140 60 10MB
English Pages 192 Year 2019
What's the Meaning of 'This''?
Digitized by the Internet Archive in
2015
https://archive.org/details/whatsnneaningofthOOaust
David
F.
Austin
What's the Meaning of
A
''This''?
Puzzle about Demonstrative Belief
Cornell University Press
ITHACA AND LONDON
Copyright
©
1990 by Cornell University
All rights reserved. Except for brief quotations in a review, this book, or
parts thereof,
must not be reproduced
in
any form without permission
in
writing from the publisher. For information, address Cornell University Press, 124 Roberts Place, Ithaca,
First
New
York 14850.
published 1990 by Cornell University Press.
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Austin, David
F., 1952What's the meaning of "this"? David F. Austin, cm. p.
:
a puzzle about demonstrative belief
/
Includes bibliographical references.
ISBN 0-8014-2409-7 2. Proposition 1. Belief and doubt. 121 '.6 dc20 BD215.A97 1990
—
(Logic)
I.
Title.
89-22110
Printed in the United States of America
S The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirements of the American National Standard for Permanence of Paper for Printed Library Materials 739.48-1984.
For
S.
Milton Jones,
who gave me such
my first
philosophy teacher,
a good start with
all this
Contents
Preface
1.
ix
Introducing Individual Propositions
i
Propositions
i
Propositions: Purely Qualitative
Kripke's
Modal Objection: What
and Individual Aristotle Could Not
3
Have Been Messy Shopper and Lewis's Two Gods
9
Perry's
2.
3.
11
Getting Rid of Individual Propositions? The Augmented Messy Shopper The Two Tubes Case The Examples Made Parallel
16 16
20 25
Why
Puzzling Pierre Does Not Suffice
27
Have
We
31
It's
Just
Gotten Rid of Individual Propositions?
Me Now:
Schiffer's
Schiffer
on
Belief
32
View
33
Pay Attention! Loaring the
36
Boom
38
Being There
41
and Sense Data Modal Objection
Russell
51
A
54 vii
Contents
4.
Rigid Belief Transformed: Plantinga and
Ackerman
on Essences
56
Plantinga's Proposal
57
Transformed Essences and the
The Greater Ignorance
5.
Two Tubes
Puzzle
of Smith: First Objection
59 61
Smith's Otherworldly Ignorance: Second Objection
62
Ackerman' s Essences
67
Believing Less by Believing More: Stalnaker and the Defeat of Belief
73
Possible Worlds, Propositions,
and Pragmahcs
Diagonalizing Assertions
The Persistence
77
of the Puzzle
83
Diagonalization and Demonstrative Belief
84
Eye Got Here First Believing Too Much by Believing More Diagonalizing Everywhere Interpretive Doubts: The Iceman Cometh
88
An
Unacceptable Counterintuitiveness?
Postscript: Stalnaker
Two
90 91 93
97
and Hintikka on Propositional
Identity 6.
74
99
Nontraditional Analyses of Belief:
Self-Attribution
and Character
Chisholm: All Belief
Lewis on
Belief
103
Is Self-Attributive
103
and the Two Tubes Puzzle
110
Three Terms Suffice
112
Kaplan's Unhelpful Character
115
Postscript:
Why
the Puzzle
Remains a Puzzle
Appendix: Must We Say What He Believes? On Semantics and Pragmatics in Belief Attribution Some Hard Data The Incorrectness of Russell and Frege Sensitive
and
149
151
of Belief
Vlll
143 144
Insensitive Attribution: Triadic Analyses
The Sensitivities of Richard The Insensitivities of the Naive View and Soames Chaos and Contextualism
Bibhography Index
135
152 of
Salmon i55
159
161
169
Preface
This book
is
intended to help readers understand one impor-
tant philosophical problem.
The problem concerns
and remind and clear and simple as I could make it, to nonspecialists and to graduate belief
sides at the intersection of contemporary philosophy of
language. The exposition, as is
intended to be accessible
who are just beginning their study of these specialties. used an earlier version of the book in a senior seminar and found that a fair portion of the material can be understood by bright, highly motivated undergraduates. I have also presented much of this material to specialist audiences and have found that my approach clarifies the problem significantly. Here, in outline, is what I have to say. Recent literature on philosophy of mind and language develops a variety of examples that raise serious problems for the traditionstudents
I
al
analysis of belief (and the other so-called propositional attitudes)
as a two- term relation
between
a believer
and
a proposition.
The
best-known examples involve beliefs typically expressed through use of the indexicals 'T' and ''now" (Kaplan 1977; Perry 1979; Lewis 1983a) or proper names (Kripke 1979). Because of the attractiveness of the traditional analysis and the initial absence of any clear alternative, the puzzles raised by these examples are ix
Preface
My purpose here is to provide a critical test case for any
genuine.
theory of propositional attitudes by presenting
(in
Chapter
2) a
puzzle about beliefs typically expressed using demonstratives
and
to convince the reader that "the puzzle
is a puzzle" (Kripke Because this puzzle can equally well be construed as a 1979, 239). puzzle about beliefs typically expressed using proper names, it may also be viewed as a sharpened version of Kripke's puzzle.
Adding
a puzzle about demonstrative belief
will help to highlight similarities
and
is
also useful since
differences
among
it
the three
types of puzzles and to guide us in the search for a comprehensive solution.
In the
first
section of Chapter
sitional analysis of belief.
I
1, 1
outline the traditional, propo-
then introduce the powerful intuitions
that underlie Saul Kripke's
modal and epistemic arguments
for
the 'directly referential' nature of proper names, indexicals, and
demonstratives. Using examples given by Kripke, John Perry,
and David Lewis, belief.
two
I
indicate the application of these intuitions to
So applied, the intuitions suggest a distinction between
sorts of propositions: purely qualitative
thesis suggested
is
and
individual.
The
that a straightforward account of the intuitions
promised only by an analysis that incorporates individual propproper names, indexicals, or demonstratives are to be analyzed as relating the believer to just such a proposition, true only in those situations where the very entity that may be referred to exists and has the attributed is
ositions: beliefs typically expressed using
property.
Chapter 2 presents the central example of the book, the Two Tubes case. I use it to show, in this chapter and the succeeding ones, that the promise of individual propositions is bound to be broken. Since propositions must be either individual or purely qualitative,
we must
therefore reject the traditional, two-termed
analysis of propositional attitudes
if
we
are to remain faithful to
1. The case constitutes a genuine countwo assumptions hold: (A) it is possible for a believer to believe an individual proposition with a contingent thing other than himself as a constituent; and (B) the believer in the Two Tubes case is in optimal conditions for believing an indi-
the intuitions of Chapter
terexample only
if
vidual proposition with a contingent thing as subject constituent.
X
Preface
however, a few theorists who attempt to save the by rejecting one or another of these assumpin Chapters 3-6, I provide a critical assessment of their
There
are,
traditional analysis tions;
views.
Chapter 3 begins with a discussion of Stephen Schiffer's views belief, as they are presented in his paper "The Basis of Reference/' He proposes to reject assumption (A) and recommends the
on
strategy of restricting the possible contingent constituents of indi-
vidual propositions to those that can be referred to or thought
about using the indexicals "I" or "now."
I
argue that Schiffer
may
need, in conflict with his stated aims, to allow demonstrative
about incorrigibly
belief either
known
visual field locations or
about nonexistent or incomplete objects. The problem that he faces in accounting for simple perceptual beliefs
same
is
virtually the
which prompted Russell to introduce sense data as objects of acquaintance, and I discuss a sense data solution to the Two Tubes Puzzle. Finally, I observe that the strategy built on a rejection of (A) is bound to run afoul of the powerful modal as that
intuitions of
Chapter
1.
Chapter 4 introduces the essence views of Alvin Plantinga and Ackerman, which may be seen as attempts to solve this just-mentioned modal difficulty. They agree that proper names Felicia
and demonstratives express individual essences referred
to.
of the objects
Plantinga' s proposal conflicts with the epistemic intu-
Chapter 1. Using an analogue of the Two Tubes case, I argue that he may also be unable to say which essences are initions of
Ackerman' s proposal respects both the modal and the epistemic intuitions of Chapter 1, but has several serious problems, which she herself points out. Among them are these: it is logically impossible that the two believers believe the same proposition (belief is 'essentially private'); it is logically impossible that one believer believe the same proposition at two
volved in our
beliefs.
different times (belief
Chapter 3 considers sis of
is
'ephemeral').
how one might
save the traditional analy-
propositional attitudes by rejecting assumption (B) of the
Two Tubes many, and Stalnaker.
Puzzle. This appears to be the course favored by it
A
finds an eloquent
and
forceful advocate in Robert
simple modification of the
Two Tubes
case provides xi
Preface
a
paradigm of
belief persistence that,
however, his strategy can-
not accommodate. His strategy therefore gives a strongly counterintuitive account of cognitive
dynamics, making
it
possible to
more in just those circumstances where one would expect retention of belief. Chapter 6 turns to (allegedly) nontraditional analyses of belief: Roderick Chisholm's and David Lewis's self-attributive analyses and the triadic account suggested by what David Kaplan writes in believe less
by believing
"Demonstratives.''
more than
I
observe that self-attributive analyses are
little
and so heir to all its defects. The account suggested by what Kaplan writes is either clearly refuted by the Two Tubes case or is lacking in crucial notational variants of Schiffer's view
details required for a solution to the puzzle.
In the Postscript,
give a comparative assessment of ap-
I
Two Tubes Puzzle, and I place it in by pointing out the puzzle's similarities to the
proaches to resolving the historical context
'problem of sense data'
(as
it
bedevils direct realism in the theory
of perception). Correlatively,
I
indicate the bearing of
Meth-
odological Solipsism on future attempts to solve the puzzle.
conclusion
is
that although the puzzle remains a puzzle,
it
My
gives
us reason to supplement, rather than completely to abandon, the
use of propositions in the analysis of thought; and
supplementing solution must do tions of Chapter i. In the Appendix,
I
briefly discuss
culties facing theorists
and third-person
to
remain
some
I
say what a
faithful to the intui-
of the additional diffi-
who attempt to devise a semantics for first-
belief attribution. After giving a bit of back-
recent work that presupposes a Naive view defended by Nathan Salmon and Scott Soames and the complex views of Mark Richard. I offer a partial assessment of these proposals using the
ground,
I
concentrate on
some
triadic analysis of belief: the
Two Tubes needs
to
case
and
its
variants, indicating
where further work
be done.
The reader
will find
no solution
to the
puzzle proposed here.
I
go no further than offering a clear statement of the problem, adding a few suggestions about constraints on a solution. Nor do I attempt a comprehensive survey of all, or even all the best, theories of belief that might reasonably be applied to solve the xii
Preface
puzzle. 1 Instead, clearest
I
discuss
what
I
believe to be the best
views that address the puzzle 2. Absent from even
at its three
stated in Chapter
and
main points
this restricted
survey
is
any discussion of avowedly and essentially functionalist theories of belief. I have found no such theory to be as clearly formulated as those theories I do discuss. I also note that functionalism has been repudiated by one of its originators (Putnam 1988), and a refutation of it has been given which I find conclusive (Kripke 1984).
Although
I
my focus linguistically, by refermy concern here is with the beliefs
have characterized
ring to certain parts of speech,
typically expressed using those terms linguistic
mechanisms involved
One moral
that
and not primarily with the
in their
thought or expression.
might plausibly be drawn from
this
book
is
that
extremely detailed attention will have to be given to the nature of
such mechanisms
if
there
is
solving the puzzles, but this
philosophy of attention. (For
ever to be any real progress is
my
in
and I do not undertake that detailed an excellent example of the necessary level of de-
linguistics,
see Levin 1981). So, for the sake of simplicity,
tail,
made
not an essay in formal semantics or
I
usually re-
by the simplest subjectpredicate sentences. There are problems enough, and deep enough, raised by these examples. Furthermore, in Chapters 1-6 and the Postscript, I assiduously avoid the problems raised by third-person belief attributions (see Kripke 1979, 251-252; and the Appendix). Every puzzle I want to focus on is expressible using first-person belief sentences ('T believe that p"), although I occasionally depart from this restriction strict
attention to beliefs expressed
for the sake of
Finally,
I
convenience or
stylistic variety.
should note that beliefs typically expressed using
proper names, demonstratives, or indexicals (or some subset thereof) are taken re,
and some
called
is
by some philosophers as paradigms of belief de and labyrinthine literature on belief so-
of the vast
certainly relevant here. But
particularly regret that
my
inability to
leaves
me unable
(1982)
and Christopher Peacocke
to discuss the
work
it
is
not
my goal to guide
the
understand what they have written Evans
of the British Neo-Fressellians Gareth
(1983).
xiii
Preface
reader through that labyrinth.
What I want
to say can,
I
think, be
said without ever again using the term ''belief de re." So the use of
my last use of
it in this book (although the term be mentioned in quotations from other authors).
it
here will be
Professor Manifold, visiting Great University, the proof of a theorem
was obvious.
claimed,
and had
A member
was sketching
lemma;
just stated a
may
its
proof, he
of the audience interrupted,
objecting that the proof was not at all obvious. They argued for a while and then stepped outside, where they continued their dis-
cussion for another twenty minutes.
was
When
they returned, the
"He was right," the objector said. "It was obvious, after all." I hope that after a reader completes this book, a great deal of it will have become obvious, after all. objector
During
many
my
quite chagrined:
years of
work on
this
book,
I
have learned from
people about the topics treated here, and
acknowledge
their help.
I
it is
a pleasure to
proceed from the specific to the
general.
Chapters
i
and 2 benefited
in clarity
from detailed comments
provided by William R. Carter and David Auerbach.
Wayne Backman and Harold Levin enabled improve several sections of Chapter 3. Letters from Joseph Mendola and Max Cresswell reassured me that the arguments of the chapter were worth extended treatment. Albert Casuilo and Stephen Schiffer were helpful correspondents. A version of Chapter 4 was published in the Notre Dame Journal Formal Logic 24 (January 1983), under the title "Plantinga's Theof ory of Proper Names," and I am grateful for permission to use portions of it here. An earlier version of that paper was presented to the Herbert Heidelberger Task Force on Propositional Attitudes. Alvin Plantinga was very encouraging. Discussion and correspondence with Felicia Ackerman helped me to understand Discussions with
me
to
her views.
The main arguments
5 were discussed at a meeting on Content, a biweekly discussion mind and language held at the National
of
Chapter
of the Triangle Conference
group on philosophy of Humanities Center during the academic year 1983-84. (The group's other members were Wayne Backman, Lynne Rudder Baker, Alan Berger, Michael Ferejohn, Robert Hambourger, xiv
Preface
Harold Levin, William Lycan, Jonathan Malino, and David Sanford.) That discussion prompted me to add "Believing Too Much by Believing More" to the chapter. Conversation with Wayne Backman and Robert Hambourger further clarified the arguments. When I gave talks based on the chapter, Richard Feldman, Bernard Kobes, Hugues LeBlanc, Ralf Meerbote, and Thomas McKay asked helpful questions. Robert Stalnaker and David Lewis were generous with assistance in correspondence and Igal Kvart,
conversation.
A letter Postscript,
from David Lewis was important
and
I
am
to
Chapter 6 and the
very grateful to him for permission to repro-
duce a portion of that letter here. A discussion with him prevented me from making an error in Chapter 3 and aided me in writing the Appendix. Discussions with Thomas Blackson, Harold Levin, and Joseph Levine led to significant improvements in the last section of Chapter 6. Responding to the comments of one of the publisher's anonymous readers made the arguments of Chapters 3, 4, and 3 clearer. With amazing speed, Takashi Yagisawa provided me with helpful comments on the entire penultimate draft. I completed that and the final draft after moving to North Carolina State University.
My department head,
Robert Bryan,
who
is
retiring after
I and my good academic home, and I thank him for building it and maintaining it in such good repair. William Lycan and Lynne Baker have been valued philosophical companions since 1980. I hope they have lost track of the number of times that they have heard me describe the Two Tubes case and its variants. I assure them that the number is at most denumerable, and I thank them for their patience and encourage-
twenty-three years of superb service, has seen to
it
that
colleagues have a
ment.
The
book was adopted because I had Gareth Matthews' s practical wisdom and philo-
overall structure of this
the benefit of
sophical insight. I
thank the National Endowment
for
Humanities
for a fellow-
ship during 1987-88. The research that the fellowship sible led to significant revisions in
and
and extensions
made
fea-
of Chapters 3
6.
There are
six
philosophers
who
deserve special thanks: XV
Had
it
Preface
not been for encouragement given by Nathan Salmon and Scott
Soames,
would not have attempted
I
work. As
to publish this
publishers' readers of the penultimate draft, they gave
the most helpful criticism that
shared an
office
with
me
while
I
I
was writing
ing with him, then and since, has better than
it
some
of
have ever seen. Earl Conee the
first draft.
made each and every
would otherwise have been. I have had
of discussing triadic accounts of belief with
one of
Talk-
chapter
the privilege
their
most able
Richard. Our many talks about have been important to my understanding of the virtues and defects of contemporary work. Herbert Heidelberger's death deprived me of a good friend and a much-valued teacher, and it deprived philosophy of an extremely
and
creative proponents,
belief
and
Mark
belief attribution
able practitioner.
A
significant portion of this work's content at-
tained form in seminars and discussions with him.
Had Herb many
lived, he might well have given us satisfactory solutions to
puzzles about
The
belief, the
greatest debt of
teacher
Edmund
Two Tubes
all,
penetrating philosophers
is owed to my friend and one of the sharpest and most have ever known; there are very few
He
Gettier. I
Puzzle included.
however, is
good at the detailed, searching criticism that is a necessary prolegomenon to philosophical progress. More than anyone else, he taught me how philosophy ought to be done. Whatever is good in this book is so largely because of what I learned from as
him.
As do
one has exacted a considerable toll from the author's family. My wife, Candice Ward, has been more supportive than I had any right to hope she would be, and more tolerant than she should have been. Her expert advice on stylistic matters has been invaluable. Our daughter, Alexandra AustinWard, helped me to gain and keep a healthier perspective on
many
all
such projects,
this
important things, work included.
Finally,
I
add
a note that,
though not an acknowledgment
for
help, nevertheless deserves to be here rather than buried in a
Given the naturalness of the requirements that generate the book's central example, it had surprised me that the same thing had not been devised by others as well: if one seeks a footnote.
puzzle case involving simultaneously held, logically consistent, xvi
Preface
occurrent, demonstrative beliefs that result from direct visual perception, one
is
virtually forced to the
checking references for the
Rosenkrantz had in
fact
Two Tubes
final draft,
I
independently devised a case
the central one of this book. Although he and quite differently, the example itself rant a sharing of credit,
example. While
discovered that Gary
and
this
I
is
am
I
see
its
much
S.
like
significance
important enough to warglad to do.
David
F.
Austin
Durham, North Carolina
xvii
What's the Meaning of
''This''?
A
CHAPTER ONE
Introducing Individual Propositions
The time has come,
the author said, to talk of propositional
things.
Propositions
One
of the earliest
osition
is
found
modern
in Bertrand Russell's ''Meinong's
plexes and Assumptions,"
and G.
E.
descriptions of the notion of a prop-
Moore with
where Russell
a similar notion:
That every presentation and every than
pen
itself
to
Theory of ComMeinong,
credits Frege,
belief
must have an
object other
and, except in certain cases where mental existents hap-
be concerned, extra-mental; that what
perception has as
its
object
enters as a constituent that
an
is
commonly
called
which concerned, and not
existential proposition, into
whose
existence
is
the idea of this existent; that truth and falsehood apply not to beliefs,
but to their objects; and that the object of a thought, even
when
this object does not exist, has a Being which is in no way dependent upon its being an object of thought: all these are theses which, though generally rejected, can nevertheless be supported by arguments which deserve at least a refutation. (Russell 1973, 21) 1
What's the Meaning of "This"?
The hardiness
of the notion, at least,
is
attested to
by
its
survival,
largely intact, during the eighty-four years since Russell wrote.
Echoing the essentials of what John Perry (1979) has called "the doctrine of propositions,'' Robert Stalnaker writes.
assume that O'Leary's believing between the man O'Leary and an abstract object call it a proposition which is denoted by the expression that pigs can fly. To make this assumption is not to say very much about what sort of things propositions are: they might be complexes made up of concepts and objects, sentences of some at least initially plausible to
It is
that pigs can fly
is
a relation
—
ideal
—
language of thought, equivalence classes of sentence tokens,
functions from possible worlds into truth values. The doctrine is
independent of the
propositional objects;
all
that
is
essential
is
.
.
.
about the nature of
details of one's theory
that propositions
have
truth values that
do not vary from time
place to place.
propositions are identified with sentences or mean-
If
ings of sentences, they eternal sentences.
If
must be
person to person, or
to time,
eternal sentences, or
meanings of
propositions are identified with functions tak-
ing truth and falsity as values, they must take possible worlds as
arguments, and not indices that may have different values in same world. The received doctrine may be summed up in two theses: 1. Belief is a relation between an animate subject and an abstract object which we will call, without prejudging its nature, a their
the
proposition. 2.
Propositions have truth values, and their truth values do not
vary with time, place or person. (Stalnaker 1981, 129-130)
Perry adds a third thesis, with which Stalnaker (1981, i49n4) concurs:
The
third [thesis] has to
tions].
It is
do with how we individuate
necessary, for that S and that
S' to
.
.
.
[proposi-
be the same, that they
have the same truth-value. But it is not sufficient, for that the sea is and that milk is white are not the same proposition. It is necessary that they have the same truth condition, in the sense that they
salty
attribute to the
same
objects the
sufficient, for that Atlanta
is
same
relation.
the capital of Georgia
capital of the largest state east of the Mississippi are
sition.
[Jimmy] Carter,
second. 2
.
.
.
it
But
and
is
the
not the same propo-
seems, might believe the
[P]ropositions
this is also not
that Atlanta
must be individuated
first
in a
but not the
more
"fine-
Introducing Individual Propositions
grained"
way than
is
provided by truth-value or the notion of truth
conditions employed above. (Perry 1979, 6)
Just hov^ fine-grained the individuation conditions for propositions
must be
agreement that necessary that
examples
a subject of
Chapter 2 which suggest that the converse
in
but the issue I w^ill
some dispute, but there is w^ide for propositions p and q, p = q only if it is logically p is true if and only if q is true. (We v^ill see
is
is
not one that
assume the
sitional identity,
when I make
I
attempt to resolve.) In
w^idely accepted necessary condition for propo-
along with the two theses stated by Stalnaker,
use of the notion of proposition.
I
will also
with Russell and other writers, not only that belief relation
between
is false,
v^^hat foUow^s,
a thinking subject
the so-called propositional attitudes
and
is
assume,
a two-term
a proposition, but that
may
also,
according to the
traditional doctrine of propositions, be similarly analyzed. Thus,
O'Leary's knowing that pigs are quadrupeds his bearing the
is
be analyzed as
to
two-term relation knowing to the proposition
pigs are quadrupeds; his
wondering whether pigs can
that
fly is to
be
analyzed as his bearing the relation wondering to the proposition that pigs can fly; his fearing that pigs
can
fly is to
bearing the relation fearing to the proposition
be analyzed as his
that pigs can fly;
and
similarly for disbelieving, hoping, wishing, thinking, consider-
and a
ing, is
variety of other cognitive states.
Although the doctrine
usually taken to apply to nonoccurrent (dispositional) states, as
well as to occurrent states
— so
while he dreams of flying pigs part, involve occurrent belief. tion,
I
will
may
that for example, O'Leary
continue to bear the believing relation to
that pigs are
— my use of
it
quadrupeds
will, for
the most
For the sake of simplicity in exposi-
avoid using the brand of the doctrine that makes
propositions equivalence-classes of uses of sentence tokens
(
per-
haps under the relation "has the same meaning as"); instead, will use the complexes and possible worlds brands.
Propositions: Purely Qualitative
Some philosophers make
and Individual
a significant additional claim
the nature of the objects of belief.
I
They say
that
all
about
such objects
What's the Meaning of "This"?
and deny that they are individual. In the one finds several ways of characterizing the complementary notions of purely qualitative proposition and individual proposition. None of the characterizations is pellucid, but one can get a tolerably clear idea of what is meant by considering several of them, especially in their applications. The most common characterizations of purely qualitative propositions are negative and linguistic, and begin by talking about purely qualitative properties out of which the purely qualitative are purely qualitative literature
propositions are then 'constructed' (or with reference to which their possible
Robert
Adams
worlds truth conditions are given). For example,
...
tive
if
"We might try to capture the idea [of a by saying that a property is purely qualita-
writes,
qualitative property]
and only
if it
could be expressed, in a language
suffi-
ciently rich, without the aid of such referential devices as proper
names, proper adjectives and verbs (such as 'Leibnizian' and 'pegasizes'), indexical expressions, and referential uses of definite descriptions" (1979, 7). The element of idealization here ("language sufficiently rich") and the avoidability of the mentioned linguistic devices are two common features of specifications of purely qualitative properties (see Chisholm 1981, 5-6, 7, 10-11; and Fine 1977a, 128). Adams offers another characterization of the notion that depends on a prior understanding of a certain sort of noTiqualitative property, which he calls a "thisness":
A thisness is the property of being identical with a certain particular individual
— not the property that we
with some individual or other, but
all
my
share, of being identical
property of being identical
with me, your property of being identical with you, .
.
.
etc.
another and possibly more illuminating approach [other than
the linguistic one quoted above] to the definition of 'suchness' this].^ All
[is
properties that are, in certain senses general (capable of
being possessed by different individuals) and nonrelational are suchnesses.
More
precisely, let us say that a basic suchness
erty that satisfies the following three conditions. (1)
ness and
is
related in
one way or another
1
"Suchness"
4
not equivalent to one.
is
Adams's term
to
(2) It is
It is
is
a prop-
not a this-
not a property of being
one or more particular individuals
for purely qualitative property.
Introducing Individual Propositions
(or
to
house
This
thisnesses).
their
suchnesses are in a sense at loii
Rose Avenue,
The property
of
some basic owning the
Arbor, Michigan,
is
not a basic
not to deny that
is
relational.
Ann
.
.
.
suchness, although several different individuals have had
cause
it
erty of being a
homeowner
because having
owns.
be-
it,
involves the thisness of that particular house. But the prop-
(3)
it
is
a basic suchness, although relational,
does not depend on which particular
A basic suchness is not a
home one
property of being identical with
way or another to an extensionally defined set that among its members, or among its members' mem-
or related in one
has an individual bers, or
among its members' members' members,
an American
and
places,
to
is
suchness. For structed
must
by
itself
Thus,
if
being
not a basic suchness.
it is
These three conditions may be taken as a suchness, but
etc.
be analyzed as a relation to a set of actual people
it is it
jointly sufficient for
being
not clear that they are also necessary for being a
seems
intuitively that
any property that
con-
is
certain operations out of purely qualitative properties
be purely qualitative. The operations
the construction are of two sorts.
those expressed by erty ascribed to x
'not', 'or',
by
and
(1)
^(3x)(})(
^(3x).
I
will
may
make
On
this view,
and
the just-
aptly be represented by the
the property being mortal:
. The
there. "^ But
latter is Perry's discovery,
"now seeming
what
(2)
< Perry, and
is
to see
expresses being
a
is
a
mess-
discovered only
he learns the additional individual proposition he could express by
after
(3)
I
am
the person
I
now seem
to see over there.
'The precise role of the explanation of action in characterizing belief is not I assume here that it serves only to make the difference in (1) more vivid and carries no heavier theoretical burden.
entirely clear in Perry's essay.
^See Chapter
18
3,
"Being There/' for some discussion of one role of "there."
Getting Rid of Individual Propositions?
Perry makes his discovery by inferring express.
From
nite description (''the is
room enough
person to
room
now seem
I
maneuver
(2)
and
(3)
for
an additional
defi-
to see over there"),
and
for a saving delay in his learn-
< Perry,
ing the individual proposition I
from what
the point of view of the advocate of individual
propositions. Perry's example leaves
that
it
being a mess-maker>
think that this response to Perry exemplifies the best sort of
response available to the advocate of individual propositions. also
response was the
to
ing a mess" could not be the individual proposition a mess-maker>.
It
some embarrassing questions. Part of the claim that what Perry expressed by "he is mak-
opens the door
But what
< Perry,
being
about the circumstances of Perry's
is it
assertion that necessarily prevents Perry from believing that indi-
vidual proposition then? Are there
some
stringent necessary con-
ditions for the apprehension of individual propositions that Perry fails to
meet?
If
so,
what
are they? Presumably, Perry can in
circumstances express the individual proposition
mess-maker> by asserting "he
is
making
a mess."^
< Perry,
some
being a
What is it about Anyone who
the mirror case that prevents his doing that there?
wishes
to claim that
is trickier
questions.
coming
to believe
an individual proposition
than Perry seems to think owes us an answer to these
What would be most
desirable
is
a clear statement of
necessary and sufficient conditions under which a believer ap-
prehends a given individual proposition. I
The embarrassthey did was to bring
said that these questions are embarrassing.
ment would not be
terribly significant
if all
our attention to a gap in the view of the advocate of individual propositions. will
Gaps can sometimes be
next present a
filled satisfactorily,
but
I
To help show this, I puzzle about demonstrative belief and beliefs ex-
argue that this gap cannot be so
pressed using proper names. ^
I
filled.
will return to indexical belief later
in the chapter.
^For a theory that denies 3,
this,
see the discussion of Schiffer's theory, in Chapter
below.
'^In view of the fact that there are puzzles about demonstrative belief and beliefs expressed using proper names that are parallel to those involving indexical belief, it is perhaps misleading to speak of "the problem of the essential indexical." See
also Boer
and Lycan
1980.
19
What's the Meaning of "This"?
The Two Tubes Case Smith
is
the subject of a psychological experiment designed to
test his ability to focus his
eyes independently of each other.
He
and he has developed this ability to perfection, having spent hundreds of hours working at the microscope, one eye on the objective, the other on the paper where he draws what he sees. The experimental apparatus consists of a large, opaque screen with two small eye holes in it. Two tubes lead from the eye holes and can be oriented in a large number of direcis
a medical student,
tions to point at a uniformly red, uniformly illuminated sheet
of plastic in front of the screen. Smith
is
to look
through the
tubes simultaneously and to report what he sees as he focuses his
He is familiar with the apparatus and knows know how the tubes are oriented. At noon on the
eyes independently. that he does not
day of the experiment. Smith steps up to the screen and looks through the tubes simultaneously, taking no notice of how his eyes are in fact oriented and focusing his eyes independently. What he sees through his right eye is a circular red spot, which he dubs "this/' what he sees through his left eye is a precisely similar circular red spot, which he dubs "that."5 Because Smith is focusing his eyes independently, he does not have one, unified visual field, with right and left halves; rather, he has two, independent visual fields and at the center of each he sees a red spot.^ He thinks to himself,
(4) this is
A
red and that
is
red.
somewhat pedantic and cautious person, he
also thinks to
himself,
(5) this
=
this
and
that
=
that,
suppose Smith uses both "this" and "that" for convenience. We could conan equally useful but harder to state puzzle case by supposing that Smith uses two tokens of the syntactic type "this" (or "that"), or even that he makes two uses of one token of the type "this" (or "that") in his dubbings. ^The assumption that Smith has two independent visual fields will be of some importance for the discussion of Schiffer's view in Chapter 3 and for the discussion of Kaplan's suggestion in Chapter 6.
—
struct
20
—
Getting Rid of Individual Propositions?
an expression in part of his belief that what he is seeing exists. Smith does not know how the tubes are oriented and knows that he is ignorant, so he wonders, ''Is this = that?'' When I say he wonders in this way, I mean to be stipulating in part that he neither believes nor disbelieves what he would express by "this = that" or by "this 9^ that." He is, however, confident of the truth of the beliefs he expresses by (4) and (3). Even though Smolens, the sadistic supervising psychologist, has threatened Smith with a fatal electric shock if he (Smith) attempts to report beliefs about how things merely appear to him to be, rather than about how they are. Smith remains confident in his beliefs, a wholly rational attitude, given the optimal perceptual circumstances in which Smith knows himself to be.^ Let us then stipulate in addition that (4) and (5) not only express beliefs of Smith's, but also express propositions that he knows that he knows. To summarize, let us imagine that Smith's interior monologue goes like this: I
know
that
I
know
red and that that
=
that,
=
that or that this
#
that,
this
And
=
that or that this
about
all
is red and that this = this and that that and I know that I do not believe that this and I know that I do not disbelieve that
that this
is
of this.
#
that.
Smith
is
entirely correct; his interior
mono-
logue expresses nothing but truths.
suppose that the tubes are
Finally,
same red I
in fact
pointed at the very
spot.
claimed above that this example would cause trouble for an
advocate of individual propositions; First,
(A)
I
assume
It is
I'll
now
explain
how
it
does.
that
possible that a believer believe an individual proposition
with a contingent thing other than himself as a constituent.
Second,
I
think
it is
mal circumstances may
clear
from the example that Smith is in optiand knowing an individual
for believing
avoid 'Spot of Theseus' worries by imagining that the sheet of red
plastic is in a stasis field (of a sort familiar to readers of science fiction),
permits no change in basic constituents or their intrinsic relations.
suppose
that
Smith knows that the sheet
is
contained in such a
which
We may
field.
21
also
What's the Meaning of "This"? proposition.
He
after
is,
all,
looking straight at the red spot, his
eyes are in perfect condition, the lighting is
an
intelligent
and
reflective
person
optimal perceptual circumstances. tion to believe or
assume
know such an
excellent,
and Smith
that
he
is
in
No one is ever in a better posi-
individual proposition. So
I
also
that
(B) If (A) is true,
then Smith believes the individual proposition he
expresses by "this expresses by "that
Which
is
who knows
= this" and ^ that."
the individual proposition he
individual propositions are expressed by "this
by "that =
that," as
=
this"
and
Smith uses them? They both express the same
individual proposition, representable as the ordered triple consisting of the spot
he sees, the identity
we use we may represent
for the spot,
sees.
If
relation,
and
these facts as follows:
(6)
the proposition that Smith expresses by "this
(7)
the proposition that Smith expresses by "that
same individual
that," as
= this"= = that"= .
Smith uses
it,
expresses the
proposition:
the proposition that Smith expresses by "this
(8)
We
=
also true that "this
It is
and the spot he
for the identity relation,
= that"=
.
therefore have the result that:
(C)
If
Smith believes the individual proposition he expresses by = this" and the individual proposition he expresses by
"this
"that
=
((C)
would
still
"or," in itself
makes (D)
it
It is
he believes the individual proposition he
that," then
expresses by "this
=
that."
express a truth
an odd
result.)
if
the "and" were replaced by an
But Smith's interior monologue
equally clear that not the case that Smith believes the individual proposition
he expresses by 22
"this
=
that."
Getting Rid of Individual Propositions?
=
seems that (D) for.^ The trouble for the advocate of individual propositions is that, on that view, all of (A), (B), (C), and (D) are true. But they are also inconsistent and so can't all be true. Before returning to discussion of Perry's Augmented Messy Shopper and indexical belief, I want to mention one, rather common, possible line of response to the Two Tubes case. (It has often been the first response that I have encountered after presenting the case.) One might try to save individual propositions by using a metalinguistic strategy: Smith does not believe the inAfter
all.
must be
Smith wonders,
true
"Is this
Smith's ignorance
if
that?"
is
to
So
it
be accounted
dividual propositions expressed using the demonstratives "this"
and
"that," but instead believes the metalinguistic propositions
(9) "this
is
red and that
is
red" expresses a true individual
=
that" expresses a true individual
proposition (10) "this
=
and
this
that
proposition
and he wonders
metalinguistically
whether
"this
=
that" ex-
presses a true individual proposition. In the absence of considerable further detail, refute this suggestion.
It is,
it is
not possible to
however, worth indicating,
in a pre-
liminary way, the sort of reply that this kind of response de-
we may suppose that Smith has the metahe could express by (9) and (10), it is clear from the example (I would claim) that he also believes the propositions expressed by the sentences mentioned in (9) and (10). Second, even if we were to grant that the metalinguistic response works in the case as described, we can add a bit to the example to disable this kind of response. (I think that this second reply amounts to a clarification of the first. It doesn't much matter how we count the serves. First, although
linguistic beliefs
replies.)
Assume
that
it
is
possible for a believer to refer to
and
demonstrate the propositions that he or she believes. ^ Let us then ^There are additional problems here. For example. Smith's wondering,
=
that?"
is,
on the view being that
=
that?" But,
^Here, of course,
is
one point
and "Is wonder that. this?"
"Is this
as his wondering, "Is this
=
by hypothesis, Smith knows better than
to
criticized, the
at
same
which additional
detail is
needed before a
refutation can be given.
23
What's the Meaning of "This"? stipulate that
Smith knows that he knows the following metalinthem as he would):
guistic facts (to state
what I dub "this" what I dub "that" = this" expresses the proposition that this = this = that" expresses the proposition that that - that - that" expresses the proposition that this - that
(11) this is
(12) that is (13) "this (14) "that (15) "this
if anyone can ever know such metalinguistic facts. Smith Not only are his perceptual circumstances optimal, as re-
Surely,
does.
corded (This
in (B), above,
is
but so are his 'metalinguistic circumstances'.
a metalinguistic version of (B), above.)
If
we
allow, in
addition, that Smith can demonstrate these individual proposi-
by an appropriate focusing of his mind's eye), then (I would suggest) the problems raised by the Two Tubes case are merely deferred, and not solved. Suppose that Smith says tions (perhaps
(16) this proposition is
expressed by "this = this"
(17) that proposition
expressed by "that = that"
and then wonders original
is
"Is this proposition
problems would recur
in
=
that proposition?"
The
semantic ascent. (This kind of
reply would also seem to render implausible a suggestion made by Heidelberger [1982] which, when applied to this case, would have it that although Smith asserts the individual propositions involved, he does not believe them.^o Clearly, he does both.) I have described the Two Tubes case as an example of demonstrative belief, but it can easily be redescribed as an example of beliefs expressed using proper names. Suppose that Smith dubs what he sees through his right eye "Harold" and dubs what he sees through his left eye "Maude." Then substitute "Harold" for "this" and "Maude" for "that" throughout the original description." lOYYhen 28, 1981,
I last discussed the Two Tubes case with Heidelberger, on December he expressed a strong inclination to adopt instead what we took to be
Stalnaker's view.
'^Unless I put myself in circumstances similar to Smith's, it seems that 1 cannot use "this" and "that" to express his beliefs and his ignorance. But it seems that
24
Getting Rid of Individual Propositions?
The Two Tubes case is designed to necessary and sufficient conditions
satisfy the strictest plausible
for
someone's believing an
individual proposition with a contingent thing other than the believer as a constituent, that
But
if it
succeeds in doing
is, it is
this,
designed
to
individual propositions to give such conditions
above, a gap that cannot be
filled satisfactorily.
concluding that the reply
justified in
mented Messy Shopper on behalf
In order to
make
(B) true.
I
is,
as
claimed
I
We would then be
offered to Perry's
Aug-
of the advocate of individual
propositions, although of the best sort,
The Examples Made
make
then the failure of an advocate of
is
not one that succeeds.
Parallel
clear the parallel
between the problems pre-
sented by these two cases. Perry's and the I'wo Tubes,
out Perry's in the same fashion as
I
did the
will lay
I
Two Tubes case in the
last section.
The that
force of Perry's
it is
tions,
example depends
possible for a believer to learn
in part
some
with the believer as a constituent, in
on an assumption
individual proposi-
much the same way as
one learns individual propositions about others. assumption rather conservatively as follows: (A')
It is
I
will
put this
possible that a believer believe an individual proposition
with the believer as a constituent, where the proposition expressed by the believer in a sentence of the form, a
synonymous
"I
is
not
am f " (or
expression).
seems that one way we could learn individual propositions with others as constituents is by seeing others. In Perry's example, he not only seems to see himself, but he also does see himself in the mirror and comes thereby to have the beliefs described in It
some quite dissimilar circumstances in which I can acquire these names and use them correctly to attribute beliefs to Smith. I defer consideration of problems raised by third-person belief attribution until the Appendix, where 1 provide a brief introduction to some recent work on the semantics and pragmatics of belief attribution. I do assume, however, that even if there are two causal chains involved, (say, one for "this" and another for "Harold"), they can share an initial segment, in a dubbing situation. there are
25
What's the Meaning of "This"? his example. Because of
some contingent facts about human
eyes.
Perry's seeing himself as he does requires a device that changes
the path of the illuminating light rays, but
how
it is
hard to understand
the contingent need to use such a device (for example, mir-
rors or lenses) could reduce the effectiveness of the example.
example could be eliminated if we were to indulge in a bit of science fiction and suppose that the believer in the example has his eyes on long stalks so that he can use his eyes to view himself more directly. 12 So, as in the Two Tubes case, the believer seems to be in optimal conditions for learning the rele-
Even
this feature of the
vant individual proposition: (B') If (A') is true,
then Perry believes the individual proposition he
expresses by "he
is
making
a mess."
Since the individual proposition Perry expresses by "he a mess'' "I
is
just the individual proposition expressed
am making (C)
a mess,"
we
by
is
making
his use of
have:
If
Perry believes the individual proposition he expresses by "he
is
making
a
mess," then Perry believes the individual proposi-
he expresses by
tion
"I
am making
a mess."
is, when Perry sees himself in the mirror, he has thereby made Perry's discovery. But it is equally clear from the example that when he first sees himself in the mirror,
That
(D') Perry
by
Again,
it
"I
does not believe the individual proposition he expresses
am making
a mess."
would seem
that (D')
must be held
advocate of individual propositions
why
Perry then
to straighten
up
fails to
if
stop pushing his cart
his sugar sack. But not
all
be true by the
to
an account
is
down
to
be given of
the aisle and
of (A'), (B'), (C),
be true since they are inconsistent. To make the parallel between the two examples closer
and
(D') can
^2We may also suppose that the stalk-eyed believers one ever sees both of anyone's eye stalks.
26
live in a
still,
we
world where no
Getting Rid of Individual Propositions?
might have Perry consider the propositions he'd express by "I = I," "he = he," and "I = he" (or grammatical variants thereof). According to the advocate of individual propositions, the same belief is expressed thrice over. But that's wrong. Again, a strategy of semantic ascent
would be no help
for reasons precisely parallel
to those discussed in the last section.
Why
Puzzling Pierre Does Not Suffice
In case
you have not yet met him,
let
me
introduce you to the
world's greatest logician. Puzzling Pierre (Kripke 1979). He was raised as a monolingual French speaker, and although not geographically omniscient, he has
amassed
a great deal of informa-
London and has come to believe, as he often puts it, est jolie." Soon after his twenty-fifth birthday (when he is
tion about
"Londres
height of his powers as a logician), he
kidnapped by the Lakatos Collective and taken to London, where he is confined to a dingy area near the London School of Economics and forced to at the
is
He
participate in degenerating research programs.
learns En-
from the bottom up, so to speak, without translating between it and French. Without abandoning any of his prior geographical beliefs, he comes to believe, as he now puts it, "London is not pretty." Feeling understandably sorry for himself, he thinks, mixing French and English in a single sentence, "London sure isn't pretty, mais Londres est jolie; I sure wish I were in Londres instead." Given the facts of Pierre's situation, and some assumptions about translation and disquotation, we face a genuine glish
puzzle, says Kripke. able to us
and
On
the basis of the linguistic evidence avail-
of Pierre's manifest
French and English,
it
seems
competence as a speaker of
clear that
we
can apply "disquota-
tion" to Pierre's English utterances to get:
(18) Pierre believes that
where the known
is
not pretty,
principle of disquotation to
^^Some of these not
London
at the
which Kripke appeals
details are revealed here for the first time.
time that Kripke wrote
"A Puzzle about
Many
of
is:
them were
Belief."
27
What's the Meaning of "This"?
(DQ)
If (in
a given context) S sincerely, reflectively
and compe-
tently assents to sentence "p", then S believes the proposi-
tion that p (expressed
by "p"
in the context).
(Please excuse the use/mention devastation.) translation of "Londres est jolie"
it
,
With the
seems equally
correct
clear that dis-
quotation yields (19) Pierre believes that
Kripke
never
London
would what is what is
insists that Pierre, as the w^orld's greatest logician,
contradiction in his beliefs pass unnoticed;
let a
expressed by the that-clause in expresses by the that-clause in are
pretty.
is
what
(18)
(19).
does not contradict
But
if
individual propositions
Pierre believes, then his beliefs are contradictory: (18)
expresses ; and (19) expresses ; so individual propositions won't do. How,
we
though, are
Chapter
1
if
to respect the doxastic
what
and modal
intuitions of
Pierre believes are not individual proposi-
tions?i4
Given the economy and ingenuity of this example, is there any need for yet another? After all, one should not multiply examples beyond necessity. A decade of experience with students (graduate and undergraduate), other philosophers (specialists and nonspecialists), and a burgeoning literature on the case ot Puzzling Pierre has convinced me that another example is needed. Here's why. The use of two languages in the Pierre case, and the consequent need to appeal to a principle of translation, have led to some unfortunate commentary. There is a large philosophical literature on translation, and issues concerning it can become quite tangled. Some have denied that translation preserves the meaning of the names "London" and "Londres." The bilingual presentation of the case may also have led some to focus on the very words that Pierre uses in his utterances, proposing that what Pierre really believes are the propositions that what "London" refers i^This
is
not exactly
to present purposes.
28
how
Kripke argues.
I
have adapted (DQ) and the discussion
Getting Rid of Individual Propositions?
and
to is not pretty,
liance
on
what "Londres"
that
refers to
some
a disquotational principle has led
is
The
pretty.
only real issue concerns defeasible linguistic evidence for
person belief
attribution.^^
And
then there
London, a
belief is about, the city of
is
re-
to think that the third-
the thing that the
vast, multipartite entity v^ith
obscure or vague identity conditions: there are more apparent routes of doxastic access
than there are roads
to it
in
provides the friends of qualitative propositions with too say and makes vv^ith
tion.
it
far easier
than
should be
it
This
it.
much
to
for others to get av^ay
vague gestures in the general direction of a possible soluThe appearance of contra dictoriness in Pierre's beliefs
Kripke's insistence to the contrary notwithstanding
some
to claim that the puzzle
ity of
such contradictory
is
— has
led
resolved by denying the possibil-
one might claim
belief. Correlatively,
that Puzzling Pierre's 'cognitive dynamics' are less stable than
somehow lost the belief in (19) when he acquired the belief in (18). And there is a disadvantage in first presenting the puzzle using a name "London" already in common use: it may lead one to think that it is only when the Kripke maintains and that Pierre
—
—
causal chain linking believer to object has exceeded the
segment
in a
dubbing
and the term
situation,
achieved linguistic currency, that the puzzle can I
initial
in question
has
arise.
believe that these attempts to avoid or minimize the puzzle
are in error.
Rather than meet them head on, however,
the following suggestion, which
To
is
as
much
I
offer
pedagogical as philo-
and minimize confusion, let us divide our labors with such puzzles into two (related) parts, one primarily concerning belief and another focusing on belief attribution and communication. In view of the preceding, we then need sophical:
force clarity
a case with the following six features:
i^But notice that Kripke did not entitle his paper tion."
A
correct account of belief attribution
puzzles about
us to the
belief.
It
should be a one-
"A Puzzle about
Belief Attribu-
clearly relevant to solving these
But a proper emphasis on belief attribution should not blind puzzles are equally ones about belief, whether or not they
fact that these
involve beliefs actually attributed by ^^I
is
(i)
offer
no catalogue
alleged errors are fairly
had not been made
someone other than
the believer.
of citations to the allegedly mistaken literature. All these
common, both
in print,
it
would
and in discussion. But even if they be useful to suggest ways of avoiding
in print still
them.
29
What's the Meaning of "This"?
no translation between natural languages between idiolects in a single language, (ii) To defer consideration of problems raised by third-person belief attribution, idiolect case, involving
or even
the case should invoke first-person ('reflexive') belief attribution,
any.
if
(iii)
There should be no apparent contradictoriness in the What the belief is about should be as simple
believer's beliefs, (iv)
as
is feasible,
to help avoid the distractions
engendered by com-
plex objects with obscure or vague identity conditions, (v) doxastic
and epistemic access
be as direct as possible:
direct,
The
of the subject to the object should
unmediated,!^ visual contact. This
feature will help to emphasize the fact that puzzles aplenty arise
even
in a paradigmatic
dubbing situation and
dal intuition to operate at obviously
full
will allow the
strength.
I
contact so that advocates of the Primacy of the Visual I
mo-
choose visual
may join in;
confine attention to the visual sense to avoid questions about
whether
different senses, say, vision
different relevant information.
and touch,
(vi)
yield essentially
Issues concerning differ-
may
also dis-
belief, stable
and per-
ences between occurrent and dispositional belief tract,
so
let
us seek obviously occurrent
throughout any period of time in the example. Each of these six features will help to give a puzzle case the sharpness needed to force real clarity in any proposed solution. These requirements are rather stringent and they are well met in the Two Tubes example. 20 That is why I add it to the extant sistent
—
stock of examples. 21
1^1
use these terms in their colloquial senses, without a great deal of philosophiI take up loaded senses in Chapter 3. thus seek to stay clear of the Molyneux Question.
cal loading.
i^In the version of the
Two Tubes example
described in this chapter, this re-
vacuously since all the relevant beliefs are held simultaneously, at noon on the day of the experiment. In Chapter 5, I present a persistence version of the example in which such stability and persistence are (nonvacuously)
quirement
is
satisfied
important features. 20Some, but not all, of these six requirements are met in Kripke's Paderewski case (Kripke 1979). The Two Tubes example was concocted independently of Kripke's examples; it is a descendant of puzzle cases devised by Edmund Gettier in 1976 before he or I had heard of Kripke's examples. It is similarly independent of the Bugsy Wabbit case (Salmon 1986). See also the Preface. 21A modest modification to the Two Tubes example yields a clear case of what Kvart has called "divided reference" (Kvart 1989): Suppose that the tubes
Igal
30
Getting Rid of Individual Propositions?
Have
We
Gotten Rid of Individual Propositions?
Let's briefly consider
we
how
things stand now. In the
flrst
chap-
arguments and examples to between a believer and a purely qualitative proposition. Perhaps no knockdown proof was given, but the arguments and examples were very persuasive. As a way of saving the view that belief is nevertheless a two-term relation between believers and propositions, ter,
show
it
took a close look
at several
that not every belief consists in a two-term relation
was suggested
that
some
beliefs,
those typically expressed
using indexicals, demonstratives, or proper names, are relations to individual propositions. 22 In this chapter,
developed
to
help
show
either. If propositions
two examples were
that individual propositions
must be
won't do,
either qualitative or individual, the
would then suggest that belief is between a person and a proposition; this
considerations of this chapter
not a two-term relation
view would have to be given up. however, a few diehards who attempt to avoid the latter result by rejecting either (A) and (A') or (B) and (B'), and I assess their views in the next four chapters. Schiffer is up next. traditional
There
are,
point at two different spots, but Smith believes (falsely) that the tubes are pointed at just
one
spot.
Smith could then use "this"
(or "that") to refer simultaneously to
is red" and "this = this" would each simultaneously express two individual propositions. To simplify discussion, I will not consider the phenomenon of divided thought and reference, though it must
two
spots,
and
his uses of the sentences "this
eventually be addressed in any adequate solution to the 22
As
indicated in Chapter
1,
individual propositions
Two Tubes Puzzle. may be said to involve
thisnesses of objects, rather than the objects themselves; but
cussion of such views until Chapter
I
am
deferring dis-
4.
31
CHAPTER THREE
Ws
Schiffer
In
Me Now:
Just
on
Chapter
2,
Belief
I
argued that neither demonstrative
belief,
names
consist
indexical belief, nor beliefs expressed using proper
two-term relation between a believer and an individual proposition. In my argument, I assumed that in a
(A)
possible that a believer believe an individual proposition
It is
with a contingent thing other than himself as a constituent.
In this chapter,
nies (A).
I
I
discuss the views of Stephen Schiffer,
who
de-
concentrate on his presentation in "The Basis of Refer-
ence'' (1978). For those
who
are impatient about getting to the
is one way Schiffer describes the relevant part of and 'now' are the only logically proper names that eschewing, as we should, Ruswe need to recognize, and sell's foundationalism, we need not recognize irreducibly de re knowledge of sense data or bodily sensations (1978, 201-202)." How, then, do other singular terms function, on Schiffer's view? The story that leads up to the punch line answers that question, and I turn to it in the next section. In the following sections of this chapter, I present criticisms of Schiffer's view and argue that he would do well to move closer to Russell's own view
punch
line,
his view: "
here
T
.
32
.
.
It's
Just
Me Now:
Schiffer
on
Belief
''Knowledge by Acquaintance and Knowledge by Descrip-
in
anywhere else book do I attempt to refute any view that simply denies either the modal or the doxastic intuition presented in Chapter 1; any attempted refutation would almost certainly be seen as question-begging by the view's proponents, of whom Schiffer is tion/' (1952, chap. V.) Neither in this chapter nor
in this
one. But
I
think that
pressed by those
That
my
one cf
is
main tasks
to
and
to other
we might
far the case
modal and doxastic
can be
intuitions.
in this chapter.
mental
call
at least part of the
meaning
of
be functionally specified: "[T]o say that a person
and such certain ways
believes such related in
the
by claiming that
Schiffer begins is
show how
useful to
View
Schiffer's
"believes"
it is
who have
is
to
states.
to say that
he
is
in a state
which
is
sepsory input, to behavioral output,
Of
special concern to us will be
what
the internal functional role of a mental state
namely, the relations of that
and counterfactual,
state, actual
to
other mental states" (1978, 178). The relations in question are those that must be met by the beliefs of any "minimally rational
person (ibid.)." Schiffer does not give a complete list of these, but he does give three clear examples of such relations: If S is a minimally rational person, then at any given time, S believes that
(i) if
(ii) if
and (iii) if
then S does not believe that not-p;
p,
S believes that p and S believes that
q,
then S believes that p
q;
S believes that p and S believes that q and S desires that q and
S believes that
if
p,
then q only
if r;
then,
ceteris paribus,
S desires
that r
for
any propositions, p, q and r.^ (i) is a central premise in argument for the part of his view of interest here. 2 It is
Schiffer's list
on minimal rationality, including (i), is given These constraints were formulated in discussions with
of sixteen such constraints
by Brian Loar
(1981, 72).
Schiffer.
^Schiffer
does not
explicitly restrict the
propositions, but for the purposes of this causes.
(It
rational during
does seem
much
to
my
make many
V
and to contingent can ignore the problems mathematicians less than minimally
range of
'p',
discussion,
'q,'
I
of the time they seek proofs of theorems.)
33
What's the Meaning of "This"?
not far from the
meaning
(i)
to the denial of (A), above.
Given that
of "believes" (at least as the term
is
(i)
is
part of
applied to 'mini-
we may suppose that it is a necessary Suppose it is possible that, at a given time, a believer, S, believes an individual proposition, , with some contingent
mally rational' believers), truth.
object, X
#
S, as a constituent.
Then, Schiffer claims,
claim with examples of the same sort that
it is
possible
He
supports his
we have
already con-
that at that time, S also believes that not-.
sidered in the previous two chapters.
The Two Tubes case can easily be modified to provide an espesharp example: Suppose that Smith suffers a momentary defect of color vision, which makes the red spot he sees through his left eye appear green, and that he is unaware of this defect; he cially
will
then believe the individual propositions that he could express
by "this is red and that is not red and this that." But then, at one time, he would believe that , and he would believe that not-, in violation of Schiffer's constraints on minimal rationality. Given these assumptions, it follows that no one can, at one time, ever believe an individual proposition, that p, and also then believe that not-p,
if
p has a contingent thing other than the
that
believer as a constituent.
we
can get from the preceding
is
a necessary condition for
believing an individual proposition:
if
S believes an individual
All
proposition, that p, with contingent thing,
then X =
more the punch
x, as a
constituent,
view than this, as line quoted at the beginning of already suggested in this chapter. Schiffer finds sufficient conditions for believing an individual proposition by considering examples derived from ones given by Perry and by Castaneda (see Chapter i, and citations to Castafieda's work in Perry 1979). Here's what he says: "If S.
But there
is
to Schiffer's
Ralph says, 'I am handsome,' then Ralph, if sincere, believes himself to be handsome, and this self-ascriptive belief is irreducibly de re [that is, belief in an individual proposition ]. But if Ralph says, 'He's an ugly fellow,' referring to a man in a photograph, who happens to be Ralph, then this [is] a non-self-ascriptive belief [and] does not differ in kind from the beliefs that Ralph has about any other material .
.
.
.
34
.
.
It's
object
and ...
is
Just
Me Now:
Schiffer
on
Belief
not irreducibly de re" (Schiffer 1978, 199).
amnesiac
Schiffer also alludes to a case of a "sensorily deprived
[who] might nevertheless
know
himself to be conscious" (1978,
Dick 1984, 246-247.) Generalizing on such examples, Schiffer concludes, "Not all beliefs that a person might have about himself are irreducibly de re) only those which he can ex200). (See also
press with the pronoun 'Y , and which beliefs" (1978, 199).
There
we might
a similar class of
is
call self-ascriptive
examples
for belief
we saw in Chapter 1. Schiffer makes use of these to what we might call "present-ascriptive beliefs," on
about time, as introduce
analogy with self-ascriptive
What applies
beliefs.
Summarizing, Schiffer says:
to the thoughts expressible
with "I" applies
tis
that the complete content of the thought
by
his utterance of "I
tion is
also, muta-
mutandis, to the thoughts expressible with "now," and
1).
one
f to the definition sche-
The generalization
will
be needed
such beliefs as one expressible by "red
in accounting for
pills
to me now to be in just nine locations.'') Two kinds of problems with (Di) and its generalizations ought to be mentioned
appear here.
First,
it
is
notoriously difficult to give a satisfactory and noncir-
cular account
"normal perceiver" and "standard circumOne recent writer has argued
of
stances," as well as of "typically."
is no unique set of standard condiunder which an object has given phenomenal properties
very persuasively that "there tions"
and
that the notion of standard conditions
is
strongly interest-
(Hardin 1983 and 1988). A great deal of work needs to be done on these notions before they achieve respectability. relative
Second, one will need to postulate
infinitely
many
rules of
inference in order to account for valid inferences of the form
(IS)
for n
>
F f
is
w-instantiated
is
instantiated at least n
-
\
times
1.
My point here has been not to show that Schiffer's view cannot meet the problems
I
have been raising
rather to demonstrate that
2iTye 1989
50
came
to
my
some
for
it
substantial
in this section,
work remains
attention too late to be taken into account.
but
to
be
It's
done
in
defending the view.
I
Just
hope
Me Now: that
I
Schiffer
on
Belief
have succeeded
in that
limited goal. 22
turn next to a brief discussion of the historical predecessor to
I
view and
Schiffer'' s
to adverbial theories of sensation, Russell's
some of the problems I have raised for Schiffer's view, but it, too, rejects (A). Indeed, it is difficult to imagine a view more extreme than Russell's in placing
view. Russell's use of sense data avoids
on the possible constituents
restrictions
of individual proposi-
tions.
Russell and Sense Data
Suppose that we were to try resolve the Two Tubes Puzzle in way: when Smith thinks "this is red and that is red," his belief is more perspicuously representable as this
(9)
the object of which this'
which
that'
is
an appearance
an appearance
is
is
is
red and the object of
red
(where the primes on the demonstratives are meant
same
to indicate
and "that" preceding (9)). meant to entail the existence of an object, X, which is an appearance, and which is, in some sense, of the spot he then sees, and a distinct object, y, which is an appearance, and which is also of the spot that he then sees; x and y will that they're not the
As Smith could use
be exactly
alike,
it,
as the "this"
(9) is
except for their being located in different visu-
Smith wonders, "Is this = that?," he wonders whether or not these two appearances are appearances of the al fields.
same
When
object.
In order to prevent the
same
sort of
problem from arising about
An
example, attributed to David Lewis, which raises some additional queshow exactly we are to understand the predicate "appears to me to be over there," is reported in chapter 4 of Hintikka 1975, 67: "Suppose that I see John in a glass, but that I cannot tell perceptually whether it is a looking glass or a transparent glass panel. Don't I then see John without seeing where he is even in 22
tions about
my own visual visual space,
space?"
even
if I
I
am inclined to think that would see where John I
example may suggest that there
is
is
in
my
whole scene to be a hallucination, but the more to appearance than meets the eye.
also believed the
51
What's the Meaning of "This"?
must be held that x and y are necessarily such that Smith cannot wonder, at the time he preceives them, 'Is x = y?" It would be ad hoc simply to stipulate this without any further explanation. What more can be said
X and y as arose about the spot seen,
it
about the nature of such appearances to achieve the desired sult?
We
must keep
in
mind
that
possible,
it is
re-
on any plausible
construal of "perceptual property,'' to have beliefs about one's
appearances not solely about their perceptual properties; for example. Smith
may
think to himself, "this'
is
my
ance." Simply requiring that appearances have
perceptual properties they appear
nores this possibility.
On
that the appearances
have
(to
and only the
the believer) to have ig-
the other hand, all
favorite appearall
it is
wrong
to
suppose
and only the properties they
are
believed (by the believer) to have; for suppose that Smith believes
something of the form, "this' is an appearance of something that and is F. " Then his belief, together with the latter supposition, will entail that there really is an F, whatever F may be. True belief cannot be that easy to achieve; it must be possible to make some mistakes about what one perceives. Russell's view, in "Knowledge by Acquaintance and Knowledge by Description," seeks to avoid this problem, and may usefully be seen as partially motivated by such puzzles as the Two Tubes Puzzle. ^3 Thus, the view imposes severe restrictions on the possible constituents of exists
propositions.
The fundamental this:
principle in the analysis of propositions ...
wholly of constituents with which
We
is
Every proposition which we can understand must be constituted
shall say that
we have
we
are acquainted.
which any process of
acquaintance with anything of
are directly aware, without the intermediary of
ference or any knowledge of truths.
.
.
we in-
.
23Some of the reasons for introducing sense data need not, therefore, come from an argument from illusion; puzzles about veridical perception raise questions to which sense data provide answ^ers. An argument from illusion is needed to establish that sense data are private mental objects; their being mental and private does not of course follow from their being useful in solving the Two Tubes Puzzle.
52
It's
We
have acquaintance
and
senses,
— thoughts,
memory
tance in
Me Now:
on
may we have
with the data of what
feelings, desires, etc.;
Belief
be called acquain-
with things which have been either of the outer
senses or of the inner sense. Further, certain, that
Schiffer
with the data of the outer
in sensation
in introspection
inner sense
Just
we have
it
acquaintance with
probable, though not
is
Self, as that
which
aware
is
of things or has desires towards things. In addition to our acquaintance with particular existing things,
we
also
have acquaintance with what we such as whiteness,
to say, general ideas .
.
.
On Russell's view,
there are in the Tw^o Tubes case tv^o exactly
similar red, circular sense data, x
visual field locations,
and
and
of w^hich
y,
w^hich differ only in their
Smith
is
directly av^are.
believes that the physical object v^hich causes x
He
red (similarly
is
and he w^onders if it's the same object that causes both x That is, he believes what he could more perspicuously
for y);
and
is
and so
Awareness of universals is called conceiving, and a universal which we are aware is called a concept. (1952, 32, 25, 28)
on. of
shall call universals, that
diversity, brotherhood,
y.
express as follows: (3z)(w)[(w causes
(10)
this'
if
(11) (3z')(w)[(w causes that'
And he wonders
as he could think
(3z){(w)(w causes
(12)
causes that'
where this'
if,
this'
and only
if
if
z
z
=
rendering of
= w)
''the
I
know
of
tion in Russell's writings. ^4
no
clear, direct
It is
and Casullo
this'
its
=
answer
objects that that'?"?
—
is
to this ques-
an important insight of sense
^^But see Russell 1956. See also Broad 1952, chaps. 8 II);
(3z')[(w)(w
thing that causes
about the nature of acquaintance and
impossible for Smith to wonder, "Is
not yet answered.
sec.
&
z']},
the thing that causes that'." But our original question
is it it
it,
and only — w) &
if z'
(12) is the Russellian
=
What make
if
and only if z = w) & z is red] and only if z' = w) & z is red]
if
and
9;
Casullo 1984 (esp.
1986.
53
What's the Meaning of "This"?
datum
chaps. 8 and 143
by Russell, Moore (1957), Broad (1952, Carnap, and Goodman (1977, 112, 130-133, 139, 246, and references to Carnap's work therein),
theory, recognized
— 144,
9),
245
that there
is
—
an irreducibly demonstrative element
datum theory
in perception,
foundation. The
an insight
built into sense
difficulties
presented for Schiffer's theory in ''Being There" sug-
gest to
me
work on
been neglected
that this insight has
belief
and
reference.
at its
Of
course, sense
in some recent datum theory is
not the only possible proposal about what to include in a restricted class of possible constituents of individual propositions.
Once one opens
the door to demonstrative belief about 'extraordi-
nary' objects, one
may wish
to consider the nonexistent objects of
Terence Parsons (1980); the inexistent objects of William G. Lycan (1987); or the existent but incomplete objects of Kit Fine (1982) as possible constituents. (As David Lewis has reminded us, there are
many
things one can do easily with nonexistent objects that
are difficult or perhaps impossible without them. See, for example,
Lewis 1983b.)
My main point here is that, whatever the prop,
the aforementioned door
A
is at
least ajar.
Modal Objection
There remains one serious, albeit standard, objection to be to Schiffer's view. In Chapter 1, I presented an intuition, forcefully and skillfully deployed by Kripke, the use of which
made
allows him to argue that description theories of indexicals, demonstratives, and proper
names
give the
wrong
truth conditions
by uses of sentences containing such terms (Kripke 1980, 6-15). Schiffer's view is inconsistent with that intuition, though it makes 'exceptions' for "I" and "now." Suppose, for example, that Sarah or Stephen fixes her or his attention on some one pill or cup and believes, "that one is red." The proposition believed thereby is, on the aforementioned intuition, an individual proposition true only in those worlds in which the for propositions expressed
very object actually attended to exists and
is
red. Schiffer rejects
and the intuition on which it is based, saying, "[N]o one who had understood and accepted the description theory this claim
54
It's
would
in the least
Just
Me Now:
Schiffer
that Stephen's belief,
and any other
himself and the time of his belief
exist;
those propositions. Even
about the essential nature of times, claim that
what
my
all,
constitu-
put aside questions
remains counterintuitive to
existence for
used by
its
me when
I
truth.
take these facts about Schiffer's view to be sufficiently objec-
tionable
the
we
"that's a rock" expresses (as
attend to a rock) requires I
it
entails
which Stephen
they are, after if
view
about a contingent
belief
object, are true only in those possible situations in
all
Belief
be inclined to accept'' the intuition (1981, 60-
61). In addition to rejecting the intuition, Schiffer's
ents of
on
by themselves
Two Tubes
cussing in this section gests a
to
make examining
other approaches to
Puzzle worthwhile. The problem is
I
have been
who
taken seriously by Plantinga,
way of resolving it. Roughly,
his idea
is
dis-
sug-
that the properties
expressed, say, by demonstratives, are expressed by definite descriptions of the form, "the object
which
is
actually F,"
and
that
they therefore express essences of the object thought about. discuss Plantinga's suggestion
and Ackerman's
I
related use of es-
sences in the next chapter.
55
CHAPTER FOUR
Rigid Belief Transformed: Plantinga and Ackerman on Essences
Because Schiffer holds
that,
except for 'T' and "now," sin-
gular terms for contingent objects are nonrigid, his view to the
modal
philosophers
criticism
who
with which
I
ended the
is
last chapter.
open
Some
are nevertheless sympathetic to the view that
proper names, demonstratives, and some indexicals have or bear significant epistemic relation to definite-descriptive content are
One such
troubled by this modal criticism.
philosopher, Alvin
Plantinga, has suggested a compromise. In "The Boethian
Com-
promise," he recommends a method for securing rigidity while retaining definite-descriptive content. Although his proposals are
directed only at proper names, of providing a resolution to the of this chapter,
I
like Plantinga's,
I
will
adapt them for the purpose
Two Tubes
Puzzle. In the last part
Her view, some of the
discuss the views of Felicia Ackerman.
embraces essences, but
it
avoids
problems for Plantinga's view. As she herself is quick to point however, her view has some rather serious problems of its
out,
own; nonetheless it may well to the Two Tubes Puzzle.^
^Felicia
Ackerman = Diana
56
F.
offer the
Ackerman.
optimum
essence-solution
Rigid Belief Transformed
Plantinga's Proposal
The relevant part
of Plantinga's theory
may be summarized
as
follows: (E)
Proper names express essences.
Plantinga's
main proposal about which essences are expressed by
proper names (Al)
is:
The essences
that a proper
name
expresses are expressed by
descriptions of the form "the f-in-a,"
a-transform of the predicate "f
Because tives
I
and
am
where "f-in-a"
is
the
.
concerned here with questions about demonstra-
indexicals,
I
will
assume, with one qualification
to
be
noted, that versions of (E) and (Al) also apply to demonstratives
and indexicals. My one qualification is to leave open the question of whether a version of (Al) also applies to "I" and "now." Although, as I have already stated in Chapter 2, I believe that these indexicals ought to be accorded no 'special treatment,' one might wish to exempt them from the transformation of (Al). In what follows, I will focus on applications of a version of (Al) to demonstratives in attempting to resolve the Two Tubes Puzzle. Plantinga does not offer a general account of which descriptions express the essences expressed by proper names, demonstratives, and indexicals, though he makes several suggestions based on views about proper names held by Russell, Frege, about which descriptions Searle, and Donnellan and Kripke one might associate with them. I will not discuss those sugges-
—
tions here;
it
will suffice for
my
purposes
to
use syntactically
simple suggestions based on Russell's views. (The suggestions ignore sense data and are Russellian without being those that
would likely have offered.) and (E) (the a-transform principle and the Essence principle, respectively) need some further explanation; specifically, more needs to be said about what Plantinga means by "essence," "express," and "a-transform." Russell himself
Both
(Al)
57
What's the Meaning of "This"?
About what names,
etc.,
and
definite descriptions express,
Plantinga has this to say:
A definite description "the F" expresses the same property as "is the sole F." (b) A proper name, N, expresses (in English)
(1) (a)
does
a property, F,
if
there
a definite description, D, in English or
is
some extension of English, such that: (i) D expresses f and (ii) N and D are intersubstitutable salva propositione in sentences of the form,
I
will also
't
is
f
(1978, 134)
suppose that
indexical tokens.
(i)(b)
holds for uses of demonstrative and
(i)(b)(ii) is
based on the following principle of
on which Plantinga seems
propositional identity,
(2)
S
a person
is
and only
I
=
Proposition p
if
proposition q
and ^4
is
A
S has
is
and only
if
necessarily, (S)(i4)[if
a propositional attitude, then S has
to
Aiopii
q)].
will not try to say exactly
that the connection
if
clearly to rely:
clear
how
(i)(b)(ii) is
enough
based on
(2); I
hope
for present purposes.
Plantinga characterizes the notion of an existing entity's es-
sence as follows:
an essence of x =^f
(3) e is
has
(i)
e is a
necessary that
e; (iii) it is
necessary that
(y)(if
y has
e,
if
property;
possible that x
(ii) it is
x exists, then x has
then x =
e;
and
(iv) it is
y).
Plantinga characterizes notions of a-transforms for both predicates
(4)
and
properties:
The a-transform proper
(5)
((5) is
name
of a predicate, "f,"
is
"f-in-a,"
where "a"
is
a
of the actual world.
The a-transform of a property, f is the world-indexed property of being f-in-a, where "a" is a proper name of the actual world. ,
can be written without a use-mention confusion;
clear
enough
as
it
stands.)
The following
trust that
relationship
hold between a-transform predicates and properties:
58
I
if
is
it
said to
the predi-
Rigid Belief Transformed
cate ''F" expresses the property F, then the a-transform of "F" (that
"f-in-a'')
is,
expresses the property being f-in-a (1978, 133).
Finally,
(6)
X has property f in state of affairs is
actual, then x has
not hard to
show
=^f
it is
necessary that,
w
if
f
Plugging in "a" for "w" in It is
w
has F in a/'
yields a definition of
(6)
that for
any
object, x,
the sole F, then the a-transform
and property,
of F, being F-in-a, is
F,
if
x
is
an essence
of X.2
Two Tubes
Transformed Essences and the
Puzzle
Plantinga considers one of the most important features of his
theory to be that names,
etc.,
may
express essences that are log-
ically
equivalent but epistemically inequivalent. (Essence
ically
equivalent to essence
which to
e is
know
ing that
if
there
e is log-
no possible world
epistemically inequivalent to essence
or believe that an object has it
is
exemplified by an object that does not exemplify
e is
Essence
e'
has
e'
(1978, 133, 134).)
e
e' if it is
in e'
possible
without knowing or believ-
Among the examples he gives of
pairs of logically equivalent but epistemically inequivalent es-
sences are being Socrates's
a (both had by morning
Plato);
best student in a, being Aristotle's teacher in
and
being a heavenly body last visible in the
in a, being a heavenly
body
first visible in the
evening in a
(both had by Venus). Presumably, Plantinga' s reason for thinking that these pairs of properties are epistemically inequivalent their
is
that
'nonworld indexed portions' are epistemically inequivalent.
Let us
now
see
how
^For a proof that relies
(Al)
and
(E)
allow Plantinga to resolve the
on S5 axioms, see Plantinga
1974, 72. Plantinga takes the
notion of logical necessity as primitive, and explains the notion of possible world in
terms of
it,
the notion of a state of affairs, the notion of a state of affairs'
obtaining (or being actual), and several logical notions. For present purposes, v^e
may assume
that propositions are just states of affairs
maximal consistent propositions. The actual world
and
will
that possible worlds are be assumed to be the true
maximal, consistent proposition. See Plantinga 1981.
59
What's the Meaning of "This"?
Two Tubes
way
Puzzle in a
that accounts for Smith's rational
ignorance and avoids the modal objection to which Schiffer's
view is open. Suppose that, according "this'' as
now
to a Russellian theory.
Smith uses
semantically equivalent to (or short for) "the object that
appears to
me
to
be on the right"; and that he uses "that" as now appears to me to be on the left/'^
short for "the object that
two portions
Recall these
(7)
I
know
(8)
I
do not know
that this
=
of Smith's interior
monologue:
this.
that this
=
that.
Plantinga's view provides an explanation for the truth of (8):
the two demonstratives, as used by Smith, express for
different, epistemically inequivalent essences: "this," as
uses
expresses the property that he could express by "being
it,
the object that
now
appears to
as "that," as Smith uses
it,
me to be on
a."
(7)
and
(8)
(on Plantinga's view)
(7')
now
appears to
me
to
be on the
thus be rewritten more perspicuously
as:
now appears to me to be on the right now appears to me to be on the right in a. I don't know that the object that now appears to me to be on the right in a is the object that now appears to me to be on the left in I
know
in (8')
may
the right in a"; where-
expresses the property that he could
express by "being the object that left in
and Smith Smith
(7)
a
is
that the object that
the object that
a.
When
they are thus rewritten,
it
seems easy to see how both knowledge in (7') is differ-
could be true, for the object of Smith's
ent from the object of his ignorance in
(8').
one of any description theory. What is distinctive about Plantinga's view is its also having the consequence that the propositions expressed in (7) and (8) are contingent truths. This may be seen most easily if we add the following to Smith's interior monologue:
The
latter virtue is also
^At the risk of being tedious, I would once again remind the reader that these descriptions are not faithful to Smith's perceptual situation. See Chap. 3, note 15. But we need some pair of definite descriptions for the present discussion.
60
Rigid Belief Transformed
I
(9)
know
that this
is
the object that
now appears to me
to
be on the
right.
we
are to avoid the modal objection made against Schiffer's what Smith knows in (9) must be a contingent truth. Plantinga's view secures this result, for what (9) says is just what If
view,
Smith could equally well express by (9')
I
know
in
And
a
is
now appears to me to be on the right now appears to me to be on the right.
that the object that
the object that
the proposition
known
here
is
contingent: there are worlds
which the very spot that Smith does in fact see remains unobserved by anyone, and so appears to no one in any way; it is a merely contingent truth that Smith happens to observe it at all, and a contingent truth that it looks the way it actually does to him. So Plantinga's view seems to have a clear modal advantage over the sort of description theory advocated by Schiffer. in
The Greater Ignorance of Smith: I
will next present
two
First Objection
criticisms of Plantinga's proposal, the
which is a simple one. There seems to be no question that, (7) and (9) express truths. Now, as Plantinga notes, there seem to be propositions that some of us are unable to believe because we do '"not even possess the concepts necessary to apprehend [them]'' (1978, 133). As an example, he mentions first
as
of
Smith uses them,
the proposition that twenty-seven eighths of the definite integral,
from zero
to two, of the function
/(jc)
=
is
odd, which, he says,
those of us with "an imperfect grasp of the calculus" are unable
even
to believe.
Suppose, then, that Smith,
like
students, has never studied The Nature of Necessity,
most medical is
unfamiliar
with possible world semantics, has never heard of any work in semantical theory, and has never ty.
wondered about logical
necessi-
In short, suppose that Smith does not even possess the con-
cepts necessary to apprehend propositions of the form "the F in a is
G" and
so, for
example,
is
unable even to believe the proposi61
What's the Meaning of "This"? tions involved in
Smith as able
(7')
and
wrong
thus
to include these in his interior
these therefore do not
by
(9'). It is
his uses of
''this''
tell
have described monologue, and
to
us any propositions that he expresses
or "that."
Plantinga might try to argue, in response, that Smith does not lack the concepts necessary to tions because
we
all
apprehend a-transform proposi-
acquire such basic concepts in learning
how
have even the simple perceptual beliefs of the sort Smith has. But since he is willing to grant that those with an imperfect grasp of the calculus may not be able to grasp many of its propositions, I don't see how he would argue for that claim. (I doubt that he would try.) Nor do I see any room in the doctrine of propositions (see Chapter 1) for making sense of 'partially grasped proposito
tions'; there is tially
no more room
than there
is
for 'par-
take seriously,
it
bedevils
for the latter
believed propositions'.
Although
this objection is
one that
I
many proposals besides Plantinga's (for example, Schiffer's). What is distinctive about Plantinga's proposal is (Al), the a-transwant next to consider an objection focuses more squarely on that principle. form
principle,
and
I
that
Smith's Otherworldly Ignorance: Second Objection
My second objection is somewhat more complex than the first. have noticed that Plantinga has introduced a new name as part of his proposal: "a." The purpose of my second objection is to force investigation of the question, "which essence, if any, does 'a' express?"
The reader
I
will
names
will
now in
describe a situation involving a pair of co-referential
which
linguistic
behavior just
but for which Plantinga's proposal that the referent of the
by means world." Suppose also tionlessly,
name "a" of the
is is
like
Smith's
is
involved,
unable to account.'* Suppose fixed, rigidly
definite
and connota-
description "the actual
that the referent of the
name
"/5" is fixed,
^This example was developed in January 1978. A similar example was presented by Saul Kripke in a talk he gave at the APA Western Division Meetings, held April
25-27, 1980.
62
Rigid Belief Transformed
and connotationlessly, by means of the definite descripworld most often named by Plantinga." As a matter of fact, the actual world is the possible world most often named by Plantinga, but Smith, whom we may suppose is aware of the fixing of "a" and "P," doesn't keep up with the philosophirigidly
tion ''the possible
cal literature, so
when he
=
considers "a
from it or withholds assent although Smith will assert
to
it.
Thus,
p," he either dissents
we may suppose
now appears to me to be on the right now appears to me to be on the right
(10) the object that
object that
as part of his interior
monologue, he
in
a
is
will refrain therein
that,
the
from
asserting
now appears to me to be on the right now appears to me to be on the right.
(11) the object that
object that
We
P
is
the
cannot account for the asymmetry in Smith's attitudes by
supposing that he knows
by
in
(lo),
but does not
(ii). The reason names "a" and
is
know
that (lo)
what he could express what he could express by
(or believes) (or believe)
and
(ii) differ
only with respect to the
both of which have been stipulated to be
connotationless; consequently, the very
same proposition
is
ex-
pressed by both, as Smith uses these sentences. This case therefore presents us with linguistic facts just like those presented
the
Two Tubes
example, but the former case
is
by
not one for which
Plantinga's proposal can account.
This line of reasoning does not, of course, present a counterex-
ample
a-transform principle. But it does, I from whatever appearance of explanaderives from consideration of the Two Tubes case
to (Al), Plantinga's
think, detract considerably
tory
power
and
other, similarly problematic examples.
(Al)
How
might Plantinga reasonably reply? He might either deny could speak a language in which some terms are rigidly and connotationlessly fixed a denial that seems implausible or he might insist that his proposal is a proposal about how, as a matter of fact, English names, demonstratives, and indexicals that
we
—
—
63
What's the Meaning of "This"?
work (where
how
the evidence for
they work
linguistic be-
is
havior like Smith's). The purpose of such insistence would be to
provide room for application of (Al) to "a" and
thus forcing a
between the propositions Smith would express by (lo) and (ii). This may be done by explaining how "a" and differ in connotation: they might have different connotations or one might lack any connotation, while the other had some connotation. So, it might be held, as an empirical thesis about English, that by attempting to stipulate that be fixed, rigidly and connotationlessly, on the possible world most often named by Plandifference
tinga,
we
instead bring
about that
it
being the possible world most often
expresses the essence
named by Plantinga
would
the object of Smith's ignorance in (ii)
in a. If so,
be, as
then
he could put
it,
now
the object that
object that
This
still
leaves
now
me
appears to
appears to
to
named by
possible world most often
me
to
open the question
be on the right in the Plantinga in a
be on the
of
is
the
right.
whether or not "a" has
connotation. Let us examine what a proponent of Plantinga's
view may have If
that
to say in
answer.
"a" has a connotation, then what
we
is its
connotation? Note
cannot explain Smith's behavior with
(lo)
and
(ii)
by
claiming that, instead of fixing "a" connotationlessly on the actual
world,
we
bring
it
about
that, contrary to
"a" expresses the property being is
had only contingently by
For then the subject of (lo) (lo)
would not express
our stated intention,
the actual world
a, the
— a property that
world which
is
in fact actual.
would not express an essence, and
a contingent truth, true only in those
worlds in which the spot actually seen exists; instead, what it expresses would be true in any world in which Smith believed himself to be seeing some spot or other that appeared to be in the center of his current right visual
Could we instead hold
field.
that "a" expresses the essence being the
actual world in a; or the essence being identical to a?
we may
More generally,
ask: Should Plantinga hold that "a" expresses an essence
that can also be expressed
64
by some term or predicate containing a
Rigid Belief Transformed
That is: Does (Al), the a-transform principle, apply to The answer to all these questions seems clearly to be "no" because the proposals they offer simply fail to answer the
use of
''a"?
''a" itself?
question, "what, in each of
There
its
are, of course, at least
uses, does
two
'a'
express?"
alternatives
here: hold that (Al) does not apply to "a"
itself,
open
to Plantinga
although
(E) does;
by means of the description "the actual world" (or its synonyms) can one fix "a," rigidly and connotationlessly, on the actual world (and thus abandon both (Al) and (E) in the case of "a"). Of these two alternatives, I think that the first is not only preferable, but would be preferred by Plantinga. My reason for thinking so is that the second alternative saddles one with a possible worlds version of the Two Tubes Puzzle. In fact, we have or hold that only
already introduced the materials for such a version in the discussion of (lo)
be
made
and
(ii),
above. All that remains
is
for the
analogy to
explicit.
So suppose that "a" and
"y5"
and
are fixed, rigidly
and connota-
Smith is aware of the fixing. Let us abbreviate the predicate obtained from (lo) by substituting "x" for "a" by "Rx." Smith's interior monologue will then go like
tionlessly, exactly as above,
that
this:
(12)
1
know
wonder:
a =
we
that is
I
know
that:
« = pi, and
P, or that
^
is
I
a = a and ^ = ^ and a is R, but I is p R?, and I don't know that
wonder:
R.
from applying either (Al) or (E) here, a by-nowproblem recurs. Given our assumptions here, the proposition that a — a simply is the proposition that a = p, and Smith can't know one without knowing the other; similarly, for him to know that a is R (that is, to know what he would express by (10)) is for him to know that ^ is R (that is, what he would express by (11)). So he can't wonder as he does, after all. But this is wrong. The parallel between the cases can be made even closer if we suppose that it is somehow^ possible to think demonstratively about possible worlds. Smith might then think, "that world is a, and this world is 13, but I wonder, is this world the actual world?" If
refrain
familiar
If
we
grant the possibility of demonstrating worlds, then
65
I
think
What's the Meaning of "This"? that
we must also grant the
possibility of
wondering in this way.^ a glance' which world is
Perhaps an omniscient being can 'see at most of the rest of us can try to resolve such ignorance only by comparing what we know with what a entails; at best, actual, but
however, that
will leave the
nonomniscient with
infinitely
many
candidates for the status of actual world. In Chapter
2,
I
how would argue against a Two Tubes Puzzle. One of Plan-
indicated roughly
metalinguistic solution to the
I
purposes in offering his view is to avoid such metasolutions to puzzles about belief and reference (1978,
tinga's stated linguistic
135). Hence, in this case, he cannot consistently hold that when Smith thinks to himself "a is K," he thereby entertains the metalinguistic proposition that '"a is expresses a truth." Given what "a is K" expresses as Smith would use it, adopting the latter
K
would be tantamount to holding one never believes an a-transform proposition, but always
sort of metalinguistic solution
that
instead believes a metalinguistic proposition to the effect that the
corresponding a-transform sentence expresses some true proposition.
None ple.
of
my
criticisms
Each of them
But since
it
is
is
weighs against
(E),
the Essence princi-
directed at (Al), the a-transform principle.
the latter that
is
distinctive of Plantinga's view,
these criticisms raise serious questions about the acceptability of that view. It is, of course, still open to Plantinga to hold that "a" expresses an essence of the actual world (or that some uses of "a" express
different,
epistemically
world). But then he
inequivalent
owes us an account
essences of
how
of
the
actual
ordinary English
speakers come to grasp such an essence, without there being a specification of
it
in
terms of a-transforms. (Plantinga concedes as
50n analogy with the Jones lottery example (see Chapter 5), we might consider God's possible worlds lottery, with the property being the actual world to be conferred on the winner; the roles of "a" and "Victor" would then be exactly parallel. For a fuller development of the analogy, see Austin 1983. ^If we suppose that we are world-bound individuals, as David Lewis suggests, then, perhaps, we 'can't miss' when we attempt to demonstrate the actual world. As one of Lewis's most vocal critics, however, Plantinga cannot avail himself of this reply. Plantinga maintains that there are infinitely many worlds in which we and our demonstrations
66
exist.
Rigid Belief Transformed
much
in 1983, 364-365, 3961117.) Plantinga's proposal seems,
therefore, to
have
little
more
to
recommend
it
than a view which
simply postulates multiple, epistemically inequivalent essences of
each object, to be expressed by proper names, demonstratives,
and
indexicals used to refer to the object.
Such a view would have
the advantages of stipulation over honest theoretical
all I
toil.^
turn next to discussion of the views of Felicia Ackerman,
who
holds that uses of tokens of demonstratives, indexicals, and proper
names express essences not
expressible
by any
definite de-
scription.
Ackerman' s Essences
Ackerman
sets out to give a theory of
names, demonstratives,
indexicals (and natural-kind terms) that preserves the following
three plausible principles:
The Essence Principle: Each use of a proper name, demonstrative, or indexical
and so such terms are
expresses an essence,
rigid
designators.
The Propositional Attitude Principle:
If
"Ti" and "T2" are singular
terms which are not interchangeable salva
whenever used in and "T2" have different
veritate
propositional attitude contexts, then "Ti"
connotations. (The connotation of a singular term that term expresses,
and which
is
to
determining what proposition
in
which the term
The Causal
on
Principle:
and only
if
the property
is
expressed by the sentence token
occurs.)
An
entity, x, is the referent of a
a particular occasion) of a
ical if
is
that term's semantic contribution
token (as used
proper name, demonstrative, or index-
x has a particular complex causal relation to the
token of the term so used, regardless of what entity, properties the users of the term believe
its
if
any, has the
referent to have. (1979, 6-
11)
^ight
Plantinga avail himself of the advantages of Kaplan's "dthat" operator?
(See Chapter 6.)
I
no advantages here. If the operator is introduced into made in "The Greater Ignorance of Smith," above, will Whether or not it is so introduced (and what could keep that see
English, then the objection
return in
full force.
from being, or even having been, done?), the problems raised worldly Ignorance," above, will still have to be faced.
in "Smith's
67
Other-
What's the Meaning of "This"?
(Ackerman calls this complex causal relation "R.") One qualificamust be added to the Propositional Attitude Principle: Acker-
tion
man
intends
to
it
apply to particular uses of tokens of singular
terms and not, primarily, to their syntactic types. This qualification renders the Propositional Attitude Principle less persuasive
than
it
might seem
For "Ti" and "Ti" to be
at first reading.
t seems to mean that (i) S "... Ti ... used and (ii) had S used instead, the resulting token would have expressed a true proposition. But this is not
interchangeable for a person S at a time
refuted by showing that rectly
used
.
.
.
preserved truth.
Ti
.
.
How,
it is .
logically possible for S to
so that the substitution
then,
is
have
cor-
would have
the principle to be applied to
what for Ackerman is one most important applications, she uses it to argue for the conclusion that no proper name, etc., has the same connotation as any definite description.^ She says that it is logically possible that a person, S, believe that T is T, without believing that T is the f where F is any property whatever. She concludes that ''T" and establish differences in connotation? In
of
its
,
"the F" are not interchangeable salva veritate in
all
belief contexts,
and uses the Propositional Attitude Principle to conclude, further, that 'T" and "the F" differ in connotation. If we make explicit
the necessary reference to particular tokens as used at par-
by
the argument seems to be
this: suppose that, at With that token, he then expresses a proposition, P, which we may represent as an ordered set of connotations: and , that he also believes So the inconsistency presented in Chapter 2
Two
Nontraditional Analyses of Belief
Before evaluating Kaplan's suggestion, I want to guard against two misunderstandings of it. We must not misunderstand Kaplan's suggestion by mistaking it for Plantinga's Boethian compromise. According to the latter, if Smith believes what he expresses by (3), then what he believes is more perspicuously expressible as
But
here and
the object that has appearance
(8)
this
now
a
in
is
red.
cannot be Kaplan's answer, because, as noted above, the
"dthat" operator
is
stipulated to yield a directly referential term,
not synonymous with a reference-fixing description.
Nearly enough, Plantinga's Boethian compromise says that what a rigidified description
expresses
is
a constituent of the proposition be-
lieved, but Kaplan's suggestion says instead that
description denotes
is
a constituent instead.
object that has appearance
here now']"
demonstrative's character, that character
is
what
a rigidified
Although "dthat['the
may
not
represent the
itself
a constituent
of the proposition determined. In this instance, the character of (3)
determines the content of
namely, the individual proposi-
(3),
tion . But the latter
is
not the proposition expressed
(8). Kaplan would clearly reject the Boethian compromise. Nor does Kaplan's suggestion construe Smith's beliefs as being
by
about which characters determine which propositions in a given
The latter would hold he knows) that
context. that
Smith believes (and knows
determines
(5")