123 49 15MB
English Pages 264 [275] Year 2018
TRANSCENDENTAL UTOPIAS
TRANSCENDENTAL UTOPIAS Individual and Community at Brook Farm, Fruitlands, and Walden RICHARD FRANCIS
Cornell University Press ITHACA AND LONDON
Copyright© 1997 by Cornell University All rights reserved. Except for brief quotations in a review, this book, or parts thereof, must not be reproduced in any form without permission in writing from the publisher. For information, address Cornell University Press, Sage House, 512 East State Street, Ithaca, New York 14850. First published 1997 by Cornell University Press First printing, Cornell Paperbacks, 2007
Printed in the United States of America
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Francis, Richard, 1945Transcendental utopias : individual and community at Brook Farm, Fruitlands, and Walden I Richard Francis. p. em. Includes index. ISBN 978-0-8014-7380-7 1. Utopias-Massachusetts-Case studies. 2. Brook Farm Phalanx (West Roxbury, Boston, Mass.) 3· Fruitlands (Harvard, Mass.) 4· Walden Woods (Mass.) 5. Transcendentalism (New England) I. Title. HX6 55 .M 4F73 1 99 7 355' .02' 09744-dc21 96-46314 Cloth printing
10
9
8
7
6
5
4
3
2
TO JO, WILLIAM, AND HELEN
Contents
Preface
IX
CHAPTER ONE
Nature versus History CHAPTER TWO
Brook Farm and Masquerade
35
CHAPTER THREE
Brook Farm: The Law of Groups and Series CHAPTER FOUR
Brook Farm as Sacrifice
100
CHAPTER FIVE
Fruitlands: Convergence
140
CHAPTER SIX
Fruitlands: Divergence
17 4
CHAPTER SEVEN
Walden: The Community of One Index
251 VII
2 18
67
Preface
I
n the introduction to The American Renaissance, F. 0. Matthiessen writes that his subject is the artistic achievement of the mid-nineteenth century in America, particularly the way in which the great practitioners fused form and content. As if worried that his monumental study might not be regarded as adequate, he goes on to confess that there were two other books that he might have written but had not. The first of these would have been called The Age of Swedenborg, and it would have dealt with the way the midcentury had "embraced the subjective philosophy that 'the soul makes its own world.'" That subjective philosophy, however, had objective repercussions. The individual's sense of self-worth made him conscious of his social rights, and this awareness in turn made possible Orestes Brownson's extraordinary anticipation of "some of the Marxist analysis of the class controls of action.'' The unwritten book necessary to explore these and related issues Matthiessen calls The Age of Fourier. These two (non) titles point to what Sacvan Bercovitch has more recently termed, in his discussion of Emerson in The Puritan Origins of the American Self, "the paradox of a literature devoted at once to the exaltation of the individual and the search for a perfect community." This paradox is the central problem one encounters when confronting the thought of the New England Transcendentalists. The most obvious way to view it is in terms of the duality of subjective and objective worlds, of the internal vis-a-vis the external. This dichotomy manifests itself in many of the actual titles of works devoted to participants in the movement, classic studies such as Stephen Whicher's Freedom and Fate: lX
X
Preface
An Inner Life of Ralph WaldoEmerson, for example, or Sherman Paul's Shores of America: Thoreau's Inward Exploration. Everywhere we look there seems to be a dialectic between liberty and restriction, the me and the not-me, the one and the totality. The dialectic can be bypassed, of course, if we simply concentrate on one of its terms. David Van Leer points out that scholars have tended to write one or the other of Matthiessen's unwritten books. His own rigorously analytical contribution, Emerson's Epistemology: The Argument of the Essays, is on the Swedenborgian, that is to say the subjective or inward, side of the argument, investigating Emerson's contribution to American idealism. Another commentator has shown great ingenuity in transferring the conflict from the Transcendentalists themselves to the scholars who in modern times have endeavored to analyze their thinking. Anne C. Rose, in Transcendentalism as a Social Movement, tracks a development from Perry Miller's emphasis on romantic individualism, through W. R. Hutchison's study of Transcendentalist efforts at institutional reform, to a modern understanding that the movement was "a matter of social consciousness and action." Her book is a valuable one, though her transference of the axis from its nineteenthcentury setting to our own time is not wholly convincing. In any case, the Fourieristic emphasis did not supplant the Swedenborgian one; the two approaches were available simultaneously and complemented each other. Emerson himself remarked, in an essay in the Dial that later became the basis for his "Historic Notes of Life and Letters in New England," that during the Transcendentalist period "mechanics were pushed so far as fairly to meet spiritualism. One could not but be struck with strange coincidences betwixt Fourier and Swedenborg." One of those strange coincidences was that both Fourier and Swedenborg had formulated serial philosophies. Fourier attempted to impose "order and series" on all things by means of a "system which was coherent and comprehensive of facts to a wonderful degree"; Swedenborg had a "doctrine of Series and Degrees," and, "like a musical composer, goes on unweariedly repeating a simple air or theme, now high, now low, in solo, in chorus, ten thousand times reverberated, till it fills earth and heaven with the chant." There was a connection between the two precisely because, in being philosophers of seriality, both took connection as their very subject matter. They may have been situated at opposite ends of a spectrum, but their principal interest was in defining and describing that spectrum. (I am talking, of course, about the
Preface
xi
Emersonian apprehension of Swedenborg and Fourier-as Matthiessen also was-not of those thinkers per se.) I have written this book in the belief that the Transcendentalists were essentially bridgers of duality rather than victims of it. Their basic mission was to solve the very problem that they are frequently taken to embody. And nowhere was the nature and significance, not to mention the success and failure, of this endeavor more apparent than in their efforts to inaugurate utopia. The Transcendentalist social experiments-Brook Farm, Fruitlands, Walden-serve to bring the movement into sharp focus better than any other achievement. We can analyze the major writings that were produced, but to do so turns Transcendentalism into a two-horse race. Other characteristic phenomena are the controversy about miracles and some second-rate philosophizing, neither of which accounts for the impact the movement made (in its own time and since), or provides an adequate context for the literary achievement of its two geniuses, Emerson and Thoreau. One's sense that these communities were somehow the key issue is confirmed by the folklore, for, despite their transitoriness and relatively small scale, anyone with even the most cursory knowledge of the period has heard of them. But this assessment is also justified by the fact that utopia itself, as a concept, inevitably brought the problems faced by the Transcendentalists onto center stage. Utopian communities juxtapose freedom and social organization; they exalt the individual and represent a search for communal perfection. To put it another way, they connect the eternal world of nature and natural law-the world, in that pre-Darwinian, prerelativistic period, of stability and pattern-with the dynamic world of history and contingency. They connect subjective and objective, inward and outward, contemplation and action. Utopias provide the bridge the Transcendentalists were seeking, for they are situated exactly halfway between the ideal and the real. I began my study of Transcendentalist utopian thought many years ago, and it culminated in two substantial articles, one on the ideology of the Fruitlands community, the other on that of Brook Farm. Then I let the matter rest. It is not always easy to reconstruct one's own past motives, as I now know, having devoted a book to reconstructing those of other people. Perhaps I felt that I had said all I could on the topic. Perhaps, like Thoreau, I simply decided that I had other lives to lead. Then a few years ago I had the good fortune to meet Lyman Tower
xii
Preface
Sargent, that great authority on utopianism, at a conference at Exeter University, and he suggested to me that I should revisit the topic and write a book on it. The more I thought about his suggestion, the more it seemed like good advice. Important work had, of course, been done in the intervening period: Rose's book on the social dimensions of the movement, Frederick Dahlstrand's intellectual biography of Bronson Alcott, and Carl J. Guarneri's brilliant study of American Fourierism are obvious examples. Much detailed scholarship had appeared in the learned journals, particularly in the pages of the yea,rbooks edited by Joel Myerson, Studies in the American Renaissance (it has been a continuing source of pride to me that my article on Brook Farm was the first piece in the first volume of that series). None of this work, though, seemed to preempt my own task. Indeed, so far as I am aware, no one has attempted a coordinated view of the Transcendentalist utopian project, despite its centrality to the movement's concerns, and despite the fact that each community in itself constituted a claim by its members that a coordinated view of human behavior was both possible and indeed necessary. And of course such seriality was precisely what my own earlier forays into the topic had lacked. To my relief I found that it was not necessary to repudiate most of my earlier analysis. Indeed, turns of phrase from that work, sentences, arguments flit ghostlike in and out of this book, and I am most grateful to the editors of American Quarlerly and Studies in the American Renaissance for permission to draw on that material. But the context in which it now appears is both more detailed and more extensive, and needless to say the discourse in which it participates has been transformed by developments in literary and cultural theory. Above all, the book overcomes the structural inconsistency implicit in producing separate and incomplete explorations of the Transcendentalist search for completeness and structural consistency. A fellowship from the American Council of Learned Societies enabled me to pursue my research as a visiting scholar at Harvard University, as did a sabbatical leave granted by Manchester University. I am grateful to many libraries and archives for the opportunity to study, quote from, and in some cases reproduce material held by them: the Houghton and Widener Libraries of Harvard University, the Boston Public Library, the Fruitlands Museums, the Massachusetts Historical Society, the John Rylands University Library of Manchester, the Manchester Public Library, the Portico Library, and the British Library.
Preface
xiii
I am indebted to the people who have given me advice and/ or hospitality during the writing of this book: Roberta Bienvenu, jinx Bohstedt, John Bohstedt, Jean Day, Clio and Anthea Harrison, the late William Henry (Pat) Harrison, Jim and Carol Hoopes, W. R. Hutchison, Joel Myerson, Tom Quirk, Lyman Tower Sargent, Michael Schmidt, and Ian Walker. Other friends have given me help that is not so direct but equally important. And I want to take this opportunity to give thanks, for everything, to my late father, Leslie; my mother, Marian; and my dedicatees, my wife, Jo, who has shared this project-and all my projects-from the beginning, and my children, William and Helen. NoTE: I capitalize Transcendentalism and its variants when referring to the New England movement, and use lowercase on the relatively few occasions when the words have a purely philosophical sense. RICHARD FRANCIS
Manchester
TRANSCENDENTAL UTOPIAS
1 Nature versus History
N
ew England Transcendentalism was a many-sided phenomenon. From a parochial point of view, it can be seen as the product of a doctrinal argument within the Unitarian Church of Boston; from an international one, as the American accommodation of European romanticism. As a movement it had literary, religious, philosophical, and social ramifications. Its proponents wrote essays on topics ranging from circles to civil disobedience, and in addition produced political articles, sermons, and manifestos, kept journals, wrote poems, edited magazines and newspapers, conducted conversations, gave lectures; they started communities, lived in huts, were feverishly active, deeply withdrawn, joined churches, left churches, founded churches, taught school, farmed, fished, waited at table. No medium of discourse, area of knowledge, or field of activity seemed closed to them. The broad explanation for such breadth of interests is that the movement was a manifestation of the American cultural project. It was a new(ish) country, and there was still a great deal to do on all fronts. Benjamin Franklin in the previous century had organized street-cleaning and fire-fighting services, studied lightning, built stoves, drawn up constitutions. The Transcendentalists, while starting from a different set of premises (though, as we shall see, not necessarily so different as all that) had a similarly crowded agenda. But one can argue that it was not simply the nature of the world they inhabited which determined the range of their activities, but also the perspective on that worldindeed on any world-which Transcendentalism by its very nature generated. In fact, one of the preoccupations of the movement was to l
2
Transcendental Utopias
analyze the relationship between the world and its knower. Because such analysis is of a fundamental kind, its ramifications can be tracked in every direction. The circle, as described in Emerson's essay on the subject, symbolizes the "Unattainable, the flying Perfect," which may "conveniently serve us to connect many illustrations of human power in every department. "1 My purpose is to consider one department in particular, the utopian aspiration which is one of the most famous manifestations of the Transcendental afflatus. Even this department can be divided into subdepartments, however: the large-scale enterprise of Brook Farm, the "consociate family" at Fruitlands, and Thoreau's "community of one." Moreover, the interdisciplinary nature of Transcendentalist thinking means that this exploration will involve trying to come to terms with other themes and preoccupations. Indeed, it has to begin with an attempt to grapple with the basic epistemology of the movement, a search for that maddening "Unattainable ... around which the hands of man can never meet." 2 If the deepest concern of the New England Transcendentalists-perhaps of anybody-is to locate humankind within the world, then a quest for the basis of their utopian ideology must take us very directly to that preoccupation, since this mission inevitably involves problems of the relation between contingent and absolute, past and future, the singular and the totality, and above all, between history and nature. I explore these issues in this chapter as the essential basis for confronting, or rather for monitoring how the Transcendentalists confronted, the central paradox of utopianism: that it acknowledges disorder (in its dissatisfaction with the status quo) while affirming order (in offering a millennial prospect). The Transcendentalists' most important task was to find a law that somehow reconciled mutability with permanence, and thereby to come to terms with the ambivalence embodied in that phrase "the flying Perfect." 1. Ralph Waldo Emerson, "Circles," in Essays: First Series, vol. 2 of Collected Works of Ralph Walso Emerson, ed. Alfred R. Ferguson et a!., 5 vols. (Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1971- © President and Fellows of Harvard College), 179. All subsequent references to this volume will be to Essays r; subsequent references to this edition will be to Collected Works. For a stimulating account of the relationship between this essay's handling of "a strange, shimmering illusive truth" and modern deconstruction, see Leonard N. Neufeldt and Christopher Barr, "'I Shall Write Like a Latin Father': Emerson's 'Circles,'" New England (!:parterly 59 (March 1986): 92-108. In this and the following chapters on Brook Farm, I have made use, where appropriate, of material originally published in my essay "The Ideology of Brook Farm," in Studies in the Amerimn Renaissance, rg77, ed.Joel Myerson (Boston: Twayne Publishers, 1978), 1-48. 2. Emerson, "Circles," 179.
Nature versus History
3
One possible explanation for Transcendentalism's scale and eclecticism is simply that it was vague and diffuse. Hawthorne suggests a paradoxical combination of bulk and intangibility when he portrays "Giant Transcendentalist" in "The Celestial Railroad" as "a heap of fog and duskiness. "3 Half a century later H. C. Goddard referred to "the popular definition of transcendental, 'transcending commonsense.' "4 But the opposite possibility is just as plausible. In Emerson's "Divinity School Address," one of the great defining documents of the movement, it is worth noting that the word "law" appears more than twenty times. An alternative explanation for the remarkable range of Transcendentalist concerns is that at the heart of them lies a preoccupation with what might hold the full range of the world's phenomena, and of the individual's experiences, together, and link them to one another: a preoccupation with the principle of consistency, with the tissue of connectiveness, with the nature of law itself. A movement asserting the unity of all things can test that faith only by the criteria of variety and heterogeneity. It is true that Emerson said he proposed to write the word "lVhim" on the lintels of his doorpost, but that may be construed as an assertion of confidence in the stability and permanence of the doorpost. In the same essay, "Self-Reliance," he claims that perception is not whimsical but fatal. He also says, of course, that "a foolish consistency is the hobgoblin of little minds," but that can be taken as an attack on a specific category of consistency, to wit, the foolish sort, rather than on the principle of order itself. At the opening of the essay he suggests that it is the task of Transcendentalism to advance "on Chaos and the Dark. "5 Perhaps we should start our inquiry where New England Transcendentalism, as a specific intellectual movement with a particular membership, is usually held to begin: with the issue of the authenticity of the gospel miracles, the central subject of Emerson's "Address.'' During the early part of the nineteenth century the Unitarian Church in New England subsisted on a doctrinal minimum. Its development had been toward a liberal, open-ended alternative to the more enthusiastic and elaborately formulated dogmas of the New Calvinists. The law 3· Nathaniel Hawthorne, 'The Celestial Railroad," in Mosses from an Old Manse, vol. 1o of Centenary t-aition of the Works of Nathaniel Hawthorne, ed. William Charvat et al., 23 vols. (Columbus: Ohio State University Press, 1g6o-g4), 197. All subsequent references to this edition will be to Centenary Edition. 4· H. C. Goddard, Studies in New England Transcendentalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1908), 10. 5· Ralph Waldo Emerson, "Self-Reliance," Essays I, 30, 38, 33, 28.
4
Transcendental Utopias
of equilibrium, however, required that the one positive element in an otherwise unassertive theology should be firmly stressed; and for the Unitarians the sticking point was the gospel miracles. These provided an essential guarantee of the truth and relevance of the Christian message. As Andrews Norton, former Dexter Professor of Sacred Literature at Harvard and leading proponent of the orthodox Unitarian position, put it in his Discourse on the Latest Form of Infidelity: "Nothing is left that can be called Christianity, if its miraculous character be denied. Its essence is gone; its evidence is annihilated. Its truths, involving the highest interests of man, the facts which it makes known, and which are implied in its very existence as a divine revelation, rest no longer on the authority of God. "6 The trouble is that the miracles which provide this essential guarantee happened so long ago that we are left with what Norton likes to call "belief on testimony," but which he acknowledges could be called "belief on authority." Obviously anticipating objections to his putting so much faith in the supernatural-and in the secondhand supernatural at that-Norton claims that belief in miracles passes the test of rational scrutiny and affirms, by discreet use of negatives, that our knowledge of Christianity can be equated with our knowledge of anything else: "In maintaining ... that the thorough investigation of the evidences and character of our religion requires much knowledge and much thought, and the combined and continued labor of different minds, we maintain nothing that gives to Christianity a different character from what belongs to all the higher and more important branches of knowledge, and nothing inconsistent with its being in its nature a universal religion."7 The gospel miracles, by an accident of history, took place in the past, so that our knowledge of them can be achieved only by recourse to secondary sources. Scholars therefore need to establish the provenance of documents and interpret their contents just as they would if they were researching the life of Julius Caesar. But a parallelism in the tasks of the historian does not imply a parallelism in the status of the historical subject. Whether as a historian or as a contemporary witness, one "knows" that Christ changed the water into wine in quite a differ6. Andrews Norton, Discourse on the Latest Form of Infidelity (Cambridge:]. Owen, 1839), 22, excerpted in Perry Miller, ed., The Transcendentalists: An Anthology (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1950), 211. Miller's book remains the best source of material on the miracles controversy, and indeed in conjunction with his later anthology The American Transcendentalists: Their Prose and Poetry (New York: Anchor Books, 1957) and George Hochfield's Selected Writings of the American Transcendentalists (New York: New American Library, 1966) provides the most convenient access to the movement as a whole. 7. See Miller, Transcendentalists, 213.
Nature versus History
5
ent way from that in which one "knows" that Caesar conquered Gaul. Norton's curious hybrid of rationalism and revelation is the direct legacy of John Locke, who, in the words of Bertrand Russell, will at one time claim that "the bare testimony of revelation is the highest certainty," and at another that "revelation must be judged by reason."" It is fascinating to see how the Transcendentalists react to this incongruity. If they are to be defined by their capacity to transcend common sense-if, for example, the characteristic Transcendentalist stance is that adopted by Jones Very, who, while a temporary patient at the McLean asylum, took down an essay on Shakespeare which was dictated to him from above-then the assumption must be that in any two-horse race between reason and revelation, their money would inevitably be on revelation. 9 But this was not the case. Indeed, they showed that they were capable of subjecting the orthodox position to a stringent critique. The fact that when Theodore Parker entered the fray he chose to assume the no-nonsense persona of Levi Blodgett is almost as significant as the arguments he put forward. The name evokes an almost depressing degree of Yankee common sense. "You make us rest our moral and religious faith, for time and eternity," Blodgett informs Norton-with rather more of a rhetorical surge than one might expect from a farmer with mud on his boots- "on evidence too weak to be trusted in a trifling case that comes before a common court of law. "10 George Ripley goes further, asserting that "we know of no unerring test, by which to distinguish a miracle of religion from a new manifestation of natural powers, without a previous faith in the divinity of the performer. The phenomena of electricity and magnetism exhibit wonders surpassing the ordinary agencies of nature. Upon their first discovery, they presented all the characteristics by which we designate miracles, except their application to religious purposes. "11 In teres tingly enough, this is precisely the point that Hume fails to make satisfactorily in his "Essay on Miracles." Anthony Flew points out that the great skeptic mars his attack on Locke by defining the laws of nature as "merely numerical universal propositions," therefore necessarily conceding that 8. Bertrand Russell, History of Western Philosophy (London: Allen & Unwin, 1946), 631. For the influence of Locke on the Unitarians, see W. R. Hutchison, The Transcendentalist Ministers (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1959), 18-20. g. See Edwin Gittleman, Jones Very, The ~Yfective Years, z8JJ-I84o (New York: Columbia University Press, 1967), 235· 10. Levi Blodgett, The Previaus Question Between Mr. Norton and His Alumni (Boston: Weeks, Jordan & Co., 1840), excerpted in Miller, Transcendentalists, 230-31. 11. George Ripley, "Review of Martineau's Rationale of Religious Enquiry ... ," Christian Examiner 21 (November 1836): 253; excerpted in Miller, Transcendentalists, 131.
6
Transcendental Utopias
a new occurrence would have to be a miracle. 12 We thus have the intriguing spectacle of a Transcendentalist out-Humeing Hume. Ripley advocates skepticism, but he does not completely rule out the possibility of miracles. In his pamphlet An Essay on Transcendentalism, published anonymously in 1842, Charles Mayo Ellis restates Ripley's argument that a sudden encounter with hitherto unanticipated natural phenomena could be mistaken for a miracle. He points out that ''were we all in a state of ignorance, and should one come among us, such as we now consider a mere common man, the wonders he would work merely from his knowledge of astronomy, the sciences, arts, mechanics, would seem to us only to be ascribed to miraculous power." Half a century early (or a thousand years late) we have a glimpse of Mark Twain's Connecticut Yankee forecasting an eclipse and blowing up Merlin's tower before an open-mouthed rabble of King Arthur's subjects. Moreover, Ellis's main argument is not that the dividing line between nature and the supernatural is a difficult one to trace, but that miracles cannot occur at all: "Now Christ had all the knowledge that man can possess. Consequently, his works must always, to all men, so long as they remain imperfect, appear miraculous; though in themselves they were no violation of God's laws, but the result of his knowledge and perfect observance of those laws."13 Four years earlier, in 'The Divinity School Address," Emerson had made the same assertion, but with more elegance. By his second paragraph he is already evoking the comprehensiveness of the laws of the universe, a comprehensiveness that at the present stage of our development we cannot fully comprehend: "Behold these outrunning laws, which our imperfect apprehension can see tend this way and that, but not come full circle. Behold these infinite relations, so like, so unlike; many, yet one." And later in the address he memorably disposes of the conception of miracle in favor of a belief in the consistent ordering of the world of nature: "But the very word Miracle, as pronounced by the Christian churches, gives a false impression; it is Monster. It is not one with the blowing clover and the falling rain. "14 Not all the New England Transcendentalists were prepared to go quite as far as Emerson and Charles Mayo Ellis, but leading members of the movement were certainly prepared to go far enough. Ripley in12. Anthony Flew, Hume's Philosophy of Belief (London: Routledge, 1961), 204-5. 13. [Charles Mayo Ellis], An Essay on Transcendentalism (Boston: Crocker & Ruggles, 1842), 82. 14. Ralph Waldo Emerson, "The Divinity School Address," in Nature, Addresses, and Lectures, Collected Wmks, 1:76-77, 81. All subsequent references to this volume will be toNAL.
Nature versus History
7
sists that, though he believes in miracles as much as the next person, he simply is not prepared to rest the weight of his Christian commitment on them. Parker meanwhile generously takes on board not merely Christ's miracles but those of "other religious teachers" too. But, really, the two of them are doing no more than making polite gestures in the direction of orthodoxy; for both of them the supernatural is a bit of unnecessary decoration on the surface of the hard and commonsensical substance of Christianity. "I need no miracle to convince me that the sun shines," says Parker, "and just as little do I need a miracle to convince me of the divinity of Jesus and his doctrines, to which a miracle, as I look at it, can add just nothing. "15 The wheel has turned full circle. Parker, like Norton, emphasizes that knowing the central truths of Christianity is no different from knowing anything else, but instead of using this argument to substantiate the gospel miracles, he dismisses them as irrelevant to his basic point. The Transcendentalists, in short, whatever their reputation for transcending common sense, have developed a more consistent position than their opponents. Indeed, they have developed a position in which consistency itself, far from being the hobgoblin of little minds, is perceived to have an intrinsic value. This does not mean that they had a perverse ambition to achieve a more arid logic than Norton. On the contrary, by bringing Christ into the light of common day-indeed, by comparing him with the sun-they hoped to redeem the day. The Transcendentalists were attempting to pit law against legalism. "Any distrust of the permanence of laws," Emerson warns in Nature, ''would paralyze the faculties of man." Fortunately their "permanence is sacredly respected, and his faith therein is perfect. "16 The outcome of this argument with Unitarian orthodoxy is twoedged. On the one hand, the common day has been redeemed; on the other, Christ has been demystified. In Emerson's loaded phrase, he turns out to have been a "true man." Christ's contribution was an act of perception: "He saw that God incarnates himself in man." In this respect his achievement can be emulated: "A true conversion, a true Christ, is now, as always, to be made, by the reception of beautiful sentiments." 17 In short, the truest, most outstanding of men can be characterized by his qualities as perceiver and receptacle. This precept is worth bearing in mind, since the Transcendentalists are often pic15. Ripley, "Review of Martineau," 253; Theodore Parker, "The Previous Question," in Miller, Transcendentalists, 229. 16. Ralph Waldo Emerson, Nature, in NAL, 29-30. 17. Emerson, "The Divinity School Address," 81, 83.
8
Transcendental Utopias
tured as aggressive, indeed idiosyncratic, individualists. The exceptionalism and mysticism that unsympathetic observers have attributed to their view of nature has also been applied to their perspective on mankind. After all, the fog and duskiness that Hawthorne claimed characterized the movement were embodied in the form of a giant. In this respect-as a study in, so to speak, comparative giganticism-it is illuminating to compare Emerson's Representative Men with the book that was in some respects its source, Carlyle's On Heroes, Hero-Worship, and the Heroic in History, published nearly a decade previously. 18 It is a testimony to our expectation of Transcendentalist arrogance that we take it for granted that great men inevitably provide the yardstick by which members of the movement would prefer to be judged. But, as it happens, Emerson's main concern is with precisely the legitimacy and relevance of this yardstick. For Carlyle the topic of great men is an "illimitable" one, since they are "the modellers, patterns, and in a wide sense creators, of whatsoever the general mass of men contrived to do or to attain." 19 The great man, in Carlyle's scheme of things, is so inordinately great that the rest of us hardly get a look in. Great men pull the strings and the puppets dance. Great men embody the history of the world and transmit the radiance of heaven. Emerson can be warm in his admirations also, though he is capable of a sudden rectifying caution which holds him back from Carlylean excesses. In the final analysis, his model of the cause and effect which operates between great men and common humanity works in precisely the opposite direction from Carlyle's. For Emerson the great man "stands where all the eyes of men look one way, and their hands all point in the direction where he should go." 20 He is, after all, great only to the extent that he is representative. Sacvan Bercovitch distinguishes between Carlyle's "titan born to master the multitude, ... the Frankenstein's monster of leftwing Protestantism," and Emerson's true American, undertaking "a battle against 'mere antinomianism.' "21 Shakespeare and Dante, for Carlyle, are "canonised, so that it is impiety to rS. Ralph Waldo Emerson, Representative Men (185o), vol. 4 of Collected Works. All subsequent references to this volume will be to RM. Thomas Carlyle, On Heroes, Hero-Worship, and the Heroic in History (1841 ), 4th ed. (London: Chapman and Hall, 1852). rg. Carlyle, Heroes, 1-2. 20. Ralph Waldo Emerson, "Shakespeare, or the Poet," RM, IDg. 21. Sacvan Bercovitch, "Emerson the Prophet: Romanticism, Puritanism, and AutoAmerican Biography," in Emerson: Prophecy, Metamorphosis, and Influence, ed. David Levin (New York: Columbia University Press, 1975), 17.
Nature versus History
9
meddle with them." They are, in short, "a peculiar Two." 22 For Emerson, by contrast, Shakespeare has "no peculiarity." Shakespeare "was the farthest reach of subtlety compatible with an individual self,-the subtilest of authors, and only just within the possibility of authorship." His abilities did not heighten his stature but instead blurred his individuality. He is (just) distinguishable by his almost complete indistinguishability. By the same token, Napoleon "almost ceases to have a private speech and opinion." Emerson relishes Napoleon's claim to be merely the creature of circumstances and, in explaining his hero's ability to hold sway over so many others, displays his own kind of intellectual daring and panache: "It is Swedenborg's theory that every organ is made up of homogeneous particles, or, as it is sometimes expressed, every whole is made of similars; that is, the lungs are composed of infinitely small lungs, the liver of infinitely small livers, the kidney of little kidneys, &c. Following this analogy, if any man is found to carry with him the power and affections of vast numbers, if Napoleon is France, if Napoleon is Europe, it is because the people whom he sways are little Napoleons. "23 Swift's remark about big fleas having little fleas upon their backs to bite 'em comes to mind, though in this case it is more a matter of little Napoleons having bigger Napoleons over their heads to rule them. When Emerson deals with Swedenborg himself, he is also keen to demonstrate that scale is, as it were, only relative. Swedenborg is to be admired because he is "vast," a "colossal soul," "one of the missouriums and mastodons of literature." In a rush of enthusiasm Emerson claims that this stature provides a perspective that cannot be achieved on a smaller scale: "A drop of water has the properties of the sea, but cannot exhibit a storm." Two pages later, however, he is backtracking rapidly. Swedenborg achieved "that native perception of identity which made mere size of no account to him," and possessed "the fine secret that little explains large, and large little." It is as though a mastodon should stand for election to the assembly of heroes on an anti-mastodon ticket. In the light of such short-circuiting, Emerson's oxymoron about Plato-"He is a great average man"-seems hardly provocative at ali.24 In sum, whereas for Carlyle a great man is "a flowing light-fountain," Emerson prefers to watch him disappear in a puff of smoke: "I find Carlyle, Heroes, 133. Emerson, "Shakespeare," 121; idem, ''Napoleon, or the Man of the World," RA1, 131, 129. 24. Ralph Waldo Emerson, "Sweden borg, or the Mystic," RM, 58, 6o; idem, "Plato, or the Philosopher," RM, 34· 22. 23.
10
Transcendental Utopias
him greater, when he can abolish himself and all heroes, by letting in this element of reason, irrespective of persons, this subtilizer, and irresistible upward force, into our thought, destroying individualism;-the power so great, that the potentate is nothing. "25 An analysis made many years ago by Woodbridge Riley might be relevant here. In his book American Thought, published in 1915, Riley identifies a paradoxical by-product of Transcendentalist individualism: "The rights of man were no longer to be measured merely in public documents, in measured terms, but each man was to follow his own private inclinations, to break down the trammels of society, to rely upon himself. Seldom before had individualism reached such heights. Indeed by a sort of paradox it led to a degree of detachment that was at times indifference."26 He gives us here, it seems to me, a beautifully compact account of what was a complex and ironic cultural development: first, the withdrawal from the "measured terms" of public authority, and its replacement by the anarchic doctrine (potentially at least) of self-reliance; then the intensification of this condition until it reached a point of detachment or even "indifference." Nobody was more aware of this paradox than Emerson himself: "In youth we are mad for persons. Childhood and youth see all the world in them. But the larger experience of man discovers the identical nature appearing through them all. Persons themselves acquaint us with the impersonal. "27 The logic of this situation is as follows: a structure that connects all phenomena cannot itself be phenomenal; ergo, it is "transparent"; if the pattern is indeed not merely consistent but also comprehensive, then it must include humankind; individuals must therefore share an identical nature, and persons must be impersonal. Perhaps nowhere is this paradoxical connection between external and internal, world and knower, more powerfully and more beautifully expressed than in the first chapter of Emerson's Nature. His opening remarks on the significance of season and setting come into sharp and memorable focus when he gives us this vignette of himself: "Crossing a bare common, in snow puddles, at twilight, under a clouded sky, without having in my thoughts any occurrence of special good fortune, I have enjoyed a perfect exhilaration. Almost I fear to think how glad I am. "28 One can recognize the experience Emerson describes without at 25. 26. rpt. 27. 28.
Carlyle, Heroes, 2; Ralph Waldo Emerson, "Uses of Great Men," RM, 14. Woodbridge Riley, American ThQUght from Puritanism to Pragmatism and Beyond ( 1915; Gloucester, Mass.: Peter Smith, 1959), 145-46. Ralph Waldo Emerson, "Self-Reliance," Essays I, 164. Emerson, Nature, 10.
Nature versus History
11
first consciously noting the oddness of the circumstances that have generated it. What we have is a series of self-canceling pairings: the common that provides the setting is bare, the snow has melted into puddles, the light is dim, the sky is obscured. Each itemized feature, in short, proves to be in actuality absent, or at least diminished. And so far as the observer of these ambivalences is concerned, he enjoys his exhilaration while lacking thoughts of any special good fortune. His gladness seems to be canceled out by fear. Cause and effect have become unglued. Emerson then proceeds, in his memory or his imagination, into woods. Here, too, the blanking out of the external world continues. Instead of being covered by trees and undergrowth, the ground is "bare," and the observer is conscious of "infinite space." The precision of these reversals is reminiscent of Wordsworth's sonnet "Composed Upon Westminster Bridge," where it is an urban environment that folds back into itself, as Wordsworth rhymes "wear" with "bare": 'This city now doth, like a garment, wear I The beauty of the morning; silent, bare . . . " If Emerson finds exhilaration frightening, so Wordsworth finds majesty "touching," and his experience culminates in the perception of a heart that has, in fact, stopped beating: "And all that mighty heart is lying still." 29 Like Wordsworth, Emerson is trying to achieve a glimpse of the deeper structure of the world, a perspective that unifies the jostling contradictions of daily life: "I become a transparent eye-ball. I am nothing. I see all. The currents of the Universal Being circulate through me; I am part or particle of God."30 In this bare environment where there is nothing to see, the eye becomes infinitely perceptive. A transparent eyeball is an eyeball that cannot be seen, and therefore establishes the observer as literally self-effacing: an indifferent Transcendentalist par excellence. The reticence of the image can be contrasted with the conventionally romantic depiction of the artist's relation to his surroundings in Asher B. Durand's painting Kindred Spirits (184g), in which William Cullen Bryant and Thomas Cole are shown standing on a high ledge, with the wild landscape of the Catskills at their disposal, so to speak. At the same time, however, the phrase in this context also suggests an eyeball that can perceive transparency. As James M. Cox has put it, "There is outside the perimeter of the eye the negative world of 29. William Wordsworth, "Composed Upon Westminster Bridge," in The Poetical Works of Wordsworth, ed. Thomas Hutchinson (London: Oxford University Press, 1964), 214. 30. Emerson, Nature, 10.
12
Transcendental Utopias
the vanished ego." 31 The question of priority between man and the world does not arise, therefore, since ultimately both are zeroes and balance each other out. It seems to me essential for an understanding of Emerson's outlook, and indeed of Transcendentalist philosophy as a whole, to realize that this equation does not leave us with nothing, however contentless it seems. What we have before us is the structure of the equation itself, a structure that connects the individual and the world, the one and the many. Once we have been liberated in this algebraic fashion from the particular and the specific, we are able to concentrate on the connective tissue in which they are found: "The name of the nearest friend sounds then foreign and accidental. To be brothers, to be acquaintances,-master or servant, is then a trifle and a disturbance. I am the lover of uncontained and immortal beauty."' 2 This experience is, inevitably, intermittent, requiring a special set of circumstances, or rather noncircumstances, to come about. The difference between the human angle of vision and the Almighty's is well brought out in a couple of sentences in "Circles": "Our globe seen by God, is a transparent law, not a mass of facts. The law dissolves the fact and holds it fluid." God, as a transparent being, is able consistently to view the transparent nature of the world. The second sentence, however, captures the fleeting nature of such experiences from where we stand, as the woods dissolve around us. It is not clear (and this is a significant ambiguity) whether the fluidity is a function of the process of perception, as the eye has a sense of traveling through the fact toward the underlying law, or whether the characteristic of that law itself is to be dynamic and "fluid." Whatever its basis, the nature of the experience is likely to be that of a pattern on the move. 'The natural world," we are told, "may be conceived of as a system of concentric circles, and we now and then detect in nature slight dislocations, which apprize us that this surface on which we now stand, is not fixed, but sliding."'' One such dislocation was observed bv Thoreau as he walked from Walden Pond to Concord along the railroad cutting. One of its banks has begun to thaw in the warming sun, and the unlocking of the frost unlocks in turn a whole sequence of associations in his mental perception. In an exuberant passage he compares the configurations of the 31. James M. Cox, "R. W. Emerson: The Circles of the Eye," in Levin, Emerson, 63. This essay provides a close and interesting reading of the "transparent eye-ball" passage in Nature, though I disagree with some of its conclusions. 32. Emerson, Nature, 10. 33· Emerson, "Circles," 179, 186.
Nature versus History
thawing sand with lava, lichen, coral, leopards' paws, birds' feet, brains, lungs, bowels, excrements, rivers, the liver, fatty tissue, feathers, wings, the grub and butterfly, and the great globe itself, not to mention various aspects of the human form: the ball of the finger, the skeleton, fingers, toes, the hand, the ear, the lip, the nose, the chin, the cheeks. All these apparently diverse phenomena resemble one another; all are reducible to one basic shape, which Thoreau nominates as that of the leaf. This one hillside can illustrate "the principle of all the operations of Nature": "The Maker of this earth but patented a leaf." 34 The most obvious manifestation of the consistency of law is to be found in the phenomenon of seriality; and, I want to suggest, the search for a, or rather the, serial component of the universe is one of the most important elements in the Transcendentalists' mission. They wish to emulate the poet who "turns the world to glass, and shows us all things in their right series and procession."35 The quest for the law of series is replete with paradoxes, ironies, complications. There is no more reason to identifY the leaf as the primitive form than (presumably) the bowels or the butterfly, though it is true that we associate leaves with repetitiveness, as is testified by Whitman's choice of a title for his own epic of seriality, Leaves of Grass. While Thoreau's spirits ride high on the tensions created by such similarity in difference, in another mood, or when one's energy is low, the effect can be vertiginous, as Emerson testifies in "Experience": "Where do we find ourselves? In a series, of which we do not know the extremes, and believe that it has none. We wake and find ourselves on a stair: there are stairs below us, which we seem to have ascended; there are stairs above us, many a one, which go upward and out of sight. ... All things swim and glimmer. Our life is not so much threatened as our perception." Ralph L. Rusk describes the aged Emerson, his mind failing, pathetically floundering in a world where objects slide into one another: "He arrived at hen only after zigzagging from cat to fish, fish to bird, and bird to cock. "36 34· Henry David Thoreau, Walden, in The Writings of Henry D. Thoreau, ed. Walter Harding eta!., 7 vols. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1971-), 304-8. All subsequent references to this edition will be to Writings. 35· Ralph Waldo Emerson, "The Poet," in Essays, Second Series, Collected Works, 3:1 2. All subsequent references to this volume will be to Essays 2. As Lawrence Buell has written: "The Transcendentalist literati were not merely committed as Yeats was to the principle that the secrets of the universe could be discovered through poetry; they also believed it." Lawrence Buell, Literary Transcendentalism: Style and Vision in the American Renaissance (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1973), 143· 36. Ralph Waldo Emerson, "Experience," in Essays 2, 27; Ralph L. Rusk, The Life of Ralph
Transcendental Utopias
Roman Jakobson divides aphasia into two broad categories: similarity disorder and contiguity disorder. The disability that clouded Emerson's final years belongs to the first type, which is characterized by difficulty in the selection of words. In such a case a word that is taken out of context ceases to have meaning: it becomes, as Jakobson puts it, "nothing but blab." In other words, the patient's language develops a sort of invisibility. Jakobson describes how key words can be superseded by abstract anaphoric substitutes, so that a French patient, as Freud recorded, used terms such as machin and chose instead of more specific nouns. Eventually "only the framework, the connecting links of communication, is spared by this type of aphasia at its critical stage."' 7 In short, all that is left is grammar itself. In Emerson's philosophy-which gave priority to the principle of connectivity over what was connected, which advocated the transparency of the eyeball and celebrated the poet's capacity to turn the world into glass-such a medical condition could almost be regarded as an occupational hazard. The facts of men and chickens dissolve into one another. The philosopher maintains his status for as long as he is able to discern that beneath the zeroes lies the equation itself. The patient is someone who has lost the ability to handle the abstract structures that are revealed by the process of verbal emaciation: "Told to repeat the word 'no,' [the] patient replied 'No, I don't know how to do it.' While spontaneously using the word in the context of his answer ('No, I don't .. .'), he could not produce the purest form of the equational predication, the tautology a = a: «no» is «no»." Jakobson goes on to explain that the problem in the case of this patient results from an inability to use a meta-language: "The examples of equational predication sought in vain from the patients cited above, are metalinguistic propositions referring to the English language.""' Strictly speaking, if the law of series is coextensive with the universe as a whole, then the philosopher should also be denied a meta-language to speak of it. This problem does not worry Thoreau, howeverat least not in the passage under discussion. The seriality of the universe is manifested in the structure of language as in the structure of Waldo Emerson (New York: Scribner's, 1949), 491. Another example of the Transcendentalist habit of climbing phenomenological staircases occurs in Bronson Alcott's 1849 MS "Tablets in Colours: Disposed on Twelve Tables," Houghton Library, 59M-3o6 ( 11), 91 (page out of order), where he quotes "Oken's Skeleton reproduced in the Head": "The Brain is the . . . Spinal Marrow I The Cranium is the vertelTrae column Iff Spine I The Mouth is the intestine & abdomen I The Nose is the lungs & thlffax I The Jaws are the limbs ... ,"and so on. 37· Roman Jakobson, ''Two Aspects of Language and Two Types of Aphasic Disturbance," in Selected Writings, 8 vols. (The Hague: Mouton, 1962-88), 2:245-46. 38. Ibid., 247-48.
Nature versus History
everything else. Philip F. Gura has used the phrase "epistemological etymology" to describe the kind of analysis Thoreau undertakes here: Internally, whether in the globe or animal body, it [the leaf] is a moist thick lobe, a word especially applicable to the liver and lungs and the leaves of fat, (A.et[3w, labor, lapsus, to flow or slip downward, a lapsing; A.of36c:;, globus, lobe, globe; also lap, flap, and many other words,) externally a thin dry leaf, even as the f and v are a pressed and dried b. The radicals of lobe are lb, the soft mass of the b (single-lobed, orB, double lobed,) with the liquid l behind it pressing it forward. In globe, glb,
the guttural g adds to the meaning the capacity of the throat.'9 The exuberance and resourcefulness of this analysis notwithstanding, Thoreau is perfectly well aware that the divide between man and nature cannot be bridged so easily. The history of the human race is out of step with the serene permanence of the laws of the universe. We may echo the language of nature, but we still cannot interpret it aright. "What Champollion," Thoreau asks, "will decipher this hieroglyphic for us, that we may turn over a new leaf at last?"40 In keeping with the general tone, the appeal he makes here is jocular and ingenious, playing on the various associations of the word leaf, the intellectual (as in page) and the spiritual, as well as the structural. Nevertheless, however optimistic and positive he and the other Transcendentalists may be, they cannot gloss over or ignore the doctrine of the Fall of Man, the separation of human history from natural order. One of the recurring concerns of this book will be to explore their efforts to come to terms with the issues raised by that separation. Meanwhile, it is interesting to watch Emerson undertake the same sort of serial analysis as his friend Thoreau. In his essay "The Method of Nature," written more than ten years before the publication of Walden, he too suggested the leaf as creation's building block, and went on to point up the irony of this sameness in diversity by referring to the "catholic character [of nature] which makes every leaf an exponent of the world. "41 Some years later he expanded and enriched this idea in "Swedenborg, or the Mystic" in Representative Men. 39· Philip F. Gura, The Wisdom of Words: Language, Theology, and Literature in the New England Renaissance (Middletown, Conn.: Wesleyan University Press, 1981), 118; Thoreau, Walden, 306. 40. Thoreau, Walden, 308. 41. Ralph Waldo Emerson, "The Method of Nature," in NAL, 125. The Brook Farmer John Sullivan Dwight also tended to seize on the leaf as a prime example of nature's method, as this claim from his pamphlet Association in Its Connection with Education and Religion (Boston: B. H. Greene, 1844) indicates: "The universe of mind and
Transcendental Utopias
We have already seen how Emerson used Swedenborg's ideas to bolster his claim that Napoleon was able to rule so successfully because we are all little Napoleons. The origin of such a paradox lies in Swedenborg's "doctrine of Series and Degrees," which insists that "Nature iterates her means perpetually on successive planes." This idea, Emerson stresses, was not peculiar to Swedenborg but "dates from the oldest philosophers, and derives perhaps its best illustration from the newest," one of whom is obviously Emerson himself. 42 Many of the philosophers Emerson is thinking of were no doubt among the writers discussed in Lovejoy's famous series of lectures called "The Great Chain of Being," since we are obviously dealing with a particularly concrete and literal version of that powerful metaphor whose persistence Lovejoy traces from classical times to the early nineteenth century. What Emerson finds in Sweden borg, significantly, is an extension of the chain into the interior of consciousness, where it can anchor the individual psyche to what Emerson himself would call the over-soul, and which the Stoic philosophers he admired identified as the universal pneuma. On the vegetative plane of natural iteration the Maker, Emerson tells us, has but patented a leaf: "In the plant, the eye or germinative point opens to a leaf, then to another leaf, with a power of transforming the leaf into radicle, stamen, pistil, petal, bract, sepal, or seed." In the higher forms of life the leaf has toughened into a vertebra: "In the animal, nature makes a vertebra, or a spine of vertebrae, and helps herself still by a new spine, with a limited power of modifying its form-spine on spine, to the end of the world." Emerson goes on to describe how the human body and indeed the human mind have been constructed out of these building blocks: Manifestly, at the end of the spine, nature puts out smaller spines, as arms; at the end of the arms, new spines as hands; at the other end, she repeats the process, as legs and feet. At the top of the column, she puts out another spine, which doubles or loops itself over as a spanworm into a ball, and forms the skull,-with extremities again; the hands being now the upper jaw, the feet the lower jaw, the fingers and toes being represented this time by upper and lower teeth. This new spine is destined to high uses. It is a new man on the shoulders of the last. It can almost shed its trunk, and manage to live alone, according
matter is one great harmony; every planet, every leaf, every atom, every action, has a destined place in which, (however small,) it is of infinite significance and worth" (g). 42. Emerson, "Sweden borg," 6o.
Nature versus History
to the Platonic idea in the Timaeus. Within it, on a higher plane, all that was done in the trunk, repeats itself. Nature recites her lesson once more in a higher mood. 43 The immediacy of the language here, and in particular the busy present tense of the verbs, gives one a sense of structure being transformed into process: "Nature puts out ... repeats ... puts out another spine, which doubles or loops itself over ... forms the shell ... recites her lesson once more." The vision, however, is essentially static, not Darwinian; the process involved is that of consciousness, as it makes the discovery of the connections between all things. Indeed, the only part of the system where some sort of variable seems at least conceivable is the area of consciousness itself, connected to the rest of the edifice by that poignant adverb "almost," as mankind is aware of not quite belonging in nature's continuum, but not successfully achieving independence from it either. Similarly, though it was the thaw of the railroad bank that caught Thoreau's attention, providing the spectacle of a pattern on the move, his emphasis is on his own capacity for cross-referencing rather than on the phenomenon of dynamic improvisation in the external world. These mental juxtapositions have been brought about by the special circumstances of this particular location, although Thoreau does celebrate the creative energy of nature-and of God. He writes: "When I see on the one side the inert bank,-for the sun acts on one side first,-and on the other this luxuriant foliage, the creation of an hour, I am affected as if in a peculiar sense I stood in the laboratory of the Artist who made the world and me,-had come to where he was still at work, sporting on this bank, and with excess of energy strewing his fresh designs about. "44 Perhaps there is some intuition here of the possibility that nature's own reproductive energies could offer the spectacle of an organic, developing pattern. Nevertheless, at this stage in his career Thoreau sees nature's dynamics as operating within strict boundaries.'5 The grub might go through its set mutations, finally turning into a butterfly, just as the seasons go through their annual cycle, but in this universal ordering it is only the human leaves that are likely 43· Ibid., 61. 44· Thoreau, Walden, 306. 45· The Transcendentalists' interest in the precursors of the doctrine of evolution, and their receptiveness to the theory itself when it came along, is illuminatingly discussed in Frederick L. Dahlstrand, "Science, Religion, and the Tra~scendentalist Response to a Changing America," in Studies in the American Renaissance, I988, ed. Joel Myerson (Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia, 1988), 10-14.
Transcendental Utopias
to be turned over, through the shift in consciousness brought about by the discoveries of some Champollion. Similarly, the coalescing forms in this passage from Emerson's "Compensation" are the product not of evolutionary generation but of lateral cross-references in a world of "appearances": These appearances indicate the fact that the universe is represented in every one of its particles. Every thing in nature contains all the powe~s of nature. Every thing is made of one hidden stuff; as the naturalist sees one type under every metamorphosis, and regards a horse as a running man, a fish as a swimming man, a bird as a flying man, a tree as a rooted man. Each new form repeats not only the main character of the type, but part for part all the details, all the aims, furtherances, energies and whole system of every other. 46 The somewhat absurd ramifications of looking at the world in this way are reminiscent of the excesses of the eighteenth-century French philosophe J. B. Robinet, who, Lovejoy tells us, pushed his faith in the chain of being to such lengths that he asserted the existence of "fishmen and fish-women (human with respect to the upper part of their bodies)" and who, in "the quest of these adumbrations of the human form in the lower orders of creation, . . . was unhappily led to find similitudes of faces, as well as of arms and legs, in the radish and other plants, and to publish drawings of these vegetable anthropoids." Mter all, Emerson himself suggests in Nature that there is an "occult relation between man and the vegetable."47 But for Emerson there is a sudden energy, as of friction, to be derived from such species juxtapositions and, more important, an implication of an elaborate process of exploration, of inventiveness, of patterned movement lying behind them. Nature, viewed phenomenologically, may be ranked and static, but the fact of consciousness gives it fluidity, airiness, abstract scope. At the end of his essay on Sweden borg, Emerson complains that the great man's system "wants central spontaneity" and, as a result, "there is no individual in it." For Swedenborg, we now discover, "the Universe is a gigantic crystal, all whose atoms and laminae lie in uninterrupted order, and with unbroken unity, but cold and still." Whereas previously Emerson has described the inability of consciousness be autonomous as a defining and tantalizing fact of the human condition (a chronic 46. Ralph Waldo Emerson, "Compensation," in Essays r, 59· 47. Arthur 0. Lovejoy, The Great Chain of Being (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1936), 271, 281; Emerson, Nature, 10.
Nature versus History
condition of almostness, as it were), he now diagnoses this problem as specific to Swedenborg himself: 'With a force of many men, he could never break the umbilical cord which held him to nature and he did not rise to the platform of true genius. It is remarkable that this man who by his perception of symbols saw the poetic construction of things and the primary relation of mind to matter, remained entirely devoid of the whole apparatus of poetic expression, which that perception creates. "4" Given the doctrine of the sameness of all things, it is not wholly surprising that Emerson's account of Goethe is at times almost indistinguishable from his account of Swedenborg. Goethe too "suggested the leading idea of modern Botany, that a leaf or the eye of a leaf is the unit of botany, and that every part of the plant is only a transformed leaf to meet a new condition." Moreover, by references to tapeworm and caterpillar, the leaf is promoted into a series of vertebrae, with the head and all it contains, "only the uppermost vertebra transformed." Once again, though, at the very moment when he makes the connection between human consciousness and the natural continuum, Emerson seems to recoil. He admires Goethe as a savant because contemplation is superior to action: "Men's actions are too strong for them," with the result that "what they have done, commits and enforces them to do the same again." Since this outcome would seem to imitate the imitative processes of nature itself, one might expect it to be welcomed, but no. Here too, then, the problem of a static or crystalline structure is paramount. In Nature, as we have seen, contemplation provides access to transcendent law; here, conversely, activity is castigated for leading to reductive pattern. Emerson evokes the context of social radicalism and utopianism to make the point: "The fiery reformer embodies his aspiration in some rite or covenant, and he and his friends cleave to the form, and lose the aspiration. The Quaker has established Quakerism, the Shaker has established his monastery and his dance, and, although each prates of spirit, there is no spirit, but repetition, which is anti-spiritual. "49 Emerson criticizes institutional Christianity in his "Divinity School Address" on the grounds that "the idioms of his [Christ's] language, and the figures of his rhetoric, have usurped the place of his truth; and churches are not built on his principles, but on his tropes." The imaginative power of language has been short-circuited by an overliteral response to metaphor and symbol, and the freedom of con48. Emerson, "Swedenborg," 74-75, So. 49· Ralph Waldo Emerson, "Goethe; or, the Writer," in RM, 158, 154.
20
Transcendental Utopias
sciousness to move from the crystalline to the fluid has been denied. As a result, Christianity has fossilized into a "Mythus."50 I think we have come here to the most confusing problem in Transcendentalist philosophy. But though it is impossible to offer a watertight solution-partly because the movement was complex and manifold, partly perhaps because the confusion was never squarely confrontedit is important for an understanding of the Transcendentalists' utopian thought and practice to get some sort of grip on the issues involved. At one and the same time the Transcendentalists believe in a unifYing structure but reject static patterning or crystallization; they think poetically but are suspicious of tropes; they celebrate their glimpses of the serene laws of nature but accept that they themselves are part of a historical and contingent reality; they assert the existence of a serial chain but suspect that the links that connect us to it are not secure. George Santayana has probably come closer than anyone else to providing an account of the inner tensions of Transcendentalist thought in "The Genteel Tradition in American Philosophy," which began life as a lecture delivered before the Philosophical Union of the University of California on August 25, 1911. He identifies two forces, pulling in opposite directions, at the very heart of the movement. The distinction is between, on the one hand, philosophical or methodical transcendentalism and, on the other, a mythic variety that is characterized by a fundamentally different stance toward the external world. 51 The first sort of transcendentalism is fundamentally empirical in its orientation. It is curious about and engaged with the external world, which indeed it transcends only to the extent of establishing for itself an a priori vantage point from which that world can be perceived. It is a transcendentalism of form, not of content, one that does no more than acknowledge the existence of mental categories to act as receptacles for external reality. The second sort, self-indulgent rather than receptive, is characterized by an undervaluing or even a complete ignoring of objective reality in favor of a subjective, ultimately solipsistic alternative. On the one hand, we have a group of transcendentalists with their eyes wide open; on the other, a group with their heads buried in the sands of a phenomenological desert. Both kinds of tran50. Emerson, "The Divinity School Address," 81. Philip Gura discusses the claim by Emerson and others that a preoccupation with tropes has led to the neglect of the laws of "nature and God" in 'The Transcendentalists and Language: The Unitarian Exegetical Background," Studies in the American Renaissance, z979. ed. Joel Myerson (Boston: Twayne, 1979), 10-11. 51. George Santayana, "The Genteel Tradition in American Philosophy," in Winds of Change (New York: Scribner's, 1913), 186-215.
Nature versus History
21
scendentalism, Santayana claims, found a place within the American philosophical tradition. The second sort, transcendental myth, provided a refuge for the now toothless remnants of the Calvinistic faith of an earlier and sterner generation. The first sort, transcendental method, suited the outlook of the young republic: "It was autonomous, undismayed, calmly revolutionary. "52 Perhaps this distinction-and in particular the way in which transcendental myth can be associated with outmoded patterns of thought and behavior-can be clarified by reference to Levi-Strauss's analysis of the difference between mythical and scientific modes of thought in The Savage Mind. Levi-Strauss compares mythical thinking with the activities of the bricoleur, the jack-of-all-trades. The bricoleur brings to bear on each task the ragbag of tools and bits and pieces (Levi-Strauss goes to the trouble of quoting the English expression "odds and ends") which he has accumulated during his previous tasks. Thus, "it might be said that the engineer questions the universe, while the 'bricoleur' addresses himself to a collection of oddments left over from human endeavours, that is, only a sub-set of the culture."53 Santayana is talking in broader terms than Levi-Strauss, but this basic outline of the two possible stances toward the external world seems to shed light on some aspects of the distinction he is making. The methodical transcendentalist, like Levi-Strauss's engineer, brings to his experience a particular intellectual structure, but one unencumbered as far as possible by ideological baggage. The result is an openness to experience (his "concepts thus appear like operators opening up the set being worked with"), while the myth-making transcendentalist brings to bear the full "treasury" of what he has accumulated (so that his "signification [is] like the operator of that set's reorganization, which neither extends nor renews it and limits itself to obtaining the group of its transformations"). 54 In his lecture Santayana points the way in which these methodical and mythic tendencies in American Transcendentalism interacted, almost alternated. Emerson, for example, "had no system" but "opened his eyes upon the world every morning with a fresh sincerity." At the same time, he was drawn to the "very verge of system-making; but he stopped short." His "notions of compensation, or the over-soul, or spiritual laws" were counteracted by his return "to experience, to history, to 52. Ibid., Ig6. 53· Claude Levi-Strauss, The Savage Mind (London: Weidenfeld and Nicholson, 22, 20.
54· Ibid.,
20.
1972),
22
Transcendental Utopias
poetry, to the natural science of his day," and therefore were never given the sustained attention that would have made them into "thin and forced" constructions like "other transcendental systems."55 One can see Emerson wrestling with these contradictory tendencies, and from a certain point of view actually reconciling them, in one of his most mysterious and problematic poems, 'The Sphinx," which was written in 1840 and accorded the status of first poem in the collection of 1846. 56 In this poem the stable domain of nature is contrasted with the world of change inhabited by the human race. After all, in our culture the most powerful utopian vision is retrospective, not prospective: it is of the golden age, the Garden of Eden, the world of nature that existed before history began and that can still be conceived of apart from its processes. There we perceive harmony: Sea, earth, air, sound, silence, Plant, quadruped, bird, By one music enchanted, One deity stirred ... Sadly, we have been exiled from that condition: "But man crouches and blushes ... " By contrast with the rest of the animal kingdom which remains stable, entranced by the Lethe of nature, man is a restless, striving creature who lives within the medium of time simply because he is conscious that he does. He takes chances, makes mistakes, commits sins, all in the search for progress: "The fiend that man harries I Is love of the Best." And when he arrives at the end of the rainbow, he promptly sets off once again: The heavens that now draw him With sweetness untold, Once found,-for new heavens He spurneth the old. Man, in short, has repudiated nature for history, being for becoming. The Sphinx tells the poet-protagonist that their relationship is not adversarial after all. It cannot be, since the Sphinx turns out to be not 55· Santayana, "Genteel Tradition," 197. 56. Ralph Waldo Emerson, ''The Sphinx," in Poems, vol. 9 of Complete Works of Ralph Waldo Emerson, ed. Edward Waldo Emerson, 12 vols. (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 19036), 21-25. All subsequent references to this edition will be to Works.
Nature versus History
a being in her own right but simply an aspect of the poet's psyche. 57 The poet incorporates the Sphinx since he asks questions continually-questions that, whatever their ostensible purport, must be variations on the theme of "Who am 1?," the most basic inquiry of all. What is consistent is the ongoing quest. The answer to the question what is man is that man is the creature who asks that question-and is perpetually dissatisfied by the answers he gets: So take thy quest through nature, It through thousand natures ply; Ask on, thou clothed eternity; Time is the false reply. At this point the Sphinx begins to ply through a thousand natures herself. This development presents a difficulty only if one loses sight of the fact that merely two stanzas previously she has claimed to be the poet's very spirit and yoke-fellow. She embodies the dynamic and questing part of his nature, the eyebeam of his roving eye. But an eyebeam has two ends, one attached to the subject (and, as Lewis Leary has pointed out, Emerson enjoys punning on eye/1), 58 the other to the world which he perceives. Since the poet is committed to a philosophy of change, he cannot be expected to see nature as the manifestation of a serene and static order. Just as Thoreau, a few years later, was to see a pattern on the move as he made his way to Concord beside the thawing sand bank, so Emerson's poet perceives the outside world to manifest his own state of flux. The Sphinx becomes Proteus. Part of the surrealism of this stanza derives from the fact that although the mythology of the poem clearly originates with the Greek Sphinx, Emerson pictures her as the Egyptian one, a vast stone statue which, like that of Hermione in The Winter's Tale, finally comes to life. In doing so the Sphinx keeps faith with her portmanteau identity57· Part of the problem that critics have experienced with this poem is caused by their tendency to see it in dramatic terms, as a dialogue between two characters, rather than in philosophical terms, as a conflict between two aspects of the poet's own nature. R. A. Yoder, for example, in Emerson and the Orphic Poet in America (Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1978), agrees with an earlier commentator, Thomas Whittaker, that "the poet is rebuked and the poem dramatizes ultimate skepticism," going on to claim that the riddle is necessarily unsolved because "one cannot understand the part before he fully understands the whole" (119). David Porter, in Emerson and Literary Change (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1978), comments that "it is unclear whether or not the poet solves the Sphinx's riddle"; the poet seems, Porter tells us, to defeat the Sphinx and then in turn to be defeated by her (8o). 58. Lewis Leary, Ralph Waldo Emerson: An Interpretative Essay (Boston: Twayne, 198o), 5·
24
Transcendental Utopias
woman's head, lion's body, serpent's tail, and eagle's wings, a concrete manifestation if ever there was one of unity in diversity, and a potent image in a pre-evolutionary cultural milieu of nature as process. The verbs tell the story: melted, silvered, spired, flowered, flowed. The words themselves almost merge into one another. Wherever he looks, Emerson's poet sees order in transience, a pattern of change. And his Sphinx identifies herself with the phenomena that most obviously represent this redemptive process (that is to say, the redemptiveness implicit in the very concept of process): cloud, moon, flame, blossoms, wave. 59 Finally and paradoxically, she who was once stone herself stands at the end of her cavortings on top of Mount Monadnock with no intention whatever of dashing herself to pieces in the valley below: "She stood Monadnock's head." The elision of the preposition emphasizes that this is the triumphant solution of both the Sphinx's riddle and the human dilemma. Verb modulates directly into noun; poet-Sphinx becomes mountain; man and nature, subject and object, become one. 60 The name itself, that of an actual New Hampshire mountain, is perhaps significant. In "History" Emerson adopts Leibniz's vocabulary to monitor "the monad through all his masks as he performs the metempsychosis of nature," and here we are able to penetrate through the series of masks to that ultimate monad. 6 ' Emerson has achieved, within the lines of a poem, his synthesis of crystal and fluid, pattern and process. At this point nature chimes in again to confirm this reading. The truth, after all, is everywhere; diversity is possible because of the inward connection of things, and successive answers are not lies after all but versions of the truth: "'Who telleth one of my meanings I Is master of all I am.'" The recognition of one meaning represents the revelatory experience of that transcendentalist method described by Santayana, 59· Something of the same effect is achieved in this rapt sentence from Dwight's Association in Its Connection with Education and Religion, in which he evokes the universal harmony: "Like the lines and curves of a landscape; like the whole perspective of the sky and clouds; like the graceful symmetry of the human form; like the musical fugue and its types in running waves of water, and in uproaring, flickering tongues of flame ... " ( 17). 6o. Ivy Schweitzer has said of Nature that Emerson converts nature into spirit partly by stylistic means, "the effect of turning nouns, the signifiers of rooted and bounded phenomena, into verbs, which perform the action they signifY." See Ivy Schweitzer, "Transcendental Sacramentals: 'The Lord's Supper' and Emerson's Doctrine of Form," New England Qyarterly 61, no. 3 (September 1988): 415. What I have traced here is the opposite process, but since my point is that for the Transcendentalists spirit and nature are simply different manifestations of the same law, priority hardly matters. 61. Ralph Waldo Emerson, "History," in &says r, 10.
Nature versus History
25
the insight of Levi-Strauss's engineer. The consequent mastery of the totality establishes faith in a preexisting mythic architecture, the treasury of the bricoleur. The issues raised by the poem can be crudely summarized: nature is the manifestation of the law of the universe, whereas the human world is temporal-that is, historical-and therefore in a state of flux. But, as a result of this division, mankind is able to see a deeper, dynamic pattern in the universe. The very act of perception transforms crystal into fluid, providing the "central spontaneity" and individual presence that Swedenborg's static system lacked. The poem builds a bridge over the structural divide-between a revolutionary capacity to see the world afresh and a conservative need to believe in ongoing systems or mythswhich Santayana identifies at the heart of the transcendentalist worldpicture, and establishes man as a composite being, that "empirico-transcendental doublet" described by Michel Foucault. 62 Emerson's poem manages to grasp the "flying Perfect." This is, in its way, a remarkable solution to the problem, but one that convinces only on an aesthetic level. When Emerson tackles the conflict between nature and history from the other point of view, highlighting the question of history itself, it proves far more intractable. His essay "History" was written at roughly the same time as the poem, and it too received pride of place in the collection in which it was featured, the Essays: First Series. But, perhaps appropriately, it bears the marks of Emerson's struggle with the structural dilemma he faced, leaving the issue unresolved. Emerson begins by asserting the solidarity of the human race"There is one mind common to all individual men"-and therefore the principle of historical continuity: "All the facts of history preexist in the mind as laws." Thus, "Belzoni digs and measures in the mummypits and pyramids of Thebes, until he can see the end of the difference between the monstrous work and himself. "63 The example is a revealing one. For one thing, it is drawn from the realm of culture rather than from political, military, or social history. Indeed, the whole essay testifies to the editing out of history's less palatable facts. Moreover, there is an evident preoccupation with artifacts that embody the intention of 62. Michel Foucault, The Order of Things (London: Tavistock, 1970), 318. 63. Emerson, "History," 3, 7· Jonathan Bishop provides an interesting analysis of the basis of Emerson's argument here in Emerson on the Soul (Cambridge: HaiVard University Press, 1964), 59-66. He also offers a trenchant dismissal of some of its ramifications: 'Thus when he says, 'All that Shakespeare says of the king, yonder slip of a boy that reads in the corner feels to be true of himself,' we are free to say, no" (63).
Transcendental Utopias
achieving the closest approximation to permanence. The Egyptian "mummy-pits" and pyramids, however alien and "monstrous" they might seem, were designed by their makers specifically to enact the principle of continuity through time. In another mood Emerson would find such structures wanting in "central spontaneity"; all that he can pit against decline and decay are examples of what he could equally well excoriate as embodiments of inertia and fossilization. The Tartar tent has solidified into the Chinese pagoda, the primeval mound dwelling into the Egyptian temple, the forest into a cathedral, the flower into stone. 64 Petrification offers itself as one possible source of historical continuity and patterning; another, more suitable for the accommodation of "winged facts," involves a kind of organic analogy, the postulation of a racial equivalent of biological growth. Thus, Xenophon's troops are "a gang of great boys with such a code of honour and such lax discipline as great boys have."65 The biological rule that ontogeny recapitulates phylogeny-that the life of the individual reenacts that of the species or race-is effectively put into reverse, so that phylogeny proves to be merely an enormous extrapolation of ontogeny. This idea can be tracked back at least to Adam Ferguson, one of the Scottish moral philosophers, who claimed in his Essay on the History of Civil Society ( 1767) that "not only the individual advances from infancy to manhood, but the species itself from rudeness to civilization."66 In short, as Emerson tells us, "the student interprets the age of chivalry by his own age of chivalry, and the days of maritime adventure and circumnavigation by quite parallel miniature experiences of his own. ""7 The inadequacy of this model of historical development hardly needs comment; nor does it support Emerson's attempt at optimism through much of the essay, since it must predict decline and disintegration as surely as it does progress and maturity. As he approaches the end, he forces his rhetoric into a millennia} crescendo, endeavoring to delineate the spirit of time itself, a being with the power to bring the historical process to a utopian conclusion: "I shall find in him the Foreworld; in his childhood the Age of Gold; the Apples of Knowledge; the Argonautic Expedition; the calling of Abraham; the building of the 64. Emerson, "History," 11-12. 6 5 . Ibid., 1 5 . 66. Adam Ferguson, Essay on the History of Civil Society (Edinburgh, 1767), 2, quoted in Ernest Lee Tuveson, Millennium and Utapia: A Study in the Background of the Idea of Progress (Gloucester, Mass.: Peter Smith, 1972), 195· 67. Emerson, "History," 15.
Nature versus History
Temple; the Advent of Christ; Dark Ages; the Revival of Letters; the Reformation; the discovery of new lands, the opening of new sciences, and new regions in man. He shall be the priest of Pan, and bring with him into humble cottages the blessing of the morning stars and all the recorded benefits of heaven and earth." Then his confidence abruptly evaporates: "Is there somewhat overweening in this claim? Then I reject all I have written, for what is the use of pretending to know what we know not? But it is the fault of our rhetoric that we cannot strongly state one fact without seeming to belie some other." He has already informed us that, although man "is the com pend of time[,] he is also the correlative of nature."68 The uneasy synthesis he has tried to establish between the dynamic world of history and the patterned one of nature, expressed in terms of the biological curve, here collapses, separating out into its individual components. The failure is hardly surprising. Ernest Lee Tuveson, in his seminal work Millennium and Utopia, claims that one of the great projects in the intellectual history of modern times has been to transfer the operations of Providence to nature. He tracks the process back to Thomas Barnett's History of the Earth ( 1684-go), and claims that it reaches its completion with nineteenth-century positivism. The distinction is between the chaotic and contingent operations of human history on the one hand, and on the other the coherent sequence of cause and effect which was determined and set in motion by God at the outset of creation. 59 The culmination of the process eliminated "Providence as a factor openly operating historically, although it was present in its disguised form, being called 'natural law.'" What Emerson is trying to unite, a century and a half of historical thought had been busily engaged in putting asunder. 70 In the end, at least in this essay, he has to admit defeat: "Hear the rats in the wall, see the lizard on the fence, the 68. Ibid., 22, 20. 69. The Transcendentalists' Puritan forefathers had an easier task because their notion of election, as Sacvan Bercovitch has pointed out in The Puritan Origins of the American Self (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1975), permitted a distinction between "soteriology and secular history, where secular history designates the providential view . . . and soteriology the mode of identifying the individual, the community, or the event in question within the scheme of salvation." In short, Providence did not have to provide utopia for all but simply had to establish the salvation of the saved, and this could be achieved "however dismal the repetitive course of human, subordinate affairs, no matter how ominous the signs of secular time" (43). 70. Tuveson, Millennium and Utopia, 119. Of course, this tendency did not stop with Emerson. G. S. Kirk points out, in The Nature of Greek Myths (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1974), that early twentieth-century psychologists, including even Freud, were guilty of falling into this "absurd kind of genetic fallacy" (73).
Transcendental Utopias
fungus under foot, the lichen on the log. What do I know sympathetically, morally, of either of these worlds of life?" Our "so-called history" is a "village-tale," reflecting our provincialism of spirit. "What does Rome know of rat and lizard?" In "The Divinity School Address" he had made an equation between the law of gravitation and the human heart which particularly aroused the ire of Andrews Norton. 71 Now he has to concede that there is a dichotomy between the natural order and human behavior. 72 The former is characterized by consistency and stability, whatever intimations Emerson may feel of the evolutionary breakthrough to come. Meanwhile, the historical domain where we humans live our lives is obstinately resistant to pattern, since it represents nothing more than an accumulation of contingencies. This state of affairs is clearly an unsatisfactory one, as the staccato shifts and changes of the concluding paragraphs of "History" testify. The one thing a philosophy of consistency cannot brook is (of course) inconsistency. If the law of series is any sort of law at all, it must be in some way discernible in the field of human behavior. And yet we are left with a curious discontinuity between the inward, spiritual dimension of humankind and the external evidence of our transitoriness and mutability. One way of solving this problem would be to establish a theory of social amelioration whereby the pattern apparently visible in the static world of nature could be shown to be slowly disclosing itself in the world of human affairs. This approach would have the added advantage of exemplifying the notion of a pattern on the move that seems such an integral part of the Transcendentalist apprehension of serial law. In "On the Progress of Civilization," published in the Boston Quarterly Review for October 1838, George Bancroft, who hovered on the fringes of the Transcendentalist movement for a time, asserts such a solution, though he fails to support his claim with anything like evidence: "The world cannot retrograde; the dark ages cannot return. 71. Emerson, "History," 22; idem, 'The Divinity School Address," 93; Andrews Norton, "The New School in Literature and Religion," Boston Daily Advertiser, August 27, 1838, 43, quoted in Miller, The Transcendentalists, 196. 72. Many years later Emerson playfully slides over this dichotomy in "Historic Notes of Life and Letters in New England": 'The German poet Goethe ... proposed . . . in Botany, his simple theory of metamorphosis;-the eye of a leaf is all. ... The revolt became a revolution. Schelling and Oken introduced their ideal natural philosophy, Hegel his metaphysics, and extended it to Civil History. The result in literature and the general mind was a return to law; in science, in politics, in social life; as distinguished from the profligate manners and politics of earlier times. The age was moral. Every immorality is a departure from nature, and is punished by natural loss and deformity." Ralph Waldo Emerson, Lectures and Biographical Sketches, in Works, 10:338.
Nature versus History
29
Dynasties perish; cities are buried; nations have been victims to error, or martyrs for right; Humanity has always been on the advance; its soul has always been gaining maturity and power." 73 Much more convincingly, in a review on the subject of social progress published in the Christian Examiner several years before Bancroft's piece (March 1834), Frederic Henry Hedge provides an analysis of the historical process that anticipates the solution subsequently adopted in the utopian ideologies of the Transcendentalists. Hedge concedes that on the face of it there is no evidence of consistent progressive development, that indeed "alternate civilization and barbarism make up the apparent history of man." But he goes on to say that although specific peoples and civilizations may founder, society as a whole has never actually gone backwards, though its forward motion may become imperceptible-or actually come to a halt-from time to time. The conception he puts forward is one of intermittent evolutionary development. He makes an analogy between intellectual progress and the action of the heart: 'The human mind, the source of this progress, has acted like the animal heart, not by a constant effort, but by successive pulsations, which pulsations, however, unlike those of the animal heart, must be reckoned, not by seconds, but by ages." 74 This notion of "successive pulsations" provides us with a way of perceiving a regular-and moving-pattern in history. Moreover, a parallel with nature gives the theory its bona fides. Intriguingly, this explanation of social evolution parallels the theory of biological evolution known as "punctuated equilibria" offered by the American paleontologists Niles Eldredge and Stephen Jay Gould in 1972.just like historians, paleontologists have to cope with a record of jerky and incoherent development. Eldredge and Gould make the point that the problem has dogged evolutionism since it was formulated: Charles Darwin decided that the absence of the "'infinitely numerous transitional links' that would illustrate the slow and steady operation of natural selection" must be explained by the imperfection of the fossil record. Gould and Eldredge's theory constitutes an alternative explanation, the argument that "many breaks in the fossil record are real; they express the way evolution occurs, not the fragments of an 73· George Bancroft, "On the Progress of Civilization, or Reasons Why the Natural Association of Men of Letters Is with the Democracy," Boston @arterly Review 1 (October 1838): 406-7, excerpted in Miller, The Transcendentalists, 429. 74· Frederic Henry Hedge, review of "An Address delivered before the Phi Beta Kappa Society in Yale College, New Haven, August 20, 1833. by Edward Everett," Christian Examiner 16, n.s. 11 (March 1834): g-10.
Transcendental Utopias
imperfect record." Richard Dawkins, in his book on contemporary Darwinism, The Blind Watchmaker, summarizes their position: "Maybe ... evolution really did in some sense go in sudden bursts, punctuating long periods of 'stasis,' when no evolutionary change took place in a given lineage. "75 Hedge elaborates his own theory of punctuated equilibria by explaining that the "pulsations" or "impulses" of the human mind are able to advance the state of society as a whole by a process akin to the effect of yeast on dough: "Each pulsation has sent forth into the world some new sentiment or principle, some discovery or invention, which, like small portions of leaven, have successfully communicated their quickening energy to the whole mass of society. "75 What we have here is a pattern on the move, or to put it another way, the reconciliation of process (or history) with pattern (or nature). The way is open for the transformation of society. When Emerson attacks reformers, he accuses them of being unable to offer, despite all their agitation and energy, any leverage whereby this process of transformation can take place. However many converts they can attract to their cause, they are still trapped in the historical world. They are incapable of creativity. Indeed, they pit themselves against the creative processes of nature. When he gives a list of reforming fads in his lecture "New England Reformers," he significantly picks on the disapproval of the process of fermentation expressed by certain radicals: "It was in vain urged by the housewife that God made yeast, as well as dough, and loves fermentation just as dearly as he loves vegetation; that fermentation develops the saccharine element in the grain, and makes it more palatable and more digestible." In taking up the cause of history, such reformers have actually alienated themselves from the creative cycles of nature. Instead they have put their faith in the mechanism of consensual change, not understanding that "all the men in the world cannot make a statue walk and speak, cannot make a drop of blood, or a blade of grass, any more than one man can."77 It is easy to misunderstand this argument. Emerson's point is that force of numbers, the inevitable goal of reformist agitation, is quite 75· Niles Eldredge and Stephen Jay Gould, "Punctuated Equilibria: An Alternative to Phyletic Gradualism," in Models in Paleomology, ed. Thomas]. M. Schopf (San Francisco: Freeman Cooper, 1972), 87, 96; Richard Dawkins, The Blind Watchmaker (London: Longman, 1986), 229. It should be pointed out that Dawkins by no means endorses the theory of Eldredge and Gould. 76. Hedge, review, 10. 77· Ralph Waldo Emerson, "New England Reformers," in &says 2, 150, 157.
Nature versus History
unnecessary: one is enough. Life, he tells us in "Fourierism and the Socialists," "scorns systems and system makers" and, eluding all conditions, "makes or supplants a thousand phalanxes and New-Harmonies with each pulsation .... The mistake is, that this particular order and series is to be imposed by force of preaching and votes on all men, and carried into rigid execution." 78 In "New England Reformers" he goes on to say: "But let there be one man, let there be truth in two men, in ten men, then is concert for the first time possible; because the force that moves the world is a new quality, and can never be furnished by adding whatever quantities of a different kind . . . . It is and will be magic." 79 It is interesting to see how Emerson's expression, perhaps unconsciously, mimics the process that is being described. The first half of the sentence that begins "But let there be ... " captures the development of the pulsation in its series of repetitive but progressive clauses and phrases; the second half, with its large and calm assertion, demonstrates the universal reach that the new force will have. Moreover, in true punctuationist fashion, the origin of the pulsation fails to leave a clear semantic track. One man will not start the process off simply by dint of being one man. "Truth" is the object of the verbal phrase "let there be," but that is not clear until we reach the second clause, with its retrospective apposition that sends the noun back. The truth is not visible until it begins to move. What we have is not an inert structure"a gigantic crystal, all whose atoms and laminae lie in uninterrupted order and with unbroken unity, but cold and still"-but a pattern on the move, like Thoreau's thawing sand bank. "It is and will be magic." One thinks of the contempt for the word miracle that Emerson displays in his "Divinity School Address." Magic in this sense will be "one with the blowing clover and the falling rain," with nature transformed into process, with history revealed as pattern, with the law of series disclosing itself through time. The fluid world of consciousness, and the crystalline structure of the universe it inhabits, will have been reconciled. In his essay "Resistance to Civil Government" Thoreau reverses Emerson's head count in order to make the same point: "I know this well, that if one thousand, if one hundred, if ten men whom I could name,-if ten honest men only,-aye, if one HONEST man, in this State of Massachusetts, ceasing to hold slaves, were actively to withdraw from this copartnership, and be locked up in the county jail therefor, it 78. Ralph Waldo Emerson, "Fourierism and the Socialists," Dia/3 (July 1842): 88-8g. 79· Emerson, "New England Reformers," 157.
32
Transcendental Utopias
would be the abolition of slavery in America. For it matters not how small the beginning may seem to be: what is once well done is done for ever." Outside the punctuationist context this might pass as an example of rhetorical hyperbole; within it we have the blueprint of a pulsation. Elsewhere in the essay Thoreau uses the image of yeast-twenty years after Hedge's use of it in his review-to indicate the rapidity and completeness of potential transformation: "It is not so important that many should be as good as you, as that there be some absolute goodness somewhere; for that will leaven the whole lump. "80 One thinks of the distinction between Transcendentalist law and Unitarian legalism. In claiming that the spiritual emancipation and subsequent imprisonment of "one HONEST man" will transform American society at large, Thoreau is making a related assertion of the authority of law (in the absolute sense) over legalities. "All health and success does me good, however far off and withdrawn it may appear," he tells us in Walden, and goes on to suggest that "if ... we would indeed restore mankind by truly Indian, botanic, magnetic, or natural means, let us first be as simple and well as Nature ourselves."81 Hedge was confident that there was nothing irregular or arbitrary about the occurrence of "pulsations." He was not, however, able to make out the details of the pattern himself. Instead, like a historiographical John the Baptist, he modestly awaited the coming of a "philosophic historian" who would be able to "trace and exhibit these successive impulses. He who can do this, and he only will be able to furnish a systematic history of Man; something very different from, and infinitely more important than the histories we now have of dynasties and tribes. "82 For the Brook Farmers just such a "philosophic historian" came along in the person of the French utopian thinker Charles Fourier. A "systematic history of Man" was provided with great precision in his "Table of the Movement of Civilization, with its Four Ages or Phases," which showed how civilization reflected the fundamental law of nature, that of "groups and series." The Fruitlanders, meanwhile, found a similar savant in Bronson Alcott's English colleague Charles Lane, who carried in his baggage a precise and comprehensive punctuationist schema which had been devised by his recently deceased colleague James PierreSo. Henry David Thoreau, "Resistance to Civil Government," in Refrmn Papers, Writings,
75· 6g.
81. Thoreau, Walden, 78. 82. Hedge, review, 10.
Nature versus History
33
point Greaves. The "Circumstantial Law," as it was called, could be shown to manifest itself progressively in the "three dispensations" of human history. Both Fourier and Lane were able to demonstrate, as we shall see, that although history was not an obvious sequence of cause and effect, it was nevertheless systematic and progressive. They both showed how fresh "pulsations" occurred just as a particular dispensation was petering out. They asserted that it was precisely when civilization was looking tired and purposeless that a new social order could come into being, like the phoenix-or indeed like America itself. In this way they were able to reconcile historical contingency with universal seriality. It is surely no coincidence that both these utopian blueprints originated on the other side of the Atlantic Ocean. Thus, George Ripley and the Brook Farmers, on the one hand, and Bronson Alcott, on the other, were able to have a spontaneous revelatory experience of a preexisting structure. Both the necessary elements in the "empirico-transcendental doublet" thereby come into play. The immediate and dynamic can be seen to merge with the universal and patterned. What becomes available in each case is not merely a theory of pulsations but the actual experience of one: a sudden apprehension of an overarching pattern. The invisible eye of the natural scientist (or poet) encounters the treasury of the mythmaker. The Americans opened their eyes with that "fresh sincerity" described by Santayana, and what they saw was a great edifice created by European romanticism. Of course, the differences in the utopian ideologies developed by the Transcendentalists are as important as the similarities, and the most significant one is of scale. In "History" Emerson tells us that the universe is "represented in an atom." For the Brook Farmers and the Fruitlanders one might argue, though in terminology they would not have been able to understand, that the fundamental unit of serial law was a molecule, a cluster of individuals interlinked in a common cause and able to transmit its composite virtue to the social fabric as a whole. For the Brook Farmers the magic unit consisted of sixteen hundred and eighty persons (as Emerson sarcastically pointed out) .83 For the Fruitlanders it was the family, though as we shall see they had some difficulty defining what a family actually was. In my next five chapters I discuss the ways in which the ideologies of these two utopian experiments provided practical and social manifesta83. Ralph Waldo Emerson, "Historic Notes of Life and Letters in New England," in Lectures and Biographical Sketches, 10:350.
34
Transcendental Utopias
tions of the law of series. I then turn my attention from these molecular versions of the law to an atomic one and consider Thoreau's "community of one." Like his friend Emerson, Thoreau had moments when he could envisage a crossover between the harmonious world of nature and the dynamic one of history, but he never succeeded in proposing a structure that would make the bridge permanent. Indeed, like the Emerson of "The Sphinx," he found art to be the most satisfactory way of reconciling the daily contingencies of life with the absolute imperatives of natural law. In a sense he can be seen to have erected two huts, one by Walden Pond, the other in the book called Walden. My overall intention is to establish the depth and intensity of social concern felt by members of the Transcendentalist movement, and to shed light on the belief that underlies and unifies its apparent eclecticism, contradictoriness, and obscurity: the doctrine of repetitive order, of the total consistency of consistency, of the universal sway of the law of series. Obviously there are profound differences between the enterprises and achievements (not to mention the failures) under discussion; but there is nevertheless common ground underlying those differences, an invisible unifying landscape that lies buried beneath the patchwork and multiform surface, like the charming one Emerson describes near the beginning of Nature, which transcends the twenty or thirty farms that are positioned on it."4 All these thinkers shared the belief that we have to address ourselves to and perfect the microcosm, though they disagreed about what that might be; and that when we have done so, a new social order will crystallize around it. This doctrine is the product of a synthesis between the conflicting forces Santayana discerned within the movement as a whole. As I track Transcendentalist communitarian and millennial thought from the large-scale enterprise at Brook Farm to the more modest community at Fruitlands, and from there to the individual utopia of Thoreau's hut, it might not be too fanciful to suggest that these different manifestations of the law of series fit together in a serial order of their own. 84. Emerson, Nature, g.
2 Brook Farm and Masquerade
T
he Brook Farm community materialized on the scene so rapidly that it appears to have something of that "frolic architecture" celebrated by Emerson in his poem "The Snow-Storm," product of a "mad wind's night-work," though in this case the contributory weather was considerably better. In the summer of 1840 George Ripley, Unitarian minister of a church in Purchase Street, Boston, and leading participant in the Transcendentalist movement, and his wife, Sophia, went on a well-earned holiday. They found a "sweet spot" for a "tranquil retreat": a place called Brook Farm in what was then the village of West Roxbury. It had not only its inevitable brook but also woods, fields, birds aplenty, and great seclusion-though their friend Theodore Parker had the nearby ministry at West Roxbury, and other Transcendentalist colleagues such as Margaret Fuller, the "brilliant sibyl of the plains," were not far off. Still, time could be spent away from the hectic cut and thrust of Boston life, allowing Mrs. Ripley to doze under the nut trees and her husband to read Burns and whistle to the birds, who obligingly whistled back. 1 By the following spring the most famous communitarian experiment in American history had been established on the same spot. There can be nothing more authentically Transcendentalist than a historical institution that appears on the scene with an air of having been produced suddenly out of a hat. Like the evolutionary transfor1. Sophia Ripley to John S. Dwight, August 1, 1841, quoted in Zoltan Haraszti, The Idyll of Brook Farm (Boston: Boston Public Library, 1937), 12-13. The original is Boston Public Library MS E.4.1 no. 26.
35
Transcendental Utapias
mations proposed by the punctuationists mentioned in the last chapter, the Brook Farm association came into existence so rapidly that it seems barely to have had time to leave behind a trace of its origins. Hedge emphasizes the speed of transformation when he describes historical pulsations in his Christian Examiner review, giving the example of the Reformation: "We need only to remind our readers, how suddenly, how almost immediately after the Reformation, society advanced to a state of civilization unknown in any former age."2 On its own small scale Brook Farm also makes its appearance suddenly, thereby approaching the revelatory immediacy so beloved of those calm revolutionaries who, according to Santayana, opened their eyes "upon the world every morning with a fresh sincerity." It would not be fanciful to propose that during those idyllic summer weeks of 1840 Ripley did experience some sort of mystical connection between himself as an individual and the universe as a whole, a linkage between his dynamic consciousness and natural harmony. His wife, after all, describes such reciprocity in her account of his whistling and the birds whistling back. It is as a result of such a crossover between inner and outer environments that serial connections can be established. This is not a flippant suggestion, however far-fetched it may seem under skeptical scrutiny. In any case, skepticism is inappropriate, since what matters is not what we think is possible but what the Transcendentalists themselves believed could-or did-happen. But their perspective tended to supplement the moment of insight or revelation, the fresh new concept that is the reward for open-minded inquiry, with consciousness of a larger historical" context. Exhilaration and spontaneity were all very well, but there was also a need to confront historical imperatives-in Levi-Strauss's words, to reorganize the cultural treasury. To return to Emerson's "Snow-Storm," the "north wind's masonry" is to be mimicked by painstaking human endeavor, "in slow structures, stone by stone, I Built in an age. "3 As a central-indeed as, in some ways, the definitive-Transcendentalist institution, Brook Farm should be a manifestation not merely of frolic architecture but also of slow structuring. Ripley himself was aware that the enterprise might seem precipitate and self-indulgent, as we can see from a long letter to Emerson of November g, 1840. Emerson was, naturally enough, the big fish he wanted to catch for his proposed community. "Your decision," he tells 2. Frederic Henry Hedge, review of "An Address delivered before the Phi Beta Kappa Society ... ," Christian Examiner I6, n.s. II (March I834): I4. 3· Ralph Waldo Emerson, "The Snow-Storm," in Poems, Works, g:42.
Brook Farm and Masquerade
37
him, "will do much towards settling the question with me, whether the time has come for the fulfillment of a high hope." If Ripley wanted to take the easy option, he says, he could rent Brook Farm for himself "at a rate, that with my other resources, would place me in a very agreeable condition, as far as my personal interests were involved. I should have a city of God, on a small scale of my own." But this kind of immediate and selfish gratification is not on his agenda. Instead, he envisages steady and prudent endeavor toward institutional self-sufficiency, with three or four families moving in on April 1, 1841, and a similar number the following autumn. "It would thus be not less than two or three years, before we should be joined by all who mean to be with us; we should not fall to pieces by our own weight; we should grow up slowly and strong; and the attractiveness of our experiment would win to us all whose society we should want." Emerson replies that though "of all the ... philanthropic projects of which I have heard yours is the most pleasing to me," nevertheless it would suit neither him nor the community were he to join! Ripley's cautious-and disinterested-gradualism was not assumed just for Emerson's benefit. Brook Farm began on the small scale he envisaged. Mrs. Ripley wrote to John Dwight on May 6, 1841, that the "number assembled round the table in our large middle kitchen is thirteen," though she adds it will soon rise to sixteen.' These were accommodated in the main farm building, which became known as "the Hive." As the years passed, other buildings were added. A house across the narrow road leading to the farm, christened "the Nest" because of its diminutive size, was used as the school for some years, and also as guest accommodation. The Eyrie was built in 1842, a somewhat flimsy construction (apparently sound traveled right through it) on the higher of the farm's two low hills. The Ripleys themselves moved into it, along with many of the younger single members of the community, including the strange and reclusive Charles King Newcomb, who was much admired by Emerson. His one short story, "Dolon," vied with Bronson Alcott's "Orphic Sayings" as the most obscure contribution to be published by the Dial in its four-year history. 6 Two more buildings 4· George Ripley to Ralph Waldo Emerson, November 9, 1840, MS Houghton Library, bMS Am 1280 (2719); R. W. Emerson to George Ripley, December 15, 1840, in The Letters of Ralph Waldo Emerson, ed. Ralph L. Rusk, 6 vols. (New York: Columbia University Press, 1939), 2:371. 5· Reprinted in Haraszti, Idyll of Brook Farm, 18. For the original letter, see Boston Public Library MS E-4- 1 no. 34· 6. Charles King Newcomb, "Dolon," Dial3 (July 1842): 112-23; A. Bronson Alcott, "Orphic Sayings," Dial1 (July 1840): 85-98; Dia/1 (January 1841): 351-61.
Transcendental Utopias
were erected during the early period of the community's history, the Cottage, which was also used as a residence until the changeover to Fourierism, when the school moved into it; and the Pilgrim House, a more substantial dwelling built in uncompromising New England style, which provided both lodgings and useful community functions, including a big parlor for amusements, the laundry and tailoring facilities, and ultimately the editorial offices of the Harbinger, the Fourierist newspaper that was edited in the community during its last years. In 1844 work began on the most ambitious building of all, the Phalanstery, which was intended to provide the basis of the community after Brook Farm became a phalanx (I shall maintain the Brook Farmers' habit of using these terms to distinguish a Fourierist dwelling from a Fourierist community). Mter nearly two years of work, the Phalanstery burned to the ground in March 1846 before it could be put to use, a catastrophe that was an important factor in bringing about Brook Farm's demise the following year. There was at times pressure on accommodation (particularly because of the large numbers of curious visitors the community attracted), though this problem would have been eased without the bad luck of the fire. 7 Numbers rose rapidly during the second year, and by 1844, the midpoint of the community's trajectory, the account book was recording the work efforts of well over one hundred members (adults and older children). 8 The poor soil of the farm, and difficulties with the other "industries" caused by lack of appropriate skills, shortage of time and facilities for the proper seasoning of wood, and inadequate access to sales outlets in Boston and elsewhere, caused the community some headaches, though the school was a success story, and the production and distribution of the Harbinger in the final years of the farm was a remarkable achievement by any standard. The point that must be emphasized from the outset is that the farm was a well-grounded institution which lasted nearly six years, a respectable time for a utopian community. It was thoughtfully organized, even if it seemed to come out of nothing. Nevertheless, partly because its founding followed so swiftly on the 7· See Lindsay Swift, Brook Farm: Its Members, Scholars, and Visitors (New York: Macmillan, 1900), 27-40. 8. See the Brook Farm Account Book for May 1844-April 1845 in the Houghton Library, fMS Am 931. Rebecca Codman Butterfield's MS account of Brook Farm, in the possession of the Massachusetts Historical Society, tells us that at the time she joined the community in 1843, there were about a hundred members (10). This document has been edited by Joel Myerson as "Rebecca Codman Butterfield's Reminiscences of Brook Farm," New England QJ.tarterly 65 (December 1992): 603-30; see esp. 61 1.
Brook Farm and Masquerade
39
heels of Ripley's summer holiday, it is frequently seen as a mere idyll, a "perpetual picnic," to use Emerson's phrase. 9 Part of the problem is quite simply that we lack adequate accounts of the thinking that led up to the establishment of the community and then propelled it along its course. This difficulty might seem an ironic one given the garrulity of the Transcendentalists in general. Whereas Coleridge spent years talking about the pantisocracy that never materialized, and Charles Fourier himself wrote at almost terrifying length about the associations to come but never did anything practical to bring them about, George Ripley seems to have grounded his institution on a minimal verbal foundation. There is no personalist fallacy involved in giving Ripley that possessive pronoun. Brook Farm was very much-and the loading of this metaphor seems appropriate-his baby. It was his conception to start with, and although in the course of time he surrounded himself with varied and energetic talents, the testimony of his leadership, from those who lived in the community or visited it, is unequivocal. He was the father figure, the Archonite Illustrissimo. 10 If, as Emerson claimed in "Self-Reliance," an institution is the long shadow of a man, then Brook Farm evolved in the shadow of this one. 11 As Emerson himself put it, following a visit to the farm in May 1843, "G[eorge]. & S[ophia]. R[ipley]. are the only ones who have identified themselves with the community. They have married it & they are it. The others are experimenters who will stay by this if it thrives, being always ready to retire, but these have burned their ships, and are entitled to the moral consideration which this position gives. "12 Indeed, one could almost go a step further and claim that Ripley was not merely the embodiment of the Brook Farm community but the essential figure in the history of American Transcendentalism as a whole. The movement could boast two geniuses in Emerson and Thoreau, a charismatic presence in Bronson Alcott, a quixotic gadfly in Orestes Brownson, and a thunderous social conscience in Theodore Parker. But the person who, more than anybody else, gave it coherence and 9· Ralph Waldo Emerson, "Historic Notes of Life and Letters in New England," in Works,
10:3641 o. See John Thomas Codman, Brook Farm: Historic and Personal Memoirs (Boston: Arena, 1894). 77-78, 110. 1 1. Ralph Waldo Emerson, "Self-Reliance," in Essays I, 35· 12. Ralph Waldo Emerson, entry for May 7, 1843, in journals and Miscellaneous Notebooks of Ralph Waldo Emerson, ed. William H. Gilman et al., 16 vols. (Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1960-82), 8:393· All subsequent references to this edition will be to JMN.
Transcendental Utopias
provided it with a succession of institutional manifestations was George Ripley. He was in the thick of the fray during the first, doctrinal phase, when he locked horns with Andrews Norton in the pages of periodicals such as the Christian Examiner and (less obviously) the Boston Daily Advertiser. Next he became one of the leading members of the Transcendental Club as the movement moved on to a phase of philosophical debate. The following stage involved the establishment of a larger public arena and a more literary identity, both of which were achieved through the journal the Dial, of which he was a cofounder, and which he put on a businesslike footing. Finally, the Transcendentalists developed a reforming and utopian commitment that received its biggest and most significant manifestation in what was called, at least during its early days, Ripley's Farm. 13 These developments, which took place during the 183os and 184os, seem to follow-at least with the benefit of hindsight-an inevitable progression. The miracles debate, as we saw in the first chapter, was characterized on the Transcendentalists' part by a search for a coherent and structured vision of the world and of the individual's place in it. This search inevitably expanded from theological to philosophical issues, and since, as an accidental by-product, the debate weakened the authority of the Unitarian Church, an appropriately informal alternative was found within the domestic setting of Transcendental Club members' own houses and apartments, and in the increasing camaraderie of the individuals involved. 14 Inevitably, though, there was a danger that the club could become cliquey and narrow, and the need for a journal became apparent. It is a sequence like that envisaged in Emerson's essay on circles, with ever-larger areas being enclosed at each successive stage, a utopian community being the next one. Ripley, troubled by the social deprivation that was becoming increasingly apparent in the neighborhood of Boston where he had his ministry, finally resigned his pulpit and established his community. The final, all-embracing stage was to come, as we shall see, with the establishment of the Harbinger and the national reforming movement. Despite Ripley's centrality he remains in some respects a tantalizing and shadowy presence. Obviously he left a substantial record of his position at the earliest stages of the Transcendentalist movement, but for various reasons the written remains tail off. All evidence of the 13. See Henry W. Sams, ed., Automog;raphy of Brook Farm (Englewood Cliffs, NJ.: PrenticeHall, 1958), 1. This anthology is presented as a student reference book, but in fact provides a handy source of primary material for all scholars of the community. 14· See Charles Crowe, George Ripley: Transcendentalist and Utopian Socialist (Athens: University of Georgia Press, 1967). 81-85.
Brook Fann and Masquerade
club's discussions is secondhand and anecdotal. Ripley abandoned his editorship of the Dial as soon as it was viable, and people complained from the time of Brook Farm's founding, and for many years after it folded, about Ripley's reticence on the subject of the community. But in some ways this relative invisibility is itself evidence of his Transcendentalist bona fides, and indeed of the power of that very thought which is not receiving its full articulation. It does not need to. The deed, so to speak, is the word. If the individual's interior world is serially connected with the macrocosm, his or her thought, despite that "almostness" which can account for human restlessness, has the capacity for operating directly on the external world and thereby transforming it. A proactive ideology does not need to leave an elaborate written account of itself. Elizabeth Palmer Peabody, as it happens, disagrees. In a letter to John Sullivan Dwight (who had not yet become a member) written a couple of months after the Brook Farm community was inaugurated, she remarks somewhat cumbersomely of Ripley that "he enjoys the 'work' so much that he does not clearly see that his plan is not in the way of being demonstrated any further than that it is being made evident."15 In fact, in talking about evidence she actually concedes the very point that she is complaining of, thus making one suspect that she is probably trying to grapple with arguments offered by Ripley himself. She was, after all, not merely a close friend of the Ripleys but also the sister of Nathaniel Hawthorne's betrothed, Sophia Peabody, so she must have been very much in touch with the thinking behind the community. Evidence is the whole point. One recalls how, during the miracles controversy, Theodore Parker (writing as Levi Blodgett) dismissed Norton's reliance "on evidence too weak to be trusted in a trifling case that comes before a common court of law," and Ripley's own requirement of an "unerring test, by which to distinguish a miracle of religion from a new manifestation of natural powers." Peabody wants some sort of public relations exercise, whereas Ripley believes that actions speak louder than words. What we find as we review this part of his career is a series of "pulsations," each one creating change, each one generated by the one before, each one with a larger scope and a sharper focus, and reflecting a greater ambition on Ripley's part to transform the process of history. It is testimony to the magical scope-and abruptness-of the pen15. Elizabeth Palmer Peabody to John Sullivan Dwight, June 24, 1841, reprinted in Haraszti, Idyll of Brook Farm, 18. The original is Boston Public Library MS E.4.1 no. 35· Peabody notes in an earlier letter to Dwight (April 26, 1841) that "Ripley still relucts [sic] from printing even a prospectus." Boston Public Library MS E.4.1 no. 33·
Transcendental Utopias
ultimate pulsation, the founding of the Brook Farm community, that not a single member of the Transcendental Club joined Ripley in his experiment. When Ripley broached the idea to the club in the autumn of 1840, Alcott-who was to embark on a utopian experiment of his own three years later-took the view that the project would be too worldly, while Margaret Fuller doubted Ripley's powers of leadership (wrongly, as events proved). Parker, Ripley's closest friend and ally, had a different problem. Ripley, it must be remembered, had decided to relinquish his ministry, partly because, like Emerson before him, he felt his own position to be too out of phase with Unitarian orthodoxy, and partly because he had come to believe that his church (and specifically his congregation) had insulated itself from social injustices that were becoming ever more apparent in the surrounding community. It is clear that for him Brook Farm would serve as an alternative, nondoctrinal, socially radical ministry. Parker shared Ripley's radical views on both religious and social matters but was determined to be an agent of change within the church (although he was nearly thrown out on one occasion). He therefore did not resign his ministry to take up residence at the farm, though he welcomed the proximity of his West Roxbury pulpit to the site of the community.' 6 In order to reconstruct the motives behind the founding of Brook Farm, it is worth giving further attention to the arguments used by Ripley in his attempt to persuade Emerson to become a member. His main point is that the community would provide the opportunity of solving the mind-body conflict. "Our objects, as you know," he reminds Emerson in his letter of November g, 1840, are to insure a more natural union between intellectual and manual labor than now exists; to combine the thinker and the worker, as far as possible, in the same individual; to guarantee the highest mental freedom, by providing all with labor, adapted to their tastes and talents, and securing to them the fruits of their industry; to do away with the necessity of menial services, by opening the benefits of education and the profits of labor to all; and thus to prepare a society of liberal, intelligent and cultivated persons, whose relations with each other would permit a more simple and wholesome life than can be led amidst the pressure of our competitive institutions. This sentence has the full rolling cadence of a considered m1sswn statement-not surprising if one accepts that the central doctrine of 16. See Crowe, Ripley, 138.
Brook Farm and Masquerade
43
Transcendentalism is the oneness of all phenomena, and that the harmony of the totality must be based on that of the individual. The argument, in the end, is between nature and history, with nature seen as the embodiment of the laws of the universe and history as the product of human consciousness. On the individual level that divide has to be healed by reconciling the physical side of our identity with the intellectual one. Ripley's point, of course, is that this reconciliation must also occur between social classes, since they have traditionally been separated on the basis of intellectual and manual roles. Interestingly, despite his overriding fear that to join Brook Farm would be to "hide my impotency in the thick of a crowd," Emerson feels it necessary to endorse the central objective of reconciling mental and physical work: "The principal particulars in which I wish to mend my domestic life are in acquiring habits of regular manual labor, and in ameliorating or abolishing in my house the condition of hired menial service. I should like to come one step nearer to nature than this usage permits." Emerson's step nearer nature was rapidly followed by a step back from it, as his household staff objected to being asked to sit at table with their employers.' 7 Ripley was perfectly well aware of, and at the same time exemplifies, the class tensions that could arise as a result of his proposals. In a postscript to his letter to Emerson of November g, he talks about the desirability of accepting some members "with whom our personal sympathy is not strong," such as a washerwoman who "is certainly not a Minerva or a Venus," along with certain farmers and mechanics. As it happened, the first small group of communitarians included a genuine farmer, William Allen; a homesteader from the West, Frank Farley; and a housemaid from Maine. At the other extreme was Warren Burton, a former Unitarian minister, who was to find it difficult to cope with the outdoor life. 18 Hawthorne was the most famous member of the community in its early days-or rather would become so-and he leaves behind a comic record of how a sedentary man coped with the new demands being made on him. In his letters to Sophia Peabody we can track his journey from innocence to experience. On April13, 1841, we find him a good-humored novice: "Mr. Ripley put a four-pronged instrument into my hands, which he gave me to understand was called a pitch-fork; and he and Mr. Farley being armed with similar weapons, we all three commenced a gallant attack upon a heap of manure." A 17. Emerson, entry for October 17, 1840, in JMN T408; Emerson, Letters 2:371; Ralph L. Rusk, The Life of Ralph Waldo Emerson (New York: Scribner's, 1949), 28g. 18. Crowe, Ripley, 144·
44
Transcendental Utopias
week later, on April 22, he claims that "my ability increases daily" and that he will soon become "a great, broad-shouldered, elephantine personage." Significantly, though, when he adds, "What an abominable hand do I scribble! but I have been chopping wood, and turning a grindstone all the forenoon; and such occupations are apt to disturb the equilibrium of the muscles and sinews," he gives a sure indication of problems to come, since he is already tending to put asunder what the Brook Farmers and the Transcendentalists in general fervently believed should be united. 19 As I have suggested, Ripley used words sparingly, in a way quite consistent with the Transcendentalist belief that a correctly arranged perspective could be carried over directly into a course of action that would magically transform the world. The one kind of discourse such an ideology can permit without embarrassment is contractual, a language directed explicitly at the task of turning intention into action. Perhaps, therefore, that public statement which Elizabeth Peabody was waiting so impatiently for Ripley to utter can in fact be seen to be manifested in a document committed to paper within a few months of the founding of Brook Farm: its Articles of Association, dated September 29, 1841. Here the community is given its title, one that establishes a clear relationship between the two halves of the human conundrum: 'The Brook Farm Institute of Agriculture and Education." The document goes on to list the subscribers to the first twenty-four $500 shares in the community, ten in all, though the Ripley family-George, Sophia, and George's sister Marianne-bought eight, a third of the total. Moreover, to minimize the danger of a capitalist hierarchy developing, the Articles of Association established that a year's labor, defined as three hundred days (of ten hours each during the summer months and eight hours during the winter), would not merely pay for a member's board but also qualifY him or her for a share in the annual dividend. The administrative structure of the community was divided into four directorates, General, Financial, Agricultural, and Educational, thus creating a structural symmetry between cash, labor, and intellectual development. 20 George Willis Cook quotes Charles Anderson Dana as saying of the Brook Farmers that "in order to reform society, in order to regenerate the world and to realize democracy in the social relations, they determined that their society should first pursue 19. Nathaniel Hawthorne, The Letters, r8IJ-I843· Centenary Edition, 15:528, 533· Octavius Brooks Frothingham, George Ripley (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1882), 112-17. The Articles of Association are in the Brook Farm records of the Massachusetts Historical Society. 20.
Brook Farm and Masquerade
45
agriculture, which would give every man plenty of outdoor labor in the free air, and at the same time the opportunity of study, of becoming familiar with everything in literature and learning. "21 The school, which, as Emerson predicted, almost immediately became the community's most important "industry" and its main bridge to society at large, was at the forefront of Brook Farm's effort to heal the mind-body divide, as the articles make clear. But the school did not merely act as one half of the dialogue between the mind and the body: that would be to distort the integrity of the serial structure. Each stage in the system had to contain within itself that interaction which the system as a whole was devised to achieve, just as, in Emerson's words, a drop of water must contain the properties of the sea. The school had a rigorous and intellectually ambitious syllabus, covering subjects such as intellectual and natural philosophy, mathematics, belles lettres, Latin, Greek, German, music, and history. But the combination of physical work and mental improvement was a fundamental policy: the curriculum included theoretical and practical agriculture, and children were required to spend up to two hours daily in manual labor. Even the pupils of the infant school, which was run by Marianne Ripley and Abigail Morton, did light field work. At the other end of the scale, the teachers had to divide their time too. We glimpse George P. Bradford leaving his hoe to go and teach, only to find that his pupil has forgotten about the lesson and is still out hunting. Charles Anderson Dana, who joined the farm in its early days after damage to his eyesight caused by an overindulgence in Dickens while a Harvard student (a perfect example of the dangers intrinsic in one-sided development), corrected the imbalance by combining teaching with organizing a corps of waiters. Ripley himself would switch from teaching philosophy to milking cows. 22 It is easy to mock these earnest New England intellectuals who insisted on getting their hands dirty; even members of the community occasionally felt that there was something incongruous about such behavior. Ora Gannet Sedgwick offers us an amusing glimpse of Charles Dana, in his menial role, "reading a small Greek book between courses," though she also states that his organization of the waiters 21. G. W. Cooke, "Brook Farm," New England Magazine, n.s. I7 (December I897): 395· 22. The Brook Farm material is rich in anecdotes of this kind. See Nathaniel Hawthorne, The American Notebooks, Centenary Edition, 8; Swift, Brook Farm; George P. Bradford, "Reminiscences of Brook Farm, by a Member of the Community," Century Magazine 45 (I892): I4I-48, esp. I44; Arthur Sumner, "A Boy's Recollections of Brook Farm," New England Magazine, n.s. I o (May I894): 3 I 1.
Transcendental Utopias
demonstrated that he ''was a very orderly young man." The waiters, she says, were chosen "from among our nicest young people," suggesting, depending on how one interprets "nicest," that there was a deliberate policy to select upper-crust members for this task. Just to even things up, the ''waiters in their turn were waited on by those whom they had served." 23 Arthur Sumner-like Sedgwick, reminiscing many years after the event-takes a considerably less sympathetic view, describing how "Mr. John Dwight used to come in from his toil in the hot sun at noon, to give me a lesson on the piano, and after faithfully doing that job, he would lie down on the lounge and go to sleep." Sumner's verdict: "What a piece of nonsense it was, to have a man like that hoeing corn and stiffening his eloquent fingers." Nevertheless, fair-mindedness compels him to restate the principles on which this organization of labor was based: "But the idea was (I think) that all kinds of labor must be made equally honorable, and that the poet, painter and philosopher must take their turn at the plough or in the ditch. "24 One must be careful not to devalue both the sincerity and the radicalism that underlay these principles. In August 1841 the publicity that Elizabeth Peabody advocated was in a measure supplied by an anonymous contributor to the Monthly Miscellany of Religion and Letters, who provides a detailed and enthusiastic account of the farm's intentions, in the course of which he or she spells out the egalitarianism evidenced by the community from its earliest days: "How dare I sacrifice not only my own, but others' health in sequestrating myself from my share of bodily labour, or neglecting a due mental cultivation?" There is, after all, a serial connection. If harmony is achieved on an individual level, it will radiate outward through the community-and vice versa. The implications for the ordering of society are far-reaching, even if not revolutionary in the more bloodthirsty sense of the term: "It seems to me that here we see brought about, in the most peaceable manner in the world, that very rectification of things which Mr. Brownson in his article on the Labouring Classes is understood to declare will require a bloody revolution, a war such as the world has not heard of; viz., that no child shall be born richer or poorer than another, except by inward gift of God, but all shall inherit from society a good education and an independent place. "25 In 1842 a "distinguished literary lady" penned a 23. Ora Gannet Sedgwick, "A Girl of Sixteen at Brook Farm," Atlantic Monthly 85 (March 1goo): 396. 24. Sumner, "A Boy's Recollections," 311. 25. "The Community at West Roxbury, Mass.," Monthly Miscellany of Religion and Letters 5
Brook Farm and Masquerade
47
report on the farm which, together with an introduction by that selfsame sanguinary individual Orestes Brownson, was published in the Democratic Review for November of that year. The Brook Farmers, she asserts, are not hastening, lemminglike, toward a lowest social common denominator; instead, "true democratic equality may be obtained by levelling up, instead of levelling down. "26 It is easy to detect the snobbishness and complacency implicit in such a formulation, and indeed we have already encountered a patronizing quality in Ripley's comments about the washerwoman who wished to join the community. A similar note is struck in an undated entry in Margaret Fuller's journal. Admittedly she was not a member of the community, but she was associated with it through her visits, her friendship with the Ripleys, and the attendance of her notorious younger brother Lloyd at the school. During one of her stays at the community she describes the following scene: "All Monday morning in the woods again. Afternoon, out with the drawing party; I felt the evils of want of conventional refinement, in the impudence with which one of the girls treated me. She has since thought of it with regret, I notice; and, by every day's observation of me, will see that she ought not to have done it." Fuller seems to have had a somewhat bruising time on this visit, which may account for her icy response to the "impudence" of the poor girl in the drawing party. On the previous Saturday she had conducted one of her public conversations, on the subject of education, but had not made a hit with her audience: 'The people showed a good deal of the sans-cuwtte tendency in their manners,-throwing themselves on the floor, yawning, and going out when they had heard enough."27 Ora Gannet Sedgwick, who was present during the first years as a boarder at the school, unconsciously reveals the patronization and tension that must have been widespread: besides those I have mentioned others joined us, with well-trained hands, but not of such good New England blood. I recall among them two Irishwomen, one of whom, a fine cook, had lived with the Danas and others of the best families of Boston. This woman came to Brook Farm for the sake of her beautiful young daughter, an only child, who (July 1841): 1 q, 1 16. The piece is introduced by the editor as "an extract from a letter written by a friend-not a member of the new community-to a lady in England." 26. "Brook Fann," Uni1£d States Magrai11£ arul Derrwcratic Review, n.s. 11 (November 1842): 491. 27. Quoted in Memoirs of Margaret Fuller Ossoli, 2 vols. ed. R. W. Emerson, W. H. Channing, and]. F. Clarke (London: Richard Bentley, 1852), 2:272, 270.
Transcendental Utopias
looked like a madonna and possessed much native delicacy. Her mother was desirous that she should be well-educated. These women were perfectly welcome to sit at the table with us all, but they preferred not to sit down until the two courses had been put upon the table, if at all!8 The contrast between the sentimental iconography of the noble savage tradition and the actual hierarchical pressures unconsciously communicated by the tone of Sedgwick's passage gives us an excellent vignette of the problems and dangers facing the Brook Farm enterprise. On the one hand, there is the comforting stability of traditional order, however unjust; on the other, the threat implicit in the social mobility necessary to bring about that structural equilibrium required in the Transcendental scheme of things. This tension was experienced at both ends of the social system of the farm. Ann Weston, who visited Brook Farm shortly after it was founded, complained of Sophia Ripley that "she was anxious to assure her own mind that in all she did, the canons of gentility were not infringed upon, and she was still more anxious to let all else know that fact." Two years later a certain Sophia Eastman, who was at the Brook Farm school for a time, enlarged on this issue in a jaundiced letter home: 'There is an aristocracy prevailing here, although many complain of being neglected." 29 At the other end of the scale, the young housemaid from Maine left because she was accustomed to serving, and egalitarianism made her uneasy. 30 Nevertheless, the point to be borne in mind is that the objective was one of "true democratic equality." This goal was reiterated many years later when Charles Dana addressed the University of Michigan in 1895 on the subject of the community. His words have the authority of one who was a member for virtually the whole of the farm's history, who was Ripley's right-hand man, and who was an intrinsic part of the community's fabric (he was a cousin of Sophia Ripley, and his sister was also a member). He was well qualified to pass a verdict, and his later career as an aggressive polemicist for a rather different set of social values suggests that he was hardly likely to have been tempted to exaggerate the community's reforming verve. And yet he is unequivocal in his judgment that the initial impulse for the establishment of Brook 28. Sedgwick, "A Girl of Sixteen," 396. 29. Sophia Eastman to Mehitable Eastman, July 25, 1843, in Abernathy Library of American Literature, Middlebury College, Middlebury, Vt., reprinted in Sams, Autobiography, So. 30. Crowe, Ripley, 147, 144.
Brook Farm and Masquerade
49
Farm-and the central purpose of the community once it was under way-was an egalitarian one. The whole enterprise was an essay in applied democracy: In this party of Transcendental philosophers the idea early arose-it was first stated by Mr. George Bancroft, the historian ... that democracy, while it existed in the Constitution of the United States, while it had triumphed as a political party under Jefferson, and while it was then in possession of a majority of the governments of the States, and at times of the government of the United States, was not enough .... If democracy was the sublime truth which it was held up to be, it should be raised up from the sphere of politics, from the sphere of law and constitutions; it should be raised up into life and be made social." The rolling clauses of this passage, with the sense they communicate of coming into focus on particularities, are reminiscent of the rhythms of Thoreau's prose when he looks for that single abolitionist who will leaven the whole lump ("if one thousand, if one hundred, if ten men ... if one . . . "). In short, Brook Farm represented a deliberate and consistent attempt to interweave democratic ideals into the very texture of social life. Yet, the trajectory involved in the process of "levelling," like the delusive gradients one sometimes encounters in hilly terrain, could sometimes seem more down than up, as Hawthorne's increasingly disillusioned testimony demonstrates. By June a certain testiness has crept into his letters to Sophia Peabody: ''That abominable gold mine! Thank God, we anticipate getting rid of its treasurers, in the course of two or three days. Of all hateful places, that is the worst." On August 1 2 he is talking of bondage: "Even my Custom House experience was not such a thraldom and weariness; my heart and mind were freer. Oh; belovedest, labor is the curse of this world, and nobody can meddle with it, without becoming proportionably brutified. Dost thou think it a praiseworthy matter, that I have spent five golden months in providing food for cows and horses? Dearest, it is not so. Thank God, my soul is not utterly buried under a dung-heap."' 2 Interestingly, even after Hawthorne returns to the farm somewhat refreshed from a sojourn in Salem, his attitude is that the Brook Farm way of life separates 31. Charles Dana, "Brook Farm," address given at the University of Michigan, January 21, 1895, printed as an appendix to James H. Wilson, Life of Charles Dana (New York: Harper, 1907), 517. 32. Hawthorne, Letters, IBIJ-4], 545, 558.
Transcendental Utapias
the realms of the physical and mental rather than integrating them: "My mind will not be abstracted. I must obseiVe, and think, and feel, and content myself with catching glimpses of things which may be wrought out hereafter. Perhaps it will be quite as well that I find myself unable to set seriously about literary occupations for the present. It will be good to have a longer inteiVal between my labor of the body and that of the mind. I shall work to better purpose, after the beginning of November," that is, after he has left the community." One man's holism is another man's split personality, particularly when the former is a Transcendentalist and the latter a skeptic. For Hawthorne the role of farmworker comes to seem a falsification of his true identity, a realization that is perhaps anticipated by his reaction earlier in his stay at the farm, when he receives a present of the appropriate garb from his betrothed: 'The thin frock, which you made for me, is considered a most splendid article; and I should not wonder if it were to become the summer uniform of the community. I have a thick frock, likewise; but it is rather deficient in grace, though extremely warm and comfortable. I wear a tremendous pair of cow-hide boots, with soles two inches thick. Of course, when I come to see you, I shall wear my farmer's dress."' 4 When he visits Sophia, Hawthorne will wear his farmer's "dress." Thomas Wentworth Higginson, the Boston man of letters later to become the bemused adviser of Emily Dickinson, describes a visit to his cousin Barbara Channing by a group of young men from Brook Farm, including George and Burri! Curtis, Samuel Larned, and Charles Dana, and establishes the self-consciousness of such attire even more strongly, though interestingly he associates it with a fashion among college students of the time. The delegation were "all presentable and agreeable, but the first three peculiarly costumed.... It was then very common for young men in college and elsewhere to wear what were called blouses,-a kind of hunter's frock made at first of brown holland belted at the waist,-these being gradually developed into garments of gay-colored chintz, sometimes, it was said, an economical transformation of their sisters' skirts or petticoats." Higginson goes on to say that Dana did not indulge in these vanities but "dressed like a well-to-do young farmer and was always handsome and manly. "'5 33· Ibid., 575-76. 34· Ibid., 540, letter of May 3, 1841. 35· Thomas Wentworth Higginson, Cheerful Yesterdays (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 18g8), 84.
Brook Farm and Masquerade
Emerson talked of watching the monad "through all his masks as he performs the metempsychosis of nature," claiming that nature "hums the old well known air through innumerable variations." 36 The roleplaying that is in evidence here, and the fascination it suggests with playing variations on a theme, is a central aspect of Brook Farm life. The problem in analyzing it lies with the selective nature of the evidence that pertains to the day-by-day experience of the Brook Farmers. It is one thing to explain away Ripley's initial reticence on the grounds of his commitment to action, another to shed light on the reasons for his reticence-and that of most of the central members of the community-after that action had failed the test of history. Amelia Russell, in a two-part article "Home Life of the Brook Farm Association," written more than thirty years after the community's collapse, poses a problem noted by Hawthorne in his preface to The Blithedale Romance and by many other former members when the time came to pen their memoirs: "I cannot understand why no one of those who better comprehended all the machinery which kept the wheels going through many trying vicissitudes (though I suspect sometimes the operators themselves felt doubtful how it was done) has ever brought its interior life to view, since a real history of its aims and endeavors after a truer life has been asked for. "37 Some years later Arthur Sumner suggested that the cause of this lapse was that Brook Farm "never had any result except upon the individual lives of those who dwelt there." It is an explanation that certainly gives ammunition to those who wish to see the community as symptomatic of a kind of death wish, an attempt to "banish the world" (to use the phrase of a hostile commentator, Jane Maloney Johnson), particularly as Sumner goes on to say, "It was a beautiful idyllic life which we led, with plenty of work and play and transcendentalism; and it gave place to the Roxbury poorhouse."'" The opposition he establishes between idyll and poorhouse supports commentators who want to see the experiment as an extended picnic, with the corollary that any attempt to restructure its ideology must be the equivalent of breaking a butterfly upon a 36. Ralph Waldo Emerson, "History," in &says z, 8, g. 37· A. E. Russell, "Home Life of the Brook Farm Association," Atlantic Monthly 42 (October t878):458. Hawthorne wrote in his preface: "The Author cannot close his reference to this subject, without expressing a most earnest wish that some one of the many cultivated and philosophic minds, which took an interest in that enterprise, might now give the world its history." Nathaniel Hawthorne, The Blithedale Romance, Centenary Edition, 3:3. 38. Sumner, "A Boy's Recollections," 313; Jane Maloney Johnson, '"Through Change and Through Storm': A Study of Federalist-Unitarian Thought, t8oo-t86o" (Ph.D. diss., Radcliffe College, 1958), 277.
52
Transcendental Utopias
wheel. At least one contemporary visitor to the farm would have endorsed Sumner's point of view. Bronson Alcott and Charles Lane, who had just embarked on their own community at Fruitlands, visited during the summer of 1843, and Lane was not impressed, describing "8o or go persons playing away their youth and daytime in a miserably joyous and frivolous manner. "39 There is, however, an alternative explanation for the retrospective reticence, one that takes us to the opposite pole from allegations of triviality and frivolity: that is, the almost simultaneous collapse of the community and of the national impetus toward association must have had a traumatic effect on those who had invested in the movement their emotional and intellectual capital (and in Ripley's case, to a disastrous degree, his financial capital). We are surely dealing with a bitter failure after years of high ideals, higher hopes, and strenuous effort, and it is hardly surprising that by 1850 Ripley, Dwight, and Dana had embarked on careers that bore little or no relation to their earlier ideals. 40 By an irony that seems rather appropriate in view of Brook Farm's precarious stance between the world of fantasy and that of harsh social realities, one of the effects of this uneasy silence on the part of the community's leaders is that we have to rely heavily for information about the daily life of Brook Farm on writers who lay great stress on the fun they had there. It is small wonder that Lindsay Swift, almost echoing Lane's grumpy oxymoron, should claim that "enjoyment was almost from the first a serious pursuit of the community," when we see the emphasis on entertainment in the reminiscences of many former members, including Ora Gannet Sedgwick, Amelia Russell, George P. Bradford, and Arthur Sumner. John Van Der Zee Sears devotes a whole chapter to the subject (it seems a long way from the Harbingers gritty sociology to his inauspicious opening: "Our slide down the knoll proved very popular"), and john Thomas Cadman's memoir includes a chapter titled "Fun Alive," which deals almost exclusively with the community's addiction to punning. 41 39· Charles Lane, letter to New Age, reprinted in Frank B. Sanborn and William T. Harris, A. Bronson Alcott, His Life and Philosophy, 2 vols. (Boston: Roberts Bros. 1893), 2:282-83. 40. Ripley became a journalist on Horace Greeley's New York Tri/mne and, with Dana, edited the New American Cyclopaedia, 16 vols. (New York: D. Appleton, 1858-63). Dana's career as a journalist on the New York Sun is charted in Wilson, Charles Dana, and Candace Stone, Dana and the Sun (New York: Dodd Mead, 1938). Dwight edited Dwight's journal of Music from 1853 to 1887; see G. W. Cooke, john Sullivan Dwight (Boston: Small Maynard, 1898). 41. Swift, Brook Farm, 53; Sedgwick, "A Girl of Sixteen," 394-404, esp. 402; Russell,
Brook Farm and Masquerade
53
The most commonly mentioned form of entertainment in the Brook Farm memoirs is masquerade, and it is surely no coincidence that this is the area of utopian high jinks covered most substantially by Hawthorne in The Blithedale Romance. Indeed, many of the reminiscences attempt to identifY the specific masquerade that provided him with his source, which was, as The American Notebooks show, a party given to celebrate Frank Dana's sixth birthday.' 2 The most convincing candidate is described in a letter appended to Codman's book and signed "Charles": "One of the ladies personated Diana, and any one entering her wooded precincts was liable to be shot with one of her arrows." Compare Hawthorne's "goddess Diana (known on earth as Miss Ellen Slade)" who "let fly an arrow and hit me smartly in the hand." 4 ' Sedgwick modestly concentrates on checking the detail: apparently Hawthorne's "one variation from the facts was making me, both there [in The Blithedale Romance] and in the American Note-book, the gypsy fortune-teller, whereas that part was really taken by Mrs. Ripley, and I was merely the messenger to bring persons to her." Arthur Sumner, who did not join the farm until after Hawthorne had left, remembers "a fancy dress picnic in the woods, which might have furnished Mr. Hawthorne his scene in the Blithedale Romance. "44 There were many similar events, and they are recalled with a graphic detail that suggests the importance of the part they played in the life of the community. John Van Der Zee Sears states that "the finest pageant we ever had was arranged by the Festal Series, after the reorganization into a phalanx. It was historic in design, illustrating the Elizabethan period in England. Dr. Ripley personated Shakespeare; Miss Ripley, Queen Elizabeth, in a tissue paper ruff, which I helped to make; Mr. Dana, Sir Walter Raleigh; Mary Bullard, the most beautiful of our young women, Mary Queen of Scots, and Charles Hosmer, Sir Philip Sidney." Amelia Russell describes another one, held at Christmastime, which featured impersonations of Hamlet, the Greeks and Circassians, an Indian, Little Nell and her grandfather, and Spanish bolero dancers. Thomas Wentworth Higginson made one of his only two visits to Brook Farm to "convey my cousin Barbara to a fancy ball at 'the Community,'
"Home Life," esp. 461-62; (November 1878): 557-59· Bradford, "Reminiscences," 14148, esp. 142; Sumner, "A Boy's Recollections," esp. 311-12;john VanDerZee Sears, My Friends at Brook Fann (New York: Desmond Fitzgerald, 1912), So; Codman, Brook Fann, 172-85. 42. Hawthome, American Notebooks, 201-3, entry for September 28, 1841. 43· Codman, Brook Fann, 260, letter of October 27, 1841; Hawthorne, American Notebooks, 202. 44· Sedgwick, "A Girl of Sixteen," 402; Sumner, "A Boy's Recollections," 311.
54
Transcendental Utopias
as it was usually called, where she was to appear in a pretty creole dress made of madras handkerchiefs and brought by Stephen Perkins from the West lndies."45 We also hear about other tableaux, charades, rural fetes, and a prodigious list of plays and operas performed in whole or in part by the Brook Farmers: Byron's Corsair, Douglas Jerrold's Rent Day, A Midsummer's Night's Dream, The Caliph of Baghdad, Zampa, Norma, and so on. Hawthorne himself mentions two evenings of tableaux in letters of May 3 and September 21, 1841. Other activities-music, tobogganing, dancing-are mentioned, but those requiring role-playing of one sort or another seem to have been the most popular, and the ones that had the deepest effect on the participants. 46 Let us now explore in some detail a few relevant passages from that most contentious and problematic of all the Brook Farm texts, The Blithedale Romance. Hawthorne left the community after a mere six months and published this work nearly ten years later. In making use of it I am not attempting to reopen the debate about the authenticity of the book as an account of the community. Hawthorne deals with that issue definitively in his preface. He acknowledges that "many readers will probably suspect a faint and not very faithful shadowing of BROOK FARM," and concedes that he "does not wish to deny, that he had this Community in his mind, and that (having had the good fortune, for a time, to be personally connected with it) he has occasionally availed himself of his actual reminiscences, in the hope of giving a more lifelike tint to the fancy-sketch in the following pages." Nevertheless, he goes on to emphasize that "he has considered the Institution itself as not less fairly the subject of fictitious handling, than the imaginary personages whom he has introduced there. "47 One notes a characteristic ambiguity in the use of that adverbial phrase "not less fairly," which picks up an equally characteristic double entendre in the title. In establishing that his book is a fictionalization of the community, he is also suggesting that there was something intrinsically fictional about the nature of the community itself, and apparently allying himself with those who see it as a refuge from the pressures of everyday reality. This may, broadly speaking, be the case, but Hawthorne is a past master at exploring the relativity of all judgments and at ensuring that his ambiguities are themselves ambiguous. Certainly, whatever his own 45· Sears, My Friends, 101; Russell, "Home Life," 462; Higginson, Cheerful Yesterdays, 84. 46. See, for example, Bradford, "Reminiscences," 142; Sears, My Friends, 8o-w6; Codman, Brook Farm, 53-68; Hawthorne, Letters, I8IJ-I84J• 542, 576, letters of May 4, 1841, and September 22, 1841. 47· Hawthorne, Blithedale, 1.
Brook Farm and Masquerade
55
final verdict on the community-if he ever allowed himself one-this "not very faithful shadowing" can shed some light on the communitarian impulse in general, on the motivations and behavior of the Brook Farmers in particular, and above all on the significance and the appeal of masquerade to the communitarians. Moreover, the two examples I wish briefly to explore both originate from Hawthorne's actual reminiscences of his time at the farm, as detailed in his American Notebooks. 48 In the chapter titled "Leave-Takings," Coverdale, the central character of the novel, a somewhat reclusive and valetudinarian poet, reveals his decision to return from the Blithedale community to the outside world for a time. His reasons are both particular (a recent "passage-atarms" with Hollingsworth, the dynamic and philanthropic leader of the community) and general ("an intolerable discontent and irksomeness had come over me"). He makes his intentions clear by the way he dresses: "I appeared at the dinner-table, actually dressed in a coat, instead of my customary blouse; with a satin cravat, too, a white vest, and several other things that made me seem strange and outlandish to myself." And not just to himself, in fact: his choice of dress indicates to his fellow communitarians that he has decided to leave them. As Zenobia, the community's beauty (with her own exuberant taste in clothing) complains: "You have just resumed the whole series of social conventionalisms, together with that straight-bodied coat." She clearly disapproves of Coverdale's need "to go and hold a little talk with the conservatives." Her belief is that only a dynamic and volatile temperament can cope with the instability of the world: "It needs a wild steersman when we voyage through Chaos! "49 Coverdale's last farewell is to the pigs. "I can in nowise explain," he confesses to the reader, "what sort of whim, prank, or perversity it was, that, after all these leave-takings, induced me to go to the pig-stye and take leave of the swine!" Certainly the pigs are about as far removed 48. Hawthorne, American Notebooks, 201-5, entries for September 28 and October 1, 1841. 49· Hawthorne, Blithedale, 138, 137, 141, 142. Charles Anderson Dana has fun with the image of a conservative in a straight-bodied coat in a satirical sketch called ''Worthy Men," which he wrote at Brook Farm and enclosed in a letter to Emerson on October 31, 1843: "Your worthy man wears a suit of fine black, loosely made, with benevolent looking wrinkles intersecting the back. His waistcoat is of black silk. His pantaloons are large and comfortable. He affecteth white cravats. Straps he eschews." Later on, Dana has the worthy man giving his opinion on Transcendentalism: "I do'nt like the Movement school. We got along well enough in my time without any German nonsense, and I do'nt see why we should'nt now. Can you get money by German? I guess not." MS in Houghton Library, BMS Am 1280 (744), 1, 5·
Transcendental Utopias
from voyaging through Chaos as it is possible for creatures to be, and therein might indeed lie the secret of their attraction. Coverdale appears to be searching for some kind of symbolic manifestation of his need for security; that, after all, is what he is hoping to gain on his return to city life from "those respectable old blockheads, who still, in this intangibility and mistiness of affairs, kept a death-grip on one or two ideas which had not come into vogue since yesterday-morning." In short, he is looking not for a wild steersman but for a safe anchor; and the firmness of the conservatives, in holding to their principles through the "intangibility and mistiness of affairs," is balanced on a physical level by the immobility and torpor of the pigs to whom he has come to say farewell: There they lay, buried as deeply among the straw as they could burrow, four huge black grunters, the very symbols of slothful ease and sensual comfort. They were asleep, drawing short and heavy breaths, which heaved their big sides up and down. Unclosing their eyes, however, at my approach, they looked dimly forth at the outer world, and simultaneously uttered a gentle grunt; not putting themselves to the trouble of an additional breath for that particular purpose, but grunting with their ordinary inhalation. They were involved, and almost stifled, and buried alive, in their own corporeal substance. 50 The pigs are as far removed as it is possible to imagine from the world of masquerade. They are themselves to the nth degree, taking the fact of simply being, as opposed to doing, as far as it can go. They can be seen as literal embodiments of nature's stasis, and it is perhaps for this reason that Coverdale admires their capacity to luxuriate in their own existence. They represent, in their own way, the sort of stability for which he is striving, and which he finds so unattainable in the complex interaction of community life. The sharp observation that irradiates the whole passage-that they grunt "with their ordinary inhalation"-is reminiscent of a line in Whitman's "Song of Myself' in which the poet celebrates 'The sound of the belch'd words of my voice loos'd to the eddies of the wind."51 Whitman's robust Anglo-Saxonism reminds us that spoken language is no more than a series of configurations of the air, eddies of the wind (in both senses of the word), and exposes our tendency to separate discourse from the world it signifies. 50. Hawthorne, Blithedale, 141, 143-44. 51. Walt Whitman, "Song of Myself," in Leaves of Grass, ed. Harold W. Blodgett and Sculley Bradley (New York: New York University Press, 1965), 29.
Brook Farm and Masquerade
57
The porkers, like the bard, find no dichotomy between word and thing, subject and object, the world of discourse and the reality it is intended to convey. Whitman would have found nothing incongruous in the comparison ("I think I could turn and live with animals, they are so placid and self-contained, I I stand and look at them long and long. I They do not sweat and whine about their condition, I .... Not one is dissatisfied ... ) . "52 Hawthorne observes in The American Notebooks that the language of pigs "seems to be the most copious of that of any quadruped." Nevertheless, rich though it may be, it can express only nature's fixed patterning and inevitably lacks the resources of human language, and in particular the sorts of encoded meanings, double entendres, and puns generated within a community, the linguistic masquerade that reflects the other forms of role-playing that take place. 53 John Thomas Codman devotes a whole chapter of his memoirs, as I have mentioned, to the subject of punning. The quantity, if not the quality, of this wordplay inevitably bathes the farm in an Illyrian glow. The activity of punning (however badly) involves camaraderie and cooperativeness, and the puns could be bad indeed: "'These Grahamites will never make their ends meet,' said one. 'You may stake your reputation on that,' said the other."54 The reference here is to the Grahamite table at the farm, where strict vegetarianism was regarded as the key to a healthy cuisine, as it was at the Alcott-Lane community of Fruitlands (though non vegetarian Brook Farmers tended to be restricted to pork and beans, and that only as a Sunday treat, with vegetables, bread pudding, and the like providing their staple also). 55 As far as such jokes are concerned, to know all is not necessarily to forgive all. But the weaker the puns, the more they rely on accomplices-a point Codman himself makes, attacking those who pun "in toto," as he puts it. The in toto punster, he tells us, "discovers some close-mouthed, tight-fisted sort of a word or a sentence doubled up like an oyster and deliberately splits it apart, one shell on one side, one on the other and the soft thing drops out between." He does not go on to define "the soft thing," but one can take it to be the organic principle that reconciles opposites. "I could only despise the brain that would do such a deed," Codman tells us. In toto punning clearly threatens the substance of community, its utopian value and meaning, since it de52. Ibid., 6o. 53· Hawthorne, American Notebooks, 205. 54· Codman, Brook Farm, •73· 55· Georgianna Bruce Kirby, "Reminiscences of Brook Farm," Old and New 5 (1872): 347-58; Sears, Friends, 50-52.
Transcendental Utopias
stroys the connective tissue necessary for creating solidarity between the different members. The sort of pun Codman admired, and which he found to be characteristic of Brook Farm, was by contrast "a part of the sunshine of words." Paradoxically, though, it achieves this warmth, whereby it imparts "a sparkle and a glow to language," by creating, albeit temporarily, an alienation effect: "It is a big pendulum that swings from torrid to frigid zone quicker than a telegram goes. If you hold on to it, you will find yourself in both places in a jiffy, and back again to the spot where you start from without being hurt, and the jog to your intellect, if you happen to have any, is only of an agreeable nature. 56 Codman's analysis is all the more extraordinary and fascinating when one knows that he is not a man of letters, nor a linguistic theorist, but a nineteenth-century dentist. But of course he is a nineteenth-century dentist who spent much of his childhood at Brook Farm. His perceptiveness is made possible by actual experience of the operations of language within utopia. He seems here to be anticipating the sort of distinctions William Empson would make in his book Seven Types of Ambiguity, where the seventh type has the schismatic effect of the in toto punster-"full contradiction, marking a division in the author's mind"-whereas "in second-type ambiguities two or more alternative meanings are fully resolved into one." 57 In the case of Codman's sunshiny pun, there is not time for the "soft thing" to drop out between the extremes. The lightning journey described by Codman perhaps has , something in common with those glimpses and perceptions of serial unity so hauntingly evoked by Emerson. The most memorable of them, after all, involved ajourney toward (or perhaps from) the frigid zone, when, as we recall, "crossing a bare common, in snow puddles, at twilight, under a clouded sky, without having in my thoughts any occurrence of special good fortune, I have enjoyed a perfect exhilaration." When Emerson thinks specifically of human solidarity, however, he pictures the serial linkages as lying beyond the realm of discourse altogether: "I feel the same truth how often in my trivial conversation with my neighbors, that somewhat higher in each of us overlooks this byplay."58 It might be that here one sees the difference between, on the one hand, the individualistic utopian whose mind mediates constantly between the polarities of the one and the totality, so that when he talks about communion he automatically triangulates the relationship into 56, Codman, Brook ~Farm, 176. 57· William Empson, Seven Types of Ambiguity (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1961), v, vi. s8. Ralph Waldo Emerson, "The Over-Soul," in Essays I, 165-
Brook Farm and Masquerade
59
the realm of a "third party or common nature" which "is not social" but "impersonal," and, on the other, the communitarian variety, in which the interaction between people remains important. 59 Codman's punsters, far from overlooking their by-play, give it full rein, enjoying the accommodation of doubleness, the reconciliation of opposites, and the cooperation it permits. In its own way masquerade also acts as a kind of pendulum between torrid and frigid zones. Terry Castle points out in her study of the eighteenth-century carnivalesque that "the pleasure of the masquerade attended on the experience of doubleness, the alienation of inner from outer." She is describing here the phenomenon of masquerade taking place within the status quo, not so much a structured utopia as an episode of misrule or holiday, so that it inevitably acts as a subversive or disruptive force, the effect being analogous to that of the in toto pun. In a passage that is coincidentally reminiscent of Codman's imagery of wrenched shells and jogged intellects, she claims that, "like the linguistic code, the code of dress may be subverted. Language ... can be stripped of its referential functions; res et verba can be jarred apart . . . . The same might be said of the sartorial language."60 Word and dress have a more benign and sunny function within Codman's Brook Farm, expanding their referential functions and finding new ways of matching res et verba. Hawthorne's porkers are unaware of such possibilities. Lacking verbal and sartorial strategies, they represent in their uncomplicated way "the soft thing," the principle of connectivity itself: 'They also grunt among themselves, apparently without any external cause, but merely to express their swinish sympathy. "61 As they are creatures of nature, one might not expect them to have anything to fear from the dialectical forces that play on human beings, but things are not as simple as that. These are farm animals, and as such they straddle two worlds, just as we do. They have their existence, as Coverdale points out, "betwixt dream and reality."62 Like the "plant, quadruped, bird" of Emerson's poem 'The Sphinx," they are entranced by "the Lethe of Nature." Nevertheless, because this enchantment takes place within the farm, they are also subjected to the vicissitudes of history. As Hawthorne put it in the passage in The American Notebooks that provided the material for 59· Ibid., 164. 6o. Terry Castle, Masquerade and Civilisation: The Camivalesque in Eighteenth-Century English Culture and Fiction (London: Methuen, 1g86), 4· 56. 61. Hawthorne, American Notebooks, 205. 62. Hawthorne, Blithedale, 144·
6o
Transcendental Utopias
Coverdale's farewell to the pigs: "I suppose it is the knowledge that these four grunters are doomed to die within two or three weeks, that gives them a sort of awfulness in my conception; it makes me contrast their present gross substance of fleshly life with the nothingness speedily to come. "63 The swing of the pendulum will be fatal: 'You must come back in season to eat part of a spare-rib,' said Silas Foster. ... 'I shall have these fat fellows hanging up by the heels, heads downward, pretty soon, I tell you!' •>&~ If the slothful pigs provide an image of Coverdale's need when he leaves the farm, the masquerade he encounters on his return surely sums up the community as a whole and embodies exactly that instability of identity and role which he finds so difficult to cope with. As he approaches Blithedale after his comparatively short absence (he leaves in August and returns in September), Coverdale begins to suspect that everything has changed since he was last here: that some sort of disaster has overtaken the community and that the farm has been abandoned. His anxiety is not a serious one, however, but a form of selfteasing which serves to increase the shock when he discovers that the buildings are in fact deserted. His anticipation has been caused by his sense that there is something intrinsically unlikely, quasi-fictional, about the community in the first place. As with any utopia, its true locale seems to be in an if-only dimension rather than in the here-andnow: I indulged in a hundred odd and extravagant conjectures. Either there was no such place as Blithedale, nor ever had been, nor any brotherhood of thoughtful laborers, like what I seemed to recollect there; or else it was all changed, during my absence. It had been nothing but dream-work and enchantment. I should seek in vain for the old farm-house, and for the greensward, the potatoe-fields, the rootcrops, and acres of Indian corn, and for all that configuration of the land which I had imagined. It would be another spot, and an utter strangeness. 65 The community is still there, as it turns out, but Coverdale is right to anticipate "utter strangeness": "Stealing onward as far as I durst, without hazard of discovery, I saw a concourse of strange figures beneath the overshadowing branches; they appeared, and vanished, and came 63. Hawthorne, American Notebooks, 204. 64. Hawthorne, Blithedale, 144. 6 5 . Ibid., 206.
Brook Farm and Masquerade
61
again, confusedly, with the streaks of sunlight glimmering down upon them." They seem, in short, to be a trick of the light, a phenomenon of perception, teetering on the verge of Emersonian transparency (and nobody could have a more appropriately transparent eyeball-or at least a more invisible one-with which to view the scene than the secretive Miles Coverdale). The masquerade he then perceives makes an impressive catalogue, comprising the following roles: an Indian chief, the goddess Diana, a Bavarian broom-girl, a Negro, one or two foresters of the Middle Ages, a Kentucky woodsman, a Shaker elder, shepherds of Arcadia, allegorical figures from The Faerie Queene, Puritans, Cavaliers, Revolutionary War officers, a Gypsy, Moll Pitcher ("the renowned old witch of Lynn"), skinkers and drawers, and the "fiendish musician, erst seen by Tam O'Shanter."66 As a sort of yardstick to measure the extent of these transformations, and in so doing to demystifY them, Hawthorne gives us the figure of Silas Foster, "who leaned against a tree near by, in his customary blue frock"-in his working garb, in short. In the Notebooks entry for the day before the one on which Frank Dana's masquerade is described, Hawthorne sings the praises of that same garment: "Others (like myself) had on the blue stuff frocks which they wear in the fields-the most comfortable garment that man ever invented." But as we have seen, for Hawthorne such a garment can be regarded as a form of disguise in itself; for a real farmer it is the stuff of a comforting normality, fitting the man as word should match thing. As such it "did more to disenchant the scene ... than twenty witches and necromancers could have done. "67 At the Brook Farm masquerade which provided Hawthorne with his material, that role was performed by "our friend Orange, a thickset, sturdy figure, in his blue frock, enjoying the fun well enough, yet rather laughing with a perception of its nonsensicallness, than at all entering into the spirit of the thing."68 The point is that Orange was not a member of the community but a helpful neighbor, and so his blue frock is not a costume but the genuine article. 69 Castle has claimed that conventional dress reinscribes "a person's sex, rank, age, occupation-all the distinctive features of the self." Orange and Foster provide a reality index to the degree of masquerade around them, a hu66. Ibid .• 20g-IO. 67. Ibid., 210; Hawthorne, American Notebooks, 200. 68. Hawthorne, American Notebooks, 203. 6g. See, for example, Marianne Dwight's account of his assistance in trying to save the Phalanstery when it caught fire. Marianne [Dwight] Orvis, Letters from Brook Farm, r844r847• ed. Amy L. Reed (Poughkeepsie, N.Y.: Vassar College, 1928), q6, letter dated March 4• 1846.
Transcendental Utopias
man equivalent of that "Realometer" Thoreau talks about, which will gauge "how deep a freshet of shams and appearances had gathered from time to time. "70 Coverdale, too, bursts into laughter at the "oddity of surprising my grave associates in this masquerading trim." He wants to embrace the concept of a stable identity, as manifested in the porkers and Silas Foster, rather than join in the freewheeling play of the revelers, though he is less secure in his selfhood than those allies are in theirs. His laughter removes the privilege of his transparency, and he flees before the good-humored onslaught of the communitarians. There is an element of panic in his flight: "The whole fantastic rabble forthwith streamed off in pursuit of me, so that I was like a mad poet hunted by chimaeras. "71 We can detect a number of ironies here. Emerson's description of the poet springs to mind, to start with. For him the poet is a being with the capacity of perceiving unity in diversity, of being able to make something coherent out of the variety of life's masquerade, one who "turns the world to glass and shows us all things in their right series and procession." 72 The version we are given in Coverdale's simile seems to lack the organizing perception celebrated in Emerson's definition; the series has become chaotic and the procession a predatory mob. A further irony, one that is clearly being utilized to "place" Coverdale as a character and ensure that the reader does not assume he has an objective vantage point within the romance, is that Coverdale himself is actually a poet by profession, though paradoxically the simile he has chosen denies that vocation even as it invokes its relevance, thus suggesting that he doubts his own claim to the title and establishing that the minor status he lays claim to is fair comment rather than an act of modesty. Coverdale succeeds in making his escape, leaving "merriment and riot at a good distance in the rear. Its fainter tones assumed a kind of mournfulness, and were finally lost in the hush and solemnity of the wood." His rejection of masquerade, we note, has involved transforming merriment to mournfulness. The sunshine has gone. He immediately stumbles on a reminder of the entropy that eats away at all our attempts to impose order on the world, as he comes across a heap of firewood that had been "piled up square" many years before, since when, "by the accumulation of moss, and the leaves falling over them 70. Castle, Masquerade, 55; Henry David Thoreau, Walden, in Writings, g8. 71. Hawthorne, Blithedale, 210-11. 72. Ralph Waldo Emerson, "The Poet," in Essays 2, 12.
Brook Farm and Masquerade
and decaying there, . . . a green mound was formed, in which the softened outline of the wood-pile was still perceptible." It is relevant to recall at this point the contrast between the spontaneous sort of Transcendentalism which lacked any a priori baggage, apart from the capacity to assimilate fresh perceptions, and the myth-sustaining kind which brought a treasury of cultural bricolage along with it. In the scene under discussion Coverdale fails to sustain the first stance, and is brought up short when confronted by the implications of the second. Only moments after fleeing the masquerade, Coverdale is imagining "the longdead woodman, and his long-dead wife and children, coming out of their chill graves, and essaying to make a fire with this heap of mossy fuel! "73 There is a stark contrast between this ghostly vision of order struggling to maintain itself long after its occasion has passed, and the gaiety and resourcefulness of the masqueraders. In his study of Rabelais, Mikhail Bakhtin has discussed the way in which the carnivalized body "is not a closed, complete unit; it is unfinished, outgrows itself, transgresses its own limits." Terry Castle has extended this argument to the eighteenth-century masquerade in England: From basically simple violations of the sartorial code-the conventional symbolic connections between identity and the trappings of identity-masqueraders developed scenes of vertiginous existential recombination. New bodies were superimposed over old; anarchic theatrical selves displaced supposedly essential ones; masks, or personae, obscured persons . . . . The true self remained elusive and inaccessible-illegible-within its fantastical encasements. The result was a material devaluation of unitary notions of the selC' That capacity for opening his eyes with fresh sincerity which Santayana attributed to Emerson is one that ought to be particularly attuned to perceiving these new bodies superimposed over the old; but, disappointingly, Emerson seems to have spent his time at the birthday masquerade for Frank Dana deep in talk with Margaret Fuller. Nevertheless, Hawthorne himself was able to register the vertiginous effect of the existential recombinations he witnessed. To him the masqueraders seemed to be "starting out of the earth; as if the every day laws of 73· Hawthorne, Blithedale, 211-12. 74· Mikhail Bakhtin, Rabelais and His World, trans. Helene Iswolsky (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1968}, 26; Castle, Masquerade, 4·
Transcendental Utopias
Nature were suspended for this particular occasion."75 There is an implication that if the everyday laws of nature have been suspended, what Hawthorne was witnessing was a manifestation of deeper, permanent laws, the sort referred to by George Ripley in a letter to Emerson later that same year in which he claims that "so many powers are at work with us and for us, that I cannot doubt, we are destined to succeed in giving visible expression to some of the laws of social life that as yet have been kept in the background. "76 Castle goes on to claim that masquerade is a form of utopia, which is precisely my point-and Hawthorne's, for that matter. She writes: "The visionary anti-society the masquerade projected was at heart utopian, for along with other oppositions, that of upper class and lower class was temporarily abolished. Roland Barthes's maxim, 'Once the antimony is rejected, once the paradigm is blurred, utopia begins,' has its relevance here.'m Ironically, the complex improvisation of masquerade has a unifYing effect, destabilizing hierarchy and synthesizing dialectic. Although it is true that, for its duration, melancholy, death, the passing of time seem suspended, this fact does not entitle us to regard masquerade as merely escapist. If it were, the conformist Coverdale would surely be running toward it rather than away. There is, in other words, a social agenda implicit in the occasion, one that meshes quite clearly with the utopian ideals of Blithedale and indeed of Brook Farm: the attempt to unite laborer and student, to enable cooks and consumers to sit together at the table. The high jinks that Coverdale comes across may in themselves constitute only a utopia of the impromptu moment, but they stand for the sustained historical endeavor of the community as a whole. Masquerade provided a ludic paradigm of the interchangeability of role that was part of the institutional fabric of Brook Farm from its earliest days. What the community was trying to achieve was a holism of the body and of the body politic, a way of accommodating that faith in human solidarity that is intrinsic not merely to Transcendentalist ideology but to the Christian tradition generally. As John Thomas Codman put it, the human race "was one body. It should be of one heart, one brain, one purpose. Whenever one of its members suffered all suffered. When there was a criminal all had part in his crime; when there was a debauchee, all partook in his debasement; when there was one dis75· Hawthorne, American Notebooks, 202-3. 76. George Ripley to Ralph Waldo Emerson, December 17, 1841, MS Houghton, BMS Am 1280 (2721). Ripley is trying to persuade Emerson to buy a share in the farm. 77· Castle, Masquerade, 78.
Brook Farm and Masquerade
eased, all were affected by it; when one was poor, all bore some of the sting of his poverty. If anyone took shelter behind his possessions, wretchedness, poverty and disease found him out."78 Because the human race can be seen as a single organism, we all play any and every role in the ongoing drama. Ironically, such protean transformations act as an affirmation of the underlying structure behind all phenomena, the serial harmony that cancels difference and distinction and enables us to perceive the monad behind the mask. We are participants in an ultimate masquerade: the criminal, sinner, impoverished wretch, Indian chief, goddess Diana, Bavarian broom-girl; the milker of cows and the teacher of philosophy. This masquerade is, so to speak, for real, not simply an extension and enlargement of the Ripleys' summer holiday, a 'Transcendental picnic" that inevitably had to give way to the West Roxbury poorhouse. As Cadman says, this belief in the unity underlying social roles was the "religion" of Brook Farm. It is not a religion to which Coverdale can adhere because he sees structural integrity-the stability of porker, conservative, and woodsman-as separate from masquerade. The former lacks the flexibility to cope with history's changes; the latter lacks the consistency to be more than a rabble of chimaeras. Hawthorne himself made a more resolute attempt to deal with this problem than his fictional opposite number, but, as we have seen, his attempt also came to nothing. It is significant that in recording his experiences at Brook Farm, he should so persistently fix on his activity as a dung shoveler. As we shall see with regard to Lane and Alcott, and indeed Thoreau, manure tended to represent for the Transcendentalists the hold that the old, exhausted, compromised past maintains on the present. Hawthorne, in using the ancient conceit of dung as treasure, accidentally allies himself with LeviStrauss's bricoleur, reorganizing the cultural treasury. The problem is that this effort cannot be seen as an affirmation of lasting values because for him, lacking the credentials of the fictitious Foster or the real Orange, it is merely a disguise, and therefore associates him with the opposite camp, the masqueraders. And as the months wore on, Hawthorne began to lose his faith in disguises. On May 4 we find him describing some tableaux of the previous evening for the benefit of his betrothed: 'They went off very well. I would like to see a tableaux [sic], arranged by my Dove." By the time he is writing the letter of September 22, in which he talks of establishing an interval between labor of the mind and the body, his attitude has undergone a radical meta78. Codman, Brook Farm, 227.
66
Transcendental Utopias
morphosis: "We had some tableaux last night. They were very stupid, (as, indeed, was the case with all I have ever seen)."79 Other Brook Farmers-those who, unlike Hawthorne, shared the Transcendentalist perspective-found masquerade, in the broad "religious" sense, a satisfying way of exploring life's possibilities and affirming human solidarity. Nevertheless, after a year or two they were beginning to feel the need for a more formal structure to underpin their utopian improvisations, a doorpost to write their whims upon. 79· Hawthorne, Letters, 543, 576.
3 Brook Farm: The Law of Groups and Series
M
any years after the failure of Brook Farm, when George Ripley's life had taken a very different shape and his principles and beliefs had become far more conservative, he went to bed one night and had a vivid dream. When he awoke from it he scribbled:
Cosmic Animal Vegetable Mechanical Chemical
Life life life life life life
power power power power power power
of action of cosmic action of animal action of vegetable action of mechanical action of chemical action 1
Many of us no doubt have had the experience of stumbling upon what seems to be a secret of universal importance in our sleep, jotting it down on a scrap of paper in the middle of the night, and being dismayed in the cold light of morning to discover that it was either gibberish or banality. At first sight Ripley's formulation seems to belong to this category of disappointments. Yet to dismiss it in this way is to misunderstand both the Transcendentalist and the Fourierist frame of mind. Its repetitiveness is the whole point. What we have here is a late aftergleam of that vision which Emerson attributes to the poet: "all 1. Charles Crowe, George Ripley: Transcendentalist and Utopian Socialist (Athens: University of Georgia Press, 1967), 260. The original (without explanation that it was a dream) is part of a miscellaneous collection of manuscripts in the Massachusetts Historical Society collection of George Ripley papers. From the context it clearly dates from the 187os.
68
Transcendental Utopias
things in their right series and procession." By definition this is a vision that cannot be communicated in terms of vivid detail because it is a vision of everything. The world, to revert to Emerson's terminology again, has been turned to glass, and Ripley's formulation is like a sequence of refracted images, each manifesting the same basic outline but receiving its own coloration and dimension from its particular context. In his autobiography the American Fourierist Albert Brisbane describes a similar moment of revelation: I perceived that there was unity of law with great diversity of phenomena; that the laws manifested themselves differently according to the differences of the material spheres in which they acted. Hence unity of law and variety in manifestation. The same law, for instance, which governs the distribution, co-ordination, and arrangement of the notes of music governs the distribution, co-ordination, and arrangement of the planets and the solar system. As sounds are notes in the musical harmony, so the planets are notes in a sidereal harmony. Continuing the analogy: the species in the animal or vegetable kingdom are the notes of a vast organic harmony; the bones in the human body are the notes of an osseous harmony, and these with the muscles and other parts of the human organism, are the notes of physical harmony. Law is unchanging, but there is infinite variety in its manifestations;-such manifestations being as rich and complex as are the varied spheres or departments of the Universe! Certain commentators have expressed surprise at Brook Farm's transition, early in 1844, from Transcendentalist community to Fourierist phalanx. Perry Miller, for example, picking up a phrase of Emerson's, claims that "nobody knows what went on in Ripley's mind as he consented, by January 18, 1844, to change Brook Farm from a Transcendental picnic into a regimented phalanx." He goes on to quote Lindsay Swift to the effect that Ripley must have come "to lay more stress on the method by which individual freedom was to become assured, than on the fact of personal liberty in itself. "3 This verdict can receive some 2. Albert Brisbane, A Mental Biography, ed. Redelia Brisbane (Boston: Arena, 1893), 258. Despite its tide, mis is an autobiography, dictated by Albert Brisbane to his secretary, and posiliumously supervised dirough publication by his widow, Redelia Brisbane. 3· Perry Miller, The Transcendentalists (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1950), 469. In "Historic Notes" Emerson describes Brook Farm as "a perpetual picnic, a French Revolution in small, an Age of Reason in a pattypan" (Works, 10:364). The reference to Lindsay Swift is to his Brook Farm: Its Members, Scholars, and Visitor:s (New York: Macmillan, 1900), 135.
Brook Farm: The Law of Groups and Series
6g
support from the testimony of the Brook Farmers themselves. Amelia Russell, for example, writing many years after the event, describes how the changeover affected her. She had been living in the Cottage, "which was in itself a beautiful little home, and I had become attached to it." With the reorganization, however, it was decreed that this building should be used as a school for the younger pupils: "As it was decidedly the prettiest house on the place, it was thought the youthful mind would be impressed by it and lessons become easier; and it was held that every means should be employed to make the hours of school discipline pleasant, so that the pupils should forget it was not an agreeable recreation." One gathers by the way she expresses herself here that she was not exactly convinced by this reasoning, and indeed she goes on to provide evidence to back up her case. She has seen the state of the desks in the present schoolroom, she tells us, and that of the other fixtures. Their sorry condition recalls the plight of the furnishings in the "academy for both sexes" that she attended in her own youth. The implication, of course, is that good facilities are wasted on the young. Nevertheless, she has no choice but to move to the Pilgrim House, which "was placed in a very barren spot, with no trees near it." She concludes her account of this upheaval: "The new Fourierite system began to be organized, and the poetry of our lives vanished in what we hoped would prove more substantially advantageous."• Charles Crowe, in his excellent biography of George Ripley, places his emphasis slightly differently. He points to the spiritual and intellectual struggles that the community's founding fathers underwent during the years that preceded its establishment, and, for that matter, during the years that followed. He takes it for granted that Ripley and his colleagues were sincere in their desire to place the whole of society on a new basis. But to the extent that they were, or developed into, programmatic thinkers, they lost the authentic Transcendentalist afflatus. "If they embraced Fourierism completely," he asks, "what became of the much-vaunted Transcendental individualism?"' His answer is, very little. In effect, he tracks what amounts to a process of action and reaction operating through time. The Fourieristic Brook Farmers step back into history and attempt to reconstruct the social order which, as Transcendentalist Brook Farmers, they had originally opted out of. Such narrow linearity seems incompatible with the complex interweaving of oppositions that we have already seen in Transcendentalist thinking, and it is not surprising to find Crowe claiming, in a previous article, 4· Amelia Russell, "Home Life of the Brook Farm Association," Atlantic Monthly 42 (November 1878): s6~. 5· Crowe, Ripley, 1 73·
Transcendental Utopias
that the "ideology of the Brook Farm leaders was from the beginning closer to Fourierism than to Transcendentalism. "6 In short, from one point of view Transcendentalism is too frivolous and self-centered to coexist with Fourierism; from the other Fourierism is an alien imposition draining the vitality from Transcendentalism. Miller describes the Brook Farm phalanx as sitting "foreign and forlorn in West Roxbury." 7 Crowe and Miller agree that Transcendentalism and Fourierism do not mix, a view that conveniently builds in the structural tension necessary to account for the demise of the community in 1847. The basis for this sort of analysis is the belief that Transcendentalism is synonymous with individualism. Certainly it is true in the case of the major literary figures the movement produced, Emerson and Thoreau, and I shall in due course be exploring the individualistic dimension of Transcendentalist utopian thinking. Nevertheless, Carl ]. Guarneri, whose book The Utopian Alternative: Fourierism in Nineteenth-Century America is the definitive treatment of its subject, has provided a more balanced viewpoint: "It is not so much that early Brook Farm was closer to Fourierism than to Transcendentalism (one can only say this by equating Transcendentalism with Emerson) but rather that Ripley's 'fraternal' or social version of Transcendentalism meshed remarkably well with Fourierist ideas." He adds, however, that "where Fourierism differed most clearly from early Brook Farm was in its systematic character and the very explicitness of its blueprint." It is my contention that Fourierism's "elaborate taxonomy of human nature" is in fact perfectly compatible with the Transcendentalists' fundamental beliefs. 8 The point I made in my first chapter-indeed, the argument that I wish to pursue throughout this book-is that the essential feature of Transcendental6. Charles Crowe, "Fourierism and the Founding of Brook Farm," Boston Public Library Q}tarterly 12 (April 1960): 87. Morris Hillquit makes the same point in his History of Socialism in the United States (New York: Funk & Wagnalls, 1903), 103. Anne C. Rose, in Transcendentalism as a Social Movement, r8Jo-r85o (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1981), also takes this basic position. She sees a development from individualism to a "social vision" as basically an inevitable next stage in Transcendentalist attempts to "apply religious principles more effectively in modern society" ( 144). 7· Miller, Transcendentalists, 464. Rose, having mentioned the Brook Farmers' appetite for enjoyment, goes on to say rather intriguingly: "This drive to live as fully as possible is the simplest reason why Brook Farm changed in the course of its six-year history ... beginning as an experiment in practical Christianity and becoming a center of reform activity to promote the social science of Charles Fourier" (Transcendentalism, 131). She is, however, simply testifYing to the reserves of energy and enthusiasm of the Brook Farmers, not attempting to establish a structural connection between the two classes of activity. 8. Carl ]. Guarneri, The Utopian Alternative: Fourierism in Nineteenth-Century America (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1991), 52.
Brook Farm: The Law of Gnrnps and Series
ism is not individualism but a belief in the all-embracing principle of seriality, the doctrine of the law of series. Tony Tanner once made a memorable complaint about the movement in these terms: 'There is the leaf-and there are the hidden laws of the universe; and nothing in between. Certainly not society, the notable omission in Emerson."" The point is that what connects the leaf with society is the very existence of those hidden laws of the universe that rank and order the whole substance of things, ensuring a series of intermediate stages between the unit and the totality, each one of which is structured in a way that parallels and fits in with all the others: "unity of law with great diversity of phenomena." As John Sullivan Dwight was to put it in a lecture to the New England Fourier Society he delivered in February 1844, one month after the switch to Fourierism: Was not the law of my individual being appointed with perfect knowledge of all the laws of the whole universe of things, and with full regard to the laws of all other individual natures like myself, so that I in my true self-development must harmonize with others, and not clash? ... We are harmonies, born each into our preestablished place in an infinite system of harmonies; every man is a microcosm, or world in miniature, reflecting all the laws of all things; and each mortal child is as indispensable to the balance and completeness of the world into which he comes so small an atom, as is each planet in the system of our sun, or each sun in the celestial sphere, or each note in the great music of God. 10 In short, what Fourierism had to offer was not the replacement of poetry with substantiality, as Amelia Russell claimed, but a substantial rendering of the poetic vision that was at the heart of Transcendentalism from its early days. It turns a mystical intuition of a patterned world into a practical program. In his Dial article on Fourier Emerson says, perhaps with tongue in cheek, that "mechanics were pushed so far as fairly to meet spiritualism. "ll As George Ripley put it in a lecture on Fourier, "Experience has shown, that it is among those whose souls are most exquisitely susceptible to the sublime harmonies of sound, his g. Tony Tanner, The Reign of Wonder (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1965), 37-38. 10. John Sullivan Dwight, Association in Its Connection with Education (Boston: Benjamin H. Greene, 1844), 4 (delivered Boston, February 29, 1844). 11. Ralph Waldo Emerson, "Fourierism and the Socialists," Dial3 (July 1842): 87.
Transcendental Utopias
vast system of the Harmonies of the Universe, has found its most enlightened and earnest adherents. "12 There is a paradox involved in achieving a picture of Fourier's structure in its pure form. To revert to Jakobson's terminology, the language must inevitably approach the condition of "blab," since it must be a language that expresses "only the framework, the connecting links of communication. "13 Nevertheless, we can catch a glimpse of that framework in Fourier's Traite de ['association domestique-agricole: 14
Pr(P.
Post. '
f :nn.\.
Cis.
LLTRA.
Trans. bTRA.
simple de has I Scric