomedies, and saints’
of auletic and citharistic forms and indicating his un-
lives instead
willingness to believe that Aristotle
meant
to refer to lyric poetry in his
references to the auletic and citharistic
arts,
Beni declared that
though Aristotle included prose works
like
the
Socratic
al-
dialogues
among poems he excluded works on history or physics from poetry by means of his stress upon fable, internal coherence, and imitation. Epigrams and short too
lyrics he perhaps excluded
both because they were
and so lacked beauty, since he determined beauty by
little
just
magnitude, and because they lacked fable and imitation, so that he
would have
called lyric poets versifiers, like Empedocles, and not poets. But Beni believed that Aristotle would have approved of a constant
new genres to respond to new social situations and had he lived in modern times would have commended the writing of saints’ lives and triumphs (like those of evolution of art forms and the invention of
Petrarch), provided they
made
use of imitation and fable. Although
Beni was often a timid formalist, he was consistently on the side of
He
the Moderns.
did not believe that Aristotle intended to confine
poetry to comedy, tragedy, epic poetry, and dithyrambs. Nor, whatever Aristotle meant, was Beni willing to go along with the notion
mere by which
that lyric poets should be called relativist
lightly
and
up
set
a scale
would be placed
in
He preferred to who used imitation
versifiers.
poets
be a only
secondary or tertiary ranks of poets but
not excluded completely. In doing
this,
he supposed that virtues to
— ornaments and excellences —could somehow compensate for lack of He
be found in what he called “poetic lights” of diction that
if
nonimitators are excluded completely from poetry, the
of poet It
imitation.
is
denied to too
many
said
name
writers of great fame and excellence.
should be observed, however, that in spite of these great concessions
to relativism, Beni
still
held to the belief that Aristotle had laid
down
general principles for the writing of poetry, even of kinds that had
not yet been invented, though he took those general principles loosely
enough
to
make room,
proved successful
in
one
way
or another, for
all
forms that had
in the practical test of influencing readers.
After showing that the term “imitation” could refer to almost any kind of analogue or proportion, to the relation between logos and
God, and nature and faculties
logos,
and concluding that some
have greater, and some
to the particular 62
less,
powers of
problem encountered
entities
or
imitating, Beni turned
in Aristotle, Plato,
and Plutarch
Modes
—whether
poets imitate
when they
of Ivtitation
own
speak in their
person in the
manner of the historical narrator. Beni felt that Plutarch did not distinguish between historical narration and imitation. As has been inBeni created a distinction between “simple” imitation, to
dicated,
include a poet’s narration in his
when
characters speak.
imitation.
As Beni
own
Complex
person, and “complex” imitation,
imitation
“dramatic” and “total”
is
interpreted him, Plato allowed imitation to consist
of the portraying of either kind. Dithyrambic, or lyric poetry,
by simple
tion
narration. Epic poetry contains
Aristotle, Beni said,
distinctions
some of each
seemed both to accept and to be unaware of
declaring that
in
imita-
is
kind.
Plato’s
Homer was imitating only when he when he spoke in his own voice. I cannot see why he is not inconsistent
presented characters speaking and not
He
added: “At the same time,
since
from the beginning he conceded imitation
ration.”
also to simple nar-
59
Beni was aware that Plato was every bit as inconsistent as Aristotle,
but he found stronger support in Plato for calling
imitators.
Unlike some of
his predecessors,
he failed to
all
poets
come
forth
with a clear theory of imitation because he refused to surrender anything.
He
tried to justify the inconsistencies in classical doctrine
by
allowing imitation to cover the whole range of “analogy” from imitating past masters of the art to the direct dramatic presentation of
“words and personae.” Thus he could say that the only imitation
was the dramatic even while he was stretching
real
kind of
his
concept
of dramatic imitation to include any kind of narration from which our
imaginations can derive the sense of a character present before us.
Although
his
declared intention was to
far less than Segni did he wrestle
for his interests
were
show
that lyric poets imitate,
with the actual problems involved,
in epic poetry, not in lyric. In his role of reviewer
of the many-sided critical activity of the century preceding him, he
encumbered himself with it
can be said that
many
virtues,
some negative
some
heatless complexities.
his interpretation of the
positive in thoroughness
Yet
in fairness to Beni,
theory of imitation has
and comprehensiveness,
make and in the weak answers Over more than two decades he waged a battle for
in the mistakes he did not
that he avoided.
the enlargement of the concept of poetry to include prose fiction
and other prose imitations. In
this
personal crusade he revealed
central to poetry he considered the mimetic concept to be. In 69
Beni, In Aristotelis poeticam covmientarii , pp. 46-63.
63
how
view of
The Age this stress
upon
of Criticism
imitation,
it is
significant to note that he consistently
strove to identify poetic imitation not with a naive holding to nature but
summed up
up
a mirror
with a sense of the voice of the individual character.
his
64
age accurately in stressing vivid concretion.
He
4
Were Empedocles and Lucretius poets?
AT
the heart of the speculating done
by
the Italian literary critics
of the late Renaissance on the nature of poetic imitation was the issue of whether or not poetry could legitimately be called imitation
when
the poet merely narrated his matter, summarized
upon
it
in his
the
own
it,
or discoursed
voice, instead of introducing characters
show from
the poet or
who would make
who would
steal
the reader forget the
presence of the poet. Following the clear but not entirely consistent leads of Plato
and
Aristotle,
they worked out interpretations of the
theory of imitation which generally implied gradations from a center of full dramatic representation shading off to
modes of expression
could be called imitative only secondarily or slightly. In
managed
to maintain subtle and important distinctions
this
way
that
they
between poetic
and other forms of discourse, to separate poetic modes from the modes of discourse used orators.
Among
by theologians, philosophers, natural scientists, and more advanced thinkers, from Robortelli to Segni,
the
Mazzoni, Buonamici, and Beni, imitation consisted of realizing the con-
was done by composing external particulars or whether abstract ideas were individualized by being passed through the particular temperament of the poet. These, however, were apex discriminations the vitality of which depended to a considerable degree on agreements reached in respect to several issues cutting tangentially across this central problem in cretion of a situation whether this
critical speculation.
Some
of these overlap so
much with 65
the central
The Age
of Criticism
problem that they cannot be reviewed
as
separate entities without
considerable retraveling of ground already covered. as the
Some
of them, such
between poetry and science and the question of
distinction
whether or not poetic imitations must be confined to human
action,
arose almost entirely out of the desire to explain Aristotle’s position fully.
Other
although likewise deriving from Aristotle or Plato,
issues,
assumed importance because answers were needed to explain variations not well covered in the Poetics.
in poetic practice
The
extension of
was one of
poetics to cover the aesthetics of prose fiction
these even
though the argument was based largely upon the interpretation of phrase or
two of
Aristotle’s, for the
a
aim was not so much to understand
Aristotle as to gain Aristotle’s authority in support of kinds of writing,
such
as the novella
and prose comedy, that the concept of poetry
as
highly ornamented verse did not account for. Here the central question
was reopened:
The
Is
imitation or verse the essential quality of poetry?
Renaissance theory of imitation cannot be fully understood with-
out involvement in these attendant questions. Aristotle said:
“Even
losophy in meter they in
common
if
still
a writer present
Homer and Empedocles
to
medicine or natural phi-
speak of him as a poet, yet there
is
nothing
except their meter; the one
is
justly called a poet, but the other should be called a natural philosopher
rather than a poet.” his substance, if
1
not
The
implication plainly was that the poet finds
his subject matter, in
and abstract discourse are
that imitation
what can be imitated and two different things. This
distinction of Aristotle’s has generally been thought of as a highly significant aspect of his theory of poetry;
one of the key aspects
it is
that ever since the revival of the Poetics during the Renaissance has
tended to separate Aristotelians and non-Aristotelians. ful in principle
faith of
way
many
most of the Renaissance
critics
were
However
faith-
to Aristotle, the
wormed their common argument that
of them wavered at this point, and they
out of their difficulty either by using their
more or less evident or by which they thought also to be Aristotle’s, that poetry should give profit and in order to give profit would have to
the essential quality of poetry can be relying on the belief,
deal with the subject matter of abstract learning.
The
great contest of
the century over Dante, culminating in the polemic between Mazzoni
and Bulgarini, was caused in large part by the unwillingness of the Aristotelians to accept the large quantity of abstract doctrine to be 1
Poetics 1447228. See Gilbert, op.
66
cit ., p. 70.
Empedocles and Lucretius found
Divine
in the
Comedy
.
Castelvetro, following, he believed, the
logic of Aristotle, assigned poetry the function of giving pleasure to
the uneducated classes, but in reasoning in this fashion Castelvetro
was
which
pas-
particularly at variance with his century, the majority of
wisdom of poetic utterance and could wisdom not somehow related to philosophic
sionately believed in the ultimate
not readily conceive of a concepts.
Tomitano’s great argument for poetry, in 1545, was that any excelmust be an intimate synthesis of eloquence and
lent kind of discourse
To
philosophy.
him, although poets should specialize in eloquence
and philosophers and the
poet was a philosopher
in abstract doctrine, the ideal
ideal philosopher a poet.
Aristotle’s distinction, for he
Tomitano
at this date
had one of the speakers
was aware of
in his dialogue
by verses or by imitation; were pronouncedly un-Aristotelian.
question whether poets are to be identified
but his sympathies on
this score
Both poets and
orators, he said, are
truth, the poet
by
concerned
“This imitation in the poet
tinued:
is
in their
by
imitating and the orator
ing.
The Count,
if this
consets
shadow follows the
an imitator of nature, a poet will obtain greater
is
grace and strength from studying nature.” This
Speroni explaining
with
study that he
a certain
himself of emulating nature, following her as a
body. Thus, since he
own way He
persuading.
why
Tomitano showing
is
and to reveal
a poet has to be learned
his learn-
another of the speakers, interrupts Speroni to ask
who
means that painters and sculptors
should, like poets, study philosophy.
Not
for the painter imitates with colors that
so,
likewise imitate nature
Speroni
which
is
made
to answer,
pertains to the eye only,
but the poet in using verses imitates that in nature which pertains to
He
the mind.
also said:
“Just as the
harmony of
the poet
is
known
more by the intellect than by the senses, its contrary, music, pleases the ear more than the mind.” 2 But Tomitano’s Count refused to be overwhelmed by these argu-
He poetry. He ments.
still
objected to the direct use of philosophic material in
found
fault
with Dante for being
fantastic articles of clothing
in interlarding philosophy
passages.
He
with alternating
and theology among
Bernardino Tomitano, Quattro
libri
this
della
who
stripes of satin
called attention to the fact that
Empedocles and Lucretius were of 3
like the tailor
created
and velvet
more purely poetic among ancient poets
his
kind and claimed that the lingua
thoscana
(Padova,
p. 86.
67
1570),
The Age
of Criticism
elucidation of arts does not belong to poets
—not medical matters
as in
Fracastoro’s Syphilis or agriculture as in Virgil’s Georgies or Columella’s verse treatise
be above
all
on gardening. Speroni agreed that
a
poet should
making and was under no obligation
excellent in verse
to
explain the subject matter of the arts but repeated that to achieve his effects he
had to be well indoctrinated in philosophy. 3
Turning from Tomitano
we
to Speroni himself,
find Speroni in
defense of his dialogues attempting to define poetry and oratory
his
knowledge, not knowledge
as imitations of as in
comedies
real prostitutes, parasites, ruffians, or
“Thus
saying:
itself,
young
lovers should
not appear but representatives that seem to be they but are not so also the doctrine is
which we
learn in
just
them [comedies and
.
.
.
dialogues]
not demonstrative science but a portrait of knowledge which re-
sembles
it.”
The
relationship
is
that of the
shadow
to the body, the
mirror to the image, or the thing in relation to the portrait. things like the natural sciences are completely
known
other things are
less
true knowledge. Process
logism
opinion
is is
less
true, for
what we
known and
Some
understood;
completely. Demonstrative knowledge
knowledge derived from the
opinion
is
generated from
find in dialogues; the effect
it.
is
dialectical syl-
This world of
persuasion through
is
eloquence and use of enthymemes and examples.
Quite possibly, Speroni, quisition in this
argument
(1) those
is
defending himself before the In-
in defense of his dialogues, did not
understood perfectly. His into three groups
who was
wish to be
classification of “cognitions or imitations”
not entirely
clear.
They
are as follows:
from things made by nature from which true knowledge
can be created, as Aristotle showed, by means of demonstrative syllogisms (2) those, as in Plato, Socrates,
and Xenophon, which use
give us probable opinions concerning our civil (3) that
found
in
Cicero’s kind of dialogue,
dialectic to
life
which persuades the
reader or listener
The enthymeme
of oratory, Speroni said,
effigy of the probable syllogism,
image of perfect demonstration, character
traits,
and the parrot
that rhetorical persuasion 3
Ibid., p. 92.
68
is
just as the
in
is
“a
more or
less
imperfect
and the probable syllogism
monkey
words. Should
a picture
it
is
of
man
is
an
in certain
not then be inferred
and imitation of opinion, and
Empedocles and Lucretius
And if And
opinion an imitation of science?
which derives from dialogue an image of images
play.
to imitate
difficulties since it
is
to play, opinion
oratorical persuasion
play also on account of
is
This argument presents as a
is
which
is 4
great uncertainty.”
its
seemingly concerns dialogues
form of oratory and not of poetry. But
it
was Speroni’s wont
to
minimize the differences between the two. Here he absolved the writer of poetry from
all
responsibility for the soundness of the ideas
he projects but defended the poet’s use of ideas. Speroni believed, in
most important ideas
fact, that the
deal
in
human
life
are those that merely
with probabilities, not with demonstrable
assigned this area of the probable to poets and orators. in the
and he
certainties,
true that
It is
“Dialogo sopra Virgilio” Speroni, following the more usual Aris-
totelian discriminations, used the principle of imitation as the criterion
among
poems the Bucolics were the most properly poetry since the Georgies were not imitations but direct instructions like the poems of Lucretius and Empedocles and since the Aeneid was more like history than like a poetic imitation 5 These concessions Speroni could make, but to him poetry had its own for poetry in deciding that
Virgil’s
.
kind of knowledge.
Varchi
said, briefly, that
Hesiod and Virgil were not poets
ing the cultivation of the earth retical Scaliger said,
basis of
“We
6 .
The much about
in teach-
historical-minded but untheo-
hear too
imitation being the
poetry in general,” and he divided poetry by subject matter
into religious
and philosophical poetry. The philosophical kind he
subdivided into (a) natural poetry, as in Empedocles and Lucretius,
and (b) moral and
political
poetry
7 .
Most poems he no doubt con-
signed to the “moral” category; the fact was, however, that this critic
whom
Northern Europeans exalted into the archwas in many key respects not Aristotelian at all, showing neither sympathy nor understanding of Aristotelian aesthetics. But Scaliger showed more clearly where he stood than did Ludovico Dolce, later generations of
Aristotelian
who
reflected Aristotle’s
all versifiers
judgment of Empedocles
in saying that not
are poets but confused the current issues
by adding, “for
beside the diversity of doctrines that this faculty requires, there
need of invention, arrangement, 4
Speroni, “Apologia dei dialogi,” in
Opere, 6
artifice,
I,
279-281.
and diction,”
all
of
0
Varchi, Lezzioni, p. 580.
7
Padelford, op.
cit.,
pp. 27,
Speroni, “Dialogo sopra Virgilio,” in
Opere,
II,
which
200-201.
69
16.
is
are
The Age necessary but hard to
of Criticism
come
by. 8 Vettori, to the contrary, followed
Empedocles and the poetry of
Aristotle closely in rejecting
specific
doctrine. 9 Bernardino Partenio, in addressing himself directly to the
problem of poetic imitation times had changed
in 1560, revealed to his readers
by showing how
how
the
the older concept of imitation as
imitation of one’s predecessors (the view presented in Partenio’s
first
two books through the mouth of the old master Trifon Gabriele) had given way to the newer Aristotelian concept, for the elucidation of which Partenio used Trissino as the spokesman. “He who does not imitate,” Partenio said, “should not be called a poet.” It
is
popular
usage only that mistakes the writing of verses for poetry; Aristotle
showed
Homer and
that
Virgil should be called poets,
Empedocles and
Lucretius philosophers, and Lucan a historian. But Partenio did not
allow Trissino to follow up
much
of reasoning. 10
this line
explored in Minturno,
who
Nor
is
the matter
took the straight Aristotelian
line.
Poets should imitate; Empedocles and Lucretius did not imitate; there-
Empedocles and Lucretius were not
fore,
poets.
Hesiod and the Virgil
of the Georgies were not poets “if the definition of poetry given
according to the opinion of Aristotle
is
true.” Minturno’s understand-
ing was that poets should not try to teach directly, and he decided that
Horace was not functioning
as a
poet in writing
poetry
his art of
in verse. 11
Had
he paid attention, the sixteenth-century reader could have
found a more complex explanation of the matter
in Capriano’s Della
vera poetic a (1555), the publication of which preceded the publication of Scaliger’s Poetices libri septem by six years. With a division of
on the mind and those of
imitations into those of senses operative
senses
operative only on the senses, reminiscent of Tomitano’s distinction,
and with truth,
a limiting of
poetry to the world of appearances and not of
Capriano was able to say that poetry could imitate anything,
either intellectual or sensible,
and to make room for a division of
poems
moral. Since poets deal with
things,
into
into
(
1
)
both of
natural and intellect
two groups:
(2 )
and of
(1) those
who
sense,
he
8
accidents
Ludovico Dolce,
I
of the senses”
quattro
libri delle
osservatione (Venetia, 1560), p. 189. 0 Vettori, op. cit., p. 16.
70
created
can divide poets
“have depicted and imitated natural
things with fictions, adumbrating and veiling
ances and
we
said,
all
(natural 10
them with the appearpoetry,
Bernardino
according to
Partenio,
Della
tione (Vinegia, 1560), p. 93. 11 Minturno, Uarte poetica, p.
imita-
4.
Empedocles and Lucretius Capriano, was anything apart from the sphere of moral behavior, in-
cluding the invisible and the eternal), and (2) those that represent
only human actions “for moral instruction and the use of Capriano
it
life.”
For
then followed that poets dealing .with the natural sciences
should as a matter of course be expert in their knowledge, “rising on the wings of intellect as an eagle, philosophizing about nature and the causes and effects of things.”
Such poets pry
into the innermost secrets
of things, into physics, astrology, theology. But Capriano did not so
much throw overboard
the concept of imitation as he conceived of
imitation as the conversion of doctrinal materials to poetry
of inventions and ornaments. Verse, he said,
is
by means
an important ingredient
from nature and brings great delight. The more mysterious would have in prose. Verse is a fitting accompaniment
in poetry because
it
is
abstract idea expressed in verse receives greater and
majesty than
it
for lofty subjects and gives emphasis to ideas. Capriano belonged to
the school, later led
by
Castelvetro, to
which
invention, the fiction,
and not imitation precisely, was the basic element in poetry. imitation, conceived as invention, gives us
is
What
the conjunction of sense
appearance and intellectual content, that conjunction in which deeper
meanings take on marvelous accidental sense forms.
The
perfect poem, Capriano said, has three essential parts: fiction,
imitation,
and
verse. Strangely
enough, he rejected Empedocles and
Lucretius as perfect poets not because they did not imitate but be-
what had said. In Capriano’s view, the trouble with Empedocles his fictions were only incidental, not dominant. The true fic-
cause they did not use fictions, and he asserted that this was Aristotle
was tion,
that
said Capriano,
whole poem “fiction”
an is
idea.
as
its
“should be diffused universally throughout the soul,”
and thus he revealed that he identified
with mythos and meant poetry to be
myth
a
A
poet whose fiction
poem
is
like a painter
not universally diffused throughout
his
does not create a consistent and completed work. that
Lucan
in describing the
he did not fictionalize
Some
or story about
But the myth or story must be created.
war
It
who
follows from this
Thessaly did not imitate because
in
12 .
of Castelvetro’s ideas about the use of special doctrines in
poetry have already been dealt with
13 ,
or, rather, his ideas
here are so
mixed with other ideas that separation is impossible. His plain intention was to agree with Aristotle that no art or science is fit subject matter 12
Capriano, op.
cit.,
sig.
Bl.
13
Supra, pp. 37-43. 7
*
The Age
of Criticism
for poetry. Castelvetro remarked that Aristotle’s insistence on this point
had perplexed the literary minds of poet to
many good
his
time since
it
some
writers and encouraged
refused the
critics to reject Aris-
important point
totle entirely. Since Castelvetro stressed invention, the
him was
for
that a poet
not doing anything original
is
his
he uses
subsequent assertion that poets dealing with
philosophic or scientific subject matter
but not good poets, for
scientists
when
This belief of Castelvetro’s squares
scientific or philosophic materials.
only partly with
name of
if
may
be good philosophers or
a poet
is
a
good philosopher or
he presumably has an original over-all comprehension of
scientist
material. Castelvetro resolved this dubiety
by
his
resorting to the belief that
the poet’s function, unlike the philosopher’s or scientist’s,
is
to “imitate
faithfully the fortuitous events of the world,” to give delight
by means
of imitations, and to leave the discovery of truth to philosophers and
The poet should stay in his own province and benefit men in his own way 14 Finally, however, Castelvetro made
scientists.
light
.
He
the principle of gradation.
Empedocles was scientific
use of
claimed Aristotle did not say that
a poet. Instead, Castelvetro
argued that the
poet could be said to bear “some of the outward marks of the
poet, just as a to bear
no way
in
or de-
wolf
in sheep’s clothing remains a
some resemblance
a concession!
He
to a sheep.” This
felt that Cicero,
is
wolf but could be
not, to be sure,
said
much
of
Horace, and Quintilian proved that
they did not understand Aristotle by calling Empedocles a good poet.
The
Renaissance critics consistently refused to believe that the text of
Aristotle’s Poetics
was not
available to
all classical
writers.
words into the false and the true was a way of distinguishing between what a poet does and what a philosopher or natural scientist does. He was the Segni’s division of the idols that can be created
Renaissance critic above
all
who
as
the use of
sufficiently enlarged the
fable or mythologia to enable a distinction
and Empedocles
by
concept of
between Empedocles
as
poet
nonpoet. But Patrizi, in spite of his attack on the
theory of imitation, clearly showed both what the province of poetry should be and
why Empedocles
amused
commentators on the Poetics had made
that the
Aristotle’s assertion that
could be called a poet. Patrizi was
Empedocles was
a big fuss
a natural scientist
sertion which, he said, had led to the cruel banishment of poets:
—an
many
,
Bongiorno, op. 72
cit.,
pp. 55-56.
his
Urania Fracastoro for ,
as-
great
Hesiod, Aratus, Nicander, Lucretius, Varro, Virgil for
Georgies Serenus, Manilius, Pontano for 14
about
his his
Empedocles and Lucretius Syphilis.
He
was based upon two concepts of both of which were unclear: (i) “that no science or art can
Aristotle’s,
claimed
this rejection
be suitable material for poetry, nor should one verses,”
make
explanations in
and (2) “that the history of things that have happened cannot
provide suitable material for poetry.” These
beliefs, Patrizi asserted,
are contrary to the general opinion of the greatest writers of
and to the
common
he shifted
his
all
time
practice of poets. But then, following Castelvetro,
argument
show
to
that Aristotle did not really say that
Empedocles was no poet and quoted Castelvetro’s saying that in sheep’s clothing possesses
vetro had asserted, as
if
some
qualities of a sheep.
anticipating Patrizi’s
Where
argument (the
fact
a
wolf
Castelis
that
they were probably both responding to typical academic briefs), that Cicero, Horace, and Quintilian revealed ignorance of Aristotle in call-
ing Empedocles a good poet, Patrizi argued that he was a good poet
because these eminent judges had called him one.
on
Patrizi’s attack
Aristotle here
use of authority, but he
proceeded with consistent, casions.
less
was one of
his outbursts against the
was not beyond complaining
than
full logical
that Aristotle had
demonstration and had been in-
having called Empedocles a poet on three separate oc-
Descending to
Aristotle’s system,
by which
entities are
termined by form, not matter, Patrizi tried to show that verse
deis
at
form of poetry, while still keeping in reserve his more many poems had become famous without having a narrative fable which made them imitations. Patrizi’s central argument was, however, that Empedocles was a true poet because he had a reputation in antiquity as a mythmaker, and he had a reputation as a mythmaker because there were many mysteries in his poetry. Thus, to Patrizi, mythology should be equated principally with mysteries. He based his case on stray passages and scraps of references for which there were no extant texts, making allusion to the exposition by Heraclides of Pontus of the natural mysteries expressed by Homer, and on discussions in Porphyry, Syrianus, and Proclus of Homer’s handling of divine mysteries. He believed that the expression
least the external
important argument that
of mysteries implied the use of allegory, and he based his defense of
Empedocles poetry.
The
as a
of poetry based tion based
poet on
his liberal use
issue as Patrizi
upon
saw
it
of allegorical meanings in his
was between the Platonic conception
upon the use of allegory and the the imitation of an action.
He
Aristotelian concep-
thought he was arguing
directly with Castelvetro and Tasso in saving: “But
if
the generality of 73
The Age
of Criticism
the opinions obtains that although the fables of
Homer are not who know,
for hidden meanings while, in the opinion of those
a veil
those
of Empedocles do contain allegories, without which neither they nor the fabric of the world nor the
and
if
allegory
works of nature can be
all
many
one of the four characteristics
is
attribute to great poets,
at
understood, [cf.
Empedocles has great merit and was
Dante]
a greater
poet than Homer.” In argument aimed particularly at Tasso, Patrizi turned to a picayune belittling of
Homer
more important
in
an attempt to show that Empedocles handled the
Homer’s
material.
was not good; he
fable
filled
his
events with acts unseemly in gods and heroes; he allowed Achilles to
be a rebel against heroic dignity.
his rightful lord;
What
is
the Odyssey but
petty noblemen of the barren great epic? events.
There
Who
is
there
much
isle
is
much low
two
jaunts
little
made by two
of Ithaca, an insignificant locale for a
and eating
talk
action instead of
can say that such material
is
Odyssey but few
in the
any better for poetry than
Empedocles? Then turning directly to Castelvetro’s three
that of
charges against Empedocles
—
(
i
)
that poets are inventors but cannot
invent the arts and sciences, (2) that speculating belongs to philosophers,
and
( 3 )
that poets should please the rude multitude,
of being pleased
by
which
the teachings of the arts and sciences
is
incapable
—Patrizi did
15
Thus was constituted his defense of Empedocles. Others, as he knew, were uneasy about Aristotle’s exclusion of scientific doctrine from poetry, but no one in the sixteenth century attacked Aristotle’s concept more vigorously. Patrizi made clear that he was prepared to defend Dante’s use of not argue but
flatly stated that all this
was
false.
doctrinal matter.
Inasmuch Patrizi’s
as Tasso’s revised
La deca
Discourses on the Heroic
On
the
followed
make
ground that
Aristotle’s con-
,
sions to Patrizi’s kind of argument.
Poem
certain conces-
disputata he had opportunity to
cept of poetic action could be understood broadly, he allowed that
Empedocles could be admitted
as a heroic
poet (although he
cluded Lucretius on the extraneous principle that times heretical), for “if sity
be
many
and since is
all
Patrizi,
La deca 74
disputata
.
the action of the intellect.”
Tasso could conceive even of 15
many
in this equivocal genus, as Simplicius said is
still
ex-
were some-
actions can be imitated, there will of neces-
species of poetry since there are
contemplation, which
his ideas
.
kinds of actions .
the
With
first
species
this latitude
dialectical progression as action; he said
pp. 137-156.
Empedocles and Lucretius some of his contemporaries were defending Dante’s Divine Comedy as a poem on the basis of its having a contemplation as its subject, an action in which Dante’s journey through hell and purgatory projects a that
“speculation of his intellect.” Tasso to
Mazzoni since he proceeded
view that the Divine Comedy found Bulgarini’s explanation
made
clear that his reference
was
to defend this position against Bulgarini’s is
merely the
retelling of a dream.
distasteful for he
Tasso
thought that an imitation
removed from reality instead even though he had to contend with
of a dream must of necessity be four times of the usual Platonic three times, the authority of Synesius, in
dreams “and that
end
as
it is
who had
believed that fables have their origin
not unfitting for poems to have dreams
vetro that Aristotle meant to treat Empedocles as a poet of rather than no poet at
ing that
if
other poets
all.
He
Empedocles was
who
followed through with a poet so
divine actions
is
low degree
his logic
by
assert-
were Lucretius, Pontano, and we would have to
had written about nature, and
suppose that the definition of poetry as the imitation of
human and
incomplete. But Tasso preferred to think of a con-
templative action as a
human
With Tasso one can never were mere facades for
his
action tell
16 .
how
often the theoretical projections
defense of poems with verisimilar historical
actions. Mazzoni’s preference for fantastic left
as their
well as their beginning.” In the main Tasso agreed with Castel-
the door open to
poetry bothered him since
making Ariosto’s kind of romance
it
central in a
definition of poetry. Tasso preferred to extend the concept of imitation to cover the conception of poetry as a
form of
logic capable
on oc-
casion of using logical demonstrations (as in Empedocles, Lucretius,
and Dante) rather than to This
to say that for
is
imitation
let
poetry be an imitation of wild
fantasies.
him probability was more important than
17 .
In the critical writings of Camillo Pellegrino, as in those of most of
war over Tasso’s Gerusalemme liberata, concerning the theory of imitation was whether
the participants in the critical the principal issue
poetic imitation should be defined in terms of invention or invention
should be made central in the definition of poetry and not imitation. Although Pellegrino approached his question in such a way that his opponent Salviati rightly understood him to mean that imitation and not verse makes the poet, Pellegrino let Attendolo, his chief speaker in 16
in
Tasso, Discorsi del
Opere
,
XII, 10-1
poema
eroico,
17
Ibid., p. 35.
1.
75
The Age his
show
dialogue,
of Criticism
himself unwilling to agree wholeheartedly with
either side. Lucretius, Lucan,
make proper choice
granted, did not
and imitation, but he
fables
and Virgil
like Tasso, Pellegrino
in the
Georgies Attendolo ,
of subject matter in not using
wa's reluctant to call
them not
was concerned about the wrong
uses of historical
subject matter rather than of philosophical subject matter
As
whole question came
has been said, this
at the
by Mazzoni
knowledge of
his
theory of imitation
18 .
to a head in the quarrels
end of the century over the place of Dante
stand the position adopted
But
poets.
as a poet.
To
under-
necessary to garner some
it is
whole from other places
as a
in
study. In defending Dante’s use of philosophical materials, he
this
neither surrendered the theory of imitation nor gave in entirely to the
He
enough fashion in claiming that Aristotle did not say that Empedocles was not a poet but said he was more a physicist than a poet, in a kind of statement in which the latitudinarians.
started out in an ordinary
use of a comparative presupposes the existence of the positive.
He
also
entertained the notion that Aristotle could have meant that Empedocles
did
wrong not
scientist
in treating scientific matters
would, not
treat materials,
as a
poet would
Mazzoni was
19 .
but in treating them
how
In deciding
close to Segni
a
and elaborated Segni’s
while basing his arguments upon Plato’s distinction between fantastic imitation. Since, according to tation, the
important distinction
fidelity to truth
purposes.
Thus
tastic imitation,
own
is
Mazzoni,
poetry, no matter
which
to
use of words
and imi-
is
false deliberately for its
how
Mazzoni meant
sake. Consequently, the
ideas,
icastic
between imitation that pretends
and that which uses the all
all
as a
poet should
to
own
verisimilar, should be fan-
practically imitation for
important question in Mazzoni’s
its
critical
system was hove a poet uses doctrinal materials, not whether or not he uses them.
The
following passage
theorizing in the Renaissance, I
say then that everyone
who
in a certain sense an idol
similitude and an
if
is
one of the high points of
not of
all
critical
time.
mirrors some true concept with words creates
by means
of speaking, since every concept
image of the thing that corresponds to
in particular, in the opinion of
both Plato and Aristotle,
it,
and names
like idols
is
a
are,
and imita-
tions of things; so that not only the historian but also the natural philosopher
and every other man of
arts
who
in teaching
something reveals the truth
creates something like an idol with his speech and imitates things with con18
Camillo Pellegrino, II Caraffa in Tasso, Opere, XVIII (Pisa, 1828), 65. 76
19
Mazzoni, Della
difesa,
I,
51.
Empedocles and Lucretius cepts and with names. But
of the sciences and arts
who might
still
say that the speech in histories and that
would not be poetic
imitation and that the poet
deal with either history or science or arts
we
of poetic imitation that
we must
stand this,
would have the kind
we
in respect to itself than to represent
and perfect
idols, since
arts,
idols
by means
and of history
they are not made solely for represent-
and whoever teaches what
degree that they are
we
can say
forms
true, although he
form them to the idols; that is, he does not establish them to the end represent or resemble something but goes beyond
that point to another
mode and
order of objective, that
is,
of wanting to
some
the truth of the things that have happened or of wanting to teach
doctrine.
But the imitator creates the perfect
that
an
it is
insofar as
it
who
(as Plato
takes history as the subject for his
differ in this respect, that the historian will
memory
the purpose of leaving behind a
write about
them
in
them
in order to imitate
the respect that
it
is
will be constrained to write about
historian
and to adorn
his
a
and recognized by anyone
who
to leave behind a
them with
reads his
will
recount the things done for
simulacrum.
writing with
poem
idol
that
of the truth, but the poet will
them and
many
colors so that the simulacrum he wishes to
It
idol, the idol in the respect
showed in the Sophist) the represents or resembles the other. So we can conclude which means
idol,
the historian and the poet
of
is
of his concepts and words, does not
only of wishing to
tell
that
is
and resemble.
ing but for teaching and for discovering the truth of things. So that the historian,
under-
have said above) that the idol
consequently, the concepts of philosophy, of the
are not true
To
have earlier called “similitudinary.”
realize (as
which has no other use
And
I
And
simulacrum
indeed the poet
greater diligence than the
lights
and with many poetic
form may be
better envisioned
poem 20 .
followed for Mazzoni that the truth-seeking philosopher or histo-
rian seeks profit primarily
whereas the poet seeks delight. In
treatments of the function of poetry he built a
much
his
longer
stronger case
than this for profit as the end for poetry, even though from the intro-
work onward he
duction of his massive
held fast to the hypothesis that
was imitation for its own sake. His philosowho went beyond the simple projecthe assertion of the truth of the words projected, the
the specific end of poetry
phers and historians were writers tion of
words
to
historian with particular facts
Unlike
Patrizi,
allegorical
who
defended Empedocles
meanings carried by
Mazzoni declared that 20
and the philosopher with abstract as a
poet because of the
his explanation of the
allegorical
ideas.
nature of things,
meanings could belong to the area of
Ibid., p. 564.
77
The Age
of Criticism
truth and be icastic resemblances while the
and
fantastic. In saying that allegory
a
is
sense could be false
literal
hybrid form of expression, he
presumably implied the existence of two kinds of allegory, for what to keep a poet
from projecting
allegorical
meanings
is
as idols in the
respect that they are idols in contrast to a philosopher’s use of allegory
means of expressing
as a
that fantastic poetry,
terms of
its
a truth
which
he wishes to maintain? Mazzoni said
pure poetry, can be considered either in
is
the fantasy,
it is
fantastic.
At
the same time,
coincide with an invented action; that tasy
21 .
poem has by chance
genesis or as a finished product. If a
history
one with origin
is,
genesis in
its
may
in the fan-
Dante’s poem, as a poetical conceit, was a creation of the fantasy,
and even
if
abstract doctrine can be found in
made
its
own
for
sake, not a direct
the
it,
propounding of
poem
is
an idol
truth.
In comparison with Mazzoni’s account, Zoppio’s defense of Dante as imitator call
was markedly shallow. Although the average man, he
Empedocles and Lucretius poets because they are
only true poets are the imitators; but Dante was
anyone
—he imitated
Bulgarini’s
was wrong
kinds of people
all
main attack upon Dante
as
said, will
versifiers, the
good an imitator
as
22 .
as
in trying to imitate himself.
an imitator had been that he
He
was, however, also con-
cerned about Dante’s dealing with philosophic matters ex professo. In returning to this question in his reply to Capponi, rather than going to Aristotle directly he built his
argument around the comment by
Averroes that poetry was not invented for purposes of disputation and argument. Bulgarini’s friend, Capponi, had argued that Dante’s primary intention had been to
tell
about
his
journeys and, being the kind of
man
he was, had naturally concerned himself with the philosophic questions he encountered along the way.
He saw no
reason
why
a reader should
not tolerate philosophy in incidental and subordinate parts of a poem. Bulgarini, in responding,
was
less
concerned with any absolute
differ-
ence between poetic and philosophic speech than with the reaction of poet’s audience to
weighty philosophic language. Like Castelvetro, he
thought poetry should be read mainly by the middle claimed, did not in general understand philosophy.
classes,
He
which, he
thought poetry
should be an imitation and provide plot structures because the
man can be child,
appealed to
by
those things.
The common man
common is
like a
but the learned can gain instruction better by turning directly
to the arts and sciences. 21
a
Ibid., p. 579.
78
The
poet cannot teach them anything they do 22
Zoppio, op.
cit.,
p. 7.
Empedocles and Lucretius not already know. These ideas came to him from Piccolomini
from
as
Castelvetro, Bulgarini said.
well
as
23
After having earlier rejected Tasso’s notion that the concept of poetic
by which
action could be extended to include actions of the intellect,
extension imitations of logical sequences could provide subject matter
Summo
for poetry, 24 Faustino
addressed himself in the tenth discourse
of his Discorsi poetici (1600) to an attack
upon Francesco
Patrizi for
extravagance in rating Empedocles higher as a poet than Homer.
his
Much
of his accomplishment was the summoning up of the usual ideas. Can writers like Hesiod, Empedocles, Pontano, and Fracastoro be called good poets? he asked. He conceded that, since Aristotle normally al-
lowed
comparative to imply
a
be
still
and that Aristotle, using the term loosely and popularly,
called half poets
identified poetry
with verse. But
After summarizing
Summo
Patrizi’s position,
show
the Poetics to
could
a positive, doctrinal poets
that imitation
held that Patrizi
went too
far.
he assembled the usual passages in the genus or essence of poetry
is
and added references to the same end extracted from Plato, Plutarch, and Maximus of Tyre. imply positives
He
then claimed that Aristotle did not always
in using comparatives
and argued that when
Aristotle,
Cicero, Horace, and Quintilian lightly called Empedocles a poet they
were speaking only verse and metaphors.
human
actions; in
“they do not
No,
said
Summo,
answering people
know what
that “imitation using verse as
makes
a
its
uses
is,
one can only say that
and they do not
in Aristotle’s
know what
way.” The truth
is
proper instrument and not verse only
poet a poet. This was the opinion not only of Aristotle but also
of Plato, of Plutarch, and of the best minds of tion
who
the poet must be an imitator of
like Patrizi,
a poetic fable
means to imitate or not to imitate
it
one
in the popular sense of “poet” as
Summo was
complex.
The
On
ages.” 25
this ques-
one of the most faithful of the Aristotelians of
century and one of the most Buonamici, in
all
his
rigid.
his Aristotelianism,
was
little less
was more between the
rigid but
instruments used to achieve the relationship
imitation in poetry and the thing imitated, he said, are colors, words,
and concepts; but
—pure
we
should perceive that concepts are of two kinds
contemplations and concepts relating to the
human
will.
The
poet cannot very well handle concepts of the contemplative kind but 23
.
.
Bulgarini, Repliche alle risposte del .
Capponi pp. 21-26. ,
24
Faustino
Summo,
Discorsi
(Padova, 1600), p. 69. 25
Ibid., pp. 70-72.
79
poetici
The Age
of Criticism should leave them to philosophers and confine himself to human since he instructs and delights
and vices
as
more
actions,
displaying manners and treating virtues
they are found in particular persons.
poets were given
Dante, he
by
He
thought the Latin
liberty to be philosophical than the
Greek
functioned well as a theologian on occasion, that
said,
conveyer of the divine
from the high
light of truth,
level of his
own
and
in so
poets. is,
as a
doing did not descend
dignity, but in playing the role of a
theologian he was not, strictly speaking, playing a poet’s role. 26 In the final years of the sixteenth century, after Segni and Mazzoni,
there
was some
theorists like
drift
back toward
a straight Aristotelianism. Critical
Summo, Denores, Buonamici, and Beni were
the fore-
fathers of the Neoclassicism of the seventeenth century, rather than
Mazzoni,
who
remained, however, the most honored authority on poetic
matters in Italy for the half century following 1587. But
it
can hardly
be said that even a majority of the Aristotelians of sixteenth-century Italy followed Aristotle so closely in their conception of poetic imita-
from the realms of poetry poets whose doctrine or speculation. Although not re-
tion as to exclude completely
subject matter
was
abstract
jecting the limitation of poetic subject matter, they struggled valiantly to discover
under what conditions the blanket proscription did not
obtain. 26
Buonamici, op.
80
cit.,
pp. 50-51.
5
poetic imitation limited
Is
to imitation of action?
THIS
question
is
the other face of the coin from that of the use of
abstract explanations in poetry, but involved here also, as
what
indicated, are the limitation of poetry to will
and
Aristotle’s ethical belief that only in action
ascertainable.
Modern
this
way
his reason,
human
If
Renaissance writers were fond of saying, therefore the imitation of something
affairs
—but not neces-
poetry
is
is
like painting, as the
poetry often descriptive and not the imitation of an
static,
which can be handled only weakly in painting? commentator on Aristotle’s Poetics although ap-
Robortelli, the first
proaching poetry
,
as “representation”
and “description”
tation” nevertheless said: “Poetic speech
any
as well as “imi-
moreover does not represent
interior habits either of virtues or of vices, but the actions
selves
which
find their origin in these habits.” This
internal habits can be revealed only in actions limitations; the poet,
painter
would with
1 .
was
them-
to say that the
Lionardi created no such
according to him, could imitate “speeches, actions,
manners, and emotions, painting
1
intention
that of the
actions are liberally interpreted to include
contemplative sequences, as Tasso did.
action,
is
human
or instincts, or emotions, and in
they in effect confine poetry to human
sarily to actions unless
human
is
writers often say that a poet’s world
whole man, not merely of
Buonamici
pertains to the
colors.”
2
all as
as
he can with words
as a
Varchi managed somehow to maintain
Robortelli, In librum Aristotelis de
arte poetic a explicationes, p.
much 2
Lionardi, op.
cit.,
p. 50.
2.
8
The Age
of Criticism
both of these positions
at once.
He
who
they must imitate somebody
said that, since poets
must
does something; hence the
imitate,
demand
for action. But he added: “Just as sculptors and painters imitate principally exteriors, that
is,
bodies, so poets imitate principally interiors, that
mind
the minds, or rather the passions of the
is,
sorrow, joy.”
poet
And
3
later
“The
said:
like love, hate, anger,
first office
and
artifice of
every
to imitate or to represent. Poets can represent or imitate only
is
those
who
he
endowed with
is
he
No
are performing something. reason.
reason. Therefore, only
No
one can really perform unless
animal except
man can be
imitated.”
4
man is endowed with By “perform” Varchi
obviously meant something like “act significantly or responsibly.” In this sense, actions reveal interiors. Practically, his
poet can imitate actions, passions, or character
meaning was traits
that the
since these
all
interlock.
Capriano made the imitation of human action only one kind of poetry
5 ,
actions
6 .
but Partenio had Trissino say that poetry aims to express
Ludovico Dolce
poet
is
said:
“The matter
to imitate the actions of that
we
7
men.”
And
select to imitate
and the deeds of the characters.”
These writers with
human
said Aristotle teaches that “the office of the
Minturno, to the contrary, the manners, the emotions,
is
8
comments
their brief
reveal that differences of
opinion did
exist,
but they passed largely unnoticed until the time of
Castelvetro.
Even
Castelvetro did
He
approached the questions
totle’s division
we
of characters into
are. In Aristotle’s
ways
stances.
He
better, the same,
and worse than
system, he said, a man’s true moral nature
is al-
firmly denies
in action in order to reveal their
moral
and of goodness and wickedness, which Aristotle
it
to be.
in action, that
like history
men
argued: “If that were true, poetry would be an imitation
chiefly of morals,
is
men
discernible since his morals determine his actions, but Castelvetro
denied that poets imitate
men
more than skirt the territory. obliquely while commenting upon Arislittle
is,
.
.
.
it is
Poetry, on the contrary, the imitation of a story
but differs from
it
in that
it
is
the imitation of
which
is
in general
has never happened, though
always within the realm of the possible.
.
.
.
Now
it
these stories are
told not to reveal the goodness or wickedness of the persons imitated
but to delight the 3
Varchi, Lezzioni,
*
Ibid.,
6
Supra, p. 70.
p. 602.
82
common
people as
much 6
p. 583. 7
8
as possible
with the novelty
Supra, p. 69, Dolce, op. cit., p. 189.
Minturno, Varte poetica, pp.
2-3.
hnitation of Action
which give them more pleasure than
of the events represented, events
do the exposition of philosophers, the portrayal of character, the exposition of doctrines concerning the arts and sciences, or the representation
of events which possess no novelty.” limited to
way had tive
to
human
he not limited
human
action
Since effects of novelty are not
action, Castelvetro could not well have his
came
in
to
all
men
this
problem with the limitation of poetry
real
connection with the other genres, and aside
these idiosyncrasies, Castelvetro’s explanation
Common
argued in
concept of poetry almost entirely to narra-
and dramatic forms. The
from
9
was conventional.
are five things, he said: mind, will, fortune, station,
and action, of which mind and
whereas the other three
will are essential
are external or accidental. Questions of mind embrace distinctions between intelligence and stupidity, those of will between goodness and wickedness, those of fortune between happiness and unhappiness, those of station between royal and private situation, and those of action between philosophical and political activity. Now any of these except philosophical activity can be a subject of poetic imitation. Genres, however, Castelvetro distinguished by differences in station and made matters of will relatively unimportant. He thought that stupidity is more likely to be found in low station and intelligence in high and that “the nobility or humbleness of a person is not revealed by his virtue or his wickedness but by his deportment.” Gentility or rusticity these proceed from intelligence or stupidity, not from morals. In barring philosophical activity from poetry, Castelvetro rejected Tasso’s “actions of contemplation.” Otherwise, his approach was negative: he accepted the
—
definition of poetry as the imitation of
human
actions, but not because
He
did nevertheless envision
these revealed the moral nature of mankind.
the possibility of imitations in poetry of five kinds of beings, of
human
which
men and women; (2) gods and supercommon people think personified moral traits and human ab-
beings were only one: (i)
natural beings, a possibility only because the
anthropomorphologically; (3) stractions such as wealth, poverty, glory, infamy, and so on (these
would seem as are
to encroach
found this
and (5)
in Aesop’s fables;
(Castelvetro did not
he took
upon philosophical
make
category).
clear
activity); (4) animals such
senseless animals
and plants
what he meant here or how
The main
drift of this classification
is
seriously that any-
thing can be imitated that can be personified. 10
Alessandro Piccolomini more directly attacked the kind of descriptive 9
Bongiorno, op.
cit.,
p. 68.
10
Ibid., p. 93.
83
The Age
of Criticism
poem in which no human
action appears.
He
said that
be mere portrayals of the events of a night or river, the
present
coming of springtime, or any
human
in asking
why
11
Later, Paolo Beni took
.
a day, the flooding of a
similar natural event but should
Poetry Should be, thus, not
action.
and not epigram
up
lyrical description
and expanded
this idea
it,
poetry provides imitations of people and not of such
things as houses and mountains.
He
felt
apparently the presence of de-
fenders of lyrical descriptive poems in his milieu
who were
descriptions of storms, sunsets, and other natural
poems and
poetry should not
pointing to
phenomena
in lyric
to long lyrical passages in epic poetry that could
stretch of the imagination be called imitations of
held out for the imitation of
human
human
by no
action. Beni
action not only in poetry but in
painting also, even though he conceded that static descriptions could
be used in subordinate parts of poems in episodes or did not
comprehend how
a
poet could write a
as
ornament.
poem about
a
man
He
asleep
or in idleness, since the end of poetry could not be reached in this way,
where no misfortunes existed from which to derive benefit. He also conceded that the description of such phenomena as night and tempests could be thought of
as imitation of
realization of experience,
another kind
which the poet
—
as enargeia, the vivid
common
shares in
with the
orator and the historian, but at this point he refused to believe that this
kind of imitation Beni were the call
did not imitate
truly and particularly the poet’s
critics
Empedocles
rigidity here
is
who
a poet
human
with
12 .
Piccolomini and
especially fought this battle. Beni refused to
not because he failed to imitate but because he
actions. Less clear
his liberalism in
is
how
he squared
his particular
conceiving of poetic imitation gen-
erally as analogue.
Segni was one of the determined opponents to the limiting of poetry to
human action, but he was less interested
aspect.
He saw
not be imitated totle
no reason as
why
in action than in the
“human”
character, passions, and thought could
well as action, thinking that neither Plato nor Aris-
had intended any such
strict limitation.
He
felt
the evidence indi-
cated that Aristotle meant his concept of action to refer only to dra-
matic poetry, since most lyrics have no action but imitate passions or mores. Most of his arguments were attempts to
show why
Plato agreed with him. His real contribution, however,
u Alessandro
Piccolomini,
Annota -
tioni nel libro della poetica d’Aristotele
(Vinegia, 1575),
84
sig.
A5r.
Aristotle and
was
his
concep-
“Beni, In Aristotelis poeticam commentarii, p. 92.
Imitation of Action
by which he
tion of fable as “false speech,”
an action in
its
did in fact give lyric poetry
projection of the conditions of falseness. 13 Tasso,
have likewise seen, interpreted “action” broadly.
human
tation in poetry should be of
He
we
did assert that imi-
fumbling with
actions, ‘but after
Stoic and Platonic opinions, he concluded that gods and animals also
could be the subject matter of imitation provided that they were treated as
if
they were human beings. This shows patently the influence
of Castelvetro, with
whom
he did not in the main agree.
In the critical contest between Mazzoni and Bulgarini over the posi-
Dante as a poet, much space was devoted to the question of whether or not dreams should be called products of the imagination and thus a kind of human action or natural fact produced by nonhuman tion of
forces. Bulgarini claimed that Dante’s
was not
human
a
as the
account of a dream
much
action, his strict Aristotelianism being
Piccolomini’s and Beni’s.
should concern
poem
human
He
like
said that “the principal poetic imitation
actions, at least in epic
and dramatic poetry”
even though in descriptions and other accidental background material
something which the poet needs
is
not
human
human
vices, a
own
added that
Furthermore, to portray virtues
actions.
poet must depend upon the free will of
dream of the kind portrayed by Dante
controlled
dream
He
be involved.
actions in order to reach his end of portraying
generalized forms of our
a
may
and vices and to achieve the pleasure that comes from seeing
virtues
and
action
is
by
will
and
we
is
a
his characters.
product of fantasy un-
cannot dream or not dream
human
a natural action, not a
one.
Since
at
The poet
over the propriety of the behavior of the characters in
our discretion, has
his
no control dreams, and
without will there can be no responsibility for their decorum. 14 Mazzoni’s
answers to these charges were substantially like Segni’s, although
he devoted
The from
it
much
space to the analysis of the nature of dreams.
reader of Faustino
Summo’s
Discorsi poetici (1600) can emerge
with the feeling that he has been perusing a
critical treatise of a
high order even though the historian of ideas can find novel or penetrating as he breaks
component
parts. In dealing
can, however, see
down Summo’s
with
how Summo’s
critical
this question of
there that
system into
human
actions,
is
its
we
urbanity kept him detached from some
of the stereotypes and truisms of his day.
He
that poets are imitators of the actions of
men
13
little
See supra, pp. 44-48.
argued in standard fashion in their happiness
“Bulgarini, Repliche .
.
.
and un-
alle risposte del
Capponi pp. 81-83. 85
The Age
of Criticism
happiness and not of their mere eccentricities of character, but in opposition to those
who wanted
to
broaden the concept of poetry to include
prose imitations he stressed the importance of verse as a means of getting
below surface action to blend
with the interior
exteriors
states of soul.
To the writers who argued that a poet is obliged to be like the painter who is more successful as a painter to the extent that his work resembles the actual features of his subject, he answered that “he will be the better
master and imitator to the extent that the figure will emphasize not only the exterior in its
its
good or bad
natural beauty or ugliness but also the interior with
soul,
making, for instance, in the imaging of Our Lady
her face shine out serene with her great humility and sanctity, and fraud
and betrayal
words the
in judas’s; in a similar
passions and the
represents.” Far
way
the poet ought to express with
manners of the characters he imitates and
from thinking of verse
as
mere ornamentation
that
Summo
be destructive of the verisimilitude carried by a poetic imitation, stressed the poet’s act as an “expression”
tion” and
made
whether or not he confined himself to If in this
as
verse an important part of the expression
however, that Summo’s poet was one
seen,
even more than
who
portrayed
15 .
may
an “imitaIt
human
can be beings
their actions.
medley of sixteenth-century opinions there
is little
that
is
constant and never questioned, the general tendency was nonetheless to
agree with Aristotle, at least to the extent of not wishing to eliminate
both action and human
norm
affairs.
Buonamici’s doctrine was as close to the
of thinking as that of anyone, even
when
he said that Dante as
theologian was not, strictly speaking, playing a poet’s role.
The
true
poet, he said, “proposes to himself the imitation of actions, directed to
chances of fortune, which are conjoined with our are various, they are
most
wills,
and when these
showing our moral
suitable for
acts,
by means
men
already habituated to acting in a set fashion.”
habits
through
of actions. Actions are determined and particular and of
absent in the critical thinking of the Renaissance
is
16
What
is
noticeably
the attempt to apply
the concept of action to lyric poems. ^Faustino Summo, Discorso in difesa del metro nelle poesie, e nei poemi, et in
86
particolare
nelle
tragedie,
e
(Padova, 1601), pp. 14-19. 10 Buonamici, op. cit., p. 51.
comedie
6
Are prose
THE Renaissance as
fictions
poems?
were quick to notice that imitation the term “poetry” becomes generic for
works
critics
poetry
if all
that exhibit renderings of concrete experience,
defined
is
kinds of literary
whether
in prose
or verse, provided at least that the works are not primarily didactic in
make seem to exist for their own sake. What was needed then, and what is still needed in order to overcome some of the confusing preconceptions based upon the meaning of terms in popular usage, is a general term for works of literature to distinguish them from tracts, treatises, recipe books, textbooks, lawnature and are such that the imitations they
court pleadings, sacred writings, most histories, and newspaper accounts.
One
of the chief advantages of mimetic concepts of “imagi-
native” literature has always been their usefulness in furthering, without entirely clarifying, this needed distinction. Since our terms “imaginative
writing,” “creative writing,” or simply “literature” have never been
more^than temporary makeshifts and have generally been understood such,
we
can sympathize with the plight of the Renaissance
as
critics in
their persistent testing of the theory of imitation against the facts of literary history
and against their
own
desire to be as
comprehensive
possible. In this respect literary criticism in later centuries has little
advance over the
Italian
Renaissance or has in
as
made
comparison sunk
into a slough of obscurantism. It will
be impossible here to give complete accounts of the
critical
debates in the sixteenth century over the relationships between prose
and verse, since hundreds of pages were devoted to the question and no clear-cut orthodoxy emerged.
no more resolved than
at the
At
the end of the period the issues
were
beginning although a great amount of heat 87
The Age
of Criticism
had been generated in the interim. In general the staunch Aristotelians,
who
put their faith in a definition of poetry based upon the concept of
imitation, took the stand that comedies, tragedies, novelle , dialogues,
romances
in prose should
Aristotelians like Patrizi
be thought of
were most vocal
as poetry,
and
while the anti-
in their rejection of prose
poetry, since they considered verse the indispensable element. But- on this
question traditional enemies often agreed with one another and
battled with their friends, so that the
lists
of the contestants should not
be drawn up on the basis of their Aristotelianism.
Among
the defenders
of the limitation of poetry to verse forms can be listed Tomitano, Speroni, Speroni’s
enemy
Cavalcanti, Giraldi Cinthio, Vettori, Scaliger,
Castelvetro, Segni, Frachetta, Patrizi, both Pellegrino and Salviati (op-
ponents in other respects in the Tasso controversy), Giacomini, Mazzoni, Buonamici,
and Faustino Summo. The
list
of those advocating the
extension of the definition of poetry to include prose writings for theirs it
was the position
that
was
at variance
with popular
is
smaller,
belief,
but
includes stalwarts such as Trissino, Varchi, Minturno, and Paolo Beni,
as well as writers
with
less
reputation such as Bonciani, Malatesta Porta,
Masini, and Michele.
The issue
in the Renaissance
hinged not only upon the weight given to
upon the exact translation of that brief of the Poetics in which Aristotle (according to said: “But the art which imitates by means of
the concept of imitation but also
passage in Chapter
I
modern translations) words only, in prose or in meter that is either the same throughout or of several kinds, is up to the present without a name. For we have no common name for the mimes of Sophron and Xenarchus and the Socratic dialogues, nor would we have any if someone made an imitation in the meters of epics or elegies or anything else of the sort; yet by associating a composition with its meter people call some writers elegiac poets and others epic poets, giving them the name of poets not because of their imitation but in popular fashion according to the meter they use.”
1
Most
specifically, the quarrel in the
Renaissance depended on
the translation of the phrase “in prose or in meter”; the 1
Poetics
cited
1447328. This translation
by permission
University U.S.A.,
Press,
a
State
Michigan,
Gilbert, Literary
Dry den (New York, based on Gudeman’s
1940), p. 70. It is In a footnote
text.
Wayne
Detroit,
from Allan H.
Criticism , Plato to
adds
of the
is
Professor
Gilbert
comment by Croce, from La 88
modern
transla-
poesia (Bari, 1936), p. 40: “There can
never be such a name, because poetry and literature, though touching on one always remain two diverse things.” might be better able to find this common term if we knew what belongs on the side of poetry and what on the side,
We
side of literature.
Are prose tion decides the question unequivocally
poems?
fictions
on the
side of those
who wanted
poetry to include Boccaccio’s Decameron and the Arcadia of Sannazaro.
The
alternative interpretation in the Renaissance
was “with meters only were
or with musical accompaniment,” and countless reams of paper
used in the scholarly search through the writings of Plato and Aristotle
meaning of the term the
to establish the range of
Italians translated as
parlari ignudi (bare speech, naked language). For the sake of brevity the technicalities of this protracted argument will be avoided here, but since for
many
of the disputants the outcome of the argument rested on
were the important part of
the authority of Aristotle, the technicalities
the dispute.
Having argued
that poetry
is
not an imitation but any kind of written
disputata to
show
that verse and not prose
V
Book
or spoken composition, Patrizi turned in is
of his
ha deca
poetry’s necessary instru-
ment. In so doing, he obviously thought he was serving to undermine Aristotle’s
theory of poetry
that theory
he
said,
their
was
a
foundation support of
have discovered that verse
argument on four
one of the by-products of
as imitation, as if
is
it.
Some
writers of our time,
not necessary in poetry, basing
loci in Aristotle’s Poetics:
(
i
)
that
poems
imitate
( sermone ), and harmony; (2) but epic poems imionly with bare speech or with meters; (3) while, to the contrary,
with rhythm, speech tate
Homer and Empedocles
have only verse in common, and Empedocles
not a poet; and (4) a poet needs a fable more than verses. These four items in Aristotle were, in fact, those most commonly
was
a physicist,
utilized,
and although Patrizi was not the
of poetry to verse, he was the question. His attack
upon the
that
upon
tain
key words,
and
Italian equivalents
Sermo, he “verse.”
first
first
to argue for the limitation
to engage in full-scale debate
on the
interpreters of Aristotle, as distinct
from
upon his different readings for cergame in which the meanings of the Latin of the Greek words were usually in question.
Aristotle himself, rested in a linguistic
said, instead
The word
of “speech” or “discourse” means “meter” or
epos can
mean
(1)
any use of words, (2) any writ-
ing in verse, or (3) only hexameters; but Aristotle intended only to refer to epic poetry in using the term. By “bare speech” ( parlari nudi) Aristotle
meant verse without musical accompaniment,
though he conceded that
it
could mean “prose” since in antiquity verse
was usually accompanied by music and had used the term in
had made too
much
Patrizi insisted, al-
this sense.
that both Aristotle and Plato
But he believed Vettori and Castelvetro
of the evidence for this reading. In Dionysius of 89
The Age
of Criticism
Halicarnassus and Strabo, Patrizi found evidence that the meaning could
be either “prose” or “unaccompanied verse.” History taught him that
poems often had had musical accompaniment, but he found no evidence that epic poems had ever been written in prose. He further argued that Aristotle implied the use of verse in all poems in describing epic
the particular meters to be used in epic poems, and he asked how,, if Aristotle
meant that iambic meters are too much
for epic poetry,
it
like prose to
be suitable
can be said that epic poetry can be written in prose.
Further points of dispute were whether Suidas was wrong in asserting
mimes of Sophron were written in prose and whether Plato’s were referred to by the “Socratic dialogues.” But after all this Patrizi said that Aristotle was wrong, for otherwise all prose containing imitations would have to be called poetry, such as the novelle of Boccaccio, the Aethiopica of Heliodorus, and the Golden Ass of that the
dialogues
The
Apuleius. as
truth
is,
Patrizi asserted, orators
and
historians, as well
other kinds of writers, use imitation for the purpose of gaining better
were poetry, Herodotus,
expression. If imitations
denied the
name
of poet,
would be
one, as
would
thenes. If the dialogues of Plato are called poems,
to
whom
Isocrates it is
Aristotle
and Demos-
necessary to point
out that they cover a great range; some are history, some natural science,
some matters of the
and
arts
sciences. Before turning to the settling of
three special problems, Patrizi said: “So
we
can conclude not only that
prose has no concern in the formation of poetry and that the Socratic dialogues were neither epics nor poetry but also that
poetry cannot be composed without verse.” Patrizi’s three special questions
were:
(1) Is the prose translation or recasting of a
(2)
If a fable is
version a
written
poem but
first in
clear that
it is
2
poem
a
poem?
prose and then versified,
is
the verse
the prose version not?
(3) Should comedies written in prose be called poems or sermoni? His answers were that comedies and pastorals written in prose are not
poems, that the
which Virgil fied
it,
Iliad in prose translation
first cast in a
is
prose form, was not a
that the tales of Boccaccio are not
prose, and that
not a poem, that the Aeneid
poems
poem
until
so long as their
works presenting mixtures of verse and prose
mixtures of prose and poetry.
Where
,
he had versi-
form
is
are simply
Castelvetro had attacked the
writing of works like Boethius’ Consolation of Philosophy or Sannazaro’s Arcadia in both verse and prose as the creation of monsters, Patrizi said: •’Patrizi,
“But unless everything composed of contraries
La deca 90
disputata, p. 120.
is
a monster,
Are prose such
man who
as
is
poems?
fictions
composed of what
is
corporeal and incorporeal,
these specified compositions should not be called monsters but compila-
what
tions of
The
and what
is
cally treated” if
was
it
is
not poetry.”
too readily that Patrizi called anything “poeti-
suspicion arises
“Thirty days hath
cast in verse form, so that
September” would have been
a
poem
for him, whereas a prose transla-
would not have been. Furthermore, he showed no com-
tion of the Iliad
prehension of the subtle distinctions that are necessary in drawing a line
between what
many
is
a verse
and what
a prose
form, distinctions of which
of his contemporaries were fully aware. This failure did not
argument but indicates that
seriously impair the efficacy of Patrizi’s
was exclusively
negative. Since the
main
critical
war between
it
the prose
defenders and the verse defenders came in the years following Patrizi’s
La deca
disputata,
is
likely that Patrizi’s
Summo, and
ideas of Beni,
This
it is
Michele.
not to say, however, that
their stands or Patrizi did
portance in
argument gave impetus to the
Patrizi’s predecessors
supported their positions with amassed evidence.
was
to elevate this contention to a position of
critical speculation. Robortelli,
as authorities,
had not taken
What
major im-
using Suidas and Eustathius
decided that the “bare speech” term simply meant “with-
out musical accompaniment.”
3
For him, consequently, the prose prob-
lem did not occur. Tomitano presented significant arguments that did not stem primarily from the text of the Poetics the context for ,
statements being a discussion of style.
He
had Speroni say that
comedy
it
his
had
poems should always be written in verse. One prong of the attack upon Speroni’s Canace had been that the verse forms were so unconventional as to become in effect prose. But in Tomitano’s version Speroni said that the always been
comedy
his
opinion that tragedy and
writers of the early sixteenth century
were converted
who
as
had written
in prose
Horace and Aristotle. Tomitano defended the use of verse with a mystical Pythagorean argument that number is the measured order of all things,
More
to verse after once mastering
significantly,
and he devoted
a couple of pages to describing the deep-seated effects
harmony and proportion upon the human spirit and the nature of things. He made measured speech important because of the greater force meter gives to words, but he was as much concerned with cadence in prose as with regularity of meter and stressed the need for rhythm of
to 3
match the sense
4 .
Robortelli, In librum Aristotelis de
4
Tomitano, op.
cit
pp. 226-235.
arte poetica explicationes, p. 13.
9i
The Age The
of Criticism
author of the principal attack upon Speroni’s tragedy, the
Giudicio sopra attributed to
la
tragedia di Canace e
Macareo (Lucca,
1550), usually
Bartolommeo Cavalcanti, presented dialogues representing
some of the writers in TrissinoV circle. Since one of the unique features of Trissino’s prosody was his introduction of blank verse, the contest between verse and prose in the Giudicio was a four-sided affair among
rhymed forms used by Dante and Petrarch, and the irregular line lengths used by Speroni. One of the minor characters in the dialogue asked why tragedies could not be made in prose “because to see vernacular verses without rhyme (conceding that they are verses) prose, blank verse, the
seems to
me
like seeing a
man without
a soul.”
This disputant was aware
that Aristotle had called fable the soul of tragedy and presumably held
The
a different opinion.
nom
Florentine (the
for himself) answered that tragedy certainly verse of
some
kind, arguing that Aristotle
essential ingredients of poetry, for
does not
make
and did teach
would be
meant verse
soulless
without
to be one of the
although Aristotle said verse alone
poetry could be written in prose
a poet, he did not say
how
de guerre Cavalcanti used
verses are written. Implying a fault in Trissino’s
from the Goths the Florentine hinted that happy form for Italian heroic poetry than terza rima, the excellence of which had been established by Dante and Petrarch, but he believed that Dante and Petrarch would surely have practice in Italy Liberated
blank verse
is
,
a less
chosen blank verse for tragedy had they chosen to write tragedies. Citing in
Bembo and
Ariosto, he also approved of the use of blank verse
comedy; the ottava rima of the romances, he
said, is closer to elegiac
verses than to heroic. 5
Since with his rhetorical orientation Speroni identified poetry with
eloquence and consequently with ornament over and beyond the
amount allowed an orator or
He
firmly stated that prose
making concepts said, “uses it
a historian, he is
clearly understandable.
contrary to
or vulgar reasonings
it
its
was
a
champion of
“Who
nature.” If poetry
would be inept
“like
uses
it
otherwise,” he
were used for doctrine going dancing to one’s
business activities or singing in speaking to one’s friends.”
we
should be able to see
verse.
speech intended for teaching and for
why poems
should not be made
6
From
this
in prose or
history in verse, he added. Giraldi Cinthio, in his turn, hardly admitted
e
5 Giudicio sopra la tragedia di Canace Macareo, in Speroni, Opere (Venezia,
1740), IV, 117-119.
92
6
Speroni, “Sopra Virgilio,” in Opere,
IV, 534.
Are prose
poems?
fictions
the possibility of poetry in prose form. In indicating his awareness that
some early comedies had been written in prose, he suggested the reason was that the verse forms had not yet been developed 7 In these early years of the development of modern literary criticism, Varchi and Minturno were firmly entrenched on the other side. Many of Varchi’s utterances and test cases were those that reverberated .
throughout the simplicity:
if
a writer imitates he
is
many
the virtues of
all
a poet, if he does not he
Varchi loudly asserted that Lucian in
called one.
Cicero in
His formula had
rest of the century.
his
cannot be
prose dialogues,
of his works, and Boccaccio in his hundred novelle
were poets and not orators. Whoever might translate Homer or Virgil into prose would be a poet and not an orator, but whoever might translate Aristotle into verse would not be a poet but a philosopher. Lucan should be called a historian, not a poet.
Varchi and in the whole of Renaissance were.
If
and
“historian,”
and
scientific observations
Varchi was
Arcadia and
at
was
to isolate and define
one with Speroni
Bembo
in his Asolani
speeches
is
it
imitates
in also
He is
what we
acknowledging the
also said that
had been true poets.
“Indeed, the very book of Bembo’s which
poetry because
century the guise under
could be called history, one of the principal
overlapping between poetry and oratory. in his
what the alternatives it was usually
appeared was that of history. Since even philosophic
tasks of the Renaissance philosopher call history.
criticism,
at least as late as the eighteenth
fiction
interesting to note, in
is
term existed for “prose writer”
a generic
which prose
It
Sannazaro
He
entitled Prose
with speeches, and that which
poetry.” After these dogmatic assertions,
it is
added:
is
really
imitates
with
perhaps with
some wonderment that we find Varchi setting up a scale of what is more and what is less poetic, in which the ideal poet both imitates and uses verse, the poet
who
without verse, and
tates
solely because poetry
is
follows only the letter of the definition imi-
lastly
comes the poet who sneaks under the wire
identified in the popular
mind with
verse rather
than imitation. So Varchi put Sannazaro and Boccaccio in the second category, and Empedocles, Lucan, and Lucretius in the third
Like Varchi, Minturno revealed a
what
the logic of poetics permitted.
evitable to 7
him
split
On
die,
come-
204.
intorno
al
his taste it
and
seemed
in-
that poetry could be written in prose since imitation and
Giraldi Cinthio, “Discorso, over let-
tera
between what
the side of logic
8 .
comporre
delle
8
et
delle
tragedie,” in
Discorsi
Varchi, Lezzioni, pp. 580-581.
93
p.
The Age
of Criticism
“feigning” determines the poet and gives to the “material which treated that
form which
is
required in poetry.” Thus, he thought the
is
parables of the Evangelists should be called true poetry even though
they were written in prose such
of verse,
as
9 .
A little later
he identified unrhymed forms
blank verse, with prose and said that Boccaccio’s
novelle and prose comedies should be classed as poetry, even though he
modern comedies would be
hinted that
better
if
written in verse.
presumably with approval, mixtures of prose and poetry
cited,
Sannazaro’s Arcadia
10 .
Still later,
at a point
when Uarte
He like
poetic a had
undergone transformation to dialogue form, Minturno returned to an
upon prose comedies, saying that the delight of the speech in drama comes from song and so requires verse. One of the speakers, Angelo, who had written a comedy in prose, reminded Minturno that attack
in his
De
poeta he had said that poetry could be written in either verse
or prose and argued that prose could better present thoughts than verse and that
demands
comedy
prose, since
in particular,
it is
which
deals
with low characters,
unnatural that such characters should speak
in verse. Minturno’s response
was
were wiser in all some Ancients wrote poetry in
that the Ancients
things than the Moderns; and although
prose, those primitive efforts did not reach the stage, “so should
we
not refrain from being presumptuous and desirous of seeking another
way
of making comedies?”
need
all
he
still
While agreeing that low matters do not more exalted matters require, comedy since verse delights more than prose.
the beautiful ornamentation that
held for meter in
Inasmuch
as
comic verse should resemble popular speech, he agreed that
blank verse was better for natural
comedy than rhymes, which were un-
11 .
Vettori’s concerns with poetics
were limited almost
entirely to in-
terpreting Aristotle; consequently, he addressed himself vigorously to
solving the questions of Aristotle’s linguistic usage in connection with
the “bare speech” problem. Although he agreed that poetry consisted
of imitations
more than
verses,
he did not believe that Aristotle meant
by “bare speech.” In interpreting Aristotle’s reference to the mimes of Sophron and Xenarchus and to the ‘fables’ of Socrates, Vettori decided that the passage was too obscure to have much made of it, al-
prose
though he took the stand that Suidas was wrong
were written 8
in prose.
On
Minturno, Uarte poetica,
w lbid.,
p.
3.
94
in claiming that these
the other side, he agreed that the identificasig.
A3V.
11
Ibid., pp. 66-67.
Are prose tion of poetry with verses
fictions
was primarily
a
poems?
product of the popular
mind. 12 Castelvetro should likewise be called a fence straddler, even though
he maintained stoutly that verse forms are the proper instruments for expressing fictions and
prose for expressing truths.
On
“bare
the
speech” question, he said that poetry “which imitates with language
may
only the
be written in prose,” and he was at pains to decide whether
mimes of Sophron and Xenarchus and the dialogues of
that they
Plato, granted
ought to be considered poems, should be classed with epic
poems or with drama. By drama Castelvetro thought Aristotle meant only those poetic forms using language, harmony, and rhythm. He found evidence in Plutarch that of Plato
were presented
after Aristotle’s time certain dialogues
dramas for children, but he
as
knew
also
that
Athenaeus had classed the dialogues of Plato with epic poems. In genCastelvetro
eral,
condemned medleys of prose and poetry
like
The
Consolation of Philosophy of Boethius, but he did divide them into
were: (i) those
made some distinctions among them. His categories works which develop their subjects with both prose
and poetry, such
as the
three categories and
the
Satyricon of Petronius Arbiter, the
Capella,
prose
part of
and the Arcadia of Sannazaro; (2) verse with introductions in Statius and the Epigrams of Martial; (3) works that
—the Silvae of
are mainly prose but with
some
or in some writings of Cicero. classes
The
He
first
Golden Ass of Apuleius, Boethius, the Philologia of Martianus
illustrative verse, as in the
Of
monstrous, especially the
Decameron two
these Castelvetro called the first
first.
classification of dialogues also
preyed upon Castelvetro’s mind.
recognized the existence of three kinds of dialogues in antiquity:
were presented on the stage, (2) those for which stage presentation was impossible since the writers wrote in a historian’s manner, as in some of Cicero’s dialogues, and (3) those that combine the first two methods, in which the author first speaks in his own per(1). those that
son and then presents
his characters dramatically. Castelvetro asserted
that dialogues are often defective said:
“Now
when they
are written in prose.
an author should never write in prose unless
truth and not fiction, and never in verse unless tion and not truth.” His conclusion
they should be written in verse.
was
A
...
He
his subject
his subject
is
is
fic-
that since dialogues are fictions
special
argument was that prose
dialogues like Plato’s are not suited to the stage because prose utterance 12
Vettori, op.
cit.,
pp. 11-18.
95
The Age calls
of Criticism
low
for speaking in a
voice,
whereas verse
is
utterance designed to
be spoken in a loud voice. This idea of Castelvetro’s was debated at
some length throughout the
On
rest of the century.
the basis of
it
Castelvetro decided that contemporary dramatists should not write in prose. Furthermore, he
found that dialogues with
defect of faulty verisimilitude, because it is
if
highly improbable that the narrator could remember
recorded or because they are rable events and these
trivialities since
have the
a narrator
they are thought of all
as history
the speeches
history deals with
memo-
would be the mere opinions of someone on
the
matters of the arts and sciences, as in Bembo’s Prose or in some of Cicero’s dialogues.
Castelvetro
made
a strange but, for him,
understandable exception for
dialogues containing conversations of animals and plants, as in Aesop or
Hesiod, since these dialogues are purely imaginary, dealing only with “lies,”
He
whereas the other kinds are true or probable.
be borne in mind, however, that the presence of does not render them contemptible, for the
lies
lies
added: “It must
in these dialogues
are both delightful and
with allegories and
instructive. Dialogues of this kind are to be classed
with the figures called prosopopoeias, to which they doubtless owe
and their form.
their origin
Now the subjects
of these dialogues delight
us for their universal and miraculous novelty, and
with them for the same reason that
we
miraculous things but with prosopoeias small pleasure
from being kept
aim of the dialogue, which to
is
opinions
is
are delighted
are delighted not only with
as well.
Moreover,
in suspense before
we
we
see the
all
drawn from this melange of not really make up his mind whether
pertinent conclusion to be
that Castelvetro did
In Segni,
him as often to chaotic inconclusiveness what was called in Tomitano the mystical
He
declared that he
who
“sophistries” of those
many had argued
question
that
it
which contain
all
wish to write poetry
could be done.
He
96
strain crops
it
in prose
up the
even though
held verse to be the neces-
from other kinds of writing
other features of poetry. Segni trusted popular in-
stincts in this respect, saying that just as
Bongiorno, op.
as to brilliancy.
would not concern himself with
sary ingredient in poetry distinguishing
13
this
too typical of his method, for his slow, grinding exploration of
possibilities led
again.
end and
13
poetry could be written in prose or not. His handling of
was
derive no
to teach us sound morals or to induce us
do or to avoid doing some particular thing.”
The only
we
cit.,
pp. 34, 37, 40-47.
common
belief
knows
that
Are prose motion of
it,
even though some philosophers have denied the possibility
exists,
so
poems?
fictions
common
opinion
is
right about poetry.
He
claimed that both
Plato and Aristotle assumed the necessity of verse. Segni’s Neoplatonic
mysticism
is
when he
revealed particularly
“The furor
says:
of the poet
—
according to symmetry that is, divine proportion and harmony, of which everything is full and it is for this reason that it is dressed out in verses and not prose, for verse is no other than symmetry and meter and proportion and harmony. I mean that God particularly wants to show is
—
harmony in poets and therefore fills them with furor, according to whence also for this reason verse seems to be essential to 14 poetry.” Although he made room for the theory of imitation, Segni his
Proclus:
gave verse higher priority.
The whole argument over in a Florentine
academy
Francesco Bonciani, a
verse and prose
lecture “Sopra
work
il
came
to one sort of head
comporre
delle novelle,”
far less frequently cited than
by
deserts
its
would warrant. Since Bonciani proceeded point by point to show how the principles outlined in Aristotle’s Poetics can be made to apply to prose fiction,
it
follows that he faced squarely the possibility of extend-
ing the term “poetry” to include prose compositions of certain kinds.
He
based his case mainly on Boccaccio’s use of plots and imitation.
“Fables,” he said,
“which are what novelle more properly should be
called, are equivalent to those kinds of
tragic, heroic,
which a
is
and comic
the imitation of
—since human
all
poetry that are called perfect
function with a
actions.” Bonciani
proper instrument for poetry, but, aware that
work, he did not choose to be overly dogmatic.
common
subject,
would add prose as was a pioneering
his
He said that the
example
mode
of Lucian should lead us to assign the novella to the representative
of poetry but was willing to argue that he can be included in the sion
lists
demanded an extension of the
Equating the term Bonciani
Jiovella
if
Lucian cannot be called
novella-principle to include dialogues.
with the Latin fabula and the Greek mythos
listed three distinct possible definitions for the novella:
entirely false
poet
a
of novellatori; he stated that this conces-
and lying mode of speech
(
i
)
,
an
—the definition used by Dante
in saying
Favoleggiava colla sua famiglia
De’Trojani e di Fiesole
and implied
in the popular equation of fables
the romances; 14
Segni, op.
e di
(2)
cit.,
a
term for
jests
Roma with
lies
and ridiculous
and the tales;
pp. 40, 44.
97
follies
of
and (3)
a
The Age
of Criticism
poem
more perfect, as that which gives it is essence and is its form, called its soul by Aristotle that which we should call ‘fable’ rather than novella .” Bonciani wanted to consider a novella not as a bare skeleton of an action but as a fully extended work designation for “that part of a
that
is
—
with
all
stressed
the parts required of a poem. Considering its
frivolity but not
its falsity.
it
as a
poem, he
In a short adventure into literary
history, Bonciani claimed that Lucian’s admission that his
work was
a
“hippocentaur” came about because philosophers had practically pre-
empted the dialogue form after Plato. Bonciani was willing to surrender the pure dialogue and said that “the mixed narrative mode is that in
which the novellatore ought
to create his imitation.” Dialogues, he said,
imitate conversations, not actions. After creating a
list
of ancient writers
of novelle , he showed how, according to Aphthonius, something like novelle had been classified as tales (i) with animals only, (2) with
animals and
men
together as characters, and (3) with human beings was the one who not only followed
only. Boccaccio, Bonciani claimed,
the best models of antiquity but enlarged the range of prose fictions “to
the imitation of the better sort of men.”
As he came
to the conclusion of his lecture, Bonciani adjusted
it,
with-
out really undermining the position he had adopted, to match the
more in
traditional views.
He
instrument only, not in
said that novelle in prose differ
mode
from poems
or subject of imitation, since poetry
always uses verse. Aristotle, he asserted, did not say that imitation or fable
He
was the poem, only
added
also that
that these
were
qualitative parts of poems.
both Plato and Horace had assumed verse to be
necessary and that Horace was even doubtful about including comedies
among poems. Bonciani
repeated that novelle can be like heroic poetry
except in the instrument used. 15
Another rarely verse
is
that of
cited treatment of the relation
Girolamo Frachetta, which comes
between prose and
as part of his explica-
tion of a canzone of Cavalcanti (1585). Since canzoni had not been
described
by
Aristotle, Frachetta felt obliged first to
remarks about the nature of poetry, while actually using
make his
general
announced
subject as a pretext for attacking Castelvetro’s ideas about the relation
of the art of poetry and the art of versifying. But like Castelvetro,
Frachetta believed that poems should be written in verse; he differed
only in
his reasons for believing so.
^Francesco Bonciani, “Sopra il comporre delle novelle,” in Prose fiorentine, 98
His point was that the ed. II,
art of
by Carlo Dati (Venezia, I,
65-83.
poetry
1751), pt.
Are prose cannot
poems?
fictions
without the art of versifying but the
exist
can
art of versifying
who
exist without the art of poetry, so that Castelvetro,
considered
them inseparable, was wrong. Aristotle, he claimed, said only that a poet is more a poet for his subject matter than for his verse. Frachetta made invention and not imitation the important feature and suggested that
poetry needed verse to make oracles. In particular
verse
is
its
he criticized Castelvetro for
needed so that an actor can declaim
Patrizi, in a
summary
—
like
argument that
16 .
,
com-
a great variety of kinds of poetry, along
methods of development, which poems were directed, but
a great variety of kinds of inventions, of
of ornamentation, and of the ends to all
his
loudly
it
life-size
of his historical studies in La deca istoriale
mented that history showed with
more than
utterance seem
the varieties had in
common
verse or measured speech, for verse had
been constant throughout the entire history of poetry.
hundred early poets existed of a pieces,
he
poem
said,
sive reliance
whom
he had
listed
in prose; if later poets
they uniformly did not
upon reasoning from
Of
the five
he reported that no record
sometimes
call
also
them poetry.
definitions
wrote prose It
was
exces-
and not observing the
actual evidence of history that led critics to extend poetry to prose, Patrizi said
17 .
Tasso in effect agreed with him. Aristotle’s “bare speech,”
he believed, meant verse without song and dance
A curious teapot tempest over the question in the interchange of critical salvos
18 .
of prose poetry occurred
between Pellegrino and
Salviati in
the Tasso controversy; the actual difference of opinion between the
two
is
whom
hardly discernible. Pellegrino, to
rather than a “feigner,” followed a
common
a poet
line in
was
a
“maker”
saying that popular
usage has limited the term “poet” to the imitator with words only definition, he claimed that led Castelvetro astray into totle
—
supposing Aris-
had meant that prose imitations are possible forms of poetry; he
was counter to the opinions of both Plato and Aristotle. came in his insisting that the traditional meaning for the “bare speech” phrase was “artful locutions.” In his gloss on Pellegrino’s dialogue, Salviati likewise insisted that verse is necessary
said this
Pellegrino’s chief originality
to poetry, with a fierceness that
is
not understandable since the two were
practically in agreement. In his reply to Salviati, Pellegrino repeated a 10
Girolamo Frachetta, La spositione la canzone di Guido Cavalcanti,
sopra
Donna mi prega 2-3.
(Venetia,
1585), pp.
17
Patrizi, Della poetic a:
18
La deca
isto-
(Ferrara, 1586), pp. 202-203. Tasso, Discorsi del poema eroico, in
riale
Opere, XII,
49.
99
The Age distinction he
of Criticism
had made between what perfect poets and mere
garden variety poets do. prose poetry, for he
To
made
common
was a defender of enough that an ordinary poet might
a slight extent Pellegrino
clear
deserve the label either for imitation or for verse, but he called attention to the fact that Aristotle in the Rhetoric had said that
beyond cadence
into verse
Salviati apparently
it
would become the
speech went
if
poet’s kind of utterance.
understood Pellegrino to mean that prose could
reveal “artful locutions” as well as verse; he argued that artfulness and
perfection of speech are necessary, not to the essence of poetry, but to
by
artfulness he
full
poetic style”
the essence of superior poetry. Pellegrino replied that
meant “both verse and and
insisted that
Then
poetry.
by
that
all
which
needed for
is
he had always argued for the need of verse in good
in the Infarinato
secondo reply
Salviati closed the dispute
pointing out that Plato in his dialogues imitated with artful locution
but for doing so was not called a poet of the
That was
first
or any other grade.
to say that Salviati recognized that prose had
the presence of
which did not
its
constitute poetry, but there
to believe that Pellegrino contested this point. 19
The
artful styles is
no reason
principal differ-
ence between them was that Pellegrino advocated using a scale bv which writers could be classed as “more-or-less” poets whereas Salviati wanted to confine the term “poet” to users of both imitation and verse, so that of the
At
two
Salviati
was on
this
occasion the rigorist.
a later point in his 11 Caraffa (1584, although
circulated earlier
it
remark that Plato and Lucian
in manuscript), Pellegrino let fall the
could be called poets because they used imitation in their dialogues. Salviati,
pouncing on
this statement,
answered, “This
doctrine and Aristotle never dreamed of
it,”
invention of a universal subject in poetry.
everyone knows
how much
is
Robortelli’s
for Aristotle called for the
He
added:
“On
such matters
one ought to pay attention to the chattering
of later grammarians and others of that sort.” Pellegrino put on a of being shocked
by
Salviati’s scorn, saying:
“This
is
show
the doctrine of
by Piccolomini and other learned and famous men in our century who did not dream it up but if the Academicians [della Crusca] make light of such men, what marvel is it that they hold little store by me?” Salviati in turn Robortelli and of Maggi,
.
.
which
has been accepted
.
replied that he esteemed those
when they run
commentators on Aristotle “but not
counter to the truth and to the teachings of their
master.” Pellegrino had further argued, in the 19
For
this material see Tasso,
100
Opere, XVIII, 26-33.
initial
dialogue, that
if
Are prose
fictions
poems?
Plato and Lucian can be called poets for using only imitation, writers like
Lucan and Lucretius can be
called poets for using verse only.
he maintained that Scaliger had defended Lucan for the
—saving Lucan was fictions
having no
a poet for
less
than
wrong
Homer
But
reason
used poetic
superimposed upon history. But Scaliger reasoned badly, Pel-
legrino said, because Lucan's inventions flourishes
and
which which he
figures,
sided with the view,
to incidental
attributed to Maggi, that there are three
sorts or grades of poetrv: (i) the best tation; (2) imitations
were confined
are “accidental in epic poetrv.” Pellegrino
without verse,
poetrv with both verse and imi-
as in the dialogues of Plato
and
Lucian and in Boccaccio's prose; and (3) verse without imitation as in Lucan, Lucretius, and the Georgies. Few, it is true, of Pellegrino’s contemporaries were so bold
as to
rank prose pieces above the non-
works of Virgil and Lucretius, and it was no doubt this ranking was all Maggi’s dream.” Pellegrino in return asked him what he meant since it seemed evident to him that it was also the belief of Robortelli, Cicero, Horace, and Quintilian, trving thus to obscure the issue bv acting as if Salviati were asserting that a mere versemaker like Empedocles could not be called a poet. He lined up the opinions of Maggi, Piccolomini, Scaliger, and Lambinus against those of Yettori and Castelvetro on the issue of the ranking of Empedocles and retorted, “But the Signori Accademici would probablv class these with the grammarians and others of that
imitative
that stung Salviati into replving, “This
sort, as
as the
thev have previouslv hinted.”
man on
and reminded
He
held that eminent
men
the street classed the Pharsalia and the Georgies as Salviati that Castelvetro
had pointed to
as
well
poems
a passage in
Athenaeus indicating that Plato, the attacker of poets, was himself poet in his dialogues. As for the use of prose in poetrv, he differ widely,
said,
a
opinions
but in such a situation could anything be wrong in
Maggi’s taking up a middle groundin rebuttal Salviati argued that Pellegrino’s classical authorities had
used the term “poet” loosely and popularlv, even Aristotle, times had written as
poets but did not
if
mean
who
some-
musicians, singers, dancers, and actors
it.
While agreeing
were
that Lucretius and Virgil in
the Georgies covered their nonpoetdc subject matter with the “mantle
of poetry” and that “Alberto da Imola might well be called ‘Bear’ dressed himself in the
form of
if
he
that beast,” he maintained that Castel-
vetro and Vettori were not merelv quibbling about Aristotle’s use of the term “bare speech” in epic poetrv, for Aristotle
meant verse withIOI
The Age out song and dance.
of Criticism
The
phrase “bare speech or verse” should be in-
terpreted not as alternatives but as restatement is,
—
“bare speech, that
as
verse” and not as “prose or verse.”
Where
Pellegrino in
Carnffa said that failure either to use verse
11
or to imitate leads to imperfection in a poem, Salviati answered that the result
poem.
is
To
not imperfection but deprivation of the essential form of a
form meant essence to Salviati, form would be tantamount to depriving it of he meant by form only outer appearance, extrinsic
this Pellegrino replied that, if
depriving a
poem
everything, but
of
if
its
aspects or accidental form, as a man’s having
two
legs, this
form
is
not
necessary in the definition of poetry. Pellegrino agreed that verse and imitation are both principal parts of poetry, the former for decoration
and the
latter for essence;
whereas imitation which
but body or outer decoration the soul
is
between body and soul
ship
only to say that verse
is
form, while agreeing that imitation
body
the lack of either
body or
either imitation or verse
body
‘Poet,’ ” Salviati said, “is
is
for poetry, not the accidental
He
essential.
soul deprives
taken
is
poetry.” “
accidental
important. Salviati, in turn, disagreed
the proper
is
is
even though the relation-
essential,
is
away
added: “Just as in the
man form
the
of his form, so is
if
removed from
one of those terms that do not take well
a
‘more-or-less’ but ‘the-better-and-the-worse.’ ” Thus, Virgil’s Georgies ,
though
by
tion
called a
poem by
the unlearned,
who know. He added
those
excellent verse but also in treatise
on an
is
it is
and
relation,
an accident
it
goodness
not essential to
would be
Pellegrino answered that this
but since
its
called a very fine composi-
doctrine, so that
its
verse
art, since
that
is
must be
so
if
it is
this
lies
not only in
not a
its
poem but
a
kind of composition.
poetry were a substance,
a quality because
as a quality it will reflect a “more-or-less.”
it
cannot be
He
a
remarked
that Castelvetro, Salviati’s man, had said this repeatedly. Salviati rejoined:
and
did not absolutely say there
I
why
do you say
commentator?
20
I
make any more
And on
upon
in poetry,
of Castelvetro than of any other
inconclusive note the exchange of opin-
this
ions ended, an exchange that relatively little bearing
was no more-or-less
was
all
the
more strange
in that
it
had
the real issues in the warfare between the
adherents of Tasso and Salviati of the Accademia della Crusca of Florence.
According to the Diario of the Accademia 20
Ibid.,
pp. 73-79.
102
degli Alterati of Florence,
Are prose Lorenzo Giacomini, one of
on November
a lecture
its
fictions
most learned and
27, 1584, in
poems?
brilliant
members, gave
which he maintained “that verse
is
necessary to poetry and that comedies in prose are not poetry but
should not for that reason be called monsters.”
21
Four years
later,
Filippo Masini of Perugia argued the primacy of imitation for the peculiar reason that Castelvetro had found fault with Petrarch’s
ing and metaphors, and Masini tried to prove that insignificant
his
rhym-
censure was an
one because of the unimportance of verse in poetry. 22 In
1587 Mazzoni added his bit to the long debate, taking the side of verse
without adding anything substantially new. Plato and Aristotle, he rarely spoke about poetry without associating
said,
with music, so that
it
confusion occurs only because of Aristotle’s assertion that epic poetry imitates “with bare speech or is
usually interpreted as
that
measured verse,” in which “bare speech”
meaning “prose.” But Mazzoni did not believe
any poetry could be written
in prose.
After reviewing some of the
usual linguistic problems and the question of
whether the dialogues of
mimes of Sophron and Xenarchus were written in prose and spending some time on the question of the propriety of
Plato and the
or verse
writing part in verse and part in prose, he stated his belief that he had
demonstrated that ignndi does not necessarily mean prose.
He
confessed
whenever he was faced with a knotty problem he sought the advice of Adouardo Gualandi, the Bishop of Cesena. When he consulted Gualandi on this “bare speech” problem, the answer he got was that the Greek word psiloi always implies the sense of “being separate.” that
Although Mazzoni recognized that Aristotle’s usage was inconsistent and that, so far as the modern argument was concerned, larger problems than the translation of the phrase and linguistic usage were involved, he concluded that in the debated place in the Poetics Aristotle
meant only “without the accompaniment of music and dance” by “bare speech” and that, to be good, poetry should use verse, especially epic poetry. 23 In view of the date of their publication
(1597), the remarks of Buonamici concerning the place of prose in poetry would seem to be-
long to the violent upheaval of the argument
at the
end of the century,
and Buonamici should be thought of in company with Michele, Faustino 21
Lorenzo Giacomini, Lezione sopra
un sonetto p.
del Petrarea (Firenze, 1808),
tico Insensato
(Perugia,
23
22.
Masini,
Lettioni
dell'Esta-
14,
Mazzoni, Della difesa (Cesena, 1688)
.
“Filippo
1588), pp.
24.
I.
28-32.
103
The Age Summo, and Paolo
of Criticism
Beni; but Buonamici
was
fighting battles with
still
twenty-five-years-dead Castelvetro, and his arguments did not
contact with those of his more exact contemporaries.
poet is,
is
one
who makes
nothing about imitation.
He
use verse.
Buonamici, a
plot structures in verse, so that both plot (that
and verse are necessary. In
fable)
To
make
He
this
connection he said practically
assumed that Aristotle meant that
all
ppets
argued that in the beginning poets could be versifying
scientists as well as
fablemakers and later the term was restricted to those
fabling in verse. Like Salviati, Buonamici held that fable
is
the soul of
poetry and verse the body, but he was unwilling to take a stand between Aristotle
who made
made
body
its
without fabling
The
the soul of anything essential and Democritus
essential. is
He
no poet
One
24 .
since music
is
in expression or
harmony can be added
something that
is
more
good for nothing. Better to the expression of them in verse
it is
express concepts in prose, he said, unless
sion of
their pro-
the ultimate justification of verse. Verse must have
some use or function results in
is
of his penetrating arguments can be found in his assertion
that a poet’s verse ought to be such that musical it,
who
writes in prose
particular strength of Buonamici’s Discorsi poetici
fundity.
to
who
he
said firmly that
beautiful than either the prose expres-
them or the prose expression
On
set to music.
the other hand,
if
the meters are so hidden that the verse forms no longer appear, the effect
is
that of a dead
does not submit
itself
man
ordinary speech. Indeed,
nounced
comparison to
so pronounced, since I
affirm this, that
in an ordinary voice, prose
since nothing
would be
if
—
man “and prose that a much greater effect
a live
harmony would have
to
made and
than verse so
in
a
it
would be more
comic
fable
would be more
altered in the speaking.
like
must be pro-
suitable for
But would he be
it,
a
who wrote thus? Certainly not, but a maker of fables only, in the same way that we believe that Aesop, Lucian, and our Boccaccio are, and they should be called mythologues. And if he did not have the poet
name of poet in doing that, he should content himself with that rank which Boccaccio has been put on account of his Decameron .” 25
into
Thus, Buonamici admitted the existence of kinds of literature that are not poetry because they are lacking the higher harmony of verse, but at the
same time he defined poetry narrowly
in terms of that higher
harmony. ^Buonamici, op. °4
cit.,
pp. 23-24.
25
Ibid., p. 58.
Are prose
poems?
fictions
In his quarrels with the ghost of Castelvetro, Buonamici objected that dialogues should aim at disputation, not at representation; that
is
to say
they belong in the area of the logical projection of probabilities and not in that of drama. Consequently,, he said that they should be written
not in verse.
in prose, certainly
presented on
He
added, however, that
people can comprehend with interest only capable of interest in fictions
if
they were
a stage an audience could be found for them, for
all
sorts of subjects.
human
if
some
events, others are
Buonamici denied that
should be written in verse, as Castelvetro had claimed.
all
He
pointed out that ?iovella writers had consistently used fictions as had
—
among the Greeks Aesop, Lucian, Apuleius. “Nor do any contradiction,” he continued, “between prose and the fable
the mythologoi I
see
that
would induce me
Buonamici
to believe that they cannot stand together.”
heightened
also objected to Castelvetro’s assertion that the
voice required in drama
is
not suited to the conversational prose of
dialogues, saying that Castelvetro had forgotten about oratory and the
by
pulpit voices used
preachers. Buonamici recognized no fundamental
difference in the enunciation of verse and prose even though he granted that stage traditions
had encouraged the perpetuation of the use of
heightened musical voices. But he added that
if
dialogues in prose cannot
be presented well in public theaters they can always be given in other places
more
fit
for them,
more
their size, if
need be. 26
This resume of opinions about the inclusion of prose within the ritory of poetry should
show
that the field had been well
harrowed before the end of the century. instead of withering
the 1590’s.
One
ter-
plowed and
It
might seem surprising that
away from exhaustion
the question burgeoned in
reason was that, although comedies had been written in
prose throughout the century, only toward the end of the century did dramatists begin in
of
comedy
in the
any number to write tragedies
status
much energy on tragedy,
and, to the Renaissance
tragedy was not poetry nothing was. Agostino Michele was
critic, if
one of the writers
who
had written
a prose tragedy; in defense of his
practice he published in 1592 his Discourse in
Shown Contrary
Which
It Is
Clearly
Opinions of All the Most Illustrious Writers Praiseworthy Fashion Comedies and Tragedies Can Be Written
in Prose. 26
The
realm of poetry had always been somewhat dubious,
but Aristotle had spent
How in
in prose.
to the
Summary
Ibid., pp.
1 1
of his discourse will reveal that
many
1— 1 14.
I0 5
of his argu-
The Age
of Criticism
ments review the century’s work on the subject while others have certain novelty.
He
others,
and
in the
two parts; in the first he more fitting instrument than more cogent and pertinent than
divided his discourse into
presented twelve reasons verse for drama,
a
why
prose
some of which
are
is
a
second he attempted to answer fifteen objections that
had been made to the use of prose. In presenting his reasons for preferring prose, Michele said that,
and comedy follow the same laws and prose has proved
since tragedy
successful in
showed
comedy,
follows that
it
it is
that Ruscelli preferred prose for
suitable for tragedy also.
comedy.
He
He
turned also to
the precedents or critical approvals of Vettori, Piccolomini, Guarini, the Sienese comic poets, Ariosto, and Caro, list
among
of tragedies that had been written in prose.
A
and gave
others,
a
fellow academician
of Michele’s had argued that although Italian prose was too sonorous for
comedy
was not lofty enough for tragedy; ATchele answered Tasso, Guarini, and other poets had demonstrated that this was not
that
it
so.
all
Another argument was that appeals to tradition are unavailing things change and rightfully so. Michele said:
There
is
nothing under the sun that remains stable and firm; and
stability that establishes taste of the arts
in
about the art of poetry,
many
in-
in food, in clothing, in habitations, in the
every other thing found here below either pro-
duced by wise nature or fabricated by human music, in which
is
laws for everything terrestrial and mortal; thus the
world often changes
and sciences, and
it
since
we
wit.
But since
I
should discover this verity in the
am
talking
arts.
Take
years ago Giusquino and Adriano flourished; in the
and Orlando were famous; and in these days Marenzio and Vecchi become singular and illustrious; and nevertheless their manners of composing are so different that it seems they are not practitioners of the past age Cyprian
same
art.
Take
painting, in
which Giovanni
Bellini
and Pordenone, formerly
very famous, had the most honored acclaim; Titian and
Salviati
were highly
gone by; and Tintoretto and Palma hold the first place in these days; and yet their pictures are so different that anyone even modpraised in times
erately expert can
tell
the author of each one of them, and
ent they are they nevertheless the same thing happens.
What
all
however
differ-
give equal pleasure. In the art of poetry
tragedy
among
celebrated than the Oedipus of Sophocles?
the Greeks was ever
What
tragedy
among
more
the Latins
was ever more praised than The Golden Rain of Antonio Telesio [a telling citation!]? What tragedy among the Tuscans was ever more exalted than Giovanni Battista Cinthio’s Orbecche? And yet in their qualitative and 106
Are prose were so
quantitative parts these
the same
name should belong
to
poems?
fictions
from one another them all. 27
far
that
it
does not seem
Oedipus
Aristotle, he indicated, created his Poetics using Sophocles’ as
mirror and called
it
revealed, but in the recent
Olympic Theater acting,
failed to
it
Muzio new show place
“the most perfect idea of tragedy” as
performance of
in the
it
in Vicenza, in spite of excellent production
and
have “that noble success promised by the immortal
acclaim of that poem.
And
sentences, the verse, the episodes,
with the soft and delicate
happened because the manner, the
that
and
its
other parts are not in accord
taste of these times.”
Thus, changes should
be expected. Since even Aristotle had described the evolution through
which comedy and tragedy had gone up to his time, Michele said, the modern change to the use of prose should be thought of as a small departure from tradition. Quoting Riccoboni to the effect that verse is
the proper instrument of poetry but not
its
essential
element and citing
Varchi’s claim that prose imitators are poets since poetry imitation,
Michele argued that prose does not
is
primarily
at all offend the essential
“however much many elevated wits of our time are more by the usages that they ordinarily observed than by any reason, even apparent.”
parts of poetry
moved see
to believe so, impelled
Another of Michele’s arguments was that
come to be used in the tradition
in
in antiquity verse
drama because musical accompaniments were
had
central
and verse was the necessary adaptation of speech to the
demands of the music. In taking considerable pains to establish this Michele showed a commendable scholarship, even though his reliance upon the current Paduan authorities such as Denores and point,
Riccoboni, along with Patrizi, Mazzoni, and Castelvetro, hints that this
range was derived from stock lecture-hall proceedings.
that regularity of meters without musical assistance in his
He
felt
day was
merely boring and cited an opinion of Denores’ that modern poets strove to
make
their verse
argument blended into verse.
seem
as
his next, that
much
like prose as possible.
This
prose allowed greater variety than
Variety in prose utterances, he had learned from Cavalcanti’s
Rhetoric
,
is
a
product of the judgment and
fine ear of the individual
writer and not of mechanical external principles. Furthermore, prose
can express our ideas
as
well as verse can. For his part, he testified
^Agostino Michele, Discorso in cui contra Vopinione di tutti i piu illustri scrittori del arte poetica
chiaramente
si
dimostra come
molto lode
le
si possono scrivere con comedie e le tragedie in
proso (Venetia, 1592),
p. 4.
107
The Age
of Criticis?n
by Valla and
that he had read the prose translations of the Iliad
Odyssey by Raffaello Volaterrano with great
of the
Prose well-
delight.
developed can express our concepts with greater gravity and sweetness than verse. Prose has
had shown in
his
its
rhythms
Dialoghi
Daniele Barbaro
as well as verse, as
much
dell' eloquenza;
prose
is
practically
metered, as he was able to demonstrate with a passage from Della Casa’s oration to Charles V. Prose has the advantage of allowing uneven line
which verse form is right for any given purpose with the attendant drawbacks that come from having to commit oneself to one choice, and can mix rhythms just as the elements in the human body combine earth, air, fire, and water. lengths, avoids the question of
In a digression, Michele reopened the question of calling prose
dialogues poetry. Using (sometimes out of context) the opinions of
and Robortelli against Zoppio to support
Castelvetro, Mazzoni, case,
he
his
and Speroni were
Lucian, Pontano,
Cicero,
“Plato,
said:
marvelous poets in their dialogues because they imitated, and to the extent that the dialogue imitates with speech tained within the species of epic poetry.”
tragedy and
comedy be
written in prose
if
it is
to that extent con-
Why,
28
he asked, cannot
dialogue can be?
In answering specific objections to his thesis Michele covered a wide
range of territory.
The
following summarizes the problems:
(1) If prose can substitute for verse,
The answer was
use prose?
why
that one
did not poets in the past
might
as
well apply the
same argument to anything: “This argument would destroy the inventions of very
awe than
many
arts
usefulness, since
it
which we now
possess with
could be said that printing,
no
less
artillery,
and musical instruments are not good and praiseworthy things because ages;
if
they were they would have been made in the early
and so invention would come to be trampled
destroyed not only in the mechanic arts but
and sciences
down and
in the liberal arts
as well.”
(2) Writing tragedies
in prose implies censure of past masters
and
imputation of greater knowledge of the art of poetry than Giraldi Cinthio, Trissino, Speroni, Guarini, Cremonini, Anguillara, Tasso,
and so on. Nonsense,
conform
said Michele.
to the usages of his time.
Every writer has the right to The same can be said about
change in painting, sculpture, architecture, music, and the tary 28
Ibid., p.
art. 19.
08
“I
am
not so stupid,” he
said,
“that
I
mili-
judge that the
Are prose entire cognition of this art
There (3)
depends upon
my
conclusion alone.”
are a thousand other kinds of excellence to consider.
No new
custom ever succeeds with the public unless
has great talent and reputation. kinds;
poems?
fictions
some come
chance. There
is
by chance;
others are created
necessary to impose changes dependent on
no reason for
is
inventor
Answer: Inventions are of two
as concomitants,
Authority
rationally.
its
a dress to be long or short. In
changes dependent on reason, fame and reputation are irrelevant. (4) Mixtures of prose
is
and verse are bad (Michele had done
this in
Cianippo). Michele gave detailed reasons showing that this
his
not
so.
(5) Castelvetro had argued that verse ought to be used because prose is too verisimilar, too much like history. Michele, who based his
argument on differs
(6)
from history
Poems with this
verisimilitude, simply reversed the argument.
are
in
its
universality, not in
its
Poetry
verses.
expressed in verse so that they can be presented
a raised voice.
argument.
It
Answer: Piccolomini had already disposed of
destroys verisimilitude to have one lover shout-
ing verses at another a
only because they
few
know
feet
away. The spectators accept
they must hear
the art
if
is
to
this
com-
municate. (7)
Denores
said that the glory of
drama
lies in
the poet’s ability to
make verse seem like prose, and the appreciation of this technique would be lost if prose were actually used. Answer: When a play is
well acted, the audience can
tell
the difference between verse
and prose. (8) Patrizi said prose could not be used in
dramas because poetry
in
(10) antiquity was always linked with song. Yes, Michele said, just so; verse was necessary so long as plays were sung.
Answer: The
(9) Patrizi said that verse and prose are contraries.
premise
is
denied; they are not contraries.
they are both instruments and no reason use contrary instruments.
no
less
“The body
is
make an
if
they were,
exists
why
made
visible to
with black than with white,” Michele
prose can
Even
said.
a poet cannot
our eyes
Either verse or
idea intelligible.
Patrizi said that, if poetry could be made without verse, verse would not be essential to it. If it could be made without prose, prose would not be essential, and the fact is that it has been made
for centuries in verse. Answer: Neither verse nor prose 109
is
essential
The Age
of Criticism
since both are instruments. It
not true that poetry has always
is
been made in verse (mimes, Socratic dialogues, comedies), but continual usage in the past (
1
1
)
no sure sign of essence. The explanation
is
poems were sung. The essence of poetry
is
that
imitation.
is
In his definition of tragedy Aristotle specified “numbers, rhythm,
and harmony.” Answer: The translation should be “speech made
which does not
delightful” instead of numbers,
necessarily
mean
verse,
and the authority of Aristotle cannot be used to support
verse.
Michele added: “Thus
am
I
composed
greatest poets tragedy had been
have given
if
in that age of the
he would
in prose
precept that tragedy ought to be written in
as a
it
sure that
prose, for these principles are not eternal as those of natural
matters are but are variable just as
ment from which they receive change the rules to (12)
Many
fit
our
human opinion and
their being are.”
We
Rhyme may
it is
easier.
present some difficulty but blank verse
easy to write. Ruscelli said that
all
sorts of
men
is
could write
Varchi debated whether prose or verse was the
verses.
need to
tastes.
will say that writers use prose simply because
Answer:
judg-
easier to
write. Actually both are very difficult. It takes as long to develop a
good orator
as a
good poet;
this
point was debated
Lodoici. Children can learn to write verses
more
by Giacopo
easily
than they
can master oratorical rhythms. (13)
Some
say that a poet writing in prose does not differ from a his-
torian.
Answer: The difference between poetry and history does
not depend upon verse, the
for
one narrates the true and
the
other the verisimilar; poetry
has unity
of action.
Poets
can color events described with emotion; historians cannot; and so on.
(14) Scaliger said that
if
imitation and not verse
were
essential to
poetry lyric poets and writers of epigrams, odes, sonnets, madrigals,
and canzoni cannot be called poets. Answer:
poems do not
imitate,
we
can say they are not poems;
the logic of definition, (b) that
poems of
(a) If these
these kinds
It
may
do not
be argued that
this
it is
follows
not true
imitate. Painters imitate
greatly in portrayals of battle scenes than in portraits of one
and more greatly
in portraying a
but the painter of the poet,
who 1
10
meadow
is
man
more
man
than in drawing a meadow,
nevertheless an imitator. “So the
does not differ from the painter, as Aristotle and
all
Are prose commentators teach
his
comedy, more
in
more
in
tragedy than in
in epic poetry,
and more in epic
imitates
us,
comedy than
poetry than in canzoni or sonnets, but these completely lacking in imitation.” For (15) It can be argued that, in prose, lyric
and epic poetry
ready seen that imitation is
however,
proof here Michele
his
comedy and tragedy can be
if
also
manifestly impossible the former
yet
last are not,
Mazzoni’s four kinds of poetic imitation.
utilized
is
poems?
fictions
Prose
essential.
tragedy,
can be, and since the is
also.
most
suitable to
to
all
comedy,
and much
to epic poems,
less suitable
We
Answer:
common
not equally
is
is
written latter
have
al-
poems and suitable to
less
suitable to
sonnets and other lyric poems. Sonnets and canzoni depend for their
form much more on meter and rhyme schemes than on it is thus a contradiction to talk of making a
external causes;
sonnet in prose since
its
dramas use
(16) Pastoral
verse
verse.
form
rigidly specified.
is
Answer: Pastoral drama
separate species of poetry but either tragedy,
comedy. But shepherds
like
to
is
comedy, or
not
a
tragi-
and verse does well in
sing,
pastorals.
Although Michele sometimes lapsed into
moved
at ease
accurately the
through the complexities of
gamut of
development of ideas slightly
is
at the
prolixity.
his
argument and
thinking of his day.
Only
was other than
accomplishment was
The
and Houdar de
la
in fashion
and
of the
exists for
a routine critical theorist of his
a tribute to the
advanced battle
state of criticism
between verse and
prose in drama was destined to be restaged at the time of
was
reflected
evil
been investigated
ideas that have
end of the sixteenth century. This
heroic drama
later in the
Dryden when
polemic between Voltaire
Few if any arguments emerged from the upon by Michele.
Motte.
contests not touched
he
in general
can be disposed of quickly. Although no reason
believing that Michele age, his
critical
inanities,
later
In the year 1600 Paolo Beni published his Oratio qua ostenditur
comediam atque tragoediam metrorum vinculis solvere a work in which it was argued that not only is prose possible in drama but even desirable. His cry was, Let drama be freed from the chains of
praestare
,
meter. In the same year, Beni’s fellow Paduan, Faustino
voted one of the discourses in
Summo,
his Discorsi poetici to the
verse and after the appearance of Beni’s attack followed
it
de-
defense of
up with
a
Discorso in difesa del metro nelle poesie e nei poemi et in particolare ,
,
The Age
of Criticism
comedie a forty-four-page booket
nelle tragedie , e
which he
in
,
panded somewhat the arguments
ex-
in his discourse of the previous year.
In his commentaries on Aristotle, which appeared in 1613, Beni summed up the controversy about the use of prose in poems and enlarged upon the ideas he had expressed more than a decade before. Beni repeated
himself so completely that earlier
work.
Summo
we need
not concern ourselves with /the
in his act of rebuttal
broached a few
Summo
In the ninth discourse of his Discorsi poetici to settle the contest
between prose and verse
joint bases of the rules of Aristotle
new
ideas.
endeavored
in stage plays
on the
and human reason. First he
listed
the arguments in favor of prose and then those in favor of verse as
he were proceeding impartially, although he weighted the side of verse. Actually, most of the discourse arized
from the
treatise of Michele,
who
is
is
if
on
his findings
shamefully plagi-
not mentioned. In support
of the use of prose he listed Michele’s reasons in order, with the same lists
of authorities and illustrations and with, rarely, the addition of
names and
citations of his
the side of verse
own. Although he
more alive and somewhat less
the tunes but with
efficacious,
reliance
called the
he again
arguments on
let
Michele
call
upon Michele’s gathering
of
evidence.
In his effort to upset Michele’s argument on the point that the
Ancients should have written in prose
Summo
if it is a
better instrument for
“Thus abandoning verse to take up prose in their compositions would be like abandoning the purple and taking up gray for clothing a great king, a change which is not proper.” He showed that Aristotle (third book of Rhetoric) had distinguished between the language of prose and poetry while admitting the presence of some metaphors and rhythm in prose, and he claimed Plato had identified poetry and verse. Other authorities in antiquity were Dionypoetry than verse,
sius
said:
of Halicarnassus and Hermogenes.
On
the “bare speech” question
he argued that since Aristotle was usually a stickler for using only certain meters for certain genres of poetry he lax
enough
also to suitable.
to allow prose. It
Summo
would never have been
seemed reasonable
as
well as traditional
that for heroic poetry only heroic meters should be
Like several of
his predecessors,
Summo
reviewed the evidence
mimes of Sophron and Xenarchus were written in prose and found it wanting. According to his taste, the Iliad and Aeneid reduced to prose would no longer be poems but pure sermoni. for supposing that the
He
argued that Michele’s syllogism 12
—comedy
is
as poetic as tragedy;
Are prose comedy tragedy
which
has been written in prose; therefore, prose
—had
minor premise since
a faulty
an argument of
useless in
is
argument that customs are
where
those matters
or another. But
that resides in the in nature
and
he
was based upon authority
said:
response to Michele’s
answer that
“I
one speaks of that good and
if
common
this is
free will in
they are fashioned in one
if
little
it is
stable usage
men and
consensus of excellent
conformity with reason,
in
satisfactory in
is
upon the consent of our
imports
it
it
this kind. In
relative,
true of that usage that depends
mode
poems?
fictions
not true.”
29
is
founded
The
varia-
came while poetry was developing toward perfection; a change now from verse to prose would be a retrogression. In refutation of the argument (which Summo tions to be
found
in early tragedy, he claimed,
called Zoppio’s thesis)
that poets should use prose because iambics
most resemble prose among meters, prose
is
Summo
better than iambics, for “prose
said
it
did not follow that
entirely alien to poetry
is
and
poetry cannot be perfect without verse.” Against the argument that verse cannot express our thoughts any better than prose,
quipped that the trouble with those
Homer
of
ears
are as
with their
ment
at the
Homer
as
Summo
say that the prose translations
that “they measure other people’s
is
he asserted, himself answered the argu-
more verisimilar in showing how a poet is conceded depart from ordinary modes of speaking in order to aim
that prose
the right to
good
ears.” Aristotle,
who
is
marvelous and
at delight.
Against Castelvetro he argued that
dialogues are not representational and like
comedy “not only because
they are simply discourse without other aids to communication but because they are merely expressions of the actions of the intellect and pertain solely to the mind, but comedies and things like
about ^he
common
life
man and
of
them
certain accidents that
all
and experience, matters very different one from the other.” telli
he answered that not
all
are actions
of us feel
To Robor-
poems must be
imitations are poems, since
showing happiness and unhappiness. dialogues were poems, “histories, and disciplines either moral or
actions occurring in ordinary If
contemplative, and even
life
the arts
all
would be poetry.” History
capable of imitating passions, actions, and manners but Reflecting the stress put
Summo
devoted more of
by Beni on
his
Discourse in Defense of Meter (1601) to
he sought to refute were that
Summo,
not poetry.
the greater lifelikeness of prose,
questions of the effects of verse in drama.
29
is
is
it
is
not
The main lifelike
propositions that
for ordinary people
Discorsi poetici, p. 67. 1
13
The Age
of Criticism
to speak in polished verses, that since art should imitate nature poetry
should follow the true or the verisimilar, that poetry should seek exact
from verse
likenesses as painting does, that audiences get less profit
because verse
and obscure and delights the ears and senses
difficult
is
only, and that verse belongs to the poetry of praise only since there a conflict
between thought and diction when
of blame.
Summo
called
it
it is
is
used for the poetry
comedy and tragedy
stupidity to argue that
should be in prose but epic poetry in verse since the same kind of
When
characters appears in epic poetry as in drama.
argued that only lyric poetry needs verse in
since, unlike
does not have to appear to be impromptu,
it
Summo
sought a
between the overelaboration of ornaments and the problem
distinction
of verisimilitude. the fact that
important to note that
It is
much
word
tude meant “lifelike”; proposition,” that
Summo was
aware of
of he whole argument rested on differences of mean-
ing attached to the
To
“verisimilitude.”
Summo
argued that
which “ought
it
to be,” that
his
us believe that simply because
men more
opponents
should is,
mean
verisimili-
“a probable
an ideal or methodized
nature and not a nature cluttered with accidents.
in
opponents
his
drama, speech
Summo would
have
often use prose than verse
normal discourse does not imply an opposition between verse and
He
verisimilitude.
more
usual the said
men
that
implication
said that the farther poetic speech gets
attractive
learned to
was
that verse
and delightful
it
becomes.
make poems because is
from the
When
dull
Aristotle
of their nature, his
the emergence of the natural.
Rhythm
is
not unnatural to man.
Summo
granted the existence of a certain obscurity in verse but
claimed that changes in language over the course of centuries accounted for
much
of
it,
a fault
not to be attributed to poets or poetry. Quite
to the contrary of being profitless it
to be
more
on account of
its
obscurity, he held
useful than prose because the delightfulness of the verse
compelled the reader or spectator to become involved in the content. Besides, he remarked, writers can write obscurely in prose as well as in verse.
Summo
poet to see to
On
always called attention to the responsibility of the it
that verse does not have the faults charged to
it.
the question of the naturalness of iambic meters, he called attention
to the antiquity of the belief that
of effects from an iambic In stating that in verse,
Summo
it is
good poets can get
a
wide range
line.
entirely proper for slaves and domestics to speak
appealed to what to him was the Aristotelian doctrine
Are prose
fictions
that poets “are imitators only of the actions of
and unhappiness, not of the
men
no violence to
men and
themselves,” that
eccentricities of character; therefore,
verse does
poems their happiness
is,
not of their
having the lowborn speak in
verisimilitude.
However, he
that
insisted
even the lowborn do speak in natural iambics part of the time, pecially in
moments
of
Although Paolo Beni, coming
at the
end of
a
long line of disputants
on the question, presented the most comprehensive treatment of to be found
of
in the Renaissance,
more rapidly
encountered in
if
been
Michele, or earlier writers. In his treatment of
problem he showed more
the complexities of the
it
not at any time, he can be disposed
solely because the expression of his ideas has
Summo,
Even when he was
es-
stress.
finesse than Michele.
talking about the inclusion of certain prose
works
within the province of poetry, he kept in mind the need for poetic “sentences and lights” and exploited fully the possibilities of the con-
cept of gradations, assigning the top place in poetry to poems with imitation and verse and fable. Imitation he held to be about the same as fable.
The
poet
who
does not use verse
diction and other ornaments of poetry.”
may
He
still
use “fable and poetic
thought of
all
poems
as
representing various possible mixtures of several ingredients that can
be excellent products
as
wholes even though imperfect
in
one or more
A comparable situation he found in Aristotle’s concept of good life as composed of many kinds of goods from which one or more might be absent without impairing the goodness of the whole.
respects.
the
In arguing that poetry should be freed
was
from the chains of
verse, he
chiefly concerned that metrical matters should not take precedence
over those pertaining to verisimilitude and decorum. slave
cannot very properly be made to mouth
He
said a
but highly recommended the use of verse in heroic poetry,
any other form
drunk
his stupidities in verse lyrics,
or
which the texture should be finely wrought and elaborate and in which a vulgar diction and pedestrian style are out of place. But he left no doubt that imitation, somehow conceived, in
should be the touchstone of poetry and not verse. Aristotle, he thought,
was
deliberately unclear about the necessity of verse and song “either
because he thought song was nevertheless a matter of some importance in this business or because he dared not differ
from general opinion,
except gradually and by dissimulation.” Aristotle that the
maker of
fables
was more
made it very clear maker of verses
a poet than a
and disagreed with Plato’s belief that poetry implies song.
Among
ex-
The Age
of Criticism
amples of works that could be called poems without verse, Beni
The Golden
carelessly listed the Aethiopica of Heliodorus, Erastus,
Ass of Apuleius, and, among the Spaniards, Splandian, i\rthur, Palmerin,
and Primaleones, holding thaC“these will have to be considered poems if
they show imitation.”
The term
be stretched so far as this but
way between which
in
should not
said,
These forms are
should.
half-
prose speech dealing exclusively with truth and poems
fables, imitations,
just as nature
“heroic poetry,” he
“poem”
and song are to be found.
He
added
that,
had created zoophytes to be part animal and part plant
and human beings to be part mortal and part immortal, “so an imitation
won
of unmeasured speech has
for
neighbor to poetry on account of
middle place
itself a
its
when
it
is
imitation and therefore fable (I
speak in the Aristotelian manner) and to history and pedestrian doctrine
on account of
unmeasured speech.”
its
He
said that if dialogues
such
as
those of Lucian are full of metaphors and poetic lights and are not
more packed with are
much
At
a later point
doctrinal precepts than with poetic inventions they
closer to poetry than the dialogues of Plato or Cicero
30 .
Beni returned to the question of dialogues and, after
Decameron Amadis, and
Greek romances can which no human action and fable can be found but which “explain and examine the subject matter more broadly for the sake of doctrine
stating that the
,
the
legitimately be called poetry, repeated his belief that dialogues in
(like the dialogues of Plato
Beni
made
a
and Cicero)” are not poetry
long study of the “bare speech” problem in the text
of Aristotle, marshaling
all
the pertinent evidence
from the
of classical authorities as well as
was
by
in Aristotle’s text
term in
its
and the
avoided some of the
difficulties
trying to argue that sometimes Aristotle used the
summed up
literary
some of the Michele and
But
He
generic sense and sometimes to refer only to heroic poetry
Thus, Beni
developments of the
Summo were more fictions
was used
Were
it
"Beni, In Aristotelis poeticam commentarii, pp. 80-83.
116
more than he
it
we
problems of their can see
as a test of the
not that 81
33
reflected
later years of the period.
specialists in the
in Beni’s treatment of the question
the Renaissance critics.
32 .
sixty-five years of Aristotelian scholarship
theory that evolved from
special
problem of prose
by
from a wide range main conclusion
Poetics. His
that Aristotle used the term epos generically to include almost
any kind of “feigned narration.”
time.
31 .
it
how
the
theory of imitation
constituted a severe
Ibid., p.
own
whole
182.
Ibid., pp. 69-74.
test,
Are prose
fictions
poems?
our long concern here with the interpretation of “bare speech” would be a digression.
It is
noteworthy
that,
although the impetus to the
works was in the interest which there was greater portrayals of “nature” than in most kinds of
extension of poetry to certain kinds of prose
of narrative fictions and dramatic dialogues in
probability of realistic
poems, the
critics
tion in terms of
terms of
its
of the Renaissance continued to explain poetic imitaits
opposition to abstract doctrine rather than in
rendering a mirror image of the world around them.
What
they wanted was concreteness and poetic inventions, not fidelity to
fact.
7
Making
Imitation as Idol
and Particularization
THE most
fully developed system of literary aesthetics in the Renais-
sance was without question that of Giacopo Mazzoni. serious
drawbacks of the
method used
necessity of splitting apart the system of
how
his separate ideas related to the
of the
Mazzoni
in order to
show
development of those ideas
in
time even though the result has been to make the force of Mazzoni’s
his
thinking a
One
in these pages has been the
evident.
less
At
this
point further advance
is
needed toward
comprehension of Mazzoni’s central concepts related to the theory of
imitation and a perception of the relationship between
had to say about imitation
as particularization
and
what Mazzoni
his ideas
about the
balance to be achieved between particulars and universals (to be dealt
with more fully
managed tions
and
in Part
Two ).
1
It
to include the narrative
how
has been
mode
shown
in
what way Mazzoni
of writing poetry under imita-
in listing the kinds of imitation as dramatic-fantastic,
narrative-fantastic, dramatic-icastic,
and narrative-icastic he made room
for a theory of imitation as particularization in order to explain the narrative-icastic this
form; and there have been some hints that he extended
theory of imitation
narrative-icastic.
How
as particularization
beyond the
limits of the
he adjusted these ideas to make them apply to
the traditional division of imitations into the purely dramatic, the
purely narrative, and the mixed form and tions of the poet’s expressing bias 1
Infra, pp. 197-202. 1
18
how
he disposed of the ques-
and passing judgments
upon
his
Making and
Idol
Particularization
material have also been viewed. Again, as part of the examination of
the use of abstract doctrines in poetry
we
have encountered Mazzoni’s
highly significant distinction between idols
and
idols
made
own
for their
question whether dreams are actions
now
made
for the sake of truth
sake and, also, his handling of the 2 .
Some
synthesis of these ideas
is
called for.
It is
evident that Plato rather than Aristotle provided the basic ideas
upon which Mazzoni’s system of completely Plato himself
aesthetics
was founded
as Plato interpreted
—but
not so
and modified by
late
Greek and Roman and Byzantine scholiasts. It is remarkable how many of his key discriminations Mazzoni was able to extract from tenthcentury Suidas, whose lexicon expositions of ideas were by their nature fragmentary but culminative of a long tradition. the perennial existence of a sound the history of
Western
ability to find ultimate
But of
body
civilization
No
can be found than in Mazzoni’s
answers in Suidas.
in his distinguishing of the idol-making arts
arts, his
and the
better proof of
of critical doctrine throughout
from other kinds
source books for kinds of idols were particularly the Sophist
sixth
book of the Republic of Plato
Mazzoni
himself. Idols,
explained, can occur either as a result of artifice or without
would have us look thought
how
it
especially at the kinds
necessary to
list
in a
He
said that idols
He but
show
not made by
can come from either bodily or spiritual matter and can be
either clear or obscure. Clear idols can
being in
it.
artifice
the other kinds as well in order to
these fitted into the larger scheme.
artifice
demanding
this
come from almost any
world; obscure idols are shadows of these,
mirror or in water. Each idol
is
or having visions are of this
not involve the imitative
class,
arts.
The
like reflections
thus a similitude of
and the cognitions that our senses have of things while
visible
some
we
object,
are sleeping
born from the body since they do ancient “heathen,” he said, divided
two classes in terms of their origin: (i) from pure intellect and (2) from souls separated from their bodies. Those of pure intellect can come either from angels or from the demons called phantasmata by the Greeks. Many visions in antiquity, Mazzoni explained, were demon inspired. The other class included, or was prin-
images of
spirit into
cipally comprised by, ghosts.
In the imitative
They 2
arts,
however, idols must be the result of
are “those images that
come from our
Supra, pp. 24-26, 51-53, 76-78, 85, 103.
fantasy and
artifice.
from our
The Age by means
intellect
ing, sculpture, or
human
of Criticism
of election and our will, such as an image in a paint-
some such
and images deriving
artifice,
These are
thing.”
totally the result of
from human
artifice all
have
as
At this point, in turning to a study of other views of idol making than what he took to be the pure Platonic view, Mazzoni rejected the definition given by Suidas, whose interpretation was close to that which was standard in North Europe from the Renaissance through the associational psychologists of the Neoclassical period that an image made by artifice must be a compoundobject an image of this kind.
—
ing of items existing in nature in order to create something nonexistent.
Mazzoni
Suidas,
called images “effigies of things nonsubsistent
said,
or centaurs.” Images of existing things,
such
as
Tritons, sphinxes,
such
as
animals or men, Suidas called similitudes instead. Mazzoni
understood that Suidas was limning Plato’s distinction between
icastic
and fantastic imitation but identified the fantastic kind exclusively with the creation of the “wonders” to be found said that tion,
we
one of the
true, as
when
the other
in
romances. Mazzoni
can learn from Suidas that there are two kinds of imita-
when
a painter attempts a faithful likeness,
the artist imitates his
Mazzoni wanted the term “idol” to apply this definition
too restrictive, collated
it
own
caprice of fantasy, but
to both kinds and, considering
with some of the definitions
of “idol” to be found in other dictionaries and glossaries left from antiquity. Hesychius, he found, said:
and
a
icastic
“The
idol
is
a similitude,
an image,
would include both
This definition, he believed,
sign.”
the
and the fantastic kinds. Likewise he found that both Phavorinus
and Ammonius defined definition he said
meant
idols as resemblances
and appearances, and
this
that idols are “of apparent things that are not
invented and of things that are invented of which they represent the similitude.”
He
then reviewed what Plato had to say in dividing imita-
tions into fantastic
and
icastic kinds in the Sophist
an imitation of what
or can
and showed that
the icastic
is
fantastic
like the capricious invention of the artificer,
is
the while that in the tenth
the object of
all
imitations
exists
exist,
whereas the
remembering
book of the Republic Plato called idols At this point Mazzoni turned to the
3 .
scrutiny of poetry as one of the imitative arts using idols with artifice
and to the cataloguing of the kinds of imitation to be found
summary 3
of
which has already been made.
Mazzoni, Della 20
difesa,
I,
7-13. See Sophist 235-236.
in poetry,
Idol
Making and
Particularization
Mazzoni’s thesis that narrative poetry can be included in the
by means of
of imitations achieves
was developed
the particularization of details
his
cataloguing of
Mazzoni anticipated no trouble with the
the four kinds of imitation,
and the nar-
three, the dramatic-fantastic, the dramatic-icastic,
rative-fantastic,
and put forth effort to show that even the narrative-
forms can be considered imitations
icastic
as particularized description,
“evidence” or enargeia or as a speaking picture. But
as
it
of his larger need to prove that Plato
as part
did not exclude narrative poetry from imitation. In
first
class
which
,
it is
evident
in his
prolonged treatment of the question that whatever can be said
about
icastic narratives in this
regard can
all
the
more strongly and
obviously be said about fantastic narratives since the problem funda-
mentally was one of defending the nonrepresentational forms of poetry as imitations
and not of defending
fidelity to fact or truth as imitation,
even though in the defense of Dante he had to protect Dante against the charge of using too
thus
Starting
Mazzoni
As
much
abstract doctrine.
with the problem of the narrative-icastic forms,
said:
for the narrative-icastic,
which he particularly. For imitate,
I
do well
will
say that the poet in if
it
is
also
obliged to
he endeavors to describe everything most
manner also are made the idols and images that pertain to narrative, as is shown at length in the second and sixty-ninth chapters of the third book. A vernacular commentator [Castelvetro] of the Poetics called this kind of imitation particularization, in which indeed Homer was very excellent; in fact, it was said by Longinus that he in this
eikonographei that ,
is,
“describes images.”
And
for this reason Lucian, in
narrating in one of his dialogues the beauties of Pantha minutely, gave the general
title
of eikones , that
the same dialogue he
named
is,
Images.
And
in
many
it
other places in
that description “image” and said the
making
of images of that sort was the business of the sculptor, the painter, and the poet
and
.
.
Homer
imitate
it.
he showed clearly that narrating anything .
.
.
And
in describing the behavior traits
an image. this
a little earlier
was to
particularly
.
.
.
And
finally,
he also shows a
little
later that
and the beauties of Penelope made
near the end of the dialogue, he concludes that
kind of poetic narrating creates images worthy of being put alongside
those of Apelles, Parrhasius, and Polygnotus. ... So
we
can see
how
Lucian clearly called particularized narrative “an image made by the Muses.”
Hermogenes said that this kind of imitation was the best that poetry could ... I conclude then that even narrative-icastic poetry will make
have.
The Age idols
and images
of Criticism
manner that I have declared. This is not shared by some believe), unless by accident only, but is always
in the
history and prose (as
property of narrative poetry
a true
4 .
Pliny the Younger, he observed, had said that frequent descriptions of places were
more poetic than
historic,
and Demetrius Phalereus had
indicated that emphasis on metaphorical qualities in comparison results in poetic parable
and belongs there rather than
book of Images
wise, Philostratus in his first
picture on account of
ment of
its
in prose forms. Like-
said
poetry was
like a
exact descriptive particularization. This state-
what Horace, Plutarch, and Cicero had said of the resemblances between poetry and painting. Filippo Beroaldo, in commenting upon Cicero’s remarks, revealed the connection between Cicero’s statement and the concept of “evidence” or enargeia. Mazzoni said, in summary: “On account of all these authorities I can warmly confess that in my judgment even in narration poetry can resemble a speaking picture. And indeed all good Philostratus reminded
Mazzoni
in turn of
poets in narrating are forced to display their subject matters with so
much
‘evidence’ that they are almost to be seen with the eyes in our
done by means of characterismos diatyposis ,
heads. This they have
,
and merismos, of which
we 5
from Ariosto, Catullus, Ovid, show the shape taken by these descriptive idols
chapter of the third book.”
and Virgil follow to
have spoken sufficiently in the sixty-ninth Illustrations
in actual practice.
In stating once again that “narrative poetry even
forms images and particularization”
idols
and
is
Mazzoni made
it
it is
icastic
sufficiently evident that
he was
modes and
that the
talking about fantastic as well as icastic narrative principle should operate even
when
consequently imitation by means of
more obviously
in the fantastic
mode
than
in the icastic.
The
heart of the problem, however,
was the necessity of
distinguish-
ing between history and poetry, for Mazzoni believed that history
could easily be said to use icastic-narrative imitation and was also
concerned with particulars and hence with particularization. In dealing with
this special aspect
of the problem, Mazzoni had to juggle Castel-
vetro’s terms, for Castelvetro
by Suidas
which true
had followed the tradition represented
were distinguished from similitudes. In the second chapter of the third book Mazzoni said: “But a great and difficult question is that one which we must now deal with that is, in
imitations
—
4
Della difesa pp. 17-18. 122
c
See infra, p. 201.
Making and
Idol
Particularization
poetry can ‘represent’ with similitudinary imitation. Certainly,
if
seems to
many
handles
if it
it
it
that poetry cannot handle this sort of imitation, since
how
they do not see
can be distinguished from history,
it
which forms that kind of idol that represents things done outside of our minds and consequently imitates (so to speak) similitudinarily. So if poetic imitation is to be distinguished from that of history, as Aristotle wishes,
will of necessity follow that fantastic imitation
it
belongs to the poetic and the similitudinary to the historic. For
many have been
reason
this
subject of the poetic.”
6
come
a slightly different route.
idols as “a similitude of that
when
He
had shown that Plato had defined
which
something that
exists,”
from
He
it.”
had
(
)
i
“according to whether
it is
the intellect” or (2) “according to whether
and by our fantasy.” Mazzoni was thus concept of idols included both the
to being a defender of Dante,
it is
a
formed by the
When
Mazzoni was,
of
in addition
contemporary of Tasso, and the
much with
he ultimately determined that in a scale from perfect to
he knowingly replaced Plato’s preference for the icastic with
Aristotle’s
compromise
that a poet
provided he handles them
Mazzoni arrived
“The and
as
may
use true or historical subjects
he should.
at three conclusions in setting
true and perfect poet
who
that fable (2)
intellect
argue that
perfect poets fantastic imitators are better poets than icastic imi-
tators,
(1)
shown
icastic, similitudinary idol
question of using historical subject matter in poetry was him.
also
presented from outside
in a position to
history and the fantastic idol of poetry. But
less
“similar
is
Plato spoke of the nature of Being his concept could be
taken either as
Plato’s
the true
same conclusion but
to practically the
to the true thing while being distinct
that
is
This was Segni’s important distinction, and
Afozzoni was prepared to
by
of the opinion that the false
is
who
he
consequently has the
false
up
his scale:
adopts fantastic imitation
and the
lie
for subject,” so
of great importance.
is
Sometimes “a true and perfect poet may imitate true things by
means of
fantastic imitation
two kinds of
and
consequence put together the
in
imitation in his writing, the icastic and the fantastic;
but the second
is
wanted for
its
own
sake and the former
by
accident. (3)
The
icastic
poet can be called truly
than the fantastic. 6
a
poet but a
less
7
Mazzoni, Della difesa
,
I,
561.
7
Ibid., pp. 562-564.
I2 3
perfect one
The Age
of Criticism
Mazzoni’s central distinction followed:
poet of any kind imitates
a
for the sake of imitation, the historian, the philosopher, or the scientist for the sake of going beyond imitation to make assertions about what is and is not true 8 According to Mazzoni, the proper objects of the two kinds of poetic imitation, the fantastic and the icastic, differ .
rather
little.
Striking in this connection
the extent to which' he
is
could find most of the significant answers in the definitions given
by
Mazzoni
Suidas, with the exception that
both to
icastic similitudes
the term “idol” refer
and to fantastic imitations. Suidas had
that the object of icastic imitation
imitation the idol.
let
Mazzoni
said:
“So
it
can be said that according
to the opinion of Suidas the object of icastic poetry
by
credible represented
poetry
ing Suidas less
similitudes
by using
is
the marvelous
and that the object of
by
the marvelous credible represented
is
said
the similitude and of fantastic
is
fantastic
After correct-
idols.”
the authority of Plato directly, he could neverthe-
approve warmly of the clarity and brevity of Suidas’ remark that
“the object of icastic poetry credible,
is
the true insofar as
and the object of fantastic poetry
the marvelous credible.”
9
One
it is
the marvelous
the false insofar as
is
it is
of the cardinal doctrines of Mazzoni’s
not sufficiently relevant to these pages, was that of the
aesthetics,
importance of the “marvelous credible” in poetry. But the “marvelous credible” for him for
its
own
was
that
which held the
reader’s interest
by
and
itself
sake and delighted him, but Mazzoni’s notion did not
exclude the possibility that the marvelous credible could be the vehicle for important truth so long as the poet
was handling
his material so
was not primary. Allegorical poetry he called had one aspect of its meaning planted on implication
that the assertion of truth a hybrid since
it
of the truth of something in the objective world. ever, that fantastic poetry
He
can be considered either
did agree,
how-
terms of
in
its
genesis in the fantasy or as a finished product.
Tasso’s concern with history trapped
him
lower aesthetic stance even though he used tion as analogy.
He
called
all
a
into a noticeably shal-
broad concept of imita-
imitations similitudes but limited poetic
imitations to similitudes created intentionally and artistically. This can
be seen in
his saying:
imitating
the intention of resembling, and
is
“I say that imitation
be imitated or resembled.”
He
is
artful similitude,
what does not
8
See supra pp. 76-78.
124
He
cannot
disagreed fundamentally, therefore, with
Mazzoni and Segni, for he claimed that not the true can be imitated.
exist
and
false
but only the
could nevertheless say that in imitating truth 0
Mazzoni, Della
difesa,
I,
575.
Idol art
is
Making and P articidarization
alchemy which
a falsifier “like
in the imitation of gold falsifies
metals or like the art of tinters
who
whiteness of the wool or the
Tasso wanted imitations to be called
silk.”
“feignings” and not “falsifications”
ence
—but he showed
ending of
a fable
merited no praise in the historical a poetical
in
mixing colors corrupt the
—seemingly
his true colors in
only a verbal differ-
arguing that the beginning and
should particularly resemble truth. as a poet,
he
He would
have
had he “narrated the true material
said,
mode,” but he was
with having “treated
satisfied
it
in
manner” and “sought out the marvelous” while keeping the
image of history and almost the appearance of truth Tasso’s handling of the terms reveal,
if
nothing
10 .
else,
the penetra-
Mazzoni and of Segni before him. But Tasso, more than Mazzoni, was motivated by a desire to remain in touch with a world
tion of
was pre-eminently credible even though tinctured with marvels. He was a poet making a defense for the kind of art he practiced. However much Mazzoni was or was not a lover of Dante (and the evidence suggests that he undertook Dante’s defense because he was a knower not a lover), his attitude toward poetry remained ambiguous, for he was a philosopher not finally committed even to broad human-
that
istic
concerns. His principal aim in
was
life
the philosophies of Plato and Aristotle; only his vast learning to
theory of
did he bring
it is
poetry was, for him, merely entertainment
true,
of the best minds of a society
worthy of
and business. Yet there was difficult
life,
such
as
a strong strain of
drawing
tions of his distinctions
the attention and the energies
—but not to be confused with the serious
and therefore important things in
which makes
by accident
bear upon the development of a comprehensive
literature. Finally,
—an entertainment,
to achieve a synthesis of
a line
philosophy, statecraft,
Pyrrhonism
between the
in
Mazzoni
finer ironic implica-
and the implications of their crass
literalness.
There should have been few real quarrels between Patrizi and Mazzoni over the theory of imitation, for by making his conceptions complex Mazzoni transcended any simple theory of imitation that Patrizi
would have
poetry rested then
attacked. as
now on
The
strength of the mimetic theory of
ability to
its
make
distinctions
the nature of poetic expression and nonpoetic expression. Patrizi
was able
inherited
to
show
Although
that a shallowly interpreted theory of imitation
from both Plato and
the nature of poetry, he failed in
Aristotle
La deca
was inadequate make
disputata to
the essential elements of poetry are. 10
between
Tasso, Del giudizio, in Opere, XII,
302-304. 25
to
explain
clear
what
Part
Two
UNIVERSALS AND PARTICULARS
t
8
What
a world should be
and what
“THE “is to
it is
business of a poet,” Imlac says in Samuel Johnson’s Rasselas ,
examine, not the individual but the species; to remark general
He
properties and large appearances.
does not
number
the streaks of
the tulip, or describe the different shades in the verdure of the forest;
he
is
to exhibit in his portraits of nature, such prominent and striking
features, as recall the original to
every mind; and must neglect the
minuter discriminations, which one
may
have remarked, and another
have neglected, for those characteristics which are alike obvious to vigilance
made
and to
carelessness.”
these remarks,
speaking of what
“What
is
Matthew Arnold,
is
interesting
not interesting
is
of any kind; that which representation
About
which
is
that
is
a century after
Samuel Johnson
in the preface to
and not interesting
which does not add
Poems
(1853),
in poetry, said:
to our
knowledge
vaguely conceived and loosely drawn;
a
general, indeterminate, and faint; instead of
being particular, precise, and firm.”
On
the surface these
son, in his
two opinions would seem
to be opposite. John-
famous passage, rigidly excluded particularization from
poetry in Neoclassic fashion, and Matthew Arnold, as an heir of
was more interested in particularity than in That the difference between them was not so great as this contrasted pair of opinions would suggest can be found from more detailed and responsible studies of the whole thought structures of the
the Romantic revolution, universality.
129
The Age two men
of Criticism
As Arnold framed
1 .
the proposition, Johnson
certainly have agreed with him, as can be seen
from Johnson’s
pressed dislike of the “general and undefined” portraits of in
Nicholas Rowe’s plays
poetry
is
some kind of
2 .
Literary critics in
ex-
nature
reconciliation of the universal and the particular,
move
the taste and metaphysics of the time
from dead
human
ages have assumed that
all
but the important question for any given period
the other
would almost
center.
The
question
is
the extent to
the emphasis one
whiqh
way
or
partly one of metaphysics
is
and partly one of style. Arnold spoke of knowledge as well as of what was interesting and asserted the interconnection of two things that he might have kept separate, for the appreciation of a poem is not a
poem
matter of the
in itself
only but a relation between the
and the experience that
as conventionalization of experience
ventionalizes. Just as
it
poem con-
synecdoche can be played both ways, by the
rendering of both the particular in general terms and the general in particular terms, to achieve greater textural depth
the interest of the reader toward a whole
upon
felt contrasts
demands some degree of
so
poem may depend in part a poem and
universality, for even
degree or kind of universal. Even the is
interest,
between the particularity or generality of
the disorder or order of the experienced universe.
of the poet
and
classicist
all
Knowledge always words signify some
Johnson
said the business
to examine the species, not the genus.
In revolt though they
were
against Scholasticism, the literary critics
of the Renaissance never penetrated far into metaphysical regions where
odd collocations or organizations of having value for their
own
particulars could be thought of as
sake as monads, or as symbolic or significant
forms, deriving meaning from intension rather than extension. extent that they
were
Platonists, the Renaissance critics
To
the
were loyal to
the Ideal and on occasion to the belief that any connection between particulars cident.
and divine universal was
The
generality
closest
was
a matter of
pure chance or ac-
they came to a universal which was not simply
in their entertaining of Aristotle’s idea that
an organiza-
tion of particulars according to causal necessity might be looked
upon
as a universal; but Aristotle had inextricably linked necessity with
probability, and probability 1
See William K. Wimsatt,
meant
Jr.,
and
Cleanth Brooks, Literary Criticism:
Short History
(New
329.
130
York, 1957),
A p.
generality.
2
Lives,
II,
Brooks, loc.
For the most part the 76. cit.
Cited by Wimsatt and
What
world should be
a
Renaissance critics had nothing of vital significance to say about the balancing of universality and particularity because they had no strong
borrowed from Aristotle. But it will be shown that, operating within their narrow limits, they did arrive at the verge of more elaborate ideas and did subject Aristotelian doctrines to cautious testing. This was in the nature of their method, for the job they set themselves was to understand fully what was contained in
ideas to play against their phrases
Aristotle’s
condensed phrasings.
ized Neoclassical aesthetics
From Horace
Few
their range.
and the classical rhetoricians the Renaissance critics
had learned doctrines of decorum
more
of the ideas that later character-
were not included within
—doctrines
that
seem to us to be
closely connected with those of universality than they did to
Renaissance writers; and from the rhetoricians, Cicero and Quintilian especially,
they had learned the importance of particularity to the
orator for the achieving of enargeia, vividness, in the mastery of the Asiatic style, in
which
case particularity
was
a matter of style rather
than of metaphysics. But in spite of the presence of these other sources for ideas, in almost
all
the significant treatments of the problem of
“the concrete universal” in the Renaissance, the repetition of Aristotle’s
key phrases was the
starting point,
and
all
too often the end point as
well.
History, Aristotle said in the Poetics
what could or should or ought
tells
what did happen, poetry
to have happened. History emphasizes
poetry universals by dealing with events according to
particulars,
probability and necessity. Poetry
is
more philosophic than
regularly were these phrases repeated
—that
—
flatly,
history.
uncritically,
So
and with
would seem on the surface that the problem of the universality of poetry was no problem at all for the Renaissance. Castelvetro, it is true, distinguished poetry from history only slight elaboration
in
its
it
feigning of actions, as opposed to the recording of real ones,
and not primarily the other.
The
in the universality of the
one and the particularity of
writers of the arts of history
which were becoming
popular in the sixteenth century were sometimes unwilling to agree that history had less philosophic import than poetry. Patrizi openly dis-
agreed with Aristotle, and Zinano was not sure that Aristotle had
made found
However, the parade of Aristotle’s opinions few phrases was long and rarely broken. Simple acceptance
the right distinctions. in his
was the rule rather than the exception. Statements that poetry deals with what ought to happen rather than with what did happen, either
The Age elaborated
of Criticism
upon or not elaborated upon, appear
of Trissino, Robortelli,
Speroni,
in the critical writings
Muzio, Lionardi,
Varchi,
Giraldi,
Capriano, Scaliger, Vettori, Minturno, Piccolomini, A. Segni, Tasso, Guastavini, Salviati, A. Guarini, Zinano, Faustino
Pescetti,
can be compiled of those
that poetry
is
in many who made
no doubt,
Beni, and Tassoni and, lists
more philosophic than
3
other places
Summo,
Quite similar
.
use of Aristotle’s assertions
history and that universality in
poetry follows the principles of necessity and verisimilitude. Concernis more philosophic than history, additional comments were made by Maggi as well as by Trissino, Robortelli, and Minturno, by Castelvetro as well as by Segni. Segni is particularly important here for working out a philosophic position
ing the notion that poetry
significant
for poetry
midway between philosophy and
Sidney did a few years 3
later.
G. G. Trissino, Poetica, Bk. V,
Tutte
in
opere (Verona, 1729), II, 98; Francesco Robortelli, In librum Aristotelis de arte poetica explicationes (Flole
rentiae,
pp.
1548),
Speroni,
Giovambattista corso intorno die
Giraldi
al
1740),
Sperone V, 426;
Cinthio,
comporre
tragedie,”
delle
et
90;
86,
Opere (Venezia,
delle
“Dis-
come-
Discorsi
in
(Vinegia, 1554), p. 226, and “Discorso intorno al comporre de i romanzi,” in ibid.,
pp.
58-59;
Benedetto
much
history
as Sir Philip
Riccoboni’s classification of four kinds of
Varchi,
Lezzioni (Fiorenza, 1590), pp. 616-617; Girolamo Muzio, DelVarte poetica, in
alia
24,
poetica (Fiorenza, 1581), pp. 1764-67; see Francesco Patrizi, Della
La deca
poetica:
disputata
(Ferrara,
pp. 161-166; Torquato Tasso, Discorsi del poe?na eroico, in Opere, 1586),
(Pisa, 1823), 22-23, 65-71, an d Discorsi delVarte poetica, in ibid., XII,
XII 2
1
1-2 13;
sovra
see
la
Tasso, Del giudizio
also
Gerusalemme
di
Torquato
Tasso, in ibid., XII, 265, 31 1; for ments by Pescetti, Guastavini, Salviati, see
Lionardo
nato pri?no,
owero
Salviati,
comand
Ulnfari-
risposta delVlnfari-
1
Alessandro Lionardi, Dialogi della inventione poetica (Venetia, 1554), p. 51;
Apologia di Torquato Tasso, (Pisa, in Tasso, Opere, XIX 1827), 133, 294-296, 300; Alessandro Guarini, “Lezione nell’Accademia degl’Invaghiti
G.
in
Rime
(Vinegia,
diverse
P.
Capriano,
Della
1551),
vera
p.
82;
poetica
nato
all
Mantova sopra
il
sonetto,
Doglia,
(Vinegia, 1555), sigs. A4r, B2; for Scaliger, see F. M. Padelford, Select Trans-
di Monsignor della che vaga donna Casa,” in Giovanni della Casa, Opere
from ScaligePs Poetics
(Venezia, 1728), I, 352-353; Gabriele Zinano, Discorso della tragedia (Reggio, 1590), pp. 12-13; Faustino Summo, Dis-
lations
Studies in English, 1905), pp. mentarii in
17;
1,
(Yale
XXVI; New York, Pier Vettori, Com-
primum librum
Aristotelis
de arte poetarum (Florentiae, 1573), pp. 92-94; Antonio Minturno, Uarte poetica (Napoli, 1725), p. 39, and De poeta (Venetiis, 1559), pp. 45, 123; Alessandro Piccolomini, Annotationi nel libro della poetica sigs.
d'Aristotele
B5V, B6r, p.
154;
Ragionamento sopra !
32
(Vinegia,
le
Agnolo
1575), Segni,
cose pertinenti
.
.
.
(Padova, 1600), pp. 41Paolo Beni, Comparazione di Omero, Virgilio e Torquato, in Tasso, Opere,
corsi poetici
42
;
,
XXII In
(Pisa,
1828),
Aristotelis
101,
poeticam
and commentarii
196-223,
(Patavii, 1613), pp. 24-29, 277, 279280; Alessandro Tassoni, Diece libri di
pensieri (Venetia, 1627), p. 473.
What universality
important in
also
is
this
a
world should be
connection. Patrizi cited Aristotle’s
dictum that poetry was more philosophic than history but again dicated his disbelief. Tasso
made important
in-
contributions, and Malatesta
Porta handled the idea curiously. Further restatements or elaborations
can be found in the pages of Mazzoni, Alessandro Guarini,
Summo,
Buonamici, and Paolo Beni. Beni’s remarks are particularly elaborate
4 .
In their use of the Aristotelian concept that universals in poetry
follow necessity and verisimilitude, the Renaissance critics found themselves
most engaged with the differences between history and poetry
and with the particular offshoot of those distinctions, the question
whether the epic or dramatic poet ought to action or invent his
question was
own
what was
select a
known
historical
action. Here, as in Aristotle, the crux of the
Since verisimilitude, or probability, was
real.
which was
usually considered as that
normal in any given
likely or
had
situation or character, interpretations involving statistical averages little
or no force. But
when
the Renaissance
necessity, the causal interlinkage of events,
critic
put
upon
his stress
and related necessity to
probability, he had to ignore the all-pervading concept of universality as
simple generality. However, the evidence here must be handled
gingerly, for the writers sality
who worked
out concepts of poetic univer-
based on causal unities likewise dealt with Aristotle’s other
phrases. Pellegrino, Bulgarini,
and Michele had more to say
universality with necessity and verisimilitude than in
other ideas
5 ,
but otherwise the
lists
are
4
Vincenzo Maggi, in Vincentii Madii Bartholomaei Lombardi Aristotelis librum de poetica communes explanaet
tiones
(Venetiis,
Trissino,
loc.
1550),
pp. 34, Robortelli, De
cit;
13 1;
arte
poetica explicationes, pp. 89, 91; Minturno, De poeta, p. 39; for Castelvetro,
H. B. Charlton, Castelvetro’s Theory of Poetry (Manchester, Eng., 1913),
see
p. 29; Segni, op. cit., pp. 66-67;
Poeticam
Riccoboni,
Antonio
per periphrasim explicans, et nonnullas Ludovici Castelvetrii captiones refellens Aristotelis
La
(Vicetiae, 1585), pp. 43-44; Patrizi,
deca disputata, p. 166; Tasso, Del giudizio, in Opere, XII, 265, and Apologia in
difesa
della
Accademici (Pisa,
1824),
sua
della
Gerusalemme
Crusca,
24-25;
in
agli
ibid.,
Malatesta
X
Porta,
II
much
in equating
making use of the
the same.
Rossi, in Tasso,
What
Opere,
is
XX
ap-
(Pisa,
Giacopo Mazzoni, Della difesa della Comedia di Dante, ed. by Mauro Verdoni and Domenico Buccioli (Cesena, 1688), I, 319; A. Guarini, op. 1828), 92, 167 ;
cit.,
p.
p.
42;
poetici
344;
Summo,
Discorsi poetici,
Francesco Buonamici, Discorsi (Fiorenza,
1597 ),
p.
17 ;
Beni,
Comparazione, in Tasso, Opere, XXII, 222-223, and In Aristotelis poeticam commentarii pp. 277, 279, 281. 5 alia Replica Pellegrino, Camillo risposta degli Accademici della Crusca, in Tasso, Opere, XVIII (Pisa, 1828), Betlisario Bulgarini, Repliche alle 5; risposte del Sig. Orazio Capponi (Siena, 1585; dated 1579 at end of book), p. cui 1 19; Agostino Michele, Disc or so in contra Vopinione di tutti i piu illustri 33
The Age parent on the surface
of Criticism is
the willingness of almost every one of
to follow the lead of Aristotle,
phrases
even
them
the interpretations of the separate
if
were inconsistent with one another.
But saying that almost
the writers agreed with Aristotle
all
the same as saying that they
were
all
in
is
not
agreement or that there was
in their theorizing. Only when we turn to the were played upon these basic Aristotelian themes do we come to the areas in which the critics revealed what their true views were. Does “what should happen” imply moral judgment? Is
no range or diversity variations that
truth an idea or a historical fact?
Are
and truth one and the
reality
same, or are realities particulars and truths universals?
Is
with universal truths or does
what
include accidents?
it
happened more probable than what a universal?
relation
Is
allegorizing the
Is
nature identical has actually
totally invented? Is a causal unity
is
same
as universalizing?
between universals and hero types?
Is
What
is
the
comedy more universal mean merely “general
than tragedy and epic poetry? Can “universal” plot outline”?
What
particularization
is
needed
in
poetry for the sake
of vividness? In the diversity of answers to these and similar questions its reliance upon comments on universality in his Poetics. In treating of the ways of creating characters in comedy, Trissino, in Book VI of his Poetica (1563), said: “A character trait has double
the profile of the period was revealed, not merely in Aristotle’s
modes; that
is,
one
is
common and philosophic, and the other common and philosophic kind
is
particular and rhetorical; and the
that
which
incites
men
to virtue
ought to be the intention of is
which words
that in
all
and dissuades them from
good
vice,
is
which
poets; the particular or rhetorical
are said or things are
done that are consonant
with the nature and disposition of each of the characters introduced into the
poem.” Since modern writers do not use the words “philo-
sophic” (that
is,
“universal”) and “particular” in this way, his distinc-
A whole tangle of ideas is presented in it. must be shown that Trissino did mean “universal” by “philosophic.”
tion should give us pause. It
This
shall
be done in due course by scrutiny of parallel statements in
Muzio and Paolo
Beni.
Here and now
the province of demonstrative rhetoric
The prevailing tendency in human activities and insights scrittori si
del
arte
dimostra come x
34
si
is
must be remembered that to show praise and blame.
Renaissance thought was to subject
all
to praise-blame discriminations, but con-
chiaramente possono scrivere
poetica
it
con molto lode in prosa
le
comedie
e le tragedie
(Venetia, 1592), pp. 29, 38.
What
world should be
a
templative or speculative thought should have been exempt.
Now
the
point
was made by many
dealt
with particulars, the point being that an orator deals with case
histories
a Renaissance writer that oratory like history
and descends to the particular
reasoning
upon them
facts of the case before him,
persuade the jurors.
as particulars in his efforts to
work with
Either judicial or deliberative orators therefore If a council must decide
what strategy to adopt in
particulars.
a military campaign,
the participants have to solve particular problems, not to formulate abstract military theory. A. situations,
and
comic poem
is
independent of specific
as a result its didactic implications, or its expository
meanings, are free-floating and abstract. But admitting that they are
not aimed at particular cases universal (or tion of
what ought
what ought
is
not tantamount to saying that the
to have been done)
to be praised or blamed,
of “ought” to moral obligation.
What is
equivalent to recogni-
is
which would be
a reduction
even more puzzling
is
labeling of character traits relating to nationality, sex, age
determinants of a character’s decorum
A
moral abstraction
is
—“particular
Trissino’s
—the
usual
and rhetorical.”
philosophical, but the reduction of an individual
character to type according to his condition
is
particular. Trissino,
however, would explain that tagging a character according to the
—nationality, country, family or disposition, habits— to define him by
usual adjustments to typicality class,
economic
accidents and
is
class, age,
social
is
not to universalize him.
the Renaissance critic
was thinking of
he embraced doctrines of decorum.
with typicality of sality
traits
It
should not be assumed that
a character’s universality
He
his
when
did not identify universality
according to time, place, or condition. Univer-
he saved for aspects of man’s moral nature.
made frequent use of the philosophic kind of character portrayal. Horace referred to this kind, he decided, in describing what is beautiful, wicked, or useful in human behavior. Obliquely, Trissino suggested that putting stress upon the philosophic mode of character portrayal detracts from the creation of Poets in antiquity, Trissino affirmed,
individual characters and encourages philosophizing about the results of
human
actions.
Apparently he approved of
the philosophic handling of character
this stress.
traits,
he
As examples
listed the
of
punishment
of Paris for breaking the rules of hospitality and the punishment of
Pandar, as
if
a
poetic action properly universalized should exhibit
poetic justice.
But
philosophically
drawn character
in
the same connection he also as the
embodiment
in a
conceived the
marked degree
U5
The Age
of Criticism
of a particular virtue. Nestor, he said,
Antenor prudent, and Hector or the other of these
is
temperate, Ulysses tolerant,
religious, so that
what
ways of being philosophic
is
is
found
in
one
the responsibility
of a character to a moral ideal as against responsibility to the conditions of his class and accidents.
He
“And
added:
good ancient
browsing through the books of other
similarly, in
many
authors, one can discern
similar qualities of char-
acter and be able, as in a spacious theater, to examine the
human
life.
poetry,
which
tions about
Plato,
it
would seem, confirms
in olden times
human
life,
and seek
Trissino was, to the
it
adorned many works, taught
and to achieve
life;
this end, it is sufficient
must be admitted, addressing himself
problem of character creation and not to
more
later genera-
virtue, so far as these general traits are concerned.”
role of universality in poetry. self
whole of
saying that
for the consideration of character traits pro-
vides an education about to flee vice
this belief in
And when,
6
in this place
a discussion of the
elsewhere, he addressed him-
directly to the question, he parroted Aristotle in terms that
suggest either the usual Aristotelian meanings or ones indifferent to this.
In
known main
V
Book
he said the poet
particularly concerned with
is
how
events should have happened. Consequently, except for the
lines of a story, a poetic action
the “ought” element, to
make
it
can be feigned in order to heighten
verisimilar, possible, necessary. It
way that the poet differs from the historian, for how things did happen and the poet how they
is
in this
the historian
tells
should have
happened. 7
But Girolamo Muzio,
in
his
well-turned verse DeH’arte poetica
(1551), had said that the poet should leave matters of truth to the historian
and should reveal the universal under the guise of private
names. Showing the universal, he
said,
is
what we should do and what we should not phrases
is
unmistakable in
totle’s universal
his lines,
indicating to the reader do.
The echo
of Aristotle’s
and yet Afuzio connected Aris-
with praise and blame. 8 Over half a century
later,
Paolo Beni likewise connected the two ideas plainly. Both the poet
and the to
historian, he said,
“descend to particular matters,” the historian
what was done and the poet
What
After asking,
that the poet narrates in such a 6 1
Trissino, op.
cit.,
II,
to
what ought
223.
way
“as to 8
36
he answered
remind us of some certain
Muzio, DelVarte poetica
diverse, p. 82.
Ibid., p. 98.
to have been done.
does “ought to be done” mean?
in
Rime
What
a
world should be
form whence mortals can in each kind of situation contemplate what ought to be avoided and what followed and imitated.” 9 The idea or
and epic
basic kinds of situation are, of course, those of comic, tragic,
poems. Comedies give instruction to the
run their
to
lives;
common
people about
how
tragedy governs kings and rulers; epic poetry pro-
vides examples for heroes. Beni added an interesting side remark that a
poet
not concerned primarily with what cannot be done.
is
Some men
object, Beni said, that in detaching poetry
Aristotle allied fell
from
torian
too
it
much with
The
into Scylla.
relating
dialectic,
and so
question can be asked,
what
is
from history
in avoiding
What
Charybdis
prevents the his-
verisimilar, considering particularly that
work
often have only legends and reputed accounts to
historians
with and
as a result
have to follow the verisimilar? Aristotle,
it
ap-
peared to Beni, implied that historians are not concerned with universal; he
was
certain that universals belong to philosophers and that
poets invade the territory of philosophy
when they concern
with universality. According to Beni, by following universality,
we
to praise
we
classes of
men
for
whom
the poet can furnish ex-
are back to Beni’s “ought” as “moral obligation,” back
and blame. But Beni was aware that there might be
the ointment.
The
added
his
demands for
human conduct, but when
verisimilitude and necessity, his terms
“do not seem so much to apply to these three ideas with verisimilar and necessary action.” Beni had
much more
particularity of poetry
place
11 ,
but nothing in
virtuous behavior this place.
a fly in
three genres of poetry, he said, provide us with
“three ideas and very noble forms” for Aristotle
themselves
concept of
can reduce poetry to three genres, each representing
one of the three amples. So
this
is
Whatever
than
this to
as to
say about the universality and
and history, to be dealt with his
in
its
proper
treatment of poems as idealizations of
inconsistent with his Aristotle
any form
10
meant by
his
warping of the concept
in
“ought to have happened,”
he quite certainly did not mean “what should have happened hero were to act according to the highest degree of virtue.”
if
the
Very few
of the literary critics of the sixteenth century did, actually, create such a farfetched reading for this specific passage in Aristotle’s text,
great
many
which B
this distortion
was congruent.
Beni, In Aristotelis poeticam
mentarii
but
a
of them did assent to general attitudes toward poetry to
p. 277.
com-
10 11
Ibid., p.
279.
See infra, p. 185. 37
The Age It
is
of Criticism
important to note that another interpretation of Aristotle’s
much
“ought” frequently found in the Renaissance led to
end and was related to cording to
the same
Acshows “what ought to have
in point of origin in Platonic doctrine.
it
this interpretation,
when
a poet
happened,” the universalizing that occurs
is
a heightening of reality
by transcending mundane affairs. The poet universalizes by making events more striking or delightful than they are in the reality we know. On one hand, as can be seen in the distinctly Platonic renderings of Agnolo Segni, this heightening can be no more nor less than an expression of the world of particulars which makes them conform “perfectly” or entirely to the dimensions of the shadowy or an approaching of reality
Idea behind them.
On
on one occasion,
the other hand, as with Tasso
can mean the substitution of events that are delightful for historical
it
events that are
less so.
we
But before
look at Segni’s distinctly Platonic renditions,
we
should be aware of the at best slight difference in net effect between Segni’s ideas
and what had already become standard doctrine
time. Trissino believed the philosophically
embodiment
in a
degree of virtue in
marked degree of is
drawn character
a particular virtue,
and
G.
a heightening of virtue. Similarly,
1 555, in a passage devoted to an explanation of the great
at the
to be an a
marked
P. Capriano,
moral
utility
of poetry, interpreted Aristotle’s “ought” phrase as universality
means of the heightening of example, the teaching of moral
ideals
by by
the universalizing of actions. But “ought” to Capriano also explicitly
meant “according to reason,” which was the implied meaning for most sixteenth-century writers. Capriano could say that a poet should reduce his historical materials “to the
to the
end of teaching us
moral value of poetry this latter
is
how
Universal Ideas of actions and manners,” to live the
good
life.
He
said the actual
greater than that of moral philosophy “since
teaches us only with bare and abstract precepts derived
merely from formal action and practice, while poetry,
as the perfect
and best instructor, the true nurse and most ardent lover of our wellbeing, taking us
by
the hand as
if
we were
by means of
children
its
use of the feigned and represented but perfect example, shows us virtue in a mirror, guides us to the cognition of
it,
and by indicating
to us
how
Thus
for a thinker of the Renaissance like Capriano these
to achieve
it
renders us most prudent with
of universality could merge into one. “Capriano, op.
U8
cit., sig.
A^x.
The
all
historical
sweetness.”
12
two views
kind of poem,
What Capriano remarked,
which since
it
is
world should be
not subject to the principles of verisimilitude
the base of morality.
is
a
The moral kind
can add instruction to
of poetry
But
delight.
at the
is
the greater
same time, for
Capriano what was morally instructive was almost identical to what
was reasonable.
He
gave himself away
as a Platonist
by
calling not
only for “Universal Ideas of actions and manners” but also for “perfect” examples. In the Phaedrus tradition, mankind, cut off from perfection
by the conditions of bodily
approach the
existence, strives always to
perfect and relies on intimations of moral beauty or other manifestations of transcendental perfection to lead
quest for beatitude.
shows
his
The
More
is
tellingly revealed
he discusses the love lyrics of Petrarch, that
Petrarch was not being a
realist
love feelings for Laura but a
in his eternal
indebtedness to Plato.
practical application of Segni’s Platonism
in his conclusion, while
and of
him onward
plainly than Trissino and Capriano, Segni
and was not describing
was creating
his real-life
a picture of a perfect lover
lady of singularly heightened virtue, even though in order to
give a concrete imitation of these models he had to have resort to the accidents of nature and history.
Segni
said:
“Human
and those of nature are never entirely
affairs
what they ought to be, or perfect; but all have defects, one here and another there, some more and some less: this is the fault of matter and of our corrupt nature and the contraries of which we are composed.
among us but is understood and perceived by the intellect. And this, among other things, gave occasion to Plato to posit his Ideas, since with the power of his mind he searched in So perfection
is
never found
things for perfection and, not finding
declared the existence of Ideas, that existing outside of things
human
intellect
is,
it
there,
and outside of the human mind, so that the
could find an object or be able to
object conforming to
its
he determined and
the most perfect nature of things
perfection.
The
come
to rest in an
Ideas outside of things are
therefore their most perfect nature, intelligible and certain in intellect, either in
that
is
the
human
or,
according to Plato, in another intellect
superhuman, divine, and
eternal, like those eternal substances
that in his opinion exist in the divine mind. This perfecting of things,
we
say,
is
the cause and
first
principle of poetry,
when
narrated in terms of the all-perfect, and each item in
materials are
its
highest and
most sovereign form, for such speech must necessarily be fabulous, not history, since
among
us there
is
false
and
no perfection, or any 39
The Age
of Criticism
semblance of what ought to be; but tion and
truth,
its
ments of
poetry.”
it is
13
theory (which, taken
his
when This as a
a fable imitates that perfec-
is
one of Segni’s main
whole,
one of the clearest
is
Renaissance statements of Aristotle’s meaning, in spite of
and from
trappings),
flows his distinction between
it
state-
its
Platonic
philosophy,
poetry, and history. Segni put his stress on the poet’s holding an action
up
to contemplating or
knowing,
a phrase
he repeated several times.
History, he had said in an earlier ragionamento
,
lets
know
us
every-
thing an Alexander or a Caesar did or suffered as single magnanimous
and brave men. But poets “contemplate strong and magnanimous
man
and the wise, and what he would form and perfect Idea and all this in
in his universality, or the just
say and do ... in terms of the person particularly
“what those things This
is,
its
named by them.” Poets show
are in their excellence
in feigned things
and perfect exemplar.”
14
of course, going beyond the arranging of particulars with a
upon what
highlight put
and Alexander conceived
seem to do
that.
is
relevant to their universality, for Caesar
as single
magnanimous and brave men would
Segni wanted a particularization of nothing but the
conceded that such perfection
attributes of perfection, although he
among corrupt
was almost impossible
particulars
to find.
Varchi, more like Tasso than like Segni, put stress on the heightening of reality in order to gain delight for the reader. Varchi said that poets should not “for the most part consider things but
how
nature, though not
beyond the reason-
able or verisimilar, so that they can procure for mortal
more
utility
actually do
they ought to be done, even to the extent of conceding
them many things beyond
to
how men
but also more delight and wonder.”
man
not only
15
In the youthful version of his discourses on heroic poetry, the Discorsi delFarte poetica (c. 1565?), Tasso said, in a passage dealing
with
how
a poet gives his
chosen material form and poetic disposition:
“But because that which principally constitutes and determines the nature of poetry and makes
it
different
from history
is
the considera-
tion of things not as they have been but as they should have been,
having regard rather to the probable in universals rather than to the truth in particulars, the poet should investigate, before he does any-
thing treat
else,
to see
whether any event
would give
13
A. Segni, op.
14
Ibid ., p. 23.
cit.,
40
greater delight pp. 64-67.
in the material he has
chosen to
had happened otherwise, with
if it 15
Varchi, Lezzioni, pp. 616-617.
What more of
either
that could have
is,
at his
of the events of this
all
happened better
some other way
in
and reduce the quantity of accidents
manner he
believes to be
with truth that
is
—he should
better, paralleling
altered.”
16
Only
in
in the material in the
what
delight compelled the difference
this insight that the greater
between what fact “ought” to be
poetry and in actual happenings. Universality, as
we may
in
paraphrase,
well as greater abstractness. In this passage, truth
term that Tasso applied only to particular
The main problem sality as a
entirely feigned
one significant phrase, in one
poetry and universality, did Tasso reveal
be beauty
is
handlings of the relations of poetry and history, of
of several of his
a
kind that he finds
will change and reshape, without any concern for truth or for
history,
may
any other
the verisimilar or of the marvelous or for
reason whatsoever; and that
world should be
a
in trying to isolate a
is
historical fact.
conception of poetic univer-
heightening of normal qualities
is
in distinguishing
it
from
ordinary normative conceptions, and in large measure the distinction
cannot be clearly made. class, that
ceived. as the
If a universal is
most perfect instance
We
is
the most perfect instance of a
also the
norm, or can be so con-
tread close to the line of the conception of the universal
composite image, Zeuxis’ perfect female form come upon by
putting together the ideal parts of several ing of delight
is
doubt, be achieved merely relevancies.
young women. The heighten-
only one kind of heightening. Heightening may, no
by
the elimination of accidents and
ir-
But where, precisely, did Francesco Buonamici stand in
saying (1597), while arguing with Castelvetro, that the poet does not so
much
follow a particular as
he presupposes a particular, but one that looks to the idea that for he does not describe
it
exactly as
actions and behavior to the degree of
and which cannot be attributed
less
it
is
or as
it
acts,
is
but
universal, raises
the
which human nature can be capable to them than to another; so that in
imitating in a given subject this or that particular fact, such as a pious act
by raising the act by considering what the cause was of this habit of piety, which in actuality did not exist, he comes to consider it according to his idea abstracted from the material and universally. In this way he considers the particular universally; and that which of Aeneas, he deals with and imitates the particular, but, to a higher degree than
is
to
in itself universal
Aeneas and to 18
Tasso, Discorsi
it
actually had and
and perhaps not found with the material he attributes
a particular case, just as dell’ctrte
philosophers say that geometry
poetica, in Opere, XII, 211.
The Age
of Criticism
considers a natural line mathematically without matter and perspective.
The
opposite view considers the mathematical line naturally; and the poet
does both of these at the same time, leaving aside the particular conditions
and considering
first
the idea, and then afterward applying
particular, just as a painter does,
tion of the a
man with
universal
who
members, of the composition of colors and all
it
to a
known
will arrive at his idea of the proporlines,
and will feign
the beauties that do exist in the materials but are nevertheless
—depicting, for instance, Venus, whom he has never seen and who
perhaps never even existed, and from the beauties resident in the material
he will form the idea and make
it
that particular picture; and even
when
particular, creating it is
it
as a
chance he sees something the changing of which would not appreciably he will strive to improve
it.
property of
naturally well mirrored,
The
if
by
alter the effigy
poet works similarly, and so
both of them both universalize and particularize. 17
which in spite of the turgidities of Buonamici’s prose is one of the most complex and valuable treatments of the subject in the period of the Renaissance, Buonamici focused his attention on the In this passage,
necessity of uniting universality and particularity in poetry, while asserting, in contrast to Castelvetro, the qualities of universality that
The
universal aspect is made manifest not only by the embodying his idea in particular matters, so that no particulars are given which do not exemplify the idea, but also by heightening qualities found in historical subject matter. If Aeneas was by nature pious, according to history or legend, the poet makes him all the more pious. The poet makes the world’s dross metal golden, as Sidney suggested. When Aristotle said that poetry deals with what ought to have been done and history with what was done, Buonamici thought he meant this heightening, even though many other ideas about the universality of poetry were present in his mind. Buonamici was not thinking about norms of behavior in wanting Aeneas to be made ever more pious nor was he thinking about probability.
hold interest.
poet’s directly
—
What
can be found in Buonamici’s system,
cept of the poet’s
work
as in Segni’s,
is
the con-
as the presentation of a Platonic Idea. In the
modern commentaries on the Poetics Robortelli had pointed out that Plato had shown in the Sophist that a painter should always aim at “the Idea and paint things more beautiful than 18 they are.” Although among the many writers who repeated Arisvery
first
of the
,
.
17
Buonamici, op.
cit.,
p. 48.
.
.
“Robortelli,
tions 142
p. 91.
De
arte poetica explica-
What totle’s
poet as
phrase that “the historian
tells
world should be things as they happened, the
they should have happened” only a minority paid
to the poet’s action,
a
much heed
need to jack up quality or intensity or beauty of
and most stressed instead
real-life
a negative sort of universality
from
deletion of accident, the ghost of Plato nevertheless hovered close
and nudged the hand of Buonamici
as well as that of
Tasso and Segni.
9
v
Tasso’s Perfect Exemplars
THE
intersection of the concept of poetic universality as moral im-
perative with that of universality as heightened reality,
or reality
transcending reality in the form of a Platonic Idea, was the point of residence of the belief, most readily to be ascribed to the aesthetics of
poem
Tasso, that the central character of a heroic
emplary behavior ideal
should exhibit ex-
one of the moral virtues and that the
in respect to
hero should be a composite of
all
the virtues needed in a prince
or leader, a mirror in which contemporaries in executive positions
could see
how
their social
and moral
easy to show, as tangentially
we
affairs
should be managed.
have already done, that
this
It is
kind of
thinking was one of the by-products in the Renaissance of speculating
on
Plato’s Ideas.
But
we
one of the forces most represented
in
As
of
it,
the
human
beings
abstractions
of
and uncomplicated and incapable of generating out
of the conflicts within their
of princely virtues. True, he his
a result
poems became stick-men, walking
virtues, flat
own
natures the unfolding actions that
were more than melodrama. Hamlet and
both theory and practice, to the
vitiating, in
poetic activity of the Renaissance.
moral
was
are also likely to feel that this doctrine
group based
is
their case
is
a
a tragic,
world away from an exemplar not an epic, hero; and Tasso
more on Aeneas than on
Achilles,
who
puzzled them. Significantly enough, the example of complex hero in epic poetry since Tasso’s
Lucifer in Paradise Lost.
day that comes most readily to mind
Modern man
has avoided the issue
is
by writing
novels instead of epic poems.
That the theory of the epic hero
as perfect
exemplar was closely
related to the Renaissance concept of the universality of poetry should 1
44
Tasso's Perfect Exemplars be obvious, especially
when
connections with Platonic Ideas are
its
understood. In fact, the relation will no doubt seem so close that discussion of
it
here runs the danger of appearing to be mere repeti-
tion or useless expansion of
what was shown
The theory was not unique
to the Renaissance or to Neoclassicism,
its
in the preceding chapter.
presence full-blown in the 1548 commentaries of Robortelli
indication that tury. It
is
it
and
is
an
had been slowly gaining force in the preceding cen-
properly enough associated with the
Gemsalemme
liberata
of Tasso, since that was the major heroic poem in which the formula was employed. But Robortelli’s efforts to demonstrate that it was well grounded in the literary theories of antiquity can be convincing that in this respect as in others what the Renaissance critic did was to
bring into focus assortments of doctrine that ancient writers had often intended but had never systematized or agreed upon.
commenced
Robortelli
his
treatment of the idea with Aristotle’s
recommendation that character
The
be heightened.
traits
tragic poet,
Robortelli declared, should provide “a perfect exemplar of the char-
which
acter traits
are to be described.”
us with an absolute example of wrath.
He should, for instance, provide He should not try to delineate
an individual exactly but should look to nature (that
and should
select the individual
is,
to the type)
example best representing the
trait.
method with that Xenophon in the Cyropaedia the warping of history in moral history making to show what ought to have been rather than what was. Robortelli drew the ends of his circle together by pointing out that Cicero had determined in his Orator ad Brutum that Plato had also embraced this method and had called the resulting perfect representaRobortelli was not reluctant to identify the poet’s
used by
,
tions “Ideas”
—“the
genes this
form of its kind.” Robortelli presented from Athenaeus, Theopompus, and Hermo-
ultimate
a collection of citations
ideon) to
show
that others had defined Plato’s Ideas in way. The subject matter of poetry for Robortelli was not the ( Peri
individual
man but man
that Aristotle had
in his
common
meant an application
form, and he did not doubt to poetry
painters heighten character traits in this his day,
he associated
when
he said that
way. As was customary
in
done by painters with Cicero’s book of De inventione of the method of
this universalizing
description in the second
Zeuxis of Croton. Robortelli concluded that
it
would seem
that a poet bent
on present-
ing a perfect picture of wrath could never use anything that had *45
The Age happened
actually
theory and
history;
in
realistic
of Criticism
practice,
was example of what
but he compromised between pure for the practical application
principle, he decided,
that the poet
excellent
existed in
was
of the
free to choose the
any given
class
most
without violating
the principle. 1
Robortelli later returned to the point in
commenting on
Aristotle’s
statement that Sophocles created characters as they ought to be but Euripides
Homer as
made them
as
they actually
are.
Here Robortelli argued that was in actuality “but
did right in portraying Achilles not as he
what the
greatest kind of hero could be.” This Robortelli maintained
knew that the detractors of Homer had claimed that Homer had made the history he was narrating incredible by heightening the character of Achilles. Robortelli added: Not only did Virgil even though he
heighten his hero’s character in a like manner, but also the creation of ideal characters
that readers feel
was the standard practice in antiquity. He believed more admiration and are more moved by perfect ex-
amples than by portraits of ordinary people. Perfect characters are those
whom we
concluded, in
“is
hope to emulate. “For what king or prince,” Robortelli
not incited to virtue on reading the education of Cyrus
Xenophon and does not hope
like
him.”
2
The
in Robortelli in
the century
is
difference
that
between
1548 and as
it
by
this
imitating
him he can become
complex of
ideas as
it is
found
appears in Paolo Beni at the end of
actually very slight.
In fact, Castelvetro was almost the only critic of the century specifically objected to the stress traits
upon
who
selection of perfect character
for poetry. Others approached the question of the universality of
poetry from other directions but without directly trying to under-
mine Robortelli’s doctrine. In the years between Robortelli and Tasso, Robortelli’s views
were more standard and accepted than the conone of his dialogues on poetic invention
trary. Alessandro Lionardi, in
mouth of Sperone Speroni an account of the way which poets show how captains or princes ought to conduct them-
(1554), put in the in
selves in
all
the activities and situations they are likely to encounter. 3
Capriano said that a poet, by means of a “feigned and represented but perfect example, shows us virtue in a mirror.”
Many
writers of the cinquecento in attempting to
their categories of logical discourse interpreted ’Robortelli,
De
arte poetica explica-
2 8
tiones, p. 91.
146
it
as
fit
poetry into
proof by means
Ibid., p. 296.
Lionardi, op.
cit.,
p. 22.
Tasso's Perfect Exemplars of example, even though, in the tradition they inherited
Thomas Aquinas had
of Scholasticism,
ample was the weakest of
from the Age
by
established that proof
ex-
kinds of proof and had consequently given
all
poetry the lowest position in
The Humanists
his scale.
in reversing
order of nobility retained the idea that poetry functioned through
this
who
example. Mario Equicola,
“we esteem
said that
poets to excel
all
other writers,” also said that poetry “reduces to our use the examples
of
many
things.”
4
Varchi fully discussed the use of example in poetry,
example poetry’s logical instrument and
calling
support
asserting, in
of his main claim that the function of poetry was to
make mankind
blessed and perfect, that the poet’s “office
—that
—
things that render
man good and
happy.” His two ways of doing or
by
this
injecting virtues, and both
to imitate
is
virtuous,
and
is,
were by removing mankind’s
methods
feign
consequence
as a
vices
called for the use of clear
examples arranged so that not only the acts but also their consequences
were understandable. Once to
found
pile of ideas, are
5
mode
Other discussions
.
use of example can be
Viperano and Bodin on the writing of history,
history, Castelvetro, Tasso,
but to follow is
by
of proof
in Speroni, Lionardi, Capriano, Luisino, Robortelli’s treatise
history,
it
under the
be found the principles of demonstrative rhetoric
of poetry regarded as a
on
again, buried
this side
on
Patrizi’s treatise
Mazzoni, Summo, Buonamici, and Beni
road would take us too far
afield.
To
6 ,
be sure,
evident that the line of reasoning which turned poetry into
proof by example did not inevitably lead to proof by example through the selection
by the poet of
Tasso’s literary speculation,
it
perfectly virtuous heroes. Principally, in
was the hero of
should be the perfect exemplar of
all
a heroic
virtues.
4
Mario Equicola, Institutioni al comporre in ogni sorte di rime della lingua volgare, con della pittura
gorie circa le
uno eruditissimo discorso e con molte segrete allemuse e la poesia (Milano,
1541), sigs. Bi, B3. 6
Varchi, Lezzioni
6
See
pp. 572-576.
Opere, V, 427; Lionardi, op. cit., p. 42; Varchi, Lezzioni, PP* 573 57
Robortelli, in
Artis
De
scribenda historia liber,
historicae
penus
(Basileae,
898;
I,
Giovanni Antonio Vipe-
1579), rano,
De
Artis
historicae
scribendi
historia
penus,
I,
liber,
848;
in
Jean
Bodin, Methodus ad facilem historia-
rum
cognitionem,
Artis
in
historicae
Francesco Patrizi, De historia dialogi X, in Artis historicae penus,
penus,
Speroni,
poem only who
I,
516;
I,
6;
Ludovico
varie critiche, ed.
(Lione, del
Castelvetro, Opere by L. A. Muratori
1727), p. 215; Tasso, Discorsi eroico, in Opere, XII, 143;
poema
Mazzoni, Della
difesa,
II,
305;
Summo,
Discorsi poetici, pp. 11-12; Buonamici, op. cit., p. 81; Beni, Comparazione, in
Tasso, Opere, XXII, 146, 199.
147
The Age
of Criticism
was the proper one. The equivalent of the which should be perfect) in poetry, he believed,
Castelvetro’s objection
Platonic Idea (that
should be found
of action, not in a static character.
in the structure
His most pertinent passage
connection
in this
mind an
true that the poet should keep in
which he ought
is:
“Moreover,
it is
not
idea of perfect virtue and
compose
good poem. What he ought to keep in mind, in my opinion, is an idea of the most perfect and delightful history, from which his mind must never swerve when he is engaged in composing a poem.” 7 As a corollary to this perfect vice,
to contemplate to
a
proposition, Castelvetro advanced the idea that characters could their functions fully
poem
fulfill
without being perfect exemplars. “To make the
perfect and like that idea,” he said, “he will have to introduce
persons of different kinds, sometimes perfectly valiant men, sometimes perfect cowards, and sometimes these
two extremes; otherwise
men who
his story will
are
means between
be only slightly possible
or slightly marvelous.” Furthermore, Castelvetro was even willing that his principle
be used to
method of Zeuxis and
question the
call into
to argue that “the art of painting does not consist in creating a figure
beautiful or ugly in the highest degree, but in
sembles the
real,
the living, and the natural.”
making one
that re-
8
In his Poetica , Castelvetro returned often to expression of doubts
about the ut pictura poesis formula. Aristotle had said that painters
ought to find perfect examples of beauty. Here was an opportunity of the kind Castelvetro was always looking for, the chance to
that less
show
that
from impeccable. Castelvetro thought Aristotle’s advice to poets to follow the painter’s method was useunless he could in addition specifically tell how perfection was judgment was
Aristotle’s
far
formed. Castelvetro wanted no rigid concept of perfection; he said that
when we
find even
more ideas about what perfection is what ideal feminine beauty is. At
try to decide
but
his
human nature we can than among those who
are dealing with the diversity of
remarks are interesting.
He
said:
this
“And
point he digressed,
Perino del Vaga,
Florentine painter of great fame in our day, was able,
beauty of beauty, to Virgin, so 7
by using
a
the
wife which he fixed in his mind as an example of supreme draw the faces of many women, especially pictures of the that one could find in all of them only one kind of supreme
his
Andrew Bongiorno,
Commentary on
“Castelvetro’s
the Poetics of Aris-
totle” (unpublished thesis, Cornell versity, 1935), p. 79. 8
48
Ibid. , p. 80.
Uni-
Tasso's Perfect Exemplars beauty. But Giotto, another Florentine painter,
mended
in times past,
(in the Portico of
who was much com-
would not or could not portray
San Pietro
Rome) with
at
all
the Apostles
the same identical ex-
awe and fear on their faces when the Lord suddenly appeared to them walking on the water, but he assigned to each one particularly a distinct expression of wondrous fear, nor was he able to judge which in his opinion was the most praiseworthy.” 9 The besetting sin of Castelvetro was his willingness to compromise his own set of beliefs in order to win a point against established authority. His intent in this particular argument was to destroy the
pression of
imputed
between poetry and painting, and to do so he had
parallel
who
to use arguments that played into the hands of his opponents
wanted perfect exemplars used the painter’s job
is
while the poet’s job character
traits;
which
work
To
two kinds of
of the
be consistent with
that
beauty,
is
to represent goodness of mind, that
is
so that the
really comparable.
show
in poetry, for he tried to
to represent goodness of body,
is,
artificers
good is
not
his theoretical system,
he
should have said that poets use characters whose actions will constitute a
good
fable.
The
terms “goodness of mind” and “beauty of mind”
presumably interchangeable, and goodness of mind
are
mere heightening of any moral
is
not the
good or bad. But Castelvetro partly protected himself by his argument that “goodness” can be manifested in many different ways in the world of particulars. And he added a significant corollary to his meaning when he stated that the painter’s perfection
does not
creating a likeness since cellent painters insights
when he remarked
were not
that
we
real-life
of a beginning painter
that he
had
raised,
is
and not
he concluded
original line of attack.
all
beauty but
the subjects of
was
all
in
ex-
close to important
can readily observe that statues do
people around us do, but the mark
may
find himself creating imitations
like people.
this particular
Why,
so
Castelvetro
alike.
look more alike than the
that are like statues
in creating perfect
lie
if this
would look
quality,
Undaunted by the doubts he argument by returning to his
he asked, did Aristotle not say a poet
should have in mind a perfect example of a fable, “since
it is
just as
possible to find a perfect example of a fable as a perfect example of a character trait”? Characters exist for action,
Modern 9
literary critics,
it
Castelvetro, Poetica d’Aristotele vul-
garizzata et sposta
(Basilea,
not action for character.
would seem, should applaud
Castelvetro’s
341-343.
1576), pp.
149
The Age having taken
of Criticism
this stand, for
he probed some of the chief weaknesses of
the thought structure of his age. But
H.
B. Charlton scolded Castelvetro
for his opposition to “idealization” (that
exemplars). Charlton’s belief Was, “Art
by
dressed, but
art nature
drawn
is
to
the creation of perfect
is,
not nature to advantage
is
Charlton’s master
ideal.”
its
who looked always for the perfect example of beauty way made the ideal and the actual interdependent. At the
poet was one
and
in that
same time, Charlton commended Castelvetro for realizing that the moral interpretation, which he thought Castelvetro was duped into accepting,
apparent
irrelevant in aesthetic criticism
is
is
that Castelvetro was unwilling to
10
But what should be
.
commit himself
fully to
Platonic ideas of beauty.
was not
Castelvetro
entirely alone in
most violently anti-Aristotelian
his
for Patrizi, the
stand,
century, likewise held up
critic of his
Now
to scorn the doctrine of the “perfect exemplar.”
usually a Platonist, but he believed that the conceiving of
was precisely what
acters as Ideas of moral behavior
intended. His effort
was
to
show
that Aristotle
Patrizi
was
model char-
Aristotle had
was wrong. In attack-
ing Aristotle’s distinction between poetry and history on the basis of
what ought
to be
and what
is,
he scornfully asked
And
high rank ought to be.
good king and
a
Nor would
supply.
Any
his people,
Homer
his
baron of
he often titled
as
did not create ideal char-
Tasso to argue that
Patrizi allow
be excused because he had
a
form “Agamemnon and Greek camp after the Idea of
good shepherd of
them”? His simple answer was that acters.
what
did he really
the other kings and captains of the a
Homer made
if
Achilles spotless so that he could be an example of
left part
Homer
could
of his meaning for the reader to
by
that argument, Patrizi an-
Homer
or any other poets of early
writer can be defended
swered.
So what
Patrizi denied
was
that
antiquity had ever created any characters as ideal types. Consequently,
he concluded that Aristotle could not have based
on
practice.
And, he added,
Greek, Latin, and
with the
sole exception of the
Scipione Gonzaga, “has
so-much-praised Idea.” zaga’s 10
poem
is
made
He
Charlton, Castelvetro' s
Aristotle
had created the
uniformly disregarded
it,
rule,
and no one,
Fidamente of Tasso’s patron and friend his principal characters
conform
to this
conceded that the main character of Gon-
“informed by
150
after
Italian poets all
his generalization
all
the virtues, chivalric as well as moral,
Theory of Poetry pp. ,
38-39.
Tasso's Perfect Exemplars
and
in addition
to a man nobly and faithfully in way from these.” The implication is
by those pertaining
love, and never deviating in any
was never taken seriously Gonzaga circle. Furthermore, Patrizi argued, if Aristotle’s “that which could be” is equated merely with “that which is possible,” the evidence from poets themselves would again be found to run counter, for poets gain effects from the impossible and the wonderful far more often than do historians. There is also no profit in arguing that in antiquity what would now be considered impossibilities actually seemed possible to the average man, since the average man must have learned his wonders from the poets, not the poets from the average man 11 But now to turn to Tasso, in whose critical writings the idea of the that the doctrine of the “perfect exemplar”
or employed
by any
poets outside of the current
.
perfect exemplar reached first
book of the Disc orsi
its
del
culmination. In the introduction to the
poema
immediately and unequivocally
eroico
Tasso presented himself
propounder of the doctrine that
as a
poetry, especially heroic poetry, presents ideal images of character.
He
even supposed that readers would want to read discourses upon heroic poetry because such discourses would contain talk about ideal characters.
their
Tasso stated boldly that readers of heroic poetry “seek to make
minds conform to the example” of virtues such
as
temperance,
bravery, prudence, justice, faith, piety, and religion to be found in
poems “in order to acquire them as a result of prolonged exercise with them or through divine grace.” Tangentially, Tasso also compared his task of creating a body of critical theory about heroic poetry to the task of Zeuxis in fashioning the Helen of Croton; and in Platonic fashion he remarked that the Idea of a perfect heroic poem should be the exemplar and ideal example of such a
In his youthful treatise later into the Discorsi del
on the poetic
poema
perfect virtues.
was impelled
He
tained
by means of
was
in tragic
poetry the “illustrious” (that
wonder-provoking) quality was ob-
upon perfect characters
to achieve a similar
Tragic characters can be of middling virtue, but characters in
“Patrizi, 163.
it
element needed in poetry that
surprises or unexpected turns of events, but the
epic poet had to rely effect.
expanded twenty years
to the creation of characters exhibiting
thought that
glittering, attention-holding,
is,
art,
12 .
eroico , Tasso indicated that
in order to provide the “illustrious”
the heroic poet
poem
La dec a
disputata, pp. 160-
“Tasso, Discorsi del poema eroico in Opere, XII, 7-9.
The Age epic poetry must
of Criticism
show extreme forms
Tasso returned to the same
of virtue
13 .
In the later Discorsi ,
idea. Tasso’s theories of
poetry were based
upon heroic poetry, and for him, as for most other critics of his time, heroic poetry was defined as the imitation of an illustrious action. The hidden shift comes in his substitution of perfect characters and heightened character traits for actions, but it was his concern for heroes that led him to his conclusions 14 He never completely lost sight of the fact that perfect characters were intended to provide grandeur .
He
and splendor. beautiful
among
said that the heroic poet should
from among
the marvelous.
beautiful
He
choose the most
from
the most marvelous
objects,
should always try to heighten novelty and
grandeur and should avoid
all
that
is
low, popular, or improper.
The
poet should “add loftiness to the mediocre, notice and splendor to the obscure, artifice to the plain, ornament to the true, and authority 15
to the false.”
In the Discorsi delParte poetica Tasso seemed to be thinking only
of the allotting of one outstanding virtue to each character (for ex-
ample, piety to Aeneas, military bravery to Achilles, prudence to Ulysses, loyalty to Amadigi, constancy to Bradamonte) that
all
these virtues might be
work he was somewhat more
combined explicit.
in
He
but he granted
;
one character
16 .
In the later
had decided that the method
of parceling out virtues to different characters (industry to Ulysses,
confidence to Diomedes, the art of archery to Teucer) was a questionable one, and he felt that Virgil had done
what the proper heroic
poet should do by making Aeneas a composite showpiece of
main
virtues
—
a
model of
piety, religion, continence, bravery,
all
the
magnani-
mity, and other such virtues. Tasso’s conclusion was that “in forming a cavalier” Virgil It
was
“came
closer to the proper idea than
Homer
did.”
17
inevitable that the Renaissance critics should perceive an
overlapping between the classical concept of decorum and the pressure for the creation of morally ideal characters.
was firm
the relation
in Tasso,
who
The
recognition of
tended to think of “decorous”
behavior as behavior fitting to dignified and respectable men. point, he
worried about an assertion by Maximus of Tyre that Nestor
was an image of perfect
virtue, for he felt that
“Tasso, Discorsi dell’arte poetica in Opere, XII, 206-207. 14
in
Tasso, Discorsi del
Opere XII, 15
At one
50.
Ibid., pp. 60-61. *
5*
poema
eroico
1(5
XII, 17
XII,
Nestor was too old
Discorsi delVarte poetica
in
Opere
206-207.
Discorsi del 105-106.
poema
eroico, in Opere,
Tasso's Perfect Exemplars for the job and that an all-virtuous hero in a heroic
man
poem
should be a
capable of heroic physical actions. Before he was through ponder-
ing this proposition, however, he had decided that there was an ideal
An
type for each age of man.
ideal,
old
man
will be “slow in action,
prudent in deliberations, mature in counsel, and cautious rather than the contrary,” while the ideal
young man
good public
will not be a
speaker but will be quick to act. Tasso derived from Horace out of
book of Aristotle’s Rhetoric sanction for the further argumust be performed by agents, and if their force is to be evident, agents must be given some marked good or bad quality worthy of praise or blame 18 Tasso wanted the complex of virtues constituting his perfect exthe second
ment
that actions
.
emplar to be Christian virtues. In forming the Idea of a perfect cavalier,
he
said,
the poet should choose to portray a Charlemagne
or an Arthur rather than a Theseus or Jason.
He
defended
his usefulness, it
is
much
better for
him
his
own
pay attention
practice in saying: “Since ultimately the poet has to
to kindle the
to
minds of our
knights with examples of the faithful than with those of infidels.”
To
have
this effect, the
and not from
poet should take
false religion.
He
his
found
a
argument from true history danger in taking material
directly from Scripture, since he thought it untoward in a poet to make up sacred stories and was convinced that without feigning a poet was simply a historian. But he argued that some sacred histories were less
sacred than others; and the history of the Crusades subject
—was
—Tasso’s
chosen
sacred enough but not so sacred that the happenings
could not be fictionalized, and the events were far enough distant in
unknown 19 soma la Gerusalemme
time to be unfamiliar but not so remote as to be
At
the very end of his
life,
in
Del giudizio
.
,
he tried to reconcile what he thought were contradictions in Plato, particularly
between the notion of exemplars and implications that
could be derived from the distinctions Plato made in the Sophist
between painters
who
who
use foreshortening and perspective and painters
render exactly and faithfully the nature, length,
colors of their originals.
Tasso associated with
The
size,
depth, and
use of foreshortening and perspective
a poet’s creation of
heightened characters; con-
was disturbed on finding that Plato considered paintings employing those expressive techniques almost phantasms and unsequently, he
realities. 16
He
thought that
Ibid ., pp. 105-106, hi.
if
one followed Plato’s 19
line
of argument
Ibid ., pp. 45-46. '5 3
The Age
of Criticism
Homer would have to best men rather than
be condemned for portraying examples of the painting
Xenophon and
solace in
men
they
as
whom
Aristotle,
But Tasso found
are.
he considered in agreement,
and chose to believe that when Plato said
book of Laws)
(fifth
that
imitation should present very beautiful objects to us he likewise
showing approval of Tasso
said: “I
a
heightened characters.
poet’s creating ideal,
think that Plato’s doctrine
is
when
true
he says that the
image should resemble the exemplar; nevertheless, the exemplar
any particular man or
good
chieftain; indeed,
chieftain,
was
is
not
man or of work resemble
the
but the idea of the
whoever wants
to
make
his
Idea will form not only better but the best characters.”
20
the
So he made
peace again with Plato.
Homer
Elsewhere, in answer to Patrizi’s objection that Achilles and
Agamemnon
perfect, Tasso said,
through
“Homer was
attacked
representing himself in a dialogue: rather strong reasons, to
somewhat
less subject;
did not a
character
by
Plato for
which objections the Aeneas of
Virgil
found
is
however, the former paid greater attention to
the universal considered in respect to actions, the latter to that is
make
in character traits;
and both of them did not intend
which
in their
manner but to form which kind is much more stable and certain.” 21 As part of this argument, Tasso made concessions to Castelvetro’s point that the heightening to be found in Homer is in action. Castelvetro’s perfection became Tasso’s universality of action. poetizing to portray particulars in the historian’s universals as philosophers do, the truth of
Tasso’s
ments
as
camp
followers, as might be expected, repeated his argu-
long as the quarrel between Tasso and Salviati was kept
alive.
Camillo Pellegrino, the originator of the quarrel, repeated Tasso’s distinction
between tragedy’s need for central characters of middling
virtue and the need in epic poetry for the highest degree of goodness
Malatesta Porta, however,
heroes should be of
came up with the strange
more than
life size in
22 .
variant that epic
presenting a
show of more
than usual passion rather than of more than usual virtue; for example, the salient characteristic of Achilles
AHlatesta Porta believed that excesses,
immoderation for the most
“Tasso, Del giudizio, in Opere, XII,
anger or immoderate love. For call
part,
in
heroic virtue consists of
and usually either an
difesa
Tasso, Apologia di Torquato Tasso
22
irascible
Gerusalemme,
in
331.
Pellegrino,
Opere, XVIII, 15 4
sua
della
Opere, XII,
331. 21
is
what we
11
113.
Caraffa,
in
Tasso,
Tasso's Perfect Exemplars 23
or a concupiscent passion, excepting cruelty or avarice to derive his theory of heroic
.
Porta tried
immoderation from the doctrines of
the Platonist school and claimed that the Peripatetics, especially Proclus (curiously identified here as a Peripatetic), tried to refute
it .
24
comment of Mazzoni’s that Homer make Ulysses prudent consistently and Penelope chaste, but what particularly upset him was the inference that if two or more characters were made consistent models of specific virtues, the poem in which they appeared would have a diversity of moral functions to perform and the unity of the poem would be destroyed. Beset by this worry, Bulgarini could not make up his mind whether “poets ought to show an extreme degree of some virtue” in creating a character, even 25 if only one character was so handled .” Jason Denores, who was Bulgarini took exception to a
intended to
similarly
concerned with the impact of the doctrine of the perfect hero
on other aspects of
literary theory, asked
whether
a
change of fortune
poem
could not be dispensed with in the action of a heroic hero needs to exhibit perfect virtues throughout.
good one
—although
tions in asking
heroes
it
side
is
since
its
question was a
Denores was apparently unaware of
its
implica-
since he unfalteringly accepted the need for nonpareil
—for how can there be
when one
The
invincible?
a true contest
between opposing forces
But Denores asserted that even the perfect
hero must suffer adversity so that his virtues can “gain force and vigor.” 26
we
In a passage of Buonamici’s that
which Buonamici
said that
poetry
is
have already scrutinized, in
more
like
philosophy than
like
history since both philosophy and poetry deal with universals, one
what universality meant to Buonamici: “Although the poet undertakes to imitate Ruggiero or Orlando, he has in mind the idea of magnanimity, bravery, or piety.” 27
sentence shows adequately
In
few of
his
literary critic for
many
doctrines
summing up
is
Paolo Beni more the appropriate
the tendencies of the sixteenth century
than in this of the perfect exemplar, since his Comparazione di Virgilio , e
Torquato made ultimate and
notions of Tasso. Beni 23
Porta,
XX, 24
11
Rossi,
in
went even
Tasso,
Opere,
101-102.
Ibid., p. 109.
“Bulgarini, Repliche
alle risposte del
Orazio Capponi, p. 102. “Jason Denores, Discorso
Sig.
intorno
rigid the
more
Omero
,
pliant aesthetic
farther than Tasso in applying the cCque'principii,
cause,
et
accrescimenti
che la comedia , la tragedia, e il poema heroico ricevono dalla philosophia morale, e civile, e da governatori delle republiche (Padova, 1587), p. 18. 27 Buonamici, op. cit., p. 17. I
55
The Age
of Criticism
by
efficacy of the examples furnished
heroic poetry only to princes
and governors. Pertinent statements can be found Beni’s critical writings, but the
“And
key idea
is
in
many
places in
expressed in the following:
surely, just as poetry wasffirst invented for the edification of life
through the encouragement of good
by means of heroic poem forms
of character
traits
imitation and delight, similarly and particularly the
the idea of the perfect captain and hero, especially through the ex-
ample of those
who
rule
Beni called Tasso a better poet than figured forth a
in either peace or war.” 28
and govern people
Homer
more noble and perfect
or Virgil insofar as he
idea of a valorous captain and
hero than they did. Beni did not doubt, however, that
what only Tasso had succeeded in doing comit was Homer’s intention in the Iliad to
Virgil had tried to do pletely.
He
Homer and
believed that
portray an ideally brave captain and in the Odyssey a perceptive, wise,
and prudent one.
It
follows from
this,
he
that the Iliad does
said,
provide “an example and idea of bravery and valor to warriors and
“To
captains of the highest rank.” Furthermore:
Odyssey wherein Ulysses ,
a fine theater, the life
is
the contrary, the
celebrated, should represent for us, as in
and manners of
both adverse and prosperous fortune
is
a
prudent and wise man,
who comes
we
need to turn to
close to being
what an
in
seen to be constant and perfect.”
But since these virtues need to be amalgamated before perfect captain,
who
Virgil’s
we
Aeneas to find
can get a
a character
epic hero should be. Aeneas
was an
outstanding leader in both peace and war, and the only real fault to
be found with Virgil was that he was a heathen. Tasso’s main superiority lay in his portrait of Christian heroes; nevertheless, in other as
what constituted Homer’s 29
well his ideas of
Virgil’s or
a perfect prince
ways
were sounder than
.
One of the specialized problems faced by Beni was whether a poet was guilty of artistic error if he allowed his hero’s attention to be deflected from serious matters such as fighting and governing to dally in affairs of love (cf. Racine’s Le Grand Alexandre ), as Aeneas was allowed to be sidetracked by Dido. Beni, of course, approved of Tasso’s solution to the problem. Tasso’s Goffredo, Beni said, although “pro-
voked by the beautiful and insidious Armida always resisted the blows and arrows of love with a constant and chaste mind, making an .
.
.
adamantine shield for himself out of the virtue of Christian con28
In Tasso, Opere,
199.
156
XXI
(Pisa,
1828),
29
Ibid.,
pp. 145-147.
Tasso's Perfect Exemplars
To
tinence.”
only to
do
this
and
maintain a love interest, Tasso allowed
still
human
his lesser captains to give in to
prove
his point of Tasso’s superiority,
weaknesses. In an attempt
Beni permitted himself an ex-
tensive study of the life stories of the great .military personages of
were imperiled by time spent in love-making when they should have kept their minds on their fighting: Holof ernes,
whose
antiquity
Hannibal,
careers
Mark Antony,
Alexander, and others
30 .
In Beni’s opinion, a dislocation can be found in the Iliad since
Agamemnon
the leader but Achilles
is
the hero, and according to
is
Tasso’s theory of heroic poetry as Beni understood
show
should principally tion
31
Related to this
.
not revealed in
his
is
a prince’s control
the proposition that,
government of
the heroic action
it,
over the events of the acif
the prince’s virtues are
what
his subordinates,
results are
the unbelievable deeds of the knight-errant of the romances heroic poetry proposes an Idea or
or
civil
prudence and since these
govern
exemplum of bravery and of
like the
who
hero of romance, Beni believed,
function of heroic poetry.
better in heroic
It is
when
ideal traits are revealed
states or lead armies, to create a character
wanderer
32 .
is
poems
is
Since
military
princes
a solitary
to evade the to have Alex-
anders, Scipios, or Goffredos as heroes than Herculeses or knights-
He
errant.
had argued for
tests
between military ments
33 .
who had
called attention to critics
Only
taken the opposite stand
Mazzoni, Denores, and Riccoboni) and
(listing Castelvetro, Speroni,
of prowess in single combat, not chess games
strategists,
in Scripture,
but he was not impressed by their argu-
he
said,
can
we
expect to find superhuman
characters.
Beni carried a
when
that occurs
Beni’s point
Idea of
was
human
little
farther Bulgarini’s concern for the
virtues are distributed
that a heroic
virtue, a notion
poem
which
among
several
should present a single Platonic clearly attaches the unity to
the character represents statically and not to the action of the
Everybody knows, he hero, in the as
same
way
said, that
that
30 31 32
33
he made
all
187.
Ibid., p.
197.
poem
treated Cyrus
Beni, In Aristotelis poeticam
34 .
— and
as
—creating him not
Polygnotus did in painting
the features of his subjects excellent in their kinds
35 .
34 Tasso, Beni, Comparazione, in Opere, XXII, 46. 35 Beni, In Aristotelis poeticam com-
Ibid., p. 157.
Ibid., p.
what
an epic poet gives a perfect idea of a
Xenophon
he was but as he should have been
when
disunity
main characters.
com-
mentarii, p. 478.
mentarii, p. 478.
157
The Age
of Criticism
Beni used Vettori as well
as Robortelli as early
modern
authorities for
the belief that heroic poetry should present a Platonic Idea of perfect virtue 36 .
Thus between
the time of Robortelli and Beni the doctrine of the
Many variamany variations
epic hero as perfect examplar remained remarkably stable. tions existed in theory, in practice.
and
Most of the
as a result there
critics
started to build their structures
was
could be
whose comments have been examined with
loci in Aristotle’s Poetics ,
but
it
their ability to convert Plato’s doctrine of ideas into an explanation
of the functioning of universality in poetry that provided most of the it was unimby centering the meaning or significance of poetry upon static ideal figures they were forced to separate meaning from action, so that action was useful only because it was pleasing. This concept of universality was hardly the only one widespread in the Renaissance, but it was the most common one.
particular coloration to their theorizing. Presumably,
portant to the sixteenth-century critics that
86
Ibid., p. 549.
58
10
Truth and Reality
A DIGRESSION
necessary at this point in order to ask
is
Renaissance critics meant, precisely,
when they
what
used such terms as
“true,” “truth,” “fact,” or “actual.” It can be seen that they
we do
nothing more consistently or precisely than
the
meant
in carelessly using
the terms. Their chief question was: are particulars or universals true,
or are there “fact”
is
be a fact?
If a fact
is
on occasion be
truth
A
two kinds
start
what
is
of truth? But there
were other
“a doing,” are only actions fact, and things not?
and nothing
true,
at variance
is
true that
in effect true but also true, since
with what in effect
is
it is
1
with
may
deal
it
never existed, but
it is
it
should be like
Speroni never quite faced up to a double standard of truth, a
trutfr of fact
and
a truth
hood of poetry was, this
can
with that which, considered by reason,
true according to reason because according to reason this.”
fact,
said, “deals
true counter to reason. Poetry
because in effect
false
not a
is
if
a passion
with reason?
can be made with Speroni. “History,” he
ought not be
questions:
Can
double standard.
of reason.
The whole
squabble over the false-
in the Renaissance, primarily the obfuscation of
The
illogicality of Speroni’s using
two ways of
defining truth but only one paired opposition of truth and falsehood
order for poetry to partake of both
in
is
apparent but also points to
the non-Platonic nominalism or fact-mindedness of the usual thinker in the Renaissance.
Poetry
is
not the truth, but an image of the truth,
Speroni continued, seemingly assigning truth to the side of fact.
image of the truth cannot be truth not have 1
made
in
forming
a
itself
distinction
—
a
An
concession he should
between poetry and history
Speroni, Opere, V, 426.
59
The Age
of Criticism
any language
since (its Platonic origins aside)
His conclusion was
and
since according to reason is
poetry
that, as fable,
false since it is part false (that it
not the thing in
is
halfway between the true
“is
and part true (that
in fact)
is,
ought to be
like this).”
The
not fable, and he defined fact
narration of
is
feigned
as “a true action, for the
may sometimes
not a fact.” Although, he granted, the historian
is,
truth of poetry
the truth of reason. Elsewhere, Speroni said history
fact,
itself.
is
invent
speeches to put into the mouths of historical personages, he intends
always
whereas the poet uses fact
a reduplication of the truth of fact,
only for the coloring of fiction and the orator departs from he needs to do so in order to persuade In a fragment left
by Speroni of
“If an orator
said:
is
not truth
itself
draw
who
man from
which
like angels
is
is
is
He who
he were a poet.
difficult to
can be seen and touched—it
a picture of truth,
being seen and
if
but a depictor of the truth
must be
hard to draw a portrait of a
If it is
corporeal being to
it
whenever
on oratory,
a projected treatise
Speroni treated the orator differently, more as
says things that resemble truth,
it
2 .
be an orator.
—
man as a much more difficult real life
an intellectual entity incapable of
and God.” The orator must have clear
knowledge of this truth in order to portray it, but the crowd to which he speaks will be capable of understanding only the portrait of truth and not truth itself as the philosopher understands
opinion and said that “just
man
as the painter
does not have cognition of the
portrayed, in himself, through true and scientific
in his essence
—
”
but only of
akin to the senses, so the orator
which
are 3
sense.”
In this
Speroni allocated portraits of truth to the area of persuasion or
treatise
is,
it.
known
In writing
“knows truth
in respect to
not through knowledge this,
knowing
—that
appearance and of the parts
his surface
scienzia ] [
Speroni was thinking of truth
its
accidents
but through as
belonging
only to the world of universals.
A
can be created between Varchi’s saying that a poet can
parallel
go beyond nature but not beyond reason mini that
“men
ought to do, achieve 2
what
in their actions
just as
II,
do not always conform to what they
she ought to do and
346. In this passage
claims to be reporting the Trifon Gabriele.
160
and assertions by Piccolo-
nature herself in her operations does not always
Speroni, “Dialogo della istoria,” in
Opere,
4
Speroni ideas
of
what she 3
desires.
Speroni,
And
“Dell’arte
Opere, V, 541. 4 See supra, p.
140.
that happens
oratoria,”
in
Truth and Reality because of the impediments that run counter to her operations and
oppose them in
world, although in this respect
this inferior
men may
be even worse off than the other objects of nature since the latter
from things with which they do not consent
receive impediments only
or concur while
senses
man
to the contrary faces
without the consent of
suffers
which with
often sidetrack
his
own
many impediments
free will,
their attractions, allurements,
man from what
that he
the fault of the
all
and seductive delights
he ought to do. For this reason
it
hap-
pens not always, not often, but in fact only very rarely that he guides his actions as
he should or intends to do at the time, so that in his
what ought
case the verisimilar and true.”
5
In Varchi, however, nature
is
to be are far fact
removed from the
and presumably truth, or
at
from reason, but in Piccolomini nature can intend that which is distinct from what happens, and the “what ought to be” is “far removed from the truth.” Segni said that nature is never as it ought to be 6 Capriano seemingly implied a distinction between truth and reason in asserting that a poet may at times make use of what has least separable
.
happened “in order to scatter some seeds of truth and so obtain greater faith” but should in general describe events as “they
happened, according to
reason .” 7
ought to have
Vettori similarly identified truth
with particulars and with what actually did happen. Poetry not true but more universal
When
is
thus
8 .
brief statements like these are taken out of context, writers
may seem
to have said things that in their larger utterances they did
not intend. However, there can be
little
doubt that most of these
writers accepted a naive position that truth belongs certainly to the
domain of actual particular rational constructs. sality
is
different
But
if
fact
and only dubiously does
it
apply to
Piccolomini and others implied that univer-
from and beyond what
is
merely
true, Segni
and
Tasso worked with a concept of poetic or universal truth which transcendent to factual truth. In other words, they entertained
is
two
kinds of truth.
More
clearly than
most of
interpretation of universality
his
contemporaries, Segni adopted an
which
since his time
we
think of as the proper rendition of Aristotle’s meaning. the question
by comparing Plato’s and
6
Piccolomini, op.
6
See supra,
7
cit.,
p. 154.
p. 139.
Capriano, op.
cit.,
sig.
A4r.
have come to
He
Aristotle’s attitudes 8
Pier
Vettori,
approached
toward poetic
Commentarii
in
pri-
mum
librum Aristotelis de arte poeta-
rum
(Florentiae,
1573),
161
p.
94.
The Age
of Criticism
book of the Republic he pointed
imitation. In the second
this
out, Plato
,
had equated fabling with
falsity
and lying, but Aristotle had emended
judgment by showing the existence of
a
kind of
false fabling that
allows us “to contemplate and recognize the truth.” Segni continued:
“The
fable that
pure
is
false narration, so
long
as its
are nevertheless possible and in conformity with ones,
I
is,
only
say, not
to history, true as to
its
but
false,
untrue matters
and similar to true
and true together;
false
semblance to the truth.”
An
9
false
as
Achilles created
what truth should be will show us “true behavior according Here nature and probability are alike. the basis of some of these distinctions, Segni distinguished be-
similar to
to nature.”
On
tween the three
and poetry. History
faculties of history, philosophy,
and philosophy represent two extremes of truth around us with
we
These
call Ideas.
history
when
their defects, the other
all
latter
two
the
—“one
the things
with their perfections that
account for philosophy and the former for
are taken separately; but the
two of them taken
together generate poetry. History, which consists of things past and present, explains
and narrates them separate from their
Ideas, just as
they are or were in themselves. Philosophy soars to the Ideas of things, as distinct
from the things themselves, and contemplates them
as
they
are in their perfect nature. Poetry joins the one kind and the other
together
were but
by narrating
things of the past and present, not as they are or
similar to the Ideas,
and showing Ideas not
resident in things that have happened or that exist
was
in themselves but
now.” The upshot
that Segni decided that “history and philosophy,
which have
their
being on the outer extremes, are both entirely true,” whereas poetry
midway between two both extremes. By participating
part true and part participating in
false,
better than history even though
because of
its
it
in philosophy
it
is
lacks history’s kind of truth, “but
participation in history and in the particulars that sense
can perceive of the historic object the poet has
is
kinds of truth yet
less
it
is
lower than philosophy, and
dignity than the philosopher.”
simple account of the same division of truth into
10
Mazzoni gave
two kinds
a
in saying
that “truth can be considered (as the logicians say) either in the con-
crete or in the abstract. facts
about some one
Truth
man
is
or another are considered.
kind of truth out of which a poet makes an icastic Idol. of truth, that 9
A. Segni, op.
which cit.,
is
taken in the abstract,
pp. 17-19.
when
taken to be in the concrete
10
is
And The
this
is
the the
other kind
found when
we
con-
Ibid., pp. 65-67.
162 1
Truth and Reality not the part of
sider,
in themselves.”
this
or that man, but the nature of vice and virtue
11
was
Tasso’s line of reasoning
equally influenced
by
similar to Segni’s
and Mazzoni’s and
Plato nist terms. Both Tasso and Segni thought
of poetry as presenting perfect exemplars.
The
poet has regard rather
“to the verisimilar in universal than to the truth of particulars,”
Tasso
said,
and similarly seemed to find truth only
in particulars in
saying that the poet need have no concern for truth or for history
But Tasso came to the center of things the poet
kills
truth with
only in particulars.
lies
The
derives
historian
Tasso continued, “but seeks
in
it
its
from
a belief that truth
with particular truth, the
needs to be said that
Salviati,
whereas to
in
Salviati universality
found
the poet does not spoil truth,”
which
are ‘ideas.’
one of
his
”
attacks
revealed that to Tasso universal truth had to be based fact,
is
perfect form, supplanting the truth
of particulars with that of universals, it
in stating that the belief that
deals
“Then
philosopher with universal truth.
12 .
meant merely the
13
However, upon Tasso,
upon
particular
false verisimilar,
and whatever truth poetry contained for him did not need to be based
upon the truth of
The
particulars
14 .
crux of the whole problem of the nature of truth,
it
can readily
be seen, was, for the literary critic of the Renaissance, more the distinction
between
historical factuality
and
fiction than a recapitulation
of the old wars between the realists and the nominalists. to notice that, although the Italian critics
of Aquinas and Scotus and
Occam on
made
Reflections of differences of attitude there
who
like
varieties of truth
curious
other occasions, on the questions
of the nature of truth, fact, and reality they left
those
It is
rather frequent use
them
quite alone.
were certainly between
Tasso and Segni explicitly made references to two
and the philosophically more naive writers
who
seem-
upon which they teetered were almost exclusively Plato and Aristotle, and the ponderings of the Schoolmen were consigned to some limbo. Even more striking, in view of the general and continuing tendency of the ingly identified truth only with particular fact; but the fulcrums
Renaissance writers to their
u Mazzoni, Della 12
make
fine distinctions
about everything, was
unconcern about resolving some of the discrepancies and opposidifesa,
I,
684.
See supra p. 141. ,
14
Salviati,
Vlnfarinato
Tasso, Opere, XIX, 133.
“Tasso, Apologia in difesa della sua in Opere, X, 24-25.
Gerusalemme
163
primo
in
The Age
of Criticism
tions in their use of terms like truth
be drawn
reality.
The only
was general agreement
that there
is
and
conclusion to
that reality
demanded
the double vision and could not be attributed solely either to Platonic Ideas or to historical fact. Tasso, the Platonist,
with the romance
Gerusalemme
fictionalizer Ariosto.
liberata
particulars even
encouraged had
The
was
war primarily
at
Neoclassicism that the
at its base the
world of
though the intention was to present
historical
gallery
a
of
Platonic perfect exemplars.
who was
Paolo Beni,
the archrationalizer of the system of beliefs
implied in Tasso’s practice
become almost
—so
absurdities
persistently, in fact, that Tasso’s ideas
Beni’s
in
renditions
clearly as did Tasso that truth could be of
—never
revealed
two kinds but
as
consistently
spoke both of the truth of history and of the truth of philosophy.
He
said,
on one hand,
that the historian’s business
comes from the
poet’s the delight that
statement
by
asserting that Aristotle eliminated
of poets because the poet’s business
list
things,” in
reason.
which instance “truth”
The
is
is
is
gathers particulars.
manner of the
The
truth and the
but he countered
this
Empedocles from the
“not to teach the truth of
identified
with the discourse of
philosopher seeks the truth of divine and
and does not confine himself to
the
false,
particulars,
human
matters
whereas the historian
poet should not represent true particulars in
historian,
but by feigning events he can reduce the
historian’s particulars to a beautiful idea better than the historian can.
What
remains unclear in Beni
is
the relation between this beautiful
idea of the poet’s and the philosopher’s truth in universal. Aristotle,
Beni
said,
did not believe that the historian and the poet differed in
respect to truth and falsehood, since true stories can also be probable; Beni, however, did agree with Piccolomini that truth
is
accidental to
the poet but not to the historian. Beni attempted a distinction of im-
portance in ruling that for the logician and the historian probability relates to questions of subject
matter while for the poet
questions of form. Beni thus had
sal
15 .
What
he stressed
even though
it is
is
little
it
relates to
to say about the truth of univer-
that poetry should appear to be like history
better for the poet to avoid both truth and necessity
than to violate the principle of verisimilitude. Fact as fact belongs to the historian
16 ,
but the poet can turn even
this defect to his
own
ad-
vantage by taking his actions from history. Comparazione, “Beni, Opere, XXII, 196-206. 164
in
Tasso,
“Beni, In Aristotelis poeticam commentarii, pp. 24, 28, 277.
Truth and Reality
common
Since, according to the
Renaissance cosmology,
more
higher intelligible beings participate beings,
can hardly be said that the
it
and
do sublunar
in reality than
critics of the sixteenth
between the range of truth and that of
distinguished
God
reality.
century
Neverthe-
the Aristotelian temper prevailed, and reality was usually at-
less,
tributed to the
world of
particulars. In this regard,
some statements
of Benedetto Varchi can be taken as typical of the thought of the
century. Varchi said: ticular things
“No
science and no art ever discourse of par-
And
but always of universals.
the reason
to the fact that the sciences are always of necessary
in addition
is,
and eternal matters
and not ever of contingent and corruptible things, that particulars cannot be reduced to rules since they are
and whatever cannot
infinite
be reduced to rules cannot be learned and what cannot be learned
cannot be known.” Platonist
is
instance,
that
An
this
was
that Varchi
with the
necessary to see
are
universals
made
particulars are
know
it is
whoever knows the
the particulars also.”
the claim
For
in ideas,
since
that,
considered,
way
seems from
who made no compromise
found truth only true
If it
rigid
of the senses and
affairs
how
a
he continues: “It
is
nothing but particulars universally universals
ambiguity
comes to know
exists
here
in a certain
for although
still,
from particulars, deductions from the universals.
that universals are, in fact, derived
knowable only
still
Varchi
said, if
as
we know
any particular mule
that
also sterile.
is
mules are
all
The
knowledge and (we may suppose) truth depend
result
solely
on
we
sterile, is
that,
if
universals,
universals are nevertheless not real things but products of our minds,
and only particulars can be called
real.
This passage of Varchi’s
is
a
comparison of the values of science and experience, rather than of truth
and
reality,
but the application can easily be made. Varchi argued:
“But because universals, which are merely concepts created by our minds, are apprehended only real things, are
—for
instance,
science,
is,
known by a
which
by
the intellect, whereas particulars, being
the senses,
good physician is
if
one wants to be
—both
qualities
are
ticulars, because, in addition to the general fact that
Donna Berta
man but always
17
would not be
able to
artificer
required, that is
of par-
no one ever gives to the particular
who knows know which meats are
or Ser Martino, anyone
that light meats are easy to digest but does not light
good
of universals, and experience, which
medicine to the universal or species or the individual
a
make
use of this kind of science.”
Varchi, Lezzioni, p. 597. 165
17
All
The Age this
is
of Criticism
reminiscent of Speroni’s or Tomitano’s stress on the necessity
of experience, the cognizance of a complex world of particulars.
Experience related,
is,
of course, not really experience unless particulars are
however dimly,
knew, entirely
to generalities, but as
both Speroni and Varchi
particulars can function as experience
fictitious
and
hence can make our vague notions of truth irrelevant to problems of
knowledge.
We in
our period have
a
semantic problem of our own.
of some item of thought depends
which we deposit
belief,
we
upon
its
fidelity to
If the truth
some system
in
can likewise refer both to the truth of
thought and to the truth of particular
fact, since
we
believe in the
constancy of nature and of our perceptions, and within
limits
we
extend credence to propositions that are based upon sense perceptions.
When members and the
light,”
of religious sects speak of their insights as “the truth
we
can equate the word truth only with what they
are willing to believe. In our everyday usage of the
do not, consequently, totelian
literary
differ
critics
word
“truth”
we
markedly from the sixteenth-century Aris-
who found
probability in the credible.
universality
in
However, only rarely
century are to be found hints of
probability and in the
sixteenth
a partitioning of truth or reality into
two contrasting systems of constructs, one to be called appearance and one reality, as is common enough in modern aesthetics as well as metaphysics. Truth with us, as a result, has several valences in place of the two ascribed to it on occasion in the sixteenth century. And we are less
unwilling than the
man
of the sixteenth century to allot truth only
to particulars or to ideas. This aesthetics
is
more
66
part of the reason
why modern
interested in particularity than the philosopher or
literary critic of the sixteenth
1
is
century was.
11
Universality as Unity
MOST
of the elements comprising the cosmos of Renaissance
man
conspired with a concept of universality equivalent to heightened and ideal morality.
evident.
The
connections between
Moral goodness was
The
of any transcendent truth.
Goodness, and he performed as did the
it
and rhetorical theory were
preceding and determining condition
a
was to co-operate with by praising or blaming,
poet’s business this
demonstrative orator.
function
Now
not
all
the literary theorists of
the sixteenth century co-operated fully in the development of this
system of sality as
ideas, for
many
of them merely referred vaguely to univer-
an emphasizing of the generic rather than the specific
character or action. But so often did writers
more
fully begin in just this
attendant ideas that unless
we
who
traits
developed their ideas
same fashion and proceed to ring find particular objection to this
of ideas, as in Castelvetro and Patrizi,
we
of
in
all
complex
cannot be certain that they
any significant way from the majority. There were, however, minority reports about the nature of poetic
differed in
universality, hesitantly,
implying
a quarrel
with the orthodox views, but made
and rarely involving an aesthetic or metaphysical system of
any complexity. One of the most important of these was the concept of universality as unity of action. Aristotle’s assertion that the universality
of poetry depended
couragement to as a
necessity and probability lent en-
view, provided that necessity was not interpreted
term synonymous with probability,
meant
by
this
upon
either “essence” or “probability,”
as it often it
was. If “necessity”
meant what ought to happen
natural or moral law in a given situation, and the floodgates
were
again opened to the then orthodox interpretation of universality. But 167
The Age
was interpreted
“necessity”
if
of Criticism as
meaning
—the “coagmentation of things,” idea — the emphasis was shifted from
as
a situation
static
commonly
law to
just as
less
was
that
when
with
bore an
coherent entity,
a
was
classifications.
was put upon “necessity” in speculawas greater readiness to identify univeror a composed unity in which the parts
stress
tions about universality there sality
it
temptation existed to
create abstract structures of causality than of static result
now,
and necessary patterns of change, and
even of an abstract dialectic of moral law, far
The
expressed the
a particular action, to
undergoing change; and although then,
possible to conceive of abstract
sequence
a necessary causal
Vettori
intelligible relationship to
one another, than with
classes of
objects or types of characters.
Riccoboni, in a significant passage dealing with the usual distinction
between poetry and
history,
following Aristotle, implied twin ap-
He
proaches to universality in terms of causes and modes.
defined four
kinds of universality, saying: “For indeed Eustratius on the
first
book
of Ethics of Aristotle wrote that the universal was triplex, one ante-
cedent to the parts, of which kind are the ideas of
mind of God; another
in the
all
things given
to the whole; the third subsequent to the parts, as genera
To
these should be added a fourth kind of universal,
to poets, concerning the parts, that
when
form
in the parts, as the relation of the parts
is,
and
which
is
species.
peculiar
concerning singular actions
modes by which they could happen are considered The first three kinds, as authority for which Riccoboni
causes and 1
universally.” cited a
minor twelfth-century Byzantine commentator, actually cor-
respond to a division commonly accepted in the great quarrels between nominalists and realists in the late medieval period.
The way
to the
conceiving of universality of poetry through unity came, however,
through consideration of universality of causes and
also
from the second
—
ways the recognition of the wholeness in the parts from the fourth kind which Riccobini particularly at-
of the three rather than
tributed to poetry.
With some of these ideas in mind, we can see the far reach of when Giulio Camillo said that a poet should rather con-
implications
any object in respect to whole than consider aspects as they
sider the aspects of
their fitting together to
form
relate to like aspects of
a
other things.
It is better, thus,
individual he
is
1
Riccoboni, op. 168
for a painter to consider the eyes of the
about to paint in respect to the totality of the individual cit.,
p. 44.
Universality as Unity than in relation to the eyes of other things, such as animals or angels
2 .
Camillo did not relate this notion to universals but was plainly telling the artist to consider the being, or existential qualities of the
was operating
to be created, rather than the essential qualities. Tasso
when, on one occasion, he
outside the circle of his usual explanations said that, to
make
work
a historical action universal, a poet should give his 3
But although was used frequently in showing the difference between poetry and history, Tasso was unusual in explicitly stating action wholeness, with a beginning, middle, and end
.
this distinction of unity
that the unity gives the action universality.
poem would be mere
Pigna said that the action of a
were not given unity
episodes
4
Moreover, a
.
history
can be made for the conjunction of universality and
airtight one,
unity in Robortelli’s constellation of ideas. In the midst of his
on
particular,” Robortelli said that
only one action,
comment
is more philosophic and grave than more upon the universal, the latter
Aristotle’s saying that “poetry
history because the former turns
upon the
if its
even though not an
case,
when
the historian handles
conspiracy of Catiline, he
as Sallust did in treating the
has something of the poet in him, but only something since “the poet
changes the action, augments, diminishes, adorns, amplifies, and rather narrates the action as
it
ought to have been done than
Later, he based the difference
as it
was done.”
5
between history and poetry on unity, or
the interrelationships of the parts, but without reference to universals. Aristotle, he said, intended epic
poetry to be unlike history in that
man
history deals with the actions either of one
man
poetry should present one
employing
in
tween
thesis
relationship triangles,
and
He moved
or of
to
at this point Aristotle’s distinction
and is
only.
taxis relations
that lines;
which
among
found
is
many men but
more
fertile
the parts of a whole.
such
in
ground
(P re die aments')
The
be-
thesis
figural entities as circles,
the taxis to the contrary,
is
a matter of quantity,
involving numbers or times, in which the particles do not have an or-
ganized coherence. “Historic actions,” Robortelli
do not have
diverse,
but
thesis
taxis,
which
disjunctive order. History therefore differs
tory uses that order in the pursuit of 2
Giulio
teria del
Camillo,
(Vinegia, 1568), 8
“Discorso
suo teatro,” in Tutte I,
maopere
26.
Tasso, Disc orsi del
Opere XII,
in le
poema
eroico, in
4
its
I
they are
said, “since
shall call fortuitous or
from poetry because
his-
matter or in the narration
Giovan Batdsta Pigna,
I
romanzi
(Vinegia, 1554), p. 44. 6 Robortelli, In librum Aristotelis de arte poetica explications, pp. 89-90.
71.
169
The Age of events that
we
of Criticism
have called disjunctive or fortuitous, or that Aristotle
has called taxis , for the matters diverse.
on account of
and Odyssey of
these
two
it
seeks a connected series, and
one action from many,
Homer and
in Virgil’s
as
we
can 6
Aeneid .”
assertions of Robortelli’s are put together, an iden-
and universality
tification of the ideas of unity
stronger and firmer than
it
apparently was
although the component ideas were partial overlapping It
and
relates are dissimilar, separate,
their affinity constitutes
see in the Iliad
When
it
Poetry does far otherwise, for
is
was Speroni and
mind appears mind of Aristotle,
in his
in the
taken from Aristotle, and their
all
at least implicit in Aristotle. his
group that particularly popularized the notion
poem contains one action of one man and history many actions many men. In one of his dialogues, Speroni had the philosopher
that a
of
what his master Pomponazzi had had to say about the difference between poetry and history. Speroni was another of Pomponazzi’s disciples, and the answer of Pomponazzi in the Speroni dialogue was the same as Speroni always gave 7 Late in the century, Denores, Zabarella asked
.
one of Speroni’s followers, was historian narrates
many
using Speroni’s formula:
still
actions of
many men,
the biographer
actions of one man, the epic poet one single, entire action of one
the
many man 8 .
Since the volume of critical comment on the question of artistic unity was great throughout the late Renaissance, there is no need to push these distinctions far. Speroni and others were willing to concede, rightly enough, that history could be unified and, sometimes, was not merely fortuitous. But it is also important to remember that Pic-
who
colomini,
devoted
much energy
between essence and accident,
dealt
to explanation of the difference
with essence in terms of actions
rather than in terms of static objects or beings that
many
sality
of these same writers
who
left
When we
consider
room for a concept of univerpoem to a unified whole
based upon the relations of parts in a
were the same
as those
who on
other occasions markedly developed
the theory of universality as perfect exemplar,
too
9 .
much upon
In the light of
the force of this
modern
less
common
literary theory, their
we
should not
concept
tendency was to err
the opposite direction. 6 7
Ibid., p. 268.
8
Denores, op.
Speroni, “Dialogo della istoria,” in
9
Piccolomini, op.
Opere,
II,
224.
170
insist
of universality.
cit.,
p. 22.
cit., sig.
B6r.
in
12
Penumbral Ideas
THE Renaissance
critics
derived from Aristotle (or thought they did)
both their concept of the poetic universal their
more unusual one
when they that
is,
as the idealized
as the unified or integrated action.
hero and
Repeatedly,
talked about unity of action they talked about necessity;
about necessary causal connections between events; but
it
is
obvious that they did not always feel compelled to identify necessity
with universality these
two
as
they used the term in
to the periphery, in all directions.
we
When we turn from
find, as
we might
aspects of the
body of
this central
ideas
expect, that ideas shoot off
These can best be handled
So what follows
common
connection. However,
ideas taken together resided at the center of Renaissance
thinking on the question.
listing.
this
unorganized
as a simple,
an account of five of the limited or un-
is
problem of universality
impinged upon
as it
the Renaissance mind. Tasso's concept of an allegorical universal. Tasso, like most of his
contemporaries, defended farfetched poetic inventions and morally
dubious portrayals in poetry by recourse to the allegorical meaning
when he was
hidden behind the indefensible surface. In one argument following this
line,
he could have been deliberately obscuring the issue
in using for illustration a tale written full
of personified abstractions such as
this fable
or parable, Tasso
as characters
“because in
by grace and made
it
said, St.
man
is
by
St.
Hope,
Bernard, Desire,
Bernard used no particular
the heir of heaven
is
filio
regis ,
men
considered universally to be elected .
.
.
which consideration or
description, being not of particulars but of universal,
than historical, and
De
and Wisdom. In
more philosophic than
is
poetic rather
not, and, in Aristotle’s 171
The Age judgment,
is
of Criticism
writer,
my
appropriate to a philosopher and, in
appropriate to a theologian. So
shows himself
St.
and in another fable
in this
as
some of
philosopher, and theologian; consequently, to be understood literally
opinion, most
Bernard, although he
is
a prose
well to be a poet,
meanings are
his
and with the obvious sense of history and
others allegorically in other senses.”
In applying this parallel to his Gerusalemme liberata
poem “some
that he had inserted into his
though they seem
false
true since they aim
it
is
This extension of meaning escence, even
remarks.
Idea,
toward which
for this reason that Aristotle affirms that
poetry has more of the philosophic in
totle’s often-cited
plainly
is
What
1
than history has.”
it
made upon
pulls us
up short
the base of Arisis
Tasso’s acqui-
only for the purposes of tactical warfare of
if
which
or feigned in their particulars are nevertheless
toward the universal and the
the poet strives, and
Tasso said
fables or allegories,
ideas, in
the limiting of the concept of universality allied with the Platonic Idea to abstractions that even in a
poem do not need
bodies. So long as he used his
mands of both
to be given particular
mask of Platonism
to reconcile the de-
universality and particularity in a figure that remained
human although
which humanity between universal meaning
raised to the highest degree of
capable, Tasso kept alive a distinction
poetry and that in philosophy; but
when
is
in
he applied Aristotle’s distinc-
tions to St. Bernard’s fable, the distinction vanished.
Comedy
as the
most universal form of poetry. Throughout history New Comedy, comic writers, tellers of tales, and
since the birth of the
writers of novels have often indicated the type of genus intended in
the portrayal of a character
Mrs. Malaprop, or Gradgrind.
by naming him Pinchpenny, Volpone,
When
a writer does this,
attention to the universal aspect of his character, or
him according
to his type and giving
him
a
is
is
he calling
he merely tagging
common
rather than a
philosophic trait of character, as Trissino distinguished the two?
Minturno, one of the influential sixteenth-century
critics,
2
arrived at
conclusions out of kilter with Trissino’s and consequently with some of the dominant ideas of the century.
De
in
poeta (1559),
something suited to
is
when essence. The
his
universality of a character 1
by
poet
his art of
Tasso, Del giudizio, in Opere, XII,
265.
The
universal,
Minturno
said,
a character either does or says
revealed
2
is
aided in aiming at the
giving him the right sort of
See supra
p. 134.
Fenumbral Ideas name, and from
this
proposition
it
follows that comic characters are
especially likely to be universalized ones, for the characters of tragedy
and epic poetry are generally given their
historic,
particular names.
Since poets should constantly refer meanings back to their generic
forms and to universal nature,
like philosophers,
it
followed that comic
poets were, in Minturno’s view, the most philosophic kind of poets. 3
Five years
later, in his
of reasoning explicit.
Uarte poetica (1564), Minturno made
Comedy, he
any other kind of poetry. This poet, in the
and to with
its
manner
is
this line
aims at the universal more than
said,
the gist of his argument:
“Thus the
of the philosopher, reduces the material to
universal nature; the historian, like the orator
its
genus
when he
deals
descends to the particular. But the comic poet shows more
cases,
how
than any other
the universal
handled,
is
who by
penetrating
within to the verisimilar makes up names as the characters and the matter require.”
4
The
illustrations
he provided came from Terence.
believed that epic poetry and tragedy, unlike historic
names but that poets
comedy, should use
He
true,
in these genres should try to stress the
generic aspects of their situations and the universal nature of the material.
That this generalizing need not be confined to Terence’s kind showed in hints that Ulysses must be always astute and
of typing he
Aeneas pious. Vettori, be
some of
his
it
noted, said in passing that
it
is
not necessary,
as
contemporaries seemed to believe, for the names given to
characters to reflect their universal qualities, especially in tragedy.
By
we
turning to a related idea here,
can see how, because of the
variety of uses for the term “universal” in vogue, the sixteenth-century critic lines
had
a harder time than his
of thought clear.
modern counterpart
Comedy was
in
said generally to deal
keeping
his
with private
matters, tragedy and epic poetry with public matters. Kings and princes
—the proper characters for epic and tragic poems—were often thought of as representing the state at large and so of the state.
The same
were universal representatives
is shown even today in the military Some of these terms could with slight
distinction
terms “general” and “private.”
juggling be realigned so that public matters dealt with in poetry were
thought of
as universal
and private matters
as particular,
an employ-
ment of the terms inconsistent with Minturno’s disposition of them. As it actually happened, the Renaissance writers remained acutely aware of the 8
Minturno,
historicity of tragedy
De
poeta, p. 123.
and epic and the identification of 4
Minturno, Uarte poetica
U3
,
p. 39.
The Age
of Criticism
Maggi muddied
history with particularity.
De
the clear flow of idea when,
commentary on Aristotle’s Poetics (1550) and while borrowing an idea from Cicero’s De oratore he said that ridiculous things come partly from art that is, always privately. 5 Art was an equivalent term for generality of statement in
in his essay
ridiculis
appended to
his
,
—
common
most
its
usage, but the equating of nature with the private
The only
and with particulars was more unusual. universal
was Malatesta Porta,
at the
What
mean
before him was,
does
it
universal? His unusual answer
conforms to actual sible.
tion
was
form
to
a fable according to the
that a fable
is
and private
those events that are generally
his
when
universal
what
history, or to accepted legend, or to
affairs
my
to
with the
affairs
end of the century. The question
Porta found principal support for
between public
who,
critic
knowledge, completed the identification of public
is
it
pos-
notion in Horace’s distinc-
affairs. 6
Public
affairs,
known, Porta thought of
which
are
as universal,
private affairs as particular. 7
Malatesta Porta’s exotic views. Malatesta Porta’s the
minor documents
much
attention
more than
it
in the
from the
has received
11
Rossi
,
one of
Tasso controversy, has never attracted
historians of literary criticism but deserves if
only because of the range of unusual ideas
about poetic universality and particularity that Porta believed that the subject of a heroic
it
poem
contains. Like Tasso,
should be an illustrious
action that really happened, but in his use of terms he promptly
deviated from Tasso’s in declaring that Virgil took from history not
only “the universal of this
his
poem but
also in a sense the particular.” In
antinomy “universal” means the general plot outline and “par-
ticular”
means the
Tasso and the poet
is
details.
In the direct quarrel between them, both
his Florentine antagonist Salviati
under obligation to
had taken the stand that
create, or invent, the
broad universal
Under
Porta’s handling
plot outline but does not create the particulars.
the question of universality
of inventions.
Many
was more than usually confused with
of the preceding analyses of the differences be-
tween poetry and history had been based on feigned (that
is,
invented) plots and plots
books, but only Porta confused those 6
Maggi, Aristotelis librum de poetica
communes 6
explanationes p. 307. Horace, Art of Poetry, ed. by Albert
13
distinctions
between
taken from the history
distinctions
with Aristotle’s
Cook (New York,
S.
1926), vv.
128-
1. 7
87.
74
that
Porta,
II
Rossi, in Tasso, Opere,
XX,
Penwnbral Ideas separation of poetry and history on the basis of universality and particularity.
Tasso and
were orthodox Aristotelians in supposing and if a poet is to borrow from what he must borrow. Porta, to the contrary,
Salviati
that history gives us particulars, history, particulars are
took pains to show that etymologically the word “poet” could mean
from which premise
“finder” as well as “maker,”
it
could follow that
the poet “finds” his general plot line in history and turns the history
by feigning or inventing
into poetry
the particulars.
We
can see the
strange cast he gave to the terms “universal” and “particular” in his
“we must recognize
saying that particulars
no
than for
less
that the poet
his universal;
find the
argument and the universal
upon
but
it;
certainly
it is
in history
and can base
his fable
incumbent upon him to invent the particular
means by which the bare argument and the bare
by
fable are converted
whole thing; and so he
into the composition of the
of the action precisely
responsible for his
is
indeed more, for he can
‘finding’
it,
making and the feigning of the means.”
will be the finder
and then maker by both the 8
Unconventional and without immediate progeny
as this explanation
weak
or merely willful.
it is
is,
not for that reason to be scorned
The key terms the universal
we would
as
have, nevertheless, been turned topsy-turvy, for
comes
to
mean
the rough argument
say in unphilosophic talk
neither to the general
—of the
meaning embodied
when
—the general idea
as
story, universality refers
in the conditions of the story
nor to the composition of the particulars to comprise
a unity.
“More-
over,” Porta reasoned, “the poet reduces the universal in history to the particularity of poetry.
And
just as the creator of a
garden
is
the
maker of it even though he obtains from someone else the terrain and space in which he makes it, so because the poet has found his universal action in history or has taken
and then by means of fable and made from is
it
a
it
from fame [legend: common
filled it
belief]
out to be verisimilar and necessary
composition of things,
not the maker of a heroic poem.” As a
it
cannot be said that he
result, the universal
is
defined
by Porta as what is publicly or generally known, and to make a fable conform to the principle of universality the poet must make it conform either to history, to accepted legend, or to what is possible. Porta was not an ignorant eccentric. His citations show that he had a sophisticate’s knowledge of the problems before him. There is some evidence that he took his meaning general idea as D O of universality J 6
lbid. } pp. 85-86.
U5
The Age
of Criticism
of the story from Mazzoni’s partition of the subspecies of fantastic
on universally known history with particular
imitation (i, founded
by
additions
from history or legend;
the poet, retaining names
2,
founded on the inventions by the poet of both universal and particular
9
).
Porta claimed, wanted only the kind of pure fan-
Salviati,
tastic imitation
“which
is all
feigned in both universals and particulars”
Flower of Agathon
as in the
In support of his definition of “poet”
made use of researches of Bartolommeo Amanzio, a unknown writer, as well as those of Scaliger; he based his
as “finder,”
generally
10 .
he
answer to the question whether or not a poet must change
a story
he finds a section of history in which everything happens accord-
line if
ing to necessity and probability and the particulars are already adequate for the universal on another little known book, the Antexegemata ad Petrum Victorium (1559) of Cristoforo Rufo, in which the ideas of
Robortelli as well as those of Vettori are carefully examined. In this place,
should be noticed, Porta allowed
it
to shift to that
which follows
his definition of universality
necessity and probability. Yet to Porta
which
the concept of probability applied principally to particulars,
must have probability
The
in every part.
possibility of finding actions in history that
were already uni-
who
versal
was pondered frequently by the
in the
Tasso controversy. Giulio Guastavini claimed that
totle called
sometimes particular; poetry
is
when
is
Aris-
sometimes universal and poetry
merely more philosophic
how
Orlando Pescetti responded by asking naively
from the
took part
poetry more philosophic than history he was not making
an absolute distinction, since history is
lesser writers
historian
11 .
To
this,
the poet differs
the poet can deal with actual deeds. In turn,
if
Guastavini replied that poetry and history can both
make
use of the
same
material, each in
its
own way,
form
it entails,
not by
its
subject matter. But actually the differences
of opinion
among some
for an art
is
determined by the
of these contestants was not great. Salviati had
agreed, for his side, that history can accidentally be poetic but had said that the poet
to ask
if
history 9
is
II 11
is
truly universal
12 .
He
further asked us
that real-life actions and history are not identical, since
a narrative
Mazzoni, Della
10
must pause frequently
uses historical accounts
the real-life account
remember
to
who
based on actual fact but
difesa,
I,
399-400.
Rossi, p. 92.
See Tasso, Opere, XIX, 294.
176
12
Ibid.,
w lbid.,
is
not actual fact
pp. 295-296. p. 300.
13 .
Penumbral Ideas Castelvetro and his opponents. rists
whose views have been
The
usual Renaissance literary theo-
scrutinized could well have availed them-
most of them, following
selves of Salviati’s reminder, for
Aristotle,
acted as though written history were an exact replica of real-life events
and not of
art.
a selection
But
Salviati’s
and rendition of data according to some principle views in general on the relationship of poetry and
were conventional enough. As in respect to many other items of doctrine, here also it was Castelvetro who struck out in untried directions, motivated, if one were to judge by his contemporaries,
history
simply by an invincible obtuseness of
spirit.
The
clue to the understand-
down any
ing of Castelvetro’s method was his willingness to follow
avenue of thought, whether or not he had any reason to believe that it
would
lead
him anywhere.
every square yard of ideas
He was
who worked
a gold hunter
As a result, even by accident.
his territory.
seem to have been arrived
at
over
most valuable
his
In his principal accounts of the relationship of poetry and history, the question of the universality of the one and the particularity of the
other was an irrelevancy. For he believed that poetry imitation of history in
attempts to be.
He
said,
make
his
“Now
if
history if
it
were
14 .
The
poem
as lifelike
it
must not be
identical
it
and convincing
identical
would not
like a
invention
as a history
would
with the matter of history,”
imitate history but
poet would not have to labor to show
he merely had to follow history;
him more
an invented
is
his skill at
the matter of poetry must resemble and imitate the
matter of history, but for
which the poet by means of
god than
like a
it is
his
his inventiveness
his inventive faculty that
makes
man. In addition to not inventing
subject matter, the historian uses a diction that
whereas the poet in handling
would be
like
is
his
ordinary speech,
invented material uses a diction unlike
ordinary speech.
But the idea of Castelvetro’s that was starkly novel was that first
must know what the
art of history
is
before
we
about the art of poetry, since before an imitation
can
is
know
we
anything
possible the thing
must be understood. The crux of Castelvetro’s problem was the old question of what is truth and what is reality. From his comments it would follow that truth pertains not to the raw datum, to be imitated
the individual fact, but to the assembling of facts according to
general principle. History he defined as
“the story of memorable
actions that have been actually accomplished, 14
Bongiorno, op.
cit.,
some
and
its
distinguishing
p. 54.
177
The Age quality
is
of Criticism
truthfulness,”
may
actions that
verisimilitude.”
tinguish poetry
15
and poetry
as “the story of
be accomplished, and
The
attribute
from history
memorable human
distinguishing quality
[is]
“memorable” does not so much
dis-
its
as it limits
and conditions the nature of
the truthful facts of history.
A
series of passages will reveal the full
scope of Castelvetro’s argu-
ment: “If either Aristotle or another had written a book on the art of history before one on the art of poetry
have been treated adequate,
we
first
—and
are certain that
if his
we
—and the
art of history should
treatment of the subject had been
should either have found the present
booklet of Aristotle’s of even greater service to us in writing poems, or should have found
unnecessary.”
it
For “truth, by nature, came before also,
verisimilitude, and,
the thing represented before the representation.
It
by nature
therefore fol-
lows that verisimilitude depends entirely upon the truth, and models itself after
it,
and the representation depends entirely upon the thing
represented, and models
itself after
it.
And
since
we
cannot have a right
knowledge of dependent and modeled things unless we have first knowledge of the things upon which they depend and are modeled, follows that
we
cannot acquire the faculty of judging aright
a it
if verisi-
militude and the representation are accurate or do not accord, unless
we
have
first a
complete and correct knowledge of the truth and the
thing represented.” His conclusion was that “no art of poetry that has
been written hitherto or
may
be written in the future can give us a
complete and distinct knowledge of the art of poetry unless first
a complete
and
distinct
knowledge of the
we
art of history.”
have
16
This novel reasoning of Castelvetro’s can be readily taken either as the
work
tion. It
of a crank or a complete fool or as an act of real penetra-
seems to prevent the poet from taking the much-celebrated
knowledge in the modifying of Plato’s placing poetry at two removes from truth by allowing the poet to turn from the world of sense and mere things directly to the creation of Ideas of transcendental truth. For in Castelvetro’s system, truth was not the truth of particulars, but an ideal truth, the method of arriving at which was to short cut to
be described in the books on the art of history that he called for. This was another way of showing that when the poet creates Ideas he has no way of assuring himself and others that what he has concocted has real being and is not merely a chimera. But since no art of history of the kind described 15
by
Castelvetro existed, or indeed can 16
Ibid., p. 8.
178
Ibid., pp. 7-8.
exist, his
Penumbral Ideas reasoning had the effect only of casting doubt upon the poet’s ability
“borrows
to create transcendent Ideas. Poetry, he said,
history, a light that does not yet
should, and, unable to ness.”
At bottom,
borrow
it,
burn or
at least
light
its
from
as brightly as
it
poetry must wander in great dark-
reasoning was a slap
this
not
at
humanistic Neo-
platonism which had tended to glorify the poet for his ability to create higher universals directly.
Granted,
hard to
it is
whether Castelvetro was thinking of the
tell
modes of gaining knowledge or more simply of the
arts of
history as matters of technique or disposition. His
“memorable.” His
were more or
art of history
would
tell
us
“memorable and worthy of
less
poetry and
key word was
what kinds of
things
a place in history.”
iVIemorability can be equated with value, and value for Castelvetro, as for
almost
all
writers of his century, led to the rhetorician’s “praise
and blame.” The rhetorician was interested in knowing effects
could be achieved technically.
desired art of history
And
would go on to what
told briefly and summarily, and
of other things; that historian
may
or
may
it
tell
us “what things should be
If the
when and where
and descriptions of
what
digres-
places, of persons, or
would have determined for us whether
the
not be allowed to pass judgment upon the things
that he narrates, praising
draw from them
his ethical
elaborately and in detail;
order should be followed in narrating events; sions should be introduced,
how
so Castelvetro stated that his
one thing and condemning another, and to
lessons useful to his readers
and to
political life.” 17
higher uses of the Jamesian “point of view” in fiction or Allen
were
Tate’s concept of “authority” vetro’s aesthetics,
it
in
any way appropriated
in Castel-
was at this point, at this conversion of epistemo-
problems to technical problems. The chances are that Castel-
logical
vetro was not unconscious of
what he was doing.
However, some hundreds of pages
later in his
commentaries Castel-
vetro attacked the problem differently and considered the “universal” part of a narrative
poem
of
how
different
to be the general outline of the plot,
meant
this
as
later.
the same legend of history. Castelvetro
totle did
much
Here the taking-off point was the problem poets could create differing tragedies on the base of
Malatesta Porta did
was done by varying the
first
assumed that Aristotle
episodes; later he decided Aris-
not mean variation to consist only in a rearrangement of the
accidents of a story
(as,
for instance, in the
way
the particulars of the
death of Clytemnestra and Aegisthus had been varied) but meant in17
Ibid., p. 9.
79
The Age stead that
we
of Criticism
reduce fables to their universal form by changing time
and place and not using the same particular characters. From Castelvetro
He
said:
was
back to renewed
led
this idea,
upon poetry as invention. as we saw above, that
stress
“So he [Aristotle] was of the opinion,
not only can imaginary names be given to the characters of the tragedy
by
we
did leave
made
room
fable
forming similar
18
fables.”
is
composed can be
wanted
are obliged to believe that he
to imagine matter for
he
which the
a poet but also the material of
imagined, since
Although Castelvetro
for the use of historical subjects, particularly in tragedy,
concession grudgingly at the expense of his usual
this
how
to teach
demand
for poetry defined in terms of invention.
Especially noticeable in Castelvetro’s treatment of universal
He
handling of them as stock-plot patterns. aspect of the broad problem and
than
his
his
more copiously
illustrated his idea
contemporaries had done. In reducing any given fable to
universal form, he said,
we
particular
ways by which
it is
And
“the
perchance Aristotle
if
holds this view and understands universality in this for poetry can then be taken not only
from
made but
others have already
way
here, subjects
tragedies and epic also
poems
from comedies and
they can be differentiated by episodes to the point of
histories, since
being no longer recognizable as having universalized,
is,
recognizable, are taken out and in then-
place other and different ones are inserted.
we and
its
should make the original specific situations
and characters no longer recognizable. So the episodes, that
that
is
delved deeper into this
whether they are
come from them, and have been
tragedies, epic poems, comedies, or
histories.”
For
instance, he added, let us consider the basic plot situation of
an ardent lover who, unable to reveal his love, shuts himself up pre-
pared to die of
his love pangs, so that his friends
scheme whereby he can enjoy
his mistress.
This
Antiochus, and Stratonice universalized, but it
applies to a Tito, Gisippo,
Giachetto and Gianetta universal to pertain
19 .
more
“ Castelvetro, Poetica
In history Stratonice
(fl.
Her husband gave her
“And because we do not
c. I
300
b.c.)
of Syria.
to his son
by
a
former marriage, Antiochus, since the was pining away with love for
latter
180
can be changed so that recognize this
to the latter than to the former,
d’Aristotele, pp.
was the wife of Seleucus
have to invent a
the plot of Seleucus,
and Sofronia or to Boccaccio’s story of
366-367.. 19
it
is
her.
Sofronia,
Gisippo,
we
can use
it
and Tito are
characters in the eighth story of the tenth day of the Decameron; Gianetta
and Giachetto of the eighth story of the second day. The plots of the three tales are not very similar.
Penumbral Ideas in
forming other
but
fables,
by which we recognize
And
if
cannot in other fables use the particulars
the universal as pertaining to certain persons.
a certain particular
as stolen
we is
used there,
will deservedly be
it
blamed
goods.” Castelvetro cited a particular incident in which Boc-
caccio duplicated too exactly a set of incidents he had previously used;
he argued that a poet must create for himself the particular ways and
means of expressing the
Doubts arose
in his
universal.
mind when he
He
the Iphigenia story.
tried to apply his principle to
concluded: “For however
when they
are taken
all
we
this universal that
together
recognize
And
not to another character.
how we
has not taught us
it
of
to other persons,
seems that they so particularize
it
as pertaining
if
this
how
is
only to Iphigenia and things stand, Aristotle
should reduce a fable to the universal, nor
any norm or adequate or
has he given us
much any one
happen
the things told universally about Iphigenia can
suitable example.”
At what
point, in other words, can the particulars be
changed and give the
when some
basic plots are already
newness to
effect of
a basic plot
closely identified with particular situations? In this connection, Castel-
vetro said positively that situation It
all
particulars that tend to identify the basic
with any particular character should be discarded.
must be remembered that Castelvetro believed the function of
poetry was to give delight, not basic tenet of his
profit, to the
hard to match with
is
“rude multitude.” This
his notions of universality
the relations between history and poetry. Quite possibly the
“universal” had
two
distinct
philosophic and one popular.
and
word
meanings in Castelvetro’s vocabulary, one
At
the time
exclusion of Empedocles and his like
when he
from the
discussed Aristotle’s
roles of poets, Castel-
vetro asserted that a poet making use of scientific or philosophic material
would not be engaging
be a poet.
He
in original creation
and so would not
foresaw the need to answer the objection that
happened to be
a
presumably create
if
that the poet’s function, unlike the philosopher’s or scientist’s,
imitate faithfully the fortuitous events of the his imitations to
who
“to
world” and by means of
phenomena
to philosophers
and
own way (one different from that of the poets) benefiting men 20 These remarks can be used as
have their
of delighting or
evidence to
is
give delight to his listeners, leaving the discovery of the
truths hidden in natural or accidental artists,
a poet
good original philosopher or scientist he would a good part of his own material, and he responded
.
show
"Bongiorno, op.
that Castelvetro broke sharply with Aristotle over
cit.,
pp. 55-56.
181
The Age
of Criticism
the differences between history and poetry and reinforced his belief
no
that
satisfactory art of poetry could be written until an art of
history had been
worked
For Aristotle had
out.
distinctly
made poetry
not an imitation of the fortuitous events of the world. But
it
should be
And
clear that Castelvetro’s theories never achieved final coherence.
yet at this point he was quite conscious that he differed from Aristotle,
even though
page before he had scolded writers bold enough to
a scant
challenge Aristotle
—“whom
we
cannot contradict without shame.”
Nevertheless, he assured his readers that poetry does not differ from
had
history, as Aristotle
more
said,
by being more
philosophical (that
universal, in the usual critical vocabulary of the sixteenth cen-
tury) than history but significant difference
by being an invented
static character.
The kind
his
contemporaries was
composed action and not character.
In the years following the publication of Castelvetro’s
on the Poetics
,
the incitements
commentary
a storm of protest arose against his ideas,
was
his giving
precedence to the
and one of
art of history. Tasso,
often did accept novel ideas from Castelvetro, objected but partly
misunderstood what Castelvetro had
preceded poetry in origin that truth
must precede
said.
Tasso denied that history
—Castelvetro had never verisimilitude.
several centuries older than history,
said that
it
did
—or
Poetry, Tasso insisted, was
and he argued that
a poet therefore
could hardly have needed to learn an art that was developed
He
in a
of universality that he consistently failed to
was the perfect exemplar of
find in poetry
The
imitation of history.
between Castelvetro and
that he envisioned a Platonic Idea in a
who
is,
supposed Castelvetro to have meant that history came
later.
first
by
nature even though not in time, but he responded firmly that “the poet considers the verisimilar only as sality
it
is
universal.”
An
art of univer-
should be learned before the art of particularity. Tasso held that
Aristotle obviously thought that the art of history
was simpler than
the art of poetry and that the rules of rhetoric should be adequate for
the writing of
it
(unless there
was some truth
in the belief of
Demetrius
Phalereus that history writers followed a few distinct principles of their
own ). 21 Patrizi,
who was no
lover of Aristotle, took Castelvetro to task
for following Aristotle too closely, and so his quarrel Aristotle.
He
between poetry and history were based upon 21
was
really
with
argued that the notions of Castelvetro on the differences
Tasso, Discorsi del 182
poema
Aristotle’s dismissal of
eroico, in Opere, XII, 22-23.
Venumbral Ideas Herodotus
poet and on
as a
statement that poetry
his
The
have been done and history what was done. here,
according to
Herodotus should have been and necessity
verisimilitude
was
Patrizi,
be found with
to
fault
achieve unity of action, not
his failure to
as Aristotle said.
poets had written history in verse
less
the
that
what should
tells
fallacy in the logic
Furthermore, since count-
form before
Aristotle’s day, the
accounting of a difference on the basis of verisimilitude and necessity carried
little
always that
force. Patrizi
if
was
rules for poetry
he asserted
a consistent descriptivist:
were
to be formulated they should be
based upon the range of actual practice. For him, the existence of histories written in verse
was proof
Scrutiny of actual practice, he claimed, would differed
from
historians in dealing
The
show
poetic.
that poets usually
with fantastic improbabilities rather
than with idealized constructions. Poetry poetically.
made
that histories could be
is
which
that
is
handled
poetic substance of minor poetry Patrizi identified
with the rhetorical principle of enargeia (vividness) or “evidence,” and he thought that the historian could use poet.
He
this principle as
what
also said the historian imitates in telling
he can compose his action so that
hang together
it
becomes
in necessary connection.
well as the
has happened:
a fable; the parts
So what difference
can
there
is
according to these criteria between poetry and history? Surely none at
all.
And
if
none,
why
are not the historian and the poet one and
the same according to these precepts?
22
After fighting
Patrizi felt that Tasso’s notion of the hero of an epic
perfect exemplar
needed
still
leveling,
and
this
as Idea
or
he proceeded to do.
Francesco Buonamici turned a large part of (1597) into a rebuttal against Castelvetro. His
battle
this
poem
his first
complex study of the determinants generally used
Discorsi poetici
discourse
was
a
in the classification
of the arts and sciences for the purpose of showing
how
senseless
and
confusing were Castelvetro’s theses about the relations between the arts
he
of poetry and history in terms of classical methodology.
said, differs
from
a science in that a science
An
art,
contemplates only, and
an art must carry science over into practice. Art can be divided into
theory and practice.
The
theoretical aspect of an art
is
science and submits to the same conditions as science.
reduced to practice,
from the as
it
actually a
When
it
is
should function with the right reason derived
theoretic; but practice depends
upon the
material used as well
on the theory employed, and the material can impede the intention. 22
Patrizi,
La deca
disputata, pp. 157-161.
83
The Age But although poetry
of Criticism
is
more
like
philosophy than
like history since
both poetry and philosophy deal with universals and history with particulars, Castelvetro
was guilty of
terms by comparing poetry
a shift of
and history and not poetics and history in saying poetry bases
shadow images of the
on what
true
Buonamici assumed that poetry
really
subordinate to politics since 'he
is
found that both Plato and Aristotle
its
true.
is
The two
said so.
of poetry are metrics and hypocritics, that
principal parts
verse forms and the
is,
explication of concepts. Hypocritics, he said, consist of “the explication
of
its
concepts with modes not signifying what
is
true, as affirmations
and negations do, but with modes signifying affective imperatives, prayers, and desideratives.” Buonamici
modern
traits
was
makes use of rhetoric
semanticist. Poetry, he added,
such
as
not unlike a in several
ways. But he made the distinction between the true and the verisimilar
fundamental to definitions of poetry, for he allowed logic and metaphysics to be concerned with what
(“which
a
is
is
true, dialectic
with the probable
semblance of the truth”), rhetoric with the persuasible,
and poetry with the verisimilar (which “shows
how
it
ought to be
done”). Buonamici’s classification here, however, was subject to further distinctions
between what
is
true in itself and
what
is
true conditionally
and between complex and uncomplex truth, even though classification
was standard
his
initial
in his time.
Buonamici made use of these general remarks
in
determining that
for both the orator and the poet “the theoretic part concerns the
true and the other part formally and as secondary intention and, leaving
consideration of essences to the metaphysician or logician, addresses itself
more
showing how they can be obtained, as, method uses sweetness of verse as guide and when one comes to practice, the former [rhetors]
to giving rules
for instance, the poetic
inducement; so that
to debates and the latter [poets] to poetizing, the [essences] are dealt
form but by means of the fable,” as in the particular condition of Aeneas’ meeting Dido at a time when her political position was insecure. The argument came to a head when Buonamici said that an art of
with according to what
made appropriate
history
is
to
is
true or verisimilar, not in universal
some one
situation
then not necessary or important for an art of poetry.
pointed out that Aristotle
made many
cross references
metrics, rhetoric, and hypocritics, but since he to an art of history the clear implication 184
is
among
made no such
that he
He
poetics,
references
found such
refer-
Penumbral Ideas ences unnecessary. History should be thought of as a kind of writing of value principally in oratory and politics “since the
good orator has
to
be a historian in order to have copious examples at hand, and a politician [has to be one] in order to base his discourses
No
art
The
is
necessary for the knowledge of history
on experience.”
23 .
contender against Castelvetro on
final principal
this score
was
when the have been laid. And
Paolo Beni, in the early years of the seventeenth century,
by then
ghost of Castelvetro’s irregularities should
some of
in actuality Beni used
He
upset Castelvetro.
Castelvetro’s arguments in the attempt to
said that the reason Castelvetro
was
led to argue
both that poetry should be derived from history and that
it is
useless
to try to determine precepts for writing poetry without first determin-
ing the rules for writing history was that the poet tries so hard to
make
us forget
we
are dealing with feigned materials that he convinces
us an actual event
is
unrolling before our eyes. Beni, like Castelvetro,
emphasized invention, but although their assertions
conformed more
seem
beliefs
similar, Beni’s
to the usual set of doctrine of his time than
“Thence it cannot be readily conceded that a poet imitates things which have happened, since he either invents everything, as in comedy, or varies, changes, and makes addidid Castelvetro’s. Beni continued:
poetry or tragedy.”
tions, as in epic
And
later
borrows some things from the monuments of represent
done.
He
them
as
they have been done but
refers everything
poet does not so
much
back
imitate
as if to
what has
as
he added: “For
if
he
history, he does not
they should have been
Ideas.” Consequently, the
actually happened as he tries
not to imitate them just as they happened. For the historian the highest praise praise
is
comes from following
in deceiving eyes
the false for the true.”
image of history
When
“In poetry the highest
a result,
poetry
is
not at
all
the
mere shadow
24 .
the extremity of Beni’s position as a defender of Tasso’s
idealized heroes
he could have
considered,
is
moved
Castelvetro stressed in
was
As
truth.
and minds and in making the auditors mistake
interested in a
away from Castelvetro
strict
becomes
common was
poem with
a matter of
cit.,
that
he and
the doctrine of verisimilitude. Beni
stories that
pp. 138-139.
wonder
What
historical subject matter universalized
adherence to history but
wanted invented
“Buonamici, op.
it
so close to Castelvetro’s position.
24
still
seemed
resembling history.
as true to life as his-
Beni, In Aristotelis poeticam
ment arii,
pp. 24, 28.
185
com-
The Age tory,
of Criticism
and he had relatively
concede that “just out from
it
fable
as a
little
shadow follows
body and seemingly comes
a
and poetry follow history and entirely flow out from
Thus, while the historian
it.
to say about universality. Beni could
is
for
you which
men
concerning himself with things
have done and pursues the deeds and saying of mortals, here
poetry
is
represents the deeds of heroes and powerful leaders, and
the misfortunes and fates of kings and of
men in high places, and the loves,
laughter, frauds, brawls, in both deeds and sayings, of citizens and
populace. ... In this respect, poetry seems to be merely the shadow
and image of history, and is
in this
feigned history and history
is
connection
or falsehood in poetry verisimilar. It
is
is
can be said that poetry
true poetry.” But the poet refers the
true events of history to the Ideas,
is
it
which
Truth
are superficially false.
unimportant, Beni
said, as
long
poetry
as the
better that a poet avoid the true and necessary than
the verisimilar. 25
The
ideas of
century such
some of the writers of the
relevant to this point in our study, since stressed verisimilitude in their
end of the sixteenth
and Faustino
Zinano, Michele,
as
tail
comments on
Summo
most
are
of them particularly
all
universality. Since the
main
Disc orso della tragedia (1590) was that tragedies should have invented plots, his link with Castelvetro is apparent. The
thesis of Zinano’s
tragic poet
does not differ from the historian, Zinano
said,
if
his
emotional effect upon his readers or audience comes from the sequence of events and not from his
art.
But “art” here to Zinano must have
meant primarily the invention of the cannot move by
by
itself,
why
itself, it is
events, for he continued: “If art
imperfect, but
if it is
move they would say
perfect and can
search further for history and truth? If
come from both, we would answer that even if this were true the movement coming from art should be the one more highly praised, and that of the feigned should be the one more praised because it comes more from art.” According to Zinano a true that the effect should
event can indeed be handled artfully, but even with the addition of art the emotion aroused
by
the resulting product
would not be
an art-produced emotion but in part raw passion. narrates things as they are
thesis
was
See supra p. 164.
186
if
the event
a defense of a
and can therefore be looked upon 26
asked: “If history
and poetry things as they ought to be,
not tragedy be history and not poetry
Although Zinano’s
He
entirely
as
were
a true
poem he had
would one?”
written
an instance of special pleading,
Venumbral Ideas new and imsomething was wrong in the
he found himself moving half-blindly in the direction of
He
portant distinctions.
recognized that
To
concern expressed about the universality of names for characters. the extent that tragedy has to
shrewdly,
it
become
he observed
particularized,
done with feigned
better that the particularizing be
is
names, and yet the use of the feigned names should not be considered a particularizing of the action, for since a
does not aim at the world of particulars. he said,
“is
meant
poem should be universal, it “By the universal in poetry,” happen to certain
relating those events that can
kinds of persons according to verisimilitude and necessity.” If tragedy
works with universal, of vital importance
26 .
then, the particularity of
names
not
is
a
matter
Zinano insisted that he was not anti-Aristotelian
even though he wished to lambast blind, narrow, and unreasonable Aristotelians.
want poetry job
is
about
He
history in poetry but
to be of the highest rank because of history.”
mind
to keep in its
“we admit
said that
the suitable
(
we do not The poet’s
convenevole ) without worrying
historical truth or falsehood. If history
is
convenevole
,
it is
poetry.
Agostino Michele’s place in literary history pleader of a special cause a battle
among
—the defense of prose
literati at
had Paolo Beni
as ally.
likewise that of a
is
as a literary instrument,
the end of the sixteenth century in It
Aristotelian fashion against Patrizi that the difference historian
and the poet
argued, “relates
its
is
27
would be expected
With
identification of history
reveals that to the
this
to say
and do according
argument he intended to
forestall
an
with prose and of poetry with verse. His logic
orthodox Aristotelian of
of poetry consists in
making universalized
painting fact with colored ornaments. For true things even
between the
not in the writing of verses. “Poetry,” he
matters in universal, which consists in saying those
things that those persons to verisimilitude.”
which he
served his purpose to argue in orthodox
when they
his
century the artfulness
imitations of fact, not in
him the
are not verisimilar”
historian “narrates
and does not need to
concern himself with the unity of action. In holding
this latter tenet,
Michele was a Speronian. The concern with the maintaining of a balance between digressions or episodes and the main action, which creates all
pertain to history, nor do
from
a poet’s expression of his
pleasing effects in poetry, does not at
the exaggerations of truth resulting 26
Gabriele Zinano, Discorso della tragedia (Reggio, 1590), pp. 11-13, 22.
27
Michele, op.
cit ., p. 29.
187
The Age emotions in
his
of Criticism
act of praising or blaming. Michele
special indebtedness to the demonstration
the second
book of
his
between poetry and Faustino
Summo
acknowledged
made by Ludovicus ,
history.
seconded both Michele and Zinano and
based poetic universality on the verisimilar and necessary. that poets and historians
and the other
Vives, in
Corruption of the Arts of the polarity existing
in prose
do not
differ
like
He
them
affirmed
because one composes in verses
but because the historian describes events
as
they really happened and the poet in the manner in which they should
have happened. So poetry
is
more philosophic than
history,
former being more concerned with universal and the particulars.
which
is
.
.
.
By
universal
suitable to each thing.”
we mean
latter
“the
with
only saying or doing that
With Zinano he proclaimed
that a poet
should invent his fable in order to achieve the proper universality
The
critical speculation in the sixteenth
between poetry and
28 .
century on the differences
history, although acquiring special impetus
from
was caused primarily by Aristotle’s prowas because of Aristotle that the differentiation involved the problem of universality and particularity. Castelvetro’s principal importance was in describing a type of universality based on the theories of Castelvetro,
nouncements, and
it
general significance of action rather than of stock character. 28
Summo,
Discorsi poetici, pp. 41-42.
13
The Grandeur
FEW
of Generality
would have
of the literary theorists of sixteenth-century Italy
disagreed with Paolo Beni
when he
said that the poet
the typical in presenting particulars to his readers
1 .
must emphasize
From
Aristotle as
well as from Plato they learned to believe that arts and sciences are
compilations of universal, so that knowledge applies only to univer-
humanly produced abstraction from particulars, but even nominalist philosophers found no value in particulars as such. Many of the writers of the late Renaissance were sal. In nominalist
theory a universal
is
a
aware of the necessity of giving the airy nothings of our minds
fully
“ a local habitation and a name”; but Beni this is
would have assumed
done by the invention of particulars that emphasize the
that
typical.
Robortelli spoke for his century when, in describing the similarity of
poetry and philosophy, he made use of dicta Platonists of
all
common among
the
time. Porphyry, he indicated, had called attention to
Plato’s belief that
one must be
silent
when
faced with particulars and
individual events, “for, since they are innumerable, there
is
no knowl-
edge of them.” And, Robortelli added, Ammonius, the interpreter of
Porphyry, said that philosophers can do nothing with
infinite
par-
knowledge must concern sempiternal fixities that remain the same state. The scientist, according to Robortelli, does not
ticulars, since
ever in
want to know about all horses but only about the species “horse,” which is general. Poetry, like philosophy or science, is a kind of discourse that does not concern particulars but universals all
of Robortelli’s contemporaries
'Beni, In Aristotelis poeticam mentarii, p. 281.
com-
were unwilling 3
2 .
Since almost
to think that poetry
Robortelli, In librum Aristotelis de
arte poetica explicationes, p. 91.
189
The Age
of Criticism
had nothing to do with knowledge, they were forced by the sequence of their
own
make
thinking to
less
than adequate
room
for the par-
ticularity of poetic effects. It
a
would seem
to follow
from
making poetry
Robortelli’s statement
kind of discourse concerning universal, not particulars, that the poet
should not “number the streaks of the tulip”; he should not descend to
an exact depiction of the particular. to infer
It
would be
a mistake,
from the weight of evidence already presented
however,
that
all
six-
teenth-century writers agreed with the idea Johnson was to express
two
from metaphysical problems of univer-
centuries later. In turning
sality
we
and particularity to rhetorical problems,
the land changes.
When
with the metaphysical poets for
was speaking
generality,” he
find that the lay of
Johnson, in the Life of Cowley, found fault failing to achieve “the
tradition that the Renaissance writers
grandeur of
and according to
in rhetorical terms
a
were largely instrumental in was
creating, but in the sixteenth century “the grandeur of generality”
an effect to be striven for by the creators of Virgilian epics and the phrase did not necessarily apply to other forms of poetry. Generality,
they indicated, belonged to sublime poetry and not necessarily to other aesthetic categories.
Pigna, in his treatise on romances (1554),
made some
concessions to
the need for details but revealed a taste for the sublime in poetry. said that “if the historian rejects lose gravity
how much more
ities.”
who
should the poet,
and not to truth, teach himself to avoid 3
But Pigna admitted that
oricians call enargeia,
The
it
particularities
do have
by means of which an
Latin language, he
said,
this
by nature
effects of the Italian
low language
was
a
and
as a result
a place in
orator describes a situation
has so
much
its reality.
majesty in
it
that
it.
But Pigna thought that the
because the Italians
as a
much
because
it
people loved amplitude
turned to the writing of romances in which there was
more concern with
detail
than in heroic poems.
language to be the hallmark of enargeia since evident and difficult things plain. Pigna, op.
poetry
effect that the rhet-
language were different, not so
as
particular-
kind of detailing, and in consequence the
chief Latin writers usually avoided
8
little
seems to be right before us and convinces us of
cannot well handle
it
looks to perfection
these very
all
on some occasions so that poetry can achieve the so that
He
minute circumstances in order not to
cit.,
190
pp. 50-51.
it
He found
figurative
makes occult things
Grandeur of Generality much the same thing, for much space on small details
he remarked that poets
Giraldi Cinthio said
should not spend
unworthy of
since these are
a heroic style.
He
or minute descriptions
Homer on
claimed that
occasion was guilty of overdetailing but Virgil never. His advice was to
follow Virgil years
4 .
This was the opposite of what Speroni was to say a few
later.
In notes that he
made
to an abstract of the
arguments in Castelvetro’s
Poetic a with the apparent intention of publishing a rejoinder
proper occasion should vetro to
mean
and the one claimed that attribute
arise,
that the poet
the
if
Tasso revealed that he interpreted Castel-
who
universalizes
who particularizes less dramatic. “Homer in particularizing paid
of poetry in general, that
to
is,
is
being more dramatic
In response, Tasso proattention to imitating.
.
.
what .
an
is
Virgil in
what is an attribute of epic poetry, that Tasso made clear here and elsewhere that his
universalizing paid attention to to the magnificent.”
is,
5
term “magnificent” should be equated with “the sublime.” Especially
noteworthy
in this
remark of Tasso’s
the recognition, so rarely re-
is
corded by other writers of the cinquecento, that the theory of poetry as imitation implied, in general, a
tion. Patrizi
considerable stress on particulariza-
argued that only in the sense of enargeia could Aristotle’s
theory of mimesis be taken seriously, and
if this
notion
is
coupled with
Pigna’s concessions to particularity for the sake of greater enargeia
,
it
becomes evident that the usual defender of Aristotle must have secretly held open a larger
room
for particularization in poetry than he took
the pains to describe.
The
identification of the nonspecific
development
with universality reached
in Alessandro Guarini at the
home
an argument in which certain chickens came logical vengeance. Guarini a
kind of poem.
Now
full
very end of the century in
was defending the
to roost
with
a
validity of the sonnet as
the critics of the sixteenth century were often
unable to account for the inclusion of lyric poetry within the category of poetry
if
poetry was imitation, for they recognized that even
speaker’s voice could be discerned in a sonnet such a
if
a
poem could not
very well hold the mirror up to a concrete world of any great complexity. Instead, the lyric poet usually
4
Giraldi Cinthio, “Discorsi intorno
comporre de p. 62.
i
al
romanzi,” in Discorsi,
See also Vida, Art of Poetry, ed.
made
by Albert
general statements even
S.
Cook (New York,
1924),
p. 89. 5
Tasso, Estratti della poetica del Ca-
stelvetro, in
Opere, XII,
364.
The Age
of Criticism
though he used highly concrete images
ornaments for
as
munications. Alessandro Guarini argued that the sonnet was a
poetry superior to heroic poetry and drama on the basis of concentration of general statements. That
is
poem must
He
tions fecundly
held that the
use thousands of verses to present a single action to
“whereas the sonnet with
us,
this greater
to say that he thought of
general statement, not unplausibly, as universality. epic
comform of
his
its
very small number vaunts
and more philosophically, and
this
all its
ac-
means with greater
nobility, since it deals with them more generally; indeed, you must remember, Signori accademici, that Aristotle wrote in his Poetics that poetry is a more philosophic thing than history, since history is aimed at particulars
heroic
poem
and poetry
at universal;
and what
we
have said about the
should also be said about both tragedy and comedy, to
which the sonnet is not was clearly based on a
at all inferior in dignity.” 6 Guarini’s
taste for the
argument
“grandeur of generality,” but by
disregarding the necessity of imitating a particular world he was led to
an unattached meaning for universality that failed to discriminate
between poetry and kinds of writing more obviously making use of general statements.
Guarini attempted to establish
orthodox Aristotelian doctrine, planations
would
his thesis
as if the
justify the unusual.
by surrounding
it
with more
propinquity of the usual ex-
But he
also
extended the usual
idea of poetic imitation so that he could think of imitation in lyric
poetry
as the imitation
of passions and not of actions.
He made
a special
point of refuting an assertion that a writer describing passions was a
purveyor of
historical truth,
not of poetic universality.
the Philosopher, having stated in his Poetics that
it
is
He
said:
not the
“For office
of the poet to recount things that have actually happened but those that could
happen
verisimilarly,
added
it is
to be granted that
if
some-
is not kept from some accidents to happen in reality in quite the same way in which they would be verisimilarly feigned by poets, whose office therefore is to treat them in their own
one undertakes to write about true happenings he
being a poet, since
it
is
possible for
fashion.” If a historian needs to portray a pitiable story, he should
narrate
it
simply and in a historian’s manner.
The
poet should, to the
contrary, pay particular attention to his ordering, ornamentation, diction,
and manner.
And
Guarini added that
if
a distinction of this kind
could be made between a historian and a tragic poet, 6
A. Guarini, op. 192
cit.,
I,
344.
it
could also
Grandeur of Generality made between narrate some fact be
action that
with it
figures,
with
way
and
a lyric poet: if a lyric
that had really
true,
is
in such a
a historian
he should do
poet “were to
happened or were to celebrate some it
with ornament of
artful arrangement,
his
own
kind,
and in short would transform
own form it would no longer seem verisimilar fable.” The conclusion then should
that in losing
to be a true thing but a
its
be that the poet “expresses for us true passions of the mind and
them not
describes
precisely as they are experienced or felt but as
verisimilar that an extraordinarily impassioned
it is
mind would experience
7
or feel them.”
Presumably Guarini did not notice a defense of lyric
his inconsistency in shifting
poetry based upon the sublime generality of
actions to a defense of
it
its
from ideal
based upon the universality of verisimilar
passions in parallelism with verisimilar actions. Less clearly than with
Pigna, Giraldi Cinthio, and Tasso can his appreciation of the nobility
of general statement be called merely a matter of style, for he connected his talk If
we
about universality too closely with Aristotle’s phrases.
Speroni between
we
made by Sperone
turn time back to look at the comparisons
Homer and
Virgil,
we
find ideas similar to those
have already encountered in Pigna and Tasso. But where these
writers had only brief
comments
to make, Speroni mulled the matter
over at length and on several occasions. Speroni’s dialogues on Virgil, several drafts or fragments of w~hich 1580,
were products of
his old age,
satisfactory completion. In his later
were written between 1563 and and none was ever brought to Speroni was more garrulous
life,
than trenchant, but up to the time of his death at 88, his flinty mind constantly struck sparks. Although his dialogues on Virgil, like his dialogues on history, are a wild disorder of inconsistent ideas, and
easy to be impatient with the old man, his suggest the
existence of large
islands
sallies
and
it is
tentative probings
or subcontinents
of
critical
doctrine of his time never entirely mapped. Speroni’s distinctions between history and poetry rested that the historian should state his action briefly, in
form, whereas the poet should be considered either action
—that
summary
of
is,
as the presenter
—or
it
as the
ments for the action. In derivative of rhetorical 7
Ibid.,
of the action
on the
summary
belief
narrative
as the imitator of
itself
and not
an
a brief
maker of concrete adornments and embellishwith this distinction, which is primarily a theory even though it owes much to the
line
pp. 348-353.
i93
The Age
of Criticism
Aristotelian theorv of poetry as imitation, Speroni felt forced to con-
Homer, was primarily a historian, whole campaign of Aeneas method of stating his action briefly, in summary
clude that Virgil, in comparison with
both because he took for
and because
in Italy
his
his action the
should be considered historical rather than poetic.
narrative form,
Poetic qualities are those that
come from amplitude
8 .
Speroni’s indiscriminate confusion of amplitude considered as
It is
imitation of concrete actions with amplitude considered as floridity of
ornamentation that
but the confusion apparently bothered Speroni he
properly copious with things (that
said, are
modem
mind,
Homer and
Ovid,
particularly disconcerting to the
is
little. is,
with the
copious only with words
tion imitated), but Virgil
is
master at creating beautiful
lines,
9 .
details of ac-
Virgil
is
the
but he did not construct a good action
and presented brief and sententious orations, “showing in that more of the historian than of the poet,
whose function
avoid brevity of utterance, because breyity allegria as
is
Speroni
full
of floridity and
10 .
“In short,
said:
not
to delight.” Poets
but does not imitate either
prolixity. Virgil narrates well
wars or fortunes well
is
it is
I
haye considered that the orations and
narrations of Virgil and his poetic descriptions are very noble, but he
does not imitate as he should, nor
is
he florid and ornate
as
he ought
more like a historian than a poet. He was studious of with which the poet should not be concerned if he wishes to
and he
to be;
brevity,
is
delight his readers, because breyity cannot be ornate and consequently
not delightful.
is
If
ornamentation demands amplification, with which
breyity cannot coexist, brevity cannot coexist with ornamentation,
which
is all
superabundance, and brevity
much
sary or as
rather than more. This
derives the notion that a
it
is
poem ought
is
a
rather less than the neces-
most notable
to
fact,
and from
be of only one action, not
only because an imitation ought to have only one thing imitated but also because, if
a
poem
poetry consists of redundant and superfluous ornament,
should have to
grow
more than one make his poem
to infinite size
were the poet
to undertake
to imitate
action poetically and provided that he should
want
perfect. Therefore, even in that aspect that
to
pedants praise, he [Virgil] merits blame, that
poem 8
in
making one
out of material comprising the Iliad and the Odyssey.
Speroni, “Dialogi sopra Virgilio,” in
Opere,
is,
II,
e
"Ibid., p. 435*
194
The poet
Speroni, “Sopra Virgilio,” in Opere,
IV, 574.
201.
single
Grandeur of Generality cannot do that and
ornament and amplify
it.
So the Virgilian
11
is
very beautiful but not poetic.”
is
carrying premises derived from Aristotle's theory of poetrv
brevity'
This
still
Our problem
as imitation to their full final implications.
in
compre-
hending their ultimate meaning can come in large measure bv attribut-
which they were written (after 1560) two decades earlier when the ideas contained in Aristotle’s Poetics impinged suddenly upon a theory' of poetry worked up out of findings in rhetorical texts. Speroni (with Tomitano) was ing these words to the time in
and not to
a time
the culminator of the fifteenth-century Humanists’ drift toward defin-
ing poetry as
eloquence.
Tomitano most
fully
defined
poetry
as
eloquence, using Speroni as his spokesman, but Speroni himself was the
writer
who most
elaborated the connection between eloquence and
the particularity of ornament.
expressing in the
with
his ideas
The
sixties, seventies,
ideas that Speroni got
and
eighties
about poetrv that were
less
around to
were not inconsistent
developed in
his dialogues
of 1540 and in Tomitano’s Ragionamenti of 1545, even respecting their
And
use of Aristotelian theorems.
important to realize that in an
it is
age of Virgil worshipers (and Speroni was one also) Speroni could nevertheless hold out for a concept of poetrv based
of detail rather than
upon
Homer and
Capriano, likewise a Virgil lover, had
is
a superfluous
that Virgil's restraint
a
is
better blending of nature and art. 12
Capriano, and Tasso was like that of
contained the richness of his
the fullness
the “grandeur of generality” of Pigna,
Giraldi Cinthio, and Tasso.
claimed in 1555 that there
upon
moment
exuberance of nature
more
tasteful
The stance of Xeo classicism;
compromise, Pigna,
in
a
Giraldi,
that of Speroni
in time, rather than, as Toftanin
used to maintain, looked ahead to the marinists and the metaphysicals. 13
Homer
delights us as he should,
Speroni
said,
by adorning and
amplifying his material, and
his poetry abounds with epithets. V irgil, on the other hand, delights with the depiction of marvels. The effects of Homer’s kind of writing are delight, joy, and hilarity'; of Virgil's
kind, stupor and melancholy
n Ibid.,
—
effects
Paduan rhetoric its own place We must be mindful that it was’ in an attack upon a metaphysical poet (Cowley) that Johnson made his most spirited defense of “the grandeur at giving
p. 439.
“Capriano, op.
belonging to the historian and
cit., sig.
“Giuseppe Toffanin,
11
C3V. cinquecento
(Milano, 1950), pp. m-112. I do not mean to deny here a connection between the spirit of Speroni and that of the seventeenth century;
I
in history.
of generality”
aim instead 195
The Age
of Criticism
not to the poet, for the effect of history comes from the thing
from
rather than
itself
ornamentation. Speroni compared the effect of
its
Virgil’s poetry to that of the
Colosseum or the pyramids and likened
Homer’s poetry
to that of the Corinthian style of archi-
the effect of
tecture or to the beauty of the
He
Laocoon
statue or the Apollo Belvedere.
which
explained that the grandeur of the Colosseum,
rough
stones,
objected,
is
can be admired without ornament. All of
more
made of can be
interesting than ultimately satisfying, and Speroni
must have realized that
here were inconclusive, for he
his speculations
added: “I do not deny that the marvelous
way
is
this, it
than the florid object
delightful, but in another
is
Brevity in Virgil, he
is.”
overwhelms
felt,
so
his
theory
the reader that he cannot feel happiness.
The
dire schism
between Speroni’s
his
concluding:
“Surely
this
perhaps
less
in
Homer’s], but style
it
is
taste
work
of
poetic.” Virgil he
He
but not in invention and disposition.
orator
who was very good
in proving, if
the other
Can we
two
it
is
moving or
at
supposed proving
is
at
and
Virgil’s
is
“as
seen
is
greater
is
[than
found noblest
would be
in
also an
portraying character but not
demanded by the
art
and
are outside the art.”
say,
Speroni asked, that in Virgil an Asiatic style of poetry
supplanted the Attic style of Homer, comparable to what happened in oratory? His speculation was that “just as the Asiatics quite outside of art
and proof proliferated in matters pertaining to movement, to figures
of speech, and to the character left aside the imitation
traits
of the speaker, so the Asiatic poet
of the fable, which
is
the soul of a poem, and
gave himself over to imitating things extra fabulam, which things he
however, imitate well and exactly.
did,
paints
shall give
I
an example: Titian
and has neither invention nor principal fable in
nevertheless, in his figures and images imitates very well, as
when
which
his painting;
are extra fabulam he
he creates a resemblance between a char-
acter and a particular person; and in the persons introduced without real cause into his paintings
face,
he will imitate very well a foot, a
leg, a
an emotion, or a movement. But such things do not pertain to
the fable of the picture. also.” 14
And
it
is
perhaps true that Virgil did
this
Probably Speroni meant by the fablelessness of Titian’s paint-
ing the lack of overriding meanings rather than pictorial composition.
His analogy was
at
best an insecure
one,
however
Speroni’s whole analysis of the difference between 14
Speroni, “Sopra Virgilio,” in
196
Opere IV, ,
574.
revealing.
Homer and
But
Virgil
Grandeur of Generality was expressive rather than definitive. His diction throughout was cautionary, full of words like “perhaps” and “it-may-be-that.” He said also that in Virgil the verses,
which constituted
his
over the truly poetic element in the Aeneid, in that gilt paint
of
might cover up the defects of
Homer “whose
poem but
verses
major
much
a statue.
effort,
cover
the same
This
way
not true
is
do not seem to be mere ornamentation of
to be naturally
born and developed with
it.”
his
15
Castelvetro said several things in line with the ideas of Speroni in the course of classifying kinds of narrative.
could be divided into two
classes,
He
said that narratives
universalized and particularized.
Universalized narrative deals with classes of beings, with species, or
with wholes; particularized narratives give us individuals or examples, he stated that the Aeneid
is
units.
a generalized narrative,
the Iliad and Odyssey are particularized ones.
The
As and
special effects of
universalized narrative, Castelvetro held, are grandeur and magnifi-
cence, and defects can easily be hidden in this kind of narrative. Particularized narrative
discerned in indistinct
it.
is
low and humble, and defects can
be
easily
Universalized narrative can be compared to small and
painting.
While bad
painters should
recognize their in-
adequacies and paint small, great painters such as Michelangelo paint larger than life size. Consequently,
proof of
his
Homer’s particularized narrative
is
great genius. Virgil, to the contrary, hid himself in
which he could produce with less labor 16 The following passage from Castelvetro likewise parallels passages in Speroni: “For since the poet imitates more fully in narrating the
the universalized form
.
particularized material of the action than the universalized, that only the particularized material of the action trast
is
it
follows
imitable, in con-
to the universalized, which can be said to be nonimitable. For
these reasons
it
seems
we
can conclude that Homer,
who
often intro-
duces characters speaking and attributes long speeches to them and
consequently uses the particularized material of the action,
and consequently
a
is
an imitator
poet but that Virgil, in rarely introducing speaking
by assigning, much more than Homer, only brief speeches them and by using material of action that is universalized, is not
characters or to
an imitator and consequently not a poet.” It is
17
with these ideas of Speroni and Castelvetro in mind that
we
should turn to the sixty-ninth chapter of the third book of Jacopo ™lbid., pp. 575-578. M Bongiorno, op. cit., pp. 100- 101.
17
Castelvetro, Poetica d’Aristotele, p.
545.
197
The Age
of Criticism
Mazzoni’s Della difesa della Comedia di Dante (1587), for the three put together, even though they do not very closely agree, give us insight into
one of the important aspects of literary speculation
in the
Renaissance. Like Speroni, Mazzoni culled from the classical rhetorical tradition the necessary distinctions
between the summary brevity of
oratory and the particularization to be expected in poetry. This distinction he introduced as part of a discussion of the differences
between
Attic and Asiatic oratorical styles in antiquity. Mazzoni held that by
manipulating
many on
we
this polarity in oratorical styles
can come to resolve
confusions that exist in poetic theory. For the source of his ideas
this score
made
he
specific reference to the Epistles of Pliny the
Younger.
The
Attic orator, Mazzoni said, considers vain and redundant the
largess
and expansiveness of the Asiatic orator. The
Asiatics, to the
contrary, are particularly concerned that an expression be carried
“with
live
force into the
memory
home
which cannot be done with-
of men,”
out lingering upon the exposition of a concept. But the important tinction for
Mazzoni was whether
a
writer or speaker wished to
he wanted to act
function as orator or as poet.
If
follow the rules of
they were
his trade as
dis-
laid
Dionysius of Halicarnassus, according to
as orator,
he should
down by Longinus
whom
or by
the four virtues of
oratory were clarity, magnificence, brevity, and probability (a simplification of the seven virtues or Ideas of
Hermogenes), so that
oratorical narration the Attic style should be
But Mazzoni maintained that brevity has place of brevity is
less
place in poetry: “But in
[poetry] should possess another virtue
it
in
generally preferable.
perhaps entirely contrary to brevity. This virtue
is
— one which
particularization,
by means of which
the poet should reveal and explain his concept
minutely, since in this
way
resemblance to
One
difference
of nomenclature.
he will put
his stress
on imitating and bearing
that he has occasion to deal with.”
all
is
clear
To
18
between Mazzoni’s and Speroni’s distribution
Speroni, Virgil
was an
Asiatic poet because he
indulged in elaborate attention to ornamental detail that was irrelevant or even inimical to successful imitation of an action, and
an Atticist because
his particularizations
were those needed
the imitation of an action. According to Mazzoni, in the Asiatic
all
to express
poets use language
manner, for they must not be frugal with particulars
they are to achieve imitations of concrete 18
Homer was
Mazzoni, Della
difesa,
I,
971-974.
reality,
if
or at least of universal
Grandeur of Generality terms of concrete actions. Mazzoni nowhere speaks of the
reality in
“grandeur of generality.”
He
however, face
did,
at considerable length
by
the question of whether or not narration (conducted
narrator) in an epic
poem could be properly
being especially important in this connection because
thought of
as
the poet as
called imitation, the point if
imitation
were
applying only to stage presentations the need for par-
poetry would apply only to the presence of the actors on
ticulars in
the stage, to details of stage effects, and not necessarily to the poetry.
This particular argument has most pertinence to Mazzoni’s theories of imitation and less to his ideas about universal and particulars.
need say only that he reviewed
between
icastic
and fantastic imitation and engaged
on an assemblage of
citations
from both Plato and
the kinds and degrees of imitation. reality,
making of
much charged with Some of the deeper as
Mazzoni’s
the imagined image of concrete
It is
(even though not untraditional)
Mazzoni believed that poetry should be
he had to dispose of the notion that an existing,
poet entirely turns
away from
Let us say
way
that,
“Now
any true exemplar,
it
since the fantastic
although previously in the beginning of the third that the idol
is
idols bear relations to
can be,
the idol of
seems that the fantastic poet
without any correspondence to
now
we must know
(as
it
seems Plato be-
some true exemplar, the
poet forms idols and simulacra of the truth. this
this position,
which is the imitation of which does not exist; that
representing an idol of the true in the
exemplary truth, nevertheless, supposing all
fantastic imitation
defend
represent the idol and the simulacrum of the true.
book we have proved lieved) that
direct explana-
idol,
cannot be of a fantasy,
that has already been shown. So
cannot in any
how
To
presupposes an exemplar in the true world:
the fantastic poet does not have
way
more
And
in order to
this
is
when
the facts about this or that
the kind of truth about
fantastic
understand
that truth can be considered (as the
logicians say) either in the concrete or in the abstract. It
the concrete
of his
and of the nature of poetic
rather than a portrait of real-life happenings.
it
aspects
theory are better revealed here in relation to
critical
something
His imitation
these idols or images, and the narrative poet
doctrine of particulars and universal than in his
is,
a poet.
this task as the dramatic.
tions of the place of imagination in poetry
imitation.
in close reasoning
Aristotle concerning
according to Mazzoni, that makes the poet
consists in the is
Here we
his interpretations of Plato’s distinctions
which the
man
icastic
is
taken in
are considered.
poet makes 199
idols.
And The
The Age
of Criticism
other kind of truth taken in the abstract the deed of this or that
And
man but
is
found when
kind of truth the idol of which
this is that
we
consider not
the nature of vice and virtue in
made by
is
itself.
the fantastic
19
poet.”
In spite of the unusualness of Mazzoni’s analysis for his time, nothing
could be plainer than
from
The
this as a justification of the liberation of the
poet
actual fact provided that he remain true to general concepts.
between Mazzoni and Tasso
chief difference
Mazzoni’s greater character. It
Taking
hero.
stress
on
hints
to be found in
universality of action rather than static
the vice or virtue that
is
is
not the image of the
static,
is
from Dion Chrysostom
20 ,
Mazzoni outlined
a
con-
cept of universalized action based upon poetic justice with citations of the case of Pandarus the perjurer dying
wound
and the glutton Antinoos by a
member
reason that
we
have
how
it
that
is
we
it
according to
in the gullet, “since
in the abstract,
that resembles the truth of
poetics and history at the place
history recounts things as they .
tongue
And
here
it
forms
in the con-
in the abstract.
.
.
.
can understand the difference that Aristotle wished to
make between to be done.
in the
he [the fantastic poet], paying attention to the nature
crete an idol of this
wound
a
peccant ought to be punished.
and the due punishment of that vice
From
by
.
.
And
thus
it
where he
were done and the poetic
can be seen
how
as
affirms that
they ought
the fantastic poet repre-
what is true universally.” 21 But although Mazzoni took full account of
sents the idol of
his reasonings, the
by
backbone of
the classical rhetoricians.
owes
Few
Mazzoni the
strated better than
to the rhetoricians, even
Aristotle and Plato in
was provided for him theorists have ever demon-
his explanation
literary
modern
poetic theory
their statements
about poetry
real debt that
though
have to be pieced and patched together from snippets did
it.
It is
just as
Mazzoni
necessary to return to the rhetorical concept of enargeia
for Mazzoni’s further elaboration of the need for particularization in
poetry. His argument again runs that
if
narrative poetry
is
imitation
by particularization. “The final reason,” Mazzoni said, “by means of which we can conclude that poetic recounting is imitation is based on particularization, which is in our judgment the proper instrument for the poetic. And by virtue of this instrument the poet
it is
19
20
imitation
by
Ibid., p. 684.
Dionis
Vrusaensis
Chrysostomum quae 200
quern
vocant
extant omnia
,
ed.
21
de Arnim (Berlin, 1896), II, 121. Mazzoni, Della difesa, I, 685-686.
J.
Grandeur of Generality ought to explicate minutely and represent distinctly that he undertakes to treat before our eyes.”
important though minor rhetoricians
all
the things
Mazzoni turned
to such
Aquila and Rutilius for the
as
partitioning of the principle of enargeia into
its
subclasses 22 while ,
basing his understanding of enargeia generally on Hermogenes. varieties
of enargeia are
The
and merismos.
char act erismos
diatyposis ,
Aquila made diatyposis apply to the external appearance and discernible objective characteristics and habits of the personae of a story, but
Mazzoni wished to extend the principle of particularization involved to the surrounding scene as well. Characterismos, according to Rutilius, applies to the manifestation of internal traits of character. Rutilius said:
“Just as a painter describes figures with colors, so the orator in this
manner
figures forth either the vices or the virtues of those of
he speaks.” Merismos
is
a
whom
formal description in which partitively
all
But
al-
aspects of a situation are given their unique characteristics.
though these three figures of thought had been defined for the orator’s use,
Mazzoni was at pains to show that according to Hermogenes the which comprises them all constitutes poetic imitation (*ai to
enargeia
/xeyt (jtov 7roL7]cr€0) 444
277-
274-275,
284, 285, 299, 401, 413, 425-428
Bacon, Sir Francis, 5, 303, 315, 361 Bacon, Roger, 422 Baker, Courtland D., 421-424
34 1
305, 307, 332,
364, 369 373 > 37 8 Francesco, 55-58, 65, 79-80,
342 , 347 355 * 358 :
294
206, 256 119,
168, 304,
Basil,
254 Batteux, Charles, 248 Battista, Giuseppe, 220
Beauty, 141, 152, 194, 317, 326, 341-348, 407, 432 Bees and silkworms, 449-451 Being, 440 Bellini, Giovanni, 106
Bembo,
Pietro, 92-93, 96, 325, 342, 350 Beni, Paolo, 7, 12, 20-24, 26, 29, 65, 80, 84-85, 88, 91, 104, 111-117, 132, 134, 136-137, 146-147, 155-158, 164, 185-186,
Caietano, see Gaietanus Camillo, Giulio (Delminio), 168 Campana, Francesco, 210
Campanella, Tommaso, 6, 307, 343 Campbell, L. B., 214 Canace and Macareo, 233 Canzoni, 27, 59, no-in Capponi, Orazio, 54, 78, 424 Capriano, G. P., 34-35, 70-71, 82,
284-290,
Cary, Henry, 372, 379
298-299, 401, 413, 428-430, 437, 458-459 Bergson, Henri, 281
Cassiodorus, 378 Castelvetro, Ludovico,
189,
244,
Bernard,
258,
281,
274-275,
Bernard of Chartres, 361
142,
209,
210,
299,
402, 423
Blackmore, Sir Richard, 59 Blank verse, 92, no Boccaccio, Giovanni, 45, 89-90, 97, 101, 104,
1
93, 95,
16, 180, 209, 259, 261, 269,
368 Boccalini, Traiano, 459 Bocchi, Francesco, 453-455 Bodin, Jean, 147
Body,
181,
148,
235, 351, 412, 450
Brevity, 196, 198, 202
,
464
*
*
167,
177-188,
*
Cataphoric ecstasy, 386
88,
92,
traits, 134, 136,
146,
11,
108, 230, 233, 300
Cavalcanti, Guido, 98-99, 345 Celestial spheres, 407
Chaldeans, 418 Character, 148, 200; 156,
Brocardo, Antonio, 231 Brooks, Cleanth, 130 Browning, Robert, 41 Bruno, Giordano, 6, 18-19, 3°7> 43 8 441, 455 456 *
157,
154,
219-220, 234, 236, 242, 244, 247, 274, 277-282, 288, 306, 349, 350“ 2 o353 355 376* 4 01 * 4 II 4 I 3 * 4 * 7 4 426, 429, 448-451 Castravilla, Ridolfo, 356 Cataleptic fantasy, 364 207,
Catullus, 122, 376 Cavalcanti, Bartolommeo,
*
72,
146-150,
197,
205-300 Catholic Church, 408 Cato, 59
Boethius, 29, 53, 90, 95 Bonciani, Francesco, 88, 97-98, 259, 294, 2 99 394 38,
37-
Catharsis,
312, 343, 345, 363, 415, 426
Bongiorno, Andrew,
11, 16, 18-19,
43, 52, 67, 71, 73, 75, 78, 82-83, 85-90, 95-104, 107-109, 1 1 3, 122, 131-132, 141-
St., 17
Bernays, Jacob, 256 Berni, Francesco, 27 Beroaldo, Filippo, 122,
132,
138-139, 147, 161, 195, 300, 402, 405 Caro, Annibale, 106
275
Characterismos, 122, 201 153, 446 Charlton, H. B., 18-19, 132, 150, 235-236 Charron, Pierre, 388 Chimeras, 393
Charlemagne,
hid ex Christian influences, 21, 55, 153, 156, 208, 209, 220, 223, 235, 242, 263, 272, 335, " . . 373 . 382, 399 4QL 4 l6 , 4 21
343 347 430, 432, 434, 436-437. 44°
Chrysippas, 366-367 Fathers, 421 Cicero, 6, 7, 31-32, 4 °. 53
Demons, 68, 7 2 " 73 .
.
79
.
16, 122, 13
266-267, 271, 285, 332, 364,
261,
375, 402, 410, 417 Civil faculty, 265
1
8,
137,
135,
13,
262-265,
255,
35, 40, 60,
30,
27,
180,
173,
278,
2 73.
97,
in,
185, 245, 249,
280,
282,
285,
287, 289-295, 298-299, 434; in prose, 88, 90, 94,
Common
105-106,
no-in,
sense, 319,
1
14 327-328, 332, 335,
340 Conceits, poetic, 360, 368-370, 376-377 Concreteness, 4, 12, 36, 53, 117
Concrete universal, 13 1, 337 Contemplation, 79, 347 Cook, Albert S., 19 Copernican universe, 436 Corneille, Pierre, 236, 275, 285, 288, 300
Corybantes, 286, 418 Cosimo de’ Medici, 335 Council of Trent, 408, 436, 447
Counter Reform,
325-326, 376-377, 382, 384, 416
Dennis, John, 446 Denores, Jason, 80, 107, 109, 155, 157, 244-246, 268,
207,
170,
298 Descartes,
Rene,
273,
275,
306-307,
303-304,
5,
294,
312, 388
Clairvoyance, 325, 384 Cogitative faculty, 320, 340 Coleridge, S. T., 348, 360, 388, 391, 395396 Columella, 68 Comanino, Don Gregorio, 394
Comedy,
410, 415, 417,
Demosthenes, 90
1, 145, 174, 205, 93, 101, 108, 209, 214, 220, 226, 229, 230, 238, 240,
255,
182, 202
419-420
Church
1
Demetrius Phalereus, 122, Demigorgons, 384 Democritus, 104, 381, 406,
223, 307, 408, 436, 447
Cremonini, Cesare, 108 Croce, Benedetto, 88, 206, 218 Cyprian, 106
Description, 28, 81,
202;
imitation,
as
121
Dewey, John, Dialectic,
8,
Dialogues,
396 184
12,
31, 61, 68, 88, 90, 93, 95,
97-103, 105, 108, no, Diatyposis, 122, 201
1
13,
1
16,
403
Dilthey, Wilhelm, 209, 214
Diodorus Siculus, Diogenes Laertius, Dion Chrysostom,
12
367, 378, 451 200, 260, 429
Dionysius of Halicarnassus, 89-90,
112,
198
Dionysius the Areopagite, 263, 286, 394, 395-396
Dithyrambic, 60, 63,
10,
37,
44, 49,
51-52, 55,
430
Dolce, Ludovico, 69-70, 82, 409 Donatus, 5, 7, 433 Dramatic poetry, 15, 23-64, 95, 118, 191r 9 2 199 438 .
.
Dreams,
119, 324-325, 332, 337, 340, 350,
-
355 359
.
368, 370, 375-389
Dryden, John, hi, 220, 223, DuBos, J. B., 16, 248, 295
Duns
275, 282
Scotus, 163, 307, 385
Eclogues,
Dance, imitation
in,
44,
56
27, 62 Ecstasy, 325, 347, 369, 386, 416
Daniello, Bernardino, 211
Effigy, 14, 16, 68, 353, 395
Dante,
Egyptians, 418
27, 29, 66-67, 74-76, 80, 85-86, 92,
97, 121, 123, 125, 209, 223, 224, 255, 303, 307 . 335 . 347 . 350 . 35 2 . 355 ~ 3 8 9 . 4° 2 .
4 2 4 435 45 2 David, 286, 294, 429, 430 Da Vinci, Leonardo, 27 .
.
Decorum,
115,
1
3 1,
135, 152, 233
Dejob, Charles, 408
De
Barba, Pompeo, 342-344 Delight, 141, 156, 181, 194-195, 231, 254, 257 2 96, 298. 333 337 443 Della Casa, Giovanni, 108, 254, 256, 259, la
.
2 94 .
.
347
.
.
45 2 -454
Della Volpe, Galvano, 218, 224, 432
Eikonopoioi 20 ,
Elegies, 27, 35, 53, 59, 92 Eliot, T. S., 4
Elledge, Scott, 333
Eloquence, 67-68, 195, Else, Gerald F., 256 Empedocles, 17-18, 20, 93,
316, 331, 435, 442 62, 65-80, 84, 89,
10 1 , 181, 387, 427
Empusas, 384 Enargeia, 10-n, 15-16,
18, 20, 22, 25, 29-
3°, 57-58, 63, 84, 121-122,
1
3 1,
134, 183,
190-191, 200, 202, 297, 332, 352, 358
Enchantments, 350
465
Index Entertainment, poetry as, 125 Enthusiasm, 286, 294, 416-417, 420, 422, 4 2 5> 4 2 9 Ephesius, see Michael of Ephesus Ephraltes, 384 Epic poetry, 10, 15, 27-31, 35, 42, 50-51, 60, 84, 89,
95,97,111,
152,
173,
154,
180,
1
14,
185,
1
16, 137, 144,
190-191,
199,
262-263, 280, 282, 293, 299, 391, 394, 423, 438, 441, 450
Epictetus, 364-365 Epicureans, 260-261, 381-382
Epigram, 59, 62, no, 450 Episodes, 179 Epithalamion, 62 Equicola, Mario, 147, 213, 402, 434-436 Erastus, 116
Floridity, 194 Florio, John, 427 Formalists, 244, 355
Fracastoro, Girolamo, 304,
315-329,
306,
18, 68,
72-73, 79,
335-336,
341,
Frachetta, Girolamo, 88, 98, 345-346 Frenzy, 325, 332 Freud, Sigmund, 207, 219, 228-229, 325, 357, 377, 39b Fulgentius, 367, 370 Furor, 286, 326, 398-459
Fusco, Antonio, 18 Gabriele, Trifon, 70, 160 Gaietanus Thienensis, 336, 338 Gale, Thomas, 264
Erizzo, Sebastiano, 409 Etherial vehicle, 363
Galen, 306, 340, 362-363, 387, 418
Ethos, 264-273
Garin, Eugenio, 425
Euripides, 422 Eustathius, 91, 381 Eustratius, 168 Evangelists, 395 Evidentia, see Enargeia
Gelli,
Example, 138, 142, 144-158, 199, 276-278, 283; proof by, 68, 147, 323
Exemplum,
28 Exercise, 451
Experience, 165, 228, 338 Expression, 86 Expressionism, 3 Expressive poems, 40 Fable, 10, 12, 16, 19, 32-33, 42, 45, 47-48, 56-58, 72, 74, 92, 97, 115-116, 139, 149, 160,
175,
183,
193,
196, 249, 257, 296,
298, 382; false speech as, 84 Fables, 75, 172, 314, 386, 457 Fancy, 350-351, 391-392, 395 Fantastic imitation, 14-16, 24-25, 34, 51, 77, 1 18, 120-125, l 7 *99> 202, 350-351,
^
359,
363, 381, 404-406
Galileo,
307
6,
Giovan
Battista,
335-339, 341
Generality, 333 Genii, 384 Genius, 326, 409, 414-415, 4*9, 4 2 4, 4 2 8, 430, 438, 443-454, 458-459
Genova, Marc Antonio,
32-33,
Genres, 62, 137, 438 Giacomini, Lorenzo,
103,
88,
331
244,
246,
251-261, 269, 299, 451 Gilbert, Allan H., 24, 88, 211, 226-227, 271, 327, 394-395, 401 Gildon, Charles, 446
Giojosi dances, 27 Giotto, 149 Giraldi Cinthio, G. 106,
108,
292,
353, 444-445
132,
B.,
191,
n,
193,
19, 88, 92-93,
196, 201,
212,
Giusquino, 106 Gladitorial games, 233, 245, 248-249, 269 God, 344; as imitator, 21; as magnet,
beauty of, 431-432; dreams created by, 325; grace of, 421, 424; ir-
422;
353, 390-39 1 , 395 Fantastics, 332
radiations from, 322; light from, 378;
Fantasy, 78, 120, 123-124, 199, 249-250, 302-396, 435 Farquhar, George, 446 Festus, 285
of, 322;
Ficino, Marsilio, 306, 343, 346, 401-402, 407, 424-425, 43i, 434 Figures, 368
Finder, poet Fine art, 4 First fantasy,
as,
176
323
Flaminio, M. Antonio, 325 Florentine Academy, 335, 339, 342, 451
466
nature imitates, 440; our knowledge Providence of, 383; reason of, 214; revealed in nature, 444
Gonzaga, Scipione, 150-151 Gorgias, 201
Grammar,
325
Grandeur,
152, 189-202
Gualandi, Adouardo, 103 Guarini, Alessandro, 19-20, 58-60, 132191, 192, 452 Guarini, G. B., 54-55, 59, 106, 108, 235,
244,
246,
259,
263, 265,
277-278, 288, 294, 299
268-273, 275,
Index Guastavini, Giulio, 132, 176, 306, 393 Gudeman, Alfred, 88, 401 Guidiccioni, Giovanni, 346 Gulick, C. B., 216
277-278,
273,
283,
294,
299,
325-326,
4~5
Humors,
258,
253,
268,
264,
259,
269,
325, 418, 425-426, 432
Hymns,
62, 277 Hypocritics, 184
Habit, 380, 451, 455 Hallucination, 358, 366, 384
Hypotyposis, 20
Harmony,
Iamblichus, 258, 264, 277, 280, 287, 347,
91
Harvey, Sir Paul, 309 Harvey, William, 306
42 7 Icastic imitation, 14-16, 24-25, 34, 51, 77, 1 18, 123, 199, 200, 202, 350-353, 390-
Hathaway, Baxter, 220, 223, 252 Hebrews, 285, 418, 430 Hegel, Georg W. F., 6, 206, 337 Heightened reality, 144- 145
39 1 395 Icons, 13, 353 Idea, 138-139, 142, 144-145, 148, 150-151, ,
Heinsius, Daniel, 220 Heliodorus, 90, 116
157-158,
Gandavo, see Henry of
Henricus a
Ghent Henry of Ghent,
Idol,
366 Heraclides Ponticus, 73, 429 Heraclitus, 417 Hermes Trismegistus, 285
Hermogenes,
10,
112, 12
Herodotus, 90, 183 Heroic poetry, 27, 156,
190,
249,
192, 262, 292, 392, 396,
15
1,
434
96
120,
395 Hippocrates, 262, 340 History: and poetry, 16, 17, 22, 24, 33, 43, 45, 50, 60, 62-63, 90, 93, 109-110, 1 13, 122-124, 129-202, 219, 273, 295; 1, 178, 182; characters from, 392; in fable, 390; in poetry, 396 Homeopathy, 210, 222, 253-254, 259,
art of, 13
261-264, 270, 277-278, 294
Homer,
10, 13, 16, 17, 18, 24, 27, 29, 38,
42, 46, 55, 66, 70, 73, 89, 90, 93, 101, ii2, 113, 121, 135, 146, 150, 152, 154, i55» *5 6 » *7°. J 74, i9*» i93> 195* i97> 199, 201, 217, 275, 353, 381, 394, 415,
4 r 7» 4i9. 4M, 435, 44i, 452, 455, 457
Horace,
5, 6, 13, 16, 55, 70,
72-73, 79, 91, 153, 174, 205,
101, 122, 13 1, 135, 212, 226, 266, 267, 332, 376, 382, 393, 402, 409, 410, 415, 419, 426, 429, 433, 444, 447, 448, 450, 45i Housman, A. E., 238
98,
Hudson,
W.
Humanists,
198,
185,
322,
342,
44-48,
25,
51,
77-78,
72,
18-
1
14,
16, 47,
321,
330,
121-122, 199, 201-202,
336-339,
332,
343-344,
353; 375, 390 Imagination, 11-12, 57, 63, 85, 199, 301-
396 92, 98, 115-116,
22, 70, 72, 79,
Hesy chius,
14,
Image,
Heseltine, J. B., 309
Hesiod,
182,
125, 199, 202, 249, 381, 390, 394-395
145, 198, 201
1,
162,
344, 354, 392, 447 Idealization, 150, 17
H., 282
147, 209, 224, 316, 329, 347,
389, 401, 416, 447-449
Humanity, 276
Hume, David, 219 Humoral psychology,
Imitation, 1-125, 191-217, 331, 349, 353, 356, 359, 376-377, 389, 39i, 440, 444449; of history, 351; of other poets, 416, 444, 448-449, 455-456 Ingegneri, Angelo, 294-295 Inquisition, 232, 402
Inspiration, 347, 352, 369, 398-459 Instinct, 324 Intellect, 311-314, 318, 322-323, 327-328,
333-338, 340, 345, 347, 354, 358371-373, 378, 384, 385, 424, 435, 454; active, 322-323, 336, 338, 345; created, 382; passive, 323, 373; pos330, 360,
sible, 344-345, 357 Intentions, 324; secondary,
Invention,
8,
174,
176-177,
182,
185-186,
308,
316-317,
326,
340,
358, 363-368, 375, 386, 415, 426, 428, 449, 457 Isidore of Seville, 422
134,
189,
196,
349-353,
356-
390-39 1
4 12
,
Isocrates, 90, 451
James, Henry, 179 Jarrell, Randall, 357 Jean de Jandun, 336 Jerome, 378 Jests, 443 Job, 59
Johnson, Samuel, 205, 268, 269-270,
380
19, 33, 51, 71, 98, 117,
129,
190,
Josephus, 285
467
195,
202
,
Index Jowett, Benjamin, 312
Marmi, 384
Judgment,
Martial, 95 Martianus Capella, 95
340, 428, 445 Jung, C. C., 396
Kant, Immanuel, 6 Kelso, Ruth, 317 Kroll,
v
Marvelous,
141,
151,
credible,
124,
390
195, 257, 388, 450;
Marvels, 30, 308, 353, 367, 391-392 Masini, Filippo, 88, 103, 346-348, 407-408,
W., 214
416, 422, 433
Masks, 16, 36, 44 Mathematics, 320, 331 Maximus of Tyre, 79, 152, 435 Mazzeo, Joseph A., 360, 369, 394 Mazzoni, Giacopo, 6, 7, 12-13, 16,
Lambinus, 10 La Motte, Houdar de, 1 1 Langer, Susanne K., 396 Lapini, Frosino, 207, 220, 237, 293 Lattantio, 367, 370 Lessing,
G.
E., 257, 300
Light, 333, 347, 378, 395, 419, 423, 432,
132,
446 Linus, 405 Lionardi, Alessandro,
32-33,
81,
132,
no
12
1,
*
Lucian, 108,
70, 71, 76, 93, 31, 45, 93, 97,
325, 417, 425-429, 455, 457
Menzini, Benedetto, 259
101, 351
100-101, 104-105,
Lucretius, 20, 65-80, 93, 101, 252, 257, 147,
306,
Merismos Metaphor, ,
as furor, 415,
121
4J5, 455 Luisino, Francesco,
393, 410,
122, 201
283,
312,
Migne, J. P., 394 Mill, John Stuart, 6
Luther, Martin, 447 Lyric poetry, 8, 35, 44, 53, 62,
Mimes, 84,
86,
Macrobius, 375, 384
132,
26,
29,
35,
61,
100-
209, 211, 214-228, 239-
246, 251-252, 264, 267, 271, 283, 287289, 292, 299, 339, 355
Magnetism, 422 Maker, poet as, 175 Malebranche, Nicolas, Manilius, 72
Marenzio, Luca, 106 Marino, G. B., 459
468
no
Mimesis, see Imitation
Mind, 311-312, 322, 333, 345, 380, 426 Minturno, Antonio, 19, 35-37, 43, 47,
274,
no
174,
382,
53, 70, 82, 88, 93-94, 132, 172-173, 207, 220, 225, 227, 229-230, 234-235, 247,
Machiavelli, Niccolo, 211
101,
380,
Milton, John, 144, 232, 256
no-in, 114-115, 191, 193, 423; imitation in, 15, 19, 35, 47, 55, 58, 60
Maggi, Vincenzo,
357-359,
450 Metaphysics, 184, 190 Metrics, 184 Michael of Ephesus, 418 Michelangelo, 197, 455 Michele, Agostino, 88, 91, 103, 105-112, 1 15, 133, 186-188, 298
451 Lustration, 205, 372, 418, 421, 425 Lutatio, 367
Madrigals, 59,
198-
Menander, 273
198, 201, 329, 332
435
Lucan,
176,
321, 328, 330, 333, 336, 338-340, 345, 358, 37i, 395, 424, 454
221, 292
Love, 341-348, 422, 432; 1
162-163,
Memory,
Lorenzo the Magnificent, 341 43
157,
304, 306, 315, 333, 349-350, 353, 355385, 386-390, 394, 396, 424
Melancholy,
Lombardi, Bartolomeo, Longfellow, H. W., 36 10,
155,
Medici, Cosimo de’, 335 Medicine, 254, 283, 325
Logic, 184, 304, 325
Longinus,
147,
202, 244, 246, 258-259, 263-270, 277, 288,
146-147, 300, 402 Lioncelli dances, 27
Locke, John, 5 Lodoici, Giacopo,
20,
23-26, 35, 41, 47, 50-54, 60, 65-66, 7578, 85, 88, 103, 107-108, in, 118-125,
388, 427
293,
353,
446-450 Mirror theory,
5,
408,
422-423,
435-436,
17, 28, 35, 40, 68, 76,
117, 119, 138, 144, 146, 191, 343,
447 Mithradatic principle, 207, 214-229, 234, 237-239, 244-245, 249-251, 267, 269-270, 288, 293, 299 Mocenigo, Alvise, 229-234
257,
261,
Moderns, see Ancients and Moderns Monsters, 393 Montagna, Bartolomeo, 27 Montaigne, Michel de, 325, 343, 359, 427
Index Moral
attraction, 135; ideals, 138; sense,
248; utility, 245
197,
Morpheus, 387 Moving, 333 Muratori, L. A., 147, 41 Muses, 407, 410, 412, 416, 424-425, 429, 432-435 27,
35,
209-210, 222,
56, 60, 67,
231, 251, 253, 255, 258, 261, 277, 286, 290, 294, 405, 448; of the spheres, 431-
436
Muzio, Girolamo,
12, 107, 132, 134,
136,
71, 97
sympathy,
220,
255,
284, 299, 426-427, 455 114, 116, 134, 139, 150, 161, 166, 195, 249, 322, 326-327, 331, 380,
imitates
387, 415, 419, 430, 437-459;
God,
21; verse
Navagero, Andrea,
from, 71
317, 405
Necessity, 16, 167-170, 175, 218 Neoclassicism, 40, 80, 129, 13 1, 145, 164, 195, 223, 236, 238, 257, 278, 282, 355, y
443, 446, 451, 457
Neoplatonism,
Painting, 197, 320, 333, 448; and poetry, 13, 14-16, 27, 30, 44, 49-50, 56-57, 6061, 67, 81, 84, 86, no, 121-122, 142, 145,
97,
306,
315,
323,
343, 346-347, 356, 360, 379, 384, 396, 414, 416, 419, 422, 428, 432, 437
Nicander, 72 Nominalism, 159, 163, 189, 441 Novella 12, 66, 88, 90, 94, 97, 294 Novelty, 152
Particulars,
27, 59, 62,
no
Passions,
31, 214,
249
393
Orators and oratory,
17, 93, 135, 160, 167,
198, 201, 231,
264, 310,
333, 4°5, 4 1 ®, 4 2 3» 426, 43, 433* 43^,
442-443, 445, 458 Orlando, 106
17,
129-202,
312,
317,
336,
59-60,
154,
159,
205-300,
192,
Pathos, 264-273
Francesco, 6, 8, 9-20, 35, 43-45, 48-49, 51, 58, 60, 72-74, 79, 88-91, 99, 107, 109-110, 125, 13 1, 132, 147, 150,
Patrizi,
251, 258,
298-299,
167,
182,
187,
191,
306,
330,
353,
392, 400, 409, 413-420,
423-426,
429, 44i. 455-457
431,
433-434.
43 6
»
438,
St., 347, 395 Pausanias, 418, 429 Pazzi, Andrea de’, 29, 209 Pellegrino, Camillo, 75, 88, 99-102, 133,
154. 39 1 . 452
Perino del Vaga, 148 Peripatetic school, 26, 48, 61, 155, 224, 260,
322-323, 335, 341, 360, 362,
Orlando,
132, 176, 306, 393
139, 209, 214, 238, 252, 262, 294, 335,
338, 196,
196, 231,
Peter of Auvergne, 208, 261-262 Petrarch, 27, 36, 43, 47, 53, 59, 92, 103,
68, 320, 335, 340, 356, 365, 368,
184,
168,
352, 361, 366, 387, 418, 430, 435 Pastoral, 90, in, 268, 434
Pescetti,
theater, 107
One and Many,
173,
160,
384-385 Persona, 8, 22, 63
Objective correlative, 352, 376
Opinion,
157,
344-345. 35 1 , 39 2 -393. 446, 453 Pascal, Blaise, 5
241,
Olympic
153,
Paul, 304,
341,
Ode,
148,
279-280,
Nature, 68, 385,
Padelford, F. M., 20, 69, 132, 410 Padoane dances, 27
Partenio, Bernardino, 70, 82, 434 Particularity, 12, 129-202, 228, 333 Particularization, imitation as, 42-43, 51, 118-125 Particularized narrative, 39
Narrative, 15, 118, 193, 197, 262; imitation in pure, 49; in poet’s own person, 51; modes, 23-64; poetry, 13, 21, 122
382,
Ottava rima, 92, 414 Ovid, 41, *122, 194, 382, 402, 429, 445
Parrhasius, 12
Mythologists, 61, 104, 105 Mythology, 46
Natural
427, 435
Palma, 106 Palmerin, 116
Myth, 379, 382 Mythologia 72
,
192-195,
115,
344, 351, 440
4°4 Mystical illumination, 421 Mystic’s furor, 415, 431
Mythos
62, 71, 77, 92,
199, 447, 453
Orpheus, 387, 405, 407, 417, Orphic conventicles, 205
Mormons, 384
Music,
Ornament,
341-348,
379, 4 r 4, 43
r
,
349,
352,
356,
375-376,
445, 447, 449
Petronius Arbiter, 95 Phantasms, 322, 325, 338-345, 377, 384, 39i, 393
Phantaso, 387
469
366-367,
Index Phavorinus, 120, 395 Philanthropy, 275-276, 283 Philo Judaeus, 362, 364 Philoponus, Johannes, 50, 307, 335, 373 Philosopher’s method, 312 Philosophic doctrine in ppetry, 8, 19, 34 Philosophy, 189; and poetry, 4, 322
Protagoras, 424 Protestantism, 447
Philostratus, 122
Psychoanalysis, 206
Phobeter, 387 Physiology, 327, 338 Piccolomini, Alessandro, 52, 61, 79, 83-
Psychology, 205, 236, 250, 255, 270, 277,
84, 100-101, 106, 109, 132, 160-161, 164,
207,
209, 220, 223, 239-240,
243,
252, 264, 266, 288, 339, 355, 358 Pigna, Giovan Battista, 11, 30-31,
190-191,
247, 169,
Pleasure, 43, 207, 213, 218, 231, 236-237, 243-244, 250, 253-254, 257, 260, 273, 278-280, 282-283, 286, 288, 297, 313, 314, 322, 334, 351, 417, 430; of imitating, 58, 331
10,
1
7,
78,
134,
175,
180-181, 257,
295 Plotinus, 50, 347, 432, 440 Plutarch, 7, 13, 21, 61-63, 79, 95,
122,
220, 238, 264, 267, 293, 332, 366, 367, 381, 395, 418, 419, 429 Poet: as creator, 449; narrating in person, 55
own
Poikilia, 31, 217-218, 260, 432, 436
Polyclitus, 456
Polygnotus,
174,
157 Pietro, 6, 170, 314, 316, 338 1,
Malatesta, 176,
50,
88,
79,
132,
108, 209
154-155,
179
Praise and blame, 52-53, 114, 134, 136137, 167, 338 Primaleones, 116
Probability,
Proclus,
7,
16,
295-296, 302-396, 455; asso-
ciational, 120, 308, 388, 392; behavioristic, 396; Gestalt, 396; see also Hu-
moral psychology Public and private, 173-174 Purgation, see Catharsis 286 Puritans,
7,
334
Pyrrhonism, 125, 386 Pythagoras and Pythagoreans,
91, 209,
Quintilian,
6,
22-23, 79,
101,
13
Racine, J. B., 156 Rapin, Rene, 220 Rational: arts, 8; being, 382;
205,
entities,
380; existence, 382; soul, 347 Rationalists, 290, 360, 437, 449-451, 455 Realism, 3, 17, 298, 350, 353, 377, 390-
377,
Realists,
163, 440-441 Reality, 159-166, 342, 357, 359, 368, 377, 380, 382, 391, 416; of dreams, 382-384 Reason, 159-160, 164, 183, 240, 257, 270-
280-281,
292-295,
289,
313,
271,
276,
323,
325 . 333 , 334 336 , 339, 364, 369,
418, 444, 447, 457 Recreation, 389 Relativism, 456 Representation, 457
Rhetoric,
24, 73, 97, 155, 214-218, 232,
415, 421, 423,
407,
430-433;
8, 92,
190,
193,
297,
307, 310,
195,
13 1, 134, 147, 182, 184, 198, 200, 205, 212, 282,
324,
331-332, 338,
325,
341, 358, 423, 433
Rhetoriqueurs, 309 Rhodigino, Celio, 366, 378
furor of, 431 Proportion, 7, 21, 62, 91, 142
Rhythm, 29 Ricci, Bartolomeo, 212, 443-444
Prose, 71, 187, 298; in comedy, 66; fiction as poetry, 8, 17, 66, 87-117; imitations, 85; in poetry, 10, 17
Riccoboni, Antonio, 61,
Prosopopoeia,
1,
264, 266, 267, 333, 358, 375, 445, 450
Reynolds, Edward, 210
167-170
249, 260-261, 264-265, 267, 286, 43i, 432 Profit and delight, 205, 249, 289
Prophecy,
the
396
12
Pomponazzi, Pontano, Giovanni, 72, 75, Pope, Alexander, 448, 456 Pordenone, 106 Porphyry, 73, 189, 346, 347 Porta,
283, 292,
Dionysius
210, 251, 280, 286, 407, 427, 434, 436
Pleasures of imagination, 314, 334 Pliny the Younger, 122, 198, 367 Plot,
Prudential lesson, 289
Pseudo- Academics, 386 Pseudo-Dionysius, see Areopagite
Purification, 205, 208, 263, 268, 270, 285-
195
193,
Prudence, 277, 281, 324, 454
24, 55,
470
96
244, 288-289, 294
Richards, I. A., 396 Richardson, Samuel, 41
107,
157,
168,
Index Robortelli, Francesco, io, 19, 26, 28-29, 61, 65, 81, 91, ioo-ioi, 108, 1 1 3, 132, 145-147, 158, 169, 176, 189, 207, 211-226, 234, 238-241, 244, 246, 251-253, 260-261, 264-266, 269, 287-288, 142,
209,
306,
292, 299,
340-343, 353, 355,
329,
410, 414
Romances, 3 5 *,
16,
Romantic
116,
28, 88, 92,
39 I_ 39 2 ’ 44
M
critics,
190, 314,
47 350,
17,
412;
move-
ment, 6, 15, 129, 309, 353 Ronsard, Pierre, 392 Rosine dances, 27 Rossky, William, 334 Rostagni, Augusto, 427
Rowe, Nicholas,
347,
362, 364, 366,
219-220,
248,
Servius, 356, 367, 370 Sestina, 59
Shaftesbury, Earl of, 248 Shakespeare, William, 4, 40, 144, 214, 300, 332, 446 Shaw, George Bernard, 4 Sidney, Sir Philip, 132, 142, 326
no
7,
351 21,
120,
124, 390, 395
me
flere, 2 66, 332, 352,
Sallust,
169
Salviati, Salviati,
Francesco Lionardo,
132,
163,
de’, 106
75,
88,
174, 176,
Sannazaro, Jacopo,
99-102,
104,
177, 391-393
89, 90, 93, 95
Rome,
Solon, 234 Somnus, 387 Sonnet, 59, no-111, 192, 414, 450 Soothsayers, 433 Sophistic, 8
13
Satires, 62, 293
Sophocles, 106, 146, 300, 441
Savio, Giovanni, 294-295 Scaliger, J. C., 18, 20, 69-70, 88, 101, no,
Sophron, mimes
132, 176, 274, 410, J.
130, 147, 163, 208, 304, 307, 310, 324, 333, 363, 371, 380, 388-
390 , 394 Science, 4, 160, 165, 183, 249, 291, 451452; and poetry, 45, 62, 65-80, 90, 207 Scientific concepts in poetry, 4, 8,
19,
34 Scientific rationalism, 6, 9, 401, 424 Scotus, see Duns Scotus
132,
80, 84, 88, 96-97,
138-140,
143,
of, 61, 88, 90, 94-95, 103,
12
3 1 1-3 12, 331, 340, 343-344, 3 6 3, 39 5 , 416, 432; vegetable, animal, rational, 27 Species, see Appearance
161-163,
Specters,
318 Spencer, Herbert, 323 Speroni, Sperone, 31-33, 67-69, 88, 9193,
108,
132, 191,
146-147,
157,
159,
187,
220,
229-234, 238, 245, 247, 299, 306, 327, 333, 339, 341, 403-404,
193,
439-442, 445
Spingardo dances, 27 Spingarn, Spirit,
J. E.,
312,
319,
206, 235
321, 327, 343-344,
123-
416 Splandian, 116 Stage presentation,
244,
Statius, 95,
246, 248, 253, 287, 293, 299, 354, 406-
407, 431
Stoicism 238,
Segni, Bernardo, 288
13,
367, 445 and Stoics,
241,
255,
59,
260-261,
85,
268,
214,
Senses,
Sublimity,
190-191
47 1
220,
270-271,
Seneca, 212, 214 249-250, 270, 313, 321, 325,
3 82 ,
27, 41
284-285, 287, 341, 3 6 4-3 6 7, 382 Strabo, 90, 285, 418-419, 429 Strowski, Fortunat, 214
Self-love, 237, 242, 256, 272, 279 165,
166,
196-198, 207, 212,
170,
310-316,
Scripture, 153, 157, 294, 429 Sculpture, 13, 44, 49, 56, 60, 440, 448, 456; and poetry, 67, 12 1, 149 Secondary intention, 380 Segni, Agnolo, 35, 43-48, 50, 53-54, 58, 124,
1
Soul,
450 von, 6
Scholasticism,
60, 65, 72, 76,
426
Skeptics, 386 Smith, J. A., 385 Socrates, 68, 266, 297 Socratic dialogues, 88, 90, 94-95
Saints’ lives, 62
W.
123
Situation, 4 Si vis
Schelling, F.
257
Similitudinary imitation, 38-41, Simonides, 13 Simplicius, 74, 263, 373 Simulacra, 381
Rutilius, 201
Sapienza, at
Sentences, 115 Sentimentalism, Serenus, 72
Similitude,
Rufo, Cristoforo, 176
154,
345,
378, 384, 435
Silius Italicus,
130
Rules, 437-439, 456 Ruscelli, Girolamo, 106,
331-336, 340,
Index Subnotion,
3
Tragedy,
19-321
Suidas, 90-91, 94, 1 19-124, 362, 367, 373, 378, 380, 418, 425 Summo, Faustino, 79, 85, 88, 91, 104, 1 1 1116, 132, 147, 186, 188, 244, 259, 274278,
361
Symbol, 432 Symbolic imitation, Sympatheia 281
7
Talentoni, Giovanni, 433 Tamburini, G. M., 378 Tasso, Bernardo, 152, 421-422
Tasso, Torquato,
12-13,
19,
39,
48-51,
169-172,
174,
176,
182,
191,
258-259, 262, 275, 294, 297, 299, 306, 315, 350, 353, 390396, 409, 423, 433, 45 0 -453 Tassoni, Alessandro, 132 Tate, Allen, 179 200,
244,
Teglia, Francesco del, 259 Telesio, Antonio, 106
-2
1
2,
273
193,
178, 317, 320, 334, 354,
Universal,
17,
129-202,
312,
317, ~
326,
poetry
Valerius Flaccus, 445 Valerius Maximus, 267 Valla, Giorgio, 28, 108, 209 Varchi, Benedetto, 32, 69, 81-82, 88, 93, 107,
no,
132,
140,
220,
223,
225,
300,
Thaumathesia, 368
228,
335-337* 344-345* 35 1 * 39 2 393* 44d, 453* 45 6 Utility, 236, 289 Ut pictura poesis, see Painting, and 322,
Thales, 210
147,
306,
160,
165, 207,
339-341, 343,
389, 445-446, 448
Themistius, 338, 364, 385, 418 Themistocles, 454 Theocritus, 27
Varro, 72, 458 Vecchi, 106
G. M., 409 Verino, Francesco, 338 Verino Secondo, II, see Vieri, Francesco
Verdizotti,
71, 360, 377, 387, 394
Theopompus,
111,
242
Terza rima, 92
Theology,
187,
133, 157, 167-171, 432 Universality, 104, 129-202, 218 Universalized action, 42
73-75, 79, 81-84, 88, 99, 102, 106, 123-125, 132, 140-147, 150-157* 108,
173,
185,
Unity,
5 5,
Terence,
lg o,
391, 393, 416, 431, 447
erasa, 323 Tacitus, 22
195,
1 1
Tropes, 7 Truth, 159-166,
Tabula
163,
173*
Triumphs, 62
Synesius, 75, 381 Syrianus, 73
193,
154*
205-300, 434, 441, 450; in prose, 8, 88, 92, 105-106, 1 14 Tragicomedy, 62, 111, 268, 272-273, 294-
2
,
16 1,
27, 30, 35, 40, 50, 60, 97,
152,
295 Trilling, Lionel, 207, 228-229 » Trissino, G. G., 26-28, 70, 82, 88, 92, 108, 132, 134, 136, 138-139, 172, 201,
300, 413, 424s 428-429
281,
Swift, Jonathan,
137,
145
Theophrastus, 210, 429 Theorematical dreams, 384 Thomas Aquinas, 147, 163, 208, 261-262,
de’
Verisimilitude,
50,
114,
175,
178,
182,
Timocles, 216, 261, 267
37 6 ~377* 3 8 4-3 8 5 Verse, 71, 109, 184, 187; and prose, 871 17; as essential element in poetry, 66
Timothy, 286
Vettori, Pier,
3°7*
3 2 4*
33^,
3 82 *
394
Tintoretto, 106 Titian, 27, 106, 196 Toffanin, Giuseppe, 195, 223, 306, 409, 432, 436, 447
^
Tomeo, Niccolo Leonico, 195, 306, 310-316, 339* 34i* 404* 44 2 -443 166,
Tommaso
da Messina, 449
Tonnelat, E., 300 Topothesia, 367 Trabalza, Ciro, 315
472
324,
88, 91, 96,
333,
106,
317,
132,
351,
7, 26, 35, 61,
158,
161,
168,
88-89, 94, 101, 173, 176, 288,
592-293* 299* 355* 365
Vida, Girolamo, 191 Vieri, Francesco de’, 344-345 Vinci, Leonardo da, 27
210, 299
Tomitano, Bernardino, 67-68,
218,
336,
Viperano, G. A., 147 Virgil, 22, 24, 29, 30, 32, 33, 42, 55, 59, 68, 69, 70, 72, 76, 90, 93, 101, 184,
141,
156,
170,
173,
193,
195,
197,
199, 210, 229,
174,
1
12, 122,
190,
191,
275, 282,
286, 317, 356, 364, 367, 394, 403, 406, 416, 430, 433, 435, 441, 442, 445, 452
hid ex Virtues and vices,
134, 136, 148, 153, 200,
219, 232, 236, 276-277, 292, 354
Vision,
1
19,
Wit,
352, 357, 404, 412, 433, 437, 449, 451-454, 457, 459
347, 352, 355, 357-359, 364,
368-371, 373, 375, 377, 387 Vives, Ludovicus, 187 Voice, 47, 191; narration in poet’s
Xenarchus, mimes 1
own,
Xenocrates, 210
65 Volaterrano, Raffaello, 108 Voltaire, 111
Xenophon,
Walker, D. P., 343, 363 Weinberg, Bernard, 216-217, 219
Zabarella,
4, 8, 33, 51,
330,
333,
339,
347>
357*
14,
145, 154,
3 2 4"
360, 377
170, 403
Zeno, 367, 378 Zeuxis, 141, 145, 15 1, 345 Zinano, Gabriele, 131-132, 2 99,
130, 337
Giacomo,
5,
157
Zanta, Leontine, 214
3^4*3 65,
37 2 -373, 385, 393
William of Occam, 163 Wimsatt, William K., Jr.,
68,
Yeats, William Butler,
Will, 79, 81, 83, 85, 120, 313-3 3 2 7,
of, 61, 88, 94-95, 103,
12
1
86- 1 88, 295-
409.
Zoppio, Hieronymo,
54, 78, 108, 113, 376