141 26 1MB
English Pages 208 [209] Year 2022
William James, Essays in Radical Empiricism
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 1
5/2/22 10:39 AM
American Philosophy Series Series Editor John J. Kaag, University of Massachusetts Lowell Advisory Board Charlene Haddock Siegfried, Marilyn Fischer, Scott Pratt, Douglas Anderson, Erin McKenna, and Mark Johnson The American Philosophy Series at Lexington Books features cutting-edge scholarship in the burgeoning field of American philosophy. Some of the volumes in this series are historically oriented and seek to reframe the American canon’s primary figures: James, Peirce, Dewey, and DuBois, among others. But the intellectual history done in this series also aims to reclaim and discover figures (particularly women and minorities) who worked on the outskirts of the American philosophical tradition. Other volumes in this series address contemporary issues—cultural, political, psychological, educational—using the resources of classical American pragmatism and neo-pragmatism. Still others engage in the most current conceptual debates in philosophy, explaining how American philosophy can still make meaningful interventions in contemporary epistemology, metaphysics, and ethical theory. Recent titles in the series:
William James, “Essays in Radical Empiricism”: A Critical Edition, by H.G Callaway Dewey and the Aesthetic Unconscious: The Vital Depths of Experience, by Bethany Henning Pragmatic Philosophy of Religion: Melioristic Case Studies, by Ulf Zackariasson Endurance Sport and the American Philosophical Tradition, by Douglas R. Hochstetler Pragmatist and American Philosophical Perspectives on Resilience edited by Kelly A. Parker and Heather E. Keith Reconstructing the Personal Library of William James: Markings and Marginalia from the Harvard Library Collection by Ermine L. Algaier IV Rorty, Religion, and Metaphysics by John Owens Ontology after Philosophical Psychology: The Continuity of Consciousness in William James’s Philosophy of Mind, by Michela Bella Richard Rorty and the Problem of Postmodern Experience: A Reconstruction, by Tobias Timm The Pragmatism and Prejudice of Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., edited by Seth Vannatta Peirce and Religion: Knowledge, Transformation, and the Reality of God, by Roger A. Ward William James, Moral Philosophy, and the Ethical Life, edited by Jacob L. Goodson Epistemic Issues in Pragmatic Perspective, by Nicholas Rescher Loving Immigrants in America: An Experiential Philosophy of Personal Interaction, by Daniel G. Campos The Religious Dimension of Experience: Gabriel Marcel and American Philosophy, by David W. Rodick Richard J. Bernstein and the Expansion of American Philosophy: Thinking the Plural, edited by Marcia Morgan and Megan Craig
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 2
5/2/22 10:39 AM
William James, Essays in Radical Empiricism A Critical Edition Edited and Introduced by H. G. Callaway
LEXINGTON BOOKS
Lanham • Boulder • New York • London
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 3
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Published by Lexington Books An imprint of The Rowman & Littlefield Publishing Group, Inc. 4501 Forbes Boulevard, Suite 200, Lanham, Maryland 20706 www.rowman.com 86-90 Paul Street, London EC2A 4NE Copyright © 2022 by The Rowman & Littlefield Publishing Group, Inc. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced in any form or by any electronic or mechanical means, including information storage and retrieval systems, without written permission from the publisher, except by a reviewer who may quote passages in a review. British Library Cataloguing in Publication Information Available Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Available ISBN 9781793653147 (cloth : alk. paper) | ISBN 9781793653154 (ebook) The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirements of American National Standard for Information Sciences—Permanence of Paper for Printed Library Materials, ANSI/NISO Z39.48-1992.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 4
5/2/22 10:39 AM
C’est Berkeley qui le premier a mis cette vérité en honneur. Esse est percipi. Nos sensations ne sont pas de petits duplicates intérieurs des choses, elles sont les choses mêmes en tant que les choses nous sont présentes. William James, “La Notion de Conscience,” 1905
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 5
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 6
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Contents
Preface
ix
Introduction: William James, Functional Psychology, and Radical Empiricism
xiii
1 Does ‘Consciousness’ Exist?
1
2 A World of Pure Experience
15
3 The Thing and Its Relations
35
4 How Two Minds Can Know One Thing
47
5 The Place of Affectional Facts in a World of Pure Experience
53
6 The Experience of Activity
61
7 The Essence of Humanism
73
8 La Notion de Conscience
79
9 Is Radical Empiricism Solipsistic?
91
10 Mr. Pitkin’s Refutation of ‘Radical Empiricism’
95
11 Humanism and Truth Once More
97
12 Absolutism and Empiricism
105
Notes 111 Bibliography
139
Index
155
About the Editor
165 vii
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 7
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 8
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Preface
The papers assembled in Essays in Radical Empiricism chiefly date from the late work of William James, 1904–1907—the single exception being the final 1884 essay “Absolutism and Empiricism.” James conceived a plan for a book in 1907 and placed a collection of his essays in an envelope carrying the title “Essays in Radical Empiricism,” making the same essays available to students; but he did not live to carry out the plan for the book, and it was left to his friend and colleague Ralph Barton Perry to first publish Essays in Radical Empiricism in 1912. The present edition of James’s papers generally follows the 1912 edition. James regarded his radical empiricism as a modification, correction, and amplification of the empiricism of Locke, Berkeley, Hume, and J. S. Mill. He aligns himself with the empiricist philosophers and especially in contrast to neo-Kantianism, continental rationalism and holistic, Absolute Idealism. Radical empiricism carries over from empiricism a strong emphasis on “experience” as the source of knowledge, but James rejected atomistic and structuralist conceptions of experience. He placed great weight on introspective methods and awareness of relations in the moving transitions, conjunctions, and disjunctions of experience. But it may be doubted that James fully grasped the import of more rigorous accounts of the logic of relations. The point is suggested by James’s pronounced nominalism and his verificationist concept of truth. James’s radical empiricism is linked to and depends on his concept of “pure experience” and to his understanding of the “pragmatism method.” We will not fully understand the development of the pragmatic tradition in American thought, including the re-emergence of naturalism after the death of James, without a deeper understanding and evaluation of James on radical empiricism. Two summary points stand out. ix
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 9
5/2/22 10:39 AM
x
Preface
The first is James’s background reliance on themes from Charles S. Peirce and his pragmatic conception of meaning in particular. Though James on relations gives distinctive emphasis to relations of one portion of experience to another, and in fact he makes no mention of Peirce in the present book, readers will recall Peirce’s “pragmatic maxim,” and his work on the logic of relations.1 The pragmatic maxim tells us that clarity concerning meaning depends on tracing out the conceivable practical consequences of an idea; and Peirce was a great innovator on the logic of relations. It follows that to fully detail the consequences of an idea, one must also attend to consequences arising specifically in light of the logic of relations, and relations in accordance with their logic are no mere “creations of mind.” The late development of the logic of relations, a major amplification of traditional logic, has significant consequences for the intentionality of veridical experience in particular. Secondly, it is important to view the pragmatic maxim and the logic of relations as they condition James’s concept of experience. In my Introduction to the present edition, I aim for a deeper view of the pragmatic tradition and of the logic of relations. Given a focus on more recent developments in semantics, the philosophy of language and mind, and functional psychology— including limitations of stand-alone introspection—a more realist concept of mind and representation and a correspondingly critical approach to James on radical empiricism recommend themselves. A chief result of the present study is to uncover and illustrate strengths and weaknesses of the Darwinian forms of functional psychology which James’s Principles of Psychology did so much to promote.2 The popular appeal of radical empiricism has, too often, obscured functionalism in psychology. The present edition chiefly retains Perry’s familiar texts for the James papers, only updating and Americanizing the orthography; and James’s longer quotations have been indented. The footnotes of Perry’s edition have been modified for clarity and uniformity of references. James’s own footnotes are retained, and some are expanded to render references explicit. Readers of the first edition of 1912 were reasonably expected to be more familiar with the cited articles and authors, but this is less true for contemporary readers. The citations of sources are here made more accessible. James’s own notes have been identified as such, and I have added others to clarify sources, concepts and briefly develop points of criticism. A full bibliography including James’s sources has been added in the present edition, and the index expanded. The present edition retains the bibliographic information and cross references Perry added in 1912, but that information has been silently incorporated into the editor’s annotations and again adjusted to accommodate the changed pagination. Perry’s references are put into a uniform, more explicit form.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 10
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Preface xi
In my Introduction, I have generally placed radical empiricism in the context of, and in contrast with, the naturalist, psychological functionalism of James’s Principles of Psychology and related sources, emphasizing the scientific naturalism prominent in James’s earlier psychological works. The Essays clearly retain a reworking of James’s functional psychology, but as I argue, the later, more philosophical elements of the Essays including the title theme suffer in comparison with James’s functionalism and the Magnus opus of James’s Principles. Contemporary functionalism in the philosophy of mind, philosophy of psychology and related fields stand to benefit from greater attention to Jamesian functionalism in psychology. The point is perhaps best illustrated in the early functionalism of James R. Angell and in the work of the contemporary, French experimentalist and cognitive psychologist Stanislas Dehaene—who explicitly follows James’s lead.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 11
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 12
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Introduction William James, Functional Psychology and Radical Empiricism
The primary aim of this introductory essay is to understand and evaluate the radical empiricism of William James, including his concept and thesis of “pure experience,”—the conceptual keynote and cornerstone of radical empiricism. This requires placing the Jamesian theses in their intellectualhistorical context. A related, more specific purpose of the essay is to recover and examine James’s conception of functional relations—one of the most interesting and suggestive themes in James’s philosophical and psychological writings. Radical empiricism has tended to overshadow the scientific naturalism of James’s functional psychology. Yet James on functional relations and psychological functions is highly relevant to developed, functionalist conceptions of consciousness. James’s work on relational conceptions of mind and consciousness drew on emerging currents in evolutionary biology, and the philosophical, theoretical, and experimental psychology of the later nineteenth century. James’s functionalism influenced his contemporaries and stimulated, especially during the first quarter of the twentieth century, an American school of functional psychology. Functionalism in psychology deserves renewed attention in light of contemporary currents of functionalist thought in the philosophy of mind, neuroscience, cognitive science and related fields. Advances in experimental technique and instrumentation may revitalize functional psychology and help answer outstanding problems in related fields. 1. JAMES, PSYCHOLOGY AND EMPIRICISM Running through the Essays in Radical Empiricism readers will find many references to earlier sources in psychology and philosophical psychology xiii
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 13
5/2/22 10:39 AM
xiv
H. G. Callaway
including James Mill (1773–1836), J.S. Mill (1806–1873), Herbert Spencer (1820–1903), Gustav Fechner (1801–1887) and Wilhelm Wundt (1832– 1920).1 He appeals to the British empiricists, and Bishop George Berkeley (1685–1753) in particular; and empiricism constitutes the central philosophical background of radical empiricism. James enlists more specific support for his approach to consciousness from those of his contemporaries who, as he put it, “seemed just on the point of abandoning the notion of consciousness” as a distinct entity.2 This appeal to and enlistment of supporting sources is to be expected and welcomed. James rose to academic prominence with the publication of his Principles of Psychology in 1890; and in his later, more philosophical writings, he selected and emphasized themes and references from his earlier work. There is advantage in this for contemporary readers. Consulting his work in psychology and his sources helps in understanding and evaluating James’s later philosophy. He argued in the Principles that “we ought to continue to talk in psychology, as if consciousness had causal efficacy.”3 The point is basic in his opposition to Kantian, neo-Kantian and “transcendental” conceptions of consciousness.4 We are to avoid transcendentalism, the Kantian doctrine of noumenal selves and things beyond all possible experience, and we are also to avoid epiphenomenalism—according to which consciousness is but a byproduct of brain processes and has no effects in the world. That we are aware in particular ways makes a difference to what we are able to do; that you see the red traffic light, for instance, helps explain why you are able to stop at the right place and time. Not all causal explanations in psychology (or elsewhere) are given directly in “physical” (or neurophysiological) terms. Consciousness, in particular according to James, is involved in psychological processes of selecting objects of attention, in setting goals, aims and purposes and also, for instance, in perceptual feedback and control of fine-tuned motor function and tasks. How we think and details of what we consciously perceive have their effects in what we do and what we are able to do—where physical efficacy is clearly involved. This has always been a chief argument against Cartesian, psychophysical dualism which posits a fundamental or metaphysical opposition of mental vs. physical entities or substances. Our physical motions and activities doubtlessly depend on physiological activation of nerves and muscles, and these activities and processes are often finely adjusted by means of conscious attention to what we are doing and intermediate effects. Our awareness of our own activities, as in hand-eye coordination, helps guide and adjust them. James’s functionalism draws on arguments from his Principles of Psychology and the nineteenth-century literature, especially the post-Darwin literature; and his emphasis on function directly influenced subsequent
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 14
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Introduction xv
developments in the field of psychology.5 James was not alone in his emphasis on function. For example, the Cambridge University philosopher and psychologist, James Ward (1843–1925), characterized consciousness as involving a Darwinian “subjective selection” that enables animals to “select” an appropriate environment in significant degree.6 In general terms, for functional psychology, mental or psychical processes are understood as psychological adaptations of the biological organism to environmental conditions. The primary biological adaptations are inherited, certainly, but fine-grained adaptations are acquired and transmitted socially. James Mark Baldwin (1861–1934), for instance, saw intelligence, plasticity of mind and “conscious action” as correlated and linked products of evolution. “This means that, the utility of the conscious type of action once established, the premium put on variation in that line, carrying with them more plastic nervous substance and decaying congenital functions, was both enormous and effective.”7 In the evolution of the human species, plasticity of mind and conscious selection of actions and habits replaced rigid, inbuilt or instinctual action and response. Accordingly, human learning and cultural development exemplify powers opened up by biological adaptation. “In this manner,” as the contemporary cognitive psychologist Stanislas Dehaene has put the point, “. . . natural selection favored the emergence of learning. The evolutionary algorithm [which is “appallingly” slow] discovered a good trick: it is useful to let certain parameters of the body change rapidly in order to adjust to the most volatile aspects of the environment.”8 2. FUNCTIONAL PSYCHOLOGY Psychologist James Angell (1869–1949) argued, regarding consciousness, in particular, that “. . . consciousness in one or other of its forms normally appears and participates only in such activities as cannot be efficiently executed by the hereditary reflexes and the acquired automatisms.”9 This is to say that the function of conscious experience and activity, as contrasted with automatic, instinctual and habitual activity, is to draw on wider resources in situations where ongoing activities are interrupted or blocked in some problematic, or unexpected fashion. Like James in the Principles, Angell looks to the functional relations and correlations of conscious experience, the environment and neurophysiological response.10 Angell makes a related claim regarding how consciousness arises in the infant: Were we to take time for a thorough exploration of all the sensory forms of consciousness, e.g., vision, taste, smell, touch, etc., we should find that they are all called forth under the same conditions of inadequacy on the part of the purely
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 15
5/2/22 10:39 AM
xvi
H. G. Callaway
hereditary physiological mechanisms of movement, to meet the demand of the physical and social environment.11
In a significant sense, functional psychology provides an account of the workings of consciousness, an account of what consciousness does and why it is needed. Examining the brain and nervous system by means of physical examination and instruments, perhaps opening up the skull, we never find the conscious experience of a subject. At best we may find more or less regular, supporting physiological correlates. Consciousness is a matter of subjective experience, involving a great variety of conscious contents, and it is difficult to tie it to purely objective criteria; but on the assumptions of mind-brain identity theories, or reductive physicalism, this fact would be problematic. On the other hand, if conscious experience, as involved, for example, in veridical perception, is or depends on functional relations to objects of perception, then one naturally expects that consciousness simply is not there in the brain or nervous system to find. It is as though one sought the function of the heart or the stomach, of a hammer or a carburetor by physical or chemical tests. Physical and chemical testing will reveal causal conditions of typical functions, but it will not reveal the functions of these organs and artifacts. To discover the functions, you have to look at what these things do or how they are used. Angell goes on to claim that consciousness arises to facilitate the development and re-workings of habits of action. But there is a temptation at this point to contrast its functional character, what consciousness does, with some competing conception of what consciousness is. Angell proposes to explain in the quoted passage, the why and when of conscious experience: under what particular environmental and neuropsychological conditions, consciousness is “called forth.” He assumes that psycho-physiological activities are continuous, unceasing even in sleep. What is it, then, that is “called forth” when such activity proves inadequate? The defense of functional psychology requires an answer to this kind of question, and part of the answer is that the question often mistakes and underestimates functionalist resources. Functions are many and varied,12 but there is a commonality insofar as various functions can be equally understood as a matter of functional relations to objects. As the point is traditionally put, consciousness is always consciousness of something (or other).13 What is it that arises in “the sensory forms of consciousness” under “conditions of inadequacy” of the infant “on the part of the purely hereditary physiological mechanisms of movement”? The infant’s emergent episodes of conscious experience are to be understood as novel, functional relations to (and awareness of) the “physical and social environment.” That’s what consciousness is. Consciousness is useful to the organism,14 conferring an evolutionary advantage, because phenomenal experience is paradigmatically a (direct or indirect) functional relation to environmental conditions. We
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 16
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Introduction xvii
may reasonably expect that episodes of veridical perceptual experience, in particular, understood as functional relations to the environment, may suffice causally to produce needed and useful modifications of the details of neurophysiology—which may in turn redirect thought and behavior. Notice that this functional account of consciousness does not depend on precisely demarcating the neurophysiological conditions of consciousness in purely neurophysiological terms. But nor does it require rejection of the pursuit of neurophysiological correlates of conscious experience. Quite the contrary. Conceiving of psychological description, including description of the content of experience, as functional in character, psychological descriptions may be more or less adequate, and some degree of vagueness is to be expected with functional description generally—in comparison, say, to physical or chemical descriptions. This follows from the plausibility of “multiple realizability” of whatever is described in functional terms. But to presuppose a fundamental, mutually exclusive contrast between what consciousness does and what it is, is to beg the question against functional psychology. Phenomenal description of “what it is like” to be conscious, say, conscious of an apple or conscious of a red light at the intersection, is to be understood as description in functional terms. Functionalism is well represented in contemporary psychology and neuroscience (with or without being married to particular versions of the computer model of mind). This includes the contemporary thesis that conscious experience is “useful” to the organism possessing it. “Experiments,” according to the contemporary French neuroscientist Stanislas Dehaene, “point to consciousness as being highly efficacious.”15 Going back a generation, cognitive psychologist G. William Farthing aims for a developed psychology of consciousness within a functionalist conception of mind.16 James on “pure experience,” is much more problematic. He employed the notion in concert with his later philosophy of radical empiricism, but it ran into very significant complications and opposition. The opposition is signaled, for example, by Sidney Hook’s early skepticism of James’s “warm attachment to sensations;” Hook made the contrasting claim that “sense impressions must be interpreted as checks and signs of what things are said and taken to be not as revelations of what they intrinsically are.”17 This is to reject, for instance, James’s claim that pure experience is the “one primal stuff or material in the world, a stuff of which everything is composed, . . .”18 Although James can be found to make a similar point, Hook’s criticism marked a philosophical shift in the pragmatist tradition away from James and radical empiricism, under the influence of Charles S. Peirce (1839–1914) and later functional and naturalist conceptions of mind and representation.19 Readers will recall the renewed prominence of philosophical naturalism at about the same time.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 17
5/2/22 10:39 AM
xviii
H. G. Callaway
3. EMPIRICISM OLD AND NEW Classical British empiricism dating from the time of John Locke (1632– 1704), George Berkeley and David Hume (1711–1776) is the philosophical doctrine that all knowledge derives from sense experience. Locke aimed to trace all ideas to sense experience and argued against innate ideas.20 Berkeley identified being generally with what is perceived. “To be is to be perceived.”21 Hume continued the empiricist tradition aiming to trace all legitimate ideas back to sense impressions. Humean “ideas” can be remixed and compounded, but simple ideas enter the mind only as impressions. James’s “radical empiricism” seeks to expand on classical empiricist accounts of what is available from experience, in terms of “the stream of consciousness”: transitions and relations of one experience to another; and while James rejects the atomistic concept of simple ideas or elements of experience, he persists in the aim of finding the source of knowledge in experience. His concept of experience as the basis and source from which knowledge derives aligns him with the classical British empiricists.22 According to James, “Consciousness as we ordinarily understand it, does not exist any more than does matter, which Berkeley gave the coupe de grace.”23 Again, James held that “It is Berkeley who first honored this truth, Esse est percipi;” James’s radical empiricism agrees with Berkeley’s dictum, “to be is to be perceived;”24 “Our sensations are not small internal duplicates of things,” he explains, “they are the same things as things are presented to us.”25 This implies identification (or conflation) of objects of perceptual awareness with the contents of perceptual consciousness and the specific manner in which we are aware of objects in perception. In short, for radical empiricism objects of perception have something of the character of relational networks of intentional contents.26 He continues, however, chiefly theorizing in terms of objects of consciousness, because he thinks (or often supposes) that contents of perceptual awareness could only be intermediate or indirect objects of perception, as in epistemological theories of indirect realism.27 But James rejects such intermediate objects of perceptual awareness. His functional approach to psychology is—in this fashion—closer to direct realism. As he puts the matter, “Radical empiricism has, in fact, more affinities with natural realism than with the views of Berkeley or of Mill, and this can be easily shown.”28 James’s radical empiricism stands in tension and contrast with empiricism understood on the model and paradigm of the later, hypothetical-deductive method and its later elaborations.29 Our latter-day empiricism is not a doctrine about the origins of knowledge, ideas or concepts. Instead, contemporary empiricism has become chiefly a matter of how theory and hypothesis are to
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 18
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Introduction xix
be evaluated through linkages to explanation, prediction and the empirical testing of theories and hypotheses. Given that we borrow the very language of psychological descriptions, for instance, talk of “a red after-image,” or “imagining the odor of cheese,” or “the concept of energy” from the language used to describe or refer to objects of awareness, it becomes extremely implausible to think of empirical or experimental testing of hypotheses as going on, as radical empiricism has it, merely within the relations of episodes of conscious experience. Contemporary empiricism is object-oriented. James’s emphasis on the origins of ideas from the introspected relations of one experience to another, tends to drive radical empiricism in the direction of phenomenology and overemphasis on stand-alone introspection. Yet his emphasis on the relational and functional character of consciousness had profound consequences for psychology. The scientific naturalism emphasized in the Principles of Psychology, takes for granted that “the omnipresence of cognition (or reference to an object other than the mental state itself),” is “of the mental life’s essence.”30 In spite of his own criticisms of classical empiricism, James makes his alignment with British empiricism explicit, for instance, in the opening lecture of A Pluralistic Universe (1909): What do the terms empiricism and rationalism mean? Reduced to their most pregnant difference, empiricism means the habit of explaining wholes by parts, and rationalism means the habit of explaining parts by wholes. Rationalism thus preserves affinities with monism, since wholeness goes with union, while empiricism inclines to pluralistic views. . . . And the first thing to notice is this, that the only material we have at our disposal for making a picture of the whole world is supplied by the various portions of that world of which we have already had experience. We can invent no new forms of conception, applicable to the whole exclusively, and not suggested originally by the parts.31
In short, empiricism involves the “habit of explaining wholes by parts,” and nothing is available for explaining the world as a whole, except what is “supplied by the various portions of that world of which we have already had experience;” moreover, “we can invent no new forms of conception.” To avoid the philosophical temptations of totalizing, Hegelian holism, James’s radical empiricism directs us back to neglected details of experience. But it is doubtful that any legitimate or acceptable approach to conceptual meaning and linguistic usage will involve tracing it all back to sense experience in the genealogical manner of the classical empiricists. Contemporary criticism of “sense-data” theories, of the sorts found in classical empiricism from Locke down to Bertrand Russell, emphasize instead the priority and public character of language generally—and of the language of psychological
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 19
5/2/22 10:39 AM
xx
H. G. Callaway
descriptions in particular—as a condition of our learning to ascribe mental states to self and others. We learn the ordinary language of psychological descriptions and how to ascribe mental states to self and others in the normal course of language learning—relying on regularities of linguistic usage and our participation in related practices; and these are publicly available matters. This is a point often taken from the later Wittgenstein’s “private language argument.” The argument was directed against the Cartesian/empiricist notion of linguistic meanings and/or referents as private objects of acquaintance or introspection to which only one person could have access.32 In the end and for the sciences, it matters less where our concepts and theories come from than how they relate to public usage and—for scientific psychology—how they may stand up to public scrutiny and the practices of experimental testing.33 Novel theories and hypotheses in the various sciences and scholarly disciplines often involve distinctive conceptual innovations, especially prominent while under initial development and elaboration; and in their novelty, they often lack for clear experimental or observational consequences. Their theoretical meaning arises and persists, in distinctive public, theoretical usage and in relation to better established doctrine and its empirical support, though the experimentalists may initially doubt of any distinctive “cash value” in the form of novel predictions or testable, new empirical consequences. The point casts some doubt on the pragmatists’ conception of meaning. Meaningful and innovative theory, especially in the initial stages, may still lack for clear and distinctive empirical consequences. In James’s second essay, “A World of Pure Experience,” he explains the “pragmatic method,” in the following terms: When a dispute arises, that method consists in auguring what practical consequences would be different if one side rather than the other were true. If no difference can be thought of, the dispute is a quarrel over words.34
But this brings James perilously close to a “verification” theory of pragmatic meaning (or of differences in theoretical meaning).35 The theorist, employing an array of distinctive concepts, mathematical formalisms and generalizations, may yet labor long and hard to draw out novel and testable experimental predictions. It is not always immediately obvious how a particular theoretical approach can be made to yield distinctive, testable empirical consequences; but this need not be immediately fatal to the approach—in the short-to-medium term. Sometimes we do not know how to test a newly proposed hypothesis or theory. This does not prove that nothing interesting, distinctive or substantial has been proposed. As epistemology or philosophy of science and relying on James’s version of the pragmatic conception of
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 20
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Introduction xxi
theoretical meaning, radical empiricism is doubtful. It threatens the meaningful character of innovative, yet-to-be tested theoretical formulations. 4. JAMES ON INTROSPECTION Varieties of functionalism, including functional approaches to consciousness, have more recently enjoyed a revival in the philosophy of mind, cognitive science, neuroscience,36 computer science and related fields.37 Partly in consequence, it will be useful in what follows to devote particular attention to James’s functionalist themes in philosophy of mind and psychology. There are old errors to be avoided and insights to be mined. The concept of “pure experience,” as unadulterated, “unvarnished news” is presumably one such error. It linked James’s functionalist themes too closely to early modern (and Berkeleyan) epistemology, to stand-alone introspection and, one may well suspect, to vagaries of historical, introspective methods. Notice that James emphasized crucial roles for “introspective observation” in the Principles: Introspective Observation is what we have to rely on first and foremost and always. The word introspection need hardly be defined—it means, of course, the looking into our own minds and reporting what we there discover. Everyone agrees that we there discover states of consciousness.38
However, it is not even clear that introspection is a kind of observation. “Looking into our own minds” appears to be a set metaphor of sorts, otherwise “listening into our own minds,” or “tasting into our own minds” might be equally appealing descriptions or quasi-definitions of introspection.39 There is no known or introspected organ for “introspective observation.” Instead of “observation,” then, one might consider introspection a matter of recalling, interpreting or thinking about episodes of conscious experience. Whatever the unconscious psychological mechanisms of access that may be involved, we are capable of describing and thinking about the conscious experience of self and others. We may fairly regard James as sometimes uncritical or overly expansive on introspection of the relations of episodes of consciousness; and much of what he seeks to accomplish tracing or projecting the relations of episodes of experience is better done by objective methods and a more objective orientation. Still, James does firmly reject claims for infallibility of reports of introspection;40 and, according to James, we need not doubt of our own consciousness in order to be better aware of the guiding, interfering or selective influence of ordinary or technical language and theory on reports of introspection. James, early on, adopted his own critical perspective on introspection
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 21
5/2/22 10:39 AM
xxii
H. G. Callaway
as conceived and practiced among the classical empiricists and later in structuralist psychology. He was skeptical of simple or substantial “elements of mental structure” in particular. “And in truth,” he wrote, “There is no evidence whatever for supposing the pure atomic ideas of red and yellow, and the other elements of mental structure, to exist at all;” They are abstractions, mere fictitious psychic counterparts to those elementary qualities of which we come to believe the real world is made up, but no one of them is an actual psychic fact. Whenever an elementary quality of the outer world is thought by us, the vehicle of the thinking is a feeling representing a highly complex object, that quality in relation with something else.41
This argument, aimed in criticism of Hume for example, carries the implication that even Hume’s elementary “impressions” of sense, must be mere “artefacta,” that is, “fictitious” abstractions from the complex and moving stream of consciousness. James wrote that “The ‘simple impression’ of Hume and the ‘simple ideas of Locke’ are abstractions, never realized in experience.”42 Pure atomic ideas are perhaps the paradigmatic, purported “entities” of consciousness, which James’s functionalism rejects both early and late. But suppose that as a matter of fact, we never have isolated, Humean, or simple impressions of sense. What would this tell us about related conceptual distinctions, vocabulary and psychological description? The question naturally arises of the adequacy of our linguistic or conceptual means of introspective description. That question, in turn, is a version of the contemporary concern with the “theory-laden” character of descriptions in supporting data. In contrast to James, one may take a more moderate, less nominalistic approach. This involves the supposition that particular developments of psychological theory may favor and depend on particular correlated modes of introspective description so that the selection of descriptive terms is not merely arbitrary. Surely, James does not intend to violate common sense to the extent of claiming that we never experience, say, the red of an apple or the green of a mass of vegetation. But something of James’s skeptical view of structuralist introspection, and related skepticism among functionalist colleagues entered into functional psychology generally and eventually into behaviorist criticism of introspective methods.43 Even if sensations or perceptual experiences of red or of yellow, did not exist in isolation, it does not follow that these descriptive terms are “fictitious.” What exists in relation to something else (say, the perception of red accompanying the perception of an apple) still exists—whether as “entity” or in relation. James’s criticism, at best, empha-
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 22
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Introduction xxiii
sizes the relations of elements of conscious experience; and to his credit, he rejects intermediate perceptual objects or sense-data. The more basic problems of structural psychology and introspective description arose from expansion and broadening of the concept and uses of introspection (including James’s emphasis on introspection of relations of episodes of experience). Within structuralist psychology, disputes arose between the reported results of different structuralist laboratories; and standalone introspection lacks for effective means of checking or falsifying reports of introspection. As a methodological stricture, it is now generally accepted that when dealing with introspective reports as data of psychology, it is important to combine first person and third person (or objective) methods and perspectives. Reports of introspection are crucial as data of cognitive psychology and neuroscience, but introspection is inadequate, weak or imperfect as a stand-alone method.44 James had resisted the restraint imposed by Wilhelm Wundt’s emphasis on “stimulus control” in introspective laboratory work, where reports of experience are linked to experimental control over an immediate perceptual stimulus. In addition, the empirical constraint imposed by correlation of reports of conscious experience with neurophysiology has grown much more significant in contemporary psychology and neuroscience.45 Techniques of electroencephalographic brain scanning and fMRI brain imaging, for example, combined with stimulus control, have become very prominent in both theoretical work and in clinical practice.46 In its historical context, Jamesian and functionalist criticism of introspective accounts of consciousness chiefly took aim at the introspective school of psychology represented by Wundt and his structuralist students including Edward B. Titchener (1867–1927). Structural psychology aimed for an exhaustive catalog of the elementary contents of the human mind—all the discriminable variety of sensations or phenomenal elements, including perception of colors, sound, smells, etc. But there was a lack of consensus on methods and results between different laboratories such as that of Wundt himself and those of his students Edward B. Titchener at Cornell University and the laboratory of Oswald Külpe (1862–1915) and his associates at Würzburg.47 Wundt had a more limited, conservative approach to introspection, because he insisted on experimental, stimulus control. In this way, it should be noted, reports of introspection in Wundt’s laboratory correlated with situations of ordinary empirical observation. James, in contrast with Wundt, and emphasizing the relations of distinct episodes of conscious experience, understood introspection, following arguments due to J.S. Mill, as a matter of “retrospection” and reports depending on recall of conscious experience.48
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 23
5/2/22 10:39 AM
xxiv
H. G. Callaway
Complications arise. The evaluation of introspection as “retrospection” would seem to depend in some degree upon specifics of theory concerning memory. Does our recall of an experience, when reporting on it, amount to bringing back the same experience? Or, is memory in some sense a matter of “re-creation” of past experience? To what extent is the memory of an experience faithful to the original? Is remembering a perceptual experience itself a kind of “inner” perception or is it more like thinking (even if imagistic thinking) about past experience? It remains unclear that James’s concept of introspection in terms of memory does much to clarify the theory and practice involved in treating introspective reports as data. Keeping introspection under strict stimulus control, augmented by techniques of brain scanning and brain imaging, though a significant limitation, would appear to be more in keeping with the goal of dependable scientific methods. Wider use of reports of introspection as data in psychological experiments, say, on dreaming or imagination or higher cognitive processes requires close and detailed consideration of the limitations of introspective methods. It is reasonable to suppose, in spite of the structuralist focus on elements of experience, that the concepts we bring with us to experience make a difference to reports of introspection. In summary, supposing, with common sense, that each person is aware in some fashion of the conscious workings of their own mind, the scientific approach to elucidation of this self-awareness has long been somewhat problematic. Wundt’s approach to introspection as “inner perception” emphasized strict stimulus control over reported experiences, and remained closer to situations of ordinary empirical observation. This has the advantage of depending on the general reliability of perception—which is surely a chief element of the plausibility of empiricism and, it would seem, an accomplishment of eons of biological evolution. James, in contrast, with his emphasis on the relations of one experience to another, conceived of “introspective observation” as depending on memory.49 None of these historical concepts of introspection had access to modern methods of brain imaging and scanning—capable of establishing more detailed correlations of stimulus objects, reports of conscious experience and neurophysiological processes. 5. INTERPRETING AWARENESS A good example of how linguistic usage effects reports of conscious experience arises from colorblind people who remain unaware of their condition. They learn and learn to use the full repertoire of color words in approximate agreement with everyone else; and the red-green colorblind will agree that apples are red and grass is green, though they will also sometimes mislabel
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 24
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Introduction xxv
the colors of things. But if in an experiment a colorblind person is shown an apple and asked if they see the red of the apple, they would, naturally, make a false report of the “introspected” color perception. Or, we might also say that they depart in details of usage from the usual visual application of color words. The example illustrates one way in which the specific conceptual resources we bring to introspection can and do influence reports of introspection.50 The example hints at the more general problem that the “theory-laden” character of descriptions of data presents for the scientific status of introspective reports.51 The limits and fallibility of introspective reports are emphasized by the mere plausibility of James’s emphatic denial that the word “consciousness,” stands for a “thing” or entity, though as he has it, “it does stand for a function.” To support his claim, James depends on his elaborate theoretical framework for reports of introspection. We may reasonably doubt that his elaborate claims are fully and adequately supported by stand-alone introspection. Historical thinkers have “looked into” their own minds and found “ideas” “sense impressions” or “sense-data,” but these amount to alternative conceptual models for interpreting and reporting on conscious experience. James also considers disputes over which qualities are attributed to external objects vs. those due to purely subjective conditions. Are things in the world objectively disgusting or morally repulsive, for example? What of the distinction between quantifiable “primary qualities” and “secondary qualities” and the banning of “secondary qualities” from accounts of the physical world in early modern science? James writes: The obstinate controversies that have arisen over such statements as these . . . prove how hard it is to decide by bare introspection what it is in experiences that shall make them either spiritual or material. It surely can be nothing intrinsic in the individual experience. It is their way of behaving towards each other, their system of relations, their function; and all these things vary with the context in which we find it opportune to consider them.52
Is the experience of color merely subjective? Is color to be banned from accounts of the physical world in favor of quantifiable, “primary qualities” such as size and shape? Whatever answer we give to the question will not plausibly be decided by introspective reports of perceptual experience alone. It is instead a more complex question of the relations of reports of experience to our developed accounts of mind, nature and physical reality. We must at least know something about the neurophysiological basis of color perception, and something about light and the reflection of light from objects; and these sorts of investigations surely require that we go beyond evidence available from stand-alone introspection. Does experience of color function to inform
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 25
5/2/22 10:39 AM
xxvi
H. G. Callaway
us about the character of the physical world? It would seem as a matter of common sense and physical observation and experiments that it does; consider only the phenomenon of prisms, observations of the visual spectrum and the uses of spectroscopy in detecting the chemical elements. However, we have good reason to doubt that the informative character of our experience of color can be established in the sciences merely on the basis of a Jamesian account of the introspected character and relations of episodes of experience. One may regard useful introspective reports as arising from “reflection,” or our thinking about our own conscious experience. Exactly how we think about it makes a difference to the reports. Jack and Shallice (2001) describe a series of experiments conducted with children of about nine years of age. The children were given problems of arithmetic of the form “Y + X -X = ?” At first the children solved such problems by adding X to Y and afterward subtracting X. However, with experience, they stopped performing the calculation and simply answered “Y.” The strategy employed could be distinguished by means of measurement of the response time. The interesting result arises from children’s reports when they are asked how they solved the problem. Once the strategy is well established, children reliably report its use. However, for the first few trials on which they use the strategy, children report counting just as they had before. In other words, the children appear to lack awareness of their own discovery and use of the strategy. This study shows that at least during development, repeated experience of a mental state or process is necessary before the model is updated to allow accurate introspective identification of that state or process.53
At the least, the children’s articulation of an introspective report on use of a mental strategy may require some prior habituation and/or reflective contrast of the new strategy with the earlier method. In a somewhat similar way, actual linguistic usage may be fully consistent with an abstract dictionary definition—which is itself based on empirical study of usage—, though those conforming to established usage cannot always provide the corresponding dictionary definition. Or, the initial difficulty of the children’s reports might be compared to the way that a skilled dancer enacts all the steps correctly, though only the choreographer can describe and report on the steps the dancer takes.54 This seems to make of introspection a matter of reflecting on or thinking about our conscious experience, on the basis of the ability to describe objects of awareness in related terms. Inspired by Darwin, William James, and figures such as James Mark Baldwin and James Ward, functionalism became a distinctive school of psychology. Overall, the critical view argued for in the present essay is that this earlier version and school of functional psychology suffered from an excess
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 26
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Introduction xxvii
of vagueness and lacked for a certain scientific and logical thoroughness. Its failures include (judged in accordance with its own precepts)—the failure to interpret specifically psychological vocabulary and description (description of phenomenal content) as functional in character. Describing perceptual experience of red does not imply that perceptual experience is itself red, just as describing perceptual experience of something wet and slippery does not imply that the perceptual experience is itself wet and slippery. It is in pursuit of related points in the present essay that James on “radical empiricism,” “pure experience,” and James’s “pragmatic method” come under scrutiny and criticism.55 Defects and weakness in radical empiricism, viewed as epistemology or philosophy of science, conditioned corresponding weaknesses in early twentieth-century functional psychology which are of interest for contemporary work in the philosophy of mind and foundational issues in psychology. We want to know in particular and in significant detail what became of James-inspired American functionalist psychology, and why it so frequently gave way to narrow forms of behaviorism. The critical perspective involved shares an emphasis on language, linguistic usage and the public or intersubjective character of the language of psychological description deriving from Wittgenstein’s later work. 6. THEMES AND PROBLEMS OF FUNCTIONAL PSYCHOLOGY In the opening chapter of the Principles of Psychology, James reflects on an argument by analogy to the effect that a machine, such as a clock, will produce correct results when it is in good working order, and produce incorrect results if it is out of order, though both kinds of results equally follow a causally determined sequence dependent on the same physical laws and on internal mechanical conditions.56 A clockwork, the structure of which determines it to a certain rate of speed, takes no notice, of course, that this speed is too slow or too fast. Whether a clock keeps good time or runs too slow or too fast, it mindlessly follows the same physical and mechanical laws. Similarly, if the brain is somehow disordered and someone, say, fails to recognize the faces of familiar friends and family members, following a traumatic shock to the head, then clearly, something has gone wrong. The strange performance, though it conforms to the same physical and chemical laws as a correct performance, is nevertheless defective and dysfunctional. What this argument suggest is that our concept of psychological function contains normative elements, and correct functioning depends not only on the physics of the nervous system, but more directly upon particularities of
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 27
5/2/22 10:39 AM
xxviii
H. G. Callaway
functional-normative organization and processes of the relevant neurophysiology structures. Though a brain conforms to the exact same physical laws, it may, in spite of that, be functionally well organized or, instead, dysfunctional in its structural forms or in the fine details of internal organization. The point is illustrated by face blindness after a shock to the brain. This arises from injury to specific brain structures. Though in a faulty clock the overall clockworks remain the same, the faulty clock can often be repaired by means of fine adjustments to the internal clockworks. To extend the analogy, we know that the adjustments to the clockworks are correct and the repairs sufficient, when the clock keeps good time: that is, when the clock functions correctly. Unfortunately, after an injury to the brain there is sometimes no way to cure the harm. Still, in a somewhat similar way, though the larger-scale, neurophysiological structures passed on by heredity remain substantially the same, the effects of learning and education may be regarded as affecting fine neurophysiological adjustments; and we know that the educational process is successful on the basis of normative standards of performance.57 This includes, for instance, conscious recognition and re-identifying a new face recently seen, or, say, common standards and testing for mastery of linguistic usage. But notice that on this kind of approach, we would not expect proper psychological functioning to correlate with states of the neurophysiological system described in purely physical terms; instead, they correlate more directly with the functional organization and processes of the (biological) neurophysiological system. The point is particularly evident in cases where an alternative area of the brain is able to take up functions otherwise lost due to injury. The detailed physics and neurophysiology varies though the psychological function is the same. This is sometimes called “the anomaly of the mental”58 or “multiple realizability”: There is no exact, consistent and complete, law-like mapping of mental states and processes onto physical states and processes. Still, we may assume that every mental process is physically embodied in some fashion or other. That is a condition of causal mind-body interactions and of the causal efficacy of mind and consciousness. Functional psychology is non-Cartesian and non-dualistic, because it requires no non-physical “substance” or entities, and it stipulates no violations or exceptions from physical laws of nature. But, on the other hand, it does not require a reductive materialism or physicalism, because no identification of psychological descriptions and regularities with purely physical descriptions and laws of physics is attempted or required. On the contrary, the developed and intricate relations of functional, psychological description and neurophysiology suffice to embed functional psychology within the life sciences. James is often suggestive of developing trends among his contemporaries. He criticized the static, descriptive and introspective, structuralist concep-
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 28
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Introduction xxix
tion of the basic or “atomic” elements of the contents of consciousness early on.59 This is essentially a criticism of the scientific adequacy of structuralist phenomenology, though the scope of the criticism extends to much of modern philosophy from Descartes onward through both the empiricists and the rationalist thinkers. James famously emphasized the relational, moving, continuous and “streaming” character of conscious experience. His criticisms of set, elementary structures in introspection were reflected later in criticism of the work of Edward B. Titchener from James’s functionalist colleagues. Though Titchener accepted Darwin in biology, he did not apply Darwinian thought to psychology in any systematic fashion.60 In contrast, psychologist James Angell wrote that functional psychology involves “identification” with “the effort to discern and portray the typical operations of consciousness under actual life conditions, as over against the attempt to analyze and describe its elementary and complex contents.”61 Angell prioritizes a functionalist conception of consciousness over a structuralist approach. If consciousness arose in biological evolution, then it must have a function. It is also worth noticing that “function” has in this passage, already been reinterpreted in terms of “operations of consciousness” and set in opposition to structuralist accounts of the contents of consciousness. We stand on the verge of a devolution of functionalism, via “operationalist” and verificationalist theories of meaning, into psychological operationalism—and eventually from there to behaviorism.62 How could one sensibly discern the operations of consciousness, understood as a matter of what functions it performs, when needed accounts and the specification of the contents of consciousness and introspective methods remained under a cloud of higher-order doubt? What was needed was some theoretical basis for discerning, describing, individuating—and correcting— introspective reports of the contents of consciousness: including an explicitly functionalist psychosemantics. But it seems clear that the pragmatists’ conception of linguistic meaning, and James’s account of “the pragmatic method” in particular, tended toward verificationism and operationalism.63 Taking up a traditional conception of the field, however, James defined psychology, in the Briefer Course (1892), as “the description and explanation of states of consciousness as such,” noting that “by states of consciousness are meant such things as sensations, desires, emotions, cognitions, reasonings, decisions, volitions, and the like.”64 Though we understand the talk of “states of consciousness” in functional and relational terms generally, still there is a need to give some account of conscious experience and contents that stand in functional relations. What was needed was a developed, functional account of experiential contents. One hope was that this might be accomplished by drawing on the empirical correlation of mental and neurological processes; and physiological studies
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 29
5/2/22 10:39 AM
xxx
H. G. Callaway
remained an important and slowly progressing sub-discipline of psychology. For example, following his introductory chapter on “The Scope of Psychology” in the Principles, James devoted the following two chapters of that work to the functions of the brain and the factual, neurophysiological conditions of psychological activities. For James, there is no denying the dependence of the mind on the brain: “The fact that the brain is the one immediate bodily condition of the mental operations is indeed so universally admitted nowadays” he writes in the Principles, “that I need spend no more time in illustrating it but will simply postulate it and pass on. The whole remainder of the book will be more or less of a proof that the postulate was correct.”65 Disputing “spiritualist” and older, pre-Darwinian philosophical approaches, James held that “mental facts cannot be properly studied apart from the physical environment of which they take cognizance,” and further, there is his directly Darwinian theme: “our inner faculties are adapted in advance to the features of the world in which we dwell, adapted, I mean, so as to secure our safety and prosperity in its midst.”66 If our psychological faculties or capabilities are biological adaptations, then it is natural to assume that psychological activities and processes are also chiefly or regularly adaptive and thereby functional in detail. It is not of course that psychological states and processes can never be dysfunctional or maladapted, according to James, but he argues, that the dysfunctional belongs not to psychology proper but instead to the distinctive discipline of psychiatry. As for psychology proper, The chief result of all this more modern view is the gradually growing conviction that mental life is primarily teleological; that is to say, that our various ways of feeling and thinking have grown to be what they are because of their utility in shaping our reactions on the outer world. On the whole, few recent formulas have done more service in psychology than the Spencerian one that the essence of mental life and bodily life are one, namely, “the adjustment of inner to outer relations.” The adjustment is to immediately present objects in lower animals and in infants. It is to objects more and more remote in time and space, and inferred by means of more and more complex and exact processes of reasoning, when the grade of mental development grows more advanced.67
The reference to Herbert Spencer in this passage, and the theme of “adjustment of inner to outer relations,” comes from Spencer’s Principles of Psychology (1855) in a passage where he explains his definition of life: “the broadest and most complete definition of life will be—the continuous adjustment of internal relations to external relations.”68 James held the working hypothesis in the Briefer Course that “mental action may be uniformly and absolutely a function of brain-action, varying as the latter varies, and being to the brain-action as effect to cause;”69 and,
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 30
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Introduction xxxi
So far as possible, then, we are to study states of consciousness in correlation with their probable neural conditions. Now the nervous system is well understood today to be nothing but a machine for receiving impressions and discharging reactions preservative to the individual and his kind.70
The point expresses James’s naturalist approach in his psychological writings. However, James on “radical empiricism” and “pure experience” involves a departure from this scientific naturalism in the direction of a metaphysics.71 He attempts to get beyond the problematic status and effective blockage of progress involved in the mere “correlation” of states of consciousness with their “probable neural conditions.” It should be observed, then, that in spite of the appeal of James’s functionalism, radical empiricism and the notion of “pure consciousness” do little by way of resolving the historical problems of research on the detailed correlations of conscious experience to its neurophysiological conditions. In contrast with James’s philosophical approach to the function of consciousness, modern experimental techniques of brain scanning and brain imagining (which James as psychologist would have surely welcomed), render it plausible to identify or detect (even unreported) episodes of conscious experience by reference to neurophysiological correlate(s) and more fully probe and understand, say, the psychological function of conscious face recognition.72 If face blindness or prosopagnosia is dysfunctional, then we should expect that episodes of conscious face recognition are functional relations to faces recognized. More generally, if consciousness is itself conceived of in functional terms, then this presents a challenge to recent versions of functionalism developed under the influence of the “computer model of mind.”73 If consciousness is adaptive in function, then we naturally come to expect that the specific, differentiated contents of consciousness are also regularly adaptive. 7. FROM DUALISM TO BEHAVIORISM? According to psychologist John B. Watson in a famous address to the American Psychological Association in 1913 “. . . behaviorism74 is the only consistent and logical functionalism.” On the same page, he also claims that “we can write a psychology,” and “never use the terms consciousness, mental states, mind, content, introspectively verifiable, imagery, and the like.”75 The oft-repeated quip is that in contrast with prior, more humanistic approaches, with the advent of Watson’s behaviorism, psychology “lost its mind.” William James might well have been surprised at this development, although he did put the very existence of consciousness in question—as traditionally conceived. James was, in fact, one of the last of the great practitioners
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 31
5/2/22 10:39 AM
xxxii
H. G. Callaway
of introspective psychology. His substantial doubts focused on particular concepts of consciousness, including dualistic versions and concepts of consciousness, linked to the Kantian “transcendental ego” and which he found in the work of philosophers and psychologists such as Wilhelm Schuppe, Johannes Rehmke, Paul Natorp, the early writings of Hugo Münsterberg and work of Richard von Schubert-Soldern.76 James is critical of consciousness conceived of as a “diaphanous” or “ghostly,” non-material entity distinct from the objects and contents of which we are conscious. In the following passage, he puts forward the proposal that consciousness is a function: To deny plumply that ‘consciousness’ exists seems so absurd on the face of it—for undeniably ‘thoughts’ do exist—that I fear some readers will follow me no farther. Let me then immediately explain that I mean only to deny that the word stands for an entity, but to insist most emphatically that it does stand for a function. There is, I mean, no aboriginal stuff or quality of being, contrasted with that of which material objects are made, out of which our thoughts of them are made; but there is a function in experience which thoughts perform, and for the performance of which this quality of being is invoked. That function is knowing.77
The proposal that consciousness is a functional relation or “a function in experience” is a keynote of what came to be called “functional psychology.” Mental states and processes came to be understood as adaptations of the biological organism to environmental conditions. One might say, in broad terms, that functional psychology aimed at a middle course, accepting a semi-autonomous science of psychology open to experimental development, and recognizing the dependence of psychological functions on brain functions, but navigating to avoid psycho-physical (Cartesian or Kantian) dualism on the one hand and reductive or behaviorist materialism (in contemporary terms, reductive physicalism plays the role of materialism) on the other. Viewed in historical perspective, however, the behaviorism of John B. Watson appears to have developed directly out of scientific discontent with functional psychology. Functionalism in the writings of William James resembles or is suggestive of a contemporary concept in the philosophy of mind, a Jamesian or pluralistic version of what is called the “anomaly of the mental.”78 James sought to avoid a dualism involving “mind stuff” in contrast to “matter;” and he also sought to avoid philosophical monisms, particularly monism formulated in holistic, totalizing and “absolutist” terms. As one of the most recognized and influential psychologists of his times, James also resisted reductive or eliminative materialism. He takes the specifics of psychological language and results of the experimental science of psychology seriously, in a quasi-
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 32
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Introduction xxxiii
realist (or “pragmatic”) manner. In opposition to philosophical, totalizing or reductive monism, James defends an empirical pluralism. How, then, best to understand anti-dualist pluralism? What is to be plural and what is to be singular? For James and radical empiricism, the answer to this question is partly his doctrine of “pure experience.” That notion represents and expresses both the originality and peculiar genius of radical empiricism and a central problem in evaluating radical empiricism. Though James maintains that “There is, . . . no aboriginal stuff or quality of being, contrasted with that of which material objects are made, out of which our thoughts of them are made,” he can also be found to claim that our thoughts are relational configurations of “pure experience.” 8. DOES PURE EXPERIENCE EXIST? James explains his concept of “pure experience,” in preliminary fashion, as follows: My thesis is that if we start with the supposition that there is only one primal stuff or material in the world, a stuff of which everything is composed, and if we call that stuff ‘pure experience,’ then knowing can easily be explained as a particular sort of relation towards one another into which portions of pure experience may enter. The relation itself is a part of pure experience; one of its ‘terms’ becomes the subject or bearer of the knowledge, the knower, the other becomes the object known.79
One quite curious point in this passage is the notion of “pure experience” as “one primal stuff,” a “stuff” of which “everything is composed.” James’s Principles is not of much help, since he there defines “experience” in terms of itself, as follows: “Experience means experience of something foreign supposed to impress us, whether spontaneously or in consequence of our own exertions and acts.”80 However, James also later says, that pure experience “is immediate flux of life which furnishes the material to our later reflection with its conceptual categories.”81 But the vivid metaphor of “the immediate flux of life,” presents a difficulty. It suggests, consistent with the broad outlines of James’s Principles, our understanding pure experience as a specifically biological phenomenon. If “pure experience” belongs to the “immediate flux of life,” it would presumably be a biological phenomenon of some sort. But in accordance with James’s own Darwinian and biologically oriented conception of psychology, since “our inner faculties are adapted in advance to the features of the world in which we dwell,” one would expect that any biological concept of experience
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 33
5/2/22 10:39 AM
xxxiv
H. G. Callaway
would reflect details and peculiarities of evolutionary development. For example, human sensory experience, comes in visual, auditory, and tactile forms, etc., while other animals possess contrasting sensory modes—for instance the developed echo-location of bats or sensitivity to electric currents in sharks. One will recall, further, that human vision is sensitive to only a very narrow band of electromagnetic radiation (likewise, we detect only sound waves in a particular range of frequencies); and experimental results suggest concepts of “innate quality spacing,” which show up as an ability to discriminate or in failure to discriminate shades of color and related phenomena in experimental results—with or without benefit of higher-order linguistic conceptualization. If “pure experience” is biologically conditioned and structured and a result of evolutionary adaptation, then presumably even the supposed “blooming, buzzing confusion” which James attributes to the experience of the newborn child, will have its functionally conditioned “inbuilt” structure.82 If on the other hand, we suppose that pure experience is somehow universal and not biologically conditioned (and in consequence not differing from one organism or species to another?), then it is hard to see how it could be fully functional or adapted. Ordinarily, we would not suppose that human experience is a “stuff” at all. Speaking of sense experience, for instance, we ordinarily think in terms of the interaction (or the results of interaction) of a person, an organism or perhaps the sense organs with the larger environment. Or, experience is often thought of in contrast with book learning and as a matter of the accumulated result of observation and direct participation in practical affairs. But in James, his notion of pure experience as a “stuff” or “prime matter,” is a kind of metaphysical hypothesis or postulate, which he invites us to accept on grounds of its explanatory value. “Knowing,” he says, “can easily be explained as a particular sort of relation towards one another into which portions of pure experience may enter,” and moreover, this relation of knowing, is “itself a part of pure experience.” But, since knowing anything is ordinarily taken to imply the truth of what is known, one may reasonably doubt that “knowing” could be generally or specifically a matter of some relation among portions or episodes of “pure experience.” James later removes something of the sting of this initial account of pure experience, by maintaining that the “stuff” of experience or of portions of experience are later organized conceptually by reference to differing “contexts”— their appearance in distinct sequences and relations of experience. James writes: A given undivided portion of experience, taken in one context of associates, plays the part of a knower, of a state of mind, of ‘consciousness’; while in a different context the same undivided bit of experience plays the part of a thing known, of
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 34
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Introduction xxxv
an objective ‘content.’ In a word, in one group it figures as a thought, in another group as a thing. And, since it can figure in both groups simultaneously we have every right to speak of it as subjective and objective both at once.83
Pure experience involves an identity of “parts” or “portions” of our experience with the object of thought, an identity of the subject and object of thought. Jamesian “humanistic epistemology” involves no Cartesian “breach;” it is instead a pluralistic philosophy of the identity of subject and object of thought or perception, an “Identitätsphilosophie.”84 Radical empiricism, moreover, is an all encompassing notion: For James, “All that is experienced is real, and all that is real is experience.”85 He compares the identity of thought and thing to the way in which the same mathematical point can belong to more than one of a pair of intersecting lines.86 A good part of his defense of the concept of “pure experience” is devoted to refutation of the Absolute Idealist thesis of internal relations; James chiefly attends to the philosophy of the British Idealist, F.H. Bradley (1846–1924). On the Idealist’s assumption that relations essentially modify and qualify whatever they relate, Jamesian “pure experience” would surely make no sense: A portion of experience, in one Jamesian context (set or sequence of relations) could not be identical with that portion of pure experience located in a distinct context. The doctrine of internal relations is the Absolute Idealists’ thesis that all relations of one thing to another are “internal” to the terms related in the sense of being essential, so that the bearers of relations would not “be what they are” without them. James rejects this notion and argues for the possibility of the self-identity of items or portions of pure experience through changes or differences in the “external relations” or context of portions of pure experience. But even if we suppose (consistent with arguments against the thesis that all relations are essential or internal to their terms), that the identity of “portions” of Jamesian “pure experience” could persist through change of some relations, it is much less plausible to think that items of pure experience (or anything at all) could persist in the claimed self-identity through each arbitrarily selected change or difference of relations, and that is just the plausibility of rejecting the concept of pure experience—on the grounds that nothing could be both (a portion of) a thought about a physical object, say a room or a table, and also (a portion of) the very same room or table. No part or “portion” of a room or table is also a part or “portion” of a thought or other conscious experience. But if no portion or element of any physical object perceived is in fact a constituent or element of a conscious thought or experience of a physical object, then “pure experience” does not exist.87 This argument rests squarely on common sense and is basic in how we ordinarily understand the contrast between the conscious contents and objects
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 35
5/2/22 10:39 AM
xxxvi
H. G. Callaway
of consciousness. There can be no “portions” of pure experience x and y, such that at a given time t, Rxa and not-Rya & x=y. If this fire, x, burns sticks and my experience of fire y, does not burn sticks, then x, the fire, is not identical with y, my experience of fire. This is not to say, though, that an experience never stands in significant relation to particular objects. The point is that the relation is not identity.88 It is not merely that James’s notion of pure experience violates common sense. The stronger point is that, given reasonable assumptions, the purported reference to items of pure experience cannot be consistently interpreted. If I see a wet and slippery bar of soap, for instance, then it may be literally described using the predicate expressions “is a bar,” “soap,” “wet,” “slippery.” On the other hand, the perceptual experience of the bar of soap is neither a bar, nor soap, nor wet and slippery. It is instead that the experience is characterized as one of such objects, of a sort properly and appropriately functioning in awareness of such objects. But James on pure experience conflates the description of objects of experience with description of contents of conscious experience, and this problem runs very deep: Pure experience is supposed to be somehow “neutral,” but on the other hand, given that it belongs to experience, it would seem to be already on the side of the subject, mind and consciousness. 9. ACT, OBJECT AND CONTENT In the philosophy of language, it is traditional and standard to distinguish linguistic acts, “speech acts,” or “utterances,” from objects of reference which may be involved, and from the propositional content of what is said, or of a statement made, a question posed, a command issued, etc. There is 1) the act of speech, 2) the object(s) which we are talking about, and 3) what is said about the objects of interest. The distinction between objects of reference and propositional content is particularly important, since it is factually possible (knowingly or unknowingly) to refer to the same object or domain of objects in quite distinctive ways. The propositional content (or meaning) of a statement “The morning star is the brightest star in the sky,” is distinct from that of “The evening star is the brightest star in the sky,” even though, as a matter of empirical discovery, the morning star = the evening star. A question of significant conceptual-theoretical interest is whether and how a similar set of distinctions can be applied to psychological phenomena generally. Conceptual differences are of particular interest in philosophy generally, and so it is, too, in the philosophy of psychology and cognitive science. It often happens that the same objects (or domain of objects) are addressed
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 36
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Introduction xxxvii
by distinctive theoretical and conceptual-linguistic means. For example, the older phlogiston theory and the later oxygen theory in chemistry, were both concerned with the phenomenon of combustion; but they differ conceptually and in doctrine, and they were concerned to explain and encompass evidence arising from specific episodes of combustion. (For example, do the products of combustion weigh more or less than objects which undergo combustion?). However, the two theories differed in their theoretical and conceptual resources and postulates. Once the success of the oxygen theory of combustion was established, there was no further use for the concept of phlogiston in chemistry. One might say that the oxygen theory amounted to an elimination theory of phlogiston. Again, both Aristotle’s biological views and Darwin’s theory of evolution recognize and make reference to the biological species, their differences and their reproduction. Though the domain of reference is substantially the same, Aristotle and Darwin differ in fundamental ways in what they say about the biological species. Ancient Greek thought failed to develop a scientific conception of biological evolution and Aristotle regarded the biological species as fixed natural forms, eternal and unchanging. Though emphasizing evolutionary developments, of course, Darwin had to also make room for the chief evidence supporting Aristotle view: the regular reproduction of the species after their own kind. In both the chemical and biological cases, substantial sameness of reference persists through theoretical and conceptual contrasts. Does a similar set of distinctions apply to psychological phenomena generally? Thought or thinking is most naturally interpreted in a similar fashion. (After all, people sometimes catch themselves “thinking out loud” saying in discussion or exchange what they had never before thought.)89 Presumably, we want to distinguish between (1) the act of thinking, a psychological process or activity, (2) what we are thinking about (e.g., we are thinking about language, or about the planet Venus, etc.) and (3) what we think about it, the content of thought. Similarly with perception. Someone may be seeing a friend in the distance, and we may reasonably suppose that there are important differences between (1) the act or activity of seeing, (2) what one is seeing, here, the friend in the distance and (3) how or in what manner one is seeing the friend in the distance, say, as a familiar person, recognized or perhaps alternatively, as vaguely familiar. With this trichotomy in mind, consider the following quotation from James, Principles of Psychology, starting from what he calls “the psychologist’s fallacy.” “The great snare of the psychologist” James writes, “is the confusion of his own standpoint with that of the mental fact about which he is making his report”:
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 37
5/2/22 10:39 AM
xxxviii
H. G. Callaway
I shall hereafter call this the ‘psychologist’s fallacy’ par excellence. For some of the mischief, here too, language is to blame. The psychologist, . . . , stands outside of the mental state he speaks of. Both itself and its object are objects for him. Now when it is a cognitive state (percept, thought, concept, etc.), he ordinarily has no other way of naming it than as the thought, percept, etc., of that object. He himself, meanwhile, knowing the self-same object in his way, gets easily led to suppose that the thought, which is of it, knows it in the same way in which he knows it, although this is often very far from being the case.90
One point worth emphasizing in this passage is that we often have “no way of naming” a cognitive state, except by borrowing the language used for the object of the state; it is “the thought, percept, etc., of that object.” (This is itself a profound point.) But this fact evokes James’s warning against the psychologist’s temptation to describe or characterize the mental state of another person in terms of the psychologist’s own thought and knowledge of the object. Though Jones is thinking about the morning star, and in fact, as the psychologist knows, the morning star is the planet Venus, still it would be (or may be) a mistake to characterize the content of Jones’ thought in just those terms. It is perfectly possible to have a thought about the morning star without knowing or believing (or even while denying) that the morning star is the planet, Venus. Similarly, though both Aristotle and Darwin wrote and thought about the biological species (which, in fact arose by evolution), it would still be an error to claim on those grounds that Aristotle proposed a (null) theory of evolution. It is important to avoid historical anachronism, reading into Aristotle something that he does not say or giving the impression that he was arguing with Darwin. Notice, however, that the need of the warning rests on the identification of the same object(s) concerning which there are differences of knowledge, theory, belief or conceptualization; and the warning might be put as a matter of the need to distinguish psychological (cognitive) content from corresponding objects of awareness. James elaborates his warning against the psychologist’s fallacy, and the elaboration presents a problem: Another variety of the psychologist’s fallacy is the assumption that the mental state studied must be conscious of itself as the psychologist is conscious of it. The mental state is aware of itself only from within; it grasps what we call its own content, and nothing more. The psychologist, on the contrary, is aware of it from without, and knows its relations with all sorts of other things. What the thought sees is only its own object; what the psychologist sees is the thought’s object, plus the thought itself, plus possibly all the rest of the world. We must be very careful therefore, in discussing a state of mind from the psychologist’s point of view, to avoid foisting into its own ken matters that are only there for ours. We must avoid substituting what we know the consciousness is, for what
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 38
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Introduction xxxix
it is a consciousness of, and counting its outward, and so to speak physical, relations with other facts of the world, in among the objects of which we set it down as aware.91
Though we can generally sympathize with James’s warnings against the “psychologist’s fallacy,” in spite of that, and just where we might expect him to be quite clear on the distinction between object and content, he is tempted to conflate object and content. He claims that “We must avoid substituting what we know the consciousness is, for what it is a consciousness of, and counting its outward, and so to speak physical, relations with other facts of the world, in among the objects of which we set it down as aware.” Here the objects of consciousness under consideration seem to be reduced to and conflated with the content of the mental state under study or consideration. The object is reduced to the content. Its as though one held, that because when I see my chair, I only see one side of it at a time, I do not “really” see the chair. For example, suppose we are concerned with Jones and his seeing of his friend in the distance. It may indeed be his friend in the distance who Jones is seeing; but holding this true does not prejudice our also saying, for example, by way of description of content, that Jones is recognizing his friend—or perhaps not, and he only perceives someone vaguely familiar. The object of perception does not reduce to the content of the perceptual experience. The general point is the importance of distinguishing objects of perception from the content of the perceptual experience—though descriptions line up in veridical cases of perception. By parity of reasoning, it is like the situation in which one person refers to the morning star and the second person refers to the evening star. In fact, and perhaps unbeknownst to them, because what they say involves contrasts of meaning (content), they are nonetheless talking about the same astronomical object. James appears insufficiently sensitive to this kind of point; and that marks him as a pre-analytical thinker. The weakness is in fact suggestive of his later doctrine of “radical empiricism.” We may still wonder whether the trichotomy of act, object and content stands up in psychology or regarding mental processes generally, but to this point at least it appears to be needed to articulate the distinction between contents and objects of awareness; and given needed emphasis on this distinction, it is much easier to understand and appreciate the general phenomenon of specific conceptual (and perceptual) differences and contrasts. Regarding “radical empiricism,” the lack of contrast between content and object is the heart of its problematic status; and the problem is rooted in James’s psychological works and his pervasive nominalism in particular. Consider the following passage from the Briefer Course, chapter XXII, devoted to “Reasoning,” where James aligns himself with Locke on nominal and real essence. James says that “Locke undermined the fallacy”:
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 39
5/2/22 10:39 AM
H. G. Callaway
xl
But none of his successors, so far as I know, have radically escaped it, or seen that the only meaning of essence is teleological, and that classification and conception are purely teleological weapons of the mind. The essence of a thing is that one of its properties which is so important for my interests that in comparison with it I may neglect the rest.92
But there is no viable scientific sense in which giving a definition, or telling “what something is,” depends merely on someone’s personal interest or purpose. We are staring at a fundamental defect, not merely in radical empiricism, but in James’s philosophy of science. Whether to deploy the trichotomy of act, object and content to conscious experience or to mental phenomena generally is a question of the empirical-theoretical viability of psychological theory involving such distinctions.93 It is not at all like someone’s passing purpose and focus of the moment where overall comprehension, experiment and collection of evidence are not relevant. The Jamesian notion that items of “pure experience” may be “classified” as constituting either conscious phenomena or external objects looks all the more doubtful in light of James’s decided nominalism regarding conceptual classification in science. The evaluation of classifications depends, in the end, on the empirical viability of developed theory which deploys them. 10. FUNCTIONAL PSYCHOLOGY AND CONTEMPORARY FUNCTIONALISM The scientific naturalism prominent in James’s Principles of Psychology is much closer to the varieties of functional psychology (following Angell for instance) in contrast to James’s later epistemology and philosophy of mind in the Essays in Radical Empiricism. In the Principles, James emphasizes the biological organism, in Darwinian terms of perceptual inputs and mental states or conditions, modifying action or behavior in order to adapt to general or specific environmental conditions. A more or less common-sense view of the world is part of the general approach of functional psychology. In spite of sharing something of a general Darwinian-functionalist scheme, contemporary computational psychology, artificial intelligence and “the computer model of mind” have developed at a considerable distance from functional psychology and have frequently been motivated by problems in computer science. The contrasting assumptions of functional psychology and contemporary functionalism may invite attention to prevalent criticism of behaviorist approaches to language and linguistic meaning. Though we regard semantic characterizations as matters of functional description, the equivalence of sensory input-behavioral output relations,
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 40
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Introduction xli
viewed as flows of information, do not suffice to capture conceptual meaning. One might say there is “something it is like” to understand “The morning star is the brightest star in the sky” in contrast to understanding “The evening star is the brightest star in the sky.” Though the difference is chiefly captured in patterns of inference, one understands in terms of distinctive vocabulary, which patterns to follow. Criticisms of familiar and prevalent, contemporary formulations of functionalism in the philosophy of mind, including criticisms centered on functionalist approaches to consciousness and the “hard problem” of consciousness have less of a bite if aimed at James’s Principles and later biological-functional psychology. In particular for James, introspective consciousness is not in doubt, and the (psychological) contents available to introspection must have their functions. The thesis that “what makes something a mental state . . . does not depend on its internal constitution,” is distinctly alien to James. The point may perhaps best be put as the claim that the language of psychological descriptions, including descriptions of experience or phenomenal consciousness, is functional in character. In consequence, one better appreciates the resistance to reductive physicalism. Gordon Allport, in the Introduction to his edition of James’s Briefer Course, argued against the computer model of mind on the basis of James’s psychology. Directing the reader to James’s chapter on “Reasoning,” Allport objects that in accordance with the computer model, “Men no longer ‘reason,’ they behave like giant computers: they receive inputs and produce outputs, and in spite of noise and redundancy, they somehow manage to code—and so it goes”: James on the other hand tells us that reasoning is “the ability to deal with novel data,”. . . He shows us how we select and recombine attributes of experience, always following a course “important for our interests.” Since machines lack interests it seems that James’s simple scaffolding may outlast the currently fashionable computer model. James draws his design from fresh daily experience, whereas today the tendency is to tailor human capacities to fit the alleged properties of the machine. Contemporary model builders will do well to return to James to see whether in fact their mechanical formulations do justice to the subtleties of process he depicts.94
Do computers and computerized systems lack interests in contrast to their functional purposes as artifacts? The formulation is suggestive. To consider it in needed detail, we would surely first have to understand more precisely what is meant by human interests. That is an important kind of question. Prima facie, an interest is a special kind of purpose and function and a widegoverning purpose. This is not a topic which easily fits within the limited
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 41
5/2/22 10:39 AM
xlii
H. G. Callaway
scope of the present introduction, but what seems important are the ways in which human beings develop interests out of preexisting purposes and biological needs and give themselves their varied and distinctive interests and purposes. It is not clear at all that computer systems have interests or that we will want them to have or develop autonomous interests. Still, the image is familiar in the form of the android, humanoid robots of science fiction. By way of a conclusion, it is more to the point of better appreciating James’s functional psychology, to consider, briefly, how computer models and computer science might benefit from functional, neurobiological approaches to human psychology—and related criticism of the computer model of mind arising from psychological studies and experiment. In fact, the idea of re-configuring special-purpose computers and programming on models of psychological processes and neurophysiological structures is already underway.95 On the other hand, there is little reason to think that projects in artificial intelligence will be much tempted to take radical empiricism to heart.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 42
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Chapter One
Does ‘Consciousness’ Exist?
‘Thoughts’ and ‘things’ are names for two sorts of object, which common sense will always find contrasted and will always practically oppose to each other.1 Philosophy, reflecting on the contrast, has varied in the past in her explanations of it, and may be expected to vary in the future. At first, ‘spirit and matter,’ ‘soul and body,’ stood for a pair of equipollent substances quite on a par in weight and interest. But one day Kant2 undermined the soul and brought in the transcendental ego, and ever since then the bipolar relation has been very much off its balance. The transcendental ego seems nowadays in rationalist quarters to stand for everything, in empiricist quarters for almost nothing. In the hands of such writers as Schuppe, Rehmke, Natorp, Münsterberg— at any rate in his earlier writings, Schubert-Soldern3 and others, the spiritual principle attenuates itself to a thoroughly ghostly condition, being only a name for the fact that the ‘content’ of experience is known. It loses personal form and activity—these passing over to the content—and becomes a bare Bewusstheit or Bewusstsein überhaupt,4 of which in its own right absolutely nothing can be said. I believe that ‘consciousness,’ when once it has evaporated to this estate of pure diaphaneity, is on the point of disappearing altogether. It is the name of a nonentity, and has no right to a place among first principles. Those who still cling to it are clinging to a mere echo, the faint rumor left behind by the disappearing ‘soul’ upon the air of philosophy. During the past year, I have read a number of articles whose authors seemed just on the point of abandoning the notion of consciousness,5 and substituting for it that of an absolute experience not due to two factors. But they were not quite radical enough, not quite daring enough in their negations. For twenty years past I have mistrusted ‘consciousness’ as an entity; for seven or eight years past I have suggested its non-existence to my students and tried to give them its pragmatic 1
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 1
5/2/22 10:39 AM
2
Essays in Radical Empiricism
equivalent in realities of experience.6 It seems to me that the hour is ripe for it to be openly and universally discarded. To deny plumply that ‘consciousness’ exists seems so absurd on the face of it—for undeniably ‘thoughts’ do exist—that I fear some readers will follow me no farther. Let me then immediately explain that I mean only to deny that the word stands for an entity, but to insist most emphatically that it does stand for a function. There is, I mean, no aboriginal stuff or quality of being,7 contrasted with that of which material objects are made, out of which our thoughts of them are made; but there is a function in experience which thoughts perform, and for the performance of which this quality of being is invoked. That function is knowing. ‘Consciousness’ is supposed necessary to explain the fact that things not only are, but get reported, are known. Whoever blots out the notion of consciousness from his list of first principles must still provide in some way for that function’s being carried on.8 1 My thesis is that if we start with the supposition that there is only one primal stuff or material in the world, a stuff of which everything is composed, and if we call that stuff ‘pure experience,’ then knowing can easily be explained as a particular sort of relation towards one another into which portions of pure experience may enter. The relation itself is a part of pure experience; one of its ‘terms’ becomes the subject or bearer of the knowledge, the knower,9 the other becomes the object known. This will need much explanation before it can be understood. The best way to get it understood is to contrast it with the alternative view; and for that we may take the recentest alternative, that in which the evaporation of the definite soul-substance has proceeded as far as it can go without being yet complete. If neo-Kantism has expelled earlier forms of dualism, we shall have expelled all forms if we are able to expel neo-Kantism in its turn. For the thinkers I call neo-Kantian, the word consciousness today does no more than signalize the fact that experience is indefeasibly dualistic in structure. It means that not subject, not object, but object-plus-subject is the minimum that can actually be. The subject-object distinction meanwhile is entirely different from that between mind and matter, from that between body and soul. Souls were detachable, had separate destinies; things could happen to them. To consciousness as such nothing can happen, for, timeless itself, it is only a witness of happenings in time, in which it plays no part. It is, in a word, but the logical correlative of ‘content’ in an Experience of which the peculiarity is that fact comes to light in it, that awareness of content takes
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 2
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Does ‘Consciousness’ Exist? 3
place. Consciousness as such is entirely impersonal—‘self’ and its activities belong to the content. To say that I am self-conscious, or conscious of putting forth volition, means only that certain contents, for which ‘self’ and ‘effort of will’ are the names, are not without witness as they occur. Thus, for these belated drinkers at the Kantian spring, we should have to admit consciousness as an ‘epistemological’ necessity, even if we had no direct evidence of its being there. But in addition to this, we are supposed by almost everyone to have an immediate consciousness of consciousness itself. When the world of outer fact ceases to be materially present, and we merely recall it in memory, or fancy it, the consciousness is believed to stand out and to be felt as a kind of impalpable inner flowing, which, once known in this sort of experience, may equally be detected in presentations of the outer world. “The moment we try to fix our attention upon consciousness and to see what, distinctly, it is,” says a recent writer, it seems to vanish. It seems as if we had before us a mere emptiness. When we try to introspect the sensation of blue, all we can see is the blue; the other element is as if it were diaphanous. Yet it can be distinguished, if we look attentively enough, and know that there is something to look for.10
“Consciousness” (Bewusstheit), says another philosopher, is inexplicable and hardly describable, yet all conscious experiences have this in common that what we call their content has this peculiar reference to a center for which ‘self’ is the name, in virtue of which reference alone the content is subjectively given, or appears. . . . While in this way consciousness, or reference to a self, is the only thing which distinguishes a conscious content from any sort of being that might be there with no one conscious of it, yet this only ground of the distinction defies all closer explanations. The existence of consciousness, although it is the fundamental fact of psychology, can indeed be laid down as certain, can be brought out by analysis, but can neither be defined nor deduced from anything but itself.11
“Can be brought out by analysis,” this author says. This supposes that the consciousness is one element, moment, factor—call it what you like—of an experience of essentially dualistic inner constitution, from which, if you abstract the content, the consciousness will remain revealed to its own eye. Experience, at this rate, would be much like a paint of which the world pictures were made. Paint has a dual constitution, involving, as it does, a menstruum12 (oil, size or what not) and a mass of content in the form of pigment suspended therein. We can get the pure menstruum by letting the pigment settle, and the pure pigment by pouring off the size or oil. We operate here by physical
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 3
5/2/22 10:39 AM
4
Essays in Radical Empiricism
subtraction; and the usual view is, that by mental subtraction we can separate the two factors of experience in an analogous way—not isolating them entirely, but distinguishing them enough to know that they are two. 2 Now my contention is exactly the reverse of this. Experience, I believe, has no such inner duplicity; and the separation of it into consciousness and content comes, not by way of subtraction, but by way of addition—the addition, to a given concrete piece of it, of other sets of experiences, in connection with which severally its use or function may be of two different kinds. The paint will also serve here as an illustration. In a pot in a paint shop, along with other paints, it serves in its entirety as so much saleable matter. Spread on a canvas, with other paints around it, it represents, on the contrary, a feature in a picture and performs a spiritual function. Just so, I maintain, does a given undivided portion of experience, taken in one context of associates, play the part of a knower, of a state of mind, of ‘consciousness;’ while in a different context the same undivided bit of experience plays the part of a thing known, of an objective ‘content.’ In a word, in one group it figures as a thought, in another group as a thing. And, since it can figure in both groups simultaneously we have every right to speak of it as subjective and objective both at once. The dualism connoted by such double-barreled terms as ‘experience,’ ‘phenomenon,’ ‘datum,’ ‘Vorfindung’13—terms which, in philosophy at any rate, tend more and more to replace the single-barreled terms of ‘thought’ and ‘thing’—that dualism, I say, is still preserved in this account, but reinterpreted, so that, instead of being mysterious and elusive, it becomes verifiable and concrete. It is an affair of relations, it falls outside, not inside, the single experience considered, and can always be particularized and defined. The entering wedge for this more concrete way of understanding the dualism was fashioned by Locke when he made the word ‘idea’ stand indifferently for thing and thought, and by Berkeley when he said that what common sense means by realities is exactly what the philosopher means by ideas. Neither Locke nor Berkeley thought his truth out into perfect clearness, but it seems to me that the conception I am defending does little more than consistently carry out the ‘pragmatic’ method which they were the first to use. If the reader will take his own experiences, he will see what I mean. Let him begin with a perceptual experience, the ‘presentation,’ so called, of a physical object, his actual field of vision, the room he sits in, with the book he is reading as its center; and let him for the present treat this complex object in the common-sense way as being ‘really’ what it seems to be, namely, a
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 4
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Does ‘Consciousness’ Exist? 5
collection of physical things cut out from an environing world of other physical things with which these physical things have actual or potential relations. Now at the same time it is just those self-same things which his mind, as we say, perceives; and the whole philosophy of perception from Democritus’ time downwards has been just one long wrangle over the paradox that what is evidently one reality should be in two places at once, both in outer space and in a person’s mind. ‘Representative’ theories of perception avoid the logical paradox, but on the other hand they violate the reader’s sense of life, which knows no intervening mental image but seems to see the room and the book immediately just as they physically exist. The puzzle of how the one identical room can be in two places is at bottom just the puzzle of how one identical point can be on two lines. It can, if it be situated at their intersection; and similarly, if the ‘pure experience’ of the room were a place of intersection of two processes, which connected it with different groups of associates respectively, it could be counted twice over, as belonging to either group, and spoken of loosely as existing in two places, although it would remain all the time a numerically single thing. Well, the experience is a member of diverse processes that can be followed away from it along entirely different lines. The one self-identical thing has so many relations to the rest of experience that you can take it in disparate systems of association, and treat it as belonging with opposite contexts.14 In one of these contexts it is your ‘field of consciousness;’ in another it is ‘the room in which you sit,’ and it enters both contexts in its wholeness, giving no pretext for being said to attach itself to consciousness by one of its parts or aspects, and to outer reality by another. What are the two processes, now, into which the room-experience simultaneously enters in this way? One of them is the reader’s personal biography, the other is the history of the house of which the room is part. The presentation, the experience, the that in short (for until we have decided what it is it must be a mere that) is the last term of a train of sensations, emotions, decisions, movements, classifications, expectations, etc., ending in the present, and the first term of a series of similar ‘inner’ operations extending into the future, on the reader’s part. On the other hand, the very same that is the terminus ad quem15 of a lot of previous physical operations, carpentering, papering, furnishing, warming, etc., and the terminus a quo16 of a lot of future ones, in which it will be concerned when undergoing the destiny of a physical room. The physical and the mental operations form curiously incompatible groups. As a room, the experience has occupied that spot and had that environment for thirty years. As your field of consciousness it may never have existed until now. As a room, attention will go on to discover endless new details in it. As your mental state merely, few new ones will emerge under attention’s eye. As a room, it will take an
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 5
5/2/22 10:39 AM
6
Essays in Radical Empiricism
earthquake, or a gang of men, and in any case a certain amount of time, to destroy it. As your subjective state, the closing of your eyes, or any instantaneous play of your fancy will suffice. In the real world, fire will consume it. In your mind, you can let fire play over it without effect. As an outer object, you must pay so much a month to inhabit it. As an inner content, you may occupy it for any length of time rent-free. If, in short, you follow it in the mental direction, taking it along with events of personal biography solely, all sorts of things are true of it which are false, and false of it which are true if you treat it as a real thing experienced, follow it in the physical direction, and relate it to associates in the outer world. 3 So far, all seems plain sailing, but my thesis will probably grow less plausible to the reader when I pass from percepts to concepts, or from the case of things presented to that of things remote. I believe, nevertheless, that here also the same law holds good. If we take conceptual manifolds, or memories, or fancies, they also are in their first intention mere bits of pure experience, and, as such, are single thats which act in one context as objects, and in another context figure as mental states. By taking them in their first intention, I mean ignoring their relation to possible perceptual experiences with which they may be connected, which they may lead to and terminate in, and which then they may be supposed to ‘represent.’ Taking them in this way first, we confine the problem to a world merely ‘thought-of’ and not directly felt or seen.17 This world, just like the world of percepts, comes to us at first as a chaos of experiences, but lines of order soon get traced. We find that any bit of it which we may cut out as an example is connected with distinct groups of associates, just as our perceptual experiences are, that these associates link themselves with it by different relations,18 and that one forms the inner history of a person, while the other acts as an impersonal ‘objective’ world, either spatial and temporal, or else merely logical or mathematical, or otherwise ‘ideal.’ The first obstacle on the part of the reader to seeing that these non-perceptual experiences have objectivity as well as subjectivity will probably be due to the intrusion into his mind of percepts, that third group of associates with which the non-perceptual experiences have relations, and which, as a whole, they ‘represent,’ standing to them as thoughts to things. This important function of the non-perceptual experiences complicates the question and confuses it; for, so used are we to treat percepts as the sole genuine realities that, unless we keep them out of the discussion, we tend altogether to overlook the objectivity that lies in non-perceptual experiences by themselves. We treat them,
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 6
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Does ‘Consciousness’ Exist? 7
‘knowing’ percepts as they do, as through and through subjective, and say that they are wholly constituted of the stuff called consciousness, using this term now for a kind of entity, after the fashion which I am seeking to refute.19 Abstracting, then, from percepts altogether, what I maintain is, that any single non-perceptual experience tends to get counted twice over, just as a perceptual experience does, figuring in one context as an object or field of objects, in another as a state of mind: and all this without the least internal self-diremption20 on its own part into consciousness and content. It is all consciousness in one taking; and, in the other, all content. I find this objectivity of non-perceptual experiences, this complete parallelism in point of reality between the presently felt and the remotely thought, so well set forth in a page of Münsterberg’s Grundzüge, that I will quote it as it stands. “I may only think of my objects,” says Professor Münsterberg; yet, in my living thought they stand before me exactly as perceived objects would do, no matter how different the two ways of apprehending them may be in their genesis. The book here lying on the table before me, and the book in the next room of which I think and which I mean to get, are both in the same sense given realities for me, realities which I acknowledge and of which I take account. If you agree that the perceptual object is not an idea within me, but that percept and thing, as indistinguishably one, are really experienced there, outside, you ought not to believe that the merely thought-of object is hid away inside of the thinking subject. The object of which I think, and of whose existence I take cognizance without letting it now work upon my senses, occupies its definite place in the outer world as much as does the object which I directly see. What is true of the here and the there, is also true of the now and the then. I know of the thing which is present and perceived, but I know also of the thing which yesterday was but is no more, and which I only remember. Both can determine my present conduct, both are parts of the reality of which I keep account. It is true that of much of the past I am uncertain, just as I am uncertain of much of what is present if it be but dimly perceived. But the interval of time does not in principle alter my relation to the object, does not transform it from an object known into a mental state. . . . The things in the room here which I survey, and those in my distant home of which I think, the things of this minute and those of my long-vanished boyhood, influence and decide me alike, with a reality which my experience of them directly feels. They both make up my real world, they make it directly, they do not have first to be introduced to me and mediated by ideas which now and here arise within me. . . . This not-me character of my recollections and expectations does not imply that the external objects of which I am aware in those experiences should necessarily be there also for others. The objects of dreamers and hallucinated persons are wholly without general validity. But even were they centaurs and golden mountains, they still would be ‘off there,’ in fairy land, and not ‘inside’ of ourselves.”21
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 7
5/2/22 10:39 AM
8
Essays in Radical Empiricism
This certainly is the immediate, primary, naïf, or practical way of taking our thought-of world. Were there no perceptual world to serve as its ‘reductive,’ in Taine’s22 sense, by being ‘stronger’ and more genuinely outer’ (so that the whole merely thought-of world seems weak and inner in comparison), our world of thought would be the only world, and would enjoy complete reality in our belief. This actually happens in our dreams, and in our daydreams so long as percepts do not interrupt them. And yet, just as the seen room (to go back to our late example) is also a field of consciousness, so the conceived or recollected room is also a state of mind; and the doubling-up of the experience has in both cases similar grounds. The room thought-of, namely, has many thought-of couplings with many thought-of things. Some of these couplings are inconstant, others are stable. In the reader’s personal history, the room occupies a single date—he saw it only once perhaps, a year ago. Of the house’s history, on the other hand, it forms a permanent ingredient. Some couplings have the curious stubbornness, to borrow Royce’s23 term, of fact; others show the fluidity of fancy—we let them come and go as we please. Grouped with the rest of its house, with the name of its town, of its owner, builder, value, decorative plan, the room maintains a definite foothold, to which, if we try to loosen it, it tends to return, and to reassert itself with force.24 With these associates, in a word, it coheres, while to other houses, other towns, other owners, etc., it shows no tendency to cohere at all. The two collections, first of its cohesive, and, second, of its loose associates, inevitably come to be contrasted. We call the first collection the system of external realities, in the midst of which the room, as ‘real,’ exists; the other we call the stream of our internal thinking, in which, as a ‘mental image,’ it for a moment floats.25 The room thus again gets counted twice over. It plays two different roles, being Gedanke and Gedachtes,26 the thought-of-an-object, and the object-thought-of, both in one; and all this without paradox or mystery, just as the same material thing may be both low and high, or small and great, or bad and good, because of its relations to opposite parts of an environing world. As ‘subjective’ we say that the experience represents; as ‘objective’ it is represented. What represents and what is represented is here numerically the same; but we must remember that no dualism of being represented and representing resides in the experience per se. In its pure state, or when isolated, there is no self-splitting of it into consciousness and what the consciousness is ‘of.’ Its subjectivity and objectivity are functional attributes solely, realized only when the experience is ‘taken,’ i.e., talked-of, twice, considered along with its two differing contexts respectively, by a new retrospective experience, of which that whole past complication now forms the fresh content.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 8
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Does ‘Consciousness’ Exist? 9
The instant field of the present is at all times what I call the ‘pure’ experience. It is only virtually or potentially either object or subject as yet. For the time being, it is plain, unqualified actuality, or existence, a simple that. In this naïf immediacy it is of course valid;27 it is there, we act upon it; and the doubling of it in retrospection into a state of mind and a reality intended thereby, is just one of the acts. The ‘state of mind,’ first treated explicitly as such in retrospection, will stand corrected or confirmed, and the retrospective experience in its turn will get a similar treatment; but the immediate experience in its passing is always ‘truth,’28 practical truth, something to act on, at its own movement. If the world were then and there to go out like a candle, it would remain truth absolute and objective, for it would be ‘the last word,’ would have no critic, and no one would ever oppose the thought in it to the reality intended.29 I think I may now claim to have made my thesis clear. Consciousness connotes a kind of external relation and does not denote a special stuff or way of being. The peculiarity of our experiences, that they not only are, but are known, which their ‘conscious’ quality is invoked to explain, is better explained by their relations—these relations themselves being experiences—to one another. 4 Were I now to go on to treat of the knowing of perceptual by conceptual experiences, it would again prove to be an affair of external relations. One experience would be the knower, the other the reality known; and I could perfectly well define, without the notion of ‘consciousness,’ what the knowing actually and practically amounts to—leading-towards, namely, and terminating-in percepts, through a series of transitional experiences which the world supplies. But I will not treat of this, space being insufficient.30 I will rather consider a few objections that are sure to be urged against the entire theory as it stands. 5 First of all, this will be asked: “If experience has not ‘conscious’ existence, if it be not partly made of ‘consciousness,’ of what then is it made? Matter we know, and thought we know, and conscious content we know, but neutral and simple ‘pure experience’ is something we know not at all. Say what it consists of—for it must consist of something—or be willing to give it up!”
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 9
5/2/22 10:39 AM
10
Essays in Radical Empiricism
To this challenge the reply is easy. Although for fluency’s sake I myself spoke early in this article of a stuff of pure experience, I have now to say that there is no general stuff of which experience at large is made. There are as many stuffs as there are ‘natures’ in the things experienced. If you ask what any one bit of pure experience is made of, the answer is always the same: “It is made of that, of just what appears, of space, of intensity, of flatness, brownness, heaviness, or what not.” Shadworth Hodgson’s analysis here leaves nothing to be desired.31 Experience is only a collective name for all these sensible natures, and save for time and space (and, if you like, for ‘being’) there appears no universal element of which all things are made. 6 The next objection is more formidable, in fact it sounds quite crushing when one hears it first. “If it be the self-same piece of pure experience, taken twice over, that serves now as thought and now as thing”—so the objection runs—“how comes it that its attributes should differ so fundamentally in the two takings. As thing, the experience is extended; as thought, it occupies no space or place. As thing, it is red, hard, heavy; but who ever heard of a red, hard or heavy thought? Yet even now you said that an experience is made of just what appears, and what appears is just such adjectives. How can the one experience in its thing-function be made of them, consist of them, carry them as its own attributes, while in its thought-function it disowns them and attributes them elsewhere. There is a self-contradiction here from which the radical dualism of thought and thing is the only truth that can save us. Only if the thought is one kind of being can the adjectives exist in it ‘intentionally’ (to use the scholastic term);32 only if the thing is another kind, can they exist in it constitutively and energetically. No simple subject can take the same adjectives and at one time be qualified by it, and at another time be merely ‘of’ it, as of something only meant or known.” The solution insisted on by this objector, like many other common-sense solutions, grows the less satisfactory the more one turns it in one’s mind. To begin with, are thought and thing as heterogeneous as is commonly said? No one denies that they have some categories in common. Their relations to time are identical. Both, moreover, may have parts (for psychologists in general treat thoughts as having them); and both may be complex or simple. Both are of kinds, can be compared, added and subtracted and arranged in serial orders. All sorts of adjectives qualify our thoughts which appear incompatible with consciousness, being as such a bare diaphaneity. For instance,
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 10
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Does ‘Consciousness’ Exist? 11
they are natural and easy, or laborious. They are beautiful, happy, intense, interesting, wise, idiotic, focal, marginal, insipid, confused, vague, precise, rational, casual, general, particular, and many things besides. Moreover, the chapters on ‘Perception’ in the psychology books are full of facts that make for the essential homogeneity of thought with thing. How, if ‘subject’ and ‘object’ were separated ‘by the whole diameter of being,’ and had no attributes in common, could it be so hard to tell, in a presented and recognized material object, what part comes in through the sense organs and what part comes ‘out of one’s own head’? Sensations and apperceptive ideas fuse here so intimately that you can no more tell where one begins and the other ends, than you can tell, in those cunning circular panoramas that have lately been exhibited, where the real foreground and the painted canvas join together.33 Descartes for the first time defined thought as the absolutely unextended, and later philosophers have accepted the description as correct. But what possible meaning has it to say that, when we think of a foot-rule or a square yard, extension is not attributable to our thought? Of every extended object the adequate mental picture must have all the extension of the object itself. The difference between objective and subjective extension is one of relation to a context solely. In the mind the various extents maintain no necessarily stubborn order relatively to each other, while in the physical world they bound each other stably, and, added together, make the great enveloping Unit which we believe in and call real Space. As ‘outer,’ they carry themselves adversely, so to speak, to one another, exclude one another and maintain their distances; while, as ‘inner,’ their order is loose, and they form a durcheinander34 in which unity is lost.35 But to argue from this that inner experience is absolutely inextensive seems to me little short of absurd. The two worlds differ, not by the presence or absence of extension, but by the relations of the extensions which in both worlds exist.36 Does not this case of extension now put us on the track of truth in the case of other qualities? It does; and I am surprised that the facts should not have been noticed long ago. Why, for example, do we call a fire hot, and water wet, and yet refuse to say that our mental state, when it is ‘of’ these objects, is either wet or hot? ‘Intentionally,’ at any rate, and when the mental state is a vivid image, hotness and wetness are in it just as much as they are in the physical experience. The reason is this, that, as the general chaos of all our experiences gets sifted, we find that there are some fires that will always burn sticks and always warm our bodies, and that there are some waters that will always put out fires; while there are other fires and waters that will not act at all.37 The general group of experiences that act, that do not only possess their natures intrinsically, but wear them adjectively and energetically, turning them against one another, comes inevitably to be contrasted with the group whose
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 11
5/2/22 10:39 AM
12
Essays in Radical Empiricism
members, having identically the same natures, fail to manifest them in the ‘energetic’ way.38 I make for myself now an experience of blazing fire; I place it near my body; but it does not warm me in the least. I lay a stick upon it, and the stick either burns or remains green, as I please. I call up water, and pour it on the fire, and absolutely no difference ensues. I account for all such facts by calling this whole train of experiences unreal, a mental train. Mental fire is what won’t burn real sticks; mental water is what won’t necessarily (though of course it may) put out even a mental fire. Mental knives may be sharp, but they won’t cut real wood. Mental triangles are pointed, but their points won’t wound. With ‘real’ objects, on the contrary, consequences always accrue; and thus, the real experiences get sifted from the mental ones, the things from our thoughts of them, fanciful or true, and precipitated together as the stable part of the whole experience-chaos, under the name of the physical world. Of this our perceptual experiences are the nucleus, they being the originally strong experiences. We add a lot of conceptual experiences to them, making these strong also in imagination, and building out the remoter parts of the physical world by their means; and around this core of reality the world of laxly connected fancies and mere rhapsodical objects floats like a bank of clouds. In the clouds, all sorts of rules are violated which in the core are kept. Extensions there can be indefinitely located; motion there obeys no Newton’s laws.39 7 There is a peculiar class of experiences to which, whether we take them as subjective or as objective, we assign their several natures as attributes, because in both contexts they affect their associates actively, though in neither quite as ‘strongly’ or as sharply as things affect one another by their physical energies. I refer here to appreciations, which form an ambiguous sphere of being, belonging with emotion on the one hand, and having objective ‘value’ on the other, yet seeming not quite inner nor quite outer, as if a diremption had begun but had not made itself complete.40 Experiences of painful objects, for example, are usually also painful experiences; perceptions of loveliness, of ugliness, tend to pass muster as lovely or as ugly perceptions; intuitions of the morally lofty are lofty intuitions. Sometimes the adjective wanders as if uncertain where to fix itself. Shall we speak of seductive visions or of visions of seductive things? Of wicked desires or of desires for wickedness? Of healthy thoughts or of thoughts of healthy objects? Of good impulses, or of impulses towards the good? Of feelings of anger, or of angry feelings? Both in the mind and in the thing, these natures modify their context, exclude certain associates and determine others, have
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 12
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Does ‘Consciousness’ Exist? 13
their mates and incompatibles. Yet not as stubbornly as in the case of physical qualities, for beauty and ugliness, love and hatred, pleasant and painful can, in certain complex experiences, coexist. If one were to make an evolutionary construction of how a lot of originally chaotic pure experiences became gradually differentiated into an orderly inner and outer world, the whole theory would turn upon one’s success in explaining how or why the quality of an experience, once active, could become less so, and, from being an energetic attribute in some cases, elsewhere lapse into the status of an inert or merely internal ‘nature.’ This would be the ‘evolution’ of the psychical from the bosom of the physical, in which the esthetic, moral and otherwise emotional experiences would represent a halfway stage. 8 But a last cry of non possumus41 will probably go up from many readers. “All very pretty as a piece of ingenuity,” they will say, “but our consciousness itself intuitively contradicts you. We, for our part, know that we are conscious. We feel our thought, flowing as a life within us, in absolute contrast with the objects which it so unremittingly escorts. We can not be faithless to this immediate intuition. The dualism is a fundamental datum: Let no man join what God has put asunder.” My reply to this is my last word, and I greatly grieve that to many it will sound materialistic. I can not help that, however, for I, too, have my intuitions and I must obey them. Let the case be what it may in others, I am as confident as I am of anything that, in myself, the stream of thinking (which I recognize emphatically as a phenomenon) is only a careless name for what, when scrutinized, reveals itself to consist chiefly of the stream of my breathing. The ‘I think’ which Kant said must be able to accompany all my objects, is the ‘I breathe’ which actually does accompany them. There are other internal facts besides breathing (intracephalic42 muscular adjustments, etc., of which I have said a word in my larger Psychology), and these increase the assets of ‘consciousness,’ so far as the latter is subject to immediate perception;43 but breath, which was ever the original of ‘spirit,’ breath moving outwards, between the glottis and the nostrils, is, I am persuaded, the essence out of which philosophers have constructed the entity known to them as consciousness. That entity is fictitious, while thoughts in the concrete are fully real. But thoughts in the concrete are made of the same stuff as things are. I wish I might believe myself to have made that plausible in this article. In another article I shall try to make the general notion of a world composed of pure experiences still more clear.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 13
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 14
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Chapter Two
A World of Pure Experience
It is difficult not to notice a curious unrest in the philosophic atmosphere of the time, a loosening of old landmarks, a softening of oppositions, a mutual borrowing from one another on the part of systems anciently closed, and an interest in new suggestions, however vague, as if the one thing sure were the inadequacy of the extant school-solutions.1 The dissatisfaction with these seems due for the most part to a feeling that they are too abstract and academic. Life is confused and superabundant, and what the younger generation appears to crave is more of the temperament of life in its philosophy, even though it were at some cost of logical rigor and of formal purity. Transcendental idealism is inclining to let the world wag incomprehensibly, in spite of its Absolute Subject and his unity of purpose. Berkeleyan idealism is abandoning the principle of parsimony and dabbling in panpsychic speculations. Empiricism flirts with teleology; and, strangest of all, natural realism, so long decently buried, raises its head above the turf, and finds glad hands outstretched from the most unlikely quarters to help it to its feet again. We are all biased by our personal feelings, I know, and I am personally discontented with extant solutions; so I seem to read the signs of a great unsettlement, as if the upheaval of more real conceptions and more fruitful methods were imminent, as if a true landscape might result, less clipped, straight-edged and artificial. If philosophy be really on the eve of any considerable rearrangement, the time should be propitious for anyone who has suggestions of his own to bring forward. For many years past my mind has been growing into a certain type of Weltanschauung.2 Rightly or wrongly, I have got to the point where I can hardly see things in any other pattern. I propose, therefore, to describe the pattern as clearly as I can consistently with great brevity, and to throw my description into the bubbling vat of publicity where, jostled by rivals and torn by critics, it will eventually either disappear from notice, or else, if better luck 15
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 15
5/2/22 10:39 AM
16
Essays in Radical Empiricism
befall it, quietly subside to the profundities, and serve as a possible ferment of new growths or a nucleus of new crystallization. 1. RADICAL EMPIRICISM I give the name of ‘radical empiricism’ to my Weltanschauung. Empiricism is known as the opposite of rationalism. Rationalism tends to emphasize universals and to make wholes prior to parts in the order of logic as well as in that of being. Empiricism, on the contrary, lays the explanatory stress upon the part, the element, the individual, and treats the whole as a collection and the universal as an abstraction. My description of things, accordingly, starts with the parts and makes of the whole a being of the second order. It is essentially a mosaic philosophy, a philosophy of plural facts, like that of Hume and his descendants, who refer these facts neither to Substances in which they inhere nor to an Absolute Mind that creates them as its objects. But it differs from the Humean type of empiricism in one particular which makes me add the epithet radical. To be radical, an empiricism must neither admit into its constructions any element that is not directly experienced, nor exclude from them any element that is directly experienced. For such a philosophy, the relations that connect experiences must themselves be experienced relations, and any kind of relation experienced must be accounted as ‘real’ as anything else in the system. Elements may indeed be redistributed, the original placing of things getting corrected, but a real place must be found for every kind of thing experienced, whether term or relation, in the final philosophic arrangement.3 Now, ordinary empiricism, in spite of the fact that conjunctive and disjunctive relations present themselves as being fully co-ordinate parts of experience, has always shown a tendency to do away with the connections of things, and to insist most on the disjunctions. Berkeley’s nominalism, Hume’s statement that whatever things we distinguish are as ‘loose and separate’ as if they had ‘no manner of connection,’ James Mill’s denial that similars have anything ‘really’ in common, the resolution of the causal tie into habitual sequence, John Mill’s account of both physical things and selves as composed of discontinuous possibilities, and the general pulverization of all Experience by association and the mind-dust theory, are examples of what I mean.4 The natural result of such a world-picture has been the efforts of rationalism to correct its incoherencies by the addition of trans-experiential agents of unification, substances, intellectual categories and powers, or Selves; whereas, if empiricism had only been radical and taken everything that comes without disfavor, conjunction as well as separation, each at its face value, the
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 16
5/2/22 10:39 AM
A World of Pure Experience 17
results would have called for no such artificial correction. Radical empiricism, as I understand it, does full justice to conjunctive relations, without, however, treating them as rationalism always tends to treat them, as being true in some supernal5 way, as if the unity of things and their variety belonged to different orders of truth and vitality altogether. 2. CONJUNCTIVE RELATIONS Relations are of different degrees of intimacy. Merely to be ‘with’ one another in a universe of discourse is the most external relation that terms can have, and seems to involve nothing whatever as to further consequences. Simultaneity and time-interval come next, and then space-adjacency and distance. After them, similarity and difference, carrying the possibility of many inferences. Then relations of activity, tying terms into series involving change, tendency, resistance, and the causal order generally. Finally, the relation experienced between terms that form states of mind, and are immediately conscious of continuing each other. The organization of the Self as a system of memories, purposes, strivings, fulfillments or disappointments, is incidental to this most intimate of all relations, the terms of which seem in many cases actually to compenetrate and suffuse each other’s being.6 Philosophy has always turned on grammatical particles. With, near, next, like, from, towards, against, because, for, through, my—these words designate types of conjunctive relation arranged in a roughly ascending order of intimacy and inclusiveness. A priori, we can imagine a universe of withness but no nextness; or one of nextness but no likeness, or of likeness with no activity, or of activity with no purpose, or of purpose with no ego. These would be universes, each with its own grade of unity. The universe of human experience is, by one or another of its parts, of each and all these grades. Whether or not it possibly enjoys some still more absolute grade of union does not appear upon the surface. Taken as it does appear, our universe is to a large extent chaotic. No one single type of connection runs through all the experiences that compose it. If we take space-relations, they fail to connect minds into any regular system. Causes and purposes obtain only among special series of facts. The self-relation seems extremely limited and does not link two different selves together. Prima facie, if you should liken the universe of absolute idealism to an aquarium, a crystal globe in which goldfish are swimming, you would have to compare the empiricist universe to something more like one of those dried human heads with which the Dyaks of Borneo deck their lodges. The skull forms a solid nucleus; but innumerable feathers, leaves, strings, beads,
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 17
5/2/22 10:39 AM
18
Essays in Radical Empiricism
and loose appendices of every description float and dangle from it, and, save that they terminate in it, seem to have nothing to do with one another. Even so my experiences and yours float and dangle, terminating, it is true, in a nucleus of common perception, but for the most part out of sight and irrelevant and unimaginable to one another. This imperfect intimacy, this bare relation of withness between some parts of the sum total of experience and other parts, is the fact that ordinary empiricism overemphasizes against rationalism, the latter always tending to ignore it unduly. Radical empiricism, on the contrary, is fair to both the unity and the disconnection. It finds no reason for treating either as illusory. It allots to each its definite sphere of description, and agrees that there appear to be actual forces at work which tend, as time goes on, to make the unity greater. The conjunctive relation that has given most trouble to philosophy is the co-conscious transition, so to call it, by which one experience passes into another when both belong to the same self. About the facts there is no question. My experiences and your experiences are ‘with’ each other in various external ways, but mine pass into mine, and yours pass into yours in a way in which yours and mine never pass into one another. Within each of our personal histories, subject, object, interest and purpose are continuous or may be continuous.7 Personal histories are processes of change in time, and the change itself is one of the things immediately experienced. ‘Change’ in this case means continuous as opposed to discontinuous transition. But continuous transition is one sort of a conjunctive relation; and to be a radical empiricist means to hold fast to this conjunctive relation of all others, for this is the strategic point, the position through which, if a hole be made, all the corruptions of dialectics and all the metaphysical fictions pour into our philosophy. The holding fast to this relation means taking it at its face value, neither less nor more; and to take it at its face value means first of all to take it just as we feel it, and not to confuse ourselves with abstract talk about it, involving words that drive us to invent secondary conceptions in order to neutralize their suggestions and to make our actual experience again seem rationally possible. What I do feel simply when a later moment of my experience succeeds an earlier one is that though they are two moments, the transition from the one to the other is continuous. Continuity here is a definite sort of experience; just as definite as is the discontinuity-experience which I find it impossible to avoid when I seek to make the transition from an experience of my own to one of yours. In this latter case I have to get on and off again, to pass from a thing lived to another thing only conceived, and the break is positively experienced and noted. Though the functions exerted by my experience and by yours may be the same (e.g., the same objects known and the same purposes followed), yet the sameness has in this case to be ascertained expressly (and
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 18
5/2/22 10:39 AM
A World of Pure Experience 19
often with difficulty and uncertainty) after the break has been felt; whereas in passing from one of my own moments to another the sameness of object and interest is unbroken, and both the earlier and the later experience are of things directly lived. There is no other nature, no other whatness than this absence of break and this sense of continuity in that most intimate of all conjunctive relations, the passing of one experience into another when they belong to the same self. And this whatness is real empirical ‘content,’ just as the whatness of separation and discontinuity is real content in the contrasted case. Practically to experience one’s personal continuum in this living way is to know the originals of the ideas of continuity and of sameness, to know what the words stand for concretely, to own all that they can ever mean. But all experiences have their conditions; and over-subtle intellects, thinking about the facts here, and asking how they are possible, have ended by substituting a lot of static objects of conception for the direct perceptual experiences. “Sameness,” they have said, “must be a stark numerical identity; it can’t run on from next to next. Continuity can’t mean mere absence of gap; for if you say two things are in immediate contact, at the contact how can they be two? If, on the other hand, you put a relation of transition between them, that itself is a third thing, and needs to be related or hitched to its terms. An infinite series is involved,” and so on. The result is that from difficulty to difficulty, the plain conjunctive experience has been discredited by both schools, the empiricists leaving things permanently disjoined, and the rationalist remedying the looseness by their Absolutes or Substances, or whatever other fictitious agencies of union they may have employed.8 From all which artificiality we can be saved by a couple of simple reflections: first, that conjunctions and separations are, at all events, coordinate phenomena which, if we take experiences at their face value, must be accounted equally real; and second, that if we insist on treating things as really separate when they are given as continuously joined, invoking, when union is required, transcendental principles to overcome the separateness we have assumed, then we ought to stand ready to perform the converse act. We ought to invoke higher principles of disunion, also, to make our merely experienced disjunctions more truly real. Failing thus, we ought to let the originally given continuities stand on their own bottom. We have no right to be lopsided or to blow capriciously hot and cold. 3. THE COGNITIVE RELATION The first great pitfall from which such a radical standing by experience will save us is an artificial conception of the relations between knower and known.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 19
5/2/22 10:39 AM
20
Essays in Radical Empiricism
Throughout the history of philosophy, the subject and its object have been treated as absolutely discontinuous entities; and thereupon the presence of the latter to the former, or the ‘apprehension’ by the former of the latter, has assumed a paradoxical character which all sorts of theories had to be invented to overcome. Representative theories put a mental ‘representation,’ ‘image,’ or ‘content’ into the gap, as a sort of intermediary. Common-sense theories left the gap untouched, declaring our mind able to clear it by a self-transcending leap. Transcendentalist theories left it impossible to traverse by finite knowers and brought an Absolute in to perform the saltatory9 act. All the while, in the very bosom of the finite experience, every conjunction required to make the relation intelligible is given in full. Either the knower and the known are: 1. the self-same piece of experience taken twice over in different contexts; or they are 2. two pieces of actual experience belonging to the same subject, with definite tracts of conjunctive transitional experience between them; or 3. the known is a possible experience either of that subject or another, to which the said conjunctive transitions would lead, if sufficiently prolonged. To discuss all the ways in which one experience may function as the knower of another, would be incompatible with the limits of this essay.10 I have just treated of type 1, the kind of knowledge called perception.11 This is the type of case in which the mind enjoys direct ‘acquaintance’ with a present object. In the other types, the mind has ‘knowledge-about’ an object not immediately there. Of type 2, the simplest sort of conceptual knowledge, I have given some account in two [earlier] articles.12 Type 3 can always formally and hypothetically be reduced to type 2, so that a brief description of that type will put the present reader sufficiently at my point of view and make him see what the actual meanings of the mysterious cognitive relation may be. Suppose me to be sitting here in my library at Cambridge, a ten minute walk from ‘Memorial Hall,’ and to be thinking truly of the latter object. My mind may have before it only the name, or it may have a clear image, or it may have a very dim image of the hall, but such intrinsic differences in the image make no difference in its cognitive function. Certain extrinsic phenomena, special experiences of conjunction, are what impart to the image, be it what it may, its knowing office. For instance, if you ask me what hall I mean by my image, and I can tell you nothing; or if I fail to point or lead you towards the Harvard Delta; or if, being led by you, I am uncertain whether the hall I see be what I had in mind or not; you would rightly deny that I had ‘meant’ that particular hall at all, even though my mental image might to some degree have resembled it. The
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 20
5/2/22 10:39 AM
A World of Pure Experience 21
resemblance would count in that case as coincidental merely, for all sorts of things of a kind resemble one another in this world without being held for that reason to take cognizance of one another. On the other hand, if I can lead you to the hall, and tell you of its history and present uses; if in its presence I feel my idea, however imperfect it may have been, to have led hither and to be now terminated; if the associates of the image and of the felt hall run parallel, so that each term of the one context corresponds serially, as I walk, with an answering term of the others; why then my soul was prophetic, and my idea must be, and by common consent would be, called cognizant of reality. That percept was what I meant, for into it my idea has passed by conjunctive experiences of sameness and fulfilled intention. Nowhere is there jar, but every later moment continues and corroborates an earlier one. In this continuing and corroborating, taken in no transcendental sense, but denoting definitely felt transitions, lies all that the knowing of a percept by an idea can possibly contain or signify. Wherever such transitions are felt, the first experience knows the last one. Where they do not, or where even as possibles they can not, intervene, there can be no pretence of knowing. In this latter case the extremes will be connected, if connected at all, by inferior relations—bare likeness or succession, or by ‘withness’ alone. Knowledge of sensible realities thus comes to life inside the tissue of experience. It is made; and made by relations that unroll themselves in time. Whenever certain intermediaries are given, such that, as they develop towards their terminus, there is experience from point to point of one direction followed, and finally of one process fulfilled, the result is that their starting-point thereby becomes a knower and their terminus an object meant or known. That is all that knowing (in the simple case considered) can be known-as, that is the whole of its nature, put into experiential terms. Whenever such is the sequence of our experiences, we may freely say that we had the terminal object ‘in mind’ from the outset, even although at the outset nothing was there in us but a flat piece of substantive experience like any other, with no self-transcendency about it, and no mystery save the mystery of coming into existence and of being gradually followed by other pieces of substantive experience, with conjunctively transitional experiences between. That is what we mean here by the object’s being ‘in mind.’ Of any deeper more real way of being in mind we have no positive conception, and we have no right to discredit our actual experience by talking of such a way at all. I know that many a reader will rebel at this. “Mere intermediaries,” he will say, “even though they be feelings of continuously growing fulfillment, only separate the knower from the known, whereas what we have in knowledge is a kind of immediate touch of the one by the other, an ‘apprehension’ in the
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 21
5/2/22 10:39 AM
22
Essays in Radical Empiricism
etymological sense of the word, a leaping of the chasm as by lightning, an act by which two terms are smitten into one, over the head of their distinctness. All these dead intermediaries of yours are out of each other, and outside of their termini still.” But do not such dialectic difficulties remind us of the dog dropping his bone and snapping at its image in the water? If we knew any more real kind of union aliunde,13 we might be entitled to brand all our empirical unions as a sham. But unions by continuous transition are the only ones we know of, whether in this matter of a knowledge-about that terminates in an acquaintance, whether in personal identity, in logical predication through the copula ‘is,’ or elsewhere. If anywhere there were more absolute unions realized, they could only reveal themselves to us by just such conjunctive results. These are what the unions are worth, these are all that we can ever practically mean by union, by continuity. Is it not time to repeat what Lotze14 said of substances, that to act like one is to be one?15 Should we not say here that to be experienced as continuous is to be really continuous, in a world where experience and reality come to the same thing? In a picture gallery a painted hook will serve to hang a painted chain by, a painted cable will hold a painted ship. In a world where both the terms and their distinctions are affairs of experience, conjunctions that are experienced must be at least as real as anything else. They will be ‘absolutely’ real conjunctions, if we have no trans-phenomenal Absolute ready, to de-realize the whole experienced world by, at a stroke. If, on the other hand, we had such an Absolute, not one of our opponents’ theories of knowledge could remain standing any better than ours could; for the distinctions as well as the conjunctions of experience would impartially fall its prey. The whole question of how ‘one’ thing can know ‘another’ would cease to be a real one at all in a world where otherness itself was an illusion.16 So much for the essentials of the cognitive relation, where the knowledge is conceptual in type, or forms knowledge ‘about’ an object. It consists in intermediary experiences (possible, if not actual) of continuously developing progress, and, finally, of fulfillment, when the sensible percept, which is the object, is reached. The percept here not only verifies the concept, proves its function of knowing that percept to be true, but the percept’s existence as the terminus of the chain of intermediaries creates the function. Whatever terminates that chain was, because it now proves itself to be, what the concept ‘had in mind.’ The towering importance for human life of this kind of knowing lies in the fact that an experience that knows another can figure as its representative, not in any quasi-miraculous ‘epistemological’ sense, but in the definite practical sense of being its substitute in various operations, sometimes physical and sometimes mental, which lead us to its associates and results. By experiment-
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 22
5/2/22 10:39 AM
A World of Pure Experience 23
ing on our ideas of reality, we may save ourselves the trouble of experimenting on the real experiences which they severally mean. The ideas form related systems, corresponding point for point to the systems which the realities form; and by letting an ideal term call up its associates systematically, we may be led to a terminus which the corresponding real term would have led to in case we had operated on the real world. And this brings us to the general question of substitution. 4. SUBSTITUTION In Taine’s brilliant book on ‘Intelligence,’17 substitution was for the first time named as a cardinal logical function, though of course the facts had always been familiar enough. What, exactly, in a system of experiences, does the ‘substitution’ of one of them for another mean? According to my view, experience as a whole is a process in time, whereby innumerable particular terms lapse and are superseded by others that follow upon them by transitions which, whether disjunctive or conjunctive in content, are themselves experiences, and must in general be accounted at least as real as the terms which they relate. What the nature of the event called ‘superseding’ signifies, depends altogether on the kind of transition that obtains. Some experiences simply abolish their predecessors without continuing them in any way. Others are felt to increase or to enlarge their meaning, to carry out their purpose, or to bring us nearer to their goal. They ‘represent’ them and may fulfill their function better than they fulfilled it themselves. But to ‘fulfill a function’ in a world of pure experience can be conceived and defined in only one possible way. In such a world transitions and arrivals (or terminations) are the only events that happen, though they happen by so many sorts of path. The only function that one experience can perform is to lead into another experience; and the only fulfillment we can speak of is the reaching of a certain experienced end. When one experience leads to (or can lead to) the same end as another, they agree in function. But the whole system of experiences as they are immediately given presents itself as a quasi-chaos through which one can pass out of an initial term in many directions and yet end in the same terminus, moving from next to next by a great many possible paths. Either one of these paths might be a functional substitute for another, and to follow one rather than another might on occasion be an advantageous thing to do. As a matter of fact, and in a general way, the paths that run through conceptual experiences, that is, through ‘thoughts’ or ‘ideas’ that ‘know’ the things in which they terminate, are highly advantageous paths to follow. Not only do they yield inconceivably rapid transitions; but, owing to the ‘universal’
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 23
5/2/22 10:39 AM
24
Essays in Radical Empiricism
character18 which they frequently possess, and to their capacity for association with one another in great systems, they outstrip the tardy consecutions of the things themselves, and sweep us on towards our ultimate termini in a far more labor-saving way than the following of trains of sensible perception ever could. Wonderful are the new cuts and the short-circuits which the thought-paths make. Most thought-paths, it is true, are substitutes for nothing actual; they end outside the real world altogether, in wayward fancies, utopias, fictions or mistakes. But where they do re-enter reality and terminate therein, we substitute them always; and with these substitutes we pass the greater number of our hours. This is why I called our experiences, taken all together, a quasi-chaos. There is vastly more discontinuity in the sum total of experiences than we commonly suppose. The objective nucleus of every man’s experience, his own body, is, it is true, a continuous percept; and equally continuous as a percept (though we may be inattentive to it) is the material environment of that body, changing by gradual transition when the body moves. But the distant parts of the physical world are at all times absent from us, and form conceptual objects merely, into the perceptual reality of which our life inserts itself at points discrete and relatively rare. Round their several objective nuclei, partly shared and common and partly discrete, of the real physical world, innumerable thinkers, pursuing their several lines of physically true cogitation, trace paths that intersect one another only at discontinuous perceptual points, and the rest of the time are quite incongruent; and around all the nuclei of shared ‘reality,’ as around the Dyak’s head of my late metaphor, floats the vast cloud of experiences that are wholly subjective, that are non-substitutional, that find not even an eventual ending for themselves in the perceptual world—the mere daydreams and joys and sufferings and wishes of the individual minds. These exist with one another, indeed, and with the objective nuclei, but out of them it is probable that to all eternity no interrelated system of any kind will ever be made. This notion of the purely substitutional or conceptual physical world brings us to the most critical of all the steps in the development of a philosophy of pure experience. The paradox of self-transcendency in knowledge comes back upon us here, but I think that our notions of pure experience and of substitution, and our radically empirical view of conjunctive transitions, are Denkmittel19 that will carry us safely through the pass. 5. WHAT OBJECTIVE REFERENCE IS Whosoever feels his experience to be something substitutional even while he has it, may be said to have an experience that reaches beyond itself. From in-
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 24
5/2/22 10:39 AM
A World of Pure Experience 25
side of its own entity it says ‘more,’ and postulates reality existing elsewhere. For the transcendentalist, who holds knowing to consist in a salto mortale20 across an ‘epistemological chasm,’ such an idea presents no difficulty; but it seems at first sight as if it might be inconsistent with an empiricism like our own. Have we not explained that conceptual knowledge is made such wholly by the existence of things that fall outside of the knowing experience itself— by intermediary experiences and by a terminus that fulfils? Can the knowledge be there before these elements that constitute its being have come? And, if knowledge be not there, how can objective reference occur? The key to this difficulty lies in the distinction between knowing as verified and completed, and the same knowing as in transit and on its way. To recur to the Memorial Hall example lately used, it is only when our idea of the Hall has actually terminated in the percept that we know ‘for certain’ that from the beginning it was truly cognitive of that. Until established by the end of the process, its quality of knowing that, or indeed of knowing anything, could still be doubted; and yet the knowing really was there, as the result now shows. We were virtual knowers of the Hall long before we were certified to have been its actual knowers, by the percept’s retroactive validating power. Just so we are ‘mortal’ all the time, by reason of the virtuality of the inevitable event which will make us so when it shall have come. Now the immensely greater part of all our knowing never gets beyond this virtual stage. It never is completed or nailed down. I speak not merely of our ideas of imperceptibles like ether-waves or dissociated ‘ions,’ or of ‘ejects’ like the contents of our neighbors’ minds; I speak also of ideas which we might verify if we would take the trouble, but which we hold for true although un-terminated perceptually, because nothing says ‘no’ to us, and there is no contradicting truth in sight. To continue thinking unchallenged is, ninety-nine times out of a hundred, our practical substitute for knowing in the completed sense. As each experience runs by cognitive transition into the next one, and we nowhere feel a collision with what we elsewhere count as truth or fact, we commit ourselves to the current as if the port were sure. We live, as it were, upon the front edge of an advancing wavecrest, and our sense of a determinate direction in falling forward is all we cover of the future of our path. It is as if a differential quotient should be conscious and treat itself as an adequate substitute for a traced-out curve. Our experience, inter alia,21 is of variations of rate and of direction, and lives in these transitions more than in the journey’s end. The experiences of tendency are sufficient to act upon—what more could we have done at those moments even if the later verification comes complete? This is what, as a radical empiricist, I say to the charge that the objective reference which is so flagrant a character of our experiences involves a chasm
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 25
5/2/22 10:39 AM
26
Essays in Radical Empiricism
and a mortal leap. A positively conjunctive transition involves neither chasm nor leap. Being the very original of what we mean by continuity, it makes a continuum wherever it appears. I know full well that such brief words as these will leave the hardened transcendentalist unshaken. Conjunctive experiences separate their terms, he will still say: they are third things interposed, that have themselves to be conjoined by new links, and to invoke them makes our trouble infinitely worse. To ‘feel’ our motion forward is impossible. Motion implies terminus; and how can terminus be felt before we have arrived? The barest start and sally forward, the barest tendency to leave the instant, involves the chasm and the leap. Conjunctive transitions are the most superficial of appearances, illusions of our sensibility which philosophical reflection pulverizes at a touch. Conception is our only trustworthy instrument, conception and the Absolute working hand in hand. Conception disintegrates experience utterly, but its disjunctions are easily overcome again when the Absolute takes up the task. Such transcendentalists I must leave, provisionally at least, in full possession of their creed.22 I have no space for polemics in this article, so I shall simply formulate the empiricist doctrine as my hypothesis, leaving it to work or not work as it may. Objective reference, I say then, is an incident of the fact that so much of our experience comes as an insufficient and consists of process and transition. Our fields of experience have no more definite boundaries than have our fields of view. Both are fringed forever by a more that continuously develops, and that continuously supersedes them as life proceeds. The relations, generally speaking, are as real here as the terms are, and the only complaint of the transcendentalist’s with which I could at all sympathize would be his charge that, by first making knowledge to consist in external relations as I have done, and by then confessing that nine-tenths of the time these are not actually but only virtually there, I have knocked the solid bottom out of the whole business, and palmed off a substitute of knowledge for the genuine thing. Only the admission, such a critic might say, that our ideas are self-transcendent and ‘true’ already, in advance of the experiences that are to terminate them, can bring solidity back to knowledge in a world like this, in which transitions and terminations are only by exception fulfilled. This seems to me an excellent place for applying the pragmatic method.23 When a dispute arises, that method consists in auguring what practical consequences would be different if one side rather than the other were true. If no difference can be thought of, the dispute is a quarrel over words.24 What then would the self-transcendency affirmed to exist in advance of all experiential mediation or termination, be known-as? What would it practically result in for us, were it true?
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 26
5/2/22 10:39 AM
A World of Pure Experience 27
It could only result in our orientation, in the turning of our expectations and practical tendencies into the right path; and the right path here, so long as we and the object are not yet face-to-face (or can never get face to face, as in the case of ejects), would be the path that led us into the object’s nearest neighborhood. Where direct acquaintance is lacking, ‘knowledge about’ is the next best thing, and an acquaintance with what actually lies about the object, and is most closely related to it, puts such knowledge within our grasp. Ether-waves and your anger, for example, are things in which my thoughts will never perceptually terminate, but my concepts of them lead me to their very brink, to the chromatic fringes and to the hurtful words and deeds which are their really next effects. Even if our ideas did in themselves carry the postulated self-transcendency, it would still remain true that their putting us into possession of such effects would be the sole cash-value of the self-transcendency for us. And this cash-value, it is needless to say, is verbatim et literatim25 what our empiricist account pays in. On pragmatist principles therefore, a dispute over selftranscendency is a pure logomachy.26 Call our concepts of ejective things self-transcendent or the reverse, it makes no difference, so long as we don’t differ about the nature of that exalted virtue’s fruits—fruits for us, of course, humanistic fruits. If an Absolute were proved to exist for other reasons, it might well appear that his knowledge is terminated in innumerable cases where ours is still incomplete. That, however, would be a fact indifferent to our knowledge. The latter would grow neither worse nor better, whether we acknowledged such an Absolute or left him out. So the notion of a knowledge still in transitu27 and on its way joins hands here with that notion of a ‘pure experience’ which I tried to explain in my [essay] entitled “Does Consciousness Exist?” The instant field of the present is always experienced in its ‘pure’ state, plain unqualified actuality, a simple that, as yet undifferentiated into thing and thought, and only virtually classifiable as objective fact or as someone’s opinion about fact. This is as true when the field is conceptual as when it is perceptual. ‘Memorial Hall’ is ‘there’ in my idea as much as when I stand before it. I proceed to act on its account in either case. Only in the later experience that supersedes the present one is this naïf immediacy retrospectively split into two parts, a ‘consciousness’ and its ‘content,’ and the content corrected or confirmed. While still pure, or present, any experience—mine, for example, of what I write about in these very lines—passes for ‘truth.’ The morrow may reduce it to ‘opinion.’ The transcendentalist in all his particular knowledges is as liable to this reduction as I am: his Absolute does not save him. Why, then, need he quarrel with an account of knowing that merely leaves it liable to this inevitable condition? Why insist that knowing is a static relation out of time when it practically
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 27
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Essays in Radical Empiricism
28
seems so much a function of our active life? For a thing to be valid, says Lotze, is the same as to make itself valid. When the whole universe seems only to be making itself valid and to be still incomplete (else why its ceaseless changing?) why, of all things, should knowing be exempt? Why should it not be making itself valid like everything else? That some parts of it may be already valid or verified beyond dispute, the empirical philosopher, of course, like anyone else, may always hope. 6. THE CONTERMINOUSNESS OF DIFFERENT MINDS With transition and prospect thus enthroned in pure experience, it is impossible to subscribe to the idealism of the English school.28 Radical empiricism has, in fact, more affinities with natural realism than with the views of Berkeley or of Mill, and this can be easily shown. For the Berkeleyan school, ideas (the verbal equivalent of what I term experiences) are discontinuous. The content of each is wholly immanent, and there are no transitions with which they are consubstantial and through which their beings may unite. Your Memorial Hall and mine, even when both are percepts, are wholly out of connection with each other. Our lives are a congeries of solipsisms,29 out of which in strict logic only a God could compose a universe even of discourse. No dynamic currents run between my objects and your objects. Never can our minds meet in the same. The incredibility of such a philosophy is flagrant. It is ‘cold, strained, and unnatural’ in a supreme degree; and it may be doubted whether even Berkeley himself, who took it so religiously, really believed, when walking through the streets of London, that his spirit and the spirits of his fellow wayfarers had absolutely different towns in view. To me the decisive reason in favor of our minds meeting in some common objects at least is that, unless I make that supposition, I have no motive for assuming that your mind exists at all. Why do I postulate your mind? Because I see your body acting in a certain way. Its gestures, facial movements, words and conduct generally, are ‘expressive,’ so I deem it actuated as my own is, by an inner life like mine. This argument from analogy is my reason, whether an instinctive belief runs before it or not. But what is ‘your body’ here but a percept in my field? It is only as animating that object, my object, that I have any occasion to think of you at all. If the body that you actuate be not the very body that I see there, but some duplicate body of your own with which that has nothing to do, we belong to different universes, you and I, and for me to speak of you is folly. Myriads of such universes even now may coexist,
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 28
5/2/22 10:39 AM
A World of Pure Experience 29
irrelevant to one another; my concern is solely with the universe with which my own life is connected. In that perceptual part of my universe which I call your body, your mind and my mind meet and may be called conterminous. Your mind actuates that body and mine sees it; my thoughts pass into it as into their harmonious cognitive fulfillment; your emotions and volitions pass into it as causes into their effects. But that percept hangs together with all our other physical percepts. They are of one stuff with it; and if it be our common possession, they must be so likewise. For instance, your hand lays hold of one end of a rope and my hand lays hold of the other end. We pull against each other. Can our two hands be mutual objects in this experience, and the rope not be mutual also? What is true of the rope is true of any other percept. Your objects are over and over again the same as mine. If I ask you where some object of yours is, our old Memorial Hall, for example, you point to my Memorial Hall with your hand which I see. If you alter an object in your world, put out a candle, for example, when I am present, my candle ipso facto30 goes out. It is only as altering my objects that I guess you to exist. If your objects do not coalesce with my objects, if they be not identically where mine are, they must be proved to be positively somewhere else. But no other location can be assigned for them, so their place must be what it seems to be, the same.31 Practically, then, our minds meet in a world of objects which they share in common, which would still be there, if one or several of the minds were destroyed. I can see no formal objection to this supposition’s being literally true. On the principles which I am defending, a ‘mind’ or ‘personal consciousness’ is the name for a series of experiences run together by certain definite transitions, and an objective reality is a series of similar experiences knit by different transitions. If one and the same experience can figure twice, once in a mental and once in a physical context (as I have tried, in my article on ‘Consciousness,’ to show that it can), one does not see why it might not figure thrice, or four times, or any number of times, by running into as many different mental contexts, just as the same point, lying at their intersection, can be continued into many different lines. Abolishing any number of contexts would not destroy the experience itself or its other contexts, any more than abolishing some of the point’s linear continuations would destroy the others, or destroy the point itself. I well know the subtle dialectic which insists that a term taken in another relation must needs be an intrinsically different term. The crux is always the old Greek one, that the same man can’t be tall in relation to one neighbor, and short in relation to another, for that would make him tall and short at once. In this essay I can not stop to refute this dialectic, so I pass on, leaving my
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 29
5/2/22 10:39 AM
30
Essays in Radical Empiricism
flank for the time exposed.32 But if my reader will only allow that the same ‘now’ both ends his past and begins his future; or that, when he buys an acre of land from his neighbor, it is the same acre that successively figures in the two estates; or that when I pay him a dollar, the same dollar goes into his pocket that came out of mine; he will also in consistency have to allow that the same object may conceivably play a part in, as being related to the rest of, any number of otherwise entirely different minds. This is enough for my present point: the common-sense notion of minds sharing the same object offers no special logical or epistemological difficulties of its own; it stands or falls with the general possibility of things being in conjunctive relation with other things at all. In principle, then, let natural realism pass for possible. Your mind and mine may terminate in the same percept, not merely against it, as if it were a third external thing, but by inserting themselves into it and coalescing with it, for such is the sort of conjunctive union that appears to be experienced when a perceptual terminus ‘fulfils.’ Even so, two hawsers33 may embrace the same pile, and yet neither one of them touch any other part except that pile, of what the other hawser is attached to. It is therefore not a formal question, but a question of empirical fact solely, whether, when you and I are said to know the ‘same’ Memorial Hall, our minds do terminate at or in a numerically identical percept.34 Obviously, as a plain matter of fact, they do not. Apart from color blindness and such possibilities, we see the Hall in different perspectives. You may be on one side of it and I on another. The percept of each of us, as he sees the surface of the Hall, is moreover only his provisional terminus. The next thing beyond my percept is not your mind, but more percepts of my own into which my first percept develops, the interior of the Hall, for instance, or the inner structure of its bricks and mortar. If our minds were in a literal sense conterminous, neither could get beyond the percept which they had in common, it would be an ultimate barrier between them—unless indeed they flowed over it and became ‘co-conscious’ over a still larger part of their content, which (thoughttransference apart) is not supposed to be the case. In point of fact the ultimate common barrier can always be pushed, by both minds, further than any actual percept of either, until at last it resolves itself into the mere notion of imperceptibles like atoms or ether, so that, where we do terminate in percepts, our knowledge is only speciously completed, being, in theoretic strictness, only a virtual knowledge of those remoter objects which conception carries out. Is natural realism, permissible in logic, refuted then by empirical fact? Do our minds have no object in common after all? Yes, they certainly have Space in common. On pragmatic principles we are obliged to predicate sameness wherever we can predicate no assignable point
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 30
5/2/22 10:39 AM
A World of Pure Experience 31
of difference. If two named things have every quality and function indiscernible and are at the same time in the same place, they must be written down as numerically one thing under two different names. But there is no test discoverable, so far as I know, by which it can be shown that the place occupied by your percept of Memorial Hall differs from the place occupied by mine. The percepts themselves may be shown to differ; but if each of us be asked to point out where his percept is, we point to an identical spot. All the relations, whether geometrical or causal, of the Hall originate or terminate in that spot wherein our hands meet, and where each of us begins to work if he wishes to make the Hall change before the other’s eyes. Just so it is with our bodies. That body of yours which you actuate and feel from within must be in the same spot as the body of yours which I see or touch from without. ‘There’ for me means where I place my finger. If you do not feel my finger’s contact to be ‘there’ in my sense, when I place it on your body, where then do you feel it? Your inner actuations of your body meet my finger there: it is there that you resist its push, or shrink back, or sweep the finger aside with your hand. Whatever further knowledge either of us may acquire of the real constitution of the body which we thus feel, you from within and I from without, it is in that same place that the newly conceived or perceived constituents have to be located, and it is through that space that your and my mental intercourse with each other has always to be carried on, by the mediation of impressions which I convey thither, and of the reactions thence which those impressions may provoke from you. In general terms, then, whatever differing contents our minds may eventually fill a place with, the place itself is a numerically identical content of the two minds, a piece of common property in which, through which, and over which they join. The receptacle of certain of our experiences being thus common, the experiences themselves might some day become common also. If that day ever did come, our thoughts would terminate in a complete empirical identity, there would be an end, so far as those experiences went, to our discussions about truth. No points of difference appearing, they would have to count as the same. 7. CONCLUSION With this we have the outlines of a philosophy of pure experience before us. At the outset of my essay, I called it a mosaic philosophy. In actual mosaics the pieces are held together by their bedding, for which bedding the Substances, transcendental Egos, or Absolutes of other philosophies may be taken to stand. In radical empiricism there is no bedding; it is as if the pieces clung
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 31
5/2/22 10:39 AM
32
Essays in Radical Empiricism
together by their edges, the transitions experienced between them forming their cement. Of course, such a metaphor is misleading, for in actual experience the more substantive and the more transitive parts run into each other continuously, there is in general no separateness needing to be overcome by an external cement; and whatever separateness is actually experienced is not overcome, it stays and counts as separateness to the end. But the metaphor serves to symbolize the fact that Experience itself, taken at large, can grow by its edges. That one moment of it proliferates into the next by transitions which, whether conjunctive or disjunctive, continue the experiential tissue, can not, I contend, be denied. Life is in the transitions as much as in the terms connected; often, indeed, it seems to be there more emphatically, as if our spurts and sallies forward were the real firing line of the battle, were like the thin line of flame advancing across the dry autumnal field which the farmer proceeds to burn. In this line we live prospectively as well as retrospectively. It is ‘of’ the past, inasmuch as it comes expressly as the past’s continuation; it is ‘of’ the future in so far as the future, when it comes, will have continued it. These relations of continuous transition experienced are what make our experiences cognitive. In the simplest and completest cases, the experiences are cognitive of one another. When one of them terminates a previous series of them with a sense of fulfillment, it, we say, is what those other experiences ‘had in view.’ The knowledge, in such a case, is verified; the truth is ‘salted down.’ Mainly, however, we live on speculative investments, or on our prospects only. But living on things in posse35 is as good as living in the actual, so long as our credit remains good. It is evident that for the most part it is good, and that the universe seldom protests our drafts. In this sense we at every moment can continue to believe in an existing beyond. It is only in special cases that our confident rush forward gets rebuked. The beyond must, of course, always in our philosophy be itself of an experiential nature. If not a future experience of our own or a present one of our neighbor, it must be a thing in itself in Dr. Prince’s and Professor Strong’s36 sense of the term—that is, it must be an experience for itself whose relation to other things we translate into the action of molecules, ether-waves, or whatever else the physical symbols may be.37 This opens the chapter of the relations of radical empiricism to panpsychism, into which I can not enter now.38 The beyond can in any case exist simultaneously—for it can be experienced to have existed simultaneously—with the experience that practically postulates it by looking in its direction, or by turning or changing in the direction of which it is the goal. Pending that actuality of union, in the virtuality of which the ‘truth,’ even now, of the postulation consists, the beyond and its knower are entities split off from each other. The world is in so far forth a pluralism of which the unity is not fully experienced as yet. But, as fast as
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 32
5/2/22 10:39 AM
A World of Pure Experience 33
verifications come, trains of experience, once separate, run into one another; and that is why I said, earlier in my article, that the unity of the world is on the whole undergoing increase. The universe continually grows in quantity by new experiences that graft themselves upon the older mass; but these very new experiences often help the mass to a more consolidated form. These are the main features of a philosophy of pure experience. It has innumerable other aspects and arouses innumerable questions, but the points I have touched on seem enough to make an entering wedge. In my own mind such a philosophy harmonizes best with a radical pluralism, with novelty and indeterminism, moralism and theism, and with the ‘humanism’ lately sprung upon us by the Oxford and the Chicago schools.39 I can not, however, be sure that all these doctrines are its necessary and indispensable allies. It presents so many points of difference, both from the common sense and from the idealism that have made our philosophic language, that it is almost as difficult to state it as it is to think it out clearly, and if it is ever to grow into a respectable system, it will have to be built up by the contributions of many cooperating minds. It seems to me, as I said at the outset of this essay, that many minds are, in point of fact, now turning in a direction that points toward radical empiricism. If they are carried further by my words, and if then they add their stronger voices to my feebler one, the publication of this essay will have been worthwhile.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 33
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 34
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Chapter Three
The Thing and Its Relations
Experience in its immediacy seems perfectly fluent.1 The active sense of living which we all enjoy, before reflection shatters our instinctive world for us, is self-luminous and suggests no paradoxes. Its difficulties are disappointments and uncertainties. They are not intellectual contradictions. When the reflective intellect gets at work, however, it discovers incomprehensibilities in the flowing process. Distinguishing its elements and parts, it gives them separate names, and what it thus disjoins it can not easily put together. Pyrrhonism2 accepts the irrationality and revels in its dialectic elaboration. Other philosophies try, some by ignoring, some by resisting, and some by turning the dialectic procedure against itself, negating its first negations, to restore the fluent sense of life again, and let redemption take the place of innocence. The perfection with which any philosophy may do this is the measure of its human success and of its importance in philosophic history. In [the last essay], “A World of Pure Experience,” I tried my own hand sketchily at the problem, resisting certain first steps of dialectics by insisting in a general way that the immediately experienced conjunctive relations are as real as anything else. If my sketch is not to appear too naïf, I must come closer to details, and in the present essay I propose to do so. 1 ‘Pure experience’ is the name which I gave to the immediate flux of life which furnishes the material to our later reflection with its conceptual categories. Only newborn babes, or men in semi-coma from sleep, drugs, illnesses, or blows, may be assumed to have an experience pure in the literal sense of a that which is not yet any definite what, though ready to be all sorts of 35
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 35
5/2/22 10:39 AM
36
Essays in Radical Empiricism
whats; full both of oneness and of manyness, but in respects that don’t appear; changing throughout, yet so confusedly that its phases interpenetrate and no points, either of distinction or of identity, can be caught. Pure experience in this state is but another name for feeling or sensation. But the flux of it no sooner comes than it tends to fill itself with emphases, and these salient parts become identified and fixed and abstracted; so that experience now flows as if shot through with adjectives and nouns and prepositions and conjunctions. Its purity is only a relative term, meaning the proportional amount of unverbalized sensation which it still embodies. Far back as we go, the flux, both as a whole and in its parts, is that of things conjunct and separated. The great continua of time, space, and the self envelope everything, betwixt them, and flow together without interfering. The things that they envelope come as separate in some ways and as continuous in others. Some sensations coalesce with some ideas, and others are irreconcilable. Qualities compenetrate one space, or exclude each other from it. They cling together persistently in groups that move as units, or else they separate. Their changes are abrupt or discontinuous; and their kinds resemble or differ; and, as they do so, they fall into either even or irregular series. In all this the continuities and the discontinuities are absolutely co-ordinate matters of immediate feeling. The conjunctions are as primordial elements of ‘fact’ as are the distinctions and disjunctions. In the same act by which I feel that this passing minute is a new pulse of my life, I feel that the old life continues into it, and the feeling of continuance in no wise jars upon the simultaneous feeling of a novelty. They, too, compenetrate harmoniously. Prepositions, copulas, and conjunctions, ‘is,’ ‘isn’t,’ ‘then,’ ‘before,’ ‘in,’ ‘on,’ ‘beside,’ ‘between,’ ‘next,’ ‘like,’ ‘unlike,’ ‘as,’ ‘but,’ flower out of the stream of pure experience, the stream of concretes or the sensational stream, as naturally as nouns and adjectives do, and they melt into it again as fluidly when we apply them to a new portion of the stream. 2 If now we ask why we must thus translate experience from a more concrete or pure into a more intellectualized form, filling it with ever more abounding conceptual distinctions, rationalism and naturalism give different replies. The rationalistic answer is that the theoretic life is absolute and its interests imperative; that to understand is simply the duty of man; and that who questions this need not be argued with, for by the fact of arguing he gives away his case.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 36
5/2/22 10:39 AM
The Thing and Its Relations 37
The naturalist answer is that the environment kills as well as sustains us, and that the tendency of raw experience to extinguish the experient himself is lessened just in the degree in which the elements in it that have a practical bearing upon life are analyzed out of the continuum and verbally fixed and coupled together, so that we may know what is in the wind for us and get ready to react in time. Had pure experience, the naturalist says, been always perfectly healthy, there would never have arisen the necessity of isolating or verbalizing any of its terms. We should just have experienced inarticulately and un-intellectually enjoyed. This leaning on ‘reaction’ in the naturalist account implies that, whenever we intellectualize a relatively pure experience, we ought to do so for the sake of re-descending to the purer or more concrete level again; and that if an intellect stays aloft among its abstract terms and generalized relations, and does not reinsert itself with its conclusions into some particular point of the immediate stream of life, it fails to finish out its function and leaves its normal race un-run. Most rationalists nowadays will agree that naturalism gives a true enough account of the way in which our intellect arose at first, but they will deny these latter implications. The case, they will say, resembles that of sexual love. Originating in the animal need of getting another generation born, this passion has developed secondarily such imperious spiritual needs that, if you ask why another generation ought to be born at all, the answer is: ‘Chiefly that love may go on.’ Just so with our intellect: it originated as a practical means of serving life; but it has developed incidentally the function of understanding absolute truth; and life itself now seems to be given chiefly as a means by which that function may be prosecuted. But truth and the understanding of it lie among the abstracts and universals, so the intellect now carries on its higher business wholly in this region, without any need of re-descending into pure experience again. If the contrasted tendencies which I thus designate as naturalistic and rationalistic are not recognized by the reader, perhaps an example will make them more concrete. Mr. Bradley,3 for instance, is an ultra-rationalist. He admits that our intellect is primarily practical, but says that, for philosophers, the practical need is simply Truth. Truth, moreover, must be assumed ‘consistent.’ Immediate experience has to be broken into subjects and qualities, terms and relations, to be understood as truth at all. Yet when so broken it is less consistent than ever. Taken raw, it is all un-distinguished. Intellectualized, it is all distinction without oneness. ‘Such an arrangement may work, but the theoretic problem is not solved.’ The question is ‘how the diversity can exist in harmony with the oneness.’ To go back to pure experience is unavailing. ‘Mere feeling gives no answer to our riddle.’ Even if your intuition
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 37
5/2/22 10:39 AM
38
Essays in Radical Empiricism
is a fact, it is not an understanding. ‘It is a mere experience, and furnishes no consistent view.’ The experience offered as facts or truths, I find that my intellect rejects because they contradict themselves. They offer a complex of diversities conjoined in a way which it feels is not its way and which it can not repeat as its own. . . . For to be satisfied, my intellect must understand, and it can not understand by taking a congeries in the lump.4
So Mr. Bradley, in the sole interests of ‘understanding’ (as he conceives that function), turns his back on finite experience forever. Truth must lie in the opposite direction, the direction of the Absolute; and this kind of rationalism and naturalism, or (as I will now call it) pragmatism, walk thenceforward upon opposite paths. For the one, those intellectual products are most true which, turning their face towards the Absolute, come nearest to symbolizing its ways of uniting the many and the one. For the other, those are most true which most successfully dip back into the finite stream of feeling and grow most easily confluent with some particular wave or wavelet. Such confluence not only proves the intellectual operation to have been true (as an addition may ‘prove’ that a subtraction is already rightly performed), but it constitutes, according to pragmatism, all that we mean by calling it true. Only in so far as they lead us, successfully or unsuccessfully, back into sensible experience again, are our abstracts and universals true or false at all.5 3 In Section 6 of [the last essay], I adopted in a general way the common-sense belief that one and the same world is cognized by our different minds; but I left undiscussed the dialectical arguments which maintain that this is logically absurd. The usual reason given for its being absurd is that it assumes one object (to wit, the world) to stand in two relations at once; to my mind, namely, and again to yours; whereas a term taken in a second relation can not logically be the same term which it was at first. I have heard this reason urged so often in discussing with absolutists, and it would destroy my radical empiricism so utterly, if it were valid, that I am bound to give it an attentive ear, and seriously to search its strength. For instance, let the matter in dispute be term M, asserted to be on the one hand related to L, and on the other to N; and let the two cases of relation be symbolized by L—M and M—N respectively. When, now, I assume that the experience may immediately come and be given in the shape L—M—N, with no trace of doubling or internal fission in the M, I am told that this is all a popular delusion; that L—M—N logically means two different experiences,
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 38
5/2/22 10:39 AM
The Thing and Its Relations 39
L—M and M—N, namely; and that although the Absolute may, and indeed must, from its superior point of view, read its own kind of unity into M’s two editions, yet as elements in finite experience the two M’s lie irretrievably asunder, and the world between them is broken and un-bridged. In arguing this dialectic thesis, one must avoid slipping from the logical into the physical point of view. It would be easy, in taking a concrete example to fix one’s ideas by, to choose one in which the letter M should stand for a collective noun of some sort, which noun, being related to L by one of its parts and to N by another, would inwardly be two things when it stood outwardly in both relations. Thus, one might say: ‘David Hume, who weighed so many stone by his body, influences posterity by his doctrine.’ The body and the doctrine are two things, between which our finite minds can discover no real sameness, though the same name covers both of them. And then, one might continue: ‘Only an Absolute is capable of uniting such a non-identity.’ We must, I say, avoid this sort of example, for the dialectic insight, if true at all, must apply to terms and relations universally. It must be true of abstract units as well as of nouns collective; and if we prove it by concrete examples, we must take the simplest, so as to avoid irrelevant material suggestions. Taken thus in all its generality, the absolutist contention seems to use as its major premise Hume’s notion ‘that all our distinct perceptions are distinct existences, and that the mind never perceives any real connection among distinct existences.’6 Undoubtedly, since we use two phrases in talking first about ‘M’s relation to L’ and then about ‘M’s relation to N,’ we must be having, or must have had, two distinct perceptions;—and the rest would then seem to follow duly. But the starting point of the reasoning here seems to be the fact of the two phrases; and this suggests that the argument may be merely verbal. Can it be that the whole dialectic consists in attributing to the experience talked about a constitution similar to that of the language in which we describe it? Must we assert the objective double-ness of the M merely because we have to name it twice over when we name its two relations? Candidly, I can think of no other reason than this for the dialectic conclusion;7 for, if we think, not of our words, but of any simple concrete matter which they may be held to signify, the experience itself belies the paradox asserted. We use indeed two separate concepts in analyzing our object, but we know them all the while to be but substitutional, and that the M in L—M and the M in M—N mean (i.e., are capable of leading to and terminating in) one self-same piece, M, of sensible experience. This persistent identity of certain units (or emphases, or points, or objects, or members—call them what you will) of the experience-continuum, is just one of those conjunctive features of it, on which I am obliged to insist so emphatically.8 For samenesses are parts of experience’s indefeasible structure. When I hear a
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 39
5/2/22 10:39 AM
40
Essays in Radical Empiricism
bell-stroke and, as life flows on, its after image dies away, I still hark back to it as ‘that same bell-stroke.’ When I see a thing M, with L to the left of it and N to the right of it, I see it as one M; and if you tell me I have had to ‘take’ it twice, I reply that if I ‘took’ it a thousand times I should still see it as a unit.9 Its unity is aboriginal, just as the multiplicity of my successive takings is aboriginal. It comes unbroken as that M, as a singular which I encounter; they come broken, as those takings, as my plurality of operations. The unity and the separateness are strictly co-ordinate. I do not easily fathom why my opponents should find the separateness so much more easily understandable that they must needs infect the whole of finite experience with it, and relegate the unity (now taken as a bare postulate and no longer as a thing positively perceivable) to the region of the Absolute’s mysteries. I do not easily fathom this, I say, for the said opponents are above mere verbal quibbling; yet all that I can catch in their talk is the substitution of what is true of certain words for what is true of what they signify. They stay with the words,—not returning to the stream of life whence all the meaning of them came, and which is always ready to reabsorb them. 4 For aught this argument proves, then, we may continue to believe that one thing can be known by many knowers. But the denial of one thing in many relations is but one application of a still profounder dialectic difficulty. Man can’t be good, said the sophists, for man is man and good is good; and Hegel10 and Herbart in their day, more recently A. Spir,11 and most recently and elaborately of all, Mr. Bradley, informs us that a term can logically only be a punctiform unit, and that not one of the conjunctive relations between things, which experience seems to yield, is rationally possible. Of course, if true, this cuts off radical empiricism without even a shilling. Radical empiricism takes conjunctive relations at their face value, holding them to be as real as the terms united by them.12 The world it represents as a collection, some parts of which are conjunctively and others disjunctively related. Two parts, themselves disjoined, may nevertheless hang together by intermediaries with which they are severally connected, and the whole world eventually may hang together similarly, inasmuch as some path of conjunctive transition by which to pass from one of its parts to another may always be discernible. Such determinately various hanging together may be called concatenated union, to distinguish it from the ‘through-and-through’ type of union, ‘each in all and all in each’ (union of total conflux, as one might call it), which monistic systems hold to obtain when things are taken in their absolute
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 40
5/2/22 10:39 AM
The Thing and Its Relations 41
reality. In a concatenated world a partial conflux often is experienced. Our concepts and our sensations are confluent; successive states of the same ego, and feelings of the same body are confluent. Where the experience is not of conflux, it may be of conterminousness (things with but one thing between); or of contiguousness (nothing between); or of likeness; or of nearness; or of simultaneousness; or of in-ness; or of on-ness; or of for-ness; or of simple with-ness; or even of mere and-ness, which last relation would make of however disjointed a world otherwise, at any rate for that occasion a universe ‘of discourse.’ Now Mr. Bradley tells us that none of these relations, as we actually experience them, can possibly be real.13 My next duty, accordingly, must be to rescue radical empiricism from Mr. Bradley. Fortunately, as it seems to me, his general contention, that the very notion of relation is unthinkable clearly, has been successfully met by many critics.14 It is a burden to the flesh, and an injustice both to readers and to the previous writers, to repeat good arguments already printed. So, in noticing Mr. Bradley, I will confine myself to the interests of radical empiricism solely. 5 The first duty of radical empiricism, taking given conjunctions at their face value, is to class some of them as more intimate and some as more external. When two terms are similar, their very natures enter into the relation. Being what they are, no matter where or when, the likeness never can be denied, if asserted. It continues predicable as long as the terms continue. Other relations, the where and the when, for example, seem adventitious. The sheet of paper may be ‘off’ or ‘on’ the table, for example; and in either case the relation involves only the outside of its terms. Having an outside, both of them, they contribute by it to the relation. It is external: the term’s inner nature is irrelevant to it. Any book, any table, may fall into the relation, which is created pro hac vice,15 not by their existence, but by their casual situation. It is just because so many of the conjunctions of experience seem so external that a philosophy of pure experience must tend to pluralism in its ontology. So far as things have space-relations, for example, we are free to imagine them with different origins even. If they could get to be, and get into space at all, then they may have done so separately. Once there, however, they are additives to one another, and, with no prejudice to their natures, all sorts of space-relations may supervene between them. The question of how things could come to be anyhow, is wholly different from the question what their relations, once the being accomplished, may consist in.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 41
5/2/22 10:39 AM
42
Essays in Radical Empiricism
Mr. Bradley now affirms that such external relations as the space-relations which we here talk of must hold of entirely different subjects from those of which the absence of such relations might a moment previously have been plausibly asserted. Not only is the situation different when the book is on the table, but the book itself is different as a book, from what it was when it was off the table.16 He admits that “such external relations seem possible and even existing. . . . That you do not alter what you compare or rearrange in space seems to common sense quite obvious, and that on the other side there are as obvious difficulties does not occur to common sense at all. And I will begin by pointing out these difficulties. . . . There is a relation in the result, and this relation, we hear, is to make no difference in its terms. But, if so, to what does it make a difference? [Doesn’t it make a difference to us onlookers, at least?] and what is the meaning and sense of qualifying the terms by it? [Surely the meaning is to tell the truth about their relative position.17 If, in short, it is external to the terms, how can it possibly be true of them? [Is it the ‘intimacy’ suggested by the little word ‘of,’ here, which I have underscored, that is the root of Mr. Bradley’s trouble?] . . . If the terms from their inner nature do not enter into the relation, then, so far as they are concerned, they seem related for no reason at all. . . . Things are spatially related, first in one way, and then become related in another way, and yet in no way themselves are altered; for the relations, it is said, are but external. But I reply that, if so, I can not understand the leaving by the terms of one set of relations and their adoption of another fresh set. The process and its result to the terms, if they contribute nothing to it [Surely they contribute to it all there is ‘of’ it!] seem irrational throughout. [If ‘irrational’ here means simply ‘non-rational,’ or nondeductible from the essence of either term singly, it is no reproach; if it means ‘contradicting’ such essence, Mr. Bradley should show wherein and how.] But, if they contribute anything, they must surely be affected internally. [Why so, if they contribute only their surface? In such relations as ‘on’ ‘a foot away,’ ‘between,’ ‘next,’ etc., only surfaces are in question.] . . . If the terms contribute anything whatever, then the terms are affected [inwardly altered?] by the arrangement. . . . That for working purposes we treat, and do well to treat, some relations as external merely I do not deny, and that of course is not the question at issue here. That question is . . . whether in the end and in principle a mere external relation [i.e., a relation which can change without forcing its terms to change their nature simultaneously] is possible and forced on us by the facts.”18 Mr. Bradley next reverts to the antinomies of space, which, according to him, prove it to be unreal, although it appears as so prolific a medium of external relations; and he then concludes that,
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 42
5/2/22 10:39 AM
The Thing and Its Relations 43
Irrationality and externality can not be the last truth about things. Somewhere there must be a reason why this and that appear together. And this reason and reality must reside in the whole from which terms and relations are abstractions, a whole in which their internal connection must lie, and out of which from the background appear those fresh results which never could have come from the premises.19
And he adds that “Where the whole is different, the terms that qualify and contribute to it must so far be different. . . . They are altered so far only [How far? farther than externally, yet not through and through?] but still they are altered. . . . I must insist that in each case the terms are qualified by their whole [Qualified how?—Do their external relations, situations, dates, etc., changed as these are in the new whole, fail to qualify them ‘far’ enough?], and that in the second case there is a whole which differs both logically and psychologically from the first whole; and I urge that in contributing to the change the terms so far are altered.” Not merely the relations, then, but the terms are altered: und zwar20 ‘so far.’ But just how far is the whole problem; and ‘through-and-through’ would seem (in spite of Mr. Bradley’s somewhat undecided utterances)21 to be the full Bradleyan answer. The ‘whole’ which he here treats as primary and determinative of each part’s manner of ‘contributing,’ simply must, when it alters, alter in its entirety. There must be total conflux of its parts, each into and through each other. The ‘must’ appears here as a Machtspruch,22 as an ipse dixit23 of Mr. Bradley’s absolutistically tempered ‘understanding,’ for he candidly confesses that how the parts do differ as they contribute to different wholes, is unknown to him.24 Although I have every wish to comprehend the authority by which Mr. Bradley’s understanding speaks, his words leave me wholly unconverted. ‘External relations’ stand with their withers all unwrung, and remain, for aught he proves to the contrary, not only practically workable, but also perfectly intelligible factors of reality. 6 Mr. Bradley’s understanding shows the most extraordinary power of perceiving separations and the most extraordinary impotence in comprehending conjunctions. One would naturally say ‘neither or both,’ but not so Mr. Bradley. When a common man analyzes certain whats from out the stream of experience, he understands their distinctness as thus isolated. But this does not prevent him from equally well understanding their combination with each other as originally experienced in the concrete, or their confluence with new
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 43
5/2/22 10:39 AM
44
Essays in Radical Empiricism
sensible experiences in which they recur as ‘the same.’ Returning into the stream of sensible presentation, nouns and adjectives, and thats and abstract whats, grow confluent again, and the word ‘is’ names all these experiences of conjunction. Mr. Bradley understands the isolation of the abstracts, but to understand the combination is to him impossible.25 “To understand a complex AB,” he says, I must begin with A or B. And beginning, say with A, if I then merely find B, I have either lost A, or I have got beside A, [the word ‘beside’ seems here vital, as meaning a conjunction ‘external’ and therefore unintelligible] something else, and in neither case have I understood.26 For my intellect can not simply unite a diversity, nor has it in itself any form or way of togetherness, and you gain nothing if, beside A and B, you offer me their conjunction in fact. For to my intellect that is no more than another external element. And ‘facts,’ once for all, are for my intellect not true unless they satisfy it. . . . The intellect has in its nature no principle of mere togetherness.27
Of course, Mr. Bradley has a right to define ‘intellect’ as the power by which we perceive separations but not unions—provided he give due notice to the reader. But why then claim that such a maimed and amputated power must reign supreme in philosophy, and accuse on its behoof the whole empirical world of irrationality? It is true that he elsewhere attributes to the intellect a proprius motus28 of transition but says that when he looks for these transitions in the detail of living experience, he ‘is unable to verify such a solution.’29 Yet he never explains what the intellectual transitions would be like in case we had them. He only defines them negatively—they are not spatial, temporal, predicative, or causal; or qualitatively or otherwise serial; or in any way relational as we naïvely trace relations, for relations separate terms, and need themselves to be hooked on ad infinitum. The nearest approach he makes to describing a truly intellectual transition is where he speaks of A and B as being ‘united, each from its own nature, in a whole which is the nature of both alike.’30 But this (which, pace Mr. Bradley, seems exquisitely analogous to ‘taking’ a congeries in a ‘lump,’ if not to ‘swamping’) suggests nothing but that conflux which pure experience so abundantly offers, as when ‘space,’ ‘white’ and ‘sweet’ are confluent in a ‘lump of sugar,’ or kinesthetic, dermal, and optical sensations confluent in ‘my hand.’31 All that I can verify in the transitions which Mr. Bradley’s intellect desiderates as its proprius motus is a reminiscence of these and other sensible conjunctions (especially space-conjunctions), but a reminiscence so vague that its originals are not recognized. Bradley in short repeats the fable of the dog, the bone, and its image in the water. With a world of particulars, given in loveliest union, in conjunction definitely various, and variously definite, the ‘how’ of which
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 44
5/2/22 10:39 AM
The Thing and Its Relations 45
you ‘understand’ as soon as you see the fact of them,32 for there is no ‘how’ except the constitution of the fact as given; with all this given him, I say, in pure experience, he asks for some ineffable union in the abstract instead, which, if he gained it, would only be a duplicate of what he has already in his full possession. Surely he abuses the privilege which society grants to all us philosophers, of being puzzle-headed. Polemic writing like this is odious; but with absolutism in possession in so many quarters, omission to defend my radical empiricism against its best known champion would count as either superficiality or inability. I have to conclude that its dialectic has not invalidated in the least degree the usual conjunctions by which the world, as experienced, hangs so variously together. In particular it leaves an empirical theory of knowledge33 intact, and lets us continue to believe with common sense that one object may be known, if we have any ground for thinking that it is known, to many knowers. In [the next essay] I shall return to this last supposition, which seems to me to offer other difficulties much harder for a philosophy of pure experience to deal with than any of absolutism’s dialectic objections.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 45
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 46
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Chapter Four
How Two Minds Can Know One Thing
In [the essay] entitled “Does ‘Consciousness’ Exist?” I have tried to show that when we call an experience ‘conscious,’ that does not mean that it is suffused throughout with a peculiar modality of being (‘psychic’ being) as stained glass may be suffused with light, but rather that it stands in certain determinate relations to other portions of experience extraneous to itself.1 These form one peculiar ‘context’ for it; while, taken in another context of experiences, we class it as a fact in the physical world. This ‘pen,’ for example, is, in the first instance, a bald that, a datum, fact, phenomenon, content, or whatever other neutral or ambiguous name you may prefer to apply. I called it in that article a ‘pure experience.’ To get classed either as a physical pen or as someone’s percept of a pen, it must assume a function, and that can only happen in a more complicated world. So far as in that world it is a stable feature, holds ink, marks paper and obeys the guidance of a hand, it is a physical pen. That is what we mean by being ‘physical,’ in a pen. So far as it is instable, on the contrary, coming and going with the movements of my eyes, altering with what I call my fancy, continuous with subsequent experiences of its ‘having been’ (in the past tense), it is the percept of a pen in my mind. Those peculiarities are what we mean by being ‘conscious,’ in a pen. In Section 6 of another [essay]2 I tried to show that the same that, the same numerically identical pen of pure experience, can enter simultaneously into many conscious contexts, or, in other words, be an object for many different minds. I admitted that I had not space to treat of certain possible objections in that article; but in [the last essay] I took some of the objections up. At the end of that [essay] I said that still more formidable-sounding objections remained; so, to leave my pure-experience theory in as strong a state as possible, I propose to consider those objections now. 47
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 47
5/2/22 10:39 AM
48
Essays in Radical Empiricism
1 The objections I previously tried to dispose of were purely logical or dialectical. No one identical term, whether physical or psychical, it had been said, could be the subject of two relations at once. This thesis I sought to prove unfounded. The objections that now confront us arise from the nature supposed to inhere in psychic facts specifically. Whatever may be the case with physical objects, a fact of consciousness, it is alleged (and indeed very plausibly), can not, without self-contradiction, be treated as a portion of two different minds, and for the following reasons. In the physical world we make with impunity the assumption that one and the same material object can figure in an indefinitely large number of different processes at once. When, for instance, a sheet of rubber is pulled at its four corners, a unit of rubber in the middle of the sheet is affected by all four of the pulls. It transmits them each, as if it pulled in four different ways at once itself. So, an air-particle or an ether-particle ‘compounds’ the different directions of movement imprinted on it without obliterating their several individualities. It delivers them distinct, on the contrary, at as many several ‘receivers’ (ear, eye or what not) as may be ‘tuned’ to that effect. The apparent paradox of a distinctness like this surviving in the midst of compounding is a thing which, I fancy, the analyses made by physicists have by this time sufficiently cleared up. But if, on the strength of these analogies, one should ask: “Why, if two or more lines can run through one and the same geometrical point, or if two or more distinct processes of activity can run through one and the same physical thing so that it simultaneously plays a role in each and every process, might not two or more streams of personal consciousness include one and the same unit of experience so that it would simultaneously be a part of the experience of all the different minds?” one would be checked by thinking of a certain peculiarity by which phenomena of consciousness differ from physical things. While physical things, namely, are supposed to be permanent and to have their ‘states,’ a fact of consciousness exists but once and is a state. Its esse is sentiri;3 it is only so far as it is felt; and it is unambiguously and unequivocally exactly what is felt. The hypothesis under consideration would, however, oblige it to be felt equivocally, felt now as part of my mind and again at the same time not as a part of my mind, but of yours (for my mind is not yours), and this would seem impossible without doubling it into two distinct things, or, in other words, without reverting to the ordinary dualistic philosophy of insulated minds each knowing its object representatively as a third thing,—and that would be to give up the pure-experience scheme altogether.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 48
5/2/22 10:39 AM
How Two Minds Can Know One Thing 49
Can we see, then, any way in which a unit of pure experience might enter into and figure in two diverse streams of consciousness without turning itself into the two units which, on our hypothesis, it must not be? 2 There is a way; and the first step towards it is to see more precisely how the unit enters into either one of the streams of consciousness alone. Just what, from being ‘pure,’ does its becoming ‘conscious’ once mean? It means, first, that new experiences have supervened; and, second, that they have borne a certain assignable relation to the unit supposed. Continue, if you please, to speak of the pure unit as ‘the pen.’ So far as the pen’s successors do but repeat the pen or, being different from it, are ‘energetically’4 related to it, it and they will form a group of stably existing physical things. So far, however, as its successors differ from it in another well-determined way, the pen will figure in their context, not as a physical, but as a mental fact. It will become a passing ‘percept,’ my percept of that pen. What now is that decisive well-determined way? In the chapter on ‘The Self,’ in my Principles of Psychology, I explained the continuous identity of each personal consciousness as a name for the practical fact that new experiences5 come which look back on the old ones, find them ‘warm,’ and greet and appropriate them as ‘mine.’ These operations mean, when analyzed empirically, several tolerably definite things, viz.: 1. That the new experience has past time for its ‘content,’ and in that time a pen that ‘was’; 2. That ‘warmth’ was also about the pen, in the sense of a group of feelings (‘interest’ aroused, ‘attention’ turned, ‘eyes’ employed, etc.) that were closely connected with it and that now recur and evermore recur with unbroken vividness, though from the pen of now, which may be only an image, all such vividness may have gone; 3. That these feelings are the nucleus of ‘me’; 4. That whatever once was associated with them was, at least for that one moment, ‘mine’—my implement if associated with hand-feelings, my ‘percept’ only, if only eye-feelings and attention-feelings were involved. The pen, realized in this retrospective way as my percept, thus figures as a fact of ‘conscious’ life. But it does so only so far as ‘appropriation’ has occurred; and appropriation is part of the content of a later experience wholly additional to the originally ‘pure’ pen. That pen, virtually both objective and
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 49
5/2/22 10:39 AM
50
Essays in Radical Empiricism
subjective, is at its own moment actually and intrinsically neither. It has to be looked back upon and used, in order to be classed in either distinctive way. But its use, so called, is in the hands of the other experience, while it stands, throughout the operation, passive and unchanged. If this pass muster as an intelligible account of how an experience originally pure can enter into one consciousness, the next question is as to how it might conceivably enter into two. 3 Obviously, no new kind of condition would have to be supplied. All that we should have to postulate would be a second subsequent experience, collateral and contemporary with the first subsequent one, in which a similar act of appropriation should occur. The two acts would interfere neither with one another nor with the originally pure pen. It would sleep undisturbed in its own past, no matter how many such successors went through their several appropriative acts. Each would know it as ‘my’ percept, each would class it as a ‘conscious’ fact. Nor need their so classing it interfere in the least with their classing it at the same time as a physical pen. Since the classing in both cases depends upon the taking of it in one group or another of associates, if the superseding experience were of wide enough ‘span’ it could think the pen in both groups simultaneously, and yet distinguish the two groups. It would then see the whole situation conformably to what we call ‘the representative theory of cognition,’ and that is what we all spontaneously do. As a man philosophizing ‘popularly,’ I believe that what I see myself writing with is double—I think it in its relations to physical nature, and also in its relations to my personal life; I see that it is in my mind, but that it also is a physical pen. The paradox of the same experience figuring in two consciousnesses seems thus no paradox at all. To be ‘conscious’ means not simply to be, but to be reported, known, to have awareness of one’s being added to that being; and this is just what happens when the appropriative experience supervenes. The pen experience in its original immediacy is not aware of itself, it simply is, and the second experience is required for what we call awareness of it to occur.6 The difficulty of understanding what happens here is, therefore, not a logical difficulty: there is no contradiction involved. It is an ontological difficulty rather. Experiences come on an enormous scale, and if we take them all together, they come in a chaos of incommensurable relations that we can not straighten out. We have to abstract different groups of them, and handle these separately if we are to talk of them at all. But how the experiences ever
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 50
5/2/22 10:39 AM
How Two Minds Can Know One Thing 51
get themselves made, or why their characters and relations are just such as appear, we can not begin to understand. Granting, however, that, by hook or crook, they can get themselves made, and can appear in the successions that I have so schematically described, then we have to confess that even although (as I began by quoting from the adversary) ‘a feeling only is as it is felt,’ there is still nothing absurd in the notion of its being felt in two different ways at once, as yours, namely, and as mine. It is, indeed, ‘mine’ only as it is felt as mine, and ‘yours’ only as it is felt as yours. But it is felt as neither by itself, but only when ‘owned’ by our two several remembering experiences, just as one undivided estate is owned by several heirs. 4 One word, now, before I close, about the corollaries of the views set forth. Since the acquisition of conscious quality on the part of an experience depends upon a context coming to it, it follows that the sum total of all experiences, having no context, can not strictly be called conscious at all. It is a that, an Absolute, a ‘pure’ experience on an enormous scale, undifferentiated and undifferentiable into thought and thing. This the post-Kantian idealists have always practically acknowledged by calling their doctrine an Identitätsphilosophie.7 The question of the Beseelung8 of the All of things ought not, then, even to be asked. No more ought the question of its truth to be asked, for truth is a relation inside of the sum total, obtaining between thoughts and something else, and thoughts, as we have seen, can only be contextual things. In these respects, the pure experiences of our philosophy are, in themselves considered, so many little absolutes, the philosophy of pure experience being only a more comminuted Identitätsphilosophie.9 Meanwhile, a pure experience can be postulated with any amount whatever of span or field. If it exerts the retrospective and appropriative function on any other piece of experience, the latter thereby enters into its own conscious stream. And in this operation time intervals make no essential difference. After sleeping, my retrospection is as perfect as it is between two successive waking moments of my time. Accordingly, if, millions of years later, a similarly retrospective experience should anyhow come to birth, my present thought would form a genuine portion of its long-span conscious life. ‘Form a portion,’ I say, but not in the sense that the two things could be entitatively or substantively one—they cannot, for they are numerically discrete facts— but only in the sense that the functions of my present thought, its knowledge, its purpose, its content and ‘consciousness,’ in short, being inherited, would be continued practically unchanged. Speculations like Fechner’s,10 of an
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 51
5/2/22 10:39 AM
52
Essays in Radical Empiricism
Earth-soul, of wider spans of consciousness enveloping narrower ones throughout the cosmos, are, therefore, philosophically quite in order, provided they distinguish the functional from the entitative point of view, and do not treat the minor consciousness under discussion as a kind of standing material of which the wider ones consist.11
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 52
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Chapter Five
The Place of Affectional Facts in a World of Pure Experience
Common sense and popular philosophy are as dualistic as it is possible to be.1 Thoughts, we all naturally think, are made of one kind of substance, and things of another. Consciousness, flowing inside of us in the forms of conception or judgment, or concentrating itself in the shape of passion or emotion, can be directly felt as the spiritual activity which it is, and known in contrast with the space-filling objective ‘content’ which it envelopes and accompanies. In opposition to this dualistic philosophy, I tried, in [the first essay] to show that thoughts and things are absolutely homogeneous as to their material, and that their opposition is only one of relation and of function. There is no thought-stuff different from thing-stuff, I said; but the same identical piece of ‘pure experience’ (which was the name I gave to the materia prima2 of everything) can stand alternately for a ‘fact of consciousness’ or for a physical reality, according as it is taken in one context or in another. For the right understanding of what follows, I shall have to presuppose that the reader will have read that [essay].3 The commonest objection which the doctrine there laid down runs up against is drawn from the existence of our ‘affections.’ In our pleasures and pains, our loves and fears and angers, in the beauty, comicality, importance or preciousness of certain objects and situations, we have, I am told by many critics, a great realm of experience intuitively recognized as spiritual, made, and felt to be made, of consciousness exclusively, and different in nature from the space-filling kind of being which is enjoyed by physical objects. In Section 7 of “Does ‘Consciousness’ Exist?” I treated of this class of experiences very inadequately, because I had to be so brief. I now return to the subject, because I believe that, so far from invalidating my general thesis, these phenomena, when properly analyzed, afford it powerful support. 53
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 53
5/2/22 10:39 AM
54
Essays in Radical Empiricism
The central point of the pure-experience theory is that ‘outer’ and ‘inner’ are names for two groups into which we sort experiences according to the way in which they act upon their neighbors. Any one ‘content,’ such as hard, let us say, can be assigned to either group. In the outer group it is ‘strong,’ it acts ‘energetically’ and aggressively. Here whatever is hard interferes with the space its neighbors occupy. It dents them; is impenetrable by them; and we call the hardness then a physical hardness. In the mind, on the contrary, the hard thing is nowhere in particular, it dents nothing, it suffuses through its mental neighbors, as it were, and interpenetrates them. Taken in this group we call both it and them ‘ideas’ or ‘sensations;’ and the basis of the two groups, respectively, is the different type of interrelation, the mutual impenetrability, on the one hand, and the lack of physical interference and interaction, on the other. That what in itself is one and the same entity should be able to function thus differently in different contexts is a natural consequence of the extremely complex reticulations4 in which our experiences come. To her offspring a tigress is tender, but cruel to every other living thing—both cruel and tender, therefore, at once. A mass in movement resists every force that operates contrariwise to its own direction, but to forces that pursue the same direction, or come in at right angles, it is absolutely inert. It is thus both energetic and inert; and the same is true (if you vary the associates properly) of every other piece of experience. It is only towards certain specific groups of associates that the physical energies, as we call them, of a content are put forth. In another group it may be quite inert. It is possible to imagine a universe of experiences in which the only alternative between neighbors would be either physical interaction or complete inertness. In such a world the mental or the physical status of any piece of experience would be unequivocal. When active, it would figure in the physical, and when inactive, in the mental group. But the universe we live in is more chaotic than this, and there is room in it for the hybrid or ambiguous group of our affectional experiences, of our emotions and appreciative perceptions. In the paragraphs that follow I shall try to show: 1. That the popular notion that these experiences are intuitively given as purely inner facts is hasty and erroneous; and 2. That their ambiguity illustrates beautifully my central thesis that subjectivity and objectivity are affairs not of what an experience is aboriginally made of, but of its classification. Classifications depend on our temporary purposes.5 For certain purposes it is convenient to take things in one set of relations, for other purposes in another set. In the two cases their contexts are apt to be different. In the case of our affectional experiences we have
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 54
5/2/22 10:39 AM
The Place of Affectional Facts in a World of Pure Experience 55
no permanent and steadfast purpose that obliges us to be consistent, so we find it easy to let them float ambiguously, sometimes classing them with our feelings, sometimes with more physical realities, according to caprice or to the convenience of the moment. Thus would these experiences, so far from being an obstacle to the pure experience philosophy, serve as an excellent corroboration of its truth. First of all, then, it is a mistake to say, with the objectors whom I began by citing, that anger, love and fear are affections purely of the mind. That, to a great extent at any rate, they are simultaneously affections of the body is proved by the whole literature of the James-Lange theory of emotion.6 All our pains, moreover, are local, and we are always free to speak of them in objective as well as in subjective terms. We can say that we are aware of a painful place, filling a certain bigness in our organism, or we can say that we are inwardly in a ‘state’ of pain. All our adjectives of worth are similarly ambiguous—I instanced some of the ambiguities.7 Is the preciousness of a diamond a quality of the gem? or is it a feeling in our mind? Practically we treat it as both or as either, according to the temporary direction of our thought. ‘Beauty,’ says Professor Santayana, “is pleasure objectified;” and in Sections 10 and 11 of his work, The Sense of Beauty, he treats in a masterly way of this equivocal realm.8 The various pleasures we receive from an object may count as ‘feelings’ when we take them singly, but when they combine in a total richness, we call the result the ‘beauty’ of the object, and treat it as an outer attribute which our mind perceives. We discover beauty just as we discover the physical properties of things. Training is needed to make us expert in either line. Single sensations also may be ambiguous. Shall we say an ‘agreeable degree of heat,’ or an ‘agreeable feeling’ occasioned by the degree of heat? Either will do; and language would lose most of its esthetic and rhetorical value were we forbidden to project words primarily connoting our affections upon the objects by which the affections are aroused. The man is really hateful; the action really mean; the situation really tragic—all in themselves and quite apart from our opinion. We even go so far as to talk of a weary road, a giddy height, a jocund9 morning or a sullen sky; and the term ‘indefinite’ while usually applied only to our apprehensions, functions as a fundamental physical qualification of things in Spencer’s ‘law of evolution,’10 and doubtless passes with most readers for all right. Psychologists, studying our perceptions of movement, have unearthed experiences in which movement is felt in general but not ascribed correctly to the body that really moves. Thus in optical vertigo, caused by unconscious movements of our eyes, both we and the external universe appear to be in a whirl. When clouds float by the moon, it is as if both clouds and moon
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 55
5/2/22 10:39 AM
56
Essays in Radical Empiricism
and we ourselves shared in the motion. In the extraordinary case of amnesia of the Rev. Mr. Hanna, published by Sidis and Goodhart in their important work on Multiple Personality, we read that when the patient first recovered consciousness and, noticed an attendant walk across the room, he identified the movement with that of his own. He did not yet discriminate between his own movements and those outside himself.11
Such experiences point to a primitive stage of perception in which discriminations afterwards needful have not yet been made. A piece of experience of a determinate sort is there, but there at first as a ‘pure’ fact. Motion originally simply is; only later is it confined to this thing or to that. Something like this is true of every experience, however complex, at the moment of its actual presence. Let the reader arrest himself in the act of reading this article now. Now this is a pure experience, a phenomenon, or datum, a mere that or content of fact. ‘Reading’ simply is, is there; and whether there for someone’s consciousness, or there for physical nature, is a question not yet put. At the moment, it is there for neither; later we shall probably judge it to have been there for both. With the affectional experiences which we are considering, the relatively ‘pure’ condition lasts. In practical life no urgent need has yet arisen for deciding whether to treat them as rigorously mental or as rigorously physical facts. So they remain equivocal; and, as the world goes, their equivocality is one of their great conveniences. The shifting place of ‘secondary qualities’ in the history of philosophy12 is another excellent proof of the fact that ‘inner’ and ‘outer’ are not coefficients with which experiences come to us aboriginally stamped, but are rather results of a later classification performed by us for particular needs. The common-sense stage of thought is a perfectly definite practical halting place, the place where we ourselves can proceed to act unhesitatingly. On this stage of thought things act on each other as well as on us by means of their secondary qualities. Sound, as such, goes through the air and can be intercepted. The heat of the fire passes over, as such, into the water which it sets a-boiling. It is the very light of the arc-lamp which displaces the darkness of the midnight street, etc. By engendering and translocating just these qualities, actively efficacious as they seem to be, we ourselves succeed in altering nature so as to suit us; and until more purely intellectual, as distinguished from practical, needs had arisen, no one ever thought of calling these qualities subjective. When, however, Galileo, Descartes, and others found it best for philosophic purposes to class sound, heat, and light along with pain and pleasure as purely mental phenomena, they could do so with impunity.13
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 56
5/2/22 10:39 AM
The Place of Affectional Facts in a World of Pure Experience 57
Even the primary qualities are undergoing the same fate. Hardness and softness are effects on us of atomic interactions, and the atoms themselves are neither hard nor soft, nor solid nor liquid. Size and shape are deemed subjective by Kantians; time itself is subjective according to many philosophers;14 and even the activity and causal efficacy which lingered in physics long after secondary qualities were banished are now treated as illusory projections outward of phenomena of our own consciousness. There are no activities or effects in nature, for the most intellectual contemporary school of physical speculation. Nature exhibits only changes, which habitually coincide with one another so that their habits are describable in simple ‘laws.’15 There is no original spirituality or materiality of being, intuitively discerned, then; but only a translocation of experiences from one world to another; a grouping of them with one set or another of associates for definitely practical or intellectual ends. I will say nothing here of the persistent ambiguity of relations. They are undeniable parts of pure experience; yet, while common sense and what I call radical empiricism stand for their being objective, both rationalism and the usual empiricism claim that they are exclusively the ‘work of the mind’—the finite mind or the absolute mind, as the case may be.16 Turn now to those affective phenomena which more directly concern us. We soon learn to separate the ways in which things appeal to our interests and emotions from the ways in which they act upon one another. It does not work to assume that physical objects are going to act outwardly by their sympathetic or antipathetic qualities. The beauty of a thing or its value is no force that can be plotted in a polygon of compositions, nor does its ‘use’ or ‘significance’ affect in the minutest degree its vicissitudes or destiny at the hands of physical nature. Chemical ‘affinities’ are a purely verbal metaphor; and, as I just said, even such things as forces, tensions, and activities can at a pinch be regarded as anthropomorphic projections. So far, then, as the physical world means the collection of contents that determine in each other certain regular changes, the whole collection of our appreciative attributes has to be treated as falling outside of it. If we mean by physical nature whatever lies beyond the surface of our bodies, these attributes are inert throughout the whole extent of physical nature. Why then do men leave them as ambiguous as they do, and not class them decisively as purely spiritual? The reason would seem to be that, although they are inert as regards the rest of physical nature, they are not inert as regards that part of physical nature which our own skin covers. It is those very appreciative attributes of things, their dangerousness, beauty, rarity, utility, etc., that primarily appeal to our attention. In our commerce with nature these attributes are what give
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 57
5/2/22 10:39 AM
58
Essays in Radical Empiricism
emphasis to objects; and for an object to be emphatic, whatever spiritual fact it may mean, means also that it produces immediate bodily effects upon us, alterations of tone and tension, of heartbeat and breathing, of vascular and visceral action. The ‘interesting’ aspects of things are thus not wholly inert physically, though they be active only in these small corners of physical nature which our bodies occupy. That, however, is enough to save them from being classed as absolutely non-objective. The attempt, if anyone should make it, to sort experiences into two absolutely discrete groups, with nothing but inertness in one of them and nothing but activities in the other, would thus receive one check. It would receive another as soon as we examined the more distinctively mental group; for though in that group, it be true that things do not act on one another by their physical properties, do not dent each other or set fire to each other, they yet act on each other in the most energetic way by those very characters which are so inert extra-corporeally. It is by the interest and importance that experiences have for us, by the emotions they excite, and the purposes they subserve, by their affective values, in short, that their consecution in our several conscious streams, as ‘thoughts’ of ours, is mainly ruled. Desire introduces them; interest holds them; fitness fixes their order and connection. I need only refer for this aspect of our mental life, to Wundt’s17 article “Über psychische Causalität,” which begins Volume X. of his Philosophische Studien.18 It thus appears that the ambiguous or amphibious status which we find our epithets of value occupying is the most natural thing in the world. It would, however, be an unnatural status if the popular opinion which I cited at the outset were correct. If ‘physical’ and ‘mental’ meant two different kinds of intrinsic nature, immediately, intuitively, and infallibly discernible, and each fixed forever in whatever bit of experience it qualified, one does not see how there could ever have arisen any room for doubt or ambiguity. But if, on the contrary, these words are words of sorting, ambiguity is natural. For then, as soon as the relations of a thing are sufficiently various it can be sorted variously. Take a mass of carrion, for example, and the ‘disgustingness’ which for us is part of the experience. The sun caresses it, and the zephyr woos it as if it were a bed of roses. So the disgustingness fails to operate within the realm of suns and breezes,—it does not function as a physical quality. But the carrion ‘turns our stomach’ by what seems a direct operation—it does function physically, therefore, in that limited part of physics. We can treat it as physical or as non-physical according as we take it in the narrower or in the wider context, and conversely, of course, we must treat it as non-mental or as mental. Our body itself is the palmary instance19 of the ambiguous. Sometimes I treat my body purely as a part of outer nature. Sometimes, again, I think of it as ‘mine,’ I sort it with the ‘me,’ and then certain local changes and
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 58
5/2/22 10:39 AM
The Place of Affectional Facts in a World of Pure Experience 59
determinations in it pass for spiritual happenings. Its breathing is my ‘thinking,’ its sensorial adjustments are my ‘attention,’ its kinesthetic alterations are my ‘efforts,’ its visceral perturbations are my ‘emotions.’ The obstinate controversies that have arisen over such statements as these (which sound so paradoxical, and which can yet be made so seriously) prove how hard it is to decide by bare introspection what it is in experiences that shall make them either spiritual or material. It surely can be nothing intrinsic in the individual experience. It is their way of behaving towards each other, their system of relations, their function; and all these things vary with the context in which we find it opportune to consider them.20 I think I may conclude, then (and I hope that my readers are now ready to conclude with me), that the pretended spirituality of our emotions and of our attributes of value, so far from proving an objection to the philosophy of pure experience, does, when rightly discussed and accounted for, serve as one of its best corroborations.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 59
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 60
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Chapter Six
The Experience of Activity
Brethren of the Psychological Association:1 In casting about me for a subject for your President this year to talk about it has seemed to me that our experiences of activity would form a good one; not only because the topic is so naturally interesting, and because it has lately led to a good deal of rather inconclusive discussion, but because I myself am growing more and more interested in a certain systematic way of handling questions, and want to get others interested also, and this question strikes me as one in which, although I am painfully aware of my inability to communicate new discoveries or to reach definitive conclusions, I yet can show, in a rather definite manner, how the method works. The way of handling things I speak of, is, as you already will have suspected, that known sometimes as the pragmatic method, sometimes as humanism, sometimes as Deweyism,2 and in France, by some of the disciples of Bergson, as the Philosophie nouvelle. Professor Woodbridge’s Journal of Philosophy3 seems unintentionally to have become a sort of meeting place for those who follow these tendencies in America. There is only a dim identity among them; and the most that can be said at present is that some sort of gestation seems to be in the atmosphere, and that almost any day a man with a genius for finding the right word for things may hit upon some unifying and conciliating formula that will make so much vaguely similar aspiration crystallize into more definite form. I myself have given the name of ‘radical empiricism’ to that version of the tendency in question which I prefer; and I propose, if you will now let me, to illustrate what I mean by radical empiricism, by applying it to activity as an example, hoping at the same time incidentally to leave the general problem of activity in a slightly—I fear very slightly—more manageable shape than before. 61
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 61
5/2/22 10:39 AM
62
Essays in Radical Empiricism
Mr. Bradley calls the question of activity a scandal to philosophy, and if one turns to the current literature of the subject—his own writings included— one easily gathers what he means. The opponents cannot even understand one another. Mr. Bradley says to Mr. Ward: I do not care what your oracle is, and your preposterous psychology may here be gospel if you please; . . . but if the revelation does contain a meaning, I will commit myself to this: either the oracle is so confused that its signification is not discoverable, or, upon the other hand, if it can be pinned down to any definite statement, then that statement will be false.4
Mr. Ward in turn says of Mr. Bradley: I cannot even imagine the state of mind to which his description applies. . . . [It] reads like an unintentional travesty of Herbartian psychology by one who has tried to improve upon it without being at the pains to master it.5
Münsterberg excludes a view opposed to his own by saying that with anyone who holds it a Verständigung with him is “grundsätzlich ausgeschlossen;”6 and Royce, in a review of Stout,7 hauls him over the coals at great length for defending ‘efficacy’ in a way which I, for one, never gathered from reading him, and which I have heard Stout himself say was quite foreign to the intention of his text. In these discussions distinct questions are habitually jumbled and different points of view are talked of durcheinander. 1. There is a psychological question: “Have we perceptions of activity? and if so, what are they like, and when and where do we have them?” 2. There is a metaphysical question: “Is there a fact of activity? and if so, what idea must we frame of it? What is it like? and what does it do, if it does anything?” And finally there is a logical question: 3. “Whence do we know activity? By our own feelings of it solely? or by some other source of information?” Throughout page after page of the literature one knows not which of these questions is before one; and mere description of the surface-show of experience is proffered as if it implicitly answered every one of them. No one of the disputants, moreover, tries to show what pragmatic consequences his own view would carry, or what assignable particular differences in anyone’s experience it would make if his adversary’s were triumphant. It seems to me that if radical empiricism be good for anything, it ought, with its pragmatic method and its principle of pure experience, to be able to avoid
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 62
5/2/22 10:39 AM
The Experience of Activity 63
such tangles, or at least to simplify them somewhat. The pragmatic method starts from the postulate that there is no difference of truth that doesn’t make a difference of fact somewhere; and it seeks to determine the meaning of all differences of opinion by making the discussion hinge as soon as possible upon some practical or particular issue.8 The principle of pure experience is also a methodical postulate. Nothing shall be admitted as fact, it says, except what can be experienced at some definite time by some experient; and for every feature of fact ever so experienced, a definite place must be found somewhere in the final system of reality. In other words: Everything real must be experienceable somewhere, and every kind of thing experienced must somewhere be real. Armed with these rules of method let us see what face the problems of activity present to us. By the principle of pure experience, either the word ‘activity’ must have no meaning at all, or else the original type and model of what it means must lie in some concrete kind of experience that can be definitely pointed out. Whatever ulterior judgments we may eventually come to make regarding activity, that sort of thing will be what the judgments are about. The first step to take, then, is to ask where in the stream of experience we seem to find what we speak of as activity. What we are to think of the activity thus found will be a later question. Now it is obvious that we are tempted to affirm activity wherever we find anything going on. Taken in the broadest sense, any apprehension of something doing, is an experience of activity. Were our world describable only by the words ‘nothing happening,’ ‘nothing changing,’ ‘nothing doing,’ we should unquestionably call it an ‘inactive’ world. Bare activity then, as we may call it, means the bare fact of event or change. ‘Change taking place’ is a unique content of experience, one of those ‘conjunctive’ objects which radical empiricism seeks so earnestly to rehabilitate and preserve. The sense of activity is thus in the broadest and vaguest way synonymous with the sense of ‘life.’ We should feel our own subjective life at least, even in noticing and proclaiming an otherwise inactive world. Our own reaction on its monotony would be the one thing experienced there in the form of something coming to pass. This seems to be what certain writers have in mind when they insist that for an experient to be at all is to be active. It seems to justify, or at any rate to explain, Mr. Ward’s expression that we are only as we are active,9 for we are only as experients; and it rules out Mr. Bradley’s contention that “there is no original experience of anything like activity.”10 What we ought to say about activities thus elementary, whose they are, what they effect, or whether indeed they effect anything at all—these are later questions, to be answered only when the field of experience is enlarged. Bare activity would thus be predicable, though there were no definite direction, no actor, and no aim. Mere restless zigzag movement, or a wild
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 63
5/2/22 10:39 AM
64
Essays in Radical Empiricism
Ideenflucht, or Rhapsodie der Wahrnehmungen, as Kant would say,11 would constitute an active as distinguished from an inactive world. But in this actual world of ours, as it is given, a part at least of the activity comes with definite direction; it comes with desire and sense of goal; it comes complicated with resistances which it overcomes or succumbs to, and with the efforts which the feeling of resistance so often provokes; and it is in complex experiences like these that the notions of distinct agents, and of passivity as opposed to activity arise. Here also the notion of causal efficacy comes to birth. Perhaps the most elaborate work ever done in descriptive psychology has been the analysis by various recent writers of the more complex activity-situations.12 In their descriptions, exquisitely subtle some of them,13 the activity appears as the Gestaltqualität or the fundierte Inhalt14 (or as whatever else you may please to call the conjunctive form) which the content falls into when we experience it in the ways which the describers set forth. Those factors in those relations are what we mean by activity-situations; and to the possible enumeration and accumulation of their circumstances and ingredients there would seem to be no natural bound. Every hour of human life could contribute to the picture gallery; and this is the only fault that one can find with such descriptive industry—where is it going to stop? Ought we to listen forever to verbal pictures of what we have already in concrete form in our own breasts?15 They never take us off the superficial plane. We knew the facts already—less spread out and separated, to be sure—but we knew them still. We always felt our own activity, for example, as ‘the expansion of an idea with which our Self is identified, against an obstacle;’16 and the following out of such a definition through a multitude of cases elaborates the obvious so as to be little more than an exercise in synonymic speech. All the descriptions have to trace familiar outlines, and to use familiar terms. The activity is, for example, attributed either to a physical or to a mental agent, and is either aimless or directed. If directed it shows tendency. The tendency may or may not be resisted. If not, we call the activity immanent, as when a body moves in empty space by its momentum, or our thoughts wander at their own sweet will. If resistance is met, its agent complicates the situation. If now, in spite of resistance, the original tendency continues, effort makes its appearance, and along with effort, strain or squeeze. Will, in the narrower sense of the word, then comes upon the scene, whenever, along with the tendency, the strain and squeeze are sustained. But the resistance may be great enough to check the tendency, or even to reverse its path. In that case, we (if ‘we’ were the original agents or subjects of the tendency) are overpowered. The phenomenon turns into one of tension simply, or of necessity succumbed to, according as the opposing power is only equal, or is superior to ourselves.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 64
5/2/22 10:39 AM
The Experience of Activity 65
Whosoever describes an experience in such terms as these describes an experience of activity. If the word has any meaning, it must denote what there is found. There is complete activity in its original and first intention. What it is ‘known-as’ is what there appears. The experiencer of such a situation possesses all that the idea contains. He feels the tendency, the obstacle, the will, the strain, the triumph, or the passive giving up, just as he feels the time, the space, the swiftness or intensity, the movement, the weight and color, the pain and pleasure, the complexity, or whatever remaining characters the situation may involve. He goes through all that ever can be imagined where activity is supposed. If we suppose activities to go on outside of our experience, it is in forms like these that we must suppose them, or else give them some other name; for the word ‘activity’ has no imaginable content whatever save these experiences of process, obstruction, striving, strain, or release, ultimate qualia17 as they are of the life given us to be known. Were this the end of the matter, one might think that whenever we had successfully lived through an activity-situation we should have to be permitted, without provoking contradiction, to say that we had been really active, that we had met real resistance and had really prevailed. Lotze somewhere says that to be an entity all that is necessary is to gelten18 as an entity, to operate, or be felt, experienced, recognized, or in any way realized, as such.19 In our activity-experiences the activity assuredly fulfills Lotze’s demand. It makes itself gelten. It is witnessed at its work. No matter what activities there may really be in this extraordinary universe of ours, it is impossible for us to conceive of any one of them being either lived through or authentically known otherwise than in this dramatic shape of something sustaining a felt purpose against felt obstacles and overcoming or being overcome. What ‘sustaining’ means here is clear to anyone who has lived through the experience, but to no one else; just as ‘loud,’ ‘red,’ ‘sweet,’ mean something only to beings with ears, eyes, and tongues. The percipi in these originals of experience is the esse;20 the curtain is the picture. If there is anything hiding in the background, it ought not to be called activity, but should get itself another name. This seems so obviously true that one might well experience astonishment at finding so many of the ablest writers on the subject flatly denying that the activity we live through in these situations is real. Merely to feel active is not to be active, in their sight. The agents that appear in the experience are not real agents, the resistances do not really resist, the effects that appear are not really effects at all.21 It is evident from this that mere descriptive analysis of any one of our activity-experiences is not the whole story, that there is something still to tell about them that has led such able writers to conceive of a Simon-pure activity, of an activity an sich, that does, and doesn’t merely
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 65
5/2/22 10:39 AM
66
Essays in Radical Empiricism
appear to us to do, and compared with whose real doing all this phenomenal activity is but a specious sham. The metaphysical question opens here; and I think that the state of mind of one possessed by it is often something like this: “It is all very well,” we may imagine him saying, “to talk about certain experience-series taking on the form of feelings of activity, just as they might take on musical or geometric forms. Suppose that they do so; suppose we feel a will to stand a strain. Does our feeling do more than record the fact that the strain is sustained? The real activity, meanwhile, is the doing of the fact; and what is the doing made of before the record is made. What in the will enables it to act thus? And these strains of experience themselves, in which activities appear, what makes them go at all? Does the activity in one bit of experience bring the next bit into being? As an empiricist you cannot say so, for you have just declared activity to be only a kind of synthetic object, or conjunctive relation experienced between bits of experience already made. But what made them at all? What propels experience überhaupt22 into being? There is the activity that operates; the activity felt is only its superficial sign.” To the metaphysical question, popped upon us in this way, I must pay serious attention ere I end my remarks; but, before doing so, let me show that without leaving the immediate reticulations of experience, or asking what makes activity itself act, we still find the distinction between less real and more real activities forced upon us, and are driven to much soul-searching on the purely phenomenal plane. We must not forget, namely, in talking of the ultimate character of our activity-experiences, that each of them is but a portion of a wider world, one link in the vast chain of processes of experience out of which history is made. Each partial process, to him who lives through it, defines itself by its origin and its goal; but to an observer with a wider mind-span who should live outside of it, that goal would appear but as a provisional halting-place, and the subjectively felt activity would be seen to continue into objective activities that led far beyond. We thus acquire a habit, in discussing activityexperiences, of defining them by their relation to something more. If an experience be one of narrow span, it will be mistaken as to what activity it is and whose. You think that you are acting while you are only obeying someone’s push. You think you are doing this, but you are doing something of which you do not dream. For instance, you think you are but drinking this glass; but you are really creating the liver-cirrhosis that will end your days. You think you are just driving this bargain, but, as Stevenson23 says somewhere, you are laying down a link in the policy of mankind. Generally speaking, the onlooker, with his wider field of vision, regards the ultimate outcome of an activity as what it is more really doing; and the most
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 66
5/2/22 10:39 AM
The Experience of Activity 67
previous agent ascertainable, being the first source of action, he regards as the most real agent in the field. The others but transmit that agent’s impulse; on him we put responsibility; we name him when one asks us ‘Who’s to blame?’ But the most previous agents ascertainable, instead of being of longer span, are often of much shorter span than the activity in view. Brain-cells are our best example. My brain-cells are believed to excite each other from next to next (by contiguous transmission of katabolic alteration, let us say) and to have been doing so long before this present stretch of lecturing-activity on my part began. If any one cell-group stops its activity, the lecturing will cease or show disorder of form. Cessante causa, cessat et effectus24—does not this look as if the short-span brain activities were the more real activities, and the lecturing activities on my part only their effects? Moreover, as Hume so clearly pointed out,25 in my mental activity-situation the words physically to be uttered are represented as the activity’s immediate goal. These words, however, cannot be uttered without intermediate physical processes in the bulb and vagi nerves,26 which processes nevertheless fail to figure in the mental activity-series at all. That series, therefore, since it leaves out vitally real steps of action, cannot represent the real activities. It is something purely subjective; the facts of activity are elsewhere. They are something far more interstitial,27 so to speak, than what my feelings record. The real facts of activity that have in point of fact been systematically pleaded for by philosophers have, so far as my information goes, been of three principal types. The first type takes a consciousness of wider time span than ours to be the vehicle of the more real activity. Its will is the agent, and its purpose is the action done. The second type assumes that ‘ideas’ struggling with one another are the agents, and that the prevalence of one set of them is the action. The third type believes that nerve-cells are the agents, and that resultant motor discharges are the acts achieved. Now if we must de-realize our immediately felt activity-situations for the benefit of either of these types of substitute, we ought to know what the substitution practically involves. What practical difference ought it to make if, instead of saying naïvely that ‘I’ am active now in delivering this address, I say that a wider thinker is active, or that certain ideas are active, or that certain nerve-cells are active, in producing the result? This would be the pragmatic meaning of the three hypotheses. Let us take them in succession in seeking a reply. If we assume a wider thinker, it is evident that his purposes envelope mine. I am really lecturing for him; and although I cannot surely know to what end, yet if I take him religiously, I can trust it to be a good end, and willingly
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 67
5/2/22 10:39 AM
68
Essays in Radical Empiricism
connive. I can be happy in thinking that my activity transmits his impulse, and that his ends prolong my own. So long as I take him religiously, in short, he does not de-realize my activities. He tends rather to corroborate the reality of them, so long as I believe both them and him to be good. When now we turn to ideas, the case is different, inasmuch as ideas are supposed by the association psychology to influence each other only from next to next. The ‘span’ of an idea or pair of ideas is assumed to be much smaller instead of being larger than that of my total conscious field. The same results may get worked out in both cases, for this address is being given anyhow. But the ideas supposed to ‘really’ work it out had no prevision of the whole of it; and if I was lecturing for an absolute thinker in the former case, so, by similar reasoning, are my ideas now lecturing for me, that is, accomplishing unwittingly a result which I approve and adopt. But, when this passing lecture is over, there is nothing in the bare notion that ideas have been its agents that would seem to guarantee that my present purposes in lecturing will be prolonged. I may have ulterior developments in view; but there is no certainty that my ideas as such will wish to, or be able to, work them out. The like is true if nerve-cells be the agents. The activity of a nerve-cell must be conceived of as a tendency of exceedingly short reach, an ‘impulse’ barely spanning the way to the next cell—for surely that amount of actual ‘process’ must be ‘experienced’ by the cells if what happens between them is to deserve the name of activity at all. But here again the gross resultant, as I perceive it, is indifferent to the agents, and neither wished or willed or foreseen. Their being agents now congruous with my will gives me no guarantee that like results will recur again from their activity. In point of fact, all sorts of other results do occur. My mistakes, impotencies, perversions, mental obstructions, and frustrations generally, are also results of the activity of cells. Although these are letting me lecture now, on other occasions they make me do things that I would willingly not do. The question Whose is the real activity? is thus tantamount to the question What will be the actual results? Its interest is dramatic; how will things work out? If the agents are of one sort, one way; if of another sort, they may work out very differently. The pragmatic meaning of the various alternatives, in short, is great. It makes no merely verbal difference which opinion we take up. You see it is the old dispute come back! Materialism and teleology; elementary short-span actions summing themselves ‘blindly,’ or far foreseen ideals coming with effort into act. Naïvely we believe, and humanly and dramatically we like to believe, that activities both of wider and of narrower span are at work in life together, that both are real, and that the long-span tendencies yoke the others in their service, encouraging them in the right direction, and damping them when they
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 68
5/2/22 10:39 AM
The Experience of Activity 69
tend in other ways. But how to represent clearly the modus operandi28 of such steering of small tendencies by large ones is a problem which metaphysical thinkers will have to ruminate upon for many years to come. Even if such control should eventually grow clearly picturable, the question how far it is successfully exerted in this actual world can be answered only by investigating the details of fact. No philosophic knowledge of the general nature and constitution of tendencies, or of the relation of larger to smaller ones, can help us to predict which of all the various competing tendencies that interest us in this universe are likeliest to prevail. We know as an empirical fact that far-seeing tendencies often carry out their purpose, but we know also that they are often defeated by the failure of some contemptibly small process on which success depends. A little thrombus in a statesman’s meningeal artery29 will throw an empire out of gear. I can therefore not even hint at any solution of the pragmatic issue. I have only wished to show you that that issue is what gives the real interest to all inquiries into what kinds of activity may be real. Are the forces that really act in the world more foreseeing or more blind? As between ‘our’ activities as ‘we’ experience them, and those of our ideas, or of our brain-cells, the issue is well-defined. I said a while back30 that I should return to the ‘metaphysical’ question before ending; so, with a few words about that, I will now close my remarks. In whatever form we hear this question propounded, I think that it always arises from two things, a belief that causality must be exerted in activity, and a wonder as to how causality is made. If we take an activity-situation at its face value, it seems as if we are caught in flagrante delicto31 the very power that makes facts come and be. I now am eagerly striving, for example, to get this truth which I seem half to perceive, into words which shall make it show more clearly. If the words come, it will seem as if the striving itself had drawn or pulled them into actuality out from the state of merely possible being in which they were. How is this feat performed? How does the pulling pull? How do I get my hold on words not yet existent, and when they come by what means have I made them come? Really it is the problem of creation; for in the end the question is: How do I make them be? Real activities are those that really make things be, without which the things are not, and with which they are there. Activity, so far as we merely feel it, on the other hand, is only an impression of ours, it may be maintained; and an impression is, for all this way of thinking, only a shadow of another fact. Arrived at this point, I can do little more than indicate the principles on which, as it seems to me, a radically empirical philosophy is obliged to rely in handling such a dispute. If there be real creative activities in being, radical empiricism must say, somewhere they must be immediately lived. Somewhere the that of efficacious
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 69
5/2/22 10:39 AM
70
Essays in Radical Empiricism
causing and the what of it must be experienced in one, just as the what and the that of ‘cold’ are experienced in one whenever a man has the sensation of cold here and now. It boots not to say that our sensations are fallible. They are indeed; but to see the thermometer contradict us when we say ‘it is cold’ does not abolish cold as a specific nature from the universe. Cold is in the arctic circle if not here. Even so, to feel that our train is moving when the train beside our window moves, to see the moon through a telescope come twice as near, or to see two pictures as one solid when we look through a stereoscope at them, leaves motion, nearness, and solidity still in being—if not here, yet each in its proper seat elsewhere. And wherever the seat of real causality is, as ultimately known ‘for true’ (in nerve-processes, if you will, that cause our feelings of activity as well as the movements which these seem to prompt), a philosophy of pure experience can consider the real causation as no other nature of thing than that which even in our most erroneous experiences appears to be at work. Exactly what appears there is what we mean by working, though we may later come to learn that working was not exactly there. Sustaining, persevering, striving, paying with effort as we go, hanging on, and finally achieving our intention—this is action, this is effectuation in the only shape in which, by a pure experience-philosophy, the whereabouts of it anywhere can be discussed. Here is creation in its first intention, here is causality at work.32 To treat this offhand as the bare illusory surface of a world whose real causality is an unimaginable ontological principle hidden in the cubic deeps, is, for the more empirical way of thinking, only animism in another shape. You explain your given fact by your ‘principle,’ but the principle itself, when you look clearly at it, turns out to be nothing but a previous little spiritual copy of the fact. Away from that one and only kind of fact your mind, considering causality, can never get.33 I conclude, then, that real effectual causation as an ultimate nature, as a ‘category,’ if you like, of reality, is just what we feel it to be, just that kind of conjunction which our own activity-series reveal. We have the whole butt and being of it in our hands; and the healthy thing for philosophy is to leave off grubbing underground for what effects effectuation, or what makes action act, and to try to solve the concrete questions of where effectuation in this world is located, of which things are the true causal agents there, and of what the more remote effects consist. From this point of view the greater sublimity traditionally attributed to the metaphysical inquiry, the grubbing inquiry, entirely disappears. If we could know what causation really and transcendentally is in itself, the only use of the knowledge would be to help us to recognize an actual cause when we had one, and so to track the future course of operations more intelligently out. The mere abstract inquiry into causation’s hidden nature is not more
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 70
5/2/22 10:39 AM
The Experience of Activity 71
sublime than any other inquiry equally abstract. Causation inhabits no more sublime level than anything else. It lives, apparently, in the dirt of the world as well as in the absolute, or in man’s unconquerable mind. The worth and interest of the world consists not in its elements, be these elements things, or be they the conjunctions of things; it exists rather in the dramatic outcome in the whole process, and in the meaning of the succession stages which the elements work out. My colleague and master, Josiah Royce, in a page of his review of Stout’s Analytic Psychology34 has some fine words on this point with which I cordially agree. I cannot agree with his separating the notion of efficacy from that of activity altogether (this I understand to be one contention of his) for activities are efficacious whenever they are real activities at all. But the inner nature both of efficacy and of activity are superficial problems, I understand Royce to say; and the only point for us in solving them would be their possible use in helping us to solve the far deeper problem of the course and meaning of the world of life. Life, says our colleague, is full of significance, of meaning, of success and of defeat, of hoping and of striving, of longing, of desire, and of inner value. It is a total presence that embodies worth. To live our own lives better in this presence is the true reason why we wish to know the elements of things; so even we psychologists must end on this pragmatic note. The urgent problems of activity are thus more concrete. They are all problems of the true relation of longer-span to shorter-span activities. When, for example, a number of ‘ideas’ (to use the name traditional in psychology) grow confluent in a larger field of consciousness, do the smaller activities still co-exist with the wider activities then experienced by the conscious subject? And, if so, do the wide activities accompany the narrow ones inertly, or do they exert control? Or do they perhaps utterly supplant and replace them and short-circuit their effects? Again, when a mental activity-process and a braincell series of activities both terminate in the same muscular movement, does the mental process steer the neural processes or not? Or, on the other hand, does it independently short-circuit their effects? Such are the questions that we must begin with. But so far am I from suggesting any definitive answer to such questions, that I hardly yet can put them clearly. They lead, however, into that region of panpsychic and ontologic speculation of which Professors Bergson and Strong have lately enlarged the literature in so able and interesting a way.35 The results of these authors seem in many respects dissimilar, and I understand them as yet but imperfectly; but I cannot help suspecting that the direction of their work is very promising, and that they have the hunter’s instinct for the fruitful trails.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 71
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 72
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Chapter Seven
The Essence of Humanism
Humanism is a ferment that has ‘come to stay.’1 It is not a single hypothesis or theorem, and it dwells on no new facts. It is rather a slow shifting in the philosophic perspective, making things appear as from a new center of interest or point of sight. Some writers are strongly conscious of the shifting, others half unconscious, even though their own vision may have undergone much change. The result is no small confusion in debate, the half-conscious humanists often taking part against the radical ones, as if they wished to count upon the other side.2 If humanism really be the name for such a shifting of perspective, it is obvious that the whole scene of the philosophic stage will change in some degree if humanism prevails. The emphasis of things, their foreground and background distribution, their sizes and values, will not keep just the same.3 If such pervasive consequences be involved in humanism, it is clear that no pains which philosophers may take, first in defining it, and then in furthering, checking, or steering its progress, will be thrown away. It suffers badly at present from incomplete definition. Its most systematic advocates, Schiller4 and Dewey, have published fragmentary programs only; and its bearing on many vital philosophic problems has not been traced except by adversaries who, scenting heresies in advance, have showered blows on doctrines—subjectivism and skepticism, for example—that no good humanist finds it necessary to entertain. By their still greater reticences, the anti-humanists have, in turn, perplexed the humanists. Much of the controversy has involved the word ‘truth.’ It is always good in debate to know your adversary’s point of view authentically. But the critics of humanism never define exactly what the word ‘truth’ signifies when they use it themselves. The humanists have to guess at their view; and the result has doubtless been much beating of the air. Add to all this, great individual differences in both 73
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 73
5/2/22 10:39 AM
74
Essays in Radical Empiricism
camps, and it becomes clear that nothing is so urgently needed, at the stage which things have reached at present, as a sharper definition by each side of its central point of view. Whoever will contribute any touch of sharpness will help us to make sure of what’s what and who is who. Anyone can contribute such a definition, and, without it, no one knows exactly where he stands. If I offer my own provisional definition of humanism5 now and here, others may improve it, some adversary may be led to define his own creed more sharply by the contrast, and a certain quickening of the crystallization of general opinion may result. 1 The essential service of humanism, as I conceive the situation, is to have seen that though one part of our experience may lean upon another part to make it what it is in any one of several aspects in which it may be considered, experience as a whole is self-containing and leans on nothing. Since this formula also expresses the main contention of transcendental idealism, it needs abundant explication to make it unambiguous. It seems, at first sight, to confine itself to denying theism and pantheism. But, in fact, it need not deny either; everything would depend on the exegesis; and if the formula ever became canonical, it would certainly develop both right-wing and left-wing interpreters. I myself read humanism theistically and pluralistically. If there be a God, he is no absolute all-experiencer, but simply the experiencer of widest actual conscious span. Read thus, humanism is for me a religion susceptible of reasoned defense, though I am well aware how many minds there are to whom it can appeal religiously only when it has been monistically translated. Ethically the pluralistic form of it takes for me a stronger hold on reality than any other philosophy I know of—it being essentially a social philosophy, a philosophy of ‘co-,’ in which conjunctions do the work. But my primary reason for advocating it is its matchless intellectual economy. It gets rid, not only of the standing ‘problems’ that monism engenders (‘problem of evil,’ ‘problem of freedom,’ and the like), but of other metaphysical mysteries and paradoxes as well. It gets rid, for example, of the whole agnostic controversy, by refusing to entertain the hypothesis of trans-empirical reality at all. It gets rid of any need for an absolute of the Bradleyan type (avowedly sterile for intellectual purposes) by insisting that the conjunctive relations found within experience are faultlessly real. It gets rid of the need of an absolute of the Roycean type (similarly sterile) by its pragmatic treatment of the problem of knowledge [a treatment of which I have already given a version in two very inadequate
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 74
5/2/22 10:39 AM
The Essence of Humanism 75
articles].6 As the views of knowledge, reality and truth imputed to humanism have been those so far most fiercely attacked, it is in regard to these ideas that a sharpening of focus seems most urgently required. I proceed therefore to bring the views which I impute to humanism in these respects into focus as briefly as I can. 2 If the central humanistic thesis, printed above in italics, be accepted, it will follow that, if there be any such thing at all as knowing, the knower and the object known must both be portions of experience. One part of experience must, therefore, either 1. Know another part of experience—in other words, parts must, as Professor Woodbridge says,7 represent one another instead of representing realities outside of ‘consciousness’—this case is that of conceptual knowledge; or else 2. They must simply exist as so many ultimate thats or facts of being, in the first instance; and then, as a secondary complication, and without doubling up its entitative single-ness, any one and the same that must figure alternately as a thing known and as a knowledge of the thing, by reason of two divergent kinds of context into which, in the general course of experience, it gets woven.8 This second case is that of sense-perception. There is a stage of thought that goes beyond common sense, and of it I shall say more presently; but the common-sense stage is a perfectly definite halting-place of thought, primarily for purposes of action; and, so long as we remain on the common-sense stage of thought, object and subject fuse in the fact of ‘presentation’ or sense-perception—the pen and hand which I now see writing, for example, are the physical realities which those words designate. In this case there is no self-transcendency implied in the knowing. Humanism, here, is only a more comminuted Identitätsphilosophie.9 In case (1), on the contrary, the representative experience does transcend itself in knowing the other experience that is its object. No one can talk of the knowledge of the one by the other without seeing them as numerically distinct entities, of which the one lies beyond the other and away from it, along some direction and with some interval, that can be definitely named. But, if the talker be a humanist, he must also see this distance-interval concretely and pragmatically and confess it to consist of other intervening experiences—of
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 75
5/2/22 10:39 AM
76
Essays in Radical Empiricism
possible ones, at all events, if not of actual. To call my present idea of my dog, for example, cognitive of the real dog means that, as the actual tissue of experience is constituted, the idea is capable of leading into a chain of other experiences on my part that go from next to next and terminate at last in vivid sense-perceptions of a jumping, barking, hairy body. Those are the real dog, the dog’s full presence, for my common sense. If the supposed talker is a profound philosopher, although they may not be the real dog for him, they mean the real dog, are practical substitutes for the real dog, as the representation was a practical substitute for them, that real dog being a lot of atoms, say, or of mind-stuff, that lie where the sense-perceptions lie in his experience as well as in my own. 3 The philosopher here stands for the stage of thought that goes beyond the stage of common sense; and the difference is simply that he ‘interpolates’ and ‘extrapolates,’ where common sense does not. For common sense, two men see the same identical real dog. Philosophy, noting actual differences in their perceptions, points out the duality of these latter, and interpolates something between them as a more real terminus—first, organs, viscera, etc.; next, cells; then, ultimate atoms; lastly, mind-stuff perhaps. The original sense-termini of the two men, instead of coalescing with each other and with the real dogobject, as at first supposed, are thus held by philosophers to be separated by invisible realities with which, at most, they are conterminous. Abolish, now, one of the percipients, and the interpolation changes into ‘extrapolation.’ The sense-terminus of the remaining percipient is regarded by the philosopher as not quite reaching reality. He has only carried the procession of experiences, the philosopher thinks, to a definite, because practical, halting-place somewhere on the way towards an absolute truth that lies beyond. The humanist sees all the time, however, that there is no absolute transcendency even about the more absolute realities thus conjectured or believed in. The viscera and cells are only possible percepts following upon that of the outer body. The atoms again, though we may never attain to human means of perceiving them, are still defined perceptually. The mind-stuff itself is conceived as a kind of experience; and it is possible to frame the hypothesis (such hypotheses can by no logic be excluded from philosophy) of two knowers of a piece of mind-stuff and the mind-stuff itself becoming ‘confluent’ at the moment at which our imperfect knowing might pass into knowing of a completed type. Even so do you and I habitually represent our two perceptions
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 76
5/2/22 10:39 AM
The Essence of Humanism 77
and the real dog as confluent, though only provisionally, and for the commonsense stage of thought. If my pen be inwardly made of mind-stuff, there is no confluence now between that mind-stuff and my visual perception of the pen. But conceivably there might come to be such confluence; for, in the case of my hand, the visual sensations and the inward feelings of the hand, its mindstuff, so to speak, are even now as confluent as any two things can be. There is, thus, no breach in humanistic epistemology. Whether knowledge be taken as ideally perfected, or only as true enough to pass muster for practice, it is hung on one continuous scheme. Reality, howsoever remote, is always defined as a terminus within the general possibilities of experience; and what knows it is defined as an experience that ‘represents’ it, in the sense of being substitutable for it in our thinking because it leads to the same associates, or in the sense of ‘pointing to it’ through a chain of other experiences that either intervene or may intervene. Absolute reality here bears the same relation to sensation as sensation bears to conception or imagination. Both are provisional or final termini, sensation being only the terminus at which the practical man habitually stops, while the philosopher projects a ‘beyond’ in the shape of more absolute reality. These termini, for the practical and the philosophical stages of thought respectively, are self-supporting. They are not ‘true’ of anything else, they simply are, are real. They ‘lean on nothing,’ as my italicized formula said. Rather does the whole fabric of experience lean on them, just as the whole fabric of the solar system, including many relative positions, leans, for its absolute position in space, on any one of its constituent stars. Here, again, one gets a new Identitätsphilosophie in pluralistic form.10 4 If I have succeeded in making this at all clear (though I fear that brevity and abstractness between them may have made me fail), the reader will see that the ‘truth’ of our mental operations must always be an intra-experiential affair. A conception is reckoned true by common sense when it can be made to lead to a sensation. The sensation, which for common sense is not so much ‘true’ as ‘real,’ is held to be provisionally true by the philosopher just in so far as it covers (abuts at, or occupies the place of) a still more absolutely real experience, in the possibility of which to some remoter experient the philosopher finds reason to believe. Meanwhile what actually does count for true to any individual trower,11 whether he be philosopher or common man, is always a result of his apperceptions.12 If a novel experience, conceptual or sensible, contradict too
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 77
5/2/22 10:39 AM
78
Essays in Radical Empiricism
emphatically our pre-existent system of beliefs, in ninety-nine cases out of a hundred it is treated as false. Only when the older and the newer experiences are congruous enough to mutually apperceive and modify each other, does what we treat as an advance in truth result. [Having written of this point in an article in reply to Mr. Joseph’s13 criticism of my humanism, I will say no more about truth here, but refer the reader to that review.14] In no case, however, need truth consist in a relation between our experiences and something archetypal or trans-experiential. Should we ever reach absolutely terminal experiences, experiences in which we all agreed, which were superseded by no revised continuations, these would not be true, they would be real, they would simply be, and be indeed the angles, corners, and linchpins of all reality, on which the truth of everything else would be stayed. Only such other things as led to these by satisfactory conjunctions would be ‘true.’ Satisfactory connection of some sort with such termini is all that the word ‘truth’ means. On the common-sense stage of thought sense-presentations serve as such termini. Our ideas and concepts and scientific theories pass for true only so far as they harmoniously lead back to the world of sense. I hope that many humanists will endorse this attempt of mine to trace the more essential features of that way of viewing things. I feel almost certain that Messrs. Dewey and Schiller will do so. If the attackers will also take some slight account of it, it may be that discussion will be a little less wide of the mark than it has hitherto been.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 78
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Chapter Eight
La Notion de Conscience
Je voudrais vous communiquer quelques doutes qui me sont venus au sujet de la notion de Conscience qui règne dans tous nos traités de psychologie.1 On définit habituellement la Psychologie comme la Science des faits de Conscience, ou des phénomènes, ou encore des états de la Conscience. Qu’on admette qu’elle se rattache à des moi personnels, ou bien qu’on la croie impersonnelle à la façon du “moi transcendental” de Kant, de la Bewusstheit ou du Bewusstsein überhaupt de nos contemporains en Allemagne, cette conscience est toujours regardée comme possédant une essence propre, absolument distincte de l’essence des choses matérielles, qu’elle a le don mystérieux de représenter et de connaître. Les faits matériels, pris dans leur matérialité, ne sont pas éprouvés, ne sont pas objets d’expérience, ne se rapportent pas. Pour qu’ils prennent la forme du système dans lequel nous nous sentons vivre, il faut qu’ils apparaissent, et ce fait d’apparaître, surajouté à leur existence brute, s’appelle la conscience que nous en avons, ou peut-être, selon l’hypothèse panpsychiste, qu’ils ont d’eux-mêmes. Voilà ce dualisme invétéré qu’il semble impossible de chasser de notre vue du monde. Ce monde peut bien exister en soi, mais nous n’en savons rien, car pour nous il est exclusivement un objet d’expérience; et la condition indispensable à cet effet, c’est qu’il soit rapporté à des témoins, qu’il soit connu par un sujet ou par des sujets spirituels. Objet et sujet, voilà les deux jambes sans lesquelles il semble que la philosophie ne saurait faire un pas en avant. Toutes les écoles sont d’accord là-dessus, scolastique, cartésianisme, kantisme, néo-kantisme, tous admettent le dualisme fondamental. Le positivisme ou agnosticisme de nos jours, qui se pique de relever des sciences naturelles, se donne volontiers, il est vrai, le nom de monisme. Mais ce n’est qu’un monisme verbal. Il pose une réalité inconnue, mais nous dit que cette réalité se présente toujours sous deux “aspects,” un côté conscience et un 79
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 79
5/2/22 10:39 AM
80
Essays in Radical Empiricism
côté matière, et ces deux côtés demeurent aussi irréductibles que les attributs fondamentaux, étendue et pensée, du Dieu de Spinoza. Au fond, le monisme contemporain est du spinozisme pur. Or, comment se représente-t-on cette conscience dont nous sommes tous si portés à admettre l’existence? Impossible de la définir, nous dit-on, mais nous en avons tous une intuition immédiate: tout d’abord la conscience a conscience d’elle-même. Demandez à la première personne que vous rencontrerez, homme ou femme, psychologue ou ignorant, et elle vous répondra qu’elle se sent penser, jouir, souffrir, vouloir, tout comme elle se sent respirer. Elle perçoit directement sa vie spirituelle comme une espèce de courant intérieur, actif, léger, fluide, délicat, diaphane pour ainsi dire, et absolument opposé à quoi que ce soit de matériel. Bref, la vie subjective ne paraît pas seulement être une condition logiquement indispensable pour qu’il y ait un monde objectif qui apparaisse, c’est encore un élément de l’expérience même que nous éprouvons directement, au même titre que nous éprouvons notre propre corps. Idées et Choses, comment donc ne pas reconnaître leur dualisme? Sentiments et Objets, comment douter de leur hétérogénéité absolue? La psychologie soi-disant scientifique admet cette hétérogénéité comme l’ancienne psychologie spiritualiste l’admettait. Comment ne pas l’admettre? Chaque science découpe arbitrairement dans la trame des faits un champ où elle se parque, et dont elle décrit et étudie le contenu. La psychologie prend justement pour son domaine le champ des faits de conscience. Elle les postule sans les critiquer, elle les oppose aux faits matériels; et sans critiquer non plus la notion de ces derniers, elle les rattache à la conscience par le lien mystérieux de la connaissance, de, l’aperception qui, pour elle, est un troisième genre de fait fondamental et ultime. En suivant cette voie, la psychologie contemporaine a fêté de grands triomphes. Elle a pu faire une esquisse de l’évolution de la vie consciente, en concevant cette dernière comme s’adaptant de plus en plus complètement au milieu physique environnant. Elle a pu établir un parallélisme dans le dualisme, celui des faits psychiques et des événements cérébraux. Elle a expliqué les illusions, les hallucinations, et jusqu’à un certain point, les maladies mentales. Ce sont de beaux progrès; mais il reste encore bien des problèmes. La philosophie générale surtout, qui a pour devoir de scruter tous les postulats, trouve des paradoxes et des empêchements là où la science passe outre; et il n’y a que les amateurs de science populaire qui ne sont jamais perplexes. Plus on va au fond des choses, plus on trouve d’énigmes; et j’avoue pour ma part que depuis que je m’occupe sérieusement de psychologie, ce vieux dualisme de matière et de pensée, cette hétérogénéité posée comme absolue des deux essences, m’a toujours présenté
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 80
5/2/22 10:39 AM
La Notion de Conscience 81
des difficultés. C’est de quelques-unes de ces difficultés que je voudrais maintenant vous entretenir. D’abord il y en a une, laquelle, j’en suis convaincu, vous aura frappés tous. Prenons la perception extérieure, la sensation directe que nous donnent par exemple les murs de cette salle. Peut-on dire ici que le psychique et le physique sont absolument hétérogènes? Au contraire, ils sont si peu hétérogènes que si nous nous plaçons au point de vue du sens commun; si nous faisons abstraction de toutes les inventions explicatives, des molécules et des ondulations éthérées, par exemple, qui au fond sont des entités métaphysiques; si, en un mot, nous prenons la réalité naïvement et telle qu’elle nous est donnée tout d’abord, cette réalité sensible d’où dépendent nos intérêts vitaux, et sur laquelle se portent toutes nos actions; eh bien, cette réalité sensible et la sensation que nous en avons sont, au moment où la sensation se produit, absolument identiques l’une à l’autre. La réalité est l’aperception même. Les mots “murs de cette salle” ne signifient que cette blancheur fraîche et sonore qui nous entoure, coupée par ces fenêtres, bornée par ces lignes et ces angles. Le physique ici n’a pas d’autre contenu que le psychique. Le sujet et l’objet se confondent. C’est Berkeley qui le premier a mis cette vérité en honneur. Esse est percipi.2 Nos sensations ne sont pas de petits duplicates intérieurs des choses, elles sont les choses mêmes en tant que les choses nous sont présentes. Et quoi que l’on veuille penser de la vie absente, cachée, et pour ainsi dire privée, des choses, et quelles que soient les constructions hypothétiques qu’on en fasse, il reste vrai que la vie publique des choses, cette actualité présente par laquelle elles nous confrontent, d’où dérivent toutes nos constructions théoriques, et à laquelle elles doivent toutes revenir et se rattacher sous peine de flotter dans l’air et dans l’irréel; cette actualité, dis-je, est homogène, et non pas seulement homogène, mais numériquement une, avec une certaine partie de notre vie intérieure. Voilà pour la perception extérieure. Quand on s’adresse à l’imagination, à la mémoire ou aux facultés de représentation abstraite, bien que les faits soient ici beaucoup plus compliqués, je crois que la même homogénéité essentielle se dégage. Pour simplifier le problème, excluons d’abord toute réalité sensible. Prenons la pensée pure, telle qu’elle s’effectue dans le rêve ou la rêverie, ou dans la mémoire du passé. Ici encore, l’étoffe de l’expérience ne fait-elle pas double emploi, le physique et le psychique ne se confondent-ils pas? Si je rêve d’une montagne d’or, elle n’existe sans doute pas en dehors du rêve, mais dans le rêve elle est de nature ou d’essence parfaitement physique, c’est comme physique qu’elle m’apparaît. Si en ce moment je me permets de me souvenir de ma maison en Amérique, et des détails de mon embarquement récent pour l’Italie, le phénomène pur, le fait qui se produit, qu’est-il? C’est,
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 81
5/2/22 10:39 AM
82
Essays in Radical Empiricism
dit-on, ma pensée, avec son contenu. Mais encore ce contenu, qu’est-il? Il porte la forme d’une partie du monde réel, partie distante, il est vrai, de six mille kilomètres d’espace et de six semaines de temps, mais reliée à la salle où nous sommes par une foule de choses, objets et événements, homogènes d’une part avec la salle et d’autre part avec l’objet de mes souvenirs. Ce contenu ne se donne pas comme étant d’abord un tout petit fait intérieur que je projetterais ensuite au loin, il se présente d’emblée comme le fait éloigné même. Et l’acte de penser ce contenu, la conscience que j’en ai, que sont-ils? Sont-ce au fond autre chose que des manières rétrospectives de nommer le contenu lui-même, lorsqu’on l’aura séparé de tous ces intermédiaires physiques, et relié à un nouveau groupe d’associés qui le font rentrer dans ma vie mentale, les émotions par exemple qu’il a éveillées en moi, l’attention que j’y porte, mes idées de tout à l’heure qui l’ont suscité comme souvenir? Ce n’est qu’en se rapportant à ces derniers associés que le phénomène arrive à être classé comme pensée; tant qu’il ne se rapporte qu’aux premiers il demeure phénomène objectif. Il est vrai que nous opposons habituellement nos images intérieures aux objets, et que nous les considérons comme de petites copies, comme des calques ou doubles, affaiblis, de ces derniers. C’est qu’un objet présent a une vivacité et une netteté supérieures à celles de l’image. Il lui fait ainsi contraste; et pour me servir de l’excellent mot de Taine, il lui sert de réducteur. Quand les deux sont présents ensemble, l’objet prend le premier plan et l’image “recule,” devient une chose “absente.” Mais cet objet présent, qu’est-il en lui-même? De quelle étoffe est-il fait? De la même étoffe que l’image. Il est fait de sensations; il est chose perçue. Son esse est percipi, et lui et l’image sont génériquement homogènes. Si je pense en ce moment à mon chapeau que j’ai laissé tout à l’heure au vestiaire, où est le dualisme, le discontinu, entre le chapeau pensé et le chapeau réel? C’est d’un vrai chapeau absent que mon esprit s’occupe. J’en tiens compte pratiquement comme d’une réalité. S’il était présent sur cette table, le chapeau déterminerait un mouvement de ma main: je l’enlèverais. De même ce chapeau conçu, ce chapeau en idée, déterminera tantôt la direction de mes pas. J’irai le prendre. L’idée que j’en ai se continuera jusqu’à la présence sensible du chapeau, et s’y fondra harmonieusement. Je conclus donc que,—bien qu’il y ait un dualisme pratique—puisque les images se distinguent des objets, en tiennent lieu, et nous y mènent, il n’y a pas lieu de leur attribuer une différence de nature essentielle. Pensée et actualité sont faites d’une seule et même étoffe, qui est l’étoffe de l’expérience en général. La psychologie de la perception extérieure nous mène à la même conclusion. Quand j’aperçois l’objet devant moi comme une table de telle forme, à
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 82
5/2/22 10:39 AM
La Notion de Conscience 83
telle distance, on m’explique que ce fait est dû à deux facteurs, à une matière de sensation qui me pénètre par la voie des yeux et qui donne l’élément d’extériorité réelle, et à des idées qui se réveillent, vont à la rencontre de cette réalité, la classent et l’interprètent. Mais qui peut faire la part, dans la table concrètement aperçue, de ce qui est sensation et de ce qui est idée? L’externe et l’interne, l’étendu et l’inétendu, se fusionnent et font un mariage indissoluble. Cela rappelle ces panoramas circulaires, où des objets réels, rochers, herbe, chariots brisés, etc., qui occupent l’avant-plan, sont si ingénieusement reliés à la toile qui fait le fond, et qui représente une bataille ou un vaste paysage, que l’on ne sait plus distinguer ce qui est objet de ce qui est peinture. Les coutures et les joints sont imperceptibles. Cela pourrait-il advenir si l’objet et l’idée étaient absolument dissemblables de nature? Je suis convaincu que des considérations pareilles à celles que je viens d’exprimer auront déjà suscité, chez vous aussi, des doutes au sujet du dualisme prétendu. Et d’autres raisons de douter surgissent encore. Il y a toute une sphère d’adjectifs et d’attributs qui ne sont ni objectifs, ni subjectifs d’une manière exclusive, mais que nous employons tantôt d’une manière et tantôt d’une autre, comme si nous nous complaisions dans leur ambiguïté. Je parle des qualités que nous apprécions, pour ainsi dire, dans les choses, leur côté esthétique, moral, leur valeur pour nous. La beauté, par exemple, où réside-t-elle? Est-elle dans la statue, dans la sonate, ou dans notre esprit? Mon collègue à Harvard, George Santayana, a écrit un livre d’esthétique,3 où il appelle la beauté “le plaisir objectifié;” et en vérité, c’est bien ici qu’on pourrait parler de projection au dehors. On dit indifféremment une chaleur agréable, ou une sensation agréable de chaleur. La rareté, le précieux du diamant nous en paraissent des qualités essentielles. Nous parlons d’un orage affreux, d’un homme haïssable, d’une action indigne, et nous croyons parler objectivement, bien que ces termes n’expriment que des rapports à notre sensibilité émotive propre. Nous disons même un chemin pénible, un ciel triste, un coucher de soleil superbe. Toute cette manière animiste de regarder les choses qui paraît avoir été la façon primitive de penser des hommes, peut très bien s’expliquer (et M. Santayana, dans un autre livre tout récent,4 l’a bien expliquée ainsi) par l’habitude d’attribuer à l’objet tout ce que nous ressentons en sa présence. Le partage du subjectif et de l’objectif est le fait d’une réflexion très avancée, que nous aimons encore ajourner dans beaucoup d’endroits. Quand les besoins pratiques ne nous en tirent pas forcément, il semble que nous aimons à nous bercer dans le vague. Les qualités secondes elles-mêmes, chaleur, son, lumière, n’ont encore aujourd’hui qu’une attribution vague. Pour le sens commun, pour la vie
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 83
5/2/22 10:39 AM
84
Essays in Radical Empiricism
pratique, elles sont absolument objectives, physiques. Pour le physicien, elles sont subjectives. Pour lui, il n’y a que la forme, la masse, le mouvement, qui aient une réalité extérieure. Pour le philosophe idéaliste, au contraire, forme et mouvement sont tout aussi subjectifs que lumière et chaleur, et il n’y a que la chose-en-soi inconnue, le “noumène,” qui jouisse d’une réalité extramentale complète. Nos sensations intimes conservent encore de cette ambiguïté. Il y a des illusions de mouvement qui prouvent que nos premières sensations de mouvement étaient généralisées. C’est le monde entier, avec nous, qui se mouvait. Maintenant nous distinguons notre propre mouvement de celui des objets qui nous entourent, et parmi les objets nous en distinguons qui demeurent en repos. Mais il est des états de vertige où nous retombons encore aujourd’hui dans l’indifférenciation première. Vous connaissez tous sans doute cette théorie qui a voulu faire des émotions des sommes de sensations viscérales et musculaires. Elle a donné lieu à bien des controverses, et aucune opinion n’a encore conquis l’unanimité des suffrages. Vous connaissez aussi les controverses sur la nature de l’activité mentale. Les uns soutiennent qu’elle est une force purement spirituelle que nous sommes en état d’apercevoir immédiatement comme telle. Les autres prétendent que ce que nous nommons activité mentale (effort, attention, par exemple) n’est que le reflet senti de certains effets dont notre organisme est le siège, tensions musculaires au crâne et au gosier, arrêt ou passage de la respiration, afflux de sang, etc. De quelque manière que se résolvent ces controverses, leur existence prouve bien clairement une chose, c’est qu’il est très difficile, ou même absolument impossible de savoir, par la seule inspection intime de certains phénomènes, s’ils sont de nature physique, occupant de l’étendue, etc., ou s’ils sont de nature purement psychique et intérieure. Il nous faut toujours trouver des raisons pour appuyer notre avis; il nous faut chercher la classification la plus probable du phénomène; et en fin de compte il pourrait bien se trouver que toutes nos classifications usuelles eussent eu leurs motifs plutôt dans les besoins de la pratique que dans quelque faculté que nous aurions d’apercevoir deux essences ultimes et diverses qui composeraient ensemble la trame des choses. Le corps de chacun de nous offre un contraste pratique presque violent à tout le reste du milieu ambiant. Tout ce qui arrive au dedans de ce corps nous est plus intime et important que ce qui arrive ailleurs. Il s’identifie avec notre moi, il se classe avec lui. Ame, vie, souffle, qui saurait bien les distinguer exactement? Même nos images et nos souvenirs, qui n’agissent sur le monde physique que par le moyen de notre corps, semblent appartenir à ce dernier. Nous les traitons comme internes, nous les classons avec nos senti-
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 84
5/2/22 10:39 AM
La Notion de Conscience 85
ments affectifs. Il faut bien avouer, en somme, que la question du dualisme de la pensée et de la matière est bien loin d’être finalement résolue. Et voilà terminée la première partie de mon discours. J’ai voulu vous pénétrer, Mesdames et Messieurs, de mes doutes et de la réalité, aussi bien que de l’importance, du problème. Quant à moi, après de longues années d’hésitation, j’ai fini par prendre mon parti carrément. Je crois que la conscience, telle qu’on se la représente communément, soit comme entité, soit comme activité pure, mais en tout cas comme fluide, inétendue, diaphane, vide de tout contenu propre, mais se connaissant directement elle-même, spirituelle enfin, je crois, dis-je, que cette conscience est une pure chimère, et que la somme de réalités concrètes que le mot conscience devrait couvrir, mérite une toute autre description, description, du reste, qu’une philosophie attentive aux faits et sachant faire un peu d’analyse, serait désormais en état de fournir ou plutôt de commencer à fournir. Et ces mots m’amènent à la seconde partie de mon discours. Elle sera beaucoup plus courte que la première, parce que si je la développais sur la même échelle, elle serait beaucoup trop longue. Il faut, par conséquent, que je me restreigne aux seules indications indispensables. Admettons que la conscience, la Bewusstheit, conçue comme essence, entité, activité, moitié irréductible de chaque expérience, soit supprimée, que le dualisme fondamental et pour ainsi dire ontologique soit aboli et que ce que nous supposions exister soit seulement ce qu’on a appelé jusqu’ici le contenu, le Inhalt, de la conscience; comment la philosophie va-t-elle se tirer d’affaire avec l’espèce de monisme vague qui en résultera? Je vais tâcher de vous insinuer quelques suggestions positives là-dessus, bien que je craigne que, faute du développement nécessaire, mes idées ne répandront pas une clarté très grande. Pourvu que j’indique un commencement de sentier, ce sera peut-être assez. Au fond, pourquoi nous accrochons-nous d’une manière si tenace à cette idée d’une conscience surajoutée à l’existence du contenu des choses? Pourquoi la réclamons-nous si fortement, que celui qui la nierait nous semblerait plutôt un mauvais plaisant qu’un penseur? N’est-ce pas pour sauver ce fait indéniable que le contenu de l’expérience n’a pas seulement une existence propre et comme immanente et intrinsèque, mais que chaque partie de ce contenu déteint pour ainsi dire sur ses voisines, rend compte d’elle-même à d’autres, sort en quelque sorte de soi pour être sue et qu’ainsi tout le champ de l’expérience se trouve être transparent de part en part, ou constitué comme un espace qui serait rempli de miroirs? Cette bilatéralité des parties de l’expérience,—à savoir d’une part, qu’elles sont avec des qualités propres; d’autre part, qu’elles sont rapportées à d’autres parties et sues—l’opinion régnante la constate et l’explique par un dualisme
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 85
5/2/22 10:39 AM
86
Essays in Radical Empiricism
fondamental de constitution appartenant à chaque morceau d’expérience en propre. Dans cette feuille de papier il n’y a pas seulement, dit-on, le contenu, blancheur, minceur, etc., mais il y a ce second fait de la conscience de cette blancheur et de cette minceur. Cette fonction d’être “rapporté,” de faire partie de la trame entière d’une expérience plus compréhensive, on l’érige en fait ontologique, et on loge ce fait dans l’intérieur même du papier, en l’accouplant à sa blancheur et à sa minceur. Ce n’est pas un rapport extrinsèque qu’on suppose, c’est une moitié du phénomène même. Je crois qu’en somme on se représente la réalité comme constituée de la façon dont sont faites les “couleurs” qui nous servent à la peinture. Il y a d’abord des matières colorantes qui répondent au contenu, et il y a un véhicule, huile ou colle, qui les tient en suspension et qui répond à la conscience. C’est un dualisme complet, où, en employant certains procédés, on peut séparer chaque élément de l’autre par voie de soustraction. C’est ainsi qu’on nous assure qu’en faisant un grand effort d’abstraction introspective, nous pouvons saisir notre conscience sur le vif, comme une activité spirituelle pure, en négligeant à peu près complètement les matières qu’à un moment donné elle éclaire. Maintenant je vous demande si on ne pourrait pas tout aussi bien renverser absolument cette manière de voir. Supposons, en effet, que la réalité première soit de nature neutre, et appelons-la par quelque nom encore ambigu, comme phénomène, donné, Vorfindung. Moi-même j’en parle volontiers au pluriel, et je lui donne le nom d’expériences pures. Ce sera un monisme, si vous voulez, mais un monisme tout à fait rudimentaire et absolument opposé au soi-disant monisme bilatéral du positivisme scientifique ou spinoziste. Ces expériences pures existent et se succèdent, entrent dans des rapports infiniment variés les unes avec les autres, rapports qui sont eux-mêmes des parties essentielles de la trame des expériences. Il y a “Conscience” de ces rapports au même titre qu’il y a “Conscience” de leurs termes. Il en résulte que des groupes d’expériences se font remarquer et distinguer, et qu’une seule et même expérience, vu la grande variété de ses rapports, peut jouer un rôle dans plusieurs groupes à la fois. C’est ainsi que dans un certain contexte de voisins, elle serait classée comme un phénomène physique, tandis que dans un autre entourage elle figurerait comme un fait de conscience, à peu près comme une même particule d’encre peut appartenir simultanément à deux lignes, l’une verticale, l’autre horizontale, pourvu qu’elle soit située à leur intersection. Prenons, pour fixer nos idées, l’expérience que nous avons à ce moment du local où nous sommes, de ces murailles, de cette table, de ces chaises, de cet espace. Dans cette expérience pleine, concrète et indivise, telle qu’elle est là, donnée, le monde physique objectif et le monde intérieur et personnel de cha-
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 86
5/2/22 10:39 AM
La Notion de Conscience 87
cun de nous se rencontrent et se fusionnent comme des lignes se fusionnent à leur intersection. Comme chose physique, cette salle a des rapports avec tout le reste du bâtiment, bâtiment que nous autres nous ne connaissons et ne connaîtrons pas. Elle doit son existence à toute une histoire de financiers, d’architectes, d’ouvriers. Elle pèse sur le sol; elle durera indéfiniment dans le temps; si le feu y éclatait, les chaises et la table qu’elle contient seraient vite réduites en cendres. Comme expérience personnelle, au contraire, comme chose “rapportée,” connue, consciente, cette salle a de tout autres tenants et aboutissants. Ses antécédents ne sont pas des ouvriers, ce sont nos pensées respectives de tout à l’heure. Bientôt elle ne figurera que comme un fait fugitif dans nos biographies, associé à d’agréables souvenirs. Comme expérience psychique, elle n’a aucun poids, son ameublement n’est pas combustible. Elle n’exerce de force physique que sur nos seuls cerveaux, et beaucoup d’entre nous nient encore cette influence; tandis que la salle physique est en rapport d’influence physique avec tout le reste du monde. Et pourtant c’est de la même salle absolument qu’il s’agit dans les deux cas. Tant que nous ne faisons pas de physique spéculative, tant que nous nous plaçons dans le sens commun, c’est la salle vue et sentie qui est bien la salle physique. De quoi parlons-nous donc si ce n’est de cela, de cette même partie de la nature matérielle que tous nos esprits, à ce même moment, embrassent, qui entre telle quelle dans l’expérience actuelle et intime de chacun de nous, et que notre souvenir regardera toujours comme une partie intégrante de notre histoire. C’est absolument une même étoffe qui figure simultanément, selon le contexte que l’on considère, comme fait matériel et physique, ou comme fait de conscience intime. Je crois donc qu’on ne saurait traiter conscience et matière comme étant d’essence disparate. On n’obtient ni l’une ni l’autre par soustraction, en négligeant chaque fois l’autre moitié d’une expérience de composition double. Les expériences sont au contraire primitivement de nature plutôt simple. Elles deviennent conscientes dans leur entier, elles deviennent physiques dans leur entier; et c’est par voie d’addition que ce résultat se réalise. Pour autant que des expériences se prolongent dans le temps, entrent dans des rapports d’influence physique, se brisant, se chauffant, s’éclairant, etc., mutuellement, nous en faisons un groupe à part que nous appelons le monde physique. Pour autant, au contraire, qu’elles sont fugitives, inertes physiquement, que leur succession ne suit pas d’ordre déterminé, mais semble plutôt obéir à des caprices émotifs, nous en faisons un autre groupe que nous appelons le monde psychique. C’est en entrant à présent dans un grand nombre de ces groupes psychiques que cette salle devient maintenant chose consciente, chose rapportée, chose sue. En faisant désormais partie de nos biographies respectives,
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 87
5/2/22 10:39 AM
88
Essays in Radical Empiricism
elle ne sera pas suivie de cette sotte et monotone répétition d’elle-même dans le temps qui caractérise son existence physique. Elle sera suivie, au contraire, par d’autres expériences qui seront discontinues avec elle, ou qui auront ce genre tout particulier de continuité que nous appelons souvenir. Demain, elle aura eu sa place dans chacun de nos passés; mais les présents divers auxquels tous ces passés seront liés demain seront bien différents du présent dont cette salle jouira demain comme entité physique. Les deux genres de groupes sont formés d’expériences, mais les rapports des expériences entre elles diffèrent d’un groupe à l’autre. C’est donc par addition d’autres phénomènes qu’un phénomène donné devient conscient ou connu, ce n’est pas par un dédoublement d’essence intérieure. La connaissance des choses leur survient, elle ne leur est pas immanente. Ce n’est le fait ni d’un moi transcendental, ni d’une Bewusstheit ou acte de conscience qui les animerait chacune. Elles se connaissent l’une l’autre, ou plutôt il y en a qui connaissent les autres; et le rapport que nous nommons connaissance n’est lui-même, dans beaucoup de cas, qu’une suite d’expériences intermédiaires parfaitement susceptibles d’être décrites en termes concrets. Il n’est nullement le mystère transcendant où se sont complus tant de philosophes. Mais ceci nous mènerait beaucoup trop loin. Je ne puis entrer ici dans tous les replis de la théorie de la connaissance, ou de ce que, vous autres Italiens, vous appelez la gnoséologie. Je dois me contenter de ces remarques écourtées, ou simples suggestions, qui sont, je le crains, encore bien obscures faute des développements nécessaires. Permettez donc que je me résume—trop sommairement, et en style dogmatique—dans les six thèses suivantes: 1. L a Conscience, telle qu’on l’entend ordinairement, n’existe pas, pas plus que la Matière, à laquelle Berkeley a donné le coup de grâce; 2. C e qui existe et forme la part de vérité que le mot de “Conscience” recouvre, c’est la susceptibilité que possèdent les parties de l’expérience d’être rapportées ou connues; 3. C ette susceptibilité s’explique par le fait que certaines expériences peuvent mener les unes aux autres par des expériences intermédiaires nettement caractérisées, de telle sorte que les unes se trouvent jouer le rôle de choses connues, les autres celui de sujets connaissants; 4. On peut parfaitement définir ces deux rôles sans sortir de la trame de l’expérience même, et sans invoquer rien de transcendant; 5. Les attributions sujet et objet, représenté et représentatif, chose et pensée, signifient donc une distinction pratique qui est de la dernière importance, mais qui est d’ordre fonctionnel seulement, et nullement ontologique comme le dualisme classique se la représente;
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 88
5/2/22 10:39 AM
La Notion de Conscience 89
6. E n fin de compte, les choses et les pensées ne sont point foncièrement hétérogènes, mais elles sont faites d’une même étoffe, étoffe qu’on ne peut définir comme telle, mais seulement éprouver, et que l’on peut nommer, si on veut, l’étoffe de l’expérience en général.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 89
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 90
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Chapter Nine
Is Radical Empiricism Solipsistic?
If all the criticisms which the humanistic Weltanschauung is receiving were as sachgemäss1 as Mr. Bode’s,2 the truth of the matter would more rapidly clear up.3 Not only is it excellently well written, but it brings its own point of view out clearly and admits of a perfectly straight reply. The argument (unless I fail to catch it) can be expressed as follows: If a series of experiences be supposed, no one of which is endowed immediately with the self-transcendent function of reference to a reality beyond itself, no motive will occur within the series for supposing anything beyond it to exist. It will remain subjective, and contentedly subjective, both as a whole and in its several parts. Radical empiricism, trying, as it does, to account for objective knowledge by means of such a series, egregiously fails. It can not explain how the notion of a physical order, as distinguished from a subjectively biographical order, of experiences, ever arose. It pretends to explain the notion of a physical order, but does so by playing fast and loose with the concept of objective reference. On the one hand, it denies that such reference implies self-transcendency on the part of any one experience; on the other hand, it claims that experiences point. But, critically considered, there can be no pointing unless self-transcendency be also allowed. The conjunctive function of pointing, as I have assumed it, is, according to my critic, vitiated by the fallacy of attaching a bilateral relation to a term a quo,4 as if it could stick out substantively and maintain itself in existence in advance of the term ad quem5 which is equally required for it to be a concretely experienced fact. If the relation be made concrete, the term ad quem is involved, which would mean (if I succeed in apprehending Mr. Bode rightly) that this latter term, although not empirically there, is yet noetically6 there, in advance—in other words it would mean that any experience that 91
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 91
5/2/22 10:39 AM
92
Essays in Radical Empiricism
‘points’ must already have transcended itself, in the ordinary ‘epistemological’ sense of the word transcend. Something like this, if I understand Mr. Bode’s text, is the upshot of his state of mind. It is a reasonable sounding state of mind, but it is exactly the state of mind which radical empiricism, by its doctrine of the reality of conjunctive relations, seeks to dispel. I very much fear—so difficult does mutual understanding seem in these exalted regions—that my able critic has failed to understand that doctrine as it is meant to be understood. I suspect that he performs on all these conjunctive relations (of which the aforesaid ‘pointing’ is only one) the usual rationalistic act of substitution—he takes them not as they are given in their first intention, as parts constitutive of experience’s living flow, but only as they appear in retrospect, each fixed as a determinate object of conception, static, therefore, and contained within itself. Against this rationalistic tendency to treat experience as chopped up into discontinuous static objects, radical empiricism protests. It insists on taking conjunctions at their ‘face-value,’ just as they come. Consider, for example, such conjunctions as ‘and,’ ‘with,’ ‘near,’ ‘plus,’ ‘towards.’ While we live in such conjunctions our state is one of transition in the most literal sense. We are expectant of a ‘more’ to come, and before the more has come, the transition, nevertheless, is directed towards it. I fail otherwise to see how, if one kind of more comes, there should be satisfaction and feeling of fulfillment; but disappointment if the more comes in another shape. One more will continue, another more will arrest or deflect the direction, in which our experience is moving even now. We can not, it is true, name our different living ‘ands’ or ‘withs’ except by naming the different terms towards which they are moving us, but we live their specifications and differences before those terms explicitly arrive. Thus, though the various ‘ands’ are all bilateral relations, each requiring a term ad quem to define it when viewed in retrospect and articulately conceived, yet in its living moment any one of them may be treated as if it ‘stuck out’ from its term a quo and pointed in a special direction, much as a compass-needle (to use Mr. Bode’s excellent simile) points at the pole, even though it stirs not from its box.7 In Professor Höffding’s massive little article in The Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods,8 he quotes a saying of Kierkegaard’s to the effect that we live forwards, but we understand backwards. Understanding backwards is, it must be confessed, a very frequent weakness of philosophers, both of the rationalistic and of the ordinary empiricist type. Radical empiricism alone insists on understanding forwards also, and refuses to substitute static concepts of the understanding for transitions in our moving life. A logic similar to that which my critic seems to employ here should, it seems to me, forbid him to say that our present is, while present, directed towards
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 92
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Is Radical Empiricism Solipsistic? 93
our future, or that any physical movement can have direction until its goal is actually reached. At this point does it not seem as if the quarrel about self-transcendency in knowledge might drop? Is it not a purely verbal dispute? Call it self-transcendency or call it pointing, whichever you like—it makes no difference so long as real transitions towards real goals are admitted as things given in experience, and among experience’s most indefeasible parts. Radical empiricism, unable to close its eyes to the transitions caught in actu, accounts for the selftranscendency or the pointing (whichever you may call it) as a process that occurs within experience, as an empirically mediated thing of which a perfectly definite description can be given. ‘Epistemology,’ on the other hand, denies this; and pretends that the self-transcendency is unmediated or, if mediated, then mediated in a super-empirical world. To justify this pretension, epistemology has first to transform all our conjunctions into static objects, and this, I submit, is an absolutely arbitrary act. But in spite of Mr. Bode’s maltreatment of conjunctions, as I understand them—and as I understand him—I believe that at bottom we are fighting for nothing different but are both defending the same continuities of experience in different forms of words. There are other criticisms in the article in question, but, as this seems the most vital one, I will for the present, at any rate, leave them untouched.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 93
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 94
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Chapter Ten
Mr. Pitkin’s Refutation of ‘Radical Empiricism’
Although Mr. Pitkin does not name me in his acute article on radical empiricism,1 [. . .] I fear that some readers, knowing me to have applied that name to my own doctrine, may possibly consider themselves to have been in at my death. In point of fact my withers are entirely unwrung. I have, indeed, said2 that ‘to be radical, an empiricism must not admit into its constructions any element that is not directly experienced.’ But in my own radical empiricism this is only a methodological postulate, not a conclusion supposed to flow from the intrinsic absurdity of trans-empirical objects. I have never felt the slightest respect for the idealistic arguments which Mr. Pitkin attacks and of which Ferrier3 made such striking use; and I am perfectly willing to admit any number of noumenal beings or events into philosophy if only their pragmatic value can be shown. Radical empiricism and pragmatism have so many misunderstandings to suffer from, that it seems my duty not to let this one go any further, uncorrected. Mr. Pitkin’s ‘reply’ to me,4 [. . .] perplexes me by the obscurity of style which I find in almost all our younger philosophers. He asks me, however, two direct questions which I understand, so I take the liberty of answering. First he asks: Do not experience and science show ‘that countless things are5 experienced as that which they are not or are only partially?’ I reply: Yes, assuredly, as, for example, ‘things’ distorted by refractive media, ‘molecules,’ or whatever else is taken to be more ultimately real than the immediate content of the perceptive moment. Secondly: “If experience is self-supporting6 (in any intelligible sense) does this fact preclude the possibility of (a) something not experienced and (b) action of experience upon a noumenon?” 95
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 95
5/2/22 10:39 AM
96
Essays in Radical Empiricism
My reply is: Assuredly not the possibility of either—how could it? Yet in my opinion we should be wise not to consider any thing or action of that nature, and to restrict our universe of philosophic discourse to what is experienced or, at least, experienceable.7
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 96
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Chapter Eleven
Humanism and Truth Once More
Mr. Joseph’s criticism of my article “Humanism and Truth”1 is a useful contribution to the general clearing up. He has seriously tried to comprehend what the pragmatic movement may intelligibly mean; and if he has failed, it is the fault neither of his patience nor of his sincerity, but rather of stubborn tricks of thought which he could not easily get rid of. Minute polemics, in which the parties try to rebut every detail of each of the other’s charges, are a useful exercise only to the disputants. They can but breed confusion in a reader. I will therefore ignore as much as possible the text of both our articles (mine was inadequate enough) and treat once more the general objective situation. As I apprehend the movement towards humanism, it is based on no particular discovery or principle that can be driven into one precise formula which thereupon can be impaled upon a logical skewer. It is much more like one of those secular changes that come upon public opinion overnight, as it were, borne upon tides ‘too full for sound or foam,’ that survive all the crudities and extravagances of their advocates, that you can pin to no one absolutely essential statement, nor kill by any one decisive stab. Such have been the changes from aristocracy to democracy, from classic to romantic taste, from theistic to pantheistic feeling, from static to evolutionary ways of understanding life—changes of which we all have been spectators. Scholasticism still opposes to such changes the method of confutation by single decisive reasons, showing that the new view involves self-contradiction, or traverses some fundamental principle. This is like stopping a river by planting a stick in the middle of its bed. Round your obstacle flows the water and ‘gets there all the same.’ In reading Mr. Joseph, I am not a little reminded of those Catholic writers who refute Darwinism by telling us that higher species can not come from lower because minus nequit gignere plus,2 or that the notion of transformation is absurd, for it implies that species tend to their 97
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 97
5/2/22 10:39 AM
98
Essays in Radical Empiricism
own destruction, and that would violate the principle that every reality tends to persevere in its own shape. The point of view is too myopic, too tight and close to take in the inductive argument. You can not settle questions of fact by formal logic. I feel as if Mr. Joseph almost pounced on my words singly, without giving the sentences time to get out of my mouth. The one condition of understanding humanism is to become inductiveminded oneself, to drop rigorous definitions, and follow lines of least resistance ‘on the whole.’ “In other words,” Mr. Joseph may probably say, “resolve your intellect into a kind of slush.” “Even so,” I make reply,—“if you will consent to use no politer word.” For humanism, conceiving the more ‘true’ as the more ‘satisfactory’ (Dewey’s term) has to renounce sincerely rectilinear arguments and ancient ideals of rigor and finality. It is in just this temper of renunciation, so different from that of pyrrhonistic skepticism, that the spirit of humanism essentially consists. Satisfactoriness has to be measured by a multitude of standards, of which some, for aught we know, may fail in any given case; and what is ‘more’ satisfactory than any alternative in sight, may to the end be a sum of pluses and minuses, concerning which we can only trust that by ulterior corrections and improvements a maximum of the one and a minimum of the other may some day be approached. It means a real change of heart, a break with absolutistic hopes, when one takes up this view of the conditions of belief. That humanism’s critics have never imagined this attitude inwardly, is shown by their invariable tactics. They do not get into it far enough to see objectively and from without what their own opposite notion of truth is. Mr. Joseph is possessed by some such notion; he thinks his readers to be full of it, he obeys it, works from it, but never even essays to tell us what it is. The nearest he comes to doing so is where3 he says it is the way “we ought to think,” whether we be psychologically compelled to or not. Of course, humanism agrees to this: it is only a manner of calling truth an ideal. But humanism explicates the summarizing word ‘ought’ into a mass of pragmatic motives from the midst of which our critics think that truth itself takes flight. Truth is a name of double meaning. It stands now for an abstract something defined only as that to which our thought ought to conform; and again, it stands for the concrete propositions within which we believe that conformity already reigns—they being so many ‘truths.’ Humanism sees that the only conformity we ever have to deal with concretely is that between our subjects and our predicates, using these words in a very broad sense. It sees moreover that this conformity is ‘validated’ (to use Mr. Schiller’s term) by an indefinite number of pragmatic tests that vary as the predicates and subjects vary. If an S gets superseded by an SP that gives our mind a completer sum
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 98
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Humanism and Truth Once More 99
of satisfactions, we always say, humanism points out, that we have advanced to a better position in regard to truth. Now many of our judgments thus attained are retrospective. The S’es, so the judgment runs, were SP’s already ere the fact was humanly recorded. Common sense, struck by this state of things, now rearranges the whole field; and traditional philosophy follows her example. The general requirement that predicates must conform to their subject, they translate into an ontological theory. A most previous Subject of all is substituted for the lesser subjects and conceived of as an archetypal Reality; and the conformity required of predicates in detail is reinterpreted as a relation which our whole mind, with all its subjects and predicates together, must get into with respect to this Reality. It, meanwhile, is conceived as eternal, static, and unaffected by our thinking. Conformity to a non-human Archetype like this is probably the notion of truth which my opponent shares with common sense and philosophic rationalism. When now Humanism, fully admitting both the naturalness and the grandeur of this hypothesis, nevertheless points to its sterility, and declines to chime in with the substitution, keeping to the concrete and still lodging truth between the subjects and the predicates in detail, it provokes the outcry which we hear and which my critic echoes. One of the commonest parts of the outcry is that humanism is subjectivistic altogether—it is supposed to labor under a necessity of ‘denying transperceptual reality.’4 It is not hard to see how this misconception of humanism may have arisen; and humanistic writers, partly from not having sufficiently guarded their expressions, and partly from not having yet “got round” (in the poverty of their literature) to a full discussion of the subject, are doubtless in some degree to blame. But I fail to understand how anyone with a working grasp of their principles can charge them wholesale with subjectivism. I myself have never thought of humanism as being subjectivistic farther than to this extent, that, inasmuch as it treats the thinker as being himself one portion of reality, it must also allow that some of the realities that he declares for true are created by his being there. Such realities of course are either acts of his, or relations between other things and him, or relations between things, which, but for him, would never have been traced. Humanists are subjectivistic, also in this, that, unlike rationalists (who think they carry a warrant for the absolute truth of what they now believe in in their present pocket), they hold all present beliefs as subject to revision in the light of future experience. The future experience, however, may be of things outside the thinker; and that this is so the humanist may believe as freely as any other kind of empiricist philosopher. The critics of humanism (though here I follow them but darkly) appear to object to any infusion whatever of subjectivism into truth. All must be
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 99
5/2/22 10:39 AM
100
Essays in Radical Empiricism
archetypal; every truth must pre-exist to its perception. Humanism sees that an enormous quantity of truth must be written down as having pre-existed to its perception by us humans. In countless instances we find it most satisfactory to believe that, though we were always ignorant of the fact, it always was a fact that S was SP. But humanism separates this class of cases from those in which it is more satisfactory to believe the opposite, e.g., that S is ephemeral, or P a passing event, or SP created by the perceiving act. Our critics seem on the other hand, to wish to universalize the retrospective type of instance. Reality must pre-exist to every assertion for which truth is claimed. And, not content with this overuse of one particular type of judgment, our critics claim its monopoly. They appear to wish to cut off Humanism from its rights to any retrospection at all. Humanism says that satisfactoriness is what distinguishes the true from the false. But satisfactoriness is both a subjective quality, and a present one. Ergo5 (the critics appear to reason) an object, quâ6 true, must always for humanism be both present and subjective, and a humanist’s belief can never be in anything that lives outside of the belief itself or antedates it. Why so preposterous a charge should be so current, I find it hard to say. Nothing is more obvious than the fact that both the objective and the past existence of the object may be the very things about it that most seem satisfactory, and that most invite us to believe them. The past tense can figure in the humanist’s world, as well of belief as of representation, quite as harmoniously as in the world of anyone else. Mr. Joseph gives a special turn to this accusation. He charges me7 with being self-contradictory when I say that the main categories of thought were evolved in the course of experience itself. For I use these very categories to define the course of experience by. Experience, as I talk about it, is a product of their use; and yet I take it as true anteriorly to them. This seems to Mr. Joseph to be an absurdity. I hope it does not seem such to his readers; for if experiences can suggest hypotheses at all (and they notoriously do so) I can see no absurdity whatever in the notion of a retrospective hypothesis having for its object the very train of experiences by which its own being, along with that of other things, has been brought about. If the hypothesis is ‘satisfactory’ we must, of course, believe it to have been true anteriorly to its formulation by ourselves. Every explanation of a present by a past seems to involve this kind of circle, which is not a vicious circle. The past is causa existendi 8 of the present, which in turn is causa cognoscendi 9 of the past. If the present were treated as causa existendi of the past, the circle might indeed be vicious. Closely connected with this pseudo-difficulty is another one of wider scope and greater complication—more excusable therefore.10 Humanism, namely, asking how truth in point of fact is reached, and seeing that it is by ever sub-
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 100
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Humanism and Truth Once More 101
stituting more satisfactory for less satisfactory opinions, is thereby led into a vague historic sketch of truth’s development. The earliest ‘opinions,’ it thinks, must have been dim, unconnected ‘feelings,’ and only little by little did more and more orderly views of things replace them. Our own retrospective view of this whole evolution is now, let us say, the latest candidate for ‘truth’ as yet reached in the process. To be a satisfactory candidate, it must give some definite sort of a picture of what forces keep the process going. On the subjective side we have a fairly definite picture—sensation, association, interest, hypothesis, these account in a general way for the growth into a cosmos of the relative chaos with which the mind began. But on the side of the object, so to call it roughly, our view is much less satisfactory. Of which of our many objects are we to believe that it truly was there and at work before the human mind began? Time, space, kind, number, serial order, cause, consciousness, are hard things not to objectify—even transcendental idealism leaves them standing as ‘empirically real.’ Substance, matter, force, fall down more easily before criticism, and secondary qualities make almost no resistance at all. Nevertheless, when we survey the field of speculation, from Scholasticism through Kantism to Spencerism, we find an ever-recurring tendency to convert the pre-human into a merely logical object, an unknowable ding-an-sich,11 that but starts the process, or a vague materia prima that but receives our forms.12 The reasons for this are not so much logical as they are material. We can postulate an extra-mental that freely enough (though some idealists have denied us the privilege), but when we have done so, the what of it is hard to determine satisfactorily, because of the oppositions and entanglements of the variously proposed whats with one another and with the history of the human mind. The literature of speculative cosmology bears witness to this difficulty. Humanism suffers from it no more than any other philosophy suffers, but it makes all our cosmogonic theories so unsatisfactory that some thinkers seek relief in the denial of any primal dualism. Absolute Thought or ‘pure experience’ is postulated and endowed with attributes calculated to justify the belief that it may ‘run itself.’ Both these truth-claiming hypotheses are non-dualistic in the old mind-and-matter sense; but the one is monistic and the other pluralistic as to the world process itself. Some humanists are non-dualists of this sort—I myself am one und zwar of the pluralistic brand. But doubtless dualistic humanists also exist, as well as non-dualistic ones of the monistic wing. Mr. Joseph pins these general philosophic difficulties on humanism alone, or possibly on me alone. My article spoke vaguely of a ‘most chaotic pure experience’ coming first and building up the mind.13 But how can two structureless things interact so as to produce a structure? my critic triumphantly asks. Of course, they can’t, as purely so-named entities. We must make
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 101
5/2/22 10:39 AM
102
Essays in Radical Empiricism
additional hypotheses. We must beg a minimum of structure for them. The kind of minimum that might have tended to increase towards what we now find actually developed is the philosophical desideratum here. The question is that of the most materially satisfactory hypothesis. Mr. Joseph handles it by formal logic purely, as if he had no acquaintance with the logic of hypothesis at all. Mr. Joseph again is much bewildered as to what a humanist can mean when he uses the word knowledge. He tries to convict me14 of vaguely identifying it with any kind of good. Knowledge is a difficult thing to define briefly, and Mr. Joseph shows his own constructive hand here even less than in the rest of his article. I have myself put forth on several occasions a radically pragmatist account of knowledge,15 the existence of which account my critic probably does not know of—so perhaps I had better not say anything about knowledge until he reads and attacks that. I will say, however, that whatever the relation called knowing may itself prove to consist in, I can think of no conceivable kind of object which may not become an object of knowledge on humanistic principles as well as on the principles of any other philosophy.16 I confess that I am pretty steadily hampered by the habit, on the part of humanism’s critics, of assuming that they have truer ideas than mine of truth and knowledge, the nature of which I must know of and can not need to have re-defined. I have consequently to reconstruct these ideas in order to carry on the discussion (I have, e.g., had to do so in some parts of this article) and I thereby expose myself to charges of caricature. In one part of Mr. Joseph’s attack, however, I rejoice that we are free from this embarrassment. It is an important point and covers probably a genuine difficulty, so I take it up last. When, following Schiller and Dewey, I define the true as that which gives the maximal combination of satisfactions, and say that satisfaction is a manydimensional term that can be realized in various ways, Mr. Joseph replies, rightly enough, that the chief satisfaction of a rational creature must always be his thought that what he believes is true, whether the truth brings him the satisfaction of collateral profits or not. This would seem, however, to make of truth the prior concept, and to relegate satisfaction to a secondary place. Again, if to be satisfactory is what is meant by being true, whose satisfactions, and which of his satisfactions, are to count? Discriminations notoriously have to be made; and the upshot is that only rational candidates and intellectual satisfactions stand the test. We are then driven to a purely theoretic notion of truth and get out of the pragmatic atmosphere altogether. And with this Mr. Joseph leaves us—truth is truth, and there is an end of the matter. But he makes a very pretty show of convicting me of self-stultification in according to our purely theoretic satisfactions any place in the humanistic scheme.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 102
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Humanism and Truth Once More 103
They crowd the collateral satisfactions out of house and home, he thinks, and pragmatism has to go into bankruptcy if she recognizes them at all. There is no room for disagreement about the facts here; but the destructive force of the reasoning disappears as soon as we talk concretely instead of abstractly, and ask, in our quality of good pragmatists, just what the famous theoretic needs are known as and in what the intellectual satisfactions consist. Mr. Joseph, faithful to the habits of his party, makes no attempt at characterizing them, but assumes that their nature is self-evident to all. And they not all mere matters of consistency—and emphatically not of consistency between an Absolute Reality and the mind’s copies of it, but of actually felt consistency among judgments, objects, and manners of reacting, in the mind? And are not both our need of such consistency and our pleasure in it conceivable as outcomes of the natural fact that we are beings that develop mental habits—habit itself proving adaptively beneficial in an environment where the same objects, or the same kinds of objects, recur and follow ‘law’? If this were so, what would have come first would have been the collateral profits of habit, and the theoretic life would have grown up in aid of these. In point of fact this seems to have been the probable case. At life’s origin, any present perception may have been ‘true’—if such a word could then be applicable. Later, when reactions became organized, the reactions became ‘true’ whenever expectation was fulfilled by them. Otherwise, they were ‘false’ or ‘mistaken’ reactions. But the same class of objects needs the same kind of reaction, so the impulse to react consistently must gradually have been established, with a disappointment felt whenever the results frustrated expectation. Here is a perfectly plausible germ for all our higher consistencies. Nowadays, if an object claims from us a reaction of the kind habitually accorded only to the opposite class of objects, our mental machinery refuses to run smoothly. The situation is intellectually unsatisfactory. To gain relief we seek either to preserve the reaction by re-interpreting the object, or, leaving the object as it is, we react in a way contrary to the way claimed of us. Neither solution is easy. Such a situation might be that of Mr. Joseph, with me claiming assent to humanism from him. He can not apperceive it so as to permit him to gratify my claim; but there is enough appeal in the claim to induce him to write a whole article in justification of his refusal. If he should assent to humanism, on the other hand, that would drag after it an unwelcome, yea incredible, alteration of his previous mental beliefs. Whichever alternative he might adopt, however, a new equilibrium of intellectual consistency would in the end be reached. He would feel, whichever way he decided, that he was now thinking truly. But if, with his old habits unaltered, he should simply add to them the new one of advocating humanism quietly or noisily, his mind would be rent
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 103
5/2/22 10:39 AM
104
Essays in Radical Empiricism
into two systems, each of which would accuse the other of falsehood. The resultant situation, being profoundly unsatisfactory, would also be instable. Theoretic truth is thus no relation between our mind and archetypal reality. It falls within the mind, being the accord of some of its processes and objects with other processes and objects—‘accord’ consisting here in well-definable relations. So long as the satisfaction of feeling such an accord is denied us, whatever collateral profits may seem to inure from what we believe in are but as dust in the balance—provided always that we are highly organized intellectually, which the majority of us are not. The amount of accord which satisfies most men and women is merely the absence of violent clash between their usual thoughts and statements and the limited sphere of senseperceptions in which their lives are cast. The theoretic truth that most of us think we ‘ought’ to attain to is thus the possession of a set of predicates that do not contradict their subjects. We preserve it as often as not by leaving other predicates and subjects out. In some men theory is a passion, just as music is in others. The form of inner consistency is pursued far beyond the line at which collateral profits stop. Such men systematize and classify and schematize and make synoptical17 tables and invent ideal objects for the pure love of unifying. Too often the results, glowing with ‘truth’ for the inventors, seem pathetically personal and artificial to bystanders. Which is as much as to say that the purely theoretic criterion of truth can leave us in the lurch as easily as any other criterion. I think that if Mr. Joseph will but consider all these things a little more concretely, he may find that the humanistic scheme and the notion of theoretic truth fall into line consistently enough to yield him also intellectual satisfaction.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 104
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Chapter Twelve
Absolutism and Empiricism
No seeker of truth can fail to rejoice at the terre-à-terre1 sort of discussion of the issues between Empiricism and Transcendentalism (or, as the champions of the latter would probably prefer to say, between Irrationalism and Rationalism) that seems to have begun in Mind.2 It would seem as if, over concrete examples like Mr. J. S. Haldane’s,3 both parties ought inevitably to come to a better understanding. As a reader with a strong bias towards Irrationalism, I have studied his article.4 with the liveliest admiration of its temper and its painstaking effort to be clear. But the cases discussed failed to satisfy me, and I was at first tempted to write a Note animadverting upon them in detail. The growth of the limb, the sea’s contour, the vicarious functioning of the nervecenter, the digitalis curing the heart, are unfortunately not cases where we can see any through-and-through conditioning of the parts by the whole. They are all cases of reciprocity where subjects, supposed independently to exist, acquire certain attributes through their relations to other subjects. That they also exist through similar relations is only an ideal supposition, not verified to our understanding in these or any other concrete cases whatsoever. If, however, one were to urge this solemnly, Mr. Haldane’s friends could easily reply that he only gave us such examples on account of the hardness of our hearts. He knew full well their imperfection, but he hoped that to those who would not spontaneously ascend to the Notion of the Totality, these cases might prove a spur and suggest and symbolize something better than themselves. No particular case that can be brought forward is a real concrete. They are all abstractions from the Whole, and of course the “through-and-through” character can not be found in them. Each of them still contains among its elements what we call things, grammatical subjects, forming a sort of residual caput mortuum5 of Existence after all the relations that figure in the examples have been told off. On this “existence,” thinks popular philosophy, things 105
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 105
5/2/22 10:39 AM
106
Essays in Radical Empiricism
may live on, like the winter bears on their own fat, never entering relations at all, or, if entering them, entering an entirely different set of them from those treated of in Mr. Haldane’s examples. Thus if the digitalis were to weaken instead of strengthening the heart, and to produce death (as sometimes happens), it would determine itself, through determining the organism, to the function of “kill” instead of that of “cure.” The function and relation seem adventitious, depending on what kind of a heart the digitalis gets hold of, the digitalis and the heart being facts external and, so to speak, accidental to each other. But this popular view, Mr. Haldane’s friends will continue, is an illusion. What seems to us the “existence” of digitalis and heart outside of the relations of killing or curing, is but a function in a wider system of relations, of which, pro hac vice, we take no account. The larger system determines the existence just as absolutely as the system “kill,” or the system “cure,” determined the function of the digitalis. Ascend to the absolute system, instead of biding with these relative and partial ones, and you shall see that the law of through-and-throughness must and does obtain. Of course, this argument is entirely reasonable, and debars us completely from chopping logic about the concrete examples Mr. Haldane has chosen. It is not his fault if his categories are so fine an instrument that nothing, but the sum total of things can be taken to show us the manner of their use. It is simply our misfortune that he has not the sum total of things to show it by. Let us fall back from all concrete attempts and see what we can do with his notion of through-and-throughness, avowedly taken in abstracto. In abstract systems the “through-and-through” Ideal is realized on every hand. In any system, as such, the members are only members in the system. Abolish the system and you abolish its members, for you have conceived them through no other property than the abstract one of membership. Neither rightness nor leftness, except through bilaterality. Neither mortgager nor mortgagee, except through mortgage. The logic of these cases is this:—If A, then B; but if B, then A: wherefore if either, Both; and if not Both, Nothing. It costs nothing, not even a mental effort, to admit that the absolute totality of things may be organized exactly after the pattern of one of these “through-andthrough” abstractions. In fact, it is the pleasantest and freest of mental movements. Husband makes, and is made by, wife, through marriage; one makes other, by being itself other; everything self-created through its opposite— you go round like a squirrel in a cage. But if you stop and reflect upon what you are about, you lay bare the exact point at issue between common sense and the “through-and-through” school. What, in fact, is the logic of these abstract systems? It is, as we said above: If any Member, then the Whole System; if not the Whole System, then Nothing. But how can Logic possibly do anything more with these two hypoth-
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 106
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Absolutism and Empiricism 107
eses than combine them into the single disjunctive proposition—“Either this Whole System, just as it stands, or Nothing at all.” Is not that disjunction the ultimate word of Logic in the matter, and can any disjunction, as such, resolve itself? It may be that Mr. Haldane sees how one horn, the concept of the Whole System, carries real existence with it. But if he has been as unsuccessful as I in assimilating the Hegelian re-editings of the Anselmian proof,6 he will have to say that though Logic may determine what the system must be, if it is, something else than Logic must tell us that it is. Mr. Haldane in this case would probably consciously, or unconsciously, make an appeal to Fact: the disjunction is decided, since nobody can dispute that now, as a matter of fact, something, and not nothing, is. We must therefore, he would probably say, go on to admit the Whole System in the desiderated sense. Is not then the validity of the Anselmian proof7 the nucleus of the whole question between Logic and Fact? Ought not the efforts of Mr. Haldane and his friends to be principally devoted to its elucidation? Is it not the real door of separation between Empiricism and Rationalism? And if the Rationalists leave that door for a moment off its hinges, can any power keep that abstract, opaque, unmediated, external, irrational, and irresponsible monster, known to the vulgar as bare Fact, from getting in and contaminating the whole sanctuary with his presence? Can anything prevent Faust from changing “Am Anfang war das Wort”8 into “Am Anfang war die Tat?”9 Nothing in earth or heaven. Only the Anselmian proof can keep Fact out of philosophy. The question, “Shall Fact be recognized as an ultimate principle?” is the whole issue between the Rationalists and the Empiricism of vulgar thought. Of course, if so recognized, Fact sets a limit to the “through-and-through” character of the world’s rationality. That rationality might then mediate between all the members of our conception of the world, but not between the conception itself and reality. Reality would have to be given, not by Reason, but by Fact. Fact holds out blankly, brutally and blindly, against that universal deliquescence of everything into logical relations which the Absolutist Logic demands, and it is the only thing that does hold out. Hence the ire of the Absolutist Logic—hence its non-recognition, its ‘cutting’ of Fact. The reasons it gives for the ‘cutting’ are that Fact is speechless, a mere word for the negation of thought, a vacuous unknowability, a dog-in-themanger, in truth, which having no rights of its own, can find nothing else to do than to keep its betters out of theirs. There are two points involved here: first the claim that certain things have rights that are absolute, ubiquitous and all pervasive, and in regard to which nothing else can possibly exist in its own right; and second that anything that denies this assertion is pure negativity with no positive context whatsoever.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 107
5/2/22 10:39 AM
108
Essays in Radical Empiricism
Take the latter point first. Is it true that what is negative in one way is thereby convicted of incapacity to be positive in any other way? The word “Fact” is like the word “Accident,” like the word “Absolute” itself. They all have their negative connotation. In truth, their whole connotation is negative and relative. All it says is that whatever the thing may be that is denoted by the words, other things do not control it. Where fact, where accident is, they must be silent, it alone can speak. But that does not prevent its speaking as loudly as you please, in its own tongue. It may have an inward life, selftransparent and active in the maximum degree. An indeterminate future volition on my part, for example, would be a strict accident as far as my present self is concerned. But that could not prevent it, in the moment in which it occurred, from being possibly the most intensely living and luminous experience I ever had. Its quality of being a brute fact ab extra10says nothing whatever as to its inwardness. It simply says to outsiders: ‘Hands off!’ And this brings us back to the first point of the Absolutist indictment of Fact. Is that point really anything more than a fantastic dislike to letting anything say ‘Hands off’? What else explains the contempt the Absolutist authors exhibit for a freedom defined simply on its “negative” side, as freedom “from,” etc.? What else prompts them to deride such freedom? But, dislike for dislike, who shall decide? Why is not their dislike at having me “from” them, entirely on a par with mine at having them “through” me? I know very well that in talking of dislikes to those who never mention them, I am doing a very coarse thing, and making a sort of intellectual Orson of myself.11 But, for the life of me, I can not help it, because I feel sure that likes and dislikes must be among the ultimate factors of their philosophy as well as of mine. Would they but admit it! How sweetly we then could hold converse together! There is something finite about us both, as we now stand. We do not know the Absolute Whole yet. Part of it is still negative to us. Among the whats of it still stalks a mob of opaque thats, without which we cannot think. But just as I admit that this is all possibly provisional, that even the Anselmian proof may come out all right, and creation may be a rational system through-and-through, why might they not also admit that it may all be otherwise, and that the shadow, the opacity, the negativity, the “from”-ness, the plurality that is ultimate, may never be wholly driven from the scene.12 We should both then be avowedly making hypotheses, playing with Ideals. Ah! Why is the notion of hypothesis so abhorrent to the Hegelian mind? And once down on our common level of hypothesis, we might then admit skepticism, since the Whole is not yet revealed, to be the soundest logical position. But since we are in the main not skeptics, we might go on and frankly confess to each other the motives for our several faiths. I frankly confess mine—I can not but think that at bottom they are of an aesthetic and not of a
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 108
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Absolutism and Empiricism 109
logical sort. The “through-and-through” universe seems to suffocate me with its infallible impeccable all-pervasiveness. Its necessity, with no possibilities; its relations, with no subjects, make me feel as if I had entered into a contract with no reserved rights, or rather as if I had to live in a large seaside boarding house with no private bedroom in which I might take refuge from the society of the place. I am distinctly aware, moreover, that the old quarrel of sinner and Pharisee has something to do with the matter. Certainly, to my personal knowledge, all Hegelians are not prigs, but I somehow feel as if all prigs ought to end, if developed, by becoming Hegelians. There is a story of two clergymen asked by mistake to conduct the same funeral. One came first and had got no farther than “I am the Resurrection and the Life,” when the other entered. “I am the Resurrection and the Life,” cried the latter. The “throughand-through” philosophy, as it actually exists, reminds many of us of that clergyman. It seems too buttoned-up and white-chokered and clean-shaven a thing to speak for the vast slow-breathing unconscious Kosmos with its dread abysses and its unknown tides. The “freedom” we want to see there is not the freedom, with a string tied to its leg and warranted not to fly away, of that philosophy. “Let it fly away,” we say, “from us! What then?” Again, I know I am exhibiting my mental grossness. But again, Ich kann nicht anders.13 I show my feelings; why will they not show theirs? I know they have a personal feeling about the through-and-through universe, which is entirely different from mine, and which I should very likely be much the better for gaining if they would only show me how. Their persistence in telling me that feeling has nothing to do with the question, that it is a pure matter of absolute reason, keeps me for ever out of the pale. Still seeing a that in things which Logic does not expel, the most I can do is to aspire to the expulsion. At present I do not even aspire. Aspiration is a feeling. What can kindle feeling but the example of feeling? And if the Hegelians will refuse to set an example, what can they expect the rest of us to do? To speak more seriously, the one fundamental quarrel Empiricism has with Absolutism is over this repudiation by Absolutism of the personal and aesthetic factor in the construction of philosophy. That we all of us have feelings, Empiricism feels quite sure. That they may be as prophetic and anticipatory of truth as anything else we have, and some of them more so than others, can not possibly be denied. But what hope is there of squaring and settling opinions unless Absolutism will hold parley on this common ground; and will admit that all philosophies are hypotheses, to which all our faculties, emotional as well as logical, help us, and the truest of which will at the final integration of things be found in possession of the men whose faculties on the whole had the best divining power?
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 109
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 110
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Notes
PREFACE 1. See e.g., C. S. Peirce 1878, “How to Make Our Ideas Clear,” Popular Science Monthly, vol. 12, January issue, pp. 286–302. Reprinted in Justus Buchler, ed. 1955, Philosophical Writings of Peirce (New York: Dover), pp. 23–41; see C.S. Peirce 1870, “Description of a Notation for the Logic of Relatives, resulting from an Amplification of the Conceptions of Boole’s Calculus of Logic,” Memoirs of the American Academy, vol. 9, pp. 317–378. Reprinted in Peirce 1933, Collected Papers vol. 3 (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), 3.45–3.148. 2. Of particular interest is James’s letter of August 9, 1903, to James R. Angell. In response to Angell’s work, James wrote, “I wish now that you or someone would write a psychology frankly on ‘functional’ lines.” See Ignas K. Skrupskelis et al. eds. 2002, The Correspondence of William James, vol. 10 (Charlottesville, VA: University of Virginia Press), p. 288.
INTRODUCTION 1. Notable among James’s French sources are Charles-Bernard Renouvier (1815– 1903), Hippolyte Taine (1828–1893) and Henri Bergson (1859–1941). 2. See James 1904, “Does ‘Consciousness’ Exist?” present edition, p. 1 and references to J.M. Baldwin, James Ward, H.H. Bawden, Irving King, etc. 3. James 1890/1950, Principles of Psychology (New York: Henry Holt; 1950; reprinted, New York: Dover), vol. 1, p. 138. Cf. the compelling argument and evidence in Stanislas Dehaene 2014, Consciousness and the Brain (New York: Penguin), Chp. 3. 4. Cf. Hilary Putnam 1990, “James’s Theory of Perception,” in Putnam 1990, Realism with a Human Face (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), p. 233.
111
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 111
5/2/22 10:39 AM
112
Notes
5. According to the Dictionary of Psychology (Gary R. VandenBos, ed. 2015, APA Dictionary of Psychology. Second ed. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association), functionalism is “a general psychological approach which views mental life and behavior in terms of active adaptation to environmental challenges and opportunities.” See also James R. Angell 1909, “The Influence of Darwin on Psychology,” Psychological Review, vol. 16, no. 3, p. 153: “. . . we may certainly attribute to Darwinism the larger part of the responsibility for the change that has brought into prominence functional and genetic psychology . . .” 6. Cf. James Ward 1886, “Psychology” in Encyclopedia Britannica, ninth ed.; James Mark Baldwin 1909, Darwin and the Humanities (Baltimore, MD: Review Publishing), p. 20. 7. James Mark Baldwin 1909, Darwin and the Humanities, pp. 23–24. 8. Stanislas Dehaene 2020, How We Learn, Why Brains Learn Better than Any Machine . . . for now (New York: Viking), p. xix. 9. James R. Angell 1906, Psychology: An Introductory Study of the Structure and Function of Human Consciousness (New York: Henry Holt), p. 63. Cf. James 1890, Principles, vol. 1, p. 142. 10. See James 1890, Principles, vol. 1, on the “cognitive function” of conscious states, on “feeling and thought” and their correlation with brain function. James remarks that “We ought to have some general term by which to designate all states of consciousness merely as such, and apart from their particular quality or cognitive function. See p. 185. Cf. John J. McDermott 1976, “Introduction” in Burkhardt, F.H. et al., eds 1976, The Works of William James, vol. 3, Essays in Radical Empiricism (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), p. xxiv: In the development of radical empiricism, James “gives up” the proposal from the Principles “to designate mental states “merely by cognitive function . . .” 11. Angell 1906, Psychology: An Introductory Study, pp. 65–66. 12. Cf. Christof Koch 2004, The Quest for Consciousness (Englewood, CO: Roberts Publishing), p. 231: “Within the last two decades, novelists, philosophers, scientists and engineers have written extensively on the function of consciousness. Most of these speculations adopt a computational stance, identifying one or several information processing tasks as critical to and for consciousness.” 13. Cf. G. William Farthing 1992, The Psychology of Consciousness (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall), pp. 6–7: “Consciousness is always about something. . . . Consciousness has contents.” See also James R. Angell 1903, “The Relation of Structural and Functional Psychology to Philosophy,” Decennial Publications of the University of Chicago, First Series, p. 61: “If the contention once be granted that psychology cannot succeed to determine what consciousness is . . . without a determination of what consciousness does, . . . [then] psychology must proceed to inquire into the how and why of conscious operations.” 14. Cf. Stanislas Dehaene 2014, Consciousness and the Brain, p. 91, “In this book, . . . I explore . . . what philosophers call the “functionalist” view of consciousness. Its thesis is that consciousness is useful.” 15. See Stanislas Dehaene 2014, Consciousness and the Brain, pp. 89–92. Cf. Christof Koch 2020, The Feeling of Life itself (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), p. 121,
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 112
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Notes 113
where Koch entertains the hypothesis that what he calls (content-less) “pure experience” is a non-functional, evolutionary spandrel. 16. See Farthing 1992, Psychology of Consciousness, p. 5: “Mind is the functioning of the brain to process information and control action in a flexible and adaptive manner.” 17. Sidney Hook 1927/1996, The Metaphysics of Pragmatism (1996, reprinted, Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books), pp. 7–8. The precursor of James’s notion of “pure experience” is his treatment of sensation in the Principles. 18. James 1904, “Does Consciousness Exist?” present ed., p. 2. Notice that James also says, in the same essay, that “there is no general stuff of which experience at large is made,” p. 10. One may doubt that the notion of “pure experience” survives the concession. 19. Cf. John Dewey 1930, “Conduct and Experience,” in C. Murchison, ed. 1930, Psychologies of 1930. (Worcester, MA: Clark University Press); reprinted in John Dewey 1984, The Later Works, vol. 5 (Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press), pp. 218–235, where functionalist themes in psychology are elaborated in criticism of naïve, “structuralist” introspection and narrowly focused, S-R behaviorism. 20. John Locke 1690, Essay Concerning Human Understanding (London; reprinted 1975, Nidditch, H. P. ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press), Bk. II., Chp. I., paragraph 2. 21. George Berkeley 1710, Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge (Dublin: Jeremy Pepyat; reprinted 1878, London: Wm. Tegg.) paragraph 3. 22. Radical empiricism is concisely defined in the “Preface” to James 1911/1977, The Meaning of Truth (New York: Longmans, Green; reprinted 1977, Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books), pp. xvi–xvii: It “consists of a postulate, a statement of fact, and a conclusion.” The postulate is that “the only things that shall be debatable among philosophers shall be things definable in terms drawn from experience,” the fact is that “relations are just as much matters of direct particular experience, neither more so nor less so, than the things themselves,” and the conclusion is that “the parts of experience hold together from next to next by relations that are themselves parts of experience.” 23. James 1905, “La Notion de Conscience,” present ed., p. 88. 24. Contrast James Angell 1907, “The Province of Functional Psychology,” Psychological Review, vol. 14, no. 2, p. 84: “Mind and relations are essentially one;” “Nor is this unity secured after the manner prescribed by the good Bishop Berkeley.” See pp. 84–85. 25. James 1905, “La Notion de Conscience,” present ed., p. 81. However, contrast James 1904, on Berkeley in “A World of Pure Experience,” present ed., p. 28: “For the Berkeleian school, ideas (the verbal equivalent of what I term experiences) are discontinuous. The content of each is wholly immanent, and there are no transitions with which they are consubstantial and through which their beings may unite.” 26. Cf. Hilary Putnam 1990, “James’s Theory of Perception,” p. 250. Putnam rejects radical empiricism understood as “A metaphysics in which reality consists of intentional objects which are themselves the ‘natures’ of bits of ‘pure experience.’” 27. See James 1892, Psychology: The Briefer Course, p. 332 in Allport’s edition, reprinted 1985, (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press): “The ambiguous
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 113
5/2/22 10:39 AM
114
Notes
word ‘content’ has recently been invented instead of ‘object’ to escape a decision; for ‘content’ suggests something not exactly out of the feeling, nor yet exactly identical with the feeling, since the latter remains suggested as the container or vessel. Yet of our feelings as vessels apart from their content we really have no clear notion whatever.” 28. James 1904, “A World of Pure Experience,” present ed., p. 28. 29. Contrast James 1890, Principles, vol. 2, pp. 630–631. The scientific naturalism of Principles is more congenial to hypothetical-deductive (and hypotheticalstatistical) methods. 30. James 1890, Principles, vol. 1, p. 186; cf. the diagram on p. 184. Cf. Franz Brentano 1874/1973, Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint (New York: Humanities Press), and his “thesis of intentionality” as the mark of the mental. Cf. also John Searle 1983, Intentionality (New York: Cambridge University Press), p. 16: “An intentional object is just an object like any other; it has no peculiar ontological status at all. To call something an intentional object is just to say it is what some intentional state is about.” 31. James 1909, A Pluralistic Universe (New York: Longmans, Green), pp. 7–8. 32. This is to understand later Wittgenstein as consistent with James’s criticism of solipsism, and the “private language argument” as directed against views such as those of Bertrand Russell in his “logical atomist” period. Cf. Russell 1918, “The Philosophy of Logical Atomism,” The Monist, vol. 28, pp. 495–527. 33. Contrast the “hermeneutic” interpretation of James’s “The Function of Cognition,” in Charlene H. Seigfried 1990, William James’s Radical Reconstruction of Philosophy (Albany, NY: SUNY Press), pp. 188–189. Seigfried emphasizes “praxis,” social interaction, “being in the world” and their importance in escaping solipsism, but neglects experiment understood as scientific practice and the public or objective character of theoretical language. 34. James 1904, “A World of Pure Experience,” present ed., p. 26. 35. Notice the reserve on pragmatism in Angell 1907, “Province of Functional Psychology,” p. 68: “I should not wish to commit either party by asserting that functional psychology and pragmatism are ultimately one.” 36. See Dehaene 2014, Consciousness and the Brain, p. 91. 37. Cf. e.g., Ned Block 1997/2007, “Functionalism” in Ned Block 2007, Consciousness, Function and Representation, Collected Papers, vol. 1 (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), pp. 63–101. See, p. 15: “Functionalism says that mental states are constituted by their causal relations to one another and to sensory inputs and behavioral outputs;” Janet Levin 2018, “Functionalism,” (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy), p. 1: “Functionalism in the philosophy of mind is the doctrine that what makes something a mental state . . . does not depend on its internal constitution, but rather on the way it functions, or the role it plays in the system of which it is a part.” See also, e.g., Ned Block, et al. eds. 1997, The Nature of Consciousness (Cambridge, MA.: MIT Press), for an overview of recent issues. 38. James 1890, Principles, vol. 1, p. 185. Cf. Güven Güzeldere 1997, “The Many Faces of Consciousness: A Field Guide,” in Ned Block, et al. eds. 1997, The Nature of Consciousness, p. 13.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 114
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Notes 115
39. Cf. Farthing 1992, The Psychology of Consciousness, p. 46: “It is important to bear in mind that . . . ‘looking within’ is merely a metaphorical description of the introspective process. . . . Introspection is a matter of thinking about one’s conscious experience.” 40. See James 1890, Principles, vol. 1, pp. 187–191: “. . . introspection is difficult and fallible; and . . . the difficulty is simply that of all observation of whatever kind.” 41. James 1884, “On Some Omissions of Introspective Psychology,” Mind, n.s., vol. 9, no. 33, p. 9. 42. James 1892, Briefer Course, p. 244; in Allport’s ed. 1985, p. 111. 43. Compare, for instance, the criticism of structural psychology in Angell 1907, “The Province of Functional Psychology,” p. 67; p. 88: “Just as behavior may be regarded as the most distinctive basic category of general biology in its functional phase so control would perhaps serve as the most fundamental category in functional psychology. . .” 44. Cf. Farthing 1992, Psychology of Consciousness, p. 61: “Fortunately, psychology is not limited to the introspective method for studying how the mind works. . . . Other measures, such as physiological responses . . . are useful insofar as they have been validated by showing their correlation with introspective reports. . .” 45. Cf. Dehaene 2014, Consciousness and the Brain, pp. 11–12; 41–45. In a significant sense, writes Dehaene, “the behaviorists were right: as a method, introspection provides a shaky ground for a science of psychology, because no amount of introspection will tell us how the mind works.” See p. 43. 46. On contemporary clinical practice and the role of brain imagining in recognizing consciousness in paralyzed coma-recovery patients, see Adrian Owen 2017, Into the Gray Zone, A Neuroscientist Explores the Border between Life and Death (New York: Scribner). See also the account of Owen’s work in Dehaene 2014, Consciousness and the Brain, Chp. 6 and pp. 209–211. 47. See, for instance, Oswald Külpe 1901, Outlines of Psychology, Based upon the Results of Experimental Investigation (London: Swan Sonnenschein; New York: Macmillan). 48. See James 1890, on J. S. Mill and Mill’s reply to Auguste Comte’s positivism, Principles, vol. 1, pp. 188–189; and J. S. Mill 1882, Auguste Comte and Positivism, 3rd edition (London: Trübner), p. 64. Cf. Farthing 1992, Psychology of Consciousness, Chapter 3, for a defense and evaluation of the limitations of introspection as “retrospection.” 49. Compare the discussion in Kurt Danziger 1980, “The History of Introspection Reconsidered,” Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, vol. 16, p. 245. 50. See, for instance, Alex Byrne and David R. Hilbert 2010, “How Do Things Look to the Colorblind?” in Jonathan Cohen and Mohan Matthen, eds. 2010, Color Ontology and Color Science (Cambridge, MA and London: MIT Press), p. 266: “The colorblind, like the blind . . . learn native languages in their entirety, not some subset with terms corresponding to their deficit subtracted. In . . . colorblindness, . . . many individuals . . . are unaware of their condition. . .” 51. Cf. Anthony I. Jack and Tim Shallice 2001, “Introspective Physicalism as an Approach to the Science of Consciousness,” in Stanislas Dehaene, ed. 2001, The
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 115
5/2/22 10:39 AM
116
Notes
Cognitive Neuroscience of Consciousness (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), p. 177: “There is a simple and fundamental reason why all attempts to get at the ‘raw data’ of experience fail: introspective evidence always arrives already interpreted. . . . In order to understand and describe an experience subjects need to employ concepts and categories.” 52. James 1905, “The Place of Affectional Facts,” present ed., p. 59. 53. Anthony I. Jack and Tim Shallice 2001, “Introspective Physicalism as an Approach,” p. 178. The authors draw on R. S. Siegler and E. Stern 1998, “Conscious and Unconscious Strategy Discoveries: A Microgenetic Analysis,” Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, vol. 127, no. 4, pp. 377–397. 54. Cf. Farthing 1992, Psychology of Consciousness, Chapter 7, p. 167: “We would expect better introspective access for novel tasks that require flexible, controlled processing that has a large conscious component. Introspective access would be less likely for habitual tasks that are performed largely through automatic nonconscious processes.” 55. In his early review, Bertrand Russell 1912, “Review of Essays in Radical Empiricism,” Mind, n.s. vol. 21, no. 84, pp. 571–575, Russell, comments that James “seems to regard ‘experience’ as something simple, with which we are all acquainted;” and “. . . the failure to analyze ‘experience’ has concealed important difficulties in the views advocated.” See p. 571. Notice, too, that when Russell published his “William James Lectures” (delivered at Harvard in 1940), he made no mention of James. See Russell 1950, An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth, The William James Lectures for 1940 (London: George Allen & Unwin). 56. I put this argument forward for consideration in the spirit of James’s functionalism. Cf. James 1890, Principles, vol. 1, p. 10. James attributes a similar argument (without fully endorsing it) to Otto Liebmann 1876, Zur Analysis der Wirklichkeit (Straßburg: Trübner), p. 489. 57. The normative character of functional accounts of the mental invites comparison to Donald Davidson on rationality and its relation to intentional explanation. See for instance, Davidson 2004, “Problems in the Explanation of Action,” in Davidson 2004, Problems of Rationality (Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press), pp. 113–116. However, Davidson’s “monism” explicitly rejects anything like Jamesian pluralism, and he states that “. . . my view of the mental is not an ontological but a conceptual category. . . . The reason mental concepts cannot be reduced to physical concepts is the normative character of mental concepts” (p. 114). 58. See, e.g., the brief comparison of Donald Davidson’s “anomalous monism,” and the “Turing machine” functionalism of Hilary Putnam and Jerry Fodor in Jaegwon Kim 2003, “Philosophy of Mind and Psychology,” in Kirk Ludwig, ed. (2003) Donald Davidson (Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press), p. 124. 59. James 1884, “On some Omissions of Introspective Psychology,” p. 9. 60. Cf. D. W. Bjork 1983, The Compromised Scientist (New York: Columbia University Press), p. 87. 61. Angell 1907, “The Province of Functional Psychology,” pp. 62–63.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 116
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Notes 117
62. Cf. Christopher Green 2009, “Darwinian Theory, Functionalism and the First American Psychological Revolution,” American Psychologist, vol. 64, no. 2, pp. 75–83. 63. “Operationalism,” was defined and set forth in P. W. Bridgman 1927, The Logic of Modern Physics (reprinted 1980, New York: Arno Press). It is a version of verificationism which sought definition of theoretical concepts in the sciences purely by reference to specified experimental operations. Bridgman’s work had a large influence in behaviorist psychology. See Christopher D. Green 1992, “Of Immortal Mythological Beasts: Operationism in Psychology,” Theory and Psychology, 2, pp. 291–320. 64. James followed a definition given by George T. Ladd. See James 1892, Briefer Course, p. 1; Allport’s ed. 1985, p. xxv. Cf. James 1890, Principles, vol. 1, p. 1: “Psychology is the Science of Mental Life, both of its phenomena and of their conditions. The phenomena are such things as we call feelings, desires, cognitions, reasonings, decisions, and the like. . .” Cf. George T. Ladd 1894/1896, Psychology, Descriptive and Explanatory (New York: Scribners), p. 4. 65. James 1890, Principles, vol. 1, p. 4. 66. James 1892, Briefer Course, p. 3.; Allport’s ed. 1985, p. xxvii. 67. James 1892, Briefer Course, p. 4; in Allport’s ed. 1985, pp. xxvii–xxviii. 68. Herbert Spencer 1855, The Principles of Psychology (London: Longman, Brown, Green and Longmans), p. 374. 69. James 1892, Briefer Course, p. 6; Allport’s ed. 1985, p. xxiv. 70. James 1892, Briefer Course, p. 7; Allport’s ed, 1985, p. xxx. 71. Cf. James 1892, Briefer Course, Chp. 1; Allport’s ed. 1985, p. xxvi. 72. See for instance, Nancy Kanwisher 2017, “The Quest for the FFA and Where it Led,” Journal of Neuroscience, vol. 37, no. 5, pp. 1056–1061, which emphasizes the fruitfulness of the fMRI methods and a “growing inventory of cortical regions with distinctive and often very specific functions” and Josef Parvizi et al. 2012, “Electrical Stimulation of Human Fusiform Face-selective Regions Distorts Face Recognition,” Journal of Neuroscience, vol. 32, pp. 14915–14920); cf. Sebastian Rogers et al. 2020, “Hallucinations on Demand” (Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 376: 20200233). 73. Cf. Ned Block 1978/2007, “Troubles with Functionalism.” Revisions in Ned Block 2007, Consciousness, Function and Representation, Collected Papers, vol. 1 (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), pp. 63–101; Dehaene 2011, The Number Sense (Revised ed. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press) p. 216: “On purely empirical grounds, the brain-computer metaphor simply does not provide a good model of the available experimental data.” 74. “Behaviorism”: a school of psychology that takes the evidence of behavior (such as measured responses to stimuli) as the only concern of its research and the only basis of its theory without reference to conscious experience (APA Dictionary of Psychology). 75. John B. Watson 1913, “Psychology as the Behaviorist Views it,” Psychological Review, vol. 20, p. 166. 76. William James 1904, “Does ‘Consciousness’ Exist?” present ed., p. 1.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 117
5/2/22 10:39 AM
118
Notes
77. James 1904, “Does ‘Consciousness’ Exist?” present ed., p. 2. Cf. James 1890, Principles, vol. 1, p. 216: “Knowledge becomes for [the psychologist] an ultimate relation that must be admitted, whether it be explained or not, just like difference or resemblance, which no one seeks to explain.” 78. Cf. Donald Davidson 1970/1980, “Mental Events” (reprinted in Davidson 1980, Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 207–227); and Davidson 1993, “Thinking Causes” in J. Heil and A. Mele eds. 1993, Mental Causation (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 3–17, on “anomalous monism” and “the anomaly of the mental.” 79. James 1904, “Does ‘Consciousness’ Exist?” present ed., p. 2. 80. James 1890, Principles, vol. 2, p. 619. 81. James 1905, “The Thing and its Relations,” present ed., p. 35. 82. Cf. Eleanor J. Gibson et al. 1999, “Perceptual Development,” and the supporting literature, in R. A. Wilson and F. C. Kiel eds. 1999, The MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), pp. 632–635. 83. James 1904, “Does ‘Consciousness’ Exist?” present ed., p. 4. 84. James 1905, “The Essence of Humanism,” present ed., pp. 75–76. 85. Cf. Theodore Flournoy 1911/1917, The Philosophy of William James (New York: Henry Holt), p. 69; and James 1905, “The Experience of Activity,” below, p. 63: “Everything real must be experienceable somewhere, and every kind of thing experienced must somewhere be real.” 86. James 1904, “Does ‘Consciousness’ Exist?” present ed., p. 5. 87. Cf. Gerald E. Myers 1986, William James, his Life and Thought (New Haven: Yale University Press), p. 310. “It is questionable whether a world in which mental and physical things abruptly exchange identities is intelligible . . .” “The so-called ‘functional’ analysis flounders on the impossibility of identifying the undifferentiated that (bit of pure experience) which functions [for instance] now as a pen and now as consciousness of a pen.” 88. Cf. James 1912, “Does ‘Consciousness’ Exist?” p. 11: “as the general chaos of all our experiences gets sifted, we find that there are some fires that will always burn sticks and always warm our bodies, and that there are some waters that will always put out fires; while there are other fires and waters that will not act at all.” 89. Cf. James 1892, Briefer Course, in Allport’s ed., p. 35: “We may think about our topic mainly in words, or we may think about it mainly in visual or other images, but this need make no difference . . .” ; Ludwig Wittgenstein 1953, Philosophical Investigations (Oxford: Blackwell) § 329: “When I think in language, there aren’t ‘meanings’ going through my mind in addition to the verbal expressions: the language itself is the vehicle of thought.” 90. James 1890, Principles, vol. 1, p. 196. 91. James 1890, Principles, vol. 1, p. 197. 92. James 1892, Briefer Course, Chp. 22, “Reasoning,” in Allport, ed. 1985, p. 224. Cf. Hilary Putnam 2002, “Introduction,” to I. K. Skrupskelis and E. M. Berkeley, eds., 2002, The Correspondence of William James, vol. 10 (Charlottesville, VA: University of Virginia Press), p. xlvi: James holds that relations are given in experience. “But the reality of a relation is the reality of a general.”
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 118
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Notes 119
93. Contrast James 1892, Briefer Course, Chap. 14, “Conception,” in Allport’s ed. 1985, p. 107ff; “Epilogue, Psychology and Philosophy,” in Allport’s ed. 1985, p. 331–333—where James expresses his introspective-based doubts on the contrast of “content” and “object.” 94. Gordon Allport 1960, “Introduction” in James 1985, Briefer Course, p. xvii. 95. This development is congruent with the functionalist conception that consciousness “is useful,” as found, for instance in the work of Stanislas Dehaene.
CHAPTER ONE 1. The chapter is reprinted from William James 1904, Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 1, no. 18, September 1, pp. 477–491. 2. Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) seminal philosopher of German idealism. According to Kant, the “transcendental ego” is the presence of the Cartesian “I think” in every datum of experience; it is a unifying, impersonal “I” which “sees” but is itself hardly describable. 3. Wilhelm Schuppe (1836–1913), German philosopher who held that the objects of consciousness are “imminent” in consciousness. Johannes Rehmke (1848–1930), German philosopher, Professor at Greifswald and critic of subjectivism; Paul Natorp (1854–1924) German, neo-Kantian philosopher of the Marburg school who employed a Kantian approach to cultural forms including an approach to psychology. Hugo Münsterberg (1863–1916), German-American psychologist and philosopher who worked in experimental psychology and was invited to Harvard by James; Richard von Schubert-Soldern (1852–1924), German philosopher and Professor at Leipzig. 4. “Bewusstheit,” “Bewusstsein überhaupt,” German: consciousness, awareness; consciousness in general. 5. James’s references: James M. Baldwin (1861–1934), American philosopher and theoretical psychologist; James Ward (1843–1925), English philosopher and psychologist at Cambridge; Henry Heath Bawden (1871–1950), American philosopher and psychologist; Irving King (1874–1937), American psychologist and philosopher; Samuel Alexander (1859–1938), Australian-born, British philosopher at Manchester; Dr. Ralph Barton Perry (1876–1957), Professor of Philosophy at Harvard, who, James notes, “is frankly over the border.” 6. “Experience”: Direct observation of or participation in events as a basis of knowledge (Merriam Webster’s). James draws on a broad historical and specialized usage and acceptance of the term “experience,” a term common to empiricist and idealist thinkers, e.g., both John Locke and F.H. Bradley; the term became very prominent in later pragmatist writers. 7. Similarly, James holds that there is no “activity of ‘consciousness’ as such.” See below, present ed., pp. 65ff. 8. Functional psychology, partly inspired by James, was subsequently developed by James R. Angell (1869–1949), John Dewey (1859–1952) and influenced many others. In general terms, mental or psychical processes are interpreted as adaptations of the biological organism.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 119
5/2/22 10:39 AM
120
Notes
9. James’s note: In my Psychology I have tried to show that we need no knower other than the ‘passing thought.’ Cf. William James 1890/1950, Principles of Psychology, vol. 1 (New York: Dover), pp. 338 ff. 10. James’s note: G. E. Moore 1903, “The Refutation of Idealism,” Mind, n.s., vol. 12, no. 48, p. 450. 11. James’s note: Paul Natorp 1888, Einleitung in die Psychologie (Freiberg I. B.: Mohr), p. 14, p. 112. 12. James’s note: “Figuratively speaking, consciousness may be said to be the one universal solvent, or menstruum, in which the different concrete kinds of psychic acts and facts are contained, whether in concealed or in obvious form.” See G. T. Ladd 1894/1896, Psychology, Descriptive and Explanatory (New York: Scribners), p. 30. 13. “Vorfindung,” German: finding; datum. Cf. “vorfinden,” to find. 14. Cf. the further statement of this view in James 1909, The Meaning of Truth (New York: Longmans, Green), p. 49; see also, present ed., “The Essence of Humanism,” pp. 75–76. 15. “Terminus ad quem,” Latin: the point at which something ends or finishes; aim, goal or destination. 16. “Terminus a quo,” Latin: point of origin. 17. For James’s view of “concepts as a co-ordinate realm” of reality, see James 1909, The Meaning of Truth, p. 42, p. 195; James 1909, A Pluralistic Universe (New York: Longmans, Green), pp. 339–340; James 1911, Some Problems of Philosophy (New York: Longmans, Green), pp. 50–57; pp. 67–70. Giving this view the name ‘logical realism,’ he remarks that his philosophy “may be regarded as somewhat eccentric in its attempt to combine logical realism with an otherwise empiricist mode of thought.” See James 1911, Some Problems of Philosophy, p. 106. 18. James’s note: Here as elsewhere the relations are of course experienced relations, members of the same originally chaotic manifold of non-perceptual experience of which the related terms themselves are parts. Cf. “A World of Pure Experience,” present ed., p. 16. 19. James’s note: Of the representative function of non-perceptual experience as a whole, I will say a word in a subsequent article: it leads too far into the general theory of knowledge for much to be said about it in a short paper like this. Cf. “A World of Pure Experience,” present ed., pp. 19ff. 20. “Diremption”: separation, disjunction, division into two. 21. James’s note: Hugo Münsterberg 1900, Grundzüge der Psychologie, vol. 1 (Leipzig: J.A. Barth), p. 48. 22. Hippolyte Taine (1828–1893) was a French critic and historian and a highly regarded exponent of nineteenth-century positivism. He aimed to apply scientific methods to the humanities. 23. Josiah Royce (1855–1916) American philosopher, James’s Harvard colleague and eventual advocate of an “Absolute pragmatism.” 24. James’s note: Cf. Alfred L. Hodder 1901, The Adversaries of the Sceptic (New York: Macmillan), pp. 94–99. 25. James’s note: For simplicity’s sake I confine my exposition to ‘external’ reality. But there is also the system of ideal reality in which the room plays its part. Rela-
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 120
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Notes 121
tions of comparison, of classification, serial order, value, also are stubborn, assign a definite place to the room, unlike the incoherence of its places in the mere rhapsody of our successive thoughts. Cf. present ed., pp. 6ff. 26. “Gedanke,” vs. “Gedachtes,” German: thought vs. what is thought about. 27. It is surely an error to equate the existence or occurrence of an experience, even if undoubted, with its validity, “truth” or veridical character. 28. James’s note: Note the ambiguity of this term, which is taken sometimes objectively and sometimes subjectively. 29. James’s note: In the Psychological Review for July 1904, Dr. R. B. Perry has published a view of Consciousness [“Conceptions and Misconceptions of Consciousness”] which comes nearer to mine than any other with which I am acquainted. At present, Dr. Perry thinks, every field of experience is so much ‘fact.’ It becomes ‘opinion’ or ‘thought’ only in retrospection, when a fresh experience, thinking the same object, alters and corrects it. But the corrective experience becomes itself in turn corrected, and thus experience as a whole is a process in which what is objective originally forever turns subjective, turns into our apprehension of the object. I strongly recommend Dr. Perry’s admirable article to my readers. 30. James’s note: I have given a partial account of the matter in James 1885, “The Function of Cognition,” Mind, n.s., vol. 10, no. 37, pp. 27–44 and in James 1895, “The Knowing of Things Together,” Psychological Review, vol. 2, p. 105. See also C. A. Strong 1904, “A Naturalistic Theory of the Reference of Thought to Reality” in the Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 1, May 12, pp. 253–260. I hope myself very soon to recur to the matter. See present ed., pp. 19ff. 31. Cf. Shadworth Hodgson 1898, The Metaphysic of Experience, vol. 1 (London: Longmans, Green); Hodgson 1878, The Philosophy of Reflection (London: Longmans, Green), bk. 2, ch. 4., §3. 32. The concept of “intentionality,” derives ultimately from Aristotle and the scholastics, and was represented in James’s times by the work of Franz Brentano (1838– 1917). Cf. Brentano 1874/1924/1973, Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint second ed. (Leipzig: Felix Meiner; English translation, New York: Humanities Press). 33. James’s note: [Herbert] Spencer’s proof of his ‘Transfigured Realism,’ his doctrine that there is an absolutely non-mental reality, comes to mind as a splendid instance of the impossibility of establishing radical heterogeneity between thought and thing. All his painfully accumulated points of difference run gradually into their opposites and are full of exceptions. 34. “Durcheinander,” German: confusion. 35. James’s note: I speak here of the complete inner life in which the mind plays freely with its materials. Of course, the mind’s free play is restricted when it seeks to copy real things in real space. 36. If “inner experience” had extension in the same sense, as that which is measured by a foot-rule, then it would have to have the same potential for being determinately measured, say in feet and inches. But an idea or imagined extension need have no determinate, measurable size. 37. Objection: “Water” that does not wet or put out fires, and “fire” that does not burn, are, contrary to James, simply not water or fire. Or, again, if my idea of wet
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 121
5/2/22 10:39 AM
122
Notes
soap is of something wet and slippery, it is nonetheless nonsense to suppose that my idea is wet and slippery. 38. See James on “mental activity trains,” in which thoughts do “work on each other,” p. 132, n32. 39. Objection: Arguably, “motions” which do not obey physical law are no motions at all. The general critical point, then, is that the usage of ordinary words, borrowed in psychological descriptions differ in meaning and pertain to a distinct domain. 40. The topic of “appreciations” is resumed in chapter 5, present ed., pp. 53ff. 41. “Non possumus,” Latin: we cannot. 42. “Intracephalic”: within the head. 43. Cf. James 1890, Principles of Psychology, vol. 1, pp. 299–305; present ed., pp. 64ff.
CHAPTER TWO 1. The chapter is reprinted with the author’s changes from James 1904, Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 1, no. 20, September 29, pp. 533–543; and vol. 1, no. 21, October 13, pp. 561–570. Several pages below have also been reprinted, with some omissions, alterations and additions, in James 1909, The Meaning of Truth, pp. 102–120. The alterations have been adopted in the present text. Cf. James 1909, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 280. 2. “Weltanschauung,” German: worldview. 3. Emphasis on the reality of relations reflects something of American philosopher C. S. Peirce (1839–1914) on “continuity” and “synechism” and ultimately Peirce on the logic of relations. See James 1909, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 398–399; Peirce 1870, “Description of a Notation for the Logic of Relatives,” Memoirs of the American Academy, vol. 9; and Peirce 1880, “On the Algebra of Logic,” American Journal of Mathematics, vol. 3, concerning the logic of relations. 4. Cf. George Berkeley 1710/1878, Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge (London: Wm.Tegg), “Introduction;” David Hume 1748/1894, An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding (Oxford: Clarendon Press), sect. 7, part 2, (Selby-Bigge’s edition, p. 74); James Mill 1829/1869, Analysis of the Phenomena of the Human Mind, second ed. (London: Longman, Green, Reader and Dryer), ch. 8; J. S. Mill 1865, An Examination of Sir William Hamilton’s Philosophy (London: Longmans, Green), ch. 11, 12; W. K. Clifford 1879/1901, Lectures and Essays (New York: Macmillan), pp. 274 ff. 5. “Supernal”: being or coming from on high; located in or belonging to the sky. 6. See present ed., “The Experience of Activity.” 7. James’s note: The psychology books have of late described the facts here with approximate adequacy. I may refer to the chapters on ‘The Stream of Thought’ and on the Self in my own Principles of Psychology, as well as to Shadworth Hodgson 1898, Metaphysic of Experience, vol. 1, ch. 7. and 8. 8. See present ed., “The Thing and Its Relations.” 9. “Saltatory”: proceeding by leaps; discontinuous.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 122
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Notes 123
10. James’s note: For brevity’s sake I altogether omit mention of the type constituted by knowledge of the truth of general propositions. This type has been thoroughly and, so far as I can see, satisfactorily, elucidated in Dewey 1903, Studies in Logical Theory (Chicago: University of Chicago Press). Such propositions are reducible to the S-is-P form; and the ‘terminus’ that verifies and fulfils is the SP in combination. Of course, percepts may be involved in the mediating experiences, or in the ‘satisfactoriness’ of the P in its new position. 11. See present ed., “Does ‘Consciousness’ Exist?” sect. 2, pp. 4–6. 12. James’s note: See James 1885, “On the Function of Cognition,” Mind, vol. 10, no. 37, pp. 27–44, and James 1895, “The Knowing of Things Together,” Psychological Review, vol. 2, no. 2, pp. 105–124. These articles and their doctrine, unnoticed apparently by anyone else, have lately gained favorable comment from Professor Strong. See Strong 1904, “A Naturalistic Theory of the Reference of Thought to Reality,” Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 1. Dr. Dickinson S. Miller has independently thought out the same results. See Miller 1893, “The Meaning of Truth and Error,” Philosophical Review, vol. 2; Miller 1895, “The Confusion of Function and Content in Mental Analysis,” Psychological Review, vol. 2, which Strong accordingly dubs the James-Miller theory of cognition. 13. “Aliunde”: from another source, from elsewhere. 14. Rudolf Hermann Lotze (1817–1881) was a German philosopher and advocate of a theistic idealism. His religious philosophy influenced modern thought by its emphasis on problems of the relations of value and existence. 15. Cf. Lotze 1841, Metaphysik (Leipzig: Weidmann), §§ 37–39, 97, 98, 243. 16. James’s note: Mr. Bradley, not professing to know his absolute aliunde, nevertheless de-realizes Experience by alleging it to be everywhere infected with self-contradiction. His arguments seem almost purely verbal, but this is no place for arguing that point out. Cf. F. H. Bradley 1902, Appearance and Reality (New York: Macmillan); and present ed., “The Thing and Its Relations,” pp. 40–45. 17. See Hippolyte Taine 1872, On Intelligence. T. D. Haye trans. (New York: Holt and Williams). 18. James’s note: Of which all that need be said in this essay is that it also can be conceived as functional, and defined in terms of transitions, or of the possibility of such. Cf. James 1890, Principles of Psychology, vol. 1, pp. 473–480, vol. 2, pp. 337–340; James 1907, Pragmatism (New York: Longmans, Green), p. 265; James 1911, Some Problems of Philosophy, pp. 63–74; James 1909, The Meaning of Truth, pp. 246–247, etc. 19. “Denkmittel,” German: means or materials of thought. 20. “Salto mortale,” from the Italian: death defying leap; fateful or dangerous decision. 21. “Inter alia,” Latin: among other things. 22. Cf. present ed., “The Things and its Relations,” pp. 35ff. 23. James’s “pragmatic method” reflects his interpretation of C. S. Peirce 1878, “How to make our Ideas Clear,” Popular Science Monthly, vol. 12; and the tendency is toward a positivistic account of the method.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 123
5/2/22 10:39 AM
124
Notes
24. That a theory over some particular domain can be provisionally formulated does not guarantee that it will be immediately obvious how it might be tested experimentally; and even if true, its practical consequences may remain equally obscure. 25. “Verbatim et literatim,” Latin: word for word and letter for letter; exactly, literally. 26. “Logomachy”: a dispute about words. 27. “In transitu,” Latin: in transit, while on the way. 28. Cf., “How Two Minds Can Know One Thing.” 29. “Solipsism”: a theory or philosophy that the self can known only its own modifications and/or that only the self exists. 30. “Ipso facto,” Latin: by that very fact or act. 31. James’s note: The notion that our objects are inside of our respective heads is not seriously defensible, so I pass it by. 32. The argument is resumed below, “The Thing and its Relations,” pp. 38ff. This is James’s classic critique of the doctrine of “internal relations” in Absolute Idealism. 33. “Hawser”: a large rope used in mooring or towing a ship. 34. Or, put in more realist terms, there is a question of fact concerning sameness of reference. 35. “In posse,” Latin: in possibility. 36. Dr. Morton Prince (1854–1929), American psychologist and physician, was the founder of the Journal of Abnormal Psychology (1906). Prince had been James’s student and was a member of the Society for Psychic Research. Professor Charles Augustus Strong (1862–1940), American psychologist, panpsychist philosopher, friend and correspondent of William James. 37. James’s note: Our minds and these ejective realities would still have space (or pseudo-space, as I believe Professor Strong calls the medium of interaction between ‘things-in-themselves’) in common. These would exist where, and begin to act where, we locate the molecules, etc., and where we perceive the sensible phenomena explained thereby. Cf. Morton Prince 1885, The Nature of Mind, and Human Automatism (Philadelphia: Lippencott) part 1, ch. 3, 4; C. A. Strong 1903, Why the Mind Has a Body (New York; London: Macmillan), ch. 12. 38. Cf. present ed., “The Experience of Activity,” p. 71; James 1909, A Pluralistic Universe, Lectures 4-7. “Panpsychism” is the philosophical thesis that everything is possessed of soul or mind. 39. James’s note: I have said something of this latter alliance in an article entitled “Humanism and Truth,” in Mind, October 1904. Reprinted in James 1909, The Meaning of Truth, pp. 51–101. Cf. also “Humanism and Truth Once More,” present ed., pp. 97–104.
CHAPTER THREE 1. Reprinted with the author’s amendments from James 1905, Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 2, no. 2, January 19, pp. 29–41. Cf. “Appendix A” in A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 347–369.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 124
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Notes 125
2. “Pyrrhonism,” school of ancient skeptics who suspended judgment on every proposition. 3. Francis Herbert Bradley (1846–1924) English, Absolute Idealist philosopher who was long a leading thinker at Oxford University. 4. James’s note: F. H. Bradley 1902, Appearance and Reality, second edition, pp. 152–153, p. 23, p. 118, p. 104, pp. 108–109, p. 570. 5. James’s note: Compare Professor MacLennan’s admirable Auseinandersetzung with Mr. Bradley, in Simon MacLennan 1904, “Two Illustrations of the Methodological Value of Psychology in Metaphysic,” Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 1, no. 15, pp. 403 ff., especially pp. 405–407. 6. Cf. David Hume 1739/1888, Treatise of Human Nature (Oxford: Clarendon Press), Appendix, Selby-Bigge’s edition, p. 636. 7. James’s note: Technically, it seems classable as a ‘fallacy of composition.’ A duality, predicable of the two wholes, L—M and M—N, is forthwith predicated of one of their parts, M. 8. See pp. 16ff. 9. James’s note: I may perhaps refer here to my Principles of Psychology, vol. 1, pp. 459 ff. It really seems ‘weird’ to have to argue (as I am forced now to do) for the notion that it is one sheet of paper (with its two surfaces and all that lies between) which is both under my pen and on the table while I write—the ‘claim’ that it is two sheets seems so brazen. Yet I sometimes suspect the absolutists of sincerity! 10. For James’s criticism of Hegel’s view of relations, see James 1897, The Will to Believe and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy (New York: Longmans, Green), pp. 278–279. 11. Johann Friedrich Herbart (1776-1841) was a German philosopher, psychologist and educator. Cf. A. Spir 1884, Denken und Wirklichkeit (Leipzig: Findel) part 1, bk. 3, ch. 4. 12. See “A World of Pure Experience,” p. 16; p. 18. 13. James’s note: Here again the reader must beware of slipping from logical into phenomenal considerations. It may well be that we attribute a certain relation falsely, because the circumstances of the case, being complex, have deceived us. At a railway station we may take our own train, and not the one that fills our window, to be moving. We here put motion in the wrong place in the world, but in its original place the motion is a part of reality. What Mr. Bradley means is nothing like this, but rather that such things as motion are nowhere real, and that, even in their aboriginal and empirically incorrigible seats, relations are impossible of comprehension. 14. James’s note: Particularly so by Andrew Seth Pringle-Pattison 1902, Man and the Cosmos (Edinburgh; London: Blackwood); by L. T. Hobhouse 1896, in chapter 12 (“The Validity of Judgment”) of his Theory of Knowledge (London: Methuen); and by F. C. S. Schiller 1903, in his Humanism (London; New York: Macmillan), essay 11. Other fatal reviews (in my opinion) are A. L. Hodder 1894, “Appearance and Reality by F. H. Bradley,” Psychological Review, vol. 1, no. 1–3, p. 307; G.F. Stout, 1901–1902, “Alleged Contradictions in the Concept of Relation,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, vol. 2, no. 1, pp. 1–24; p. 1; and MacLennan 1904, “Two Illustrations of the Methodological Value of Psychology in Metaphysic,” p. 403.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 125
5/2/22 10:39 AM
126
Notes
15. “Pro hac vice,” Latin: for, or on the occasion. 16. James’s note: Once more, don’t slip from logical into physical situations. Of course, if the table be wet, it will moisten the book, or if it be slight enough and the book heavy enough, the book will break it down. But such collateral phenomena are not the point at issue. The point is whether the successive relations ‘on’ and ‘not-on’ can rationally (not physically) hold of the same constant terms, abstractly taken. Professor A. E. Taylor drops from logical into material considerations when he instances color-contrast as a proof that A, ‘as contra-distinguished from B, is not the same thing as mere A not in any way affected,’ Taylor 1899/1903, Elements of Metaphysics (London: Methuen), p. 145. Note the substitution, for ‘related’ of the word ‘affected,’ which begs the whole question. 17. James’s note: But “is there any sense,” asks Mr. Bradley, peevishly, on p. 579, “and if so, what sense in truth that is only outside and ‘about’ things?” Surely such a question may be left unanswered. 18. James’s note: Bradley 1902, Appearance and Reality, second edition, pp. 575–576. 19. Bradley 1902, Appearance and Reality, p. 577. 20. “Und zwar,” German, and in particular . . . ; and specifically . . . 21. James’s note: I say ‘undecided,’ because, apart from the ‘so far,’ which sounds terribly half-hearted, there are passages in these very pages in which Mr. Bradley admits the pluralistic thesis. Read, for example, what he says, on p. 578, of a billiard ball keeping its ‘character’ unchanged, though, in its change of place, its ‘existence’ gets altered; or what he says, on p. 579, of the possibility that an abstract quality A, B, or C, in a thing, ‘may throughout remain unchanged’ although the thing be altered; or his admission that in red-hairedness, both as analyzed out of a man and when given with the rest of him, there may be ‘no change’ (p. 580). Why does he immediately add that for the pluralist to plead the non-mutation of such abstractions would be an ignoratio elenchi. It is impossible to admit it to be such. The entire elenchus and inquest are just as to whether parts which you can abstract from existing wholes can also contribute to other wholes without changing their inner nature. If they can thus mould various wholes into new Gestaltqualitäten, then it follows that the same elements are logically able to exist in different wholes [whether physically able would depend on additional hypotheses]; those partial changes are thinkable, and throughand-through change not a dialectic necessity; that monism is only an hypothesis; and that an additively constituted universe is a rationally respectable hypothesis also. All the theses of radical empiricism, in short, follow. 22. “Machtspruch,” German: claim or pretension to power. 23. “Ipse dixit,” Latin: an assertion left unproven; dogmatic claim. 24. James’s note: F. H. Bradley 1902, Appearance and Reality, pp. 577–579. 25. James’s note: So far as I catch his state of mind, it is somewhat like this: ‘Book,’ ‘table,’ ‘on’—how does the existence of these three abstract elements result in this book being livingly on this table. Why isn’t the table on the book? Or why doesn’t the ‘on’ connect itself with another book, or something that is not a table? Mustn’t something in each of the three elements already determine the two others to it, so that they do not settle elsewhere or float vaguely? Mustn’t the whole fact be
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 126
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Notes 127
pre-figured in each part, and exist de jure before it can exist de facto? But, if so, in what can the jural existence consist, if not in a spiritual miniature of the whole fact’s constitution actuating every partial factor as its purpose? But is this anything but the old metaphysical fallacy of looking behind a fact in esse for the ground of the fact, and finding it in the shape of the very same fact in posse? Somewhere we must leave off with a constitution behind which there is nothing. 26. James’s note: Apply this to the case of ‘book-on-table’! W. J. 27. James’s note: Bradley 1902, Appearance and Reality, p. 570, p. 572. 28. “Proprius motus,” Latin: special or peculiar movement. 29. James’s note: Bradley 1902, Appearance and Reality, p. 568, p. 569. 30. James’s note: Bradley 1902, Appearance and Reality, p. 570. 31. James’s note: How meaningless is the contention that in such wholes (or in ‘book-on-table,’ ‘watch-in-pocket,’ etc.) the relation is an additional entity between the terms, needing itself to be related again to each! Both Bradley (Appearance and Reality, pp. 32–33) and Royce 1899, The World and the Individual (New York: Macmillan), vol. I., p. 128, lovingly repeat this piece of profundity. 32. The ‘why’ and the ‘whence’ are entirely other questions, not under discussion, as I understand Mr. Bradley. Not how experience gets itself born, but how it can be what it is after it is born, is the puzzle. 33. See “A World of Pure Experience,” p. 45.
CHAPTER FOUR 1. Reprinted from James 1905, Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 2, no. 7, March 30, pp. 176–181. 2. James’s note: “A World of Pure Experience,” present ed., pp. 15–33. 3. “Esse is sentiri,” from Latin: its being is what is felt or sensed. 4. James is more explicit on this expression in present edition, pp. 11–12. 5. James’s note: I call them ‘passing thoughts’ in the book—the passage in point is in James 1890, Principles of Psychology, vol. 1, pp. 330–342. 6. James’s note: Shadworth Hodgson has laid great stress on the fact that the minimum of consciousness demands two sub-feelings, of which the second retrospects the first. Cf. the section ‘Analysis of Minima’ in Hodgson 1878, Philosophy of Reflection, vol. 1 (London: Longmans, Green), p. 248; also the chapter entitled “The Moment of Experience” in Hodgson 1898, Metaphysic of Experience, vol. 1 (London: Longmans, Green), p. 34. “We live forward, but we understand backward” is a phrase of Kierkegaard’s which Höffding quotes. Cf. Harald Höffding 1905, “A Philosophical Confession,” Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 2, no. 4, p. 86. 7. “Identitätsphilosophie,” German, a philosophy of identity of subject and object of knowledge. 8. “Beseelung,” German: inspiration, animation. 9. Cf. present ed., “The Essence of Humanism,” p. 51; p. 77. 10. Gustav Theodor Fechner (1801-1887), German physicist and philosopher and a key figure in the founding of psychophysics.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 127
5/2/22 10:39 AM
128
Notes
11. Cf. James 1909, A Pluralistic Universe, Lecture 4, “Concerning Fechner,” and Lecture 5, “The Compounding of Consciousness.”
CHAPTER FIVE 1. Reprinted from James 1905, Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 2, no. 11, May 25, pp. 281–287. 2. “Materia prima,” Latin: prime matter. 3. See also “A World of Pure Experience.” 4. “Reticulation”: network of intricate relations. 5. Notice the decidedly nominalist assumption about classifications. 6. Cf. James 1890, The Principles of Psychology, vol. 2, ch. 25; and James 1894, “The Physical Basis of Emotion,” Psychological Review, vol. 1, p. 516–529. 7. See present ed., “Does ‘Consciousness’ exist?” sec. 7, pp. 12ff. 8. See George Santayana 1896, The Sense of Beauty (New York: Scribners), pp. 47–54. 9. “Jocund”: marked by or suggestive of high spirits or mirth. 10. Cf. Herbert Spencer 1862/1867, First Principles, second ed. (London: Williams and Norgate), Chp. 16, §138, p. 380: Evolution is “a change from an indefinite, incoherent homogeneity, to a definite, coherent heterogeneity, through continuous differentiations.” 11. See Boris Sidis and Simon P. Goodhart 1904, Multiple Personality (New York: D. Appleton), p. 102. 12. Cf. Paul Janet and G. Séailles 1902, History of the Problems of Philosophy, Ada Monahan, trans. (London; New York: Macmillan), part 1, ch. 3. 13. Cf. Rene Descartes 1641, Meditation (many editions) 2; Descartes 1644, Principles of Philosophy (many editions), part 1, 48. 14. Cf. A. E. Taylor 1899/1903, Elements of Metaphysics, bk. 3, ch. 4. 15. Cf. Karl Pearson 1892/1900, The Grammar of Science, second ed. (London: Adam and Charles Black), ch. 3. 16. Is the reality of relations, for James, merely experiential or not? While radical empiricism requires that they be “objective,” it seems that for James, when experience is later “contextualized” this is merely a matter of our temporary or convenient “classifications.” Does the unreality of relations return in this fashion or do our classifications of things (sometimes) enjoy empirical-theoretical justifications? 17. Wilhelm Wundt (1832–1920) was a German physiologist and psychologist and generally recognized as the founder of experimental psychology. See Wundt 1894, “Über psychische Causalität und das Prinzip psychophysischen Parallelismus,” Philosophische Studien. vol. 10, pp. 1–124. 18. James’s note: It is enough for my present purpose if the appreciative characters but seem to act thus. Believers in an activity an sich, other than our mental experiences of activity, will find some farther reflections on the subject in my address on “The Experience of Activity.” 19. “Palmary”: exemplary, outstanding or best instance or example.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 128
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Notes 129
20. Overall, this paragraph belongs to James’s critique of the limitations of introspective methods. It is only because relations also belong to experience that classification into “mental” and “physical” becomes possible; and the point appears to hold without recourse to the Jamesian doctrines of “pure experience” and “radical empiricism.”
CHAPTER SIX 1. James’s Presidential Address to the American Psychological Association, Philadelphia Meeting, December 1904. Reprinted from James 1905, Psychological Review, vol. 12, no. 1, January, pp. 1–17. Also reprinted, with some omissions, as Appendix B, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 370-394. Several pages have also been reprinted in James 1911, Some Problems of Philosophy, p. 212. The present essay is referred to in James 1911, Some Problems, p. 219n. James’s corrections were adopted in the present text. 2. See the references to John Dewey’s work, in the end notes, p. 123; pp. 133–134. 3. Frederick J. E. Woodbridge (1867–1940), Professor of philosophy at Columbia University from 1902, defended a realist, non-reductive naturalism. He was a founding editor in 1904 of the Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods— which later became the Journal of Philosophy. 4. James’s note: F.H. Bradley 1902, Appearance and Reality, second edition, pp. 116–117―Obviously written at Ward, though Ward’s name is not mentioned. 5. James Ward 1887, “Mr. F. H. Bradley’s Analysis of Mind,” Mind, vol. 12, pp. 573–574. 6. “A Verständigung” is “grundsätzlich ausgeschlossen,” German: (our) coming to an understanding is excluded in principle. 7. See Josiah Royce 1897, “G. F. Stout, Analytical Psychology,” Mind, n.s., vol. 6 p. 379–399. 8. Cf. C. S. Peirce 1878, “How to make our Ideas Clear”: “Consider what effects, that might conceivably have practical bearings, we conceive the object of our conception to have. Then, our conception of these effects is the whole of our conception of the object.” 9. James’s note: James Ward 1899, Naturalism and Agnosticism (London: Adam and Charles Black), vol. 2, p. 245. One thinks naturally of the peripatetic actus primus and actus secundus here. “Actus autem est duplex:” says Aquinas, “primus et secundus. Actus quidem primus est forma, et integritas sei. Actus autem secundus est operatio.” Thomas Aquinas 1485/1894, Summa Theologica, edition of Leo XIII. (Rome: Forzani), vol. 1., p. 391. Cf. also Blanc 1909, Dictionnaire de Philosophie (Paris: Lethielleux), under ‘acte.’ 10. F.H. Bradley 1902, Appearance and Reality, second edition, p. 116. 11. See Immanuel Kant 1787/1905, Kritik der reinen Vernunft, in Kant 1905, Werke, vol. 4 (Leipzig: Theodore Voss), p. 110; trans. by Max Müller, second edition (London: Macmillan), p. 128.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 129
5/2/22 10:39 AM
130
Notes
12. James’s note: I refer to such descriptive work as G.T. Ladd 1894/1896, Psychology, Descriptive and Explanatory, part 1, chap. 5, part 2, chap. 11, part 3, chaps. 25 and 26; as J. Sully 1892, The Human Mind (London: Longmans, Green), part 5; as G.F. Stout 1902, Analytic Psychology, 2 vols. (London: Sonnenschein; New York: Macmillan), book 1, chap. 6, and book 2, chaps. 1, 2, and 3; as Bradley’s (in his long series of analytic articles on psychology in Mind); as E. B. Titchener 1906, Outline of Psychology (New York: Macmillan), part 1, chap. 6; as Alexander F. Shand 1894, “An Analysis of Attention,” Mind, n.s., vol. 3, no. 12, p. 449; vol. 4, p. 450; vol. 6, p. 289; as Ward 1887, “Mr. F. H. Bradley’s Analysis of Mind,” Mind, vol. 12, p. 67; p. 564; as Thomas Loveday 1901, “Theories of Mental Activity,” Mind, n.s., vol. 10., no. 1, p. 455; as Lipps 1902, Vom Fühlen, Wollen und Denken (Leipzig: J.A. Barth), chaps. 2, 4, 6; and as Henri Bergson 1902, “L’effort intellectuel,” Revue Philosophique, 53, no. 1, pp. 1–27―to mention only a few writings which I immediately recall. 13. James’s note: Their existence forms a curious commentary on Prof. Münsterberg’s dogma that will-attitudes are not describable. He himself has contributed in a superior way to their description, both in Münsterberg 1888, Willenshandlung (Freiburg i. B.: C. A. Wagner), and in Münsterberg 1900, Grundzüge der Psychologie, part 2, chap. 9, § 7. 14. “Gestaltqualität,” German: quality of an overall form or configuration; “fundierte Inhalt,” German: grounded content. 15. James’s note: I ought myself to cry peccavi [I have sinned!], having been a voluminous sinner in my own chapter on the will, James 1890, Principles of Psychology, vol. 2, chap. 26, “Will.” 16. Cf. F. H. Bradley 1902, Appearance and Reality, second edition, pp. 96-97. 17. “Qualia,” from the Latin: felt qualities of experience. 18. “Gelten,” German (verb), to count or qualify; to count as. 19. Cf. the references to Lotze, “A World of Pure Experience,” p. 28. 20. That is, the percipi, perception of them, constitutes their esse, their being. 21. James’s note: Verborum gratiâ: [Latin: words of grace] “The feeling of activity is not able, quâ feeling, to tell us anything about activity” (Loveday 1901, “Theories of Mental Activity,” Mind, n.s., vol. 10, p. 463); “A sensation or feeling or sense of activity . . . is not, looked at in another way, an experience of activity at all. It is a mere sensation shut up within which you could by no reflection get the idea of activity . . . Whether this experience is or is not later on a character essential to our perception and our idea of activity, it, as it comes first, is not in itself an experience of activity at all. It, as it comes first, is only so for extraneous reasons and only so for an outside observer” (Bradley, Appearance and Reality, second edition, p. 605); “In dem Tätigkeitsgefühle liegt an sich nicht der geringste Beweis für das Vorhandensein einer psychischen Tätigkeit” (Münsterberg 1900, Grundzüge der Psychologie). I could multiply similar quotations and would have introduced some of them into my text to make it more concrete, save that the mingling of different points of view in most of these author’s discussions (not in Münsterberg’s) make it impossible to disentangle exactly what they mean. I am sure in any case, to be accused of misrepresenting them totally, even in this note, by omission of the context, so the less I name names and the more I stick to abstract characterization of a merely possible style of opinion, the safer
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 130
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Notes 131
it will be. And apropos of misunderstandings, I may add to this note a complaint on my own account. Professor Stout 1902, in the excellent chapter on “Mental Activity,” in vol. 1 of his Analytic Psychology, takes me to task for identifying spiritual activity with certain muscular feelings and gives quotations to bear him out. They are from certain paragraphs on ‘the Self,’ in which my attempt was to show what the central nucleus of the activities that we call ‘ours’ is. [James 1890, Principles of Psychology, vol. 1, pp. 299–305.] I found it in certain intracephalic movements which we habitually oppose, as ‘subjective,’ to the activities of the transcorporeal world. I sought to show that there is no direct evidence that we feel the activity of an inner spiritual agent as such (I should now say the activity of ‘consciousness’ as such, see “Does ‘Consciousness’ Exist?”). There are, in fact, three distinguishable ‘activities’ in the field of discussion: the elementary activity involved in the mere that of experience, in the fact that something is going on, and the farther specification of this something into two whats, an activity felt as ‘ours,’ and an activity ascribed to objects. Stout, as I apprehend him, identifies ‘our’ activity with that of the total experience-process, and when I circumscribe it as a part thereof, accuses me of treating it as a sort of external appendage to itself (G.F. Stout 1902, Analytic Psychology, vol. 1, pp. 162–163), as if I ‘separated the activity from the process which is active.’ But all the processes in question are active, and their activity is inseparable from their being. My book raised only the question of which activity deserved the name of ‘ours.’ So far as we are ‘persons,’ and contrasted and opposed to an ‘environment,’ movements in our body figure as our activities; and I am unable to find any other activities that are ours in this strictly personal sense. There is a wider sense in which the whole ‘choir of heaven and furniture of the earth,’ and their activities, are ours, for they are our ‘objects.’ But ‘we’ are here only another name for the total process of experience, another name for all that is, in fact; and I was dealing with the personal and individualized self exclusively in the passages with which Professor Stout finds fault. The individualized self, which I believe to be the only thing properly called self, is a part of the content of the world experienced. The world experienced (otherwise called the ‘field of consciousness’) comes at all times with our body as its center, center of vision, center of action, center of interest. Where the body is, is ‘here’; when the body acts is ‘now’; what the body touches is ‘this’; all other things are ‘there’ and ‘then’ and ‘that.’ These words of emphasized position imply a systematization of things with reference to a focus of action and interest which lies in the body; and the systematization is now so instinctive (was it ever not so?) that no developed or active experience exists for us at all except in that ordered form. So far as ‘thoughts’ and ‘feelings’ can be active, their activity terminates in the activity of the body, and only through first arousing its activities can they begin to change those of the rest of the world. [Cf. also James 1909, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 344, note 8.] The body is the storm center, the origin of co-ordinates, the constant place of stress in all that experience-train. Everything circles round it and is felt from its point of view. The word ‘I,’ then, is primarily a noun of position, just like ‘this’ and ‘here.’ Activities attached to ‘this’ position have prerogative emphasis, and, if activities have feelings, must be felt in a peculiar way. The word ‘my’ designates the kind of emphasis. I see no inconsistency whatever in defending, on the one hand, ‘my’ activities as unique
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 131
5/2/22 10:39 AM
132
Notes
and opposed to those of outer nature, and, on the other hand, in affirming, after introspection, that they consist in movements in the head. The ‘my’ of them is the emphasis, the feeling of perspective-interest in which they are dyed. 22. “Überhaupt,” German: in general, at all. 23. See Robert Louis Stevenson “Lay Morals,” in Stevenson 1914, Lay Morals and Other Essays (London: Chatto), p. 19. 24. “Cessante causa, cessat et effectus,” Latin: when the cause ceases, the effect must (also) cease. 25. David Hume 1748/1894, Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding (Oxford: Clarendon Press), sect. 7, part 1, Selby-Bigge’s edition, pp. 65 ff. 26. “Vagi nerves,” from Latin: variant of “vagus nerves,” literally, wandering (brain) nerves, chiefly serving autonomic functions. 27. “Interstitial”: located between, in the interconnections or the interstices. 28. “Modus operandi,” from the Latin: method or mode of operation. 29. “Thrombus of the meningeal artery”: blockage of the blood supply, a stroke. 30. See p. 66. 31. “In flagrante delicto,” Latin: caught in the obvious or guilty act. 32. James’s note: Let me not be told that this contradicts, “Does Consciousness Exist?” (see especially present ed., section 6, pp. 10ff), in which it was said that while ‘thoughts’ and ‘things’ have the same natures, the natures work ‘energetically’ on each other in the things (fire burns, water wets, etc.) but not in the thoughts. Mental activity-trains are composed of thoughts, yet their members do work on each other, they check, sustain, and introduce. They do so when the activity is merely associational as well as when effort is there. But, and this is my reply, they do so by other parts of their nature than those that energize physically. One thought in every developed activity-series is a desire or thought of purpose, and all the other thoughts acquire a feeling tone from their relation of harmony or oppugnancy to this. The interplay of these secondary tones (among which ‘interest,’ ‘difficulty,’ and ‘effort’ figure) runs the drama in the mental series. In what we term the physical drama these qualities play absolutely no part. The subject needs careful working out; but I can see no inconsistency. 33. James’s note: I have found myself more than once accused in print of being the assertor of a metaphysical principle of activity. Since literary misunderstandings retard the settlement of problems, I should like to say that such an interpretation of the pages I have published on Effort and on Will is absolutely foreign to what I meant to express. [See James 1890, Principles of Psychology, vol. 2 ch. 26] I owe all my doctrines on this subject to Renouvier; and Renouvier, as I understand him, is (or at any rate then was) an out and out phenomenist, a denier of ‘forces’ in the most strenuous sense. [Cf. Renouvier 1885, Esquisse d’une Classification Systématique des Doctrines Philosophiques (Paris: Au Bureau de la critique Philosophique), vol. 2, pp. 390–392; 1859, Essais de Critique Générale (Paris: Au bureau de la Critique), vol. 2, §§ 9, 13. For an acknowledgment of the author’s general indebtedness to Renouvier, cf. James 1911, Some Problems of Philosophy, p. 165n.] Single clauses in my writing, or sentences read out of their connection, may possibly have been compatible with a trans-phenomenal principle of energy; but I defy anyone to show a single sentence
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 132
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Notes 133
which, taken with its context, should be naturally held to advocate that view. The misinterpretation probably arose at first from my defending (after Renouvier) the indeterminism of our efforts. ‘Free will’ was supposed by my critics to involve a supernatural agent. As a matter of plain history, the only ‘free will’ I have ever thought of defending is the character of novelty in fresh activity-situations. If an activity-process is the form of a whole ‘field of consciousness,’ and if each field of consciousness is not only in its totality unique (as is now commonly admitted) but has its elements unique (since in that situation they are all dyed in the total) then novelty is perpetually entering the world and what happens there is not pure repetition, as the dogma of the literal uniformity of nature requires. Activity-situations come, in short, each with an original touch. A ‘principle’ of free will if there were one, would doubtless manifest itself in such phenomena, but I never saw, nor do I now see, what the principle could do except rehearse the phenomenon beforehand, or why it ever should be invoked. 34. James’s note: Josiah Royce 1897, “G. F. Stout, Analytical Psychology,” Mind, n.s., vol. 6; cf. pp. 392–393. 35. Cf. James 1909, A Pluralistic Universe, Lecture 6 (on Bergson); Henri Bergson 1907/1911, Creative Evolution, trans. by A. Mitchell; C. A. Strong 1903, Why the Mind has a Body, ch. 12.
CHAPTER SEVEN 1. Reprinted with James’s amendments from James 1905, Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 2, no. 5, March 2, pp. 113–118. Also reprinted, with slight changes in James 1909, The Meaning of Truth, pp. 121–135. The author’s corrections were adopted for the present text. The article was written apropos of the appearance of three articles in Mind, n.s., vol. 14, no. 53: H. H. Joachim 1905, “‘Absolute’ and ‘Relative’ Truth,” pp. 1–14; H. W. B. Joseph 1905, “Professor James on ‘Humanism and Truth,’” pp. 28–41; Arthur Sidgwick 1905, “Applied Axioms,” pp. 42–57. Of these articles the second and third “continue the humanistic (or pragmatistic) controversy,” the first “deeply connects with it.” 2. James’s note: Professor Baldwin, for example. His address, Baldwin 1898, “On Selective Thinking,” Psychological Review, vol. 5, pp. 1–24, reprinted in his volume, Baldwin 1902, Development and Evolution (New York; London: Macmillan), seems to me an unusually well-written pragmatic manifesto. Nevertheless, in Baldwin 1904, “The Limits of Pragmatism,” Psychological Review, vol. 11, pp. 30–60, he (much less clearly) joins in the attack. 3. James’s note: The ethical changes, it seems to me, are beautifully made evident in Professor [John] Dewey’s series of articles, which will never get the attention they deserve till they are printed in a book. I mean: Dewey 1895, “The Significance of Emotions,” Psychological Review, vol. 2, pp. 13–32; Dewey 1896, “The Reflex Arc Concept in Psychology,” Psychological Review, vol. 3, pp. 357–370; Dewey 1900, “Psychology and Social Practice,” Psychological Review, vol. 8, pp. 105–124; Dewey 1902, “Interpretation of Savage Mind,” Psychological Review, vol. 9, p. 217–230; Dewey 1892, “Green’s Theory of the Moral Motive,” Philosophical Review, vol.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 133
5/2/22 10:39 AM
134
Notes
1, pp. 593–612; Dewey 1893, “Self-realization as the Moral Ideal,” Philosophical Review, vol. 2, p. 652–664; Dewey 1897, “The Psychology of Effort,” Philosophical Review, vol. 6, pp. 43–56; Dewey 1902, “The Evolutionary Method as Applied to Morality,” Philosophical Review, vol. 11, pp. 107–124; 35–-371; Dewey 1898, “Evolution and Ethics,” Monist, vol. 8, pp. 321–341; to mention only a few. 4. F. C. S. Schiller (1864–1937) was an English philosopher who studied and taught at Oxford University and later in the United States. He called his philosophy both humanism and pragmatism. 5. James employs the term ‘humanism’ either as a synonym for ‘radical empiricism’ (cf. e.g., above, “The Experience of Activity,” p. 61); or as that general philosophy of life of which ‘radical empiricism’ is the theoretical ground (cf. below, in the present essay, p. 74). For other discussions of ‘humanism,’ cf. below, essay 11, “Humanism and Truth once More,” and James 1909, The Meaning of Truth, essay 3, “Humanism and Truth.” 6. The line was omitted from the reprint in James 1909, The Meaning of Truth. The articles referred to are “Does ‘Consciousness’ Exist?” and “A World of Pure Experience.” 7. James’s note: Frederick J. E. Woodbridge 1904, “The Field of Logic,” Science, November 4, p. 599. 8. James’s note: This statement is probably excessively obscure to anyone who has not read my two articles, “Does Consciousness Exist?” and “A World of Pure Experience.” 9. Cf. “How Two Minds can know one Thing,” p. 51; and in the present essay, p. 75. 10. Cf. p. 51; p. 75. 11. “Trower,” believer, from “trow”: faithful, true. Compare: “I pledge thee my trow.” 12. “Apperception”: perception or understanding of something based on prior experience. 13. H. W. B. Joseph, (1867–1943) British philosopher at Oxford University. 14. The line was omitted from the reprint in James 1909, The Meaning of Truth. The review referred to is reprinted in present edition, pp. 97–104, under the title “Humanism and Truth Once More.”
CHAPTER EIGHT 1. An address given in French at the Fifth International Congress of Psychology, in Rome, April 30, 1905. and reprinted from the Archives de Psychologie, vol. 5, no. 17, June, 1905. Cette communication est le résumé, forcément très condensé, de vues que l’auteur a exposées, au cours de ces derniers mois, en une série d’articles publiés dans le Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, 1904–1905. (English translations of this piece are widely available in academic libraries; as is customary, the present edition stays with the original French text.) 2. “Esse est percipi,” Latin: To be is to be perceived.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 134
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Notes 135
3. George Santayana 1896, The Sense of Beauty (New York: Scribners), pp. 44 ff. 4. George Santayana 1905–1906, The Life of Reason, vol. 1, Reason in Common Sense (New York: Scribners), p. 142.
CHAPTER NINE 1. “Sachgemäss,” German: appropriate to the subject-matter. 2. Cf. B. H. Bode 1905, “‘Pure Experience’ and the External World,” Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 2, p. 128–133. 3. Reprinted from James 1905, Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 2., no. 9, April 27, pp. 235–238. 4. “Term a quo,” from Latin: the term from which something starts. 5. “Terminus ad quem,” Latin: the point at which something ends or finishes; aim, goal or destination. 6. “Noetically”: in thought, intellectually; “noetically there”: present in thought. 7. James appears to equivocate on the question of whether his “conjunctive relations” require the existence of any particular accusative term. Is “direction toward” a (non-existing) object a genuine relation, or is it instead an (intransitive) characterization of content? 8. James’s reference: Harald Höffding 1905, “A Philosophical Confession,” Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 2, no. 4, February issue, pp. 85–92.
CHAPTER TEN 1. Reprinted from James 1906, 1907, Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 3, no. 26, December 20, p. 712; and vol. 4, no. 4, February 14, where the original is entitled “A Reply to Mr. Pitkin.” See W. B. Pitkin 1906, “A Problem of Evidence in Radical Empiricism,” Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 3, no. 24, November 22, pp. 645–650. 2. Above, “A World of Pure Experience.” 3. James Fredrick Ferrier (1808-1864) Scottish, idealist philosopher who taught at the University of St. Andrews. See, for instance, Ferrier1854, Institutes of Metaphysic, the Theory of Knowing and Being (Edinburgh and London: W. Blackwood). 4. W. B. Pitkin 1907, “In Reply to Professor James,” Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 4, no. 2, January 17, pp. 44–45. 5. James’s note: Mr. Pitkin inserts the clause: ‘by reason of the very nature of experience itself.’ Not understanding just what reason is meant, I do not include this clause in my answer. 6. See above, “The Essence of Humanism,” p. 74. 7. Elsewhere, in speaking of ‘reality’ as “conceptual or perceptual experiences,” the author says: “This is meant merely to exclude reality of an ‘unknowable’ sort, of
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 135
5/2/22 10:39 AM
136
Notes
which no account in either perceptual or conceptual terms can be given. It includes, of course, any amount of empirical reality independent of the knower.” See, James 1909, The Meaning of Truth, p. 100.
CHAPTER ELEVEN 1. Reprinted from Mind 1905, n.s., vol. 14, no. 54, April issue, pp. 190–198. See the criticism of James in H. W. B. Joseph 1905, “Professor James on ‘Humanism and Truth,’” Mind, n.s., vol. 14, no. 53, January issue, pp. 28–41. James 1904, “Humanism and Truth” first appeared in Mind, n.s., vol. 13, no. 52, October issue, pp. 457–475. 2. “Minus nequit gignere plus,” Latin: the lesser cannot generate the greater. 3. Joseph 1905, “James on ‘Humanism and Truth,’” p. 37. 4. Cf. present ed., “Mr. Pitkin’s Refutation of ‘Radical Empiricism,’” pp. 95–96. 5. “Ergo,” Latin: therefore. 6. “Qua,” from the Latin: as; conceived as. 7. Joseph 1905, “James on ‘Humanism and Truth,’” p. 32. 8. “Causa existendi,” Latin: the cause of the existence of something. 9. “Causa cognoscendi,” Latin: the cause of (our) understanding of something. 10. James’s note: Mr. Joseph deals with this (though in much too pettifogging and logic-chopping a way) on pp. 33–34 of his article. 11. “Ding an sich,” German: thing in itself. 12. James’s note: Compare some elaborate articles by M. [Edouard] Le Roy [“Science et philosophie,” “Un Positivisme nouveau,” (and replies to objections)] and M. [Joseph] Wilbois [“La méthode des sciences physiques” and “L’esprit positif”] 1900, 1901, 1902 Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale, vols. 8, 9, and 10. 13. Cf. James 1909, The Meaning of Truth, p. 64. 14. Joseph 1905, “James on ‘Humanism and Truth,’” p. 36. 15. James’s note: Most recently in two articles, “Does ‘Consciousness’ Exist?” and “A World of Pure Experience.” 16. James’s note: For a recent attempt, effective on the whole, at squaring humanism with knowing, I may refer to Prof. Woodbridge’s very able address at the Saint Louis Congress, “The Field of Logic,” printed in Science, NY, November 4, 1904. 17. “Synoptical”: affording a general view of a whole.
CHAPTER TWELVE 1. “Terre-à-terre,” French: down to earth. 2. Reprinted from Mind 1884, vol. 9, no. 34, April issue, pp. 281–286. See the journal Mind for 1884. 3. John Scott Haldane (1860–1936), British physiologist and philosopher. 4. J.S. Haldane 1884, “Life and Mechanism,” Mind, vol. 9, no. 33, pp. 27–47.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 136
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Notes 137
5. “Caput mortuum,” Latin: dead head; worthless remains. 6. Cf. Paul Janet and G. Séailles: History of the Problems of Philosophy (London; New York: Macmillan) vol. 2, pp. 275–278; 305–307. 7. “Anselmian proof”: the “ontological argument” due to St. Anselm (1033– 1109); here, the notion that the existence of the idealists’ Absolute follows from its definition. 8. “Am Anfang war das Wort,” German: In the beginning was the word. 9. “Am Anfang war die Tat,” German: In the beginning was the act. 10. “Ab extra,” Latin: from outside; in addition. 11. “Orson”: an old French, masculine, given name meaning bear-like. 12. “Ever not quite,” as James later put the matter of his pluralism. 13. “Ich kann nicht anders,” German: I can do no other.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 137
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 138
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Bibliography
Angell, James Rowland (1903) “The Relations of Structural and Functional Psychology to Philosophy,” Investigations Representing the Departments. University of Chicago, The Decennial Publications, First Series. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 55–73. Reprinted (1903) Philosophical Review, vol. 12, no. 3, May issue, pp. 243–271. ———. (1906) Psychology: An Introductory Study of the Structure and Function of Human Consciousness. fourth ed. New York: Henry Holt. ———. (1907) “The Province of Functional Psychology,” Psychological Review, vol. 14, no. 2, pp. 61–91. ———. (1909) “The Influence of Darwin on Psychology,” Psychological Review, vol. 16, no. 3, pp. 152–169. Aquinas, St. Thomas (1485/1886/1893) Summa Theologica. Pope Leo XIII., ed. Rome: Forzani. Baldwin, James Mark (1898) “On Selective Thinking,” Psychological Review, vol. 5, no. 1, pp. 1–24. ———. (1902) Development and Evolution. New York; London: Macmillan. ———. (1904) “The Limits of Pragmatism,” Psychological Review, vol. 11, no. 1, pp. 30–60. ———. (1909) Darwin and the Humanities. Baltimore, MD: Review Publishing. Bergson, Henri (1889) Essai sur les données immédiates de la conscience. Paris: F. Alcan; (1910) Time and Free Will: An Essay on the Immediate Data of Consciousness. London: Allen and Unwin; New York: Macmillan. ———. (1896) Matière et mémoire: Essai sur la relation du corps à l’esprit; (1911) Matter and Memory. Paul, Nancy M. and W. Scott Palmer trans. New York: Macmillan. ———. (1900) Le Rire: Essai sur la signifiance du comique. Paris : F. Alcan; (1911) Laughter: An Essay on the Meaning of the Comic. New York: Macmillan.
139
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 139
5/2/22 10:39 AM
140
Bibliography
———. (1903) Introduction à la métaphysique; (1909) Einführung in die Metaphysik. Jena: E. Diedericks; (1912) An Introduction to a New Philosophy. Boston: J. W. Luce. ———. (1907/1911) L’évolution créatrice. Paris: F. Alcan; Creative Evolution, Mitchell, Arthur trans. New York: Henry Holt; (1983) Reprint of the 1911 trans. Lanham, MD: University Press of America. Bjork, Daniel W. (1983) The Compromised Scientist, William James in the Development of American Psychology. New York: Columbia University Press. Blanc, Elle (1909) Dictionnaire de Philosophie ancienne, moderne et contemporaine. Paris: Lethielleux. Block, Ned (1978/2007) “Troubles with Functionalism,” originally published in Savage, C.W., ed. (1978) Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 9. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 261–325; reprinted with revisions in Block, Ned (2007) Consciousness, Function and Representation, Collected Papers. vol. 1 Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 63–101. ———. (1997/2007) “Functionalism,” reprinted in Block, Ned (2007) Consciousness, Function and Representation, Collected Papers. vol. 1 Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 15–26. Block, Ned, Owen Flanagan and Güven Güzeldere, eds. (1997) The Nature of Consciousness, Philosophical Debates. Cambridge, MA. MIT Press. Bode, Boyd Henry (1905) “‘Pure Experience’ and the External World,” Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 2, pp. 128–133. Bradley, Francis Herbert (1902) Appearance and Reality. Second edition. London: Sonnenschein; New York: Macmillan. Brentano, Franz (1874) Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt. Leipzig: Duncker and Humblot; (1924) Second ed. Leipzig: Felix Meiner; (1973) Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint. Rancurello, A. C., D. B. Terrell and Linda L. McAlister trans. New York: Humanities Press. Bridgman, Percy Williams (1927) The Logic of Modern Physics. New York; reprinted (1980) New York: Arno Press. Byrne, Alex and David R. Hilbert (2010) “How do Things Look to the Colorblind?” in Cohen, Jonathan and Mohan Matthen, eds. (2010) Color Ontology and Color Science. Cambridge, MA and London: MIT Press, pp. 259–288. Clifford, William Kingdon (1901) Lectures and Essays. 2 vols. London; New York: Macmillan. Danziger, Kurt (1980) “The History of Introspection Reconsidered,” Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, vol. 16, pp. 241–262. Davidson, Donald (1970) “Mental Events,” in Davidson (1980) Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 207–228. ———. (1993) “Thinking Causes,” in J. Heil and A. Mele, eds. (1993) Mental Causation. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 3–17; reprinted in Davidson (2005) Truth, Language and History. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 185–200. ———. (2004) “Problems in the Explanation of Action,” in Davidson, Donald (2004) Problems of Rationality (Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press), pp. 101–116.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 140
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Bibliography 141
Dehaene, Stanislas, ed. (2001) The Cognitive Neuroscience of Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. ———. (2011) The Number Sense, How the Mind Creates Mathematics. Revised ed. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. ———. (2014) Consciousness and the Brain. New York: Penguin. ———. (2020) How We Learn, Why Brains Learn Better than any Machine . . . for Now. New York: Viking. Descartes, René (1641) Meditations; (2017) Meditations on First Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ———. (1644) Principles of Philosophy; (1986) Principles of Philosophy, Miller, V. R. and R. P. Miller trans. Boston, MA: Reidel. Dewey, John (1892) “Green’s Theory of the Moral Motive,” Philosophical Review, vol. 1, November issue, pp. 593–612. ———. (1893) “Self-realization as the Moral Ideal,” Philosophical Review, vol. 2, November issue, pp. 652–664. ———. (1895) “The Significance of Emotions,” Psychological Review, vol. 2, pp. 3–32. ———. (1896) “The Reflex Arc Concept in Psychology,” Psychological Review, vol. 3, July issue, pp. 357–370. ———. (1897) “The Psychology of Effort,” Philosophical Review, vol. 6, pp. 43–56. ———. (1898) “Evolution and Ethics,” The Monist, vol. 8, April issue, pp. 321–341. ———. (1900) “Psychology and Social Practice,” Psychological Review, vol. 7, pp. 105–124. ———. (1902) “Interpretation of Savage Mind,” Psychological Review, vol. 9, pp. 217–230. ———. (1902) “The Evolutionary Method as Applied to Morality,” Philosophical Review, vol. 11, pp. 107–124; 353–371. ———. (1903) Studies in Logical Theory. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ———. (1930) “Conduct and Experience,” in Murchison, C., ed. (1930) Psychologies of 1930. Worcester, MA: Clark University Press; reprinted in John Dewey, The Later Works, vol. 5, pp. 218–235. Farthing, G. William (1992) The Psychology of Consciousness. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Ferrier, James (1854) Institutes of Metaphysic, the Theory of Knowing and Being. Edinburgh and London: W. Blackwood. Flournoy, Theodore (1911/1917) The Philosophy of William James. New York: Henry Holt. Gibson, Eleanor J. et al. (1999) “Perceptual Development,” in Wilson, R. A. and F. C. Kiel, eds. (1999) The MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 632–635. Green, Christopher D. (1992) “Of Immortal Mythological Beasts: Operationism in Psychology,” Theory and Psychology, vol. 2, pp. 291–320. ———. (2009) “Darwinian Theory, Functionalism and the First American Psychological Revolution,” American Psychologist, vol. 64, no. 2, pp. 75–83.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 141
5/2/22 10:39 AM
142
Bibliography
Güzeldere, Güven (1997) “The Many Faces of Consciousness: A Field Guide,” in Block, Ned, Owen Flanagan and Güven Güzeldere, eds. (1997) The Nature of Consciousness, Philosophical Debates, pp. 1–67. Haldane, John Scott (1884) “Life and Mechanism,” Mind, n.s. vol. 9, no. 33, pp. 27–47. Hobhouse, Leonard T. (1896) Theory of Knowledge, A Contribution to some Problems of Logic and Metaphysics. London: Methuen. Hodder, Alfred L. (1894) “Appearance and Reality by F. H. Bradley,” Psychological Review, vol. 1, no. 1–3, pp. 307–311. ———. (1901) The Adversaries of the Sceptic, or The Specious Present, A new Inquiry into Human Knowledge. London: Sonnenschein; New York: Macmillan. Hodgson, Shadworth Hollway (1878) The Philosophy of Reflection. 3 vols. London: Longmans, Green. ———. (1898) Metaphysic of Experience. 4 vols. London: Longmans, Green. Höffding, Harald (1905) “A Philosophical Confession,” Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 2, no 4, February issue, pp. 85–92. Hook, Sidney (1927) The Metaphysics of Pragmatism; (1996) Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books. Hume, David (1739/1888) Treatise of Human Nature. Selby-Bigge’s edition. Oxford: Clarendon Press. ———. (1748/1894) An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. Selby-Bigge’s edition. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Jack, Anthony I. and Tim Shallice (2001) “Introspective Physicalism as an Approach to the Science of Consciousness,” in Stanislas Dehaene, ed. (2001) The Cognitive Neuroscience of Consciousness, pp. 161–196. James, William (1884) “On some Omissions of Introspective Psychology,” Mind, n.s., vol. 9, no. 33, pp. 1–26. ———. (1884) “Absolutism and Empiricism,” Mind, n.s. vol. 9, no. 34, April issue, pp. 281–286. ———. (1885) “On the Function of Cognition,” Mind, n.s., vol. 10, no. 37, January issue, pp. 27–44. Reprinted in James (1909) The Meaning of Truth, pp. 1–42. ———. (1890) The Principles of Psychology. 2 vols. New York: Henry Holt; (1950) Reprinted. New York: Dover; (1981) The Principles of Psychology. 3 vols. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. ———. (1892) Psychology, the Briefer Course. New York: Henry Holt; London: Macmillan; (1961) Allport, Gordon, ed. (selections) New York: Harper; (1985) Reprinted. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press. ———. (1894) “The Physical Basis of Emotion,” Psychological Review, vol. 1, pp. 516–529. ———. (1895) “The Knowing of Things Together,” Psychological Review, vol. 2, no. 2, pp. 105–124. ———. (1897) The Will to Believe and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy. New York: Longmans, Green; (1956) Reprinted. New York: Dover Publications. ———. (1904) “Humanism and Truth,” Mind, n.s., vol. 13, no. 52, October issue, pp. 457–475.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 142
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Bibliography 143
———. (1905) “The Experience of Activity,” Psychological Review, vol. 12, no. 1, January issue, pp. 1–17. ———. (1905) “The Thing and its Relations,” Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 2, no. 2, January 19, pp. 29–41. ———. (1905) “Humanism and Truth Once More,” Mind, n. s., vol. 14, no. 54, April issue, pp. 190–198. ———. (1905) “La Notion de Conscience,” Archives de Psychologie, vol. 5, no. 17, June issue, pp. 1–12. ———. (1905) “Is Radical Empiricism Solipsistic?” Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 2, no. 9, April 27, pp. 235–238. ———. (1905) “The Place of Affectional Facts in a World of Pure Experience,” Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 2, no. 11, May 25, pp. 281–287. ———. (1905) “The Essence of Humanism,” Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 2, no. 5, March 2, pp. 113–118. ———. (1905) “How Two Minds can Know One Thing,” Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 2, no. 7, March 30, pp. 176–181. ———. (1906) “Mr. Pitkin’s Refutation of ‘Radical Empiricism,’” Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 3, no. 26, December 20, p. 712. ———. (1907) Pragmatism: A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking. New York: Longmans, Green; (1955) Reprinted with four essays from The Meaning of Truth. New York: New American Library. ———. (1909) A Pluralistic Universe. Hibbert Lectures at Manchester College on the Present Situation in Philosophy. New York: Longmans, Green; (1914) Das Pluralistische Universum. Goldstein, J. trans. Leipzig: A. Kröner; (1994) German translation reprinted. Schubert, K. and U. Wilkesmann intro. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft; (1977) In The Works of William James, vol. 4, Bowers, F. and I. K. Skrupskelis, eds. Bernstein, Richard intro. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; (1996) Reprint of the 1909 ed. Levinson, S. intro. Lincoln, NB and London: University of Nebraska Press; (2008) Callaway, H. G. ed and Intro. Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing. ———. (1911) The Meaning of Truth: A Sequel to “Pragmatism.” New York: Longmans, Green; (1977) Reprinted. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books. ———. (1911) Some Problems of Philosophy: A Beginning of an Introduction to Philosophy. New York: Longmans, Green; (1996) Reprinted, Lincoln, NB and London: University of Nebraska Press. ———. (1912) Essays in Radical Empiricism. Perry, R. B., ed. New York: Longmans, Green; (1996) Reprinted. Lincoln, NB and London: University of Nebraska Press. Janet, Paul and Gabriel Séailles (1902) History of the Problems of Philosophy. Monahan, Ada trans. London; New York: Macmillan. Joachim, Harald Henry (1905) “‘Absolute’ and ‘Relative’ Truth,” Mind, n.s., vol. 14, no. 53, January issue, pp. 1–14. Joseph, Horace William Brindley (1905) “Professor James on ‘Humanism and Truth,’” Mind, n.s., vol. 14, no. 53, January issue, pp. 28–41.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 143
5/2/22 10:39 AM
144
Bibliography
Kant, Immanuel (1781, 1787) Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Riga: Johann Friedrich Hartknoch; (1838-1842) Sämtliche Werke, vol. 4. Leipzig: Voss, Theodore; (1881/1896) Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason. 2 vols. Müller, F. Max, trans. London: Macmillan; (1978) Critique of Pure Reason. London: Macmillan. Kanwisher, Nancy (2017) “The Quest for the FFA and Where it Led,” Journal of Neuroscience, vol. 37, no. 5, pp. 1056–1061. Kim, Jaegwon (2003) “Philosophy of Mind and Psychology,” in Ludwig, K., ed. (2003) Donald Davidson. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 113–136. Koch, Christof (2004) The Quest for Consciousness, A Neurobiological Approach. Englewood, CO: Roberts Publishing. ———. (2020) The Feeling of Life itself, Why Consciousness Is Widespread but Can’t Be Computed. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Külpe, Oswald (1895/1901) Outlines of Psychology, Based upon the Results of Experimental Investigation. Titchener, E. B. trans. London: Swan Sonnenschein; New York: Macmillan. Ladd, George Turnbull (1887) Elements of Physiological Psychology: A Treatise on the Activities and Nature of the Mind from the Physical and Experimental Point of View. London: Longmans, Green. ———. (1894/1896) Psychology, Descriptive and Explanatory. New York: Scribners. Le Roy, Edouard (1899-1900) “Science et philosophie,” Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale, vol. 7, pp. 375–425, 503–562, 708–731; vol. 8, pp. 37–72. ———. (1901) “Un Positivisme nouveau,” Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale, vol. 9, pp. 138–153. Levin, Janet (2018) “Functionalism,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https: // plato. stanford.edu. Liebmann, Otto (1876) Zur Analysis der Wirklichkeit, eine philosophische Untersuchung. Straßburg: Trübner. Lipps, Theodor (1902) Vom Fühlen, Wollen und Denken, Eine psychologische Skizze. Leipzig: J. A. Barth. Locke, John (1690) An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. London; (1975) Nidditch, H. P., ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Lotze, Rudolph Hermann (1841) Metaphysik. Leipzig: Weidmann. Loveday, Thomas (1901) “Theories of Mental Activity,” Mind, n.s., vol. 10, no. 1, pp. 455–478. Ludwig, Kirk, ed. (2003) Donald Davidson. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press. MacLennan, Simon F. (1904) “Two Illustrations of the Methodological Value of Psychology in Metaphysic,” Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 1, no. 15, pp. 403–411. McDermott, John J. (1976) “Introduction” to James, William (1976) Essays in Radical Empiricism, in The Works of William James, vol. 3. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. xi–xlviii. Myers, Gerald E. (1986) William James: His Life and Thought. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 144
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Bibliography 145
———. (1997) “Pragmatism and Introspective Psychology,” in Putnam, Ruth A., ed. (1997) The Cambridge Companion to William James, pp. 11–24. Mill, James (1829) Analysis of the Phenomena of the Human Mind. 2 vols; (1869) second ed. London: Longman, Green, Reader and Dryer. Mill, John Stuart (1865) An Examination of Sir William Hamilton’s Philosophy. Second edition. London: Longmans, Green. ———. (1882) Auguste Comte and Positivism. third edition. London: Trübner. Miller, Dickinson Sergeant (1893) “The Meaning of Truth and Error,” Philosophical Review, vol. 2, no. 4, pp. 408–425. ———. (1895) “The Confusion of Function and Content in Mental Analysis,” Psychological Review, vol. 2, pp. 535–550. Moore, George Edward (1903) “The Refutation of Idealism,” Mind, n.s., vol. 12, no. 48, pp. 433–453. Münsterberg, Hugo (1888) Willenshandlung. Freiburg i. B.: C. A. Wagner. ———. (1900) Grundzüge der Psychologie. Leipzig: J. A. Barth. Natorp, Paul (1888) Einleitung in die Psychologie nach kritischer Methode. Freiburg i. B.: Mohr. Owen, Adrian (2017) Into the Gray Zone, A Neuroscientist Explores the Border between Life and Death. New York: Scribner. Parvizi, Josef, Jacques Corentin, Brett L. Foster, Nathan Withoft, Vinitha Rangarajan, Kevin S. Weiner and Kalmit Grill-Spector (2012), “Electrical Stimulation of Human Fusiform Face-selective Regions Distorts Face Recognition,” The Journal of Neuroscience, vol. 32, pp. 14915–14920. Pearson, Karl (1892) The Grammar of Science; (1900) Second edition. London: Adam and Charles Black. Peirce, Charles Sanders (1870) “Description of a Notation for the Logic of Relatives, Resulting from an Amplification of the Conceptions of Boole’s Calculus of Logic,” Memoirs of the American Academy, vol. 9, pp. 317–378. ———. (1878) “How to Make Our Ideas Clear,” Popular Science Monthly, vol. 12, January issue, pp. 286–302. Reprinted in Buchler, Justus, ed. (1955) Philosophical Writings of Peirce. New York: Dover, pp. 23–41. ———. (1880) “On the Algebra of Logic,” American Journal of Mathematics, vol. 3, pp. 15–57. ———. (1933) Collected Papers vol. 3. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. ———. (1955) Philosophical Writings of Peirce. Buchler, Justus, ed. New York: Dover Perry, Ralph Barton (1904) “Conceptions and Misconceptions of Consciousness,” Psychological Review, 11, (4–5) July, pp. 282–296. Pitkin, Walter B. (1906) “A Problem of Evidence in Radical Empiricism,” Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 3, no. 24, November 22, pp. 645–650. ———. (1907) “In Reply to Professor James,” Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 4, pp. 44–45. Prince, Morton Henry (1885) The Nature of Mind, and Human Automatism. Philadelphia, PA: Lippincott.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 145
5/2/22 10:39 AM
146
Bibliography
Pringle-Pattison, Andrew Seth (1902) Man’s Place in the Cosmos and Other Essays. Edinburgh; London: Blackwood. Putnam, Hilary (1990) “James’s Theory of Perception,” reprinted in Putnam, Hilary (1990) Realism with a Human Face. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 232–251. ———. (2002) “Introduction,” to Skrupskelis, I. K. and E. M. Berkeley, eds. (2002) The Correspondence of William James. vol. 10. Charlottesville, VA: University of Virginia Press, pp. xxv–xlvii. Putnam, Ruth Anna (1997) The Cambridge Companion to William James. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Putnam, Hilary and Ruth Anna Putnam (1989) “William James’s Ideas,” Raritan. Winter issue, pp. 17–44. Reprinted in Putnam, Hilary (1990) Realism with a Human Face. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 217–231. Renouvier, Charles-Bernard (1859) Essais de Critique générale. 2 vols. Paris: Au bureau de la critique; (1912) 3 vols. Paris: A. Colin. ———. (1885) Esquisse d’une classification systématique des doctrines philosophiques. Paris: Au Bureau de la critique. Rogers, Sebastian, Rebecca Keogh and Joel Pearson (2020) “Hallucinations on Demand: the Utility of Experimentally induced Phenomena in Hallucination Research,” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 376: 20200233. Royce, Josiah (1897) “G. F. Stout, Analytical Psychology,” Mind, n.s., vol. 6, pp. 379–399. ———. (1899) The World and the Individual. The Gifford Lectures. 2 vols. New York: Macmillan. Russell, Bertrand (1912) “Review of Essays in Radical Empiricism by William James,” Mind, n.s. vol. 21, no. 84, pp. 571–575. ———. (1918) “The Philosophy of Logical Atomism,” Monist, vol. 28, pp. 495–527; reprinted in Russell (1956) Logic and Knowledge. ———. (1950) An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth, The William James Lectures for 1940. London: George Allen & Unwin. ———. (1956) Logic and Knowledge, Essays 1901–1955. Marsh, Robert C., ed. London: Allen & Unwin. Santayana, George (1896) The Sense of Beauty, being the Outlines of Aesthetic Theory. New York: Scribners; (1955) Reprinted. New York: Dover. ———. (1905/1906) The Life of Reason, or The Phases of Human Progress. 5 vols. New York: Scribners. Schiller, Ferdinand Canning Scott (1903) Humanism; Philosophical Essays. London; New York: Macmillan. Searle, John (1983) Intentionality. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press. Seigfried, Charlene H. (1990) William James’s Radical Reconstruction of Philosophy. Albany, NY: SUNY Press. Shand, Alexander F. (1894) “An Analysis of Attention,” Mind, n.s., vol. 3, no. 12, pp. 449–473; (1895) “Attention and Will: A Study in Involuntary Action,” vol. 4, pp. 450–471; (1897) “Types of Will,” vol. 6, no. 3, pp. 289–325
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 146
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Bibliography 147
Sidgwick, Arthur (1905) “Applied Axioms,” Mind, n.s., vol. 14, no. 53, January issue, pp. 42–57. Sidis, Boris and Simon P. Goodhart (1904) Multiple Personality, an Experimental Investigation into the Nature of Human Individuality. New York: D. Appleton. Siegler, R. S. and E. Stern (1998) “Conscious and Unconscious Strategy Discoveries: a Microgenetic Analysis,” Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, vol. 127, no. 4, pp. 377–397. Skrupskelis, Ignas K. et al., eds. (2002) The Correspondence of William James. vol. 10. Charlottesville, VA: University of Virginia Press. Spencer, Herbert (1855) Principles of Psychology. London: Longman, Brown, Green and Longmans; (1905) 2 vols. New York: D. Appleton. ———. (1862/1867) First Principles of a New System of Philosophy. Second, revised ed. London: Williams and Norgate. Spir, Africa (1873) Denken und Wirklichkeit, Versuch einer Erneuerung der kritischen Philosophie. 2 vols. Leipzig: Findel. Stevenson, Robert Louis (1914) “Lay Morals,” in Stevenson (1914) Lay Morals and Other Essays. London: Chatto. Stout, George Frederick (1896/1902) Analytical Psychology. 2 vols. London: Sonnenschein; New York: Macmillan. ———. (1902) “Alleged Contradictions in the Concept of Relation—A Criticism of Mr. Bradley’s Appearance and Reality,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, vol. 2, no. 1, pp. 1–24. Strong, Charles Augustus (1903) Why the Mind Has a Body. New York; London: Macmillan. ———. (1904) “A Naturalistic Theory of the Reference of Thought to Reality,” Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 1, no. 10, May issue, pp. 253–260. Sully, James (1892) The Human Mind: A Text-book of Psychology. London: Longmans, Green. Taine, Hippolyte (1870) De l’intelligence. 2 vols. Paris: Hachette; (1872) On Intelligence. Haye, T. D. trans. London: Reeve; New York: Holt and Williams. Taylor, Alfred Edward (1899/1903) Elements of Metaphysics. London: Methuen. Titchener, Edward Bradford (1906) An Outline of Psychology. New York: Macmillan. VandenBos, Gary R., ed. (2015) APA Dictionary of Psychology. Second ed. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. Ward, James (1886) “Psychology,” Encyclopedia Britannica Ninth Edition, vol. 20, pp. 37–85. ———. (1887) “Mr. F. H. Bradley’s Analysis of Mind,” Mind, n.s., vol. 12, pp. 564–575. ———. (1899) Naturalism and Agnosticism: Gifford Lectures given at the University of Aberdeen, 1896-1898. 2 vols. London: Adam and Charles Black; (1915) fourth ed. London: Adam and Charles Black. Watson, John B. (1913) “Psychology as the Behaviorist Views it,” Psychological Review, vol. 20, pp. 158–177.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 147
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Bibliography
148
Wilbois, Joseph (1900) “La méthode des sciences physiques,” Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale, vol. 8, no. 3, pp. 291–322. ———. (1902) “L’esprit positif,” Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale, vol. 10, no. 3, pp. 334–370. Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1953) Philosophical Investigations. Anscombe, G. E. M., ed. Oxford: Blackwell. Woodbridge, Frederick J. E. (1904) “The Field of Logic,” Science, vol. 20, no. 514, pp. 587–600. Wundt, Wilhelm (1894) “Über psychische Causalität und das Prinzip psychophysischen Parallelismus,” Philosophische Studien. vol. 10, pp. 1–124.
SUGGESTIONS FOR FURTHER READING Alexander, Samuel (1912) “On Relations; and in Particular the Cognitive Relation,” Mind, n.s. vol. 21, pp. 305–328. ———. (1920) Space, Time and Deity. 2 vols. London: Macmillan. Allen, Gay Wilson (1967) William James: A Biography. New York: Viking; (1970) William James. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Baldwin, James Mark (1889–1891) Handbook of Psychology. 2 vols. New York: Henry Holt. ———. (1893) Elements of Psychology. New York: Henry Holt. ———. (1901–1905) Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology. 3 vols. New York; London: Macmillan. ———. (1903) “Mind and Body, from the Genetic Point of View,” Psychological Review, vol. 10, pp. 225–247. ———. (1903) Fragments in Philosophy and Science, Collected Essays. New York: Scribner; London: Nimmo. ———. (1906–1911) Thought and Things, or Genetic Logic. 3 vols. London: Sonnenschein; New York: Macmillan. ———. (1915) The Story of the Mind. London: Newnes. Barzun, Jacques (1983) A Stroll with William James. New York: Harper and Row. —(1987) “James, William,” in The Encyclopedia of Religion. Eliade, M., ed. New York: Macmillan, vol. 7, pp. 517–519. Bawden, Henry Heath (1902) “The Functional View of the Relation Between the Psychical and the Physical,” Philosophical Review, vol. 11, pp. 474–484. ———. (1903) “The Functional Theory of Parallelism,” Philosophical Review, vol. 12, pp. 299–319. ———. (1904) “The Meaning of the Psychical from the Point of view of the Functional Psychology,” Philosophical Review, vol. 13, pp. 298–319. Bergson, Henri (1932) Les Deux Sources de la morale et de la religion; (1935) The Two Sources of Morality and Religion. Audra, R. Ashley and Cloudesley Brereton trans. New York: Henry Holt. ———. (1959) Oeuvres. Robinet, A. notes and Gouhier, H. intro. fifth ed. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 148
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Bibliography 149
———. (2002) Bergson: Key Writings. Pearson, K. A. and J. Mullarkey, eds. New York: Continuum. Bird, Graham (1987) William James. London and New York: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Bjork, Daniel W. (1987) William James: The Center of His Vision. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. Bode, Boyd Henry (1908) “Some Recent Definitions of Consciousness,” Psychological Review, vol. 15, pp. 255–264. Chalmers, David J. (1995) “Facing Up to the Problem of Consciousness,” Journal of Consciousness Studies, vol. 2, no. 3, pp. 200–219. ———. (1996) The Conscious Mind. New York: Oxford University Press. Chevalier, Jacques (1926) Bergson. Paris: Plon; (1928) Clare, L. A. eng. trans. New York: Macmillan. Cotkin, George (1989) William James, Public Philosopher. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press; (1994) Reprinted. Urbana and Chicago, IL: University of Illinois Press. Dehaene, Stanislas (2009) Reading in the Brain, the Science and Evolution of a Human Invention. New York: Viking. Elliot, Hugh (1917) Herbert Spencer. New York: Henry Holt. Fairbrother, W. H. (1900) The Philosophy of Thomas Hill Green. Second edition. London: Methuen. Fechner, Gustav Theodor (1860) Elemente der Psychophysik. 2 vols. Leipzig: Breitkopf und Härtel. ———. (1877) In Sachen der Psychophysik. Leipzig: Breitkopf und Härtel. ———. (1882) Revision der Hauptpunkte der Psychophysik. Leipzig: Breitkopf und Härtel. Goldman, Alvin I., ed. (1993) Readings in Philosophy and Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Goodman, Russell B. (2002) Wittgenstein and William James. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Green, Christopher D. (2018) Psychology and its Critics: A New History of Early American Psychology. New York: Routledge. Hookway, Christopher (1997) “Logical Principles and Philosophical Attitudes: Peirce’s Response to James’s Pragmatism,” in Putnam, Ruth A. (1997) The Cambridge Companion to William James, pp. 145–165. James, Henry (1926) The Letters of William James. 2 vols. Boston: Little, Brown; Reprinted. (1969) New York: Krause. James, William (1884) “The Dilemma of Determinism,” Unitarian Review, September issue; reprinted in James (1897) The Will to Believe and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy, pp. 145–183. ———. (1898) Human Immortality. New York: Houghton Mifflin; (1956) Reprinted. New York: Dover Publications. ———. (1899) Talks to Teachers on Psychology and to Students on Some of Life’s Ideals; (1962) Reprinted New York: Dover; (1983) Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 149
5/2/22 10:39 AM
150
Bibliography
———. (1902) The Varieties of Religious Experience: A Study in Human Nature. New York: Longmans, Green; (1936) New York: Modern Library. ———. (1903) “Address on the Philippine Question,” in Burkhardt, F. and F. Bowers, eds. (1987) The Works of William James, vol. 17, Essays Comments, and Reviews. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 81–86. ———. (1910) “The Moral Equivalent of War,” McClure’s Magazine, August issue, pp. 483– 468. ———. (1911) Memories and Studies. New York: Longmans, Green. ———. (1920) Collected Essays and Reviews. New York: Longmans, Green. ———. (1982) Essays in Religion and Morality. Burkhardt, F. and F. Bowers, eds. vol. 11 in The Works of William James. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. ———. (1987) The Works of William James, vol. 17, Essays, Comments, and Reviews. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. ———. (1975-1988) The Works of William James. 19 vols. Burkhardt, F. H., F. Bowers, and I. K. Skrupskelis, eds. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. James, William and Henry James (1997) Selected Letters. Skrupskelis, I. K. and E. Berkeley, eds. Charlottesville and London: University of Virginia Press. Jankélévitch, Vladimir (1959) Henri Bergson. Paris: Presses universitaires de France. Joachim, Harald Henry (1906) The Nature of Truth: An Essay. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Kahn, Sholom J. (1953) Science and Aesthetic Judgment: A Study in Taine’s Critical Method. New York: Columbia University Press. Kallen, Horace Mayer (1910) “James, Bergson and Mr. Pitkin,” Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 7, pp. 353–357. ———. (1953) The Philosophy of William James. Selected from his chief Works. New York: Modern Library. ———. (1999) “James, William,” Encyclopedia Britannica. Chicago: Encyclopedia Britannica. King, Irving (1903) The Psychology of Child Development. Dewey, John, Intro. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ———. (1905) The Differentiation of Religious Consciousness. New York: Macmillan. Kloppenberg, James T. (1995) “James, William” in Fox, Richard W. and James T. Kloppenberg, eds. (1995) A Companion to American Thought. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, pp. 346–349. Kuklick, Bruce (2001) A History of Philosophy in America, 1720-2000. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. Lamars, Robert W. (1990) Richard von Schubert-Solderns Philosophie des Erkenntnistheoretischen Solipsismus. Frankfurt a M.; New York: Peter Lang. Leary, David L. (2018) James’s Principles of Psychology. New York: Routledge. Levine, Steven (2019) Pragmatism, Objectivity and Experience. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press. Levinson, Henry S. (1981) The Religious Investigations of William James. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press. Lewis, R. W. B. (1991) The Jameses: A Family Narrative. New York: Anchor Doubleday.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 150
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Bibliography 151
Loar, Brian (1981) Mind and Meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Lyons, William (1986) The Disappearance of Introspection. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. ———. (1995) Approaches to Intentionality. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. Münsterberg, Hugo (1906) Science and Idealism. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. ———. (1990) Frühe Schriften zur Psychologie. Berlin: Springer. Myers, Gerald E. (1981) “Introduction: the Intellectual Context,” in James, William (1981) The Principles of Psychology, vol. 1. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. xi–xl. Natorp, Paul (1903) Platos Ideenlehre: Eine Einführung in den Idealismus. (Plato’s Theory of Ideas: An Introduction to Idealism); Reprinted (2016) Hamburg: Felix Meiner. Passingham, Richard E. et al. (2002) “The Anatomical Basis of Functional Localization,” Nature Reviews Neuroscience, vol. 3, pp. 606–616. Passingham, Richard E. and J. B. Rowe (2015) A Short Guide to Brain Imaging: the Neuroscience of Human Cognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Passingham, Richard E. (2016) Cognitive Neuroscience, A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pawelski, James O. (2007) The Dynamic Individualism of William James. Albany: State University of New York Press. Perry, Ralph Barton (1912) Present Philosophical Tendencies. New York: Longmans, Green. ———. (1935) The Thought and Character of William James. 2 vols. Boston: Little, Brown. Pitkin, Walter B. (1910) “James and Bergson: or, Who Is Against Intellect?” Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 7, pp. 225–231. Prince, Morton Henry (1908) The Disassociation of a Personality: A Biographical Study in Abnormal Psychology. New York: Longmans, Green. Rehmke, Johannes (1880) Die Welt als Wahrnehmung und Begriff: Eine Erkenntnistheorie. Berlin: Reimer. ———. (1894/1905) Lehrbuch der allgemeinen Psychologie. Leipzig; Frankfurt am M.: Mayer. ———. (1902) Die Seele des Menschen. Fourth ed. (1913) Leipzig; Berlin: Teubner. Renouvier, Charles-Bernard (1842) Manuel de Philosophie. Paris: Paulin. ———. (1844) Manuel de Philosophie ancienne. Paris: Paulin. ———. (1869) Science de la Morale. Paris: Libraire Philosophique de Ladrange. ———. (1901) Les Dilemmes de la Métaphysique Pure. Paris: F. Alcan. ———. (1901) Uchronie. Second ed. Paris: F. Alcan. ———. (1906) Critique de la doctrine de Kant. Published by Louis Prat. Paris: F. Alcan. Renouvier, Charles-Bernard and Louis Prat (1899) La nouvelle Monadologie. Paris: Armand Colin and Cie. Richardson, Robert D. (2006) William James, In the Maelstrom of American Modernism. Boston and New York: Houghton Mifflin.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 151
5/2/22 10:39 AM
152
Bibliography
Royce, Josiah (1885) The Religious Aspect of Philosophy. Boston: Houghton, Mifflin. ———. (1892) The Spirit of Modern Philosophy. Boston: Houghton, Mifflin; (1983) New York: Dover. ———. (1908) Philosophy of Loyalty; (1924) New York: Macmillan; (1995) Reprinted. Nashville: Vanderbilt University Press. Russell, Bertrand (1911) “Review of Memories and Studies, by William James,” Cambridge Review, vol. 33, p. 118. ———. (1914) “On Scientific Method in Philosophy.” Reprinted in Russell (1917) Mysticism and Logic, pp. 97–124. ———. (1914) “On the Nature of Acquaintance,” Monist, vol. 24, pp. 1–16, 161– 187, 435–453. ———. (1914) “On the Relation of Sense-data to Physics,” Scientia, vol. 16, pp. 1–27; Reprinted in Russell (1917) Mysticism and Logic, pp. 145–179. ———. (1914) The Philosophy of Bergson. Cambridge: Bowes and Bowes. ———. (1917) Mysticism and Logic. London: Allen & Unwin. ———. (1919) “On Propositions: What they are and How they Mean,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary vol. 2, pp. 1–43; Reprinted in Russell (1956) Logic and Knowledge, pp. 283–321. ———. (1921) The Analysis of Mind. London: Allen & Unwin. ———. (1927) The Analysis of Matter. London: Allen & Unwin. ———. (1927) An Outline of Philosophy. London: Allen & Unwin. ———. (1945) “William James,” in Russell (1945) A History of Western Philosophy. New York: Simon and Schuster, pp. 811–818. Schiller, Ferdinand Canning Scott (1966) Humanistic Pragmatism: The Philosophy of F. C. S. Schiller. Abel, R., ed. New York: Collier-Macmillan. Schubert-Soldern, Richard von (1884) Grundlagen einer Erkenntnistheorie. Leipzig: Fues Verlag. ———. (1887) Reproduktion, Gefühl und Wille. Leipzig: Fues. ———. (1896) Über den Begriff der allgemeinen Bildung: Antritts-Vorlesung gehalten an der Universität Leipzig. Leipzig. Haacke. Schuppe, Wilhelm (1870) Das Menschliche Denken (Human Thinking). Berlin: Weber. ———. (1878) Erkenntnistheoretische Logik (Epistemological Logic). Bonn: Eduard Weber. ———. (1894) Grundriß der Erkenntnistheorie und Logik (Outline of Epistemology and Logic). Berlin: R. Gaertners Verlagsbuchhandlung; Hermann Hayfelder. ———. (1902) Der Zusammenhang von Leib und Seele, das Grundproblem der Psychologie. Wiesbaden: Bergmann. Sidis, Boris (1898) The Psychology of Suggestion. James, William. intro. New York: D. Appleton. Simon, Linda (1996) William James Remembered. Lincoln, NB and London: University of Nebraska Press. ———. (1998) Genuine Reality, A Life of William James. New York: Harcourt Brace. Stace, W. T. (1946) “Russell’s Neutral Monism,” in Schlipp, Arthur, ed. (1946) The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell. The Library of Living Philosophers, vol. 5. Evanston, IL: Library of Living Philosophers, pp. 351–384.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 152
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Bibliography 153
Stout, George Frederick (1899) A Manual of Psychology. New York: Hinds and Noble. ———. (1903) The Groundwork of Psychology. New York: Hinds and Noble. ———. (1931) Mind and Matter. The Gifford Lectures, 1919, 1921. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Taine, Hippolyte (1857) Les Philosophes français du XIXe siècle. Paris: Hachette; (1966) Reprinted. Paris: J. J. Pauvert. ———. (1864) L’idéalisme Anglais. Etude sur Carlyle. Paris: G. Baillière. ———. (1898) Introduction à l’histoire de la littérature anglaise. Babbitt, Irving, ed. Boston: D. C. Heath and Co. Taylor, Eugene and Robert H. Wozniak, eds. (1996) Pure Experience, The Response to William James. Bristol, England: Thoemmes Press. Thorndike, Edward Lee (1943) “James’s Influence on the Psychology of Perception and Thought,” Psychological Review, vol. 50, pp. 87–94. Titchener, Edward Bradford (1898) “The Postulates of a Structural Psychology,” Philosophical Review, vol. 7, pp. 449–465. ———. (1909) Lectures on the Experimental Psychology of the Thought-Processes. New York: Macmillan. ———. (1921) “Wilhelm Wundt,” The American Journal of Psychology, vol. 32, no. 2, April issue, pp. 161–178. Tully, Robert E. (2003) “Russell’s Neutral Monism,” in Griffin, Nicholas, ed. (2003) The Cambridge Companion to Bertrand Russell. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 332–370. Van Gulick, Robert (2014) “Consciousness,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Spring 2014 ed. Stanford, CA: Metaphysics Research Lab. Ward, James (1883) “Psychological Principles,” Mind, n.s., vol. 8, pp.153-169; and vol. 8, pp. 465–486. ———. (1918) Psychological Principles. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Watson, John B. (1914) Behavior: An Introduction to Comparative Psychology. New York: Henry Holt. Weinstein, Leo (1972) Hippolyte Taine. New York: Twayne. White, Robert W. (1992) “Who was Morton Prince?” Journal of Abnormal Psychology, vol. 101, no. 4, pp. 604-606. Wild, John D. (1989) The Radical Empiricism of William James. Garden City, NY: Doubleday. Wollheim, Richard (1959) F. H. Bradley. Harmondsworth: Penguin. Woodbridge, Frederick J. E. (1905) “The Nature of Consciousness,” Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol. 2, pp. 119–125. ———. (1916) The Purpose of History. New York: Columbia University Press. ———. (1926) The Realm of Mind: An Essay in Metaphysics. New York: Columbia University Press. ———. (1929) The Son of Apollo: Themes of Plato. Boston: Houghton, Mifflin. ———. (1937) Nature and Mind: Selected Essays. New York: Columbia University Press. ———. (1940) An Essay on Nature. New York: Columbia University Press.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 153
5/2/22 10:39 AM
154
Bibliography
Wundt, Wilhelm (1896) Grundriß der Psychologie; (1902) Outlines of Psychology. Judd, C. H. trans. Leipzig: W. Engelmann. ———. (1901) Gustav Theodor Fechner. Leipzig: W. Engelmann. ———. (1902) Grundzüge der physiologischen Psychologie. Leipzig: W. Engelmann; (1904) Principles of Physiological Psychology. Titchener, E. B. trans. London: Sonnenschein; New York: Macmillan. ———. (1907) System der Philosophie. Third ed. 2 vols. Leipzig: W. Engelmann.
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 154
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Index
Absolute Idealism, ix, xxxv, 16–17, 19–20, 22, 26–27, 31, 38–40, 108, 124n32, 125n3, 137n7 Absolutism, 109 abstractions, xxii, xxxvi, 3, 7, 15– 16, 18, 36–39, 43–45, 50, 70–71, 77, 81, 86, 98, 103, 105–107, 126n16, 126n21, 126n25, 130n21 acquaintance, xx, 20, 22, 27, 102. See knowledge-about activity (l’activité), xxxvii, 1, 17, 48, 53, 57, 61–71, 84–86, 118n85, 119n7, 122n38, 122n6, 124n38, 128n18, 130n12, 130n21, 131n21, 132n32, 132n33, 133n33, 134n5 activity, mental (l’activité mentale), 67, 71, 84–86 action, xv–xvi, xxx–xxxi, xl, 32, 55, 58, 67, 70, 75, 83, 95–96, 113n16, 116n57, 131n21 affectional facts, 12, 54, 56 after-images, xix, 40 agnosticism, 74, 79 aims (ends, purpose), xiv, xl–xlii, 1, 17–19, 23, 42, 51, 54–55, 57–58, 64–65, 67–68, 74–75 Alexander, Samuel, 119n5 Allport, Gordon, xli–xlii
Angell, James R., xi, xv–xvi, xxix, xl, 111n2 anomalous monism, 116n58, 118n78 Anselm, St., 107–108, 137n7 apperception (l’aperception), 11, 77, 80–81 appreciations, 12. See affectional facts Aquinas, St. Thomas, 129n9 attention (l’attention), xiv, 3, 5–6, 49, 58–59, 82–83, 130n12 awareness, ix, xiv, xvii, xviii–xix, xxiv, xxvi, xxxvi, xxxviii–xxxix, 2, 50 Baldwin, James Mark, xv, xxvii, 2n, 111n2, 119n5 Bawden, H. Heath, 111n2, 119n5 behavior, xvii, 112n5 behaviorism, xxii, xxvii–xxix, xxx– xxxiii, xl, 113 n19, 115n45, 117n63, 117n74 Bergson, Henri, 4, 61, 71, 130n12, 133n35 Berkeley, Bishop George, ix, xiv, xviii, 4, 16, 28, 81, 88, 113n21, 113n24 Bewusstsein, Bewusstheit, 1, 79, 119n4. See consciousness Block, Ned, 114n37, 114n38, 117n73 Bode, Boyd Henry, 91–93, 135n2. See fulfillment, cognitive
155
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 155
5/2/22 10:39 AM
156
Index
body, xv, xxvii, 1–2, 12, 24, 28–29, 31, 39, 41, 55, 58, 64, 76, 107, 131n21 Bradley, Francis Herbert, xxxv, 37–38, 40–44, 62–63, 74, 123n16, 125n3 brain imaging, xxiii–xxiv brains, brain cells, xiv, xvi, xxiii–xxiv, xxvii–xxviii, xxx–xxxii, 67, 69, 71 Brentano, Franz, 114n30, 121n32. See Searle, John Bridgman, Percy W., 117n63. See behaviorism “cash value,” xx, 27 causality, causation, xvi, 69–71 cause, causes, xxx, 70, 101 change, xv, xxxv, xxxvii, 17–18, 31, 36, 42–43, 50–51, 57–58, 63, 73, 76, 97–98, 112n5, 118n87, 126n21, 128n10, 131n21 classification, xl, 5, 54, 56, 84, 121n25, 128n5, 128n16, 129n20, 132n33 cognition, xix, xxviii–xxix, 50, 114n33 cognitive fulfillment, 21, 23, 29, 32, 92 cognitive relations, 19–23. See relations, functional cognitive science, xiii, xxi, xxxvi color-blindness, xxiv–xxv, 30, 115n50 conjunctive relations, 17–19, 30, 35, 40, 66, 74, 92, 135n7 common sense, xxii, xxiv, xxvi, xxxv– xxxvi, xl, 1, 4, 10, 20, 30, 33, 42, 45, 53, 56–57, 75–76, 77–78, 99, 106 conscious contents, xvi, xxxv, 3, 9 conscious experience, xv–xvii, xix, xxi, xxiii–xxvi, xxix, xxxi, xxiii– xxvi, xxix, xxxi, xxxv–xxxvi, xl, 3, 115n39, 117n74 consciousness (das Bewusstsein, la conscience), xiii–xix, xxi–xxiii, xxv, xxviii–xxix, xxxi–xxxii, xxxiv, xxxvi, xxxiii–xxxix, xxxiv, xxxvi, xxxiii–xxxii, xli, 1–13, 27, 29, 47–51, 53, 56–57, 67, 71, 75, 79–89, 101, 112n9, 112n10, 112n12, 112n13, 115n46, 118n87, 119n4,
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 156
121n29, 127n6, 131n6, 132n32, 133n33 consciousness, personal, 29, 48–49 content (der Inhalt, le contenu), xvi– xviii, xxiii, xxvii, xxix, xxx–xxxii, xxxv–xxxvi, xl–xli, 1–4, 6–9, 19– 20, 23, 27–28, 30–31, 47, 49, 52– 54, 56, 63–65, 80–82, 85–86, 95, 100, 113n15, 113n25, 114n29, 119n93, 123n12, 130n14, 131n21, 135n7 context (le contexte), xi, xiii, xxiii, xxv, xxxiv–xxxv, 4–8, 11–12, 20–21, 29, 47, 49, 51, 53–54, 58–59, 75, 86–87, 108, 128n16, 130n21, 132n33 context, historical, xiii, xxiii continuity, 18–19, 22, 24, 26, 122n3 Darwin, Charles, Darwinism, xiv–xv, xxvi, xxx, xxxiii, xxxvii–xxxviii, xl, 97, 112n5, 112n6, 117n62 Dehaene, Stanislas, xi, xv, xvii, 112n14, 115n45, 117n73 Democritus, 5 Descartes, René, xxix, 11, 56. See dualism determinism, See indeterminism Dewey, John, 61, 73, 78, 98, 102, 113n19, 119n8, 123n10, 129n2, 133n3 discontinuity, 18–19, 24 disjunction, ix, 16, 19, 26, 36, 107 disjunctive relations, 16 dualism (le dualisme), xiv, xxxi–xxxiii, 2, 4, 8, 10, 13, 79–80, 82–83, 85–86, 88, 101 dualistic philosophy, 48, 53 Dyaks of Borneo, 17 dysfunction, xxvii–xxviii, xxx, xxxii Earth-soul, 52. See Fechner, Gustav effort (l’effort), xxix, 3, 16, 59, 64–65, 68, 105–107, 130n12, 132n32,132n33, 133n33, 134n3. electroencephalography, xxiii
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Index 157
emotion, xxix, 5, 12–13, 29, 53–55, 57–59, 109, 128n6, 133n3. See James-Lange theory empiricism, British, xviii, xix empiricism, contemporary, xviii–xxi empiricism, radical, ix–xi, xiii–xiv, xvii–xix, xxi, xxvii, xxxi, xxxiii, xxxv, xxxix–xl, xlii, 16–18, 28, 31–33, 38, 40–41, 45, 57, 61–63, 70, 91–93, 95–96, 112n10, 113n22, 113n26, 16n55, 126n21, 128n16, 129n20, 134n5 epiphenomenalism, xiv epistemology, xviii, xx–xxi, xxvii, xxxv, xl, 3, 22, 25, 30, 77, 92–93 experience (l’expérience), ix–x, intro, xi–xlii, 15–34, 53–60, 61–72, 79–81, 85–89 experience, conscious, xv, xvi–xvii, xix, xxi, xxiii–xxvi, xxix, xxxi, xxxv–xxxvi, xl, 3, 115n39, 117n74 experience, conceptual, 9, 12, 23 experience, non-perceptual, 6–7, 120n18, 120n19 experience, perceptual, xvii, xxii, xxiv– xxv, xxvii, xxxvi, xxxix, 4, 6, 12, 19, 120n18, 135n7 experience, immediate, 9, 37 experience, individual, 25, 59, 87 experience, practical, xxxiv, 9, 22, 25, 49, 56, 76. See pragmatism experience, pure, ix, xiii, xvii, xx–xxi, xxvii, xxxi, xxxiii–xxxvi, xl, 5–6, 9–10, 13, 15–33, 35–37, 41, 44–45, 47–49,51, 53–59, 62–63, 70, 86, 101, 112–113n15, 113n17, 113n18, 113n26, 118n87, 129n20 experience, theory-laden, xxii, xxv. See apperception experiment, xxv, xli, xlii, 22–23, 114n33 explanation, to explain (expliquer), xiv–xv, xviii–xx, xxix, xxxi–xxxiv, xxxvii, 1–3, 9, 13, 25, 27, 44, 49,
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 157
63, 70, 83, 91, 100, 108, 116n56, 118n77, 124n37 external relations, 14–15, 26, 41, 63–66 face blindness, xxviii, xxxi. See Kanwisher, Nancy fallacy, psychologist’s, xxxvii–xxxix fallible, fallibility, 70, 115n40 Farthing, G. William, xvii, 112n13, 113n16, 115n39, 115n44, 115n48, 116n54 Fechner, Gustav, xiv, 51, 127n10 feeling, xxii, xxx, 12–13, 15, 21, 36–38, 41, 49, 51, 55, 62, 64, 66–67, 70, 77, 92, 97, 101, 104, 109, 112n10, 114n27,127n6, 130n21, 132n32 Ferrier, James, 95, 135n3 Flournoy, Theodore, 118n85 fMRI imaging, xxiii, 117n72 free will, 133n33 freedom, 74, 108–109 fictitious entities, xxii, 13, 19 fulfillment, cognitive, 21, 23, 29, 32, 92. See Bode, Boyd Henry functionalism, x–xi, xiii–xiv, xvii, xxi– xxii, xxvi, xxix, xxxi–xxxii, xl–xlii, 112m5, 114n37, 116n56, 116n58, 117n62, 117n73 functionalism, contemporary, xi, xiii, xxvii, xxxii, xl–xlii, 115n46 functional psychology, x–xi, xiii, xv– xvii, xxvi–xxxi, xxxii, xl–xlii, 111n2, 112n13, 112n14, 113n24, 114n35, 115n43. See Angell, James R. functional relations, xiii, xv–xvi, xviii– xxix, xxxi–xxxii Galileo, (Galileo Galilei), 56 gelten (Geltung), 65, 130n18. See validity God (Dieu), 13, 28, 74, 80 Goodhart, Simon P., 56 Green, Christopher D. 117n62, 117n63 Güzeldere, Güven, 114n38
5/2/22 10:39 AM
158
Index
Haldane, John Scott, 105–107, 136n3 hallucination (la hallucination), 80, 117n72 Hamilton, Sir William, 122n4 Hegel, G. W. F., Hegelians, xix, 40, 107–109, 125n10 Herbart, Johann Friedrich, 40, 125n11 Hobhouse, Leonard T., 125n14 Hodder, Alfred L., 120n24, 125n14 Hodgson, Shadworth, 10, 121n31, 122n7, 127n6 Höffding, Harald, 92, 127n6, 135n8 holism, Hegelian, xix Hook, Sidney, xvii, 113n17 humanism, 33, 61, 73–78, 97–104, 124n39, 125n14, 134n5, 136n16 Hume, David, ix, xviii, xxii, 16, 39, 67, 122n4, 125n6 hypothesis, xviii, xx, xxx, xxxiv, 26, 48–49, 73–74, 76, 99–102, 108, 126n21 hypothetical-deductive method, xviii, 114n29 hypothetical-statistical method, xviii, 114n29 idealism, ix, 15, 17, 28, 33, 74, 101, 119n2, 120n10, 123n14, 124n32. See Absolute Idealism; transcendental idealism Idenitätsphilosophie, xxxv, 51, 75, 77, 127n7 identity, personal, 22 identity, philosophy of, xxxv, 51, 75, 77, 127n7 illusion (la illusion), 22, 80, 84, 106 images (l’image), 7, xix, xxxi, xlii, 5, 8, 11, 20–22, 40, 44, 49, 82, 84, 118n89 imagination (l’imagination), xxiv, 12, 77, 81 immediacy, 9, 27, 35, 50 immediate experience, 9, 37. See experience, pure indeterminism, 33, 133n33
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 158
infallible, xxi, 109 intellect, 35, 37–38, 44, 98 intelligence, xv, xl, xlii, 23, 70, 123n17 intention, xviii, 10–11, 61–62, 113n26, 114n30, 116n57 intentionality, x, 114n30, 121n32. See Brentano, Franz internal relations, xxx, xxxv, 124n32. See Bradley, F. H. intimacy, of relations, 17–18, 42 introspection, ix, x, xix, xx, xxi–xxvi, xxxi–xxxii, xli, 3, 59, 86, 113n19, 115n39, 115n40, 115n44, 115n45, 115n49, 116n51, 116n54, 119n93, 129n20. See retrospection introspection, stand-alone, x, xix, xxi, xxvi. See stimulus control introspective observation, xxi, xxiv irrationality, 35, 42–44, 105, 107 Jack, Anthony I., xxvi, 115n51, 116n53 James-Lange theory, 55 Janet, Paul, 128n12, 137n6 Joachim, Harald Henry, 133n1 Joseph, H. W. B., 78, 97–98, 100–104, 133n1, 134n13, 136n1 Kant, Immanuel, 13, 64, 79, 119n2, 129n11 Kanwisher, Nancy, 117n72 Kierkegaard, Soren, 92, 127n6 King, Irving, 111n2, 119n5 knowing, xxxii–xxxiv, xxxviii, 2, 7, 9, 20–23, 25, 27–28, 48, 75–76, 95, 102, 121n30, 136n16 knowledge, ix, xviii, xxxiii, xxxviii, 2, 7, 20–22, 24–27, 30–32, 45, 51, 69–70, 74–75, 77, 118n 77, 119n6, 120n19, 123n10, 127n7 knowledge-about, 20, 22 Koch, Christof, 112n12, 112n15 Külpe, Oswald, xxiii, 115n47
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Index 159
Ladd, George T., 117n64, 120n12, 130n12 language, x, xix–xx, xxii, xxvii, xxxii, xxxvi–xxxvii, xl–xli, 33, 39, 55, 114n32, 114n33, 115n50, 118n89 language, private, xx, 114n32 language, psychological, xxxii, xli, 122n39 laws, law-like gneralization, xxviii, 6, 55, 103, 106, 122n39 Le Roy, Edouard, 136n12 Levin, Janet, 114n37 Liebmann, Otto, 116n56 life, xxviii–xxx, xxxiii, 5, 13, 15, 21, 23–24, 26, 28–29, 32, 35–37, 40, 49–51, 56, 58, 63–65, 68, 71, 93, 97, 103, 108, 112n5, 117n64, 121n35, 134n5 linguistic usage, xix–xx, xxiv, xxv– xxvii Locke, John, ix, xviii–xix, xxii, xxxix, 4, 113n20, 119n6 logic (la logique), ix–x, 16, 28, 30, 76, 80, 85–86, 92, 98, 102, 106–107, 109, 111n1, 122n3, 134n7. See Peirce, Charles S. logic of relations, ix, x, 122n3 logomachy, 27, 124n26 Lotze, Hermann, 28, 65, 123n14, 123n15 Loveday, Thomas, 130n12, 130n21
memory, xxiv, 3. See retrospection mental activity (activité mentale), 61–72, 84, 122n38, 130n12, 130n21, 131n21, 132n32 mental images, xix, 5, 8, 20, 40 mental processes, xxvii, xxxix, 71 mental states, xx, xxviii, xxxi–xxxii, xl, 6, 112n10, 114n37 metaphysics, xxxi, 113n17, 113n26 Mill, James, xiv, 16, 122n4 Mill, John Stuart, ix, xiv, xviii, xxiii, 28, 115n48, 122n4 Miller, Dickinson S., 123n12 mind, minds, x–xi, xiii, xv–xviii, xxi, xxiii–xxv, xxvii–xxviii, xxx–xxxii, xxxiv, xxxvi–xlii, 1–13, 15–33, 38–39, 47–52, 54–55, 57, 62–63, 66, 70–71, 76–77, 92, 98–99, 101, 103– 104, 108. 113n16, 113n24, 114n37, 115n44, 115n45 mind, Hegelian, 108 mind-stuff, 76–77 monism (le monisme), xix, xxxii–xxxiii, 74, 79–80, 85–86, 116n57, 116n58, 118n78, 126n21 Moore, G. E., 3, 120n10 motion, 12, 26, 56, 70, 125n13 multiple realizability, xvii, xxxviii Münsterberg, Hugo, xxxii, 1, 7, 62, 119n3, 120n20, 130n13, 130n21 Myers, Gerald E., 118n87
MacLennan, Simon F., 125n5, 125n11 materialism, xxviii, xxxii, 13, 68 materia prima, 53, 101, 128n2 matter (la matière), 80, 85, 87–88, 101, 128n2 matters of fact, xxii, 24, 30, 107 McDermott, John J., 112n10 meaning, x, xix, xx, xxix, xxxvi, xxxix, xl–xli, 11, 23, 36, 40, 42, 44, 62–63, 65, 67–68, 71, 98, 122n39 meaning, linguistic, xx, xxxix, xl meaning, pragmatic, xx, 67–68
Natorp, Paul, xxxii, 1, 119n3, 120n11 naturalism, ix, xi, xiii, xvii, xix, xxxi, xl, 36–38, 114n29, 129n3, 129n9 natural realism, xviii, 15, 28, 30. See common sense nerves, nerve-cells, xiv, 67–68, 132n26 neo-Kantian, ix, xiv, xxxii, 2–3, 51, 57, 119n3 neurological correlates of consciousness xvi, xvii neurophysiology, xiv–xv, xvii, xxiii– xxv, xxviii, xxx–xxxi, xlii
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 159
5/2/22 10:39 AM
160
Index
neuroscience, xiii, xvii, xxi, xxiii. See Dehaene, Stanislas; Kanwisher, Nancy Newton, Isaac, 12, 122n39 nominalism, ix, xxxix, xl, 16 novelty, xx, 33, 36, 133n33 objective (objectif), xvi, xxi, xxiii, xxxv, xxxv, 4, 6, 8–9, 11–12, 24, 24–28, 29, 39, 49, 53, 55, 57–58, 66, 83–84, 91, 97–98, 100, 114n33, 121n28, 121n29, 128n16. See Perry, R. B. objective reality, 29 objective reference, xxxvi–xl, 24–28, 91 objectivity, 6–8, 54 observation, xx–xxi, xxiii–xxiv, xxvi, xxxiv, 115n40, 119n6 ontological argument, 107–108, 137n7 ontology, 41, 115n50 operationalism, xix, xxix, 117n63. See Bridgman, Percy Owen, Adrian, 115n46 panpsychism, 32, 124n38 pantheism, 74 parallelism (le parallélisme, der Parallelismus), 7, 80, 128n17 Pearson, Karl, 128n15 Peirce, Charles S., x, xvii, 11n1, 122n3, 123n23, 129n8 perception, 5, 11–13, 18, 20, 24, 39, 54–56, 62, 75–77, 80–82, 100, 103– 104, 111n4, 130n20, 130n21 Perry, Ralph Barton, ix–x, 119n5, 121n29 personal consciousness, 29, 48–49 philosophy (la philosophie), x–xi, xiii– xiv, xvii, xxxv–xxxvi, xl–xli, 1, 4–5, 15–18, 20, 24, 28, 31–33, 35, 41, 44–45, 48, 51, 53, 55–56, 59, 62, 69–70, 74, 76, 95, 99, 101–102, 105, 107–109 philosophy, dualistic, 48, 53 philosophy of identity (Identitätsphilosophie), xxxv, 51, 75, 77, 127n7
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 160
philosophy of language, x, xxxvi philosophy of mind, xi, xiii, xxi, xxvii, xl, 114n37 philosophy of psychology, xi, xxxvi philosophy of science, xx, xxvii, xl physical objects, 48, 53, 57 physical reality, xxv, 53 physical things, 5, 16, 48–49, 118n87 physical world, xxv–xxvi, 11–12, 24, 47–48, 57 physiology, xiv–xvii, xxiii–xxv, xxvii, xxix, 115n44. See neurophysiology Pitkin, Walter B., 95–96, 135n1, 135n4, 135n5 pluralism, xix, xxxii–xxxiv, 32–33, 41, 74, 77, 101, 116n57, 120n17, 126n21, 137n12 positivism (le positivisme), 79, 86, 115n48, 120n22, 136n12. See Taine, Hippolyte postulates (les postulats), xxx, xxxiv, xxxvii, 25, 27–28, 32, 40, 50–51, 63, 80, 95, 101, 113n22 pragmatic method, xx, xxvii, xxix, 4, 26, 61–63, 123n23 pragmatic principles, 30 pragmatism, 38, 95, 103, 113n17, 114n35, 120n23, 133n2 primary qualities, xxv, 57 Prince, Morton, 32, 124n36, 124n31 Principles of Psychology (James), x–xi, xiv–xv, xix, xxi, xxvii, xxx, xxxiii, xxxvii, xl–xli, 49, 112n10, 113n17, 114n29, 114n30, 120n9, 122n7, 123n18, 125n9, 130n15, 131n21, 132n33 Pringle-Pattison, Andrew Seth, 125n14 private language argument, xx, 114n32 problem of evil, 74 psychical (le psychique), xv, xxii, 13, 15, 47–48, 80–81, 84, 87, 119n8 Psychology, The Briefer Course (James), xxix, xxxi, xxxix, xli, 113n27, 115n42, 117n64, 118n89, 119n93
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Index 161
psychological descriptions, xvii, xix–xx, xxviii, xli, 122n39 psychologist’s fallacy, xxxvii–xl pure experience (l’expérience pure), ix, xiii, xvii, xx–xxi, xxvii, xxxi, xxxiii–xxxvi, xl, 5–6, 9–10, 13, 15–33, 35–37, 41, 44–45, 47–49, 51, 53–59, 62–63, 70, 101, 112–113n15, 113n17, 113n18, 113n26, 118n87, 129n20 purpose, purposes, xiii, xiv, xl–xli, xlii, 15, 17–18, 23, 42, 51, 54–56, 58, 65, 67–69, 74–75, 127n25, 128n18, 132n32 Putnam, Hilary, 111n4, 113n26, 116n58, 118n92 Pyrrhonism, 35, 125n2 qualia, 65, 130n17 qualities, primary, xxv, 57 qualities, secondary, xxv, 56–57, 101 radical empiricism, ix–xi, xiii–xiv, xvii– xix, xxi, xxvii, xxxi, xxxiii, xxxv, xxxix–xl, xlii, 16–18, 28, 31–33, 38, 40–41, 45, 57, 61–63, 70, 91–93, 95–96, 112n10, 113n22, 113n26, 116n55, 126n21, 128n16, 129n20, 134n5 rationalism, ix, xix, xxix, 1, 16–19, 36–38, 57, 92, 99, 105, 107 rationality, 35, 43–44, 107, 116n57 realism, xviii, 15, 28, 30, 111n4, 120n17, 121n33 realism, logical, 120n17 realism, natural, xviii, 15, 28, 30 realism (Spencer’s), 121n33 reality (la réalité), xxv, 5, 7–9, 12, 21–25, 29, 41, 43, 53, 63, 68, 70, 74–78, 79, 81–86, 91–92, 98–100, 103–104, 107, 113n26, 118n92, 120n25, 121n33, 122n3, 125n13, 128n16 reason, reasons given (la raison), xvii, xxiv–xxvi, xxix–xxx, xxxix, xli–xliii,
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 161
11, 18, 21, 25, 27–28, 38–39, 42–43, 48, 57, 68, 71, 74–75, 77, 83–84, 92, 97, 100–101, 103, 106, 109, 116n51, 116n57, 117n64, 118n92, 130n21 Rehmke, Johannes, xxxii, 1, 119n3 relations, ix–x, xiii, xv–xix, xxi, xxiii–xxvi, xxiii–xxxi, xxxiv–xxxv, xxxviii–xl, 4–6, 8–11, 16–23, 26, 31–32, 35–45, 47–48, 50–51, 57–59, 64, 74, 92, 99, 104–107, 109, 113n22, 114n37, 120n18, 122n3, 124n32, 125n10, 126n16, 128n16, 129n20, 135n7 relations, external, xxx, xxxv, 9–10, 17, 26, 42–43 relations, functional, xiii, xv–xvi, xviii– xxix, xxxi–xxxii relations, H. Spencer on, xxx relations, internal, xxx, xxxv, 124n32 relations, logic of, ix, x, 122n3 religion, religious, 28, 67–68, 74. See humanism Renouvier, Charles-Bernard, 111n1, 132n33, 133n33 representations, x, xvii, 20, 76, 100, 114n37 retrospection, xxiii–xxiv, 9, 51, 100, 115n48, 121n29 Royce, Josiah, 8, 62, 71, 74, 120n23, 127n31, 133n34 Russell, Bertrand, xix, 114n32, 116n55 Santayana, George, 55, 83, 128n8, 135n3 satisfaction, 15, 92, 99, 102–104 satisfactoriness, 98, 100, 123n10 Schiller, F. C. S., 73, 78, 98, 102, 125n14, 134n4 Scholasticism, 10, 97, 101, 121n32 Schubert-Soldern, Richard von, xxxii, 1, 119n3 Schuppe, Wilhelm, xxxii, 1, 119n3 Séailles, Gabriel, 128n12, 137n6 Searle, John, 114n30 secondary qualities, xxv, 56–57, 101
5/2/22 10:39 AM
162
Index
Seigfried, Charlene H., 114n33 self, the, xx–xxi, 3, 17–19, 36, 49, 64, 108, 122n7, 124n29, 131n21 self-transcendency, 21, 24, 26–27, 75, 91, 93 sensation (la sensation), xvii–xviii, xxii–xxiv, 3, 5, 11, 36, 41, 44, 54–55, 70, 77, 81–84, 101, 113n17, 130n21 sense-datum theories, xviii–xix, xxiii, xxv. See Russell, Bertrand sense of life, 5, 35, 63 Sidgwick, Arthur, 133n1 Sidis, Boris, 56 similarity, similars, xvii, xxvii, xxxvi, 5, 8–9, 16–17, 29, 39–41, 50–51, 55, 61, 68, 71, 74, 92, 105 skepticism, xvii, xxii, 73, 98, 108, 125n2 solipsism, 28, 91–93, 114n32, 114n33, 124n29 soul, 1–2, 21, 52, 66, 124n38 soul-substance, 2 space (l’espace), xxx, 5, 10–11, 17, 30–31, 36, 41–42, 44, 53–54, 64–65, 77, 82, 85–86, 101, 121n25, 124n37 Spencer, Herbert, xiv, xxx, 55, 101, 121n33, 128n10 Spinoza, Baruch, 80 Spir, Africa, 40, 125n11 spirit, spiritual (spirituel), xxv, xxx, 1, 4, 13, 28, 37, 53, 57–59, 70, 79–80, 84–86, 98, 127n25, 131n21 states of mind, 17. See mental states stimulus control, xxiii, xxiv Stout, George Frederick, 62, 71, 125n14, 130n12, 131n21, 133n34 stream of consciousness, xviii, xxii stream of experience, 43, 63 stream of life, 37, 40 stream of thought, 122n7 Strong, Charles Augustus, 32, 71, 121n30, 123n12, 124n36, 124n37, 133n35
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 162
structuralism, ix, xxii–xxiv, xxvii–xxix, 113n19. See Titchener, Edward B structuralist psychology, xxii–xxiii. See Wundt, Wilhelm structures, xxviii, xxix, xlii subjective, the, xv–xvi, xxv, xxxv, 4, 6–8, 11–12, 24, 50, 55–57, 63, 67, 80, 91, 100–101, 121n29, 131n21 subjectivism, 73, 99, 119n3 subjectivity, 6, 8, 54 substance, xiv–xv, xxviii, 1–2, 16, 19, 22, 32, 53, 101. See soul substitution, 23–24, 40, 67, 92, 99 Sully, James, 130n12 synechism, 122n3 Taine, Hippolyte, 8, 23, 82, 111n1, 120n22, 123n17 Taylor, Alfred E., 126n16 teleology, xxx, xl, 15, 68 tendency, xli, 8, 16–17, 25–26, 37, 62, 64–65, 68, 92, 101, 123n23 theism, 33, 74 thing-in-itself, (Ding an sich), 32, 101, 136n11 things (choses), xxv, xxxv, xl, 3–8, 10–12, 15–6, 18–19, 22, 26–27, 28, 30–32, 35–45, 47–47–52, 53–54, 56–57, 63, 70, 75, 79–85, 88–89, 93, 96, 108–109, 118n85, 121n33, 126n21, 131n21, 136n11 things, material, 8, 80 thinking, xxi–xxii, xxiv, xxvi, xxx, xxxvii–xxxviii, 7–8, 13, 19–20, 25, 45, 48, 59, 68–70, 77, 99, 103, 115n39, 118n78, 121n29, 133n2 thinking out-loud, xxxvii, 118n89 thought, (la pensée, der Gedanke), ix, xiii, xvii, xx, xxii, xxix, xxxii–xxxv, xxxvii–xxxviii, 1–2, 4, 6–13, 23–24, 26–27, 29–31, 51, 53, 55–56, 58, 64, 75–78, 80–82, 85, 87–89, 97–102, 104, 107, 112n10, 118n89, 120n9,
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Index 163
120n17, 121n25, 121n26, 121n29, 121n30, 121n33, 122n38, 127n5, 131n21, 132n32 time (le temps), xxx, 10, 17, 36, 65, 82, 87–88, 101 Titchener, Edward B., xxiii, xxix, 180n12 totality, rationalistic, xix, xxxii–xxxiii, 105 transcendental ego, xxxii, 1, 31, 119n2 transcendental idealism, 15, 74, 101 transcendentalists, 20, 25–27 transcendentalism, xiv, 105 transitions, ix, xviii, 9, 18–26, 28–29, 32, 40, 44, 92–93, 113n25, 123n18 truth (la vérité), ix, xviii, xxii, xxxiv, 4, 9–11, 17, 25, 27, 31–32, 37–38, 42–43, 51, 55, 63, 69, 73, 75–78, 81, 83, 88, 91, 97–104, 105, 107–109, 121n27, 123n10, 126n17 unity, 11, 15, 17–18, 32–33, 39–40 universals, 16, 37–39, 100, 107
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 163
validity, 7, 9, 25, 28, 45, 53, 98, 107, 115n44, 121n27 veridical perception, xvi verification, ix, xx, xxix, 25, 32–33, 117n63 volition, xxix, 3, 29, 108 Ward, James, xv, xxvi, 62–63, 112n6, 129n9, 130n12 Watson, John B., xxi, xxxii Weltanschauung, 15–16, 91 will, the, 65–68, 130n15, 133n33. See volition will, effort of, 3, 64, 70, 84, 106, 132n32, 132n33, 134n3 Wilbois, Joseph, 136n12 Wittgenstein, Ludwig, xx, xxvii, 114 n32 Woodbridge, Frederick J. E., 61, 75, 129n3, 136n16 Wundt, Wilhelm, xiv, xxiii–xxiv, 58, 128n17
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 164
5/2/22 10:39 AM
About the Editor
Professor H. G. Callaway has published widely in both the United States and Europe on the philosophy of language and meaning and on the interpretation of American moral-intellectual history. His publications include scores of professional articles in scholarly journals; and among more than a dozen books, Context for Meaning and Analysis (1993) and Meaning without Analyticity (2008) are devoted to the philosophy of language and interpretation. A native of Philadelphia, he holds the doctorate in philosophy from Temple University, has lectured widely both in the United States and Europe and has taught at American and European universities and at the University of Ibadan, Nigeria. His work in the philosophy of science and its history includes a critical edition of astrophysicist Arthur Eddington’s classical account of The Nature of the Physical World (2014). Callaway’s work in American philosophy and intellectual history includes many scholarly articles and reviews and his (2008) critical edition of William James’s A Pluralistic Universe. In recent work he has published a collection of his essays, Pluralism, Pragmatism and American Democracy: A Minority Report (2017).
165
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 165
5/2/22 10:39 AM
Callaway 9781793653147.indd 166
5/2/22 10:39 AM