252 23 58MB
English Pages [444] Year 1968
- W
SACRAMENTUM VOLUME
MUNDI
FIVE: PHILOSOPHY— SALVATION
SACRAMENTUM MUNDI An Encyclopedia of Theology
Edited by Karr RauNER S], Miinster and
Juan ALFARO S], Rome
ALBERTO BELLINI, Bergamo Carro Coromso, Venegono
Hengr1 CrouzeL 5], Toulouse JeaN CarDINAL DaniErou S], Paris ApoLF DarLAP, Munich Cornervius Ernst
OP,
Oxford
José FonpEvILLA S], Barcelona PieT FrRANSEN, Louvain
FErcus
Kerr
OP, Oxford
P1ET SCHOONENBERG, Nijmegen KEeviN SMyTH, Paris
T GustavE WEIGEL S ], Woodstock
© Hermann-Herder-Foundation,
Basle— Montreal
Published by Herder and Herder New York - Burns & Oates London - Palm Publis hers Montreal
- Herder
Freiburg
- Editions
Desclée
de Brouwer
Bruges
- Editorial
Barcelona - Edizion) Morcelliana Brescia - Paul Brand Hilversum
Herder
SACRAMENTUM MUNDI AN
ENCYCLOPEDIA
VOLUME
OF
THEOLOGY
FIVE
PHILOSOPHY TO
SALVATION
BURNS
&
OATES
|
1970
.
HERDER AND HERDER 232 Madison Avenue, New York, N. Y, 10016
BURNS & OATES LIMITED 25 Ashley Place, London S. W. 1
General Editor: Adolf Darlap
Nibil obstat: John M, T, Barton, $.T.D., L.S.8., Censor
Imprimatar: + Patrick Casey, Vic. Gen., Auxiliary Bishop of Westminster Westminster, 24th November 1969,
The Nihil obstat and Imprimatur are a declaration that a book or pampbhlet is considered to be free from doctrinal or moral error. It is not implied that those who have granted the Nibil obstat and Imprimatur agree with the contents, opinions or statements expressed.
First published in West Germany
© 1970, Herder KG
Printed in West Germany by Herder
SBN 223 97682 2
ABBREVIATIONS The following list does not include biblical and other well-known abbreviations. Whenever an author, not listed below, is cited in an article by name only, followed by page number(s), the reference is to a work listed in the bibliography at the end of the article.
AAS ACW Billerbeck
Acta Apostolicar Sedis (19094.)
J. Quasten and ]. C. Plumpe, Ancient Christian Writers (1946 1.) (H. L. Strack and) P. Billerbeck, Kommentar gum Newen Testament
CB{
ans Talmud wnd Midrasch, 1-1V (1922-28; reprint, 1956), rabbinical index, ed. by J. Jeremias and K. Adolph (1956) Catholic Biblical Quarterly (1939 11.)
Chalkedon
A.
CiC CiO Collectio Lacensis
Grillmeier
and
H.
Bacht,
eds.,
Das
V:
Kongil von Chalkedon,
Geschichte und Gegenwart, 3 vols. (1951-54; 2nd enlarged ed., 1962) Codex lTuris Canonici Codex Iuris Canonict Orientalis (Unless stated references are to the law relating to persons.)
otherwise,
the
Collectio Lacensis: Acta ei Decreta Sacrorum Conciltorum Recentiorum,
CSEL D
ed. by the Jesuits of Maria Laach, 7 vols. (1870-90) Corpus Secriptorum Ecclesiasticorum Latinorum (1866 11) H. Denzinger, Enchiridion Symbolorum, Definitionum et Declara-
DB
F. Vigouroux,
tionum de Rebus Fider et Morum (31st ed., 1957); see also DS L. Pirot, ed.,
ed., Dictionnaire de la Bible, 5 vols. (1895-1912) Dicitonnaire de fa Bible, Supplémeni,
A. Robert (1928f1) DS
DSAM DIc
H.
Denzinger
and
A.
Schoénmetzer,
Enchiridion
continued
by
Symbolorum,
Definitionum et Declarationum de Rebus Fidei ef Morum (331d ed,, 1965); see also DD M. Viller, ed., Dictionnaire de Spiritnaltté ascctique et mystigie. Doctrine et Histoire (193211} A, Vacant
and E. Mangenot,
eds., Dictionnaire de théologie catho-
ligue, continued by E. Amann, I-XV, Table analytique and Tables
genérales, XVIH
(1903 f1.)
\‘..'l'
ABBREVIATIONS
|
-
r
.
Enchiridion Biblicum Enghividion Biblicum. Dotumenta Ecilesiastita Sacram Seripistran: Spectantia (3rd ed., 1956)
ETL GCS
Hennecke-
SchneemelcherWilson HERE JBL JjTs$ LTK Mansi NRT NTS PG PL Pritchard RGG
RHE RHPR RSPT RSR RSV s U TWNT
Ephemerides Theologicar Lovanienses (1924 1. Die griechischen christlichen Schriftsteller der ersten drei Jabrbunderte (1897 {£.) E. Hennecke, W. Schneemelcher and R. McL. Wilson, eds., New Testament” Apocryphba, 2 vols. (1963—65)
J. Hastings, ed., Encyclopedia of Religion and Ethics, 12 vols. + index (1908-26; 2nd rev. ed., 1925-40) Journal of Biblical Literature (18814.) Journal of Theological Studies (189911.) J. Hofer and K. Rahner, eds., Lexikon fir Theologie und Kirche, 10 vols. + index (2nd rev. ed., 1957-67) J. D. Mansi, Sacrorum Conciliorum Nova et Amplissima Collectio, 31 vols. {1757-98); reprint and continuation ed. by L. Petit and J. B. Martin, 60 vols. (1899-1927) Nouvelle Revue Théologique (1879 f1.) New Testament Studies (19544) J.-P. Migne, ed., Patrologia Graeca, 161 vols, (1857H.) J.-P. Migne, ed., Patrologia Latina, 217 vols. + 4 index vols. (1844 11.) J. B. Pritchard, ed., Awmcient Near Eastern Texts relating to the Old Testament (1950; 2nd revised and enlarged ed., 1955) K. Galling, ed., Die Religion in Geschichte und Gegemwart, 6 vols. +-
index (3rd rev. ed., 1957-65) Revue d'bistoire ecclésiastique (190041.) Revue d’histoire et de philosophie religiense (19211.) Revue des sciences philosaphigues et thévlogiques (1907 ) Recherches de science religiense (191041.) Revised Standard Version of the Bible Theological Studies (194011.) Texcte und Untersuchungen gur Geschichte der altchristlichen Literatur., Archi far die griechisch-christlichen Schriftsteller der ersten drei Jabr. bunderte, hitherto 62 vols. in 5 series (188211.) G.
Kittel,
ZAW ZKT
VI
Theologisches
Wirterbuch
zum
Newen
Testament,
contifiued by G. Friedrich (19338.); E. T.: Theological Dictionary
of the New
WA
ed.,
Testament (1964 1L.)
Martin Luther, Werke: Kritische Gesamtausgabe (*“ Weimarer Aus-
gabe’’ ) (188311)
Zeitschrift fiir die alttestamentliche Wissenschaft (188141.) Zettschrift fiir Katholische Theologie (1877 f1.)
(continued)
PHILOSOPHY
If the primary source of errors is thought to be in the illusions of the senses, the negative
I. The Basic Questions: A. Philosophy: The Word and its Many Meanings. B. Philosophy and Christian Faith. IL. History of Philosophy.
effort of the philosopher will be to liberate
I. The Basic Questions
effort of knowledge.
A. Parrosoruy: MeanNINGS
T
WORD
thought from the entanglement of the senses,
the positive
to practise a purely
spiritual
Ultimately he tries to
“purify” the soul from all bodily influences:
AND 1Ts MaANY
According to the literal meaning of the word, philosophy is not a learned science, but an attitude to life: hence the call *to live philosophically” (priocoguedig CFv). 1t differs from
other attitudes inasmuch as its goal and supreme value i1s “wisdom” (copia), while other attitudes see the highest values else-
where {puiapyupix aims at riches, prioTipio at
honours, and so on). For the self-understanding of philosophy, 1t 1s always of decisive importance to know whether it
maintains the claim to be a way of life, as its
philosophy
is catharsis,
with a leaning
to-
wards a body-hating dualism, as in Platonism.
When it is noticed that the body and its senseorgans are not of themselves a menace to knowledge, but only through the excitation of affections and passions which hamper
thought with prejudices, the philosopher tries negatively to liberate himself from these
affections and passions, positively to practise a courageous imperturbability (philosophy as araraxia, indifference, especially in Stoicism). But if the unquestioned validity of traditional opinions is thought to be the most dangercus source of misleading prejudices,
the philosopher
tries negatively
to
origin demands, or whether it is content to be a particular type of knowledge or a particular method of attaining knowledge.
criticize the accepted notions, positively to practise independent judgment by 2z skilful
1. Philosophy as a way of life. Philosophy as a way of life is orientated both by its goal (cogta) and by its relationship (puiia) to this
thinking
goal.
a) Since the philosopher values wisdom (oopix) 2bove all other goods, he is inclined to prefer the contemplative attitude to the practical. The philosophical life i1s regarded as the Biog OewpnTinds, vita contemplativa, Negatively, he strives with particular care
to overcome error and blindness. Positively, he tries to practise the dispositions which are favourable to the acquisition of knowledge.
use of probative arguments, and to attain
the
high-minded
subject (philosophy
mept Tuhg AGyuug, Plate’s
sovereignty
Phaedo;
the
as the
art
of the
free-
as the Téyvy
of reasoning,
methodical
In
assurance
of independent judgment and hence liberation
from
authority
Enlightenment;
and
as practice
tradition
in
the
in the virtue of
highmindedness [générosité] in Descartes). This notion of philosophy as a way of lite forms the transition to an understanding of
philosophy as science or the fundamentals of science. In more recent times, a still more dangerous source of errors has been found in the
1
.
~
+
. PHILOSOPHY | methode&ngwal mflmsm” of one or other
particular scienice or of modern science in
than thc thwrctleai reason. 'I‘he qacmm as
nflgatwely, to refute the universal claim of 2
Kant attacks pseudo-scmnnfic dogmatism,
sal of the mind) or social upheaval (revolution) is objectively prior remains one of the main points of controversy between Marxist
claims universal validity (philosophy as ra-
enumerated and many others claim to be ways of life, or at least to make possible 2 way
general. The effort of the philosopher is then, science which transgresses its bounds. Thus
Jaspers “scientific superstition”. Positively, the effort is to be open to the modes of truth which threaten to be lost sight of as science
tional faith in Kant, as philosophical faith in Jaspers, as a questioning more primordial
- than science in Heidegger).
Finally, it may also be thought that the most radical threat to the faculty of knowledge is that human thought is swayed by economic and social group-interests. Then the philosopher sees as his main task, nega* tively, the critique of ideologies, positively,
the preparation of social upheaval which is to
libetate thought from ideologies as well as
bring about the classless society {philosophy as the pioneer of revolutionary praxis in
Marxism). These and a number of other views of the nature and task of philosophy agree in affirming that philosophy should not merely
give certain insights, but by that very fact
should also make possible a way of life — catharsis, ataraxia, générosité, philosophical
faith, revolutionary action, etc. — and sum-
mon men to it. In each case the way of life in
question is not what is actually practised but
what is “demanded™. It can only be attained by turning away from the manner of life and the self-understanding in which man *mostly and most easily” lives. Plato spoke in this sense
of a “‘reversal
of the whole
mind”,
using terms and thoughts which recall the
tamiliar demand for “conversion” in religion. In modern times this reversal of the whole
mind was understood by Descartes as the eversic omnium opinionum and thus also pro-
pounded as the elimination of traditional and authoritative opinions. Kant saw the required conversion
through
as a “Copernican
which
man
revolution”,
learns to understand
that it is not nature which gives him laws but his mind which gives laws to nature. He saw it further as the moral “revolution in the mind” through which man gains moralauton-
omy and restores the proper relationship between reverence for the moral law and the
search for happiness. The Marxist notion of
philosophy as a preparation for social revolution seeks to link up with the anti-traditional elements of the Cartesian erersio and the
2
to-whether individual conversion {the rever-
and non-Marxist philosophy. The fact that all the philosophies hitherto. of life, does not exclude, but rather implies,
that knowledge is demanded for these ways of life and is made possible by them. Since in all these types of self-understanding the philosophical way of life aims at wisdom, it remains orientated to philosophy as a form of knowledge and a method of secking knowledge (see under A 2 below). b) For the philosopher — the term being still understood as designating a way of life — cogle, wisdom, is not an assured possession but the object of a @iAix, loving desire. The philosopher knows enough to recognize his ignorance and to see that it is necessary to
overcome it. But he is so ignorant that he must first strive for wisdom. This love of wisdom distinguishes him from the fool who
does not see his own defects and hence cannot strive to overcome them. It also distinguishes him from the sage (or a godlike intellect} who lacks nothing and hence does not need to strive. Since he differs from the fool not by the real possession of knowledge but merely by consciousness of his own ignorance, if he ever took himself for a wise man, he would
at once become the greatest and most help-
less fool of all. Hence philosophy, as love of wisdom, 15 based on self-critical reflection —
compare Plato’s interpretation of the Delphic inscription I'véd ceavtov, “Know thyself!” In the course of his reflections the philosopher comes upon the paradox that selfcriticism consists in thought measuring itself and its supposed attainments against a standard, and judging itself to be inadequate. The
standard,
however,
by which
the in-
adequacy of thought can be demonstrated,
(s none other than truth itself. But in order
to be able to measure itself by this standard, the mind must first know it. Thus selfcriticism seems only necessary because the mind does not know
the truth, but at the
same time only possible if it knows it, Hence philosophy is based on the
ex-
perience that we men are seekers, that is, not
knowers,
but that without a precognition
L
PHILOSOPHY
/
of what is sought we should neither know that we did not know it, nor weigh critically our attempted answers (cf. the dpoTinde Myog in Plato’s Mems). Many types of docttine about a knowledge which. is active a priori but only becomes explicitly conscious later are based on this experience. These include Plato’s doctrine of the unknown ideas working unbeknown in the consciousness (“forgotten” but as residual memories stimulating search and self-criticism); also the Cartesian doctrine of the idea
of the ens perfectissimum which is what makes possible all questioning and even ali doubt. Thus
the
intermediate
position
of the
philosopher between God and the fool is based on the knowledge of the unknown implied in (conscious) ignorance. This is
what
makes
unknown
it possible
in explicit
to designate
questioning,
to
the
see
whether the answers one sketches or others
offer bring one closer to the object of the search or lead away from it, and hence gradually to make progress in knowledge. The knowledge of truth implied in knowledge
of one’s own ignorance makes philosophy, as 2 way of life, into a pursuit (uéfodog}. And
this alone provides the basis on which a philosophy can be deveioped as a method.
Hence
the sense
of philosophical
methed
stems from the fact that the philosopher reflects on his way of life under the aspect of
euia (love as pursuit of wisdom). The manifold consequences of this consideration include — along with the directives thereby gained — the two following
elements which can appear in many modifications. (i) There is a dialecrical relationship in the strict sense of the term between truth and human thoughr. Truth, precisely 1n the form of non-realization, is *“closer’ than any object into which it can enquire, closer
indeed than man himself. It is the hiddenness of truth that makes possible all searching
and
finding.
The
negativeness
of its non-
realization proves to be the positive and the impelling, absolutely. Here one may note in particular Hegel’s exposition of the un-
known and the negation.
Truth in the form of the non-realization
which makes all searching and questioning possible is often distinguished as the “veritas gua cognoscitur” from all real and possible objects of knowledge, the “veritas guae cognoscitur”, and then often represented by the metaphor of light. The light becomes
“visible”
by
its
making
the
illuminated
objects visible. The specifically philosophical knowledge is in this sense not knowledge of abjects, but knowledge of the conditions
under which the objects as such can appear. The transition from knowledge of objects to knowledge of the conditions of possibility of their existence as objects, first made in Plato’s metaphor of the sun, later became one of the main tasks of philosophy, under the name of “transcendental reflection”’. (1) The truth which the philosopher aims at in his love of wisdom, as the one possible
source of the wisdom sought for, has therefore for him a twofold function. It is the
standard by which he critically measures himself (veritas iudicans de bomine), and the
ground of possibility by which he is enabled to know objects, to see through to the preconditions of their appearance and to pass criticat verdict on the manner of their appearance (wverilas qua bomo iudicat}. It is precisely to his self-criticism, in the light of the unknown truth which makes all knowledge possible, that the philosopher owes his
ability to be objectively critical of the objects before his eyes. The specific nature of philosophical @uix necessarily brings
with it this unity of self-criticism and objectcriticism which is the criterion which marks it off from all else.
2, Philosophy as a learned discipline. 2) The
transition from philosophy as a way of life
to philosophy as one of the learned disciplines was
brought
about
historically
chiefly
through the following internal processes. (i) Since philosophy directs its effort to
wisdom and hence reflects on the origin of error and seeks a criterion to distinguish truth from falsehood, it becomes a special type of knowledge. More than any knowl-
edge of objects, it seeks knowledge of how ostensible
(illusory)
knowledge
is
to
be
distinguished from real knowledge. Thus Plato designated philosophy as a “knowledge of nothing” (i.e., of no particular
object) “but of knowledge itself”. Since true
knowledge must prove itself in contrast to illusory knowledge by means of argument to and fro (in the dialogue) with a skilful use of proofs, philosophy becomes the art of dialogue (dtahextiny; Téxvy) and the skilful use of arguments (téxvy Tept Toug Abyoug Of noyuen texvy).
This in turn could demand
the effort to propound
“dialectic”
and
“logic”.
it in a theory This
of
knowledge
3
PHILOSOPHY.
about knowledge thus became the model for all later theoties of knowledge snd critiques
of knowledge, for theories of science and
othier words, the functionof the philosophi-
cally basic téyvn mept sobg Mdyoug — the art
methodology. But it also contained an invitation to the thinker to reflect upon himself
of argument — can be claimed by the phi-
of the soul and philosophical anthropology, of the doctrine of the rational subject or
be a form of guala. ¥t tries to understand
and thus became the origin of the doctrine
existence, and prepared the transition from
“ronsciousness” to “consciousness of self”’,
the analysis of existence and so on. In this
process the question could arise s to whether
priority was to be accorded to the “anthro-
pological” or “logical” foundations of phi-
losophy. This is a question which has led in recent times to the controversy (iméer alia) about whether philosophy should be founded on purely formal logic for its questions and initial answers, or whether there should not
be an “anthropological reduction” of philosophy. Compare, for instance, the opposition between the Kantian school and lifephilosophy. This does not prevent the above-mentioned questions being detached from their origin in reflection on the nature and con-
ditions of possibility way
of
“partial
They
life.
disciplines”
of the philosophical
become
in
independent
philosophy,
and
debate can arise as to which of them takes
priority among them as the “basic discipline” of philosophy.
In the course of the history of philosophy, the anthropological starting-point under-
went essential modifications, as the variation
in thought-forms from culture to culture, from social group to social group and at various
of history
epochs
was
explicitly
noted. The doctrine of the thinking I took on an ethnological, social and historical dimen-
sion. The philosophy of culture, society and history was added to the ancient “doctrine of
the soul” or took its place, taking over also
its claim to discipline. The logical thed through logos exists in as the spoken deduced that completed by
be
the
basic
philosophical
starting-point was also modthe consideration that the the concrete for man only word, From this it could be tormal logic needed to be a philosophy of langurage or a
linguistic analysis, or that logic itself was
basically the unselfconscious theory of a special language — that of science. But since
language must go with hearing and hearing with understanding, the task of a philosophy
of language involved the task of a philosophy
4
losophy of language, as also by hermeneutics, (if) Philosophy then understands itself to of the conditions
of
itself in the
light
the unknown
implicit in its conscious ig-
possibility of its effort to move onwards, and hence of its search for the knowledge of
norance. This gives it at once its own propet
theme. It does not ask merely about knowl-
edge itself or the objects of knowledge. It
also investigates the conditions of possibility which underlie two possibilities at once. It
asks how it is possible that the thinker seeks,
asks and is capable of judging his (real or ostensible) findings. It also asks how it is possible that the objects are capable of showing themselves to the secker as that which they are. In this sense, Plato describes the object of philosophy as the “third factor”, which “imparts power to thought and truth to the thing known”. This tpltov yéveg is not a particular object but lies “beyond being™. Nothing can then be known of it except that ““it is essentially there to link together (mediate) the two” (thinking and the thing known).
With this description, transcendental reflection, i.e., the question of what is behind the subject-object relationship, was designated for the first dme, and in a historically effective
way,
as the special
task
of phi-
losophy. But with this special theme, philosophy is also assigned a special type of knowledge. What it seeks must be prior — as the condition of seeking and finding — to all knowledge of objects and indeed to all questions about objects, since it makes this
possible. In other words, what is sought in
philosophy is the objective 4 priori of knowl-
edge in general. Hence even with regard to its form it can only be found when thought reflects on the elements which are active
in thought
itself “from
knowledge
they
a priorf, though quently
the very
outset”,
in the order of conscious
are
in reflection.
grasped
only
Philosophy
as
subse-
tran-
scendental reflection is a striving for knowl-
edge of the 4 priors, and as regards its form, also reflection on the 4 prisri elements of knowledge.
Thus transcendentai reflection and the problem of the a prieri can also be deduced from the way in which philosophy, as a way
PHILOSOPHY of life, explains its own nature and condittons of possibility. But this does not prevent it in turn from becoming an independent discipline with regard to phi-
losophy as a way of life. And as it makes itself independent, it too can enter a claim to
play the role of a basic philosophical discipline. However,
transcendental
reflection,
like
the working out of the problem of the 4
priori, admits of many variations, In the search for the “mediating third factor”, for the light which illuminates the
intellect (gives it the power to know) and
throws light on the objects (makes them knowable), Plato found himself referred to
the good, as the sun in the realm of the
spirit ( Repaublic). In his later works he sees the One more and more clearly as the common principle of being and knowledge. Aristotle could prove negatively that the
loss of unity
(in contradiction
with
itself)
makes thought incapable of thinking, and the object incapable of existing (the priaciple of contradiction as the gnoseological and also the ontological principle being the principle of mediation between thought and being). Finally the principles of wmitas and bomifas discovered in the search for the
mediating
ground
of thought
and
being,
joined to the veritas thus made possible (knowability) were ascribed as passiones gene-
rales to all beings as such. In this way tran-
scendental reflection became the doctrine of the transcendentals. The rediscovery of the transcendental enquiry in its original sense was due above all to Kant and after
him to the German Idealists. Kant, however,
did not seek the conditions of possibility of
known
objects in a third factor, but in the
forms of thought (and intuition) itself. Schelling took the indeterminareness of the
undifferentiated
ing-point.
Hegel
subject-object as his start-
sought
to
describe
the
constitution of the subject and the objectworld as the life of the self-realizing spirit.
Hence too the a priori form of philosophi-
cal knowledge could be understood in different ways: as the original (innate but “forgot-
ten””) insight into determinate principles (ideas), reflection on the forms of thought
and intuition,
the conscious
of the spirit and so on,
self-realization
(iii) Philosophy, as a special way of life, does not consider itself as a subjectively
conditioned “variant? of the possibilities of
human life. It claims to be a form of life which
is necessarily demanded of man. Hence it expresses itself in norms of behaviour and thus gives rise to a special philosophical treatise under the name of “ethics”. This
too, as in Kant, can make the claim to have
a central role among the philosophical disciplines, which by now have become independent of each other. b) Once the transition has been made from
philosophy as a form of life to philosophy
as a rmultiplicity of special treatises, the question arises as to how philosophy is distinguished from the other modes of knowledge and acquisition of knowledge and then as to how it can be co-ordinated with them. As regards this process, it is significant
that
as early
as
Aristotle
the
name
“philosophy” had been extended to take in all types of knowledge. But philosophy in
the strict sense, as the “first philosophy™, claimed an objective precedence over all
philosophies, partly as the formal logical erganon (made possible by reflection on the
TEXvY Tepl Toug Aoyuug), partly as the doctrine, with ontological content, of the “first
and most universal principles” {made possible by reflection on the conditions of pos-
sibility for all objects of knowledge}).
On this basis philosophy became the way of founding the sciences. It was the foundation which was to assure the various steps in the acquisition of knowledge. And it
became the specific doctrine of the universal principles which was to assign to individual
objects and individual items of knowledge their place in the ordered whole of beings {or of the knowable) and thus make it possible to synthetize the known into a system. And
sinice both the formal rules tor the acquisition
of knowledge and the system-forming principles claim to be universally valid for all that is known, philosophy could contrast itself as the “universal science” with all other forms of knowledge. Inasmuch as philosophy claims to be the universal science, it has to make it its business
above
all tc assure the universality of the
knowledge at which it aims. It has to avoid
being “bogged down in the particular™.
As regards the formal rules of the acquisi-
tion of knowledge, their purely formal character seemed to guarantee of itself indifference to the variery of content and hence assure their universal validity for all types of knowledge. (The principle of contradiction for the formation of concepts and the exercise of judgment, the dictum de omni el de nulio for 5
PHILOSOPHY
deductions, are principles which simply because they are pureljr formal, hold good for ‘all concepts; all judgments and all conclusions, no matter what objects are referred to.) It is only in recent times that doubts have
been ralsed as to whether the formalization of thought through such logical rules does
not restrict knowledge to certain spheres of possible content — for instance, to the sphere of “objects” which according to the view of life-philosophy, Heideggerian ontology and Jaspers’s metaphysic constitute only a partial region of the possible content of thought. . It has been felt still more difficult from the beginning to assure the universality of the “supreme principles” of things, which were to permit the philosopher to order the results of the particular sciences within a totality of the true and real. This concrete universality
could be sought in the logical universality of a supreme concept under which the concepts of all particular objects could be subsumed or in the physical reality of a real structure in which all the particular realities are incorporated. In the first case philosophy becomes the science of “being
sciences
varions
while
as such”,
the
deal with the gemera entis
proper to them in each case. In the second case philosophy understands itself as the
ROW
ap
OB
s
Gl
LR
thhal
from the seien;:cs of the regmfis in-qfi'; (natural science, histoty, art) by the ¢laim to go beyond appearances and to answer the question of the essence of the phenomenon, Philosophy, which had become a theory of
the most universal principles through reflec-
tion on a way of life, changes once more into the question of the particular essences of particular types of beings. When it is thus understood, philosophy is exposed to the sharpest criticism from the
various sciences in question. It is objected
that the universality of its notion of being is
gained at the expense of the content of the
notion, which becomes empty. The content of its notions of essence 15 said to be due to the “arbitrary speculation™ of 2 non-demonstrated point of departure. The individual sciences strive to adduce examples which will contradict and shatter the ostensible philosophical concept of essence, in order to demonstrate its arbitrary character. This is particularly clear in the polemics of histor-
ical science against all speculative philosophy
of history. As a reaction to the twofold accusation of formal emptiness and *“arbitrary speculative-
ness” of content, philosophy has recourse
regions of the world. But then the universe
mainly to the following attitudes. (1) It maintains its claim to universality in the realm of logic, if necessary by expanding
understood in the light of an ultimate real
matical logic or linguistic analysis.
science of the universe or cosmos, while the
patticular
sciences
a5 a2 whole
investigate
the various
cannot be described
unless
it is
ground, while the particular sciences do not endquire into the ground of the world but
have
to
be
concerned
with
the
various
regional systems of explanations within the world. In other words, philosophy tries to
justify its self-understanding as universal science by becoming ontology, natural philosophy or philosophical theology (natural theology, philosophy of religion).
If in the course of furthet development the “world” is no longer taken as the sum total of the real, but as a special region of
beings — along with God and the soul — cosmology, theology and psychology become
types of “special metaphysics” and are sub-
ordinated
inersal
word.
to
“general
ontology™
as
the
science in the strict sense of the
Bur once
metaphysics”
the notion
has come
of 2 “special
up, the view
that
only what is strictly universal can be the theme ot philosophy is already in principle abandoned. Regional philosophies — of nature, history, art, the State, religion, etc. —
6
classical logic through new forms of mathe-
(1i) It tries to take the notion of beings in
general (or of being) in such a way that — in
contrast to all other concepts — it can combine the greatest concreteness and fullness of content with complete universality. One example of this is the notion of existence, as
used
in existential
(existence)
philosophy.
Since it is 2 matter of “myself and my power
to be”, I am concerned
with “my
own
in
each case”, which is at the same time “the
whole”,
within
which
all particulars
and
individuals can enounter me. Another pos-
sibility of proving that the concept of being need not be empty of content in order to be universal is based on the revival of the ancient doctrine of the intrinsic connotations of the one, the goad, the true, the beautiful and so on, which being itself has, (1) It revives the ancient programme
of
transcendental reflection, according to which
the object-world is left to science and sur-
mounted. The task of philosophy then remains the profounder question of the condi-
PHILOSOPHY
tions of possibility of the object as over
against, or of the self-disclosure of beings in general. An example of this is the ontology
of Heidegger, which seeks to speak not of beings but of being and hence enquire into
the condition of possibility of beings as such. (iv) It re-activates the origin of transcendental reflection itself by considering anew how this reflection can be the possible basis
of 2 special way of life. Marxism understands
its critique of ideology (in reflection on the
conditions of possibility of thought and its object) as initiating revolutionary changes in ways of life. Martin Heidegger’s philosophy, with its “remembrance of being”, the ground of possibility of thinking as of beings, tries to prepare men for a new “coming of destiny”. Philosophies as diverse in form as these are examples of how philosophy, while bearing in mind all the possibilities of theory-formation gained in the course of history, gains a new relationship towards its original self-
1. Love of wisdom and love of God. One point of comparison between the Christian and the
philosophical way of life is that both present themselves as a form of love which demands
that for the sake of the prized good all other goods should be despised. (According to Plato, all goods should be exchanged for “the true coin™. According to Mt 13:45, all possessions are to be sacrificed for the “one
pearl of great price”.} Here there is a similat-
ity of form (purla) but a problematical relationship as regards content (cogixor Gebe), a) Christian and philesophical love. 'The Christian as well as the philosopher knows himself to be a dweller in an intermediate realm, even
though for different reasons and in a different way. He i1s part of this world and still not simply subject to the “world-elements”. He
1s of the “household of God” and still not absolutely at home in the divine sphere. And
he knows himself, like the philosopher, as a
As soon as the Christian message entered the
traveller. He has received the Spirit as a “pledge” and still lives entirely in expectation. And though it is certainly not merely his own reflection which has made him a being in an intermediate realm and a traveller on the way, he is nonetheless called to assimilate the work of God’s grace in him and its promise for the future. He must make
join issue with philosophy.
just as the philosopher becomes really and
understanding: as thought which by the form it takes guides human life into new
ways,
B.
PaiLosoruy
anD
CHRISTIAN
FArTH
sphere of Hellenistic culrure, it was forced to
This necessity
was based in part, as it still 1s today, on the tact that the biblical preaching (the kerygma} produced a Jewish and Christian doctrine of the faith (didascalia). The discussion was also necessitated zabove all by the very fact that the
biblical preaching claims to make a new way
of lifepossible and summonsto it. Hence itap-
pearsasarivaltophilosophyasashaper of life. In the early days of Christianity this
rivalry was signalled above all by the fact that the procedures of the Christian preachers
resembled those of the wandering teachers of
the Stoic and Cynic type. This led to the forging of certain links — the lists of virtues and vices in the Pauline letters resemble the
corresponding
texts
from
the
diatribe
of
popular philosophy — but also to sharp conflicts. The only text in the NT which uses the word philosophy warns against falling
victim to “philosophy and empty deceit” (Col 2:8). The highly chequered history of
the encounter between biblical (chiefly Christian} preaching and philosophy cannot be
traced here. But some of the main issues involved may be indicated in order to understand the discussion.
it his own in his own /Joges (dporoyeiv). And
hopelessly foolish when he does not see and
proclaim himself a fool, so too the Christian
is really and hopelessly a sinner when he does not see and proclaim himself a sinnet but tries to ‘“‘establish his own justice” (the
apostasy of the “‘Judaizers”). And just as the philosopher misunderstands and forfeits his
relation to the truth when he takes it as an assured possession instead of as the goal of
his love, so too the Christian misunderstands
and
forfeits
his
relation
to the
promised
glory when he fancies that he already pos-
sesses it (the apostasy of the “enthusiasts’™).
Like the way of life of the philosopher, the Christian way is also a self-understanding which is intrinsically self-criticism.
When the philosopher affirms that he can only seek truth inasmuch as it has already presented itself to him (as the wveritas gua
cognoscifur), the Christian can regard this as an
interpretation
for
he
can
of
only
his
be
relationship
on
the
way
to
God,
to God
because God 1s already with him, and indeed
—
like truth to the philosopher —
“more
intimately than he to himself”’. The philos-
opher owes his critical freedom with regard
v
PHILOSOPHY
.
to objects to his self-criticism in the light of the veritas ludicans dr homine which discloses his inadequacy. The Christian can see here an interpretation of his own relationship to the world. He is free to judge the world critically precisely because he knows himself as one
who
is judged by God
and who
cannot
survive under the judgment of God. And if
truth is present to the philosopher precisely in
the form
of its non-givenness,
so too the
glory and grace of God is essentially manifest to the Christian swb comtrario. Thus philo-
sophical reflection on the pature and conditions of possibility of the philosophical life can prefipure ways by which he can understand himself in his own Christian existence and in the light of its grounds of possibility. This seems to be an essential reason why the
given b}r thnsc wha see: the istim truth as the “true wisdom™ — after 1 Cor 2168, for instance —
and
hence proclaim the
Christian faith as the true love of wisdom,
The difficulty of the relationship between love of God and love of wisdom becomes
clearer and more concrete when the Christian
tries to assess the philosophical answers to the question of where the source of human
faults is to be sought and what practices are to be adopted if man is to attain “wisdom™.
Here philosophy and the preaching of faith agree in demanding of man 2 radical con-
version {cf. Mk 1:15). But the object from
which one must turn away, and the direction
to which one is called to turn, are far from
there is a resemblance between the Christian
being determined in the same way. The depreciation of the senses, and with them the body, in favour of the intellect is justified for the philosopher by theories of knowledge and hence has no primordial function within the Christian message. None-
are determined by love (ptAla), the different
(volg)
self-understanding
of the Christian can be
expressed in a theology using philosophical
instruments.
b} God and truth as object of love. Though
and the philosophical life, inasmuch as both
objects of this love — God for Christians,
wisdom for philosophers — sct up a large nurnber of tensions between the philosophical
and the Christian life. The following ques-
theless, Paul uses the contrast between mind
and members
(péin)
to indicate an
inward division of a completely different type in sinful man (Rom 7:23). This was one of the circumstances which enabled some Christian theologians to bring the Christian
tions arise.
demand for catharsis from sin into close con-
sibility which enters into rivalry with the love
mainly Platonic — for the catharsis of the
Is love of wisdom, as a shaper of life, a pos-
of God,
so
that
a choice
must
be
made
between them? Such is the answer given by
those who emphasize the foolishness of the
cross — after 1 Cor 1:18-25, for instance —
and conclude that the lover of the God of the
crucified is forced to say Yes to foolishness, so that he cannot recognize wisdom as the supreme value. Or is love of wisdom fundamentally (implicitly or explicitly) an expression of the
yearning for the “divine light”, so that it
nection with the philosophical demand —
soul from the body. The struggle against the emotions and the
summons to practise the attitude of ataraxia
(indifference) were variously judged on the part of Christians. As early as the Letter of James, desire (émbupia) is said to be the mother of sin, and anger (dpy+) the opponent of divine righteousness (Jas 1:15, 20}, though the other NT authors seem to understand the
evil passions as consequences of sin rather
than its origin (cf. Rom 1:24-27). But on the other hand Augustine affirms that Stoic ataraxia deserves to be called a stupor animi,
comprises implicitly the love of God and in the course of its further effort paves the way for the explicit love of God? Such is the answer given by those who understand the Christian message — after Acts 17:23-28, for
while fear and hope, grief and joy should be
rightly received by those who have first recognized how well worth guestioning is
maintained as authoritative by traditions and
instance — as an answer which can only be
their human condition, have learned to put
questions and long for an answet. Or
15 the
God
of
the
message
really identical with the wisdom
of
faith
for which
the guhdoopag strives, so that philosophy only really understands itself properly when it 8
counted as necessary elements of the Chris-
tian life. The repudiation
institutions,
and
of
untested
the demand
opinions
to practise
a
generous independence of judgment were concerned with myth in the actual polemics of antiquity. In the age of the Enlightenment, polemical eftort was directed against the authority of Christian tradition and the institutions established to protect it. Hence
PHILOSOPHY
the attitude to life articulated in these philosophical claims found expression above all in criticism of religion and of the Church. Inasmuch as the Christian message challenges all human boasting, it cannot accept the ideal of the autonomous subject and must oppose the claim to autonomy with the demand for
the “obedience of faith”. On the other hand
the Christian knows that precisely because he is subject to God’s judgment and grace, he is emancipated from the world and empowered to judge it dispassionately. “The spiritual man judges all things, but is himself to be judged by no one” (1 Cor 2:15). In this sense practice of independence of judgment 1s to be demanded in the name of Christianity as well as in the name of the philosophical way of life. And “growing out of culpable infancy” (Kant) can be seen as a demand for Christian maturity as well as the programme of the Enlightenment. The struggle against the methodological monism of this or that science or of the modern notion of science in general, along with the development of attitudes of another kind, has engaged both philosophy and Christian faith in a defensive artitude common to both. They reject positivism and also all systems of interpretation of the world
based on mechanism, biologism or any other
particular science. But this common ground should not obscure their difference. Philosophical critique of science demonstrates the
sin) not merely as the moral defect of individ-
uals, but as a state in which mankind and the world in general find themselves. The Chris-
tian call to individual, on a2 new individual’s
conversion is addressed to the but Christian hope is firmly set state which far surpasses the transformation and brings about
a “new heaven and a new earth”, But while Marzxist philosophy sees true philosophy as
the pathway to revolutionaty praxis, the Christian must bear in mind that he cannot expect the renewal of the world from his own effort. This would be to fall victim to 2 new form of “righteousness by works”
which would contradict the hope of salvation
from grace alone.
The examples show that wherever Christian love of God encounters in the concrete the human love of wisdom, philosephia, and
the Christian and philosophical summons to
conversion have to show their compatibility or their opposition,
distinctions have to be
made. This can only be done by a new con-
sideration of the nature and conditions of possibility of the philosophical and the Christian way of life. Such reflection on the
philosophical and the Christian way of life
(inspired by the kerygma) gave rise to philosophy and theology as learned disciplines. Hence the discussion between the two forms of life is followed by discussion between philosophical and theological doctrine.
2. Philosophy as a learned discipiine and Chris-
limited nature of all possible scientific knowledge, by analysing the form in which science arrives at its results. The Christian critique
tian theology. 1t is characteristic of the biblical
its
learned discipline from the proclamation of a
of human
wisdom,
inadequacy
from
however,
the
demonstrates
inability
of the
“wisdom of this world” to grasp a definite content: the saving work of God
(cf. 1 Cor to extend restricted based on
in Jesus
2:7-8). The philosophical effort the mental horizon which was by a methodological monism is the given mode of being of the
reason or of existence, or on a transformation
of consciousness which man himself brings about. The Christian effort to hear the word
confesses that God himself as he speaks must
open man’s ears and eyes in a new way, so
that he can see and hear God’s sign and word. Finally, when Marxist philosophy sees the cause of human enslavement not in a subjective and individual failure butr in an objective and collective state of society, the
Christian critique of the world agrees with
it in one respect. Christianity also sees the
enslavement of man (under the lordship of
and post-biblical religions {Judaism,
tianity, Islam)
Chris-
that they have developed
2
message (kerygma). Like Christian faith and philosophy as a way of life, Christian theology engages in a close but complex relationship
with philosophy as a learned discipline.
First the kerygma has to mark itself off both from philosophy and mythology. These latter
are two ways of interpreting the direct experience of man — they reduce phenomena
to their ultimate ground (&gy7) — and remind men of what they already knew in 2 way unknown to themselves: they have the character of anamnesis. But the kerygma announces what has proceeded from the
decree
of
God
hitherto
kept
secret,
and
says something to man which he could never
find himself in any process of anamnesis.
Hence too the message does not put forward arguments {which would mean leaving the hearer to judge of the message) but announces 9
PHILOSOPHY God’s judgment and grace (and 50 places.the
hearer under God’s judgment). But this very characteristic of the biblical religions, that they are based on 4 kerygrna, neeessitated in the second place a theology. For the kerygma is itself interpretation. The newly proclaimed action of God interprets
all earlier ones, and needs itself tb be inter-
preted, It does not work magically by the recitation of a spell, as it were, but demands
to be understood. But since the kerygma is
~ interpretation and demands interpretation,
it calls for an art of interpretation (éppmvela) and also a theory of interpretation (hermeneutics). These take shape in reflection on controversies of interpretation (e.g., the
Sententize of Peter Lombard) and in the effort
to reach a critical decision on them (e.g., the Onaestiones of Aquinas). The learned theology which was built up in this way had already foreruniners in the biblical writings of the OT and the NT. It developed its methodology later, especially in the sphere of Hellenistic
eapable of undmmdmg it, must there firstqfafitrytopmducemhishmxersam! e which cor~ — & task of their own ignoranc re:spflnds to the use of antinomy (apomm:s) in philosophy. Thus the evocation of 2 critical self-understanding, which is one of the central tasks of philosophy, is a prerequisite for initiation into understanding of the message. Theology, like philosophy, needs both an anthropological and a logical foundation and hence has no other instruments at its disposition than those which it takes over from philosophical reflection. (iii) The biblical message claims to be true, And here it does not merely claim to display correctly a particular matter. Rather, in the salvific event which it proclaims, e.g., the exodus of Israel from Egypt or the resurrection of Jesus from the dead, it seeks to proclaim the manifestation of the unlimited and
hence all-embracing lordship of God over
been collected {senfentiae) and the question
the world and man. Hence it cannot make the salvific action which it announces intelligible, unless it also proclaims the God who acts there 25 Lord of heaven and earth — which means that the proclamation of history has to be interpreted by a theological cosmology.
theology no less than philosophy needs an art
the NT the “cosmological Christology” of
téyvy) and hence a skilful management of proofs (téxvy mept Toug Adyoug). The rules of this dialectic and logic cannot be other than those alteady developed in philosophy. Theology cannot avoid using the logic and methodology of philosophy. In arguing
to compete with philosophical theories of the cosmos and its supreme priaciple and is
culture, in controversy with philosophy. a) Theology as reflection on the message of faith
with the instraments of philosophy. (1) As soon 2s divergent interpretations of the message have of their assessment of reciprocal
({gwaestiones) is raised,
argumentation
(SlxhexTixn
agatnst one another, each of the participants
can appeal to the rules of logic to demand
that his partner be consistent in his affirmations (Sporoyel éautd). This forces every attempt to interpret the message to become a coherent whole in relation to its individual
assertions. In this way systematic theology grows out of the guaestionss under the influence of philosophical dialectic and logic. (11) The fact that the message needs inter-
pretation at all presupposes
that it is not
(See for the OT the account of creation, for
Col 1:15-17.) But with this, theology begins
forced either to acknowledge philosophical cosmology and *“‘theology™ (doctrine of the
supreme principle of the world) as “natural
knowledge” of the truths which theology proclaims on the basis of ‘“supernatural
revelation”, or to outdo them by a specifically
biblical cosmology and theology. For the former, one may compare Thomas Aquinas, who explains the philosophical reflection on the cawra prima of the world as similar in content to the confession of the divine creator
of the world: “Er hoc est quod omnes dicunt Deum.”
(1v) The claim to truth put forward by the
biblical message not only involves the claim
immediately intelligible of itself as soon as it
to speak of the unqualified and hence uni-
hearers cannot at first hear in the way which is demanded for a proper understanding. This is because the hearers are impelled by their illusory knowledge to pass a hasty verdict onthe message (e.g., “foolishness and
which the message speaks can recognize the
is proclaimed. The announcer finds that the
scandal’®), instead of allowing it to convince
them of their ignorance. He who intetprets 10
versal lordship of God biblical cosmology — the event which alone the hitherto concealed who are chosen by God
— the occasion of a but also to announce enables man to grasp mystery. Only those in the act of grace of
message as the “power of God” (1 Cor 1:25).
To the rejected it remains foolishness (/44
PHILOSOPHY
1:8). Hence the message does not merely
proclaim the lordship of God as the central veriias guae cogmoscitar. It also proclaims the grace of God as the transforming wserites gua
cogmoscitwr,
Tt
is
undoubtedly
no
zccident that one finds in the OT (Is 42:6) and in the NT (Jn 12:35f.) the comparison
so well-known from philosophy by which
the new source of knowledge is compared to the light which illumines the eyes and makes the object recognizable. To explain this claim of the message, the interpreter must appeal to the hearer’s sense of not being himself master of his powers of hearing, but of needing to be enabled to hear by a condition of possibility over which he cannot dispose. Here the theologian appeals
to the transcendental reflection of the philosopher on the conditions of possibility of “being able to see” in general. Only thus does it then become clear how the interpretation of the biblical message differs from philosophical reflection. For the message claims that the conditions of possibility of the new
hearing and understanding are mediated by a definite figure within history: I am the
hght” (Jn 8:1). (v) It follows from what has been said that theology uses the logical and anthropological principles of philosophy in order to make the gospel message properly intelligible. It claims to answer the question of philosophical cosmology about the beginning and ground (2pyn) of all things and the question of tran-
scendental philosophy about the conditions of possibility of knowledge by pointing to the true Lord of the world and the true light which enlightens every man who comes into the world. And by asserting the uncenditional
Luther objected) or of “Hellenizing” the understanding of the biblical message, that 15, submitting it to the conditions of specifically Greek thought for its understanding. Thus the positive association of theology with philosophical questions in cosmology and transcendental analysis and with philosophical principles of logic and anthropology is open on principle to theological criticism — among the ‘“anti-dialecticians” of the Middle Ages and above all in the theology of the Reformers and their successors.
(i) Philosophical logic is either classical or dialectic. The former takes the principle of non-contradiction as its supreme principle,
the latter ranges oppositions under a perspieuous law for their mediation. But theology
can underline the “paradox” as the necessary
form in-which the divinely-wrought salvation is manifested and in which it must be
proclaimed. Against theses of philosophy,
the anthropological theclogy can object
that faith cannot build on the rightness of man’s self-understanding.
On the contrary,
only the light of faith can free man from his
self-deceptions and enable him to reach a true seli-understanding. Philosophical “theology”’, as doctrine of the supteme “principle”
of the world, is opposed by Christian eschatology, which shows that the God of the
Bible is not to be defined as the ground of the world, but is equally capable of destroying
the existing world and bringing about, at his good pleasure, a new heaven and a new earth,
The natural relationship of the philosophicallv-investigated ground of the world to the world contrasts with the relationship of the judge of the world, as proclaimed by the bib-
of the divine illumination it also makes this
lical message, to a world condemned by his judgment and dependent on his free grace. The transcendental reflection of philosophy
its programme,
knowledge and knowability in general. But
lordship of God and the sovereign freedom
claim, in point of fact, even when, taithful to
it refrains from intervening
in philosophical debate.
b) Theslogical critigue of philosophy as theolopical self-criticism. The programme just mentioned, that of refraining from inter-
ventionin intra-philosophical debate, wasnot adopted merely in order to leave due room for freedom in natural reflection. Very often, the effort of theologians to exclude philosophical problems from their own terms of reference was in the nature of a fundamental critique of philosophy. The use of philosophical reflection to interpret the biblical message is open to the suspicion of mixing
the word of man with the word of God (as
enquires into the conditions of possibility of the biblical message is the historical announcement of an ever new possibility of hearing a definite content. To use the metaphor of light: the eternal, necessary light of truth is contrasted
with the free, historical
illumination of grace. (ii) Nonetheless, these fundamental contrasts do not spare theology the necessity of undertaking in tact philosophical reflection — though often against its will and then for the mast part unconsciously. Theology can-
not renounce the effort of relating the various
enunciations of the Bible to oneanother(e. g., relating them to some “central” affirmation 11
PHILOSOPHY - of Scripture). It mnst therefore.accept the . be to bring abeut a theology “patif challenge to remain in harmony with itself ok ';;_phlcai elements; Its fusction (m:gq:mw'i‘i isutd) throughout the multiplic-
ity of its assertions. If it then engages in
polemics with classical and dialectical logic, it is continually forced to take its stand,
explicitly or implicitly, on another logic (as
the regulator of its harmony). Further, since theology cannot rencunce the effort to-make
the message intelligible to the hearers, it must always seek out man in his self-understanding and convince him of the inappropriateness of his existing self-understanding. If, in doing so, it considers that the
traditional notions of the “soul”, the “I”,
the “reason” and so on are inadequate, it is forced to substitute another “anthropological
contrary, is to produce an sttitude azE aa%:tl if thealogy counti criticism intheology. For the laws of phllflsophlcal logic (m its dtalactical a5 well as its: classical form) with the
paradox as the manifestation of divine freedom, it questions the possibility of all systematization, in theology as well as in philosophy. But this would
imply
renunciation of all
possibility of assuring its own consistency (oupgovsiy éavré).
sophical
If
anthropology
it
counters
philo-
(in its traditional,
idealist or existential form) with the noveity of the new creation which frees the divine
word from a link with the hearing of the
“old man”, it questions the philosophical
of the
method of appealing to a pre-existing though
philosophy), in which case it throws itself open to philosophical criticism. And then,
of the message is kept apart from all anamnesis. But further, it calls in question any possible theological appeal to the self-
foundation™
(as,
for instance,
that
analysis of existence in the sense of existential
theology may regard the world asa wholeasa creation dependent on its creator, or as an object of judgment submitted to its judge. But it has spoken of the world “as a whole”,
and hence has in fact made a cosmological
statement.
Finally,
when
it contrasts
the
“light” which makes zll knowledge posstble by its nature, with the “illumination™ which takes place in grace, it has undoubtedly given
a historical and event-oriented turn to transcendental reflection — and thus called
the attention of this branch of philosophical effort to a new possibility of enquiry. None-
latent consciousness, and the announcement
consciousness of the “old man®. This, how-
ever, involves renunciation of all argumenta credibilitatis intended to bring the message closer to unbelieving hearers. It is, in 2 word, reliance on the power of the self-explanatory word. But such exclusive reliance would ultimately make all theology superfluous. Finally, if theology counters the philosophical
enquiry into the wholeness of the world and the ground of the world with the freedom of the divine Lord who can destroy or renew the
theless, it has thus intervened in the philo-
world in judgment, it calls in question not only “metaphysical theology” but also all
“seetng”, “hearing” and “understanding”.
this involves renunciation of all possibility
sophical discussion of the grounds of human
In a word: even when undertaking on principle a critique of philosophy, theology
inevitably does in fact philosophical work and intervenes precisely in the intra-philosophical discussions in which according to its programme it did not wish to be involved. The corresponding observation may be made that the repudiation of philosophy in the
name of the faith — as propounded above all by the representatives of dialectical theology
— generally takes the field against one philosophy in the name of another, e.g., against
Aristotelianism in the name of existence philosophy. Its claim to be free of philosophical premises then turns out to be an evasion of the duty of critical reflection on
the philosophical
principles
which
are in
fact applied. (11t} Hence the function of a fundamental
critique of philosophy
12
by theology cannot
possibility of “theological cosmology™. But
of joining in, in the name of faith, when matters of this “worldly world” are spoken of. If it remains
consistent,
2 radical
theo-
logical critique of philosophy makes an equally radical self-criticism of theology necessary. In this way it brings about not a separation between philosophy and theology (which shows itself as impossible), but the recognition of the difference between theology and faith. The critique of philosophy undertaken
in the name
expounded.
This self-critical consciousness
of faith reminds
theology that every effort to expound the message of faith through human reflection necessarily falls short of the message to be which proceeds from the debate with philos-
ophy seems to be as necessary for theology
as the positive service which philosophical logic, anthropology, cosmology and metaphysics have to render in this matter.
PHILOSOPHY
c) Particular tasks of theology and philosophical aids. Under the influence of this self-criticism induced by criticism of philosophy, theology may be inclined to renounce systematization (with the help of philosophical logic), the
appeal to human
self-understanding (with
the help of philosophical anthropology and existence-analysis), interpretation of the
world (and debate with philosophical cosmology and metaphysics) and reflection on the possibilities of its own intelligibility (with the instruments of transcendental
reflectinn). For in all these activities it had
found itself necessarily making use of philos-
ophy. To avoid this, theology can try to
restrict itself to making the word of God audible, announcing the hour of this word and confessing this word before the peoples
in the urgency of its claim. But even so theol-
ogy does not escape the necessity of calling on the help of philosophy. Pure service of the word is not possible without reflection on 15
what
“word”,
how
the
word
can
be
“administered’ and how the passage is made from hearing to “‘understanding”. But with such reflections one has already entered the
field of linguistic philosophy and hermeneut1cs. tion it is that
The announcement of the hour of salvaor judgment calls for reflection on how that the world and man are so constituted decision is taken about them as a2 whole
in such an “hour”. The question arises, for instance, as to how the “historicity” of men
existing in such hours is related to the *“history as dates” of such events. But with such re-
Aections theology is immediately involved in the themes of philosophy of history (see Histery 1). Finally, it the urgency of the message 1s to be proclaimed to the peoples,
the theologian has to reflect on how this message stands to the religions or the irreligion of these peoples. The question arises, for instance, as to whether Christianity 1s to be presented as the “true™ religion in contrast
to the “false” religions of the peoples or as
the “fulfilment of religion in general”, or whether its very essence takes it out of the
genus “religion”, so that it has to achieve the conquest of all religion positively, and hence more radically than modern atheism.
How-
ever the relationship of the Christian message to the religion or the irreligion of the peoples
many reasons for thinking that philosophical
effort in the field of linguistic philosophy, hermeneutics, philosophy of history and philosophy of religion have more pressing services to render theology in its present-day problems than reflection on logic, natural philosophy and metaphysics {though even today these cannot be dispensed with). d) Retrospect: Basic elements of the relationship between philosophy and theology. (i) In the minds
of philosophers and theologians, the mutual
relationship of these two modes of “love of truth” seems, for some hundreds of years
now, to be marked by the fear that each of them threatens to limit the freedom and
independence of the other. On the side of philosophy there is the implicit or explicit suspicion that theology expects philosophy to help it to prove or at least make probable, with the help of natural
reason, propositions which faith finds certain for other reasons. Given such 2 mandate as
to
its contents
by
theology,
philosophy
would be forced from the outset to link its questioning and seeking to predetermined results and could exemplify only externally frankness of questioning and the critical nature of research. It would be condemned to the slavish role of the ancilla theologiae. On the theological side there 1s the suspicion that the systems sketched by philosophy see the contents of the message of faith as new ‘‘cases” to be subsumed under the ancient rules of logic, metaphysics and anthropology, of non-theological origin. The hu-
man spirit would be judge of the word of God. If philosophy penetrated into theology,
it would submit the free call of God to the laws of human wisdom. (i1} This suspicion, voiced from both sides,
can be documented by historical examples,
likewise on both sides. In the history of theology, repeated efforts have been made to
exploit philosophy, for missionary or apologetical purposes, as a2 subsequent confirmation of matters of which the assured on other grounds. So
believer is too in the
history of philosophy, repeated efforts have been made to “‘explain™ biblical assertions or even to “save” them, by expounding them
as testimonies
to a basically
philo-
always include a statement about religion as
sophical consciousness which only expressed itselfin religious form for lack of an adequate self-understanding. But their truth is said to
philosophy of religion. The history of the human sciences suggests
anthropology or even existential philosophy is made explicit.
may be described, this characterization must such,
and
hence
has
entered
the
field
of
be clear as soon as their inherent metaphysics,
13
PHILOSOPHY
(it} But-these historically verifisble efforts
subject-abject
are based, nonetheless, on mutnal misander-
thing known, such 2 are to be&fi'-'_' At
and the resulting fundamental mutual distrust
standing between theology and philosophy. Theology and philosophy relate to a truth which is neither exlusively nor primarily the
mdiatim.
.
ditions of poussibility of knowing:
and the
philosophically, do not contain 4 law for such factual changes through which thaught can be given a new-power of
perspicuity of an object, but much more the
objects a new mode of visibility. And thc
“thing seen™. Hence each of them grasps its own nature only inasmuch as it remains conscious of the necessaty inadequacy of its
conditions
condition of possibility of “seefng” and the
utterance. They must use the language of objects to designate something which, as the condition of possibility of knowing as of the known, remains essentially distinct from all objects. Both are therefore modes of service of a truth which is always greater than what
can be said of it in philosophical or theo-
logical propositions. This constitutive relationship to the veritar semper maior prevents both theology and philosophy from discharging their task within the closed frame-
work
of a system.
language
and
hence
But
if inadequacy
corrigibility
and
of
in-
completeness of thought are essential notes
both of philosophy and theology, there is no teason to fear that either of them could impose its own closed system on the other
and hence subject it to an alien law. That the contrary impression may
arise,
however, i1s due to the fact that the intrinsic
incompleteness
of philosophy is otherwise
based and hence of a different type than that
of theology. The basis in philosophy is the transcendental and hence non-objectivated character of truth, in theology the sovereign
and hence incalculable
decision of divine
freedom. The resulting type in philosophy is the non-definitive transcendental reflection, in theology the confession of the mysterious character of the divine decree.
The philosopher then has the impression that
theology breaks off discussion about the conditions of possibility of the factual by
theologian is still free to allot the detual ‘“‘under which
thought
to power and the known its knowability” the constitution of sinful reason or to that of an understanding enlightened in grace. In a similar way, theology has been compelled by intrinsic reasons, when speaking of God’s free saving acts, to change from a description
of “brute facts” indifferent to interpretation,
to an exposition of events which by their very natute gave tise to a new understanding (cf. the unity of the Easter event and the initiation of the Easter faith). Hence the theological appeal to God's free acts does not demand that philosophy should cease to enquire further as to how this act as such had to be able to make itself intelligible to the new human understanding which it produced. And the philosopher remains free to take this unity of new truth and new under-
standing as a particular mode of historical and factual subject-object mediation, and to enquire into its transcendental constitution (see also Hermeneutics). It therefore appears that philosophy and
theology can only threaten to force systems
on each other when they disregard in each
of the two doctrinal systems its specific relationship to the truth. The fundamental openness
which
the
relationship
other. This openness will be safeguarded insofar as both theology and philosophy remember that as learned doctrines they have their historical origin and their actual source
in the love (ptAla) which inspires philosophy
of possibility subjects God’s freedom to a
and Theolagy.
by tntrinsic reasons to change from a doctrine
of eternal 4 priors forms to a doctrine of so
many 14
historical and factual modes
of the
the
them into a much closer relationship to each
or theology as the case may be.
law which has decided beforehand what is possible and what is not, But this impression too is only superficial and is fundamentally countered by the history of the sciences of the spirit. Transcendental philosophical reflection has been compelied
to
veritas semper maior demands of them brings
declaring that “such was the good pleasure of God”. The theologian gets the impression
that philosophy’s reflection on the grounds
has its
See also Theological Methodology 1, Philosophy BIBLIOGRAPHY.
on
A:
On
the
basic
texts,
see R. Schaefller, Wege 2o einer ersten Philosophie (1964), pp. 221-9. — W. Dilthey, Das Wesen der Phitpsophie (1907), E. T.: The Essence of Philosaphy (1954); ]. Rehmbke, Philosaphic als Grundwissenschaft (1910); H. Rickert, “Vom Begriff der Philosophie”, Leogos 1 (1910-11), pp. 1-34; E. Husserl,
“Philosophie als strenge Wissenschaft™, ibid., pp. 289-341.
W.
Windelband,
.4wn
Introduction
1o
PHILOSQOPHY Philosophy (1921); H. G. Gadamer, “Das Verhiltnis der Philosophie zu Kunst und Wissenschaft”,
Uber die Ursprimglicbkait der Philosophic (1948), pp.
15-28;
K. Jaspers, The Perennial Scope of Philosopby
(1949); ]. Pieper, Lessure: The Basis of Cwlinre (1952); W. Stegmiller, Metapbysk — Wissen-
sehaft — Skepsis (1954); M. Heidegger,
Was ist
das — die Philosophie? (1956), E. T.: What is Philosopby? (1958); D. Robinson, Crwcial Issues in
Philosophy
(1955);
.
Pieper,
Was
heisst phi-
losophieren? (1959); K. Lowith, Weltgeschichte und Heilsgescheben (4th ed., 1961); D. ]. B. Hawkins, Approach te Philesaphy (1964); K. Jaspers, Philosapbical Faith and Revelation (1967); J- Breanan, The Meaning of Philosophy (2nd ed., 1967); J. Passmore, “Philosophy”, The Encyciopedia of Pbilosophy, V1 (1967), pp. 216-26. on &: E. Przywara, “Religionsphilosophie katholischer Theologie”, Handbuch der Pbhilosopbie (special vol., 1927) = Sebriften, 11 (1962), pp. 373-511; id,, Analogta Entis (1932) = Schrifien, 111 (1962); W. Bange, “Formeinheit von Philosophie und Theologie?”, Catholica 2 (1934), pp. 10-26; E. Brunner, Natural Theology (comprising “Nature
and Grace” by E. Brunner and the reply “No!”
by K. Barth) (1946); G. Schngen, Die Einbeit der Theologie (1952);
id., Philosopbische Einlibung in dir
same
time,
doxography
represents
a first
stage in the writing of the history of philosophy,
1. The first stage in the transition from
doxography to history of philosophy took
place when the question was asked whether disagreement among contemporaries corresponded essentially to the “change” of opinion in the course of generations. Aristotle tried, especially in the Mezaphysies, to arrange the answers given by “the ancients” to the question of the “principles” into a temporal and also intrinsic sequence. The solution which he himself offered — the doctrine of the “four causes” — was presented as the provisional goal to which the efforts of his predecessors had gradually approximated. From Aristotle down to the present day,
systems of philosophy have often been preceded by a historical introduction.
2. A further step to attaining a historical
Theologie {(1955); R. Bultmann, Ersays Philosophicat
view of philosophy was taken by Augustine
G. Ebeling, “Theologie und Philosophie”, RGG,
2f1.} that it was not merely opinions with regard to identical problems which differed, bur that the questions themselves varied according to place and time. The interests
and Theologiral (= Glanben snd Verstebhen, 11) {(1955); V1,
cols.
782-830;
E.
Brunnet,
Philosophy
1:
The
Heidegper
of
Religion (1958); R. Bultmann, Existence and Faith (= Glanben und Versteben, 1, 111, selections) (1961}; J. M. Robinson and ]. B. Cobb, Jr., eds., New Frontiers i
Theology,
Later
and
Thealogy (1963); id., New Frontiers in Theology, 1H Theology ar Histery (1967), W. Pannenberg, History and Hermenentte (1967);, W, Weischedel, *Von der
Fragwiirdigkeit einer logie™, Philosophische
151-78.
philosophischen TheoGrengginge (1967), pp.
Richard Schaeffler
I1. History of Philosophy The history of philosophy and its meaning
are themselves
philosophical
problems.
In
earlier times, it was mainly seen as the various solutions which could be given to
the same problems. The registration of such opinions, “‘doxography”, is best known from the relatively late work of Diogenes Laertius
(Lives of the Philosophers, 3rd century A.D.; Theophrastus collected the
[4th century 8.c.] had also oquowal 36Ear, Dactrines of
the Physicists, preserved in frg.). Doxography could be made to serve systematic philosophy. Typical solutions could be compared, and each new solution was compelled to take into account divergent opinions and discuss the arguments critically. But at the
when he pointed out (De Civiiate Dei, VIII,
of the
those
lonians
of the
were
Italians
mainly
cosmological,
anthropological
and
ethical, those of Plato embraced both trends
synthetically. The question remained as to whether the differences in the problems
raised were due to differences of regional
cultures or of periods of time.
3, The third and decisive step to a historical understanding of philosophy was taken
when the theses of the ‘“*historicity of reason” was put forward (not without opposition). [t means that not only are philosophical problems and the doctrinal solutions to
them subject to historical change, but also and
above
enunciates
all human
such
reason
questions
itself,
which
and offers solu-
tions. Hence the same type of question and
answer was not and is not possible at all times. On the contrary, the traditional assertions of philosophy display in each case a specifically historical form of human reason.
Hence
too problems
which
were felt at a
certain period of history need not necessarily
be capable of appealing to other ages, and
the apswers given at any particular time need not be acceptable as such by all men. Both question and answer have to be under15
IR
PHILOSOPHY stood in the light of their times, and the liter
mm forr athm ehmgw i ptineiple of mm
cally” his own attitade to them. This thesis presents the history of philosophy with 2 double task. It must read traditional philos-
osophical) reason is opposed by the notion Elf . a pbzlampfim perennis, which ~was proclaimed
see contemporary philosophy as distinct from and as in continuity with earlier philosophy. The history of philosophy has therefore to take a “historical” view both of its own and of other philosophies.
fact already upheld by the rationalistn of the 17th century against the incipient historical relativism of the English empiricists.
reader must be prepared to “state histori-
ophy against its historical background, and
a) The thesis of the historicity of reason has been put forward in various terms. Vico tried to discern 2 development in the reason
of the various
families
of languages
by
examining the history of language. He assigned “academic” language, and hence philosophy and science, to a relatively late stage in the history of the various nations.
in human life, b) The thesis of the historicity flf ljphil«-
chiefly by neo-Thomism against the histnrifi:i’am of the 19th century. But it was in
According to the upholders of the pbilosophia peremnis, it is irrevelant to historical problems that they should have been first formulated or answered, for extrinsic reasons at particular times. Hence questions once enunciated and answers guaranteed by suffi-
cient proofs belong henceforth to a perma-
and hence the political raison d'état are the older forms of language and speech. Lessing, however, abandoning the consideration of
nent tradition and can be re-lived by all men at all times, given sufficient formation. The “classical” findings of philosophy can be adopted, in spite of their actual origins at various times, into a supra-historical system of objective questions and answers. History
universal history of human
deutic role. The student of systematic philos-
Poetry and hence the poetical reason, law
national
characteristics
and,
envisaging
reason,
a
saw in
the development of the philosophical spirit a divine “pedagogy of the human race”, which permits the errors which beset this
spirit on account of the stimulus which they provide. Vico and Lessing are typical of subsequent
history-writing in philosophy inasmuch as
both of them assign the history of philosophy
a place in history as viewed by philosophy.
History of philosophy becomes part of the philosophy of history. But they differ in the view 'they take of the significance of the
history of philosophy in history as a whole.
For Vico, history of philosophy is part of national history, with a universally valid law
of development which guides the spirit of peoples from a poetic youth to a political
and practical maturity and then to a late academic phase. But Lessing regards universal history as essentially the development
of theoretical and practical insights. History of treligion and philosophy is not a random
part of the total historical development,
but
its central action. Thus the two writers may
be
consideted
as representatives
of two
notions of the task of history of philosophy. One view tries to explain the historical change of philosophical reason by non-philosophical factors such as biogenetic or socio-economic changes. In the other view, the history of philosophy can be explained by intrinstc elements and can be used as a 16
of philosophy is assigned a purely propaeophy is to “go back™
which problems
to the situations in
were first posed and an-
swered. His task of finding for himself, as it were, the same “classical” answer is thus
made easier on two counts. He travels once more
the way
to the answer
and
he also
understands subjectively the “erroneous paths” on which others wander who have
come upon the questions but have not yet
found the right answer., The main argument that “true philosophy” should display the
characteristics of a pbrlosopbia perensis is that the historicity of reason precludes all hope of establishing a set of eternal truths. It can
only engender scepticism. The
rejoinder
relativism
and
ultimately
is that it is the very im-
practicability of the ideals of the philosophia perennis itselt which forces men into scepticism. No philosophy up to this time has in fact resisted historical change, and even the “classical” philosophers have always been understood in a different way historically by each of their followers. Hence, since only one philasapbia perennis can be true, and since so many generations, in spite of continual improvements
in method,
have never suc-
ceeded in finding the “true philosophy” in this sense, the effort should be abandoned as
hopeless.
¢} In this exchange of arguments, the history of philosophy seems to become a
PHILOSQPHY
school for scepticism. It proves that what is demanded systematically is impossible his-
torically. This poses a question of principle.
Is there 3 necessary and indissoluble link between the “historical” self-understanding of philosophy and the attitude of scepticism? The way was paved for an answer by Kant’s allotting to scepticism a merely
relative historical role. Kant considered it to
be a necessary outcome of philosophical experience at a certain stage, but interpreted it as an intermediate stage in the development of reason. Reason goes from dogmatism to criticism via scepticism (H. Liibbe). He thus provided the historian of philosophy with a schematic system. The schema was taken over by Hegel, but given a completely new function as part of an altered complex of problems.
Hegel sought to resolve two kindred problems by means of one principle. The
experience
of evil
in
history
in
general
suggests that there are only two choices: moral despair (immoralism) which abandons
all effort to measure the historical process by the
standard
of
the
good,
and
rigorism,
which demands that the world be morally condemned and hence leads to the notion of a
maoral élite apart from the mass of those who
fall victim to the world. In the same way, the
experience
ot error
in the
history
of the
pursuit of knowledge suggests that there are
oaly two choices: noetic despalr (scepticism) which abandons all effort to measure actual
opinions by the standard of the true, and a dogmatism which dismisses all other opinions as irrevelant to its own insights and thus leads to the formation of an intellectual élite in contrast to the mass of those who are incapable of true insight. Once the alterna-
tives are recognized as pernicious, the task of the student of universal history is to solve the problem of evil in such a way that the demand for the victory of the good in history and the
experience of the actual rule of evil do not
lead to the condemnation of the actual course of history. (This is the task of an “ontodicy” or “theodicy”.) In the same way, the historian of philosophy has the double task of answering the problem of error in such a way that the demand for the conquest of all deceit by truth and the experience of the de facto rule of error do not lead to a condemnation on principle of the actual facts of philosophical history. The solution offered by Hegel is to show
that in both cases the negative element (error
or evil) is a driving force, which does not cven disappear when conquered, in the
“negation of negation”, but remains on a higher level. But rigorism and dogmatism,
moral despair and noetic despair, are modes
of the negation of evil or error, and hence modes of the negation of negation. But both
are subject to misunderstanding. In despair,
the immoralist or the sceptic abandons the norm and hence no longer recognizes the negativity of evil and error as such. And the rigorist
and
dogmatist
merely
seeks
to
destroy the negative, not to save it on 2 higher level. But even this misunderstanding 15 2 propulsive error, since it produces the alternatives mentioned above, and which
called for a solution. The principle to which
Hegel appealed for the understanding of the
negation and its resolution, and hence for his answer to the problem of evil and error is the
nature of the spirit. The spirit, as consciousness of something, is necessarity lost at first in its object and hence alienated in the “other of itselt” (first negation}. Ina second movement,
it rescues itself from this self-forgetfulness
and estrangement, in a consciousness which negates this foreign object in doubt (negation
of negation). Finally, it recognizes itself once
more in what had hitherto seemed foreign, in the act of true knowledge. (This is the
structure of the Phenomenology of the Mind, which describes this way of the spirit’s
tinding itself in terms which also provide a guiding-line for the presentation of the history of religion and of philosophy.) Hegel thus succeeds in giving the Kantian schema of the philosophy of history a systematic foundation which in turn gives it
universality. Kant had used the metaphor of
childhood, youth and manhood to describe
the development of reason. Hegel deduces it from the nature of spirit itself, which must find its way back to itself through alienation. Kant had traced his three stages of evolution
only in the history of modern philosophy,
where dogmatism corresponded tionalistic systems, scepticism to tions of the English empiricists, himself introduced the critical
Hegel
presents
to the rathe objecwhile Kant approach.
this third stage as a basic
structure of philosophy of history as a whole and one traceable in all its epochs.
The view as thus presented by Hegel in his
lectures on the History of Philasophy may be regarded as the first effort to present the
whole history of philosophy in the guise of a philosophical
treatise.
Many
textbooks
of
17
PHILOSOPHY . the history of philosophy have since tried to follow this programme, drawing on wider
historical resources and working out details more
The
precisely.
of Erdmann
wotk
shows most clearly the influence of the Hegelian model. Marx also explains evil and error as the consequences of alienatien, and understands
these forms of negativity as driving forces in history. But he is not concerned with interpreting evil and error in such a way that
the actual course of history can be justified. Against.
efforts,
such
his
concern
is
to
“change” the world by revolution. In furthering (or resisting) such change, philos-
ophy also has a historical function — mostly unconscious — that of a tevolutionary (or reactionaty) ideology. It is the task of the Marxist historian of philosophy to desctibe this function. History of philosophy is understood not as the autonomous development of the spirit but as the reflection of social conditions at each stage. While Hegel could deduce from the nature of spirit the necessity of transitory alienation, Marx had to give it an economic and social
foundation.
Men
are
forced
to
produce
goods to satisfy their natural needs. To do this they must enter upon social relationships based on the division of labour. The division of labour calls for exchange of goods, and thus subjects individuals to laws of the
market which they find less and less intelligible (first form of alienation). Society with its division of labour only allows its members
to produce insofar as the owners of the means of production ordain. The owners are thus enabled to exploit the labours of other
men like natural resources such as lands and
mines. The “proletariat’ is subjected to the
laws which the search of the “capitalists” for profits imposes on them (second form of alienation).
This
twofold
alienation by division
of
labour (commodity market) and exploitation (labour market) is unavoidable at the stages
of development characterized by them in the
relationships of production. Tt cannot there-
fore be dealt with by positing ideal moral
values
in the
name
of which
it can
be
condemned. Hence the historical significance
of philosophy takes on another guise in the Marxist presentation of the history of philosophy. Each historical critique of alienation is itself merely a symptom of the fact that the existing relationships of production do not allow the forces of production which they 13
consrol to deploy their full offieacity. (Difh- culties of marketing, for example, preventthe
full utilization of the forces of productivity
developed in capitalism.} In the history of philosophy, critique in the arder of ideds 15 to be intetpreted as a “reflection” of this disturbance in the order of the real. On
recurring
this basis, the constantly
phenomena of dogmatism and scepticism are given a Marxist interpretation. As soon 4s. division of labour has led to a social division between men of thought and men of practice, dogmatism appears as a form of theory-building which refuses to be tested by practice. When the theoretician notices his alienation from reality, he can react against it,
while still remaining within the bounds of his
theory, by calling reality fundamentally in question. His dogmatism is transformed into scepticism. Hence dogmatism — even when it appears in a Marxist society — reflects the alienation of the theoretician from the working masses, and scepticism — 2 late feudal or late bourgeois phenomenon — reflects the alienation of the sceptic from social reality in general.
The Hegelian and the Marxist theories of the history of philosophy have remained to the present day the most fully developed concepts of the history of philosophy in general. Subsequent histories of philosophy were either merely doxographical (factual historiography of philosophy)
the model
or followed
of Aristotle and presented
the
history of philosophy as 2 series of precursors
leading up to some author seen as classical (neo-Kantian history of philosophy). Other
authors, like Spengler, had recourse to Vico’s concept of recurring cultural cycles.
Others confined themselves to presenting the history of particular problems or sketched a typology of “great philosophers”™ (e.g., Jaspers). d} The initial stages of an integrated notion of the history of philosophy are also to be found
Comte
in
and
Nietzsche,
though
without detailed application and hence without verification in the light of existing materials.
For
Comte,
philosophy
begins
with religion and develops through a stage of speculative metaphysics to the fundamental methodology of science. The growth of empirical knowledge and the formation of the sense of rational method determine this development. Nietzsche calls the the philosophy history of (European) history
of
Platonism,
which
he
sees
as
PHILOSOPHY
characterized by the dualism between sensible reality and ideal values. This dualism
appears in the cultured ss philosophy, in the uneducated as religion (Christianity is the “Platonism
of the
people™).
The
recent
history of philosophy is mainly the process of
the “emptying out of the supreme values” and hence identical with the “tise of nthil-
ism™. This process in turn paves the way for
the
“‘reversal
of
all
values”,
to
which
Nietzsche dedicated his own philosophical effort. The aim is to free life from the
bondage of spirit and to present the “pres-
ervation and intensification of life” as the real principle of all values, and indeed as the fundamental activity of all the real. ¢) M. Heidegger’s notion of the history of (European) philosophy links up with Nietzsche’s concept of nihilism, but takes a critical attitude to his programme of the “reversal of values”. Heidegger too sees the history of philosophy as the history of metaphysics, which i1s now drawing to 2 close. But it is not in the dissolution of metaphysics, the emptying out of the supreme values, that he sees the first signs of nihilism. Metaphysics itself is “‘nihilistic”,
not because it dentes life in the name of ideas,
but because of its “oblivion of being”. Metaphysics sought the transcendental condi-
tion of possibility of beings in a supreme being: the ideas, God, values, etc. In doing so
it constantly forgot the “ontological difference” by which being itself is distinguished
from all beings. But this oblivien of being was not an avoidable error on the part of thinkers. It is essentially due to the fact that
being
‘“‘sends”
(“equips”)
and
‘‘uses”
{“needs’”) men in different historical ways to “disclose’ beings as such. In this disclosure
of beings being itseif remains undisclosed. In modern technology and scitence, where beings are disclosed and presented as “ob-
jects”’, and man understands himself as a “subject” in relation to these objects, this oblivion
which,
of being
however,
elimination.
4.
At
the
arrains
prepares
its clearest
the
way
form,
for
its
can be shown to omit many instances to the
contrary, and every present-day interpreta-
tion is alive to the fact that its way of understanding earlier philosophy is different from the way the latter understood itself. Further, every effort to give an overall picture finds itself opposed by the higher value now placed on non-European interpretations of reality. These are now designated by the Greek term “philosophy™, in 2 broad sense of the word perhaps, but still must be included in a presentation of the history of philosophy. Hitherto it had still been possible to regard the history of European philosophy 25 a more or less continuous tradition, which could therefore be examined
for certain dominant trends. The possibility ceases when the independent traditions of Indian or Far Eastern “philosophy™ have to
be taken into account. Hence the effort to present a consistent “history of philosophy”™ and a2 theory to explain it is giving way to the effort to make
the “historicity of philosophy™ intelligible.
But this makes it impossible to treat relativism and scepticism as a necessary but
provisional stage in a logical development of philosophy,
Kant. A theory of the historicity of philos-
ophy is faced once more with the question of
how a historical self-understanding of philos-
ophy can be preserved, without the effort to
establish necessary truths being abandoned. See also Philasophy |, History 1. BIBLIOGRAPHY.
time,
most
students
of the history of philosophy have fundamental misgivings about deducing the overall movement of the history of philosophy from
sets of principles. This is partly due to the growth in material knowledge of European philosophy, and partly to a more refined approach to history. Every systematic survey
See
bibliography
on
_Aris-
toteltanism, and the histories of philosophy, e.g., F.Ueberweg, Grundriss der Geschichie der Philosophie,
1 (12th ed., by K. Praechtet,
1926), I (11th ed,,
by B. Geyer, 1928), IIl {(12th ed., by M. Frischeisen-Kohler and W.
Moog,
1924), TV (12th ed.,
by T. Oesterreich, 1923}, V (12th ed., by T. Oesterreich
1928), reprinted
1n 3 vols.
(1956-57);
]. E.
Frdmann, Geschichie der Philosophie, 2 vols. (4th ed., 1896); F. Caopleston, Hisior1 «f Philosophy, &8 wvols. (1946-66); A. Rivaud, //listire de la philesophie, 5 vols. (1960-07); also: Aurelius Augustinus, De Civitate Dei, ed. by E. Hoffimann, in CYEL,
present
as has been the tendency since
XL,
2 parts (1899-1900);
G.
B. Vico,
Principii di wna sctenga nwova d'intorno alla natura commune defle nagions (1725), BE. T.: The New Science
by T. Bergin and M. Fisch, from 3rd enlarged ed. (1048); id., De Norirs Temporis Studeoram Ratione, E. T.: On the $tudy Methods of our Time, by E. Gilan--
turco (1963); G. l.essing, Die Menschengeschiechts (1780}, L. Kant,
Ergiehung des Werks, ed. by
W. Weischedel, 1II (On the progress of metaphysics in Germany) (1959): G. W. I'. Hegel,
T.eciures on the Flistory of Philosephy, tr. and ed. by
19
PHILGSOPHY AND THEOLOGY E. Haldane, 3 vols, (1892} 3rd impression, 1963);
id., Reason iu Flistory, E. T. by R. Hartroann (1953); A. Comte, Conrs de la philosophie positive, 6 vols. (1830-42); F. Nietzsche, The Us and Abwse of
History, B. T, by A. Cellins (1957); M. Heidegger,
Essays in Metaphysics: Identity and Differsnce (1960); id., Nietzsche, 2 yols. (1961); H. Liibbe, *Philosophiegeschichtc als Philosophie”, Ejnsicbien (Fessshrift G. Kruger) (1962), pp. 204-29; H.-G. Gadamer,
Wabrbeit snd Methode (20d ed., 1963);
K. Marx and F. Engels, German Ideology, ed. by
L. Goldmann (1969).
Richard Schasffler
P
_
sense to.
philosophy as an independent activity of man
(cf. D 1799 etc.)? The solution given by
Vatican I, that the truth in both cases comes
ultimately from the same God and hence
cannot be contradictory, is not enough when
taken by itself. For then it is postulated that
the same results will be arrived at, but philosophy and theology are not shown to be reconciled in their claims to be sciences and
methods, each universal in its own field. It is
AND
PHILOSOPHY
THEOLOGY
A. INTRODUCTORY
[t is hard today to define philosophy. Any
answer to what philosophy is proves to be
itself one of the many philosophies which now exist. Naturally —— because philosophy differs from “regional” thinking by including its own nature in its thought and hence neither can nor will exclude anything from its questioning « prieri. (Hence it can on principle take in a self-understanding of man
based on revelation, since philosophy finds
it at least a datum of history.) Then again, in
spite of its claim to absolute “universality”
in its object and methods, the historicity of
man and the endless multiplicity of his (sources of) experience suggest strongly that
there will be
more
than one philosophy
(quite apart from disagreement among philos-
ophers). And this pluralism is again a matter of conscious reflection, prior as such to the
not clear whether one can be both a philosopher and a theologian or whether a choice has to be made. This is still true when one
affirms that faith has a “healing” function, not only in the realm of moral action but also in the realm of natural knowledge, to counter its de facto exrors, and that the Church has the right to claitn that its magisterium is at least a negative norm for the Christian philosopher and his philosophy (D 1619, 1642—5, 1674, 1710-14, 1786, 1798f., 1815, 2085, 2146, 2305, 2325) — which would still leave room for a positive assessment of philosophy (Vatican I, Gaadium et Spes, arts, 44, 57, 62; Optatam Totius, arts. 14, 15).
In answering this question, one should not be tempted to try to set a higher value on the independence of theology by stressing the discredit which now attaches to philosophy — “the end of metaphysics”. At the very least, one would merely transfer the problem
to the realm of science, inasmuch as it claims
question of the truth of any particular phiiosophy. There are so many different themes,
to be the heir to classical philosophy. The other problems which have to be discussed will be immediately clear.
to other sciences, and to philosophical tradi-
B.
starting-points, terminologies, relationships
tion that no individuzl or small (efficient) teatmn can take in the whole of philosophy,
though they know that other philosophies
exist besides their own. The question arises
at once as to how theology is to deal with
this — at least de facto — pluralism. Another question at oace involved is how philosophy
and theology can co-exist, since both claim
to be basic sciences, that is, to throw light scientifically, methodically and consciously on existence as such and as 2 whole and hence to
be
universal.
How
can
this
be,
when
faith — and hence theology — judges all things and is itself judged by no man (cf. 1 Cor 2:15), while the same faith in its Catholic understanding rejects fideism and traditionalism and so recognizes a natural 20
Tue
FuNDAMENTAL.
TWEEN
We
PHILOSOPHY
RELATIONSHIP
AND
BE-
THEOLOGY
prescind for the moment
from
the at
least d¢ facto pluralism of philosophies today,
among which even the Church can no longer
simply choose one particular philosophy as the only true one (in spite of what will be said under D below
on “Christian philos-
ophy”). We also prescind from the fact that philosophy cannot today be the only means by which the theological relevance of the “world” can be made clear to theology. The
basic question is the possibility of the coexistence of two fundamental sciences in the Christian.
1. In approaching the question, it should first be noted that Catholic theology makes
PHILOSOPHY AND THECLOGY
an essential distinction between nature and grace, and hence between natural knowledge of God and revelation. Hence by its very
essence, It not merely tolerates philosophy
but actually calls for it. Revelation and faith are not built up on the absolute incapacity of man (the sinner), and the failure of his thought. Then, it is a matter of history that theology has always used philosophical instraments in its thinking, and against modernism and all religions of feeling Catholic theology maintains that this historical process was justified. Revelation and grace are addressed from the outset to the whole man,
and hence to the thinking man,
this claim to human ary clement in the believing Christian by the conviction
and
cthought is not a subsidinature of religion. The is as such always inspired that spirit, nature and
history are the creation, revelation and pos-
. session of God, who as the one truth is the
source of all reality and truth and who has also given revelation by his words in history,
to perfect and surpass the creation which is his own. There are things which lie outside the realm of reality in the world demarcated
by
historical
revelauon,
the
Church
and
theology. But the Christian does not see them as outside the realm of his God. Hence he may not and need not set an absolute value
on theology, to the detriment of philosophy.
If he did, he would be confusing his theology
with his God. But the Christian in particular recognizes that there is a pluralism in the world, the unity of which is mastered positively and adequately by no one (apart from God), not even the Church and its theology. This is not, of course, to suggest that there could be a “double truth” in the sense of
behaves as if the religious question no longer existed either does not know what we mean by God or is a transparent technique of flight from God — and a pose.) 2. This second point, however, is decisive. Insofar as philosophy tries to be systematic transcendental reflection (and if it does not, it now falls under the heading of a nonphilosophical discipline), it cannot by its very nature claim to be a concrete, salutary and adequate interpretation of existence. Hence it is impossible for it to claim to
replace the concrete and historical reality of
religion — and so its theology. Philosophy might try to be more than such transcendental reflection (*‘mediation”), and attempt the concrete introduction into real
existence, which can never be exhaustively analysed but still remains as such imperative and 1nexorable. This would be an effort to
generate an actual religion, and philosophy
would then be the manifold unity of theology and philosophy. It would be both o priors
self-understanding and revelation, under the
guise of philosophy — or it would be a false theology, because mostly secularized. It
would then be a question of terminology and
of the correct analysis of the one comprehensive attempt to master existence. The analysis would show that this existence was something
which could never be adequately mastered
by reflection — the unity of the 2 priori of the spirit and of history, of reason and revelation,
of theology and philosophy.
But if, in keeping with its whole tradition,
philosophy
regards itself as transcendental
reflection, it can never materially embrace the whole
concrete
nature
of
existence,
even
other while still remaining true.
though the concrete is known to be a ground of existence and not regarded as an indifferent
the intellectual grasp of human existence as it
concrete
assertions which simply contradict one an-
On the other hand, if philosophy is to be
actualily is and in its whole breadth and depth
— and even purely transcendental inmitiatives in philosophy
have to have
regard
to the
history of the spirit — philosophy cannot overlook the phenomenon of religion. Even
where atheism is extolled as the true interpretation of existence and hence as ““religion™, religion remains everywhere and at all times
part of the fundamental structures of human life. A philosophy which did not in some way include “philosophy of religion” and “natural theology” would be a poor kind of thing,
since it would subject-matter.
not be looking at its own (A tranquil atheism which
residue. Historicity is less than real history,
love
is
more
than
subjectivity
formally analysed (“one can and ought to love”), experienced dread is more than the concept of this basic condition in which man finds himself. But such assertions are self-
determinations of philosophy. They are therefore among the fundamentals of philosophy, inasumuch as it is the “first” (basic)
science, to which
as such no other science
except
reality
can be prior (as ground) — nothing in fact the
actual
which
is greater
than it. But then philosophy, as the doctrine
of the transcendence of the spirit, points on
to God as the absolute mystery “in person’.
As anthropology and philosophy of religion, 21
PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY
L
it makes man a possible “hearer of the word™
of this lving God (pethaps already under the influence of the supernatural existenual) And as pure reflection and never-ending mediation it sends man — who finds himself historically and not merely reflectively — to
history itself for his real existence. Hence
ph.llusr::phy, by nature, is not -the type of basic science which would claim to be the
sole illumination and master of the concrete
existence of man. If it rightly understands
itself and its own freedom (freed by the secret grace of God), it is the first conscious light on existence which gives man courage to take history and the concrete seriously. But then it opens up for man the possibility of finding God in concrete history, where God has communicated himself to man in the incarnation.
3. Revelation in the concrete, and hence
the Church and its magisterium,
make the
claim — necessarily, by their nature — to represent the whole of reality (as supreme
principle and salvation of all things).
By
virtue of the unity of his existence, therefore,
the Christian qua believer, living this unity and hierarchical gradation in faith, cannot
treat the doctrine of the Church as simply indifferent and irrelevant to him qua philos-
opher. For his philosophy as such this doc-
trine is not a source of truths, but it is at least
a norma negativa (cf., for instance, I 1675,
1703f., 1711, 1714, 1810). In view of the permanent distinction between philosophy
and theology demanded by theology itself, this does not mean that there must always be
a positive synthesis (comprehensible in terms of the historicity of man) which man must be able to grasp as he gives himself to philosophy and theology. He may and must leave the ultimate unity of his philosophical and theological destiny to the one God of philosophy and theology, who is always greater than
either or both.
C. ParLosorny
ot
itions and mental
horizons
mvjl?f a g:@m;T historically: gmated selfi.unde:mtandmg of man which 18 due in part
to philasophy oris the material of philosophy
in a spontaneous, pre-scientific state. This: self understanding may be termed rightly a
pre-scientifi¢ philosophy. Leaving this aside, we must at any rate. note that theology — in contrast to fevelation and preaching — is a reflection on revelation and Church preaching. The theologian, questioning and critical in both directions,
confronts
revelation
with
his
whole understanding of existence, on which he has also reflected philosophically to some extent. This confrontation,
in the concrete
situation, is to help him really to assimilate revelation, to interpret it as it affects him,
to eliminate misunderstandings by an effort
of criticism — and vice versa, to allow his
own pre-existent mental horizons to be called
in question by revelation. This means that in
theology one necessarily ‘“‘philosophizes™. Such “philosophical” self-understanding
(implicit or explicit) which the theologian brings with him is (at least) one of the forces
which divide theology from revelation and set it in motion. This philosophical start of theology is possible because revelation is a call to and a claim on the whole existence of man and is therefore open at once to the selfunderstanding of man. And revelation itself also contains some such self-understanding,
philosophical, pre-philosophical or originally philosophical but having relapsed into the apparent obviousness of ordinary life and common sense. Those who think that they must not “philosophize” when doing theology merely fall victim to a dominant philosophy which is unconsciously accepted or confine themselves to edifying discourse which does not discharge the theologian’s task. To do philosophy in theology does not mean that a closed philosophical “system” is presupposed as permanently valid and
directly applicable. Philosophy may in fact
IN THEOLOGY
We prescind here from what is no doubt the more important problem, philosophy in the
original revelation. Its first utterances and the traditions by which they were handed on
be somewhat *eclectic” in reflecting the unsystematic pluralism of the history of human experience and thought, and it must be ready to undergo changes in its theological use.
were In human concepts and propositions, within mental frames of reference, which
D.
word of) revelation, though they were no
If such a thing exists at all, it must remain
existed prior to and independently
of (the
doubt also modified by that revelation. These 22
THE OPHY’
ProerLEM
oF
“CHRISTIAN
PHILOS-
philosophy in principies and method, and aim
PHILOSOPHY
AND THEOLOGY
at being nothing else. Otherwise it would not be philosophy as a fundamental science. Philosophy can be the “ancilla” of theology, that is, a mere element in a higher totality to-
the world. Here too philesophy is now ac-
afraid of open-ended dialogue, not steered in
do not allow philosophy to prescribe to them
wards which it points of its own nature, only if it remains free. Theology too must not be a certain direction from the outset by man himself and the Church. Theology must also
be prepared to listen to things that it does not
know g priori.
The philosopher can be “Christian” inasmuch as he accepts his Christian faith as a negative norm. This is not contrary to philosophical principles, as has been shown under B above. A philosophy can be called Christian inasmuch as it received impulses from Christianity to do its own work. Without such impulses it would not have been what it is in
fact. A philosophy will also be Christian when the philosopher who is a Christian strives for the greatest possible convergence between
his philosophy and his faith, and so with his theology, without overlooking the essential difference and disproportion between the two realms, and hence the asvmptotic nature
of his effort. Such effort prevents his assuming
a harmony
between
philosophy
and
faith
with no threat of tension, and also forbids
companied
by
the
modern
sciences
(of
history, nature and society). And these do not
consider themselves branches of a single philosophy, though they undoubtedly recognize philosophy as their origin. But they their self-understanding, their nature and their methods. They are rather inclined to regard philosophy as superfluous for contact with existence, or as an after-thought which analyses formally the methods of the autonomous sciences. Whether this self-understanding of the modern non-philosophical sciences is fully justified or not is another question. But the fact 15 there, and theology has to take it into account. The sciences are
also partners in a dialogue which has effects on both sides. Theology has then to consider the various methods and results of these
sciences, and as well as this, the basic mentality of modern science and its titillating situa-
tion with regard to knowledge (an irreducible pluralism of sciences). try to help the scientist dignity in face of this cence (which can at schizophrenia).
Theology must also to maintain his human situation of concupistimes be a spiritual
F. PuiLosoraicAar TEACHING
IN THE CHURCH
him to take refuge in 2 “double truth™, A philosophy can also be Christian when it
In spite of the pluralism of philosophies today, which will never be thoroughly
Christianity as a de facto phenomenon in the
pluralism in theology, certain points must be maintained. The ene Church with the one
uses philosophical methods — with the help of the history of religion — to analyse
philosophy and phenomenology of religion. This is legitimate, since philosophy is essentially a fundamental science. But in practice, the distinction between such philosophy and a theology working philosophically will be Auid.
E.
PurLosopHy, SCIENCE
THEOLOGY
AND
MODERN
The de facto relationship between philosophy and theology has been changed by the extensive pluralism of present-day philasophies, which in this age of historicism, of the “one world” and the greater range of communtcation media is perceived at once as existing
and irremediable. But the relationship has also been changed by the fact that philosophy is no longer the unique and not even in fact the primary mediation of the “world” for theology, whose work is done in contact with
synthetized, and which also evokes a parallel
confession and the one magisterium for all its members cannot but havea theology which is to some extent identical throughout. The Church needs it for the interpretation and
preservation
of the one confession
of faith,
terminology
beyond what is demanded by
and it can even imply a certain regulation of the nature of the matter in question. Such a standard theology, homogeneous to some extent, in terminology and so on, at the disposal of the magisterium, implies also a certain teaching philosophy, standardized in
methods,
in concepts,
presupposed
as ac-
cepted and current etc. — in spite of remaining in the stream of historical development. It may of course be asked whether such a
Church philosophy is still philosophy in the strict sense, or is really nothing more than a language and mental hotizon which may indeed have been taken over from philosophy
but now represents only the general mentality 23
'PIETISM
4.
of an epoch
in its unreflecting and
non-
systematic state, ' | | But this stock of standard philosophy does exist. It is necessary in a theology which is
demanded by the onen¢ss of the confession of faith. It must still be respected and cherished, though this ecclésiastical teaching philosophy cannot close its mind to outside factors or claim to call itself the philosophia
peresmis in the manner of the neo-scholasticism of the last century (cf. Vatican I,
Optatam Totiss, art. 15).
E. Brunner,
Revelation and
Rearon (1946); M. Blondel, Exigences phitosophigues du christianisme (1950); J. Moller, Existentialphilosaphic wnd katholische Theologie (1952); J. Trethowan, An Erray in Christian Philosophy (1954); A. Flew and A. Maclntyre, New Essays in Philosophical Theology (1955); L. Foucher, La philoropbie catheligue (1955); A. Marc, Raison philosophique et religion révélée (1955); G. S6hngen, Philosophische Eindibung in dis Theologie (1955); E. Reisner, “Die Frage der Philosophie und die Antwort der Theologie”, Zeitschrift fir Theologie und Kirche 53 (1956), pp. 230-51; P. Tillich, Biblical Religion and the Search Jor Ultimate Reality (1955); H. Bouillard, “Théologie et philosophie d’aprés Karl Barth et Rudolf Bultmann”, Archives de Philosophie (1957), pp. 163 f.; H. Duméry, Philosophse de la religion (1957); B. Lohse, “Ratio und Fides”, Forschungen zur Kirchen- und Dogmengeschichte 8 (1957) (on Luther); W.
Schulz, Der Go#t der nenseitlichen Metaphysik
(1957);
P.
Delhaye,
La
philosophic
chritienne
au
- Moyen Age (1959); G. Siewerth, Das Schicksal der
Metaphysik von Thomas gu Heidegger (1959); L. Bogliolo, /f problema della filosofia cristiana (1959); M. Nédoncelle, Ir there a Christian Philosophy?
(1960); J. B. Metz, “Theologische und metaphysische Ordnung”, ZKT 83 (1961), pp. 1-14;
M. Blondel and L. Laberthonnitre, Correspondance pbilosopbigue (1961}; G. Ebeling, “Theologie und Philosophie”, RGG, VI, cols. 782-830; H. Goubhier, Bergson et le Christ des évangiles (1962);
E. Gilson, Philssopby and Theolagy (1962); C. Tres-
montant,
Les
idées maitresses
chritienne (1962);
G.
Noller,
de la métaphysigue
Sein und Existenzy
(1962); L.-B. Geiger, Philosaphic et spiritualité (1963); B. Rioux and others, “Saint Thomas d’Aquin aujourd’hui”, Recherches de Philosophie 6 (1963); R. Bultmann,
Glanben und Versteben, IV
(1965), pp. 104 . (on “philosophical theology™); K. Rahner, Schriften zur Theologie, V1 (1965), pp.
91-103; H. Goliwitzer and W, Weischedel, Denken
und Glauben;
M.
Curtain,
“The
Integration
of
Philosophy and Theology™, Irish Theological Quar-
terly 33 (1966), pp. 457 66; C. ]. Curtis, “The Task
of Philosophical
Theology”,
Chureh
Lnarterly
Review 167 (1966); 1. A. Martin, The New Dialogue
Between Philosophy und Theology (1966); 1. Mnitma;m, “Theologie in der Welt der modernen Wissen-
24
-
.
pp. . Dvengelisehs Thoolsgje filos26 (1968), fico & fimlfl- |
",
621-38; . Murio; "Plaralismo
g
gico gell'ambito di nd flosofin
Pesch, °
hermencutische Ort der Theologie bei Thomas von Aquin und Martin Luther und dic Frage nach dem Verhiltnis von Philfis‘l?hie und Theologie™,
Theologische Puartaischrift 146 (1966), pp. 159—212;
G. Picht, Dar Gott der Philosophen wnd die Wissenichaft der Newzeit (1966); D, ]. Shine, An Interior Metaphysics: The Philosophical Synthesis of P. Schessr
(1966); B. Welte, Heilsverstindnis (1966); K. Rah-
ner, Schriften gur Theologie, VIXI (1966); H. Urs von Balthasar, The God Duestion and Modern Man (1967);
See also Philoiophy, Faith IV, Fundamental Theolegy, Transcendenial Philosophy. BIBLIOGRAPHY.
schaften”,
1-
K. Jaspers, Philosopbiral Faith and Revelation (1967);
O. Muck, The Transcendental Method in Philésophy
(1968).
Karl Rabner
PIETISM Pietism is a comprehensive term for a widespread and manifold movement within Protestantism in the early 17th century. The first half of the 18th century was its heyday but it made itself felt in 19th-century tevivalism
and
1s still a force even
today
(e.g., among the Moravian Brethren and some types of Methodism). Pietism does not look onthe Reformation asa mere occurrence in the past that is now embodied in an institution, but as an event that the Church must
constantly acrualize if Christ’s kingdom is to be a living reality. The substance of all pietism
is a longing
for praxis pietatis, the
“exercise of godliness”. For pietism, the real purpose of redemption is to bring the
teligtous
subjectivity
of man
into
lively,
spontaneous play, and such is also the main
interest in theology. There is no difficulty in
the old-established Protestant denominations about stressing a subjective approach, but radical pietism has the effect of loosening Church bonds.
Calvinist pietism derives from 17th-century
English Puritanism. John Bunyan (d. 1688),
author of The Pilgrim’s Progress, held that salvation
is
communicated
in
a
“break-
through” which one feels happening at a particular moment. Preachers driven from England brought this Puritan idea to Holland, where it soon spread. ]J. Labadie led the first group of pietists who formed a separate Church (1669). Calvinist pietism was sustained through the efforts of Gerhard Tersteegen-(d. 1769), composer of many hymns, Samuel Kollenbusch (d. 1803), G. D. Krummacher(d. 1837), and H. F. Kohl-
briagge (d. 1875).
-PIETISM
P. J. Spener’s Pia Desideria (1675) marks the first appearance of German Lutheran pietism. He set down the classic programme of pietism in his six proposals for reform. The codisgia pietatis which he founded soon proved
to foster separatism, and therefore met with much opposition from the authorities of the otficial Church. Spener’s work was continued in the pietism of Halle, notably by Spener’s
disciple August Hermann Francke. Being a
professor of theology (1691) and the founder of an orphanage with 2 college attached to it {1695),
Francke
was
able to exert
a very
prevasive influence on the religious, intellectual and social life of his time. His orphanage contributed towards shaping the spirit of Prussia and the minds of many philosophers of early German Idealism. It soon became a centre for foreign and Jewish missions, for the
distribution
of the
care of the Protestant
Bible,
diaspora
and
for the
in South-
Eastern Europe and North America. Francke gave pietism an educational theory of its
own; guided by the experience of his own
conversion, he educated children in view of
leading them to conversion. Count
Nikolaus
T.udwig
of Zinzendorf,
Pietism in general must be seen as part of
the great process whereby modern man has been discovering his own autonomous subjectivity, Pietism is a grandiose attempt to refer this process back to the sources of Christian life. Emancipated from tradition, autonomous man is to decide the shape of his own religious life by confronting the Bible and contemplating the situation of the primitive Christian community. No doubt the understanding of faith largely in terms of religious life, as it can be actually led and experienced, released considerable moral and religious energies and ensured that pietism would make its mark on the history of the spirit. Protestantism is indebted to pietism
tor more than stimulation of missionary activity, of religious instruction and education, and thus of personal piety. Having to
conduct controversy with the impatient and lively pietist mind gave official theology a
flexibility in its understanding of religion that enabled it more than anything else to enter upon constructive discussion with the post-Christian 1ntellectual life of modern times. In particular, by reviving appreciation
ot Scripture, pietism helped to pave the way
who had been a member of the Halle group, created an independent pietist body by tounding the settlement of Moravian Brethren at Herrnhut. They adopted an imaginative form of religious life, blending preReformation traditions with the spirit of Luther (their own calendar of feasts, congregations divided into choirs, etc.). The zealous life led at Herrnhur left 2 mark on Protestant piety that has endured to the
faith is an open-ended discussion with history. All forms of pietism are prone to look on religious subjectivity as the actual source of religious life, so that doctrine
powerfully
life. Looking for verifiable conversion in the
preseat day (the “warchwords of the Brethren””). Pietism in Warttemberg
affected the existing Church there. In J. A. Bengel and F. C. Oetinger 1t was combined with mystical speculation (from Jakob Béh-
me, E. Swedenborg) to produce a devotion based on literal interpretation ot the Bible. Lt
greatly
influenced
19th-century
German
Protestant
Idealism
theology
().
Beck, d. 1878; Adolf Schiatter, d. 1938). Compared
and
T.
with these schools of thought,
radical pietism had only a transitory influence, owing to its anti-ecclesiastical enthusiasm. Still it can boast a number of important
personalities,
above
all
Gottfried
Arnold
(d. 1714). His Impartial History of Churches
and Heresier {1699)
is the first large-scale
attempt to present the history of the Church since NT times as the progressive decay of
Christian life.
for modern
biblical
science.
Thus
it ulti-
mately helped to hberalize the rigid outlook
of the various denominations. Stressing, however, subjective independence at the expense of tradition, pietism was
always in danger of forgetting that the life of
becomes a purely pragmatic function of that
Christian, regarding the converted person as an ecclesiola in ecclesia, imperils the concept of grace, makes the Christian fellowship an
arbitrary association of religious individuals, and at worst leads to separatism. The heir of pietism and the champion of modern Prot-
estantism,
has
Schleiermacher,
drawn
the
logical conclusion as instructively as could be wished: religious experience becomes the
criterion according tn which one selects such
points of tradition as one cares to consider still valid. The ambivalence of pictism shows the task which the preaching of the faith will
have in coping with modern subjectivity., See
also
C hurches.
Protestantism
1,
N,
Methodist 25
PILGRIMAGE
BIBLIOGRAPHY. A. Ritschl, Die Geschichsr des
Rome. In the time of Christ, pilgfimages€8 to10
X, pp. 6-9; H. Leube, V, cols. 370f; 1. Hirsch,
B. Kétting traces this to-2 general decline in
Pigtismus, 3 vols.
“Pictism”, HERE, “Pietismus”, RGG,
Watechouse,
E.
(1880-86);
der neueren evangelischen Theologis, 11 {1951), Geschichte
pp. 91£.; . Weinlick, Couns Zingendorf (1956); C. Towlson, Moravian and Methodist (1957); E. Langton, History of the Moravian Church (1957).
Wenzgel Lobff
1. Definition. The idea of pilgrimage has three agpects. 2) Under cettain circumstances God responds to prayer in a special way. b) This
special activity of God
or a divinity
1s
particulatly manifest in certain places which on that account become centres of pilgrimage. ¢) In order to benefit by this special responsiveness of God, of the divinity or of certain heroes and holy persons, one must make a pilgrimage to this place of favour of deliverance, undertake 4 journey which forms a unity with the visit to or stay in the
sacred place. K. Nitzschke accordingly gives the following definition: Pilgrimage is a “journey to (and from) a holy place, of sucha kind that the visit to the shrine in conjunction with the journey forms one cultic action™,
The saving power of God or of the divinity, in Christianity
as espe-
is regarded
cially operative through the intercession of certain saints, especially of the Blessed Virgin Mary, takes effect as tangible help in sickness and distress. Or it may be that
people want blessing and assurance in important decisions, and pray for this at a
of pilgrimage.
place
Sometimes
man
is
tormented by the uncertainty of his lot after death and is impelled to seek out particular holy places in order to gain certainty about his after-life. Or he may undertake a pilgrim-
age in gratitude for benefits already received or in ordet to preserve divine goodwill by regular visits to the holy places (B. Kotting, p. 12). 2.
Non-Christian
pilgrimages.
a)
Graeco-
Roman antiguity. The chief places of pilgrimage were indubitably those of the gods of healing, for belief in miracles largely concerned miraculous cures. Healings were not
expected from all the gods but only from
certain
divinities,
the
best
known
being
Asclepius with his sanctuaries in Cos, Epi-
daurus,
26
Pergamon,
health, The intense interestinoracles suggests a wide drop in vitality and psychic energy,
with the majority affected by neurasthenia
and psychosomatic illnesses. The seeking of
divine oracles for the merest trifles indicates a
general passivity (ibid., pp. 4301.). At leastat this stage, therefore, pilgrimages were 4 sign
of religious weakness and dispiritedness, and
PILGRIMAGE
which
shrines of Asclepius were very populir.
Tricca,
Athens
and
were thus distinguished from the Christian pilgrimages which soon started and which, at
beginning,
least at the
a sign
were
of
religious energy. As a result the early Christians very soon drew theé contrast between Asclepius and their true Asclepius,
Christ, the Saviour. Apologists led the way,
Justin in particular: “If we say that (Christ) healed the lame and the halt and people ill since birth, and raised the dead to life, that
may be considered similar and equal to what are related as the deeds of Asclepius” { Apology, 1, 22, 6). Those afraid of the future
consulted the god
Apollo at the ancient
Greek oracles of Dodona and Delphi, or visited the sibyls, augurs, soothsayersand representatives of Roman divipation or supposed prophecy in their special centres. Others journeyed to obtain earthly blessings and hopes for a better lot after death (Eleusis), or went as pilgrims to Ephesus to
Artemis “from whom visited places
relics and honoured.
where
statues
all good comes” or
the
graves
of “‘divine
of heroes,
men”
were
b) Jewish centres of pilgrimage. There were
certain sanctuaries of Yahweh (Siloh, Bethel,
Gilgal, Beersheba) which were opposed by
prophets because of inadmissible practices
(cf. Amos 5:5), certain places of healing (in Jerusalem, the pool by the Sheep Gate
[the efficacy of the water connected with an
angel],
the
pool
of
Siloam
[]n 5:7],
springs near Tiberias) and tombs of holy
people.
But
the temple
of Jerusalem
was
pre-eminent. In the eyes of the Jews, who had to go on pilgrimage to it from the age of 12 onwards,
it was
the
centre
of the
whole
world, to which in the last days the Gentiles too would go on pilgrimage (Is 2:24.). At
the same time this piigrimage was a profession of faith in the one God and had great
social importance {cf. Kétting, p. 62). c) Other pilgrimages. We may also note the pre-lslamic, Arabian centres with pilgrimages
to the gods and cult of burial-places, the
PIL.GRIMAGE sanctuaries of Hinduism (seven holy cities) and of Buddhism (places of the birth, illumination, preaching and passing over of
the Buddha).
3. Pilgrimages in Christianity. At first pilgrimages did not enter into the perspective of Christians. They at first avoided this form
of devotion because it had flourished among the
pagans.
Moreover,
unlike
the
Jews’,
Christian worship was not centralized. Their imminent expectation of the parousia made the idea of pilgrimage to the places of our Lord’s earthly life seem superfluous. Finally, there is no sign at the beginning of veneration have
would
which
martyrs,
of saints and
prompted pilgrimages to their graves. Very
soon, however, the extreme reserve in regard
to paganism
diminished,
and
the
its forms
of expression
was
coming
Lord’s
not
scen, and veneration of martyrs and saints,
and liturgical forms developed. Legal recognition of Christianity also represented an important condition for the development of pilgrimages, which now could be public. Very soon the various goals and motives of pilgrimage were defined. B. Koétting
has listed eight for eacly Christianity: burialplaces and memorials as places of pilpersons;
living
to
pilgrimages
grimage;
pilgrimage as an ascetical mode of life; the
pilgrimage site {grave of martyr) as Chris-
tian burial place; pilgrimages of intercession (healing, help and advice as pilgrims’ inten-
tions), pilgrimages of devotion, pilgrimages of penance, pilgrimages to relics.
Particularly
among
important
these was
the pilgrimage to the holy places in Palestine
(Helena, mother of Constantine, after 324; Itinerarium Burdigalense, 333; Peregrinatio ad
foca sancta of the pilgrim Aetheria, about 400).
This also explains the coasiderable influence of Jerusalem on liturgical practices and rites in other countries {procession of palms, veneration of the Cross on Good Friday),
and also the fact that Rome had 2 “ Jerusalem” of
its
own,
“Bethlehem”,
very
important
Santa
Croce,
and
Santa Maria Maggiore. were
pilgrimages
own
its
to
Also
the
graves of the saints, above all to the tombs of
the Apostles Peter and Paul, Sergius in the Syrian desert, Thecla at Seleucia, Menas in
Palestine more closely connected with her life (D. Baldi, “I santuari mariani in Terra Santa”, Studi biblici franciscani 3 [1952-3),
pp-
219-69).
It is certain that numerous
Marian pilgrimage churches were built in Constantinople (icons of Mary and articles of clothing : the Church at Blachernae; Chalcoprateia, ¢. 450}, In the Middle Ages the penitential system played a very important role in promoting pilgrimages to Jerusalem, Rome and Compostela. These long pilgrimages, it has been noted, also served to remove the penitent from his usual surroundings for some time, which was important where he had committed a crime of violence. He was out of the reach of the primitive law of the blood-feud (cf. V. and H. Hell, p. 14). There were also
the pilgrimages to famous pictures of Christ (Holy Face at Lucca), relics (shrines at Aachen, Cologne, Trier), to places where “bleeding hosts” were kept {(Seefeld near Innsbruck, Heiligenblut) and to Marian shrines and those of other saints (Matthias in Trier, Francis and Anthony in Assisi, Padua and Alverna}. From the Counter-Reformation down to the present day the centres of Marian
pilgrimage
have
predominated,
and
this
meant, at least tn Germany, that the medieval
long-distance pilgrimages gave way in the Baroque period to local pilgrimages (A, Veit
and L. Lenhart, Kirche und Volksfrimmigkeit im Zeitalter des Barock [1956], p. 178). Austria in particular became well-known for its Marian pilgrimages (Mariazell). Among the most important pilgrimage
centres at the present time are: Lough Derg, Guadalupe,
Einsiedeln,
Kevelaer,
Czesto-
chowa, La Salette, L.ourdes and Fatima.
In connection with present-day pilgrimages, Popes and bishops have pointed out the deeper meaning of pilgrimage: “The
pilgrim’s journey is long, and begins with a
parting. He leaves his home, his everyday
life, and forgets all his unimportant, trivial
cares . . . 2nd then sets off courageously . . . and so prayer makes its way to God more easily. The company of other pilgrims
increases the ardour of the soul and gives rise to prayer in common, singing, exchange of thoughts and feelings. It culminates 1n
hear nothing of Marian pilgrimages in the
restrained exuitation when at the altar Christ offered in sacrifice comes with his body to strengthen the Christian on the way to God.
have developed soon after in the places m
of
the Maraeotic desert, Demetrius in Thessa-
lonica, Felix at Nola and Martinat Tours. We first
four
centuries;
they
must,
however,
The pilgrimage reawakens in you the spirit penance,
the
sense
of
Providence
and
27
PLATONISM
"
)
_
trast in ‘God. It instructs you afresh about the meaning of life: to turn away from the present, from everyday joys and sorrows,
~and to turn towards the goal whose radiance | shmes on you” (Pius XII 1952).
4. Theolagical assessment of pilgrimeagss today. Some are inclined to assign pilgrimages to
the peripheral zone of piety (B. Kotring in
LTK, X, cols. 945-6). A pointer in the same
direction is the absence of any reference to
pilgrimages in the new German catechism.
- Nevertheless it seers that this practice which is found in nearly all religions should maintain its central place even in Christianity at the present day. Stronger emphasis should of course be laid on aspects that have been largely lost sight of, which is why this form of religious expression has come to seem peripheral.
A new impulse to pilgrimage might be given by the idea of the pilgrim Church, in
the midst
of distress, imperfection,
tainty and perplexity,
uncer-
wanderng
yet not
aimlessly, but as a community whose aim is
petfect salvation and redemption in Christ.
That goal, however, is still distant, for the
Churchasa wholeand for each of its members. The remoteness of the still unattained goal leaves the Church without
rest, and
some-
times even weakens the hope of what is securely promised, and the faith that the promise has already been attained by the saints in the vision of God. If the Church’s great journey is given symbolic expres-
sion In a pilgrimage, the Church’s wayfaring is experienced on a smail scale as a
living
process,
and
not
merely
as
a sad
luum::yflnwlnmhthe?
mma&
eagaged. Obscutely pemeiwwg thiut perteet redemption is already at work within them, they can rejoice that the goal which in anticipation is already visibly ‘reached in the pilgrimage, is their own oal, though still to be attained, namely to bae wholly in and with Chtist.
See also Sacred Times and Places, BIBLIOGRAPHY.
Gretser,
religiosis peregrinationibus (1606);
De
saerir
P. Geyer, ed.,
Itinera FHlierosolymitana Sascwli fifi—vifii (CSEL, XXXIX, 1898); The Library of #the Palestine Pilgrimy Text Society, 12 vols. (1888-97); G. Schreiber, Wallfabrt und Volkrtum (1934); H. Leclercq,
“Pelerinage saints”,
4 Rome”,
in
F.
Dictionnaire
“Pélerinages
Cabrol
and
4'archiclogie
H.
chritienne
aux
Leclercq,
ef de
lieux eds,
litwrgie,
XTIV (1939), cols. 40-176; B. Kétting, Persgrinatio
Religiosa. Wallfabrien in der Antike und das Pilgerweren in der alten Kirche (1950); Reallexikon fir Antike und Chrittentum, 1 {1950) (Asclepius); R. Roussel, Ler Pélerinages d travers les siécles (1954); T.
Klauser,
Christlicher
Mdrtyrerksnit,
heidnischer
Heroenkult und spitisidisebe Heiligenvershrang (1960}; K. Nitzschke, Evangelisches Kirchenlexikon (2nd ed., 1962), col. 1729; H. Graef, Mary: A History of Doctrine and Devoiion, 2 vols. (1963, 1966); V. and H. Hell, Tke Grear Pilgrimages of the Middle Ages
(1966).
Ekkart Sanser
PLATONISM A. MEaNING
distance from the goal, fulfilment in God.
The meaning of Platonism depends on how
Christ
elements are considered essential and char-
Pilgrims zlso feel in this way that the goal, and
saints
who
the
are
saints,
comes
closer.
honoured,
specially
The
with
Christ at their head, strengthen faith in the
active presence of the Redeemer and the efficacious intercession of his saints with
him. The pilgrim congregation at the shrine is more intensely conscious of itself as a
community
united
to
the
Lord
and
the
Church triumphant. It has 2 better understanding of the redemption and of the
presence of Christ and his saints, realizing
that Christ and the saints do not stand aloof from the pilgrim Church on earth, but form
with
it a communion
the
work
acteristic.
of Plato
is assessed,
Till the beginning
and
which
of the
19th
century, Plato was considered above all for his contribution to ontology, natural theology and cosmology. This was the view
transmitted through the interpretation and continuation of Plato’s philosophy by his pupils Aristotle, Speusippus and Xenocrates, by Middle Platoaism (Plutarch, Albinus, Apuleius, etc.) and by neo-Platonism. The Timaens, which deals with cosmology (Latin
translation and commentary 4th-5th
century
A.p.)
was
by Chalcidius, probably
the
intercession and aid. In the unity thus experi-
dialogue which had the greatest influence down to the Middle Ages. The effort to
pilgrim
Platonist tradition began with Schleierma-
enced
28
between
group
“above”
of saints, and
offering
“below”,
the
also realizes that the saints
understand Plato independently of the neo-
'
PLATONISM
cher’s translation and commentary. The writer, artist and the philosophical significance of the dialogue form came to the fore.
constantly
at once
with
(Phasdo, 742-T5¢),
itself (Svrwg 8v)
Plato was scen as the setter of problems and dilemmas rather than as the constructor of systems. Stress was laid on his dialectic (Hegel), his epistemology (neo-Kantianism: Natorp), and his political and pedagogical theories. Recent research points to the
(témog Gpardc), in spite of the difference of
and medieval interpretations. It does not base itself solely on the dialogues, like
immutable
historical justification
of the neo-Platonist
Schleiermacher, but also on the lecture “On
the Good”, preserved only in the later writings of his disciples. The work had considerable influence on the traditiohs of the school. It is oot certain whether the work was first produced in Plato’s old age or whether the system here apparent was already at work behind all the dialogues. B. Basic THEMES
1. The form (idea). Plato’s starting-point was the ethical investigations of Socrates, whose
debate with the relativism of the Sophistic
Enlightenment was concerned with the establishment of an inviolable norm for moral action. Man cannot be good, just, brave and so on, unless he knows what is the
goodness,
mains
the
justice, courage,
same
in all
etc., which
situations.
re-
Hence
Socrates sought for definitions of the general concepts of ethics. According to Plato, the moral norm cannot be derived from experience. For no
particular good action is good from every respect. The good man 1s not necessarily
always good. The action is good and the man is good, but they are not the good. There is need of a spiritual vision which grasps the
good in its perfect and unchangeable “form”
(e180¢,18éa). Plato then transferred this doc-
trine from the ethical to all predicates. Their application to visible things, in the judgment, presupposes an z prier; knowledge ot them. In the proposition, “These two pieces of wood are the same size”, the concept of
2. Participation and analogy. If the vision of
the forms is to give us a true judgment of the things perceived through outward show,
the world of the forms {xéopog vanréc) can-
not be fully separated from the visible world
being, The thing participates in the form (wéOebig, participation). The being which is changeable manence
and necessary
is preseat in the
and contingent (mapovsie:
of the transcendent),
But
im-
it is a
being {obstx) which is realized only in an imperfect way in the visible thing. Since the form represents the good, all things “strive” to be like it; it is the archetype and goal (téhog) for whose sake they exist. The various
degrees
of participation
set up an
analogy between beings, which is illustrated by means of a line in which two unequal divistons are made.
The smaller reptresents
the realm of the visible, the larger that of the
intelligible. The sections are then divided again in the same proportions. The lower sections of the visible stand for shadows and
bodily things, those of the intelligible for mathemathical proportions and forms (Re-
public,
509d
— 511a).
The
meaning
of the
simile is that the visible and the intelligible are as different from each other (ywptowpdc) by virtue of their being as shadows and reflections are from real things. But just as the thing is reflected in the shadow, so too the intelligible appears in the visible (tébezeg).
The visible has only the being of a reflection,
but as an image, it points to the archetypal being. The shadows (or words) can lead to
sight of the things, the things to knowledge of mathematical laws vision of the forms.
and
these
to
the
The analogous participation brings about degrees of being, which the Symposium (210a - 212a) expounds with teference to the
beautiful, which is the only form which can
be grasped
in sensible as well as spiritual
equality cannot be derived from experience,
vision. The beauty of individual beings is a less perfect presence of the form of the
exist
This again is only a stage which leads to the beauty of morals and laws, which point in turn to that of the sciences and through them
since this only offers objects of approximate equality. But the presupposition of this knowledge of “equality itself” is that it has
an object.
Hence
ideal essences
must
‘apart from perceptible things. In contrast to the changing visible things which include a variety of aspects, the forms are unchangeable, simple and true reality, which remains
beautiful than the beauty of all bodily things.
to the unchangeable
ultimate beauty,
The
lecture “On the Good” illustrates by analof model the participation and ogy
the mathematical
sequence of the one (&)
29
"PLATONISM ’
|
of multiple positing of the one}—numbers —
lines — surfaces — bodies. The principles of
unity ahd duality are present'in all sub-
sequent “‘dimensions” and also transcend
them. So too the higher are contained in
. the following “dimensions”™.
3. Ascont and dialectic. 'The human soul posscsses an 2 priori knowledge of the
mathematical proportions and the forms, of
which it had vision in a pre-existence and which can be awakened through instruction and sensible perception (&véuwaig). Hence man can know the structure of being at the level of the forms. Plato distinguishes the method of mathematical knowledge (Siavera)
from that of eidetic (vénotg or émoethun or dialectic) (Republic, 510b — 511¢). The mathematician starts from
untested presupposi-
tions (Omobésets) from which he draws conclusions. He proceeds deductively, He
cannot reduce his axioms to some ultimate
principle. And he must also invoke the aid of sensible intuition. The dialectician exam-
ines the conclusions from his hypotheses to see if they are free from contradiction. If
they are not, he rejects the hypothesis and proposes another. Otherwise he looks for a higher hypothesis which is contained in the as
it~
presupposition
and
from
which the latter can be deduced as its con-
sequenice. The procedure is continued till a first principle (&pyh} is reached which has no
presuppositions and cannot be derived from anything else. This is the form of the good
{@yaltdv)
or the One. The dialectical ascent
takes place without the help of the visible.
From the form of the good the dialectician can then descend to the individual forms.
The good itself is beyond the forms (eménewva. tiic odolug, Republic, 509b). Fach
form
partakes
of the good
(just as in its
quality of ideal number it partakes of the One) and is ordained to the good as its end
or goal, as is particularly
clear from
the
forms in the ethical realm. Thus the relation of things to the forms as their exemplars and
goals has a parallel in the relation of the various forms to the good, the One, as the
Absolute.
The
seventh
epistle (341cd)
de-
scribes the knowledge of the highest beings in the language of later mysticism: through
long familiarity with the truth, a light is “suddenly” enkindled in the soul and this light then nourishes itself. The dialectical ascent is not s be separated 30
PR
.
.
i
and the dyad (Suds) (the latter as the principle |
previous
.
good in order to be himself good
edge
serves the ‘“assimilation to
GO
(buolwoong 7 663) which consists of man’s growing just and pious through insight
(Theastetns, 176b). The philosopher is to return from the vision of the good to political reality. The dialectic of the later dizlogues
( Phasdrys, Sophist, Statesman, Philebus) dis-
plays greater interest in logic. It is concerned with the division of concepts (Swxlpeoig),
their hierarchical arrangement and the possibility of uniting them in the judgment. Plato shows in the Sophist that there is nonbeing even in the realm of the forms. The identity of each form with itself implies a difference as regards the non-identical forms and hence that it ““is not” — they. 4. Soul, State, cosmos. Since the unchange-
able forms have no efficient causality, another principle is needed to co-ordinate the: world of becoming with that of being. This principle is the soul. It moves itself and the inert, and is therefore immortal rus, 245c—). Plato compares it
objects
of mathematics.
Like
(Phaedto the
them,
it is
between the form and the appearance. The
totality of beings is reflected in the soul as in the realm of mathematics. Hence it can know all beings. As Eros, the soul is the desire of ascending to the eternal essences and of rendering them visible in the world of becoming. Since it is a principle of movement it can bring about participation. The threetold division of the human soul expresses its intermediate position. The rational or spititual soul is endowed with thought, and its function includes that of guiding the other parts of the soul. Its immortality and its affinity with the forms is proved in the Phaedo. The lowest part is the instinctive passionate soul (gmupmtindv), while the
courageous {Supoedéc) is the bridge between
them. Plato’s myths of the other world atfirm the freedom and responsibility of man.
The Platonic State follows the siructure of the
soul.
There
are
three
corresponding
classes: the ruling class of the philosophers, the warriors and the providers. The analogy
of structure is based on the common end: both soul and State are to realize the good in
the visible order. Each part of the soul and
the State is ordained to a virtue: the first to
wisdom or prudence, the second to courage and the third to self-discipline. The cooperation of the parts leads to justice. The
\
PLAY
harmenious movement of the cosmos is ascribed to the world-soul. According
PLAY
(Smiuovpyds), who arranges the all according
the usual contrast between the playful and the serious, play is primarily thought of in
the myth of the created by the
Timaexs, this is d1rectl Maker of the Wurld
to the ideal pattern of the “perfect soul”, since he is good and without envy and wishes that all should be as like him as possible. Through the world-soul, divine
providence (mpévoix) makes
animated and rational living demiurge uses the rest of the which he made the world-soul immortal part of the human Aristotle and Xenocrates the been asked as to whether the teaches
Timacus
the world
an
thing. The matter from to make the soul. Since question has myth of the
thar the world
had a be-
ginning in time, or merely its dependence ona cause. But the debate is of secondary impostance compared to the central philosophical assertion that the visible world participates in the good. It is an image of the order of the forms and so has the good as its end and goal. The rational soul is the cause of this participation and finalitv. The order of the cosmos 1s knowable because the law of the cosmos 15 also the law of the human spint.
See
also
Neo-Platonism,
Analogy
of Being,
Good, Participation, Dialectic.
BIBLIOGRAPHY. souvrcrs: |. Burnet, Plasonis Opera, 5 vols. (1900-7); F. Ast, Lexicon Plate-
aicwm, 3 vols. (reprint, 1936); E. de Places, Lexigue
de la langse philosepbique ef religrense de Platon, 2 vols.
{1964). TEXTS AND TRANSLATIONS: Floeb Classical Library, 12 vois. (1921-33); B. Jowen, The Dia-
logues of Plaro, 4 vols. (4th revised ed. by ID. Allan
and
H.
Dale,
1953).
WORKS:
BIBLIOGRAPHICAL
T. G. Rosenmever, “Platonic Scholarship, 1945
1953, The Classical Weekdy 50 (1957), pp. 172-211;
H. F. Chermiss, ' Plaro Seudies, 1950 - 377, Lusiram 4 (1939, pp- 5-308; 5 (1960), pp. 323-048. WorKs:
GENERAL
and F. Praechrer,
F. Ueberweg
Grundriss der Geschichte der Phifosaphie, 1 (12th ed., 1926); A. E. Tavlor, Plafa: The Man and His [Varia of Plats (1930); (1926); G. C. Field, The Philosaphy
R. Klibansky, The Continuity of the Platonic Tradi-
tion during
the
Middle
Ages
(1939);
].
Stengel,
Plata’s Method of Dialecric (1940); M. Heidegger,
Febre ron der Wabrbes' (19477, W. Ross, Plates Theory of fdeas (1951); P. Merlan, From Plato to \e:capt“.-,:ram:m 933}, 31 Armstrong, ed.,
Flatons
The Cambridge Histary of Later Greek and Early Mediaeral Philosophy {1967} vaRIOUS DIALOGUES, E. T. AND CcoMmMENTaRIES: Fo M. Cornford, Theaesetus and Sophist (1933), Timaens (1937), Parmenides (1939}, Repubiic (1941); R. Hackforth, Philebus (1945), Phaedrus (1952); ]. B. Skemp,
Statesman (1952); R. 5. Bluck, Phaeds (1953}, E. R.
Dodds,
(1960).
Gorgias
(1939);
G.
R.
Morrow,
Laws
Friede Ricken
1. Introduction: Homo Iudens. In keeping with
connection
with
childhood,
of which
it is
thought to be the typical activity. Thus it is explained as excess of energy (H. Spencer), as rest after strain, or as practice and selfeducation for the serious matters of life (K. Groos), though subjectively stemming from the urge to activity and motivated by “delight in fuactioning™. E. Haigis, how-
ever, sees it a5 an encounter with the risks of
life in which the I becomes conscious of itScheut]l
H.
self, while
notes
it is con-
that
cerned less with a function than with the resulting form of movement (as with whipping-tops or the play-group). This definition
is influenced by the aesthetics of Schiller and thus goes beyond the usual contrast of the playful and the setious. The various types of
play {which can be classified from different be carried
can
viewpoints)
in various
on
frames of mind, from the “merely playful”
which is not “play” because not “‘serious”
enough, to an unbending tension which is no
ionger play and *‘ruins the game” because it takes it “‘too seriously”. Since it is so easily transformed
only
be
very
into
something
widely
else,
Its
defined.
play can
charac-
teristics, according to J. Huizinga, are its freedom — that it cannot be a *‘command performance” — its departure from ordinary,
“real” life, that is, from the direct effort 1o
supply one’s needs and desires, its setting up in consequence a sort of closed and limited universe (in space and time) and, throughout all, its orderliness {(“‘the rules”), in spite of the elements of chance and uncertainty. Thus play is the construction of a sort of “freefloating” form. But as such it is an action which is meaningful in itself, with a function
outside the utilitarian (so that it can have a
therapeutic value), not merely in the child (J.-]. Rousseau, W. Frobel, M. Montessori)
but in the realm of the specifically human. No doubt animals zlso play, especially in the “colt” stage between being dropped and reaching
maturity,
though
also
at
other
times, as in mating-play. But their “world” of play remains within their specific environment.
Thev
are, so to speak,
limits and “playing while still in 2 “‘fAuid” in human play is the and the freedom and
finding
their
out” their possibilities stage. What is essential constitution of a world openness which make
31
PLAY such an effort posgible: the world of play is
the play [“display”] of 4 wosld. 2.
Philesophical:
2
As
the world af play.
world at play, play appears along with work, language, love and other forms of the structure of the world. But it is not simply on the same level as these. The dimensions of human existence penetrate one another. Man
world
‘gam
shauM
really be uflderstm -
the playground
of superhuman
foroes a: destiny or luck. It is either “mere? play, from which one taust stand aloef and detached ot an emblem of bliss which can raise one above all distress, even the anxieties
of one’s own life.
At the present time, this notion of play has been stripped of all emotional content and is
characteristics which distinguish it from the other dimensions of existence. Hence it is
used in a purely formal sense. Apart from its usage in individual sciences (such as the sketch-plans of logic or economic theory) it is used to interpret the world and the existence of man in general, and not merely in such
mode of existence like the others; however,
philosophy (cf. the theme of the “language-
is 2 whole man not merely at play, but when
working,
fighting,
loving,
confessing
his
guilt and accepting his death. But play has
not a marginal phenomenon,
but a basic
it still remains in 2 strange contrast to them. We can “play” at being serious, authentic, working, fighting, that is, we can transform the actions in which man expresses his concern for himself (as an “anxious being’’) into the unquestioning detachment of an action which has no set purpose but still remains rational. Man at play along with others takes with him into this free-floating universe his partners {and to some extent the spectators) and also the world of things along with his “playthings” (which need be
no more than his own body).
When things become playthings and partners playmates, they have been transformed, rmt through a (sick[y) confusion between “appearance” and reality but through a knowledge which is agam “poised”’, not
fixed, of their two meanings, each validin its own way: the world of play is a symbolic
world. Here, therefore, one must pay careful
attention to the power and reality and zlso
the ambiguity of the symbol. It must not be
whittled away to a “mere symbol” in contrast to ““reality”’, but neither should its value be
aesthetically exaggerated into an absolute. This consideration leads to the conclusion that the player “plays with something that
fields
as
those
of art,
mathematics
and
game” in the later Wittgenstein). It then becomes a “‘game without player” (E. Fink), since all questions about the player are rejected — either man or God or luck — since there is nothing outside the totality considered. (It is not yet clear in what sense the later Heidegger assigns a source [a “whence”] to the “happening” of the play of mirrors between the heavenly, earthly, divine and human;
see D.
Sinn in Philoso-
phische Rundschaw 14 [1967], pp. B1-182). Such formal thinking may be contrasted with the existentie/ and concrete concepts of a theology of play.
3. Theological: racred piay. Play, especially in
its purest form, that of the dance, is one of
the primary phenomena of the history of religions {van der Leeuw). Here it functions as responsible participation in the foundation and conservation of the world (its order, fertility, etc.), as a re-enactment in praise and
thanksgiving of the “cosmic” order and as a prayerful and efficacious component
in an
anticipation of its pure and final fulfilment. The main work of collecting patristic texts
unpre-
on this theme has been done by H. Rahner. Here it appears that man joins in God’s play by taking part in the dance of the cosmic liturgy, in the seriousness and gaiety of
they must be if play is not to lose its “charm” and very nature. The world of play as a2 whole 15 more than the production of the player. It
ness” (Plato, Laws, VII, 803 be). According
plays with him” (Buytendijk). It is not only playthings
and
playmates
that are
dictable (within the rules laid down) — as
abandonment in humility, knowing that his own life is at stake, but trusting in him “who alone is worth taking seriously in all glad-
also holds 4z spell-bound — above all, when
to the allegorical interpretation of Gen 26: 8,
which
in this way before the “King™, as an image
he joins others at play. From this it is only a shott step to an idea
Socratic
is not
confined
thought
(cf.
to Indian
Heraclitus,
or pre-
frg.
52)
and which is also propounded in many forms in myth and ritual: that even the “real” 32
the Fathers find that in man himself “Laughter”” (Isaac) and “Patience” (Rebecca) play of
“Wisdom”,
the
first-fruit
of
which according to Prov 8:27-31 before God in the beginning,
creation,
played
PLURALISM
It is thus that the Church can see itself not only as militant or on pilgrimage, but also as /udens: “‘playing before him” in its liturgy
social ethics, the Catholic approach,
angels and ‘the blessed, where the Logos
individuality. The principles arising from
as the pre-lude to the heavenly dance of the
himself is the “leader of the dance™ (Hippolytus), and, most profoundly, the triune God himself. For the circum-insessio of his processiones is not static, but both in himself and as “all in all”’, “the love that moves the
sun and the other stars” (Dante), See also Ared, Aesthetics,
World,
gwage, Charity 1, Symbol. BIBLIOGRAPHY.
F.
von
Work, Lan-
Schiller,
On
the
Aesthetic Education of Mar (from the German) (1795); J. Buyrendizk, Wesen und Sinn des Spicles (1933); R. Guardini, The Church and thr Catholic (1940); id., The Spirit of the Liturgy (1940); V. AxeR. Hartley and others,
line, Play Therapy (1947);
Understanding Children's Play {1952); ). Huizinga,
Homo Ludens: < Study of tbe Play Element in Culture (1955);
M.
Vortrdge
Heidegger,
und
Aufidtze
Denken™ and **Das
(especially “Bauen, Wohnen,
Ding”, cf. “What is a Thing?”" [1966]) (2nd ed.,
1939); A. Sapora and H. Mitchell, Theory of Play
and Recreation (3td
Play
and
Guamer
ed.,
(1961);
1961):
Sacred and Profane Beauty:
). Pieper,
G.
R. Caillois,
van
der
Man,
Leeuw,
The Holy in Art (1963);
Theory of
In Tune with the World: A
Festivsty (1965); H. Rahner, Man ar Play (1967).
Jorg Spleit
PLURALISM
society displays a high degree of heterogeneity in comparison with a society regarded
as homogeneous. Sometimes the term is used unfavourably, to signify disintegration in comparison with a society regarded as
integrated. It can also be used to contrast the immanent dvnamism of modern society with Instead
of “pluralist”,
it would
be pre-
ferable to speak of the “"plural” society when registering existing structures. Pluralism
would then be a positive assessment, the programme of a society conceived of in this way. It would be contrasted with integralism, the tendency to overcome plural structures. Historically, the theory of pluralism can be referred to sources as diverse as liberalism and Christian social teaching. But whereas the pluralist notions of liberalism were
strongly
individualistic,
its emphasis on the person and subsidiarity, was towards a pluralism which saw that the
social nature of man was as essential as his such pluralism guarantee not only individual rights but the equal riphts of the various societies against trespass. Social pluralism appears mainly under the following aspects.
1. Group pluralism. In the strict sense, this
15 the division of society into numerous groups with varying interests, each of which
considers itself equal to the others. In a wider sense it is a non-systematic and
dynamic organization and associations with A society with such represented by a series as if 1t were built up
of society in groups goals chosen at will, structures cannot be of concentric circles into a whole by the
integration of each unit into a larger one.
Group pluralism should be rather represented by a number of intersecting circles, arranged unsystematically and mobile in
character.
And
overlapping
occurs
within
the individual himself. He belongs simultancously to various social units, with no intermediate unit to provide continuity. Nonetheless, this is where pluralism reveals its ambivalence,
for
the
plural
structure
is
constantly being reinforced by intermediate
formations.
2. Value pluralism. This aspect reflects the
Pluralism is a term now used to characterize madern society in various ways. The pluralist
motre static societies.
with
to the
neglect
of
absence or the weakening of a homogeneous
system of norms and values. The system of norms extends from absolute values accepted as universally valid to moral norms and then conventional views of behaviour. But de-
peading on the width of the field of observation,
a
certain
multiplicity
of
wvalues
and
norms has always existed, specifically attached to
various
regions
or
strata.
Hence
what
strictly characterizes a value pluralism is that society as a whole is confronted with it. The apenness and mobility of society are responsible for the fact that the development of social forms is no longer characterized by the spread of a homogeneous system of norms but by the competing offers of several
possible ways of life. On pluralism of world views
( Weltanschaunngen)
see World (Views
of }, Ideolngy; see also Religion 1 A, Philosaphy, Thealagy 1.
3. Partial social integration.
in the plural society
The tendency
is for the individual
to
33
POLITICAL THEQLOGY
be integrated only partially into any given social group. This means that no group can claim him totally. But then-again thete is no group which will help him to bear his social burdens as a whole.
4. With the partial social integration and
the division of functions in modern society
there is an increasing differentiation of roles. The various
social interactions no longer
involve the whole person. The individual
IflfiP@flHH1HHWy;:nflu¢ orienttate its pedagdgy living of such stroctures to the sac Liberal democracy is the political a anin zation propex to such a social structure. Th:s is the only form which allows group life to develop
freely.
But
pluralism
presents
a
political problem, since public policy must
take the common good 35 its norm. Hence
democracy must be prepared to wotk for
civic integration,
because
a pluralism
of
There is no such thing as a purely monistic
opinions and interests, even when institutionalized, does not suggest political decisiops orientated to the total needs of society. Nonetheless, since pluralism is a partial social integration, it provides a norm or orientation for politics, since it insists on proof being shown that a given policy is
can evoke contraty trends and defensive reactions. And the assessment of these phenomena as normative in anthropology
regulated by the government. Pluralism helps men to see that the common good is a social goal and not merely a political objective and cannot therefore be attained by
plays various roles as father, as worker, as member
of a Church,
as citizen, etc. The
change of roles .can occur frequently and at short intervals.
This is all 2 matter of dominant trends,
ot putely pluralist society. Further, the trends are only relatively compulsive. They
really of universal interest, and should be
is also debatable. But there seems to be general agreement that justice is not done
merely political means.
from the point of view of loss of unity, either
Integralism, Politics
or above all of decay of culture. As always,
BIBLIOGRAPHY. H. A. Myers, Syrtepatic Pluralism (1961); W. Walter, Die sogialethische Definition der Demokratie (1962); K. Rahner,
to the social situation by envisaging it solely in society or individual, or of disintegration it is a matter of dangers and opportuntties.
At first sight pluralism of groups and values
seems to increase the number of possible social conflicts. But partial integration and differentiation of roles also function in favour of peace, since the conflicts are then only
partial, which must already be regarded as an element of the elimination of conflict. This is apparent, for instance, when a two-tiered class society (*‘dualistic™) is followed by 2 plural group-society.
The dangers, for instance, of fragmentary adaptation, which can react on the person,
See
also
Society
1,
Social
Movements
1V,
Schriften gur Theologie,VI (1965), pp. 46-58 (on dialogue in a pluralist society); M. Banton,
Raoles: An Introduction to the Study of Social Relations (1965); M. Hattich, “Das Toleranzproblem in der Demokratie”,
Civitas
4
(1965);
id.,
National-
bewussirein und Staatshewusstsein in der pluralistischen Geselischaft (1966); R. A. Dahl, Pluralist Democ-
racy in the United States (1967); ]. P. Schaver and H. Berlak, Controversy in a Pluralistic Society (1967); K.
Bosl,
(1967).
Pluralismus und pluralistische Gesellschaft
Manfred Hittich
should not obscure the increased sense of
responsibility which results from this structure of society, both in the individual and the groups, with regard to their own way of life. The integralist patterns of society develop
social structures on the basis of one single principle and hence neglect the real differ-
POLITICAL
THEOLOGY
The term “‘political theology™ is used in present-day theology in the context of a
definite
set of problems
and
ideas.
This
ences in human life. While the pluralist principle keeps the relationship between individ-
context must be taken into account, because
for all in favour of collective elements. Since
the latter tendency can appeal toa certain need
actual term comes from Stoicism which divided theology into three parts, mythical, natural and political {ct. Varro in St. Augus-
to provide opportunities
political theology took precedence over natural theology (in contrast to the Hellen-
uality and social obligations in the balance, integralism tries to solve the problem once and in man of total integration, a society which is resolved to mainrain its pluralist structure,
34
for freedom
and
the term could be ambiguous and misleading, as well as being historically “loaded”. The
tine,
De
Civitate
Dei,
VI,
5).
In
Rome,
POLITICAL THEOLOGY
istic tradition). Here it was used to justify
theologically the primacy of politics and the “absalute” claims of the State. This political
Human society is seen primarily as an essential medium for the discovery of theological truth and for Christian preaching in general.
1. This notion of political theology was in
2. In this sense, political theology is not primarily a new theological discipline among others, with a regional task of its own. And it is not simply a sort of “applied theology” — theology applied to politics and human society. It cannot then be simply identified with what is called in theology *“political ethics” or with what was aimed at by the laudable movements of a social theology or the “Social Gospel”. Political theology
theology of Rome was revived in the Renaissance. It was championed by such writers as Machiavelli and Hobbes, and by the French traditionalists of the 19th century with their notion of restoring the “Christian State™.
force until Romanticism,
when
social con-
ditions forced it to take on a restorative and Integralist tinge or voluntarist traits. But in present-day theology, when dealing with the hermeneutics
of basic problems,
it has
the two following aspects. a) Political theology is a critical corrective
of a certain tendency to confine theology to
the realm of the private and personal, as in its transcendental, existential and personalist forms.
is 2 tendency
There
to reduce
the
heart of the Christian message and the practical exercise of faith to the decision of the individual standing apart from the world — a reaction to the separation between religion and society as suggested by the Enlightenment. Here political theology intervenes, not in the sense of a spontaneous, pre-critical identification of religion and society, but as a new deliberate effort to
define the relationship.
In this eflort at critical correction, political
theology aims at “nationalization” — taking
theological concepts, and the language of preaching and spirituality out of the private realm. It tries to overcome the exaggerated of
csotericism
discourse
about
stubborn opposition between itual
life
and
social
God,
the
private spir-
freedom,
which
1s
claims
to be a basic element
structure
of critical
in the whole
theological
thinking,
motivated by a new notion of the relation between theory and practice, according to
which all theology must be of itself “practical”,
orientated
to action.
Only
when
this
fundamental interest of political theology is ignored can it be mistaken for a theology dabbling
in politics,
ie., in direct contact
with socio-political public life, which would be wrong. It is in fact one of the aims of political theology and its society-directed thinking to prevent the Church and theology
being saddled as it were unwittingly with this or that political ideology.
3. This political theology sees everything in the light of the eschatological message of
Jesus.
But
provided
it tzkes
the
new
standpoint
by the critical reason, for which
the way was paved by the Enlightenment
and which was given articulate expression at least since the middle of the 19th century, since Hegel and Marx. In the wake of the
purely ldealist and then the personalist and
obviously widening the universal gap berween what theology and preaching puts forward as peremptory and what the Christian in fact lives by and surrenders to. b) Political theology is now also the effort to formulate the eschatological message of Christianity in the conditions of present-day
obscured in the eyes of theclogians. The distinctive feature of the new starting-point is the fundamental relation between reason and soclety, the society-directed character of critical reflection, the compulsion felt by
structure in public life. In other words, it 15 an effort to overcome z purely “passive”
light of society and the impossibility of the critical reason’s justifying its claims “‘on the
of present-day society. Society 18 not regarded as a secondary object of Christian
problem
claim to be heard in public on the loeal, national and international level — 2 claim
“hermeneutic problem”
primarily
coloured by the desire for political power.
and history. It is rather the problem of the
society, taking into account the changes of hermeneutic
of Christianity
in the context
activity. And it is not a matter of the Christian which
seems
always
to
be
more
or
less
existentialist
tradirions,
the
wvalue
of
this
approach had long been underestimated or
the critical reason to consider itself in the level of pure reasoning”. Thus the classical of the relation between
faith and
teason appeats once more in political theology on this new plane. And the basic
and
the
historical
relation
of theology is not
between
theology,
systematic
between
dogma
35
POLITICAL THEOLOGY
understandmg
of faith and
Sociflty.. cerod
practice.
Ay The mew theory-practice relationship, theologically. In the context of new developments
in Protestant theology after Bultmann, especially in J. Moltmann and W. Pannenberg,
political theology stresses the basic nature
of eschatology and brings the eschatological message of the kingdom of God into the foreground of theological thinking in 2 new
way. It thus tries to do justice to the close and
intrinsic
link between
God
and
the
coming reign of God in the NT tradition. The futurity of this loedship of God is an intrinsic and permanent element of theological assertion about the Godhead of God. The category “future” and the societydirected category of “kingdom”
and reign
of God become fundamental in all theologi-
cal reflection. For if the promised “new wotld” corresponds to the Godhead of God, the truth of God’s Godhead cannot in any
way be adequately conceived under the con-
- ditions of the present. The world as it exists
at any given moment cannot be a sufficient
basis for the understanding of this truth. Only a change of the present age and of the
Idealism and: jts successots ji petsoualisi and ‘existentialism. But the tradit
Hegelian Left with its characteristic skete:hu
plans of the philesophy of history was more
or less lost sight of. Political theelogy also takes up the discussion with the critique of teligion based on this philosophy, where it appeared as critique of ideologies. Religion was there seen as a derivative function of certain social practices and power groups. The notion of “false conscience” was used to explain the religious believer in terms of a society as yet unaware of its nature.
b) Public affairs, theologically. Taking into
consideration the world situation which has felt the impact of the Enlightenment and secularization, political theology tries to
study afresh the relationship to public life and human soctety which is implicit in the NT message of salvation, forgiveness and reconciliation. Tt insists that the trial is on,
on a capital charge, between the eschatological message of the kingdom of God and any given form of social and political life, in its various historical changes. It does not deny the legitimate individual relationship to God
(as an element of the NT in contrast to OT
conditions which make its insights possible
tradition),
Godhead of God. A theology which takes seriously the eschatological nature of its
freedom,
can give access to the future truth of the “object”
is
condition
necessarily
orientated,
of possibility
transcendentally,
self-understanding
to an
of thought,
which
articulation
as
a
i.e,
of its
will be directed
to action (J. Habermas). This is the perspective in which political theology regards the new theory-practice
relationship as propounded in the dialectical
philosophies of history (with the history of revolutions
in mind)
especially since Hegel,
in the and
19th
century,
in the tradition
of the Hegelian Left. It does not see it as a poor version of Christian eschatology in
popular terms, as the degradation eschatology
into blue-prints
of this
of a self-con-
tained world history and social utopias. It sees It as a token that the eschatological sense of crisis here becomes part of historical (world)
consciousness
(cf.
J.
Habermas),
Thus political theology undertakes to con-
front critically a philosophical tradition which was too little considered in modern
theology. Recent systematic theology (and Catholic theology chiefly where it broke out of the neo-Scholastic system) debated the transcendental philosophy of Kant, German
36
but
it affirms
peace,
justice,
that
the
central
promises of the reign of God in the NT — reconciliation
—
cannot be made radically private affairs. They
cannot be entirely interiorized and spiritual-
ized as corresponding to the individual’s longing for freedom and peace. They make
the individual free with regard to the political soclety around him, in the sense of commit-
ting him to it in a free critique of it. The view of the society-directed, “public” character of the Gospel promises can be distorted in tw0 main ways. (1) The first mistake is to follow the type
of political theology which was worked out in early Christian tradition under the influence of the metaphysics of the State in
Rome. It becomes 2 “political Christology”
(H. Schmidt) or a “political monotheism” (E. Pedersen), in which a dangerous fallacy
turns the kingdom of God into a political entity. This meant, in the Constantinian age,
that political theology
couid
be the direct
successor of the religious ideology of the State in ancient Rome. This way of giving
the Christian message a political bearing has
had a detrimental effect up to the present day, distorting the fundamental societydirectedness of the NT message and barring the way to an unambiguous use of the term
POLITICAL THEOLOGY
“politieal theology”. Indirectly too this line of tradition had questionable effects. Particularly since Augustine, thete was an understandable critical reaction to this ideological
degradation of Christian eschatology. The content of the promises was unduly inter-
torized, spiritualized and individualized. (i) There is another misapprehension which hinders a proper grasp of the “public” natute of the eschatological message. Its critically negative function — negativity which is a liberation — is commonly overlooked. When the public element of the message is emphasized, the spectre of a Christian or ecclesiastical neo-integralism is conjured up, as if political theology sought to undermine a secularized and religiously emancipated society and infilrrate it with “restorative’’ tendencies. But in fact political
theology tries to take this “secularized” world seriously, as the starting-point of theology and preaching. This does not mean “emancipating it” unconditionally by eliminating the social bearings of the eschatologi-
cal message, as in many modern theological
theories of secularization. It means that it
asserts its essentially universal categories “only” as a negative critique in this society.
Being 2 particular element in society, Chris-
tianity can only formulate the decisiveness (““absoluteness’’) and universality of its message without falling into an ideology when it formulates it as critical negation (of and in given situations).
This shows that when political theology brings out the public pature of the Christian
message, it does not relapse into a direct challenge to the socio-political world. There
are two reasons. One is that Christianity and its message cannot be simply identified with a given political institution {in the narrow sense). For there is no political party which
can be merely such a critique. And no political party can take as its platform — without
falling
in
the
totalitarianism
end
—
into
that
Romanticism
which
or
forms
the
*whole
of
horizon of the critical stipulation of Christianity: the totality of history as reserved
eschatologically
to God.
(The
history under the eschatological reserve of God” sums up the negative critique. There
is nothing intramundane which can be identified as the motive force of all history, so that it could take the coming of all histnry as the programme of its polirical action). On the other hand, the “negative conscience”, the critical attitude to society in which the
public claim of the gospel makes itself heard,
must
not
be
underestimated.
Its critical
contestation of socio-political conditions is a “determinate negation”. It flares up in criticism of very definite conditions. Being a critical artitude to society, it may well take the form, under certain conditions, of revo-
lutionary protest. This negative voicing of the gospel is not the void and vagueness of the “purely negative”. It has within it a powerful force for the positive. New possibilities are opened up in and through this critical negation, though only by going right through and out of it (a strictly dialectical process). It gives contour to the formal figure of Christian hope, inasmuch as the promised fulfilment in the resurrection of Jesus Christ can only
be attained through the *death-dealing” negation of the existing world, such as is expressed in the message of the crucifixion of Jesus.
The other reason why political theology
to society is that
1s not a direct challenge
problems of political rule can never be strictly reduced to the single dimension of technological rationalization {cf. H. Marcuse). The political decision itself — above and beyond all technological planning — remains orientated to debatable goals. The process of rationalization undertaken by political
has
itself always
action
a certain
horizon of utopian interests. This may be denied by the pragmatism that takes decisions
in the dark, but the horizon cannot be eliminated and must be answered for (“dia-
lectically™). H this is regarded as the site of the theoretical decisions of Christianity’s
critique of human society, its utterance cannot
be open
to the
suspicion
a
of being
ditect and therefore misplaced challenge to the social and political realm. 4, Political theology
as described
above
could also be termed “‘dialectical theology™,
in view of its methodology and the historical problems which form its context. But it 1s not a dialectical theology in the sense of the early Barth, where it indicates that the God-
man relationship is a paradox which cannot be
resolved
(and
hence
too
works
non-
historically). It is dialectical theology in the sense of a historical communication of the biblical
message,
in which
communication
of the message attests its transcendence in a critical, liberating “over-riding” of existing conditions, 37
5. Political theology can and wnust also
propound the. central truths of theology in the light of its statement of the relation be-
tween faith and society-directed teason. It displays the Christian faith in the form of freedom to be critical of society, and the
Church as the homeland of this freedom to which the Christian knows that he is called in face of the eschatological message.
a) Faith, bope and Jove as the form of freedom
fo criticize society. “Dogmatic faith” appears
here as acceptance of doctrinal propositions in which 2 perilous past is remembered and revived,
which
means
that
the
claim
of
promises held out and hopes experienced are
BIBLIOGRAPHY. HistoRY OF TBE THRM: G Schmitt, Politisché Theologie (20od ed., 1934); E. Peterson, “Der Mbnotheismusals politisches
. Problem®, Thealogische Trakiate (1951), pp.
147; H. Schmidt, “Politics and Christology: the
Historical Background”, Concilium6, no. 4 (1968),
pp. 39—45. PRILOSOPRY AND THEOLOGY: H. Marcuse, One-Dimensional Man (1964); H. Cox, Tht Secular City (1965); J. Moltmann, The Theologyof
Hope (1967); W. Pannenberg; Grundfragen systematischer Theologie (1967); ]J. B. Metz, “The Church’s
Social Function in the Light of ‘Pelitical Theo-
logy’*”’, Concilium 6, no. 4 (1968), pp. 3—11; sec also the essays in nos. 5 and 6 of this volume (on faith and the socio-political reality); ]. Habermas, Erkenntnis und Interesse (1968); ]. B. Metz, Theoiogy
¢
of the World (1969).
Jobann Baptist Meiz,
called to mind to break the spell of the predominant mentality — and its “repressions” — by a critical thrust. Hope appeats
as the protective criticism which liberates the individual so that he can definitely reject any totalitarian view of history and society. For in the foresight of hope, the totality of history is reserved to the eschatological action of God. Love is not merely an interpersonal happening. It is a social matter, being the unconditional and selfless resolve to work for freedom and justice for others. This could be the point of insertion for theological discussion of revolution.
b) The Church as the place and institution for socio~critical freedom. 'This tentative definition of the Church is not an adequate dogmatic
definition of its essence. But the Church in
action (in preaching, worshipping and sacraments) and in its central task of reconciliation and forgiveness may take the direction of social criticism. This description of the Church implies above all 2 new hermeneutic of the Church in society. This will explain
the role of tradition and institution in the
post-histoire
society;
how
the
ecclesiastical
institution, conscious of its own provisional
status, does not repress critical freedom but makes it possible, this being the formal contour
of
the
“servant
Church”:;
how
criticism 1s part of the public life of the
Church; how partial identification with the institution is to be positively treasured; how rights and freedom in the Church are not merely constitutionai problems but elements
of the process of attaining knowledge in the Church’s theology; and so on.
See also Politics, Enlightenment,
Theory and
Practice, Reign of God, ldealogy, Secularigation, Society TV, 38
45~
POLITICS 1. Definition. In the broadest sense, a policy is a calculated, purposeful line of action. But since there can be policies in every field of life, this does not give any specific notion to attach to politics. This is also true if politics is defined as the activity of the *“powers that be” or as activity directed by the desire for power. To escape the difficulties involved in distinguishing specifically political activity from other social fields of action, it is sometimes attributed to the social entity. A social
entity is considered as a subject which deploys itself in face of other social entities. One
speaks of the politics of the State, but also of
an enterprise, an association or of the Church.
But this notion of politics is again too wide.
If the concept is restricted to the politics of the State, the definition will depend on that
of the State. The specifically political element comes more clearly to the fore if that means
governmental actton and action in the State
designed to influence the government. In contrast to these dehnitions which prescind
from
values,
efforts are made
to
define political action as an activity orientated to
certain
instance,
norms.
Politics
as the realization
is defined,
for
of the common
good. The classical tradition of political theory always sought to understand politics with the help of cthical categories. An un-
critical acceptance of the political theory of Aristotle seems to be hardly possible in the conditions of modern
society. At any rate,
in the perspectives ofa liberal society, it would
be an undue restriction of the norm if the attainment of the common good were linked
exclusively to the phenomenon of the State.
-t
4
EEN -
POLITICS
POLITICS
Since we can no longer identify State and
soclety as in the (Greek) city-state { polis}, the political realization of the commor good presents itself as a special case of the general norm of the common good. The specifically political is not the common good as such, but
the particular mode of its realization.
Another approach is to take politics as a certain aggregate of social existence. Social
relations would then crystallize under certain
coaditions to political relations. This is the
concept
underlying
the defnition
of the
political as a friend-and-foe relationship. This political theory is now rightly rejected, but one should not forget it contains elements which go to determine political practice. The stress on the friend-and-foe relationship points to a certain stage of integration
of
societies in which the strictly political can be seen. The possibility of enmity reflects the highly integrated existence of the social
body
in
question.
other
aside
Leaving
society political rule is one of the most important factors in order. The order of society, insofar as it is produced by political rule, can be called political order. Political activity is then action related to this order. be
2. The concerns of politics. Three aspects may which
distinguished,
are
in
practice
combined, but which represent specific objects. a) Politics concerned with order is interested above all in the necessity of authoritative regulations for human life in society, Politics always includes the authoritative imposition of rules of order and their implementation. b) Politics concerned with welfare is orientated to the satisfaction of economic needs, which must be assured by the positive material achievements of political rule. c) Politics also appears as concerned with certain interests. It is an activity carried
on between groups, each of which seeks to
have its interests recognized and catered for
limited.
by the others. The combination is obvious when the three aspects are formally considered. Rules of order are elements of welfare and always
of politics from the modern concepr of the
of orderareatleastto some extent conditioned
objections, this makes it clear that the defini-
tion in guestion is orientated to the modern national State and hence is historically too Basically, the derivation of the definition since such
State is problematic,
definitions
constantly presuppose the existence of a “political society”, the maintenance of which is then the primary constituent of politics. This function is then appealed to to justify the necessity of rule. But in reality, political rule is not just 2 consequence of the existence of societies. Often enough it is a decisive
factor in their origin. Political structures are as much
of political
consequences
rule as
their causes. Even the political integration through which the structure is maintained is to some extent produced by the sovereign power. It may be affirmed that political rule
have an impact on group interests. Notions
by vested interests, ot they become group interests by having
notions.
Welfare
to compete
with rival
politics is penetrated by
group interests and sees itself as confronting such interests. Since it intervenes to shape social life, it also affects the de facto order. This is also true of the politics of interests,
whose connection with the general welfare is evident.
These three aspects can be verified in the
regions under political rule and the subject-
matters of politics. They can be used to analyse political procedures on all territorial levels. Here the units in each case themselves
in
turn
groups
upholding
is a universal phenomenon of society and that political societies are to a great extent a
become
Since the definition of the State in general presents no small difficulties, it 1s well to start with the general fact of authority or
aspects regularly appear combined.
consequence of this phenomenon of rule.
rule. Political rule is distinguished trom other rule by the universality of its character. It s universal.
materially
personally
and
historically
variable
social realm to which
The
such rule extends is
but
the
phenomenon
itself is always met with. If one prescinds from historically condirioned goals, one can affirm in general that political rule has the function of maintaining order. In every
their
interests against units on the same or a higher level. In traditional interior politics the three
Where
the structure is federal or where there is local communal authority, the same applies to the provinces or other divisions, The politics
of the national State has also determined the difference between home and foreign aftairs. Foreign affairs have been primarily politics concerned with the interests of the naticnal State. The notion that foreign policy takes
precedence reveals how restricted the actual activity of polirics has become.
Social welfare can no longer be catered for 39
on the national level slone. International
affaits’ are in great need of sorre positive inciple .of order in wotld politics, where
with democratic pflnflplas, But if thielmmts
tion have given tise to groups of interests on
to be ass.ured,_ there must be a pluralist
a]]mnr:cs, blocks and the general social situa-
a scale wider than the npational. Fot this
reason, the subject-matter of politics (constitutions, laws, social conditions, economics,
finance, cultute, armaments) can no longer be regarded asinternal politics. These are matters
which must be dealt with on all regional levels, like the demarcation of the regions where political action applies.
3. Political norms. The centtal problem is the legitimacy of political rule and its reguiations. De facto rule is not fpss facto legitimate. Nonetheless, not all the regulations of an illegitimate governmentlack legitimacy, since they can derive their legality from indispensable necessities (e.g., traffic laws or the struggle against crime). And on the other hand, since the legitimacy of 2 government
laid down by the nosm for pelitical rule are
structure of rule, so that transgression of the
limits by 20y one organ of government may
be hindered of penalized by the decisions of another.
See also Society 1, 111, State, Law 11, Pluralism. BIBLIOGRAPHY.
D.
Easton,
The
Political
Jystem: An Inguiry into the Siate of Political Scicnce (1953); L. Freund. Pofitik sl 1450 (1033 E. Welil, Philosophie politigns (1956}, G. Burdeau,
Miéthods de la scignce politigne (1959); F. Hermens,
Introduction to Modern Politics (1959); M. Cowling, The Nature and Limits of Political Science (1963);
M. Durverger, The Idea of Politics (1966); M. Hit-
tich, Lebrbuch der Politikwissenschaft, 1: Grandlegung wnd Systematik (1967); H. Kuhn, Der Staat: Eins philssophirche Darstellung (1967). Manfred Histich
does not at once establish the legality of all its regulations, a distinction must be made
between the legitimacy of a government and
the legality of its actions. Further, the de facto process of legitimation must be distinguished from legitimacy as a norm higher than positive law. Without entering into the controversy about the knowability of supra-positive norms, the
POPE 1. Theological: A. Definition. B. Biblical Foundations. C. Historical Development. 11. History of the Popes: A. The Roman Empire. B. The Early
the legitimacy of a government is a matter
Middle Apes. C. The Predominance of the Popes in the Middle Ages. D. Late Middle Ages and Renzissance. E. Catholic Reform and Counter-Reformation. F. From the Peace of Westphalia (1648) to the French Revolutivn. G. The Papacy in the
it is not necessary that all should vote for the government, but all must consent to the
I. Theological
fact that only agreement on their existence
works shows that there must be such a set
of norms for every society. The question of of its installation, In a free democratic order,
procedures by which the government comes
to power. This legitimation confers legality on many of the political decisions. But it is
not sufficient, since even a legitimate government may offend against positive and supra-
positive norms. To register such trespasses,
there must be a consensus which goes beyond
the formalities of appointing a government
and of legislative procedures to envisage the
cthical
quality
of political
means that human
decisions.
This
rights and basic rights
must be listed in modern constitutions. One
of their main objects is to mark the limits within which anything can be regulated
politically, i.e., in a universally binding way. Without such norms all types of rule, from one-man dictatorship to majority rule, become the rule of the arbitrary. Hence the 40
19th Century. H. The Papacy in the 20th Century.
A. DEFINITION
The Pope is the vicar of Jesus Christ, the
successor of the Apostle Peter, the head of
the Catholic Church and also Bishop of Rome, Patriarch of the West, Primate of ltaly,
Archbishop and Metropolitan of the eccle-
siastical province of Italy, Sovereign of the
Vatican City (cf. _Annuwario Pontificie). In ancient times, the title “Pope” (“Father”) was given to bishops. It was widely used in
monastic
circles
Catholic
Church.
and
became
the ordinary
title of a priest in the Orthodox Churches, as also in the Romanic parts of the Roman In
Egypt,
it
was
the
prerogative of the Bishop of Alexandria. From the middle of the 6th century on, the title came to be restricted in the West to the
POPE
Bishop of Rome. This usage was juridically
and in conjunction with the rest of the apos-
established by Gregory VII.
tles, and indeed, with the Church as a whole.
B. BisLicaL FOUNDATIONS
further defined by Jesus as the power of the keys and the power to bind and loose. In the
The function of the rock foundation is
The papacy can only be understood in the
tramework of the Church as a whole and in connection with the hierarchical structure of the Church. The Church cannot be properly understood either as a papal or a5 an episcopal Church. But it does not exist except with the Pope as the visible representative of Christ, the invisible head of the Church. According to Catholic faith, the papacy grew out of the mission of the apostle Peter, who, according to reliable testimonies (not, however, universally accepted), ended his life tn Rome.
In the N'T, Peter appears as the first of the
apostles in rank. The gospels show him as
their spokesman (Mk 58:29; Mt 18:21; Lk 12:41; Jn 6:67£.). In the lists of the apostles
given in the synoptics he is always named frst (Mk 3:16-19; Mt 10:1-4; Lk 6:12-16; cf. Acts 1:13; Mk 1:26; Lk 9:32; Mt 16:7).
A most important point is that, in what 1s obviously a traditional formula, Peter is named by Paul as the first to whom the risen
Christ appeared, though chronologically he
house where Jesus is the householder, Peter 18 given authority to rule as representative df the master. The formula also includes authority to teach and to impose doctrine. The
metaphor of binding and loosing means to
exclude from the community and to re-admit,
also to impose an obligation and to release
from it, finally, to declare something lawful or prohibited. This triple function is also assigned by Jesus to the other apostles (Mt 18:18), but it is clearly Peter’s in a special way which is his alone. The Gospel of Matthew does not explain what the primacy of Peter
consists of. But the two-fold conferring of
authority does not make sense unless a single function is meant, though shared at various
levels.
According
to
Lk 22:27-32,
a
quartel
among the disciples inspired by ambition and desire for power gave Jesus the occasion
of proclaiming the law of the kingdom of
God,
readiness
to serve the brethren.
And
here Jesus gave a special task to Peter, promising him his prayer to enable him to
was not the first (1 Cor 15:5). The Easter apparition is a revelation of his call. Since
tulfil 1t. According to the words of Jesus,
primordial
Peter was not to be spared this crisis of faith (cf. Lk 22:33f.). But the prayer of Jesus,
the formula in 1 Cor 15 15 a very ancient piece of tradition, it is an expresston of the
conviction
that Peter
was
the
primary witness to the resurrection. Three texts in particular bring out specifically the
special
22:311€.;
place
of Perer:
Jn21:158f.
In
Mt 16:13-19;
the
first
text,
Lk
the
authenticity of which as part of the gospel cannot be seriously doubrted, though its place
in the arrangement of the text is perhaps due
to the redaction, Jesus gives Simon 2 new and
symbolic name, by calling him Petres (Kephas — Rock). Jesus promises the apostle that he is to be the rock foundation of the Church
which
he planned.
Peter
is to guarantee
stability and security, permanence and untty.
the foundation of the Church, Christ is himself
but this foundation appears visibly mn Peter. The other apostles are also included in this function (Eph 2:19f). One must also re-
member that according to the Letter to the Ephesians, the Church is also founded on the
prophets, i.e., the charismatics. None of these elements should be overlooked. Though
Peter alone was given a special charge, 1t 1s clear that he can only exercise it in unity with
Satan
was
to
bring
rhe
disciples
into
a
situation of severe trial for their faith. This took place in fact at Jesus’ death. And even
offered for Peter in particular, was to help
him to recover, and it would then be his task
to provide support for his “brothers™, that 1s, for the whole community. Peter is to be a stronghold of the faith.
According to Ja, Jesus fulfils his promises
and completes his transmission of authority after the resurrection. It is understandable that the confirmation of the authority should
be after the resurrection, since the existence
and life of the Church are linked to the resurrection of the Lord. Peter is made
shepherd
common
of
the
flock.
This
metaphor,
in the OT and NT, comes from an
agrarian culture and is based on the notion that the shepherd has to find pastures and watering-places for the flock, to defend 1t against attack and to preserve due order within the flock. What is meant therefore is that the I.ord who will no longer be visibly and historically present appoints a representative who
has to mediate Christ’s salvation,
41
POPE the life of salvatxnn, by
preaching
-
and establishing salfl.fic symbnls He must
also protect this life from all threats from
within agd from without.
In the Acts of the Apostles, Peter appears
as the head of the young Church, conscious
of his responsibility and full of the power of the Spirit. He is the successful, enterprising
and courageous preacher of the gospel. He is equipped with authority to combat anything unholy within the Christian community. It is he who breaks through the bounds of Judaism into the universality of the message of salvation. He is the pace-maker for the mission to the world. This is all described without any effort to glorify him or to gloss over his weaknesses (cf., for instance, Acts 1:15-26;
5:29;
2:14-40;
8:14-17;
3:1-26;
8:18-25;
4:8;
9:32-43;
5:1-11;
10:15).
The importance and the limits of Peter’s authority are shown in the dispute between him and Paul at Antioch when the question of the persistence of the ritual law of the OT arose {Acts 15:7-12; Gal 2:11-21). And in general, it was only normal, in view of the simple, rudimentary and hence undeveloped organization of the primitive Church, that the exercise of the Petrine functions should have been on a modest scale. Further, according to the words of Jesus, the authorities were to see themselves and to behave as the
servants of the rest and not as their lords (Mt 20:26ff.; Lk 22:254.; In 13:1-20). The primacy of Peter was not in any way dimin-
ished by the fact that he exercised his function
of head by keeping in touch with the consensus of the Church and remaining in loving
fellowship with it. He remained head of the Church when he left Jerusalem and went to
Rome (cf. Acts 12:17;1
11:13).
Lyons. Peter’s going 1o Roine p— be‘ adcribed to the impulse of the Spirit pervading
the Church s well as to Petat’smdmfim
- And it is not mpasmble that the link between
Rome and succession to Peter was based on a decision of the Church towards the end of the apostolic age. The Roman papacy passed from a rudimentary to a fully-developed stage. Under the stress of circumstances, in the
course
of history,
many
alien tasks
accrued to the Popes, including the government of the Papal States. Then as political,
cultural and social conditions changed, the Popes freed themselves once more from such tasks, though only slowly, hesitantly and often uawillingly, fearing that the loss of worldly power might involve restrictions on their spiritual mission. The changing shape of papal power corresponds to the changes in the whole Church. It is determined by political and cultural shifts in the course of history, though also by the personal character of any given Pope.
In the early centuries, there are many proofs that the Church was conseious of the primacy of the Roman Pontiff, but the testimonies are in germ, so to speak, and not fully explicit. The first is provided by a letter of Bishop Clement of Rome to the Church in Corinth at the end of the 1st century, Quarrels
have broken out in Corinth, and Clement acts
as peace-maker. He does not intervene authoritatively, but displays a deep sense
of responsibility for the whole Church. It is this sense of responsibility which inspires his initiative. The spirit, the force and the claim of the Roman Pontiff are heralded in the letter, which was held in extraordinarily high esteem throughout the Church in the 2nd century.
Church is “president of love”, that is, first in
DEVELOPMENT
himself did not appoint
successors
either to Peter or 1o the other aposties. The
succession follows from the nature of Peter’s
mission (Mt 28:18f.), which is to the ends
of the earth and the end of time. The succession to Peter is not on the same lines as succession to the other 1pnstIcs since he can
have only one successor at a time. According to the faith of the Church, this is the Bishop
of Rome, since Peter was in Rome and suffered a martyr’s death there. Sufficient proof for
this is given
Romanoes,
42
Tre
[gnatius of Antioch says that the Roman
C. HistoricaL
Jesus
Pet 2:11:5:13; Heb
Roman preshyter G&,ma and
4,
in lgnatius
3),
Dionysius
of Antioch
of Corinth,
(.44 the
the realization of the new principle introduced by Christ into history. He goes on to say that the Roman Church teaches others but does
not itself receive instruction. He begs it to take care of the Church in Syria. The reason
for Rome’s precedence, as explained by Ignatius, is that Peter and Paul lived in the Roman Church and preached the gospel there.
Irenaeus of L.yons defends tradition against Gnosticism. To establish what the tradition is, the local Churches founded by the apostles
ate the competent witnesses. The apostolic
succession guarantees the truth of the doc-
.
POPE
trine. In such a matter sufficient proof has been given when it is shown that in the
greatest and most ancient Church, one universally known and founded by the glorious apostles Peter and Paul, its line of bishops goes back to the apostles and that its
doctrine is therefore apostolic. “With this
Church,
on account of its more
primordial
authority (or: more effective priority, “propter potentiorem principalitatem’) all other
Churches in every place cannot but agree,
since in it the Christians of all places have preserved the apostolic tradition™ (.Adrersus
Haereses, 111, 3, 3).
Tertullian and Hippolytus regard Peter as the first in the line of Roman bishops. Cyprian sees the unity of the Church as founded on Peter. The link with Peter provided by succession to the episcopal office is, according to Cyprnan, the fundamental justification of all episcopal power and likewise determines the unity of the Church universal.
When Peter settled in Rome, the primitive
Church embodied in Peter also settled there. Hence the Roman Church is the ecclesia principalis. Optatus of Milevis (d. before 400) held that communion with the Roman Church guaranteed the legitimacy and divine authority of the other Churches. Ambrose (on Ps 40:30) says: “Where Peter is, there is the
Church.” Augustine 1n his struggle against Pelagianism strove with growing vigour to gain the support of Rome, because, as he said, only the verdict of the Apostolic See could give the proper emphasis to the decision of the African bishops (Epistle, 172, 29).
From the 2nd century on, the Bishop of Rome was asked to decide in questions of controversy, e.g., the date of Easter (see the
accounts of the numerous journeys to Rome
in Eusebius’s History of the Church). From the 4th century on there is the fact that bishops
lock to Rome
for protection
of their rights,
and that Rome is the court of appeal in matters of law, while appeals against its
decisions were held to be inadmissible. The Roman baptismal Creed came to be authot-
itative. Rome played 2n essential role in the fixing of the canon of Scripture, as also in the struggle against Gnostics, Marcionites and
Montanists. In the Middle Ages, the papacy was dis-
cussed only incidentally, in connection with other problems such as the manner of ordination of priests, the analysis of faith and especially in solving the questions raised by the founding of new religious orders in the
13th century. These orders wished to be dependent only on the Pope, and not the bishops, especially in financial matters, Religious thus became in a special way the “sons of the Pope”. A tendency in the opposite direction has only set in recently, In late scholasticism, the pressure of historical circumstances, i.e., the occupation of the papal
throne by rival Popes, gave rise to the “conciliar theory”, which made the Council and not the Pope the supreme authority in the Church (see Concrliariom, Schism IV). The conflict between Conciliarism and the doctrine of papal primacy went on for centuries,
in spite of the condemnation of the theory at
the Council of Florence, till the First Vatican Council, at which the question was decided
in favour of the papal primacy (see Gallican-
ism}. But at the Second Vatican Council a
certain
synthesis
was
arrived
at, withourt
prejudice to the primacy of the Pope. Thomas Aquinas used ancient Greek notions of monarchy rather than biblical ones
to justify the papal primacy
as the most
perfect form of government.
It guaranteed
the unity and peace of the Church. According
to Bonaventure, there is a first and supreme principle in every realm, to which all particu-
lars can be reduced, and from which mn turn
all particulars derive. The Pope is the summit
of the whole hierarchical structure of the Church. All duly constituted power in the Church stems from him. This was a consideration inspired by neo-Platonist think-
ing, and led Bonaventure to a view of the
primacy which differed considerably by its exaggerations from what was later defined as Church doctrine. Peter John Olivi came in the course of his defence of the Spirituals against the Curia to hold the view that the Pope was Antichrist. Here he anticipated one of the theses of the Reformers. In theology
after the Council of Trent, as the concept of
the of
ecclesiastical
the
hierarchy,
magisterium,
was
especially
worked
out
that m
opposition to the Reformation, the doctrine
of the primacy was given a more and mote systernatic
form
till it finally
reached
the
stage in which it was adopted by the First Vatican Council,
The way in which the Bishops of Rome understood their universal mandate 1s Instructive. To some extent, such self-interpretations were included in the declarations of the First
Vatican
Council.
This
is
true,
for
instance, of the declaration of the papal legates at the General Council of Ephesus
43
' POPE. -flffi%,thflfig‘htfittflififim'
Eastern bishops and thus ended the Acacian
themselves took the injtiative more and mozreé in making decisions. For 2 long time they
das, which was subscribed to by some 250 Schism (484-519; cf. DS 3066, 363). It was
also accepted by the eighth General Council,
Constantinople IV (869; DS 128). So too
finally the profession of faith of the Emperor
Michael
which
Palaeologus,
he
made
as
representative of the Eastern Church and swore to through his legates at the Council
of Florence. Mention may also be made of 2 pronocuncement of Pope Siricius (384-98; D5 181), which says that it is the task of his office to bear the burdens of all, since “the
blessed Apostle Peter bears them in us” (DS 181) and thus protects his heritage. Innocent I (401-17), in the course of a letter written at the instigation of Augustine to the bishops of Africa during the Pelagian contro-
versy, wrote as follows: ““In your search for
the things of God . . . you have followed the examples of ancient tradition ... and confirmed the strength of your faith in true insight, since you affirmed that the matter in dispute among you should be referred to our judgment, knowing as you did what was due to the Apostolic See. For from this See comes all episcopacy, and 2ll the authority which goes with this title” (DS 217). In 1302 Boniface VIII declared in the bull Unam Sanctam: ‘““Therefore this one and only Church has not two heads like 2 monster, but only one body and one head, Christ and his vicar Peter and the successor of Peter . . . For all men, it is absolutely necessary for salvation to submit to the Roman Pontiff. This we declare, affirm and proclaim™ (DS 872;
D 469). Wycliffe’s spiritualizing image of the Church
and
the views
of Huss,
who
was
theologically dependent on Wycliffe in many respects, gave rise to a number of papal
condemnations of theses in which the papacy was
rejected
or
underestimated
(D
633,
635-9, 646-50, 652, 655; D5 1207, 1209-13, 1220-3; 1226, 1229). Other important affirmations of the primacy include that of the
Council of Florence (17th General Council,
1438-45), the Lateran (18th General Council,
1512-17), the bull Exsarge Domine of 5 July 1520 and the rejection of Gallicanism
Febronianism,
two movements
and
in which the
Concilianism rejected by Florence lived on. A distinction must be made between the
dogmatic
statement
of the
primacy,
e,
explicit faith, and the actual exercise of the
44
. !
tlon
{431; of. DS 3056), which was acclaimed unanimously by all the fathers present. So too the profession of faith of Pope Hormiis-
1
between affirmation and action. Inthefirst.
thousand years the exercise of papal
pfi
took the form of arbitration: Latee the Pfipm
'
exercised their authority by mieans of fraternal admonitions. But as early as the 2nd
century, it also tock the form of juridically binding precepts. Pope Victor (189-98) gave
forceful expression to the primacy. The Churches in Asia Minor had refused to accept
the Roman dating of Easter. In face of the
resulting disunity, Victor excommunicated
them,
not just by bresking
off his own
communion with them but by expressly excluding them from the fellowship of the whole Church. In doing so he appealed to the fact that the graves of the Apostles Peter and
Paul were in Rome. Pope Stephen 1, the first,
as far as we can see, to appeal to Mt 16:18f,, demanded of all the acceptance of his doctrine on the baptism of heretics and threatened those who opposed it with excommunication, appealing to the authority conferred on the Apostle Peter, which he claimed had been transmitted to Peter’s successors. From the 4th century on the Roman Pontiffs, Siricius
(384-98), Innocent I (402-17) and Zozimus (417-18) in particular, claimed the primacy in more and more explicit terms. Leo the Great
was
especially
clear
and
definite
on
the
matter. Human and subjective elements may
have played a part, bur their action was primarily inspired by the conviction that as successors of Peter they had a task to fulfil
which was committed to them by the Lord of the Church. That the claim of Rome was fully in keeping with the mind of the whole
Church was clearly manifested at the General Council of Chalcedon, to take one example.
When the letter of Pope Leo was read to the
Council, the fathers cried out: *“This is the
faith of the Fathers. This is the faith of the apostles. Peter has spoken through Leo.” The letter sent by the Council to Leo describes the Pope as the interpreter of the voice of the Apostle Peter. Gelasius (492—6) laid down the basis of the theory of the two powers which led in the Middle Ages to the subordination of the temporal to the spiritual
power (Innocent III, Innocent IV, Boniface VIID), If the
affirmations
and
exercise
of the
primacy in Christian antiquity are compared with the doctrine of the First Vatican Council and subsequent practice, the extent of the
i
POPE
develepment cannot but be apparent, Nonetheless, there is an undeniable continuity between apostolic times and the present day.
In action and reaction, both the Bishops of
Rome and the Church universal became more
and more clearly conscious of the primatial position of Rome. For the organization of the wide-ranging Church provinces, the patriarchate structure was historically characteristic.. This form was undoubtedly affected by the development of papal authority, but it was not eliminated. For in general, this structure only came into play in its function of supreme judicial authority, even in matters ot faith. In later history, since the beginning
of the Eastern
Schism
(1054), patriarchal
authority in the West was absorbed into the
primatial. Bishops are appointed directly by Rome and are directly subject to the Bishop
of Rome, withourt the intermediate authority of a metropoliran. The First Vatican Council determined the full extent and also the limits of papal authority, against episcopalist tendencies on
the one hand and integralist tendencies on the
other. The Council aimed at stating its faith in such a2 way that the rotal self-understanding of the Church could find expression in it. By reason of external circumstances and also of the immarmrity of ecclesiclogy, only part of the problem could be dealt with, that of the
papal primacy. As regards the bishops, the Council was content to pur in a saving clause, which was meant to ensure that no detriment should be done to the ordinary power of the
bishops, given them by Christ. The strong emphasis on the primacy launched a line of development which took the concrete form of Roman centralization and which now prompts a search for a form of exercise of the which
primacy
will allow
the bishops,
not
merely in theory but also in practice, the freedom of movement which properly be-
longs to them. The most important text of
Vatican I is as follows: “We
teach
and
declare
that the Roman
Church has the primacy in ordinary authority,
by the disposition of the Lord, over all other Churches.
This jurisdictional power
of the
Roman Pontiff, which is truly episcopal, is direct. Towards this authority the pastors
and
faithful
of every
rite
and
rank,
both
individually and collectively, are bound by
the duty
of hierarchical subordination
and
true obedience, not only in matters of faith and morals but also in matters of discipline and government in the Church throughout
the whole world, By maintaining the unity of fellowship as well as of the same faith with the Roman
Pontiff, the Church of Christ is
thus one flock under one supreme pastor . . . The authority of the Supreme Pontiff does no detriment to the ordinary and direct power of jurisdiction by which the bishops, the successors of the apostles, appointed by the Holy Spirit, are truly pastors of the flocks assigned to each of them to rule and feed. It is, on the
contrary, acknowledged, strengthened and defended by the supreme and universal pastor, as was affirmed by St. Gregory the Great when he said: ‘My honour is the honour of the universal Church, My honour
is the vigorous strength of my brothers. I am only truly honoured when due honour is paid to each of them ...” Because the Roman Ponuff 15, by divine right of the apostolic primacy, head of the whole Church, we also teach and declare that he is the supreme judge
of all the faithful, to whose judgment appeal can be made in all matters which come undet ecclesiastical examination. But the verdict of the Apostolic See may be rejected by no one, since there is no higher authority, and no one
may pass judgment on its judgmeni. Hence
they stray from the right path of truth who affirm that it is permissible to appeal to a
General Council against the judgments of the as if the General
Pontiffs,
Roman
Council
were a higher authority than the Roman Pontift. “If anyone therefore says that the Roman Pontiff has only the office of supervision and guidance, bur not full and supreme power of jurisdiction
the
over
whole
Church,
not
merely in matters of faith and morals but also in matters of discipline and government tn
the Church throughout the whole world; or if he says that the Pope has only the major share
but
supreme
not
power;
the
whole
fuliness
of this
or that this power is not
ordinary and direct over both the Churches
individually and collectively and the pastors and faithful individually and collectively: let him be excluded’ (D) 1827-31; D.5 3060-64), Other statements about the papal primacy are to be found in the encyclical of Pius XII
Mystici Corporis, 29 June 1943, and in many texts of the Second Vatican Counctl. The primacy of the Pope defined
by
Vatican I refers not to the power of orders
{ potestas erdinis} but to the pastoral power { potestas jurisdictionis). The teaching authori-
ty, the magisterium,
incorrectly,
regarded
which s often, though
as a distinct
type of 45
|I
T
L
-
authority, should be ranged under the pastoral or jurisdictional power. (See Bl siastival Axthority; Magisterism.) As regards the power of ordets, the Pope is not superior to the bishops. Nonetheless, power of
jurisdiction and power of orders are linked very closely to the Pope, since his supreme pastoral power is based on the fact that as Bishop of Rome he is the successor of the Apostle Peter. Even though a baptized person when elected Pope at once possesses papal power when he accepts the election,
episcopal consecration, by virtue of the link between power of ordets and power of jurisdiction, is essential to the taking up of supreme power in the Church. The two powers form an organic unity, though they need not come at the same time.
In the realm of jurisdiction, the Pope possesses supreme, full and universal power in the Church. Itis truly episcopal and takes in every member of the Church. Its extent is determined by the revelation which took place in Jesus Christ. The Pope has no authority in purely worldly matters. Claims
. of such a nature put forward in the Middle Ages
were due to historical circumstances
and did not derive from the to the Pope. According to Vatican I, the papacy is to instituted by Jesus Christ
primacy proper the teaching of be regarded as and not as the
result of historical developments or even as
the outcome of intrinsic necessities in the Church. The Pope is not given his mandate by the Church, and he is not the delegate of
the bishops, even though he acts in the name
of the whole
Church
and of the bishops
representing the whole Church — as he does, even when acting on his own initiative. The election,
which
has
gone
through
many
represented by the Pope a8 the visible head.
from
excluding,
rather presupposes
the
spontaneity, freedom and individual qual: ities of each wieclder of the primacy. In the activities of the primacy, Christ comes to the fore precisely in the fragility of men. The
personal character of each Supreme Pontiff is
fraught with consequences, in spite of his cail
to be the instrument of Christ. Nonetheless,
the authority of the Pope is ultimately the authority of Christ. When the Pope exercises his power of jurisdiction, his pastoral office,
he is owed internal and external obedience.
Since it is Christ who acts in the primatial actions of the Pope, the papal power is rooted in the sacramental character of the universal for
(cf.,
Chuzch
example,
Jn
20:21-23).
Normally, only those united with Christ in the Spirit are called to transmit to others the salvation given by Christ. According to Jn 21:15€, Peter’s love of Christ is the presupposition of his being charged to feed the flock of Christ. The wielders of spiritual
authority are to live in peace with God and
with the brethren. The Church had indeed to learn by experience in the course of history that union of heart with Jesus Christ ¢an be lacking, but that this does not mean the loss of papal
authority
(against Wycliffe,
Huss
and Luther). The primacy would in fact be null and void if it were dependent for its value on something which could never be definitely ascertained, like the mind and heart of the holder of the office. Nonetheless,
the normal situation is that the representative of Jesus
Christ lives in union
with
Jesus
Christ, Otherwise not only would the salva-
tion of the Pontiff himself but that of the
whole
messianic
papacy itself is based on the commissioning
of the Apostie Peter, though the Pope is not
question has yet to be solved as to who should determine the fact of heresy in such a
apostles were at once the (direct) bringers and
primacy isa grave scandal. The intrinsic bond between power of orders and of jurisdiction
witnesses of revelation, while the bishops are
always
endan-
gered.
the Apostle Peter, any more than the bishops are apostles, The main difference is that the
toc it has
be
changes of form in the course of history, though now long since stabilized, serves to
designate the holder of the office. But the
Hence
community
been
the
conviction of the Church that a Pope who fell into heresy would lose his office. But the case.
In any
case, a sinful holder
of the
shows that the actions of the Pope, even in
about in the course of Church history. The
juridical matters, are concerned with salvation and sanctification. The reason why Christ combined the full and supreme pastoral power in one member of the Church,
one, tnasmuch as the invisible head, Christ, is
continuity and unity of the Church are guaranteed and displayed in this office. Communion with the Pope brings out the
{indirect) transmitters of revelation,
Vatican I gave no formal explanation of
how the succession to Peter actually came
Christological perspective in which the Pope was placed is of particular importance. The Church does not have two heads, but only 46
the Bishop
of Rome,
seems to be that the
| i
{
|
'
.
.
POPE
full membership of the saving community,
the communio samctorum as communion
szints and communion
of
in the holy, in the
most visible zad reliable way. Hence the institution of the primacy appears as a mani-
festation of Christ’s concern for the inner
unity and the reliable proclamation of the
message of salvation both within and without the people of God. The universal episcopate of the Pope naturally brings up its relationship to the episcopate. The question is all the more important because Vatican 1 affirmed that papal power was truly episcopal. In spite of
the division into local Churches under the
personal rule sal bishop, so as comprised the pope is
of a bishop, the Pope is univerthat the whole Church appears within one diocese. Though not superior to his fellow-
bishops by virtue of the power of orders, he
is, in this view, jurisdiction and members of the faithful. And he copal power in Nonetheless,
by virtue of his power of its primacy, bishop over zll Church, both bishops and can make use of this episany part of the Church,
there
are
not
two
bishops
in
each diocese, the local ordinary and the universal Pontiff. In spite of the direct episcopal power of the Pope, the local bishop
remains the immediate
pastor of the flock
entrusted to him. It seems impossible to reduce the relationship between the universal episcopal authority of the Pope and the local episcopal authority to a satisfactory juridical formula. But it is certain, at any rate, thart the
universal
episcopal
authority
of the Pope
does not entitle him to intervene at will. In particular, he could not abolish episcopal rule in the Church. “The right of the Pope to intervene in the government of a diocese rests therefore not on an authority of like nature to that of the local ordinary, and one which would be in competition with it in every way, but on a higher right which is
people of God and hence of the salvation of the individuals. The Pope is appointed as
member Church.
of the Church
on behalf of the
His actions, by virtue of Christ’s
dispositions, stem from the Church and in turn serve the Church. Pope and Church do not face each other like strangers who come from different parts. On the contrary, the
Pope speaks as a member of the Church to the other members, though as one equipped with special and indeed supreme authority.
And the Church in turn is a brotherly fellow-
ship within which the Pope lives as brother
and father. Highly as 2 member of the Church
may be placed by the primacy, he is just as
profoundly at the service of all. Thus the primacy may mean supreme authority, but its truest meaning is the most intensive
service (rervus servoram ). The Pope has to answer to Christ for the way in which he serves the salvation of all (1 Pet 5:1-4). Thus
the primacy is itself also a form for the expression of love, placing itself at the service of men in obedience to God’s eternal plan of
salvation
(1 Cor 13:13).
But
the
love
of
which we speak here is of such a type that it
cannot connive at or confirm man’s selfassurance or selfish ease, his worldly longings ot his enslavement to the world. It has to teli the arrogant and self-centred to go out of themselves and find the liberty of the children of God, freedom from anguish and freedom
in joy. For man, this often means disquiet
and disturbance. He shrinks from taking the
step across the abyss to God and hence finds the challenge to do so an imposition. Hence
an iastitution which binds him formally by law to go out of himself and give himself to Christ, is for him 2 scandal. While it is true
that all the eflorts of the Church can become
a scandal, the character of scandal is concen-
trated in the papacy as in a focus, because from it comes the supreme statement of the obligations which are intended for man’s
prevented by the principle of subsidiarity from intervening except when the ordinary competent organ fails’ (K. Mérsdorf). But here again it is for the Pope to judge when
well-being but can nonetheless be felt as threats to earthly self-assurance and appear furthermore at times in forms which are not consistently understandable, since they have
in fact grave obligations on the holder. He is
same
speak, and again, he may not speak out of turn. There is much in all this which remains and must remain the decision of the Supreme
the salvation of men. It cannot be used to
such a situation has arisen. The primacy lays
not free to remain silent when he ought to
Pontiff
himself,
Christ.
This
but
he
is nonetheless
in-
exorably bound to the charge given by Jesus charge
means
service
of the
to pay the tribute of human frailty. At the time,
these considerations
show
that
the exercise of the primacy is determined as to its necessity, its proportions and its limits, by the approach of the reign of God and by train
men
obedience.
in obedience Hence
it must
for the
respect
sake
of
human
freedom, which is man’s highest natural good
47
POPE
to
the extent
that
restriction is necessary for his salvation.
such
Vatican I left the question open as to how
the relationship between primacy and epis-
copacy should be determined. The solution
given by Vatican II was the affirmation of the
collegiality of the bishops. It was not the
intention of Vatican I¥ to limit the primacy, but to complete the affirmations of Vatican 1 and supply what was omitted there. The collegiality of the bishops is to be understood in a broad
sense.
Vatican
II used
gteat
emphasis and piled up formulations to point put that the college of bishops essentially includes the Bishop of Rome, the Pope, and that as head of the college he is so much part of it that without the Pope there is no college of bishops, and that the college only possesses spiritual authority inasmuch as the Bishop of Rome is a member of the college and is over it as its head. Without his membership, the college would be reduced to a sum total of individual bishops. An exceptional situation occurs when a Pope becomes incapable of acting as Pope, as for instance when he is
mentally ill or falls into heresy or has died. In such an exceptional case, the college of bishops would not cease to exist as a college.
It would not disintegrate into a number of individual bishops, because important factors
of unity remain eflective —unity in confession of Christ, unity in the Spirit, in love, in the celebration of the memorial sacrifice. These
factors are also effective and play a decisive role in normal times, when the Pope presides over the college of bishops as its head. And
these factors make it clear that the unity of the college is not just an external juridical bond. Its basis must be uaderstood as sacramental. That the Pope is essential to the
constitution
of the college
is the visible
manifestation of a unity which is ultimately based on the sacramental element. For the rest, in an abnormal and exceptional case the Church 1s obliged to give itself a head once more. This is done by the election of a new
which
universal
n
supplemented it to the effect that the college af' bishops, in common with the Bishop of Rome as its head, is also {guague) holder of full and supreme power over the Chutch universal. The Council thus affirmed with regard to the college of bishops a doctrine had
already been
in the
Church with regard to the General Councils.
The statement on papal power includes the
word “‘universal”, which is not used in the Council’s statement on the power of the
college of bishops. But this does not change matters in any way. Though the relationship between the holder of the primacy and the college of bishops (with the Pope as its head) is made quite clear in the texts of the Council,
the “Nota
Praevia
Explicativa” added
to
Lumen Gentium (cf. H. Vorgrimler, ed., Com-
mentary on the Documents of Vatican I, vol. 1
[1967], pp. 297fL.) put the matter beyond all possible doubt by saying that the distinction is not “between the Roman Pontiff and the bishops taken collectively, but between the Roman Pontiff by himself and the Roman Pontiff together with the bishops. Since the Supreme Pontiff is bead of the college, he alone can perform certain acts which in no
wise belong to the bishops, for example, convoking and directing the college, approving the norms of action, etc.” But it is worth noting that the introductory explanation says that the Pope can use various methods
in
making these decisions, as the circumstances of the times demand. He need not confine
himself to a form laid down once and for all.
The Pope being entrusted with the care of the whole
flock of Christ, it is for him
to
judge, as the needs of the Church change in the course of time, the manner in which he
will exercise this charge, either personally or collegially. Though the final text of the Council does not say so, it may be assumed that even when the Pope acts on his own initiative, without the suggestions of the bishops
and
without
their
co-operation,
in the
exercising his authority for the whole Church, he then acts as head of the college. For he always speaks in the name of the Church as
with a difficult problem. Vatican 1I declared
he never acts as a private person, but always
Pope.
The
context
collegiality
of the
of the primacy
bishops
presents
theology
that the Bishop of Rome, by virtue of his office as vicar of Christ and as pastor of the
Church
universal
48
universal,
authority,
has
full,
which
he
supreme can
and
exercise
well as for the Church. When he acts as Pope,
a3 successor of the Apostle Peter, whose task it is to give effect to what has been handed down in the people of God. The college of bishops possesses full and supreme power not
g
except
I. .Bu’t me
o
freedom
mspended to Yam
o o
and takes priority in doubtful cases, since man in his freedom is analogously the lmagt of God. Hence the primacy cannot restrict man’s
POPE
because this has been given it or conceded to
it by the Pope, but by virtue of its own competence, in consequence of institution. But since the Pope, his teristic membership, is essential constitution and effectiveness of the
Christ’s characto the college,
the consent of the Pope is required for every decree of the college of bishops. This
consent is to be taken in the strict sense. It is
notasubsequent confirmation, butan element
intrinsic to the decree from the start and indeed a vital element. This is so even if the consent of the Pope only comes in the external form of a subsequent approbation. The same conclusion may also be drawn from the formulas used in the publication of the decrees of Vatican II since the holding of the Council.
But the manner in which the Pope exercises
his function as chief member of the episcopal college can vary very widely. Here the actual situation can be of extreme importance. The participation of the Pope can range from a voluntary or even silent acceptance of a decree of the bishops to a solemn promulgation. And the Pope can decide which form he chooses.
especially
In view of the historical facts,
the
proceedings
of the
ancient
Councils, we are justified in assuming that the way in which the Pope exerts the rights
or authority which are his by divine institution, is dependent on human factors and historical circumstances — so much so, that the observer who does not view the processes in the light of faith may be able to sec only the
human and historical factor. The fact that the Pope with the college (or the college with the Pope as its president) possesses full and supreme authority in the Church, while the Pope alone also does so without the college, leads to a question which seems to be insoluble and indeed to contain an inner contradiction. The question is: are there two supreme powers in the Church, in rivalty with one another? Or: is not the college of bishops once more stripped of its power by the fact that the Pope exercises supreme power, even without the bishops?
The Council itself left the question open. The
traditional answer is that there inadequately distinct organs of
ecclesiastical
power:
inadequately
are two supreme distinct,
inasmuch as the Pope is himself a member of the college of bishops. Another view is that there is only one wielder of supreme authority in the Church, the college as constituted under the Pope, the holder of the primacy. To avoid
prejudicing the primacy of the Pope, the supporters of this thesis add that even when the holder of the supreme authority is so defined, a distinction must be made between
actions which the Pope alone performs, without the college, even though in the name of the college, and actions which have a strictly collegiate character by virtue of authoritative papal participatios. To proceed according to the strict logic of law, it would perhaps be more correct to say that the Pope is the one organ of supreme authority, and then add that he can exercise this authority either alone or along with the
bishops in a collegiate act. This thesis would
appear most suitable to ensure the unity of
the Church insofar a2s it stems from the supreme living authority within it. Burt the unity is also assured by the supposition of two tnadequately distinct organs, since the two organs are combined together in unity
by the fact that the Pope is head of the college. Parallel to this is the truth that the primacy suffers
no
detriment
or danger
when
the
supreme authority of the college of bishops is affirmed, with the due precautions.
It may
well be that in deciding for one or the other
solution, psychological and jurisprudential factors may be more strongly at work than strictly theological ones. What is always true is that the Pope is never alone, but i1s always in essential union with the bishops. Even if it is undeniable that he can always exercise freely his supreme authority, nonetheless, by virtue of his
responsibility for the unity of the Church, he is perpetually being thrown back upon his
unity with the bishops. Rather than being a
“free’ agent, the Pope, like the college of the bishops, has to adhere to divine revelation,
as attested in Scripture and tradition, as handed on incorrupt through the apostolic succession and in particular through the
concern of the Bishop of Rome, and as preserved in its purity and faithfully inter-
preted in the light of the Spirit of truth in the Church {(Vatican 11, Lumen Gentium, art. 23).
The activity of the Bishop of Rome must be
directed to the well-being of the Church (¢bid., Introductory Explanation, art. 3).
Hence
not only the bishops but also the
Supreme Pontiffs are bound to take adequate steps, by appealing, for instance, for help to
theological science, by exploring the faith of believers, to strive to ascertain correctly the revelation attested in Scripture and also to
find the way to present it in adequate terms.
49
. POPE
o
: Thmcfieflmanmu&mmfllmtofthepuw
" of jurisdiction belonging to the Pape. He has nofl: therefore just a formal authority, but one
which is also determined as to its content. If it is to be exercised in accordance with the “will of Christ, it must, like the exercise of the
freedom which is man’s right, a2lways submit
itselfto the true message which-comes from
God, that is, to what is attested in Scripture.
But then, it is the Holy Spirit who is at work in the Church universal, It is he who links the
faithful who discharges a spiritual office with
the faithful who have not such an office,
binding them together in a unity which is
ofter: full of tension.
See also Church 111, Bishop 111, Conciliariem, Episcopalism, Gallicanism. BIBLIOGRAPHY.
See bibliography
msrory.
ot Pope IT; also P, Aratd, “Bibliographia historiae
pontificiae”,
_Arcbivum
historize pontificiae
1L,
(1963 ff.). THEOLOGY. See the textbooks on Fun" damental Theology and De Ecclesia; also: S. H. Scott, The Eastern Churches and the Papacy (1928); M. Maccarrone, Vicarivs Christi (1952); M. ]. Wilks, “Papa est nomen jurisdictionis”, /7.5, new
series 8 (1957), pp. 71-91, 250-71; U. Betti in
Antonianum 34 (1959), pp. 161-244, 369-408; id. in Divinitas 3 (1959), pp. 95-143; C. Colomboin Secuola cattolica 88 (1960), pp. 401-34 (on episcopate and prunacy); F. Afanasieff and others, lLa primanuté de Pierre dans Eglise Orthodoxce (1960) G. Thils, Primanté pontificale et prérogatives épisco-
pates (1961); W, de Vries in Scholarerke 37 (1962), pp.
341-69;
U.
Betti,
Divinitas 6 (1962),
pp.
113-33; K. Rahner and J, Ratzinger, The Epir ¢copate and the Primacy, Quaestiones Dispuratae 4
(1962);
H.
Kiing,
Sirukturen der Kirche
(1962),
E. T.: Structares of the Church (1965), cf. Kevin
Smyth in frish Theological Quarterly 33 (1963), pp. 53-66; T. L. Jiménez-Urresti,
Episcopade’”
(1962),
G.
£ binomio " Primado-
Baum
and
P.
de
Letter in The Thorusr 27 (1963), pp. 211-35 (Pope and bishops); P. Bertrams, De Relatione inter episcopaininm et pnmmfmw (1963); B. M. Xiberta, “Il papa e i vescovi’, Divas Themas (Piacenza) 67 (1964), pp. 165-82; Y Congar, ed., La coliegialite épiscopale. Histoire et thévlogie (19(}5:}; G. Baum,
s e Coneinati copecilly o fihurch“b eftlie
ical
K.,
(un arts. 18-—27); L Bachit, *Pritinat tmd Ep
im Spannungsfeld der beiden Vatikanischen: Konzile”, Wabrbeit und Verkindigung ( Festuchrift M. .i':bm) (1967), pp. 1447-66. Michael Schpmans
I1. History of the Popes According to the Catholic faith, the papacy
was instituted by Jesus Christ (for which it appeals in particular to Mt 16:16-18, 28:20; Lk 22:31f.; Jn 21:15-17 and to the tradition of faith). The Popes are thus successors of the
Apostle Peter in his office of Bishop of Rome and the primacy connected with it. Histori-
cally, it may be taken as certain that Peter
worked in Rome for some time with apostolic
authority and was martyred there in the persecution under Nero, The martyrdom may be dated to between 64 and 68. The development of the papacy from the modest form of Peter’s office to the papacy of the present day was accompanied by considerable resistance and
hesitation
within
and
without,
in
a
tension between episcopal federalism and papal centralism which was due to the nature of the Church itself.
A. TeE
RoMaNn
EMPIRE
Little beyond their names is known of the Bishops of Rome in the first two centuries. But the list given by Irenaeus of Lyons ¢. 180
(Adversus Flaereses, 111, 3, 3) gives us a reliable
account of the succession of the guardians and guarantors of the apostolic tradition: “The Blessed Apostles (Peter and Paul),
after founding and buiiding up the Church,
handed over to Linus the office of bishop. Paul mentions this Linus in his letters to
Timothy.
He was succeeded by Anacletus,
The Constitution on the Church (1965); P. Anciaux,
after whom, in the third place after the Apostles, Clement was appointed to the bishopric. He not only saw the Blessed
Le Pape et le concile (1965); W. Bertrams, Papst and
had their preaching ringing in his ears and
The Episcopate in the Church (1965); O. de la Brosse,
Bischofskolleginm als Trager der Rirchlichen Hirtengewalt (1965); id. in Gregorianum 48 (1907}, pp. 28-48; P. Bilaniuk, D¢ magisiratu ordinario Summi
Pentificis (1966); D. Flanagan, The Meaning of the Church
(1966);
H.,
King,
The
Church
(1967);
A. Flannery, ed., Vafican I1 on the Church (2nd ed.,
1967);
G.
Thils,
“Papauté
Gottes ( Festschrift J. Hifer)
et Episcnpat”,
"olk
(1967), pp. 41-63;
H. Fries,
“Ex
sese, non ex consensu
Element
der
Kirchenverfassung”
ecclesiae”,
ibid., pp. 480-500; K. Mérsdorf, “Das Synodale (Vatican
II},
ibid., pp. 568-84; H. Vorgrimler, ed., Commentary
50
Apostles but also conferred with them, and
their tradition before his eyes . . . Now while Clement was bishop thete arose no small dissension among the brethren in Corinth, and the Church in Rome sent 2 most weighty letter to the Corinthians . .. Evaristus suc-
ceeded this Clement, Alexander followed Evaristus; then Sixtus was appointed, the
sixth after the Apostles. After him came Telesphorus, who had a glorious martyrdom, Then
Hyginus,
Pius,
Anicetus
and
Soter;
POPE
and now, in the twelfth place from the Apostles, Eleuthetius occupies the see. In the same order and succession the apostolic preaching in the Church and the preaching
of the truth has come down to our time.” The chronology later supplied for the most
ancient list of the Bishops of Rome down to
¢. 230 is unreliable. But the list of names is genuine ancient tradition. Meagre as is our information about the early years, it is still clear that the Roman community with its bishop appears as the centre of Church unity, with a certain precedence in the whole Church. The exercise and acknowledgment of this precedence become more and more clear, especially in matters of doctrine and discipline. The priority is based — according to the self-understanding of the Roman Church and the mind of Christianity —
on
the activity and martyrdom of the Apostles
Peter and Paul, especially of Peter, in Rome,
where their tombs were also preserved. In
the whole of this early period, the office of
Peter appears to function according to the principle of subsidiarity — only in urgent cases, when the authority of the local
bishops and patriarchs is inadequate. When Constantine the Great transferred the imperial residence to the East, the Bishops of
Rome
became
of increasing
political
im-
portance. They were more widely active in social welfare and at times, during the
Barbarian Invasions, could protect and feed the peoples of Rome and Italy. But the
Bishop-Patriarch
of
Constantinople
soon
became, with the help of the Emperor, the rival of the Pope (can. 2 of the Council of
Constantinople, 381; can. 28 of the Council
of Chalcedon, 451).
After the able Popes Damasus I, Siricius
and Innocent I, a period of steady advance
began with Celestine 1 (422-32), to reach its high-point under Leo the Great (440-061). Following in his footsteps, Gelastus [ (492
96) propounded in a letter to Emperor Anastasius I the outlines of the theory of the
two powers:
“There are two means, your
Majesty, by which this world is chiefly ruled,
the sacred authority of the bishops and the royal power. Of these the importance of that of the priest is all the greater, because they
will have to render an account in the divine
judgment even for the kings of men™ (DJ
347). These views
were taken over by the
False Decretals (attributed to lIsidore of Seville), and in conjunction with the legend of Pope Silvester (from the end of the 5th
century), which was further enhanced by the
“Donation of Constantine™ (probably in the
8th century), gained widespread currency in
the Middle Ages, being taken to mean that the worldly power of the Emperor was
subordinate to the spiritual authority of the Pope. The baptism of the Frankish king, Clovis I, as 4 Catholic, in 496 was a turning-
point in history. The cultural, linguistic and national gulf between the Latin and German West and the Greek East grew steadily
greater. The unity of Holy Church as desired
by Cyprian of Carthage came to an end, chiefly through the fault of the East, though not without grave responsibility on the part of the West. For on the Roman side the spirit of love and unity cherished by Cyprian had
weakened as early as Gelasius I, and was re-
enkindled in this period only for a time by Gregory 1. Most of the German rulers were
Arians and set up national Arian Churches in their kingdoms. The close ties established by the papacy with the East after 519 (begun by the successes of Popes Hormisdas and
Agapetus I) led to the long subjection of the
Roman Church to the imperial Church system of Emperor Justinian I (527-65). The Exarch of Ravenna ruled Italy as part of the Byzantine Empire and the Bishop of Rome was treated as a patriarch under the Empire — as was, for instance, Pope Vigilius I, 537-55. The great figure of Gregory 1 (590-604) comes at
the end of the history of the Popes in antiq-
uity. He knew he belonged to a vanishing
Christian antiquity but could still pave the way
Popes
for the
in the
world-wide
Middle
authority
Ages.
The
of the
papacy
appears in its purest form under Gregory: a
rule which meant responsibility; a pastorai office embracing the whole Church and wholly given up to Christian service of the brethren. B. Tur
EarLy
MiDDLE
AGES
In the early Middle Ages the Popes played an
important part in the entry of all the Germanic peoples into the Church and to some extent
that of the Slavs. The special reverence 1n
which the Germans held the Prince of the Apostles, Peter, the “‘keeper of the gates of
heaven’”, meant that they also held his successors in high esteem, since they bound
and loosed on earth for heaven. At the same
time,
the
papacy
extended
its
authority
universally, in spite of checks during some
periods of profound decadence. lts history 51
POPE in the Middle Ages was determined to a great
extent by the close connection between the spiritual and the temporal (imitiated by
Constantine), with all the problems this involved for both sides. The gulf widened between Rome and the Edstern Empire, which was profoundly shaken by wars and
religious disturbances and could no longer offer protection to Italy. The breach was
complete with the eastern schism of the 11th ceatury. The unity of Christendom was
destroyed. After the painful experiences of
the Crusades, the Unions of Lyons (1274) and of Florence (1439), carried out on the level of the hierarchy and involving political issues, with the papal primacy strongly underlined in both cases, remained ineffective.
The Anglo-Saxon (Benedictine) missionaries set up a close link between the German Church and the papacy, from the end of the 7th century on. Boniface also established close links between the papacy and the Frankish
Chutch,
which
had
almost
lost
touch with Rome, and with the ruling mayors of the palace. Thus the Franks became
conscious once more of the papacy as the
supreme authority in the Church, and the way was paved for the alliance between the papacy and the Frankish kings, and the link between Pope and Emperor which was to be
fraught with such consequences. The alliance
Nicholas I (858-6?) thm:twasna mn::e thgn an empty € of the end of the S‘Ith and mur:h aft:iw 1Uth
century was the saddest period in the history
of the Popes, apart from some pontificates of the Renaissance. Where the Emperor didnot
intervene effectively, the Holy See was at the
mercy of various despots and the jungle law of the Roman nobles.
The pdpacy was rescued by the German
King Otto I, who was then crowned as Emperor by John XII at 5t. Peter’s, in 962. The dignity of Roman Emperor remained
attached to the German King till the end of the Holy Roman Empire in 1806, Anointing and coronation were tesetved to the Pope in 1452
(last done
at Rome
and
at
1530
Bologna). In the following decades, the Popes were only safe as long as the imperial
power
was
conscientious
at hand.
The
energetic
and
Salian king, Henry III, took
swift steps to end the distress of the Church. Under his leadership the synods of Sutri and Rome in 1046 deposed the three rival Popes, Benedict IX, Silvester III and Gregory VI The move was almost universally accepted,
and greeted indeed with applause
friends of reform.
by the
C. THE PREDOMINANCE OF THE POPES IN THE MI1pDLE AGES
with the Franks materialized under Pope Stephen II (7527}, who came to France for help. Pepin the Younger swore an oath of friendship to Peter, Stephen II and his suc-
Along with the hereditary status of patrician, Henry III received from the Romans the
The rich donations of the Carolingians helped
German Popes in succession, able men and
cessors, promising to defend and help them.
the ancient Patrimonium Petri to take on the dimensions
of a Papal State, which
was to
remain for centuries in (contested) dependence on the FPrankish-German King and
Emperor. Charlemagne, 786-814, ordered his whole kingdom to adopt the Roman liturgy and canon law, while at the same time
Church and papacy became subject to strong Germagic influences. For all his reverence
for the Prince of the Aposties, Charlemagne left no room for doubt that he was the
temporal This was crowned Christmas
and spiritual ruler of his kingdom. not affected by the fact that Leo III him as Emperor in St. Peter’s at 800. As the power of the Carolin-
greater
independence
right of designation for the next appoint-
ments to the Holy See. The result was four zealous for reform: Clement II, Damasus 11,
Leo IX and Victor II. A new epoch began. A reformed papacy rose swiftly to be a worldpower. The Popes began at last to take the
work of reform in hand (Cluny, Gorze). Leo IX in particular (1049-54) brought home to
the whole West the universal significance of the papacy. Through his forceful and sometimes radical helpers, mostly from Lorraine
and
Burgundy,
the
college
of cardinals
quickly developed from a mainly liturgical
ministry into 2 body which was henceforth to be at the service of the Pope for the government
of the universal Church
—
2
to
change with which the establishment of the Roman Curia was closely connected. After the decree of Nicholas II on papal elections,
and Saracens. Even under the able rule of
sole right to choose the Pope. As the programme of the Gregorian Reform was pro-
gians
declined,
the
Popes
—
seemed
they
to
began
gain
bestow the imperial crown — but found themselves defenceless against the Normans 52
1059,
the
cardinals
gradually
obtained
the
POPE
gressively
realized, especially through
the
efforts of Cardinals Humbert of Silva Candida and Hildebrand (Gregoty VII), the urge for
faller “freedom™ for the papacy (libertas esclesiae) became more insistent. The papacy should not be part of an imperial Church system but be independent and above all kingdoms. The contrasting views of the Imperium held from the start by the Curia and by the German court, the differences of opinion with regard to royal and papal rights led under Gregory VII (1073-85) to open conflict with the Emperor Henry IV in the
Investiture Controversy, which had parallels
— though less violent — in most countries. With all the dedicated passion of his personality, Gregory upheld the purity and freedom of the Church and the absolutely unlimited authority of the Pope in the Church, to which kings and emperors must bow. The powers which earlter Popes had at times claimed were clearly and indeed drastically formulated by Gregory (in the Dictatus Papae) and were actually exercised, even to the excommunica-
tion and deposition of the most eminent ruler of Western Christendom. This papal
policy brought with it strong trends to ecciesiastical centralization and the imposition of Roman canon law and liturgy on the whole
Church.
Along
with
the
Emperor,
the layman, the non-cleric in the Church was
also in principle affected. The Gregorian age — in its glories as in 1ts miseries — is un-
doubtedly the greatest turning-point in the
history of the Popes. Right down to presentday efforts at a new orientation, the Catholic
Church has essentially been dominated by the thinking of Gregory VIL
The new authority and leadership of the
papacy was shown in the initiative taken — by the Pope and not the Emperor — in the
direction of the liberation of the Holy Land
(Urban I, 1088-99). Inspired by their sense of responsibility for all Christianity, the
Eugene I (1145-53), depicting the ideal papacy as spititual in character, The Pope
should be the successor of St. Peter and not of Constantine. Under the Emperor Frederick I, Barbaros-
sa, the second great conflict between medieval Imperium and Sacerdotium began (Hadrian IV, 1154-59, the only English Pope; Alexander
I11, 1159-81). The main issue was the imperial
suzerainty over Italy, Fearing that the Papal
State would be encircled and absorbed, papal
policy opposed the union of the kingdom of Sicily with the Empire. The conflicts became
more
and
empire”’
more
bitter.
of Innocent
from the new mendicant orders (Franciscans, Dominicans), were clouded by the conflict
with the Emperor Frederick II, which finally
became a merciless war of annihilation against the whole house of Hohenstaufen. The fall
of the ancient imperial house of Germany was
soon followed by the decline of the worldwide authority of the papacy. There was no
winner in the end in the struggle between the “two heads of Christendom™. The two
institutions
suffered
irreparable
the “secularization”
losses
in
power and standing. The “protection” lent
by the French kings to whorm the Popes appealed weighed far more heavily on them
than the rule of the Hohenstaufens. As the national consciousness of the European
peoples awoke,
there was universal protest
against the “‘secularization™ of the papacy, the misuse of tithes collected for the Crusades
and the frequent imposition of ecclesiastical penalties to further political ends. The desire for a Pastor Angeliews who would renew the
Church was fed from many sources. But the
hermit Celestine V (1294} was followed by the domineering Boniface VII1 (1294-1303). His immoderate attempts to regain universal
D. Late
dangers:
the
during which Church and papacy gained strong though at times troublesome support
after the Gregorian age brought with it grave
Curia,
III (1198-1216)
greatest heights. The following pontificates,
of the King of France.
of the
“spiritual
power of the medieval papacy reached its
Popes devoted themselves for centuries to the Crusades, during which, from the end of the Middle Ages on, the notion of liberating Jerusalem was succeeded by the need to ward off Turkish aggression. The
increased political commitment of the Popes
In the
recognition
for the worldly power
of the
papacy (the Bull Unam Sanctam) ended in ruin. He was = -attered by the national power
MIDDLE
AGES
AND
RENAISSANCE
its lust for power and money, unheaithy centralization which disregarded the tradi-
In the early Middle Ages the young nations
This was what Bernard of Clairvaux opposed
whole
tional rights of the bishops and national traits. when he wrote his De Consideratione to Pope
of Europe
Later,
the
had gathered
circle
Church
ruled
of Western
round
from
life.
the Church.
In
Rome the
the
later
Middle Ages the forces at work in all realms
53
POPE of life were centrifugal. Nationalism became
stronger and stronger in States and peoples, Men
began
to be preoccupied
with the
freedom of the individual and sought to loosen the close social ties of the medieval
order. The Defensor Pacis of Marsilius of
Padua (1324) already anticipates, long before their time, the great upheavals of modern society,
After the failure of Boniface
VIII
the
(French) Popes — to the great detriment of
their universal standing — came to a great
extent under the influence of the French crown. From 1309 to 1377 they resided in the . “Babylonian Captivity” of Avignon. During this period, when existing canon law was disregarded in favour of a new system of
appointments and finances, the centralizing
trend of the Curia was greatly intensified and the influence of the Pope within the Church thereby greatly extended. But the papacy suffered still further losses in religious substance, 1n spiritual standing and in political importance, 2s the nation-States grew stronger and their rulers built up national Churches successfully. The struggle between the Avignon Popes, especially John XXII (1316-34), and the Emperor Ludwig IV,
the Bavarian —— the last great conflict of Impersum and Sacerdotinm in the Middle Ages — showed how dangerously low papal authority had suak. Interdict and excommunication,
too
often
abused,
had
become blunted weapons. The call for “reform of the Church in head and members” became ceaseless. There was radical criticism of the papacy as an institution from such men as Marsilius
of Padua,
William
of Occam,
John Wycliffe and John Huss. The “Exile”
had weakened the papacy so much that its greatest humiliation came upon it: the great Western Schism (1378), not conjured up by wotldly powers, like so many anti-Popes of the past, but induced by the highest circles in the Church, The difficult question ot whether after 1378 the Pope in Rome or the Popein Avignon had thebetter credentials could not be satisfactorily answered by the men of the day, as it still cannot be by Church
historians. The “Conciliar Theory”, propounded by earlier theologians and canonists and with roots in the thinking of the ancient Church,
was
now
voiced
more
firmly
as
jadge and deposs him.
This.
was’the
lin
taken at Pisa in 1409 and then by the General
CouncilofConstance, whichin the toomentary emergency affirmed the superiority of the General Council and happily re-established unity. In the long Conciliarist conttoversy it became clear that the greatest .crisis of the Church of the late Middle Ages was 2 constitutional one. The election of Martin V
(1417-31) was the turning-point in the highly dangerous Conciliarist movement. It was
due 10 no small measure to the tactlessness of Eugenc IV (1431-47) that a crisis arose
once more, at the General Council of Bagle,
with regard to the place of the Pope in the
Church. And it was also due to Eugene IV that so much stress was laid on the primacy of the Pope on the occasion of the union with the Greeks at Florence (1439). With the noble, cultured Nicholas V (1447-55), under whom the last anti-Pope (so far) abdicated (Felix V), the close relationship
between papacy and Humanism or Renais-
sance began on the whole to take shape, which -was to last till well into the 16th century. He 2nd many of his successors were interested in lending new lustre to the papacy and the Church by making them leading forces of culture. But the urgent question of reform was left unresolved. Under the successors of Pius I1 (1458—-64) the religious character of the supreme spiritual
office in the Church was woefully obscured
(Sixtus 1V, Innocent VIII, Alexander VI).
Julius 1T (1503-13) was a typical Renaissance
prince, full of warlike energy and with a fine feeling for art. Julius strengthened the Papal States as the external buttress for the modern papacy. With the undistinguished Fifth Lateran Council (1515-17), the last chance of self-reform before the “Refo:mation” was missed. Since the reform of the
Church had not been realized, the action of
Luther in the pontificate of the easy-going
Medici Pope, Leo X (1513-21) meant the gravest catastrophe for the Church and the papacy: the separation of the Germanic North and great parts of Central and Eastern Europe, as also of parts of France, in the
Protestant Reformation. E. CatHoLIC
MATION
REFORM
AND CounTER-REFOR-
the tribulations of the Church grew more dite. The General Council, as the representa-
With the cleavage of the Church in the 16th century the universal authority of the Pope
above the Pope and to be able if necessary to
shock
tive of the universal Church, was held to be
54
finally ceased to function, But the dreadful
finally
helped
the
movement
for
f
POPE
renewal within the Church to succeed, even
in the Curia, in a very painful process. The
short-lived efforts of the noble Hadrian VI (1522-23)
ended
in failure, and then
the
turning-point came slowly with the reign of Paul IIT (1534-49). reform,
lending
new
A thorough-going
life
to
Catholicism,
was powerfully launched by highly active new religious orders, especially the Jesuits, but above all by the General Council of Trent (1545-63). The Romans were now heavily predominant, and this gave postTridentine Catholicism its characteristic stamp. In contrast to the radical attack of the Protestant reformers, the Catholic reaction was manifested in the Counter-Reformation,
F. FroM THE PEACE Or WESTPHALIA (1648) TO THE FrRENCH REVOLUTION
The modetn age has been signalized by a progressive secularization in every field. Individualism and subjectivism quickly flourished. But the great rejection of faith and revelation only came with the Enlightenment of the 17th and 18th centuries. The papacy, though highly esteemed and inwardly consolidated, had to suffer further losses in
political and ecclesiastical influence, even in the Catholic States. It was a time of difficult
conflict with State and royal absolutism, with
an Enlightenment which was often hostile to the Church and the Pope, with Gallicanism
and theologically also in the special stress laid on the office in the Church, especially that of the Pope. After the merciless criticism
in France, Episcopalism (Febronianism) in
spontaneity and women in the late past. There
in the hope of avoiding political conflict, the cardinals elected honourable but mostly not outstanding men in the period between
voiced by the Reformation, authentic criticism within
the necessary, the Catholic
Church became difficult. The and frankness with which men had expressed their misgivings Middle Ages were things of the
was a new narrowness of mind. Strict pro-
hibitions and close supervision of the faithful became major preoccupations of the ad-
ministration. The grandiose flowering of Baroque splendour and even the world-wide
thrust of the missions under the guidance of the papacy could not make up for the losses
of the 16th century. Only minor successes attended later efforts at reunion with Protestants,
for
which
minds
noble
on
sides strove. The place of the Pope
both
in the
Church proved to be, as 1t still is, the most intractable problem, Though some post-Tridentine Popes betrayed serious faults of character or intelligence, there could be no question now of “unworthy Popes™. The great reform Popes, Pius V (1566-72), Gregory XIII (1572-85) and Sixtus V (1585-90) made the papacy,
as was fitting, the decisive and successful leader of the Catholic reform. Clement VIII, Paul V and Gregory XV continued the work. The permanent papal nuncios became henceforward important figures in the po-
litical
and
ecclesiastical
realm.
With
the
establishment of the Propaganda Congregation (1622) the papacy finally took over the guidance of the expanding foreign missions. But the political weakness of the papacy was exposed in the Thirty Years” War and
the
Peace
of
Westphalia
(Urban
1623—-44; Innocent X, 1644-55).
VIII,
the German State Church, with Josephinism
in the Hapsburg lands and in general with
the sovereignty increasingly claimed by the national Churches everywhere. Probably
the
Peace
and
of Westphalia
the
French
Revolution. The incorruptible, deeply reli-
gious Innocent X1 (1676—89) and the learned, conciliatory Benedict X1V (1740-58) formed between Relations brilliant exceptions. Church and State underwent a series of
grave
crises
throughout
at the end
of the
17th
and
the 18th century, especially in
Catholic lands. The problem was to find a modus vivendi which would do justice to the
modern State and satisfy the Church, without
detriment to the essence of the Church or the
just claims of the State. The problem was not to be solved without fierce struggles,
The papacy was not prepared at first to
yield any of the rights which it had hitherto exercised or claimed or even to give up the wishful thinking of the Middle Ages as regards papal authority in the Church. The
ecclesiastical doctrine of papal rights was further developed. It was confronted by
the actuality of the State Churches of the 18th century, where the central notion which
dominated everything wasthat of the absolute
power of the State to which all were to be subject, whether as individuals oras corporate
bodies.
According
Enlightenment,
to
the
jurists
of the
even in Catholc lands, the
ordre naturel de [ Etat was such that its sovereignty could not be challenged from within or from without. The rights exercised and claimed by the bishops and superiors
of orders were thereby questioned, as was
55
POPE
thepasition of the Pflp& in the Church. The
Papal States, the whole notion of 2 State under a priest, had become questionable to the new age. The programme of the Enl.lght:nmcnt of the 18th century remained in essentials the ideal of the 19th and even of the early 20th century. The attitude taken by Church and papacy towards the Enlightenment was to
be decisivein their relationship to the modern wotld. From the beginning of its history the
Church had always been the spearhead of each new break-through of fertile impulses
in various realms of life. But in the modern
age it allowed itself to be forced back on the defensive or even withdrew voluntarily to such positions. In the 18th and 19th centuries the Popes often clutched convulsively at the traditional forms and formulas of a2 vanishing or vanished world. The clearest losses of the Church in the 18th century were in France,
where it lost vital contact with the cultured classes. Thete was a disastrous separation of faith and knowledge and there was no intellectual giant among the faithful, like Augustine or Albertus Magnus or Thomas, to build a new bridge between the brothers
who
had become enemies. There was no
lack of sincere efforts in the 18th, and above
all in the 19th, ceatury. But success was slight,
The preliminaries to the suppression of the Society of Jesus, and the actual suppression by the Pope (1773), or the humiliating and
practically fruitless pilgrimage of Pius VI
in, Previous diffic: Mpate with what Pius V1 {1??5—»99) nmi h.is smwsor Pius VIIT (1800-23) had to suffer from the French Revolution and Napoleon. two Popes had to undergo the
These wosst
humiliations which befell the modern papacy.
The brutal violence done to them and the courage with which they bore their grievous fate won
them
sympathy
throughout
the
whole civilized world. The final act of the Congress of Vienna on 9 June 1815 restored the Papal States to the Popes with little loss
of territory, Consalvi, the Cardinal Secretary
of State to Pius VII, began carefully to rebuild the badly shattered order. The new otder in Church and Papal States was set up, like the structure of most European countnes of the time, in the spirit of “restora-
tion”, the closest possible approximation to
conditions as they had been before the Revolution. But no *“Holy Alliance”, no between covenant concluded painfully “Throne and Altar” could bring back the days before 1789. The papacy seemed at first to find strong support in the new trends of the day. The Pope was applauded, by Protestantsas wellasCatholics, as the mainstay of the religious and conservative tendency and the guardian of “legitimacy”. Even more eagerly than the political forces, whose sincerity was often questionable and whose main interest was the preservation of order, the
poets
and
thinkers
of the
Romantic
Movement such as Novalis and F. Schlegel in Germany, hailed the papacy as their champion.
of the papacy. But the Popes of this century
In France, the genius and eloquence of Chateaubriand depicted Christianity as the religion which towered high above all
disasters that came upon them. When one looks at the long list, there are only a few
gyrics of the papacy is given by Joseph de Maistre in his Da pape of 1819.
to the Emperor Joseph IT at Vienna in 1782 are telling examples of the political impotence were
entirely
not
unmistakable
without
blame
for the
to changed
others. The classical example of such pane-
circumstances and abandon ocutmoded claims,
The French Revolution and the meteoric passage of Napoleon had unleashed forces
(1721-24),
channelled for a short while by the triumph
though short
efforts
to adapt
there were such efforts under
reign
of lnnocent
XIII
the
and especially under the cultured Benedict X1V (1740-58), as also under the unhappy pontificate of Clement XIV (1769-74). G. Tye Paracy
iN THE 191H CENTURY
The 19th century, the era which really runs
from the French Revolution to the First World War, is the century of revolution and
industrialization. With the revolution against tradition the tradition of reveolution also set
56
in Europe which could only be superficially
of the ancient regimes. The spirit which had provoked the upheaval could not long be gainsaid. After the banishment of Napo-
leon Europe was in a ferment in which forces
were working for and against the Church and the papacy. The new dawn which had come up in thunder also revealed new positive possibilities for the Church, Had they been taken up, the Church could have contributed considerably to the inward peace of the disturbed continent. But down to the end of
the century
the Popes
mostly
missed
the
POPE
chance of allying themselves with the just demands for freedom, for better living conditions for all and for sound progress — as they ought to have done to enable the
Church to carry out its task in the world. Time and again throughout the many years of grave decision the papacy of the 19th century proved to be completely at a loss. It took no major and inspiring initiatives. Down
to the pontificate
of Leo
XIII,
the
Popes were content in general with a hostile condemnation of the real and sup-
posed errors of the age, which were, however,
very widely regarded as laudable progress. Retrospectively it is clear throughout that the
restoration of the Papal States, which were in
the spiritual liberty of the Holy See, Pius refused to transform his crumbling
States
into 2 modern constitutional State. After the
revolution of 1848, when he had to flee in
disguise, he returned completely to the system of his predecessor, with the support of his Secretary of State, Cardinal Antonelli. The educated classes in the Papal States became more and more estranged from the Church and the papacy. They were embittered by a spiritual government which allowed no political freedom to the citizens and even interfered gravely with private life. The Ttalian Minister Cavour had little difficulty in exploiting this situation in
the
favour of national unity under the Piedmontese House of Savoy. During the FrancoPrussian War the remnants of the Papal
of Consalvi, and like his successor, Pius VIII,
porated into the new kingdom of Italy (1870). After some hesitation, Pius rejected the guarantees offered in the law of the new
a permanent state of mortal agony till their
inglorious
end
in
1870,
constituted
gravest hindrance to the universal task of the papacy. Leco XII (1823-29) abandoned the policy steered
a
strictly
centralizing,
absolutist
course. Gregory XVI (1831-46), personally
amiable and undemanding, remained as Pope the unworldly political innocent which he had been as 2 monk. His uncompromising notion of papal authority, as depicted in his 11 trionfo della Santa Sede of 1799, determined
the whole policy of his pontificate. The Papal States were heavily in debt and badly
administered,
but
the
necessary
reforms
were neglected. The Pope, like his successors, refused
to
countenance
the
Risorgimento,
the popular movement for nationzl unity in Italy. The Papal States were constantly convulsed by rebellions and assassinations, and papal rule could only be maintained
States, Rome and its hinterland, were incor-
Italian State. From then on he regarded himself as a prisoner in the Vatican. The Catholics of Italy who were loyal to the Church found themselves faced with a grave conflict of conscience, since they were
forbidden
by the Holy
See to co-operate
actively in any serious way with the State. Peace was only made in 1929 between the
Vatican and the Quirinal, the papacy and
the Italian State. Within the Church, the long reign of Pius was marked by the further growth of foreign missions and of the hierarchy, but still more by the increasing centraltzation in
Rome, by the flourishing state of popular
piety, in which the papacy playedanimportant
phenomena of the new age. In the encyclical
role, by the universal growth of Ultramontanism and by the progress of Catholic movements and parties in the potlitical
errors and the concrete claims of the liberalism
of neo-scholasticism,
with the help of unpopular foretgn troops. Gregory showed himself hostile to all the
Mirari vos of 5 August 1832, he rejected the which was then a mighty force throughout Europe, condemning along with indifferent-
ism the freedom
of the press and freedom
of conscience, and the principle of the separation of Church and State. Under Gregory, the way was paved for the predominance of the “Roman” theology of neo-scholasticism. He steadily supported the expanding foreign missionary activity of the Church and the development of the hierarchy. Under the pontificate of Pius IX (1846-78), the jubilztion which had greeted the accession of a supposedly “liberal” Pope soon gave way to a sober re-appraisal. In the name of
sphere. There was also the full development
the great affair of the
Syllabus with its list of eighty of the “main errors of the day” and the First Vatican
Council. The intention of Pius IX in publish-
ing
the
encyclical
Quanta
Cura
and
the
annexed Syllabus (1864) was to protest againstlaicization, naturalist views of religion and the erection of the will of the State or of
the human will to an absolute. A solid barrier was to be set up against the general process of
secularization and the spiritual revolution of the new age. The publication of the Syllabus,
in a set of propositions in which no reserves
ot distinctions were made, was greeted by a storm
of protest.
In libera] circles, and
also
57
a
1
-
-
'
.
f
-
A L
*
*
S LR
' I"|I’
POPE
" subseq there uen were varions tly forms of the mpf. giins and lay people, it was zegarded as 3 KulturkaFirst Vatican Council had taken up The among many open-minded Catholic theolo-
harsh rejection of modern culture and the
modern
State, as also of the conguests of
whete the Council of Trent had left off three
liberty in the last two hundred years. The preparations for the First Vatican
bundred years before, at 2 point whete the
declarations (1869-70) can only be under-
a2 definitive solution: the relationship of papal power to the other powers in the
Council, its actual course and its doctrinal
stood in the light of the situation of the Catholic Church and the papacy in the 19th century.
Only two of the schemas or drafis came before
the Council for discussion and these again were only voted on in part. The dogmatic constitution Def Filius, drawn up against
pantheism, materialism and rationalism, was
a clear, brief summary of Catholic doctrine
on God the Creator of all things, on revela-
tion, faith and
the relation between
faith
and reason. Serious difficulties arose only with the draft text of the De Eeclesia Christi
in which the position of the Pope in the
Church, his primacyand universal episcopacy, including the infallibility of his magisterium
in matters of faith and morals, were to be
dealt with. The dogmatic constitution Pastor Aetersus of 18 July 1870, having described the papal primacy over the whole Chutch, the full effective jurisdiction of the papacy, then goes on to define papal infallibility as follows: ‘““The Roman Pontiff, when speaking ex cathedra, that is, when in the exercise of his
office of pastor and teacher he defines with his supreme apostolic authority a doctrine
of faith or morals to be held by the universal
Church, possesses, through the divine assistanice which was promised him in blessed Peter, the infallibility with which the divine redeemet wished that his Church be endowed in the definition of a doctrine of faith
ot morals. Hence such definitions of the Roman Pontiftf are irreformable of themselves, and not by virtue of the assent of the
Church.” With the enunciation, as dogma, of the universal jurisdiction and the doctrinal infallibility of the Pope a long development had
reached a climax. As the worldly power of the papacy collapsed, the solidity of the Church was impressively demonstrated at a central point of vital importance. Some countries wrongly feared that the new dogma would cause a shift in the relationship
had struggled
Fathers of Trent
mast
pas-
sionately and finally given up the effort to find Church and in the wotld, the doctrine of the Chutch. In 1870, however, the solution given
was only a partial one, with the stress entirely on the papal element. The intespreta-
tion of the texts, which were very difficult in parts, and further clarification of the relation-
ship between Pope and bishops remained
a task for theologians. It was taken up once more ninety years later at the Second Vatican Council, where 2 more precise view of the functions of the Catholic episcopate was to restore the displaced balance. On the whole, the legacy of Pius IX was an oppressive one. Undoubtedly, the Catholic Church was inwatdly strengthened, but it stood in isolation within a hostile world. Leo XIIT (1878-1903), with his humanistic and conciliatory approach, succeeded in calming most of the storms and disturbances which had arisen, and in many ways initiated the correct approach of the Church to the modern world and its problems. Leo’s openness as regards the “social questions™ which had long become acute is significant. His Rerum Novarum {1891) began the series of the great papal social encyclicals. Intellectual discussion in the Church had been lamed and repressed in the fight for the Syllabus
Vatican
and
totally quenched.
I, but had
The views
not been
of the many
important theologians and laymen who aimed at up-to-date reforms soon led to new
conflicts, which are associated with the terms “Americanism”, ‘““Modernism’ and “‘Inte-
gralism”.
and
They
reached
started
a dramatic
under
Leo
climax under
XII
the
non-political Pius X (1903-14), whose main
concern was religious revival. Along with some wayward developments and errors
a
number
of
promising
initiatives
were
mercilessly suppressed. The fact that so many good men of all ranks, bound in love
medieval Popes. In some countries, especially
and a sense of responsibility to their Church and the papacy, were needlessly treated as heretics casts a dark shadow on the pontificate of Pius X — a Pope who did much for
were taken against the Catholic Church, and
Christo”)} and reforms within the Church.
between Church and State, seeing jt as a new assertion of the authoritarian claims
Prussia
58
and
Switzerland,
harsh
of the
measures
religious
renewal
(“Instaurare
omnia
in
POPE H., Tue Paracy 1Ny Tae 201w CENTURY
work,
As a historical era, the 19th century ended only with the First World War (1914-18).
The whole reign of Benedict XV (1914--22)
was within the shadows of this war, which he
tried in vain to shorten. His repeated efforts to act as mediator in the cause of peace, especially in 1917, ended in failure. In 1917
Benedict published the Code of Canon Law
which had been in course of preparation for many years and came into force at Pentecost, 19 May 1918. His encyclical Maximum illud of 30 November 1919 gave new directives
to Catholic missions. Europeanization was to be abandoned and due attention paid to the national and cultural charactenistics of the peoples in missionary lands. Continuing the preliminary work of Benedict XV, Pius XI (1922-39) worked hard
ruled the Church
from a centralized
standpoint during the war and the post-war
years. He found himself forced to extreme caution. The Pope had to be among and aboveall nations. He was soberly and emphatically reserved as regards all political systems and forms of State organization. True to the
motto which he had chosen on his election —
“Opus justitiae pax” — he strove for peace on the basis of justice. He took up many fundamental religious questions in his frequent allocutions and encyclicals. The greatness of his pontificate will only be fully measured in later times, when partisan hatred and favour have yielded to a dispassionate assessment. The brief but epoch-making reign of John XXIII displays clearly an unremitting
but completely relaxed and unhurried effort to understand and exercise the Petrine office in the spirit of sacred Scripture. John’s new
at the ecclesiastical consolidation of countries ravaged by war and constant revolutions. In the bankruptcy which was the legacy of
and often unconventional and even improvized style of Church government grew out
attention to the supra-temporal kingship of
Christian pastoral concern — but also out of
the
World
First
War,
called
Prmus
men’s
Christ. In 1929 the “Roman question” which had been kept open since 1870 was finally resolved. The Lateran Treaties made
peace between the Holy See and the Italian State. The Pope received the tiny Vatican City with some extra-territoriai estates as a
sovereign State ( Statodella Cittadel Vaticano ). It
was
a happy
The
solution.
necessary
external independence was preserved, without the burdens of a large State. Since the end of the old Papal States, the papacy has stood out all the more clearly as a spiritual institution, as a moral authority in the world, down to the present day. Many of the concordatsand otheragreements between Church and State under Pius XI were but of short duration. The Second World War (1939-45) shook
the world to its foundations in new upheavals.
This devastating war, withitsstill incalculable
consequences,
could
be prevented
neither
nor shortened by Pius X1 or his Cardinal Secretary of State and successor, Prus XI1.
Since the days of Benedict XV, the Popes had found themselves confronted —
in the
midst of a world to a large extent unChristian — by the anti-Christian totalitarian
systems of the century: by Fascism, National
Socialism and Communism
transmutations. formation,
Pius
extensive
XII,
in their various
with
historical
a classical
knowledge,
sober objectivity and a strong appetite tor
of his compelling human kindness and his
the conviction that the Church had to find
new, contemporary forms if it was to do its work properly in the modern world. The
hieratic rigidity in which
the Church
was
undoubtedly locked now came to be loosened. After a long period of papal centraliza-
tion, a2 new
sense of the significance of the
episcopate and of the co-responsibility of lay-folk in the Church began to develop. Immpelled by the spirit of brotherly love and a sincere desire to understand, a new phase began in the encounter with the Churches
separated
from Rome,
and a new encounter
ensued with the modern
world and all its
problems. The new insight into the Petrine
office was manifested above all in the effort
to promote the unity of all Christians and in
the
convocation
and
actual
course
of the
Second Vatican Council {1962-65), in the introduction of necessaty ecclesiastical re-
forms,
in
the
presentation
of
the
true
universality of the Church as transcending all
national and cultural barriers, 1n 2 new sense
of Christian responsibility for all mankind. The Second Vatican Council, brought to its conclusion by Paul VI (Pope since 1963), was the clear sign of the serious will of the
Catholic
Church
to
self-reform.
It was
a
fundamental re-consideration on the part of the Church with regard to its missionary mandate in the world of today. The pontificate of Paul V1 is wholly in the service of this
59
POSITIVISM programme. This may be seen from the consistent implementation of ecclesiastical reforms, and, externally, from such matters
as the meetings with the Ecumenical Patriarch
of Constantinople at Jerusalem and Istanbul,
the reciprocal annulment of the excommunications of 1054, the journey to the Eucharistic
Congress at Bombay and to the headquarters of the United Nations Organization at New York, meetings with representatives of non-
Christian religions, contacts with statesmen
including those of communist countries and the ceaseless, passionate endeavour to bring about peace and social justice.
It should not be forgotten that the break-
through
in the Church since John XXIII
would not have been possible without the
preparatory work done by the papacy since Leo XIIL In the last century and a half of the history of the Popes, the way has led from a hostile rejection of all seemingly menacing trends to a loving understanding
of the modern world, even of the fallen, guilty, irreligious world, inspired by a sense of Christian responsibility. In the 20th century
the papacy appears as a world power of the Spirit, which proclaims the word of God and serves the cause of justice and peace in an
unquiet and gravely threatened world. The Catholic knows in his faith that the Church and its papacy will live till the consummation of the world.
See also Early Church, Constantinian Era, Invasions ( Barbarian), Schism 111, IV, Crusades,
Middle Ages, Reform, Investiture Controversy, Avignon
Exile,
Renatssance,
Conciliarism,
Reformation,
ularization, fansenism,
Humanitm
Enlightenment,
Gallicanism,
1,
Sec-
Episcopa-
lism, Josephinism, French Revolution, Romanti-
cism, Liberalism and Liberal Theology, Indiffer-
entism, Charch and State,
Infallibility, American-
s, Modernism, Integralism, Ecumenical Movement, Church and World. BIBLIOGRAPHY.
See¢ the articles on the indi-
vidual Popes in DTC,
LTK,
Oxford Dictionary
of the Christian Church (1957), New Catholic Encyclopaedia (1967); also: L. von Pastor, The History
of the Popes from the Close of the Middle .Ages, 40 vols, (1891 8.); H. Mann, Liver of the Popes in the F:orly Middle
Ages,
18
vols.
(1902-32);
E.
Caspar,
Gesehichte des Papsttums von den Anfingen bis gur Flibe der Wheltherrsehaft, 2 vols. (1930-33); ]. Schmidlin, Papstgeschichte der newesten Zeit, 4 vols.
(1933-39); |. T. Jalland, The Church and the Papacy (1944);
(1960);
E. P.
E.
Y.
Paschini
Hales, and
Revolution
V.
and
Monachino,
Papacy
eds.,
I papi nella storia, 2 vols. (1961); F. X. Seppelt and
60
é!:.r zm' G’gamrr (1%@ Job# and bis Revolution (1965), G SCMe@_ Grschichie dar Pdpsie im 20, Jabrbunders,
sources and bibliographies (1968).
with
Georg Schwaiger
POSITIVISM 1. Philosophical, I1. Moral.
1. Philosophical 1. Concept. Positivism is not a definite doc-
trine which can be assigned to any particular
epoch of philosophy, but 2 certain attitude towards science and theory. It is always characterized by distaste for traditional philosophy, with especially sharp criticisin of metaphysics, not only with regard to certain tendencies or results, but even with regard to its basic problems and methods. It is further
characteristic
of neo-positivism,
as
the genuine development of older positivist principles, to make philosophy a science directed by the methods of the exact natural sciences. This does not lead to a categorical rejection of philosophy, but to the effort to set up a “‘new’”’, “different” philosophy, purified from zll unscientific, speculative or metaphysical elements.
The starting-point of positivism, epistemclogically, is that the only possible source of
knowledge is the empirically tangible datum, by which is understood the multiplicity of
sense
impressions.
All
the
assertions
of
traditional philosophy which go beyond this cannot be vertfied in the light of given facts
and hence are not objects of science.
The
human ego is ultimately the sum of a number of regular psychological, logical and other relationships. Its independence with regard to the world, in the sense of its being a person, cannot be deduced from the data and
hence i5 not an object of human knowledge.
2. History. There were positivist tendencies
in ancient scepticism, in Epicurus and the nominalism of the Middle Ages (in the controversy about universals). But the English empiricists are regarded as the real
founders of positivism. F. Bacon (1561-1621) sought to base all human knowledge on ex-
perimental and inductive science. T. Hobbes (1588-1679) rejected all metaphysical bases of law and only recognized law as laid down by the State. But the most decisive contribution to the development of posi-
POSITIVISM
tivism was that of D. Hume, who held that.
human knowledge could only rest on mathematics of on empirical facts. of causality is nothing of an
the sciences dealing with His discussion of the principle typical. Experience tells us intrinsic connection between
cause and effect. We can do no more than register how often the same result follows
the same cause and apply our experience to natural phenomena in the guise of “laws” recognized by us. Causality is not an objective link between
cause and effect, founded
on
being, but a subjective recognition of temporal succession which is arranged systematically
with
the
help
of
psychological
associations. Hume divides the data accessible to our cxperience and knowledge into two main groups: impressions, which arise both from sense perception and our experience of our
outward
ideas,
and
states,
inner
and
which are reflections of our impressions. Positivist
notions
to
came
the
France with the Encyclopédistes
fore
in
(I3’ Alem-
bert [1717-83] and Turgot [1727-81]). They also demanded that scientific activity should be restricted to what is perceptible by the senses and rejected all specuiative and hypothetical knowledge which went beyond the
of
domain
sociological
The
experience.
positivism of A. Comte (1798-1857) was the most influential of all. Applying the notion of science as concerned with facts to history, he divided it according to the three
scientific stages of humanity into the ages of
theology, metaphysics and positive sciences. In this process man frees himself from the
hondage and tutelage of faith in God and the then
gods,
fruitless
the
from
eflort
of
philosophy, and finally attains to independence
and
to mastery
over
nature,
whereby
he creates for himself the possibility intervening in the course of the world
of to
change and improve it (“voir pour prévoir, prévoir pour prévenir,
voir’).
prévenir pour pou-
The basic positivist attitude was given a new orientation in the neo-positivism which
originated in the Vienna Circle. It is distinguished from the older positivism by the
shift of philosophical enquiry to the realm of logic and linguistic research — the instru-
ments of scientific assertions. The most important representatives of this trend are M. Schlick, L. Wittgenstein,
Neurath
and
B.
Russell,
one
R. Carnap, of the
O.
main
proponents of symbolic logic. The task of philosophy is not the investigation
of facts,
which are left to the exact sciences, but the
logical analysis of the units of language (words, propositions, speech as a whole) with which we speak of the wotld (investigated by science). Neopositivists allow only two types of meaningful propositions: propositions about factual relationships stemming from experience (4 posteriori) and verifiable by experience; propositions about purely logical relationships which provide no knowledge about facts and hence are valid independently of experience.
The logical analysis of these propositions, which are made with the help of language, is the task of philosophy. According to Wittgenstein, philosophy is not a doctrine but an results
It
activity.
not
in
“philosophical
assertions” but in the clarification of propositions. Language can be reduced to “elementary propositions” deducible, as logical
data,
constructions,
from
elementary
the
them
the effort is to give
and
sense-
greatest possible consistency and exactness. This also helps to show that all the traditional
of philosophy
problems
are either strictly
scientific ones or are actually meaningless,
since the exact investigation of the logical
structure of language ultimately eliminates all false views about the object of scientific research.
3. A critical discussion of positivism must start with its claim to make philosophy an
exact
science.
The
positivist
attitude
is
induced by the scandal of disagreements in philosophy. In contrast to the natural sciences, with their constant gaining of ground,
philosophy gives the impression of being at a stand-still. The problems which philosophy took up at the beginning of its course still
remain unsolved. Positivism draws the con-
clusion
that
whatever
be
the
interest
of
philosophy, it provides no access to knowledge in the sense of science.
The preference of positivism for the purely factual and experimental is in keeping with the
mood
of
modern
times.
But
while
positivism boasts of its objectivity, it repre-
sents in fact an arbitrary and unjustified restriction both of the object and method of enquiry. Its method is to determine beforehand what can be accepted as real, thereby
forbidding reality to display itself in its full
ambit.
FExperience
is more
than
what
1s
equally available to all. Experience of the given is only open to us within a transcendental horizon. If philosophers failed to reach
61
N,
B
SITWISM .
agresment, amnm
")
frmlackufpxwfs
' but because their approach was dictated by
different presuppositions. in each case. Positivismn fails because it lacks openness to
experience in all its dimensions including the
religious and metaphysical, from which synthetic 4 priori judgments could be jus-
tified. This want of openness means that pasitivismo, in spite of its humane intentions,
is silent in face of the great human problems. But the verdict on positivism should not
be entirely negative. Without its restrictive negations it can be salutary. When it insists
that knowledge must build on human ex-
perience, it is a sharp reminder to the philosopher that his task is to explain and change
this world and not to construct possible worlds.
Further,
for proofs
its unconditional
of a statement
forms
demand
a good
counterpoise to the dogmatism which can appear in philosophy. The nature of truth is not just to satisfy the mind. [t must express the reality which is displayed in experience. Positivism has also a contribution to make to theology. It reminds the theologian that faith and redemption are not so much a matter of theory as of history and experience. If theology is taking on a new form today, it is partly because it recognizes that its first task is not the erection of a logical system but the
patienit investigation of what God has revealed. — For positivistic aberrations in exegesis, dogmatics, and moral theology, see
Biblical Exepesis1, DogmalV, Moral Theology . See also Principle, Knowledge, Logic, Natural Law 11, Empiricism.
IE Maml‘
L
|
1. The conceps. Motal positivisms hotiu&t the
denizl ‘of universal,
fibjflfitlw and changeiesy
norms in the moral order. Whenever the good is reduced to defimble norms and not
lc& in the state of a general exclusion of the bad, there is always some changein standards.
But moral pnfltwlsm also rejects all absolute
imperatives in morality, which might then in turn be formulated as changeless norms, No
human
acts are essentially good
or bad,
absolutely imperative ot forbiddtn, and hence possibly so for all men. The objective
morality of an act and the moral obligation in its regard do not depend on the mentality
and on the object of the act, but on something which is outside the object and can be subject to change,
2. Types. Two kinds may be distinguished.
a) Theonomous moral positivism holds that
the moral order depends for its structure and obligation entirely on the “absolutely” free will of God. It is not founded on the nature of God and a reality formed according to his “tmage”. Good is whatever God decrees is good, evil is whatever God decrees is evil. Moral values depend entirely on God’s free will. This view, held by Occam and the nominalists, is based on the assumption that
there is neither good nor evil prior to the decree of the divine will, which is absolutely free to decide one way or the other, b) Autonomous moral positivism holds that moral norms are not derived from the nature of things or of man, or from divine
A, Comte, Cours de philosophie
revelation. They are rather “invented” than
positive, 4 vols. (1851-54), E.T.: System of Positive Polity (1875-77; teprint, 1966); John Stuart Mill,
soctal life in its various political, economic and human relationships. This notion of the
BIBLIOGRAPHY.
positive, 6 vols. (1830—42); id., Systéme de politique
“uncovered”, their purpose being to regulate
A. Comie and Positivism (1866); L. Wittgenstein,
moral norms was already put forward by the
Tractatus logico-philosophicus (1922),
German
text
with E. T. by D. Pears and B. McGuinness {1961); R. Carnap,
The Logical Syntax of Langaage (1937);
M. Black, Language and Philosophy, Studies in Method (1949); V. Kratt, Der Wiener Kreis: Der Uriprang des Naapa.rififif:mm
(1950);
M.
Macdonald,
ed.,
Philosophy and Analysis (1954); R, Carnap, Meaning and Necessity (2nd ed., 1956); ]J. Lacroix, La soctologie d Anguste Comte (1956); ]. Hospers, Introduction to Philosophical Analysis (1956); A. ]. Avyer, ed., Lagical Positivism (1959); W. M. Simon,
Enropean Positiviim in the Nineteenth Century
(1963);
R. Carnap, The Logical Structure of the World (1964); id., Pseudoproblems in Philesophy (1964);
F. Belke, Spekulative und wissenschaftiiche Philosaphie (1966); K. Dirr, Metaphysik und wissenschaftiiche Philosophie (1967).
Robert Q. Johann
62
Sophists
of antiquity,
provides
no universally
who
held
that the
difference between right and wrong, good and evil, was based not on the nature of things but on human convention (so Protagoras, Aristippus and Gorgias). Montaigne and Hobbes likewise held that nature
valid norms,
The
only general rules are those laid down by the law of the State.
With the progress of the empirical sciences,
ethnology and comparative religion, more was learned about the differences in the moral
laws as formulated among various peoples. Doubts were expressed abour the existence of general and objective norms recognizable
POSSESSION, DIABOLICAL
as such. Developments were also noted in
the course of the history of ethics, which suggested that morals, like the rest of cul-
ture, had evolved from primitive starting-
points,
3. Critigue. It cannot be denied that morals
differ from people to people. And the differences are due to the various social,
“prophetic” formulation, the moral “imperative”, Seealso Discernment of Spirets, Ethics, Morality, Naitnral Law 1, Situation Ethics. BIBLIOGRAPHY.
Morakity;
also:
E.
A.
See bibiiographies on E#bicr,
Westermarck,
The
Origin
and Development of Moral Ideas, 2 vols. (1906-8);
the conclusion drawn from these data by the
H. Sidgwick, Outlines of the History of Ethics (6th ed., 1931); J. Leclercq, Les grandes lignes de la philosophie morale (1946); D. ]. B, Hawkins, M and Morals (1960); B. Russell, Human Society in
historical world of values, but because of an
lagir bumain (1962); A. tion: The Foundations of (1964); J. Maritain, J. Pieper, Reality and Melsen, Physical Science
economic and political conditions in each case. But the question remains as to whether
moral positivists is valid. Morality is reduced to an empirical problem. Nonetheless, it is more than a question of statistics and history — not in the sense that there is a supraunconditional dimension in moral reality, which remains beyond human measure even though ittakes concrete form in the historical. It is given with the essence of man and the
nature of things. Man’s self-realization as a
Ethics and Politics (1962); 1. de Finance, Fssai sur
Sesonske, Value and Obligaan Empiricst Etbical Theory Mora/ Philosophy (1964); the Good (1967); A. van and Etbics (1968).
Irenee Gonzdley POSSESSION,
DIABOLICAL
person and in society, his shaping of the world or his dealings with it, confront him with an “ought” in the demands of morality which is not at the mercy of his arbitrary will, The obligation is tc be defined for each concrete situation, but is of itself prior to each historical situation. The fact thar this claim of morality is given different answers at
In the study of religions, “possession’ means
that he is conditioned to some extent by his
hour™ of the good itself. The very changes
though his responsibility is diminished or at times totally absent, his personality is not tully disintegrated. The many evil powers mentioned in the
permanently the same, point not only to the opposition between an abstract, non-his-
power of evil, which is designated as Satan or the devil. Since they are called “power”,
contrast between a concrete, ““incarnational™
threats from higher powers. Their inward drive is towards corruprion and destruction
various times and in various places is simply due to the “‘historicity” of man - the fact
culture. But his history is what it is not just by the favour of man, but because it 15 “‘the which
ensue,
being
changes
of
what
is
torical “rationalistic” morality and the relativism opposed to it, but, above all, to the morality and a moral positivism which 1s in fact amoral. The contrast therefore is not between
being dominated by extraordinary forces of
good, personal or non-personal (see Enthuszasm). In Christian usage, it means the exceptional action of non-hurman but personal evil,
the
“principalities
and
powers”.
Someone is “beset” from outside or taken
possession of from within. He can fall sick,
physically and mentally, and break out in aggressive and blasphemous rages, but
NT
appear there as the agents uf a basic
“force”, “‘might”, etc., that s what they are:
(1 Cor 10:10;
]Jn 8:44),
iliness
and
death
(cf. the affinity with death, Mk 5:1f.), sin
the
(often connected with the devil, cf. 1 Jn 3: 8). They lie, disguise themselves as angels of
tions of it. Moral positivism has a real task to perform, but in a new and legitimate sense.
sow weeds among the wheat (Mt 13:39), They make themselves masters of the world.
rationalism and relativism, but between
comprehensive truth and one-sided falsifica-
The changeless good has in fact to be realized differently in time and place, on the social as
well as on the individual plane, and there is
always need to establish new positive norms.
In this sense, the task of moral positivism 1s
both to maintain the permanent cizims of the
“principles” and to aim also at the “applications™, the “discernment of spirits”, the
light (2 Cor 11:14), set saares (1 Tim 3:7),
They make the elements appear as gods (Gal 4:8f.; Col 2:104.). Political and social institutions (Rev 13) and historical situations (1 Thess 2:18; Rev 2:10) heir mischievous spirit. sphere, they are active in (1 Cor 10:196.;12:2; Rev
are permeated by In the religious heathen worship 9:20), they induce
feelings of self-complacency within the law
63
POSSESSION, DIABOLICAL (Ju 8:44; Rev 2:9), and defbrm the wisdom
of Christian teaching inte heresy (2 Cor 11:13€.; 1 Tim 4:1; 1 Jn 4:1). If men allow themselves
atmosphere,
to be infected by the they
become
Satanic
themselves: car-
riers of disease. They make room fotr the devil {Eph 4:27) and become his “children™ (cf. Jn 8:41,44). Thus sin is the work of both
man
and the
demonic
forces
devil
show
Mote
palpably,
themselves
the
in men
through illness and possession. The latter is then simply an exceptional manifestation
of a “religious” element which affects all men, that of demonic influences, ana can only be properly understood against this %‘El-?em background of dizbolical activity. ough in the NT possession as such is distinguished from sickness, the latter always has the connotation of possession, because
ultimately caused by The victim “‘has” the is his dwelling-place. is the place where the and the source from
the great destroyer. demon (Lk 8:27) and And again, the demon possessed man dwells which
he lives. The
usurpation can be so complete that the victim identifies himself with the demon{Mk 5:6.). However,
the
observable
phenomenon
of
possession is “already a combination of demonic influences and the mentality of an individual {or age), his dispositions, susceptibility to illness and even parapsychological powers. It 15 neither possible nor necessary
to distinguish
their various
proportions”
(K. Rahner, LLTK, 11, cols. 29941},
Though
God,
they
the
use
demons
their
were
power
as
created their
by
own,
in opposition to God. They have been overcome by Christ. His work on earth was an endless struggle against them. “The reason
the Son of God appeared was to destroy the
works of the devil” (1 Jn 3:8). Jesus commands in the power of God (Lk 11:20),
which is his through his obedience. His victory is complete, though the triumph is
not manifested before the parousia. Till then, the “principalities and powers” continue to work, though knowing that they are doomed (Mt 25:41; 1 Cor 2:6). Hence the virulence of their assaults (Rev 12:12), which
is particularly manifest in possession (Mt 8:28f.).
Their
attack
is
concentrated
on
Christ and his Church. Through baptism, Christians are exposed more than ever to such attacks, but are equipped to meet them,
Here it is also true that God allows no one
to be tempted beyond his strength and that the Christian can be his Christian self, 64
through grace, in every sitwation {cf+ D
1092). Jyst as the demon. is at work in the
“sons of disobedience” (Eph 5:6), so toa the
obedience of the Christian places him within the sphere of Christ’s victory. He bears in Christ the “armour of God”, part of which is “all prayer and suppliciation” (Eph
6:11-18). This usually takes the form of the “deliver us from evil” of the QOur Pather,
but there is also an exceptional form, the solemn prayer of exorcism uttered in the name of Christ and the Church and by their command. Since a clear distinction cannot be made
between possession and sickness, be-
cause every sickness can be at least to some
extent the effect of demonic forces, exorcism
and medicine go hand in hand in the struggle against possession. In view of the remarkable similarities between posscssion and the symptoms which can be observed in psychiatric clinics, extreme
reserve is necessary in diagnosing a case of possession. “The guiding lines laid down
by the Church are clear and firm, both for the recognition of a miracle or apparition
and for deciding on the reality of a case of demonic possession. A supernatural explana- |
tion of the facts may be accepted only when
every natural explanation is impossible and
has been proved to be so. To have reasonable
doubts, it is not necessary that the natural
explanation should be proved or that it is probable. It is enough if it remains possible. Furthermore, if something which is really pathological is taken to be supernatural on grounds which are not absolutely compelling, the harmful consequence ensues that the illness is ultimately encouraged and reinforced,
instead
of being
cured”
(J.
de
Guibert), It must also be noted that modern parapsychology shows that we must not be too hasty in declaring that something is beyond man’s powers. Hence many things which
were
once
taken
as
signs
of true
possession can no longer be taken as such, without further proof. In practice, the victim must be helped
to bear his trials with resignation, whether they be sickness or possession. He must be
convinced that even the demonic is spanned by divine providence and that God allows nothing that would be beyond human strength, with the help of grace. Anything which might make the sufferer more excitable must be avoided, such as any publicity, This latter precaution is very necessary where there is 2 disposition to hysteria. If the
POTENTIA OBOEDIENTIALIS
condition persists and deteriorates, the doctor
accepted (pofentia oboedientialis for the act). The legitimacy of this concept can of course
must be called in and eventually the Church
authorities, the latter alone being competent to decide whether the rite of exorcism should
only
Summers,
The
History
of Witcheraft and Demonology (1926); J. de Tonquédee, Les maladier merveuses ou mentales ot les
manifestations
diaboligues
(3td
ed.,
1938);
J.
de
Guibert, ZLegons de théologie spirituelle, 1 (1946), lecons 23--24; Safan { Etudes Carmelitaines) (1948); E. Fascher, Jesus und der Satan (1949); A. Rodewyk, “Die Beurteilung der Besessenheit”, ZKT 72 (1950), pp. 460-80; A. Huxley, The Dervils of Londun (1952); ]. Lhermitte, V'rais et fanx possédés (1956); H. Thurston, Gbhests and Poltergeisis (new ed., 1959); B. Thum, R. Schnackenburg, A. Rodewyk 294-300; H.
the
New
and K. Schlier,
Testamens,
(1961).
Rahner in L.7TK, 11, cols. Principafities and Powers in
Quaestiones
Disputatae
in
the
light
of the
his sclf-communication, the fulflment of the
See also Devil, Psychology IV M.
recognized
revealed truth that God himself can be, by
be used (cf. Ritwale Romansm, Titulus X1I, czp. 1, no. 3).
BIBLIOGRAPHY.
be
3
Karl Viadimir Trublar
spiritual creature. The creature is open to such fulfilment but still must accept it as a grace, not something owing to it. Hence too the concept can only be legitimately
applied to the relationship of nature and
grace (and hence also union). This does not analogy with the notion of in which every degree of because
of
the
divine
to the hypostatic exclude a certain self-transcendence, the created world, dynamism
of
its
becoming, leaves itself behind by rising to the next degree of being (see God-Worid
Relationship,
FEvolution).
But
this
self-tran-
scendence, which is implied in an evolution-
ary
world-view,
differs
from
the potentia
oboedientialis in the classical sense, inasmuch
as self-transcendence means the ahsorption of the earlier in the new (matter-life-spirit), while the porentia oboedientialis specifies a
possibility of self-transcendence in the direc-
POTENTIA
tion of immediacy
OBOEDIENTIALIS
found
in
Thomas
looser sense,
Aquinas
is already
and
Peter
of
Tarantasia. It is not found in early scholastic-
ism. In a very general sense, it means the capacity of the creature, obediently accepting the disposition and action of God, to receive a determination for which the creature 1s not “inpotency” in sucha way that this determination is *due” to it. The potency is not such
that if not actualized by the determination in question it would be frustrated, and hence
could not have been constituted by a wise creator
unless
this
determination
were
to
be added. The concept is used above all to
define
more
supernatural
in the
precisely
order (of grace) the relation between nature
and grace. Nature communication
to the creature.
2.
is a pofentia choedientialis
supernatural
the
for
The
a) Hence
grace,
of God,
material
the concept
which,
as self-
is in no way owed
content
of
the
which
does not
eliminate the nature of man. The concept of
1. The formal notion. The actual term, though
used in a somewhat
to God,
nolion.
of the potentia obne-
dientialis points to the fact that there can be a genuine fulfilment (act of the potency)
which is not due to the natute in guestion,
ie., cannot be counted on and claimed by virtue of the nature but only “obediently”
potentia oboedientialis can be explained in human terms through the experience of love between two persons. Each receives the love of the other as the fulfilment of his existence,
but still as a gratuitous gift which he cannot claim. by The potentia oboedientialis of man ot another spiritual creature for grace cannot be any individual potency (faculty, etc.) of a
particular,
regional
kind
/7 man.
This
is
excluded by the nature of grace as the selfcommunication
of God,
which of its nature
necessarily claims the whole man. It s also
excluded
by
the
concept
of
the potentia
oboedientialis ttself. For a particular faculty,
ordained from the outset only to actualization by grace would be frustrated without this actualization and hence would not be “aboedientialis’”. Hence the patentia oboedientialis
must be identical with the spirituai, personal
nature of man as such. By reason of 1ts unlimand konowledge in transcendence ited freedom, this nature can be potentiality for the
self-communication
of God,
since it is
thus capable of receiving this self-communica-
tion without being eliminated thereby and
ceasing to be a human
and creaturcly being,
This being is purely pofentia “obaedientialis”, hecause this unlimited natural transcendence
in knowledge and freedom, being the condi65
tion of possibility of personal being and
sexi’”, Angustinus concinente Thotma-séhisel
have meaning without this self-communica-
“La stmcturc analogique de'!’ tellfict, fondem ent
the mete condition of encountering the world (fellow-men and environment} in knowledge
and action. But if this transcendence is recognized as the material element of the
poténtia oboedientialis, one sees that grace fs still the fulfilment of the spiritual nature itself — not something tacked on arbitrarily and ‘“‘extrinsically” to the being of man, Nature is not pure potency for grace in the sense of a purely negative non-repugnance,
as it is often described in modern theology. In warding off this misunderstanding, the doctrine of Aquinas about the desiderium naturale of the vision of God is still relevant. The fulfilment of a nature and the gratuitousness of that fulfilment are not contradictory concepts in the case of spiritual beings. c) Inasmuch as the spiritwal faculties (intellect, will) participate in the unlimited transcendence of human nature and effectuate it, one can of course also speak of their being
potentia oboedientialis for supernatural grace. Inasmuch as these faculties necessarily have active aspects as well as passive, the notion of a potentia obeedigntialis activa cannot be absolutely rejected as meaningless. But when
Lagrange,
obédientielle
av
surnaturel”,
miste 10 (1927, pp. 3-1%; R. Gamgou “L'appétit
naturel
et la puissance
obédienticlle”, Reswe Thomiste 11 (1928}, pp 474-528; G. Laporta, “Les notions d'appétit naturel et puissance obédienticlle chez S, Thomas”, ETL 5 (1928), pp. 257-77; P, Balzaretti, “De natura appetitus naturalis”, Asgeficum 6 (1929),
pp- 352--86, 519-44; H. Lange, D¢ Gratia (1929),
especially pp. 525fl' A. Pirotta, “Disputatio de
potentia nboedlentmh“ Divus Thomar (Piacenza) 32 (1929), pp. 574-85; 33 (1930), pp. 12548,
360-85,
560-75;
M.
Blondel,
Lz problime de /s
Natural Desire for God
in 8t. Thomas”™,
philosophie satheligue (1932); A. Darmet, Les notions de raison séminale et de puissance obédientielle cheg S. Thomas et S. Angustin (1934); A. Rainer, “De possibilitate videndi Deum per essentiam”, Divus Thamas (Piacenza) 39 (1936), pp. 307-30, 409-29; 40 (1937), pp. 3-21, 113-28; W. R. O’Connor, “The
New Scholastivism 14 (1940), pp. 213-67; V. Carro, “La distincién del orden natural y sobrenatural, segian St. Tomas y su trascendencia en la teologia y en el derecho”, Ciencia Tomista 62 (1942), pp. 274-300;, H. Bouillard, Conversion et grice cheg St. Thomas d' Aquin (=
Théologie 1} (1944}, pp.
80-82; E. Elorduy, “La potentia obédiencial en Suirez”, Lar Ciencias 9 (1944), pp. 815-33; L.-B. Gillon, “Aux origines de la puissance obédientielle”, Revwe Thomiste 47 (1947), pp. 304-10; V. de Broglie, De fine uitimo bumanae vitae (1948),
pp- 245—6G4; G, Frénand, “Esprit et grice sanctitiante”, La pensée catholigue 5 (1948), pp. 25-47;
H.
de Lubac,
“St. Thotnas.,
Compendium
theo-
rightly understood, in contrast to many Molinist theologians, it means that man per-
logiae, c. 1047, RS R 36 (1949), pp. 300-5; M. ].
from a faculty already elevated by grace. The
all’apertura dell’ordine naturale a quello
forms a salutary action which does not come
action only receives this elevation qua act.
See Grace and Freedom.
3. The notion of potentia oboedientialis can also be applied correctly to the relationship
of the human nature of Jesus Christ to the
hypostatic union. (See Imcarnation.) Human nature
is
a pofentia
oboedientialis
for
the
radical self-expression of God, which is actualized in Jesus Christ. (See K. Rahner,
Theological
157-92.)
Investipations,
BIBLIOGRAPHY.
V
[1966),
pp.
See bibliographies on Grace,
Nature and Grace; also: |. von Kuhn, Natur and Ubernatur (1864); K. von Schitzler, Natur und Ubernatur (1865); M. Limbourg, “Uber die
potentia oboedientialis”, ZX7T 16 (1892}, pp. 231-72; R. Martin, “De potentia passiva hominis ad gratiam et de potentia obocdientiali®, £TL 1 (1924), pp. 3526f.; A. D'Alés and A. Gardeil, “Autour
de
la
puissance
obédientielle’”,
Revwe
Thomiste 3 (1926), pp. 523 -7; . Sestili, “De natura
Deo
66
subiecta
in ordine ad supernaturalia
quid
Scheeben, Gesammelte Gnade (4th ed., 1949);
Schriften, 1: Natur und G. Cali Ulloa, *“Intorno
naturzle”, Sapienga 5 (1952), pp. 242-56;
sopra-
H. Urs
von Balthasar, “Der Begriff der Nartur in der Theologie”, ZXT 75 (1953), pp. 452-64; E. Gutwenger, “‘Nator und
Ubernatur™, ZKT 75 (1953),
pp- 482-97; ]. Martin Paluma, “La potencia obédiencial activa en el plano metafisico segin
Suirez”, Archive Teoldgico Granodine 16 (1953), pp. 32?—75; G. Colombo, “Il problema del sopra-
natutale”, Problemi et orientaimenti di tealogia dom-
matica (195?)
pp. 5>45-607
(with bibliography);
V. Canchy, Diésir naturel et béatitnde chez §. Thomas (1958); J. Alfaro, “Person und Gnade”, Mflnrbe— ner Theologische Zeitschrift 11 (1960), pp. 1-19; U. Kihn, Nater and Gnrade (1961); K Rahner,
‘Cflncernmg the Relationship between Nature and Grace”, Theological Investigations, 1 (1961) pp. 297-318; E. Przywara, Religionsphilosophische $chriften (]962) especially PP 443-59; B. Stoeckle, “Gratia supponit naturam’, Geschichte wnd Anralyse
eines theologischen Axioms (1962); H. Rito, Recentioris theologiae guaedam tendentiae ad conceptum ontologica-personalem gratize (1963); G. de Braglie,
“Possibilité et impossibilité de la ‘foi naturelle’”, RSR 52 (1964), pp. 541, 370-410; D. Dockx, “Du désir naturel de voit 'essence divine selon St. Thomas
d’Aquin®,
Archives de Philosophie 27
TN
the transcendence were actualized only as
R#FHETga
uissance
T T
tion of God, i.e.; if the reference to God in
Thomas (Piscenza) 4 (1?2'?},;? 57-93; A.Gatdeil,.-
N
freedom’s histoty,; can be in act and hence
Diows
N
POTENTIA OBOEDIENTIALIS
POVERTY
(1964), pp. 49-96; H. dc Lubac, Augustinisme o théologie moderme (= Théologie 63) (1965); K.
Rahnet, “Nature and Grace™, Theological Investigafioms, IV (1966), pp. 165-88; H. de Lubac, The Mystery of the Supermatural (1967); K. Rahner,
Hearers of the Word (1968).
Karl Rabner
POVERTY I. Christian Poverty. II. Medieval Movements.
they embody men’s sheer need of deliverance,
I. Christian Poverty
Poverty is a lack of the means of subsistence
(food,
clothing,
shelter,
and
so
on).
But
besides privations of this kind, poverty also connotes helplessness when faced with the demands of life: ignorance, wezkness, bondage, isolation, defencelessness against injustice. Such poverty is more or less relative. The most radical experience of poverty is the absolute destitution of death. 1. Seripture. Revelation gives poverty its
full meaning which
both
opens
a man
as inescapable for God,
and
distress
as the
humble, loving abandonment of one’s own
rights. a) Though the OT often represents wealth as a blessing and poverty as divine chastisement and retribution, the rich man as godly, the poor man as a sinner, the prophets and
post-exilic thinkers began to realize that the rich man is all too likely to harden his heart
at the distress of his neighbour, to succumb
to self-righteous “‘impiety”’, ruthlessly using his power to exploit others, whereas personal
experience of distress often fosters solidarity with one’s fellow-sufferers {(in exile, for
instance). It was the humiliating experience of want
and
servitude
in Babylon
tion. So seriously did he take men’s distress that he proclaimed the poor blessed and promised that they should have their £l (Mt 5:1-12). He promised salvation (Mt 11:1-6) to all who in their need should trust him, not presuming to shut themselves against him (Mt 9:12). The “food” which Jesus promises the hungry is the kingdom of God. Thus he does not come as a social revolutionary. He loves the poor because
which
and because in their distress they are prepared to listen to his message. He shares their poverty, requiring the same poverty of those who would follow him (Mt 8:20 par.; 19:12-21
par.),
so that they
may
devote
themselves wholly to God’s kingdom. Jesus
does not commend poverty out of contempt
tor wealth or for purely ascetical reasons (ct. Mk 14:3-9; Lk 8:2f.; 10:38). Christ makes love for our suffering brethren mean-
mgful (Mt 25:31-40) as a disclosure of the Father’s perfection and glory (Mt 5:16, 48). The famifia Dei (Jn 15:9-17) is grounded in helplessness freely accepted and sincere altruism. Acts 4:32 (““they had everything in
common”) does not mean that the primitive
Church rejected private property; it explains the preceding statement: ““The company
of those who believed were of one heart and
soul.” In the NT
only the Letter of James
ical
his
actually condemns possessions and riches. Jesus’ attitude, especially the sacrifice of his life for his brethren, reveals the soteriologcharacter
of
poverty.
In
him,
ali
poverty is a sign of man’s forlorn and needy state, and at the same time a possible way of salvation. 2. Moral
recognized
theology.
by
the
Poverty
sufferer
must
first be
as a fact.
By
chiefly made poverty a religious term, synonymous with “humility” and “piety” (Isaiah, Psalms, Zechariah, Proverbs). For
nature every form of poverty demands admission of one’s own inadequacy. It is
Israel, which
finds refuge only in its God
efforts, whatever the successes of civilization
and
development brings new problems and dangers — or first makes us aware of them. Man can never make his life perfectly secure,
Isaiah
(14:32;
the
preached
“poor”
25:4;
are
49:13).
to these,
simply
God's
“Yahweh's
oppressed
kingdom poor”,
1is
they are exhorted to await his coming glory
with perfect trust. b) New Testament. It is only with Christ that the religious significance of poverty
becomes fully clear. His unbounded abnega-
tion and self-sacrifice unto death reveal the glory of the Father (Phil 2:5-11}. Sharing
men’s distress unto the end, Christ made the
living God present by his death and resurrec-
part of the human condition that distress can
never be altogether abolished, whatever our
and technology, that each advance, each new
Certain privations are thrust upon us; certain
others
must
be “voluntary”
in a special
sense - the sacrifice of our life, or something
precious, if the gnod of our neighbour or of the community requires it, or it we know we are called to follow Christ and serve God’s kingdom.
67
POVERTY
a) Material poverty. In the Western wotld
only
isolated
individuals
lack
the
bare
necessities of life. The understanding of povetty bas largely disappeated from these countries. Instead of material poverty we often find other forms of poverty— desolation of heart, a sense that life is meaningless,
anxiety, isolation —which must be interpreted 2s 2 kind of longing for redemption and love. A Christian who finds these things in himself ot in others must accept them in the spirit of Christ as a means of encountering God, as a call to travel new roads in Joving our neighbour. Besides such distress, there is the appal-
ling poverty of Asian and African peoples, which demands an enormous extension of
Christian love. We may no longer confine it to a narrow circle of people close to us, we must love people afar, everywhere. For if
voluntary poverty can be a redempttve thing,
destitution can beget hatred, bitterness, and
despair, and be a sign that men have not found love. Particular works of mercy alone
(almsgiving and works of “supererogation”)
can no longer cope with world-wide poverty.
Rational planning
is necessary.
Christians
must realize once more, as the primitive Church did, that private property is a trust,
given us to be intelligently used for the needs of all in accordance
with
*“social justice”,
This may mean renouncing personal wealth and the power it brings. Certainly we must consider how far certain economic systems (such as economic liberalism and uncontrol-
led capitalism) can be transformed so as to satisfy
justice
and
answer
contemporary
needs. No effective help can be given in modern mass societies without soundly organized, well-directed co-operation. b) “Spiritual poverty” plays an important role in Chnstian life. It means trying to live “as one who hopes”, humbly, in expectation
of Christ’s coming, leatning to dismiss the
cates of this acon in Christian detachment, The Christian is undemanding, and frugal in managing his goods. Religious seek to practise a special form of spiritual poverty, the basis of which
munities as such, St. Francis of Assisi gave this poverty its deepest and most beautiful form, Coenstant readiness to serve the kingdom of the good of one’s fellow-men, patience, love of one’s enemies,
are the fruit of spiritual poverty, which is 68
and
phatisaic formalism, the touchstone of genuine spitituality, what makes our total expropriation at death a salutary testimony.
3. The Church of the poor. People sometimes
speak romantically of the “Church of the poot”, There are two dangers here. Firstly,
Christians may be asked to livein a “Franciscan” way which is in reality only a dream of
the past,
This
is to ignore the changed
economy and manners of modern society, which is after all part of God’s providence. Secondly, this romantic ideal could be used
to evade the duty of alleviating (or even abolishing) distress to the extent which Jesus’ command of charity imposes on his disciples. After all, man’s increasing mastery of the world and his own political economy must be seriously acknowledged as a divine challenge, which summons Christians to be abreast of such developments in giving practica! effect to their charity. Nonetheless, just as there is no ultimate security in human life, whatever man'’s technical achievements,
so0 too in a deep theological sense the Church
will always remain “poor” — men following the Lord who emptied himself, accepting in faith and confidence the abandonment into which Christ preceded them in his death.
See also Charity 11, 111, Justice Y1, Evangelical Counsels, Soctal Mavements 111, IV, V. BIBLIOGRAPHY.
religiense
panvreté
La pauvreti. Probiimes de ia
daujourd’bni
(Paris
1952);
A.
Gelin, Ler panvres de Yapré (1953); P. Grelot, “La
pauvreté dans I’ Ecriture Sainte™, Christas 8 (1961),
pp. 306-30; G. Lucques, La nonvelle pauvreté (1961); ]. B. Metz, Armut im Geiste (1962); V.
Breton,
ed.,
Lady
Christian
Porerty
(1963);
Responsibility
(1963); G. Montin,
and
A.
McCormack,
World
Poverty
The Christian in the Material
World (1964); P. Régamy, Poverty (1964); Y. Congar, Power and Porverty in the Church (1964); A. -van Corstanie, The Covenant with God's Poor
(1966); 1. Gobry, Through the Needle's Eye (1967); F. Mussner, Der fakobusbrief (2nd ed., 1967), especially Excursus 1 on the spiritnality of the poor (E.T. in preparation).
Sigismund Verbey
is the actual, voluntary
poverty of individuals if not of their com-
God and penitence,
self-righteousness
for
best cure
the
II. Medieval
Movements
Many currents in a complex and many-sided
movement for renewal of the Church in the 12th, 13th and 14th centuries were stimulated
and
shaped
by
the
ideal
of evangelical
poverty, The Church — not only or even mainly the hierarchy — was attempting to do
POVERTY
justice to the contemporary
situation,
to
find a form for itself that would both accord
with its tradition and be appropriate to the times. The original concem of the reform movement was to establish the “liberty of the Church”, to free it from lay control as embodied in the system of imperial and proprietary churches. Its efforts to this end, first directed against the abuses resulting from too close an involvement of the Church in the world, led to 2 major separation of the
spiritual
domain
from
the
temporal
and
fostered the ideal of a spiritual Church apart from the world (thus Joachim of Fiore, for example). The conflict between Church and
Empire logically followed from the Church’s
growing sense of independence, its claim to primacy over the temporal power, and an associated idea of the Church that was rather narrowly clerical. Once disengaged
from the structures that had hitherto given it support and protection, the Church itself
laid claim to worldly powers, as was particu-
larly clear in the centralization of the Roman Curia and the papal claims to universal rule, e.g., by Innocent ITI. But the medieval Church, in spite of all its efforts, could not altogether separate itself from secular structures. The leading role in this Christian society increasingly devolved upon it, and even in the nonspiritual realm it had become part of the texture of the West. This may be seen from
the
impractibility
of the
solution
to the
Investiture Controversy proposed by Paschal IT and the unsuccesstul pontificate of Celestine
V. At the turn of the millennium, to be sure,
the compenetration of the spiritual with the power
temporal
had
been
beneficent,
and
prince bishops (like Ulrich of Augsburg) were revered as the kind of saint appropriate to the times. Even when the papacy had
triumphed over the emperar, the best representatives of the poverty movement did not object to the Church’s temporal grandeur;
and the mightiest of the Popes, [nnocent 111,
recognized poverty.
the
legitimacy
of evangelical
Moreover, the Crusades
were mo-
tivated not simply by the Church’s new consciousness of power but to a great extent by religious enthusiasm as well, and there is no doubt that they helped to turn the renewal
of secular politics, and not alone in the
struggle for supremacy berween Pope and emperor and in the tremendous influence of the Cluniac reform, Even the movement of the Pawperes Christi was not devoid of worldly interests. This is clear as early as the Patarines of Lombardy. Evangelical poverty influenced the Crusades and the foundation of the orders of chivalry. And it did not prevent St. Bernard of Clairvaux from intervening in politics. It sometimes threatened Church and State with nearanarchy (cf. Arnold of Brescia and Peter Waldo with the one-sided spiritualist conclusions they drew from the evangelic renewal; the Catharists with their unchristian dualism),
Nevertheless,
the tendeny
from the world, which
to withdraw
for various
reasons
kept reappearing in one form after another,
was basic to the medieval reform movement.
Large numbers were attracted to the monastic
life, and this flight from the wotld found characteristic expression in the eremitical
movement, which combined the tradition of the Eastern anchorites with the cenobitical
life, usually
Benedict
on the basis of the Rule
(for
example,
the
of St.
Camaldolese
and Carthusians). The simplicity and austerity
of life in the wilderness were also found attractive, as by the Cistercians. The cases of St. Bernard, and of St. Peter Damian, who
exerted a powerful influence as an ecclesiastical statesman
and author,
show
that strict
detachment from the world did not necessarily mean that one could not make oneself felt in the life of the Church.
The popularity of pilgrimage, which en-
couraged
many
to forsake
all things,
was
another facet of flight from the world. This
form of piety, which also contributed to the
Crusades (cf. Peter of Amiens and his followers), took on 2 different character when the more mobile townsmen began to
develop a monetary economy alongside the
stable,
localized,
agricultural
feudal society. The new
bourgeoisie
{rising
both
economy
of
men of the rising economically
and
soctally) now take abandonment of the world to mean turning their custom of “travelling about the world for the sake of gain” (St.
Francis of Assisi, Regula non bullara, cap. 8)
into an apostolic way of life, and proclaim
the gospel
as itinerant
preachers
without
of medieval piety in the direction of evangelical poverty.
money or possessions, living on alms (7644., cap. 9). No doubt, the beginnings of this
movement made themselves feltin the domain
mitical and monastic life, Robert of Arbrissel,
On the other hand, the effects of the reform
movement are closely linked with the ere-
69
POWER
for example, and Norbert of Xanten, with their followers, based their community life on the Benedictine or Aungustinian rule, in accordance with the requirement of eccle-
siastical authority that some existing rule be
adopted (for example, Fourth Lateran Council, can. 13). But the later forms of the
mavement for poverty retained their own
proper character — the Waldensians in opposition to Church authority, and the Franciscan Order as a renewal of Christian
life 2ccepted by the Church as thoroughly Catholic.
In this situation the dualistic rejection of
the world
preached
by the Catharists
was
dangerously misleading. Their condemnation of the Church’s wealth and worldliness sprang from such wholly unchristian prin-
St. Bernard
of Chiirvaux — increasingly
became the spur of reform, the standard in the light of which men judged the successors
of the apostles,
sometimes
therefore
occasion of anti-clerical movements (the Waldensians, for example) in cases where the clergy were hostile to change. St. Francis of Assisi set the most felicitous example of holy poverty, combining affirmation of the world with utter seif-denial in an evangelical life that he made acceptable to the Church of his titme, without any suggestion of dualism or anti-clericalism. Quarrels
among the Friars
Minor (over the question of mendicancy and communal property) later led to institutional forms being imposed on the spirit of religious poverty in the Order of 5t. Francis and in the Church.
The vital urge was thereby,
tion and the visibility of the Church.
no doubt, to overshadowed.
which the reform movement characteristically referred, whether aiming at correcting
See also Reform 1, Middle Ager 111, Crusades, Catharists, Religious Qrders.
ciples that they even denied Christ’s incarna-
Primitive observance was the criterion to
abuses or at establishing new forms of life. Thus monks who adopted oriental practices and withdrew into desolate places revived the Benedictine rule in a new, austere observ-
ance, notably in the Cistercian reform. The case of St. Bernard indicates on what depths the renewal of religion drew, not motivated by the letter of the rule or human achievement but by the redemptive image of the incarnate
Son of God who became poor for our sake.
Many clerics, too, no doubt influenced in part by the monastic revival, began to embrace a life of poverty. It was chiefly the Augustinian rule that commended itself to these zealous reformers. It became the rule,
for example, of Orders founded tensians) and St. affected by the entered
the Austin Canons and the by St. Norbert (PremonstraDominic. Laymen too were religious awakening: they
monasteries
as
cemverst,
or
formed
secular brotherhoods associated with religlous houses 50 as to live a semi-momnastic lite in the world. The orders of chivalry are
notable examples.
Whatever part was played by the influence of the Crusades and by changing social conditions, the religious renaissance in the
medieval Church sprang largely from new
reflection on the gospel and the life of Christ,
on the manner of life of the apostles (ILk
9:111.) and the primitive Church in Jerusalem (Acts 2:4411. and 4:32f1.). The poverty and
humility of Christ, the vita apostolica — already the theme of the new Benedictine piety, as in 70
thé
some
BIBLIOGRAPHY.
extent
repressed
or
Curia,
D. Douie, Nature and Effect
of the Heresy of the Fraticelli (1932); H. Grundmann, Religidse Dewegungen im Mittelalter (1935); P.
Hughes,
A
History of the Chaurch,
111 {1947);
A. Fliche and V. Martin, eds., Histoire de 7’ Eglice (194811.), VII, pp. 427-62; IX[1, pp. 13-42, 91-132; 1X/2, pp. 288-352; X, pp. 156-94; M.
D.
(1961).
Lambert,
Franciscan
Poverty,
1210-7323
Sigtsmund Verbey
POWER 1.
Nature
of the gquestion.
There
are
two
theological reasons why it is important to understand what is meant by power. a) Power is one of the primary religious tdeas;
mankind’s
awareness
of God
is an
awareness ot him as powerful. Power is of the first of God’s attributes. That is the case in OT and NT revelation. possihility and existence of the creation
on
God’s
omnipotence;
the
election
one also The rest and
guidance of Israel are viewed as its manifesta-
tion in history; Jesus’ good news concerns the reign and kingdom
of God,
that is, the
perfect expression and exercise of his power;
as Christ and Lotd, Jesus shares in that power and even the new knowledge of the God who is love discloses this love precisely as the essential and central feature of God's power. b} A right attitude to power is fundamental in human social relations. The Christian’s
POWER
citizenship
in heaven
(Phil 3:20), and
the
knowledge that to Christ the Lord all power
is given in heaven and earth (Mt 28:18) and that he will return to establish and perfect
God’s kingdom, exclude any absorption in
the possession of, striving for, exercise of or dependence on earthly power. Renunciation of force and the passive suffering of violence are imposed as an obligation on his disciples
by Jesus’ teaching and example. Nevercheless, power 13 to be exercised by God’s commission
for the sake of 2 well-ordered life in this aeon
(Rom 13:1). Readiness to accept this acon as
the moment granted by God will lead to serious respect for power as well, In fact, out of charitable respoasibility for others, the Christian must even be ready on occaston to
the second degree, the difference enters into the being of beings itself: power as active self-preservation in being. This stage is met with when the being of beings goes out of
itself, when this present being determines its future form. Such power only occurs where
being is “‘present to itself”; then it attains the
plane of self-determination and is an active potency and faculty, freedom. Yet power is only perfect and reaches its highest and authentic level, when being can determine not only itself, its own form, but can also determine what is other than itself which comes to exist by it, yet without its origina-
tor’s ceasing to be one with itself and to endure. This is power no longer as persistence
in being,
nor as self-preservation,
but as
assume and exercise power, though here too he will only hold it as though he did not
giving. Such power, however, annuls in itself the difference between present and
2. Natnre of power. 2y Power is chiefly in question in the sphere of human social
everything
(1 Cor 7:2911).
reiations, but it is also present in nature and
indeed in all domains of reality. To exist is the most universal and primordial form of power; what s, In proportion as it is, is powerful; being and power are identical, Why then speak of power at all and not merely of being? Power is both identical with being and an intenstfication of being, 2 “plus”
being,
alwavs
being.
At
the
intended
very
in
and striven for by
least
it signifies
that
mysterious “plus” contained in the fact that
the being of beings does not simply disappear
and
dissolve
quired
remains
1nto,
when
it is contemplated,
grasped:
tdentical
with
it is
“‘still”
itself, remains
it was despite the difference berween and earlier; man
perceived
it, inquired
in-
there, what
later Into
future. power
It is the productive, creative of being itselt, thanks to which exists and
is what
it is, and
by
which everything ultimately — in the passive sense — can be, in other words, omnipotence.
c) All beings presuppose the omaipotence which causes them to be and determines their
being. Such a power itself cannot therefore
be
a particular
powerful
being,
it must
yet
in
absolutely
order
and
to
be
pre-emi-
nently bear within it the degrees of power. Omnipotence absolute
must
source,
be
thought
in possession
of as
an
of itself and
freely deciding what is not itselt. By causing this
other
to
be,
it gives
it a share
in its
power, empowers what is not itself to persist
in being,
freely
to preserve
itself and
to
transcend itself by giving. For finite being to transcend itself freely into what is other than
itself, is only possible in social inter-relationships; here power has its authentic and
The idea of power does not arise in the silent
highest place within the creation. Power is thus essenatially identical with love: power, like love, is unity with itself in bestowing being on what 1s other than itself and allowing 1t to be and to be free.
maintain its unity with irself if it is to manifest
3. Political sncial pewer is the will of individ-
it, dealt with i1, but it proves resistant to his grasp, maintains itself against him, For power
to be in question a “difference”™ must intervene, the possibility of negation, or otherness.
absorption of pure being; the latter has to itself as powerful. Power 1s unity of being with itself despite a difference, the presence of future being in present being.
uals or groups exercising determining influ-
lowest, which belongs to the being of beings, and is identical with it, has just been examined:
powerful by the mere fact of willing, but because it imposes what it wills externally.
outside and maintains its own identity. With
at the same time it represents their will, by
b)
Power
exhibits
three
degrees.
The
power as persistence in being. The difference here, in face of which being persists, 1s external to it; being is called in question from
ence
on
people
the communal
within
otganized
life of a number
a common
strucrure.
Such
living a
will
space 1s
of
or
not
This external domain is the living space shared by a number ot people; they carry on their existence there, 1t is their “world”, and
71
PRAGMATISM
L}
which they fulfil themselves in their world.
If the powerful will works through the freely consenting
1
L]
will of others
in 2 common
domain of reality, power assumes the form of authority. If it acts directly on the external
" and manifested by the Father in the tesurreeof the Son.
power
tion as the supreme
Nevertheless the cross of power involves for
the Christian not only readiness for seifsacrifice, but willingness to accept power in
reality and determines the world of other people’s wills from outside, it takes the form of force. The possibility of foree belongs to power, but the latter is all the more powerful the less force it needs to employ and the more
its vulnerable earthly conditions. But even then it will only be accepted with detachment and will be valid only because it comes from
from extrinsic means. However, in the world
tions
nated; in the widest and fundamental sense
Totalitarianism, Revolution and Restoration Political Theology.
the power flows from within and not merely
as it is in fact, force cannot be entirely elimiit is posited by the very fact of corporeal
existence. The powerful will must not only be at one with the world and with the consenting will of the others who acknowl-
edge it, it must be at one with itself. This demands that what it wills ought to exist and its act ought to be posited, i.e., power must
be good and must be rightful. Finite will is not its own independent ground, consequently it must be responsible, and therefore good;
it must be empowered to act and therefore
God.
On the problems of the concrete manifestaof
power,
Authority,
State,
BIBLLIOGRAPHY.
see
the
Church
B.
articles
and
Russell,
Sitate,
Power,
Socdety,
Law,
A
1,
New
Social Introduction to its Stedy (1938); G. Ritter, Démonie der Macht (1940); B, de Jouvenel, Dx powvoir.
Histoire naturelle de sa croissance
E. Brunner, Mclver,
(1945);
The Divine Imperative (1947);
R,
The Web of Government (1947); A. Pose,
Philosophie du Freedom, Power P. Tillich, Love, dini, Power and
powveir (1948); and Democratic Power and Justice Responsibility. A
K. Mannheim, Planning (1951); (1954); R. GuarCosurse of Action
rightful; in that way it becomes authority. The real purpose of power is the powerfulness of what is good and right, in the form of the
Jor the New Age (1961); W. Foerster, ' ¢ovola™,
of the will with the world, “horizontally” in
Kiaus Hemmerle
common good. Power is therefore a harmony harmony
with
other
wills
in
a
TWNT,II,
pp. 560-75; K. Rahner, ““The Theol-
ogy of Power”’, Theological Investigations 1V (1966),
pp. 391-409; |. B. Metz, (1969).
Theology of the World
society
deciding and shaping a common world, and
“vertically” in harmony with the norm of the
PRAGMATISM
effective ordering of human society as existence in the world.
Pragmatism is the name gtven to a philosophical trend which appeared in the U.S.A.
4. Pawer and powerlessness. Power is at once
tounder was Charles Saunders Peirce (1839
good and rightful. In short, power
is the
persistence, self-preservationand giving. The
dimensions which are coterminous in omnipotence, split up in the realm of the finite. By willing itself, power wills what is other than
towards
the end
of the
1%th century.
Its
1914) and its most important representatives William James (1842-1910), who helped to
itself. The transition to the other, to allowing
make it widely known, and John Dewey (1859-1952), whose long activity ensured its continuing influence. Pragmatism is the
to the generosity of the divine will, demands
Western
the will of others, to unconditional consent
of the finite will, which is not the source of its
own power, a self-abandonment,
fice, self-mediation
questioning
its own
through
power.
self-sacri-
weakness, That
by
is why
first great original American contribution to
philosophy.
It began
by being a
method of logical analysis, i.e., of explaining
the content or significance of concepts and phrases and it went on to present itself in consequence of its analyses as a doctrine of
finite power is tempted to establish itself in
the nature of truth, at least insofar as this is
independence in face of the competition of other finite wills and against the claim of the absolute power. The redemption of power is
beginning.
self-assertion, to shut itself off in ostensible
the
cross.
Supreme
love,
in
Jesus'
death,
accepts self-abandonment to the will of the
Father on behalf of many, to be confirmed 72
known by man. As a theory of truth and knowledge 1t found wide hearing at the Pragmatism, as a theory of meaning, was
first formulated by Peirce (Fow to Make Our
Ideas Clear [1878]): “Consider what effects, that might
conceivably
have
bearings,
we
PRAGMATISM
conceive the object of our conception to have, Then our conception of these effects is the whole of our conception of the object.” The
notion of an object or event contains no more significance than that of the practical consequences to be considered, the attitudes and behaviour suggested, the experiences to be foreseen. If the concept is wrongly applied to a situation, the actual consequences will be other than those foreseen with and in the concept. If a number of concepts have the same results in practice, they are only different in name, but really mean the same thing. A concept without practical consequences, which
means
nothing
for our actions,
our
expectations and possible reactions, has really no meaning. This pragmatic rule for meaning, which included
the
reactions
of our
senses,
was
derived from scientific practice. In the theory
of Peirce, it was primarily a means of analysing
concepts
and
meanings
which
was
also,
to
his mind, the first if not the only task of philosophy — compare the preseni-day “linguistic
analysis”
in
England
and
the
U. S, A. Nonetheless, Peirce also had in mind
to re-shape traditional metaphysics, showing up its “verbalism and endless discussions™ as meaningless by means of his pragmatic
criterion of signification. This idea recurs in
logical positivism in a still more form.
emphatic
One consequence of the pragmatic criterion of meaning is that the truth of an assertion cannot be recognized through purely contemplative consideration or through comparison of the proposition with the object of
which it is asserted. The assertion has to be
tested in practice to see whether the empirical
results coincide with the expected ones or not: the “testing of a hypothesis by its actual working”. A judgment is true if it actually
regulates
our conduct,
that 1s, 1f it leads
to
successful adaptation to the possibilities and
demands of the matter in hand, As W. James
and F. C. S. Schiller said, more succinctly than
truth is concerned only with the “value” of thoughts. Dewey therefore suggested a correction which James afterwards accepted: truth is merely the value which is characteristic of thoughts which under practical testing
lead to the expected experiences. A judgment
about reality is true if and only if it is con-
firmed or is or can be verified by the further
course of experiences, directly or indirectly, A judgment about the past is only indirectly verifiable, by means of the traces which the past has left and which can be registered in the present. But no verification of judgments of experience can ever be complete, i.e., check all implied expectations. Hence the certainty which they offer can never be absolute. Thetr evidence is never apodictic. They can give rise only to judgments of a possibly
fallacious type — to what Peirce called “fallibilism™. They are propositions for which there are good grounds or a certain degree
of probability,
speaking proved.
They
but are not strictly
have what Dewey
called “warranted assertibility™, Finally, it is characteristic of pragmatism that it does not consider knowledge as an
independent function but as part of the process of life in the concrete. Knowledge
and science are in the service of life. They are
the most important means at man’s disposal
tor adapting himself to his natural and social environment and for meeting successfully
of daily life.
the difficulties and problems
Ideas, hypotheses and theories are so many “tools” for bringing about concrete aims in life. Hence Dewey could also term his theory “instrumentalism’™, Pragmatism was applied to the field of sncial science by George Herbert Mead
(1863-1931). He develeped a theory of the
genetic relationship of individual and society,
according to which society can be regarded as a complex of social customs developed by
man in order to master his environment. It is only by assimilaring these social customs in
his thinking,
feeling
and
that the
action
In
individual develops spiritually and is enabled 1o become a “‘self’’. Ideas like those of Peirce
has the right to hold this faith as true. But even Peirce and Dewey found themselves forced to modify the formula suggested
and W, Jerusalem of Vienna. What pragmatism was trying to determine
clearly, something is true if it is useful in life
and
brings
about
satisfactory
results
practice. If faith in God is usetul tor life, one
were represented outside of the U.S. A, by such thinkers as F.C.S. Schiller of Oxford was not truth in the abstract, independent of
by James. They held that while all that is true is 2 good, it did not follow that all that is good
.the process of knowledge, but truth as 1t 1s
value are not to be identified. In particular,
process of living experience. Butits upholders disregarded the important distinction be-
is also true. Endless peace would be a good, but must it therefore come abourt? Truth and
also
verified
and
justified
in
the
actual
73
PRAYER
Philosopher of the Secial Individusl (1945);
tween the element of validity or truth in jtself, and the procedure by means of which this
Thayer, The Lagicef Pragmatism(1952); A. Reeban,
The Pragmatic Humanism of F. C. 8. Schiller (1935);
validity is established or this truth is recog-
W. B. Gallie, “Pragmatism”, Engyclopasdia Britan-
nized. Truth and knowledge of the truth
wica, XVIII
rmust not be confused.
'This obscutity is compounded by a further defect of pragmatism, that the method of
establishing a truth is unduly empirical. The truth to be known and the field of meaningful discourse are restricted to what is given in
rience. This means the exclusion of all « priori or essential knowledge of a nonanalytic, i.e., synthetic type. In consequence, there could be no metaphysical principles by virtue of which, in a categorically valid way, experience could be transcended and the suprasensible known. And there could be no absolute moral norms by which one could determine what is good in itself, independently of what “one” (individually or socially) wishes or likes or in fact pronounces good. An ethical relativism, extending to the order
See
also
Experience,
be
would
Science
the
sources:
W.
James,
The Encyclopedia
“Pragmati_sm",__
Thayer,
H.
(1967),
VI
of Philosophy,
pp.
430-36: G. Bzorsky, ‘Pragmatic Theory of Truth”, ibid., pp. 427-30; J. Habermias, Erkesninis und Interesse (1968).
PRAYER A. Tue History oF CHRISTIAN PRAYER
Prayer, as generally understood, can take many forms. And it is significant that “in early times . .. the OT contains no general term for prayer” (RGG, 11, col. 1213). This
suggests that we should consider the subject,
which is certainly a unified theme, from more
than one aspect if we are to avoid over-hasty
conclusions. There are two classical defini-
tions. “Speaking to God” (or Christ) has been a spontaneous desctiption of prayer since the Apostolic
Fathers
(Swxhefic,
the
“raising
of the
bomilia,
con-
versatic). But theology adopted another definition, generally attributed to John Damas-
11, Positiviim,
Truth 1, Value, Social Philosophy.
BIBLIOGRAPHY.
(1959);
Clemens Schoonbrood
experience or what can be tested by expe-
of society and the State, inevitable consequence,
H.
cene:
God™.
to
soul
Undue stress on the notion of speaking to
ke
Will to Believe and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy
God
Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking (1907); id., The Meaning of Truth: A Sequel to * Pragmatism’
of reducing the divine person to the level
(1897;
reprint,
1937);
id., Pragmatism:
A
New
Journal
Does
Pragmatism
of Philosophy
Democracy
and
5
Education:
Mean
(1908), An
by
pp.
Introduction
id,
to the
Philosophy of Education (1910); id., Human Nature
and Conduct: An Introduction to Social Psychology
(1922); id., Logic: The Theory of Inguiry (1938}; id.,
“Philosophy of W. James’’, Problenss of Men (1946), po. 3794, id., *The Development of American Pragmatism™,
in
D.
D.
Runes,
ed.,
Twenticsh
Century Philosophy (1947), pp. 449#.; — F. C. S. Schiller,
Studiesin Humanism (1907} ;id., Humanism .
tmatism’,
Encyclopacdia Britannica,
A Philpsophical Essay (2nd ed., 1912); id., “Prag-
Papers,
ed.
by
8 (1927); C.
C.
S. Peirce,
Hartshorne
and
P.
Collected Weiss,
V: Pragmatism and Pragmaticism (1934); ]. Buchler, ed., The Philosophical Writings of Peirce (1955). sTUDIES: H. G. Mead, “Working Hypothesis in Social
Reform™,
(1899), pp- 3674.;
American fournal of Sociology id., “Genesis
5
of the Self and
Social Control”, ibid. 35 (1924-25), pp. 2511%; B. Russell, *Pragmatism and William James’s Conception of Truth”, Philosephical Essays (1910} C. Morris, Logical Positivism, Pragmatism and Scientific Empiviciem (1937); 1. Buchler, C. . Peirce's Empiricism (1939); P. Schilpp, ed., The Philosophy of /. Dewey (1939); G. Lee, G. H, Mead,
74
runs
the
insignificant nonentity of Deism or of thinking in terms of magical influences. Undue
stress on “lifting up the heart”, however,
may easily obscure the fact that we meet God in the man Jesus Christ. The encounter may be treated as a pleasant occasion for indulging in pious sentimentality. Or there
may be a “mystical”’ effort (see Neo-Platonism)
to lead back the scattered multiplicity of the
creature to the unity and recollection of the
Origin.
X XII (1922,
id., “W. James and the Making of Pragmatism”’,
The Personalist
1123--30)
of other beings, of making the Absolute the
Practical?”,
85ff.;
11, cols.
risk of seeming to profane the divine mystery,
(1909); id., The Will to Believe (1910); ]. Dewey, “What
(DSAM,
1. History of religion. A glance at the history of religion provides examples of such errors.
But in judging the prayer of the nations, there are two points to which more attention must be paid than was done by the historians of comparative religion. One is that prayer is not something that can be adequately described
in
equivalent
terms
from
other
fields of reality. The other is that prayer, of its nature, is an effort to give expression to a personal attitude which is only fully real in
this effort at expression — while it can never
PRAYER
find conceptual categories to comprise its total riches. It mass be an effort to objectify something which cannot be fully objectified. It must be the impossible effort to translate
the personal into terms of things. Hence we
the truth that Israel is a holy people (Lev 20:7). This basic assurance gives unity to the many forms which prayer can take: from almost disrespectful argument (Gen 18:234,; Jer 14f.) to peaceful confidence in
true attitude,
way
supplication to despairing protest (Ps 74:1 1., Job 31), from adoration, praise and thanksgiving (1 Chr 29:31) to humble repentance
with God is vaporized in speculative thinking
enumerating here the various forms, texts, gestures and postures (cf. Krinetzki). It is more important to insist on the all-pervasive attttude, which may be roughly described as confidence in the divine goodness, and at the
must “demythologize”, reduce the many “alienated” forms to their ultimate content. This will undoubtedly bring to light the which
will be in some
theistic, even though combined with idolatry and badly disfigured by magical practices. The same process must be applied to the philosophical ar “mystical” forms of prayer in the higher religions, where the encounter or nihilistic self-annihilation. Here too only extremely cautious interpretation will avoid
confusing a profoundly religious act with its possibly atheistic form of expression. 2. Old Testament. Prayer in the OT shows
with an astonishing clarity that all such errors, actual
An
or
possible,
examinarion
have
of rhe
been
left behind.
inirial stages,
as
disclosed by the sources, shows that magical practices,
long
since
integrated
into
true
prayer, are only marginal phenomena. The theological ground for the purity of this praver 1s to be sought in Israel’s experience of the saving deeds of God, who after the
wanderings of the parriarchs and the trials in Egyvpt finally gave his people the covenant made with Abraham: 1 will be with you and bless vou™ (Gen 26:3). The faithfulness
of Yahweh (Exod 34:6) is the serting of all forms of praver, which has three aspects. One
1s the memory
of the past:
“He
has
delivered his people from the bondage of Egvpt (cf. Exod 32). Then there is the present certainty: “He will not forget the covenant™ (Deut 4:31) and finally the expectation of the great final deliverance: “See, thy king comes
to thee’” (Zech 9:11).
Israel’s
prayers,
A large portion
as collected,
for
of
instance,
in the Psalter, are inspired by the memory of
God’s great deeds in the past to beg for his help in present distress. Just as the prophets recall the past in their constant exhortations to repentance, so too the sapiential books may reflect on it in hymns of praise and
thanksgiving.
This
sense
of the personal
guidance
of
God pervades the prayer of the individual,
and also that of the community.
The king-
ship, the sacred precincts of the temple, the sacred times and rites, the prohibition of certain types of food and clothing embody
God’s
providence
(1 Chr 21:17;
(Ps 127),
Ps 51). There
from
ardent
is no point in
same time a sense of awe before the divine majesty.
This basic attitude could undergo changes.
The familiar conversation with Yahweh in early times appears later in reflections which
may seem perhaps too sentimental — “When
Israel was a child, I loved him” (Hos 11:2;
cf. Jer 2:2; Is 5:1ff.). But in the disasters of
the monarchy, the Babylonian exile and the
dramatic struggles of Yahweh with his people it came to appear 1n a2 purer form as a reverent personal ptety: “For thou hast no delightin sacrifice. . . Thesacrifice acceptable to God is a broken spirit” (Ps 51:16¢f.). It
was finally stabilized as prayer according to
the law and the liturgy in the last five centuries B.C. (**Then wilt thou delight in right
sacrifices”, Ps 51:19). This shift of emphasis within the one basic attitude is associated with
the growing
sense
of
of the majesty
Yahweh. Thus his proper name is not uttered in prayer, mediators such as angels intervene between him and his people, and a painfully
meticulous legalism threatens to form a barrier, impeding free dialogue between them,
3. New
Testament and the primitive Church.
Though it was only in the course of Christian dogmatics that the traits of prayer described
above came to stand out so clearly, the prayer
of Jesus — inextricably interwoven in the
sources with that of the primitive Church —
may undoubtedly be regarded as a definitive
stage in the history of prayer (cf. Lk 11:1).
The
Sermon
on
the Mount,
in both redac-
tions, shows Jesus’ childlike confidence in the Father in heaven, his sense of security, his conversing with God as the child speaks to
its father. Gethsemane and Calvary provide the clearest instances of the polarity of active and passive tension in the prayer of the Lotd.
It is a dialogue with God which can go so far 75
PRAYER
as to beg that the Father’s will may be avetted, and also submit silently to the divine plan.
everyday attitude expressed in the exhorta-
cannot tell whether the frequency with which our Lotd is portrayed as praying in Lk is
or again in the bold and frank approach to
Both
attitudes
one.
are indissolubly
We
theological interpretation or historical fact.
But there is no doubt that Jesus’ prayet
reveals the perpetual unity of his will with
that of the Father (cf. the invocations before healing the sick or Mt 11:25fL.). In Jn this unity is 50 central that the prayer of Jesus,
which could express some kind of subordina-
tion, is explained as merely uttered for the benefit of the bystanders (Jn 11:42). The prayer of the primitive Church is inspired by the actuzl encounter with Jesus, the intercourse (bomilia) with the Lord, as well as by his example. The model proposed by Jesus is seen most clearly in the QOur Father, though here as elsewhere(Jn 4:22 deals with another matter)
Jesus distinguishes his own prayer from that of others, Two things were taken over by the
Church from the Lord. One was an absolute
confidence in the goodness and power of the heavenly Father. This was so dominant that
the “certainty of being heard” does not seem
to have been a problem in the early years. The other was the expectation of the parousia
of the Lord. All prayer was focussed on this. The certainty of being heard in all petitions was centred and founded on the “Maranatha
—
Qur
Lotd,
come!”
(1 Cor 16:23;
Rev
22.:20; Didacke, 10, 6). Itechoesthe preaching
of the kingdom of God by the Lord. But the NT
also shows clearly how the
intercourse of the disciples with Jesus, with
the risen Lord and the Spirit of Christ, became the medium of prayer (cf. the development in the use of the title Kyrios). Closeness to Jesus gives access to prayer. This conviction,
intensified by the experience of the Resurrec-
tion, underlies such texts as “Lord, teach us
to pray” (Lk 11:1), the accounts of the sick kneeling to Jesus (especially in Mt) or the confessions of the demons. The classic ex-
pression of this conviction is the “through
Christ” of the Pauline letters. According to
St. Paul,
it is the mvebua
Christi,
i.e., the
closeness of the Lord (gradually distinguished
as 2 person} which enables us to pray. It is the
Spirit within us who cries, “Abba, Father!” (Rom 8:15; Gal 4:6). The Spirit is the bond which unites the many forms of prayer in the primitive
Church:
charismatic
stammering
or choral hymns, cultic assemblies or private
prayer, the high-point in the Eucharist or the
76
tion to “prayalways”. The Spirit bestows the
new assurance which is expressed in ecstasies
God {rappnoix). Through the medium of the Spirit, with the person of the Lord as the historical focus, the three factors of Jewish prayer are brought to their fulfilment. There is the backward look to the historical action of God in raising up the Crucified — the supreme and all-embracing saving deed of God in history. There is the presence of the Lord in the
Spirit in the Church, by which all the prayer
of Christians is inspired. There is the expectation of the coming of the Lord. But his return was experienced day by day in its initial stage in the prayer of the Church, and was far more important to the Church than the expectation of the Messiah had been in the OT.
4. Tradition. We examine here the transmission of the biblical heritage merely to see how the innumerable manifestations of Christian spirituality, in its most personal act, that of prayer, can fertilize our present thinking. Prayer is not only part of Christian history, it is perhaps one of its main driving forces.
Hence a sketch of the history of prayer must
retrace the many
factors of the history of
dogma, which are here briefly summed up under a number of headings. We cannot of course attempt to describe the whole tradition, but in a negative way, by mentioning
some of the main deformations, some notion of the true riches of Christian prayer may be given,
a) It is quite clear, and to some extent already visible in Scripture itself, that prayer
turned from the Jesus af time, soon to return
to judge the world (the expectation of the
imminent parousia), or at death (theology of martyrdom), to the Jesws of supra-temporal vlessings. Contemplation frees itself from past and future to sink tranquilly into itself.
Historical expectations are sometimes revived
in heresies (e.g., Joachim of Fiore). While the world-picture
was
symbolic,
this static and
spiritualizing tendency — the lingering look instead of the urgent expectation — was
checked. The inner unity of concrete reality and spiritual sense still linked prayer to time and place. But when the symbolic worldpicture was “demythologized™, prayer came dangerously close to a contemplation of the beyond, denying the world to cleave to the spiritual.
PRAYER
b) Equally obvious is the decline of the
charismatic element, such as was apparent in
the Church of Corinth with its prophecy, hymnic inspitation, etc. No doubt the religious orders must be regarded as a series of fresh charismatic approaches. But it is typical that the Spiritual Exercises of St. Ignatius, in which there is a delicate balance of the charismatic movement of the Spirit and the regulated procedure, were soon reduced to the
element
of “exercise”.
A
number
of
developments fit in here. The charismatic element appears only in heresy or in private prayer, where the gratia gratic data for the sake of the Church becomes an individualistic mysticism. Public prayer is strait-jacketed by laws
becomes
and
the prerogative
of the
hierarchy: the priest officiates, the faithful “attend”. Increasing stress is laid on the formula,
so
that
where
faith
is active
it is
misinterpreted legalistically, and elsewhere
misused as a sort of magic. c) In practce, from the Middle Ages on, the place of Christ in the economy of redemption, the biblical “through Christ”, is hardly
a real factor any longer, even in devotion to the Sacred
Heart or the incarnation, as the
latrer was practised in the school of Bérulle ( Ecole Frangaise). Indulgences, pilgrimages,
adoration of the Host and so on, which have
no meaning except in relation to the historical humanity of our Lord, were accorded a sort of absolute value. Even if much Protesrant polemic must be dismissed as mistaken, there is no doubt that in the practice of piety devotion to the saints and the Blessed Virgin often enough took the place of the humanity
of Christ. The pendulum naturally swung also
in
the
opposite direction.
The
ecclesial
character of private praver, which can only be offered per Christum et Ecclesiam, was lost
mystical obscurity in which man ceases to be the partner of God in dialogue. The final exaggeration is found among the ' followers of Evagrius of Pontus (4th century) as well
as in the “Brethren of the Free Spirit™ (13th century): man rids himself of all impurity, including that of prayer, and merges in sheer purity with God himself. We for our part seem to hear a faint echo of this movement when, for instance, as in Origen, St. Thomas Aquinas or O. Karrer, the prayer of petition 15 stripped of all real activity and is reduced to abandonment to the divine will. e) When the degrees of the “way of perfec-
tion” were kept rigidly separate, perfect prayer was reserved for the perfecti, and the difference in state of life was equated with a difference in perfection. But since the basic
sense of sinfulness before God, of humility,
of always falling short of one’s call belongs to the existentials of prayer, the too static
notion of the degrees of prayer could be easily transformed, especially by seekers of perfection, into tormenting doubts about one’s election. There is a wide literature to attest this — Luther being by no means a marginal case,
f) In the same way, the analysis of the
various elements of prayer led to a series of “methods of prayer”, where it could be too easily forgotten that no method was more than a handmaid to prayer. On the same
principles,
distinctions
were made between
Scripture reading and prayer,
between the
pursuit of theclogy and the longing for God,
etc. At the opposite extreme, the reaction to this was to identify too readily the Christian attitude with actual praver. Clement of Alexardria could say that the true Gnostic was always praying, Evagrius that true theology was prayer. Ebeling, following
sight of. d) The temptation to spiritualize is intrinsic
Luther, takes a similar position,
Christianity cannot be traced merely to Gnostic or neo-Platonist influences. Possibly the whole history of prayer is that of the struggle against such temptations. They suggest that prayer must be elevated to “pure prayer”, since the prayer of petition s only for beginners and all emotions are
turned
to all forms of piety, and its appearance In
unworthy. Gregory the Great’s longing for
contemplation reappears as the enjoyment of
esoteric truth. As the effort is intensified, it
becomes the purely intellectual intuition of the apex mentis, the cime d'esprit, the fine point of the mind; or it becomes pure darkness, the
g) A similar principle is at work when 5t. Paul's “Pray constantly” (1 Thess 5:17) 1is
into
such
exercises
as the
“Jesus
Prayer” (incessantly repeated, cf. J. Salinger’s “Franny and Zooey”). The “attitude™ is identified with an “exercise”. The true Christian attitude must comprise both things. The Christian prays and asks at regular intervals, He “lifts up his heart” to God
afresh on each occasion. And heis perpetually
in the attitude of prayer, which is what really makes a2 man a Christian, h) A further splintering occurred when normal prayer was distinguished from the
mystical, There were broad historical reasons
77
PRAYER
behind this development, but the impulse
happiness, not seeking emoti Honal sati’fificflah
censolation?”) and from movements outside
action, which ultimately can only be-reglized in face of a person who is imamanent to all
also came from controversy within the Church {*May one, or must one, strive for
but personal fulfilment. It is the will to free
that
possibilities of freedom and summons man
degrees of prayer, but the common ground, the experience of personal eficounter with
therefore sensitive openness to the God who transcends all the encounters of everyday life but who uses them and goes beyond them to demand an answer to the basic question of
the Church
(the Messalians
holding
grace was vision of God). There are of course God,
is greater than all differences.
It is
understandable that in view of such distine-
tions normal prayer should lose much of its freshness. To be truly addressed by God was
reserved for the higher degree of prayer.
Normal, everyday prayer was regarded rather as a duty to be performed and an exercise to
be done, not as something also capable of
soaring to the heights, under the impulse of the petsonal summons of God. i) Many of these phenomena may be explained by the growing distinction between the subjective, the proper realm of prayer, from the objective, which means in Christianity Christ, Scripture, the Church, the sacraments, the liturgy, and so on. Thus, for instance, the same principle is at work when the Eucharist, the communion in common,
“‘private communion”,
becomes
when
the
strictly sacramental element is separated from
the many
other religious acts, and when
adoration of the Blessed Sacrament is performed in isolation. One result of this development is the persistence of the notion that true prayer must be in private, a misinterpretation of “in your room” (Mt 6:6)
which is not yet fully eliminated.
B. Tue
EsseNceE oF CHRISTIAN
1. The concepr. An
informed
to freedom. In a word, it is unconditional and
our existence, the meaning of life. Hence
tradition tries to define prayer as the “ascent
to God” and Scripture speaks of “‘pouring out the soul before God” (1 Sam 1:15), of
longing for God “as the hartlongs for flowing
streamns” (Ps 42:1), of lifting up the heart (Ps 25:1), of taking refuge in the Lord (Ps 31:1f.). Inmodern terminology it can become “man’s self-commitment to the transcendence of his own being, hence the humble, receptive
and reverent admission of, and the re-active,
responsive affirmative dedication to his call and destiny, the impact of the mystery of God as person on human existence, to which man cannot but be somehow sensible” (K. Rahner in LTK, IV, col. 543). But it is equally important to recall the simple description of prayer as “the great art of conversing with Jesus” (Imitation of Christ, I, 8). It is like Abraham’s negotiations with Yahweh (Gen 18:23-33) which strike us as
very anthropomorphic, or the dialogue of
our Lord in Gethsemane as he wrestles with
the will of his Father, or the encounters with
God of which we read in the lives or legends
of the saints, and
familiar
PRAYER
discussion
of
as almost
which
we
to seem
find so over-
blasphemous.
While the first definition strives to convey the majesty and uaiversal omnipotence of
Christian prayer has to take into account in ‘the matters described above. The two classical definitions mentioned at the outset will also be important factors.
God, the definition of prayer as “speaking
really is in the depths of his being, something that cannot be static but must be realized in a fundamental activity in time yet transcend-
above all in the prayer of petition. The attempt to make abandonment to God’s
Prayer s the great religious act. What man
ing time — that is prayer. It is the acceptance
of the prime fact of being created, not in a stupor of resignation, but alert to its coming from the Father’s hands. It is committing oneself to the basic dynamism of the kernel
of the person, wishing
in 2 way to break
through all limits of time and space, but still
seeing its fulhilment not in infinite being, but in the Thou who speaks and answers and
first calls. It is the all-pervasive longing for 78
to God” bears on the truth that God hears “me”, that he has chosen “me” very per-
sonally, and that “my"” casual steps are guided
by his infinite wisdom. This truth is operative
providence the quintessence of prayer ignores its character of dialogue. It stresses one truth,
the immutability of God
isolation
would
mean
(which taken
that
real prayer
in
is
impossible} and forgets the other, that God
s “personally”
concerned with our affairs.
The immutability of God must not be reduced
to a proposition which can be manipulated in the usual categories of human thought. [t must be kept open for the truth of the
incarnation
and
crucifixion,
for
the
truth
PRAYER
that God “changes” for the sake of man. This is the only possible source of the dialogal
character of prayer. In true Christian prayer, the granting or refusal of requests is not a problem. One
need only think of the typical pilgrimage where the believer whose request has not been granted in spite of or because of his ardent prayer still gains the profound peace of answered prayer. This may be illustrated by an analogy from personal relationships. Any genuine request is always put forward as the minor wish in which the general plea for the other’s favour is crystallized. But the Christian prayer of petition takes its impetus (1.e., has its certainty of being heard) from the saving gift of God to men, which is Jesus Christ, 2. Basic forms.
whole
distance
(Bonaventure’s with
praise,
God,
sacrifice,
If prayer then
between
swrsamactio)
its
basic
thanksgiving, etc.
connotations.
—
are
ascent and
forms
—
petition,
seen
Adoration
to be
is
spans
to
the
God
dialogue
adoration,
repentance,
its natural
undoubtedly
closer to the “asceut”, bur withourt dialogal encounter there can be no adoration, just as
there can be no genuine petittion without the
inward impulse of the Spirit of God, such as is expressed in the wriumactio.
This span is wide enough to take in much
that
is often
too
quickly
rejected
in
the
phenomenology of religion as un-Christian. Christian praver, in which the intrinsic tension is again surpassed in the person of the Lord, who is God, filling all things while remaining the same, and man, limited and changing historically,
appears
even
phencmenolog:-
cally as the climax and fulfilment of the prayer
of the nations. And this does not mean that
non-Christian prayer must be at once branded
as un-Christian non-prayer.
3. The essential structures. a) The first essen-
tial component follows at once from what has been said. Prayer is a grace, a gift of God,
a response to something which waspreviously
put on man’s lips and in his heart. But prayer is also man’s own free act. To have some idea of this mystery, we must first distinguish the aspect of what is given by God from the aspect of what is accomplished by man’s own force. All prayer is wholly the gift of God. There is nothing in it that we can keep for ourselves.
There is no previous foot-hold that we can provide for God’s action, and no later response that we can give of ourselves. But prayer is likewise human action. Man is not a machine kept in motion by God. He is free, and there can be no question of prayer unless
it is rooted in man’s freedom, an action fot
which
he is personally responsible.
These
two aspects, which both take in the total act
of human prayer, must be clearly distinguished. Only then can we truly admire the new mystery, that prayer is after alla response to the call of God,
that cutting across the
different levels, divine grace and human freedom still meet. This has been the bliss of great saints, often experienced in fear and trembling. But this interplay of call and
response is at the heart of all prayer, even the praver of petition, whose structure only
seems to be different when it is considered
superficially.
b) Prayer is also a unity of the inward and
outer man. Man prays when he is inwardly and outwardly recollected, when he is himself. “Interior prayer” always seeks to
express
itself in word
and gesture,
while
“external” or vocal prayer can influence the inner attitude when one is tired and distracted. The traditional distinction between “atten-
tion” and “intention”
is relevant here, and
this s one way to understand the rosary (though there are also other approaches). But the practical consequences are more important. Prayer must of course aim at being
“interior”, but since man lives in the external
world it must also be guided by external
rules, postures and formulas and follow the
cycle
of feast-days
and
times
for
prayer.
See Breviary, Liturgy 111, Worship. ¢) The importance of the link between the inner and the outer appears plainly in the third essential factor: prayer is always both individual and social. The theological reason for this is the unity of the Spirit, who is the Spirit of the Church and also animates each of
the
faithful.
praise God
The
has
Christian
both
to
in a fellowship of prayer and
formulate his own
prayer for himself. But
he must not forget that the prayer of the individual relies on the community which it serves, and that the only ultimate meaning
of community prayer is to lead the individual to God. There can be no problems of preced-
ence
here,
since
each
man
is,
irreducibly,
at the same time both an individual called
personally by God and part of the chain of
mankind
whose
link
with
God
is Jesus
79
PRAYER
Christ. The closer it is to the Eucharist, the
centre of prayer in.commeon, the higher the degree of unity in prayer. The breviary is
C. SYsTEMATIC OUTLINE
Any “systematization” of the complex reality
congregational devotions. The same principle of social prayer also explains, for
of prayer, the “concretissimum” of Christian life, must note that it is conditioned by the given historical and personal situation. One
for
encounter, take “the encounter of man with
prayerin common in its own way, as are also
instance, the precept of going to Mass on
Sundays,
and
the
of praying
duty
parents and relations. The notion of proclaiming fellowship before God can throw new light on a feature of the early Church, prayer as a confession of faith, which in turn may throw new light on pilgrimages and so on. d) A further basic structure of prayer bond
tellowship. It is the most perfect expression of the inward man. Language here means
that the Word
became
encounters us in the word of Scripture and the articulate action of the sacraments. It is only today that this dominant role of language is coming into view. If prayer is
really the basic religious act and the verbaliza-
tion (its personal outcome) is not merely a vehtcle of prayer but its essence — prayet is speaking to God — we can measure the
responsibility of those who have to deal with the words. The verbal character also throws light on prayer as a confession of farth, since all honest language is at once the
giving of testimony. e} The essential deficiency of human prayer.
These demands bring cut one further quality,
that prayer
falls short of what
it should
really do. This is not a matter of sin, though closely connected with it, nor of incidentals
which
might
be avoided,
say, by greater
recollection. Man, as he encounters God, is
at once conscious of his darkness before the radiant light. This is not a matter of a mystique of sin or of fiducial faith, though the existentiell ground of such notions may well be found here. Man essentially receives at prayer, and prayer, with all the due
reserves made above, is essentially a process of receiving. It has often been experienced as such by great men of prayer, who saw theit own poverty better the more gifts they
received. The prayer, “Lord, 1 am not worthy” is not just for beginners but also —
to keep to the terminology — for the perfect. Penitential prayer, adoration and many other torms must be interpreted this ptinciple.
80
of human
God in Jesus Christ” as the quintessence and the comprehensive description of prayet. Thete are three points here. One is that God and man face each other, an oppoesition
which is clearest, phenomenologically, in the prayer of petition. The second is a
consciousness of unity which is perceptible
flesh and
the
simply
the analogy
encounter of God and man it can cover everything from the touch of grace to the
Language
words, which in its highest form is identity. personal
using
of
the link between prayer and real
then,
on the personal level of will, but is rooted in the depths of being. A good phenomenology can note such consciousness in human
follows from
is
may
in the light of
encounters,
but when
it is applied to the
supreme forms of mystical union. The third point is that this “vertical” relationship is localized in the “horizontal” encounter with Jesus Christ in space and time. The whole riches of Christian prayer can be easily taken in from this vantage-point.
Objectively, the encounter with Jesus Christ gives rise to the trinitarian movement of prayer, which is expressed, for instance, in the doxologies of the liturgy. A Christocentric pneumatology and ecclesiology also founds the social character of Christian prayer. A
petition which is communal in character is at once “intercession”.
And
prayer to the
saints 18 also rooted in this sense of fellowship,
which is more pneumatological than sociological in origin. Liturgical and sacramental
prayer, like scriptural prayer, which stems from meditation on the Scriptures and rises
to contemplation,
are
based
us by the Church
through
on
the
fact
Scripture
and
that the encounter with Christ 1s mediated to tradition.
The
importance
of tradition
for
prayer should not be underestimated, because
prayer is a concrete act and not an abstract construction of the mind. But life is transmit-
ted by life, not by abstractions. The subjective aspect also gives access to
the social character of prayer. The Church, the liturgy, the example and intercession of
the saints, etc., are the type of thing which
modern
anthropology
actually
finds
im-
perative. The relationship between the inner and the outer could also be inserted into the system at this point, the external action
not being considered as merely the “prac-
PREACHING
tice of prayer” involving problems of method
and so on. It is the relationship to activity in general, the age-old problem of action and contemplation. The inward action would take in such matters as mysticism and the prayer of quiet. The degrees and types of prayer (as types of encounter with God) would also be in place here. In general, it should not be difficult to take advantage of the findings of modern anthropology from this perspective, applying it, for instance, to prayer at the various ages of life and the traditional themes of impediments to prayer, distractions and the fruits of prayer. A psychology of prayer according to personal or ethnic dispositions would soon expose such generalizations as “ecstatic-prophetic” or “Hellenistic-Semitic” as over-simplifications. Finally, to sum up the many components, It seems to us that it is best to group them under two heads, which are really aspects of the same thing. One is the grace of God, which could be directly defined as the bond of unity between the two aspects, “subjective” and ““objective”, described above. It comprises the whole range of individual and community prayer. The second is the verbal
expression, which would rather sum up the
“external side”. The theology of the word,
as the word of God, shows at once that this is
not an exaggeration of what might perhaps
be taken to be theologically incidental. The
linguistic element makes it possible to consider all human activity, including praver, from a single perspective, which can also take the varieties of time and place into account. And it also underlines the dialogal character, the dimension in which Christian
prayer reaches its greatest heights.
C. Vagaggini and others, La preghiera nslia bibbia ¢ nella tradivions patristica ¢ momastica (1964);
W.
Godel,
Irisches Beten im frithen
(dissertation,
Inasbruck,
cf.
1963),
Mittelalter ZKT
85
(1963), pp. 261-321, 389-439; L., Krinetzki, Lrraels Gebes im Alten Tostament (1965); 1. Hausherr, Hiésychasme ¢t pritre (1966), PHENOMENOLOGY OF RELIGION: F, Heiler, Prayer (1932); E. Gruehn, (1956); E, de Places,
LYie Frimmigkeit der Gegenwari
“La priére des philosophes grecs”, Gregorianum 41 (1960}, pp. 253-72; H. Sundén, Die Religion und die Rollen (1966). THEOLOGY AND PRACTICE (MODERN): A. Poulain, The Gracer of Interior Prayer (1910, reprint, 1950); K. Rahner, Happiness
through Prayer (1948); id., Encounters with Silence
(1960); ). de Guibert, The Theology of the Spiritual Life (1956); R. Guardini, Prayer in Practice (1957); H.
Urs
(1961);
C.
Letters
to
Comtemplative
Balthasar,
von
i
Prayer
Butler,
Prayer
Practice
(1962);
Prayer
{1964);
F. Moschner, Christian Prayer (1962); F. Fisher, Prayer in the New Testament (1964); C. S. Lewds, M.
Malcolm:
Chiefly
on
The Nature and Uses of Prayer, or,
Nédoncelle,
Man's Encounter with God (1904); F. von Hiigel,
Writings,
Selected
). de Fraine,
ed.
Praying
P.
by
with
Chambers
(1964);
the Bible (1965);
R.
The Interpretation of Prayer in the Early
Simpson,
Church (1965); G. Ebeling, On Prayer (1966).
Josef Sudbrack PREACHING I. The Mediation of the Word. 11, Homiletics.
I. The
Mediation
of the Word
Preaching can mean a2 number of different types of spiritual discourse (see part I1, 2 b, below), such as are indicated, for instance,
in the N'T: gospel (ebayyéhov), Acts 8:40; 15:7; 16:10; proclamation {x7puypa), Acts 8:5; 10:42; discourse (Adyos), 1 Cor 2:4;
1Tim4:6;consolation-encouragement (mapd-
winarg), 1 Cor 14:3; 1 Cor 1:6; 2:1.
testimony (paptiplov),
wutstoricar: H. Bremond, BIBLIOGRAPHY. Histoire littéraire du sentiment religieux en France, 11 vols. (1916-33), E. T. {vols. [-I1l}: A Literary
The nature and function of preaching may be described as follows. Preaching is the public proclamation of the word of God in the Church, in the form of discourse, by the consecrated and authorized ministers of the Church (Rom 10:15; 2 Tim 1:2; 1 Tim
P. Pourrat, Christian Spirftuality, 3vals. (1922-27),
individuals
See also Martyrdom,
Spiritual Exercises,
sticisam 11, Saints 11, Lord's Prayer.
My-
History of Religious Thought in France (1928-306);
H. Hempel, Gebet wnd Frimmigkett im Alten Testa-
ment (1922);
J. Nielen,
Gebet and Gottesdienst im
Nenen Testament (1937); E. Behr-Siegel, Priére ef sainteté dans ! Epfise russe {1950); A. Hamman,
La Pritre, 11 Le Nouvean Testament (1959), 11: f.es irois premiers siécles (1963); L. Bouyer, L. Cognet,
). Leclercg
Spirttualité “La priére
and
F. Vanderbroucke,
Flistoire de fa
B. Bobrinsky, chrétienne (1960f.}; ... dans la tradition orthodoxe”,
Verbam Cara 15 (1961), pp. 338-56; H. Beintker
(on
Luther),
Luther-fabrbuch
(1964),
pp.
47-68;
5:22). Its object is to bring the hearers, as deliberate
and
as a community,
acceptance
of the
to a free,
message
of
salvation which will be a testimony in action. It strives to make them alert to the divine life within them, to promote its
growth, to strengthen their unity as Church and people of God, to present them as "a living sacrifice, holy and pleasing to God”
(Rom art,
7;
12:1;