415 82 38MB
English Pages [320] Year 1966
THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY
THE SEVENTEENTH by
EMILE ,BREHIER
TRANSLATED BY WADE BASKIN
THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO PRESS CHICAGO AND LONDON
677
H
210153
Originally published in 1938 as Histoire de
La Philosophic moderne.
©
The
I:
la
philosophic:
Le dix-septieme
siecle.
1938, Presses Universitaires de France
present bibliography has been revised
and enlarged
to
include recent publications. These have been supplied by the translator and others.
Library of Congress Catalog Card Number: 63-20912 The University of Chicago Press, Chicago London
&
The
University of Toronto Press, Toronto 5, Canada Translation 1966 by The University of Chicago
©
All rights reserved. Published 1966 Printed in the United States of America
WW CONTENTS
i
General Characteristics of the Seventeenth Century
ii
Francis Bacon and Experimental Philosophy in
Descartes and Cartesianism
iv
v
126
Thomas Hobbes Spinoza
vi
vii
Leibniz
141
155
Malebranche
viii
ix
Pascal
46
197
225
John Loc\e and English Philosophy
x
Bayle and Fontenelle INDEX
307
292
267
21
i
—
GENERAL CHARACTERISTICS OF THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY i
The Conception
of
Human
Nature:
Authority and Absolutism
no century has
exhibited less confidence than the
seventeenth century in the spontaneous forces of unbridled nature.
Where
could
we
find a
more wretched
the hapless victim of conflicting passions political thinkers
point
and moralists
man
portrait of natural
—than
that provided by
of the seventeenth century?
On
this
Hobbes agreed with La Rochefoucauld and La Rochefoucauld
with the Jansenist Nicole: Hobbes held that
men
in the state of
nature were sinister beasts of prey that could be subdued only by
an absolute
and the
ruler,
any charitable or
were unwilling
impulse in
altruistic
concupiscence could have
The
Jansenists
its
men
to
admit that
given, through sin, to
source outside divine grace.
seventeenth century was also the century of the Counter-
reformation and of absolutism.
The Counterreformation
eradicated
the pagan elements of the Renaissance and brought into full a Catholicism
and
souls of
aware of
men. The
hundred schools
its
obligation to offer guidance to the
Jesuit Society,
minds
which had more than two
in France, provided educators, spiritual directors,
and missionaries. Thomism universally taught i
bloom
and
as
formulated by the Jesuit Suarez was
finally
supplanted the doctrine of Melanch-
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
2
The Counter-
thon, even in the universities of Protestant countries.
Rome and drew
reformation was instigated in private efforts.
The French
English royalty was Anglican.
support from
its
was Gallican and the
royalty itself
the rulers of France did not
Still,
shrink from using violent means to assure religious unity, and the
blow came when the revocation of the Edict of Nantes simply
final
did away with Protestantism.
The
absolutism of the king was not the power of a strong indi-
from
vidual to exact obedience
by violent means;
tige or
his subjects
was a
it
long minorities
when omnipotent
lute
more than
tion of
God,
is
imposed
it
by divine right but
exercised
who
benefits.
en-
during
in the
name
imposed is
abso-
subjugated to his task by
elec-
the exact opposite of the Renaissance tyrant.
by people
who
tolerated in religion
and
understood their necessity as well as their
Rigid rules constituted not thraldom but support, and with-
out them
man would
in his Essays. ritual
it
origin,
and the king, who
rights,
is first
Thus harsh measures were accepted and in politics
—even
it
ministers exercised
phenomenon, of divine
of the prince. This social duties even
phenomenon which
social
—independently of the person who
dured
through personal pres-
was
his
fall,
disjointed
Ceremony was
his
and uncertain,
guide in
Montaigne
social relations just as
guide in church.
There were instances of
resistance,
however, and they were
quent. In England, absolutism grounded lided with the
like
common
will
on divine
and succumbed;
fre-
right twice col-
in France, religious
unity was established only at the price of periods of persecution.
Throughout the seventeenth century Holland served the persecuted gal,
the Socinians
France
—but
endangered. its
from
it
all
countries
—the Jews from
from Poland, and
later
was a precarious refuge where
The
Catholic religion was
itself
as a refuge for
Spain and Portu-
the Protestants their lives
from
were often
threatened in France,
adopted country, by the quarrel of the Jansenists and the Moli-
nists
and, at the end of the century, by the
non's mysticism. Behind these
known
stir
facts lay
raised by
hidden an
Mme
Guy-
intellectual
ferment which was translated into thousands of incidents, books, or
CHARACTERISTICS OF THE CENTURY
3
lampoons
now
forgotten. Declarations in support of
freedom and
tolerance did not begin in the eighteenth century; they were heard
continually throughout the seventeenth century, especially in Eng-
land and in Holland, and the century drew to a close with a bitter
who
debate between Bossuet,
and
supported the divine right of kings,
Jurieu, the Protestant statesman
who defended
the sovereignty
of the people.
On
closer examination,
however,
we
find that these protestations
and debates bear the mark of the century they were not penned by :
individualists concerned only with
Here we should note tions of the century
promoting
their private opinions.
most
characteristic produc-
that one of the
was the
De
Hugo who men even
jure belli ac pacts (1625) of
Grotius (1583-1645), the author of the doctrine of natural law,
claimed he had discovered universal laws binding on
when
they resort to the use of force.
reason determines whether a
war
is
Not
all
individuals but impersonal
just or unjust,
whether a prince
has the right to impose a religion on his subjects, and what
Where
legitimate scope of his authority.
is
the
Machiavelli saw conflicts
between individual forces that could be resolved only through violence, Grotius
saw
clearly defined relations based
on law. Natural
commands or prohibits an action depending on whether such action is in harmony or disharmony with the nature of rational beings. The rule is in no way arbitrary and
law
is
a rule of reason that
could not be changed by tive law,
which
is
God
himself. Natural law
established either by
God
is
joined to posi-
(in matters of positive
religion) or by the sovereign (in matters of civil legislation); the
one great rule of positive law the
same token, within these
is
not to contradict natural law. By
limits, it is the
law of nature
to respect
positive law. Consequently, Grotius' system leads generally to the
conclusion that the established powers must be respected. For ex-
ample,
it
does not recognize the right of the people to
sovereign; indeed, the reason
why
the people
resist their
formed a nation and
weak to prevent them from
accepted a sovereign was that the individuals were too subsist alone.
Moreover, there was nothing to
giving their sovereign absolute control over their lives
—the control
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
4
a master has over his slaves.
The tendency
of his
ously to justify rationally certain positive laws
men
purpose of making
obvi-
is
—the laws of warfare,
Law
punishment, property, and sovereignty.
argument
not for the
exists
independent of each other but for the
purpose of uniting them. Although Grotius pleaded for tolerance
toward
all
atheists
and
who
those
to
natural religion
The
he drew the
positive religions,
is
when
to
as natural law.
question of tolerance was posed in the same
made by men who thought
spirit.
In Eng-
were of two kinds:
land, for example, pleas for tolerance
they were
came
it
denied the immortality of the soul:
binding
as
line
that they
either
were rediscovering
reason through a natural religion comprehensive enough to unite all
churches and bring an end to dissension, or they were directed
toward freedom of interpretation of the
Bible, "the only religion of
the Protestants," according to Chillingworth. Associated with pleas of the
De
men
kind were
veritate (1628)
versies all
first
like
Herbert of Cherbury,
the opinions of the doctors, or reject
know how separating common universal,
These
to choose."
necessary,
common
in his
advocated a means of ending religious contro-
men embrace
and "the stubbornness with which wretched
do not
who
*
The
them
choice
—which were certain—from
notions
and
wholesale, as
was
to be
if
they
made by
primitive, independent,
adventitious
all
beliefs.
notions constituted a veritable credo which predi-
cated a sovereign
power
that worship consisted
that
must be worshiped and which taught
mainly in a virtuous
life,
that vices
must
be expiated through repentance, and that vices would be punished after death just as virtue
would be rewarded
that established universal peace,
—a
natural religion
though not without a trenchant
criticism of the illusion of "private revelations"
and
for salvation.
same
At
the end of the century
Locke
especially of
was necessary
the notion that divine grace, individually bestowed, still
clung to the
notions.
Associated with pleas of the second kind were
men who
pre-
served the spirit of free thought inherited from the Reformation. 1
1639 edition,
p. 52.
CHARACTERISTICS OF THE
5
But, according to
its
CE
N1 U
defenders, free thought
RY
had the
sole function
of eradicating gradually, through independent criticism, everything
Bossuet called "private opinions" and "variations," with the result that
was but another means of arriving
it
the route chosen
was
different
thought together with the
from
that of authority.
conflicts that
it
though
at "catholicity"
Freedom
of
implied seemed to Milton
{Areopagitica, written in 1644, after Cromwell's victory) to be the
must be won by continuous progress;
prerequisite of a truth that
the waters of truth "flow not in a perpetual progression, they
if
muddy
sicken into a
pool of conformity and tradition." Truth, of
course, "turns herself into
shapes except her own, and perhaps
all
tunes her voice according to the time," but this of skepticism:
"Truth
is
is
not an instance
strong next to the Almighty."
Whereas tolerance was linked
to a strong religious
2
sentiment,
which united men, the skepticism of the freethinkers led gious intolerance velli
—another
championed a
path to unity.
describes a state church that
state,
in
Commonwealth
would be
clergy in the universities. Conversely,
background that there emerged
to reli-
Machia-
disciples of
Hobbes provides us with
state religion.
example, and James Harington in his (1656)
The
it
good
a
Oceana
of
controlled by the
was against a
religious
England the idea of a
secular
completely independent of religion; at the beginning of the
century the Anabaptists proclaimed that a national church to which
belonged from birth contradicted
all
Holy
Spirit,
Despite
all
and they preached
faith, a
personal gift of the
revolt against intolerant princes.
these conflicts, advocates of a natural religion
revelation, defenders of tolerance,
and
3
and
apologists of a state religion
had a common goal: unity capable of binding individuals together and keeping them together. Socinianism, the
and England
movement
after the
that spread
from Poland
end of the sixteenth century,
to
also rejected
everything in religion subject to controversy and dissension. 2
Quoted by Denis Saurat, Milton
et le
Named
materialisme chretien en Angleterre (Paris,
—Trans.]
1928), p. 206. [English follows the Areopagitica. 3 Freund, Die Idee der Toleranz im England 1927), pp. 224-25.
Holland
der grossen
Revolution
(Halle,
—
6
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY who fled to Poland in The Socinians denied the
after
Faustus Socinus (Sozzini), an Italian
1579,
it
was
like a revival of
Arianism.
and the sacramental value of the
Trinity, the divinity of Christ,
Eucharist and infant baptism; furthermore, they denied the theory
which divine
of atonement according to
only through the suffering of God's
by eliminating
religion
all its
own
justice
son.
mysteries and
could be fulfilled
Thus
its
they simplified
supernatural side
not because they refused to base religion on the revelation of Scripture but because "they think that they are not excluding reason but
rather including
it
when
cient for salvation."
And
their plea for tolerance,
"With
under the same law
who
The Arminians after the
Synod
of
and
bond
that
hold different opinions
concerning divine things," they wrote to the (1614), "comes the collapse
suffi-
as the necessary con-
the severance of the
those
all
is
was joined
to the rationality of beliefs
which they posited
dition of social stability:
unites
Holy Scripture
they state that the
states
of
Holland
retrogression of everything."
or Remonstrants,
Dort (1618-19),
who
broke with Calvinism
tried in the
same way
to eradicate
from the theory of grace every element of mystery, everything incompatible with
human
notions of justice. Arminius (1 560-1 609)
denied the "absolute decree" of
God who,
according to Calvin,
predestines the salvation of the souls he elects; against
Gomarus (1563-1641)
that each
man was
and he argued responsible for
whatever sanctions he might incur.
Using a
different approach, the Catholics
seeking unity. in the
They found
unbroken
tradition
it
also
were diligently
only in divinely inspired authority,
and
discipline of the
Church (whereas
the other sects under discussion grounded their search
The
on reason).
debate about grace, which pitted Jansenists against Molinists
after
1640,
was a debate between theologians who accused one
another of being unfaithful to tradition or of breaching discipline.
Their
conflict focused attention
on
the Christian
life
itself
rather
than on theoretical discussions. In addition, the Jesuits adhered to the policy of transferring the
debate from the domain of doctrine and
dogma
to that of discipline.
CHARACTERISTICS OF THE CENTURY
7
They had Port Royal condemned not for supporting dogma concerning grace but for resisting the authority and of the king. Richelieu kept
a particular of the pope
Cyran in prison in the
St.
fortress
of Vincennes after 1638, at the instigation of the Jesuits, because St.
Cyran had defended the
The main
rights of the secular hierarchy.
incident of the struggle hinged
on the question
of the
1649 the syndic of the faculty,
of spiritual authority. In
limits
Father Cornet, presented five propositions concerning efficacious grace to the faculty, hoping to have
them condemn the doctrine
advanced by Jansen and his supporters, but without naming
its
condemned by Pope Innocent although it was accepted without
author. These five propositions were
X
in
But
1653.
his
decision
protest
by Arnauld and
wished
to
—did not
go even further and have the
from
as extracts
"Are these fact,
—
his friends
who
five propositions identified
Jansen's Augustinus. Thus, to the question of law,
was added the question
five propositions heretical?"
"Are they Jansen's?" The
lished only
satisfy the Jesuits,
on the
validity of the
basis of authority,
law could be
but the validity of
facts
of
estab-
could
be established only by experience. Consequently, in 1654 a convocation of bishops decided that the five propositions were in the
Augustinus, not because they found them there but because the
seemed
bull of 1653
to
attribute
them
to
Jansen. In
1655
Alexander VII renewed the condemnation by treating those
Pope
who
did not believe that the propositions were Jansen's as "children of iniquity."
and the
A
formulary was drawn up setting
facts;
it
was
to
be signed by
religious orders in France. In 1665 a
of the formulary
all
new
down
clerics
and members of
bull prescribed the signing
and prohibited any accompanying
nuns of Port Royal kept protesting
both the law
that,
restriction.
The
although they submitted
completely to the pope with respect to the law, they could not affirm the existence of a fact that they
were not in a position
to verify
independently.
With respect to the heart of the dispute, the theory of grace, the aim of the Port-royalists (gratuitously called Jansenists) was to direct man's attention to his utter helplessness when isolated and sep-
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
8
from the universal source of
arated
he
is
being.
all
Man
and what he can accomplish only through
power of
his will to
pursue the good
is
The
the influence of efficacious grace.
can learn what
and the
revelation,
realized fully only under
theory of efficacious grace
brings out clearly the deep-rooted hostility between the naturalistic
humanism
power of human
of antiquity proof of the tions
governing the Christian
tune, for
which claimed
of the Renaissance,
we must
whatever was
and
nature,
wonders
and the condi-
But the new emphasis was oppor-
life.
note that Jansenism
vital
to find in the
and even enhanced
left intact
fruitful in the intellectual current that
issued
from the sixteenth century. Nicole
object
is
not linked in any
way
had
said of geometry: "Its
to concupiscence."
4
Thus
there
—knowledge of things in the mateinterests have no part —where
a whole sphere of knowledge
is
world, astronomy, physics
rial
and where the
light of nature,
selfish
undimmed by
conceded that a observing the
society,
maxims
sin,
allows
man
to
Arnauld went even further and
discover the truth for himself.
whatever
its
nature, could not exist without
which are rooted in a natural law
of justice
and of which man has innate knowledge. The
Jansenists,
still
hostile
in this respect to Scholasticism, accepted every particle of Renais-
sance innatism; they were, in their
own
way, true humanists.
Truths revealed by the light of nature and conduct inspired by
it,
In
1
however, cannot justify us in the eyes of
641
Arnauld refuted the book of La Mothe
God and le
save us.
On
Vayer,
the
Virtue of the Pagans, in which the author marshaled telling examples
from antiquity
Christ.
we
if
5
Pagan
to
virtues
prove the are sterile
futility
and
of
illusory,
salvation
through
Arnauld
replied,
seek out their cause: ambition, vanity, the search for inner
satisfaction
in our
—in short, the fundamental sin that consists in believing
own
self-sufficiency.
This
is
true because nothing
more
closely
resembles the effects of charity than the effects of self-love. "In states
where
man 4
5
[charity]
cannot enter because true religion
is
excluded, a
can live as peacefully, as securely, and as comfortably as
Quoted by
J.
Ibid., p. 137.
Laporte,
La Doctrine de
la
Grace chez Arnauld,
p.
in,
n. 74.
if
—
CHARACTERISTICS OF THE CENTURY
9
he were in a republic of the
main
ity,
kindness, moderation.
We
1665.
tive to pity, I
what he
recall
would do
believe that
and
my
The
What
Maxims were
celebrated
were completely
I
same views
Jansenists adopted the
am
written in
not very sensi-
insensitive to
one ought even .
go
to .
with expressing compassion without actually feeling
better
commentary could
If the Jansenists
were
on
there be
right, there
is
Still,
also
hold that one must be
also
I
I
much com-
so far as to express
but
.
it.
and
best to comfort a person in distress,
passion for his suffering satisfied
because self-love "imitates
is
said about himself: "I
wish
I
This
and produces "human decency," humil-
actions of charity"
La Rochefoucauld, whose
as
6
saints."
it."
7
Jansenist views!
no morality, no
virtue other
than Christian morality and Christian virtue. These must be separated
from worldly
which has
life,
They
support in nature or society. sort of
grace
own
its
they find no a
transmutation of our will under the influence of divine
—an
irresistible influence, yet
rather fortifies, free will
one that does not destroy, but
God and
the soul, instead
realities external to
each other, fuse
if it is
of being two complementary
true that
and interpenetrate under the influence of
The Conception
II
rules;
are possible only through
of External Nature:
Galileo, Gassendi,
Thus man's
grace.
and Atomism
idea of his
own
The and gave way to
new
nature took on a
individualistic ardor of the Renaissance subsided
form.
the belief that the individual
must be guided by order and unity
unity grounded on reason or
on
authority.
Man's image of external
nature had undergone a similar change: the taneity that
men
like
Bruno saw
rules of
mechanism; only
mained,
still
6
P.
7
in nature gave
(Paris,
way
faint traces of Renaissance
represented by Campanella.
Nicole, Essais de
ed. C. Jourdain
exuberant spon-
vital,
morale, in
Not
only was
CEuvres phllosophiqiies
1845), P- J 8i. Autobiographical sketch printed in 1658.
et
to the rigid
animism life
re-
withheld
morales de Nicole,
—
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
10
from nature; Descartes even withheld living
being which he made
stantial
from the
so to speak,
it,
into a simple machine. Aristotle's sub-
forms were condemned even in the universities. At Leiden,
men were wondering
even before 1618, "really distinct
from matter and
about the nature of beings
yet material, whether a part of
matter changes into form, whether form pre-exists in matter, as a
bench
pre-exists in the
plank from which
made."
it is
8
Prevalent everywhere was a mechanistic conception that eliminated
from nature any semblance of
vital spontaneity.
The
tend-
ency was dominant in Galileo, Hobbes, and Descartes as well as in
more obscure philosophers
who
Gassendi, Basson, and Berigard,
like
revived the teachings of Democritus and Epicurus.
was not
Galileo (1564-1642)
actually the author of a theory of
groundwork
universal mechanics, but he laid the
for such a theory
by creating a physico-mathematical science of nature that would
accommodate diverse phenomena.
He
did not say what things
were, but he proved that mathematics with
its
triangles, circles,
and
geometric figures was the sole language capable of deciphering
book of nature.
the
He
was more
interested in the
method
of
deciphering nature than in studying the nature of living beings;
method draws together under
the "compositive" or synthetic single mathematical
formula a great number of observed
a
facts
the formulas that he discovered concerning the laws of gravitation, for instance
—and
the "resolutive" or
possible for us to deduce arate facts.
law
For the
first
from
time
as a functional relation;
would keep pace with the philosopher a tion
analytic
method makes it number of sep-
these laws a great
we
find a clear, pure idea of natural
henceforth the progress of mathematics
that of physics,
new manner
and
this
would impose on
of posing the problem of the rela-
between the mind, the author of mathematics, and nature,
which the mind
interprets
through mathematics. Furthermore, the
new methods were
possible only by virtue of the exact measure-
ment
phenomena, and the numerical data provided
of individual
by experiment were the only data that applied 8
Quoted
in Bayle's Dictionary, art.
Heidanus.
to the discovery of
CHARACTERISTICS OF THE CENTURY
II
was led
laws. Galileo therefore
ured as the only true
reality.
to consider that
Thus we
which can be meas-
him
see in
a revival of the
ideas of Democritus: sensible qualities, such as color
we
are not in things, for
sound and Galileo
from the mind,
heat, apart
was inclined
and
smell,
can imagine things without these qualities;
for the
are but
same reason
modes
of motion.
to favor the corpuscular
theory of matter although he did not accept
He
as proved.
it
also
supported the theory of Copernicus and tried to find experimental proofs of the theory; and
we
recall that
he was forced by the
Inquisition to renounce his opinion before the
We
see, then, that
Holy
Office (1632).
Galileo treated universal mechanics as a technical
discovery and not as a necessity grounded in the nature of
and of
things; that
is
why he
allowed
many
traces
mind
of the old
elements to subsist in his thought: Aristotle's distinction between natural
and
motion, for example, and the spontaneous
violent
tendency of the
stars to
move
in circles
(which implicitly denies 9
the principle of inertia, the basis of universal mechanics).
The
atomistic
and
anti-Aristotelian
movement which emerged
in France at the beginning of the seventeeth century in fact issued
and which
from the atomism of the Renaissance showed the same
tendency. Sebastian Basson, in a book which even has an aggressive title
(Philosophiae
naturalis
adversus Aristotelem
quibus abstrusa veterum physiologia restauratur, rores solidis
rationibus refelluntur) , offers
XII, in
libri
et Aristotelis er-
us an image of the
universe based on elementary particles of a different nature: they are surfaces as in the Timaeus, not corpuscles as in Democritus.
These atoms, aggregated in the form of bodies, do not void but are immersed in a
fluid, continuous ether
through which the divine power
transmitted.
is
exist in a
—the
The
medium
hypothesis of
continuous ether obviously discouraged acceptance of the notion of physical mechanics.
Claude Berigard
(1 578-1 663),
a French
professor
in
Padua,
published in the Cir cuius Pisanus (1643) a series of commentaries 9
On
45-78.
the last point,
cf.
A. Koyre, Galilee
et la
hi
d'inertie
(Paris,
1939), pp.
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
12
on Aristotelian physics
which he contrasted the
in
corpuscular physics of Anaxagoras.
number
with the
latter
conceived of an infinite
of qualitatively different corpuscles. Like Descartes,
in contrast to Democritus,
motion
He
as a
and
he accepted the plenum and explained
continuous ring of bodies each of which immediately
replaced the preceding one (Anaxagoras' system of physics was of
course annular). nien, a ible
The Democritus
reviviscens (1646) of Jean
French professor in Pavia, posited atoms that were
and
yet capable of
Mag-
indivis-
changing their shape. Here he was guided
by Epicurus' theory of minima, according
to
which the atom was
not simple but composed of very small particles which, in their relative
to
arrangement, produced the shape of the atom. Magnien added
the hypothesis the notion that the inner arrangement
might
change even though the number of minima remained identical
That
in a particular atom.
mechanics
is
moving cause
was reluctant
he, too,
to accept universal
demonstrated by the fact that he searched for the of atoms in sympathetic attraction or in the tendency
of atoms to join together to produce a body with a determinate essence. It
is
strange that not one of these atomists saw collision
as the cause of
motion; Basson's ether, Berigard's vortex, Magnien's
sympathetic attraction
all
show how
indistinct
was the idea
of
mechanism when Descartes gave it a new formulation. to Lucretius and at the same time more closely linked intellectual trend of the time was the atomism of Pierre
universal
Nearer to the
Gassendi (1592-1655), whose detailed explanations of natural phe-
nomena long
rivaled those of Descartes. Gassendi, provost of the
cathedral at Digne,
championed astronomical observation and the
system of Copernicus.
wrote during his
by the
corresponded with Galileo, to the
Holy
Office: "I
am
whom
he
deeply disturbed
fate that awaits you, O you greatest glory of the century; Holy See decides something contrary to your belief, endure
if
the
it
as befits a sage.
that
He
trial at
May you
you have sought
at least live secure in the
after truth."
knowledge
From Epicureanism he
the sensualist theory of knowledge.
He
innatism and especially for the idea of
accepted
censured Descartes for his
God
he professed
to have,
13 since
CHARACTERISTICS OF THE CENTURY God remains incomprehensible to a mind enslaved by sensible To Herbert of Cherbury he objected that investigation into
images.
the inner nature of things results
know, and
to
whatever
indispensable to
is
from intemperance
human knowledge ought life
—that
in our desire
to be restricted to
to the external qualities
is,
under the senses; only the creator of things can
that fall
nature.
that
10
His atomism bears no
trace of originality;
ism of Lucretius and of Epicurus' Letters ferent shapes, falling through the void.
him: Gassendi makes gravity
—the
—invisible
know
it is
their
the atom-
atoms of
Only two
traits
dif-
identify
motion inherent
principle of
in the atom, "a propensity to motion, unengendered, innate, im-
—something given
possible to lose"
move through them have the That
is
the void at the effect of
on the
speed,
velocity following collision
collisions
it
follows that no body
is
at rest;
rapid but very slight internal motions. that the universe
is
between
mechan-
dependent not only
velocity of the colliding bodies but also
any case
is
and
their direction, not their motion.
diametrically opposed to the principles of Cartesian
which makes
ics,
same
changing
atom by God. All atoms
to the
on
their mass. In
apparent
The second
rest hides
very
distinctive trait
considered as a completely integrated, regular
whole, which cannot be the result of a fortuitous concourse of
atoms but can be explained only by an omnipotent God. Super-
imposed on Epicureanism, then, finality.
is
theology
a
Gassendi even superimposed a
introduces
that
theory
spiritualistic
upon
Epicurus' materialistic theory of the soul which he accepted in entirely:
the effective, vegetative,
and
sensitive
soul
is,
its
in effect,
merely a very subtle and tenuous body, and sensation, for example, is
adequately explained by the impression
made on
this substance
by the idola emitted by each body; but above the soul that perishes with the body of reason,
A
is
an immaterial substance capable of
and of freedom.
similar combination of mechanistic
and
spiritualistic theories,
so unfaithful to the authentic spirit of Epicurus,
of the period. Nature 10
Opera,
self-reflection,
III,
413.
was
was abandoned, turned over
characteristic to
its
own
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
14
mechanism; penetrated
was forsaken by the mind that had studied
it
it,
and found in
more apparent
in Descartes
no
it
and
it,
The consequences were
support.
Hobbes.
in
The Organization of Intellectual Life: Academies and Scientific Gatherings
in
The
were translated into profound
aspirations of the century
disgust for the sectarian struggles that
upon the
sance. Meditating
the rule.
La Mothe
le
and
Skepticism" to be the joint dismissal of
both of
Aristotle,
was no longer
Vayer considered one of the most important
results of his "Christian
Plato
had inflamed the Renais-
texts of Plato or Plotinus
whom
contradict theology, thus leaving
"the soul of the Christian Skeptic like a field that has been cleared
and
rid of
bad
plants."
n
Distaste for sectarianism
was matched
by a marked reaction against the study of Greek. Except
Port
at
Royal the course of studies did not include Greek because of the
pagan
spirit
Moravian
associated with
it.
Comenius
teacher, did not include
nor did he see
to include
fit
Greek
(i 592-1 670),
the great
in his plan of studies,
dangerous Latin authors. "With the
exception of Seneca, Epictetus, Plato, and other such virtuous and
honorable masters, he would like to see other pagan authors banished from Christian schools."
12
Reduced, or almost reduced, to
Latin, studies of the ancients were intended solely to shape literary taste, to contribute,
ing,
and
by means of spirited statements, to moral
to give students practice in
language. That
under the
Jesuits
use in educating
at the
scientific
his classical studies
—in
other words, nothing that might be of any
him
as a philosopher.
philosophers viewed erudition reached
and
using the current
what Descartes retained from
is
train-
The contempt with which its
limit with Malebranche,
end of the century Locke eliminated Greek from
his
plan of education.
On 11
account of
its
sectarian particularism, therefore, Greco-Latin
Prose chagrine, in (Euvres completes (Dresden, 1756), V, 299-318. Heyberger, Jean Amos Comenius (Paris, 1928), p. 146.
"Anna
—
CHARACTERISTICS OF THE CENTURY
15
antiquity posed as great a danger to science as to faith. Philosophy
has as the object of
search true universality.
its
Its
exemplar
is
found in mathematical and experimental techniques developed
known
without reference to any
Harvey, and a century
philosophy. Cavalieri, Fermat, and
Ambroise Pare and Bernard
earlier
were independent of the philosophers of
their
Palissy,
time just as Ar-
chimedes, Apollonius, and Hero of Alexandria were independent of their Stoic contemporaries. It less to intellectual
and the
obvious that nothing contributed
progress in mathematics and the natural sciences
mind
than the theories of the
ment
is
practice of dialectic,
elaborated during the Middle Ages
which was intended
In exposition, philosophy was stripped of ratus. all
to reveal agree-
or disagreement between opinions.
Discourses,
were
literary
essays,
meditations,
all its
technical appa-
conversations,
dialogues
forms borrowed from Christian or pagan antiquity
and revived by sixteenth-century humanists. Direct and unencumbered by scholarly discussion, these forms found favor with seventeenth-century thinkers. Descartes wanted people to read his Principles for the first
time just as they would read a novel. Like
Montaigne, Bacon (a great admirer of Machiavelli) wrote Essays in
which he
and
as a
set
man
The same
down
fully his experience as a
generality
was manifested even in the
who were anything who expended so much energy
great philosophers, courtier
of the court
French gentleman
who
great English lord
and a frequent
who had
lives
of the
but academics: Bacon, a
upholding in judicial
in
practice the doctrine of royal prerogative of
noza, a Jew
man
of the world.
James
I;
Descartes, a
lived in seclusion; Hobbes, secretary of a
on the Continent;
Spi-
been expelled from the synagogue and
who
traveler
earned his living by polishing lenses; Malebranche, an Oratorian; Leibniz, minister of a petty
always
filled
with vast
German
political projects;
prince,
whose mind was
and Locke, a good,
liberal,
middle-class Englishman.
Outside and remote from the universities
were formed, private ones
new
intellectual circles
at first, like the society of scholars
and
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
l6
philosophers the
who
gathered around Father Mersenne, a
Minim Order and
a friend
Pascal said of Mersenne:
member
and correspondent of Descartes.
"He was
responsible for several outstand-
ing discoveries which probably would never have been
he had not stimulated other scholars."
13
Then came
of Sciences (1658), offshoot of private gatherings
Montmor the
two
Lincei
the
made if Academy
which began with
and were attended by Roberval, Gassendi, and
in 1636
Pascals.
of
14
There was a
Academy, founded
similar development in Italy: the
in 1603,
welcomed Galileo in
1616;
and
the Cimento, founded in Florence in 1657, maintained relations
with the Parisian Academy and communicated
some of
its
studies.
15
it
the results of
In England the Royal Society of
London drew
to
together, after 1645, all those interested in "philosophical matters,
anatomy, geometry,
physics,
astronomy,
navigation,
magnetism,
chemistry, mechanics, experiments with nature." Their rules stated that "the society will not subscribe to any hypothesis,
any system,
any doctrine concerning the principles of natural philosophy, proposed or mentioned by any philosopher, ancient or modern." than anything thoughts
else,
they refused to risk passing off their private
common
as
notions;
experience
alone
Finally, in the last year of the century Leibniz in Berlin that later
became the Academy of
The voluminous correspondence Leibniz (their
More
letters
of
to the vigor of intellectual exchanges.
But
decide.
founded a
16
society
Science.
men
were often veritable
must
like
treatises)
Descartes
and
bears witness
in the second half of the
century there also came into being a press devoted to scientific
news: in France, the Journal des Savants (1644) and the Nouvelles de la Republique des Lettres, a review which was founded by Bayle (1684) 13
and which
later (1687-1709)
became the Histoire des Ou-
du P. Mersenne. The first two were published by Mme Paul Tannery (Paris, 1933; Beauchesne, 1937). Publication of the remaining volumes has been assured by C. de Waard, in collaboration with Lenoble and Rochot. Volume V (1635) This volumes
activity
(letters
is
revealed in the Correspondance
from 1617
to 1630)
appeared in 1959.
"Alfred Maury, Les Academies d'autrefois (Paris, 1864). 15 A. Maugain, ttude sur revolution intellectuelle de Vltalie (Paris, 1909). 18 P. Florian, "De Bacon a Newton," Revue de Philosophie, 1914.
CHARACTERISTICS OF THE CENTURY
17
wages des Savants, edited by
Protestants. Finally, in Leipzig, Leib-
niz founded the Acta eruditorum (1682).
Nothing from the past compares with collective quest for a universal
years between 1620
and yet human
and 1650 were
the
movement: Bacon published
the
De
dignitate et
this tenacious, continuous,
truth.
The
thirty
decisive years in the history of
the
Novum organum
(1620) and
augmentis scientiarum (1623); Galileo wrote
Dialogo (1632) and his Discorsi (1638); Descartes published the Discourse on the Method (1637), Meditations (1641), and Prin-
his
ciples (1644)
;
the philosophy of law and political philosophy were
taken up by Grotius
(De
cive, 1642)
.
of the Renaissance
erudition
jure belli ac pads, 1625)
and by Hobbes
—which had always, to some degree, confused —had definitely ended. An emergent
and philosophy
tionalism set
point of
(De
All these works indicate that the humanistic phase
its
itself to
consider
divine origin but
ra-
human
reason not from the stand-
from the standpoint of
its
positive
activity.
Would
reason be the principle of order, of organization, sought
Would it be capable, if human knowledge and even, beyond that, of introducing a social bond between all men? This question accounts for the enduring interest of that new upsurge by
all
during the seventeenth century?
"properly managed," of advancing
of intellectual activity.
Bibliography
and Anthologies
Useful Translations
The English Philosophers from Bacon
New
to Mill.
Edited by
Edwin A.
Burth.
York, 1939.
The European Philosophers from Beardsley.
New
Descartes to Nietzsche. Edited by
Monroe C.
York, i960.
Philosophers Spea\ for Themselves. Edited by T. V. Smith and Marjorie Grene. New ed. 4 vols. Chicago, 1957. Vol. Ill, From Descartes to Loc\e. Philosophic Classics. Edited by Walter N.J., 1961. Vol. II,
The Philosophy
of
Bacon
New
and Studies
Histories Burtt, E. A. ed.
New
Kaufmann. 2
vols.
Englewood
and Seventeenth Centuries. Edited by
York, 1966.
of Seventeenth
The Metaphysical Foundations
of
Century Thought Modern
Physical Science. 2d
York, 1955.
Butterfield, Herbert.
The
Origins of
1962. Butterfield, Herbert, et
al.
A
Cliffs,
Kant.
Sixteenth
the
Richard H. Popkin.
to
Modern
Science. Rev. ed.
New
York,
Short History of Science. Garden City, N.Y.,
1959.
The Problem of Knowledge. Translated by William H. Woglom and Charles W. Hendel. New Haven, Conn., 1950. Clark, G. N. The Seventeenth Century. 2d ed. Oxford, 1947. Copleston, Frederick C. A History of Philosophy. 7 vols. London, 1946-62. Vol. IV, Descartes to Leibniz; Vol. V, Hobbes to Hume. Crombie, A. C. Augustine to Galileo: The History of Science, A.D. 400-1650. London, 1952. Dampier, W. C. A History of Science and Its Relations with Philosophy and Cassirer, Ernst.
Religion. 4th ed. Cambridge, 1949. Dibon, Paul. La philosophic neerlandaise au siecle d'or. Amsterdam, 1954. Dunning, W. A. A History of Political Theories from Luther to Montesquieu. New York, 1905. Flint, R. Philosophy of History in Europe. London, 1874.
Gilson, Etienne,
Kant.
New
Hall, A. R.
The
and Thomas Langan. Modern Philosophy from Descartes York, 1963. Scientific Revolution, 1 500-1800.
18
2d
ed.
London,
1962.
to
CHARACTERISTICS OF THE CENTURY
10,
Hazard,
The European Mind,
P.
1953.
A
Hoffding, H. Laporte,
History of
New
vols.
J.
1680-1715. Translated by
}.
L.
Modern Philosophy. Translated by
York, 1950. Etudes d'histoire de
la
philosophic francaise au
May. London, B. E. Meyer. 2
XVH e
siecle. Paris,
1951.
Lovejoy, Arthur O.
The Great Chain
of Being. Reprint: Cambridge, Mass.,
1948.
Popkin, Richard H. The History of Scepticism from Erasmus to Descartes. New York, 1964.
The Career
Randall, John H.
Enlightenment.
New
from the Middle Ages
of Philosophy
to the
York, 1962.
History of Political Theory. Rev. ed. New York, 1950. Procedures and Metaphysics: A Study in the Philosophy of Mathematical and Physical Science in the Sixteenth and Seventeenth
A
Sabine, G. H.
Strong, E.
W.
Centuries. Berkeley, Calif., 1936.
Cberweg, F. Grundriss der Geschichte der Philosophie. 12th ed. 5 vols. Berlin, 1923. Vol. Ill, Die Philosophie der Neuzeit bis zum Ende des XVIII Jahrhunderts, edited by M. Frischeisen-Kohler and W. Moog. Wightman, W. P. D. The Growth of Scientific Ideas. New Haven, Conn., 1951.
Willey, Basil.
A
A
The Seventeenth Century Bac\ground. London,
1934.
History of Science, Technology and Philosophy in the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries. 2d ed., revised by D. McKie. London, 1950.
Wolf, A.
Critical History of
Western Philosophy. Edited by D.
J.
O'Conner.
New
York, 1964.
Texts Bodin, Jean. CEuvres philosophiques. Edited and translated by P. Mesnard. Paris, 1951.
Studies Busson, H. Laporte,
J.
La pensee religieuse francaise de Charron a Pascal. ha doctrine de Port-Royal. 2 vols. Paris, 1923-52.
Mesnard, P. h'essor de Moreau-Reibel,
J.
Le
droit
au
XVI e
siecle. Paris, 1936.
Jean Bodin et le droit public compare dans ses rapports avec
la philosophie .
la philosophie politique
Paris, 1933.
de Vhistoire. Paris, 1933. de societe interhumaine
et
le
jus
gentium
.
.
.
jusqu'a
Grotius. Paris, 1950.
Pintard, R.
Le
Paris, 1943.
libertinage erudit dans la premiere moitie
du XVII e
siecle.
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
20
"Economique et politique au XVI e siecle: L'Oceana de James HarRevue francaise de science politique, 1952, pp. 24-41. Reynolds, B. Proponents of Limited Monarchy in Sixteenth Century France: Francis Hotman and Jean Bodin. New York, 1931. Polin, R.
rington,"
Texts Gassendi, Pierre. Opera omnia. Edited by H. L. Habert de Montmort. 6 vols.
Lyons, 1658-75. .
Dissertations en
and .
forme de paradoxes contre
les Aristoteliciens.
Edited
translated by B. Rochot. Paris, 1959.
Disquisitio metaphysica. Edited
and
translated by B. Rochet. Paris,
1962.
Studies Brent, G. S. The Philosophy of Gassendi. New York, 1908. Koyre, A. Etudes galileennes. 3 vols. Paris, 1939. Rochot, B. "Gassendi et la logique de Descartes," Revue philosophique, 1955.
Ill
Text Mersenne, Marin. Correspondance. Edited by
Mme
P.
Tannery, C. de Waard,
R. Lenoble, and B. Rochot. 5 vols. Paris, 1933-59.
Studies Lenoble, R. Mersenne; ou, .
"Les origines de
La
la
naissance
du mecanisme.
Paris, 1943.
pensee scientifique moderne," in Histoire de la
science, edited by M. Daumas. Paris, 1957. Pp. 369-534. History of Science. Edited by R. Taton. Translated by A. J. Pomerans. 3 vols. New York, 1964. Vol. II, The Beginnings of Modern Science from 1450 to 1800.
FRANCIS BACON AND EXPERIMENTAL PHILOSOPHY i
The
and Workj
Life
of
Bacon
francis bacon (1561-1626) was the son of Sir Nicholas Bacon,
Lord Keeper
he
became learned counsel
later
of James
I
he was appointed
education was that of a
who
of the Great Seal,
career as a statesman. Elected to the
jurist.
to
of the
1584,
reign
to the highest judicial offices.
His
Licensed in 1582, he began teaching
law in London in 1589; Law, which was to serve as
at the school of
Maxims
prepared him for a
House of Commons in the Crown; during the
in
1599 he edited his
a basis for the codifica-
tion of English laws. Ambitious, scheming, adept at changing sides
whenever
this
was
to his
pretentions of James
I,
advantage and
at flattering the absolutist
he rose gradually through the ranks, becom-
ing Solicitor General in 1607, Attorney General in 161 3, Lord
Keeper in
1617,
and Grand Chancellor
Baron Verulam in
161 8
and Viscount
defended the royal prerogative.
St.
in 1618.
He was
demnation of Talbot, a member of the
He
was created
Albans in 1621.
He
always
responsible for the con-
Irish Parliament,
who had
approved Suarez' ideas on the legitimacy of tyrannicide. In the matter of ecclesiastical that judges
commendams he
established the principle
must suspend judgment and confer with the king
whenever the king 21
believes that his
power
is
at issue in a
pending
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
22
was the meeting
suit. It
his downfall.
of Parliament in 1621 that brought about
Accused by the House of
corrupt dealings in chancery
from
received gifts
suits,
Commons
of bribery
he admitted that he had indeed
involved in pending litigation.
parties
and
The
House of Lords sentenced him to a fine of 40,000 pounds and prohibited him from ever discharging any public office, from sitting and from
in Parliament,
living close to the Court. Old, sick,
dishonored, he tried in vain to win reinstatement.
He
and
died five
years later.
In spite of such an active career, Bacon was forever concerned
with the advancement of learning. His works, considered as a whole, have a unified character.
It
was undoubtedly
career that he conceived the comprehensive
preface of the ratio
magna,
pared a
Novum organum
(1620)
and
work
early in his
outlined in the
later called the Instau-
treatise
on the subject
forty years earlier.
The
pre-
treatise, entitled
Temporis partus maximus {The Greatest Parturition
may
had
for in a letter written in 1625 he stated that he
of
Time),
be identical with the Temporis partus masculus sive de inter-
pretation naturae, a short posthumous
treatise
containing a plan
almost identical to that found in the preface to the
ganum. In any
tiones scientarum"
organum
Novum
or-
plan contains six divisions: (1) "Par-
case, the last
(Classification of the Sciences);
(2)
"Novum
de interpretatione naturae"; (3) "Phenomena historia naturalis et experimentalis ad condendam phi-
sive indicia
universi sive
losophiam"; (4) "Scala intellectus sive filum labyrinthi"; (5) "Pro-
dromi
sivi anticipationes
philosophiae secundae"; (6) "Philosophia
The
secunda sive scientia activa." with
all its
lacunae (I),
first
to replace that of Aristotle
of facts (III), passed
on
realization of his plan called for
from the
actual state of learning,
discussed the
new organon designed
a series of treatises which, starting
(II),
then described the investigation
to the investigation of
laws (IV), and
returned to the actions and knowledge that allowed us to control
(V and VI). The treatises that we possess are like the dismembra of a vast undertaking which could never be realized,
nature jecta
as
Bacon was the
first to
admit, by a single man.
We
cite
most of
BACON AND EXPERIMENTAL PHILOSOPHY
23
them by
classifying
them according
to the plan of the Instauratio
(though they were not written in that order) According .
admission, only the
De
the
dignitate et augmentis scientiarum libri IX, published in treatise was a Latin translation, with many additions, Advancement of Learning, published in 1605. His papers
This
1623.
of the also
own
work was completed:
part of the projected
first
to his
contained other outlines of the same subject: the Valerius
terminus, written about 1603 and published in 1736, and the Descriptio globi intellectualis, written
1653.
The Novum organum
around 1612 and published in
sive indicia vera
de interpretatione
naturae, published in 1620, corresponds to the second part.
whose aim
third part,
Novum
indicated in a tract published after the
is
organum, the Parasceve ad historiam naturalem
mentalem,
is
et experi-
treated in the Historia naturalis et experimentalis
condendam philosophiam 1622.
The
Phaenomena universi, published This work announced a number of monographs, some sive
which were written or outlined
ad in
of
after the Chancellor's downfall: the
Historia vitae et mortis, published in 1623; the Historia densi et rari (1658); the Historia
ventorum (1622); and the Sylva sylvarum,
To
a collection of materials published in 1627.
the fourth part
belong the Filum labyrinthi sive inquisitio legitima de motu, com-
posed in 1608 and published in 1653; the Topica inquisitionis de luce et lumine (1653);
and the
magnete (1658).
Inquisitio de
To
the fifth part (Prodromi sive anticipationes philosophiae secundae,
published in 1653) belong three works published in 1653: the fluxu et refluxu maris, written in 1616; the in 1612;
Thema
caeli,
De
written
and the Cogitationes de natura rerum, written between
1600 and 1604. Finally, second philosophy
is
the subject of the
Cogitata et visa de interpretatione naturae sive de scientia operativa
and of the third book of the Temporis partus masculus, published in 1653.
Even to
it:
treatises that are
not integral parts of his great work relate
the Redargutio philosophiarum, published in 1736;
pecially the
New
and
es-
Atlantis, a plan for organizing scientific research,
published in 1627.
To
these
must be added
his literary works, the
2
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
24
Essays (1597), which were enlarged with each
and
and a great
1625),
Through
number
new
and
to
awaken and
edition (161
legal works.
writing he was the herald of a
his
trumpeter whose mission was
movement
of historical
new
spirit,
a
new
to initiate a
would transform human life by assuring man's He had the zeal of an initiator and a vivid
that
domination over nature.
imagination that engraved precepts in unforgettable characters; but
he
had the systematic mind of a
also
legislator or
an administrator,
prudence that bordered on fastidiousness, and the desire to apportion to each individual
(the observer, the experimenter, the dis-
work
coverer of laws) a limited and precise role in the secular
he was
The Baconian
11
that
initiating.
Understanding
Ideal:
and Experimental Science Bacon considered the existing intellectual world.
He
and of the
state of the sciences
saw around him (he ignored or
failed to
recognize the works of the great minds of his era, notably those
and complacency
of Galileo) rigidity, stagnation,
and he
of the end;
determine
tried to
and advanced. What was
revitalized
how
—early
learning could be
his criticism of the sciences
and
of his era? "Their hasty, premature reduction to arts
ods; after
which learning progresses but
as learning it
is
dispersed in the
keeps increasing; once
however,
it
it
little
or not at
form of aphorisms and
has been imprisoned in
cannot be increased."
*
state.
Learning comes into
its
own, according
adopted by Bacon himself in the
Novum
finds free expression in the absence of
De
augmentis,
I,
41.
he
said,
to
meth-
So long
its
its
methods, its
mass
less arti-
existing
the procedure
organum, only when
it
any preconceived plan. Bacon
so apprehensive about rigidity that
certainty. "In speculations," 1
all.
"Methods," then, are but more or
expository procedures that solidify learning in
to
observations,
can be polished and refined by usage, but
ficial
was
symptoms
he was even afraid of
"whoever begins with certainty
BACON AND EXPERIMENTAL PHILOSOPHY
25 will
end with doubt; whoever begins with doubt and
entertains
it
for a while will
end with
certainty."
be the methodical doubt of Descartes but for Descartes really
Bacon held
that concluded
is,
patiently
This seems to
in fact, the opposite;
"began" with certainty implied by doubt, the
certainty of the Cogito, ties.
2
and
this certainty led
him
to other certain-
was not the beginning but the end
that certainty
any investigation.
All of Bacon's criticisms derive from his primary criticism of the
humanists
who saw
in the sciences nothing
more than
theme
who by
development; his criticism of the Scholastics
literary
a
for
"im-
prisoning their minds in Aristotle just as they imprison their bodies in their cells," solidify all
those for
whom
dogmas
learning
{rigor
dogmatum);
his criticism of
something already completed, some-
is
thing from the past; his criticism of the specialists first
their favorite field of learning contains the
the Pythagorean geometers
and
Cabalists,
saw numbers everywhere). Whatever is
who renounce
philosophy, take refuge in their discipline, and imagine that
whole of
who,
classifies,
like
reality
(like
Robert Fludd,
whatever
solidifies
bad.
Hence
his distrust of the very
intellectus intellect
instrument of
or understanding. Left to
denced by disputes among
"intellectualists" in
Aristode.
work
the
which the
He knew
Arabs and
nothing of the
subtlety of
sterile intellectual exercises.
only intellect ever recognized by Bacon
classifying intellect that the
at
(permissus sibi)
itself
can only produce one distinction after another, as was evi-
matter ruled out anything other than
The
classification, the
St.
is
the abstract
Thomas
3
and
discovered in
intellect that Descartes
found
in mathematical discovery. According to him, then,
it
is
not through an inner reform of the understanding that learning
can ever become tractable and perfectly clear: the ideas in the
and
will never
fruitful.
human
On
this
2 3
is
understanding do not have
have anything to do with the divine ideas according
which the Creator made the universe. "There
to
point Bacon
Novum organum, Novum organum,
I, I,
aphorism 45. aphorism 19;
De
augmentis,
I,
43.
is
a vast difference
26
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
between the images in our minds and the ideas in the divine mind,
God
between our vain opinions and the true characters that imprinted in his creatures." there
is
4
no natural kinship.
without metaphor, uniformity,
intellect
Here Bacon could jusdy invoke the most
analogy.
celebrated metaphysical speculations of the Renaissance lations of Paracelsus or of If it is
the subtlety of the to nature itself that
edge of
it.
Experience
—the specu-
Giordano Bruno.
mind cannot equal the subtlety of nature, we must turn in order to acquire knowl-
is
the true teacher. Francis
Bacon
is
linked
experimental natural science which, since Aris-
to the tradition of totle,
and truth
a distorting mirror;
constrained to see everywhere equality,
is
it
Between human Intellect is like
has
had always had a rather obvious place in Western thought,
and which appeared
in the
Middle Ages in the work of Roger
Bacon. This natural science had two aspects.
On
one hand were the
Historiae or collections of natural facts, such as Aristotle's History
Animals and
of
which embraces
especially Pliny's all
the
Natural History
—a
compilation
kingdoms of nature and which was
centuries a source of inspiration for those
who
for
sought a more
concrete and vivid image of the world than that of the philosophers.
Alongside the Historiae were the operative techniques, tainted by all sorts
of superstitions,
designs of
which supposedly forced nature
man—natural magic which
to
and alchemy which changed base metals into gold. These were
like astrology,
all
derived from Stoicism and from Neo-Platonism vealed to us only by experience. techniques, appealed strongly to all
sciences,
grounded on a representation of the universe
of mysterious sympathies or antipathies
withstanding
obey the
controlled nature's caprices
The
men
whose
:
the representation
secret could be re-
histories, like the operative
of the sixteenth century. Not-
the superstitions that they carried with them, they
had the
concrete, progressive character that
that he
would
Bacon sought in science, and they gave man hope of controlling nature provided that he would obey it (natura non vincitur nisi parendo) that is, provided
—
*
learn the laws of nature.
Novum organum,
I,
aphorism 23.
Bacon did not
fail to
recog-
BACON AND EXPERIMENTAL PHILOSOPHY
27
nize in these sciences
many
elements of credulity and imposture,
but he gave his unqualified approval to their aims
—to
investigate
"the influence of things above on things below," as in astrology;
from myriad forms of speculation
"to divert natural philosophy
and focus attention on the importance of operative techniques," in natural magic; "to separate
of bodies that are hidden
and
and intermixed,
to purify
impurities," as in chemistry. All these ends are proval,
5
as
extract the heterogenous parts
and the means employed, absurd
them
worthy of
of their his ap-
as they often were, never-
theless resulted in fruitful discoveries.
The
Instauratio
magna
among
does not rank
contributions to
mathematics or mathematical physics, where advances were the distinctive trait of the seventeenth century.
Here Bacon abandoned
the sciences of argumentation and concentrated tionally the tangled
mass of
on organizing
ra-
assertions about nature, of operational
procedures, and of practical techniques that constituted the experi-
mental sciences.
The
in
We
Division of the Sciences
turn
now to the first De dignitate
resolved in the
fication of the sciences
task of the Instauratio, the one that et
augmentis scientiarum
intended not so
much
into those that existed as to indicate those that
The most of the
general division
memory,
is
.
It is
is
a classi-
to introduce order
were
still
lacking.
the division into History, or science
Poetry, or science of the imagination,
and Philoso-
phy, or science of reason. History and Philosophy each have two distinct objects, nature
into natural history
of nature
and
and man. History civil history,
is
therefore subdivided
and philosophy
into philosophy
and philosophy of man.
Natural history
is,
in turn, divided into historia generationum,
praetergenerationum, artium. This
is
the division that Pliny the
De augmentis, III, 5 (ed. Spedding, p. 574), on the transmutation of metals. Spinoza (ed. Van Vloten, II, 330), Malebranche {Entretiens sur la metaphysique, X, 12), and Leibniz {New Essays, III, 9, 22) consider this a perfectly legitimate 5
and soluble problem.
—
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
28
Elder made. As in Pliny's second book, the "history of generations" relates
phenomena,
to celestial
composed of the same element, the phenomena. After
come
this
"history of the arts" through
nature. These are the
two
and
sea
finally
to
man
which
and the
changes the course of
subjects of Pliny's seventh
and VII
masses
rivers, the earth, volcanic
the "history of monsters"
part included between Books II
Bacon deserves
and
to meteors,
is
book (the
devoted to geography).
not for bringing the study of abnormal
credit,
conditions and the arts into natural history, but for stating that
such study constitutes an indispensable part of natural science and is
not merely an appendage of curious
bring to light forces that were natura omnia
which
force
is
regit.
In the
arts,
facts.
Monsters and technics
obvious in natural generation
less
for instance,
man
can create no
not in nature; he can only place bodies closer to
way The new
new
each other or farther apart and in this
create
for the interplay of natural forces.
spirit justifies
decision to
derata)
chap.
As
number among
the
the sciences that are
two new subdivisions
of
for civil history,
lacking {desi-
history
(Vol.
II,
subdivisions correspond to the historical
its
which were prevalent in Bacon's time and which
were rooted in the
past.
They
Eusebius of Caesarea, and
are ecclesiastical history, initiated
civil history
according to the documents on which antiquities, ancient stories
and complete
proper,
it is
based: memoirs (fastes),
such as the Judaic Antiquities of Josephus,
historical accounts
such as biographies, chronicles
Bacon outlines a
scheme of scholarly investigation and adds
which
"literary history,"
primarily the history of advances in technics and the
is
sciences.
by
which he subdivides
of a reign, or the narration of particular events. vast
Bacon's
i).
literary types
true
still
natural
conditions
This was the program adopted universally by scholars
throughout the seventeenth century. After
civil history
come
the divisions of philosophy. Here, too,
the divisions are traditional, but their spirit deviate as
little as
possible
is
new.
"I desire to
from the opinions and manners of speak-
ing of the ancients," said Bacon (Vol.
Ill,
chap,
iv,
sec. i).
God,
BACON AND EXPERIMENTAL PHILOSOPHY
29
nature,
and man
(or, as
Middle Ages
of the
he says
—luminous
—reminding us of the perspectivists source,
its
refracted ray,
its
reflected
ray) are the three objects of the three great philosophical sciences.
This
is
Aristotle's division into theology, or first philosophy, physics,
and moral philosophy. But the first
spirit is quite different: in Aristotle,
philosophy, or metaphysics, was, at the same time, science of
axioms, science of causes or principles of every substance, sensible or intelligible,
and
ments in Bacon, but
We
God.
science of
rediscover
arrangement
their
these ele-
all
completely different.
is
First philosophy refers to the science of axioms, metaphysics to the
science of causes,
and theology
to the science of
First philosophy, or the science of axioms,
of the three branches
According
—the
sciences of
is
common
sufficiently universal
to apply equally to divine things, to natural things,
things.
For
is
also the
in physics, the horror of the void
state
politics,
and
to
human
"Whatever can best preserve the order of
instance,
things (conservativum formae)
mass; in
trunk
God, of nature, and of man.
"axioms" are adages
to Bacon, the
God. the
most powerful"; whence,
which preserves the
terrestrial
the pre-eminence of the conservative forces of the
over private interests; and in theology, the pre-eminence of
the virtue of charity,
which
unites
all
men. In
short,
Bacon asks
that these universal notions be treated "according to the laws of
and not
nature rather than of discourse—physically,
Adages about understand
rarity
why one
and quantity,
for example,
product, such as gold,
is
logically."
should help us
rare,
and another,
such as iron, plentiful.
Theology becomes the
first
of the philosophical sciences. After
comes the science of nature, which
is
it
subdivided into metaphysics,
or the science of formal and final causes, and special physics, or the science of efficient and material causes.
We
recall that
medieval
knowledge of forms, or the true inaccessible to the human mind. Thus,
followers of Aristotle considered differences of things, as
what Bacon sought a
new
Later
to create,
under the name of metaphysics, was
science, a science intimately related to the study of nature.
we
shall
examine
this
new
science in detail
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
30
The man,
and
third
the philosophical sciences, the science of
last of
subdivided according to the
is
human
faculties into the science
of the intellect, or logic, the science of the will, or ethics, and,
men
finally, the science of
living together in societies.
separated the science of societies
Baconian logic
but the description of the natural progress of
is
science. First, there
invention or discovery of truths, accomplished
is
only through experience (experientia
down
are set
the
Novum
in writing),
litterata,
or experiences that
and induction, the
particular object of
organum. After invention comes judgment of pro-
posed truths, for which the principal instrument syllogism. Its function truths
to
sophisms; tiple
universal it
is
Logic
The
human mind—that contrast
physics.
the Aristotelian
useful
is
also
in
is, its
—for
and
instance, "little"
brings to light the "idols"
it
making mistakes. and classical ethics
reasons for
between Baconian
ethics
is
no
than that between Baconian physics and Aristotelian
Bacon censured the ancients
for offering
no
practical
of attaining their proposed goal, for speculating about the
good without knowing about the future teaches us to seek the to subordinate the
to
refuting
prevents the incorrect use of general words with mul-
"much," "like" and "different"; and
less striking
is
precise but limited: to reduce proposed
principles.
meanings used in every discussion
of the
Thus Bacon
from morality.
life
supreme good, and, in
good of the individual
which he belongs.
It
in
which Christianity
particular, for failing
to the
good of the
was because of such ignorance
falsely stated that the speculative life
is
that throughout antiquity the sovereign
means
supreme
society
that Aristotle
superior to the active
good was sought
tranquility of the individual soul, without reference to the
life;
in the
common
good; and that an Epictetus taught that the sage should find in himself the principle of his happiness
individualism with
—an
outgrowth of ancient
emphasis on achieving a tranquil
its
from external concerns, and
its
life,
choice of serenity rather than
free
mag-
nanimity, passive enjoyment rather than active good manifested
through works. Bacon's than speculative.
He
ethics, like his science,
was more operative
preferred the tyrant Machiavelli, with his
BACON AND EXPERIMENTAL PHILOSOPHY
31
power
love of
for
joyless virtues;
its
own
sake, to the Stoic sage with his inert
he preferred a true
on materials taken from
from
ethics,
and which
is
man
with
and
passions, based
to Theophrastus'
historians,
Finally, he completed the science of distinct
on the
treatise
Characters.
politics,
which
is
chiefly a doctrine of the state
and of power.
Along with History and Philosophy, Bacon recognized a science, Poetry, the science of the imagination.
men
with which Renaissance
myths and
fables
—the
We
recall the
third
ardor
returned to the interpretation of
basis for a science of
enigmas and images.
Descartes himself, as a young man, paid some attention to such
whimsical notions. They are the subject of the in
which Bacon
finds in the fable of
Cupid
De
sapientia veterum,
the idea of the original
motion of the atom and of the action of atoms on each other across distances; in the song of Orpheus, the prototype of natural
philosophy, which has as of corruptible things. It
its
aim the
this
is
restoration
whole
and renovation
collection of fables, inter-
preted in the context of the great reformation of the sciences, that
Bacon
calls poetry.
But, at bottom the three sciences of history, poetry,
phy
are only three successive advances of the
mind
and
philoso-
in the formation
of the sciences: history, the accumulation of materials; poetry, the first,
wholly chimerical use of materials
beyond which the ancients solid construction of reason.
This
is
whenever he was thinking not of
De
—a kind of dream of science
failed to progress;
and philosophy, the
how
things appeared to Bacon
all
the sciences listed in the
augmentis, but only of the one that truly engrossed him, the
science of nature.
The Novum Organum
iv
A new the
new instrument was needed sciences systematized
Novum
ganum and
organum. the
De
to effect the
by Bacon, and
it
development of the
was
to
be created by
Is the difference between the
augmentis the same
Novum
as the difference
or-
between
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
32
method
a systematic plan of the sciences and a universal, over-all
promoting them? No. In
of
organum
from
to poetry,
with ethics and
and
and nothing
work everything
De
logic.
Now
it is
man
science of
a
the
relates
everything that has to do
Novum organum
program
with the part of logic that
and
that relates to history
remains the program of the science
politics, there
else:
augmentis.
on philosophy everything that
the chapters
and from
to theology,
of nature
the
Novum
the content of the
coincides exactly with certain parts of the
we remove from
If
reality,
is
precisely that
of the sciences of nature together
relates to
The
them.
errors treated in
and
the theory of idols concern only man's conception of nature; the
organum, or
reason as a compass aids the hand,
tool, that aids
pertains exclusively to the science of nature.
The
description of idols, or mistakes
follows
its
ganum and
is,
therefore,
of the necessity of the idols.
made by
the
natural flight, stands at the beginning of the
an opportune prelude
new
mind
it
or-
our understanding
to
instrument. There are four kinds of
Idola tribus ("idols of the tribe"), are natural fallacies
ing laziness and inertia.
as
Novum
We
reflect-
generalize solely on the basis of
affir-
mative instances and thus create superstitions, such as astrology, because
we
fail to
been wrong.
by virtue of
take into account instances where predictions have
We
desire to see realized in nature the notions which,
their simplicity
and uniformity,
best
fit
our minds. This
accounts for the birth of ancient astronomy, which denied the stars
any trajectory other than a circular one, and science of the Cabala (revived in
England
to the
by Robert Fludd), which imagines non-existing to
we
have base
them correspond our
conception
activity, so alchemists
things as well as
to
of
our the
of
realities
among men.
nature
in order
As
on human
among
Idola specus ("idols of the cave")
and training which imprison the
as in Plato's cave. Idola fori ("idols of the
are the
Bacon
combinations.
discovered sympathies and antipathies
relate to the inertia of the habits
mind,
numerical
activity
whole pseudo-
in the time of
words that influence our conception of
market place")
reality. If
we wish
—
BACON AND EXPERIMENTAL PHILOSOPHY
33
to classify things, tion, interferes.
common
language, with
Furthermore,
its
ready-made
many words have
and many have no counterpart in
(as
reality
indistinct
classifica-
meanings
when we speak
of
chance or of the heavenly spheres). Idola theatri ("idols of the theater")
are traceable to
philosophical theories
exotic
certain
those of Aristotle, "the worst of the Sophists,"
and
Plato, "the jester,
was no
the bombastic poet, the impassioned theologian." Bacon less critical
provisions,
who collected facts as an ant collects rationalists, who constructed their spider-web
of the empiricists,
and of the
theories without benefit of experience. Idols, then, are not sophisms
or errors of reasoning but vicious mental dispositions which, like
some kind
make
of original sin,
Bacon's aim,
strictly
speaking,
is
not knowledge, but power over
Knowledge, however,
nature, operational science.
determined by the end
rules are
its
us disregard nature.
enunciated his aim in these words:
them
natures and to introduce
into
a means,
create
one or several new
a particular body."
"nature" means specific properties such as density and
and
cold, heaviness
and
and
lightness, volatility
the pairs of properties listed in the fourth
orology and used as a model by
all
and
supposed to serve. Bacon
it is
"To
is
heat
—in
short,
Aristotle's
Mete-
The
the physicists.
Here
rarity,
stability
book of
6
operational
technique, particularly that of the alchemists, consists in engen-
dering one or more properties in a body that does not already possess them, in changing
and
so forth.
it
Bacon thinks,
from cold
to hot,
from
stable to volatile,
like Aristotle, that each of these natures
is
the manifestation of a certain
If
we
are masters of forms,
we
form or essence
shall
But we cannot be masters of forms
that produces
it.
then be masters of properties. until
we have knowledge
of
them.
Here the
positive task of the
ent: to provide
6
becomes appar-
knowledge of the forms which engender
Aristotle failed to solve this
petuated by
Novuum organum
Thomism)
Novum organum,
II,
problem (and
his
failure
natures.
was
per-
because the differences that enable us to
aphorism
i.
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
34
determine a genus and to define a specific essence are not "true
Now
what Bacon
credits
himself with grasping: "form," "true difference," "thing in
itself"
7
differences."
true differences are precisely
(ipsissima res), "nature-engendered nature," "source of emanation,"
determination of the "pure
such expressions
intention.
Furthermore, one means by
Aristotle determined essence
and law was induction; Bacon
Bacon's
indicate
clearly
which
—many
"law"
act,"
employs the same kind of reasoning for the same purpose.
The Novum organum then ancient one
—
has the same external design as the
knowledge of forms or
beginning with
essences,
through induction. But Bacon claimed
to succeed
where
facts,
Aristotle
moreover, he makes knowledge of forms the prelude to a
failed;
practical operation rather than the satisfaction of a speculative need.
How
this possible?
is
The
study of forms was compared by Bacon to the
who through
alchemist
looking for from the forms with which
matter he
is
When we
are seeking a form,
nature
is
inextricably
form
there, but
is
thing which
How
is
is
we
concerned.
obtain
Induction
it
only by separating
is
He
when
mixed. its
it
from every-
is
the question with
which Bacon was primarily
never asked himself what constitutes good observa-
observation alone
superficial remarks.
and
tists like
is
a process of elimination.
is
being considered, or what
precautions are to be taken; on this point he
inately,
it
find through observation that
observation to be conducted in order to effect the desired
elimination? That
tion,
it.
of the
mixed with a mass of other natures; the
we can
not
work
a series of operations separates the pure
He
for this he
Liebig.
What
made
tended in practice to gather
was
severely censured
critical
only vague,
facts indiscrim-
by professional
scien-
mattered most to him was to multiply and
to diversify experiences in order to prevent the
mind from becom-
ing rigid and immobile. This accounts for the procedures associated
with Pan's hunt (venatio Panis), the pursuit of observations in
which the
sagacity of the hunter plays the
in the ancient fable the sagacity of 7
See E. Brehier,
The Hellenic Age,
trans.
dominant
Pan enabled him J.
Thomas
role just as
to find Ceres.
(Chicago, 1963), p. 179.
BACON AND EXPERIMENTAL PHILOSOPHY
35
Experiences must be varied {variatio) forest trees in the
same way
—for
as fruit trees,
instance,
by grafting
by observing
how
warmed, or by changing the quantity of substances used experiment; they must be repeated distilling
new
(repetitio)
—for
an
instance,
by
must be extended
(extensio)
—for
instance,
serving certain precautions and, while keeping water apart in the
same
stance,
They must
lighter parts.
from nature
(translatio) artificially
to
the case of the rainbow
in
as
art,
also be transferred
produced in a waterfall; inverted (inversio)
by observing that heat
is
stance,
—for
in-
propagated by means of an ascend-
ing motion and then determining whether cold
means of
by ob-
and wine
receptacle, trying to separate the heavier parts of
wine from the
the
is
in
wine from wine that had already undergone
spirit of
distillation; they
the
rubbed amber varies when the substance
force of attraction of
a descending motion;
is
propagated by
suppressed (compulsio)
—for
in-
by determining whether certain bodies placed between a
magnet and a properties
of iron
piece
applied (applicatio)
—that
is,
will
suppress magnetic attraction;
they must be used to disclose useful
determine the salubrity of the
(for example, to
different places or in different seasons
Finally, several experiences
air in
by the rate of putrefaction).
must be combined
(copulatio), follow-
ing the example of Drebbel who, in 1620, lowered the freezing point of water by mixing ice and saltpeter. There remain accidents (sortes) of experimentation,
tions slightly
which
result
from changing the condi-
—for instance, producing combustion, which ordinarily
takes place in the
open
air,
inside a closed vessel.
8
These eight experimental procedures do not indicate the means of producing a given result, for
what ple,
will result
from
under the rubric
we
variation, repetition, variatio
know
in advance
so forth.
For exam-
can never
and
Bacon proposes
to
the velocity of heavy falling objects will increase increased;
is
and (apparently ignoring
determine whether
when
their
weight
Galileo's celebrated experi-
ments) he maintains that one must not assume a priori that the
answer will be either affirmative or negative. Pan's hunt does not 8
De augmentis V, ,
2, sees.
8-14.
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
36
yield fertile (fructifera) observations since
whether the outcome will measure up observations falsity of
are
illuminating
presumed
more obviously linked
Still
we
are unable to forsee
our expectation, but such they
since
(luctifera)
and
relations
to
expose
to the
aim of induction
is
the divi-
sion of experiences into the three tables: presence, absence, degrees.
with
To
the
lay the basis for elimination.
and
the "table of presence" or "essence" he consigns, along
all their
circumstances, experiences involving the production
whose form
of the nature
"declination," those in
sought; to the "table of absence" or
is
which
this
same nature
"table of degrees" or "comparison," those in
is
absent; to the
which nature
varies.
understood, in addition, that the table of presence will also
It is
include the experiences in which a nature exists in subjects that differ to the
utmost degree; and the table of absence will contain
experiences that are as similar as possible to those included in the table of presence.
Induction consists wholly and exclusively in inspecting the three
Comparison
tables.
will suffice to eliminate
from the form sought,
numphenomena which accompany nature. It will obviously be necessary to eliminate all phenomena not found in every experience
spontaneously and with almost mechanical certainty, a great ber of
in the table of presence; then
among
the remaining
phenomena,
all
those present in the experiences in the table of absence; finally,
all
those in the table of degrees that are invariable, in contrast to
nature,
which
varies.
The form
sought will of necessity be in the
residue that persists "once the rejections and exclusions have been
made is
to be determined.
heat is
in the appropriate manner." Suppose that the
is
Bacon
specifies
twenty-seven cases in which
produced; thirty-two, similar to the
not produced
form of heat
first
group, in which
it
—for example, the fact that the sun warms the earth
(presence) in contrast to the fact that the sun does not melt perpetual
snow (absence); and
due that
forty-one in
persists after elimination
produces the
effect
is
which
it
varies.
The
the vibrating motion
resi-
which
observed in a flame or in boiling water. Bacon
BACON AND EXPERIMENTAL PHILOSOPHY
37
defines
which
it
way: an expansive motion which goes upward,
in this
affects
not the whole body but
repelled in such a
is
manner
that
it
its
smallest parts,
and which
becomes intermittent and vibra-
tory.
The which
difference
between
this operation
consists of simple enumeration,
is
and
Aristotle's induction,
obvious. Aristotle enumer-
ated every case in which a certain circumstance (the absence of
accompanied the phenomenon (longevity) whose cause he
gall)
was seeking. by Bacon
He
therefore restricted himself to the cases assigned
to the table of presence.
periences in this
domain was
The
utilization of negative ex-
truly Bacon's discovery.
Form: Bacon's Mechanism
v
is
One
of the conditions governing the success of Bacon's induction
that
form be not the mysterious thing sought by
element observable in the world about us
—something
perceived by the senses or by instruments that as the microscope.
A
form
is
Aristotle but
assist
not inferred but
of obervation; induction only enables us to
is
an
that can be
the senses, such
made
the object
narrow more and more
the field of observation surrounding the form.
We
should add that in
all
problems of
outlined a solution, the residue certain constant mechanical
is
this type for
which Bacon
always, as in the case of heat, a
arrangement of matter.
If
we
investi-
gate the form of the whiteness that appears in snow, in foaming water, or in pulverized glass,
we
see that in every case there
is
"a
mixture of two transparent bodies, together with a certain simple,
uniform arrangement of
their optical parts."
passage that Descartes reproduced almost
9
Furthermore, in a
word
for
word
in his
Rules, he sees the "form" of colors in a certain geometric arrange-
ment
of lines.
We
see that induction has the effect of eliminating,
in order to identify the form, every qualitative or sensible element in our experience. 9
De
augmentis,
We
III, 4, sec.
can therefore say that in a sense Bacon was 11.
38
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
a mechanist, for he ascribed the essence of each thing in nature to
a permanent geometric
and mechanical
the "latent schematism"
—that
is,
structure. It
true that
is
form from what Bacon
there have been attempts to separate
called
the intimate constitution of bodies
that escapes us because of the smallness of their elements
make
it
—and
a superaddition to a mechanical structure or schematism,
which then would be the material condition of the form and not Bacon
substance. But
—that
operations through which a body acquires
its
Hidden
has reference to a mechanical process.
schematismos
tions (pccultos
of physics.
10
Thus
his
et
motus)
thought has
when he
them. Besides,
explicitly identifies
speaks of latent progress (progressus latens)
—these
its
of insensible
is,
properties structures
—he
still
and mo-
are the true objects
place in the great mechanistic
its
tradition that took shape in the seventeenth century. If there re-
mained
in his thinking any trace of the Aristotelian concept of
form, would he have treated the investigation of final causes, which to Aristotle
was inseparable from the
investigation of form, as a
"sterile virgin" ?
But Bacon's as
is
a
mechanism
something unexpected,
chanical structure
is
as a
of a particular type.
what remains
many
In addition, he posited inexplicable absolutes.
appears
many mechanical
structures
first
The me-
and exclusion."
after "rejection
forms,
Whereas
It
simple result of induction.
structures as
were the things
to
be ex-
plained in the case of Descartes and Gassendi, they were to Bacon the things that explained. Thus, in his view, mathematics did not
have the dominant role assigned
to
it
trusted mathematics, especially after he
by Descartes; Bacon
saw the
results of a
dis-
mathe-
matical conception of nature in the case of his contemporary, the Cabalist Robert Fludd,
who had no
objection
when
his calculations
arrived at the most arbitrary combinations of figures in nature;
of physics
and he wanted mathematics
—that
is,
to
and numbers
remain the "handmaid"
to be limited to providing
him with
a language
for his measurements.
Novum organum, II, aphorisms 6, 39; De augmentis, Lalande, Quid de mathematica senserit Baconius (Paris, 1899), 10
III,
p.
4,
38.
sec.
11.
Cf.
BACON AND EXPERIMENTAL PHILOSOPHY
39
Experimental Proof
vi
Let us return to the organon. Bacon
tells
which a form
us to narrow the field in
we
tion indicates the exclusions
us that induction allows
to
is
be sought. But
make,
are to
it
induc-
if
obviously cannot
indicate the
New
force us to
process of induc-
tion
moment of completion of the process. make new exclusions. The result of the
provisional;
is
how
Just
to
it is
a
first
facts
could
vintage (vindemiatio prima).
reach a definitive result
something that Bacon
is
promises to explain in his discussion of the "more powerful auxil-
provided by reason. 11
iaries" iaries,"
He
but discusses only the
draws up a
first,
which he
of facts" {praerogativae instantiarum)
How
of "privileged facts."
Why
we
are
he
;
to
of nine such "auxil-
list
calls
lists
the "prerogatives
twenty-seven types
interpret
expression?
this
are these facts not included in the preparatory tables associ-
Take
ated with induction?
the "solitary instances," that
ences in which the nature under investigation
is
is,
experi-
manifested with-
out any of the circumstances that ordinarily accompany
it
(for ex-
ample, producing colors by sending light through a prism). This
and the same
fact belongs in the table of presence,
stantiae
migrantes,
(the whiteness of
instances
where
a nature
foaming water). The
destinae, instances
where a nature
is
to the table of degrees; the instantiae
is
true of in-
is
suddenly manifested
instantiae ostensivae et clan-
maximal or minimal, belong monodicae et deviantes, where
a particular nature appears under exceptional conditions (a
among
minerals, monsters), belong to the table of presence; the
instantiae divortii
which reveal
ordinarily paired (for example
density without being
in the tables.
to us
When we
two separate natures
—
low density and heat
warm) belong
even the famous crucial
II,
has low
in the table of absence.
hesitate
between two forms
must show
tween one of these forms and the nature Novum organum,
air
that are
Not
facts {instantiae crucis) fail to find a place
particular nature, the crucial facts
11
magnet
aphorisms 21
et
seq.
is
to explain a
"that the union be-
stable
and
indissoluble,
—
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
40
whereas that of the other
(Aphorism
variable"
is
to interpret this formula? It
is
36).
How
easy for us to understand
we
are
how
facts
in the table of absence conclusively demonstrate such variability (this
how to
an instantia dwortii), but
is
is
hard for us
to
understand
a stable, indissoluble union could be demonstrated according
Baconian
We can
logic.
continue to narrow the
we have
tion but can never say that
view
stance, in Bacon's
gravity the
it
is
we
reached the limit. For in-
can show that the form or cause of if we observe when brought near
the earth's attraction of heavy objects
pendulum
moves
of a clock
but
earth's center;
table of presence,
this is clearly a
and
it
faster
contradicted by another fact.
add nothing
Never does Bacon
at all to the
new
the
not
it is
offer decisive proof
Thus
the "prerogatives
instrument created by Bacon,
and when he includes among them
means
that
simple fact to be added to the
will be probable only so long as
of affirmations; only negations are proved.
of facts"
field of investiga-
instantiae lampadis
—simple
of extending our information either through instruments
that aid the senses, such as the microscope or the telescope, or
through
such as the pulse in sickness
signs,
much more
attentive to the
means
—we
see that
he
is
of gathering materials than to
their possible utilization.
vii
The Last
Parts of the "Instauratio
The Novum organum then
Magna"
merely a description of one phase
is
in the constitution of the sciences of nature.
the Instauratio were supposed to
from the very
The
first step,
make
the Historia, to the
third part concerns the Historia,
The
last
and
last,
operative science.
this is the
engrossed Bacon particularly toward the end of his to 1626.
Aided by
sylvarum
all
the
his secretary
odd
facts
four parts of
natural science a reality
life,
work
that
from 1624
Rawley, he stuffed into the Sylva
he could find in books of
travel, physics,
chemistry, or medicine. His authorities are not the best: he bor-
rowed
freely
from Paracelsus; he took
gold from the alchemists.
He
found
recipes for the fabrication of better guides, however,
in
BACON AND EXPERIMENTAL PHILOSOPHY
41
works on magnetism and
Gilbert's
The
thermometry.
Sylva
a particular history
is
in Drebbel's experiments with
a general history.
Bacon stipulated that
must be written about each "nature," and he
himself drew up some of them, the Historia vitae et mortis, for
which was often directed against Harvey, who through
instance,
decisive experiments
Not
blood.
had
just
very careful in the matter of direct observation, he
committed the same error
on
demonstrated the circulation of the
Roger Bacon;
as
presumed experience (transmitted by
traditional statements of
Pliny) rather than on experience
The
itself.
fourth part of the Instauratio
resume and
supposed to
organum.
in his Historia he relied
to
apply
—the the
—was
Scala intellectus
theme of the
Novum
Its title,
the ladder of the intellect, refers to the need for
not leaping from
particular observations to general axioms, but,
instead, for
moving
gradually, through intermediate axioms, to the
general ones.
The
fifth part,
supported by general axioms, prepares the ground
for the operative science realized in the sixth part
man
give
goal, his
He
and designed
mastery over nature. But even as he advances toward
to
this
fragmentary work becomes increasingly vague and sketchy.
understood that his aim could not be realized through blind
empiricism but only at the price of an intellectual revolution of
which he was the self-proclaimed herald, that he must not consider returning to the field of action until the revolution could be carried
He
out.
understood that
scientific
work must be
a collective en-
deavor shared by a great number of investigators, and he devoted
one of
his last
works, the
republic in
tific
New Atlantis,
which each individual
to the description of a scien-
is
assigned a task. First
the factual investigators: the mercatores lucis
who go
to investigate strange observations, the depraedatores
ancient books, the venatores sans,
and the
Then come
who
come
to foreign lands
who
strip the
discover the secrets of the
arti-
who initiate new experiments. who assign the facts to the three tables, the those who extract provisional laws; then those who
fossores or pioneers
those
divisores; then
devise experiments to prove the provisional laws;
and
finally those
—
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
42
who
Even remote from the
carry out experiments under their direction.
imaginary republic, Bacon was
which everything
science for
still
else
here, in his
operational
was made.
Experimental Philosophy in England
viii
Voltaire in his Philosophical Letters rendered an opinion
Bacon
must have been
that
England
fairly general in
on
at the begin-
ning of the eighteenth century: "The most singular and the best of his
works
Novum
is
today the least read and the most useless.
scientarum organon.
philosophy has been
built,
and now
that the
constructed, at least partially, the scaffold
Chancellor Bacon
know
did not
still
roads that lead to nature."
The
I
mean his new
the scaffold with which the
It is
fact
is
new
no longer of any
knew
nature, but he
is
been
edifice has
that there
was
all
use.
the
in England,
beginning about 1650, remarkable progress in what was called the
new
philosophy, experimental philosophy, or effective philosophy
that
is,
in the
whole
field
of experimental natural science.
Royal Society of London, founded around
1645
and
The
officially
recognized in 1662, the work of the physicist Robert Boyle (16271691),
and
Royal
the
especially
the stages in the Society
—an
new
work
endeavor
was a unique attempt
Newton (1642-1727) mark The collective work of the catalogue natural phenomena of
development. to
to realize the first
requirement
set
by Baco-
nian science: a History. Glanvill in his Scepsis scientifica (1665) sees "in the
New
Atlantis the prophetic project of the Royal Society."
The same man clearly expresses the spirit of the Society by showing work the uncertainty of our knowledge about every matter dealt with by Cartesian philosophy the union of mind and body,
in his
—
the nature
and origin of mind, the origin of
of causes ("we cannot
one thing
is
we
it
expect
called
know," he
the cause of another, to be;
attention
to
even
this
the
vast
path
living bodies, ignorance
said, earlier if is
it
is
than
Hume,
"that
not the cause of what
not infallible"). But Glanvill
number
of
discoveries
engendered
by the practical and experimental part of philosophy, by the
BACON AND EXPERIMENTAL PHILOSOPHY
43
"new philosophy which he
intends to
make
subject
Every demonstration must be experimental;
treatise."
the essential precept of the Society which to
the
achieve only provisional results, since
this
was henceforth "it
of his
was
to seek
probable that the
is
experiments of future ages will not agree with those of the present, but on the contrary will oppose and contradict them." Hooke, the secretary of the Society
lam," censured "those
and an admirer of "the incomparable Veru-
who wish
transcribe
to
only
own
their
thoughts and therefore risk making general statements about things that are peculiar to them." Until the time of
most eminent member of the in chemistry
cular theory
in the theory of
especially interested
favored the corpus-
and mechanism, and he deduced the "secondary
from the primary
ties"
But
and
Newton, Boyle was the
He was matter. He
Society.
his theory of
qualities of extension
quali-
and impenetrability.
mechanics was that of an English experimental
philosopher; in discussing Descartes' mechanics he used the very
terms
employed by Hooke: "The mechanical explanation that
Descartes gives of qualities depends so
much on
his private views
of a subtle matter, of globules of the second element, similar things,
and he has interwoven these notions
the rest of his hypothesis that
we
can rarely put
it
and other
so closely
with
to use unless
we
adopt his whole philosophy." Descartes' theory, too systematic and personal, stifled the free flow of ideas,
experience.
mental;
it
The
which must be responsive
starting point of Boyle's mechanics
was the mathematical theory of machines,
was
to
experi-
a theory "that
permits the application of pure mathematics to the production or modification of motions in bodies."
Bibliography
I
to
VII
Texts Wor\s of Francis Bacon. Edited by James Spedding, R. L. and D. D. Heath. 7 vols. London, 1857-59. The Letters and Life of Francis Bacon. Edited by James Spedding. 7 vols. London, 1861-74. The Philosophical Worlds of Francis Bacon. Edited by J. M. Robertson. London, 1905. Selected Writings. Edited by H. G. Dick. New York, 1955. The Advancement of Learning. Edited by G. W. Kitchin. London,
Bacon, Francis. The Ellis, .
.
.
.
1934.
-.
J. M. McNeill. London, 1959. Organon and Related Writings. Edited by
Essays. Edited by
The
New
F.
H. Anderson.
Indianapolis, Ind., i960.
Studies
Adam,
C. La philosophic de F. Bacon. Paris, 1890. Anderson, F. H. The Philosophy of Francis Bacon. Chicago, 1948. Francis Bacon: His Career and His Thought. Los Angeles, 1962. Bevan, B. The Real Francis Bacon. London, i960. .
Bowen, C. D. Francis Bacon: The Temper
The Philosophy
of a
Man. Boston,
1963.
Cambridge, 1926. Brochard, V. "La philosophic de Bacon," Etudes de philosophie ancienne et de philosophie moderne. Paris, 1912. Pp. 303-13. Crowther, J. G. Francis Bacon. London, i960. Church, R. W. Bacon. London, 1884. Eiseley, L. C. Francis Bacon and the Modern Dilemma. Lincoln, Neb., 1962. Farrington, B. Francis Bacon: Philosopher of Industrial Science. New ed. New York, 1961. Gibson, R. W. Francis Bacon : A Bibliography of His Wor\s and of Baconiana to the Year ij$o. Oxford, 1950. Broad, C. D.
Green, A.
W.
of Francis Bacon.
His Life and Wor\s. York, 1954.
Sir Francis Bacon,
Jameson, T. H. Bacon.
44
New
New
York, 1948.
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
45
Baco Verulamis alchemicis philosophis quid debuerit. Angers, 1889.
Janet, P.
Lalande, A. Quid de mathematica vel rationali vel naturali senserit Baconius
Verulamius. Paris, 1899. Les theories de Vinduction. Paris, 1929. "Sur quelques textes de Bacon et de Descartes," Revue de metaphys.
.
ique
et
de morale,
XIX
(191 1), 296-311.
Levi, A. // pensiero de Francesco Bacone. Turin, 1925.
Von Liebig, J. Vber Francis Bacon von Verulam. Munich, De Maistre, J. (Euvres completes. New ed. 14 vols. Lyons, and IX, Examen de la philosophic de Bacon. Rossi, P. Francesco Bacone; della
magia
1863.
1884-86. Vols. VIII
alia scienza. Bari, 1957.
M. La pensee de Lord Bacon. Paris, 1949. G. La philosophic moderne depuis Bacon
Schuhl, P. Sortais,
Paris, 1920-29. Vol.
I,
Steegmuller, F. Sir Francis Bacon: 1930. Sturt,
New
M. Francis Bacon.
jusqu'a Leibniz. 3 vols.
Bacon.
The
First
Modern Mind.
New
York, 1932.
Williams, C. Bacon. London, 1933.
VIII
Texts Robert Boyle. Opera omnia. Venice, 1697. The English Wor\s. Edited by T. Birch. 5 .
vols.
London,
1774.
Studies Florian, P.
"De Bacon
a
Newton," Revue de philosophic,
Masson, F. Robert Boyle: Sprat, T.
The History
A
1914.
Biography. Edinburgh, 1914.
of the Royal Society of
London. London,
1667.
York,
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM i
Life
and Worlds rent
prominent family
descartes
in Touraine.
(1596-1650)
descended
from
a
His grandfather, Pierre Descartes,
fought in the religious wars. His father Joachim,
who became
a
counselor to the parlement of Britanny in 1586, married Jeanne
Brochard. daughter of the lieutenant-general of Poitiers.
who succeeded his father, was the youngest. From 1604 to 1612 he studied at
three children; Pierre,
Rene was of
La
the
Fleche, founded by
There during
his last three years
which consisted of works of
Henry IV and
Organon
third year. This training
Father Clavius' recent
commentaries on the
in the first year, the books
was intended
During
treatise
the college
he received training in philosophy
physics in the second year, the Metaphysics and
to tradition, for theology.
and
directed by the Jesuits.
expositions, summaries, or
Aristotle: the
They had oldest,
his
to
On
on
the Soul in the
prepare him, according
second year he also studied
on mathematics and algebra. In 1616
he passed his examinations in law
at Poitiers.
Like
many
of the
gentry of his time he was freed from any material concern by his
modest fortune. In Holland, then
allied
with France against Spain,
he enlisted in the army of Maurice of Nassau, Prince of Orange.
There he struck up a friendship with Isaac Beeckman, medicine
at the
a doctor of
University of Caen. Beeckman, born in 1588, noted
46
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
47
in his journal that he
and Descartes were both
interested in mathe-
matical or physicomathematical problems. Released from his com-
mitment
to the Protestant prince in 1619, Descartes turned to the
army assembled
against the king by the Catholic duke, Maximilian
of Bavaria.
At Frankfurt he attended
the coronation of
Ferdinand.
On November
German his own
10, 1619, in a
with enthusiasm," according to
"filled
1
sciences.
At
that time Descartes
through a period of mystical exaltations.
His
method capable
refers to a universal
ducing unity into the
He was
Ulm,
statement, he dis-
covered "the basic principles of a marvelous science."
ment undoubtedly
Emperor
village near
state-
of intro-
was passing
affiliated
—perhaps
Ulm —with
through the agency of Faulhaber, a mathematician in
the Rosicrucians, a society that prescribed the free practice of medi-
cine
among
members. The
which only a few
period, of
menta
its
titles
lines
of the manuscripts of this
remain, are significant the Expert:
deals with sensible things, the Parnassus with the realm of
the muses
during
and the Olympica, with divine
this
period that he had a prophetic
in a collection of Latin poets
from Ausonius: "Quod
things. Further,
dream
which he used
vitae sectabor iter?"
in
was
it
which he
read,
as a student, this line
He
interpreted the line
as the sign of his philosophical vocation.
From
1619 to 1628 Descartes traveled.
in Italy,
where he took part
Loretto,
which he had vowed
From
From
1623 to 1625 he
in the pilgrimage to the at the
was
Holy House
time of his dream
of
to visit.
2
1626 to 1628 he remained in Paris, studying mathematics and
dioptrics. It treatise,
was probably
in Paris that he wrote the unfinished
Regulae ad directionem ingenii, which was published in
1701, Rules 12
and
13 of
which are translated
Logic of Port Royal (Part IV, chap,
ii,
into
1664).
French in the
During
the
same
period, Cardinal Berulle, founder of the Oratory, encouraged him
pursue philosophical studies in order to serve the cause of
to
reli-
gion against the free-thinkers. 1
2
(Euvres de Descartes, ed. Adam-Tannery (hereafter identified as AT), X, 179. is some doubt as to whether he actually carried out his vow; see Maxime
There
Leroy, Descartes, le philosophe an masque,
I,
107-18
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
48
Toward
end of
the
France in 1644, he remained there
he changed his residence several times. Be-
1649, although
until
tween 1628 and 1629 he wrote a "short
on the
God and
existence of
was then
physics. It
on the
His
1633.
Rome
reflections
—the
phenomena
On
on the phenomenon of parhelions, observed
him
to
formation
an orderly explanation of of
the
man and
human
the
Office for
in
natural
all
gravity,
planets,
tides
—and
Then came by condemned was
the event that was to change his plans: Galileo
Holy
the World. His
can be traced in his correspondence until
finally to his explanation of
the
on metaphysics,"
1629 he turned his attention to
that he wrote the treatise
treatise
in 1629, led
treatise
of our souls, designed to lay the
foundations of his physics. In
progress
Holland in search
1628, Descartes retired to
of solitude. Except for a trip to
body.
upholding the principle that the earth moves.
"This came as such a shock to me," he wrote to Mersenne on
have almost resolved to burn
July 22, 1622, "that
I
or at least not to
anyone see them.
let
of the earth's motion]
losophy are also
by them and
is false,
false, for this
then
I
all
confess that
is
it
without invalidating
papers,
[the principle
the foundations of
principle
my
phi-
obviously demonstrated
so closely linked to every part of
is
could not remove
my
all
if
all
my
treatise that I
the rest."
The
treatise
remained among Descartes' papers and was not published until 1677.
He
making his physics Method; the
did not, however, abandon the idea of
known, and
in
1637 he published a Discourse on
Dioptric; the Meteors; and the Geometry.
The
three essays
and the
Discourse that precedes them are intended, according to his
state-
ment, merely "to chart the course and to determine the depth of
The
the water."
1635, actually
Dioptric,
which he had already completed in
contained a report on studies
glass-cutting machine;
made
in
1629 of a
a chapter on refraction, written in
1632;
and the elaboration of the corresponding chapter on vision in the treatise
1635,
The
On
the World. Meteors
and tn e Geometry original
title
of the
was composed in the summer of
in 1636, while Meteors
work was "Plan
was being
printed.
of a universal science that
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
49
can
raise
lar,
Dioptric, Meteors
our nature to
its
highest degree of perfection; in particu-
and Geometry,
in
which the most curious
matters that the author could select are explained in such a
manner
who have not studied can understand them." Desgave it a new title: Discourse on a Method of Properly
that even those cartes later
Guiding Reason
in the Search for
Dioptric, Meteors
and Geometry, Which Are Essays
In
Truth
in the Sciences; Also, in this
philosophia in quibus Dei existentia et animae immortalitas strantur, to
which he had completed in
1640.
He
prima
demon-
took every precaution
have the theologians look with favor on his Meditations on First
Philosophy. According to his
foundations of his physics. a
Method.
641 Descartes published in Latin the Meditationes de
1
letter to
He
young Dutch theologian;
first
was
it
contained
to
it,
from them what should be changed,
to learn
added before
it
is
published."
theologians of the Sorbonne,
Mer-
treatise to
judgment
corrected, or
was preceded by a
It
the
together
replies (first objections), to
have Mersenne bring the
the attention of the theologians "in order to have their
and
all
submitted the work to Caterus,
then, late in 1640, he sent
with Caterus* objections and his senne. His intention
Mersenne,
letter to the
whose approbation he sought by
stress-
ing the definitive character of his demonstrations against the ungodly.
Mersenne then
gians
(second
collected the objections of different theolo-
objections),
Hobbes
(third
objections),
Arnauld
(fourth objections), Gassendi (fifth objections), and other theolo-
gians and philosophers (sixth objections). lished,
since
it
The
treatise
followed by the objections and by Descartes'
was erroneously assumed
that the
was pub-
replies,
work would have
and the
approbation of the Sorbonne, on the bottom of the cover was printed
"cum approbatione doctorum." This
from the edition of
1642,
and the
corpore distinctio replaced
Animae
title
tions of the Jesuit
disappeared
was modified {Animae a
immortalitas)
contained, in the reply to Arnauld, a passage
which Mersenne had suppressed
notice
.
This edition also
on the Eucharist
in the first edition,
and the
objec-
Bourdin (seventh objections). Finally, Descartes'
Correspondence made public other objections
—from an anonymous
50
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
person nicknamed Hyperaspistes and from the Oratorian Gibieuf
French translation of the
first
appeared in 1647; the second edition
A
contained the
also
(1661)
.
by Descartes,
edition, revised in part
seven objections. Descartes' persistent effort to have his ideas widely accepted
based on something
much
greater than personal ambition;
it
was was
an awareness of the profound significance of his work, the "true
man
generosity that causes a
to rate himself as
high
he
as
legiti-
mately can." In 1642 he manifested to Huyghens his intention to publish
On
the
World
in Latin
losophiae "in order that
it
may
and
entitle
to
Summa
it
phi-
be more easily introduced into the
conversation of educated people
who now condemn
His sum-
it."
mation was actually the Principia philosophiae, which appeared in 1644
and
for
which he
Jesuit masters,
tried to obtain the approval of his
who were
The French
losophy different from Aristotle's. Picot, published in 1647,
former
in the best position to disseminate a phi-
was preceded by a
translation
by Abbe
letter to the translator
designed to reveal the over-all plan of Descartes' philosophy.
From manded
this
moment
Descartes'
on,
ethical
attention.
questions
seem
to
have com-
His correspondence with Princess
Elizabeth, daughter of Frederick, the titular king of Bohemia,
had found refuge
in Holland, provided
to elaborate his ideas treatise
On
who
him with an opportunity
on the highest good and culminated
in the
the Passions, his last work, published in 1649.
His long stay in Holland was often disturbed by polemics. The Discourse of 1637, communicated to the learned
Mersenne, the great reporter of
mathematicians Fermat and Roberval,
upon unsympathetically by those
More than once
in the
Descartes had the opportunity to as well as his
own
virtuosity,
criticism of the Dioptric.
disputes with the French
who
caused
it
associated with the
challenges
that
show
of his time by
developments, brought
scientific
down upon him Morin's and Hobbes's The Geometry was the cause of bitter
men
to
be looked
young
Pascal.
he made or answered,
the fertility of his
and he found an ardent
method
disciple in
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
51
Florimond de Beaune, whose commentary on the Geometry was published in 1649, along with Schoot's Latin translation of the
work. In Holland, ministers and
saw
members
of the teaching profession
that the success of Descartes' philosophy posed
their teachings,
began
at the
and they fought
Academy
a threat to
The polemic
violently for Aristotle.
of Utrecht between Regius, a professor of
medicine, and Gisbert Voet, a theologian. Regius, one of Descartes'
"even gives private lessons in physics and in a few
admirers,
months makes
heaping ridicule on the old
his disciples capable of
March
philosophy." Troubles increased until
"first
because
the old,
ous
it is
new, next because
wholesome philosophy, and
false
new
and absurd opinions." From
this
because
it
moment
personally defended himself against personal attacks. pletely exonerated at the University of spite of his repeated protestations, the
Groningen
the
philosophy,
turns our youth
it
finally
when
1642,
17,
Senate of Utrecht prohibited the teaching of the
away from
teaches vari-
on, Descartes
He
was com-
in 1645, but in
Utrecht magistrates did not
consent to review their sentence declaring his letter to Voet defamatory. Besides,
he was no longer supported by Regius,
who
misunder-
stood his philosophy and whose theses on the soul he was forced to attack in 1647. versity of
accused
The
next attack on Descartes came from the Uni-
Leyden during the same
him
year. Revius, the theologian,
of blasphemy, a crime punishable under the law.
defend himself, Descartes was obliged to appeal
to the
To
ambassador
of France.
His
stay in
Holland was interrupted only by three short
France, in 1644, 1647, and 1648.
young Pascal and suggested later,
a
to
his
second
trip
he met the
to a report written
the notion of conducting experiments with quicksilver
vacuum.
It
was
a pension which
also
on
his second trip that
was never
paid.
parliamentary Fronde and the Paris.
On
him, according
trips to
The
air there,
he
said,
His third
Day
"makes
and
Mazarin granted him
trip
coincided with the
of Barricades.
me dream
He
never liked
instead of thinking
52
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
philosophical thoughts. There in their opinions
there
is
and
see so
I
many
in their calculations that
a universal sickness"
In September, 1649, he
(AT, V,
left
who
people it
are
seems to
wrong
me
that
133).
Holland and traveled
He
died there on February
11
The Method and Universal Mathematics
Stockholm.
to
11, 1650.
In the preface to the French edition of the Principles (1647) Descartes, wishing to present his doctrine according to the traditional outline of philosophy, divided
and
Physics.
His
logic,
however,
it
into Logic, Metaphysics,
not traditional but
is
and because usage plays an important
for us to devote
much
"that
which
which we
teaches us to use reason wisely to discover truths of
ignorant;
is
part,
it
is
are
good
time to practicing the rules that apply to
simple, easy questions, such as those of mathematics."
We
can easily find the
metaphysics
is
last
two
parts of Descartes' philosophy:
explained in the fourth part of the Discourse, in the
Meditations, and in the
first
book of the Principles; physics
explained in the Dioptric and Meteors, in the treatise
World, in the
fifth
and
sixth parts of the Discourse,
three books of the Principles.
the logic of
We
and
On
is
the
in the last
are hard put, however, to find
He wrote no Organon comNovum organum of Bacon. The
which Descartes speaks.
parable to the Analytics or to the
second part of the Discourse, which contains the rules of the
method, does not go beyond
generalities,
and the Rules, probably
written before 1629, are unfinished. There remains the
Geometry
which, according to Descartes, "demonstrates the method." Further-
more, it
to
it
demonstrates the method not by explaining
solve problems,
and we are wrong
simply as a mathematical procedure. matics in and for
itself
numbers and imaginary
mind
to procedures that
We
to treat
it
it
but by using purely and
are not to study mathe-
in order to find the properties of "sterile figures,"
but in order to accustom the
can and ought to be extended to objects
important in an entirely different sense. Descartes always treated
DESCARTES AND CARTESIAN ISM
53
mathematics
am
"I
as a
product of his method, not as the method
minds guided
ceived by superior
definable, divine part of the
consciousness, the
useful thoughts have been deposited, so that often,
may
neglected and repressed they
Historically, strides
his
it
to
with Beeckman
association
we
see in the
determine whether the prodigious
mathematical discoveries
his
how
no matter
and geometry."
hard
is
marked by
seeds of
first
be as a result of prejudicial
spontaneously; this
studies, they yield their fruits easiest sciences, arithmetic
per-
by nature. For in an un-
solely
human
itself.
method has already been
convinced," he said, "that this
—beginning
and culminating
(1619)
with the
in
theory of equations advanced in the Geometry (1637) and in his
—
on the problem of tangents (1638) precede or follow the method "for the orderly direction of his
letters
discovery of a universal
thoughts" in any matter whatsoever.
One
thing
is
certain: "practice" in the
method was
to
be based
not on "vulgar mathematics" but on what since Aristotle had been classed as "pure mathematics" sions
which studied numbers and dimen-
and "applied mathematics" such
optics. Descartes
was
first
drawn
astronomy, music, and
to applied
he studied the acceleration of falling sure exerted by liquids
as
objects,
mathematics. In 1619 musical chords, pres-
on the bottom of a container, and,
later,
the
laws of refraction. His investigations tended at that time, like those of Kepler
and
toward the mathematical expression of the
Galileo,
laws of nature. But his thought subsequently took an entirely
dif-
ferent course, in the direction of a universal mathematics. Rejecting
the subject matter of vulgar mathematics
sounds
—
this universal
and measure:
order,
—numbers,
mathematics was concerned only with order
by which the understanding of one term
the necessary result of understanding another;
which
objects are related to
What
is
figures, stars,
this universal
is
and measure, by
one another through some shared
trait.
mathematics that a philosopher must learn
in order to train himself in the
method? The fundamental idea
is
expressed at the end of the Geometry: "In the matter of mathematical progressions, after
we have
grasped the
first
two or three
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
54 terms,
A
not hard to find the others."
is
it
essentially of a series of
progression consists
terms arranged in such a manner that the
following term depends on the preceding one. Order, in this case, allows us not only to put each term in the right place but also to
on the
discover,
the
unknown
basis of the place assigned to
terms;
it
has an inventive, creative capacity.
was not the
sure, Descartes
them, the values of
no idea had been more commonplace
order;
whereas
earlier logicians treated order as a
showed
of the terms
and makes possible
determined are always
be
to
(I,
774),
Descartes
which does not
inherent in the nature
is
their discovery.
unknown
In a mathematical problem,
be
or less arbitrary
that a progression manifests a type of order
depend on an arbitrary judgment but
To
consists in
Ramus. But
since
more
arrangement of previously discovered terms
are
method
realize that
first to
quantities
linked
whose values
known
to
quantities
through relations implicitly defined in the statement of a problem.
For
instance,
Pappus' problem, solved in the
may
Geometry,
straight lines
first
book of the
be stated most simply in this way: given three
on a plane,
to find a point
from which
straight lines
can be drawn on them, resulting in equal angles so that the product of the
first
two angles
is
equal to the square of the third. Then,
"without taking into account any difference between
unknown
lines,
which shows others, until
two ways
we must
in the
we
most natural way
find a
known and
study the difficulty according to order,
means
how
each depends on the
of expressing the
same quantity
in
—in other words, an equation. And we must find such an
equation for each of the 372).
Having brought
mine
the value of the
unknown
lines that
we assumed" (VI, we can deter-
to light the "natural" order,
unknown
the inventive capacity of order
line is
by solving the equation. Thus
truly demonstrated
by the
ex-
pedient of equations.
Universal mathematics, therefore, had to surmount several technical difficulties. In the first place,
from it is
all
it
was necessary
the geometric representations to
which
it
to free algebra
was
linked.
And
not surprising that Descartes began the Geometry by showing
—
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
55 that
a and b represent straight
if
X
a
lines,
b or a
a rectangle or a square but another line that
is
2
represents not
to a as
b
is
to unity.
In the same way, a quotient and a root represent straight lines; as a rule, the results of operations are always straight lines. In the
second place,
it
was necessary
more thoroughly
to investigate
the
methods of solving equations independently, without relating symany geometric quantity. This
bols to
book of the Geometry.
of the third
show
is
the fertility of his
method
the subject of the
Finally,
all
The
exhibit a given property.
analytic geometry,
to
Thanks
to
—that
is,
whose
lines
was the creation of
result
mathematics
in
is
to the expedient of co-ordinates,
any point on a line can be determined
if
we know
between two indeterminate straight
relation
was necessary
it
which Descartes' work
often (wrongly) reduced.
half
in the solution of geometric prob-
lems, such as the construction of co-ordinates points
first
lines
the constant
whose points of
intersection supply each of the points of the curve. It follows that
any problem depends on the discovery of a relation between straight lines
—a
braically.
fore
Knowledge
amenable
Such
is
method; dering
of qualities or properties of curves
it
situation in
do" (Rules,
But
science.
universal mathematics,
its
under which
this
mathematics
method
own
it
life,
xii).
is
is
the
is
not the
same time engen-
at the
knowledge which the
intellect
nature and, consequently, of the conditions
exercised.
Wisdom
the intellect will
To
and
accomplish
first
this,
consists
but "in order to prepare objects presented to
itself to it."
imagination, sense, and
perceive
truth"
xii).
memory
This
this:
academic
true, solid
Now among
intellect,
(Rules,
make
in
"in each
show the will what it must the mind must increase its
insights, not "in order to resolve a particular
all
there-
but the application of the method to the simplest
is
Descartes'
acquires of
is
whose procedures have today
the universal mathematics
Above it,
seen, can be expressed alge-
to algebraic calculation.
become part and parcel of objects.
we have
relation which, as
difficulty"
judgments about
the cognitive faculties
—"intelligence
intellectual
alone can
knowledge alone
should be the primary concern of the wise man. "It surprises
me"
—
56
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
says Descartes, "that ties
most
men
study with the greatest care proper-
and the
of plants, transmutations of metals,
like,
while only a
number concern themselves with the intellect and with which we are speaking." Nevertheless, many philosophers of the past had meditated on the nature of the very small
the universal science of
but Descartes studied the intellect neither in order to
intellect;
determine
place in the metaphysical scale of beings (like a
its
Platonist) nor in order to discover the
mechanism
of ideas through sensations (like the Peripatetics) tions reappeared in the eighteenth
Condillac censured Descartes for ideas nor
and the
how
was
to
him
an
aspects of
We
must
centuries,
and
neither the origin of our
They did not concern
Descartes,
The
sciences are distinguished
their objects
but as distinct forms or
intellect eternally identical to itself {Rules, i).
first
apprehend pure
way we
intuition, "conception of a
we have
distinct that
by isolating
intellect
it
"from the
and the deceptive judgments of the
variable testimony of the senses
imagination." In this
stand,"
These two ques-
not a reality to be explained but a
point of departure and a fulcrum.
from one another not by
of the formation
and nineteenth
knowing
they are generated.
intellectus
.
Neo-
identify
its
two
essential faculties
pure and attentive mind, so easy and so
absolutely
no doubt about what we under-
and deduction through which we understand a truth
being the consequence of another truth of which
we
as
are convinced.
Descartes borrowed his vocabulary from traditional philosophy,
and he did not schools
try to hide this fact.
much
not "worry
these
to
Aristotle, the
He
also stated that
he did
about the meanings attached by the different expressions"
word
{Rules,
iii).
In
"intuition" signifies at the
the
language of
same time knowl-
edge of terms prior to their synthesis by judgment, knowledge of the unity that connects the different elements of a concept,
and
knowledge of something present
two
instances,
it
is
as
being present. In the
intuition that arrives at the elements
first
from which
judgments are formed. Similarly, Cartesian intuition has object
first
"It
often easier to examine
is
the "simple natures" of
which everything
several
is
as
its
composed.
natures joined together,"
—
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
57
remarks Descartes
from the
others.
even though tains
I
{Rules, xii), "than
For example,
may
knowledge of
to
separate one of
my
never have noticed that
and
angles, lines,
so forth,
and
prevent our saying that the nature of the triangle
and
these natures since they are
that they are better
what we understand
which,
is
For
composed
other
of all
than the triangle
—extension,
But
we
first
motion, figure realities
follows that their
realities. It
not the simplicity of an abstraction, and that a term
does not become simpler as true.
is
known
does not
which judgments are composed but
when combined, produce
simplicity
knowledge conthis still
in the triangle."
should note that these simple natures are not concepts of
them
can have knowledge of a triangle
I
becomes more
it
instance, the abstract surface of a
limit of the body; although
it
To
simple than this notion.
abstract.
The
body
defined as the
is
reverse
implies the notion of body,
it is
is
less
the intellect, simple natures are ulti-
mate, irreducible terms, so clear that they can be grasped only
reduced to something more
intuitively but not explained or tinct.
There
is
"no
logical definition" of those "things
very simple and which can be recognized naturally place, time,
and the
like"
(AT,
II,
but one surface." existence, or is
attributed
It
is
size,
apprehends not only notions
"I exist," "I think," "a globe has
should be understood that a simple nature,
thought
is
apprehended in a subject
first
and from which
process of abstraction. that
:
which are
—shape,
597).
Intuition, according to Descartes,
but also undeniable truths such as
dis-
it
Number,
to
which
it
can be separated only through a for example,
is
only in the thing
counted, and the "follies" of the Pythagoreans,
who
ascribed
miraculous properties to numbers, would have been impossible
if
they had not conceived numbers as being distinct from the things that are counted {Rules, xiv) therefore,
is
.
The
first
step
not the concept from which
toward understanding,
we
fabricate propositions
but intuitive knowledge of certain truths, the certainty of which will be extended
Finally,
we
by degrees
to their
dependent
truths.
perceive through intuition not only truths but also
the link between one truth
and another immediately dependent on
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
58 it
(for example,
between
1+3 = 2 + 2
and
on
1
+3=
the other)
4,
2
+2=4
on the one hand
and what we
;
common
call
notions (for example, "two things equal to a third thing are equal to
one another") are revealed immediately by the intuition of
these relations.
Such
is
the threefold nature of intuition, the "natural light" or
we
by which
"intellectual
instinct"
"much more
detailed than
onstrate countless propositions"
This demonstration
knowledge
acquire
one might think and
(AT,
VIII, 599).
by which "we understand
things that are the consequence of certain other things"
Cartesian deduction
syllogism.
The
is
dem-
accomplished by means of the second
is
intellectual operation, deduction,
iii).
that
sufficient to
syllogism
quite
is
is
from the
different
all
the
{Rules,
traditional
a relation between concepts, deduction
a relation between truths; the relation between the three terms of the syllogism
is
determined by complicated rules that can be applied
mechanically to reveal whether the syllogism
deduction
is
known by
can be omitted
mind
if
intuition
—through
is
conclusive, whereas
evidence such that
"it
not perceived but cannot be impaired by the
least suited to logical reasoning."
The
syllogism
is
character-
ized by fixed relations between fixed concepts, and these relations exist
even
when
they are not perceived; deduction
is
"the continu-
ous and uninterrupted motion of thought that perceives things, one after the other,
that there
is
with absolute clearness" (AT, X, 369).
It
follows
a place in Cartesian deduction only for propositions
that are certain, whereas the syllogism
accommodates propositions
that are merely probable.
All these differences are easily explained that Cartesian deduction tities
is
typified
if
we understand
clearly
by the comparison of two quan-
by means of a unit of measurement. "Any knowledge that
not acquired through intuition pure and simple
is
comparison of two or more objects. In any process of reasoning, is
only through comparison that
the truth. If there
is
in a
we
we
it
acquire exact knowledge of
magnet a type
ever perceived by our minds,
is
acquired through
of being unlike anything
can never hope to acquire knowl-
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
59
edge of
The
through reasoning" (Rules, xiv).
it
nature of an
unknown thing is determined by its relations with known things. The unknown quantity in an equation is nothing in itself apart from its relations with the known quantities, and it draws its nature entirely from these relations; the same applies to any truth
known through logic)
The
deduction.
object
is
not (as in Aristotelian
to determine whether an attribute belongs to a subject
whose nature
is
known, but
rather to determine the very nature of
the subject, just as a term in a progression
is
determined wholly
by the principle of the progression that engenders deduction essences
—a
a solution to the problem of the determination of
is
Intuition
Cartesian
it.
problem which
baffled the Peripatetics.
and deduction are not method. Method
indicates
"how
we must and how
use intuition to avoid falling into error contrary to truth
arrive at
knowledge of
deduction should operate in such a manner that all
things" (Rules, iv).
proposition, mathematicians choose sitions placed at their disposal
To
from among
we may
demonstrate a
the certain propo-
by intuition and deduction those
immediately applicable, with the result that the convergence of those propositions
produces a
censuring the mathematicians
have arrived
at their choice,
of luck" (Rules, iv). rules for
making
is
new
truth.
that they
which seems
The whole problem
the right choice:
do not
tell
to result
reason for
us
how
they
from a "stroke
method
of
"Method
order and arrangement of the things the
Descartes'
consists
is
to provide
wholly in the
mind should turn toward What we must learn is
in order to discover a truth" (Rules, v).
not to see or deduce truth but infallibly to choose the propositions that bear
on the problem
at
hand.
We
arrive at this result by an
exercise described by Descartes in his sixth rule. It includes three steps
:
"We must
first collect
indiscriminately
all
themselves, then gradually determine whether
them other I
truths,
and from the
truths that present
we can deduce from
latter still others,
and
so on."
Thus
deduce one number from the other in a continuous progression by
always doubling the preceding number. "That done, attentively
on
the truths that
we have
we must
reflect
discovered and examine care-
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
60
why we were
fully
and which
others,
able to discover
it
me
to
is
me
harder for
12, for
deduce from the proportion that (this
is
manner
in
consists
which
to
me
here
exists
to
necessary for
it is
between 3 and 12
determine the geometric
to
the third step) "it follows that
know, when we approach a
method
than
mean
to discover the proportional
another proportion that will allow
mean. Finally
easily
following term by doubling the preceding
between the extremes 3 and
intercalate
them more
of
truths they are." Thus, in the preceding progres-
sion, I easily discover the
one, but
some
we
shall then
particular question, the appropriate
begin our study." Thus, according to the Rules,
mainly in providing the mind with various schemes
know, when faced with a new problem, on how many truths the solution depends. And "store them in the memory [like the rules of the
that will enable us to
which truths and on the object
is
not to
syllogism] but to shape the
mind
in such a
them immediately whenever the need order
is
way
that
arises."
will discover
it
The
discovery of
not accomplished through the mechanical application of a
rule but through the strengthening of the
mind by
exercising
its
spontaneous faculties of deduction. follows that
It
method must
which our knowledge
absolute
us
to
distinguish between
which our knowledge depends on nothing
things of of
train
and what
is
else
relative.
progression, the absolute of the terms; in the
unit of volume;
is
a geometric
the principle that allows us to determine
measurement of
in the
is
Furthermore, the two notions depend
on the nature of the problem under consideration. In all
and things
always conditional; between what
is
measurement
length. In general, the absolute
is
a body, the absolute
of a volume,
the
is
the
unit of
the ultimate condition of the
solution of a problem.
Does method tion, dealt
consist entirely in order?
with in the seventh
rule,
At
seems
to
first
be
glance,
enumera-
less a rule of dis-
covery than a practical means of enlarging the scope of intuition.
We
recall that
deduction
is
an uninterrupted motion,
of truths. After apprehending intuitively the truth
and the next, we can
bond
like a chain
that unites one
(this is the process of
enumeration)
DESCARTES AND CARTESIAN ISM
61
"rapidly survey the different links so that
we seem
be apprehend-
to
ing them at a single glance, barely helped by memory." Successive revelation
truth
change into a
revelations tend to
intuitive
instantaneous
single,
which we apprehend the bond between the
in
and the
last in
also to designate a slightly different operation: "If
were neces-
it
which
sary," said Descartes, "to study separately each of the things relate to the goal
be
first
one intuitive glance. But enumeration seems
we have
no man's
set ourselves,
would
lifetime
because they are too numerous or
sufficient for the task, either
because the same things would reappear too often." Enumeration is
a methodical choice that excludes everything not necessary to
the solution of the problem at hand,
and
it
eliminates in particular
the examination of countless individual cases by reducing things to definite classes, just as
we might
reduce
conical sections to classes
all
according to whether the plane that cuts the cone
is
perpendicular
to its axis, parallel, or oblique. "It
to
is
be noted," wrote Descartes to Mersenne, "that
follow the order of materials but only of reasons"
That
do not
I
(AT,
260).
III,
the distinctive trait of the Cartesian method; for the real
is
order of production he substitutes the order that legitimatizes our
famous
affirmations concerning things. This accounts for the four
precepts of the Discourse, the first
was never
of these
be
clearly perceive to
meaning
and
so,
that
I
to
is
now
clear
anything that
my
to accept in
more than what was presented tinctly
which
of
to accept as true
my mind
I
:
"The
did not
judgments nothing
and
so clearly
could have no reason to doubt
it."
dis-
This precept
excludes any source of knowledge other than the natural light of intelligence; the clarity of to the attentive
contains in
mind;
an idea
distinctiveness
—knowledge
itself
another idea.
What
is
constitutes
the very presence of the idea
knowledge of what the idea
is
such that
method
it
is
cannot be confused with
certainly not natural light,
for neither intuition nor deduction can be learned; but for us to learn to
up each
employ nothing
of the difficulties that
parts as possible
and
as
I
else.
it is
"The second was
was going
to
might be required
examine into
to resolve
possible
to divide as
them
many in the
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
62
manner. The third was
best
with the objects
ning
to think in
an orderly fashion, begin-
which were simplest and
easiest to
under-
and gradually, by degrees, reaching upward toward more
stand,
complex knowledge, even assuming an order among things that follow no natural sequence." These are the two rules of order; the the identification of the simple natures
prescribes
first
and the
absolute of a problem (study of the equations of the problem)
;
the
second refers quite clearly to the formation of schemes of increasing
known
complexity
"And
the last
reviews
general
so
omitted."
to us
It is
from the Rules (composition of equations).
was always that
make enumerations
to I
was
certain
nothing had been
that
through enumeration that everything necessary and question
sufficient to resolve a
words added
see clearly in the
is
studied methodically. For as
to the
rendis), the important thing
we
Latin translation of the Dis-
quam
course (tarn in quaerendis mediis
memory once
complete and
so
in difficultatibus percur-
not to retain demonstrations in the
is
they have been accomplished, but to discover every-
thing necessary to their accomplishment.
Metaphysics
in
Descartes wrote to Mersenne on April all
those to
employ I
must
of themselves.
tell
you that
I
foundations of physics
Thus, according
God and tian's
has given the use of reason are obliged to
That
is
why
I
undertook
would never have been if I
had not searched
to Descartes, metaphysics,
of one's
self, fulfills
by methodical order;
knowledge of
my
studies,
for
them
which
is
in this way."
knowledge of
draws support from metaphysics.
is
a Chris-
combat the negations of is
finally, physics
the
first
and
able to discover the
several requirements. It
obligation to use reason to
thinkers; furthermore, metaphysics
it
1630: "I believe that
principally for the purpose of acquiring
it
him and
whom God
15,
free-
question necessitated
cannot achieve certainty unless
—
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
63
The in the
of these three reasons reveals Descartes' participation
first
campaign against the
retired to Holland, Descartes
he
was asked by Cardinal Berulle
to
and
support the cause of religion,
We
recall that before
free-thinkers.
that the Meditations, considered
in this light, belong to the tradition of the rationalistic apologetics
wanted
that originated in the sixteenth century. Descartes his
and
part
(AT,
stated
240).
III,
He
repeatedly that he supported "God's cause"
sought the approbation of the theologians
and asked Mersenne
the Sorbonne
to theologians. It
is
do
to
to
at
submit the Meditations only
clear that his metaphysics
had a place in the
and we need only note the use
religious
movement
which
was put by the philosopher-theologians of the second half
it
of the century
But that important
edge of
He
is
is
God
of his time,
—Bossuet,
Arnauld, and Malebranche.
merely an external aspect of Descartes' thought. Most the place
it
has in his system; to Descartes the knowl-
provided by metaphysics was not an end but a means.
thought the goal he had
judgments concerning
—"to
himself
set for
make
first
What was
seeking the foundation of cer-
tainty in
God
tainty of
mathematics and physics which underlie
himself.
at stake
that collectively constitute the happiness of
and
true, valid
the objects that present themselves"
all
could not be attained without
cine,
ethics. "I will tell
was
certainty, the cer-
of the arts
all
man—mechanics,
you privately," he wrote
to
medi-
Mersenne,
"that these six meditations contain the complete foundations of physics, but this arbitrarily
Catholic
to
must not be
told to others."
my
Never did Descartes
introduce the least trace of a specifically Christian or
dogma
into the fabric of his doctrine.
He
affirmed his
faith not as a philosopher
but as a citizen of a country associated
with a religion in which
God had
graciously caused
him
to be
born. His attachment to religion, obviously sincere, quite naturally
implied the conviction that no philosophical truth can be incompatible with the truth of revealed
dogmas (which
is
the generally held
concept of the relations between faith and reason in therefore,
when
Thomism);
theologians criticized his theory of matter and
—
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
64
stated that
it
was not consonant with the dogma of transubstantishow that the two are compatible.
ation, Descartes took pains to
Thus we and
see that religious considerations intervene only indirectly
and that the Cartesian vision of the universe
accidentally,
independent of dogma.
essentially
The eminent
in all
life.
would "one day" demonstrate some of the
soul. In 1628,
it
God and
truths of faith
the immortality of the
not certain of his physics, he composed a "short
still
on metaphysics." The unfinished dialogue On the Search
for Truth, probably written in life,
to the attention
While writing the Rules he announced
probability the existence of
treatise
must have come
role of metaphysics
of Descartes early in that he
is
also begins
deduce "what
possible for us to
(AT, X,
creatures"
Stockholm during the
with the rational soul and
505).
most
is
During
its
year of his
last
creator,
which makes
certain concerning other
was
the intervening years he
always preoccupied by the same thought: the Discourse (1637), the Meditations, the Principles of metaphysics,
—of
which the
entitled "Principles of
is
agree on the point that no certainty existence of It is
first part,
Human
an exposition
Knowledge"
possible unless based
is
—
all
on the
God.
hard for us to imagine
have seemed
Descartes'
to
how
contemporaries. In Scholasticism the
God owes
affirmation of the existence of
effect to
intuition
of the
cause, to things
its
certainty wholly to
which lead us back
the certainty of sensible things
from an
paradoxical this thesis must
to
God
as
a cause; inversely, Neo-Platonism begins with
divine principle
—the
and goes from God
effects of this cause.
—the
first
Descartes was apparently
confronted with two alternatives, but his chain of reasoning pro-
vided an escape.
The
first
two
steps of his metaphysics point
up
the impossibility of either course: methodical doubt, by showing that there
is
no
certainty in
sensible
matical things, prevents us from going
things or even in mathe-
from things
to
God, and
the theory of eternal truths prohibits our deriving the essence of
things
from God
as the
model.
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
6$
The Theory
Metaphysics:
iv
Let us
first
of Eternal Truths
consider the theory which Descartes expounded in
his letters as early as 1630
but did not take up again in his published
works. According to the Platonic thesis which suffused the Middle
Ages and the Renaissance, the essence of a created thing in the divine essence, so that there
is
of the divine essence. Degraded, confused, applies to created things,
nearly as
it
and inadequate
which merely
God
you
participate in his eternal essence. Des-
as
do
independent of
all
15,
less
1630).
is in effect to
and
The
to subjugate
possible
To
wholly
say that such truths are
speak of
him
God
to the Styx
and the good are not
omnipotence; possible only are "the things that
he were
as if
and
to fate"
rules to
the will of God, in creating things, submits, for this his
than their
God and depend
were established by
other creatures.
him
Jupiter or Saturn
(April
no
were created by God: "The mathematical truths that
call eternal truths
on him,
it
the creator of existences but not
is
cartes held that the essences of created things,
existences,
as
such knowledge will be perfected, as
can be in a created being, only in the illuminative
vision. It also follows that
of essences,
participates
no knowledge other than that
which
would
God
limit
willed to
be truly possible" and "the reason for their goodness depends on the fact that he
saw
an attachment, then,
fit
to create
to the
them" (May
freedom of
God
Gibieuf, a friend of Descartes, devoted a
to
1644).
Why
such
which the Oratorian
work published
in 1630?
Because, in the finite understanding of man, this theory alone
compatible with a perfect knowledge of essences. "There particular one [of these eternal truths] that if
our minds are disposed to consider
understand the greatness of
with
it"
(April
16,
By bond of
1630).
essences of finite things a
God
it.
we
no
cannot understand
In contrast,
even though
positing
is
is
we cannot
we are familiar God and the
between
creature to creator
and not a bond
of participation, Descartes ruled out the possibility of any meta-
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
66
might
physics or physics that of being
and of knowledge from
make God
to
deduce the forms
aspire rationally to
and he was
their first cause;
the guarantee rather than the
able
model of our under-
standing. In other words, according to the general precept of his
method, he no longer followed the order of God's production of things but "the order of reasons,"
how
can engender another, for us the principle of
which shows how one
certainty
God
certainty of the existence of
any other
is
certainty.
Metaphysics: Doubt and the Cogito
v
In the three published expositions of his metaphysics (the fourth part of the Discourse, the Meditations,
and the
Principles), Descartes always followed the
book of the
first
same order: doubt con-
cerning the existence of material things and the certainty of mathematics; the unshakeable certainty of "I think, therefore
am"; the
I
demonstration of the existence of God; the guarantee that
judgments grounded on
existence provides for
and the resulting
ideas; soul,
the
which
is
existence
doubt
and
clear
concerning the essence of the
certainties
thought, the essence of the body, which of
material
things.
to certainty, or rather
plied in doubt
itself,
this
distinct
Thus
from an
metaphysics
size,
is
judgment im-
initial certain
growing succession of
the Cogito, to a
and
goes from
certain
judgments, for only certainty can engender certainty. Since
the
Skeptics
third
century
b.c.
followers
the
had accumulated reasons
for
of
and the
Plato
doubting sensible things.
Descartes took up these reasons. In the illusions of the senses and in
dreams we believe things
false
—sufficient
ceived us. But
to
be true that
we
judge to be
later
reason to distrust the senses that have once deif
his
arguments were the same
Skeptics, his intentions
were quite
different.
He
for his doubt in his reply to the sensationalist
as
those of the
gave the reason
Hobbes:
"I
used
[reasons for doubting] partly for the purpose of training readers'
minds
to consider intellectual things
corporeal things, for
and
to separate
which they have always seemed
them from to
me
to be
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
6y
Summary
an absolute necessity." In the
of Meditations he stated
means
that "doubt provides us with an easy
of accustoming our
minds to detach themselves from the senses," and that such detach-
ment
the necessary condition of certainty.
is
Doubt concerning material an
ascesis
comparable
things, therefore,
to the effort
made by
is
methodical doubt,
Plato's prisoner to turn
toward the light, and Descartes utilized skepticism to achieve, in the nothingness of the sensible world, an awareness of the spiritual reality.
Theologians
who
criticized Descartes
on
point were
this
not mistaken, and objections to his methodical doubt were raised
not by theologians but by sensationalists Cartesian doubt goes
much
—Hobbes
and Gassendi.
further in one sense than does skep-
doubt. For once Descartes had established even the slightest
tical
reason for doubting, he did not hesitate to posit other reasons that amplified
and carried
it
to the
it
utmost degree, proceeding here
who "assume
(he remarked to Gassendi) like those are true in order to cast for instance,
more
who "add new
light
on the truth"
lines to
Such doubt,
—the
geometers,
given figures." This makes
possible the "hyperbolic doubt" that has to
propositions.
that false things
do with mathematical
truly extraordinary since
it
causes us to
hold as uncertain knowledge considered the most certain of is
made
possible by the hypothesis of an
whose hypothetical power ever
I
is
such that
it
add two and three or count the
Rules. But apart
how
is
on knowledge
sides of a square or
is
is
still
unknown
make
eternal
truths
of
God whose
to us, a spirit that has the
same power
If
"evil," this spirit will
things at the very instant us to
the hypothesis of
the very possibility of such doubt conceivable
through his omnipotence? but
Thus
make
classed as intuitive in the
from Descartes' God who has decreed the
existence
all,
"evil spirit"
can introduce error "when-
a decision about something even simpler." the evil spirit casts doubt
omnipotent
we
posit,
instead
be capable of changing the truths of
we
perceive them,
and thus of causing
mistakes.
In another sense, however, Cartesian doubt skeptical doubt. It does not
fails to
go
as far as
go beyond "notions so simple
that,
—
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
68
by themselves, they provide no knowledge of anything that {Principles,
or at
I,
10), such
common notions —for instance, the principle that least as much reality in the total efficient cause as
effect.
Furthermore,
differs
it
whereas the skeptic
Thus he
and the absence of
tainty
all
considered only they are
objects of
my
no middle ground between if
realities
doubt, which
intelligible or sensi-
where there
doubt
this relation,
my
my
is
without seeing with certainty that
and every reason
I I
thought,
is
no doubt. But
—my
doubt would again
existence as thought
is
my
linked to the
is
cannot perceive that
for doubting that I
reasons for repeating
thought;
am: Cogito ergo sum. entail
my
I
If I
think
came
affirmation,
have managed to adduce
doubt about sensible things, the existence of an
new
cer-
Descartes, like his predecessors,
whether they are
existence of the self that thinks;
to
its
knowledge. Like Plato's prisoner, he
cannot turn toward a world of sense
in
doubting, Descartes would have
he considers uncertainty independently, as thought in this
is
certainty.
objects, for
its
all
there
propositions that give us the slightest
leaves
Such doubt would lead nowhere ble,
must be
there
by nature from skeptical doubt, for
persists in his
us consider as patently false
reason to doubt.
exists"
as the notions of consciousness or existence,
evil spirit
The
affirmation.
the necessary condition of
— are
certainty of
my
doubt.
but
my
Thus
Descartes arrives at an initial judgment of existence by abandoning the vain pursuit of objects
and substituting
on the very
reflection
thing that pursues them.
The it
function of the Cogito, according to Descartes,
provides the paradigm of a certain proposition, and
the
radical
distinction
certain because
my
I
everything which is
my
grounded on
I
a
and
distinctly the relation
existence. Therefore
perceive with the relation,
I
am
I
is
between
can consider as true
same evidence.
My
conviction
a deduction, a progression from one
notion to another, from the notion of existence.
twofold;
establishes
between mind and body. The Cogito
perceive clearly
thought and
is
it
my
thought
to that of
my
not searching for an identity like the one that the
ancient metaphysicists
from Parmenides
to Plotinus tried to estab-
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
69
between thought and being
lish
—an
on an attempt
identity based
to attain to the total reality of the universe within the confines
of thought.
The
total
apprehension of
reality that Plotinus
through the intuitive act of a soul co-extensive with
achieved reality
all
must not be sought in the Cogito. Descartes warns us that the Cogito is not "an illumination of the mind through which it sees
God
in a divine light the things that
means of a
direct impression
standing" (AT, V, 133);
at
it is
sees
fit
to reveal to
of divine lucidity
by
most "a proof of the capacity of
our soul to receive intuitive knowledge from God." Above
shows that the mind can have complete,
it
it
on our under-
total
all else,
knowledge of a
particular object in the absence of total certainty with respect to
the whole of reality. This
a necessary condition of the application
is
The human mind is so only a very small number
of method. distinctly
and
must be instantaneous
certainty
mind could have no certainty
after Descartes, It is
that
tion.
to
of objects at the
same time,
about anything without having
many
metaphysicists
still
believed
then certain knowledge would be impossible.
attained.
But
it
reflection
on
his
all
other certainties
does not follow that other certainties
be attained by the same path
Through
can perceive
it
in order to be effective. If the
only in this sense that the Cogito typifies
might be
ought
certainty
about everything, as
limited that
—that
is,
through
self-reflec-
thought Descartes found no existence
own God or
other than the existence of his
thought, and from this he could
not deduce the existence of
of matter.
The
Cogito has noth-
ing to do with any type of idealism that seeks progressively to define all
forms of
reality as conditions of the reflection of the self
upon
itself.
The second
function of the Cogito in the system
the distinction
upon which
—the distinction between mind and body. thinking being and uniquely as such.
know through a subtle
fire,
I
It is
the Cogito alone whether
I
know
I
still
to establish
am
do not
is
based
myself only as a
true that
I still
cannot
not also a substance,
or something entirely different; I
thinking being, but
is
the whole of Cartesian physics
know
know whether
I
myself as a
am
only a
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
70
thinking being.
my
can nevertheless be certain of
I
being as a
being that thinks, senses, and wills without knowing anything
A
about the existence of bodies. the
mechanism
"perceive
which probably implies corporeal
of these acts,
conditions of which
am
I
totally ignorant,
them immediately by
also sensing the
same thing
as
and the
ourselves," a
which makes "not only hearing,
istic
must be made between
distinction
willing,
common
which
thinking" {Principles,
Thus
relates.
it
it is
character-
and imagining but I,
9)
would
It
.
mind
be a mistake to try to define the operation of the of the object to
we
fact that
in terms
assumed that bodies are
known by sensation; but if I try to determine how I know a piece of wax which is at first fragrant, hard, and cold but later loses all these qualities on being heated, or how I know its flexibility, which is the capacity to receive an infinite number of changes of figure, I
perceive clearly that
of
its
my
I
imagination (which
of figures), but "only action of the
mind
is
that bodies are not
must is
my
on
rely neither
change from one
sensible qualities
state to
all
unable to apprehend an infinite number
on mental
inspection."
not defined by
its
\nown through
It
or object of the senses,
follows that the
object or limited by
it
and
sensation. This affirmation
of great significance. Descartes denied that there reality,
senses (since
another) nor on
and another
is
is
one corporeal
intelligible reality, or
object of the intellect or understanding, as medieval thought with all its
inherent Platonism
had conceived
not defined from without by
its
it.
The understanding
objects but
from within by
is
its
inner need for clarity and distinction.
When
theologians became acquainted with Descartes'
Arnauld was quick thing. Indeed, St.
to note that St.
Augustine used the idea "Si
from pessimism; furthermore, demonstrate that the soul
He
used
it
is
in the
spiritual
also to reveal the
tine's texts.
But
in St.
doubt comparable
De and
jailor,
trinitate
distinct
sum"
to escape
he used
from
was acquainted with
it
to
the body.
image of the divine Trinity
soul. In all probability Descartes
Cogito,
Augustine had said the same
St.
in the
Augus-
Augustine the Cogito did not terminate a
to the
methodical doubt of Descartes and did
71
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
not initiate a study like physics. If he came under
Augustine's
St.
influence, consciously or unconsciously, Descartes used his ideas as
he would use one of Euclid's theorems in a demonstration in his
Geometry.
What
matters
not a truth so simple and so readily
is
accessible as this one, but the use to
noted in
this context,
dated in
its
—the
we must
which
"explore
author." Augustine seized
and the
acquisition of certainty
failed to see in
it
was
As
put.
an idea
Pascal
accommo-
is
immediate consequences
its .
it
how
He
spirituality of the soul.
the "remarkable series of consequences" that
made
"the firm and constant principle of a whole system of physics."
it
Metaphysics:
vi
The
The
Existence of
certainty of the Cogito
thought.
At
first
is
God
limited to the existence of our
glance Descartes seems to have followed
in the path of the Skeptics
when,
to the ideas that are in us,
he defined an idea
after
reducing
it
I
conceive that
fear, I give
my
desire or fear at the
I
and
desire
fear a place
as the idea of a triangle or a tree.
things to the
is
is,
strictly
is
is
mode to
of
"the
"everything
desire or fear ("be-
same time
among my
I
desire or
ideas") as well
In this sense ideas, in their formal
equal and imply nothing other than
my
the solipsism of the Skeptic which reduces
all
or essential reality, are
thought. This
wax"
can receive." Hence an idea
conceived immediately by the mind," that cause
simple
as a
own
our knowledge
all
thought, thought being to ideas as "a piece of different figures that
3
modes
all
of being of the
self,
between an emotion and the notion of an
making no
distinction
object.
was by choosing a completely different path that Descartes emerged from doubt. Doubt is an act of the will through which It
we
retract the
judgments that we have spontaneously made con-
cerning things.
Our
act leaves unaltered the ideas
by which
we
represent these things to ourselves; our beliefs have changed but
not our notions.
Doubt
is
not intended to accustom us not to feel
or perceive or relate ideas; 3
De V esprit
it
is
intended to accustom us not to
geometrique, ed. Brunschvicg, p. 192.
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
72
believe that the objects of these sensations, perceptions,
and
rela-
tions exist.
Our
from
ideas (in the language of philosophy, inherited
Plato,
"ideas" meant "forms of divine understanding" and models of
things) continue, however, to be representations or images of things.
They have an
which
"objective reality"
represented, in so far as this being
the
one hand
is
is
in the
by geometers
sion, for instance;
—the
and on the
mind. There are on
immutable natures," such
ideas that represent "true,
as those utilized
the being of the thing
idea of a triangle or of exten-
other, ideas that cannot be said to
represent either a positive nature or a privation
—ideas
like heat or
cold.
Thus we
own
ideas
find that there
—a
difference
a qualitative difference between our
is
which
"suspension" of the Skeptics.
second
and
class are so vivid
doubting, to believe they
exist.
We
Now
us, before
exam-
bases of Peripatetic physics)
from
the right to existence only to ideas of the
between the two types of
compel
these are the ideas (for
—the
that Descartes rigorously excluded
rules out the
should note that ideas of the
forceful that they
heat or of cold
ple, the idea of
and which
decisive
is
his physics; first class.
ideas, therefore,
is
he conceded
The
distinction
one of the moments
(and perhaps the main one) in the vast seesaw movement by
which Descartes was
to
after
would deal only with
very distinction
we
—until then the science —into a science which there-
transform physics
of sensible, obscure, fleeting qualities true,
also discover
immutable natures. But in
one of the great
difficulties
this
of his
system: at this point in his exposition Descartes could not justly attribute to these natures a higher value
employment and
fertility in physics,
by referring
to their future
but only by considering them
independently before he used them as the point of departure for the methodical elaboration of the system.
Descartes
knew
too obvious that
that they could be so used at the time he
meditating on metaphysics, but to
It is all
it
is
also obvious that
was
he wanted
prove the value of his principles independently of their applica-
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
73 tion.
He was
a principle
apart
probably fully aware that the explicative
was
sufficient to confer
on
"moral certainty" and
it
from any metaphysics, mechanical
type of certainty
principles
they served to explain a great
if
phenomena; but
it
fertility of
that,
would have
number
this
of natural
only by "relying on metaphysics" that one
is
can give them "something more than moral certainty" {Principles, IV,
art.
205)
from doubt,
.
That
to
is
make
why
Descartes decided, even before emerging
a distinction between true,
immutable natures
(he cited the familiar example of the objects of mathematics) and all
the disorder
senses,
all
and confusion associated with the
and
the arbitrariness
objects of the
with the
associated
irregularity
objects of the imagination.
Descartes' innatism
is
merely the formulation of
Innatism means that there are ideas which the its
own
resources
and uses
pendence and the
to initiate
interiority
of
the
this separation.
intellect
thought;
it
succession
draws from
asserts the inde-
of
methodically
connected thoughts in contrast to the arbitrary succession of the impressions of the senses and the imagination. Innatism strange doctrine that
Locke
tried to refute
—
not the
is
the doctrine of an
inner awareness, actual and constant, of every principle of our
knowledge. The innatism of ideas consists in the disposition and,
them;
so to speak, the vocation of the understanding for conceiving
they are innate in us just as gout and gravel are hereditary in certain families.
Like Plato's reminiscence, innatism means the independ-
ence of the intellect in
much with
its
investigations. It
is
the question of origin (obviated, as
concerned not so
we have
seen,
by
the conditions of the problem) as with the question of value.
But what are the objective reality in the
true,
immutable natures which have
mind? Thanks
to the ascesis of methodical
doubt, thanks also to mathematics and to the
muddled
their
manner
in
which the
ideas of the senses, such as the idea of heat, are eliminated,
Descartes accepted only the objects of pure understanding of a facile, even a
common
—objects
or vulgar type of knowledge, like the
knowledge of number, thought, motion, extension. Essences
are
no
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
74
longer grasped with great difficulty and always incompletely even
much
after
in Aristotelian
as
labor,
logic,
but are apprehended
immediately as points of departure. It
was the contemplation of objective God. Not
to the existence of
there
objects;
idea of an
more
is
some than
in others
angel, for instance, than in the idea of a
hard
is
ideas are equal with respect to their
perfection in
question of determining point
all
reality that led Descartes
—in
the
man. The
how ideas are comparable from this standWhat mattered to Descartes was that
resolve.
to
such a comparison necessarily implies the idea of an absolutely perfect being, the standard
The
was
"true idea"
I
am
secretly present
how would
tion began, "for
doubt and that
on which it
all
comparisons are based.
when
metaphysical medita-
be possible for
me
to
know
—that that lack something — did not have within me an
desire
I
I
is,
not wholly perfect
if I
that
and
I
that
idea of a
being more perfect than mine to serve as a basis for comparison
and reveal perfect
and
inasmuch
me
to
infinite
as
it
is
also the first
to
that
my own
nature?" Thus the idea of
not only a "very clear and very distinct idea,"
contains
it is it
the defects in
more
and the
clearest of all ideas,
conceive finite and limited beings.
I
any other, but
objective reality than
and
We
it is
in relation
cannot
say, then,
with the theologians of the second and the fourth objections, that
was fabricated by a mind
this idea
that arbitrarily
augments the
it conceives of and combines them into a fictitious being. Hence a first argument to prove the existence of God. Descartes drew support from the following enunciation of the principle of
perfections
causality:
"There
is
at least as
much
reality in a cause as in
an
Here we recognize the old Aristotelian maxim, "A potential being can become actual being only under the influence of an effect."
actual being." is
provided by
cause
is
An its
effect
can have no perfection except that which
cause; this formulation
makes
sense only
if
the
conceived as an actual being and the effect as residing in
a potential being that
comes under its influence (by itself brass cannot become a statue). Descartes applied the principle to ideas in our minds, considered as an effect: "There is at least as much
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
75
formal
reality in the cause of
the idea
The
itself."
an idea
new
idea of a
as there
is
objective reality in
mechanism could only in the mind
horological
not spring up indiscriminately but was possible
and well trained
of a talented
artisan. It follows that all
and require
in order to find out whether our ideas represent
"formal" reality different from our thought of a being outside our thought selves
have enough
ideas.
Now
it
—
is
to
—that
a
the existence
is,
determine whether
we
our-
reality or perfection to be the authors of these
obvious that we, imperfect beings that
is
we need
we
are,
cannot be the author of the idea of the perfect being; only the perfect being has
enough
produce
reality to
it
fore exist with the infinite perfections conceived
Descartes' proof received further confirmation line of
argument:
the author of
my
am
I
of a perfect being;
it
by
being, for
if
I
I
there-
us.
from the following
an imperfect being and
follows that
and must
in us
have the idea
I
cannot conceive of myself as
had the power
to create myself,
would have the power a fortiori to give myself all the perfections of which I conceive; for the same reason I can eliminate causes which would be less perfect than God (since they would have given I
themselves every possible perfection) and also responsible only for
my
body; therefore,
I
am
my
parents,
who
are
created by the perfect
being. His proof appears to be similar to the proof a contingentia
mundi, which begins with any kind of back to the
first
cartes begins
cause, but
with a
finite
it
is
and
finite effect
traces
it
actually quite different, since Des-
mind
possessed of the idea of the
first
cause.
Thus two
existences have been established: that of myself as a
thinking being and that of
God
outside me.
The
point worth
noting, the reason for Descartes' radical originality in spite of the alien material he
employed,
the existence of things only of
them
—for
is
this: it is possible for us to establish
when we have
a clear
and
instance, thought or the perfect being.
axiom of Aristotelianism was
that existence
This implies that
A
methodical
must be proved before
investigating essence, in order to avoid pursuing like the stag-goat.
distinct idea
we can make
mere chimeras, a judgment of
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
j6
we know
existence before
we
are affirming
the nature of the thing
whose
existence
—an attitude wholly in keeping with the common-
sense approach that forces us to accept for the very same reason
many
obscure and ill-defined notions. Against
this,
methodical doubt
rules out the existence for the
human mind
of anything that
muddled
idea. Certain
judgments of existence
object of an obscure,
made
can be
only
if
their
and
are clear
subjects
distinct
the
is
ideas.
Descartes was able to dispense with existence and posit essence
because he had a means, not accessible to Aristotle, of separating "true natures"
from the chimeras of the imagination. By conceding
existence only to objects of clear ideas,
thought flight
is
in a realm of
its
own and
we
arrive at a reality
can engage in
its
without fear of being submerged by an ocean of alien
inaccessible to the
realities
mind.
Descartes' intention effected his intention
that hyperbolic
where
methodical
is
—
manifested in the means by which he
proof of the existence of God.
doubt revealed the
evil spirit as a
We
recall
being capable of
introducing error even into clear and distinct thought, with the result
that
thought was never master of
demonstration of the existence of
God
own domain. But
its
destroys
the strength of
such doubt. Knowledge of that true nature represented by the idea of a perfect being
shows us that the
our imagination, for an omnipotent being has tions at the
cannot be deceived about things that
clearly
and
all
distinctly. If
is
a chimera of
the other perfec-
same time and could not be malicious or
existence of this benevolent being, therefore,
we
was
evil spirit
deceptive.
The
our guarantee that
we have once
perceived
"an atheist cannot be a geometer"
it is
be-
we make mistakes the our will. Our understand-
cause he lacks this guarantee of certainty. If fault lies not in
ing
and to
is
finite
our understanding but in
—that
distinct ideas.
is,
it
Our
has obscure, confused ideas alongside clear will
is
finite— that
is,
we have
full
freedom
adhere or not to adhere to the conjunctions of ideas presented to
us by our understanding.
Judgment
is
not knowledge of a relation
but rather assent through an act of the will.
We
are free to act in
:
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
77
such a manner that only the light of our understanding will determine the consent of our will; methodical doubt proves this precept and is merely its application.
This marks a veritable turning point in philosophical thought.
That
truth perceived through
human
understanding had
foun-
its
Thomism
dation in divine understanding was a familiar precept of
"Uncreated truth and divine understanding are neither measured
nor produced, but they measure and produce a double truth, one
and the other
in things
notions are exist in
still
in the soul."
images of the
how
matter
is
Descartes,
become
intellectual
it is
a reflection
toward
therefore turned naturally
and our true vocation
reflection will
blurred, our
intelligible reasons of things as they
God; our knowledge, authenticated because
of divine understanding, origin,
No
in the eternal
is
life
which
in
its
this
a direct vision. Against this, according to
knowledge
is
participation in divine understanding,
not in
and
it is
the
least
degree a
well for us to recall
here that in his thinking the essences which are the object of
human
understanding are creatures of God. In consequence
God
is
the guarantee of our knowledge, not through an attribute relating to his
understanding but through attributes relating to his creative
power, omnipotence, and goodness. standing life.
is
The
vocation of
human
under-
not to consummate the vision of essences in the eternal
Clear and distinct knowledge, which was the object or goal
when
these essences
were viewed
in divine understanding, in search of
its
as reflections of those that existed
became a point of departure
combinations and
effects.
for the
mind
Descartes looked forward
toward the methodical analysis of things rather than backward their transcendent origin.
The
natural destiny of
standing had no supernatural destiny as
its
clarity of
elect
did not in
human knowledge, which
proceeds not from obscurity to clarity but from clarity to Descartes,
who
established a close relation
God, and even went
under-
complement, and the
thought of the dazzling vision promised to the
any way obscure the perfect
human
at
so far as to say that
clarity.
between knowledge and
an
atheist could not
be
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
jS
same time
a geometer, at the
radically separated
any theological design by putting understanding, which has
But was Descartes
A
doubt?
this point.
justified in
relying
human
wholly on the plane of
God.
a certainty authenticated by
using this means to emerge from
number of his contemporaries took issue with him on They discovered that he had been caught in a vicious
God
for the existence of
circle,
it
knowledge from
on the evidence of
clear
could be demonstrated only by
and
distinct ideas, yet such evidence
depended on prior demonstration of
his existence. Descartes
an-
swered the objection by saying that there are two types of certainty, the certainty of axioms,
which are grasped
directly
and which are
not subject to doubt, and the certainty of acquired knowledge,
which ing.
consists of conclusions that
depend on a long chain of reason-
As we proceed we are able to grasp successively each of the make up the links in the chain and to see its relato the preceding link. Having reached the conclusion, how-
propositions that tion ever,
we
we
recall that
clearly perceived the first propositions
though we can no longer perceive them now. In thentication
is
useless in the case of
even
short, divine au-
axioms and necessary only for
acquired knowledge. Descartes' reply
the existence of
is
somewhat perplexing.
itself
God depends on
a rather long
First, if
proof of
and complicated
chain of reasoning, the vicious circle persists. Furthermore, Descartes
seems to have extended doubt far beyond the
When
in his reply.
results
assumed
he said that the simplest operations, such
as
counting the sides of a square, were subject to doubt, he was certainly not limiting
doubt
to the conclusions
of reasoning. Finally, even
Descartes
God
still
fallible,
ceived an obvious
memory depends As
memory,
clear,
two
solely
when
on our is
there
drawn from
difficulties it is
for nothing
from leading us truth
far as the first point
found a
these
could not have meant, as
authenticates
from being
if
a chain
were removed,
sometimes
stated, that
would prevent memory
to believe that
we had
was none; the
per-
fidelity
of
attention.
concerned, Descartes thought he had
axiomatic proof of the existence of God: the one
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
79
customarily called the ontological proof, expounded for the
time in the Discourse and for the
God
the existence of
property of a triangle
we
perfection,
deduced from the definition of
is
Once we understand
God
that
God
see that
perfection. Existence
time in the Meditations;
last
deduced from the notion of God,
is
just as a
this figure.
the being possessed of every
is
possesses existence since existence
a perfection:
is
But God
have of him
as
an
to say that there
he a
To
therefore not absolutely perfect,
is
this
power.
viewpoint
power
God
that produces
Descartes referred
ground of
the
is
its
own
when he
we
say that he does not exist
him some power which
in
which his
existence.
contradictory.
is
This
is
is
not realized, that
is
own
a
upon
through the idea that
reveals himself to us
infinite
is
is
power
implies a positive
it
in the thing that exists or in whatever has conferred existence this thing.
first
From
being {causa sui), the proof to
said he did not believe "that the
which
human
mind could know anything with greater evidence and certainty." Thus the first difficulty vanishes if proof of the existence of God acquires the certainty of an axiom.
But the second to
remains, since hyperbolic doubt seems
difficulty
extend even to axioms. Here
it
is
necessary for us to note one
distinction that Descartes clearly established in his reply to Regius,
who had
objected that divine authentication
axioms of reply
clearly
truth
and
clear
(May
22, 1640)
understood?
self-evident "I agree
:
it
clearly.
with the nature of God, however,
if it
is
It
God
follows that
in
his
long as they are
this too, so
So long
we
as
we
are unfamiliar
cannot conclude that the
will appear to us again with equal clearness even
an axiom.
tability of
stated
for
therefore not possible for us to doubt a
It is
whenever we perceive
same proposition
Descartes
truth.
with
was not necessary
is
What
guarantees the goodness and the
immu-
the constancy of positive proof throughout time.
we need
only recall having clearly perceived a
proposition (provided of course that our
order to be sure that
it
is
memory
true. Certainty derives
is
faithful)
from an
in
instan-
taneous vision, and successive instants are in themselves independent of each other.
We
therefore could not conclude that one
mo-
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
80
ment's truth will endure until the next
have divine immutability instants.
together
link
to
moment
we
if
did not
host of successive
a
4
Metaphysics: Soul and Body
vii
Descartes had a good reason for stressing the necessity of raising
doubts "on even the slightest metaphysical pretext": at stake was
which was a web
the certainty of his physics,
contemporaries.
and
distinct
things
and
and the
The
was
human
ideas of
which they are composed;
him was
criticism constantly leveled against
make
not have the right to
new
man
that
thought, as Gassendi phrased
rule of the truth of things."
clear
this:
understanding are the measure of
indicate to us the natures of
adversaries as a
of paradoxes to his
result of Descartes' theology
Thus
"the
it,
Descartes was depicted by his
who
Protagoras
did
did not draw support from
anything solid or lasting.
He
answered Gassendi confidently: "Yes, the thought of any
individual of
its
is,
—must be the standard
his perception of a thing
truth; in other words, to be sound, all his
conform I
—that
can have a clear and distinct idea of myself as a thinking being
and can conceive notion of
this
my body. my soul
to say that
my
judgments must
to his perception."
thinking being without introducing any
According is
to the rule, then, I
have the right
body. But Arnauld raised an objection: because
acquire
some knowledge
about
my
when
I
body, can
I
of
be certain that
I
am
is
*Cf. Jean Wahl, (Paris, 1920).
no reason Du
role
nothing to
am
do
so.
de Videe de
to
making
not
certain, for to attribute materiality to the soul
attribute that contributes
I
able to
myself without knowing anything
exclude the body from the essence of
quently there
from
a thinking substance wholly distinct
my is
I'instant
I
to confer
our knowledge of
The
a mistake
soul?
can be
on
it;
it
spirituality of the soul dans
la philosophic
an
conse-
and
de Descartes
—
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
8l
the distinction between soul
from
are derived
A
body, in turn,
stance only that
and
and body then are
rational truths
is
distinct
which by
distinct idea apart
from a
itself
soul
and contains
from any other
its
sub-
idea: for instance, three-
as existing independently,
it
in
can constitute the object of a clear
dimensional extension, the object of geometers. Since to conceive
and
their notions.
I
am
able
must be the material
it
substance that physicists have long sought. Obviously, therefore, I
should
make
it
a rule to attribute to
only those properties that
it
imply extension, and to refuse to attribute ness, lightness, heat, cold
and
indistinct notion,
—of
to
it
—heavi-
any quality
which the mind has but a confused
and which does not seem
mode
to us to be a
of extension.
Regius objected, of course, that stance only as thinking substance
we
can conceive thinking sub-
and
are
under no compulsion
whatsoever to attribute extension to the same substance, but that
nothing prevents us from doing so "since these attributes
and extension cartes could
—
—thought
are not contradictory but merely different." Des-
answer the objection (which Spinoza seems
adumbrated in
to
have
only by showing that thought and
his doctrine)
extension are both essential attributes and that a substance can have
but one such attribute. "If attributes that constitute the natures of things are different
and the notion of one
in the other,
we
would mean
that the
But
how
thing?
cannot say that they
same
fit
attribute
the
subject could have
is
not contained
same
subject, since this
two
different natures."
can an attribute be said to constitute the nature of a
The
explanation
is
that the attribute
that includes" everything that here, for instance, that the
might be
body
is
is
"the
common
reason
said about a substance
susceptible to figure
and
to
motion.
There
Of
is
in the dualism of Descartes something completely
new.
course Peripateticism recognized thought apart from the body,
and the corpuscular physics of Democritus advanced mechanical explanations in which
mind played no
part.
In the
first
place,
82
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
however, the word "thought" did not
and
Aristotle
to Descartes.
"By the word
that occurs within us in such a
by ourselves; that but also sensing
why
is
the
is
the thinking intellect
way
that
mean
we
same thing
the
'think,' I
mean
perceive
to
everything
immediately
it
not only hearing, willing, and imagining
same thing here
as thinking." In Aristotle
was separated from the
active or sensitive
which the body was indispensable. But methodical
functions for
doubt proved that the act of sensing or willing in no way implied the existence of the body. Therefore spiritual
and
rational in all
its
it
is
mind
the whole
that
functions, to the degree that "it
is
must
always think."
As
for Democritus, he
was not
merely to refrain from
satisfied
introducing a spiritual soul into his explanation of things; in his theory of mechanics he denied outright the existence of this soul.
Democritus and Epicurus rejected because of Descartes excluded because of his method.
We
should add that the
point of departure for Descartes' corpuscular physics ideas of
from the body, and
that
thinking substance
God
exists,
which
is
extension.
The
exists, that it is distinct
we do not know whether we are familiar with their
but
bodies exist outside us even though
it is
existence of a
body
not evident;
is
not contained in our idea of the body, and this idea
perfect that
it
is
not so
could not have been produced by us. There remains
our strong natural inclination to believe in
doubt showed that our inclination did not
its
existence although
no longer the same
after
and could
entail assent
be offset by equally compelling, opposing reasons. is
was not obscure
atoms and the void but the clear idea of extension.
We are certain that the
essence,
system what
their
we know God. This
Still,
the situation
perfect being could
not have wished for our natural inclination to mislead us, and his
goodness therefore
is
one more guarantee for
tesian proof of the existence of bodies. It
inasmuch
as
it
is
us.
Such
is
the Car-
rather disconcerting
attributes to nature, to propensity, to inclination, a
property that would seem to belong only to clear and distinct ideas.
To
appreciate
its
significance
we must remember
within us a faculty— imagination
—whose
existence
that is
we have
not in any
—
83
way
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM necessary to the thinking being as such. Distinct
standing,
it
perceives
its
particular mental contention" that
is
we
easily
as
example, the
certainty, for
each figure; but our image of the
through "a
of no use in intellection.
can apprehend intellectually a myriagon
and know with
from under-
objects as being present only
first is
sum
as
We
pentagon
a
of the angles of
quite indistinct, whereas
can easily imagine the second. Universal mathematics served
by and large
mathematical thought and the imag-
to disentangle
Thus
ining of figures.
the imagination always appears as something
essentially alien to the
mind,
an intrusive, obfuscating element
as
that can be explained only through a force outside the
sequently,
no matter how paradoxical
the existence of external things
us of confused clear
and
of these
viii
If
and
is
may
mind. Con-
seem, affirmation of
grounded on the presence within nothing
indistinct ideas that contribute
distinct idea of extension
same
it
which
constitutes the essence
things.
Physics
we wished
to
examine Descartes' physics from the standpoint
of his positive contribution to the history of this science,
need
to the
to
separate
from metaphysics,
in
we would
which he chose
them, a number of discoveries that do not belong there discoveries
made
before 1627,
when he was The law of
for his physics in metaphysics.
bodies that he expounded to
Beeckman
to
place
—that
is,
trying to find support the velocity of falling
as early as 1619
is
a
mathe-
matical investigation that assumes the law of inertia (the conservation of acquired
motion in a moving object) and has nothing
with the cause of gravity which he explained early as 1626 he
to
at a later date.
had discovered the law of the equality of the
of the angle of incidence
and the
do
As sine
sine of the angle of refraction
the starting point of formulas for the fabrication of lenses
—through
an experiment which he described quite independently of the pre-
sumed demonstration
that he offered later (1637)
In October, 1637, he wrote for
*
n tne Dioptric.
Huyghens an "explanation
of en-
84
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
gines that will enable the operator, lift
a heavy burden." This short effect of a force
he defined the
displacement that
it
by applying a small
treatise
force, to
on machines, in which
(action or
work)
by the
solely
produced in a unit of mass and without
taking into account the speed of
its
motion, introduced general
notions which he never employed in his physics.
Such investigations led
to
the discovery of natural laws that
could be expressed mathematically, like those of Kepler and Galileo;
based solely on experience and mathematical techniques (in 1619 Descartes used the
method
of indivisibles devised by the physicist
Cavalieri to express the law of falling bodies), they implied no
hypothesis concerning the constitution of matter. This orientation
toward mathematical expression of the laws of nature disappeared in the definitive version of Descartes' physics; in the last
we
of the Principles
find
no mathematical formulas
two books
but, instead,
a description of mechanical combinations capable of producing the effects
observed through experience. Descartes was apparently con-
vinced that the prodigious complexity of causes prevented
from arriving for
at effects that
he did not pursue
his investigations of the
and he challenged the oscillations of the
him
could be expressed in simple formulas,
validity of the
pendulum. The
law of
falling bodies,
law of the isochronism of
result
was a strange anomaly:
Descartes, the inventor of analytical geometry,
which
later
became
the indispensable instrument of physicists, found not the slightest
use for
One
it
in his physics.
admirably elucidated by Pierre Boutroux, 5
contrast,
who
noting. Kepler,
vision of the universe,
is
worth
introduced aesthetic considerations into his
and
Galileo,
whose conception of the
prin-
remained vague, discovered exact laws that make
ciple of inertia
possible a rigid prediction of
phenomena; Descartes, whose
chief
concern was the exactness and precision of principles such as those
expounded finally
in
the second
managed
book of
his
to describe (in the third
Principles of Philosophy,
and fourth books) mech-
anisms which would provide a rough explanation of things but 5
Revue de Metaphysique (November, 1921).
.
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
85
would make
possible
We
no prediction.
now
turn our attention to
those principles.
The
essence of matter
and
infinitely small
extension. It follows that matter
is
infinitely large
(that
the indivisible atoms of Democritus totle),
and
that
it
is
one (that
between the matter of
A
ments).
body can
When
body
differ
is
is
presumed
The
is
be at
to
reject
any distinction
first is
its
shape and position.
and the
rest
position of a
never the same at different
means
that
two bodies cannot be
properties of bodies
known
to us
all
by experience
which have prescribed shapes and
which are animated by
certain motions
—a
the effects and
to a
combination
by man. Descartes
modeled the intimate constitution of natural bodies on artifice
"The example
me
tween the machines constructed by
artisans
human
no difference be-
and the
different bodies
alone, except that the effects of
pend only on the arrangement of
such
in this matter," he said, speaking
of his mechanical explanations; "for I recognize
composed by nature
just
of several bodies constructed by
has been of great use to
and
relative positions
combination similar to
that observable in mechanical artifices invented
artifices.
in
place.
physical problem consisted in reducing
of bodies
ele-
said to be in motion. Moreover, each
impenetrable, and this
same
both
world of Aris-
but a limited portion of extension, and one
moments, the second body the
reject
finite
and the matter of the
from another only through
one body
is
we must
celestial things
second body in relation to the
body
is,
we must
is,
and the
is
machines de-
certain tubes or springs or other
instruments which, since they must be proportionate to the hands of their makers, are always so big that their shapes
and movements
can be seen, whereas the tubes or springs that cause the
effects of
natural bodies are ordinarily too small to be perceived by our senses.
And we
can be certain that
all
metaphysics, with the result that
the rules of mechanics pertain to all artificial
things are also natural"
{Principles, IV, 203)
known to allowed man
Mechanics was processes that
the ancients only as the totality of the to
produce "violent" motions
—for
ex-
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
86
ample, to
lift
existed only
weights by means of a lever or a windlass; thus
human
on the
scale.
it
In contrast, physics was the study
of "natural" motions, such as falling
—that
is,
a spontaneous motion
which in the absence of any obstacle directs a spontaneous motion toward
its
natural place, the center of the world. In an infinite
world, however, there was no longer a center, no longer a natural place,
and consequently no longer
means
a
of separating natural
motions from violent motions. By the same token there was an obvious necessity for a law of inertia; by of changing
remain
move
its
state of rest or of if
state is
changed by
collision
visible
scale
visible scale
incapable
it
will continue to
and uniform motion unless
with an external body. Impact
state,
and
this cause
Mechanical structure, therefore,
size of the scale,
is
If it is at rest, it will
motion
in
indefinitely with a rectilinear
only cause of a change of ical.
and
at rest indefinitely,
body
a
itself
motion.
is
is
its
the
eminently mechan-
wholly independent of the
is
and we must picture
to ourselves
it
by analogy with mechanisms known
on the
to
in-
us on the
through experience.
This analogy was responsible in the eyes of Descartes' contemporaries for the real difficulty of his physics. "In nature,"
wrote to him, "can be found
magnet.
as those relating to the
about
celestial influences,
different,
they
for they act in a
anything other than
many
God
effects that
And
if
told
I
Morin
have no equal, such
you what
I
know
would again be something wholly
manner
himself"
that defies
(AT,
II,
comparison with
411). Descartes
was
when he wrote in his who were convinced that for each new effect for a new species of beings unknown to them
thinking of physicists with just such views
Rules (1628) of those they "must search previously."
Descartes' mechanics
is
one of impact, impact being the only
action capable of modifying the state of a body. It
must be added
that the colliding action
it
state of the
body that
is
is
instantaneous, that
is,
modifies the
struck at the very instant the impact occurs.
Descartes' physics recognizes only instantaneous actions. as
And
just
methodical doubt eliminated any type of certainty other than
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
87
immediate perception,
of
that
which would require duration
The
action.
action of light
the luminous
body
in order to unfold the effects of
transmitted from
an impulse
is
transmitted from
stick to the other.
makes
rience of the senses
The
point
is
so important to
(AT,
the extreme statement
showed any delay
was not demonstrated by Roemer
would
How
and the
light
(The
at all."
308) that the expe-
velocity of light
The
until 1675.)
I,
if
slightest delay
imply a discontinuity and a void in the interval
in effect
between
its
is
"whole philosophy would be radically destroyed
his
any force
instantaneous and
to the eye just as
one end of a rigid Descartes that he
is
eliminates
physics
his
eye.
are such instants, each powerless to prolong itself in another,
linked together ?
By
a
law of permanence based on the immutability
and constancy of God, a law
that corresponds in physics to the
divine attribute of perfect veracity in the theory of knowledge. the
It is
At every
famous law of the quantitative conservation of motion.
to the universe at the initial instant
motion of a body
of
motion imparted by God
instant in time the quantity of
is
remains identical; the quantity
the product of
its
mass (calculated accord-
ing to the geometric dimensions of the body) and state of the universe at a particular instant
to the state of the universe at just
The
only remaining modifications
are
themselves instantaneous, due to impact.
after
motion
how If
is
Thus
all diffi-
modifications
The
that
as
before
impact.
are
seven laws of impact
They show how
the
is
the
quantity of
divided between two bodies following their collision and
their direction changes.
two bodies (assumed
and moving the
therefore equivalent
instant.
dominated by the principle that the quantity of motion
same
The
inherent in change are eliminated.
culties
are
is
any other
velocity.
its
at the
same speed and
to
be completely impenetrable) are equal
same speed, each rebounds
after
in the opposite direction. If
one of the bodies
impact with
and both have the same velocity, the larger body continues in the same direction and at the same velocity while the smaller
is
larger
one maintains the same velocity and moves in the opposite direc-
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
88
tion. If
both are equal, and one of them
moving more
is
rapidly
than the other, the slower object rebounds while the faster one maintains
its
direction; furthermore, both
the faster imparting half of
body
is
it
at rest, the smaller
is
same conditions the smaller one
move
in the
the smaller one, to
which
the larger one continues to
along with
velocity,
one
body
re-
motion while the larger one remains
its
motionless. If under the
motion.
and
larger than the other
bounds and maintains
assume the same
excess velocity to the slower. If
its
they are equal and one
same
is
at rest,
direction, carrying
transfers a part of
it
while the other
its
is
in
motion, the body in motion rebounds but loses one-fourth of
its
If
motion, which in the
the
same
imparts to the other body.
it
direction
moment
and one
of impact
two
motion of the slower body the faster
it
is
moving
possibilities
a part of
body its
If
both bodies are going
faster arise:
than the other, at
carries the slower
its
motion; in the opposite
one along with
are based
sideration
are
imparting
it,
motion.
These "laws of nature," though inexact, apply
They
the quantity of
if
greater than that of the faster one,
is
body rebounds but maintains
case, the faster
to
at rest
is
on the assumption absolutely
that the
impenetrable,
a
an ideal
case.
two bodies under con-
is
Descartes
that
fiction
admittedly accepted only "in order that things
mathematical examination." Another fiction
to
may
fall
under
that such bodies are
not subject to any influence emanating from adjacent bodies, for this is
tion
impossible in the plenum.
Whereas Newton's law
of attrac-
(which was considered the paradigm of a natural law in the
eighteenth century) issued from experience and led to the predic-
and discovery of phenomena, the laws of impact were derived from reason and could not be used deductively. No human under-
tion
standing can predict every impact to which adjacent bodies will subject a particular
body
at a
given instant
speed and direction at the next instant. Just as
or,
consequently,
human
artifice
its
cannot
reproduce natural mechanisms because of their complexity, so "one can indeed make a machine that will remain in the air like a bird,
metaphysice loquendo (for as
I
see
it
even birds are such machines)
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
09
but not physice or moraliter loquendo, for this would necessitate
such delicate and at the same time such strong springs that they could not be fabricated by a say that everything
explain
all
man" (AT,
III,
163). Similarly,
we can
we
cannot
accomplished through collision but
is
the details.
Descartes' conception of the nature of matter involves the necessity of vortexes.
In the
a vortical motion;
body pursuing
it,
plenum
the only possible motion
when one body
the second body
relinquishes
its
must take the
have
to
in effect
place to the
place of another
body, the latter of a third body, and so on until the will immediately
is
body, which
last
occupy the place vacated by the
body.
first
Descartes compared the circular motion of one of the bodies that
make up the move at each
vortex to that of a stone in a sling: the stone instant in a straight line at a tangent to
its
would
trajectory
not held back by a strap; similarly, the body in a vortex must
if
constantly be pressed toward rectilinear
its
Our has if
solar system,
at a
with
its
axis
by adjacent bodies that oppose
tangent to its
trajectory.
its
planets, issues
axis in the sun. Descartes described
its
we
motion
from
its
a vortex
which way:
genesis in this
suppose that the matter of the vortex was formed at the
outset by almost equal bodies, then
it is
necessary for these
moving
bodies constantly to find something to oppose their motion, with the result that their angles are rounded off
The
scrapings of these spheres engenders a fine matter or
ment capable through all
its
tenuousness and agitation of
the interstices between the spheres
sible shape.
As
and they become
it
slips
The
spheres. first ele-
filling
and of assuming every
that
we
its
pos-
spheres themselves constitute the second element.
through the spheres of the second element, fine matter
tends always to escape from the center of the vortex and to
toward
up
periphery. Light
feel
when
possible, the first
it
is
merely the force of the fine matter
presses against our eyes. Since
element that escapes from
replaced by other corpuscles of the
then produces of the heavens.
light,
move
first
its
axis
element.
is
The
no void
is
immediately first
element
and the second element produces the matter
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
90
The
particles of the first element, set in the interstices of the
spheres of the second, are shaped like a curvilinear triangle with concavities or flutings. If these particles are halted in their motion, their flutings will
we
as is
mesh, gradually forming a rough, crusty matter,
and
see in sunspots
the third element,
in solid planets such as the earth: this
made up
of multiform particles,
some
of
them
forked, others long, others almost round. In short, they exhibit as
many
differences
among
play the same role;
themselves as Democritus' atoms, and they
was through the conjunction of
it
particles
with
determinate shapes that Descartes explained the diverse bodies seen
on the
earth.
solid matter
With
with
wishes, Descartes terrestrial
its
his subtle matter, his liquid heavens,
parts to
hoped
phenomena:
to
and
his
which he can give whatever shape he construct
heaviness,
mechanisms heat,
light,
composition of bodies, magnetism.
We
shall
to
explain
all
the chemical
tides,
not attempt to follow
his detailed explanations.
We
must
try to grasp the spirit of
The most
"fiction of the vortexes."
what
his adversaries called the
notable point
to explain the present state of the universe,
of affairs
that, in
order state
(the division of matter into corpuscles of equal size)
which he chose matters
"It
is
he began with a
as arbitrarily as
he
little,"
said,
geometers choose their hypotheses.
"how
I
reach the assumption that
matter was arranged in the beginning, for
it is
scarcely possible for
us to imagine an arrangement that did not change continuously, as
we
can prove according to these laws, in such a manner that
would
finally constitute
a world quite like this one, since these
laws cause matter successively to assume III,
In
art.
it
all
shapes" {Principles,
45).
this
way
Descartes freed physics
Hellenic cosmos, that state of things
is,
from the obsession
from the image of a
that satisfies our aesthetic needs
duced and maintained only through the action of
gence—an
obsession
from which even
Galileo were not exempt.
There
is
of the
certain privileged
and can be proa
supreme
physicists like
no such thing
intelli-
Kepler and
as a privileged
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
91
state since all states are equivalent;
nor
there a place in physics
is
for the investigation of final causes or for the consideration of the best possible state.
"Even
we
if
we
posited the chaos of the poets,
could always demonstrate that through them [the laws of nature] this
confusion must gradually return to the order that
now
exists
in the world."
The
physicist could divest himself of the stable concept of the
cosmos only by imagining a theory which was too capacious for experience and which went beyond the explication of what
For
instance,
effects
from
principles
we
can deduce an infinite
wholly different from those actually realized, just
is
given.
number as a
of
watch-
maker, using the same methods, can contrive movements quite
from those
distinct
actually imagined.
But the absence of conformity
is
precisely
what makes experience
indispensable in the Cartesian system of physics. state a priori that the universe is
We
can indeed
composed of a unique,
divisible
matter animated by circular movements, and that motion served.
"But we were unable in the same way
size of the parts into
which
which they move, or the
this
matter
circles that
is
to
is
divided, or the speed at
they describe; for since
might have ordained these things in countless ways,
it
is
God
through
experience alone and not through the power of reason that
we
know which of these ways he has chosen" {Principles, III, The physicist with his principles therefore would not have slightest
pre-
determine the
can 46).
the
chance of falling upon the combination actually realized
(since there are
innumerable similar combinations), and he must
"anticipate causes through effects."
In each instance experience indicates the particular problem that principles are supposed to provide the
can be no cosmology unless exactly
what we
we have
means
for resolving.
There
begin, like astrologers, by describing
see in the heavens;
no theory of the magnet before
enunciated in detail the properties discovered by such
experimenters as Gilbert. in
we
hand with
From
this point of
view theory goes hand
experience, as Descartes clearly stated in his Rules:
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
92
"The
answer the question, 'What
physicist cannot
but only the question, 'What
is
the
experiments conducted by Gilbert ?
Thus
magnet
is
the magnet?'
in the light of the
" '
important for experiments to be as numerous and as
it is
precise as possible. Descartes liked always to join experience with
He
reasoning.
mathematics
—
began, as
we have
with problems of applied
seen,
He
music, barology, dioptrics.
held Bacon in high
esteem and concluded that there was "nothing more to be said"
he had given the rules for carrying out useful experiments.
after
"A
phenomena following
history of celestial
method
the
of Veru-
lamius," he wrote in 1632, "without the introduction of reason or hypotheses, first
seem
would be more
to be,
and
useful to the public than
would
it
me
relieve
of
much
Descartes always promoted experimentation;
at
it
might
difficulty."
at
Thus
the end of the
Discourse he asks rulers to subsidize the vast expenditures required for experiments necessary for the
he retired
to
Egmond,
advancement of the
sciences. After
Descartes himself was deeply interested in
anatomical research and practiced dissections. In short, he was a rationalist
who
never disavowed the contempt manifested in the
Rules for astronomers
who
studied the nature of the heavens with-
out having observed their motions,
from
physics,
who
studied mechanics apart
and who neglected experiment, thinking that they
could extract truth from their brains.
But here a distinction must be made. There
is
a world of differ-
ence between precise experiments involving measurement and
cal-
—long practiced by astronomers and exemplified by Galileo Pascal— and experiences which simply recount the immediate
culation
and
perceptions of the senses
Those of the specific
first
and which
are exact only qualitatively.
type suggest numerical laws concerning the
phenomenon under study and provide
that can be confirmed or invalidated
by
new
a basis for predictions
experiments. Those of
the second type, since they are descriptive, can lead only to theories
which are themselves ically,
and which
descriptive,
which are not
in consequence provide
no
stated
mathemat-
basis for prediction.
Only experiments of the second type were used by Descartes
in his
93
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM His descriptions of the heavens,
physics, at least in the Principles. tides,
and the magnet contain no
precise mathematical data.
imagined in order
over, the mechanical structures that he
phenomena
diverse
for
relations to provide a
explain tides through lunar pressure did not allow
That was not
had the same deep-rooted causes
interest in the investigation of laws
ematically.
Such experiments were
simplicity of mathematical laws causes,
him
to indicate
phenomenon.
aim. His disdain for experiments involving
his
exact measurements
is
as his lack of
which could be expressed mathuseless in a
world
like his; the
possible only in a universe in
such as gravity and universal gravitation, act in
numbers and always
limited
to explain
mathematical deduction. For instance, his attempt to
the exact nature of the
which
More-
are simply "rough" descriptions, as Pascal said,
and do not give detailed dimensions and basis
6
in the
same manner; experience
in-
volving measurement, laws expressed mathematically, and physics of central forces go together.
The mechanism any attempt
infinite complication, jeopardizes
of impact, with to
its
reduce nature to
mathematical form.
Whenever Descartes ciples,
ceased to be the theoretician of the Prin-
however, he adhered to the tradition that led by way of
Roberval, Pascal, and
Huyghens
to
Newton—he used mathematics
to determine certain effects numerically
check the
to
For
results.
instance,
in
and
called
his
correspondence with
on experience
Mersenne and Cavendish concerning the discovery of
a
simple
pendulum isochronous with
a compound pendulum, even after he had determined mathematically the length of a simple pendulum
(by using methods of integration that transcended the limits he had prescribed in the Geometry), he objections arising
showed
Or, rather,
if
felt
constrained to answer to
Cavendish,
were inaccurate. Furthermore, he
that his results
that such experiments 6
still
from experiences which, according must be
subject to
specified
precise measurements and
they are precise they are inexact; for instance, he assumed that
astronomical distances were
cosmogonies modernes
much
(Paris,
less
than they actually
1924), p. 20 (note).
are.
Cf.
P.
Busco, Lcs
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
94
gave the following
rule,
which
menter: "I
that
in
believe
greatest skill
is
actually that of a true experi-
of
experiences
the
required for choosing those which are least depend-
ent on diverse causes true causes"
is
the examination
and which have the most
easily discovered
(AT, IV, 392) The rule is apt but strictly inapplicable where everything depends on innumerable .
to a universe like his,
causes.
The
This was not
cartes.
overshadowed the theoretician in Des-
scientist constantly
true,
however, in the works intended for the role
that
we have
the World, written between 1629
and
1632, con-
Here experience always retained the
public.
indicated.
Physiology
ix
The
treatise
On
cluded with some chapters on man, a sample of which appears in the fifth part of the Discourse, in his discussion of the motions
human
of the heart. In 1648 Descartes wrote a description of the
body (published by of the Foetus.
Clerselier in 1664) entitled
Here Descartes expanded
On
the Formation
mechanics
his
to
make
it
include the functions of the body, "the digestion of food, the beat-
ing of the pulse, the distribution of the five senses" (AT, XI, 221). "I
am now
anatomizing the heads of different animals," he wrote
to
Mersenne, "in order to explain imagination and memory" (AT,
I,
263).
That the bodies
machines or automatons
Greek philosophy, even vestiges
machine body do.
is
We
structed
and men are comparable
of animals is
a notion
in Plato
which
and
found frequently in
is
Aristotle,
and which
left its
throughout the Middle Ages. Yet the idea that the body is
to
is
a
—to the idea that the
linked traditionally to another idea
an instrument for a soul that uses find nothing like this in Descartes,
and made
to function in
as a
mechanic would
whose machine
is
con-
accordance with the universal
laws of nature, with the result that there
same image,
it
for a particular mechanic.
is
Hence
no need,
to use the
the possibility of the
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
95
famous theory of animal-machines, which eliminates any governing
made
soul in the aniaml. This theory,
possible by the universal
mechanism, derived from something more than
from the body: by with-
the soul as a thinking substance distinct
drawing any
his conception of
animal function from the soul and making
vital,
pure thought, capable of
self-reflection,
it
Descartes in effect elimi-
nated every motive for attributing souls to animals. Descartes' physiology rests entirely that
Harvey had
tive juices are
made
just
on the experimental discovery
of the circulation of the blood. Nutri-
converted into blood in the liver and carried to the
right auricle of the heart through the vena cava, then to the lungs
through the pulmonary vein, then to the
pulmonary all its
tory
and
artery,
branches. But
movement
through the
Descartes agreed with Harvey on the circula-
if
of the blood, he differed completely with
the cause of circulation. peller which,
left auricle
throughout the body by the aorta and
finally
Harvey looked upon the heart
by contracting, drove blood into the
and
of the heart (systolic
clinging
Descartes,
the
and
movement
caused the circulation of the
diastolic) to
as a pro-
arteries,
which, by expanding, drew blood from the veins; the blood.
him on
ancient
concept,
Aristotelian
looked upon the heart as a source of heat capable of dilating the
blood that entered
its
the blood,
cavities;
when
dilated the cavity of the heart that enclosed outlet
through the pulmonary vein when
and through the aorta when
movement
of the heart
was
it
it
it,
was
dilated, in turn
until
it
found an
in the right cavity,
in the left cavity; thus the
was no longer the cause of the
circulation of
the blood but the result, passively sustained, of the dilation of the
blood produced by
and contrary
its
heat.
Thus
Descartes, in opposition to
to the facts, reversed the true order of the
the heart, for he
assumed that
it
dilated in the systole
Harvey
motions of
(when
the
and that it contracted in the (when blood came in through the vena cava). His mistake was not accidental but was tied in with his whole
blood escaped through the aorta) diastole
physiological system. After criticizing Harvey, Descartes goes so
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
96
far as to say: "It
the true cause of
knowledge we can know
medicine" (AT, XI, 245). His
to the theory of
nothing relating mistake was, in
know
very important for us to
is
the motion of the heart, for without this
responsible for the revival of the traditional
effect,
theory of animal spirits and for the establishment of a link be-
tween
all
of the functions
known
today as relational functions and
the circulation of the blood. For "the most agitated
and
active parts
come
of the blood are carried to the brain through the arteries that
by the straightest
wind
subtle air or
prepare
it
common
—that
spirits
is,
they prepare
and
also impres-
organ or seat
same
this
air or
flow from the brain through the nerves into
member" (AT, XI, "which
heart's heat,
to be the
it
a very
by dilating the brain,
and memory. Then to serve as
and by distending the muscles
to every
and they make up
spirits; these,
and prepare the nerves
the muscles senses;
animal
sense, imagination,
same
these
called
heart,
to receive impressions of external objects
sions of the soul
of
from the
line
is
227)
.
variously, they impart
motion
All of these effects depend on the
main spring and
like the
all
organs of the external
the cause of
all
the
motions" of the body.
According canals
and
to Descartes, the
cavities
various modifications, cavities
or
tubes
are
and which passively spirits. It felt.
was
The
is
composed of
all
of
a system of
undergoing
circulates,
them dependent on
its
heat.
These
simple containers which function no
actively than similar organs
or
body
through which the blood
might function
in an
artificial
less
machine
receive the effects of the dilation of the blood
cause of these effects
is
the heart's
own
in this sphere that lack of experience
heat.
was most acutely
"Descartes was too familiar with the lacunae in our present
knowledge of the history of man," wrote the anatomist Steno
a
short time later, "to undertake to explain his true composition.
Thus he does not attempt
to
do
it
in his treatise
on man, but he
does try to explain the workings of a machine that performs the actions of sians
which men
who went
are capable."
And
addressing the Carte-
further than the master, he added: "Those
undertake to demonstrate that Descartes'
all
man
is
made
who
like other
:
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
97
men
will learn
through the study of anatomy that their undertak-
ing cannot be successful."
x
7
Ethics
Wisdom, first
conflict
no
the goal of philosophy,
shows the will the choice that
is it
attained
when
"intelligence
should make." But there
and the exigencies
that "perfect
knowledge of
knowledge of moral
method and
of
of order, which teach us
the other sciences necessarily precedes
all
This
science."
the conflict supposedly re-
is
solved in the "provisional morality," which Descartes to his statement in the Discourse)
become aware of the vanity not remain irresolute in
me
to be irresolute
The moral maxims "The
first
to
was
to
drew up
of the sciences, "in order that
had
should
I
reason might
of Descartes, enunciated in the third part of
imbued with
rational considerations
obey the laws and customs of
the religion in which
God
my
country, holding
graciously caused
from childhood, and basing
instructed
(according
in 1618, after he
my actions even though in my judgments."
the Discourse, are nevertheless
fast
a
between the urgency of moral wisdom, since action admits
delay,
oblige
is
my
me
conduct in
to
all
be
other
matters on the most moderate and least extreme opinions which
were commonly accepted in practice by the most those with
whom
I
had
conformity because
social
to
live."
it
is
conduct according to those with tion because the practice."
"My
possible in
once
I
my
maxim was
actions,
had made up
my
and
truth,"
for
to
to follow the
II,
7.
to
pattern our
live,
and modera-
certain." is
in
most dubious opinions,
less
constancy than
Such constancy, having no
if
they
roots in
nevertheless rooted deep in a "very
inconstancy in conduct, which
N. Steno, Discourse on the anatomie of the Brain,
hagen, 1910),
must
be as firm and resolute as
mind, with no
the certainty of opinion,
7
"most profitable"
whom we
most moderate opinions are "most appropriate
second
had been absolutely certain
intelligent of
Here Descartes recommended
in
derives
from
Opera Philosophica (Copen-
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
98
instability of opinions, does is
not promote contentment of
and repentance.
forever producing remorse
"My
third
mind but
maxim was
to try always to master myself rather than fortune, to change
my
desires rather than the order of the
world; and generally to accus-
tom
is
myself to believe that nothing
wholly in our power except
we have done our best with respect to we fail to accomplish is far as we are concerned." This attitude
our thoughts, so that after
the things that are outside us, everything absolutely impossible so suffices to
make me
eliminate desires that cannot be satisfied and "thus to
content." is
the art of living happily in
persists in
our judgments of things but
Provisional morality, therefore, spite of the
which
in
doubt which
no way
conformity,
affects the conditions of
constancy of the will, moderation of desires
standards reflecting a
wisdom
paganism were the very ones
and
conflict
our happiness. Social
independently of the clash
identified,
between speculative opinions, by moralists
Vair, Montaigne,
—these
easily traceable in origin to ancient
like
Du
and Charron. The provisional elements of
his
They
re-
moral philosophy were not identical appeared in the same form
when
to these standards.
Descartes, after constructing his
metaphysics and his physics, treated moral questions systematically in his letters to Princess Elizabeth, his correspondence with
and
his treatise
on the passions. In speculative matters
remained independent of doubt and of tive
Chanut,
their veracity
certainty, but in the defini-
statement of his moral philosophy Descartes based his precepts
on a
rational, analytical conception of
In the study of
man
as in
everything
man. else,
Descartes followed the
"order of reason" rather than the "order of matter"; consequently his notion of man was fashioned from clear and distinct elements which he discovered one after the other as deduction progressed.
Metaphysics, knowledge of the distinction between soul and body,
knowledge of the union of soul and body edge was matched by the entry of a
—every advance in knowl-
new element into the notion man was fashioning of himself. Man was first defined as a thinking and spiritual substance. But
that
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
99
and
to Descartes sensation, passion,
and
intellectual notions were. Passions
new
imply a
will are
modes
of thought just as
sensations not only did not
feeling soul superadded to the intellectual soul but
merely aspects of the thinking faculty. In thought distinguishes
two groups of modes
—
"passion" designates in a general sciousness without any action
on
passions
way
its
and
The word
everything given to con-
part: the clear
notions of understanding (extension and thought,
well as true sensations and passions
Descartes
itself
actions.
were
(desire,
and
distinct
first
axioms) as
anger).
The word
"action" designates only the free will that enables us to judge or to abstain
from judging,
that
is,
to give or
withhold our assent to
the associations of ideas that are presented to us by the imagination,
understanding, or the senses.
but the
finite, is, it is
human
will
free to give or to
The whole
is
Human
knowledge
is
limited
"infinite" like the will of
and
God—that
withhold assent.
of Cartesian philosophy assumes this infinite will, the
freedom of which
proved
is
to us
by a strong inner
feeling.
The
first
—his firm, constant resolution to adhere only
steps of the philosopher
methodical doubt which results from
to positive proofs,
tion
—these
there
is
are the fruits of an initiative of will. In philosophy
no separation between extension of knowledge and nurture
of judgment.
But judgment, subjecting
the light of faith," first
which
causes
—that
is
distinct idea of his
Here man
is
the understanding,
"the acquisition of knowledge of truth
is,
wisdom."
Physics, in turn, adds to man's
and
itself to
good considered by natural reason without
leads to the "highest
through
this resolu-
knowledge by giving him a
body and of the world
to
clear
which he belongs.
merely a machine obedient to the general laws of na-
and the concept of thinking substance does not intervene. The mechanism of the animal spirits which travel from the heart to the ture,
brain and are spread through the nerves to the muscles, where they
produce motion,
is
the
same
in nature as the
mechanism
of any fluid
whatsoever. But knowledge of this unlimited world and of the universal
mechanism
of
which our body
is
an infinitesimal part inclines
us to judge rationally events of the outer world and accidents that
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
100
world that has
befall us. It destroys the false idea of a
man: "For
if
we imagine
that
end in
its
beyond the heavens there
nothing
is
but imaginary spaces, and that the fulness of the heavens exists only
and the earth
for the benefit of the earth
that life
we
are inclined to think this earth
our best
life
we
sumption,
.
and beginning
.
.
number
Nothing
show an impertinent preand with him assume of
which gives
and
it
happens
would be wrong
way." This entails,
is
to us
it is
an
is
over the
preserves. "Every-
and "we ought
think
to
necessary and inexorable, so
wish for
for us to
a resurgence of Stoic fate
now
but
God
belief in the providence of
directed by divine providence"
that everything that
that
rise to
vexations." Descartes' denial
mechanism which he has created and which he is
is
this
incompatible than elimination of the study of
is less
final causes in physics
thing
result
no way a denial of divine provi-
in
is
all
and
of vain concerns
of anthropomorphic finality
dence.
man, the
aspire to be in God's council
charge of the conduct of the world, infinite
to
for
our principal abode,
is
it
to
happen any other
and the resignation
that
tempered by reason and divested of the
it
false
notion of a finality favorable to man.
Metaphysics has recourse to notions of pure understanding to acquaint us with the soul and
its
of imagination gives us a clear
we need is
maker, and physics with the help
and
distinct idea of the body.
only practice "suspension of the senses" to realize that
something other than a soul and a body, that he
and
joined to a body,
composite
is
that fusion
an independent
action: the action of the
the action of the soul
entity.
is
so complete that the
is
passion, the soul spirits that
and
natural
is
totally
totally
has produced
of the complicated
it;
human
and
passion,
name of unknown to
union,
it
is
because the
the soul; in experiencing
unaware of the mechanism of animal
knows nothing moves an arm or a leg;
in exercising the will,
mechanism by which
it
it
such relations were instituted by nature. Furthermore, these tions
have a special
mode
inter-
in voluntary acts. If the relation
of action to passion merits the relation
in sensation
man
also a soul
This union consists in an
body on the soul
on the body
is
But
of intelligibility
—
finality.
rela-
Descartes had
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
101
excluded
finality
from
—a —and
and body
soul
our being
supreme
in the
union of
enters explicitly into the definition of the pas-
effects are felt as in the
mind
itself
on corporeal
and which gen-
cannot be related to an immediate cause"; moreover, they are
erally
fully
reigns
passions are defined as being dependent
"whose
causes
it
union decreed by nature for the conservation of
it
The
sions.
physics, but
understood only in light of their
fact that they fortify
that the
mind
The same
utility,
which
consists "in the
thoughts and cause them to endure."
"preserves them, for otherwise they
natural finality
is
seen again in the corporeal
that spontaneously execute voluntary decisions:
It is
movements
for instance, the
pupillary reflex depends on will, "for although the subject narily
unaware of
its
performance, his
ments that enable the called voluntary
lips
and tongue
movements because they
to the will;
in
ordi-
none-
and move-
pronounce words are
to
are a consequence of the
manner
will to speak, notwithstanding our ignorance of the
which they must be executed
is
ability to see clearly is
dependent upon and a consequence
theless
well
might be effaced."
pronouncing each
letter"
in
(AT,
VI, 107).
The
notion of the union of soul and body, sharply criticized by
Spinoza, Malebranche, and Leibniz but considered by Descartes as
being as "primitive" and legitimate as the notions of extension and thought, provides a clearer understanding of his view of intelligibility.
God
manner
in
is
not deceptive; any error originates in us, from the
which we employ notions outside the sphere of
proper application. Physics has been
falsified
because
it
has
their
made
use of sensible qualities, forces, substantial forms, finality; but these
notions are not illusory in themselves (as Spinoza later believed);
and
if
they are related to the union of soul and body, their veracity
will be
brought
to light. Sensible qualities serve to
of the dangers of the body.
form which represents extended form
is
the soul
notion of a force or a substantial
for us a spiritual being acting within an
true as soon as
and body. The natural it
The
warn
finality
we
apply
it
to the
union of soul
contained in this union even makes
impossible for our desires or our natural needs to deceive us,
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
102
may
except by accident. For instance, a dropsical person
ence
even though
thirst,
it is
dangerous for him
ism
—a relation normally useful and
—continues to exert
Man,
that
come
to
him from
degree the master of his corporeal
so ferocious that trary,
it is
ness in It is
an organ-
subjected to the sensations
is
his body, but
he
On
movements.
solely
to a certain
is
the other hand,
upon
his passions.
cultivate," said Descartes, "is not so barbaric or
I
rejects the
it
his feeling
indispensable to
man's happiness and unhappiness depend
"The philosophy
and
its effects.
as a soul united to a body,
and passions
experi-
to drink, because
the relation between a certain motion of his spirits of thirst
still
enjoyment of the passions; on the con-
to this alone that I attribute all the sweetness
and happi-
life."
important for the moralist
nature and
have knowledge of the
first to
each passion, then measurement of the influ-
utility of
ence passions have on
will,
and the influence
will has
on
passions.
Passions are "affections or emotions which are related specifically
way from
sensations,
and which
are engen-
to the soul itself [they are distinguished in this
which are
related to objects outside the soul]
dered, continued,
mal
spirits."
senses
The
and augmented by a
particular
study of this motion,
its effects, is
each passion and the reason for
known
modifications
unknown
to the
mind
ani-
that
part of the physics of the body. Descartes tried
determine the particular motion of
to
motion of the
as
its
spirits that
corresponded to
continuation through the organic
expression of the emotions
—angry
out-
bursts, tears, depression.
The motions
of animal spirits generally have their source in the
impression of an external object on the senses, or at least in the
image of the
object.
assumed by the
will,
Passion
is
with respect to eternal objects. Thus the necessary
condition of
Descartes
is
its
all
other
first
passions
—
is
spirits,
of the passions—the
wonder, which in
but one form of spontaneous attention. Thanks to
wonder, an object of
the attitude passively
essentially
under the influence of the motion of
is
somehow brought
novelty in relation to the others.
into the foreground because
Then comes
love in
which
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
103
the will
disposed to unite with an object, and hatred which dis-
is
poses the will to evade the object. Joy and sadness imply prior love
and hatred, passions
since
one of them derives from the
and the other from
satisfaction of
such
failure to realize their satisfaction. All
other passions are but variations or combinations of these five primitive passions.
By
out what
useful (love),
is
such dispositions
from the
solely
us, causes
them
reason inter-
Of
to seek
from danger (hatred). But
to flee
judgments concerning good and
are true so long as passions
remain within
course "the utility of any passion derives
fact that to
and
contain
also
and such judgments
their natural limits.
will, before
welcome new knowledge (wonder),
venes in any way, to
evil,
our
their nature passions predispose
fortifies
it
thoughts and, fortunately for
be preserved in the mind," but Descartes added:
any
evil that they
can cause also derives from the fact
that they fortify
and preserve
these thoughts to a greater degree
".
.
just as
.
than
is
necessary."
The
finality of passions,
union of soul and body, thing
we
love
is
is
which depends on the
only general and imperfect: not every-
we
good, not everything
hate
is
bad. These judg-
ments are largely determined by accidental circumstances.
First,
physical circumstances, such as the constitution of the brain, can
produce vast differences in the capacity of each of us to be affected
by objects; secondly, the same object can be neutral and can arouse either love or hatred,
depending on personal experiences;
finally,
accidental associations, by transferring our passion to objects associated with the
a
primary
object,
manner which we would
can cause us to love or fear things in
least
expect and which
is
least
advan-
tageous to us.
But
it is
precisely this imperfection in the finality of the passions
that will provide a foothold for the will
In the
first
place
man
and give
it
sovereign power.
can influence the conditions that govern the
—through medicine, through hygiene, —and such physical therapeutics are not negli-
flow of spirits in the brain
through alimentation gible. its
But there are
influence
also intellectual therapeutics.
on the mind, according
The body
to Descartes,
exerts
through a par-
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
104
organ
ticular
—the
pineal gland. This
little
organ, located at the
base of the brain, was selected as the "seat of the soul,"
because
on
located
it is
assymetrical parts of the brain,
from
inferred
the
structure
its
that
it
could be shaken by
flow of animal
the
from the brain
motion
—that
is,
law of
its
impulsion.
It
Thus
gland and in
it
this
mind can change
his steed
without contributing to
its
can change the direction of motion of the pineal
way
influence the flow of spirits to the brain
and
muscles.
We
gland
voluntary only in the sense that the pupillary reflex
is
voluntary. it;
must bear
The
a
uses force without adding anything to
horseman guides
just as a
Accord-
motion in the universe. Without
conservation, however, the
the direction of motion. it,
The mind
spirits.
cannot add even the slightest quantity of
it
to the constant quantity of
violating the
moving
mind cannot be
ing to the principles of Cartesian physics, the force
spirits
into the muscles.
through the pineal gland on the motion of the
moving
first
one of the few
the heart or sense organs into the "cavities" of the
brain or descending acts
is
and secondly because Descartes
and location
disturbance in
slightest
upward from
body and
the axis of the
will
is
in
mind, however, that the motion of the
unaware of
it
and
is
not linked directly to
but the will provokes modifications in the flow of
willing a particular motion,
and
is
by
spirits
these modifications produce the
desired muscular contraction in accordance with natural laws gov-
erning the union of soul and body.
Thus ence
when
and consequently on the
appropriately exercised
fixes the attention of the
produce the passions
body assume it
on the motion of
the will has only an indirect influence
the animal spirits
is
mind on
we wish
passions, but
influ-
unlimited, either because
objects
opposed
to those
to destroy, or because
attitudes incompatible
its
it
it
which
makes
the
with bad passions, or because
and makes a passion Through the mechanism
takes advantage of associations of ideas
change
its
object by a voluntary transfer.
of habit
we
opposed
to the
can cause an object to produce an effect diametrically
one
it
produces naturally, just as
to set or point in the presence of
we
game which,
can train a dog
spontaneously, he
105
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
would pursue. In that
way
this
do not present things
they are
—are
allowed
The consequences nature have
only
as
passions
"licit"
—joys
desires
being better and more desirable than
to subsist.
of this progressive, orderly inspection of man's
not been exhausted. "According to the rule of
still
measured by
reason," said Descartes, "each pleasure ought to be
the magnitude of the perfection that produces the highest
and
good
knowledge of truth and
is
it."
follows that
It
that the sole virtue
is
a
firm and constant resolution to subordinate the will to the light of
our understanding. For our good can be only in "that which some-
how
and
appertains to us
is
we must have
such that
achieve perfection," and the only such thing in us It
if
the rule of reason
used,
is
must be independent of the passion which bears the
same name,
since
its
it
in order to
our free
will.
must produce the
follows that the rational exercise of the will
greatest pleasure
is
and that such pleasure
issues
from the body and
dependence upon the body would
introduce an element of imperfection. Therefore "the soul has
own
pleasures," and, in a general way,
depend on the body
its
has passions which do not
—love and joy—"the causes of which are clearly it
known to us." These are the passions which the Stoics, under the name of exmdOeiai^ attributed to the wise man; they are the seat of consummate It is
sions
from which
bliss.
a clear
and
himself clearly not only as a being
body but
a soul united with a
which we could not
and more
survive.
must
nature that the pas-
Each of us
issue.
endowed with a
also as a part of a
"Each of us
is
free will
is
and
as
whole without
a part of the universe,
joined by his dwelling place, his oath, his
and he must always prefer the
which he belongs over those of rational consideration,
when
it
is
his
interests
of the
whole
to
person in particular." This
perfectly clear to us,
panied by an "intellectual love" for the whole to which perfections
sees
especially a part of the earth, the state, the group, the
family to which one birth;
human
distinct idea of
constitute our beatitude
is
accom-
we owe our
—a love that links us to the whole voluntarily, as sensible
love linked us to our bodies.
Love
for the
whole
is
not charity
dis-
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
106
tributed equally
and
which enables us
and which
indifferently to everyone;
worth
increases as our
only for that which
it
is
decreases.
We
—for
sacrifice ourselves
worth more than we
is
a rational love
our worth in relation to the whole
to estimate
our country, for
instance, but not for wealth.
The
exact estimation of our
passion which
worth
the fruit of generosity, a
is
when we
but one aspect of the search for truth
is
are the object of the search.
Knowing
severely limited, the generous
man
human knowledge
that
realizes that his
is
worth depends
not on the superiority of his intelligence but solely on his will and
on the firmness with which the best to his intelligence.
He
will always chooses
whatever seems
therefore has neither misplaced humility
nor scorn for other men, for he knows that each of them has a free will
which
infinite
is
and capable of equal
But he knows that God, among
whom created
he
his will. "Before
what every
and he willed
we count
he sent us into
inclination of our wills
thus." In the
it
for so
little
is
our being
this
would
world, he
be; he
knew
particular thing;
whole consisting of God and our-
that our love for
great as possible. Furthermore, our love is
upon
the one
free acts themselves are
would make us decide on a
that our free wills
it
is
most completely dependent. Not only
is
exactly
selves,
virtue.
other beings,
and preserved by God, but our
dependent upon
knew
all
is
him should be
intellectual
and
as
rational;
born of natural illumination and independent of faith or
grace;
and
it
in
acts
utterly to our wills,
such a
we
way
"surrendering ourselves
that,
divest ourselves of our
have no passion other than that of doing what
own we
interests
and
believe to be
pleasing to him."
Cartesian philosophy, based on method, tion of judgment.
by reason of thing that
It is
their clarity
I try to
ics is
and
teach in
tinct ideas of the things
The fundamental
is
an unflinching will
essentially the cultiva-
to
distinctiveness.
my
Meditations
is
adhere to ideas only
"The most important the formation of dis-
about which judgments are to be made."
intention of mathematics, metaphysics,
and phys-
not to augment our knowledge of quantities, of God, or of
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
107
nature, but to fortify judgment. Since
judgment
is
an
act of the free
follows that from the very beginning philosophy embraces
will, it
this attitude of the will,
which
constitutes virtue.
Cartesianistn in the Seventeenth Century
xi
Cartesianism was a fashionable philosophy. Physics, especially,
aroused enthusiasm. In his celebrated novel, Cyrano de Bergerac described sunspots in terms of Descartes' hypothesis, and in Les
Femmes
savantes, the following exchange takes place:
Belise I
can take small bodies in
endure, and
I
my
stride,
find subtle matter
but the void seems hard to
much more
palatable.
Trissotin Descartes' theory of
magnetism makes sense
to
me.
Armande I
like his vortexes.
Philaminte
And
I
his falling worlds.
Theologians and Peripatetics saw their vested interests imperiled
and managed the public
to
convince the king and even the parlement that
good was
was prohibited,
at stake. Descartes' doctrine
not by a spiritual power enunciating the truth, as in the case of St.
Thomas Aquinas and
Siger of Brabant, but by a temporal
charged with the administration of public
affairs.
There
ward, anecdotal side to the history of Cartesianism.
amusing, as
when
Boileau,
on the point of passing
warned
Jansenists,
debate was
may
It
be
was
a decree prohibiting the teaching of any
writing his famous Arret burlesque; but the
power an out-
that the parlement of Paris
philosophy other than that of Aristotle, prevented
when
is
it
may
its
also
passage by
be
tragic, as
complicated by conflicts between
and Oratorians,
all
of
whom
insisted
Jesuits,
on directing the
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
108
The
education of youth.
and clung
Jesuits
were generally
hostile to Descartes
Arnauld
to their traditional courses; the Jansenists, like
and Nicole, showed
their liking for Descartes
by introducing whole
passages from the Rules into their Logic; and the Oratorians,
whom
of
Descartes had
numbered among
his friends
beginning, were favorably disposed toward they saw between his spiritualism and
St.
him by
many
from the very
the resemblance
Augustine's. This compli-
cated affair culminated in pamphlets such as Father Daniel's
Voyage du monde de Descartes, in the heresy and
(Father Valois),
of
M. de La
Ville
formulary brutally imposed by the
a
in
Le
on Oratorian professors (1678), who were forced to state and in the
Jesuits
that they believed in substantial forms, in real accidents, void.
But these noisy episodes do not constitute the true history of Cartesianism.
What
matters to us
through
assimilation
the slow, silent process of
is
which mental
gradually
habits,
modified
through meditation on Cartesian truths, were once again harmonized.
The philosophy Holland:
of Descartes spread throughout Europe. First to
Daniel
1653); Jean de
Heerebord,
(Specimina
Lipstorp
Raey (Clams philosophiae
who
published his
et cartesianae philosophiae, in
whose Annotations spinoza
philosophiae
(1690).
to the
first
cartesianae,
naturalis, 1654);
work, Parallelismus
1643; Geulincx;
Adrien
aristotelicae
and Chr. Wittich,
Meditations (1688) was followed by Anti-
In England, Antoine
Grand, a Frenchman,
le
spread the ideas of Descartes and defended (Institutiones philosophiae,
him
in his
handbooks
London, 1672 and 1678), against Samuel
Parker. In Germany, there were Clauberg and Balthasar Bekker,
author of a
and
De
philosophia cartesiana admonitio Candida (1691);
in France, Rohault, Sylvain Regis,
Cordemoy, La Forge, and
Malebranche.
Of by to
its
course Cartesianism did not progress in the direction intended
founder, and while
it
be sufficiently established,
especially in medicine,
advanced principles which he thought it
made
little
which required
for
progress in physics and its
development
difficult
—
.
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
109
and
costly
own
experiments that an individual could not conduct at his
On
expense.
this point
Leibniz was harsh in his criticism of
the sterility of Descartes' disciples.
Cartesians could cite 1675)
and
The
only physicist
whom
the
by way of rebuttal was Jacques Rohault (1620-
his investigations of capillarity. In his Treatise
on Physics
he gave in Paris over a period of
(1671), based
on
several years,
he advocated a science inspired by Cartesianism
lectures that
replace Aristotle's treatises,
which the
universities
were
to
teaching
still
under the name of physics. Rohault's physics, divided into four parts according to the Cartesian order
—natural
bodies and their
and of
properties, the system of the world, the nature of the earth
and animated bodies
terrestrial bodies,
ence,
which
is
—
stresses the role of experi-
especially useful in verifying suppositions.
When we
formulate a hypothesis concerning the nature of a subject,
we
believe about
certain
its
nature
manner we must
had not
yet imagined;
we had thought
is
verifiable,
of necessity reveal a
and
to test
"if
then by arranging
new
our reasoning
it
what in a
effect which we we do whatever
capable of causing the subject to produce this
effect" (Preface)
But the imprint and continuing influence of Cartesian thinking
was manifested much more
clearly in metaphysical principles, the
nature of ideas, the value of knowledge, and the union of soul and
body.
had
Having
to discern
lost
any right
to refer to the sensible, the Cartesian
through intrinsic qualities what constitutes the true
value of objects of the
mind
ideas
—and
what keeps us from con-
fusing ideas with fictions. For just as Descartes, in the
name
of
clear ideas, censured the Peripatetics for attributing reality to sensi-
ble qualities, his adversaries in their turn pretended that
he was
substituting a figment of his imagination, an invention of his for the real world.
xii
mind,
Such was the preoccupation of Geulincx.
Geulincx
Arnold Geulincx (1625-1669) studied at the University of Louwhere he later taught for six years. Forced for obscure reasons
vain,
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
110
up
to give
his post,
he became a Protestant and sought refuge in
among
Leiden, where he gave private lessons after 1663. His works,
them a Metaphysica vera and a Metaphysica ad mentem peripateticam, appeared belatedly after his death
after
(1 691-1698,
Male-
branche's works).
The
was
central idea of all his investigations
to escape
from "the
human mind to base the modes of its own thoughts on known things." Aristotle was the exemplar of those who succumbed, Descartes the model for those who sought to resist. One of the first mistakes of the Peripatetics was to imagine inclination of the
corporeal agents capable of producing in us a great variety of sen-
and
sations I
ideas; for
I
am, on the other that
am
simply acknowledge on the one hand that
many
have
I
is
No,
for
a simple being,
which therefore has
this diversity,
But
am
is
it
its
that
I
"quite obvious that there
scious
I
follow
my
and of which
and
I
know
I
do not
that the cause of
modes
no action unless there
is
the
which
me
mode
is
that fire pro-
I
I
see clearly
am
not con-
of production; con-
lacks consciousness, cannot
of thought can only be a thinking
being outside me. But every thinking being
can therefore produce diverse
maintained?
"natural instinct,"
know
that the body,
such
spite of
as Aristotle
cannot be the author of an action of which
sequently act,
when
I
source in an external agent.
consciousness in the agent. Prejudice convinces
duces heat; but
of thought;
cannot produce in myself
I
found in bodies,
the agent to be
modes
remain the same in
also a simple being, since I
diversity; since I
different
effects
is
simple like
me
and
only through the intervention
of something capable of diverse changes that give rise to diverse objects
of
thought— through the intervention of extension and
bodies. "Bodies then act as instruments act as the instruments of
more things than sionalist thesis
I
as causes."
can conceive. This
is
who
They
can create
one form of the occa-
advanced by Malebranche. 8
Geulincx went
much
to consider bodies as 8
and not
an ineffable cause— God
further in his reasoning. Descartes learned
being intelligible and attributed to them exten-
Metaphysica vera, ed. Land, pp. 150-51, 153, 268 (note).
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
Ill
sion, infinitely divisible, impenetrable,
and endowed with diverse
other properties. But these properties are intelligible and therefore
must have been
intro-
put into matter not only motion but
all its
as such; they
cannot belong to brute bodies
God
duced by a mind. other properties.
We
tendency of his reasoning.
see the
we must
of thought to the end, ceive
we
If
follow his train
mind can
conclude that the
and know nothing about a thing except what has been
duced into the thing by the mind. But the principle, he
was much
he drew from
application.
its
less
sure about the consequences that
Sometimes he viewed the mind's con-
things as they are in themselves (ut sunt in se)
from us
conceal
modes, genera, and
but of
human
their physical
species,
considerations
or right or the rules of
—
knowledge of
for instance,
reality.
Similarly,
when when
were beings and that he was describing
Aristotle said that things their
intro-
Geulincx was firm about
if
tribution to things as an obstacle to the acquisition of
qualities
con-
he was not speaking of things
which had no more
grammar and which,
reality
For example, "being
stitute a discipline (doctrina).
than
left
like these, could conis
nothing but
mode of thinking through which we apprehend something on which we have decided to state an opinion," and the same is true of parts and wholes, of unity and plurality. But human wisdom a
would then have
severe limitations; it would reach only things which we ourselves have produced: "such is our consciousness of love, hatred,
affirmation, negation,
and
all
our other actions," in
other words, immediate psychological data.
Wisdom sometimes ("ideas"
are
is
radically
thoughts"), yet an idea
defined as knowledge derived from ideas
distinct is
from "human considerations and
not simply an image of a thing in
itself
we saw in the example of the body) but an addition of the mind. The distinguishing mark of an idea—the idea of extension, (as
for instance
—
is
this:
because
it
derives
from the divine mind,
it
acquires the character of a rule or law, something not found in
human modes 9
of thinking.9 In any case, nothing
Metaphysica ad mentem peripateticam, ed. Land,
II,
is
more
199; 191 (note).
instruc-
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
112
than the fluctuation in the reasoning of Geulincx who, finding the thing-in-itself only in immediate consciousness, tried to provide science with an object by tracing a line of demarcation, never quite tive
distinct,
between thoughts that have
their source in us
and true
ideas.
Clauberg
xin
Johann Clauberg (1622-1665), a Westphalian who wrote two of German (noteworthy in view of the
his philosophical treatises in
practice of his contemporaries), taught first at at
Duisburg (1652).
An
Herborn
erudite Cartesian, he
(1650), then
was familiar with
Renaissance Platonism, with Marsilio Ficino, Plotinus, and Plato.
The
essential characteristic of his
attention
it
deserves,
Platonic tradition.
is
work, which has not received the
his attempt to relate Cartesianism to the
Nothing
is
more
singular in this respect than his
teaching concerning the theologian Conrad Berg. According to
Clauberg, in his unpublished writings Berg defended a theory of ideas "similar in every tical to Plato's:
way
to Descartes' theory,"
and almost iden-
ideas are "species" of the absolute Being, have
more
perfection than the things they represent in proportion as they are spiritual,
and are "something inanimate." Berg was even familiar
with the proof of the existence of for this proof
is
at
God through
the idea of
God,
bottom only one aspect and one application of
the principle that led Plato to infer the existence of ideal models
from
sensible things: things are natural signs of spiritual realities;
similarly, the idea of ity."
10
It
was
God
is
"the natural sign of the divine real-
his Christian Platonism, suffused
of the dignity of the soul, that led Clauberg to
with an awareness
deny that any
cor-
poreal modification could produce a modification in the soul, since
an
effect
could not be more noble than
its
cause. It follows, he
said (using a Stoic expression), that "the motions of our bodies are
only procatarctic causes that provide the mind, as well as the prin-
De
cognitione, exercise xvi, pp. 619-20,
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
113
with an occasion (menti occasionem dant) for
ciple cause,
always potential {semper
call forth ideas that are
ticular time." This thesis clearly reveals
its
it
to
virtute) at a par-
Platonic origin.
Digby
xiv Sir
Kenelm Digby tried
Paris,
construct
to
from
Gassendi's as
who
(1603-1665),
lived for
corpuscular physics
a
To
Descartes'.
dynamic physics he fused three
many
as
years in
remote from
construct the corpuscles of his
forces: condensation, rarefaction,
reveals his hostility to the thesis of the
and weight. His system
identity of extension and matter. But
also
it
shows that on many
axiom
points his thinking parallels that of Geulincx. "Aristotle's that there
the understanding which was not
nothing in
is
ously in the senses
falls so far
he says in his
Demon stratio
p. 216), "that
we ought
sensible things,
parts
immortalitatis animae rationalis (1664,
was
—we
are
in the senses."
first
when we speak
and wholes, cause and
stances
short of being true in a strict sense,"
rather to say the opposite: there
in the understanding that
previ-
With
of existence, relations
effect,
is
nothing
respect to
—for instance,
number, the continuum, or sub-
making statements about
their
properties
that
cannot pass for our inner images of things. "The things behind the relations
drawn
we
making
are
in appropriate colors, but
and have an image of in
statements about can be depicted and
common between
a pile
made up
signification of the
number
cent of Geulincx)
why do we
tions
we
formulate,
subsistent
mind with
thing
how
can
half, or of cause
if
ten
?
And
it
attention to the
way
in
is
there
and the
ideal
(according to terms reminis-
not "because substance— that its
own
limits
which
it
somehow depend?" These
reflected in the notions
What
attribute substantiality to the no-
circumscribed by
can
depict their relations
effect?"
of ten objects
a convenient, solid basis to
and on which
we
and
—
is,
a
provides
can attach
self-
the itself
characteristics call
which the exigencies of our minds are
which we have of
things.
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
114
La Forge
xv
In the preface of his Treatise on the
Mind
of
Man,
Its Faculties
and Functions and Its Union with the Body, according to the Principles of Rene Descartes (1666), Louis de la Forge tried, like Clauberg, to show that Descartes' ideas are in harmony, not only with
Augustine's but also with those of Marsilio Ficino and the
St.
other Platonists.
he
cast light
One
He
main
had
was
results of his meditation
on one another and the
the action of bodies soul.
of the
on the manner in which a Cartesian was
interaction of
to struggle not only against materialists
that
to interpret
body and
who, imagin-
ing that any action would have to be modeled on action through contact, declared that a soul could not act
was
itself
verse as a real quality
and
to clear ideas,
clear
and
of a
moving
:
neither harder [nor easier] to
that one
motion
the soul
is
its
The
is
consider the it
no notion
one body on another,
and the
if
it
itself
materialists erred in
mind since understand how a mind can spirituality of
than to understand
only moving force
and obliges the
"directs
to bodies in
to the
with bodies and .
power which
.
it
we
how one body
pushes
God, the universal
is
we
can say
the particular cause of another motion or that
moving power
laws of motion the
we
the particular cause of a corporeal motion only
have acted, according govern
it
are both inimical
if
the motions in the world. Consequently
all
that
dynamism
—extension—we find in
"action'* of
unintelligible,
is
who viewed
introduced into the uni-
an argument against the
it
another" (p. 254).
and
body
The
force.
on a body and move
mean
God
materialism and
distinct idea of
deducing from
cause of
body unless the soul
for identical reasons. Indeed,
consider only bodies,
act
a
corporeal, but also against certain Cartesians
the constant quantity of motion that
"it is
on
.
and
for
manner
first
cause to apply
whose absence in
minds—for
which
it
it
its
if
we
force
would not
has resolved to
bodies according to the
minds according
to the extension of
has elected to accord to the will."
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
115
Gerard de Cordemoy
xvi
Gerard de Cordemoy, counselor to the king and reader to the grand dauphin, followed the same course in his own reflections. Like La Forge, he published
work in 1666: Ten Discourses Body and Soul. He had formu-
his first
on the Separation and the Union of
on the
lated his ideas
and had discussed
with several friends.
of this thesis in his fourth discourse
"What we
:
others
moved, they
("The
mean when we
really
at least at the
come
same
speed,
what was
and
clear formulation
First
say that
that all bodies are impenetrable
is
see that
most Cartesians. Cordemoy offered a
strongly to
tion")
We
ascendancy and appealed
occasionalism was in the
called
later
it
subject seven or eight years earlier (p. 72),
Cause of Mo-
some bodies move
and cannot always be
that consequently,
when
mind that moved the first with The interaction of body and soul
together, they provide the
move
an occasion to
the second."
same way. "A
moves a body when, because
is
conceived in the
it
wishes this to happen, whatever was already moving the body
actually
moves
it
in the direction desired
Cordemoy drew
considerations
rather surprising. Since there is
commonly
these terms,
is
and
called cause
we
soul
by the
From
such
some of which
conclusions,
no
soul."
intrinsic relation
effect deriving
are
between what
from the nature of
can imagine, between a soul and a body or between
one soul and another, modes of relation quite different from actual
mind, separated from the
modes; for instance,
it is
body, to imagine
bodies, without union with one precluding, as
it
to
now
does,
all
possible for the
union with another.
We can
communicate thoughts, need only
a thought can, after
than
a
motion;
all,
upon us
Words, pp. 75-79).
It
imagine minds which, communication, for
more
easily
discloses
new
occasion another thought even
furthermore,
thoughts to us whose cause to the influence
also
will their
is
inspiration,
which
we cannot grasp, can probably be traced minds unknown to us {Discourse on
of
obvious that Cordemoy's Cartesianism
tends toward the sort of disconnected vision of the universe which
—
Il6
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY and which almost
caused Leibniz to censure the occasionalists anticipated
Hume's
vision
—a conclusion wholly consonant with the
type of atomism that he substituted in physics for the master's
continuous matter. Finally, he concluded from his
thesis, as
Male-
branche also concluded, that belief in the existence of bodies can be guaranteed only by faith.
xvn
and Huet
Sylvain Regis
suit the tastes of
known that his metaphysics was too strong to many. The history of Platonism proves that ideal-
ism based
on
Descartes
made
solely
it
spiritual realities, unless
tempered by the
rigor-
ous discipline, self-control, and generosity typified by Descartes, in
danger of becoming visionary. The fault
in the his
weak minds
System
of those
of Philosophy
who
lies
is
not in Descartes but
tried to interpret idealism. In
Regis
Sylvain
(1690)
(1632-1707)
one of the most celebrated popularizers of Cartesianism in Toulouse (1665), Montpellier (1671), of Cartesianism
and Paris
which eliminated
—expounded
that danger.
speculative excesses in the doctrine
He
put an end to
by considering
These ideas derive
reference to non-spiritual realities, with
all
realities
—as
simple images of
all their
value from their
even innate ideas and clear and distinct ideas non-spiritual realities.
a bland variety
which
their existence begins
and ends; furthermore, the same principle applies even more fully to truths
grounded on such
ideas.
force-
"Numerical, geometric, and
metaphysical truths can be eternal neither according to their matter
nor according to their form cause this
is
—not
on the
basis of their matter be-
nothing other than the substances that
produced, and not on the basis of their form because this other than the operation through which in a certain way,
mind
God is
has
nothing
considers substances
and the mind's operation cannot be
Cartesian then accepted Aristotle's axiom, "there
is
eternal."
This
nothing in the
understanding that has not been in the senses," and tried to find in things a stable foundation for truth. But he also accepted the doctrine of innate ideas,
though only in the sense that they
exist in the
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
117
mind from
the time of our earliest experiences
and remain there
permanently. For instance, any external experience a
mode
of extension,
extension with
properties;
and the same
mode
is
true of the idea of
of thought. Regis' opinions con-
with those of Malebranche who,
answer the objections of
to
knowledge of
and any mode of extension implies the idea of
all its
thought enveloped in any trast sharply
is
as
we
had
shall see,
concerning the ideas which
his critics
he saw directly "in God." Regis assumed the role of defending Descartes against the attacks
who
of Pierre Daniel Huet,
Cartesianae in 1689.
Huet appears on
Weakness
Treatise on the
published his Censura philosophiae the basis of his Philosophical
Human
of the
Mind, written before
1690 but not published until 1723, to be a sensationalist and, con-
The
sequently, a skeptic.
"species" of objects, because they pass
through diverse media and then through our senses which
them
by the time they reach
more, are distorted
still
skepticism
is
a definitive avowal of powerlessness, intended
It is
to "prepare the
mind
upon everything
to receive faith."
human
in
and
Descartes' rationalism
must look with doubt
things reason can attain to cer-
in the light of faith. easily
is
discerned;
for marshaling an arsenal of causes,
can explain imaginary (p. 172),
We
that reason teaches us or at least believe that in
and even
tainty only through
at the
his
not, like that of the ancient Skeptics, a continuous
search for truth.
divine things
us.
alter
But
all
of
His attitude toward
he
them
suspect since they
effects as readily as real ones.
Huyghens was
the
first to
Descartes
criticizes
For example
discover Saturn's ring,
time of Descartes was assumed to be two
satellites;
which
Descartes
"thought that he had adduced perfectly valid reasons to explain
why
the imaginary planets
for his criterion of clear
the set.
famous
move
and
vicious circle for
distinct ideas, its
which he was
In his Reply to Criticism
physics in an
odd manner.
quite slowly around Saturn."
He
worth
criticized
is
not pertain to
it,"
refuted by
from the
out-
(1691), Regis defended Cartesian
maintained that "speculative physics
can be dealt with only problematically, that whatever strative does
As
and
that
its
role
is
demon-
was limited
to devis-
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
Il8
ing a mechanical arrangement for deducing effects from experience.
As
for the vicious circle,
human
of a perfect being, but
the truth of an idea
Toward biased
for
it
was on the
the
it
was on the plane of the absolute
depended on the existence of
end of the century,
that
this idea.
in the opinion of
many men
less
than Huet, Cartesian rationalism was dangerous simply
because to
was merely apparent;
it
plane that the certainty of a true idea led to the existence
it
was a form of rationalism. The "cause of God" was hard
defend through recondite arguments. "I have learned," said
God
Jaquelot, for example, in his Dissertations on the Existence of
(1690), "that several metaphysical proofs to strike the heart perceptibly.
too subtle, even though
The mind
arguments that seem
resists
might find nothing
to refute
them."
argument, Jaquelot substituted for proof of the
to clinch his
ence of
it
do not have enough body
God
his idea of the old proof a contingentia
And exist-
mundi. Fur-
thermore, this was the age that witnessed the appearance of a
number
of
refutations
the
of
Cartesian
proof,
refutations
that
struck at the very heart of his philosophy. For instance, in his
]udicium de argumento Cartesii petito ab ejus idea (Basel, 1699), Werenfels wrote that the idea of God is no more an immutable nature than
is
the idea of "horse," since
one or more of whether
its
its
perfections.
existence
is
compatible with truths
with to
unknown
truths.
He
possible, since
known
we
can arbitrarily eliminate
added that we cannot know
to us,
even it
if
can
Even Fenelon, though
we
still
God by
setting
down
it
is
entirely sympathetic
Descartes, thought that he should begin his
Existence of
grant that
be incompatible Treatise on the
the most obvious
proof, that of final causes written for "intelligent
and popular
men" who
did
not have "a thorough knowledge of physics." In the period that lay ahead,
more
stress
was
to
invention of sound reasons.
be placed on persuasion than on the
Bibliography
I
to
X
Texts Descartes, Rene. (Euvres. Edited by C.
Adam
and
Adam
and G. Milhaud.
P. Tannery. 13 vols. Paris,
1897-1913.
Correspondance. Edited by C.
.
8 vols. Paris,
1936-63. .
(Euvres
The
.
et lettres.
Ross. Repr. 2 vols.
New
London,
ed. Paris, 1953.
S.
Haldane and G. T. R.
York, 1955.
Descartes' Philosophical
.
New
Edited by A. Bridoux.
Philosophical Wor\s. Translated by E.
Writings. Translated by
N.
Philosophical Writings. Edited and translated by E.
.
Kemp
Smith.
1952.
Anscombe and
Geach. Edinburgh, 1954. Philosophical Essays. Translated by L. F. Lafleur. Indianapolis, Ind.,
P. T. .
1964.
Discours de la methode. Edited by E. Gilson. 2d ed. Paris, 1930. Les Meditations metaphysiques. Edited by E. Thouverez. Paris, 1932. -. Correspondence of Descartes and Constantin Huyghens, 1635-1647. Edited by L. Roth. Oxford, 1926. .
.
Studies Alquie, F. Descartes:
Vhomme
Balz, A. G. A. Descartes
et
VCEuvre. Paris, 1956.
and the Modern Mind.
New
Haven, Conn., 1952.
The Method of Descartes. Oxford, 1952. The Metaphysics of Descartes. Oxford, 1965. Brunschvicg, L. Rene Descartes. Paris, 1937. Le progres de la conscience dans la philosophic Beck, L.
J.
.
.
occidentale. Paris,
1927. -.
Spinoza
Delbos, V.
ha
et ses
contemporains. 3d ed. Paris, 1923.
philosophic franqaise. Paris, 1921.
Fischer, K. Descartes
and
his School. Translated
by
J.
P. Gordy.
1887. Fouillee, A. Descartes. Paris, 1893.
Gibson, A. Boyce.
The Philosophy 119
of Descartes.
London,
1932.
New
York,
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
120
Gilson, E. Index scholastico-cartesien. Paris, 1913.
Etudes sur
.
role
le
de
la
pensee medievale dans
la
formation du
systeme cartesien. Paris, 1930. Gouhier, H. Essais sur Descartes. Paris, 1937. La pensee mctaphysique de Descartes. Paris. 1962. .
S. Descartes: His Life and Times. New York, 1905. Hamelin, O. Le systeme de Descartes. Paris, 191 1. Jaspers, Karl. Descartes und die Philosophic 3d ed. Berlin, 1956. Keeling, S. V. Descartes. London, 1934. Laberthonniere, LeP. Etudes sur Descartes. 2 vols. Paris, 1935. Laporte, J. M. F. Le rationalisme de Descartes. Paris, 1945.
Haldane, E.
Lewis, G. Rene Descartes, francais, philosophe. Tours, 1953. Liard, L. Descartes. Paris, 1882.
Roth, L. Descartes' Discourse on Method. Oxford, 1937. Spinoza, Descartes, and Maimonides. New York, 1963. .
Scott,
F.
J.
The
Wor\
Scientific
of
Rene
Sebba, G. Bibliographia Cartesiana: ature, i8oo-ig6o.
The Hague,
London, 1952. Guide to the Descartes
Descartes.
A
Critical
Liter-
1964.
I'homme et le penseur. Paris, 195 1. Studies in the Cartesian Philosophy. London, 1902.
Serrurier, C. Descartes,
Smith, N. .
Kemp.
New Studies in
the Philosophy of Descartes. London, 1952.
La
philosophic moderne depuis Bacon jusqu'a Leibniz. 3 vols. Paris, 1920-29. Vol. Ill, Descartes.
G.
Sortais,
Vartanian, A. Diderot and Descartes. Princeton, N.J., 1953. Versfeld, M. An Essay on the Metaphysics of Descartes. London, 1940. Meta-Meditations. Edited by A. Sesonske and B. N. Fleming. Belmont, Calif., 1965.
Studies
Adam,
C. Vie et oeuvres de Descartes. (CEiwres, Vol. XII.) Paris, 1910. .
Descartes; ses amities feminines. Paris, 1937.
"Rene Descartes, Manuscrit de Gottingen," Revue bourguignonne de I'enseignement superieur, 1896. .
Baillet,
Adrien.
La
vie
de Monsieur Descartes. 2
vols. Paris, 1691.
Cantecor, G. "La vocation de Descartes," Revue philosophique, November, 1923. .
"A
Revue
E.
Cassirer,
quelle date Descartes
d'histoire
de
Descartes:
la
a-t-il
philosophic
Lehre,
ecrit
Cohen, G. Ecrivains francais en Hollande dans si eel
c
Paris, 1920.
la
Recherche de
(1928). Personlich\eit, Wir\ung.
la
Verite?"
II
la
Stockholm, premiere moitie du
1939.
XVH e
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
121
Gouhier, H. "Sur
la
date de
la
Recherche de
Revue
la Verite,"
d'histoire
de
la philosophie, III (1929).
Les premieres pensees de Descartes. Paris, 1958. Descartes, le philosophe au masque. Paris, 1929. Milhaud, G. "L'ceuvre de Descartes pendant l'hiver 1 619-1620," Scientia, .
M.
Leroy,
January, 191 8. .
"Une
crise
mystique chez Descartes en 1619," Revue de metaphysique,
July, 1916. .
Sirven,
"La sincerite de Descartes," Revue de metaphysique, May, 1919. Les annees d'apprentissage de Descartes, 1^6-1628. Paris, 1928.
J.
II
Studies Alquie, F.
La decouverte metaphysique de I'homme chez
Descartes. Paris,
1950.
Articles on Descartes commemorating the third centenary Revue philosophique, 1951. H. Gouhier, and M. Gueroult. Descartes. (Colloque de Royau-
Alquie, F., et
al.
of his death,
Alquie, F.,
mont.) Paris, 1957. J. "La methode de Descartes," Revue de metaphysique, 1896. Boutroux, P. L' imagination et les mathematiques selon Descartes. Paris, 1900. "La signification historique de la Geometrie de Descartes," Revue de metaphysique, 19 15. Brunschvicg, L. Ecrits philosophiques. Paris, 1951. I, 11-108. Berthet,
.
Gibson, B. "The Regulae of Descartes," Mind, 1898.
"La geometrie de Descartes au point de vue de de metaphysique, 1896. .
la
methode," Revue
M. Descartes, selon I'ordre des raisons. 2 vols. Paris, 1958. Vol. I, L'dme et Dieu; Vol. II, L'dme et le corps. Hannequin, A. "La methode de Descartes," Revue de metaphysique, 1906. Gueroult,
Reprinted in Essais sur Vhistoire des sciences 1908.
Milhaud, G.
quantum
Num
Cartesii
methodus tantum
et
de
la philosophie. Paris,
valeat in sui opere illustrando
senserit. Montpellier, 1894.
.
"La Geometrie de Descartes," Revue generale des
.
"Descartes et l'analyse infinitesimale," Ibid., 1917.
.
"La querelle de Descartes
et
sciences, 19 16.
de Fermat au sujet des tangentes,"
1917.
Vuillemin,
J.
Mathematiques
et
metaphysique chez Descartes.
Paris, i960.
Ibid.,
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
122
III
Studies Gilson, E. 1914.
"L'inneisme cartesien
Reprinted
1921, pp. 146
et
Etudes
in
la
de
Revue de metaphysique,
theologie,"
philosophic
medievale,
Strasbourg,
ff.
Natorp, P. Descartes Er\enntnisstheorie: Eine Studie zur Vorgeschichte des Kriticismus. Marburg, 1882. Virgier,
J.
"Les idees de temps, de duree et d'eternite dans Descartes," Revue
philosophique, 1920.
Wahl,
J.
Du
role
de Videe de Vinstant dans
la
philosophic de Descartes.
Paris, 1920.
IV
Study Boutroux, E.
De
veritatibus aeternis
apud Cartesium.
eternelles chez Descartes. Translated
Paris, 1875.
by Canguilhem.
Des
verites
Paris, 1927.
V Studies Blanchet, L. Les antecedents historiques
du
"]e pense,
done
je suis." Paris,
1920.
Gueroult,
M. Nouvelles
reflexions sur la preuve ontologique de Descartes.
Paris, 1955.
VI
Studies M. "Le Christianisme de Descartes," Revue de metaphysique, 1896. La doctrine cartesienne de la liberte et la theologie. Paris, 1913. Gouhier, H. La pensee religieuse de Descartes. Paris, 1924. Blondel,
Glison, E.
Hannequin, A. "La preuve ontologique de Descartes defendue contre Leibniz," Revue de metaphysique, 1896. Laberthonniere, L. "La religion de Descartes," Annales de philosophic chretienne, August, 191 .
"La theorie de
1.
la foi
chez Descartes,"
Ibid., July, 191
1.
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
123
"Le pretendu rationalisme de Descartes au point de vue
.
September, 191 1. Laporte, J. "La finalite chez Descartes," Revue d'histoire de
religieux,'
Ibid.,
philosophic
la
(1928).
II
Russier,
J.
Sagesse
I'immortalite de
carte sienne
Vdme
et
religion:
Essai
sur la
connaissance
de
selon Descartes. Paris, 1958.
VII
Study Schwarz, H. "Les recherches de Descartes sur exterieur," Revue de metaphysique, 1896.
la
du monde
connaissance
VIII
Studies Belaval, Y. Leibniz critique de Descartes. Paris, i960.
Carteron, H. "L'idee de
Revue philosophique, Gilson,
E.
"Meteores
la force
mecanique dans
le
systeme de Descartes,"
1922.
cartesiens
et
meteores
scolastiques,"
de
Etudes
in
philosophic medievale, Strasbourg, 192 1, pp. 247 ff. Hoffman, A. "Die Lehre von der Bildung des Universums bei Descartes,"
Archiv fur die Geschichte der Philosophic, XVII (1904). Korteweg. "Descartes et Snellius, d'apres quelques documents nouveaux," Revue de metaphysique, 1896. Milhaud, T. "Descartes experimentateur," Revue philosophique, 19 18. Reprinted in Descartes savant, Paris, 1920. .
"Descartes et Bacon," Scientia, 19 17. Reprinted in Descartes savant,
Paris, 1917. .
"Le double aspect de Pceuvre scientifique de Descartes,"
Scientia,
1916. Reprinted in Descartes savant, Paris, 1917. .
"Notes sur Descartes,"
Revue philosophique, 19 18. Reprinted
in
Descartes savant, Paris, 19 17.
Tannery, P. "Descartes physicien," Revue de metaphysique, 1896.
IX
Studies Berthier,
"Le mecanisme
cartesien et la physiologie au
XVII e
siecle,"
Isis,
1914.
Canguilhem, G. La formation du concept de reflexe aux XVII e siecles. Paris, 1955.
et
XVIUe
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
124
"Organisme et modeles mecaniques, Reflexions sur la biologie carRevue philosophique, 1955, pp. 281-299. Gilson, E. "Descartes et Harvey," Revue philosophique, 1921 and 1922. Re.
tesienne (i),"
printed in Etudes de philosophic medievale, Strasbourg, 1921, pp. 191 fT. in der Heil\nude am
Sommer, E. Die Entstehung der mechanischem Schule Ausgang des iy. Jahrhunderts. Leipzig, 1899.
Studies Boutroux, E.
"Du
cartesienne,"
rapport de
la
morale a
Revue de metaphysique,
Brochard, V. "Le
traite
la
science
dans
la
philosophic
1896.
des Passions de Descartes et l'Ethique de Spinoza,"
Revue de metaphysique,
1896.
Reprinted
in
Etudes
de
ancienne et de philosophic moderne. Paris, 1912. Pp. 3271!. "Descartes stoi'cien," in Etudes de philosophic ancienne .
sophic moderne. Paris, 1912. Pp. 320
philosophic et
de philo-
ff.
Espinas, A. Descartes et la morale. 2 vols. Paris, 1925.
Lanson, G.
"Le heros cornelien
et
le
genereux
selon
Descartes,"
Revue
d'histoire litteraire, 1894.
Lewis, G. L'indiridualite selon Descartes. Paris, 1950. Le probleme de Vinconscient et le carte sianisme. Paris, 1950. La morale de Descartes. Paris, 1957. .
.
Mesnard, P. Essai sur la morale de Descartes. Paris, 1936. Seailles, G. Quid de ethica Carte sins senserit. Paris, 1883.
XI
Studies
New York, 195 1. de la philosophie cartesienne. 3d ed. 2 vols. Paris, 1868. Mouy, P. Le developpement de la physique cartesienne, 1646-17 12. Paris,
Balz, A. G. Cartesian Studies. Bouillier, F. Histoire
1934Prost,
J.
Essai sur
Vatomisme
et
V occasionalisme dans
la
philosophie cartesi-
enne. Paris, 1907.
XII
Text Geulincx, Arnold. Opera philosophica. Edited by
Hague, 1891-93.
J.
P.
N. Land. 3
vols.
The
DESCARTES AND CARTESIANISM
125
Studies
Van
der Haeghen, V. Geulincx: Etudes sur sa
vie,
sa philosophic et ses
ouvrages. Ghent, 1886.
Land,
J.
P.
N. Arnold Geulincx und seine Philosophic The Hague,
1895.
XIII
Text Clauberg, Johannes. Opera. Amsterdam, 1691.
Study Miiller,
Hermann. Johannes Clauberg und
seine Stellung
im Cartesianismus.
(Dissertation) Jena, 1891.
XV Study Seyfarth,
H. Louis de
la
Forge und seine Stellung im Occasionalismus.
(Dissertation) Gotha, 1887.
XVII
Texts Regis, Sylvain. Systeme de philosophic contenant la logique, la metaphysique,
physique
la
et la
morale. Paris, 1690.
Huet, D. Censura philosophiae carte sianae. Paris, 1689. Traite philosophique de la jaiblesse de Vesprit humain. Amsterdam, .
1723.
Studies Bartholmes, C. Huet, eveque d'Avranches, ou
le
scepticisme
theologique.
Paris, 1850. Sortais,
G. "Le cartesianisme chez
siecle,"
les Jesuites francais ail
Archives de philosophic, VI (1929).
XVII e
et
au XVTI e
PASCAL i
The Methods
of Pascal
blaise pascal
was not
(1623-1662)
a philosopher.
He was
a scientist
scientist
he had a place in the tradition of mathematical and ex-
and an apologist
for the Catholic religion.
perimental physics that led from Galileo to Newton.
he did not
start
by attempting
to
To answer
a
apologist
demonstrate by reason
truths of faith that are demonstrable.
he turned
As an
As
all
the
the freethinkers
whole spectrum of human
to history for evidence, to the
behavior, just as he turned to experience
and not
to reason
for
proof of a physical truth. Descartes was also a scientist and, to a certain degree,
an apologist, but his genius prevented him from
being both without being a philosopher at the same time
—without
introducing science and apologetics into the "chain of reasons"
from which he had excluded the truths of on the contrary, allowed him neither getics
to
make
an integral part of a philosophy nor
sideration the truths of faith.
almost contemporaries,
is
so
The
faith. Pascal's genius,
science
and apolo-
to fail to take into con-
contrast between the
two men,
profound and so striking that in
all
probability nothing else in history can provide us with a better
human mind. when Pascal was hardly
understanding of the nature of the
The Essay on
Conies, written
out of his
childhood (1639), reveals one of his characteristic intellectual
When
traits.
dealing with a specific problem (to find the principle from 126
—
PASCAL
127
which
all
the properties of conic sections can be deduced), he
devised a specific
of resolving this problem
method capable
and
only this problem. Pascal discovered that every property of a conic
depended upon the invention of a certain hexagon, which
section
he
Thus each problem
the mystic hexagram.
calls
the ability to discover the precise notions
why
This explains
solution.
its
and
principles needed
showed
that
and of the
sur-
Pascal subsequently
in order to find the center of gravity of a cycloid faces or
volumes that depend upon
this curve,
we must
take into
consideration the properties of so-called triangular numbers.
who
points out in his Thoughts, those
and
repelled by definitions
and
the
intuitively,
hexagram and the
seem
sterile to
them; they cannot
to
slightest
As he
are not geometers will be
principles that
by propositions incomprehensible ately
new
on the part of the mathematician, who must have
inventive effort
for
requires a
relation
them and
see,
immedi-
between the mystic
properties of conical sections, between triangular
numbers and the question of
centers of gravity.
The
discovery of
such relations depends not upon a method communicable to every-
one but upon a certain mentality possessed by few
few men with
men.
whom
"I
I
—the
geometric
was bothered by the
is
were
could discuss them," Pascal later remarked
in speaking of the abstract sciences.
He
used the word "method" in
the plural, for he maintained that there
procedures to be devised
—which
mind
fact that there
were
as
many methods
—as there were problems to be solved. The
geometer separates objects from one another, and the geometric
mind in turn separates The geometric mind Pascal
who
endowments
"Some
the geometer is
from other men.
only part of the scientific mind.
studied hydrostatics did not use the as
the Pascal
who
same
The
intellectual
invented the mystic hexagram.
people," he said, "have a clear understanding of the effects
of water,
which involves few
so subtle that only the
Such men would not includes
many
principles; but their consequences are
most penetrating minds can reach them.
necessarily be great geometers, for
principles,
and a
certain kind of
geometry
mind may be
able to
gain a thorough grasp of a few principles and yet be unable even
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
128
begin to understand things that involve
to
mind" with "power
"discriminating
and
still
many
to penetrate"
principles."
A
can be narrow
serve to investigate the effects of water (since the prin-
ciple of hydrostatics
is
unique)
the geometric mind,
;
on the other
hand, must be able to grasp a great number of principles without confusion and
As
is
search for principles
is
plenum through
lieved
an
must
correct is
is
be weak.
useless, or rather, in
"They
1
it.
say that because
you be-
empty when you saw nothpossible.
This
Or
they say that because you were told in school
—which understood impression— was corrupted and
no vacuum, your common sense
wrong
your
to
Consequently, no recourse to principles
But experience
certainty that the weight of a
column
first
nature" (No. 82).
possible in the question
is
with certainty that the tube
establishes
above the quicksilver in a barometer liberated
which the
claim to establish
your senses, strengthened by custom, and science
must be corrected by going back of the void.
may
Cartesians
principles:
quite clearly before this
it
may
you believed that a vacuum was
them,
illusion of
that there
futile.
child that boxes were
a
as
ing in is
it
a scientist, Pascal also applied himself to other studies in
which knowledge of principles the
though
therefore broad even
is
empty, and with equal
of quicksilver
by a pressure acting on the
free surface.
the celebrated experiment at Puy-de-D6me,
must be equiFurthermore,
which showed that the
height of the column decreases as the altitude of the apparatus increases,
The
proved that the pressure
—
vacuum
existence of the
affirmed nor denied
on the
is
caused by the atmosphere.
or the weight of air can neither be
basis of principles.
Geometric mind, discriminating mind, and experimental method all
these are
modes
of investigation that require different intel-
endowments. Pascal did not describe them or speculate on them from the standpoint of an outsider but entered into each mode with enthusiasm and passion. He was able to make a sharp
lectual
distinction 1
between these modes of investigation because of
Pensees (references are to numbers in Brunschvicg's edition).
his
PASCAL
129
experience with each of them. His success was prodigious in each instance,
and
in a
few years he had managed
to
break
new ground
everywhere. In mathematics he created the calculus of probabilities,
and one of
his
remarks about curves on a characteristic triangle
suggested to Leibniz the procedure for the infinitesimal calculus. In physics his
work with
and barometry provided the
hydrostatics
stimulus for the study of the mechanics of fluids.
Adjusting the mind to the domain of the objects studied
key
A
to Pascal's approach.
will be
"wrong and
geometer Pascal learned Chevalier de la
mind
"right" in
if
it
changes
its
its
the
own domain domain. The
through his association with the
this
Mere and
is
that
insufferable"
is
other
men
of the world.
had sound judgment about manners and
Many of them Had they
personalities.
reasoned like a geometer in reaching their convictions? Reasoned, yes; like a geometer, no.
The geometer
ber of principles; each principle has is
uses a large but finite
its
own
distinct formulation,
grasped perfectly by any attentive mind, and
other principle and to the conclusion. But the is
num-
is
linked to every
man
of the world
not interested in these principles since they are of no use to him.
His principles are "in
How
common
would he engage
usage and there for everyone to see."
in geometric reasoning, using principles
"which are sensed rather than known" and which can be communicated
numerous
to others only
"with
that demonstrating
infinite pains,"
them
with principles so
in an orderly fashion
would
be "an infinite thing," with principles that cannot be formulated distinctly since
"no
man
is
capable of expressing them"?
of the world does reason, but "he does
This
is
because he
is
endowed with
a
it
The man
tacitly, naturally, artlessly."
mind
quite different
from the
geometric mind, the "discriminating mind" that consists primarily in "seeing the thing at a glance
and not through progressive reason-
ing.
The
discovery of the discriminating
mind
is
of capital impor-
Here we have an authentic type of reasoning which bears almost the same relation to geometric reasoning as Cavalieri's
tance.
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
130
principle of indivisibles bears
mathematics; the relation
is
and the
the inexpressible
Pascal isolated
that
to
the calculus of finite
between the
expressible, intuition
discourse.
"mind" depends on
lems in is
to
for
its
judge
man
but to estimate
man.
On
its
and we must
as a specialist,
it
as a
worth in
also
this point Descartes
this
determine
gence employing a single method. Pascal acted as a concluded that to be productive in exclusive:
its
of
only
worth
its
single
all
intelli-
specialist
and
domain, a mind must be
men
"Geometers rarely have discriminating minds and
with discriminating minds are rarely geometers."
men
way
did not hesitate:
judgment because they represent a
sciences fortify
from
The worth
appropriateness to the solution of prob-
its
own domain;
for a
of the intellect. But
another point of view he associated and compared. a
in
finite,
and separated, whereas Descartes searched
method grounded on the unity
unity of
and
sums
and the
infinite
Is
it
good
for
them away from man, I saw that he is not fitted for abstract sciences and that I deviated farther from my condition by immersing myself in them than did others by ignoring them" (144). to devote themselves to studies
more important
tasks?
"When
that take
began
I
to study
Pascal devoted himself to the "science of
man"
only after he had
undertaken his apology for the Catholic religion. This science and the apology
are interconnected in his
poses problems
without
it,
He
cannot understand himself. In the to
solve Pascal
nature
Christianity;
new problem
remained wholly
faithful to
searched for a solution that would conform to every
circumstance and omit none. relation to the
Human
which can be solved only by revealed
man
which he undertook his genius.
thinking.
problem of
The
man
revelation of Christ has the
as the
or triangular
numbers
solution to the
problem will never come through analysis of
to
same
mystic hexagram to conies the
the center of gravity of cycloids;
no matter how penetrating. Original
notions,
whose
its
data
relation
to
the question can be understood only by exceptional minds,
must
be found or forged. Such notions do not have the Cartesian
intel-
ligibility that pertains to
notions considered independently; through
PASCAL
131
them other things are intelligible. The same thing applies in the science of man. Here too, here especially, the solution must come from without
—from
according to our
the Christian religion which,
human
alone capable of
criteria, is
unintelligible
making man
comprehensible to himself. Criticism of Principles
11
He we arrive at the element common to tions. He abhorred principles which could
all
of Pascal's specula-
be applied indiscrimi-
and from which everything could be deduced. His antipathy
nately
toward the
Jesuits' casuistry
stemmed
even from contempt for lax morals.
from partisanship nor
neither
He
men
detested the fact that
of their capabilities were adept at finding the subterfuge through
which they could
way
in this
relate
any action
abominable
justify
to
an established principle and
And
offenses.
in the Provincial Letters does not differ,
his criticism of
from
them
certain points of
view, from the criticism of Descartes' physics which he expressed
"We must
in his
Thoughts:
figure
and motion,
for
compose the machine
it is
is
say
summarily that
what
true; but to say
ridiculous, for
this is
made by
these are
and
useless, uncertain,
it is
to
and
painful" (79). Principles which are sufficiently universal to apply to everything, such as Descartes' mechanics, explain
nothing with
certainty.
But Descartes was wrong in thinking that he could principles intelligible in themselves
and
relate to
them
start
his
from whole
chain of deductions. His mistake was the same as that of the
who
atomists
make up
believed they could
the whole
first
identify the elements that
and then reconstruct the whole by juxtaposing
the parts, for "the parts of the world are to
one another that
I
deem
it
impossible to
other and without the whole" (72)
atom is
no
and
is
illusory.
less
But the
what
a
.
The
and linked
so related
know one
without the
intelligibility of
intelligibility of Descartes'
Gassendi's
simple nature
"man cannot understand what a body is, mind is, and less than anything else how a
illusory, for
still less
all
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
132
body can be joined
to a
anything
at first principles in
nature.
Man,
with the
mind"
The
(72).
reflects
in the order of nature,
Infinite,
is
impossibility of arriving
a radical defect in
an All in comparison with Nothing, a mean
between nothing and everything." Furthermore, "his the
same position
world of thought
in the
as his
the expanse of nature. All he can do, then,
how
things look
either their
What
human
"a Nothing in comparison
from the
body occupies in
to gain
is
intellect holds
some idea
of
knowing
center, in eternal despair of
beginning or their end."
are the "principles"
of departure for
which
are supposed to serve as a point
human knowledge and which
Pascal himself often
mentioned in connection with the geometric or discriminating
mind? The axioms and a
principles in
strict
definitions of Euclid cannot be classed as
sense,
for
the perfection of the geometric
method would require defining and demonstrating everything
We
—an
when confronted with indefinable and indemonstrable principles. Which of these is not suspect? Can we appeal to nature? "But there is no principle, however natural it may seem to be and even if it dates from childhood, that may not be a false impression attributable either to instruction or to infinite
undertaking.
have
to stop
the senses" (82). Descartes thought that he
had
established a clear
between nature and custom through methodical doubt.
distinction
Pascal allied himself with Montaigne
and the Pyrrhonians: "What
are our natural principles but principles based
ent custom
would
nature that destroys the
not natural?
I
first.
But what
is
Custom
nature?
greatly fear that this nature
A
on custom?
result in different principles.
is itself
is
Why
differ-
a second
is
a first
custom custom"
(9 2 >39)-
Here
Pascal's criticism of principles did not disagree with the
use to which he put that they
them
in geometry
and
in physics, for he said
were not absolute beginnings and that they were not
intelligible in themselves.
But nothing (and
and geometry) prevented
their being perfectly fitted to their role,
which was
to
account for a certain
through reason, such
number
this
is
true of physics
of properties
as the properties of conical sections, or
known through
PASCAL
133
column of quicksilver
observation, such as the height of the
"We
barometer.
always find that the thing to be proven
and the thing used
to
Pascal could break
source of knowledge
prove
it
obscure
clear."
away from Pyrrhonism only by and
is
in a
virtue of the
certainty that he called heart or, less fre-
quently, intelligence. Heart or intelligence contrasts with reason
which, in the language of Pascal, means reasoning or discourse in
knowledge of consequences. Reason "can be bent
general, the
(274), for the conclusion
direction"
premises received from other sources. in the sphere of principles
the heart" (278)
The
in
who
is
knowledge "sensible to
and the axioms of geometry. "The heart
But was he not
any
determined by
is
heart provides
—knowledge of God
that there are three dimensions in infinite."
reaches
it
space and that
senses
numbers
in a sense contradicting himself
he accepted both the views of the Pyrrhonians and, under the
are
when name
of heart, a particular faculty for arriving at principles with cer-
By
tainty?
edge
of
heart he
principles,
knowledge
that
meant not a but
a
certain
faculty for acquiring
manner
of
knowl-
accommodating
would otherwise remain "uncertain and
unsettled."
Pascal often contrasted the faith of simple people, strong and sure,
with the discourses of philosophers strate the existence of
how
God.
logical, are of little
who
He knew
used reason to demon-
that discourses,
use in winning over the impious: "meta-
physical proofs are so remote
from the reasoning of men and
involved that they are not very convincing; and use to some,
it
an hour
Thus
one thing to
is
if
they
may
so
be of
can only be during the time they witness the demon-
stration, for it
no matter
another to sense
it
later they are afraid of
know
being mistaken" (543).
truth through reason
and quite
through the heart. Because principles are sensed
as the believer senses
God, the geometer can surmount Pyrrhonism.
Pascal the Apologist
in
Pascal's religious apologetic therefore
is
not a demonstration of
the truth of the Christian religion, or rather his demonstration
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
134
(the traditional one through the
Old Testament and
but one part of a demonstration, the part
is
main stream
in the set
of tradition.
But when he had
to prove, as
out to do, that the Christian religion answered
truth.
Why
to that of
should
many
its
all
human
truth superior
method
revelation
is
heart
and
that
known
its
divine grace. In the
is
on the Vacuum, composed before
Treatise
Thoughts, he wrote the well that the only
its
other Christians, that the only proof
of the truths of the Christian religion
the
he
of man's
other religions that are the fruit of our prejudices?
only means of access to the to
make
perfect expedience
Pascal knew, along with
preface
all
and completely, expedience took precedence over
needs, uniquely
is
the miracles)
where he remained
his
pages in which he revealed
of investigation of truth in religious matters
based on authority which has
its
source in
God
himself. In his
Thoughts he treated revealed truths concerning our supernatural destiny
and meditation on Christ
If traditional
the
same
would be
as a
datum
or point of departure.
proofs in the form of miracles or prophecies were
in nature as geometric proofs, the rest of the apologetic useless.
But these proofs are such that they cannot con-
vince the unbeliever; through reveals about himself;
and
them God
that
is
why
conceals as
faith
much
as
he
remains meritorious
and depends on grace rather than on reason. Accordingly, instead of using proofs
when he
addressed the
unbeliever, he had to show that only the Christian religion can make man comprehensible to himself. He therefore had to make man desire truth, to "free him from passions and prepare him to
may find man must know
follow truth wherever he
But for
this,
Descartes, man's nature
is
it."
his
own
nature. According to
revealed to the philosopher gradually,
according to the order of reasons. Pascal, on the other hand, tried to concentrate all of
experience which of his nature.
man's knowledge of himself into a unique
would
"When we
reveal to
him simultaneously
every facet
seek effectively to reprove someone and
show him that he is wrong, we must take note of the standpoint from which he is observing a thing, for from that angle it is gen-
PASCAL
135
and we must admit
erally true,
him
tried before
judge
He
This
is
who
maintained,
in his "thought"
is
things, even including his
all
(9).
criticism of those
his
determine the nature of man.
to
with Epictetus, that man's greatness his faculty to
him"
that truth to
on which Pascal based
the principle
own
—that
is,
weakness;
but the Stoics were ignorant of man's wretchedness and, consequently, their doctrine
words were directed control.
Montaigne was
and
ness
is
frailty of
and
ineffective
their advice sterile; their
man
to a fictitious
right, therefore,
when he showed
man, duped constantly by
cepting as natural justice something that
endowed with
country,
capable of absolute
is
self-
the weak-
his imagination, ac-
merely a custom of his
a mental volubility that makes him
in-
capable of choosing an exact point from which he could see himself
and nature
in the right perspective, so enslaved to opinion that
he attaches more importance
him than
to
the "last act
of the
and
.
.
.
is
the
taigne into his
is,
subject to afflictions
always tragic, no matter
comedy may
that
judgments that others pass on
to the
what he himself
be. Finally
end of
own
some
dirt is
Pascal put
it all."
all
he
finally
toward
without
and
fear
tranquillity of soul that the Stoics
tain
through opposing paths
certain traits
Mon-
is
why, through
selfit,
from the
is
without
remorse; ... he
and Montaigne
illusory
because, by eliminating
made
picture, they
(63).
tried to at-
it
more coherent than
is.
Here, too, there must be a is
his head,
and indolent manner"
The
what
thrown over
the substance of
the "foolish things" he said as a result of
all
salvation,
actually
beautiful the rest
reached a state worse than despair, an "indifference
thinks only of dying in a cowardly
it
to death,
work. Yet Montaigne's vision was defective, for
he was ignorant of man's grandeur. That
complacency and
how
and
asserted with equal veracity.
and contradiction: a
unified experience.
total,
stated as true concerning
Man
is
entail
an
matter
the epitome of incoherence
tragic incoherence
vealed to us as in a painting which
most would
No
man, the opposite can always be
intellectual
we
inasmuch
as
it
is
not
re-
could ignore or which at
dissatisfaction;
it
touches our
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
136
innermost being;
eliminates the very basis of our moral
it
life,
—the confidence of the Stoic as well —leaving us bewildered and
every vestige of our assurance
as the nonchalance of the Skeptic
"What kind
oriented.
how
contradictory,
of
how
myth
Many
philosophers
and a
titanic part
prehensible in
how
chaotic,
things, a senseless
(after the
riff-raff
Orphics) had, of course, looked
merely to
by attributing
it
make
celestial part
The new
the situation com-
to the order of
to his logical place in the
nature and
descending hierarchy of
vision of the universe that the Renaissance
had engendered made
this
relation to the totality of nature im-
possible. In the terrifying silence of infinite space, lost in the
man
of nature,
He
destiny.
is
nothing.
He knows
realm
neither his origin nor his
can no longer find support in the chimerical image
of a finite, ordered universe in
which
He has to fall back upon himself. What does he find in himself? had the
and
of the universe."
engaged in a struggle; but they had intended
itself
man
living beings.
new,
all
an intermediate being composed of a
as
(especially the Neo-Platonists)
assigning
How
truth, a cesspool of uncertainty
crowning glory and the
upon man
man?
is
prodigious! Judge of
earthworm; a storehouse of error; the
dis-
His
—
"foolish plan" of depicting
and which
the center of everything
his place
own
a self
is
is
self,
clearly indicated.
which Montaigne
which seeks
at the
to
become
same time unjust and
may
irritating so far as others are concerned. Reciprocal politeness
indeed remove false,
for
irritation,
man
from the
possible
Whenever he
is
but not injustice (455). But even this
seeks through "diversion" to escape as self
to
which he
sacrifices
diversions prevent us that
fragile
we
(139).
love so
and thousands of other
from thinking about the weakness of the
much. But
and deceptive. The truth
to us to be
everything
is
as
alone with himself, he lives in an intolerable state
of boredom. Conversations, games, reading,
self
much
remedies actually are
these external supports are also is
that the diversions that
much worse
seem
than boredom, for
they "take us farther than anything else from the search for the
cure to our
ills."
The
result
is
that
man, constantly
tossed
from
self
PASCAL
137
and from things
to things
to self, searches in vain for happiness
"without ever finding contentment because in creatures but only in
This portrait of tianity.
It
suffering
human
destiny of
neither in us nor
is
owes nothing
separated
clearly
to Pascal's Chris-
from the
His interpretation of the portrait
offers.
of
human
must be
it
God."
every aspect
as follows:
is
he
interpretation
nature can be explained in terms of the supernatural
man
The
revealed through Christianity.
deluded by the notion that there
is
philosopher was
which everything
a nature to
We must change our perspective and see man in the drama in which he is an actor: his grandeur which derives from his divine origin, his wretchedness which originated with the fall of Adam whose children can no longer resist concan be related. supernatural
cupiscence,
and
hope of salvation through the redemption of
his
whose absence knowledge
Jesus Christ in
man. In keeping with the
use to
ascribed a purely internal
drama
of creation,
fall,
we
seen and which
and
God would
of
be of no
age and milieu, Pascal
spirit of his
religious significance to the three-act
and redemption which we have frame (we
shall again see as the
monotonous rhythm of station-procession-conversion)
so often
the
recall
com-
for the
prehensive representation of the universe.
The is
close correlation
between Christianity and human nature
the thing that Pascal sought to emphasize, the thing that could
the freethinker to religion.
attract
Man
wager (333).
his
celebrated
has a penchant for gambling, and the gambler
naturally places his bet in other respects,
This explains
on the
table where,
the odds are
if
all
equal
he has a chance to win the most. Suppose the odds
are equal with respect to the truth or falsity of the Christian reli-
gion. Suppose truth:
I
I
place
my
wager
give myself over to
pay no heed
to the
demands
duties that can procure for
my
gain or
from gion
all
my
loss in
all
first
on
its falsity
of the Christian
me
or
my
if I
net gain,
and find
when compared with
its
and
perform the
I
Now we
each instance:
nothing
life,
eternal salvation.
the painful duties of the Christian
is false, is
and then on
the pleasures of concupiscence
compute
free myself
that the reli-
the eternal salvation
I38 that
I
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY can obtain by leading a Christian
true. Since the odds favoring falsity are
to place
presumed
my
to
wager on
be equal, its
truth.
it
is
Man
life
and finding
that
obviously to is
my
it
will
make you
believe
and
work
of
God
and
"Take
will stupefy you." Pascal
was not concerned with transforming human nature, the
its
advantage
a creature of custom
imagination. True religion must also become a custom.
holy water;
it is
and the odds favoring
truth
its
alone and of his grace.
He
for this
is
sought simply to
bring to light the points through which Christian truth could gain access to this corrupt
and decayed nature. For
not the art of demonstration (as
we noted
this
purpose he used
earlier,
the proofs of
religion are for believers), but the art of persuasion, adjusted to
the hearer's disposition conviction, since
men
and "based
are governed
as
much on
more by
acquiescence as on
caprice than by reason."
Bibliography Texts Pascal, Blaise. (Euvres completes. Edited
by L. Brunschvicg,
P. Boutroux,
and
F. Gazier. 14 vols. Paris, 1904-14.
(Euvres completes. Edited by J. Chevalier. Paris, i960. (Euvres completes. Edited by L. Lafuma. Paris, 1963. Thoughts, Letters, and Opuscules. Translated by O.
.
.
.
W.
Wright.
Boston, 1888.
The Great Shorter Wor\s
.
J.
of Pascal. Translated
C. Blankenagel. Philadelphia, 1948. Pensees and The Provincial Letters. Translated by .
New
T. McCrie.
York, 1941. Pensees. Translated by H. F. Stewart. 2d ed.
.
Cailliet
and
F. Trotter
and
by E.
W.
New York,
1965.
Studies M. Pascal: The Life of Genius. New York, 1936. Blanchet, L. "L'attitude religieuse des Jesuites et les sources
Bishop,
Revue de metaphysique
du
pari de Pascal,"
de morale, 1919. Boutroux, E. Pascal. Translated by E. M. Clark. Manchester, 1902. Brunschvicg, L. Le genie de Pascal. Paris, 1924. .
et
Pascal. Rieder, 1932.
Blaise Pascal. Edited by G. Lewis. Paris, 1953.
.
Cailliet, E. Pascal:
Chevalier, .
J.
The Emergence
of Genius.
2d
ed. Gloucester, Mass., 1961.
Pascal. Paris, 1922.
"La methode de connaitre d'apres Pascal," Revue de metaphysique,
1923.
Fletcher, F. T.
H. Pascal and the Mystical Tradition. Oxford,
Giraud, V. Pascal, .
Vhomme,
1954.
I'oeuvre, I'influence. Fribourg, 1898.
"La modernite des Pensees de Pascal," Annales de philosophic
chretienne, 1906. -.
Blaise Pascal, etudes d'histoire morale. Paris, 1910.
Goldmann,
L. Correspondance de Martin
Paris, 1956. .
The Hidden God. London,
Hatzfeld, A. Pascal. Paris, 190 1.
139
1963.
de Barcos, abbe de Saint-Cyran.
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
140
A.,
Jolivet,
Romeyer, and
B.
J.
Souilhe.
on
Studies
Pascal.
Archives de
philosophic 1923. Jovy, E. Etudes pascaliennes. 5 vols. Paris, 1927-28. Lacombe, R. E. L'apologetique de Pascal, etude critique. Paris, 1958. Lahorgue, P. M. Le realisme de Pascal. Paris, 1924. Laporte,
J.
"Pascal et la doctrine de Port-Royal,"
Revue de metaphysique,
1923.
he
.
coeur et la raison selon Pascal. Paris, 1950.
Lhermet, J. Pascal et la Bible. Paris (no date). Maire, A. Bibliographic generate des ceuvres de Pascal. 5 vols. Paris, 1928. L'oeuvre scientifique de Blaise Pascal. Paris, 1912. Malvy, A. Pascal et le probleme de la croyance. Paris, 1923. Mesnard, J. Pascal: His Life and Wor\s. New York, 1952. Mortimer, Ernest. Blaise Pascal: The Life and Wor\ of a Realist. New York .
1959.
Rauh, F. "La philosophie de Pascal," Revue de metaphysique, 1923. Ravaisson, F. "La philosophie de Pascal," Revue des deux-mondes, 1887. Russier,
J.
La
Souriau, P.
foi selon Pascal. 1 vols. Paris, 1949.
L ombre de Dieu. Paris,
Stewart, H. F.
The
1955.
Secret of Pascal. Cambridge, 194 1.
Strowski, F. Pascal et son temps. 3 vols. Paris, 1907-9. Vinet, A. Etudes sur Pascal. 2d ed. Paris, 1856.
Webb,
C. Pascal's Philosophy of Religion. Oxford, 1929.
Blaise Pascal,
I'homme
Paris, 1956.
et l'oeuvre.
(Cahiers de Royaumont, Philosophie,
I.)
THOMAS HOBBES born in 1588
He
son of a clergyman.
become private onshire).
He
fruit of this period
A
second
quam
sit
Oxford in 1608
his pupil to
France and
to
Italy in 1610
until 1628, the year of his death.
was
the
William Cavendish (Lord Dev-
The
only
Thucydides, of which
his translation of
later in his versified
visit to
Thomas Hobbes was
the University of
left
accompanied
ostendit mihi
Westport,
tutor to the son of
and remained near him he was to say
at
autobiography: "Is democratia
inepta."
France lasted from 1629 until 1631. Not until
then did he become acquainted with Euclid's Elements, which was to serve thereafter as his
1634 to 1637, brought
model.
him
A
third visit to the continent,
into contact with
Mersenne and
from
all his
learned associates in Paris, and with Galileo near Florence. In 1640 he wrote
The Elements
Law, Natural and
of
Politic, the first
formulation of his philosophical and political system. In 1650 the
manuscript was published, without his approval,
works
{Human Nature and De
whole was not published
corpore politico).
as
two separate
The work
as a
until 1889.
In 1640, believing that he was in danger because of his royalist convictions, he fled to France,
was crowned kind of the Scots Paris in 1642
and Leviathan
eight years of his
life
141
in
where he resided in 1651.
in 1651.
He
During
England he spent
until Charles II
published
De
ciue in
the remaining twenty-
his energies in polemics
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
I42
with theologians, scholars, and politicians: with John Bramhall, the
whom
Arminian bishop of Londonderry, against
he upheld the
who
doctrine of determinism; with the mathematician John Wallis, in his Elenchus geometriae hobbianae (1655)
the mathematical errors in
De
with the physicist Robert Boyle,
who was
Hobbes because
Society, closed to
a
examined
ruthlessly
same
corpore, published the
member
year;
of the Royal
of his aversion to experience;
Edward Hyde and several bishops who accused "for making the Church dependent on he said by way of justification. He died in 1679.
with Chancellor
him the
and heresy
of atheism
Crown,"
as
Hobbes gave the following account of the ical investigations at
the time he published
already advanced far
enough
In the
dealt with bodies
first
of these
in the second faculties,
I
and
I
to divide
man from
studied
his affections;
and
for meditation the social polity
The
was
state of his
De
my work and
:
"I
had
into three sections.
their general properties;
a particular point of view, his
in the last part,
and the
used
I
duties of those
it.
first
philosophy and some elements of physics; here
that the first part included
as a basis
who com-
what
pose
result
philosoph-
cive (1642)
I
is
called
tried
to
discover the reasons for time, place, causes, powers, relation, proportion, quantity, figure,
memory,
imagination,
honesty, dishonesty,
homine, and plan
fails to
De
and motion. In the second
intellect,
I
considered
reason, appetite, will, good, evil,
and other things of
this sort."
De
corpore,
cive are the titles of the three sections.
give any indication of the
thought was actually shaped.
manner
He had
in
But
De this
which Hobbes's
no idea of presenting a
when he composed The Elements of Law, Natural and Politic in 1640. In this political treatise, which covers the same ground as De cive, he makes no reference systematic outline of his philosophy
at all to the first
had begun political
to
two
parts of his philosophy. Finally, although he
conceive and execute his general plan after 1640,
circumstances caused
before he published the
De homine
(still
the preface to
De
first
him
to publish
two
parts:
fragmentary) in 1658. cive that "there
De
cive in 1644, long
De corpore in And he stated
was no danger in
1655,
and
plainly in
this reversal
THOMAS HOBBES
143
of the order, for principles,
it
was
which are
no need of the
first
The common
clear that this part,
two
own
its
had
experience,
parts."
link between his physics
and deductive
constructive
grounded on
known through
sufficiently
and
his politics
his
is
In each of the two areas Hobbes
spirit.
begins by defining precisely the terms or notions that he will use
order that
in
may be
consequences subsequently
all
through simple reasoning. Philosophy
we
or appearances, as
is
acquire by true ratiocination
ratiocinationem) from the knowledge
we have
first
(per rectam
and again, of such causes or generations
from knowing
their effects."
by which we Still,
know
and ...
things]
the
against empirical
may
be
empiricist: "Sense [is] the principle
those principles [by
all
as
1
Hobbes was an
course,
effects
of their causes
or generation;
Of
explained
"such knowledge of
which we know
knowledge we have
is
knowledge based on the
other
all
derived from
it."
2
association of ideas
and on the expectation of a future conforming
to
the past
and
suggesting prudence, he set purely rational knowledge in the form
wisdom
of
or science. Such rational
knowledge begins with the
use of signs, which are the words of our language. appellation
...
to bring to his
is
the voice of a
man
arbitrarily
it is
words
truth, error, reasoning acquire
imposed."
proposition
the subject
is
meaning.
said to be true or false,
depending upon whether
and the predicate designate the same thing. "A
has three sides" means "this thing which has three angles
thing which has three sides."
tical to this
finally to link
same thing
we
use
two names by
as the first
numbers
things themselves. 1 2 3
in
two.
is
iden-
syllogism enables us
We
use
names
in our reasoning, just as
our calculations, without ever considering
That
is
317.
Elements of Law, chap,
A
triangle
virtue of a third that designates the
why,
Opera philosophica, ed. Molesworth, Ibid., p.
or
mark
mind some conception concerning the thing on 3 Thanks to speech and to speech alone, the
which
A
"A name
imposed, for a
v, sec. 2.
I,
in spite of the continual flux of 2.
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
144
we
experience, distinct
reach
definite,
knowledge
certain
that
is
quite
from empirical knowledge.
The philosophy
of nature outlined in
De
corpore might be called
"motionalism," according to one of Hobbes' recent interpreters:
"Hobbes
is
the philosopher of motion, just as Descartes
is
the
disregard logic) includes three parts:
first
philosopher of extension."
His philosophy
(if
we
4
philosophy, which shows the elements that comprise the notion of bodies, the theory of
motion {de rationibus motuum
we
tudinum), and physics. First explain mechanically the
way
human body and produce
consider physics,
et
which aims
which external bodies
in
perceptions
magnito
affect the
and related phenomena.
Affected by the motions of external objects, the senses are set in
motion, and their motion
is
transmitted by the brain to the heart;
here begins a reactive motion in the opposite direction; the onset (conatus) of the reactive motion in the heart
is
the basis of sensa-
tion. Sensible qualities, sounds, odors, tastes, etc. are
merely modi-
fications of the affected subject, not properties of things.
association of ideas, pleasure
We
and pain
Memory,
are connected with sensation.
have memory when the motion which produced sensation con-
tinues in the absence of an object,
between two
establishes a link
association
when
experience
sensitive motions, pleasure or pain
depending upon whether the flow of the blood
is
facilitated or
impaired by sensible impressions. Hobbes's physics
is
not, strictly speaking, a study of the external
laws of nature, as in Galileo and Descartes, but a mechanical theory of perception
composed
was intended on animal cepts,
and of mind. This was true from the time Hobbes work,
his first to
spirits
his Short Tract
show how
on First Principles, which
species given off
whose motions
by bodies act
locally
in turn constitute sensations, con-
and judgments.
Thus when we
see that in the first
two
parts of
De
corpore
Hobbes, under the influence of Galileo and Descartes, superimposed *Frithiof
Brandt,
hagen, 1928),
p.
378,
Thomas Hobbes' Mechanical Conception
of
Nature
(Copen-
THOMAS HOBBES
145
on
and motion,
his physics the study of general notions of bodies
we must
bear in
mind
that his
aim was not
to achieve a
compre-
hensive view of the universe but rather to lay a foundation for his
The
mechanical theory of mind.
notions of body
having no dependence on our thought,
is
which
("that,
coincident or co-extended
with some part of space"), space ("the phantasm of a thing existing without the mind simply"), and time ("the phantasm of before
and
after in
Descartes,
motion") are not very original.
always be at
to
remain
at
is
manner, whatsoever
like
it
is
it
to rest"
(p.
But he
115).
moved,
(like Galileo) that
to rectilinear
his
it
on
(p. 215).
By
made through
De
of motion,
the
same token, which
corpore he defined en-
the length of a point,
instant or a point of time." (Similarly, impetus instant.) Later, of course,
so far as to
that of conatus or endeavor,
is
his preoccupations. In
deavor as "motion
and went
applied to circular motion as well as
and uniform motion
most important concept
bears directly
is
and
first
this notion.
consisteth pleasure or pain," he wrote in
this solicitation is the
of animal motion." effort is
We
which
The Elements of Law draw near to
also a solicitation or provocation either to
the thing that pleaseth, or to retire
And
an
used the notion of conatus to
describe the motions of a living being. "This motion, in
(p. 22),
in
speed at a given
mathematicians exploited his infinitesimal
and Leibniz and Spinoza made use of
can be certain that Hobbes
is
will
which
it,
failed to realize the full sig-
nificance of the second part of the principle
assume
by
it,
no longer
always be moved, except there be some other body besides causeth
will
rest
besides
place by motion, suffers
its
... In
at rest.
stated clearly, after
some other body
unless there be
rest,
endeavoring to get into
He
"Whatsoever
the principle of inertia:
made on
He
from the thing
that displeaseth.
endeavor [conatus] or internal beginning
also applied the notion of conatus to the
the eye by the
one of the main points of
medium
that transmits light. This
his discussion
with Descartes on the
subject of optics. Descartes spoke of an "action or inclination to
motion" which he wished
to separate
from motion;
replied that "vision occurs through an action derived
to this
Hobbes
from an
object,
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
146
for any action to the eye."
5
the aggregate of
is
is
propagated from light
the endeavors through
all
body supported by the
of a
{De
and a motion
a motion,
is
Generalizing this notion, he concludes that "weight
The
corpore, p. 351).
which
His
it
cive
was published prematurely because of the use
might be put
at that
ple
rest.
with the emotions and concerns of his
politics is suffused
De
downward"
notion of conatus then introduces motion
everywhere, even where there appears to be absolute
era.
the points
all
scale of a balance tend
in
which
to
view of the conditions that existed in England
time (1642). "In England," he explains in his preface, "peo-
were beginning
engage in heated discussions concerning the
to
and the duty of
right of the sovereign
which began
subjects.
several years before the civil
These
presage of the misfortunes that threatened and assailed
Thus, since this last part
I
foresaw the conflagration,
and the two
communicated
it
I
parts that precede
were
fully justified
my
country.
hastened to complete it
a few years ago to only a small
persons." His fears
discussions,
wars broke out, were a
even though
number
had
I
of discreet
by the revolution that abol-
ished the throne (1648).
The
political thesis that
arch.
From
illegitimate.
Hobbes sought
was
construction of society thesis
it
thesis
had gained ascendancy
Hooker denied
power
on a
rational
I;
it
same stand when he made
is
England under
during the reign of Elizabeth the
that a political
or in part, sovereignty that
in
body could recapture,
in
whole
had once relinquished, and he held
that the principle extended even to spiritual power. James
the
mon-
of the
can be deduced that any revolution
this
The
Elizabeth and under James jurist
to establish
that of the absolute
this
I
took
statement concerning the divine
source of his authority: "Whatever relates to the mystery of regal
power ought not
to
be the subject of a debate; this would divest
princes of the mystical veneration that pertains to those seated at the throne of God."
obviously clashes at
all
The
who
are
divine-right theory of sovereignty
points with the theory of the social contract,
which was prevalent during the Middle Ages and which placed 5
"Tractatus Opticus," in
The Elements
of
Law,
ed. Tonnies, p.
171.
THOMAS HOBBES
147
everyone on an equal footing by attributing the birth of society to
an agreement between the people and the monarch. In 1606 the assembly of the Anglican clergy condemned those
"men roamed through woods and them
who
until experience taught
fields
some from
the necessity of government; that they then chose
among them
to
held that
govern the others, and that
power therefore
all
is
derived from the people."
The
novelty and originality of Hobbes's system derives from the
he supported absolutism and
fact that
to the theory of the social contract.
at the
same time subscribed
For he did not believe he could
construct society without the notion of a social contract, any
more
than he could explain the nature of intelligence without speech.
Nor
did he think that the social contract impaired absolutism in
any way.
when
On
the contrary, he believed that the social contract,
rightly interpreted, of necessity led to absolutism.
and
absolutist without being a theologian,
apart I to
from
we must examine
disposition to
we
This
man
most ferocious animals: "Man
Hobbes recognized
in
is
a wolf to
man was
right reason,
ever he
it
savage
we
call
and most right the
conformity to
to use his natural faculties in
man has by nature the right to do whathis own preservation, that is, to do or But at the same time reason shows man
follows that
deems good
for
possess whatever he likes.
that the right to to all other
as
man." The only
the simplest
elementary, the instinct of self-preservation. If
freedom each of us has
according to
false,
is
seeks in a civil society only
him, and people are by nature
to
Most
are born with a certain natural
societies.
that each
is
which seems good
instinct that
from James
the necessity of the social contract.
that
form human
Hobbes. The truth that
was an doctrine
6
political writers believe
as the
He
his
sets
that of the other absolutists of the century,
Bossuet.
First
this
all
things
men, who
is
of
no use
are his equals;
his right, the result will
if
to
him
each
be a war between
since
man all
XV, 436-41.
also belongs
men, which
trary to the preservation of all as well as of each. "Fifth warning to Protestants, ed. Lachat,
it
wishes to exercise
The
is
con-
experience of
I48 civil
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
wars shows that
omnium
bellum
this
contra
omnes
something imaginary but an ever present danger. Nature the instinct of self-preservation
us that for our
own
not
is
—that
is,
—guided by reason, therefore teaches
we must seek peace if it is attainwe must cease trying to exercise our Thus men are constrained by the law of
preservation
able; in our search for peace
own
right in
things.
all
nature and of reason to draw up contracts in which each of the
some
parties divests himself of full
in
freedom
common. Their
contract
is
pact or promise to observe the terms of the
one party has reason
—that
is,
both formerly held
motivated solely by the instinct of self-preservation.
follows that in the state of nature the pact if
and grants the other
of his rights
to exercise the natural right that
if
in
is
to believe that the other
own
he has reason to fear for his
is
of peace, natural
law obliges us
no way binding not observing
preservation.
since compliance with the terms of such contracts
It
is
it
Still,
the guarantee
them and to repay kindit commands us to
to observe
ness with kindness rather than ingratitude;
show clemency;
it
prohibits vengeance, cruelty, insult, pride;
commands moderation and
equity;
it
differences to impartial judges. All these laws are
some moral
instinct or universal consent
which searches for means of because they are conclusions
Reason shows that the
They
self-preservation.
drawn from
deduced not from
but from right reason
immutable
are
a process of reasoning.
nature and the accomplishment
state of
of natural laws are incompatible. In the state of nature
no motive
for respecting contracts,
antee of peace.
The
must therefore be
which
might
instilled in
result
men—fear
presumed advantage of exercising
men
have
are nevertheless the guar-
only motive for respecting contracts
of the consequences that
it
counsels us to submit our
from
is
the fear
their violation.
keen enough
Fear
to offset the
their natural right over all things.
That is precisely the problem which the social state must resolve, and the conditions of the problem will determine the character of this state.
Here reason alone
together in a civil society. is
why animal
societies
Men
are in
speaks, for
no
instinct
draws
are not like bees or ants,
men
and that
no way comparable, according
to
THOMAS HOBBES
149
Hobbes,
to civil societies
ment and
made up
of rational beings.
the voluntary consent of
who
is
believe they
and who, through
superfluous,
wars."
know more
follows that there
It
Mutual agree-
are too artificial
and
pre-
some
will always be
For "there
carious in nature to insure peace.
persons
all
than others, whose knowledge
their innovations, stir
must be
up
civil
a single will to control all
things necessary for peace: "This can be done only
if
each individ-
ual submits his will to that of another individual or an assembly
whose counsel absolutely
is
followed
who compose
the body
in matters concerning the general peace
and adopted
as that of all those
of the republic." Natural law, as
we have
seen, dictated that
should relinquish a part of our natural right to
and pushes
state generalizes
law, for
all
authority;
cause
all
The in
men
dictamen of natural
to the limit this
convey to the sovereign the right
to exercise his
and the sovereign acquires such strength
who would
those to tremble
sovereign, whether
which the majority
possession of rights.
it
is
confronted by no multitude in
The multitude if
that he can
break the bonds of concord.
be a single man, a king, or a council
decides,
of unified will or action:
we
things; the social
all
is
not a single subject capable
people do not join together to form
a social body, everything belongs to everyone;
if
they form a social
body, they transfer their natural rights to the sovereign. Conse-
quently the sovereign has the power to coerce, to punish, to war, to
make
laws.
He
wage
outlaws doctrines such as popery or even
many give to the him and which some bishops seek to usurp in their diocese," with the result that many wars break out. He is not himself subject to laws (and we recall
Presbyterianism because of "the authority which
pope in kingdoms that do not belong
that Chancellor
the state above is
to
Bacon had no scruples about all
law). Putting
the welfare of the people
it
another way, his supreme law
—protecting them
mies, promoting internal peace,
and
from a
to
This objection seems natural
it.
contract,
it
against external ene-
facilitating
But the objection might be raised that issues
setting the right of
if
commerce.
the sovereign
can be dissolved by those to those
who
who
power
are parties
seek to ground
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
15O
on nothing
regal authority it
less
than divine right, but in practice
Unanimous consent would be required
has no merit.
This can never be obtained, of course, and
dissolution.
men
number
of
and
are illegitimate.
Even an assembly
He
feared the ignorance of the
assembly with respect to internal
norance of external
affairs,
which can give and
ferred a king
ment
if
"The
folly of the
that deliberated in the
members of more their
still
remain
is
ig-
also
evil,
and
why he
pre-
good the appearance of
That
He
secret.
the
by the king, even though
public assemblies can be a legitimate govern-
its
individuals surrender their natural rights to the body politic.
of States"
One
to
rise to sedition.
a privy council selected
a democracy with
and
affairs
which ought
feared eloquence, which can give factionalism,
revolu-
all
was always suspect
in conformity to the laws
eyes of Hobbes.
its
through the deliberation of a small
tions that are accomplished
publicly
for
(De
people and eloquence contribute to the subversion
cive,
ii,
12, 13).
serious difficulty inherent in his doctrine
between the sovereign and
relation
designate a
power
distinct
from
civil
religion.
remains: the
still
Does not
sovereignty
—a
religion
power
that
exercises complete control over everything relating to eternal salva-
tion? In Hobbes's time such a distinction
was not only a
subject
for discussion but also the cause of serious conflicts all over Europe.
dogma
God
"There
is
human
sciences that does not give rise to dissensions, then to quar-
almost no
rels, to insults,
mas
and
finally to wars.
are false but because
ing a certain
relating to the worship of
man
as
wisdom and wants it
all
liefs
and
his
others to hold is
him
in equally
the concern of the sovereign
threatens civil peace. But even Hobbes, bold
indefatigable arguer that he was, radical solution
This happens, not because dog-
by nature prides himself on possess-
high esteem." Clearly, then, religion
inasmuch
or to
—to
was reluctant
to
permit the sovereign to impose his
own form
and
advocate one
own
of worship on everyone. "I do not see
be-
why
he would allow anyone to teach and do things which in his judg-
ment would
entail eternal
wish
entangled in resolving this
to get
damnation," says Hobbes; "but difficulty."
The
I
do not
difficulty
THOMAS HOBBES
151
in a country like England,
was indeed great
governed Protestant
Though he
subjects.
where Catholic kings
disregarded the individual
opinion of the sovereign, he nevertheless asserted that the state
form of worship,
institute a unique, obligatory
the most
must
"for otherwise all
absurd opinions relating to the Divinity
and
all
the most
impertinent and ridiculous ceremonies that have ever been seen
would be found was
in a single
The
only restriction he imposed
must not obey a sovereign who commands him
that a subject
God and
to revile
city.'*
to
worship instead a
man on whom
he has con-
ferred divine attributes.
But (since
was the Christian
his only concern
religion)
do we not
have, either in the Decalogue or in the evangelical precepts, obligatory laws
Here a
which have
logue are
a different source
civil laws, for
makes no
same condition civil
laws that
commandment such
We
"Thou
sense until laws have defined property,
sin, justice,
and
find in the Gospel
yours and what
is
as
Thus it come into
applies to all the others. injustice
the precepts of the Gospel, they are not laws at faith.
that of civil laws?
Moses possessed temporal sovereignty over
the Jews. Furthermore, a steal"
from
must be made: the commandments of the Deca-
distinction
is
no
all,
is
shall
not
and the
only through
existence.
As
for
but an appeal to
rule that allows us to discern
mine, no standard that serves
what
as a basis for
regulating exchange. Therefore the sovereign alone must establish
what
is
just
and what
is
unjust.
In short, the basis of religious harmony, which social
harmony,
raries thought,
is
but conformity.
the same, the
(1651)
is
by the
state
and
critical attitude
is
necessary for
many of Hobbes's contempoThough the doctrine of Leviathan
not tolerance, as
title
refers to the gigantic
reveals even
more
toward the Church.
clearly than
He
was
power represented
De
cive Hobbes's
so critical, in fact, that
even though he could pass for the stanchest supporter of the royalist
cause, he
had
to
break with the English royalist party, which
counted on the Anglican church to insure Hobbes's "naturalism" in as his "materialism."
its
success.
political matters
Both are expressed in
is
essentially the
his rationalism,
same
which
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
152 consists
enough
in
reducing "nature" to elements simple and tractable
them
for us to use
storing concrete realities
and
self-preservation
:
in a process of deduction capable of re-
body and motion on the one hand,
instinct
Hobbes required nothing
else for
on the
other.
the construction of his system of physics
seventeenth century," said Nietzsche, therefore of will."
No
"is
and of
politics.
the century of reason
one provides better
justification
idea than Hobbes: he was the logician of politics, the tried
with
unequaled determination
but he was also
—a passionate ated
man who
—and
this
man who
"The
to
untangle
for
and this
man who
incoherencies;
accounts for the severe beauty of
De ewe
could dominate his passions, an opinion-
could examine even his most cherished opinions in
the light of clear reason.
Bibliography Texts
W.
Hobbes, Thomas. Wor\s. Edited by
Molesworth. 16
vols.
London, 1839-
45.
Selections. Edited
by F.
E.
J.
Woodbridge. Reprinted:
New
York,
1959. .
.
.
La
Body, Man, and Citizen. Edited by R. S. Peters. New York, 1962. The Elements of Law, Edited by F. Tonnies. 2d ed. Cambridge, 1928. The Metaphysical System of Hobbes. Edited by M. W. Calkins. 2d ed.
Salle,
The
.
111.,
1948.
Citizen.
Edited by
S.
P.
Lamprecht.
New
ed.
New
York,
1962. .
Leviathan. Edited by Michael Oakeshott. Oxford, 1946.
Studies Bowie,
Hobbes and His Critics: London, 1951.
J.
A
Study of Seventeenth-century Con-
stitutionalism.
Thomas Hobbes' Mechanical Conception of Nature. London, 1928. Thomas Hobbes. Kiel, 1895. Dewey, John. The Political Philosophy of Hobbes. (Studies in the History Brandt, F.
Brandt, G. Grundlinien der Philosophic von of Ideas, Vol.
Gough, ed.
J.
W. The
I.)
New York,
19 18.
Social Contract:
A
Critical
Study of
Its
Development. Rev.
Oxford, 1956.
Honigswald, R. "Uber Thomas Hobbes' systematische Stellung," Kantstudien,
XIX
(1914).
Hobbes und die Staatsphilosophie. Munich, 1934. Hood, F. C. The Divine Politics of Thomas Hobbes. New York, Laird, J. Hobbes. London, 1934. .
1964.
Landry, B. Hobbes. Paris, 1930. Levi, A. La filosofia di Tommaso Hobbes. Milan, 1929. Lyon, G. La philosophic de Hobbes. Paris, 1893.
Macdonald, H., and M. Hargreaves. Thomas Hobbes:
A
Bibliography. London,
1952.
Macpherson, C. B. The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism: Hobbes to Loc\e. A/ew York, 1962. Mintz, S. I. The Hunting of Leviathan. London, 1962.
153
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
154
Peters, R. S.
Hobbes. London, 1956.
Polin, R. Politique et philosophic chez
Thomas Hobbes.
Paris, 1952.
Robertson, G. C. Hobbes. London, 1886. Sortais,
G. La philosophic moderne depuis Bacon jusqu'a Leibniz. 3 Vol II, Hobbes.
vols.
Paris, 1920-29.
Stephen, Leslie. Hobbes. London, 1904. Strauss, Leo.
New
The
Political
Philosophy of Hobbes. Translated by E. Sinclair.
ed. Chicago, 1963.
Thomas Hobbes. London, 1908. Thomas Hobbes: Leben und Lehre. 3d ed. Stuttgart, 1925. Warrender, Howard. The Political Philosophy of Hobbes. Oxford, 1957. Taylor, A. E.
Tonnies, F.
Watkins,
J.
Zagorin, P.
W. N. Hobbes' s System
A
of Ideas.
London,
1954.
Hobbes
1965.
History of Political Thought in the English Revolution. London,
Studies. Edited
by K. Brown. Oxford, 1965.
I VI} SPINOZA i
Life,
Background, and Wor\s the circumstances
relating to the life
and back-
ground of Spinoza are complex. Born into the Jewish community in
Amsterdam, he was influenced by
details of
which are
his religious heritage, certain
particularly interesting.
He
descended from
Portuguese Jews who, along with their Spanish brothers, settled in
Amsterdam toward
brought with them a in the Netherlands.
who were of 1492 but
the
Most
compelled
end of the sixteenth century. They
spirit quite different
to
of
from
that of the Jews
them descended from Marranos
—men
embrace Catholicism by Ferdinand's
who remained Jews
at heart.
Under
edict
these circumstances
the traditional teaching of their religion was denied
them and they
knew nothing about Hebrew or the Talmudic commentaries on the Bible. In Amsterdam they found a community in which the mysticism of the Cabala was studied almost exclusively and the profane sciences were neglected. This explains the dissension that existed
among
the Jews in
Amsterdam throughout the first half who knew logic, metaphysics,
of the seventeenth century; those
and medicine da Costa,
resisted rabbinical instruction.
who was born
Holland around
went
161 5,
so far as to write that "the
'55
One
such man, Uriel
Oporto in 1585 and emigrated to denied the immortality of the soul and in
law of Moses
is
a
human
inven-
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
156
found between
tion" because of the contradictions that he
it
and
"natural law."
Baruch Spinoza (1632-1677) was the son of a Jewish merchant of
Amsterdam; he received provided for classes
all
the intensive but purely Hebraic training successive
devoted to the learning of Hebrew, the reading of the Books
of Moses, Kings,
Talmud.
He
and the Prophets, and
prepared himself for the
his studies after leaving school.
and
community: seven
the children of the
certain
Crescas,
Jewish
whom
rabbi and continued
office of
Thus he
philosophers
finally the study of the
learned about the Cabala
Middle Ages. Hasdai
the
of
he cited once in his Letters (Ep. XII), taught in the
God
fourteenth century that the perfection of
consists not in
knowl-
edge but in love and that the perfection of a creature depends on his
participation
in
this
love;
this
doctrine,
closely to the beliefs of the Franciscans,
which corresponds
the one found at the end
is
may have been alluding to Maimonides or to a commentator on the Zohar when he spoke of ancient Hebrews who saw that God, his understanding, and the object of this of Spinoza's Ethics. Spinoza
understanding were identical {Ethics,
came
into possession
ii,
of the Plotinian
7,
scholium).
thesis
Thus he
of the identity
of
thought, the thinking subject, and the object conceived.
The
son and grandson of wealthy merchants, he directed the
family business from 1654 to 1656. Excluded from the Jewish com-
munity by the
civil authorities
(and
not, as
it
is
often alleged, by
Amsterdam and went The Hague, where he
the Jewish theologians), he left short time later he
went
to
to Leiden.
lived
on
A
his
earnings as a lens grinder and perhaps on the income from his commercial enterprise
if it is true, as is
after his departure to operate
fore his cles
it
now
believed, that he continued
through an intermediary. Even be-
excommunication he had begun
to
frequent Christian
where he found teachers who introduced him
sciences, as well as friends
and
disciples.
The
cir-
to the profane
physician
Van den
Enden taught him physics, geometry, and Cartesian philosophy. Van den Enden was an adept in the theosophy prevalent in Italy and Germany during the Renaissance and the seventeenth century
SPINOZA
157
which held
that nothing existed apart
from God. Through him
Spinoza became acquainted with Bruno who, a century
had
and the
asserted the unity of substance
and who made a statement
nature,
"The
place in Spinoza's Ethics: attributes,
The
and one of these
Christians with
dependent
traits
noted
is
earlier,
God and
would hardly seem out of
principle
first
attributes
whom
that
identity of
is
infinite in all its
extension."
he associated exhibited the two
earlier:
Christianity
almost
inter-
divested
of
dogma and a spirit of complete tolerance. Briefly, their Christianity was more practical than speculative and put more stress on living according to the precepts of the Gospel than on speculating about the nature of God.
The Mennonites,
for example,
who had
already
been in existence for a century, abstained from any form of violence
and refused
to participate in war, to
assume a public
office,
or to
take an oath; furthermore, they rejected the priesthood and sacra-
ments
—even
baptism
—and
denied
all
dogmas except
the Trinity,
the divine sonship of Christ, and salvation through Christ.
known
as the Collegiants,
among whom Spinoza found
The
sect
friends like
Simon de Vries and Jan Bredenburg, a weaver of Rotterdam, was founded by Jan, Adrian, and Gilbert van der Kodde, after the Synod of Dort (1618-19), on the belief that the Holy Ghost was revealed to every pious man and that there was no need of theologians to interpret the Bible. They were also tolerant enough to accept into their fellowship the Catholics
Such a
members from groups
as divergent as
and the Socinians.
practical
form of Christianity
left
the field open to
gious speculations independent of dogmatic theology. In his veritate
religionis
christianae
(1687)
Philip
reli-
De
van Limborch used
eternal salvation as a basis for classifying the diverse opinions of his era
and he divided
these opinions into three groups: those of
the Christians, those of the Jews, and those of people he called atheists or deists. "I
put these two together," he wrote, "not because
the words 'atheist' and
'deist'
have the same meaning but because
most of the time deism hardly
who
call
differs
from atheism, and those
themselves deists are generally atheists inwardly; both
158
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
refuse to
acknowledge God, or
into a natural, necessary agent
and in
this
certain rule of life or, if they
way
completely subvert
any revelation, they have
religion; furthermore, since they reject
no
change him
at the very least they
have one,
no more perfect
is
it
than the rule deduced from the principles of nature." With obvious malice Philip van Limborch included in this naturalism
which were independent
lations concerning salvation
theology
had no
which
and
Spinozism.
The
an
evidenced
consequently
Collegian ts,
who met
specu-
all
of dogmatic affinity
with
twice a year in Rijnsburg,
scruples about discussing the supernatural character of the
mission of Jesus, the authority of Scripture, or the reality of miracles.
Indeed,
it
is
the
possibility
of
such free speculation, accom-
panied by the practice of Christian virtues independently of any formal confession of
that Spinoza himself, in his Political
faith,
Treatise, asks the public authorities to secure for all
Descartes
left to
salvation
and
to
the theologians the task of dealing with eternal the princes the
allotting to each a distinct sphere, all
members
sophical,
men. Whereas
management
of public affairs,
Spinoza follows the practice of
of his milieu in affirming the radical unity of philo-
and
religious,
political
problems.
His
philosophy,
as
expressed in the Ethics, contains a theory of society and concludes
with a theory of salvation through philosophical knowledge. His Theologicopolitical
served for
Treatise
men who do
indicates
the paths
of
salvation
re-
not go beyond obedience to the prescrip-
tions of positive religions. Finally, his Political Treatise describes
an
organization of the state that leaves freedom of thought to each
man; and we know
that Spinoza,
actively in public affairs,
though he did not
participate
was an ardent supporter of Jan de Witt,
whose government guaranteed such tolerance
until 1672, the year
of the Orangist triumph.
Spinoza carefully avoided everything that might alienate his dependence. Admired by the great Conde,
him
in Utrecht during the
of a pension
and residence
campaign of in France.
who
1673,
invited
him
in-
to visit
he refused the offer
The same
year the Palatinate
SPINOZA
159
elector, Princess Elizabeth's brother, offered
him
a chair at Heidel-
berg University, where he could freely teach his philosophy; again
he refused.
should be noted that his delicate health must have
It
placed severe limitations on his activity; tuberculosis, with which
he seems
His
life,
to
which was
an
that of
have been
ascetic;
afflicted, necessitates
so orderly, so moderate,
was
it
much and
that of an invalid for
rest
and calm.
so simple,
whom
was not
health
is
a
age of forty-four, he died.
priceless possession. In 1677, at the
Spinoza wrote two general expositions of his philosophy: the Short Treatise on God, Man, and His Well-Being, which he wrote
and which has survived through
in Latin for his friends (1660)
two Dutch
translations;
and
his Ethics
Demonstrated according
to
the Geometrical Order
(Ethica or dine geometrico demonstratd)
which he attempted
complete on several occasions.
suggested in differs
letters
to
written in 1661 to Oldenburg and
from the order followed
version,
and
in
,
The
order
De
Vries
in the first part of the published
1665 he had almost completed the work, which
then contained only three parts. But between 1670 and 1675 he revised the third part lished version
—the
two
expositions,
De
emendatione
and made
it
the last three parts of the pub-
Passions, Slavery,
Spinoza wrote a intellectus,
and Freedom. Besides
treatise (unfinished)
before 1662.
The
these
on method,
Theologicopolitical
was written between 1665 and 1670, and the Political Treatise (unfinished) between 1675 and 1677. Many years earlier, Treatise
between 1656 and
1663,
he had written Renati Descartes principia
philosophiae, an exposition of Cartesian philosophy for the use of
a pupil. Cogitata metaphysica, which explains the terms used in
philosophy, dates from the same period.
During
his lifetime
Spinoza
published only Principles of Cartesian Philosophy, with the Cogita as
an appendix (1663), and the Theologicopolitical Treatise (1670). But his Opera postuma which appeared as early as 1677, included Ethics, the treatise Political Treatise,
On
the
Improvement
of the Understanding, the
and an important body of correspondence which
unfortunately was revised and softened by his friends.
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
l6o
The Improvement
ii
No
of the Understanding
other doctrine has aroused as
Few
tion as Spinoza's.
more
ent ways and judged poraries Spinoza
much enthusiasm and
indigna-
more
others have been interpreted in
contem-
diversely. In the eyes of his
final causes,
and
Holy Word,
the
was the denier of Providence, of
of free will, the critic of the authority of the
differ-
author of a pantheism in which the individual founders.
As
is fre-
quently the case, his contemporaries were struck by the negations of his system rather than by
its
which are nevertheless
affirmations,
their counterparts.
Taken
as a
whole, the Spinozist doctrine
through knowledge of God.
The end
is
a doctrine of salvation
of philosophy
to "search
is
good which can be imparted and of which the discovery
for a
insure throughout eternity possession of lasting
Thus
does not at
it
of Descartes
first
and supreme
will joy."
appear to be in line with the philosophies
and Bacon, who relegated
question of the ultimate end of
to the sphere of faith the
man. Spinozism bears an
external
resemblance to the Neo-Platonic theosophies that have flourished
throughout history. Spinoza's
first
step
the
is
same
many who
as that of
theorized
on the love of God during the Middle Ages: "All these passions (sadness, envy, fear, hate) things.
are our lot
But love that goes out
to
when we
love perishable
something eternal and
infinite
nourishes the soul with pure joy
—a
These words are the same
found in the Imitation of Christ
(ii,
7.1)
:
"Qui adhaeret
Jesum firmabitur
in
as those
creaturae, cadet,
joy
cum
is
does not belong to ing,
labili;
qui amplectitur
aevum." In the sixteenth century Leone Hebreo
used these words to explain the nature of
"Although love
untainted by sadness."
also
higher kind of love:
found in corporeal and material things,
them
and every other
this
alone; but just as being,
life,
perfection, goodness, or beauty
depend upon
spiritual beings
and descend from immaterial things
things, so love
found
is
first
and
it
understandto material
essentially in the purely conceptual
—
SPINOZA
l6l
world and descends from there tical
problem posed
the Understanding
at the
world of bodies."
beginning of
On
same one which
the
is
to the
the
1
The
prac-
Improvement
of
resolved in the last
is
propositions of the Ethics. All the rest of Spinoza's philosophy leads to the
same
And
propositions.
yet Spinoza
is
removed from the atmosphere of vague
far
experiences, devotion, asceticism, ciated with divine love.
then, one
"Love
it
rests
all else,
a
in such a
without error and as perfectly
as possible." Its
mented. Here Spinoza's point of departure Cartesian method: there
traditionally asso-
on knowledge. Before
way of healing the understanding and way that it will know things successfully,
must think of
of purifying
and enthusiasm
power must be augmeditation on the
is
a methodical chain of truths that begins
is
with clear and distinct ideas and manifests the unrestricted fecundity of the understanding
physics.
Opposing
knowledge any
this
through the creation of mathematics and
chain are the disconnected fragments of
come from
that
spiritual initiative.
the senses
Spinoza
is
and the imagination, without
also a Cartesian
in direct contrast to the Neo-Platonists, that the
when he assumes, human mind can-
not ascend by degrees from knowledge of sensible things to intellectual
knowledge,
immediate
from an image
intellectual
sage in the
and
the lowest level
from the day of
my
to
its
model, but must achieve
knowledge. This theme
Improvement
various classes
At
as
in
is
found in the pas-
which he divides knowledge
retains only those that will serve his purpose. is
knowledge by hearsay, knowledge
birth and, in a general way,
thing that comes to
me from
tradition;
that
I
dental comparison of similar occurrences are mortal for example; then effect
—from
the union of soul
—
knowledge of every-
this
is
how
comes knowledge that
I
I
acci-
know men
have of cause
the fact of sensation, for instance,
I
deduce
and body. These three kinds of knowledge
juxtaposed to one another, inert, and an end to themselves 1
have
next comes knowledge
based upon undisciplined experience, knowledge coming from
through
into
— are
Quoted by H. Pflaum, Die Idee der Liebe bei Leone Hebreo (Tubingen, 1926),
p. 105.
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
l62
power of the
rejected because they will not serve to increase the
understanding. Quite different
is
knowledge through which an
deduced from a cause: from
effect is
its
definition
properties of a figure, for example. Quite different too
knowledge
intuitive
edge
is
that
deduce the the certain,
have of certain propositions. Such knowl-
I
The merchant who
truly productive.
1 is
applies the rule that
he has been taught (hearsay) in order to find the fourth propor-
when
tional
who, having
three terms are given, or
successfully
carried out the operation in simple cases, applies the process that
he has discovered to more complicated cases (undisciplined experience), arrives at the quantity to be discovered or at a result as
who demonstrates a rule (knowledge or the man who intuitively apprehends that when the terms given are i, 2, and 3. But
surely as the mathematician of effect through cause)
the
number sought
is
6
no
the merchant goes
further,
whereas a Descartes, by meditating
on proportionals, discovers the means of resolving equations of a higher degree.
From tain
Descartes Spinoza also learned that the acquisition of cer-
knowledge precedes the discovery
natural
—through
force
harm each
of a method.
other," according to Descartes
—the
on the
knowledge. The in the theses
essentials of these
of the
method
attainment of
expends
its
advanced in the Improvement. Just
can advance
it
more
its
search.
perfectly, so the
Method does not precede it
new
as the artisan first
follows them.
hammer
understanding
native strength in forging instruments with
effective intellectual procedures;
is
developments are incorporated
beats iron with natural instruments before fabricating a
with which he can forge
its
understanding spon-
new knowledge; the basis order that has made possible the
taneously discovers reflection
Through
and deduction "which cannot
intuition
which
investigation It is
it
and
knowledge
we know things through ideas before we know we know them. The idea of the circle is knowledge of a thing
of knowledge, for that
that has a center
and a periphery, but the idea
center nor periphery itself;
consequently
and
we
is
can
something quite
know
itself
from the circle knowing the idea
distinct
a circle without
has neither
SPINOZA
163
of a circle.
on the
in turn,
is
but the idea of the idea, that
is,
is
an instru-
or a standard for acquiring further knowledge.
Here we
reflection
ment
The method,
true idea to the degree that the idea
new
have everything that separates the to things themselves,
and a perpetual
analyses of concepts
spirit,
which goes
from ancient philosophy, which dialectic
directly
with
rests
based on opinions.
The method of the Rules is complemented by the doubt of the Meditations. The method begins with natural certainties immanent in the mind and shows through the rule of order how these certainties can engender new knowledge. Doubt searches for a sure means
and
of excluding everything uncertain,
it
the apparatus of methodical doubt, the Cogito
according to Descartes,
is
Spinoza abandons Descartes
ing to him, contain their
own
tive essence of a thing," that
understanding; fail to
it
work,
the thing as
is,
clearly
and
dis-
at this point: true ideas, accord-
certainty; certainty
follows that the
know
his
indispensable in preparing the will to
which the understanding perceives
assent to that
cannot
and the guarantee
God. The whole of the second part of
of certainty through
tinctly.
employs, besides
mind
that they are true;
only "the objec-
represented in the
in possession of true ideas
no
reach them, and they require no guarantee. fictitious ideas (idea ficta), false ideas,
it is
is
truly sincere
We
doubt can
need only identify
or doubtful ideas in order to
avoid confusing them with true ideas.
The
distinction
between true ideas and other ideas
tion of Spinozism, just as the doctrine of true
natures
is
mind can
substance, or extension, the
forge ideas such as those of God,
whole structure of Ethics would
difficulty
when he wrote
be assumed that after
we have
forged the idea of a thing and
stated freely
and voluntarily that
are unable to conceive of
it
it
and "compromising
fidence grounded?
A
its
as existing otherwise."
own
fictitious
these lines: "It
actually exists in nature, then
not disconcerted by the "absurdity" of a itself
col-
Spinoza foresaw the
lapse.
we
the founda-
the foundation of Cartesianism. If there were the slight-
est suspicion that the
may
is
and immutable
freedom."
idea
is
Spinoza was
mind being deluded by
On
what was
his con-
identified primarily
by
its
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
164
We
indetermination. or not existing;
we
can arbitrarily imagine
object as existing
its
can arbitrarily attribute such and such a predi-
known to us imperfectly —for example, we can imagine that the mind is square; the fictive idea is the idea that permits an alternative. But if we possess the true idea of a being, indetermination disappears. To anyone who knew the entire a being whose nature
cate to
is
course of nature the existence of a being
who knew
or an impossibility, and anyone
could not suppose
A
conceives
its
example,
is
the nature of the
class.
It its
mind
attributes
to
a subject a
mind manner. Doubt
nature because the
nature only in a confused, indistinct
from
springs
same
not deduced from
is
either a necessity
be square.
in the
false idea is
predicate that
to
it
would be
Descartes' celebrated hypothetical doubt, for
error.
possible only because of a belief in the possible existence
of a deceitful
God.
A
on
true idea,
the contrary,
is
a completely
determinate idea that contains the cause of everything that can be stated or denied concerning
its
object.
For
instance, in the
a worker the idea of a well regulated mechanism
when
the relation between
though the mechanism idea
not
is
its
may
parts
its
is
is
mind
of
a true idea
conceived distinctly even
not be realized.
What
constitutes a true
correspondence with an external reality but
its
"in-
trinsic character."
Here Spinoza to
form, of
ideas
itself,
is
thinking of the power of the understanding
true ideas in mathematics.
which could only be true
be wholly determinate It
since,
—extension,
It
begins with simple
being simple, they have to
quantity, motion, for example.
forms complex ideas by linking simple ideas
sphere, for example, circle
around
its
which has
its
diameter. Each such idea
and the mind never has
essence,
—the
idea of the
origin in the rotation of a semi-
to pass
is
a wholly determinate
through universal, abstract
axioms.
But
is
tion of is
not the power of the understanding limited to the produc-
mathematics?
Is it
not here and here alone that the
mind
a "spiritual automaton" acting in accordance with the laws of the
understanding, whereas in knowledge of nature
it
"has the condi-
SPINOZA
165
tion of a patient" subject to the senses
and
to "the operations that
give rise to images produced in accordance with laws quite differ-
ent from the laws of the understanding"? In short,
any knowl-
is
edge of nature reached through the understanding? Methodical
problem
analysis of the conditions of the
Knowledge
is
of
is
the effects of nature, just as the essence of a circle
its
properties.
From
minds reproduce nature
we might
for
all
as perfectly as possible.
assume, a
new
its
The
thesis of the
principle
descending hierarchy from the
is
not, as
incursion of Neo-Platonism into
Neo-Platonic explanation moves
the
the cause
other things, so that our
nature through deduction of
at first
is
the idea of the true essence the understand-
ing deduces, objectively, the idea of
intelligibility of
if it is
the universal cause
all
philosophy,
solution.
its
of nature can pertain to the understanding only
capable of representing a true essence which
of
the key to
One
through a
or First Cause to the sensible
world, to the world of duration, generation, and corruption: a spurious intelligibility, ignorant of the conditions of mathematical
can be deduced from
intelligibility in
which only eternal
eternal
Nature, which the understanding deduces from
verities.
verities
the objective essence of the principle, cannot be "the succession of
singular things subject to change, but only the succession of fixed, eternal things (seriem
rerum fixarum oeternarumque) ." What are
To
these fixed, eternal things?
understand what they
which
are,
we need
posits in nature fixed essences
and
eternal verities, such as extension, the conservation of motion,
and
to recall Cartesian physics,
the laws of impact. Spinoza's "fixed, eternal things" are also the
whole
set
of laws
which
nature, laws "according to are regulated."
These
constitute
the permanent structure of
which
singular things
all
res fixae then
happen and
are also particular essences,
well defined and determinate verities (just as the essence of a right
angle or a circle
is
a determinate essence in mathematics), although
they are present throughout nature and play the role of universals.
The world to
rule of as in
method
prohibits Spinoza
from deducing the
sensible
emanative metaphysics. Moreover, he does not pretend
deduce the whole gamut of
res fixae (in the
manner
of Plotinus ?
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
l66
who
caused an intelligible world to derive from the One), for "to
conceive everything at once surpasses by far the powers of the
human
understanding." Just as
we deduce one
mathematical truth
from another without ever reaching the end of the chain or using to
form
a whole, Spinoza sees each of the res fixae as nothing
than a link in a chain or a part of a whole.
And
moment
in a progression
is
the solution of the problem that
was
human
hi
God Thus
nature,
power, and
its
its
oriented; its
oriented toward
it is
point of departure
the design of the philosophy of Ethics owes
a theory of the
as a
first
principle,
De
human
man,
its
intellectus
God, on which
then the determination of the place of ticular, the singular essence that is
—that
union with God.
methodical exigencies developed in first,
more
and not
just as in mathematics, Spinozist deduction
does not proceed haphazardly but
of
it
origin to the
emendatione: depends;
all else
nature and, in par-
in the res fixae et aeternae
deduced from divine nature. Spinoza indicated precisely the inner
way the dependence of all things on God; the fifth part shows the same thing but through consideration of the essence of the mind" (v, prop. 35, scholium). As in Descartes, who provided the model in his Replies
plan of Ethics: "The
first
mathematical frame adopted by Spinoza, or
to the Objections, the
more and
precisely, the
its
once
it
Euclidean frame with
propositions,
is
its
when we compare
its
with the definitive revision of the Ethics.
nitions are introduced.
is
An
axiom
modified and
is
Our
emendatione, for
it
illusion
is
find
is
restated
new
defi-
illusory
a traditional treatise
that follows "the order of matter"
order of reasons."
We
Such a synthetic exposition may be
and may suggest that what he has written
on metaphysics
axioms,
a letter written to Oldenburg in
as a proposition, the order of definitions
De
definitions,
merely a procedure for explaining a truth
has been discovered, not a method of invention.
proof of this 1 661
part shows in a general
and not "the
dissipated as soon as
we
turn to
reveals to us in the discovery of the notion
167
SPINOZA
God
the result of an exigency of method,
of
that Spinoza's thought
is
and
it
should warn us
thoroughly analytical, probing ever more
man
deeply for the conditions under which nature and
can be
apprehended through the understanding.
One
of the
main
properties of the understanding
positive ideas before negative ones."
we
negative one, for
The
is
that "it forms
idea of the finite
call "finite in its class
is
a
anything that can be
terminated by something else of the same nature. For example, a
body
(Ethics
i,
and
def. 1),
The paradigm
of
all
in general
number
is,
essence"; positive because that
which
"any determination
is
a negation."
endowed with an
which expresses an a substance, that
it is
is
the idea of God, "the abso-
is
the substance
of attributes, each of
and
can always conceive a larger one"
positive ideas
lutely infinite being, that
itself
we
called finite because
is
conceived by
itself,
is,
infinite
eternal, infinite
"that
which
is
in
the concept of which
has no need of the concept of something else from which to be
formed." This
no Aristotelian substance, the hidden essence of
is
things beyond the reach of the mind,
hending properties and of a substance cipal attribute sion.
is
limited to appre-
accidents. Descartes taught that the essence
was known
—for
which
clearly
and
distinctly
through
prin-
example, the essence of a body through exten-
Spinoza follows Descartes in defining the attribute
which the understanding perceives of the substance its
its
as "that
as constituting
essence."
On
the other hand, Descartes twice denied the positive character
of the idea of substance. First, he believed that the real distinction
between two
which
is
attributes,
such as extension and thought, each of
conceived independently, forced us to posit two distinct
substances, soul
and body:
to limit a substance to
God, the absolutely
to limit
its reality.
number
of attributes, each of
and thought, both also believed that
which expresses
infinite, are
one attribute
infinite being, has
two such
an
is
infinite
his infinity; extension
attributes of
God. Descartes
thinking substance and extended substance did
not exist independently but had to be produced by the divine substance: "it pertains to the nature of the divine substance to exist,"
l68
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
for to be conceived independently
to
is
have need o£ nothing
else
in order to exist.
"Extension
is
an attribute of God." This
seemed most shocking
make God
Spinoza's assertion physics
and the
not
its
bodies
it
makes between extension
it
and extension
imagined
constituent parts but is
Did
and
divisibility
as
an object of the imagination.
infinite
is
and
indivisible; bodies are
—that which
conceived by this thing."
From
is
Modes
in another thing
are
and
is
the standpoint of the physicist,
of extension (they are conceived through exten-
sion), not parts of extension as
Spinozist thesis
between
limitations; the distinction
its
"the affections of substance
modes
an object
as
not a real distinction but a modal distinction.
bodies are
not
it
passivity?
comprehensible only in terms of Cartesian
is
is
him
attribute to
distinction
of the understanding
Extension as
one of the theses that
Spinoza's contemporaries.
to
and
corporeal
is
is
it
might be conceived by them. The
possible only because extension
the principle
is
of intelligibility.
This
clarifies
the Spinozist notion that unique substance and
universal intelligibility are one, provided that the relation of a
substance to
its
attributes
not a simple relation of subject to
is
predicate; an indivisible substance
the existence of the
modes
must be the reason
of their essential difference, have one to
modes
explain the
that
depend on the nature of an the order according to
are
common
them.
in
trait
—their
attribute, for intelligibility
among
geometry enables us
to
understand
ideas can be identical with an order
equation of the curve just as
its
among
and
its
between
how
and
in each attri-
an order
the affections
linked to the
depend on
its
equation can be treated
one and the same being since their being order.
is
properties actually
nature, with the result that the curve
and the same
order,
which modes derive from each other
of extension: the idea of the properties of a curve
as
is
capacity
does not
Intelligibility
attribute can be identical in spite of the distinction
butes. Cartesian
that explains
in each attribute. All attributes, in spite
is
constituted by one
Unity of substance, therefore,
versal intelligibility provided that substance
is
signifies
uni-
not a subject but,
—
SPINOZA
169
more than anything each attribute.
else,
the root of the unique order displayed in
"The order and
order and relation of things"
relation of ideas
Everything in Christian dogmatism relating
own
of his
resolves
will
free
is
prominently as
it
God
that
a fable in
to
who
effect;
first
or,
who
subjects his will to the final
figures as It is
true
a reason {causa sive ratio) that
is
God
in this sense
cause, a cause of essences as well as of existences,
absolutely
as the
a Creator
does in the accounts of the pagan gods.
makes us understand an
nature
same
which anthropomorphism
a cause, but a cause
is
the
produce the things conceived
to
through his understanding and cause of good
is
prop. 7).
(ii,
is
an
efficient
an independent or
cause, a cause that acts according to the laws of
putting
it
another way, a free cause
—a
cause that
an immanent cause
is
—one
efficacious only independently;
he
whose action does not pass
being outside himself; consequently
he
no
is
natura)
different
The
also
is
from what philosophers
call
nature (Deus sive
.
Human
iv
to a
Nature
third exigency of
that the
mind
is
to order things in
will not be exhausted
direct deduction
useful to us
method
by
such a
useless efforts; that
way is,
to
only toward those things that yield knowledge
—knowledge
of
human
nature.
Beginning with the
second part, Spinoza devotes his Ethics entirely to the study of
human and
nature to the extent that
attributes of
infinite
are
of
them
is
man—body and
plicity, birth,
finite
corruption.
first
the notion of
mode.
of God's infinite attributes
known; each
nature of
can be deduced from the nature
God. But he must introduce
mode, then the notion of
Only two
it
—extension
and thought
simple, infinite, eternal. Alternately, the
—connotes
soul
How
was
it
duration, change, multi-
possible for the
changing
to
spring from the eternal? This problem, which was the cross of every
philosophy
derived
from Platonism, was transformed by
Spinoza. Descartes' notion of extension could give birth to a physics
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
170
only by virtue of motion which alone distinguishes one body from another, inasmuch as bodies are not distinct simply because they are extended; moreover, the quantity of this
and the laws of
motion
is
constant,
communication or distribution (which alone
its
The constant quantity of motion, according to Spinoza, is a mode or affection of the attribute of extension, but it is an eternal mode like the attribute itself, and an "infinite mode" since it indicates the accounts for distinctions between bodies) are eternal verities.
elements of immutability in "the aspect of the universe taken as a
whole" (fades
universi).
totius
mode
thought a
attribute of
But there
necessarily
is
mode
infinite
that contains "objectively," along with the idea of
of attributes
universi.
totius
the "infinite intellect," or intellect of
is
"infinite
immutable order that assumes a
God
aspect in each attribute, they have
God,
God, an infinitude
and corresponding modes. Since these
are the expression of one
the
that contains "objectively" the whole,
immutable order of nature constituted by fades This
in
modes"
different
as their "absolutely proxi-
mate cause." They make us pass from "naturing" nature {natura naturans) to "natured" nature {natura naturatd) which consists in
modes, but they do not take us away from the eternal and the infinite. If
we now
consider a finite
mode
of extension, a body,
which
is
nothing but an extended mass whose parts are animated by motions
which are
interrelated
in such a
manner
find in
it
and transmitted from one part
that the
nothing that links
The
of extension.
whole it
to another
persists for a certain term,
we
to the eternal essence of the attribute
existence of the
body has
its
reason in other
modes, in other bodies that have imparted motion to it and, through their causality, actually make it what it is. The other finite
finite
modes, in turn, have their reason in other indefinitely.
modes
What
is
true of
modes, and so on is
also true of
of thought or ideas, for the order of objects in our thought
reproduces the order of
realities in
correspondence of attributes. has a
modes
finite
of extension
manner
From
extension in accordance with the this
it
of existing quite different
follows that a finite
from
that of
an
mode
infinite
SPINOZA
171
mode
The
or an attribute.
mode and
infinite
the attribute possess
eternity or infinite usufruct of being (infinita essendi fruitio), in
which essence
merged with
is
from the standpoint
sidered
begins to exist
it
of
when
only
existence; but the finite its
essence,
another
duration
and
essence, ity
of
existence
is
belongs solely to the
it
being outside
its
and duration,
causality
the extent
to
itself. is
finite
Thus
merely possible, since
mode produces it and mode excludes it. Existence
finite
ceases to exist as soon as another finite
in
is
that
himself.
cause
is
God God
from
distinct
is
it
being that has the causal-
the finite world, with external
characterized uniquely by a deficiency
and, as such, cannot be deduced immediately the attribute of
mode, con-
God, whose consequences are
from the nature
of
God
just as eternal as
mode which
is
its
himself modified in a certain manner, but he
is
its
indeed
is
its
cause since the finite
remote cause (causa remota).
Such was Spinoza's conception of human nature and
Man
ties.
consists of a
of extension
body and a mind
and of an
actual
mode
—that
of an actual
is,
what the
body could be within the universal mechanism.
the individuality of a machine
proper-
mode
of thought constituted by the
idea of this body. Spinoza tried to imagine of a
its
whose
individuality
He saw
it
as
different parts are arranged
by external causes in such a manner that they impart motion in accordance with a permanent order; an individual being
formed of other individual beings, and the human body a very
is
is
complex machine composed of other machines. In the
bute of thought
is
an idea which corresponds
itself
therefore attri-
to a corporeal indi-
vidual and which has no object other than the actual individual. the soul
is
external cause in other finite the
modes
modes
of thought corresponding to
of extension that are the causes of the body.
All the properties of soul are deduced from this definition soul
is
the idea of the body. But Spinoza's idea
outside the soul
judgment by
It
which begins and ends with the body and which has an
—"a
to give
itself affirms
its
is
mute image painted on a board" assent.
The
the existence of
idea, its
mode
object,
:
the
not something
—waiting for
of a divine attribute,
and
its
affirmation per-
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
172 as
sists
as this existence is
long
What must
another idea. negation, and
is
it
not excluded by the existence of
be explained
not the position but the
is
explained by the positive elements in whatever
Thus
excludes the thing negated.
the idea of a body
but rather the position and affirmation of
tion
thought. Besides, the idea
just as
is
not
is
its reflec-
existence
its
composite as the body
in
itself,
and the individuality of the mind, with the variety of perceptions that
it
includes, does not differ in nature
from the individuality of
the body.
But because the soul the idea that
bodies
are
it
has of
a finite
is
its
An
inadequate ideas.
cause or reason
known
is
at the
quate whenever the opposite finite
mode, limited
since the finite
finite
mode;
its
mode
finite
itself,
adequate whenever
is
as its object;
mode
body
that has
of itself
of thought, its
has of
its
inade-
it is
will of necessity be inadequate
mind has
knowledge of
it
has of external
it
Alternately, any idea of a
true.
is
essentially the
is
side itself; the idea that the
quate since, as a
idea
same time
mode,
to this
mode
mode, the idea that
body, and the idea that
is
it
has
is
its
its
cause out-
therefore inade-
cause in another
inadequate since the
exist-
ence and constitution of this body depend on an elusive influence exerted by external bodies; finally,
depends on the impression they external perception depends
its
knowledge
make on
of external bodies
own
its
body. Thus
on the nature of our bodies more than
on the nature of external bodies. Furthermore,
for
if
bodies, in the absence of an external impression,
any reason our
happen
ceive the external
imagination. In
body
fact, just like
the actual existence of if
as if
its
it
we
dis-
per-
were present: hence memory or
perception, the
object;
be
to
posed again as they were at the time of this impression,
and the
memory image
latter
implies
can be denied only
excluded by other ideas.
Man depends on a He is unintelligible
course of nature completely
according to Spinoza, unintelligible.
To
ence would be a
is
To
to
be
him.
finite,
simultaneously to exist in time and to be
search for the finite futile,
unknown
himself by his very nature.
to
modes
that explain our exist-
impossible undertaking, for they are them-
SPINOZA
173
Such
selves unintelligible.
is
the
first
notion that
we have
of
human
nature.
Spinoza demonstrates that in the prehensible to reattaching
human
soul, limited
in this detached, isolated
itself,
itself to
the whole, reason
must
we must
and incom-
fragment incapable of originate.
To
mind
under-
the
two
notions of intelligibility which Spinoza categorically excludes:
first,
stand clearly his demonstration
bear in
the Neo-Platonic notion of an intelligible world
—a
kind of ideal
transposition of the sensible world; second, the notion of universals
—blurred images of the intelligible world which the understanding, starting
from the
sensible
process of abstraction.
world, attains through a complicated
The two
types of intelligibility are both con-
ceived, in effect, in terms of their relation to the sensible world, as its
model and the other
as its extract.
one
Spinoza thinks he has
demonstrated that in the course of nature the mind can possess only mutilated and indistinct ideas. Descartes identified a completely different type of intelligibility in the absolute ideas
from
are detached
all
other ideas and have inherent intelligibility:
the idea of extension or of thought, for example.
nature Spinoza deduces the presence in the ideas. In Descartes they are characterized
be wholly present in a being no matter to the Meditations, thought,
parts.
which
how
is
of these absolute
fact that they
limited
is
it is;
wholly in each of
the total nature of extension
Spinoza demonstrates that
idea of that
mind
by the
From human
we
necessarily
is
its
suf-
mani-
in each of
its
have an adequate
found in both the whole and the
we must have adequate
can
according
whether considered in passion or
fering or in intellectual conception, festations, just as
which
part; that
ideas of the attribute of extension
and of
we have an idea, no matter how mutilated and indistinct, of a mode of extension or of a mode of thought; and that we have an adequate idea of God the attribute of thought for the very reason that
whose nature
is
quate ideas are
wholly present in each of the modes. These ade-
common
notions since they are equally present in
each individual, and collectively they constitute reason. arrive at the notion of
man
as a rational being.
Thus we
174
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
Man, of
then, acquires
knowledge
in several ways.
together by a simple succession. reason,
of
consists
common
and
from them: knowledge whose object and
entails the
is
abstracted
from duration
shows
knowledge
in
how human
na-
which the mind
intelligible to itself.
human nature how man, by his very
This conception of Spinoza shows
is
distinct
from
nature, sometimes
Descartes'.
succumbs
sometimes attains to truth. Descartes imputed to
free will capable of avoiding error
the clear
deduced
apprehension of things "under a certain aspect of
ture gives rise to a third kind of
to error,
of knowledge, or
of everything
eternity." Finally, all the rest of the Ethics
becomes
kind
and images linked
The second kind
notions
first
he has through
consists of the inadequate ideas that
knowledge
the ordinary course of nature: sense perception
The
and
distinct
and
of giving
ideas of the understanding.
Descartes' theory of error
is
man
a
assent only to
its
his false notion of ideas:
The
root of
having
inter-
preted ideas as simple pictures or images, he had to posit along with
them the empty power This "will" credited. volition,
is
and
to affirm
to
deny what he called
will.
but one of the universal terms which Descartes
The power
and
to affirm
and with
to deny,
it
belief
dis-
and
belong to each of our ideas. Error does not consist of assent
based on an inadequate idea;
adequate idea. For example, that the sun
is
demonstrated
its
the inadequate idea
it is
in a certain sense, in so far as
it is
it is
itself, at least
not excluded and denied by an
perception that makes us estimate
two hundred yards away, true distance. Error, then,
until the is
geometer has
not perception but the
absence of true ideas that correct perception, and the absence of
doubt that accompanies error ideas: the first
the
is
mark
is
not the same thing as assent to true
of our weakness, the second of our
strength.
Thus Spinoza
new
introduces a whole
into the theory of
man:
the object
is
intellectual equilibrium
no longer
to justify but to
demonstrate. Everywhere Descartes posited free wills— human or
divine—engaged justified
his
in the pursuit of
method by
relating
an end posited it
to
the
as a
good.
He
good of man, God's
SPINOZA
175
immunity from
error by ascribing error to the will of
them
passions by depicting
as
man, and the
something instituted by nature for the
benefit of man. Spinoza demonstrates that man, whether succumb-
ing to error or searching for truth,
from human
deduces the passions will
—
a spiritual being,
is
nature.
The
engaged in the pursuit of an end, the notion of good and
evil
these are illusory, mutilated, indistinct notions.
The
v
Error
Bondage
Passions:
a necessary product of
is
human
nature,
and passion (con-
trary to the widely accepted opinion of the Stoics,
contradicted nature is
and he
notion of a free
and
that the will
natural and necessary. Passion
which
it
that the being
sity
it
it)
that a living being experi-
itself is
not the cause or of
but the partial cause; action, on the contrary, means
is
which are
held that
had absolute control over
means
which the being
ences an affection of
who
in
subject
is
passion,
to
body, which
the complete (adequate) cause of the affections
In the ordinary course of nature,
it.
is finite,
has
since its
man
is
of neces-
any affection experienced by
his
source in a proximate body and so on
by degrees throughout the whole order of nature; and the mind in like
manner has inadequate
cause.
But
man
Thus
which
also acts in so far as
deduces from them cause.
ideas of
still
it
is
not the integral
he has adequate ideas and
other ideas of which he then
is
the total
the natural course of the passive affections contrasts
with the rational concatenation of ideas in the understanding just as the first
kind of knowledge contrasts with the second kind of
knowledge.
How, then, do inadequate ideas produce the passive affections that we call joy, sadness, and the like? "Every being tends to persevere in its own being," for every being is an expression, near or remote, of divine power;
The endeavor the
first
ment
no being can be destroyed except by another being.
(conatus) to persevere, inherent in every being,
of the passive affections. In the
to self
is
body the immediate
termed appetite (appetitus) and
is
is
attach-
the very essence
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
176
man;
of
in the soul
termed desire (cupiditas) and
it is
tendency to self-affirmation inherent in any idea. only an image
principle
causes act
of
all
other
the
on our bodies and
to persevere in our
which
arise: joy,
perfection, fection.
an affirmation of
An
idea
is
not
obvious that
itself. It is
from being dependent on any idea of a pursued good,
desire, far
the
but also
simply the
is
is
own
affections.
For
is
external
instance,
promote or impede our endeavor
either
being, with the result that
two
affections
the (adequate) idea of an increase in a body's
and sadness, which
Furthermore, love
the idea of a decrease in
is
arises
when
the idea of joy
per-
its
combined
is
with the (inadequate) idea of the cause believed to have produced hatred arises under the same conditions,
it;
bined with the idea of
its
cause.
The
when
sadness
com-
is
diversity of the passions
is
explained by the endeavor of the soul to imagine things that increase
vent
it
of love
power
its
from
to act
and
images of things that pre-
to exclude
acting. It follows that all passions are modifications
and hatred. Thus these two passions are spread by virtue
of the laws of the imagination,
from
primary object
their
to objects
which are themselves neutral but which were perceived along with
and bear some resemblance
it
may
individual
same it
class or to the
to objects
state of fluctuation,
virtue of the
same nation. By
for
one
virtue of associations linking
and hatred
same time,
at the
resulting in a
which makes us love and hate the same thing.
same
laws, images of things produce the
affections as things themselves: to ourselves
For example, hatred
it.
which produce sadness, an object that arouses love or
joy can arouse sadness
By
to
be transferred to every individual belonging to the
same
hope and fear when we represent
something that will probably produce joy or sadness;
hope and fear that become security and despair when we no longer entertain doubt concerning
impending joy and
—images
laws also explain contentment and regret ness produced by things
Another of a
effect of the
human
affection,
we have hoped
imagination
being similar to
sadness.
us,
:
it is
who
The same
of joy
and
sad-
for or dreaded.
impossible for us to think is
experiencing a certain
without experiencing the same affection ourselves. This
SPINOZA
177
which
explains commiseration,
the sadness caused by our aware-
is
ness of another person's sadness,
and emulation, which
is
the desire
caused by the image of the same desire in another person. this
reason that
we
try to
promote joy in others; we
It is for
desire to
do
when we we praise them. Another consequence, however, is that we try to make others become similar to ourselves to hate whatever we hate and to love whatever we love. Our ambition, identical in each of us, is whatever will please others, and acting in the
same way toward
imagine that they are
us,
—
thwarted by that of
all
the others who, in their turn, are trying to
transform us according to their wishes, with the result that hatred
is
generated. This law of the imagination which
much
makes us
love an object loved by another person also produces the modification of hatred called
envy
the object in question can be possessed
if
man
by only one individual, and
is
thus torn between pity for the
unfortunate individual and envy or jealousy with respect to those
who
are fortunate.
Now we
see
how
resemblance engenders hatred which, having
once sprung up, multiplies more or sible for us to
him
in turn,
less
independently.
It is
impos-
imagine that another person hates us without hating
and our hatred
for destruction
which
is
is
accompanied by a desire
necessarily
manifested through anger or cruelty. But
"hatred can be overcome by love, and hatred that has been over-
come by
love
becomes
love,
preceded by hatred." For love for me, he
is
which
if I
and the joy
I feel
to banish sadness,
through
greater than
imagine a
a cause of joy for
by the mind Still to
is
this love
me;
if it
man whom
I
had not been hate, feeling
then begin to love him;
I
promotes the endeavor made
which was enveloped
in hatred.
be explained are certain modifications of love and hatred
that originate in the
freedom that we imagine present in the object
and hatred are stronger toward
a
being believed to be free than toward one bound by necessity, for
I
loved or hated.
It is clear
that love
conceive the free being as the sole cause of find itself
it
impossible,
if I
my
joy or sadness, but
see that the cause of this joy or sadness has
been produced of necessity by other beings, not to transfer
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
178
my
love or hatred to
these beings.
all
cations of our affections are different
they relate to a singular
to have nothing in common with objects What is then produced is admiration, which becomes if we dread the object, veneration if the man involved
which we imagine
object
known
to us.
consternation is
For the same reason, modifi-
when
superior to us, honor
when we
he has vices that exceed the norm, scorn
if
believe that he does not actually possess the qualities that
caused us to admire him. Finally,
to
our joy becomes
act,
we
ourselves are the cause of
we imagine
our joy or sadness, inasmuch as
power
if
our power or lack of
and our sadness
self-satisfaction
humility.
We
see that all the passive affections relate to the
the soul to persevere in
own
its
body) has an individuality which distinguishes
from
all others,
and which
different persons,
endeavor of
being. But each soul (and each
and separates
it
it
changes with time. Consequently,
itself
and even the same person
at different times, are
not in agreement about the objects to be loved or to be hated. Passive affections express
our
own
nature rather than the nature of
external things,
and believing that we are apprehending
we
what we love good, what we hate
itself,
Such
vainly call
is
the
mechanism
evil.
of the passive affections that reveal to us
man's bondage. The soul
is
what
it
every wind, hating
reality
a finite being that shifts
its
has loved and loving what
course with it
has hated
under the influence of external causes. Our passive affections are determined by the whole course of nature, which has complete control over
human vi
human
nature inasmuch as
it
nature as does the infinite to the
bears the
same
relation to
finite.
Freedom and Eternal Life But not everything
in proportion to the
every affection
is
in
is
is
determined by the course of nature: his ideas,
of necessity passive
idea. Joy, for instance,
fection. It
man
adequacy of
is
he
acts.
and linked
to
Moreover, not
an inadequate
the idea of that which increases our per-
a passive affection
if
the cause of the increase
is
out-
SPINOZA
179
side us, but
are
its
it is
an affection without being a passion
adequate cause. In the same way, desire
only to the extent that
we
which we are the adequate
passive affection
is
there
if
depend on
can be only passive, since by
it)
cannot seek self-destruction and since
a part of
is
cause, the affection of desire
remains, without passion. Sadness alone (together with fections that
ourselves
are able to continue in existence only
through the concurrence of external causes, for ourselves of
we
if
it is
all
the af-
itself
a being
absolutely necessary for a
being to have an external cause.
Given the fundamental tendency of
own
man must
being,
good and whatever hinders interest,
and
a being to persevere in
it evil.
Good, then,
virtue consists in loving one's
are those determined by adequate ideas or
we that
the most perfect of
we
We
also
because of reason, which consists of lar
and
To do
much
as possible)
grounded on reason,
for
On
we know our good among other men in know that all men are similar common notions, and dissimi-
all actions.
fewer obstacles to
shall find
so far as they resemble us.
clear that vir-
and an action of which we are the
are their adequate cause, is
identical to self-
is
self. It is
tuous actions (those which increase our power as
cause
its
consider whatever promotes this tendency
the other hand,
in conflict with each other because of their passive affections.
everything possible in order to prevent such conflict
in conformity to reason: this ciety. It
is
is
to act
the purpose of the institution of so-
should be noted that in Spinoza's view the social power
not an educative power but only a coercive power.
prevent conflicts between us, not by
making men
It is
is
intended to
rational but, in
keeping with the principle that an affection cannot be destroyed except
by a stronger
punishment
—to
affection,
by using a stronger
mutual security of men: hatred, jealousy, nature each evil
man
own
constitution,
—fear
of
the
cruelty. In the state of
has the right to decide what
according to his
affection
that endanger
oppose the passive affections
which
is is
good and what
is
of necessity deter-
mined by universal nature; consequently he has the right to avenge wrongs something which now belongs to society. Sin and goodness,
—
justice
and
injustice can
now
be defined only by society.
We
are
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
100
therefore following the rules of reason
men
the affections which tend to unite
In a general way, preservation
all
when we
the affections that are conducive to
good "a wise :
man
will restore his
moderate and agreeable nourishment, delight scent
and bright
cles"
(iv, 45,
self-
body through with the
his senses
games, and specta-
colors of plants, enjoy music,
scholium). In contrast, the passions that depend on
humil—particularly hatred, but also melancholy, fear, —are bad, debilitating, and always contrary to rea-
sadness
son.
all
are good.
—even passive affections—must be judged good. Joy and
gaiety can only be
ity,
decide that the pas-
by society are bad and that
sive affections declared illegitimate
pity,
and remorse But not
all
depend on joy are good; those
of the passions that
capable of excess, such as love, and those excessive in themselves,
such as pride, are not good. Pride indicates an ignorance of oneself
and
a
weakness matched only by contempt for
The
common
principle
passions
is
to
these
all
oneself.
judgments concerning the
obvious: just as truth destroys the error of sensible per-
ception without destroying
its
welcomes
positive elements, so reason
the positive elements of the passions. "Appetite that produces the passions
is
the
is
scholium).
same
as
The endeavor
derived from reason"
appetite to
(iv,
fundamentally identical to the endeavor to persevere in being,
since the being of the
mind
is
an idea; consequently, ideas of the
passive affections that increase our being contain only that is
good and
rational.
Wisdom, which impels
can preserve and increase our power, but on
life"
(iv,
which obviates
67).
perils,
the joy that results is
18,
understand, characteristic of reason,
The and
man
wise
far
attains the inner peace,
the wise
if
man
is
freer in the city
than in solitude"
The freedom
of the wise
where he
to act.
strives to
practices gratitude
still
from considering the laws of the
his freedom, "he
common law
does not despise prudence
from the contemplation of our power
the benefits of the ignorant, he
and
us toward whatever
meditation, not on death
way he
in this
not the inner peace of a hermit:
faith;
"is
which
His
avoid
and good
city as obstacles to
lives
according to
(iv, 73).
man
in
no way depends,
as Descartes
SPINOZA
l8l
make man an "em-
thought, on a hypothetical free will that would
an empire." According
pire within
between body and
Whatever
soul.
to Descartes there
interaction
is
passion in the soul
is
is
the result
of an action of the body; inversely, however, the soul has the to
modify the pineal gland, with the
motion of the animal
Such
passions.
respondence
exists
sion in the soul
is
is
impossible
if it is
We
directly
on the body but must to
to
is
will
it
engenders. But this
nature drives us to this affection.
ambition
acts.
For example,
—the desire of each —and the serious
to himself
true only
is
we wish
If
when the course of make other men
to
why
such a transformation
loved or hated for reasons
is
sequently no object loved or hated sadness, but
is
is
necessary. In passion
drawn from
its
nature; con-
the true cause of our joy or
is
merely an imagined cause. This joy or sadness not
only can be separated from
we
affec-
which promotes peace among men.
obvious
no object
as
same
which we are the adequate cause then becomes the virtue
of piety, It is
not
affections will
similar to ourselves with respect to our rationality, the tion of
is
of the affections of
Such
become virtuous
we know the passive affection called man to make all other men similar conflicts that
"pas-
always utilizing the same
the inadequate cause.
no longer be passions but
pas-
is
word
can deduce the conditions that
become the adequate cause
he, in passion,
its
offer vain precepts for acting
try,
we
determine whether
man
whatever
whose adequate cause
must not
method,
which
soul;
equally passion in the body, for the
contained in a being.
power
upon the
true that a perfect cor-
between the body and the
sion" designates only the elements
will allow
acts
it
and acquires absolute control over
spirits
a result
result that
its
apparent cause;
and sadness
learn through reason that joy
versal course of nature,
we
it
must result
be.
As soon
from a uni-
cease to love or to hate the things that
our imagination presented to us as their causes; similarly, sadness
brought about by the as soon as
sion
is
to
affection
we learn know the
it
loss of a
good
that the loss passion, that
is
was is,
assuaged in a singular manner inevitable.
to
To overcome
a pas-
have an adequate idea of the
envelops. Alternatively, affections that originate in ade-
1
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
82
quate ideas have a singular claim to survival and to constancy.
an
number
affection varies in strength according to the
that arouse
it,
no
affection will be stronger than the
If
of causes
one linked
to
adequate ideas; for whereas the objects of inadequate ideas are changeable, and transitory, the objects of adequate ideas are
finite,
and whereas the
constant and eternal; variable
and
we always
our passions
knowledge of our perfection
by
joy,
when we
diverse,
find the eternal laws of nature.
affection, in so far as
true cause
God, and
this love of
of
God
it is
is
traceable to
man
is
accompanied by the idea of God,
God, grounded on adequate
myth
counterpart any love of affection; finally, far
it
ideas, differed
for
men,
from the
is
how love
constant and cannot change
is
of the fallen angel;
God
accompanied
it is
God, the principle of the
adequate cause. Spinoza stressed
its
discussed by theologians:
to hatred, as in the
Adequate
adequate, expresses the
and power of our being; consequently
whose
eternal laws of nature. This joy,
love of
objects of our passions are
consider the affections embraced by
since
it
God
from resembling the
cannot have as
its
exempt from any
is
mystic's solitary love,
it
men closer to one another because it is grounded on reason. Thus man achieves a certain degree of mastery over his passions by utilizing common notions of the second kind of knowledge. The idea that we have of our finite individuality as such is an inadequate idea. The idea that we have of God and of the principles of nature is an adequate idea, and we know that it is from this that all things, indraws
cluding ourselves and our passions, are of necessity deduced. This idea transforms the idea that selves as beings lose
we have
of ourselves;
identify our-
determined by the laws of the universe and thus
none of the positive elements of our individuality. Instead of
we
eliminating the conatus through which
own
we
being,
we somehow draw
tend to persevere in our
support for
it
from the conatus of
the universe (v, props. 1-20).
But such knowledge such that
we
of the universe, as parts.
That
is
universal. It
relate to the universe
is
why
is
not our individual being as
but our individual being as a part
having something in the second kind of
common
with
all
the other
knowledge does not exempt
—
SPINOZA
183
us entirely from conflicts engendered by the passive affections or
from
life
under conditions of duration, two things which are nec-
Superimposed upon the second kind of knowledge
essarily related.
knowledge by which we apprehend
the third kind,
is
with the same that 6
and 3
is
clarity that characterizes
numbers
the fourth proportional to the three simple
—the
God and
such to the nature of
to
By
his attributes.
imagine ourselves
inexplicable in our isolation, besieged
the
universal laws of
its
kind of
by insurmountable and un-
we know
the
which we are the expression; but by the third kind
knowledge we are able
To know
first
as finite individuals,
explained forces; by the second kind of knowledge
see that
1, 2,
necessary dependence that relates our individuality as
knowledge we were able
of
intuitively
our apprehension of the fact
to consider
our individual being and
to
uniqueness derives from the nature of God. oneself in this
way
pendent of any duration. Eternal
to
is
life
achieve eternal
life,
inde-
has nothing to do with sur-
vival of the soul following destruction of the body, or immortality,
for the soul exist
is
the idea of the
only so long as the body
what
is
ments
eternal life?
in the idea
We
man
body and therefore can continue itself
must once again imagine the three mo-
fashions of his
sees himself as a finite, singular
being
own
nature: at the outset he
(first
moment)
agines his reabsorbtion in universal necessity
he
is
;
next he im-
(second moment);
he reappears to himself as a singular being, except that
finally
moment). Thus the Ethic being as it passes from time
eternal (third
transfiguration of
to theologians,
spirit of Descrates,
who
The attribute foreground when he dealt with this basic point.
is
now
kind of
to eternity,
from
relegated such questions
seems incontestable. All the
found in Descartes' thought sprang from
beings
reveals a
That we are confronted here with something
finitude to infinity.
wholly alien to the
to
continues in existence. But just
his creative
of
difficulties that
their divergent views
God which will:
on
Descartes put in the
the relations between
and providential
Spinoza
God
God and
himself
is
finite
the cre-
ator of eternal truths, the guarantee of the criterion of evidence
through his veracity; he insures the constancy of motion, creates
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
184
the world at each instant through a soul
and body
by Descartes
for the
new
act, institutes
good of man. These were
to establish the impossibility of
all
the union of
notions advanced
deducing the nature
from God and, consequently, the
of finite, singular beings
necessity
of relegating to faith supernatural destiny and everything having to
do with the union of the soul with God; these were vehemently for us to
criticized
draw
by Spinoza. Nevertheless,
a hasty conclusion, for instead of pondering Des-
and the way he applied
his
method was
essence of his
method
geometry and physics. The
and
proceed
to
through intuition and deduction from one singular thing
solely
any
we
to
should note that (theoretically
rate) his explanation of the singular bodies of nature, the
heavens, or individual
man
left
no
unintelligible residue,
—manipulated
and
which did not originate
from
to
method
to consider his
to leave universals aside
another. In physics, for instance, at
we ought
theology and metaphysics,
cartes'
it
also the notions
would be wrong
and
that his corporeal
way by a woven in its
dealt with in this
in sensation
—was
physics entirety
intelligible relations.
Such considerations should guide our thinking. able to pass
passage,
if
from time
to eternity?
passage there
ment he begins
is,
is
is
to
quadam
aspect of eternity {sub
was Spinoza
has been asked. But such
an accomplished
to use the second
notions, for to use reason
it
How fact
from the mo-
kind of knowledge and
common
apprehend things under a certain aeterni specie). But there
is
really
no "passage" from time to eternity. Spinoza states this explicitly: "The desire to know things by the third kind of knowledge cannot arise from the first kind of knowledge." The whole treatise On the Improvement of the Understanding shows in fact that rational knowledge
is
direct contact
a point of departure with if
that "it can arise
it
is
ever to reach
its
which the soul must have goal,
though Spinoza adds
from the second type of knowledge"
indicates that he assumes,
(v, 28).
This
on the contrary, a perfect continuity
be-
tween knowledge sub quadam aeterni specie derived from common,
and
universal notions specie aeternitatis
.
eternal
The
life
our knowledge of ourselves sub
explanation
—
this
bears repeating
—
is
that
SPINOZA
185
the spiritual
an original
was not conceived by Spinoza
life
from which man has
state
progression; not one that to
perfect
makes us
that
knowledge deduced from
to
toward
methodical
makes us move from imperfect knowledge
knowledge but one
knowledge
as a return
fallen but as a
it.
pass
from
perfect
The common notions of God is deduced
reason are sources of deduction: from the idea of
an infinitude of
infinite attributes;
modes, such as the
infinite
from each
infinite
attribute are
sion,
which moves
inert
common
the attribute of
in
intellect
thought and constancy of motion in extension.
deduced
It is
in this progres-
by step toward singular things, and not in
step
And
notions that reason consists.
it
seems
at first
glance that deduction ends here, for Spinoza does not deduce finite
modes
from the absolute nature of
existing in time
though the singular being that we these modes.
such
But the
resides in
of the Ethics shows precisely that
fifth part
not the case and that deduction, as
is
and body,
are, soul
even
attributes
continues, brings us
it
same singular
beings,
endowed now, however, with
ent type of existence
known
not in time but sub specie aeternitatis.
to the
The
individual
was defined by
is
a differ-
not an obscure quiddity; the corporeal individual
a fixed, intelligible relation between motions (Defi-
nition, following
ii,
13)
without thinking of
;
its
therefore,
if
we
consider the relation
existence in time,
we apprehend
it
itself,
in
its
mode of mind is the
eternal essence as a necessary consequence of the infinite
And
extension represented by the laws of motion. idea of the body,
follows that even
"some part of
perishes,
namely
it
its
essence
divine intellect,
something
it,
which proceeds
from an
infinite
if
eternal,
from the
we
are eternal"
(v,
"We 23,
feel
body
(v, 23),
infinite or
of thought, just as
proceeds from the laws of motion in extension.
through experience that
the
must remain"
eternally
mode
if
the actually existing
its
body
and know
scholium), but
demonstrations involve "the eyes of the soul."
The
eternal life of the soul
essence that proceeds essence
which
we it
is
like the internal
from the divine
development of the
intellect.
By knowing
this
acquire a better understanding of the principle from
emanates, just as
we know more about
a geometric being
l86
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
we deduce more of the consequences of its definition: "The more we know about particular things, the more we understand about
as
God"
(v, 24)
knowledge
.
Thus
the third kind of
mind can
that the
knowledge
is
the
most perfect
attain. It yields the eternal joy that
God arises in the joy. The love which
culminates in beatitude, and an intellectual love of
God as the source of this God and which is linked to his essence must itself have God as its cause; since God is absolutely infinite, he must love himself with an infinite intellectual love; the soul's love for God mind when
it
identifies
the soul feels for
does not differ from God's love for himself but
This joy and
this love are affections
elements since by these affections
nature the soul
its
do not
produced the passive
is
is
it.
adequate cause. Yet,
their
is
differ essentially
from the conatus which
affections, since the conatus,
the essence of beings,
rather a part of
which no longer include passive
which constituted
pure affirmation which posits beings with-
Omnis One) contrasts with (statement from Part Five). A de-
out any temporal limits; they have lost only their limitations. (statement from Part
determinatio negatio
essentia particularis affirmativa
termination which
not contain
its
comprehends tistically
is
own
itself
but sees
a negation
the limit of a being that does
which
reason; a singular thing
because
its
is
it
no longer
falls
affirmative
is
back upon
dependence on the universe in
its
itself
ego-
very singu-
larity.
vii
Positive Religion
and
Politics
In his Theologicopolitical Treatise Spinoza shows the contrast
between an eternal
life
based on
ways of salvation taught by the
way
revealed to
clear, distinct
religions.
He
him by philosophy:
believer will be saved.
How,
then, are
knowledge and the
seems to regard the
we
to explain the outcries
occasioned by the appearance of the celebrated Treatise?
son
is
that Spinoza carefully isolates
by religions
—the
and
latter
like the philosopher, the
separates
The
rea-
two things united
teaching of truth and the rules of conduct to be
followed. For religions consider their sacred books not merely as a set of
commandments but
as a revelation that has
its
source in
God
187
SPINOZA
himself. In this
way there arises, alongside a religion that prescribes among men, a theology which is based on the pre-
and love sumed authority piety
God
shows us a
and
to anger,
of the divine revelation of Scripture
and which
subject to every passion, to repentance, to jealousy,
to pity.
Thanks
method
to the allegorical
Philo the Jew had provided the model, the theologians in ability
had long been accustomed not
sions that
and a
similarity
Cartesian and Spinozist
life,
prob-
were too offensive; but such half-measures assumed a
the second)
first
kind of knowledge to
between them, in direct contrast
spirit;
and in Spinoza's
powerful images that he throws into
Moses and the prophets owe
their
to the
exegesis of Scrip-
breath of
relief (the
the mythology of the angels, divine apparitions)
his opinion
all
to interpret literally expres-
passing from image to idea (from the
ture, the
which
for
show
hold on the
that in
common
people to the strength of their imagination; they do not go beyond the
domain of the
senses
and have no
clear
and
distinct
of things divine. It goes directly against the nature of ciate particular
God
to
enun-
laws which have a beginning in time and which are
addressed to only one
man
or only one nation; only eternal conse-
quences can be deduced from the nature of God. prohibited
knowledge
Adam
from eating of the
fruit
The
edict that
"was a law only with
man Adam and necessitated by the defectiveness his knowledge." That is also why God revealed himself to Moses a princely legislator. If God had spoken to him immediately, he
respect to the one
of as
"would have perceived the Decalogue not truth." Spinoza's
was the
first
attempt,
Richard Simon's, to perform a purely
as a
law but
much more
literal exegesis
as
an eternal
radical than
of the Bible;
thus he reached not the content of the precepts themselves but the reasons adduced to support them.
The ratives
dissociation
2
between the worth of
biblical or evangelical nar-
and the worth of the precepts they contained was accepted
as a matter of course in the religious circles that attracted Spinoza's 3
Louis Meyer, a close friend
who
published Spinoza's posthumous works, had
written a Philosophia scripturae interpres
(1666)
in
which he surmised
standard for interpreting Scripture was the agreement between the truths
and reason.
that it
the
taught
1
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
88
sympathy. In that
spirit
short,
of
all
consisted
them were animated by
the Socinian
expurgating religion of any theological
in
teaching and in accepting only precepts conforming to the light of nature; moreover, they found in Scripture
itself
many
passages that
strengthened their conviction. Here, therefore, Spinoza constructed nothing; he had before
him
a religion of salvation in
faith consists not in the idea of
from
it,
God and
but in the belief that obedience to the orders of God, con-
sidered as our king, can save us.
At
of faith.
the
He was
phy: "Even
if
we
not cease to give
and
religion
cal Treatise goes sible,
did not first
aware of the value
that "religion"
is
not
outlined in his philoso-
life as
know that our soul is eternal, we would among the objects of human existence
place
—in
short, to everything that relates to the in-
and generosity of the soul"
trepidity
fully
end of the Ethics he shows
dependent on knowledge of eternal
to piety
which saving
the consequences deduced
much
further, for
(v, 41).
The
Theologicopoliti-
declares that salvation
it
is
pos-
even without the second kind of knowledge, through the
simple, practical attitude of obedience.
The
theory of salvation through faith
thing Spinoza observed around him. his
consonant with every-
is
Is it
equally consonant with
whole system of philosophy? F. Rauh noted that the human
understanding, because of the infinite distance that separates
from the divine understanding, must admit salvation incomprehensible to in the Ethics, consists not in
it;
that there are
and he noted
it
ways of
that salvation, even
knowledge but rather
in the affection
it
and which can
conceivably be associated with other conditions.
We
should add that
Spinoza had direct experience with a religious
life
independent of
of joy
and blessedness which are
associated with
philosophy, and that even though he criticized experience as a source of intelligibility, he never denied certainty.
its
Furthermore, the entire Treatise
the positive elements of this experience
human
error
ideas of
God
—a
separation
is
worth
as a source of
devoted to separating
from the elements added by
accomplished by virtue of adequate
provided by philosophy. Spinozism
patible with the value of the religious experience.
is
perfectly
com-
SPINOZA
189
Be
that as
it
may,
was linked
his outlook
United Provinces, for
that prevailed throughout the
gion independent of theoretical beliefs or munities.
The
must stand
to the spirit of tolerance
rites that
must not support
state itself
as the defender of
fundamental tenet of Spinoza's
made
it
reli-
separated com-
a particular belief but
freedom of thought: that was the politics.
noza's description of the origin of society
We
saw
earlier that Spi-
was the same
as
Hobbes';
but whereas Hobbes concluded with the annihilation of the rights
and the sovereignty
of the individual
with a
liberal state that
individual even while
it
of the state, Spinoza
ended
did not abolish the natural rights of the instituted civil rights based
and
tional conception of justice
injustice.
This
is
on a conven-
true because his
point of departure, notwithstanding appearances, was not wholly identical to Hobbes's: in Spinoza's view, the
endeavor of a being
own being when implicated in passion is the same as its endeavor when it has become rational; or, to use the language of Hobbes, agreement among men led by reason is effected through the same forces that unleash universal war. The to persevere in its
state, therefore, is
role
is
its
limited to using fear of punishment to prevent conflicting
passions lates
not to use violence to suppress these forces;
from being
destructive; but for this very reason,
the rational affections that unite
of producing
have the right
them to
or excites hate
directly.
judge the
among
its
posed to that of Hobbes,
From
men, though
this
it
it
is
it
stimu-
incapable
follows that individuals
state or to rebel if the state uses violence
subjects: a conclusion diametrically op-
who
wrote with the intention of prevent-
ing revolution in his country, whereas Spinoza continued to support the liberal government of Jan de Witt following the Orangist party's
usurpation of authority.
viii
Spinozists
and AntiSpinozists
Spinozism remained an
ment
in
Holland.
essentially religious
Van Leenhof
(1 647-1712)
and
sectarian
move-
and Van Hattem
(1641-1706), both clergymen, popularized Spinoza's ideas on beati-
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
I9O
tude and eternal
"When we
life
through works written in the vernacular.
consider the necessity of hardships in the eternal order
Van
of God," says
Leenhof, "and
when we can
fashion for our-
an adequate idea of his sufferings, hardships are no longer
selves
hardships but contemplations of the order of nature that always contain elements of satisfaction."
3
The
Spinozist sect
was
severely
persecuted by theologians.
The doctrine was The Cartesians were
not favorably received by other philosophers. particularly conscientious about replying to ac-
cusations such as those of Leibniz,
The same
of Spinozism."
who saw
in Descartes "the seeds
accusations are found again in a
work
of
Aubert de Verse entitled The Sincere Unbeliever or Dissertation
Which Are Refuted the Foundations of His Atheism (1684). The work contained not only a refutation of Spinoza's impious maxims but also a refutation of the principal against Spinoza, in
hypotheses of Cartesianism which were said to be the origin of
Spinozism. These were the hypotheses of extended substance and continuous creation.
Thus
the refutations of the Cartesians con-
tinued without intermission.
Among them
were Wittich (Anti-
(Fundamenta atheismi
spinoza, 1690), Poiret
eversa, in the second
edition of Cogitationes rationales, 1685), Regis (Refutation of Spi-
noza's Opinion of the Existence
and Nature
of
God, following The
Use of Reason and Faith), and the Benedictine Francois Lamy (New Atheism Destroyed, or Refutation of the System of Spinoza,
Drawn Man,
for the
Most Part from the Knowledge
of
Truth and of
1706).
But the anti-Spinozism of Bayle, the exponent of the
and of
We
tolerance, equaled that of Leibniz,
need only
many
recall the
systematic atheist," "the
man who 3
he
aussi ct
ciel
who
reduce atheism to a system," the
God was
subject to extension
and conse-
denied the principle of contradiction and
sur la terre, ou description breve et claire de la veritable et solide joie,
conforme a
la raison
sous toutes les formes
cartesienne,
notes in his Dictionary against "the
first to
admitted that
quently divisible,
critical spirit
Malebranche, or Fenelon.
I,
419.
qu'a la sainte ecriture, presentee a toute espece
d'hommes
(1703). Quoted by Bouillier, Histoire de la philosophic
191
SPINOZA
said that
God was
subject to contrasting modes,
who
denied moral
"The Germans killed ten thousand Turks," but "God in the form of Germans killed God in the form of ten thousand Turks"). Bayle's indignation was passed
responsibility
on
(for
one must not
say,
and even found its way into the Encyclopedia. Not German Romantic movement was there a rivival of in-
to Voltaire
until the terest in It is
Spinozism.
true that in his
De
ficto Baylii
Poiret charged that this indignation
adversus Spinozam certamine,
was
spurious. In his article
(Note O) Bayle did in
fact attribute the origin of Spinoza's system
to the objections of the
Manicheans
the grounds of the existence of evil. are invalid
if
(as in
to the unity of the principle,
They
Spinoza) the principle
ing in accordance with the infinitude of are all valid
if this
principle
is
zism gave Bayle an opportunity ness of the
Manichean
—those
Spinoza
is
its
a necessary cause act-
power but
a providential nature.
that they
Thus Spino-
to call attention to the persuasive-
objections.
Other pretended refutations of
of the Collegiant Jan
Bredenburg {Enervatio
tatus theologicopolitici, Rotterdam, 1675) lainvilliers
on
note that these objections
trac-
and of the Count of Bou-
{Refutation of the Errors of Benedict Spinoza) also can
be classed as disguised apologies intended to promulgate the doctrine.
I
Bibliography
I
to VIII
Texts Spinoza, Benedict de. Opera quotquot reperta sunt. Edited by
and .
.
}.
N. Land. 3d ed. 4 vols. The Hague, 19 14. Wer\e. Edited by C. Gebhardt. 4 vols. Heidelberg, 1925. The Chief Wor\s. Translated by R. H. M. Elwes. New
New York,
Earlier
.
van Vloten
P.
J.
— York, — Wolf. — The — The
ed. 2 vols.
1955.
Philosophical
Writings.
Translated
by F.
A.
Hayes.
dianapolis, Ind., 1963. Ethics. Translated
.
by
W. H.
White. Edited by James Gutmann.
In-
New
1949.
Short Treatise on God,
.
.
.
New
Man and His
Well-Being. Translated by A.
York, 1963. Political Wor\s. Translated by A. G. Wernham. Oxford, 1958. Correspondence of Spinoza. Translated by A. Wolf. London,
Reprinted:
1928.
Studies Appuhn,
C. Spinoza. Paris, 1927.
Bidney, D.
The Psychology and
Ethics of Spinoza. 2d. ed.
New
York, 1962.
Brunschvicg, L. Spinoza et ses contemporains. 3d ed. Paris, 1923. Ecrits philosophiques. Paris, 1951. I, 109-78. .
"Le platonisme de Spinoza," Chronicon spinozanum,
III (1923). R. Spinoza. Paris, 1936. Couchoud, P. B. de Spinoza. Paris, 1902. Delbos, V. Le probleme moral dans la philosophic de Spinoza. Paris, 1893. .
Carre,
J.
.
Le spinozisme.
Paris, 19 16.
Duff, R. Spinoza's Ethical and Political Philosophy. Glasgow, 1903. Feuer, L. S. Spinoza and the Rise of Liberalism. Boston, 1958. Fischer, K. Spinoza, Leben,
Frances,
XVI
Wer\e, und Lehre. 5th
M. Spinoza dans e
les
ed. Heidelberg, 1909.
pays neerlandais de
siecle. Paris, 1937.
Gebhardt, C. Spinoza: Vier Reden. Heidelberg, 1927.
192
la
seconde moitie du
,
SPINOZA
193
Gilson, E.
Chronicon spinozanum,
"Spinoza interprete de Descartes,"
III
(1923)-
Gunn,
J.
A. Benedict Spinoza. Melbourne, 1925. F. Aeternitas. Oxford, 1930.
H.
Hallett,
Benedict de Spinoza. Oxford, 1957.
.
Emanation and Salvation. The Hague, 1962. Hampshire, Stuart. Spinoza. New ed. New York, 1961. Joachim, H. H. A Study of the Ethics of Spinoza. New .
Creation,
ed.
New
York,
1964. .
Spinoza's Tractatus
De
Intellectus
Emendatione: Commentary. Oxford,
1940.
Lagneau. "Notes sur Spinozisme," Revue de metaphysique, 1893. R. The Philosophy of Spinoza. New York, 1928. Oko, A. S. The Spinoza Bibliography. Boston, 1964.
McKeon,
Parkinson, G. H. R. Spinoza's Theory of Knowledge. Oxford, 1954. and Philosophy. 2d ed. London, 1899.
Pollock, F. Spinoza: His Life
Rivaud, A. "Documents inedits sur
la vie
de Spinoza," Revue de metaphysique
1934. Pp. 253-62.
Roth, L. Spinoza. London, 1929. Spinoza, Descartes, and Maimonides. .
ed. New York, 1963. Study in the Philosophy of
New
Saw, R. L. The Vindication of Metaphysics:
A
Spinoza. London, 195 1. Serouya, H. Spinoza, sa vie, sa philosophic 2d ed. Paris, 1947. Sullivan, C. J. Critical and Historical Reflections on Spinoza's Berkeley, Calif., 1958.
Wolfson, H. A. The Philosophy of Spinoza.
New
ed.
New
"Ethics."
York, 1950.
Studies Colerus.
Korte
dog
waarachtige
Levcns-Besckrybing
van
Benedictus
de
New
ed.
Spinoza. Amsterdam, 1705. Von Dunin-Borkowski, S. Spinoza.
Munich, 1933-36. Freudenthal,
1933.
J.
Band
II,
Band I, Der junge de Spinoza. Aus den Tagen Spinozas. 4 vols.
Die Lebensgeschichte Spinozas
Heidelberg, 1899. Spinoza, sein Leben .
und
in Quellenschriften
Miinster,
Ur\unden.
seine Lehre. 2 vols. Stuttgart, 1904.
Die Schriften des Uriel da Costa. (Bibliotheca spinozana, Vol. II.) Amsterdam, 1922. Meijer, W. "Wie sich Spinoza zu den Collegianten verhielt," Archiv fur Gebhardt, C.
die Geschichte der Philosophic,
Meinsma, K. O. Spinoza en
XV
zijn Kring.
(190 1-2).
The Hague,
1896.
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
194 Menzel.
"Spinoza und die Collegianten," Archiv fur die
Geschichte
der
XV
(190 1-2). "Spinoza et les heretiques de
Philosophic,
la communaute judeo-portugaise Revah, J. S. d'Amsterdam," Revue de Vhistoire des religions, 1958, pp. 173-218. Spinoza et le Docteur Juan de Prado. Paris, 1959. The Oldest Biography of Spinoza. Edited and translated by A. Wolf. London, .
1927.
II
Studies Gebhardt, C. Spinoza Abhandlung uber die Verbesserung des Verstandes. Eine entwic\lungsgeschichtliche Untersuchung. Heidelberg 1905. -
,
Leon, A. Les elements cartesiens de la doctrine spinoziste sur de la pensee a. son objet. Paris, 1909.
les
rapports
Ill
Studies Brehier, E. "Neoplatonisme et spinozisme," Etudes de philosophic antique. 1955. Pp. 289 ff. Brochard, V. "Le Dieu de Spinoza," in Etudes de philosophie ancienne et de philosophic modern. Paris, 1912. Pp. 332 ff.
Huan, G. Le Dieu de Spinoza. Arras,
1913.
Lachieze-Rey, P. Les origines cartesiennes du Dieu de Spinoza. Paris, 1932. Lasbax, E. La hierarchic dans Vunivers chez Spinoza. Paris, 19 19.
Rivaud, A. Les notions d'essence et d'existence dans
la
philosophie de Spinoza.
Paris, 1906.
IV Studies Baensch, O. "Die Entwicklung des Seelensbegriffs bei Spinoza als Grundlage fur das Verstandnis seiner Lehre vom Parallelismus der Attribute,"
XX
Archiv fur die gesamte Psychologic, Freudenthal, J. "Cber die Entwicklung Parallelismus (1907).
bei
Spinoza,"
(1918). der Lehre
von psychophysichen Archiv fur die gesamte Psychologic, IX
SPINOZA
195
V Studies Godfernaux, A. Mielisch, G.
De Spinoza
psychologies physiologiae antecessors Paris, 1894.
Quae de affectuum natura
et viribus
Spinoza docuit. (Disserta-
tion) Erlangen, 1900.
VI
Studies Brochard, V.
"L'eternite
ames dans
des
Etudes de philosophic ancienne Pp. 271
et
la
de Spinoza,"
philosophic
in
de philosophic moderne. Paris, 1912.
ff.
Dyroff, A. "Zur Entstehungsgeschichte der Lehre Spinozas
vom Amor Dei
Archiv fur die Geschichte der Philosophic, 1917. La morale de Spinoza. Paris, 1959.
intellectualis,"
Zac, S.
VII
Studies Bonifas. Les idees bibliques de Spinoza. (Thesis) Borrell, P.
"Spinoza interprete du judai'sme
et
du
Montauban,
1904.
christianisme," Annales de
philosophic chretienne, 19 12. Frances,
M. "La
liberte politique selon Spinoza,"
Revue philosophique, July-
September, 1958, pp. 317-37. Gebhardt, C. Spinoza als Politiker, in Proceedings of the Third International Congress of Philosophy.
Karppe,
S.
"Richard Simon
la philosophie. Paris,
et
Spinoza," in Essais de critique et d'histoire de
1902.
Rauh, F. Quatenus doctrina quam Spinoza de
fide exposuit
cum
tota
ejusdem
philo sophia cohaereat. Toulouse, 1890. Zac, S. "Societe et
communion chez
morale, April-September, 1958.
Spinoza," Revue de metaphysique et de
196
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
VIII
Studies
Van
der Linden, Spinoza, seine Lehre und deren erste Nachwir\ungen in Holland. 1862.
Yerniere, P. Spinoza et la pensee francaise avant la revolution. Paris, 1954.
MALEBRANCHE Life
i
pleted
and Wor\s
—with
born in Paris little
enthusiasm
theology at the College of
became
1659),
(1664),
—
1638, Nicolas
and except
Malebranche com-
courses in philosophy
his first
La Marche and
a novice in the Oratory (1600),
and
the Sorbonne
(1654—
was ordained
a priest
for occasional sojourns in the provinces, resided
in the Oratory of the to
in
Rue Saint-Honore
until his death.
He
is
said
have discovered the philosophy and method of Descartes in 1664,
upon reading the lished,
and
quivered.
to
treatise
On Man which La Forge had
just
pub-
have been so deeply moved by his discovery that he
Even
this
if
account
is
not true,
we
can be sure that
meditation on the works of Descartes awakened in interest in philosophy.
In 1674 he published the
first
him an volume
avid
of his
Search for Truth, followed in 1675 by the second volume, then by a third
volume
of Clarifications.
During
his lifetime the
work went
through several editions. Christian Conversations (1676), a sum-
mary
Due
of the Christian doctrine,
was published
at the request of the
de Chevreuse. His Short Meditations on Humility and Pen-
itence
(1677)
initiated a
polemic with Arnauld on grace. Male-
branche developed his theory of grace in his Treatise on Nature and
Grace (1680), which was censured by both Bossuet and the Jansenist.
"Pulchra,
Fenelon,
in
nova, falsa'/ wrote
Bossuet on his copy;
agreement with him, published 197
his
Refutation
and of
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
190
Malebranche's System concerning Nature and Grace, while Bos-
him
reproved
suet
publicly
in
funeral
the
oration
of
Marie
Therese. Arnauld, in turn, began by attacking Malebranche's philosophical theses in his
many
followed by
On True and
book
rejoinders
brought charges against Malebranche in
having less
book placed on the Index
his
False Ideas, which was
and counter-joinders; furthermore, he
Rome and
in 1690.
succeeded in
Malebranche neverthe-
defended his ideas by publishing the Treatise on Morals (1683),
Christian Meditations (1683),
and Religion hove
(1688). In 1697 he wrote his short Treatise on the
him with Bossuet in the famous quarrel His relations with M. de Lionne, a bishop who
God, which
of
and Conversations on Metaphysics
over quietism.
allied
served as a missionary in China, prompted the tract Conversation
between a Christian Philosopher and a Chinese Philosopher on the
God
Existence of
(1707). Finally, in 1714, Boursier's book,
tion of
God on
his last
work, Reflections on Physical Promotion.
The Ac-
from Malebranche
the Creature, elicited a reply
He
in
died in Octo-
ber, 1715.
Philosophy and Theology
11
"He maintained tranquillity,"
his personal integrity in
wrote Lelong after the death of Malebranche.
uniformly pure and
style, too, is
tumult as well as in
lively.
Without irony or
1
His
bitterness,
but always with the appropriate tone, he depicted the intellectual inconsistencies of
danger of
minds
men
solely
men,
especially those of scholars,
with "powerful imaginations"
who dominate weak who are
and imagination which
forcibly
which appealed
imposed
Malebranche's two great enemies. Inflexible in his
beliefs,
itself
new commentary on There 1
is
were
he yielded
neither to Bossuet nor to Arnauld; moreover, each of his
a
also the
through the vividness of their images and
responsible for all kinds of superstitions. Erudition to authority
and
works
is
the same themes.
nothing, according to Malebranche, that will not lead
Quoted by Blampignon, Etude
sw
Malebranche,
p. 40.
MALEBRANCHE
199
us to
God when
summation of life.
and
that
we
is
is
only a part of
re-
take his most celebrated theses: the theory of occa-
assumes that only the actions of
duped by our imagination
are
form whatsoever
—even
God
is
our sole
knowledge of material bodies
and meditation teaches us
that self-love, far
when he
leads him,
God. Malebranche's system things appear clearly to the
pend upon God
if
God are efficacious we attribute efficacy
to his creatures; the theory of the divine
origin of ideas assumes that, because
knowledge
from God,
the
is
essentially religious or rather
that living according to reason
To
sional causes
in any
which
his philosophy,
which assumes ligious
properly used as a basis for meditation. This
is
—leads
light,
any
us to him;
from separating man
has been enlightened, to the love of
which
a vast act of conversion in
mind and allow
us to see that
we
all
de-
"God is wholly everywhere," said St. Auguswhy we are able to remember him. Man remembers enough to turn toward God as toward the light which reaches him in some way even when he departs from it." Such thoughts
tine,
"and that
alone.
is
were the object of constant meditations dre Martin
(Ambrosius Victor),
in
in the Oratory. Father
An-
Sanctus Augustinus: de
his
Dei (1653), had brought together all of the eternal truth, identical with God, uncreated, im-
existentia et veritate saint's texts
mense, to
on
this
infinite, superior to
any created
intelligence, yet accessible
man's understanding through the rules of geometry or moral
precepts;
and he had contrasted the
which denied that
intellectualist theory
which sought truth
sensationalist theory
man
in
with the
sensible images
and
could attain through ethics anything other
than unstable precepts, or go beyond knowledge of bodies and whatever resembles bodies.
In minds so disposed,
tween the
this
Augustinianism. life
find
no exact
limit of philosophical thought
religious life;
gious
we
is
To
line of
and the
a resurgence of St.
demarcation bestarting point of
Bonaventure's
spirit
appreciate thoroughly the integration of
and philosophy, we must
recall the affinity of
of
reli-
Augustin-
ianism and Cartesianism which already existed long before the
appearance of Search for Truth. Descartes, even more forcefully
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
200
than
Augustine, separated the intellect from the senses, saw
St.
truth only in the intellect,
and grounded
leave
God and
face to face with
it
been alleged,
we can
itself.
and
Contrary to what has often
be sure that Malebranche did not find univer-
When
he entered the
make
Congregation, his superiors took every precaution to
was
that the only doctrine taught
generally accepted
ascetic
the sensible world
sympathy for Descartes in the Oratory.
sal
on
his philosophy
mind from
practices designed to isolate the
and necessary
certain
that of Aristotle, "the only one
for students."
2
But
their precau-
tions prove that there existed a current favorable to the idealistic
One
views of Plato and Descartes.
thing
is
certain
—Malebranche's
profound admiration for Descartes. In 1673 he retracted the signature which he, along with all the others in the Oratory, had affixed to
an anti-Cartesian statement.
He
nevertheless
He
abandoned a
certain
number
of Cartesian doc-
has an idea of
God is the creator of eternal truths, that man God, that man has a clear and distinct idea of his
soul, that soul
and body
trines.
That
his negations
accord lation
denied that
is
and the general
easily discernible: truth
God
between soul and
sented by an idea; ourselves.
general
are united through
we
is
spirit of
is
mutual
interaction.
Augustinianism are in
uncreated and infinite; the
God
immediate;
find only obscurity
re-
cannot be repre-
when we
retire
within
His negations are equally consonant, however, with one
trait
observable in the evolution of Cartesianism.
type of clear and distinct idea
mechanics in physics: anything that
serves as the basis of
extension or
number
is
The
the notion of extension,
not within the province of
is
human
only
which is
not
under-
standing. Malebranche expressed his point of view clearly when,
toward the end of
work and took
his career,
issue
with Spinoza. "To demonstrate," he
to develop a clear idea
and
idea necessarily includes;
enough tension 2
to be
he commented on the whole of his
to
and
it
said, "is
deduce with certainty whatever the
seems
to
me
that the only ideas clear
used in accomplishing demonstrations are those of ex-
and numbers. Not even
the soul has any
Quoted by G. Gouhier, La vocation de Malebranche,
knowledge
p. 53.
of itself;
MALEBRANCHE
201 it
has only an inward awareness of
even
ing
finite, it is
ity.
... As for me,
regarding
capable of
less I
am
I
owe
I
mainly
it
modifications. Be-
its
knowing the attributes of infindogmas of faith in things
certain for a thousand reasons that
they are solidly grounded; and verity,
and
build only on the
because
faith,
itself
to
if
these
have discovered a theological
I
dogmas."
Here we
3
warned: apart from mathematics and physics, nothing strable because tions; this
we have no
clear idea of the basis of
demon-
our demonstra-
the antithesis of the view of Leibniz,
is
duly
are is
who was
con-
vinced that metaphysical truths are demonstrable. It
would seem
two points of view: that of the theologian who draws
from dogmas and and
and
grace,
tries to
who works
that of the scientist
theologians
—Arnauld,
is
with physics and
by no means so simple, for contem-
and
Bossuet,
Fenelon
Malebranche mainly because he placed too much
As
of reason.
early as 1671 Rohault advised
own
point of view, the warning
stress
thesis: reason or the
makes
little
sense. All of
men and who lated,
despite
God who became
flesh in
mysteries
incomprehensible
and thought and philosophical
example, prayers like a prayer
with truth. essentially
man 3
elicit
grace,
which the
The
no
to
the
different
life
and the attention
Word
identical
order to save is
trans-
human mind, exists
between
and thought. For of the scientist
is
answers by illuminating his mind
steps followed
by
God
in creating the
world are
from the methodical process through which
understands nature.
"To
"Correspondance avec Mairan,"
P-345-
is
bestows on them divine grace. This identity
through an analogous relationship that somehow religious life
governed
is
inward word that illuminates
the meditations of the mathematician and the physicist
with the Word, the Son of
role
him not to shock peoif we assume Male-
Malebranche's philosophical and religious speculation
by the following
—censured
on the
But
ple by appearing to miscere sacra profanis.
branche's
his inspiration
understand the divine scheme of nature
mathematics. But the question porary
embraces
to follow that Malebranche's philosophy
consider the properties of extension
in Cousin,
Fragments de philosophic cartcsienne,
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
202
Malebranche, "we must begin, like Descartes, with
in order," writes
and pass from the simplest
their simplest relations
the most
to
this way of examining our ideas and mind and is simplest, but also because it
complex, not only because their relations helps the will give us a better
understanding of the works of God, inasmuch
he always chooses the shortest course and
as
4
manner."
And,
in a
review of his whole system, he called attention
"new philosophy" and
the identity of the
to
new philosophy
called
overturns
in complete
For
religion.
cause."
The two
if
new
gion, the
harmony with
the
"The
religion:
so-
the reasons of the freethinkers
all
through the establishment of the greatest of is
an orderly
in
acts
first
its
principles,
which
principle of the Christian
religion teaches us that there
is
but one true
philosophy shows us that there
is
reli-
but one true
5
influence of the
new
spirit is
seen in his theology, which has
principles that are basically identical:
God
through
acts only
general manifestations of his will, and he acts through the simplest
ways.
We
same thing when we say
are stating the
cerned only with himself all his acts,
and
consequences of
when he
acts, that "his
that
God
is
that he wishes only to manifest his attributes. this principle are
con-
glory" determines
The
obvious: Christian theology seems
in effect to posit "particular" manifestations of the divine will in
the sense intended by Malebranche.
Incarnation as a consequence of
For
Adam's
instance, sin
and
ransoming man; miracles, which are contrary of nature, also will; the
seem
to
God
willed the
for the purpose of
to the ordinary course
be particular manifestations of the divine
same thing applies
to the election of those saved
by grace.
Malebranche, on the other hand, in his interpretation of these dogmas,
tries to
explain
them without
lar manifestation of his will.
problem of
attributing to
maximum and minimum:
the problem
the greatest effect by the simplest means, particular end. 4
5
and
incarnation of the Son of
la Verite, Book VI, Part Two, chap, Book VI, Part Two, chap, iii, 68.
Recherche de Ibid.,
The
God any
Creation, for example,
this
God
iv, ed.
is
was
to
particu-
God
a
to obtain
excluded any is
independent
Bouillier,
II,
72.
—
MALEBRANCHE
203
man; the redemption is its result and not its end; the incarnation would have taken place even if Adam had not sinned because the world would otherwise have been a production of the redemption of
unworthy of God. Miracles themselves inasmuch
into the
fit
scheme of things
with respect to the
as they are objects of a particular will
laws of nature and therefore are included in the more general laws of the
Kingdom
For Grace too
of Grace.
most deeply the theologians of
(this
his time) has
Kingdom God had willed a
scandalous to assume that the
Adam's
to
sin
and
that
sequences would be
He
Kingdom
of Grace
through an absolutely general act of will through which he produced nature Malebranche's aim
the part that stirred
of Grace was subordinate
world, one of whose con-
Kingdom
of Grace.
—the kingship of Christ
to
which even the
act of will
subordinate.
is
obvious: to eliminate from
is
would be
laws. It
its
order to establish the
sin, in
willed instead the
is
Christianity
everything that makes the vision of the universe a veritable drama characterized by unforeseeable initiatives, everything that
He
an actual history characterized by accidents.
is
makes
it
not trying to
submerge Christianity (following a pattern now familiar
to us) in
drama become the divine reality and in which
a metaphysics in which the events of the sacred
necessary
moments
physics
indistinguishable
is
with the Cartesian
in the evolution of a
from theology; but he seeks
which
spirit
and
it
sees at the heart of reality only a
reason acting methodically and by isolate the clear
to infuse
own
its
initiative,
and which can
distinct ideas that will provide
man
with a
physics independent of theology.
One
difficulty
remains
is
:
not original
sin,
Christian faith transformed the conditions of
unforeseeable initiatives that do not
Malebranche's study of the soul the outset by the to
dogma
of original
misconstrue his conclusions
made
if
we
fit
is
which according
human
into the
life,
to the
one of the
scheme of things?
dominated wholly and from
sin,
and
it
would be easy
failed to realize that
for us
he always
two psychologies: Adam's psychology and Adam's psychology after his sin, which is our
a distinction between
before his sin,
own. Our psychology
is
characterized by the dependence of the
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
204 soul,
which has become
upon the body.
passions,
and of the
a plaything of the imagination
dependence which we experience
this
It is
continuously and which the Search for Truth describes in detail.
Reason, however,
inasmuch
us that this dependence contradicts order
tells
as the soul
is
superior in perfection to the body: normally
Thus "experience
the body ought to obey the soul.
proof that things are not as our reason
and
it is
its
transmission to
abnormal, confused psychology that the
body
things
is
men
all
ours.
is
adequate
us they ought to be,
tells
Only Adam's
ridiculous to philosophize against experience."
and the dogma of
sin
offers
can explain the
The predominance
of
the effect of sin. But sin did not change the scheme of
and Malebranche
will
show
that confusion
the consequence
is
of universal laws themselves, not of a modification in the conduct
God toward man
of
Human
in
following Adam's
sin.
Nature
Malebranche
belong to
attributes to the soul faculties that
it
in-
dependently of any connection with the body: understanding, which is
the faculty to receive ideas,
motion of the soul, the
two
soul. Since
faculties
and
inclination,
we have no
clear
which
and
to the body,
and
idea; understanding
inclination
Both before and
the natural
distinct idea of the
can be understood only by analogy with the
modalities of extension, the only object of which
and unmistakable
is
after
is
is
to the soul
Adam's
sin,
we have
to the soul
what motion
these faculties
a clear
what shape is
is
to the body.
were operative
only in connection with certain modifications of the soul caused by its
union with the body. Intellection
is
always accompanied by im-
ages that originate in the senses, just as inclinations are always ac-
companied by
passions,
which
are to inclinations
are to pure understanding. Inclinations are the
and
so
is
there are
what the
same
senses
in everyone,
understanding; by contrast, depending on the individual,
many
varieties of passions
and
sensations. Prior to sin,
imagination was subservient to understanding, just as passions were subservient to right inclinations.
We
know
that the
image has a
MALEBRANCHE
205
double role in Cartesian psychology: as
when
at times
a cause of error,
it is
the senses deceive us with respect to the distance of the
sun; at times
it is
an aid
when
to the intellect, as
to a state in
which, before the Fall, the image was always an aid,
which man, capable of directing
and
in
how
to eliminate useless or
The same
the intellect uses
Malebranche referred
straight lines to represent abstract quantities.
his attention at will,
knew
harmful sensations.
applies to passions: a passion implies a prior determi-
nation of inclination or will toward an object which the will represents as
good or toward an
represents as evil,
and
this
of love, desire, or aversion.
the union of soul a
way
determination
is
accompanied by feelings
Only then do passions
and body, the animal
spirits
by virtue of
arise;
move about
body in the proper position
as to put the
one which the will
object contrary to the
to unite
in such
with good
or to shun evil; and this motion generates in the soul an emotion
accompanied by feelings of love or hatred much more intense than those that accompanied simple inclination. to the order of nature,
Thus
passions belong
and before the Fall they had no
role other
than that of reinforcing right inclinations; but in the same way
and
in accordance with the
that have It
same
laws, they reinforce inclinations
become bad and depraved. and body,
follows that sin did not create the union of soul
whose laws remained
identical before
change the union into a dependence. ing, even
though
it
did not participate in
the free initiative of the will,
degree that
though
it
its
lost
and
It also
exercise
none of
its
clear
and
it
did
follows that understand-
sin,
which was a
was nevertheless
depended on
but
after the Fall,
affected
by
result of it
to the
attention, a faculty of the will; distinct ideas,
ously submerged in the flow of images. This
is
it
was continu-
the state depicted
by Malebranche in the Search for Truth, in which
five of the six
books are devoted to an investigation of the causes of errors in the senses, imagination, understanding, inclinations,
Man
subjects
his
and
judgments of material things
wrongly assuming that the senses give him the
passions. to
the senses,
real qualities of
things instead of expressing the relations of things to our
own
bod-
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
206
Imagination depends
ies.
on the constitution of the brain;
first
women,
that are too delicate, like those found in tal application, for
they cannot resist the invasion of images; fibers
that are too hard, like those
images to
settle,
fibers
any men-
rule out
found in old people, do not allow new
with the result that an old
man
is
dominated by
Imagination also depends on properties acquired by the
his past.
brain: animal spirits follow
most
easily routes that they
have
al-
ready traveled. This accounts for the kind of spiritual inertia that gives us the illusion of finding again in
already know.
based on our
It also first,
tion. Finally, a
with a weak imagination
we
men
dependent on
is
seduced by poets, orators, writers,
is
who impose upon him images and beliefs. also susceptible to errors when it fails to dom-
storytellers
The understanding
is
mainly in taking abstractions
inate images: such errors consist real, in
the things that
irradicable impressions acquired through educa-
man
with powerful imagination; he
and simple
new things
accounts for our absurd respect for authority,
introducing into things
all
to be
the powers of occult forces which
Scholastics accept as explanations.
As of
for inclination,
depravation through original sin
our errors. Inclination,
all
The motion tinct idea
God
its
of the soul
—no
more
is
will, love
—
all
is
the basis
are one to Malebranche.
not apprehended through a clear and
so than
any other mental faculty
—but
dis-
since
has his end in himself, he could not have given to the soul any
impulsion other than toward universal order, toward good in general.
"The
desire for formal beatitude or for pleasure in general
the gist or essence of the will to the degree that
ing the good." This impulsion includes love of
we
capable of lov-
it is
self:
is
"God
wills that
should will the perfection of our being through the invincible
love that he has for immutable order." In the theological controver-
over quietism, Malebranche takes a decisive stand against the
sies
advocates of disinterested love
excluded love of
God
puts in me],
self like
Sin
is
self.
who
"Through
when
the Stoic sage,
I
I
put
it
pretended that true love of
this [natural love for
to
good use instead
seek only him,
I
God
myself that
of pleasing
my-
tend only toward him."
precisely the misuse of such love. Since
God
has
endowed man
MALEBRANCHE
207
with a motion that carries him toward the universal good, he always has enough power to go beyond particular goods presented to
by
But suppose he
his understanding.
the will
—a failure of the will
love of self gives
way
ward
good the
a particular
Man
universal good. also free to is
still it
arrests his will in the presence
Thus
of a particular good: then he sins.
sin
is
a kind of failure of
Then
power.
to exercise its full
to vanity
and concupiscence;
man
him
force that has been given to
and cause
it
to deviate. In either case, his
not the creation of a force, for
tesian physics the deviation of a
we know
true
turns tofor the
free to follow the divine impulsion;
is
him
he
is
freedom
that according to Car-
motion requires no supplementary
force.
Foremost among these deviate inclinations which give errors are the desire for limits of
rise
to
knowledge, which spurs us on beyond the
our minds, the desire to appear wise, which produces the
love of paradox,
and the individual friendships
that cause us to ap-
prove the thoughts of others uncritically. In the absence of a clear and distinct idea of the mind, the
dogma
of original sin then allowed Malebranche to obtain in psychology a result
analogous to the result reached by Descartes in physics: with
his clear
and
distinct idea of extension, Descartes substituted for the
confusion of sensible qualities a mechanistic physics in which the
mind sin,
proceeds in an orderly fashion; with the
dogma
of original
Malebranche, in order to understand the disordered complica-
tions of
our inner
life,
made
defines the relations of soul,
of nature; the soul
the body. This
is
use of a normative psychology which
God, and body according
to the order
God and
in control of
then in subservience to
dogma,
like all the others,
enabled
him
to introduce
order and reason into his interpretation of the universe.
Malebranche's moral philosophy conception of
human
through principles curved nius
lines
is
to
is
wholly dependent upon his
nature. "Ethics demonstrated to
and explained
knowledge of man what knowledge of
knowledge of
and Archimedes are
the relations of
is
straight lines";
to Euclid.
it
is
Mathematics has
what Apolloits
source in
magnitude which the mind contemplates in the
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
208
Word;
divine
perfection which are no tions of
from the contemplation of
ethics derives
magnitude.
are four, that
immutable and
relations of
certain than the rela-
can see with equal clearness that two and two
I
mind
less
superior to matter,
is
estimable than a stone and
and
that a beast
more
is
estimable than a man. Moral virtue
less
made
begins with sustained attentiveness,
by sin and per-
difficult
haps impossible by the absence of grace, which allows us to see the
immutable order of perfection and to
conform
to
it;
the difficulty
An
the light appears." the sight of
God
to cause our conduct, like God's,
in "always suspending assent until
is
and
act will be meritorious
will justify us in
when accomplished through
only
love of order
based on our vision of relations of perfection. Love of order
mon
to all
men and
subsists
our vision of order that
is
is
com-
even in the greatest sinners; thus
it is
rendered impossible by the depravity of
our inclinations, and only inner meditation, together with the suspension of action associated with
The
mind
the mind," that
is,
ments of the world from at every
moment
to listen
same language." These
virtues of the pagans:
often
is
Freedom
in order to gain the
belief
is
the understanding
is
in "retiring within oneself
virtues are quite different
from the
the injuries inflicted It is
uses false
upon
his laziness that
his Stoic pride that consoles
that an effort of the will as,
of
by sentiment
and determine whether inner truth
neither moderate nor patient.
own
life
consists in hearing the judg-
and
all sides
out meditation upon order, just
iv
work
"One who endures
makes him immobile and branche's
to
in not letting oneself be misled
but in arriving at clear ideas.
him
power and freedom. Power
cardinal virtues then are mental
consists in "putting the
the
can combat this depravity.
it,
is
him." Male-
impossible with-
in the sciences,
all
the
work
of
unproductive without method.
Occasional Causes
Even before Malebranche,
of course,
the theory of occasional causes.
To
identical with simple extension
was
belong to the body since
it
many
Cartesians arrived at
consider a physical body as being to say that
was not contained
motive force did not
in the notion of exten-
MALEBRANCHE
209
sion. Indeed, Descartes
God at
motion with
identified the first cause of
and, adopting the thesis of continuous creation, assumed that
moment
each
modes
other hand,
On
must be repeated.
in time the divine act
(idea or feeling in thought,
the
motion in exten-
sion) always imply substance in the Cartesian sense, but substance
never implies the effective existence of this or of that mode; consequently the existence of a
mode
is
due
an
to
efficient
cause alien to
substance which (unlike the substance of Aristotle or of Leibniz) receives
its
modes without producing them.
Finally, as
presented
it is
by Descartes, the distinction between soul and body makes any kind
two substances
of interaction between the
and the
unintelligible,
—in sensations, passions, or —necessitates recourse to a cause superior to both. Fur-
correspondence that exists between them voluntary acts
thermore, the paradigm of mathematical intelligibility consists in constant relations which do not contain the idea of any efficient
power.
Malebranche uses
all
belief that creatures
only through
its
have
idea,
common
of these arguments to refute the efficient
and
powers.
We
can judge a thing
obvious that extension does not
is
it
embrace a motive force or a force capable of producing modificamind. But Malebranche goes further in
tions in the
Considering independently the idea of to act,
he shows that
true cause it
and
is
its effect."
condition.
this
such that the
Any
Only the
mind
perceives a necessary link between
will of is
body can be modified through itself
his analysis.
cause or of power
notion includes something divine, for "a
true causality
pable of creating
efficient
an omnipotent being
satisfies this
essentially creative: to say that the
its
own power
is
to say that
it is
ca-
with modifications different from those willed
by God. Belief in the efficacy of natural causes
and
Aristotle's doctrine
was but one
that this analysis alone enables causality in the soul even stance.
He
was
of
its
at the root of
forms.
Malebranche
though he has no
to
We
paganism,
should note
deny any
efficient
clear idea of this sub-
goes even further than his predecessors and denies
not only any power over the body but also any power over
it
itself.
—
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
210
(Freedom,
Thus he
we saw
as
earlier,
not a true power of the soul.)
is
puts on the same plane the philosophical exigency of in-
telligibility
and the
religious notion of the powerlessness of created
beings.
The
affirmation that
God
alone
an
is
A
such a theory.
cause
efficient
complete theory of occasional causes, but
is
it
a
first
not the
is
toward
step
on the part of the Muslim
similar affirmation
theologians of the ninth century introduced discontinuity and arbitrariness into the universe.
who
fore acts through versal
laws.
of Malebranche
in the simplest
immutable decrees and
a
is
ways and who
God
there-
in accordance with uni-
Furthermore, these laws produce the most varied a mathematical function, while yet preserving
results, just as
identity,
God
But the
and proceeds
loves order
when
assumes different values
Here the
to the variable.
such conditions
variable
—and the constant
is
event
this or that particular
is
meeting of two bodies that
for example, the
its
different values are assigned
collide
under such and
the laws by which motions are
moment to assume determinate The collision is then said to be the
imparted, causing the bodies at this speeds in a determinate direction.
occasional or natural cause of the motion.
not a
natural cause then
cause but only an occasional cause, and
real, true
author of nature act in
God
A
this or that
manner on
is
makes the
it
this or that occasion;
continuously adjusts the efficacy of his action to the state of his
creation.
That
is
enough
to satisfy experience,
which requires only
a constant relation between the modalities of nature
herent power to It is clear
that experience
constant relation. state the
from the
and not an
in-
act.
To
is
indispensable to the discovery of this
state that
God
has a constant will
nature of his will in addition. Descartes
not to
is
deduced
its
laws
which
is
itself
rule of the conservation of motion, a rule
based on the principle "that the action of the creator must bear the
stamp of
his immutability." "Nevertheless," says
perience has convinced us that Descartes
metaphysical principle of his opinion clusion that he draws
from
it is
is
is
Malebranche, "ex-
wrong, not because the
false
but because the con-
not true, even though at
first
glance
MALEBRANCHE
211 it
seems highly probable" {Search,
II,
Thus
397).
in 1698, in re-
sponse to Leibniz* criticism, Malebranche changed the laws of impact
which he had based on the principle of the conservation of
motion in the
The notion
first
of occasional cause, therefore,
When
notion of law.
and body,
edition of his Search.
linked closely to the
is
Malebranche, speaking of the union of soul
God
says that in sensation or passion
has established
certain modifications of the body which are the occasional causes
of certain modifications of the soul, or that
God
has established in
the will certain thoughts which are the occasional causes of certain
motions, by the same token he
is
teaching the existence of laws
governing the union of soul and body, and these are the laws he tries
to
determine through his psychophysiological investigations
which play such an important part in is
his
work. Moreover, a thought
the occasional cause of another thought in the soul; consequently
the soul also has constant laws. of these laws
Malebranche
calls attention to
—the one which holds that attentiveness
by the perception of
is
no man achieves
clear ideas. Finally,
vided
it is
God
his actions (prayers or
good works) that have pro-
him
with the occasions for bestowing grace on
cordance with certain laws
unknown
justifica-
on him by
tion independently but only through merit conferred
grace; yet
one
accompanied
in ac-
to us.
Occasionalism, far from assuming a "perpetual miracle" (Leibniz* criticism),
is
whose laws v
The
therefore inseparable
rigidly determine the
X attire
of
All Things in
from
whole
a
deterministic doctrine
series of events.
6
Knowledge and Seeing
God
All the philosophers inspired by Descartes dealt with the different
"kinds of knowledge"; like Spinoza, however, they accepted the clear
and
distinct idea as the
viewed any other knowledge
paradigm of perfect knowledge and
as
an obscure and indistinct
Malebranche was a great innovator. In his work •Principal texts: Recherche,
v and
vi: Entretiens, vii.
Book VI, Part Two, chap,
iii;
we
idea.
Here
find neither
Meditations chreuennes,
—
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
212
and
the notion of an obscure
whatever
is
indistinct idea nor the thesis that
known through
not
a clear
and
distinct idea
through an obscure and indistinct idea. Whatever
through a idea.
and
clear
distinct idea is not
Here we find an
known known
is
not
is
known through any kind
of
implicit criticism of Cartesianism, for Male-
branche implied that his concept of ideas was quite different from Descartes'.
To
Descartes, ideas were "images" of things
which con-
tained "objectively" whatever things contained "formally," objective existence being an inferior degree of formal existence. rejected such a distinction,
word
tributed to the
model.
It is
which seemed obscure
result that things
finite
the
for
at-
"idea" only the Platonic sense of archetype or
must be judged according to
assume three
knowledge: from things themselves
God,
Malebranche him, and
only in this sense that ideas represent things, with the
Malebranche had of
to
it is
can see
to their ideas.
different
—for
ways
of
Thus
acquiring
example, our knowledge
obvious that he has no archetype and that the In-
itself
only in
knowledge we have of
itself;
"all
from awareness or inner
feeling
things that are indistinguishable in-
dependently" and the only knowledge
we have
from our ideas of things
that pertains exclusively to
things different as
—knowledge
from ourselves and unknowable
our knowledge of natural bodies.
that the
knowledge of bodies
to
It is
of our souls;
and
in themselves, such
important for us to note
which Malebranche here
refers is
not the analytical knowledge of the physicist but ordinary perception of external bodies. If ideas are
was bound
the archetypes of things they represent, Malebranche
to arrive at the celebrated thesis of seeing all things in
God. Ideas cannot be the hovering species which Democritus made
an intermediary between body and mind. Ideas are not creatures
when one
of the mind, for an idea, senses, appears as a
much
of a cube are
both
realities
resist the
two things
no longer a prisoner
of the
truer reality than the material thing
represents. It has properties
which somehow
is
which the mind discovers
in
it
it
and
mind. The idea of a square and the idea
and to make mind would be to
that exhibit real differences,
depend upon one
creative act of the
MALEBRANCHE
213
attribute to
it
Nor can
the omnipotence of God.
it
be said that these
ideas are innate in the soul, for they appear to the soul
and
the other in the succession of our perceptions;
assumed
to be present in the soul, they
also the
power
if
would have
to choose within this chaotic state.
one
after
they were
all
to be accorded
The
process of
elimination leaves only one possible hypothesis: they are seen directly in
God. God must have within himself the ideas of
human
beings he has created; in addition, the
mediately with
God and
ways by revealing
God
the
acts in the sim-
an external
to us in himself the idea of
moment when this body nally, on our own bodies. Seeing all things in God was the
body
all
united im-
is
always sees a particular, determinate being
only as a limitation in infinite Being. Finally, plest
soul
produces
at the
its
impression, exter-
subject of an ardent polemic
with the Cartesians Arnauld and Regis, for criticism of Malebranche on
this point
was always made
Arnauld, though not very receptive
in the
to
initiated his
Malebranche's theses on
to his attention a year earlier.
polemic against seeing
On True and theses
of Descartes.
Nature and Grace (1680),
grace, did not reply to his Treatise on
which Malebranche had brought
name
things in
all
God
He
with the book
False Ideas (1683); not until 1685 did he attack the
on grace. Regis, who had supported Arnauld's opinion
in his
System of Philosophy, engaged in a discussion with Malebranche in 1694. In the
long
series of rejoinders
and
counter-rejoinders, the
same arguments often reappear. One common postulate to
Descartes separates
stated
Malebranche from
by Arnauld as follows:
we
to determine the nature
is
ception of is
it;
the
known
No
and origin of object
is is
our ideas [and
one thinks of denying
acquired through ideas.
Arnauld, the idea of an object
was
see immediately and which are
the immediate object of our thought."
knowledge of bodies
attributable
adversaries. It
"It is quite true that
not bodies] are the things which that
his
no
The
sole
aim
is
these ideas. According to
different
from the
identical with the act
soul's per-
by which
it
known. This unique thing, this perception-idea, has only two
relations:
one
to the soul that
it
modifies (perception), the other to
—
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
214
the thing perceived in so far as
it
exists objectively in the
under-
standing (idea). Here objective existence designates the manner in
which
"objects are
perfect
manner
an
wont
to exist in the
mind," a "much more im-
of being than that through
existent." Perception,
the soul; consequently an idea
object
is
really
a modification of
is
also a modification of the soul. It
is
follows that the origin of ideas
adequately explained by the fac-
is
which God has endowed our minds. The
ulty of seeing bodies, with
thesis that all things are seen in ficulty, since it entails
which an
Malebranche agrees,
God
involves one very great dif-
the admission that there are in
particular ideas as there are bodies, each with
its
God
as
many
contingent modali-
ties.
Malebranche answers both questions: the
between perception and
tinction
by making a
first
dis-
by advancing the
idea, the second
theory of intelligible extension.
The
difference
to Regis,
seems
knowing
subjects
between ideas and perception, Malebranche wrote clear "as the difference
as
between ourselves
and the knowledge we acquire." The
as
contrast
is
we have no clear and distinct Our modalities, such as pleasure and sorrow or perception we have of our ideas, are obscure in so far as we
indeed striking. As knowing subjects, idea of ourselves.
even the
ourselves are concerned.
him, is
is
clear
soul.
Man's substance,
unintelligible to him. In contrast,
and
distinct,
For example,
I
and
I
know
know
if it
as
were a mode of if
my
soul, for a
this
Furthermore, Malebranche's reply to the related to his reply to the second.
For
the
mind
(as
Arnauld supposed) but rather an it
from
my
this
mode cannot
thesis
its
would be be ap-
could be dem-
ideas could be seen in the soul as distinctly as
roundness can be seen in extension, and
then
distinct
from myself, and
prehended apart from substance. Arnauld's onstrated only
—an idea
what we know
something
the idea of a square together with
properties as something distinct
impossible
it
from enlightening
far
if it
is
first
question
is
closely
can be demonstrated that
really perceives not finite, limited,
will follow that the idea
not possible.
is
and contingent bodies
infinite intelligible extension,
to the soul
what the
infinite
is
MALEBRANCHE
215
mind, which
to the finite; the
duce a finite
mode
is
finite,
lacks the capacity to pro-
such as intelligible extension, which
does not have enough reality to imagine
His argument bodies
valid only
is
if
constituted not by as
is
"The
is infinite.
the infinite."
the true object of the perception of
many
particular ideas as there are
To
bodies but by a unique idea, the idea of intelligible extension.
understand Malebranche's thinking on
point,
this
it
which
singular bodies, as in
are merely
geometry a body
extension.
its
limitations. In physics as well
determined by a limit in a pre-existing
Our knowledge
of the physical world, therefore, does not
to the
whole;
it
does not consist in placing in juxta-
which the world
position with one another the finite bodies of It
goes from the whole to the parts;
ning only in
infinity.
is
a kind of universal
is
extracted in
a
Furthermore, according
some way from an
summation of
it
some way over
from
it
which the
this
it
an
applies to
—beyond
implies
particu-
not the result of
is
infinite
number
the particular ideas
—the idea of universal or infinite being
diffused
particular ideas. This generality cannot be
ourselves, for
is
begin-
Malebranche,
to
infinite source
particular ideas, for
which exemplify
its
law of knowledge: any particular knowledge
of such ideas; consequently
in
can have
it
knowledge determines. Thus a general idea
lar
prior to
is
is
go from parts the sum.
necessary
is
for us to recall that extension, according to Descartes,
we
are particular beings.
ternal bodies obeys a general rule,
The
drawing
drawn
perception of ex-
support from the
its
apprehension of intelligible extension, which, according to Cartesian physics, constitutes the archetype of the
unique idea are.
Here
to
which we must turn in order
to find out
any knowledge, the thought of
as in
prior to the
world of bodies
immediate union of the soul with
only by virtue of this union. of course, for
it
Not
infinity
God and
—the
what they is
always
can exist
that the soul understands infinity,
can be perceived without being understood; that
a particular body
is
limited for us in an extension
is,
which we perceive
—an extension without limits but with a positive infinitude that we can nevertheless apprehend.
The
epistemological thesis, however,
was matched,
perforce, by a
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
2l6
new
theological thesis that gave rise to is
not a creature since
everything which
it
infinite;
God forms
in
is
is
ligible extension is to see the
attacks. Intelligible extension
it
God. But
therefore in
is
if
part of his essence, to see intel-
very essence of
God—an
unacceptable
but necessary consequence which Malebranche's adversaries used
He
against him.
replied by introducing a concept of infinity wholly
inspired by mathematics. In the seventeenth century the concept of
had become
infinity
sumed
be infinite only in relation to each other.
to
example, can be viewed as an infinite
word "infinity" does not necessarily Only God is not infinite in a relative
when
considered independently, he extension
telligible
quently,
God
relation
to
extension
were
relative; infinities of different orders
sum
A
as-
finite line, for
of infinitesimal lines; the
designate the whole of reality. sense, for is
he contains
infinitely
all
infinite.
being;
But
in-
simply the archetype of bodies and, conse-
is
not here considered independently but only in his
is
When we
possible material creatures.
we do
see
intelligible
not see the essence of God: "Essence means the
absolute being [infinitely infinite] that represents nothing finite";
we
God
only see the substance of
"considered in relation to
creatures or in so far as they participate in
In
it."
world seen in
the thesis of the intelligible
all
God
there remains
one singularity that attracted the attention of Malebranche's contemporaries. Descartes
had managed
ciple of his physics only
sensible perceptions;
mon
to posit extension as the prin-
by using methodical doubt
to eliminate
through the concept of extension, then, com-
perception was excluded from this wholly intellectual knowl-
edge. But
common
perception
is
precisely
to explain. If intelligible extension
which
lacks
—which
is
single
and continuous,
any variation or modification, and which
any sensible properties in physics,
what Malebranche sought
it is
—
is
hard for us
is
deprived of
the principle of intellectual
knowledge
to see
how
it
could produce the variety
of perceptions that reveal to us a multitude of separate bodies en-
dowed with
sensible qualities
branche explains
common
accomplished by Descartes,
which make them
distinct.
Male-
perception by reversing the operation
who through
analysis
had
isolated ex-
MALEBRANCHE
217 tension the
from the
two things and
smell,
so
qualities, are
forth
—which,
tions are purely
is
no knowledge.
It
color,
He
stresses the contrast be-
the object of an idea, whereas sensa-
would be
sound
—of
considered by themselves, as
and simply modalities of the
to the sensation of rejects
when
not related to extension.
tween the two: extension yield
Malebranche considers
rest of sensible perception.
separately: first extension, then sensations
futile, for
soul, feelings
example, for us to turn
out what sound really
to find
which
is;
acoustics
any sensation of sound and substitutes instead the study of
intelligible
to give us
mathematical
relations.
and
sensations
If
feelings fail
any knowledge of things, they are connected according
to precise laws (laws of the
union of soul and body)
to states of
our
bodies and their relations with external bodies, with the result that the external bodies are their (occasional) causes. These laws, established in the interest of the preservation of the body,
against the dangers
it
a dissociation even
Descartes (inasmuch as sensation at all),
Malebranche
is
more
rigid than that of
not confused knowledge but no
still
how
has to determine
God
two
body
is
perceived as an intelligible figure in unintelligible extension, for applies intelligible extension to our
on the diverse
relations that exist
minds
diversely,
depending
between our bodies and external
bodies. Modalities of the soul or sensations,
moment, extend through
may
the
A
elements join together to produce external perception. first
the soul
can incur.
Having accomplished knowledge
warn
produced
at the
same
bodies; moreover, each limited extension
contain several sensible qualities which
somehow
interpenetrate,
for the property of being extended belongs essentially to
none of
them.
"Man
is
often ignorant of things he thinks he knows,
knows well certain The perception of vides us with
things about which he thought he
bodies
knowledge
lishes in us a relationship
is
proof of
this:
of the external world, but
with the archetype of
and with the modalities
of our soul.
the external world
no sense given; nor can
is
in
It
had no
we imagine this
it
that
and he ideas." it
pro-
only estab-
world in God,
follows that the existence of it
be demonstrated,
"
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
2l8
as can the existence of a cause of
no
efficacy other
our sensations, since
than that of God;
it is
we apprehend
established only by the reve-
lation of sacred writings.
This
final
doubt gave
rise to the last
his correspondence (1713-1714)
his thesis to Spinoza's. "It seems to
writer's errors,"
polemic of Malebranche in
with Mairan,
me
who
that the
tried to reduce
main cause
of this
wrote Malebranche, "go back to the fact that he
mistakes the ideas of creatures for creatures themselves and of bodies
and assumes
for bodies themselves selves."
But
if
anyone
Mairan, because he telligible
is
in error
is
God and
word
modes.
intelligible,"
intelligible,"
is
Malebranche, according to
incapable of seeing any distinction between in-
extension which
God and
in
is
extended material bodies,
made by Spinoza between
other than the distinction of
that they can be seen in themit
"We must
not
let
the attribute
ourselves be fascinated by the
he wrote. "The essences of things are purely
and there
really
is
no
distinction
between the extension
contained in the concept of body and the extension called intelligible.
"Once they
are rightly interpreted the terms 'representative essence,'
'participable
save
by
bodies,'
and 'archetype of
bodies,'
and mitigate the consequence, are reduced
which seem
to
'substance of
to
bodies.'
Nothing penetrates more deeply
into the system of
Malebranche
than Mairan's criticism. Arnauld and Regis held that an idea was essentially representative; to the is
being was limited to objective being,
its
being of an image of things. Malebranche held that the idea
intelligible in itself since
essentially
representative;
happens through his will
it is
becomes representative only
it
to
a divine archetype but that
wish
to create beings
known to we have of
model; his will can be made tion.
The knowledge
—since
it is
that
us,
it is
if
not
God
according to this
however, only by revela-
bodies
—physical
knowledge of the unique idea of extension,
knowledge is
therefore
completely independent of the knowledge of their existence and
complete without
this
is
knowledge.
This theory breaks the
last
link that
seemed
to
bind the mind to
something other than God. The mind no longer has
to yield to the
MALEBRANCHE
219
contingency of an existence independent of counters
is
only in
in the
itself. It is
mind
it.
The
that
resistance
knowing
with sensing, ideas with feelings, inner truth which
with personal inspiration which
is
is
it
en-
contrasts
immutable
forever changing, the clarity of
the natural light with the vivacity of instinct. In each instance the
term designates the mental faculty that leads us
first
to truth, the
second the one given to us for the preservation of our bodies.
by confusing them; the philosopher's task
errs
is
to
Man
keep them
clearly separated at all times.
The Malebranchists
vi
In spite of powerful adversaries, the philosophy of Malebranche
was widely acclaimed toward the end of the seventeenth century. It
was popular among the
elite
and
the Congregation of the Oratory
and
Jesuits.
Such eminent
in the universities as well as in
and even among the Benedictines
ladies as
Mme
readers of the works of Malebranche,
Grignan were assiduous
whose
niece,
Mile Vailly,
sembled the Malebranchists of Paris in her salon each week.
was himself
a
member
of the
as-
He
Academy of Sciences and had among among them, the Marquis de
his colleagues dedicated supporters:
l'Hopital,
on of the advocates of the infinitesimal calculus; Carre,
the mathematician to
was but one
of geometry
physics"; the engineer ricians
who
whom,
according to Fontenelle, "the whole
step in the direction of his beloved meta-
Renaud
d'Elissagaray;
and
several geomet-
continued to favor Cartesian physics.
In the congregations
it
was
of Malebranche, several of
difficult to
support publicly the ideas
whose works were again placed on the
Index in 1709 and in 1714. The Oratorian Thomassin (1619-1695) wrote Dogmata theologica, of which the second volume
De Deo Deique Proclus,
proprietatibus.
is
eternal
wisdom
entitled
avid reader of Plato, Plotinus,
and Dionysius the Areopagite, he followed the
of the Renaissance scholars
same
An
and attributed
tradition
to these philosophers "the
that dictated the evangelical law."
Though
he never named Malebranche, he was probably influenced by him, especially
when he
attributed to Plato the doctrine that the
first
220
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY word and
principles subsist eternally in the divine
are continually
present to every intellectual nature that seeks to attain them.
Malebranche's of
life
came
to
an end
time
at a
when
the empiricism
Locke and the physics of Newton were on the verge of triumph.
Nonetheless, throughout the eighteenth century there existed in
England and France a current of
antisensationalist thought. It ap-
pears in Montesquieu's Persian Letters: "Justice lation
between two things. The relation
matter whether the being
man"
who
considers
re-
God, an angel, or
is
it
an expedient
is
always the same, no
is
(Letter 81). Jean-Jacques Rousseau related that he
was
a
in-
troduced to philosophy in 1736 in books "which mixed devotion
with the sciences;
and from Port Royal." More
particularly,
hundred times" Conversations about the Bernard
Lamy
ones from the Oratory
this is especially true of the
he "read and reread a
Sciences, by the Oratorian
(1640-1715) who, in the third edition of his Dis-
course on Philosophy (1709), exalted the Malebranchist doctrine of
shows more
external perception. This doctrine
other man's exclusive dependence
The
literature to
than any
which Rousseau alluded was copious and must
have been widely read.
A
good example
is
Father Roche's Treatise
on the Nature of the Soul and the Origin of the System of
clearly
upon God.
Loc\e and
Knowledge
Its
his Supporters (1715). It
was
against
also to refute
the empirical tendencies of the Cartesian Regis that Lelevel, a resolute
supporter of Malebranche, wrote
Metaphysics (1694). Moreover, of divine efficacy
many
and the action of
The True and
the False
polemics involved the thesis
creatures.
A
Malebranchist like
Fede {Metaphysical Meditations on the Origin of the Soul, 1683) seemed to incline toward Spinozism by attributing to creatures an "infinite duration"
by virtue of their connection with divine im-
mensity. There was in any harmony which, according
to Lefort
edge That
and the
the
Is in
Knowledge
God,
KnowlBenedictine Francois Lamy {On de Moriniere
of One's Self, 1701), attributed too
action. All the while
a
171 8)
case criticism of Leibniz' pre-established
the
much
Malebranche was being defended
—against the charge of denying free
calumny
{On
will.
—as
This
to
human
if
against
is
one of
221
MALEBRANCHE
the principal themes of the Letters which the counselor at the
Chatelet
Miron wrote in Europe savante (1718-1719). Father Andre
of the Society of Jesus (1675-1764), in spite of the persecutions that
he endured, was a faithful disciple of Malebranche, and wrote his biography. His Essay on the Beautiful and his Discourses propa-
gated the
He
spirit of the doctrine.
held that the philosophy of
which was currently being taught by the
Aristotle,
which the great principle
is
that there
is
and "of
Jesuits
nothing in the mind that
has not passed through the senses, obviously overthrows
all
the
sciences, especially ethics."
The same polemic was Locke was writing
An
also being
conducted in England. In 1695
Examination of Malebranche 's Opinion of
Seeing All Things in God.
Two
English translations of the Search
had appeared in
1694.
John Norris
for Truth
(1 667-1 711), a
Male-
branchist, criticized Locke's empiricism in the second part of
An
Essay towards the Theory of the Ideal or Intelligible World (1701-
Locke mainly
1704), censuring
for posing the
problem of the origin
His own thinking was
of ideas before determining their nature.
suffused with the doctrine of St. Augustine.
During the eighteenth ist
theses
fisica
were supported in
contro
il
and Malebranch-
century, antisensationalist Italy
by Mattia Doria (Difesa
Ange
signor G. Loc\e, 1732), by
humanae natura ab Augustino
subsequently Defense of P. Malebranche
(Animae
by Cardinal Gerdil (Im-
detecta),
of the Soul Demonstrated against Loc\e,
materiality
della mata-
Fardella
s
View
1747,
and
of the Origin
and
Nature of Ideas against Loc\e's Examination)', in France by Cardinal Melchior de Polignac (Anti-Lucretius, 1747) to
whom
Bouillier attributed, perhaps
;
Created Infinity, published under the
name
a treatise which holds that matter
infinite, that
that there
similar to
is
an
man,
are worlds,
and
infinite
the Inner Sense, 1760),
Terrasson,
of Malebranche in 1769:
mind
infinite,
is
of worlds inhabited by beings
many
incarnations of
that the duration of the worlds
Abbe Lignac (Elements sional causes.
number
that there are as
is
Abbe
wrongly, the Treatise on
is
God
infinite)
as there ;
and by
of Metaphysics, 1753, and Testimony of
who remained
a stanch supporter of occa-
Bibliography
I
VI
to
Texts Malebranche, Nicolas. CEuvres. Edited by Jules Simon. 4 vols. Paris, 1871. CEuvres completes. Edited by A. Robinet. 20 vols. Paris, 1959-
— Dialogues on Metaphysics and Translated by M. Ginsburg. London, — Correspondance avec Dortous de Mairan. Edited by V. New by Moreau. — du Malebranche M. Arnauld. de Religion.
.
1923.
J.
.
ed., edited
.
Cousin.
J.
Paris, 1947.
J.
toutes les reponses
Recueil
a
P.
Paris,
1709.
Studies Church, R.
W. A Study
in the
Philosophy of Malebranche. London, 1931.
Cousin, Victor. Fragments de philosophic cartesienne. Paris, 1852. Gueroult,
M. Malebranche.
3 vols. Paris, 1955-59.
Luce, A. A. Berkeley and Malebranche.
New
York, 1934.
Rodis-Lewis, G. Nicolas Malebranche. Paris, 1963.
Rome.
B.
K. The Philosophy of Malebranche. Chicago, 1963.
Studies Pere Andre Martin (Ambrosius Victor). Philosophia Christiana. 6 vols. Paris, 1671. .
De
la
vie
du Rev. Pere Malebranche
,
pretre
de VOratoire, avec
de ses ouvrages. Edited by Ingold. Paris, 1886. Gouhier, H. Malebranche: textes et commentaires. (Les Moralistes chretiens.) I'histoire
Paris, 1929.
Robinet, A. Malebranche et Leibniz, relations personnelles. Paris, 1955. Roustan, D. "Pour une edition de Malebranche," Revue de metaphysique, 1916.
222
MALEBRANCHE
223
II
Studies Blampignon, E. A. Etude sur Malebranche. Paris, 1862. Blondel, M. "L'anticartesianisme de Malebranche," Revue de metaphysique, 1916. Bouillier, F. Histoire
de
la philosophie carte sienne.
3d
ed. 2 vols. Paris, 1868.
15-207.
II,
Boutroux, E. "L'intellectualisme de Malebranche," Revue de metaphysique, 1916.
Delbos, V. Etude sur la philosophie de Malebranche. Paris, 1924.
La philosophie
.
francaise. Paris, 1921. Pp. 91-132.
Figures et doctrines des philosophes. Paris, 19 19. Gouhier, H. La philosophie de Malebranche et son experience religieuse. Paris, .
1926. .
La vocation de Malebranche. Paris, 1926. M. "Etendue et psychologie chez Malebranche," Les
Gueroult,
Belle s-Lettres,
1939-
Hubert, Rene. "Revue de quelques ouvrages recents sur Malebranche," Revue d' histoire de la philosophie, igiy. Olle-Laprune, L. Pillon, F.
La
philosophie de Malebranche. Paris, 1870-72.
"L'evolution de l'idealisme au XVIII e
critiques,"
philosophie de
la
Annee philosophique,
siecle:
Malebranche
et
ses
1893, 1894, 1896.
Rolland E., and L. Esquirol. "La philosophie chretienne de Malebranche," Archives de philosophie, XIV (1938).
Ill
Studies
Van Biema. "Comment Malebranche
conceit
la
psychologie,"
Revue de meta-
physique, 1916.
La volonte selon Malebranche. Paris, 1958. Thamin, R. "Le traite de morale de Malebranche," Revue de metaphysique, Dreyfus, G. 1916.
IV Studies
Duhem, Mouy,
P.
Revue de metaphysique, 1916. Les his du choc des corps d'apres Malebranche. Paris, 1927.
P. "L'optique de Malebranche,"
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
224
Novaro, M. "La
teoria
della
causalita
Malebranche," Reale Academia dei
Lincei, 1890. Prost,
J.
Essai sur I'atomisme
et
Voccasionalisme
dans
la
philosophic
de
Malebranche. Rennes, 1909.
Studies Delbos, V. "La controverse d'Arnauld et de Malebranche sur l'origine des idees," Annales de philosophic chretienne, 1913. Gaonach, J. M. ha theorie des idees dans la philosophic de Malebranche. Rennes, 1909. Gouhier, H. "La premiere polemique de Malebranche [with Foucher] ," Revue d'histoire de la philosophic, 1927. Pillon, F. "La correspondance de Mairan et de Malebranche," Annee philoso-
phique, 1894. "Spinozisme .
.
et
Malebranchisme," Ibid.
"L'idealisme de Lanion et
le
scepticisme de Bayle," Ibid., 1895.
VI
Studies Pere Andre Martin. CEuvres philosophiques de Pere Andre, avec une introduction sur sa vie et ses ouvragcs, tiree de sa correspondance incdite.
Edited by Victor Cousin. Paris, 1843. de la philosophic carte sienne. 3d ed. 2
Bouillier, F. Histoire II.
Ch. 17-19, 27-28, 30-31.
vols. Paris, 1868.
LEIBNIZ German Philosophy
i
before Leibniz
in a tract entitled Aurora se initia scientiae generalis, fire
Leibniz contrasted the primitive, barbaric practice of drawing
from
friction generated
borrowing
fire
from the
terrestrial
matter at
light
then heat, and
first,
substances." light,
The
sticks
with the
rays of the sun:
first,
title
by
"On
scientific practice of
the one hand, heavy,
then heat, then light; on the other hand,
through heat, fusion of the hardest
finally,
symbolism of
of the tract, like the
fire
and
was borrowed from Jakob Bohme. Here we enter a universe
from
of thought quite different
branche.
We
cannot ignore
that of Descartes
this fact if
we
and of Male-
are to understand Leibniz.
Germany, which produced Eckhart and Nicholas of Cusa, was the center of speculative mysticism, in contrast to the religious or
contemplative mysticism of the Latin countries. Speculative mysticism, expressed in the vernacular,
is
represented at the end of the
sixteenth century by Valentin
Weigel
were not published
and
until 161 8,
teenth century by Jakob
Bohme
(i 533-1588),
at the
whose works
begining of the seven-
(1575-1624).
What Bohme's most
him can probably be said of all the other "Bohme sought not gnosis but salvation; knowledge would have been given him only as a bonus and would even
recent biographer said of
German
mystics:
have come as a great surprise 1
A. Koyre, La Philosophic de Jacob
225
to
him."
Boehme
*
But
if
they wished
(Paris, 1929), p. 30.
first
of
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
226
to save themselves, the conditions
all
problem of salvation led them
which
later
provided the Romanticists
Weigel and Bohme were both salvation through faith, that
is,
man
tion,
God and human
Weigel's theosophy
somehow
Lutheran
hostile to the
to us
thesis of is
based
from without. They held
is
nature that constitutes a veritable theosophy.
God
based on the idea that
will, or
personality,
reveals himself to himself
attributes.
and
is
primitively
he
that as he creates,
and makes manifest
of his
all
His creature contains elements of nothingness and for
very reason has the possibility of straying from him, of exerting
own
Adam, nality
will,
and thus brings about the Fall
the true Hell that
seems to
is
—the
knowing
of the
object but in the
(Gegenwurf)
subject:
is
passive
who
knowledge). In the
from the standpoint
"Knowledge and judgment
man who
judges what
is
knowl-
has been saved
are not in the
before him."
The
external
merely the occasion of his judgment; but "no object can
object
is
judge
itself,"
opposite
to his source (supernatural
the object
and
of knowledge,
to the state of the fallen creature (natural
and brought back state,
of Lucifer
two modes
edge) and the other to the state of the creature
first
fall
within each fallen man. Weigel's origi-
relate to his description of
one corresponding
is
models. For
their
achieves salvation through a positive, intimate transforma-
devoid of action,
this
with
through a veritable rebirth; such a rebirth implies a representa-
tion of
its
metaphysical constructions
to the belief that salvation
on the merits of Christ and comes that
under which they posed the
to the vast
is
no
truth,
no wisdom can come from without. The
true of supernatural knowledge.
wholly active and
silence; yet such
man
knowledge
which God, who
is
Here the
object
(God)
has nothing to do except to wait in is
also internal, or
in us, acquires of himself
is
merely knowledge
by using
man
as
an
The salvation of man is therefore the last phase of the act by which God acquires knowledge of himself; supernatural knowlorgan.
edge
is
a transformation of being.
The famous Jakob Bohme was
neither a popular preacher en-
croaching on the territory of pastors nor a sectarian leader competing for followers. "I do not keep
company with
the
common
peo-
227 pie,"
LEIBNIZ he
said.
Bohme, who descended from prosperous peasants of
Upper Lusatia and became fact
among
have
his friends doctors
and whose knowledge he the nobility.
a master
He was
shoemaker in Gorlitz, did in
who were
assimilated,
disciples of Paracelsus
and enlightened members of
impelled to write "in order to give an account
and
of his gift, his knowledge,
his experience,"
but not in a
critical
or proselytizing spirit.
Bohme began with
the experience of evil, the feeling of melan-
him when he saw that the impious man; and his culmination was the
choly and sadness that engulfed
man was
as
happy
as the pious
"triumphant joy of the
spirit," the veritable rebirth
him
the illumination that allowed
and thereby
to free himself
from
which followed
understand the will of
to
God
his sadness.
His liberating illumination suggested rather than formulated a doctrine which he expressed
An
ages rather than ideas.
—following
his
custom
was impressed by the striking images developed ism
—the
wrathful
destructive
fire,
also acquainted
God
—through
im-
assiduous reader of the Scriptures, he fully in
Old Testament with
of the
and the God of love of the Gospels with the hidden, ineffable
God
Lutheran-
his avenging,
—but
he was
of the mystics.
A
friend of the alchemists, he saw in the attempt to transmute metals
an image of the purification through
into gold through calcination
which the
fallen soul achieves salvation.
His mind impregnated with such images, he theme, after considering
many
others:
What
is
finally settled
on one
the relation between
—the eternal Nothing, the absolute absolute freedom— and the concrete,
the bottomless abyss (JJngrund)
being without essence which personal It is
God who knows
necessary for
him
is
himself and
to posit
the
God
Bohme of wrath
finds
the creator of the world?
with the JJngrund a will toward
manifestation or self-revelation. festation,
is
As
for the conditions of this
them through meditation on
the identity of
and the God of love unifying love can :
self-
mani-
exist
only
through victory over hate, light only through the heat that destroys
and absorbs matter, pure gold only through the calcination
of im-
pure elements. All these images express the same graphic scheme,
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
228
which may be formulated in the
Bohme never life of God as
"Yes implies no."
abstract as
same scheme
tired of using the
well as his act of creation
to express the inner
and the
of his creatures.
life
This scheme suggests a solution to the problem of
evil.
Since the
must be within
created world expresses divine nature, there
it
an
obscure corner, conflicting forces, an egotistical desire; but above
and
victorious there
subjugated.
it is
come,
must be an ordering, harmonizing
Though
evil exists for the
exists of necessity.
it
man who
other: a
But
fire
this solution
runs counter to an-
has dark desire and disorder deep in his heart
God and
subordinate
of desire to the light of the spirit, or he can relinquish the
victory to the forces of disorder,
new
which
purpose of being over-
possesses complete freedom; he can imitate
the
will to
it
and through
manifestation of God, as Savior.
ambiguity between of the wrath of
his fall bring about a
We find here the
evil as a necessary condition of
fundamental
—an image
good
God in nature—and the introduction of a fugitive, man who, created in the image of God, has freely
contingent evil by eradicated
from
his person the traces of his divine origin.
biguity persisted in the thinking of Leibniz
and
in
This am-
German meta-
physics of the nineteenth century.
Life
ii
and Wor\s
Gottfried
of Leibniz
Wilhelm Leibniz (1646-1716) studied ancient
ophy with Thomasius Jena,
at
and jurisprudence
filiated
at Altdorf.
became councilor a
philos-
with Weigel at
At Nuremberg he became
af-
with the Rosicrucians. In 1670, thanks to Johann Christian
von Boyneburg, formerly
was
Leipzig, mathematics
sent
at the
first
minister to the Elector of Mainz, he
supreme court of the
on a diplomatic mission
memorandum
urging Louis
electorate. In 1672
to Paris; in the
XIV
to
he
same year he wrote
put an end to the influence
Turks by conquering Egypt. In France he associated with Arnauld and studied the mathematical works of Pascal; he resided of the
there until 1676 (except for a trip to
England
in 1673
when he met
Boyle and the mathematician Oldenburg). In 1676 he invented the
LEIBNIZ
229
differential calculus (as early as 1665
In 1676 he returned to
of fluxions).
Newton had used Germany by way
and Holland (where he met Spinoza) and became private councilor to
He
method England
the of
and
librarian
John Frederick, Duke of Brunswick-Liineburg.
devoted part of his time to assembling the sources of the history
of the house of
Scriptures
Brunswick and, in
rerum brunswicensium
1701,
began publication of the
illustrationi inservientes. In Leip-
zig he founded the Acta Eruditorum (1682) and
became the
president (1700) of the scientific society that Frederick
transform into the Berlin Academy.
He
I
Louis XIV, he turned
first
where he
Czar and the Emperor.
He
tried to effect
having
to Charles XII, then,
in 171 1, after his defeat at Poltava, to Peter the Great.
resided in Vienna,
to
did not abandon his idea
of a union of the Christian nations against the Orient; failed to persuade
first
was
an
alliance
He
next
between the
died in 171 6.
Leibniz formulated the essentials of his philosophy in 1685. Prior to this date, his writings
motus concreti
(De
arte combinatoria, 1666,
and Theoria
et abstract!, 1671)
bear no trace of his fundamental
doctrine of individual substances.
systematic account of the doc-
trine
is
given in his Discourse on Metaphysics (1686).
His work treatises in
is
a lush tangle, with countless short philosophical
each of which he attempted to give a systematic account
of his whole system; with
all his
encyclopedia of information;
down
A
in the
form
of
plans for a universal science, for an
with
memoranda)
political reconciliation of
all
for
his
practical
promoting the
projects
(set
religious
and
Christian nations and the religious or-
ganization of the earth; finally, with his voluminous correspondence
with the time.
scientists,
Both of
philosophers,
theologians,
his long philosophical
was approaching old age:
New
and
of his
jurists
works were completed
Essays concerning
Human
as
he
Under-
standing (written between 1701 and 1709 and not published until 1765) in
which he examined Locke's Essay paragraph by paragraph;
and the Theodicy (1710),
in
which he explained
his
optimism by
re-
ferring mainly to the objections raised in the article "Rorarius" in Bayle's Dictionary.
23O
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
These works, in which he defended the against Locke's empiricism
theologians
who defended
thesis
of innate ideas
on the one hand and supported the on the
other,
must be sought
in his
the thesis of Providence
The
are not expositions of his system.
latter
shorter writings, such as the Discourse on Metaphysics (1686),
plemented by
correspondence with Arnauld, the
his
New
com-
System
of Nature and of the Communication of Substances (1695), and the Monadology (1714), written for Prince Eugene of Savoy (1714).
General Science
Initial Position of Leibniz:
in
we compare Leibniz with Descartes, Spinoza, and Malebranche, common traits are quickly noticed; like them, he is a mathematician; like them, he is a mechanist. But we also see contrasts: If
their
Leibniz the mathematician finds in Aristotle's logic the principles
from which he
will evolve his metaphysics; Leibniz the mechanist
restores the substantial
causes in physics.
forms of Scholasticism and the use of
But the
their thought. Descartes
main
difference
had reversed the order
grounding the certainty of physics on
and
of oneself; Leibniz goes back
tional order.
We
it
is
is
work
of philosophy by
to the tradi-
that corresponds to
in fact a theory of
knowledge;
by beginning with matter and mechanics that he
able to rise to metaphysics
what was preliminary
and
to
it
is
God. Thus questions are reversed:
to Descartes
becomes
question of the origin of our ideas," he said, philosophy, and
of
knowledge of God
beyond Descartes
will find nothing in his
Cartesian metaphysics, which rather
reflective
final
rhythm
in the
lies
final to Leibniz. "is
"The
not preliminary in
can be satisfactorily resolved only after
much
progress has been made."
Furthermore, and even more important perhaps (for
this
is
his
point of departure and his persistent idea), Leibniz views as a
whole and
as
existing simultaneously parts of philosophy
which
Descartes subordinated to one another: those which, no matter what is
being studied, admit of demonstration. Leibniz finds demonstra-
tions to be in order not only in
geometry but
also in logic, meta-
LEIBNIZ
231
physics (especially in Plato
ophy
and the theologians), and moral
He was
(particularly jurisprudence).
philos-
attentive to the efforts
Erhard Weigel (1625-1699), who showed that Aristotle used the method of Euclid in his Analytics, and who wrote an Ethica of
which Leibniz
euclidea,
one of his
dissertations (Dissertatio
first
he himself
cites in a letter to
tries, after
Thomasius (1663). In
de arte combinatoria, 1666),
demonstrating different theorems concerning
combinations, to show their applicability to the whole universe of
and
the sciences, particularly logic,
Mathematics then tion,
is
but one application of the art of demonstra-
which can be extended
dreams was
also to jurisprudence.
to
many
to create a general science
other subjects.
which had
One
of his
at its disposal a
system of symbols or a universal language (characteristica universalis)
which would have
in mathematics,
in all subjects the role that
and which would allow us
instead of "Let us discuss," no matter [a
language] such as the one
I
to say
what the
conceive,
we
symbolism had
"Let us calculate"
question. "If
we had
could reason in math-
ematics and in moral philosophy; for symbols would stabilize our thoughts, too vague and too variable in these subjects in which
imagination trasts
is
of
no help
with the Cartesian
ing point or as
ideal,
To
progresses.
it
The ideal of his science conwhether we consider it from its start-
to us" (1677).
demonstrate, in his science,
is
to
reduce given propositions to identical propositions in which the the
same
as the attribute; but such a reduction
subject
is
only
the notions that enter into the propositions can be analyzed
if
is
revealed,
are such that the
and only
possible
which they are composed and
into the simple elements of identity
is
if
their
the symbols chosen for the elements
complex notion
is
of necessity
deduced from the
notions of the simple elements. "Reasoning in any form
is
merely
the connecting or substituting of characteristic symbols; any substitution arises
from
a certain equipollence; [reasoning]
a combination of symbols." strate that
1+2 = 3
1
we
in a strict sense
we
therefore
can demon-
are dealing with numerical sym-
and perfectly defined on the basis of the simple and +. Because Descartes prescribed self-evident prop-
bols completely
notions of
Thus
because
is
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
232
he failed
ositions as the starting point,
which
a subjective characteristic
is
to attain the goal; evidence
varies according to the individ-
and which can engender only chimeras. Descartes generally
ual
failed to pursue notions that should be subject to further analysis,
such as the notion of extension. Leibniz was not rigid enough to
He
adopt the Cartesian method. acquainted with
for
it,
hold," the Geometry
it
his
even "in
strong-
its
as insoluble to
that Leibniz easily resolved through
Leibniz thought that his reductive analysis
his infinitesimal calculus.
and
sterile
which Descartes considered
in
human mind problems
the
doubted that he was adequately
had proved
system of combination employed symbols that "ought to be
useful in discovery
new
analysis, the
and
judgment"
in
if
here, as in mathematical
notions were simply combinations of previously
acquired notions. Finally, according to Leibniz, one of the greatest
advantages of method was the weighing of advantages and
dis-
advantages through a process of deliberation and the calculation of probabilities.
Leibniz' initial position
His aim
Descartes.
through which the
on evidence, and that
is
would
so forth
suffice to nullify
of
identities
man
is
involves
mental processes reflection
due
to
—doubt,
determine the necessary relations
from one proposition
him than
to
God to sin.
no doubt.
another.
Cartesian doubt, which
any philosophical undertaking, for
posited, the existence of fallibility
—but to
to pass
more abhorrent
is
free,
arrives at truth
not to describe the
human mind
compel the mind
Nothing
therefore closer to Aristotle than to
is
cannot remove
it,"
"if
especially
if
it is
the
The
resolution of propositions into
"We
acknowledge postulates and
axioms not only because they are proved by an
infinity of experi-
ences but also because they immediately satisfy the mind; nevertheless, the perfection of science requires that
they be demonstrated."
Leibniz was on the path which led to the symbolic logic and the
non-Euclidean geometries that came into being in the nineteenth century as a result of attempts to demonstrate postulates. Leibniz' system of combination, therefore, consists essentially of
fashioning
all
possible connections
—that
is,
noncontradictory con-
LEIBNIZ
233
—between
terms given
nections
initially,
and thus proving
the reality of a concept as such. But such a accessible to the
notion of last
human mind,
number
for there
method
a priori
generally in-
is
no notion other than the
is
that will enable us to determine by analysis the
"requisites." Clarity
Not only must an
and
distinctness of ideas are insufficient.
idea be clear (that
is,
not susceptible of being
confused with other ideas, such as the idea of color) and distinct (that
we must have
is,
from other
apart
thought);
it
must
The
ideas also
must be analyzed
a clear
—for
knowledge of the marks that instance,
—that
be adequate
extension the
is,
set it
relation
in
to
marks themselves
into their last elements.
possibility of a concept
is
proved, not a priori by method,
but a posteriori by experience; and even in the clearest of the sciences
—the
leave
at that.
it
science of
numbers
—we
For example, Leibniz
are
cites
sometimes obliged
to
one of Fermat's theorems
involving prime numbers which could be verified in every concrete
proof attempted but which had not been demonstrated
was demonstrated by art of instituting
Euler, in 1736).
What
is
(it finally
needed, then,
experiments that will supply what
is
is
"an
lacking in
our data."
iv
The Doctrine The
of Infinity
logic of concepts
finitude
:
a fixed
of genera
and
number
is
traditionally linked to the doctrine of
of species constituted by a definite
differences; a finite
number
world in space constituted in
such a manner that species remain fixed as individuals change.
Everything which in
viduality, continuity, infinity
the order
frame
reality resists inclusion in this
—
and dependent on an
is
viewed
as
—indi-
being excluded from
unintelligible principle of disorder.
In the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries the doctrine of infinity
impregnated every sphere of mathematics and physics; time the logic of universals collapsed. Leibniz, no is
an impassioned advocate of the doctrine of
less
at the
same
than Spinoza,
infinity:
any
definite
notion whatsover, any notion that does not envelop infinity,
is
ac-
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
234
him an
cording to
the inexhaustible
real.
is
and could he remain
He
holds that only
these conditions,
how would he
incomplete notion.
abstract,
Under
faithful to the spirit of Aristotelian logic and,
both are essentially
to a certain degree, Aristotelian physics, since
The
finite?
expression he uses so often, "infinite analysis," shows
the union, essential in his view, between the
ophy, which must be infinite in so far as
it
two
aspects of philos-
relates to the actual
universe and analytic in order to penetrate the sphere of intelligibility.
Leibniz
finity,
and
all
concerned exclusively with creating a logic of
is
of his doctrines
and
in-
studies in mathematics, physics,
metaphysics, theology, and moral philosophy are but
its
several
aspects.
In geometry, infinite analysis seems impossible because the very definition of geometric continuity
the elements
which would,
and
ertheless,
the
for
in
same
makes
it
impossible for us to find
sum, reproduce the continuum. Nevreason,
we can imagine a how small.
quantity
smaller than any given quantity, no matter
Leibniz'
concept of infinitely small quantities contrasts sharply with Cavprinciple of indivisibles,
alieri's
finite
infinite lines, tity
able
which
same
in nature as
aggregation of points, a surface as an infinite aggregation of
and
To
so forth.
Leibniz, however, the infinitely small quan-
in the case of a line to
an infinitesimal
is
neity of
The
curves.
space,
ilar figure
observation
property
a
that
of their absolute dimensions lines
is
enables
is
based on the homogeus
to
imagine a
corresponding to a given figure, no matter
follows that the relation between
become
the relation
when
its
is
straight lines
its
how
is
small.
It
independent
Leibniz shows that the direction
points depends solely on the determination of
the lines are infinitely small, so that
recourse to infinite analysis the curve (that
two
sim-
and can remain the same when the
infinitely small.
of a curve at one of
between
Leibniz then
line.
turn to account one of Pascal's incidental observations
concerning
two
are the
magnitudes. For example, Cavalieri regarded the line as an
when we need
tangent) at any given point.
his logic of infinity
and
we
can have
to find the direction of
Aristotelian logic
The is
difference
crystal clear:
235
LEIBNIZ with given concepts whose relations are studied
his does not begin later, for these
would have
concepts
ber of elements; instead,
an
infinite
number
it
composed
num-
of a finite
of terms (the points of the curve).
Leibniz' philosophy
based essentially on the discovery in each
is
instance of a kind of algorithm role of
to be
begins with a relation that engenders
which plays mutatis mutandis the
an infinitesimal algorithm in the infinitesimal calculus.
In mechanics, the law of the conservation of force, which should
account for the indefinite
series of
mechanical changes in the world
of bodies; in metaphysics, the notion of individual substance, is
which
simply the law of their consecutive changes or the pre-established
harmony which
is
the law of the interrelationship of individual sub-
stances; in theology, the divine attributes
—understanding, which
the law of essences, the will or choice of the better, of existences,
and
potentiality,
essence to existence;
all
which
is
these notions,
the
which
is
is
the law
law of the passage from
how
no matter
different in
appearance and origin, have no function except that of introducing universally the intelligibility of infinity
which the infinitesimal
cal-
we must endeavor fecundity. We may diswe please; if we relate
culus contributed to geometry. In each instance to
apprehend a notion with an inexhaustible
tribute points
them on the
on
a surface as arbitrarily as
basis of a continuous trait,
an equation will give the
law of distribution of these points. Our example brings into
clear
focus the thought that permeates Leibniz' whole system: there
always a law to explain infinite variation.
The most theory of
celebrated of Leibniz' doctrines
life,
his theory of
of this unique idea,
—his
freedom and contingency
and considered apart from
it
dynamism,
they sometimes
them
to
his theory of substance
from
which we could
one another or deduce them from one another.
There have been attempts, derives
his
if
same thought, we must not assume
that they are contained in a coherent system in easily relate
his
—are corollaries
tend to present a rather disconcerting aspect. Furthermore, doctrines are the fruit of the
is
for example, to relate his
on the ground that
his notion of force; the truth
dynamism
his notion of the is
to
monad
that each of the
two
—
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
236
notions had
both
origin in independent considerations, though they
its
into the
fit
We
same pattern of thought.
shall
examine them
one by one, but without exaggerating their systematic elaboration.
A common rithm)
characteristic of these notions (of these sorts of algo-
that, unlike Descartes* clear
is
and
distinct ideas, they are
not the object of intuition but are present as conclusions
from two universal
analysis
principles
The two
A
is
whose
fertility
was erroneously denied by the
great principles are the principle of identity
any given term
equivalent to
evident
is
its effect;
or:
provable a priori.
it is
soever: nature never acts state to
aries. It
is
and not otherwise;
A, when
or: a cause
any true proposition which
To
these
continuity which states a property
one
Cartesians.
—A
—and the principle of sufficient reason —every-
thing has a reason for being as is
drawn by
principles applicable to all things
by leaps
must be added the
common
—that
is,
to
is
any diversity what-
discernible
number of intermedimust be composed of
parts that are indiscernible; nothing can originate suddenly
sciousness
no more than motion." Reality then
us as a continuum
v
whose
parts
we
self-
a thing can pass from
another only through an infinite
follows that "whatever
not
is
principle of
is
—con-
always revealed to
cannot exhaust.
Mechanics and Dynamism Leibniz was
first
and always
a mechanist
and an advocate of the
plenum. As early
as 1669 he looked upon the modern explanation phenomena by size, figure, and motion as being the most acceptable one and even "the one closest to Aristotle." In 1670 he gave
of
all
a systematic explanation of a system of mechanics in his Theoria
motus
abstracti, in
which the notion of conatus
(that
small quantity of motion), borrowed from Hobbes, tance. Later, to explain
how motion was
by impulsion, he had
to
imagine that
in a fluid that offered
no
resistance but
the solid bodies, that the fluid
swimming
in a fluid
still
more
itself
subtle,
is
is,
of
an
infinitely
first
transmitted in the
solid bodies
was
plenum
were swimming
fluid only in relation to
was composed of and
impor-
so forth
solid bodies
ad infinitum, the
—
LEIBNIZ
237
having no
subtlety of the fluids
and
cartes,
In both Leibniz and Des-
limit.
reasons, such a theory of mechanics ruled
same
for the
out any system of mathematical physics as conceived by Galileo,
Newton; and whereas
Pascal, or
Newton with
the calculation of fluxions provided
the language needed for his physics, Leibniz never
used his infinitesimal calculus to express the laws of nature.
Leibniz nevertheless heaped criticism on Cartesian physics. His
may
criticism
be
by Descartes
ited
summed up
in
one statement: the principles pos-
—extended substance, conservation of motion, and —are not principles of
laws of nature derived from such principles
unity capable of explaining the infinite diversity of things. First,
extension cannot be a substance, for tion,
and every being of
derives
if
each being of which
its reality,
this
it is
gation"; extension, which
this is precisely
no
different
what
(whatever
tition of this
from the
composed
is still
when of
it
exists,
it
may
void,
strictly
does not have
motion
—since
it
it
be)
is
extension." Since extension
nor does
same
fill
it.
it
its
coexisting parts."
violates the principle of reason
wrongly assumes that motion
the motion of the
first
is
The law
is
force
the velocity of the
weight
—the
of conservation
causa adaequat effectum
A
fallen four feet has obviously acquired
is
to the
one
foot.
motion of the second is
That
as 2
is
identical in
product of the mass and the square of
two weights (mv2 )
constant sought by Descartes,
laws of impact
like time,
proportionate to force.
determined by Galileo's laws. That what
both instances
explain the va-
Motion,
force as a four-pound weight that has fallen
to 4 easily
is
would be the
contains nothing which
speaking, because an aggregate never exists
one-pound weight that has the
an aggregate, not
constitutes the essence of a body; the repe-
which characterizes the things that
"never
reality at all
a being through aggre-
is infinitely divisible, is
sufficient cause of resistance or mobility,
riety
have no
will
it
must be "something extended or continuous,
a substance. So there
and
kind implies simple beings from which
with the result that
it
a "being through aggrega-
it is
is
—which
is
therefore the true
also easily determined. Descartes'
are, in turn, contrary to the principle of continuity,
primarily because he often supposed that there was an instantaneous
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
238
change in either the quantity or the direction of motion of the liding bodies at the
moment
should have warned bodies which, lose their
if
him
is
principle of continuity
they rebound on contact with another body,
motion gradually (without a corresponding
in turn results
it
anew by
from the inner an inner
ity therefore expresses
any
agitation of their parts. Elastic-
which
force, intrinsic to each body,
not produced by the external bodies that determine
bodies represented by Descartes' elements, any
The
loss of
first
virtue of their elasticity,
action. Leibniz therefore cannot accept the perfectly
accept atoms.
col-
that in nature there can be only elastic
part of their force), then acquire
which
The
of impact.
existence of elasticity
its
mode
of
homogeneous
more than he can
and of inner
forces sup-
poses the infinite divisibility of actual bodies which accordingly can-
not have exact, determinate shapes. So there
no matter how
matter, parts,
each of which
body
differs
force that
it
is
small,
which
is
in nature
not composed of
is
from another not by
tween data becomes very
shape but by the inner
size or
which holds
becomes very
slight.
slight,
fails to
when
its
if
B
direction should
to
him,
if
two
follows that
metaphysical.
if
is
The
larger than
everything in nature
Cartesians
is
namely
C
by even the
forces
its
actions, are
this
when
is
to
is
It is
"the
first
And
indeed the permanent cause
the actions a body can accomplish
can endure.
they
suppose that
within bodies themselves something superior to them.
in fact force, as conceived by Leibniz, all
and
conservation the arbitrary
will of a deus ex machina, for the only alternative is
slight-
explained mechanically,
must have understood
introduced as the cause of motion and
of
colliding bodies,
remain the same.
the very principles of mechanics,
there
appreciate
the difference be-
C, have the same mass and velocity, they will both rebound
amount,
It
that
the difference between the results
According
with the same velocity; but est
smaller
and one
manifests.
In the elaboration of his rules Descartes also
B and
still
constantly in a state of agitation,
the principle of continuity,
also
no part of
and of
all
the passions
entelechy" which "corresponds to
or substantial form." In discovering the constancy of force
it
mind {mv 2 )
LEIBNIZ
239 to
which he attaches
law of conservation of quan-
as a corollary the
progression (that
tity of
projection of velocities
sum
constancy of the algebraic
is,
on an
axis),
of the
Leibniz thinks that he has found
a veritable reality.
What
dynamism
the significance of Leibniz'
is
reality of force,
which would constrain us
or theory of the
from physics
to pass
metaphysics? Particularly worthy of our attention
is
to
the contrast
between his dynamism and the dynamism of central forces that was being evolved at the same time by Roberval, Huyghens, and
Newton
ton.
New-
did not accept the plenum and saw as the paradigm
of force the force of gravitational attraction which, following his investigations,
We
that,
recall
must
became
a particular instance of universal gravitation.
according to his famous pronouncement, physics
steer clear of metaphysics,
gravitation
with the result that the formula for
was important (following the
logic characteristic of the
Newton) because it algreat number of phenomena,
scientific current that linked Galileo and
lowed him
to calculate
and not because
it
and
revealed
foresee a
some hidden
of attraction. In contrast, Leibniz,
(mv
2
)
disclosed a
profound
which could be used
we
have, perhaps for the
Newton
who thought
first it
that his formula
could deduce from
in the exact calculation of
ent minds. Paradoxically, criticism of
reality,
essence, such as a real force
time, the confrontation of
would seem
it
two
in his letters to Clarke
For
physics.
it is
differ-
at first glance that Leibniz' is
identical with his
criticism of Descartes: the inability to dispense with a
machina in
nothing
phenomena. Here
Deus ex
easy to demonstrate that by virtue of
the prolonged action of gravitation, a system such as the solar sys-
tem
will gradually deteriorate unless
just as a
light
mechanic repairs
on the degree
to
God
his contrivances.
repairs the
which Leibniz deemed the metaphysical
superstructure of his physics to be indispensable. arbitrary metaphysics cessity or
by choice,
machinery
Their encounter sheds
He
shunned the
which Descartes and Newton added, of ne-
to their physics.
In force he had something real
to account for all mechanical changes.
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
24O
The Notion
vi
of Individual Substance
and Theology
Everything in the system of Leibniz hinges upon the infinitude of the world
not in
is
pate in
seen, extension
body
and there
is
no
not divided into
is
own way
at the is
satisfied.
a "syncategorematic"
and which
series
its
2
The
infinity,
we
which
is
has as
its
necessary
which
is
series.
Similarly, as
typified
we
A
and which
is
by a mathematical our ever
syncategorematic in-
complement a "categorematic
the law of the series
infinity"
is
of necessity outside the
shall see, Leibniz'
concept of infinity in
the sensible universe has as the series of changes
its
necessary
which Leibniz
But substances or
stances.
inherent in each
find in the universe
consists essentially in the impossibility of
arriving at the last term of a progression. finity
traces of
whole future.
infinity that
infinity
each
the infinitude of the universe,
same time the exigency of
never
and limited
which does not contain
state of a substance
whole past and the germs of But
finite
infinitely subdivided; furthermore,
is
real substance contains in its
thing,
which
own way infinite, any element which does not particiown way in this infinitude. Even in the world of bodies,
bodies; instead, each
its
reality
its
its
we have
as
and the impossibility of carving out any
complement the laws of
identifies
with individual sub-
subjects, in turn, constitute not a real
being but an indefinite multiplicity. Above this infinitude of substances
we must
therefore conceive an infinite being, a kind of law
or "hypercategorematic infinite being,"
consideration of infinitude in finitude or perfection
universe
is
what the law
God—that
and is,
this brings us to the
to theology.
Divine
in-
to the eternally incomplete infinitude of the
of a series
is
to the infinitude of
its
terms in
mathematics. Metaphysics and theology then are inseparable; the truth of a metaphysical notion, such as the notion of substance, can
of course he proved "without mentioning 2
A
notion probably derived from William of
from Peter of Spain. edition of Plotinus.
On
the origin of the idea,
cf.
God
except
when
neces-
Ockham, who had borrowed it the notice on Ennead VI in my
LEIBNIZ
24I
sary to indicate
when
forcefully
my
dependence; but
the notion in
source from which
it is
this truth
is
drawn." The same applies
more
expressed
question has divine knowledge
as the
to all of the no-
tions in Leibniz' philosophy, whether they are taken at their lower
God)
level (in the creature of
God) where
source in
Here we
analysis
or at their higher level (in their
comes
to
an end.
—the
Neo-
same total reality more concentrated and
closer
find a doctrinal scheme long familiar to us
Platonic scheme according to which the
expression at different levels, being to the
One
lower
level.
at the
higher level and more divided and diluted at the
We recall the Neo-Platonic design that became prevalent
during the Renaissance and the
which "each thing was
all
intelligible
things"
when we
world of Plotinus
him and
to
"any substance
is
signs of all that will
like a
whole world and
in
read that "in the soul
of Alexander there reside eternally remnants of
pened
finds
happen like a
all
to
that has hap-
him," and that
mirror of
God
or of
the whole universe."
The long as stance,
crux of Leibniz' metaphysics
we do not discern what we shall have nothing to
is
is
the notion of substance. "So
truly a complete being or a sub-
halt us."
But we must reach
a halt,
as Aristotle said, at least in the order of reasons. Descartes defined
created substance as that
which
need only of the concurrence of
on the one hand attribute
sole
there could be
no
is
conceived independently and has
God
in order to exist. This
that the essence of a substance
cast
no change
in
it,
and on the other that
on the very
to a
it
involved
with the result that doubt
existence of a world, that
interrelated substances. Cartesianism
germ
was reduced
(extension or consciousness), with the result that
relation to other created substances,
was
meant
(and that
is,
is
the aggregate of
why
it
contains
little value upon the individuality mind as well as bodies had ceased to be substances and become modes of thought or extension. As the language of Leibniz suggests, his notion of substance has its source in completely different traditions. For example, when he
the
of Spinozism) placed
of substances, for
referred to "individual substance" in his Discourse on Metaphysics
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
242
he was using the language of Aristotle and trying like him to individual substances
make
(which are merely subjects) the only true
word "monad," a Neo-Platonic term which he probably borrowed from Bruno and which Proclus used to designate the "units" which are subordinate to the Supreme One Later he used the
realities.
and
reflect
universe.
from diverse points of view the whole
But the dynamism of
his physics
is
multiplicity of the
another source of his
notion of substance and probably of his vitalism as well.
We is
need
first to
examine the notion of individual substance
revealed in his Discourse on Metaphysics.
main concern lem of God's
is
as
it
Here Leibniz, whose
the solution of the theological problem (the prob-
relation to his creatures), follows a
method, showing
how
notions of individual substance, and then of divine attributes,
issue
from investigation
of the conditions of
what
is
called a con-
tingent truth.
In contrast to truths of reason, which can be reduced to identities
and of which the opposites imply contradiction, contingent truths or truths of fact are those of which the opposites do not imply contradiction; the "metaphysical necessity" of eternal truths contrasts
with the absence of metaphysical necessity. But necessity complete indetermination
?
It
is
is
the absence of
not, for that
would be
contrary to the principle of sufficient reason. But does not determi-
nation entail necessity, that
come?
If so,
is,
the impossibility of a different out-
contingency would not differ from necessity. Determi-
nation implies necessity but not metaphysical or logical necessity; there
is
also
an ex hypothesi
necessity, consequential or conditional,
according to which a thing exists on condition that something else exists
first.
The
metaphysical or logical necessity of an identical
from the examination
proposition issues immediately or mediately of
its
terms; but the necessity of a proposition of fact (Caesar has
crossed the Rubicon)
is
due
to prior events
(Caesar's decision to
secure his power). Since the prior events themselves are necessary
only by virtue of their conditions, and so on indefinitely, said that for Caesar not to have crossed the
physically possible.
it
can be
Rubicon remains meta-
LEIBNIZ
243
This accounts for the positive definition of contingent truths or
whose
truths of fact: truths
by an
of reason,
integral reason could be identified only
beyond the scope of the human mind. Truths
infinite analysis
on the other hand, may be demonstrated by
a finite anal-
ysis.
The
notion of individual substance
is
obtained by an application
of the principle of reason to true propositions that have an individual being as their subject. "It
predication has a proposition
an established
is
some foundation not identical
is
—that —
expressly included in the subject
and
that
is
what philosophers
fact that
is,
when
the predicate
must be included
it
Thus
call in esse.
ways includes the predicate term, with the
any true
and when
in the nature of things,
not
is
potentially,
the subject term that
result
al-
whoever
understood perfectly the notion of the subject would also think that the predicate belonged to
it.
Therefore
we can
of an individual substance or a complete being so complete that
from This
it
is
all
sufficient to
it is
embrace and
the predicates of the subject to
demonstrable a
is
priori.
have a notion
to
is
to allow us to
which
the application of the great principle
true proposition
say that the nature
which
But
deduce
attributed."
is
it
states that
any
not the ex hy-
is
pothesi necessity of contingent truths transformed thereby into a
metaphysical necessity
if,
here too, their truth issues from an ex-
amination of notions?
The
objections raised by Leibniz' correspondents are
worth con-
To
say that all
sidering. First, Arnauld, speaking as a theologian:
changes in an individual being are deduced from properties of sphere are deduced
from
its
notion, as the
its
definition,
is
to eliminate,
along with contingency and freedom, any kind of true individuality.
Then
Voider, speaking as a geometer: "Everything deduced from
the nature of a thing persists; thus
is
invariably in the thing as long as
from the notion of individual substance
low that nothing
is
on the part of the
active
by nature, for action
creature." Leibniz here
jections analogous to those
is
comes
it
nature
would
fol-
always variation to grips
which Aristotle was unable
he was called upon to choose between
its
with ob-
to resolve:
intelligibility that pertains
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
244
only to necessary propositions and individuality that escapes intelligibility.
To answer
the objections of the geometers Leibniz compares the
nature of individual substance to the law of a series that embraces the indefinite progression of
its
terms or to the equation of a curve
that allows us to determine at will
an
But he quickly adds:
is
make
of points.
the clearest statement
constitute
the infinite evolution
human mind
those that a
infinitely surpass
of predicates]
human minds
we know we
for this reason:
predicates, but
its
ourselves are never in possession of such a notion. This
we
cause "although
antecedent
state,
is
true be-
can account for a subsequent state in terms of
and then of the antecedent
can never come to a final cause within the is
surpass
infinitely
can understand."
that the notion of a substance produces all
its
state in its turn,
series."
But
we
since there
always a connection that leads us indefinitely from one term to
the next,
no matter how
which
never complete and will never be complete (Leibniz
it
can
I
geometric minds, although these kinds of lines [lines that
to
They
"I believe this
number
infinite
is
far
syncategorematic infinity),
ries is a
cause which
makes
we go
in the infinite series of terms
we must assume
all
and a
priori
stance can belong only to It
follows that it
is
Thus we have
knowledge of each of the predicates
infal-
that belong
and such immediate recognition of an individual sub-
to substance,
and
that outside the se-
the terms and their dependence im-
mediately intelligible (categorematic infinity). lible
calls
on
we must
this
level
God, the author of
all
things.
seek the root of contingent truths in God,
Leibniz takes his stand to answer
that
Arnauld's objection. There
is
an a
priori
proof for any truth,
whether contingent or necessary, drawn from the notion of terms;
if
the truth
mind;
if
contingent, proof exists only in God. But
is
necessary, this proof
is
proof, the total, unique "infallible vision" that
not exclude
all
accessible to the finite
God
how
has of
can
this
all
things,
contingencies? In Cartesian theology, which
makes
eternal truths or essences as well as existences will, the real is
its
depend on the divine
not separated from the possible. Whatever
is
belongs
LEIBNIZ
245
same
of necessity to the
and
and contingent
God. Through possible, that
were no longer applicable
we
to theology,
see that nec-
God
conceives everything that
is
everything that does not imply a contradiction.
he decides
his will
presented to
Spi-
truths refer to distinct attributes of
understanding
his
is,
is
two great
the belief that the
sufficient reason,
For when we apply them
in theology.
essary truths
Through
and Descartes' true successor
stemmed from
noza. Descartes' error principles, identity
order,
him by
to create
his understanding.
one of the possible worlds Consequently his
infallible
same
vision of real substances with their predicates cannot be of the
nature as his knowledge of the possibility of these substances; and his
knowledge of the
essences,
distinct
is
Knowledge
possibility of these substances, that
from our knowledge of the
is,
of their
truths of reason.
of substances (and consequently of contingent truths)
belongs in fact to the divine intellect in so far as the latter relates
knowledge of
to will;
possible; it is
knowledge of
possible substances to a will
same
real substances to the
which
itself
is
will in so far as
Knowledge of the truths of reason, however, belongs Thus God's infallible vision is explained by he knows which of the substances conceived by his in-
effective.
solely to the intellect.
the fact that tellect
The fore,
is
he has decided distinction
to create
tween two divine
which
will.
between the contingent and the necessary, there-
identical to the distinction
between existence and essence. will
through his
It
between the has
its
attributes, intellect
real
and the
possible,
source in the distinction be-
which
relates to essences
and
relates to existences.
But God's vision of individual substances
is
infallible
virtue of the principle of sufficient reason, his will
is
only
if,
by
not arbitrary
but determinate with respect to the choice of possible substances.
The
only choice worthy of the perfect being
is
the choice of "the
best of all possible worlds," the wholly a priori principle of the
famous Leibnizian optimism which cannot be proved or disproved by experience and which cannot be impaired by the mockery of Voltaire's Candide.
The word
"best,"
in the ears of theologians to assert
which Leibniz often exploded
more
forcefully his anti-Spino-
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
246 zism,
sometimes replaced by the expression
is
sence." In fact, the existence of
"maximum
of es-
one possible can be incompatible
with the existence of another; two or more possibles whose ence
compatible (that
is
among
possibles;
one which contains the
God
the one
not contradictory) are said to be corn-
is,
combinations of possibles, there
all
exist-
maximum
is
obviously
and
of reality or essence,
this
is
chooses.
Theology and Monadology
vii
The
analytic exposition of Leibniz' system in the Discourse on
Metaphysics was followed by a systematic exposition in which his debt to Plato
At
is
to derive the
God: "At
is
But
The
established a priori
this proof, as
existence of
God
it
is
is
on the
I
manage
if
and
perfect be-
basis of so-called ontological proof. is
incomplete.
The
deduced from the idea of God, of course, but is
possible, that
The proof becomes: "God
essence; therefore ity
existence of the infinite
conceived by Descartes,
on condition that the idea tradiction.
a deeper level in philosophy
supreme laws of natural things from some knowledge
of divine perfections."
ing
monad.
revealed in his concept of the
the summit,
he
of the existence of
is
possible,
he
is
is,
does not imply con-
necessary by virtue of his
To show
exists."
the possibil-
God, Leibniz has recourse sometimes
simplicity, since contradiction exists only in a concept
to his
whose
ele-
ments are mutually incompatible, sometimes
to proof a contingentia
mundi, which thus becomes the preliminary
step of the ontological
proof.
For we know of the existence of beings that
other, finite beings.
Such beings are possible a
God
and
his intellect
is
if
there were not
neces-
intellect,
and
will.
His power
is
the foundation of essences or possibles.
might say that he corresponds
Platonists
through if
also be impossible.
has three attributes: power,
creative,
We
would
but
were impossible, beings
sary being or independent being {ens a se) that exist through others
exist
fortiori,
to the intelligible
two important
place, the field of possibles or of essences
is
world of the
differences. In the first infinitely greater
than
LEIBNIZ
247
the field of existences, so that
which
possibles will
come
a possible
into existence
into being through
an edict of
which
actual
down
tains
come
will never
necessary for us to separate the
it is
will
become
to the smallest detail
actual being.
"My
creation of an
everything that will belong to the
of
whom
Thus
God,
in
it
to
God
come
God
willed the
he had a vague, incomplete notion,
Adam whom
he conceived as
as Plotinus said, there are ideas
God
of individuals. Finally, the will of
causes
not an ideal model but con-
is
but that he willed the creation of an
it
In the second place,
supposition," he said, "is not that
Adam
a definite individual."
ences; through
will.
from those which
the foundation of exist-
is
chooses the best combination of possibles and
into being.
Further elaboration of the divine attributes yields a clearer understanding of determination and that
its
mechanistic character.
any possible tends toward existence
essence
is
grant
or that
for each possible achieves ex-
it is
degree of perfection
its
the one that possesses the his metaphysical
maximum is
is,
of reality.
mechanism, linked
mechanism
just as his physical
—that in —and the total combination
not blocked by other possibles
istence in so far as
accordance with
From
we
merely the exigency of existence, creation becomes a prob-
lem of equilibrium and of maximum,
is
If
(exigit existere)
the optimal will
to
linked to force, Leibniz deduces
a priori the general characteristics of the universe.
We
cannot speak of
infinitude. parts,
and
reality
Only imaginary, that
niz, therefore,
is
without speaking
one more proof of
had
their
to find a universe in
ing real which was not at the same time of his notion of the is
as
commonly it
up
into finite
imaginary character. Leib-
which there could be nothinfinite.
That
is
the origin
monad. Leibniz began by substituting
for
what
called the real universe a representation of the universe
exists in the
mind. The universe assumed
an insubstantial phenomenon; tations.
same time of
at the
abstract beings can be cut
reality is the
to
be real
mind with
its
is
merely
represen-
Furthermore, he generalized the idea of representation,
which became equivalent
to the idea of expression:
becomes the expression of another (in
my
language)
"One thing when there
a
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
248
a constant, regular relation between
is
what can be
said of the other. Expression
and
ural perception, animal feeling,
From
species."
what can be
the
minds
whose aggregate
we
tations each of
us.
follows that the repre-
it
intellectual
knowledge and con-
Representation does not imply conscious-
observe that within ourselves there are represen-
which involves an
indefinite
division into parts,
The
without our having the slightest awareness of such perceptions.
sound of the surf, for example, between many tiny totally
unaware.
Or
particles
is
sum
the
—elementary
of the sound of collisions
sounds of which
we
are
again, a perceptible quality, color, or smell
deceptively simple, for
number
its
constitutes the universe are not
endowed with
by
sciously perceived ness; indeed,
nat-
knowledge are
popular point of view and his gen-
his reversal of the
that are
one and
... a genus, and
is
intellectual
eralization of the idea of representation, sentative beings
said of
it
results
from the aggregation of a huge
of elementary perceptions of unnoticed motions.
are states, such as that of being in a faint, in
no longer accompanied by any fore be expressed in countless
feeling.
ways
tions in a distinct representation.
is
And
there
which perceptions are
The same
thing can there-
since there are countless grada-
Thus we not only can but must
(since the universe has to contain the
maximum
of reality) con-
ceive the universe as an aggregate of beings representative of the
infinitude of the universe. since there
is
an
There must be an
infinity of such beings
infinity of degrees in the clearness
and
distinctive-
ness of the representation of the universe.
Thus through tion of
generalization the notion of
monad. The universe of Leibniz
is
mind becomes
the no-
in a sense analogous to
Plotinus intelligible world in which the total reality of the world ,
appears through each idea, and
it is
important for us to
recall that
the notion of a descending hierarchy in which each universe repeats all is
of the others at different degrees of concentration or of dilution
one of the most
common
notions in Platonic philosophy. This
indeed what monads are: each of them "windowless," isolated, and perfectly also a different expression of the
same
is
a spiritual universe
self-sufficient
universe,
and
world; each all
is
—
is
such expres-
LEIBNIZ
249
sions constitute a hierarchy descending
But
least perfect.
from the most
no longer Neo-Platonism
this is
:
perfect to the
the gradational
universes of the Neo-Platonists, taken in their descending order, exhibit less
and
unity until finally, at the lowest degree, they
less
reach the state of juxtaposition in space which characterizes the sensible
world. Here nothing of the sort happens; each of the
monads
keeps the same indivisible unity from one hierarchy to the next. reason
is
that Leibniz rejects the concept of the distinction
The
between
unity and dispersion, required by the realism of the spatial world
he no longer
and puts
accepts,
distinctiveness
and
in
its
place the Cartesian concept of
confusion and obscurity,
clarity in contrast to
which remains wholly
spiritual in nature.
Monads then
differ
among
themselves only in so far as they express the same universe with
varying degrees of
clarity.
It
is
thought that introduces into the exist in the gradational
the spiritual nature of Leibniz'
monad
dynamism
a
that did not
worlds of the Neo-Platonists, for each
monad
not only expresses the whole universe at every instant with a certain degree of clarity but also tends spontaneously to express best possible
way. Each
monad
it
or variety in the unity by which the infinite detail of things
resented in
it
at every
in the
then has two attributes: perception
moment, and
is
rep-
appetition or the spontaneous
tendency to pass from obscure perceptions to clearer perceptions.
And
there
monad"
is
a hierarchy of
monads extending from
that has only perceptions without
ing to the rational sciousness
and
monad
or
reflective acts,
mind
any apperception or
feel-
that possesses, along with con-
knowledge of necessary
intermediate level are the animal
the "naked
truths.
monads which, thanks
can predict the future by anticipating,
when an
ready taken place recurs, the event that followed
to
On
event that has it
an
memory, al-
on the previous
occasion (empirical successions).
Furthermore, any
and fore,
is is
pregnant with
its
contains traces of
not rely on our experience. "I
shall take a trip but
I
its
whole past
whole future. Everything about
determined by internal reasons. This
we must I
monad always
am
am
we know
it,
there-
a priori, and
uncertain as to whether
not uncertain as to whether
I shall
always
25O
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
be myself, regardless of the
trip.
Such things seem indeterminate
us only because the signs or indications of
The
not recognizable to us."
them
we
events that
to
in our substance are
contingent are not
call
indeterminate.
Monads
same universe. The only
are mirrors or expressions of the
difference between
them
relates to the degree of clarity in their ex-
But an infinitude of monads must be postulated, for the
pression.
law of plenitude and continuity applies equally extension. Furthermore, just as there
between two points of a straight
is
an
to
forms and
infinity of other points
line, so there
is
an
infinity of in-
termediate expressions between two expressions that differ in
This
is
characteristic of divine infinitude: "Because
sees
fit
to
God
clarity.
from
reveals
way
the general system of
phenomena
produce in order
to manifest his glory,
and views every
every aspect and in every
he
to
no
aspect of the world in every possible manner, letting
relation
escape his omniscience, the result of each view of the universe a certain spot
is
from
from
a substance that expresses the universe
that
this
angle."
The
infinity of
monads
whole or a substantial by
itself, it is
principle is
(the aggregate) in
reality that
we might
one of the syncategorematic
must be sought outside the
no way call
the world.
infinities
series.
The
constitutes a
Taken
whose unifying Leibnizian view
therefore diametrically opposed to the idea of a world soul or a
universal mind.
viii
Pre-established
The
serial
established will
and
way
as to
law which
harmony.
his
Harmony relates
It is
monads
to
one another
grounded on the
belief that
is
called pre-
God, by
wisdom, has acted on the being of monads
make
at every instant,
in such a
each monad's perceptions correspond to one another each perception differing from the others because
of the point of view
from which the universe
using a metaphor, because of
harmony means
his
that
God,
its
degree of
in creating
is
seen or, without
clarity. Pre-established
one monad, had
all
other
LEIBNIZ
25I
monads
in
mind. The will
from
events that issues for there
of
all
is
it is
no fragmented
to create a particular
monad with
all
the
never a primitive or an absolute decree, will in
God. But having willed the
best
possible worlds, he gave to each substance every possible per-
fection,
with the result that his decree with respect to a particular
substance or to an event involving this substance
always an ex-
is
hypothesi decree resulting from the universal order.
harmony explains the monad. The whole being of
Pre-established ideal) of a
action in a
monad
action or passion (always
monad
a
is
representative;
from a higher degree of
designates passage
clarity,
passion to a lower degree. Further, by virtue of pre-established har-
mony an tive a
increase of clarity in one
diminution of
clarity in
therefore said to act (ideally)
such interaction
is
monad
has as a necessary correla-
one or more other monads the ;
upon
the others.
A
first is
particular case of
brought to light in connection with the problem
of the union of soul
and body. Between the two there
is
neither real
influence, as Descartes maintained, nor occasional causality, as
Male-
branche maintained, but pre-established harmony like that between
two clocks
so well regulated by their
indefinitely to
maker
that they will continue
keep the same time. Such independence and spon-
taneity does not prevent us
from speaking
in the sense that whatever
is
sion in the other,
and
an interaction
(ideally) of
action in one will be
matched by
pas-
vice versa.
Freedom and Theodicy: Optimism
ix
The problem There
is
of
freedom
also finds
its
solution in monadology.
no modification of the monad which
is
not spontaneous
and which does not come about independently, but there of
all types,
tinct
ranging from those whose perceptions are
even than the perceptions that
consciousness to the rational
by
clear
and
distinct ideas.
we have during
monads whose
Such
monads more indisare
a total loss of
actions are determined
acts are called free,
freedom being
nothing except "spontaneity of intelligent being." Freedom then in
no sense indetermination, nor does
it
is
involve indetermination.
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
252
Free
acts,
derived like everything else from the internal law of the
monad, manifest
Arnauld coun-
a kind of rational determinism.
tered Leibniz, however, by saying that such freedom implied no responsibility
on the part of the author of the
Adam
the notion of the creation of
divine decree, then
we must
and
say that
God
is
Every theologian since Plato had taken pains
For example,
act.
his sin
if
the object of a
is
the author of sin.
to set aside this very
objection.
Leibniz dealt at length with the problem in one of his longer works, the Theodicy, which defends is
God
the author of sin and, in general, of
against the charge that he
The book
evil.
inspired for
is
the most part by the traditional teachings of the Stoics gustine,
which Descartes
Leibniz makes a distinction between metaphysical tion, physical evil or pain,
rives
that
from the
God
and moral
its
all
if
we
realize
place in the
its
possible worlds,
we
infer
scheme of things every creature possesses
just proportion of perfection; since
hend things only
in isolation
and
seems to us to be
less perfect
than
is
Au-
Here
evil or imperfec-
limits inherent in every creature; but
whole and that he created the best of each instant
St.
evil or sin. Imperfection de-
created no being without awareness of
that within the total
and
also used in his fourth Meditation.
abstractly, it
might
we
at
can appre-
however, each creature
be. Physical evil or pain
explained as being a consequence, established by divine justice,
of either imperfection (pain being associated with passivity) or sin.
Adam's sin is not a simple imperfection but which sprang from his own initiative and which
Last comes moral a positive evil
evil:
transformed the destiny of mankind;
it
introduced into things the
kind of discontinuity that Leibniz sought everywhere
from
his vision of the universe.
onciled with
dogma?
We
peculiar to Leibniz, but
How,
was
God's not
Adam, though
free,
God and which was having known infallibly
would
tion, equally traditional,
sin.
We
sin be rec-
difficulty
traditional in a theology
an omnipotent and omniscient to account for
moral
then, could
should note that the
to eliminate
was not
which posited
therefore unable in advance that
should also note that the solu-
was provided by
St.
Augustine,
who
stated
LEIBNIZ
253 that
God
can foresee events but that events are not thereby prede-
termined. Leibniz' position
he can
of
it is
God
man
that each
responsible for
each
to
is
decree.
According
man
is
then one can say that it.
Though
God
willed
the implication
Adam
God
by
best of all possible worlds; consequently
he
Adam
Adam
as
was entering the
object;
its
Adam, he would not have made him created the best of
all
if
Adam would
was metaphysically to sin,
best of all
he had created only
would he have
a sinner, nor
possible worlds. Leibniz believes, then, that
he can avoid the absolute decree by imputing certain that
and
cannot be said to have willed Adam's sin since
have
his will did not
sin
God created we know this is total decree
to sin because
possible worlds.
Adam's
that
is
through one particular, original decree,
which God created the
damna-
destined either to salvation or to
not true, for the particular decree depends on the
allowed
to Cal-
by a decree dependent on the sovereign and arbitrary will
tion. If this is true, is
The only way in which show how it is possible, in his
less tenable.
from Calvin's absolute
system, to escape vin,
is
satisfy the theologians
sin,
sin to
Adam.
It
was
but his sin was not necessary since
possible (that
noncontradictory) for
is,
it
him not
and the reason with which he was endowed enabled him
to
understand the sin that he was committing.
The sume
nature of Leibniz' optimism
made
it
that the best of all possible worlds
him
possible for
to as-
accommodated dogmas
such as those relating to the small number of the
elect.
No
pages
bring out more clearly the significance of his doctrine of infinity
than those in the Theodicy dealing with eternal damnation, the endless suffering
which seems
to provide a contrast intended to
the beauty of the universe. sent,
and divine
justice
is
Here the
man
to
is
enhance
completely ab-
no more rigorous than a geometrical
orem. For the tragic sense can destiny of
tragic sense
exist
only for those
who
the-
consider the
be a kind of entity, isolated to some degree from
the universe through an initiative of the will. But in a system in
which only individual substances their spontaneity,
exist
and everything
even the slightest element has
universe as a whole. This
is
its
issues
from
function in the
because these individual substances are
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
254
universes
and contain,
substance,
only by
at least potentially, everything possible.
which seems
its
relations
be complete by
to
with
damned
in a hierarchy that includes the
actually defined
itself, is
other beings and by
all
Each
definite place
its
as well as angels
and the
elect.
x
Living Beings
Monadology
also helps
Leibniz resolve the problem of the nature
In a sense the problem of living beings, which never ceased
of
life.
to
concern him, was at the outset one of the sources of his theory of
monads. In
1671,
when he was
them
Rosicrucians, he expressed with
kind of
invisible nucleus of the
of microscopists
—Leuwenhoek,
made important
his conviction that there
body which
discoveries
is
a
will subsist until the
was drawn quite naturally
Resurrection. His attention
and
associating with alchemists
to the
works
Swammerdam, and Malpighi—who
between 1670 and 1690 concerning
mals or animate elements invisible to the naked eye.
ani-
The microscope
enabled them to see in the living being not (in keeping with the ancient tradition of Aristotle) organs
formed of homogenous
tissues
but
organs whose parts were themselves organized. This offered a kind of experimental confirmation of the alchemists' subsistent nucleus,
and
it
allowed Leibniz to introduce his infinitary ideas indirectly
into biology. It also allowed as Plotinus is
had already done,
nothing in nature which
that matter
is
it
grows
is
to universalize the concept of
to the extent of
not animate.
organized to infinity
how small, that we cannot
ter
that
him
is itself
organized.
assert that
until
it
—that
From
an animal
becomes
visible
is
is,
assuming that there
was
It
it
born or
dies;
we
human come
organization also allowed
race:
him
to
is
until
it
be-
indestructi-
assume the "pattern-
Adam
germs are organisms and can decrease
infinitely small.
can only say
and then decreases
ing of germs" to explain the pre-existence in
no mat-
follows immediately
comes imperceptible; the germ of the animate being ble. Infinite
assume
sufficient to
that every part,
this
life,
Each organism, no matter how
of the
whole
until they be-
small,
is
com-
LEIBNIZ
255
posed of an
number of parts; there must be a law of their "central monad" whose representations correspond
infinite
relation in the
between
ideally to the relations
material universe
and which
is
this
to the
organism and the
organism
rest of the
as the soul
we
body. Corresponding to the growth of the body, to what birth
and
its
adult state,
in the central
an increase in the
is
monad. Thus Leibniz, who
moment
call its
clarity of perceptions
in his correspondence
with Arnauld (1686) had seemed to concede that created at the
to the
is
human
souls
were
were pre-
of birth, later believed that they
existent but raised to a higher degree of clarity with the birth of the
body. Moreover, in his view rational souls not only subsist after
death (like the souls of brutes, which state of
fall
back into their primitive
confusion) but are also truly immortal
decree of
God
enables
them
—that
to preserve their reason
a special
is,
and personality
independently of their bodies. Leibniz' biological and organic theory, therefore, allowed
speak of unity in bodies. Such unity, as
we have
him
to
seen repeatedly,
cannot be due to extension, which spontaneously crumbles. But do
we
not run into difficulty
monads? gate of larly,
We
we
if
attribute
it
to
an aggregate of
have seen that the universe was formed of an aggre-
monads which did not monads
the aggregate of
constitute a unit.
That
is
why
constitute a
whole or a
that corresponds to a
unit; simi-
body
will not
Des Bosses
in his correspondence with
(1706) he postulated a substantial bond {vinculum substantiale)
between monads, thereby making constant application of the same principle: to realize, outside the infinite series of terms infinity of
monads
in relation to a single body), the
(here the
law of the
series.
xi
Innate Ideas: Leibniz and hoc\e
Monadology provided Leibniz with the solution to the problem of innate ideas. "The question is somewhat equivocal," he said, apparently referring to the ficulty
way
which he examined
in
which Locke had handled the
in his turn in the preface
and
first
dif-
book
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
256
New
of the
Essays concerning
Human
Understanding.
The
first
we can refute the doctrine of we do not always have actual knowlbeing known to us when we concentrate make them innate. Furthermore, the word
equivocation consists in thinking that innate ideas by showing that
edge of them
—for
upon them
enough
"innate"
own
is
to
equivocal: to the degree that everything comes from
is
resources
nothing that
mon
their
is
and
am
I
subjected to
not innate in the
monad
that
I
my
action, there
is
am. But "in the com-
system" that postulates the influence of bodies on minds, that
which does not come from
and
no external
this
the
is
sensible
knowledge
called "innate,"
is
meaning implied by the famous adage which denies
innatism: "Nihil est in intellectu guod non prius fuerit in sensu."
This is also the meaning generally accepted by Leibniz, but the word embraces so many nuances that precision is not always easy. The mark of innatism is necessity, which pertains either to the primreason
itive truths of
reason
ficient
—or
—the axiom of identity and the principle of suf-
word
a "priori"
proof). is
As
inconceivable
as a
be proven a priori (the
used by Leibniz only with reference to such a
is
—the
and not
to
For example, intellect
accept the Scholastic
"There
nothing in the itself
apriority are merely
marks
which
perience
—that
rience:
"Inasmuch
is
by which
as
of innatism.
which
is
sensations
is,
it
from that which
"intelligible
being"
think. Leibniz can
one
restriction:
in sensation,
ipse)" But necessity and
The word
"innate" properly
within us independendy of any external ex-
to that
but only that which
we
which has not been
{nisi intellects
the object of pure internal expe-
and inductions can never teach
completely universal truths or that which
partially
which
impossible for a thing
adage, but with
intellect
except the intellect
is,
it is
be at the same time. All of our innate ideas taken
therefore
refers to that
which a truth
ideas of being, possible, same, identity,
whole constitute the is
may
for innate ideas, they are ideas without
enter into an innate truth. to be
can be reduced to the
to the derived truths that
principle of necessity; to truths that
follows that is
is
absolutely necessary,
we have drawn such
within us." So
all
truths
ideas are reduced to
—to the "object of pure understanding" which
is
LEIBNIZ
257 the
constituted by inner experience.
self,
stance, action,
from
my
and of
of myself
and
"The notion
that I have
thoughts, and consequently of being, sub-
identity,
"reflective acts," as
comes from an inner experience" or
he says elsewhere (Monadology, 30).
And
in a letter to Sophia Charlotte, he adds the following restriction to the Scholastic
adage: "With the exception of the understanding
or whoever understands."
itself
But inner experience natural light of reason us and which
we
:
now it
designates something greater than the
signifies
see there
everything which
when our
vision
is
is
naturally in
not obscured by the
needs and inclinations that come from the body. Alongside reason constituted by confused but innate knowledge:
instinct,
is
must pursue joy and avoid
sadness," for instance
whose reasons are unknown and which are .
.
.
so."
along with customs, though
—natural sentiments untangle
"difficult to
generally possible for us to do
Here, as in the thinking of Descartes, the innateness of an idea
does not exclude
The
xii
its
being indistinct.
Existence of Bodies
Monads
We
it is
"One
are the only substantial realities that exist in the universe.
saw how Leibniz removed
rior world,
deprive
such as
of every
it
it
substantial existence
was conceived by the
mode
of existence?
the mind, though "windowless,"
is
We
from the
ought
exte-
But did he
Cartesians.
first to
note that
quite certain, even in the absence
of the complicated machinery of the Cartesian proof, that something exists in the outer
world. Descartes
ous truths "I think, and there :
is
since
is
only the
great variety in
the second truth "proves that there
which
knew is
first
my
of
two obvi-
thoughts." For
something other than ourselves
the cause of the variety of the things that appear to us,"
one and the same thing cannot be the cause of the changes
within
it.
The
representation of the external world then
is
to
me
a
"well-founded phenomenon," founded on the existence of the substantial diversity of
monads outside ourselves. But it is also by inner phenomena" are distinguishable from the
characteristics that "real
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
258
'imaginary phenomena" of dreams
enon in
non
is
and
its
itself,
by
its
animation,
:
its
first, if
permanence or
consider the
multiplicity (the real
endowed not with one but with
phenomena, by
we
phenom-
phenome-
several sensible qualities),
integrity in time; then,
we
if
consider other
agreement with prior phenomena, by the mutual
its
agreement of minds, and by success in the prediction of phenomena.
These we should note, are the are derived
criteria
mentioned by Descartes they :
from the Academic and Skeptic schools of
and Leibniz brings out
their true
worth when he
antiquity,
says that they pro-
vide moral certainty rather than metaphysical certainty. If
we
examine, looking beyond things themselves, the order in
which they time. Far
coexist
and succeed one another, we obtain space and
from being
which they are contained, things possible
and
antecedent to things or receptacles in
realities
as the
Newtonians thought, they are
relative only to the beings of
order. "I hold that space
is
an order of coexistences,
something purely
just as
time
is
ideal
which they are the
relative, like time, to
an order of successions,"
Leibniz wrote to Clarke. "For space indicates in terms of possibility
an order of things that
exist at the
same time
together, without entering into their
we
see several things together,
we
ways of
in so far as they exist existing.
notice the order
And when
among
the things
themselves."
Ethics
xiii
From
his theology
and monadism Leibniz deduces a moral
phi-
losophy. "I submit," he wrote to Conring as early as 1670, "that
may require no more than a God and the immortality of the
ethics
demonstration that the existence
of
soul are probable or at least pos-
sible."
Why? On
one hand he assumes with Carneades that
without an appropriate folly;
eral
utility,
on the other hand he
whether present or future,
justice
is
utter
sees clearly that justice seeks the gen-
good or the good of the
society to
which we belong. Only a
providential theology can resolve the problem of the just corre-
spondence of virtue and
—the problem attacked by
utility
Cicero in
a
LEIBNIZ
259 the
De officiis—and "we
must do what
is
we
just unless
first
demonstrate that there
petual [avenger] of the public interest, that
much
he
as
be another
clearly not always the
is
had discovered
Later, after he
avenger in
monads
his
and
are capable of discovering necessary
are
a per-
must
this life, there
and transmuted
from angels
subjects (ranging
of his city
is
justice,
world the greatest good that our happiness] are formulas
there
if
is
is
to
men)
which
we
if
a
his universe into a
monarch (God) whose
Minds
are
is
certain [to contribute to
a Providence that governs
we
of every type.
consists "in procuring for the
can; this
which we should not forget
guage of monadology it
—"substances that think truths"— he followed the
Minds" ruled over by
"universal republic of
that each
is
that inas-
of a higher degree
ancient tradition of the Stoics
mum
God and
system of monads and shown
minds
Indeed,
is,
life."
that
The law
man
cannot demonstrate with precision that
all
things."
These
to translate into the lan-
are to understand their full significance.
through a natural law derived from the will of
mind
God
in the universe acquires at each instant the maxi-
of perfection compatible with the whole, but the
consciously while the bare will that thrusts us
mind
acts
monad is divested of sensation; and the common utility is illuminated by
toward the
knowledge of our own nature, with the "the inner power that keeps
man from
result that virtue
is
actually
being diverted from the right
path to happiness by the passions of his soul." Such
is
the jatum
christianum ; in a "good sense" fatutn means the decree of Providence.
"And
those
who submit
to the decree
divine perfections, of which the love of
through knowledge of
God
is
a consequence, do
not (like the pagan philosophers) simply resign themselves to patient
endurance but are even happy in the knowledge that whatever
God
ordains
is
for the best."
escape the jatum
God were
,
interrelated, as well as quietism
since, in his opinion, It
But Leibniz thought that he could
mahometanum which denied
would seem
knowledge engendered
that the decrees of
and
"idle
argument"
action.
that the idea of a universal republic should have
persuaded Leibniz to accept a universal religion of some kind
—
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
200
humanism
superior to positive religions
he tried to show
cally,
mas were
no way contrary
in
—but
it
did not. Theoreti-
that the positive elements of Christian dog-
we have
to reason; practically, as
seen,
he conceived a religious organization of the world in which Chris-
and united
tians, politically reconciled
in the
same Church, would
spread Christian civilization throughout the world. In keeping with his genius, his universalism
Stoic thinkers; instead, filtrates
One
is
not the abstract universalism of the
assumes the most concrete forms and
it
in-
the infinite realm of singular political realities.
of his
first
works had been an anti-Socinian Defensio Trini-
(about 1665), in which he boasted of having already found "a
tatis
more profound philosophy" more
to supply
applicable to meditation
him with
precepts
on sacred things and
him
well as to physics, and which would allow
which were
civic affairs as
"to lead a tranquil
Consequently he never separated these three objects: religion,
life."
physics,
and
civic life.
He
did everything possible to eliminate seem-
ingly wide divergences between the discontinuity of the Christian vision of the universe instance, as
it
and
was revealed
his
own
conception of continuity
Other elements
to us in his theory of sin.
of the Christian faith (miracles, transubstantiation) also
interrupt the continuity of nature: the Port-royalist jected that Leibniz'
monadology excluded
—for
miracles,
seemed
to
Arnauld ob-
and the
Jesuit
Des Bosses believed it to be irreconcilable with transubstantiation. Drawing support from his doctrine of infinity, Leibniz defended his view of miracles as follows: we know that when points are indicated on a surface in any manner whatsoever, we can find the equation of the curve that contains them and accounts for their arrangement. Suppose, then, that
and
that
some
them while must
indefinite series of events
others do not
—in other words, they are
we understand miraculous; we
conceive, in divine infinitude, a law of the series that will
brace both kinds of events.
what we verse,
we have an
of the events obey natural laws as
call
and
The miraculous
events,
em-
which interrupt
the natural order, have a place in the order of the uni-
their failure to
divine attributes.
As
have a place in
for transubstantiation,
it
would contravene
we saw how
the
Leibniz in
LEIBNIZ
26l
his reply to
Des Bosses conceived
the substantial
bond
to
account for
monads correspond "well-founded" phenomenon; but
the unity of bodies; in transubstantiation the to the subsistent bread,
which
is
a
through a miracle the substantial bond of the body of Christ places the substantial
In practice, almost
bond all
re-
of the bread.
were directed toward
of Leibniz' activities
the triumph of Christianity. But he
felt that its
triumph could not
be assured without a return to unity, which should have
begin-
its
ning in the union of Lutherans and Calvinists, 3 followed by the reuniting of the Protestants in
As
Germany with
the Catholic Church.
early as 1673 he discussed the matter with Pellisson, through
whom
he tried
and
to reach Bossuet,
Systema
in 1686 he wrote the
theologicum in which he proposed a formulary for conciliation. Pellisson died in 1693, but as late as 1701 Leibniz
me
hope: "You are right in judging
he wrote
to
Mme
de Brinon. "The essence of Catholicism
communion with Rome;
be in
cated unjustly
would
otherwise those
who
munion, which makes us a part of the body of he
lost all
are
.
.
.
,"
not to
is
excommuni-
cease to be Catholics in spite of their wishes
and without being inculpated in any way. The this spirit
had not
to be a Catholic at heart
tried, for the benefit
true, essential
Christ,
is
com-
charity." In
of Bossuet, to attenuate the impor-
tance of doctrinal differences that separated the confessions, pointing
out that they originated in the Council of Trent, whose ecumenical
was not even recognized
character
no more
significant than the
in France,
and
divine love which did not destroy the unity of the the
Roman community. "What
the
dogmas
can
prevents reunion
as the practices" of the
(perhaps unwise) spirit that
facility
that they
Roman
Church within is
Church.
not so
And
Church and recognize
Cf
.
and
with a
he called Bossuet's attention to the Galli-
and other
pastors." Bossuet also sought unity
but on condition that the Protestants simply return to the
3
much
animated France, to the "limits placed there on the
authority of the popes
variations
were
unending controversies about grace and
all
of
its
Roman
decisions; unity did not include the
differences that Leibniz
wished to safeguard.
"Correspondance inedite," Revue philosophique,
July, 1934.
Bibliography
I
Texts Jakob Bohme. Samtliche Schrijten. Edited by
W.
Peuckert. 2 vols. Stuttgart,
1955-61. .
Samtliche Wer\e. Edited by K.
W.
Schiebler. 3d ed. 7 vols. Leipzig,
1923.
Studies Boutroux, E. "Le philosophe allemand Jacob Boehme," in Etudes d'histoire
de la philosophic Paris, 1897. Koyre, A. La philosophie de Jacob Boehme. Paris, 1929. "Maitre Valentin Weigel," Revue d'histoire et de philosophie religieuse, .
1928.
II to
XIII
Texts Wilhelm von. Samtliche Schrijten und Briefe. Edited by Akademie der Wissenschaften. 40 vols. Berlin, 1923 Opera philosophica. Edited by J. E. Erdmann. 2 vols. Berlin, 1839-
Leibniz, Gottfried
the Preussische .
40. .
Die philosophischen Schrijten. Edited by C. Gerhardt. 7
vols. Berlin,
1875-90. .
Die mathematischen Schrijten. Edited by C. Gerhardt. 7
vols. Berlin,
1849-63. .
Opuscules
.
Textes inedits d'apres
et
fragments
inedits.
les
Edited by L. Couturat. Paris, 1903.
manuscrits de la bibliotheque de Hanovre.
Edited by G. Grua. 2 vols. Paris, 1948. Opuscula philosophica selecta. Edited by P. Schrecker. Paris, 1939. Philosophical Papers and Letters. Translated by L. E. Loemker. 2 .
.
vols.
Chicago, 1956.
262
LEIBNIZ
263 .
.
Selections. Edited
by Philip P. Wiener. Reprinted:
New
York, 1959.
Discourse on Metaphysics. Translated by P. G. Lucas and L. Grint.
Manchester, 1953. .
Monadology and Other Philosophical Writings. Translated by Robert
Latta. Reprinted: Oxford, 1948. .
New
Essays Concerning
Langley. 3d ed. La Salle, .
111.,
Human
Understanding. Translated by A. G.
1949.
The Leibniz-Clarke Correspondence. Translated by H. G. Alexander.
Manchester, 1956. Theodicy. Translated by E. M. Huggard. London, 1952. .
Studies
W. H. Leibniz in France from Arnauld to Voltaire. Oxford, 1955. H. W. Lectures on the Philosophy of Leibniz. Oxford, 1949. Carr, H. W. Leibniz. New ed. New York, i960. Joseph, H. W. B. Lectures on the Philosophy of Leibniz. Oxford, 1949. Barber,
Brindly,
The Great Chain
Lovejoy, A. O.
of Being. Reprinted:
Cambridge, Mass., 1948. J. North-
Martin, Gottfried. Leibniz: Logic and Metaphysics. Translated by K. cott
and
Meyer, R.
P.
W.
G. Lucas.
New
York, 1964.
Leibniz and the Seventeenth-century Revolution. Translated by
J. P. Stern. Cambridge, 1952. Saw, R. L. Leibniz. London, 1954. Yost, R. M. Leibniz and Philosophical Analysis. Berkeley,
Calif.,
1954.
II
Studies Baruzi,
}.
Leibniz
et
V organisation
religieuse
de
la terre. Paris, 1907.
Belaval, Y. Leibniz critique de Descartes. Paris, i960.
Burgelin, P. Catalogue critique des manuscrits de Leibniz. Poitiers, 1914-24. .
Commentaire du Discours de Metaphysique de Leibniz.
Paris,
1959.
Daville, L. Leibniz historien. Paris, 1909. .
"Le sejour de Leibniz a Paris," Archiv fur Geschichte de Philosophic,
1922.
Friedmann, G. Leibniz et Spinoza. 4th ed. Paris, 1946. Harnack, A. Geschichte der preussischen A\ademie der Wissenschaften. Berlin, 1900. Vol I. Ravier, E. Bibliographic des ceuvres de Leibniz. Alcan, 1937. Robinet, A. Malebranche et Leibniz, relations personnelles. Paris, 1955. Stein, L. Leibniz
und Spinoza.
Berlin, 1890.
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
264
III
Studies Balaval, Y.
Pour connaitre
Boutroux, E. "Notice sur
de H. Poincare sur
pensee de Leibniz. Paris, 1959. de Leibniz, suivie d'une note
la
la vie et les ceuvres
les
Principes de
la
mecanique dans Descartes
et
dans
Leibniz," in Leibniz, Monadologie, Paris, Delagrave. .
"Introduction a l'etude des nouveaux essais," in Leibniz,
Essais, -.
Book
I,
Paris, Delagrave.
La philosophic allemande au
Cassirer, E. Leibniz's
XVH e
siecle. Paris,
Nouveaux
1929.
System in seinen wissenschaftlichen Grundlagen. Mar-
burg, 1902.
Couturat, L.
La logique de
Fischer, K. Gottfried
Leibniz. Paris, 190 1.
Wilhelm Leibniz. 5th
ed. Heidelberg, 1920.
Halbwachs, M. Leibniz. 2d ed. Paris, 1929. Hannequin, A. Quae juerit prior Leibnitii philosophia ante 16J2. Paris, 1895. Mahnke, D. "Leibniz als Begriinder de symbolischen Mathematik," Isis, 1927. Moreau, J. L'univers leibnizien. Paris, 1956. Olgiati, F. // significato storico di Leibniz. Milan, 1930.
Russell, Bertrand.
London,
A
Critical Exposition of the
Philosophy of Leibniz. 2d ed.
1937.
IV
Studies Dunan, C. "Leibniz
et
le
mecanisme," Annales de philosophic chretienne,
1910.
M. Dynamique et metaphysique leibniziennes. Paris, 1934. Hannequin, A. "La philosophic de Leibniz et les lois du mouvement," Revue Gueroult,
de metaphysique, 1906. Helmholtz, H. "Zur Geschichte des Princips der kleinsten Action," Sitzungsberichte der berliner A\ademie der Wissenschaftcn, 1887, pp. 225 ff.
V Studies Couturat, L. "Sur la metaphysique de Leibniz, avec
Revue de metaphysique,
1902.
un opuscule
inedit,'
265
LEIBNIZ
Jalabert,
J.
La
theorie leibnizienne de la substance. Paris, 1947.
Werckmeister,
W. Der
leibnizsche Substanzbegriff. Halle, 189c
VI
Studies Albrich, C. "Leibniz's Lehre des Gefiihls," Archiv jur die gesamte Psychologie,
XVI. Dillmann, E. Eine neue Darstellung der leibnizschen Monadenlehre. Leipzig, 1891.
De infinitato apud Leibnitium. Paris, 1878. Die Apperzeption im philosophischen System des Leibniz. (DisserJ. tation) Bonn, 1900. Vallier, C. A. De possibilibus apud Leibnitium. Bordeaux, 1882. Penjon, A.
Rulf,
VII
Studies Iwanacki,
J.
Leibniz et
les
demonstrations mathematiques de Vexistence de
Dieu. Paris, 1934. Rodier, G. "Sur une des origines de
Revue de metaphysique,
1902.
la
philosophic de Leibniz
Reprinted
in
Etudes
de
[Plotinus],"
philosophic
grecque.
Zymalkowski, N. Die Bedeutung der prdstabilierten Harmonie im Leibnizschen System. (Dissertation) Erlangen, 1905.
VIII
Studies
De libertate apud Leibnitium. Paris, 1903. W. Vber den Freiheitsbegriff und seine Grundlagen
Cresson, A.
Winhold,
bei Leibniz.
(Dissertation) Halle, 1912.
IX
Studies Blondel,
M. De Vinculo
nitium. Paris, 1893.
substantiali et de substantia composita
apud Leib-
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
266
Bois-Reymond, E. du. "Uber leibnizsche Gedanken in der neueren Naturwissenschaft," Monatsberichte der berliner A\ademie der Wissenschajten, 1870, pp. 835
ff.
H. "Leibniz
Peters,
wissenschajt
als
Chemiker," Archiv fur die Geschichte der Natur-
und der Techni\,
1916, pp. 85
ff.
X Study "Lockes Lehre der menschlichen Erkenntnis im Vergleich mit der leibnizschen Kritik derselben," Abhandlungen der sachsischen
Hartenstein, G.
Gesellschaft der Wissenschajten,
X
&
(1865), 4 11
XI
Studies
Van Biema,
E. L'espace et le
W. Die
Volp,
temps chez Leibniz
Phenomenalitat
der
Materie
et
bei
chez Kant. Paris, 1903. Leibniz.
(Dissertation)
Erlangen, 1903.
XII
Study Nathan,
B.
Uber das Verhaltnis der leibnizschen Ethi\ zu Metaphysi\ und
Theologie. (Dissertation) Jena, 1918.
XIII
Studies Grua, G. Jurisprudence universelle .
La
justice
humaine
et theodicee selon Leibniz. Paris, 1953.
selon Leibniz. Paris, 1956.
JOHN LOCKE AND ENGLISH PHILOSOPHY i
and Wor\
Life
Loc\e
of
john locke (1632-1704),
the son of a small land-
owner and attorney from Wrington, near war began and
the civil
his father enlisted in the
From
the parliamentary side.
was
Bristol,
1652 to 1658 he
sixteen
when
army supporting
was a student
at
Oxford, where he took courses normally associated with preparation
for
service
as
shifted to medicine
a
clergyman; in 1658, however, his interest
and he completed courses in
this
field,
but
without ever receiving the degree of doctor. In 1666 he formed close ties
with Lord Ashley, afterward Earl of Shaftesbury, whose
mented
political life
had
its
repercussions on Locke.
France on two different occasions, 1675
and
1679,
when he
first
in 1672
and
He
tor-
resided in
later
between
spent a year at Montpellier for the sake
of his delicate health; but his second period of residence in France
was prolonged by the disgrace of the Earl of Shaftesbury. In 1684 he had to leave England once again. Shaftesbury failed in his attempt
to
provoke a revolution and had to seek refuge in Holland
(where he soon died), and Locke, suspected by those decided that he in turn should
make
remained until the Revolution of
England
in 1689,
his
1688.
way
to
Following
his
he declined, primarily on account of
267
in power,
Holland, where he return to his health,
—
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
268
him by
the post offered
Brandenburg
of
—and
Concerned
peals.
was then
(it
—the
embassy
retired
Masham
to
1
to the Elector
Commissioner of Ap-
office of
political as well as
Some
that he wrote
on the Consequences of the Lowering of
the Value of Money),
He
new king
with religious and
especially
economic questions tions
the
accepted the
Interest,
Considera-
and Raising
he also had to reply to numerous polemics.
Oates, not far
from
Lord and Lady
friends
his
(daughter of the philosopher Cudworth), and remained
there until his death.
In 1670 Locke, then thirty-eight, had been Shaftesbury's personal physician since 1667, and there was nothing as yet to suggest his
A
philosophical vocation.
whom 1668,
and
friend of the physician
he collaborated, and a
member
he had written two short medical
De
Sydenham, with
of the Royal Society since treatises
Anatomica (1668)
medica (1669), in which he stated "there is no knowledge worthy of the name except knowledge that leads to some new, arte
useful invention.
Any
other speculation
an
is
idle pursuit."
General
theories are injurious because they check
and
only special hypotheses are useful
apprehending immediate
—in
he had
causes. In addition,
reflected
on the
political
questions that were disturbing his country and
and Reflections on the Roman Republic, encroachment of the clergy upon the scripturae interpres
non
ciple that the Bible
necessarius, in sufficient for
is
in
stabilize
knowledge;
and
religious
had written Sacerdos
which he protested the
civil
authority;
Infallibilis
which he advanced the prin-
our salvation; and
An
Essay
concerning Toleration (1667), in which he reflected on the tolerance
toward nonconformists (Puritans)
that should be manifested
had not accepted the Act of Uniformity of Charles
who
II.
In the winter of 1670-1671, following discussions with his friends
(among them James
to the revolution that
Orange 1
to
—the lawyer who was
Tyrell
overthrew James
—and
the throne
II
and brought William of
physician David
Thomas)
his
The campaigns which he conducted at that time against factitiously raising the money culminated in a monetary reform and in the creation of the Bank England in 1698. Cf. Rodocanachi's communication to the Academy of Moral
value of of
the
later to contribute
Sciences, session of July 24, 1933.
LOCKE AND ENGLISH PHILOSOPHY
269
thoughts took an unexpected turn. According to Tyrell's testimony,
he noticed that
it
would be impossible
"principles of morality
ining "our
own
and revealed to
abilities
see
for us to establish firmly the
religion" without
what
exam-
first
objects our understandings
were, or were not, fitted to deal with." This was the origin of
Human
Essay concerning
Understanding, which does in fact end
with a discussion of the certainty of moral truths (IV, the relation between faith
and reason (IV,
humano
intellectu
in
and
4.7)
of
Although the Es-
18).
Locke had written
say did not appear until 1690, as early as 1671
De
An
which the reduction of
all
of our ideas to
simple ideas was presented in the same was as in his Essay, which
was the
fruit of the rare
moments
of leisure afforded
him by
his
turbulent career during the nineteen-year interval. After 1688 his
were
ideas
accessible
lished in Jean
Le
through an abridgement of the Essay pub-
Clerc's Bibliotheque universelle et historique.
second edition (1694) contains II,
many
and changes
xxxiii; IV, xix)
additions
(II, xxvii; II, ix, 8;
(II, xxi; II, xxiii);
translation (1700), revised by Locke, also includes a
and
ditions
11
The
Coste's
French
number
of ad-
corrections.
Political Ideas
The Essay was
not devoted to speculation for
this reason a brief analysis of
light the conditions
Locke struggled against
its
own
sake.
Locke's political ideas will bring to
under which he wrote.
all his life
two interdependent
against the Anglican theocracy, that theses:
first,
that
no
less
is,
by divine right the
king wields absolute power; second, that the king's power itual
For
is
spir-
than temporal, giving him the right to impose on the
nation a creed and a form of worship. In this doctrine the royal
power appears lished
and not
as
he was
as
we
to
to
be something of a mystery, something pre-estab-
susceptible to analysis.
To
criticize
it
Locke proceeded
proceed in the study of the understanding. In the Essay,
shall see,
tries to identify
he reduces complex ideas to simple
factors; here
he
by analysis the simple factors into which the royal
a
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
27O
power can be
come under
divided. In neither case does their historical genesis
consideration.
His analysis was favored or even made possible by the idea (then current) that since the social state
we must
originates in a pact,
nature prior to the pact.
state of
and
not natural to
mankind but
Is
injustice to a convention, or
is
view, advocated by those
ural
law
expanse of land a
man
The
a political one.
—
The second
He
accepts as nat-
on work and consequently lim-
can cultivate, and paternal author-
based on the premise that the family
is
a natural institution, not
school that inspired Locke
to the doctrine of innatism
idea of jus-
(following the Stoics) subscribed to
the right of property based
ited to the ity
who
the one adopted by Locke.
is
in his
there a lex insita ration!
natural moral law which was imposed prior to the pact ? the law of nations,
man
the state of nature the absence of
Hobbes maintained, which reduces any
a standard, as tice
is
study, in the abstract,
first
which he
rejects.
He
is
linked, however,
maintains that
it is
possible to demonstrate the rules of justice without recourse to the
doctrine of innatism
mandment tions to
of
and predicates
God who
his
demonstration on the com-
established these rules
them; consequently
his
and attached
sanc-
demonstration depends on religious
views.
The
social pact creates
individuals
who
tive force to
no new
right. It
is
an agreement between
join together for the purpose of using their collec-
bring about the execution of natural laws, and
who
renounce the use of individual force in bringing about their execution.
This conception
is
purely nominalistic and utilitarian;
it
re-
duces society to a stabilizing force effective in repressing infractions of the law.
It
follows that the royal
owe obedience
tations. Citizens
to their
permanent laws, not with respect day.
There are
power
is
subject to precise limi-
king only with respect to
to
laws improvised from day to
legislatures but they
cannot act capriciously; more
particularly, they
cannot arbitrarily dispose of
citizens'
property by
levying a tax without their consent. In a word, the pact between subject
and sovereign
revolt against
is
bilateral,
and the
subject has the right to
any violation of the law. Such
is
the origin
and the
271
LOCKE AND ENGLISH PHILOSOPHY
nature of royal authority; cised illegally.
The
result
it
has a legal basis and cannot be exer-
is
the total reversal of the doctrine of
Hobbes, and Locke was one of those
who gave
their intellectual
assent to the Revolution of 1688.
From
such considerations the doctrine of toleration was derived.
In England the object was not to prevent a spiritual power distinct
from the temporal power,
as in
Roman
ing upon the temporal power in the all
men; on the
Elizabeth
Catholicism, from encroach-
name
"the religion of the subject
I,
regularly debated in a parliament
civil
was determined by a law
composed
laymen, statesmen, and businessmen,"
whether the
of eternal salvation for
contrary, in a country where, since the time of
2
for the
the object
was
most part of to
determine
authority created by the pact could regulate the
Under these conditions Locke refused to The sovereign is indifferent to the beliefs when they are expressed by acts contrary to
spiritual life of the people.
grant absolute toleration. of his subjects except
the purpose of the political society; the king will therefore prohibit
"papism," which allows the intervention of a foreign government,
and
will repress atheism since belief in
God
is
the principle of the
certainty of natural laws.
in
The Doctrine
The Essay
contains the doctrine
which was
to establish religious
by revealing the nature and
limits of
understanding. But before taking up this doctrine
we ought
and philosophical
human
of the "Essay": Criticism of Innate Ideas
to consider
toleration
one incident that will give us a better insight into
author's intentions. In 1678, while
Locke was meditating on
its
his
work, Cudworth published The True Intellectual System of the Universe. Cudworth, one of the
moving
spirits
of the
Cambridge
Platonists during this period, maintained that demonstration of the
truth of the existence of
God
is
inseparable
from the
thesis of innate
and that the famous empirical adage, "Nihil est quod non prius fuerit in sensu," led directly to atheism.
ideas,
2
C. Bastide, John Loc\e, p. 131.
in intellectu If all science
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
272
or knowledge
merely the informing of our minds by things
is
ted outside us, he said (following the line of
situa-
argument used
in the
tenth book of Plato's Laws), the world has to exist before there can exist a
notion and knowledge of the world; nor can knowledge and
intelligence precede the
he wrote, that
cious,
world
as
cause; but this thesis
its
carried to
if
logical conclusion
its
so falla-
is
would
it
exclude from existence not only reason and intelligence but even the faculty of feeling, for this faculty cannot be apprehended by the senses.
Cudworth's
system, for
it
thesis, if it
were
true,
was on the hypothesis
would upset Locke's whole
and
to
prove the existence of God.
the only possible one
sis
things
we must
Locke
of sensationalism that
sought to show the existence of the understanding and
Why
nature,
its
was the empirical hypothe-
Because in order to have the right idea of
?
introduce the
their inalterable relations,
mind
and not
to their inflexible nature
and
what
to
our
strive to introduce things to
assumed
to
be
immediate, inward knowledge and obviously accommodates
all
of
prejudices. Innatism, however, begins with
main theses that ought to bring
our individual prejudices; thus the us peace of
—the theory of the understanding and the existence
mind
God—are assumed
of
The
is
to
be inseparable from our prejudices.
internal structure of the Essay
is
largely explained
by Locke's
concern to reply to the Cambridge Platonists, although he never
names
his adversaries. In
Book
I,
which
is
a criticism of the doctrine
of innate ideas, the long chapter on the existence of
God and
the
chapter on enthusiasm complement and support each other.
In
Book
innatism
is
I,
Locke
clearly indicates his intention: to
would be
sufficient" for
him
use of their natural faculties,
to
may
criticize the doctrine itself
certainty without
show "how men, barely by the knowledge they
any such original notions or
one of the most dangerous of
proclamation of
infallibility
(I,
all ii.
and
attain to all the
have, without the help of any innate impressions, and
is
that
the doctrine of the prejudiced. If he were writing for
unprejudiced readers, he would not "it
show
doctrines in that 20;
I,
iii.
may
principles." it
24), that
arrive at
But
this
leads to the is,
to
an
ir-
reducible certainty based on nothing except the affirmation of an
273
LOCKE AND ENGLISH PHILOSOPHY He
individual.
dogmatism characterized by groundless
inspired if
therefore sees in innatism a kind of individually
there were truly innate principles, they
men, universally and first
But
eternally.
if
and then the
we examine
known
to
use.
few people, even
To
and
we
etc.),
bitter;
we
see
immediately their dissimilarity,
in
impossible for a
it is
itself.
This criticism of innatism
Book IV
others as
see that they are
Nor are they of we need only perceive
not bitter
is
without having to resort to the principle that thing to be different from
and con-
in enlightened circles.
decide that sweet
the ideas of sweet
of
individually
("Do unto
practical principles
you would have them do unto you," any
to exist in all
the speculative principles (the principles of identity
tradiction)
For
affirmations.
would have
is
supplemented by the tenth chapter
which the existence of God
is
proved by the simple
use of natural faculties, without resort to innate ideas. This
is
imply a preconceived notion of God;
constructed with the proof
itself.
ence of the contingent being that otent being of
who
knowing, and who
mind and
it
I
According
am
also intelligent since
is
is
was much
a
mundi, which, unlike ontological
variety of proof a contingentia proofs, does not
is
to
this notion
Locke, the
exist-
implies an eternal, omnip-
he created in
me
the faculty
the creator of matter, since he created
easier for
him
to
my
have created matter. This
proof alone can lead us to an exact, constant notion of the Divinity. Conversely, the notion that of such proof
men
have of the Divinity in the absence
confused and incoherent. There are even savage
is
who have no God is suffused
God; among the common people
tribes
idea of
of
with anthropomorphism.
Finally, the chapter
on enthusiasm (IV,
second edition of the Essay) illusions
which
is
xix,
the idea
introduced in the
a criticism of all of the individual
in religious circles are ascribed to divine inspiration.
This chapter corresponds to Malebranche's chapter on vivid imaginations
and
to Spinoza's
also note that in less sects to
Theologicopolitical
England the
disease
spring up, and Locke recognized
than anyone
else.
He
Treatise.
was endemic; its
it
We
should
caused count-
danger more clearly
called attention to the contrast
between such
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
274
an imaginative, personal religion and the rational character of
The Reasonableness
Christianity (in
and he reduced
the Scriptures, 1695), Christianity to that that his his
of Christianity as delivered in all
of the essential
which can be demonstrated by
dogmas of
reason.
It is clear
condemnation of enthusiasm in religion corresponds
to
condemnation of innatism in philosophy.
Simple Ideas and Complex Ideas
iv
How and
can he introduce the
to their inalterable
comprehensible sian doctrine
if
was
we
to the inflexible nature of things
relations?
Locke's system would be in-
did not assume that reflection on the Cartesource;
its
What
"an idealism."
mind
role
it is,
as his critics pointed out to
do ideas play in
him,
his system?
All knowledge consists in the perception of similarity between ideas
—yellow
are equal,
the
first
not red, two triangles which have three equal sides
is
and
so forth; this perception
case or reducible
The
tion as in the second.
what the term either
is
is
by demonstration idea, then,
is
to
either to
immediate
as in
an immediate percep-
knowledge approximately
to the proposition in logic. Ideas themselves are
complex (that
formed of simple ideas into which they
is,
can be analyzed) or simple and irreducible. Locke's exposition
is
actually the reverse of the order just indicated; he first tries to de-
how they combine to form how we perceive the simi(Book IV). We shall now
termine the nature of simple ideas, then
complex ideas (Book larity
II),
and
finally
or dissimilarity between ideas
follow the order of his exposition.
Actually his somewhat atomistic approach, which resolves the contents of sense and reflections into ideas,
than
we might
at
first
(simple ideas) or their simplicity of
suppose, whether
mode
communicated
more complicated
we consider To begin
of combination.
an idea does not refer
that cannot be
is
elements with, the
to its intrinsic character: ideas
to us if
we do
not have them from
experience (bitter, cold) are simple, and the absolute impossibility of our originating within us a single
new
simple idea (whereas
we
LOCKE AND ENGLISH PHILOSOPHY
275
do form complex ideas) marks the
limits of
our knowledge. Our
simple ideas are divided into three classes: simple ideas of sensation
—warm,
solid,
smooth,
simple ideas of reflection
within
us,
hard,
—that
extension,
bitter, is,
motion;
figure,
we
ideas of the faculties that
find
such as memory, attention, will (the word "reflection"
designates only our inward
perception
of
these
faculties);
and
simple ideas of both sensation and reflection, such as the ideas of
and number.
existence, duration,
This
is
sentative;
tive?
where complications begin: the Cartesian idea an image of things.
it is
Undoubtedly, for
as
we
the value of representations
Is
is
repre-
Locke's idea also representa-
he raised the question of
shall see,
and asked,
at
with respect to
least
simple ideas of sensation, which ideas actually represented the external world.
But then such ideas would play two
hand they would be which all
constitute our
roles:
on one
the points of departure or ultimate elements
knowledge and, by the same token, they would
be equal; on the other hand they would represent material
things and, like intermediaries between us quite unequal in value.
As
and
Locke
a physicist,
things,
would be
in fact adopted the
conclusions of Boyle's mechanics: only extension, figure, solidity,
and motion, together with the Colors, sounds,
and
ideas of existence, time,
which represent
are "primary qualities"
tastes are
and number,
to us things as they are.
"secondary qualities" produced in us
by the impression made on our senses by the several motions of bodies so small that
we
are unable to perceive them.
that even with respect to primary qualities to
achieve the certainty of Descartes.
world the
should note
failed
by far
represent the external
physicist uses these ideas because he cannot use others;
for example,
if
we make
impulsion the cause of motion,
it
what
it
does not touch ...
other
way than by motion"
is
this is
only
"impossible to conceive that body should operate on
because
or, (II,
when
it
viii,
n;
does touch, operate any first
edition); but that
is
not an irreducible objection to the physics of cen-
which
posits attraction as the cause of motion. Further-
"impossibility" tral forces
To
We
Locke
more, the idea of extension
is
far
from
clear to
Locke: the cohesion
—
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
276
of bodies cannot be explained by
and he
tradictory;
all
and
it,
at
qualities,
is all
that
we know
from the idea of the substance of body
are as far
all."
Thus simple
ought not
The double
is
when he
constates
complex idea of extended, figured, colored,
other sensible qualities which
nothing
infinite divisibility
hardly faithful to Descartes
16) that "by the
(II, xxiii,
and
is
as if
we we knew of
it,
even those of the primary
ideas,
to be taken for the real elements of things.
interpretation of ideas of sensation
—as
the ultimate
elements of knowledge and as representatives of the real world did not persist
among
others,
only from the
among
the "idealists"
who
was decidedly opposed first
followed Locke. Berkeley,
to
it;
he considered ideas
point of view and abandoned the notion that
they were representative.
By
positing, along with simple ideas of sensation, simple ideas of
reflection,
the
and by conceding
that our
mind cannot be reduced
Locke eliminates the
to
knowledge of the
faculties of
our knowledge of sensible things,
traditional link
(as
found in Hobbes) be-
tween empiricism and sensationalism. By means of the kind of inner experience which he called reflection, as original as external experience, he answers the strongest objections of the
Cambridge
and we saw how
Platonists against the atheism of the empiricists;
he used inner experience to demonstrate the existence of
God
with-
out recourse to innate ideas. Locke's speculation concerning complex ideas was to entail the elimination of vain philosophical discussions, for he showed the true origin of the ideas that
"simple ideas" do not
fit
were
at issue. It
into the
categories
is
obvious that his
which
traditional
philosophy used to classify the objects of knowledge; they are neither substances nor
innovations but, as
we
Complex
is
modes
of substance.
One
of Locke's most important
that he considers such categories not as primary ideas
shall see, as
combinations of simple ideas.
ideas are separated into
two groups: those in which
simple ideas are combined in the idea of one thing (the idea of
gold or the idea of man), and those in which combined ideas continue to represent distinct but united things (the idea of "filiation"
LOCKE AND ENGLISH PHILOSOPHY
277
which unites the idea of son and
The
relation).
of
first
modes which
group
father,
and
in general all ideas of
divided into two classes: ideas
itself
is
are the ideas of things that cannot subsist by them-
selves (a triangle or a
number); and
which are
ideas of substances
the ideas of things that subsist by themselves
(a
man). Modes
themselves are divided into simple modes in which the same simple idea
is
combined with
bination of units,
itself (for
example, number which
combination of homogeneous parts)
composed of
is
a com-
and space or duration, each of which ;
a
is
and complex or mixed modes
different kinds of simple ideas, such as beauty or the
idea of a murder.
Locke's composition (or deduction) of categories allowed
many
resolve
lems of
among them
controversial problems,
infinity,
him
to
the three prob-
power, and substance which only theories of
in-
nate ideas were thought to be capable of resolving.
According
Locke, infinity
to
repetition of units of the differs tion.
from
Therefore
it is
is
no
limit
is
not true that the infinite
from the
since
it
consists of
time, or space)
;
it
assigned to this repetiis
a limitation of the infinite, that
finity of perfection different
just
mode
same kind (number,
finitude only in that
that the finite
have
a simple
is
prior to the finite,
we
conceive an in-
we
infinity of quantity that
examined; the infinitude of God, in particular
is
conceived
number or an unlimited extension of his acts relative Of course, divine infinitude is different; actual inwhich is realized, is in no way our idea of infinity, which is
by us only
as a
to the world. finity,
endless progression; similarly, eternity
which we conceive, for "what infinity lies in obscurity,
negative idea, wherein all I
would,
it
I
lies
is
not the endless duration
beyond our
positive idea towards
and has the indeterminate confusion of a
know
I
neither do nor can
being too large for a
finite
comprehend
and narrow capacity"
(II,
xvii, 15).
Analysis of the idea of power and of the idea of freedom which
depends on
it
should, in Locke's
way
of thinking, put an
the endless controversies over this question.
simple
mode formed by
The
idea of
end
power
is
to
a
the repeated experiencing of certain changes
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
278
we have
that
noted in sensible things and in ourselves.
When we
perceive that our ideas change under the influence of sensory im-
and when
pressions or of voluntary choices, ceive the possibility of a similar
power
idea of active
power
power
active
a reflective idea;
is
will produces in bodies. is
also
which produces change and of passive
in that
which undergoes change. But
in that
The
it
in general the idea of
from the change
derives
will, then, is
who
ask
if
the will
ask
if
one power
tion since a
is
move
wishes to
free is
is
his legs
free
power
invested with another to
—a
an agent. But
so.
To
it is
to
senseless ques-
we
can ask
if
has the power to act on the basis of his knowledge
—that
is,
has the power to perform or not to perform
free to will or not to will
whatever
is
to
in his
do
so
—
in addition
is
power: that question
can be resolved through analysis of the motives of to will
to act
the will: a paralytic,
not free to do
is
an action depending on whether he wishes
duced
power
the
It is
made by
therefore to ask an absurd question;
power can belong only
who
the agent
and who
is
that our
an active power. Freedom
an active power, but of another kind.
or not to act according to the choice for instance,
we conwe have the
in addition
change in the future,
We
will.
are in-
by uneasiness or dissatisfaction caused by privation of
a good, but our uneasiness
not proportionate to the excellence of
is
we have
the good. Further,
the
power
to
compare one good with
another and, on the basis of our examination, to suspend actions that
would produce
uneasiness.
indifference but consists in of
judgment rather than
The most
question of the nature of substance
controversial. Substance
able to state clearly attributes.
stance
is
Locke
was
in
The
on the
—a is
is
basis
one of the
any case considered by
realities, yet,
all to
no philosopher had been
what he understood by
a false simple idea
of simple ideas
decisions
(II, xxiii)
tried to resolve the question
Here Locke's thought
ity is illusory.
not a freedom of
is
desire (II, xxi).
be the paradigm of primary
idea.
Freedom, then,
making voluntary
this
substratum of
complex idea mistaken
for a simple
not easy to penetrate, and
substance of gold seems at
all
by showing that sub-
first
its
simplic-
glance to consist
which are shown by experience always
to be
grouped
LOCKE AND ENGLISH PHILOSOPHY
279
together (yellowness, fusibility, ductility, great weight) and which, collectively, are
always referred to by the same name. But in
this
case a substance
would not
also
a constant
Locke
sides,
from
differ
mind
to
from
a substance in
name
to designate their group,
imagine these simple ideas
to a single thing stitutes a
its
it is
in fact impossible for the
and are
we
because
it is
actually linked to
properties.
Locke
"We
states
if
believe they belong
union that con-
in a
it
use a single
known, would explain the
we have no
how
But he
[simple ideas of sensible
what we discover through sensation and Locke something is,
less
emphatically
—
—Aristotle's
lying the relation of simple ideas
it
no
states
idea of this substance: to explain the cause under-
our understanding, which can add nothing
know what
relation of
emphatically his belief in the existence
cannot conceive
qualities] should subsist alone."
to
we
If
whole. For example, gold must have an intimate constitu-
of substance:
is
by themselves, apart
as existing
which they are inherent.
—a real essence which,
that
is
beyond
to these ideas
beyond
quiddity
Substance then
reflection.
like actual infinity:
it
exists,
but
we do
and the only kind of investigation open
the experimental investigation of coexisting qualities. This
need
to separate
mind need
(a
mass of simple ideas of
to resolve the question of
we
with
reflection); but
nature.
That
is
both Descartes,
is
is
we
to
God
we
what
it
things,
that
man
and the
man
knowl-
or to angels.
idea, according to Locke,
true of complex ideas
all
incompatible
who assumed
Scholastics, with their substantial forms, attributed to
edge that belonged only
not
absolutely nothing about
had knowledge of the intimate mechanism of
Every
to us is all
determining whether matter can or
we know
why
is
it
cannot be sure that the power of thinking
its
not
body (a mass of simple ideas of sensation) and
cannot think, for since is,
is
objects to being criticized for mistaking simple ideas
for the real elements of things since
tion
mixed mode, which
a
group of simple ideas designated by a single name. Be-
is
and of simple
correspond to the reality of things
?
representative. This ideas.
Some
To what
ideas
is
equally
extent do they
—ideas of substances
—are always incomplete, for we can never know which of their un-
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
280
known powers
will be revealed to us
contrary, are always complete;
we have formed by
ideas that ideas
—
gratitude, justice,
we
than what
conceive
ception. Furthermore,
the sense ascribed to
and
we
by the word used if
be since they exist only by our con-
to
same way an idea
when we
to express
is
words that designate ideas
attribute to
of
its
think of the
when
sum
complex mode
than the notion that
reality other
substance in general
is
we
in-
is
it
represents some-
of the characteristics that
constitute the conventional sense attributed to stance, the idea of a
complex mode
of a
conventional meaning. In the
said to be true both
when we
idea of a
think of everything designated
and the idea
it,
we omit an element
thing real and
uniting arbitrarily certain simple
them by unanimous convention, the
substance can be complete
complete
mixed or complex
moral ideas can be nothing other
all
them
if
by experience. Others, on the
these are the
it.
In the
always true since
fashion of
it,
first
in-
has no
it
and the idea of
always false in the sense that
it
never ex-
and it is sometimes false when it unites simple shown by experience to be separated or separates ideas which
presses real essences;
ideas
are in reality united. In the second instance,
when words
are not
given their exact meaning, ideas of individual substances are
most always
true, the idea of
mixed modes often
al-
false.
Finally, the analysis of ideas affords a definite solution to the
famous question of say "This
When
universals.
lead" or "This
is
is
nates a real essence the answer
ing with real essences
and how can we
is
we can
simple
never
Never. For
:
know
precisely
ceases to be of the species of horse or of lead.
nates a
nominal essence fashioned from a
associated with a
proposition
is
legitimately
a horse" ? If the universal term desig-
If,
we are dealwhen a thing
if
however,
it
desig-
collection of simple ideas
name, we can know with certainty when such a
legitimate
and with even greater
certainty as
the
convention becomes more firmly established.
But
is
this
mind? No,
nominal essence
in turn constructed arbitrarily
ideas, are representative. In a chapter (II, xxxiii),
by the
for according to Locke, general ideas, like all other
which corresponds
on the association of ideas
to Malebranche's
book on the imag-
LOCKE AND ENGLISH PHILOSOPHY
28l ination,
Locke manages from
own
his
point of view to separate
general ideas that result from individual imaginings from those that are truly valid.
Here experience and usage
modes, such
our moral or legal ideas (the idea of murder), are
as
formed quite
are our masters.
Mixed
freely but not haphazardly; given social conditions
(the existence of certain laws or customs) force us to choose certain
combinations. Similarly, in the formation of general ideas of substances
we
not only conform with usage but must also follow
nature and link together only simple ideas which are constantly linked together in experience; the
our general ideas can be valid only in nature.
The
last
condition
there
if
is
a certain
general idea of substance, then,
manship but founded on the nature of
possible
is
is
of
and
permanence
human work-
things. This correspondence
between our ideas and nature raised many questions in the minds of Berkeley
v
and Hume.
Knowledge Knowledge
is
among The bonds between our ideas
the perception of agreement or disagreement
our ideas, expressed in a judgment.
can be of three sorts: identity or diversity, relation (there of relations, such as father
and
and
son, greater
is
a host
smaller, equal
and
unequal, similar and dissimilar), and coexistence. But identity and coexistence are merely singular instances of relation. is
therefore the perception of a relation.
always certain, and what
is
commonly
By
definition
Knowledge
knowledge
is
referred to as faith, belief, or
probability always falls short of knowledge,
which can nevertheless
—as when we have intuitive perception of agreedisagreement—or mediate, as when we apprehend the
be either immediate
ment
or
relation of
agreement or disagreement only through a demonstra-
tion that gradually brings us nearer to
But Locke
identifies
still
an
intuitive perception.
a fourth sort of knowledge, "that of
actual real existence agreeing to any idea." It
is
clear that the per-
ception of existence cannot be reduced to the perception of a relation
between two
ideas, for existence
is
not an idea like that of sweetness
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
282
Locke
or bitterness. Moreover,
identifies (IV, ix, x, xi)
we have concerning the we have intuitive knowledge
degrees of
the certainty
existence of real things: by
reflection
of our
to this
own
existence; linked
demonstrative knowledge of the existence of God; but "the
is
knowledge of the existence of any other thing, we can have only by sensation." Certainly
it is
absurd for us
which are capable of producing
jects
doubt the
to
in us pleasure
which produce the impressions responsible
and
sensation,
to
doubt impressions that
pieces of sensory evidence that confirm
recognizes that such certainty daily
life,
The
—
for all of our ideas of
we
cannot prevent, and
one another. But Locke
relative to practical situations in
is
which do not require a higher degree of
duality of these
two judgments
clearly illustrated in Locke's
is
There are two categories of
false
reality of ob-
and pain and
certainty.
—of relation and of existence
handling of the problem of truth.
judgments: in one the relation ex-
pressed by language in the proposition does not correspond to the intuitively perceived relation
correct sists
it
by returning
between
ideas,
and
it is
to intuition; in the other the
We
things.
ideas,
is
not a centaur, for example) and true
but only in the second case do
we have
knowledge.
real
follows that real knowledge implies the union of the
we have
It
two elements
separated: the perception of the existence of a relation
between ideas and the is
it
to the real existence of material
can perceive with equal certainty relations between
fanciful ideas (a hippogriff
idea
mistake con-
not in perceiving a relation incorrectly but in perceiving
between ideas that do not conform
that
easy for us to
real existence of
an archtype of which an
the representation.
From
this
it
follows that there are
two
different
ways of posing
the problem of the reality of knowledge, depending
upon whether
we are considering mixed modes whose ideas, fashioned by the mind under the conditions we have examined, have no archetype other than themselves, or substances whose archetypes are outside us.
In the
everything
mind:
first is
instance
we have
absolutely certain
traceable to relations
these are the mathematical
knowledge
since
between notions posited by the
and moral
sciences (particularly
LOCKE AND ENGLISH PHILOSOPHY
283
the juridical sciences) which have the since they are based
ample,
we
same
certainty as mathematics
on equally constant and secure
notions.
For
ex-
can use these notions to demonstrate that murder must
be punished, and the soundness or our demonstration will equal that of a mathematical theorem. In the second instance experience
alone will determine whether the coexistence of ideas in our judg-
ments corresponds
Thus
to reality.
the dualism that
we have
noted in Locke from the very be-
—the dualism between the idea as an element of knowledge the idea as a representation of reality— was finally translated
ginning
and
into a radical distinction between ideal sciences
and experimental
sciences.
The
English sage originated the ideological analysis that was to
dominate philosophy for a long time: a compromise between a combinatory art which derives
and
distinct elements,
possible
all
knowledge from simple
and an empiricism which determines by
perience and custom which elements
ex-
and which combinations of
elements are valid. This analysis reveals the limits of the understand-
ing from two angles
:
it first
eliminates
all
knowledge not obtainable
through combination (such as knowledge of actual stance, real essence, free will), then all
experience. tolerance
vi
To
and
sub-
infinity,
knowledge not
confine knowledge within these limits
justifiable is
by
to assure
social peace.
English Philosophy at the
End
of the Seventeenth Century In England the transition from the seventeenth to the eighteenth a resurgence of religious philosophy. Locke
century was
marked by
was the
witness to the intellectual ferment which characterized
first
the eighteenth century.
Three currents can be
Platonism of Cambridge;
(2)
natural
identified:
religion,
(1) the
represented
Clarke; and (3) criticism of positive religions, as in
by
To land and
Collins.
The
oldest of these currents
is
Cambridge Platonism, which
dates
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
284
from the middle of the seventeenth century. Heirs
to the erudite
Platonism of the Renaissance, the Cambridge clergy preserved the traditions of
lasticism
Greek culture and evidenced
their
throughout the century. Their work
contempt for Schois
similar to that
accomplished by French Oratorians like Father Thomassin. Like
him
they viewed Platonism not as a theory of mystical knowledge
but as a theory of rational knowledge, and in 1670 one of them
wrote a refutation of Bohme, whose ideas were being introduced
England. But the Cambridge Platonists, more
into
Thomassin could not
be,
viewed reason
dimmed by
the Fall
and which
whose
essential
dogmas (according
religion,
number and tical,
intelligible to
all.
is
the necessary foundation of
notions and in ranking
man—one who,
of his soul logically, sees
imbued with the
to
them) are few
in
Smith (1616-1652) followed
Plotinus in ranking the enthusiast above the
intuitive
which was
Their rationalism, though not mys-
lacks the aridity of Locke's. John
common
than
liberal
as a natural light
still
man who
reasons with
higher the contemplative or
incapable of demonstrating the immortality it
in a superior light. Locke,
liberal spirit of
who had
been
Cambridge (which, according
to
him, makes reason the judge of divine revelation), nevertheless
condemned
the innatism
and enthusiasm
Cudworth.
Still
follow-
ing Plotinus in their criticism of mechanism, Cudworth
(1617-
1688)
and Henry More considered
different degrees. Leibniz,
was persuaded by Cudworth
who
of
bodies as having
all
—true
The second Samuel Clarke
which, since they act physically and
forces
current
—natural
(1 675-1729), a
Newtonian who delivered stituted in his will
from Leibniz' monads.
religion
—
is
well
a fervent
the Boyle lectures against atheism (in-
by the physicist) which resulted in
work was written
and other deniers
by
represented
London clergyman and
A
Discourse
concerning the Being and Attributes of God. According to the
in
to take a position against the "plastic natures" posited
construct organisms, differ markedly
title,
life
also attributed life to all things,
"in answer to
of natural
and revealed
establish the notion of liberty
its
Mr. Hobbes, Spinoza
and prove
religion," its
and
sub.
.
.
in order to
certainty, in contrast
LOCKE AND ENGLISH PHILOSOPHY
285
to reason
and
Clarke attempted to convince unbelievers through
fate.
reason and sought, setting aside revelation and even the diversity of proofs of the existence of God, to use an unbroken chain of closely
connected propositions from which he could deduce successively the existence
and
God. Like Locke, he
attributes of
started
principle that something has existed throughout eternity;
from the
from
this
he then deduced all the attributes of God. He was a Newand he always found the best answers to materialism in Newton's The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy. "The eternity
tonian,
he wrote
materialists,"
Leibniz, with
to
whom
he corresponded
frequently in 1715, "suppose that the structure of things
from the mechanical
that everything can arise
and motion, from of philosophy
and
necessity
show on
only from a
such
the mathematical principles
the contrary that the state of the universe
(the constitution of the sun arise
fate;
is
principles of matter
and the planets)
free, intelligent cause."
is
such that
can
it
His identifying Newton
with natural religion and his opposition to mechanism are important in the history of philosophy. Leibniz
demonstrate that his theism and freedom.
The
third current
reptitiously at
materialists
first,
and
tion of 1688.
own mechanism
—free
at the
thought
was trying vainly
to
could accommodate both
—which
appeared almost sur-
beginning of the century,
among
sects of
"moralists," developed vigorously after the Revolu-
We
find in
Toland (1670-1722)
all
of the themes that
sustained the anti-Christian polemic during the eighteenth century: the diatribe against priests
who
allied
themselves with the
magistrate in order to delude the people and
who
civil
invented dogmas
such as those of the immortality of the soul in order to consolidate their
power.
He
contrasted their religion with primitive Christianity
—that of the Nazarenes
and Ebionites, grounded
with neither tradition nor
priests.
he advocated a pure mechanism
solely
on reason,
Moreover, in his Pantheisticon
—an
eternal
world endowed with
spontaneous motion which leaves no room for chance, a theory of materialism which makes thought a motion of the brain. Anthony Collins (1676-1729) in
A
Discourse of Free-Thinking, Occasioned
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
286
by the Rise and Growth of a Sect Called Free-Thinkers (1713) protested especially against the extravagances of the Bible
and
its
miracles which were merely frauds, against the absurdity and in-
coherence of
man from
who, under the pretext of
interpreters
official
its
and protecting him from
setting aside dangerous opinions
own judgment.
error,
Remarks on a Pretended Demonstration of the Immateriality and Natural Immortality of the Soul 3 is a reply to the letter which Clarke wrote prevented
—
using his
—
who
against the theologian Dodwell, soul
which
a principle
is
immortal by the Collins trine of
showed the union
to
which
is
rendered
punish or reward man." In his
of materialism
knowledge: "Since thought
of matter on our senses,
maintained in 1706 that "the
naturally mortal but
is
God
will of
Collins'
we have
is
and the
letter
sensationalist doc-
a consequence of the action
every reason to conclude that
it is
a property or affection of matter occasioned by the action of matter."
Such were the three forms of rationalism prevalent
at the begin-
ning of the eighteenth century: the rationalism inspired by the
Cambridge
Platonists, the rationalism of Clarke,
alism. Shaftesbury (1671-1713),
out on an independent course which drew
Cambridge
and
Platonists
order and beauty society,
is
man an
in
whose development
its
He
is
inspiration
set
from the
and
maintained, contrary to is
love of
expressed in the universe and
perfection in
responsible for
is
its
innate moral sense which
—an order which
and which has
critical ration-
stressed the affective, sentimental,
aesthetic elements in their teachings.
Locke, that there
and
grandson of Locke's protector,
all
God; natural
affections
of the unhappiness of
men.
This view of universal order, in which apparent disorders disappear,
—one
provided a solution to the problem of evil recognized as being similar to his
was
own
which Leibniz
optimism. But Shaftesbury
careful to call attention in his Letter concerning
Enthusiasm
(1708) to the difference between the false enthusiasm of the fanatic (observable in the English sects of his period) 3
Published
taining
in
English as
Some Remarks
.
la nature et la destination
.
.
A (2d
Letter to
the Learned Mr.
Henry Dodwell; Con-
1709) and in French under the humaine (London, 1769).
ed.,
de Vame
and true enthusiasm, title
Essai sur
287
which ligious
LOCKE AND ENGLISH PHILOSOPHY is
man. The
religion.
ligion
the awareness of a divine presence in the artist or the reletter affirms the
preeminence of morality over
"This science," he added in Soliloquy (ijio), "judges
itself,
examines inspiration,
miracles; the sole standard
is
re-
prophecies, distinguishes
tests
derived from moral rectitude."
4
On the
whole, his thought resembles a commentary on Diotima's discourse in the
Symposium and,
after so
much
dry
dialectic, is singularly re-
freshing. 4
Quoted by A. Leroy, French translation of the
Letter, p. 263, note.
Bibliography
I
to
V
Texts Locke, John. Wor\s. 3 vols. London, 1714. 10th ed. 10 vols. London, 1801. The Philosophical Wor\s. Edited by J. A. St. John. 2 vols. London, .
1854.
by
Selections. Edited
.
Essays on the
.
Law
Leyden. Oxford, 1954. Essay Concerning .
Oxford, 1894. Repr. 2 Essay Concerning .
2 vols. .
New York,
Loc\e on
Cranston.
S. P.
Lamprecht. Reprinted:
of Nature. Edited
New
York, 1928.
and translated by
W. von
Human Understanding. Edited by A. C. New York. Human Understanding. Edited by John W.
Fraser.
vols.
Yolton.
1961.
Politics,
New York,
Religion,
and Education. Edited by Maurice
1965.
Two Treatises of Government. Edited by Thomas I. Cook. New York, 1947. Locke's Two Treatises of Government. Edited by Peter Laslett. Cambridge, i960. A Letter Concerning Toleration. Edited by Patrick Romanell. 2d ed. .
.
.
Indianapolis, Ind., 1955. Original Letters of Loc\e, Sidney .
Forster.
2d
ed.
London,
and Shaftesbury. Edited by T.
1847.
Studies Aaron, R. I. John Loc\e. 2d ed. Oxford, 1955. Alexander, S. Locke. London, 1908. Burtt, E. A. The Metaphysical Foundations of Modern Physical Science. 2d ed. Reprinted: New York, 1955. Cox, R. H. Loc\e on War and Peace. Oxford, i960. Dewhurst, K. John Locke (1632-1704), Physician and Philosopher. London, 1963.
Fowler, Thomas. Loc\e. 2d ed. London, 1892. Gough, J. W. John Locke's Political Philosophy. London, 1950.
288
LOCKE AND ENGLISH PHILOSOPHY
289
Hefelbower,
G. The Relation of John Loc\e to English Deism. Chicago,
S.
1918.
Albert. Loc\e and Scepticism. New York, 1936. Lamprecht, S. P. The Moral and Political Philosophy of John Loc\e. New ed. New York, 1962. Macpherson, C. B. The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism. New York, 1964. O'Connor, D. J. John Loc\e. London, 1952.
Hof stacker,
Smith,
Norman Kemp. John
Loc\e. Manchester, 1933.
Studies Bonno, G. Relations
intellectuelles
de Loc\e avec
la
Prance. Berkeley,
Calif.,
1955-
The Life of John Loc\e. 2 vols. London, 1876. M. John Loc\e: A Biography. London, 1957. Lord King. The Life of John Loc\e with Extracts from his Correspondence, Journals and Commonplace Boo\s. New ed. 2 vols. London, 1829-30. Yolton, J. W. John Loc\e and the Way of Ideas. Oxford, 1956. Fox, H. R. Cranston,
II
Studies Bastide, C.
John Loc\e: Ses theories politiques
et leur influence
en Angleterre.
Paris, 1906.
La
Polin, R.
politique morale de John Loc\e. Paris, i960.
III-V
Studies Carlini, A.
La
filosofia
de Loc\e. 2
vols. Florence, 1920.
Frazer, A. C. "Locke," in Encyclopaedia Britannica, 9th ed., 1882. .
.
Loc\e. London, 1890. "John Locke as a Factor in Modern Thought," Proceedings of the
British
Gibson, ed.
J.
Academy, I (1903), 221 ff. Loc\e's Theory of Knowledge and
New York,
Hertling, G. V. Loc\e 1892.
Its
Historical Relations.
New
i960.
und
die Schule von Cambridge. Freiburg
im
Breisgau,
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
29O
Jackson, R. "Locke's Distinction between Primary and Secondary Qualities,"
Mind, XXXVIII (1920), 56 Lamprecht,
XXXVI
ff.
"Locke's Attack
S. P.
(1927), 145
upon Innate
Ideas," Philosophical
Review,
ff.
/. Loc\e: Sa vie et son oeuvre. 2d ed. Paris, 1893. H. La philosophic generate de Jean Loc\e. Paris, 1908. Tellkamp, A. Das Verhaltnis John Loc\e's zur Scholasti\. Miinster,
Marion, H. Ollion,
1927.
VI
Texts Clarke, Samuel. Wor\s. Edited by B. Hoadley. 4 vols. London, 1738-42. Cudworth, Ralph. The True Intellectual System of the Universe. 2 vols. London, 1743. Lord Herbert of Cherbury. Autobiography. Edited by S. L. Lee. London, 1886. .
.
De veritate. Translated by M. H. Carre. Bristol, 1937. De religione laid. Translated by H. R. Hutcheson. New Haven,
Conn., 1944.
More, Henry. Opera omnia. 3 .
vols.
London,
1679.
Philosophical Writings. Edited by F.
The Cambridge
Platonists.
I.
MacKinnon.
New
York, 1925.
Edited by E. T. Campagnac. London, 1901.
Studies Albee, Ernest. "Clarke's Ethical Philosophy," Philosophical Review, (1928), 304 Cassirer, Ernst. Pettegrove.
Hutin,
S.
ff.
and 403
The
XXXVII
ff.
Platonic Renaissance in England. Translated by
London,
J.
Les disciples anglais de Jacob Boehme. Paris, i960. Un precurseur de la franc-maconnerie , John Toland, suivi de
Lantoine, A.
traduction francaise
P.
1953.
du
la
Pantheisticon. Paris, 1927.
Leroux, E., and A. Leroy. ha philosophie anglaise classique. Paris, 1952. Lyon, G. L'idealisme anglais au XVIII e siecle. Paris, 1888.
Muirhead,
J.
H. The Platonic Tradition
in
Anglo-Saxon Philosophy. London,
1920.
Passmore,
De
J.
Pauley,
A. Ralph Cudworth:
W.
C.
The Candle
An
Cambridge, 1951. Lord: Studies in the Cambridge Plato-
Interpretation.
of the
nists. New York, 1937. Pawson, G. P. The Cambridge Platonists and Their Place in Religious Thought. London, 1930. Powicke, F. J. The Cambridge Platonists. London, 1926.
29I
LOCKE AND ENGLISH PHILOSOPHY
N. Logic and the Basis of Ethics. Oxford, 1949. Theology and Christian Philosophy J. Rational Seventeenth Century. 2d ed. 2 vols. Edinburgh, 1872.
Prior, A.
Tulloch,
in
England
in the
Tuveson, E. L. Imagination as a Means of Grace. Berkeley, Calif., i960. Ward, R. Life of Henry More. New ed., edited by M. H. Howard. London, 1911.
—
BAYLE AND FONTENELLE i
Pierre Bayle
the principal works of Pierre Bayle prior to his celebrated Historical
France or forced
become
to
a Protestant family
and
when
date from the grievous period
Critical Dictionary
(1697),
Protestants were expelled
converts. Bayle himself,
and who returned
he had embraced Catholicism
(i 647-1 706),
briefly
to the
who was from
reformed religion
rest of his life.
Thoughts Written the
to a
All of his subsequent works
Doctor
Comet which Appeared
at the
where
Diverse
Sorbonne on the Occasion of
December
in
of
in 1680, fled with
several coreligionists, including Pierre Jurieu, to Rotterdam,
he spent the
after
Academy
(1669), left the
Sedan where he had been teaching philosophy and,
from
MDCLXX
(1681), the
General Criticism of Louis de Maimbourgs History of Calvinism (1682),
and Philosophical Commentary on These Words
Christ:
Compel Them
ance, but their tone
is
to
Come
wholly
in (1686)
different.
—are
demands
of Jesus for toler-
Bayle did not speak as a
member of a humble, outlawed sect, nor did he protest, in the name of a religious truth which was the exclusive
like Jurieu,
property of
Calvinism, for his intellectual awareness of the absurdity of intoler-
ance was no
less
acute than the feeling of revulsion caused by the
horror of the religious persecutions.
He knew
that Calvinism
just as intolerant as Catholicism; all theologians,
292
even
when
was
they at
BAYLE AND FONTENELLE
293 first
agree to discussion, end like the "converters of France; around
1680 these gentlemen began to offer to discuss their religion with
promised
their errant brothers; they
lighten them, to instruct
them
to hear their doubts, to en-
answering two
cordially; but after
or three times, they would no longer endure contradiction and insisted that
anyone
opinionated. That ning, for to
it is
who would
not accept their explanations was
what they should have
is
from the begin-
said
ridiculous to enter into discussion unwilling to listen
an oppenent's reply" {Dictionary,
article
on Rufin, Note C)
.
matter which side he was on, no theologian observed the law of cussion. Bayle himself
found a most implacable enemy
No dis-
in the person
of the Protestant minister Jurieu.
How,
then, did this spirit evolve ?
The
great metaphysical systems
which dominate the seventeenth century conceal the profound terest in history that characterized this period, yet
more widespread. "For one
in-
nothing was then
investigator of physical experiences,"
writes Bayle, "or for one mathematician, you find a
hundred
serious
and its dependencies." Bayle strongly condemns maxims" of those who scorn historical investigations.
students of history the "disdainful
Mathematicians ness in
may
contrast the clarity of their logic with the dark-
which the investigation of human
reasons that historical facts can be tainty perfect in
its
own
and cannot
known with
but Bayle
a degree of cer-
right; in addition, the historian, in contrast
to the mathematician, deals not
of our soul"
facts leaves us,
with beings that are merely "ideas
"exist outside
our imaginations" but with
true realities. Mathematicians, Bayle adds (and here
we
are
bound
to recall Leibniz), stress the great ideas of the infinitude of
God
yielded by the "abstract depths of mathematics"; against this the historians set the priceless
the failings
and
The tendency
knowledge yielded by
limitations of is
human
investigations of
reason.
obvious: thanks to Bayle, scholars broke out of
and became interested in philosmore profound and more important data on the nature of man than had ever been provided by philosophers versed in geometry. As a matter of fact, as he noted in the
their
ophy.
narrow
fields of investigation
They sought
to provide
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
294
draft of his Dictionary, Bayle's intention
first
factual errors
found
in the dictionaries
had preceded him, by checking
was not
and works of
He
was
toward Spinoza, he used blunted weapons against
implacable
who answered him
dogmatism
What was was
who
and philosophers.
criticized all the great metaphysical systems of his time.
Leibniz the
historians
their sources, but rather to challenge
the validity of the opinions held by theologians
He
to refute
in his Theodicy,
of philosophers
no
and he disapproved
than that of theologians.
less
the nature of Bayle's criticism?
obvious that he
It is
human
intrigued by the spectacle of the medley and variety of
opinions, but his interest
of
was not the same,
either fundamentally or
formally, as that of a skeptic like Montaigne. Bayle belonged to an
age of impassioned (and excessive) controversy: never had there
been so
and the
much dry debate over "grace" or "the way of examination way of authority." Bayle himself was a controversialist when
he locked horns with Jurieu in defense of tolerance. Moreover, the opinions which were upheld in a controversy were presented in the
manner most appropriate doctrines
to their defense
—that
is,
as established
marked by inner coherence and based on universally It was this form, appropriate to controversy,
accepted principles.
that Bayle tried to give to the theses
how
which he examined;
stand the
test.
is
Leibniz' monadology failed the test because of "all
—for
the impossibilities that strike in the imagination"
substance which
causing
its
first
simple and which
is
is
step
its
and of passing from
opposite in the absence of any external reason.
toward putting an end
that neither of the
example, a
nevertheless capable of
perceptions to vary spontaneously
one perception to
The
that
he tested them, and he rejected them because they did not with-
to controversy
was
two adversaries understood himself or
to
show
said any-
thing intelligible.
He
was quick
relationships
to sense not only the slightest incoherence but also
between ideas even when these relationships were
veiled or dissimulated by the partisan spirit of the controversialists.
For example,
a considerable part of his
Thoughts on the Comets
is
BAYLE AND FONTENELLE
295
based on the rather explicit assumption of an
Church and
miracles officially accepted by the
common
future events accepted by the
between
affinity
the prediction of
people on the basis of the
appearance of comets; that his method of criticism was effective
On
obvious.
is
the thorny question of grace he suggests to adversaries
that they cannot fail to understand each other once they agree to
examine
their doctrines instead of
championing
the matter of liberty there are only say that
two stands
their causes: to take.
it
the
make
it
resolve to act in a certain
stand
is
that taken by Molinists, the other that taken
who
"On is
to
of the distinct causes that converge in the soul confer
all
upon
power
to act or not to act; the other
way
that
it
is
cannot
to say that they resist.
and Protestants of the confession of Geneva
Jansenists,
One
oppose Molinism and
who
therefore
must have
same dogma. But the Thomists vehemently
The
first
by Thomists,
—three groups essentially the
insisted that they
were
not Jansenists, and the Jansenists insisted with equal vehemence that they
were not Calvinists on the matter of
liberty
.
.
.
and
all
of this for the purpose of avoiding the dire consequences envisioned in case of
agreement on some point with either the Jansenists or
the Calvinists.
On
the other hand, there has been no sophism
which the Molinists have not used
to
show
that St. Augustine did
not teach Jansenism" {Dictionary, article on Jansenius, Note C).
Bayle
likes,
prejudices,
however, to separate things which we, because of our
deem
to
(a then novel idea
be indissolubly united. For example, he notes
which was
logical investigations)
to be of great significance in ethno-
that belief in
magic and demonic powers
does not imply belief in God; and he was able to the religions of the Far East
cite as
evidence
which were then becoming known in
Europe.
This foils
relentless criticism,
based on unreserved intellectual sincerity,
biased opinions by taking individual theses
and revealing
their
inner contradictions or unintelligibility, by showing the affinity that sometimes exists arbitrariness of the
between opposing theses and, by
bond
contrast, the
that unites certain affirmations. This re-
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
296 lentless
manipulation of ideas,
pursued
this collation of theses is
indefatigably (to the unending delight of the reader) throughout the pages of the Dictionary.
But was
assume?
was
It
precisely because of
its
and hardly conform
to ordinary
me
distinguished layman like
judgments: ...
called attention to
be no reason for anyone to be concerned.
guide in such matters an author
ments
which are "rather If a
rank, un-
an error in vast
involving religion or morality, there would
historical collections
incidentally,
at first
dissemination that Bayle
tried to attenuate the significance of his reflections, free
we might
widely disseminated as
this criticism as
and who,
who
.
.
.
No
one chooses
as a
speaks only in passing and
for the very reason that he scatters his senti-
like needles in a haystack, clearly indicates that
wish to be followed." Montaigne's to disturb theologians until they
ideas,
he does not
he continues, did not begin
were reduced
to a
system by Pierre
Charron. In reality
we
find in
ment which always
fective. It consists in
of any support in that
Bayle,
managed
of Bayle's criticisms a dialectical
all
retains
its
identity
and which
is
move-
singularly ef-
depriving metaphysical and religious theses
human
nature or
human
reason, with the result
while pretending always to subscribe to orthodoxy,
to relegate
them
they laid claim. Almost
solely to the divine authority to
which
of the great metaphysical systems since
all
Descartes had implied that certain theological theses were linked to the very nature of
human
reason: existence and unity of God,
Providence, immortality of the soul.
most
liberal advocates of tolerance
leave in peace the atheists
thought
to
main
the
or materialists
be contrary to any moral
nection between the
At
religious
same time even the
were nevertheless reluctant life. It
to
whose opinions were was
this
dogmas and
presumed con-
the fundamental
needs of reason and morality that Bayle's criticism gradually undid. In dealing with the existence of God, Bayle said: there
is
ample
this existence
liberty."
"On
this point
"Provided that a doctor acknowledges that
can be proved by some other means, he
is
allowed
the liberty of criticizing this or that particular proof" (Article on
:
BAYLE AND FONTENELLE
297
Note G). In plain language he
Zabarella,
saying that there
is
first
mover implies
notion. Furthermore,
movers
the eternity of the world
no
means
universally accepted proof. In fact, the Aristotelian proof by of the
is
—an unacceptable
can be used to prove a multiplicity of prime
it
just as surely as
can be used to prove that there
it
God. The Cartesian proof was
criticized
from the Sorbonne, L'Herminier, was
from
all
quarters.
one
is
A
doctor
able freely to reject every
Thomist proof and accept only the proof grounded on the order of the universe.
On
this question, therefore,
evidence. Luther's teacher, Biel, of the existence of
Providence
God
had
was no absolute
there
moreover that "proofs
stated
provided by reason are only probable."
Bayle's favorite question, the question to
is
The problem
returns time after time.
of theodicy
had
which he
in effect been
stimulating vain discussions for centuries but had never been resolved.
The
istence of
existence of evil could not be reconciled with the ex-
an
good and omnipotent
infinitely
goodness must be limited it
its
power must be limited
to prohibit evil
but could not. Everything said to justify
him an absurd
despot.
order to manifest his
would allow
To
wisdom
him
to see in
is
two
issue.
principles,
will not
"a monarch
marvel
hypothesis
better than
who
its
theory of
one good and the other bad, could resolve the at
itself in
and who
a
most singular
situation
will not deplore the destiny of
our reason? Take the Manicheans: with a tradictory
God makes
sedition to spread in order to acquire the glory of
Thus human reason found
"Who
wished
if it
example, that he permits sin in
say, for
having brought a remedy." Only Manicheism, with the
its
permitted the existence of evil which
if it
could have prohibited, or
principle; either
they explain
totally
absurd and con-
experiences a hundred
times
orthodox thinkers with their righteous, necessary, and
uniquely true hypothesis of an infinitely good and omnipotent First Principle" veiled,
Can
is
Note E).
the immortality of the soul, in
Pomponazzi's prove
(Art. Pauliciens,
its
Bayle's irony,
though
unmistakable.
treatise clearly
showed
its
turn, be
proven rationally ?
that Peripateticism could not
immortality: "Here only the system of Descartes has laid
—
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
298
down
firm principles." But, the Cartesian principle
ituality of the soul)
Descartes satisfied It
not evident to
is
many
might be alleged
all,
(the spir-
itself
and Gassendi's
reply to
people (Art. Pomponazzi, Note F).
dogmas
in defense of these
that they are in-
dispensable to public morality, but experience reveals that atheists
may
sometimes have good morals and that believers
be criminals.
Bayle gave his approval to Pomponazzi's observation "that a great
number
of rogues
and
rascals believe in the immortality of the soul
while several saints and righteous
Thoughts on the Comet,
in
existence of ethical principles
men do
not."
which Bayle repeatedly
among
him. "This
versaries to raise their voices against
stressed the
had caused many ad-
atheists,
is
because they do
not wish to admit that religious motives are by no means our only
The Sadducees who were more virtuous than the
motives for action," he says; "there are others.
denied the immortality of the soul
who were
Pharisees
God"
men
we
doubt or
learn that there
to
fail
men
Note C). The
ions
and
about
little
another
is
illusion springs
life
after
But nothing
is
so
uncommon
as consistency in
who
one"
this
can be
it
belief in a future life will serve as a
practices. Jurieu, for instance,
we
from the assumption
always act according to their principles, so that
demonstrated a priori that restraint.
would know
believed that "our morals are corrupted because
(Art. Sanchez, that
We
Sadducees, Note E).
(Art. if
meticulous in the observation of the law of
moral
our opin-
conceded that our
reli-
gious beliefs depend on our mental dispositions and tried logically to
deduce tolerance since
not open to dispute, proved to
tastes are
be the most intolerant of men. Furthermore,
it is
wrongly assumed
that religious motives are our only motives for action; there are in fact
many
others
—love of praise, fear of infamy, and many more
which are often stronger than
religious motives
ing to virtuous actions" {Dictionary, ed. of 1715,
These few indications reveal the Bayle pursued his
work
of
infinite
and capable III,
988).
patience with which
removing one by one every prop sup-
porting the metaphysical and religious truths inherent in nature, every
of lead-
argument adduced
to
make them
a
human
human
necessity;
—
BAYLE AND FONTENELLE
299
in short, every reason for believing derived
He
nevertheless pretended that he
and
comparison with
God
it,
was
permitted
it;
it
to
to authority alone
proval, this letter
reason in
Every doubt raised by :
"This
is
remove doubts: God
and
just,
Note C) Recourse
done, wisely permitted" (Art. Rufin,
and
fallible
therefore true
is
single true
human
eliminated by authority
and the true way
the right choice
did
is
infallible divine authority?
the problem of theodicy
God
was not removing a
what
solid support for religion:
from the essence of man.
surely
said
it,
wisely
to authority
.
obligatory. Bayle cites, not without ap-
is
from Perrot d'Ablancourt
to Patru:
"You
believe
in the immortality of the soul because your reason dictates this
course,
and
I
my
against
because our religion
judgment.
commands me
I
believe our souls are immortal
to believe in this way. Consider
both views and you will probably admit that mine (Art. Perrot,
Thus he
Note
much
better"
I).
puts metaphysical truths on such a high plane that they
no longer have any human
from
separated
is
rationality
interest.
and
Reduced
to
its
own domain,
ethics, isolated in its majesty, reli-
gion remained helplessly suspended. Will authority provide a basis for
agreement? No, not so long
assess
worth. "Scripture
its
is
as
human judgment
intervenes to
used to support both sides of a ques-
Note C). There is no agreement on the interpretation of Scripture. Nicole and the Catholics supported the method of authority which made the Roman Church an infallible tion" (Art. Semblangay,
interpreter; but
who,
in the absence of lengthy investigations not
accessible to the faithful, can assure us of the unity of this tradition
The method isters, itself
of critical examination, supported by Protestant min-
engendered disputes. Thus there
for evaluating authority. that
men
What
recourse
is
is
no human method
there except to believe
are led to religion by purely irrational means,
"some
through education and others through grace?" This time any
between religion and reason has been broken, duly and religion
is
we might religion
is
?
wholly divine but infer
from the
after all a
mere
it
first
tie
decisively;
is in no way human. Or perhaps, as means of access to it education
—
custom, traceable like other customs to
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
300
the accident of birth. Bayle's thought flections
which he
communion by education
certain
may
be expressed in these
"When
attributes to Nihusius:
be gained by the change
it
if
unless something
is
—a better position, for instance; for what
would we gain by abandoning the communion and shaped us
re-
to a
or birth, the resulting disadvan-
tages are not a legitimate reason for leaving to
one belongs
by leaving
it
we
that has
produced us
only exchanged one sickness for
another?" (Art. Nihusius, Note H).
Thus moved but for
Bayle's negative dialectic resulted in tolerance religious conviction
had
it
as its positive counterpart
(and
significance) a concrete, historical,
its
human
which
from the domain of human this, especially,
re-
disputes,
accounts
and human conception of
nature which had no transcendent term as a referent.
Fontenelle
ii
Bernard Fontenelle (1657-1757),
who
first
devoted himself to the
writing of minor poems, pastorals, and an unsuccessful tragedy, tions in public
more than any of his contemporaries on revolutaste, on "changes that are forever occurring in the
minds of men,
tastes that are
must have
reflected
what might be described
in
imperceptibly replaced by
as a relentless,
or an eternal revolution of opinions
tle
Do one
these changes in taste follow
taste supplants another; there
den link"
He
taste.
(II,
434).
gan
1
to meditate
Sur Vhistoire, 1
81 8).
Worlds he demonstrated
in his
that he
Con-
knew
astronomy.
Academy of Sciences, he bemovement of his time, particularly
he became secretary of the
in mathematics
Paris,
attentive to public
and the Hotel de Rambouillet, and
to interest the ladies in
after
not by chance that
his contemporaries' distaste for the preciosity
versations on the Plurality of
But
"It is
*
ordinarily a necessary but hid-
Here he was obviously being
was aware of
of the age of Voiture
how
is
tastes
mutually destructive bat-
and customs."
no rule ?
new
II,
on the
and 434
scientific
became the
historian or rather
and subsequent references are
to Fontenelle's (Euvres,
physics; thus he (this
BAYLE AND FONTENELLE
301
the historiographer of the sciences through eulogies written for de-
members
ceased
changes in
eral
human mind
beneath the
of
discerned, beneath
ephem-
among
the in-
new
the emergence of a
taste,
tellectual elite and,
the
Academy, and he
of the
which
interest in his essays
new
spirit,
spirit
the fundamental traits of
was but one form. Fontenelle's
it
sole
(sometimes uninspired), in the prefaces to
The Analysis of Infinitely Small Objects, The Geometry of Infinity, and The Utility of Mathematics and Physics, in his short History and The Origin of Fables, and in his somewhat longer History of Oracles (whose subject matter he borrowed from Van Dale), was to arrive at a description of the human mind which would take into account the prodigious advances that had occurred in the mathematical and physical sciences during the seventeenth century.
Fontenelle saw these advances as the point of departure for an
ascending
movement whose
assume that the sciences are colleagues.
"The
task of the
future could not be foreseen just
:
"We may
approaching birth," he wrote
Academy
is
to
to his
provide an ample supply
of authenticated facts, for the structures of physics cannot be raised until experimental physics
is
able to provide the necessary materials"
The example
of
progress in infinitesimal geometry in the seventeenth century
is
(I,
37).
What
direction
topical; all of the great
row, Mercator
—"each
would
this progress
geometers
take?
—Descartes,
one following
his
own
Fermat, Pascal, Barparticular route
was
led either to infinity or to the brink of infinity. It permeated all things, followed the geometers everywhere,
them freedom to escape" and discovered the means
21).
to
employ
common
in calculus "this infinity
It is
not the analytical development
principles accepted by everyone;
efforts, at first
is
just
coming
scattered truths
them
it
is
the unanimity of
dispersed, which are harmonized thanks
spired discovery of a general principle: etry
to birth,
we
"When
to the in-
a science like
geom-
can apprehend almost nothing but
which do not cling
separately, as best
along
which
Thus knowledge does not begin with
unity but tends toward unity. of
Newton and Leibniz came
(I,
could no longer be rejected."
and would not allow
together,
and we prove each of
we can and almost always with considerable
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
302
But
difficulty.
after a certain
we
been found, ples begin to
how
see
emerge"
number fit
of these unitary truths have
together and their general princi-
27).
clear that the expression "general principle" here signifies
It is
nothing comparable is
(I,
they
to the principle of identity or its analogues;
it
rather a principle that accords science a deductive form, such as
the infinitesimal calculus in
all
of attraction in every particular
form
an
is
ideal
remote from
problems of quadrature or the law
law in astronomy. The deductive
science,
but
it is
of any science, even history. Fontenelle sees
nevertheless the idea
an
affinity
between the
system of motive powers by which Tacitus explained the history of the
Roman
emperors and the system of vortexes by which Descartes
explained natural phenomena, and he entertains the notion of going
even further and constructing a priori a history in which a sequence of historical events will issue
from the
once these are thoroughly understood
principles of
(II,
taneity of separate thoughts,
number (I,
work it
in
human
development. it
later
is
which are only the
implies the spon-
The mind
only after a certain
and when same
its
turn arrives"
force
does not, in
always explains the
with the known. This
fables,
to light
this regularity implies that the
ways of proceeding;
it
nevertheless subject to a regulative
knowledge comes
of prior items have been clarified
But
21).
is
nature,
429).
Progress in the direction of principles, though order: "Each item of
human
is
always at
fact,
have two
unknown by comparing
the same procedure that gave birth to sciences of primitive
man, and which
caused the advance of the sciences. Fables are generally ex-
plained (and here Fontenelle
is
probably thinking of Bacon) by the
uncertain faculty of the imagination. In reality
many
antiquity on, assumed that myths were etiological to explain
people,
—that
is,
from
intended
phenomena. Fontenelle was a vigorous exponent of the
etiological theory;
Homer and Hesiod were the first Greek philosomen of extraordinary intelli-
phers, but even "in those crude times
gence were naturally inclined saw";
if
must be
to seek out the cause of
whatever they
water always flowed in a stream, they reasoned that there a
nymph
holding an urn from which water flowed without
BAYLE AND FONTENELLE
303 ceasing
(II,
389). Fontenelle offers a singular proof of the rational
character of fables, namely, the identity that he finds (thus antici-
pating comparative mythology) between the fables of the Greeks
and those of the American Indians
(II, 395). Gods and goddesses, from the same principle which regulated modern
therefore, issued
sciences: the relating of the
concludes: "All pidities of
any
men
tribe
unknown
to the
known. Fontenelle
resemble one another so closely that the stu-
whatsoever should
make
us shudder"
(II,
431).
modern man is attributable to the development of his knowledge and not to his intelligence, which Fontenelle equates with that of primitive man. Fontenelle went still further in his thinking, but he had to take
The
superiority of
every precaution before expressing himself. of Christianity
the action of
is
God
One
in history
of the foundations
—an action translated
by the miracles and the Incarnation. Fontenelle envisions a positive history taire's
which teaches
man
only about himself; the
spirit of
God. Fontenelle points out that "there are two parts of history studied": the fabulous history of primitive times, the invention of
two
Vol-
Essay on Morals contrasts sharply with that of The City of
men, and the true
and
first
be
The
after the gen-
been provided by morals"; their usefulness
discovery of "the soul of facts," which in the of errors
man,
to
wholly
is
history of times closer to us.
histories will reveal "a detailed portrait of
eral portrait has
which
is
in the
instance consists
One could hardly made an attempt to be so in his
in the second of passions (II, 431).
be more explicit, though Fontenelle
One
History of Oracles.
of the historical proofs of the
power
of
Christ was said to be that the pagan oracles, which were necessitated by demons,
had ceased
to speak at the time of his
Following the account of
Van
plaining oracles through
demons
commodiousness, which made
Dale, Fontenelle
it
is
first
coming.
shows that ex-
unsound because
of their very
possible for the Christians easily to
explain the miracles of paganism; then he shows that the fact of the cessation of oracles
is itself
spurious.
If in all of his essays Fontenelle, like Bayle, implies the
of the action of
God
in history, he suggests,
negation
by way of counterpart,
—
304 that
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
God must
be sought in nature: "Physics follows and untangles
the signs of the infinite intelligence all things, whereas history has as
and whims of men" of history
but the
(I,
its
and wisdom which produced
subject the effect of the passions
35). Fontenelle's
God
is
—the God manifested in the intolerant
God
of nature
who
acts
no longer the God sects of religions
through fixed laws. Physics
elevated to the status of theology."
itself "is
Bibliography
Texts Bayle, Pierre. Dictionnaire historique et critique. 3 vols. Rotterdam, 1697. 3d
Rotterdam, 1715.
ed. 4 vols.
New
ed., edited
by A.
J.
Q. Beuchot. 16
vols.
Paris, 1820-24. vols. The Hague, 1727-31. from Bayle's Dictionary. Edited and translated by E. A. Beller and M. du P. Lee, Jr. Princeton, N.J., 1952. Historical and Critical Dictionary, Selections. Translated by Richard H. Popkin. Indianapolis, Ind., 1965.
CEuvres diverses. 4
.
Selections
.
-.
Studies
W. H.
Barber,
"Pierre Bayle: Faith
and Reason,"
in
The French Mind. Ox-
ford, 1952. Pp. 109-25.
Constantinescu-Bagdat, E. Pierre Bayle. Paris, 1928. Delbos, V. "Fontenelle et Bayle," in
La
philosophic francaise. Paris,
1919.
Pp. 133 ff. Delvolve, J. Essai sur Pierre Bayle, religion, critique, et philosophic positive. Paris, 1906.
Labrousse, Elisabeth. Inventaire critique de la correspondance de Pierre Bayle. Paris, 1961. .
Pierre Bayle. 2 vols.
The Hague,
1963-64.
Levy-Bruhl, L. "Les tendances generates de Bayle et de Fontenelle," Revue d'histoire de la philosophic, I (1927), 50 ff. Mason, H. T. Pierre Bayle and Voltaire. London, 1963. Puaux, F. Les precurseurs francais de la tolerance au
XVHI e
siecle.
Paris,
1881.
Robinson, H. Bayle the Sceptic. Smith, H. E.
The
New York,
193 1.
Literary Criticism of Pierre Bayle.
New
Haven, Conn.,
1912.
Pierre Bayle:
Le philosophe de Rotterdam. Edited by Paul Dibon. Amsterdam,
1959.
305
THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY
306
II
Texts Fontenelle, Bernard de. CEuvres. 5 vols. Paris, 1825. Histoire de V Academic royale des sciences. Paris, 1702-33. .
.
De
Vorigine des fables. Edited by
J.
R. Carre. Paris, 1932.
Dialogues on the Plurality of Worlds. Translated by York, 1929. .
}.
Glanvill.
New
Studies Carre,
J.
La philosophic de
R.
Fontenelle, ou le sourire de la raison. Paris,
1932.
Cosentini,
}.
W.
Fontenelle's Art of Dialogue.
Delbos, V. "Fontennelle et Bayle," in
Pp. 133
Delorme, ^
New York,
La philosophic
1952.
francaise. Paris, 1919.
ff.
S.
"Etudes sur Fontenelle," Revue d'histoire des sciences, 1957,
pp. 288-309.
Gregoire,
F.
"Le dernier defenseur des Tourbillons, Fontenelle," Revue
d'histoire des sciences, 1954, .
pp 220-46.
Fontenelle: une philosophic desabusee. Nancy, 1947.
Levy-Bruhl, L. "Les tendances generates de Bayle et de Fontenelle," Revue d'histoire de la philosophic, I (1927), 50 ff. Marsak, L. M. Bernard de Fontenelle. Philadelphia, 1959.
INDEX Academies and
scientific gatherings,
ences,
experimental
27-33;
phi-
losophy, 21-43; experimental proof,
14-17
Instauratio magna, 40-42; and works, 21-24; mechanism, 37-39; Novum organum, 31-37;
Adam-Tannery, 47 n. Alexander, 241 Alexander VII, 7
39-41;
Anabaptists, 5 Anaxagoras, 12
theory of idols, 32-33; understanding and experimental science, 24-
life
Andre, 221 Apollonius, 15, 207
27 Bacon, Nicholas, 21
Archimedes, Arianism, 6
Barrow, 301
15,
Bacon, Roger, 26, 41
207
Aristotle, 10-11, 14, 25-26, 29-30, 33,
Basson, 10-12
37-38, 50-51, 53, 56, 76, 82, 85, 94, 109-11, 113, 116, 167, 209, 221, 230-
Bayle, Pierre,
32, 234, 236, 241-43, 254,
279
Aristotelianism and Aristotelians, 59,
C,
271 n. 16,
190-91, 229, 292-
300 Beaune, Florimond de, 51
Beeckman,
74-75, 95 Arminians, 6 Arminius, 6
Arnauld, 7-8, 8
Bastide,
Isaac, 46, 53, 83
Bekker, Balthasar, 108 Benedictines, 190, 219-20 n., 49, 63, 70, 80, 108,
197-98, 201, 213-14, 218, 228, 230,
243-44, 252, 255, 260 Ashley, 267
Berg, Conrad, 112 Bergerac, Cyrano de, 107 Berigard, 10-12 Berkeley, 276
Atomism, 9-14
Berulle, 47, 63
Augustinianism, 199-200 Ausonius, 47
Biel,
297
Blampignon, 198
n.
Bohme, Jakob, 225-28, 225 Bacon and experimental philosophy, 2 i-53
Bacon, Francis, 149,
Bossuet, 15,
16
n.,
17, 52, 92,
160, 302; division of the sci-
307
n.,
284
Boileau, 107 3, 5, 63, 147,
197-98, 201, 261
Bouillier, 202 n., 221
Boulainvilliers,
Count
of, 191
3 o8
INDEX
Bourdin, 49
Chillingworth, 4
Boursier, 198
Christianity
Boutroux, Pierre, 84
30,
Boyle, Robert, 42-43, 142, 228, 275 Boyneburg, Johann Christian von, 228 Bramhall, 142 Brandenburg, Elector of, 268
and Christians,
130-31,
62,
134,
6, 9,
137-38,
156-57, 203, 229, 260-61, 274, 285,
303 Christian Platonism, 112
Christian Skepticism, 14 Cicero, 258
Brandt, Frithiof, 144 n.
Bredenburg, Jan, 157, 191
Clarke, Samuel, 239, 258, 283-86
Brehier, E., 34 n.
Clauberg, 108, 112
Brinon,
Clavius, 46
Mme de, 261
Brochard, Jeanne, 46 Bruno, 9, 26, 242 Brunschvicg, 71 n., 128 n.
Clerc, Jean
Busco, 93 n. Cabala, 32, 155, 156
Collins, Anthony, 283, 285-86 Comenius, 14 Conde, 158
Cabalists, 25
Condillac, 56
Caesar, 242
Conring, 258 Copernicus, n-12
Clerselier,
Calvinism and Calvinists, 261, 292, 295 271-72,
Platonists,
276,
283-84, 286
Campanella, 9 Carneades, 258
Cordemoy, Gerard
de, 108, 115
Cornet, 7 Coste, 269 Council of Trent, 261
Counterreformation, 1-2 Crescas, Hasdai, 156
Cartesianism and Cartesians, 128,
269
Cousin, 201 n.
Carre, 219 118,
le,
94
Collegiants, 157-58, 191
Calvin, 253
Cambridge
14,
151,
130,
161,
163,
46-
13,
168,
165,
187, 190, 199, 200, 203, 205, 207-8,
Cromwell, 5
Cud worth,
268, 271-72, 284
Cupid, 31
212-13, 215, 219, 220, 230-32, 23638, 241, 244, 249, 257, 274-75,
297-
98 Cartesianism in the seventeenth cenCaterus, 49 Catholicism and Catholics, 130, 151, 155, 157, 261, 292,
(Lord
shire), 93, 141
Ceres, 34 II,
212
63,
299
Descartes, Rene, 10, 12, 14-17, 37-38, 43, 46-118, 45,
Devon-
158,
126,
160,
130-32, 134, 144-
162-64, 166-67,
^9,
173-74, 183-84, 190, 197, 199, 200, 202, 207, 209-1 1, 213, 215-17, 225,
230-32, 236-39, 241, 245-46, 251-
Chanut, 98 Charles
85, 00,
Bosses, 255, 260-61
Descartes and Cartesianism, 46-118 1-2,
Cavalieri, 15, 84, 129, 234
William
Costa, Uriel, 155, 269
Democritus, 10-12, 80-81,
Des
tury, 107-9
Cavendish,
Di
Daniel, 108
257-58, 275-76, 279, 296-98, 301-2; doubt and the Cogito, 6652,
141, 268
Charron, Pierre, 98, 296 Chevreuse, Due de, 197
71; ethics, 97-107; existence of
God,
71-80; metaphysics, 62-83; method,
3°9
INDEX
52-62; physics, 83-94; physiology, 94-97; soul and body, 80-83; theory
Gassendi, Pierre,
of eternal truths, 65-66
Gerdil, 221
Digby, Kenelm, 113 Dionysius the Areopagite, 219 Diotima, 287
298
German philosophy
before
Leibniz,
225-28 Geulincx, Arnold, 108-9, IX 3
Dodwell, Henry, 286
Gibieuf, 50, 65
Drebbel, 35, 41
Gilbert, 41, 91-92
Du Vair, 98
12-13, 16, 38, 49,
9,
67, 80, 113, 131,
Glanvill, 42
Gomarus, 6 Ebionites, 285
Gouhier, G., 200 n.
Eckhart, 225 Edict of Nantes, 2
Grignan,
Elizabeth
Guymon, Mme, 2
I,
Grotius,
146
Elizabeth, Princess, 50, 98, 159 Enden, van den, 156
English philosophy
at the
end of the
seventeenth century, 283-87 Epictetus, 10, 12, 14, 30, 135
Epicureanism, 12-13 Epicurus, 13, 82 Euclid, 71, 132, 141, 207, 231 Euler, 233
Eusebius of Caesarea, 28
Mme,
219
Hugo,
3, 4,
17
Harrington, James, 5 Harvey, 15, 41, 95 Hatten, van, 189 Hebreo, Leone, 160, 161 n.
Heerebord, Adrien, 108
Henry IV, 46 Herbert of Cherbury,
Hero
4,
Experimental philosophy in England,
Hesiod, 302 Heyberger, Anna, 14 n.
42-43 Experimental proof, 29-40
Hobbes, Thomas,
Fardella,
Ange, 221
Faulhaber, 47 Fede, 220 Fenelon, 118, 190,201 Ferdinand, 155
Ferdinand II, 47 Fermat, 15, 50, 233, 301 Ficino, Marsilio, 112, 114
Florian, P., 16 n.
Fludd, Robert, 25, 32, 38 Fontenelle, Bernard, 219, 300-304 Franciscans, 156
Frederick of Bohemia, 50 Frederick I, 229
Freund, 5
90, 92, 126, 141, 144-45, 237
1, 5,
10, 14-15, 17,
49-50, 66, 141-52, 189, 236, 270-71, 276, 284
Homer, 302 Hooke, 43 Hooker, 146 Huet, Pierre Daniel,
Hume,
1
17-18
42, 116
Huyghens, 50, 83, 93, Hyde, Edward, 142
117,
239
Hyperaspistes, 50
Idols, Bacon's theory of, 32-33 Innate ideas, 255-57, 2 7 I- 74 Innocent X, 7
Inquisition, 11
n.
Galileo, 9-12, 16-17, 24, 35, 48, 53, 84,
13
of Alexandria, 15
James James
I,
21, 146-47
II,
Jansen, 7
268
INDEX
310
Jansenism and Jansenists,
1-2,
6-9,
251-54;
harmony,
pre-established
250-51; theology and monadology,
107-8, 197
246-50
Jansenius, 295 Jaquelot, 118
Lelevel, 220
and
Jesuit Society
Jesuits, 1, 6-7, 14,
46, 49, 107-8, 131, 219, 221,
260
Jesus Christ, 6, 134, 137, 157-58, 160, 203, 261, 292, 303
Lelong, 198 Lenoble, 16 n. Leroy, Andre, 287 n. Leroy, Maxime, 47 n.
Jews, 2, 15, 151, 155, 157
Leuwenhoek, 254
John Frederick, 229
L'Herminier, 297
Josephus, 28
L'Hopital, Marquis de, 219
Jourdain,
C, 9
Liebig, 34
Jupiter, 65
Lignac, Abbe, 221
Jurieu, 3, 292-94, 298
Limborch, Philip van,
157, 158
Lionne, M. de, 198 Lipstorp, Daniel, 108
Kepler, 53, 84, 90
Locke and English Philosophy, 267-
Kodde, Adrian van der, 157 Kodde, Gilbert van der, 157 Kodde, Jan van der, 157 Koyre, A., 11
n.,
225
87 Locke, John,
14-15,
4,
73,
220-21,
229-30, 255, 268; Essay, 271-74; innate ideas, 271-74; life and work,
n.
267-69; political ideas, 269-71; simLachat, 147 n. La Forge, Louis de, 108,
and complex ideas, 274-81; theory of knowledge, 281-83
ple 1
14-15, 197
Lalande, 38 n. Lamy, Bernard, 220
Louis XIV, 228-29
Lamy, Francois, 190, 220 La Mothe le Vayer, 8, 14 Land, non., in n.
Lucretius, 12-13
Laporte,
J.,
Lucifer, 226
Luther, 297
Lutherans and Lutheranism, 227, 261
8 n.
La Rochefoucauld, 1, 9 La Ville (Father Valois), 108
Machiavelli,
Leenhof, van, 189-90
Le Grand, Antoine, 108 Leibniz,
27
Gottfried
Wilhelm,
15-17,
101, 109, 116, 129, 145, 190,
n.,
201, 211, 220, 225-61, 284-86, 294,
301;
doctrine of infinity, 233-36;
ethics,
258-61; existence of bodies,
257-58; freedom and theodicy, 25154; general science, 230-33; individual substance and theology, 240-
46; innate ideas, 255-57;
life
and
works, 225-30; and Locke, 255-57; mechanics and dynamism, 236-39; nature of
life,
254-55;
3, 5, 15,
30
Magnien, Jean, 12 Maimonides, 156 Mainz, Elector of, 228
optimism,
Mairan, 201
218
n.,
Malebranche,
Nicolas,
63, 101, 108,
no,
251, 273, 280;
14-15,
27
n.,
190, 197-219, 225,
human
nature, 204-
and works, 197-98; nature and knowledge, 211-19; occasional causes, 209-n; philosophy and the8;
life
ology, 198-204; seeing
God, 211-19 Malebranchism 219-21 Malpighi, 254
all
things in
and Malebranchists,
3H INDEX and
Manicheans
Manicheism,
191,
Martin,
Occasional causes and occasionalism,
209-11 Oldenburg, 159, 166, 228 Optimism, 251-54
297 Marie Therese, 198 Marranos, 155
Andre (Ambrosius
Victor),
Oratorians, 15, 50, 65, 107-8, 219, 284
Oratory, 47, 197, 199, 200, 219, 220
199
Masham, Lord and Lady, 268
Orpheus, 31
Mattia, Doria, 221
Orphics, 136
Maugain, A., 16 n. Maurice of Nassau, 46 Maury, Alfred, 16 n. Maximilian of Bavaria, 47 Mazarin, 51
Palissy, Bernard, 15
Pan's hunt, 34, 35
Pappus, 54 Paracelsus, 26, 40, 227
Pare, Ambroise, 15
Mennonites, 157 Mercator, 301
Parker, Samuel, 108
Mere, Chevalier de
Mersenne,
16, 16 n.,
Parmenides, 68
129
la,
48-50, 61-63, 93,
Meyer, Louis, 187 n. Middle Ages, 26, 29,
2 37>
65, 94, 146, 156,
301 l of
criticism
apologist,
133-38;
principles,
131-33;
methods, 126-31; wager, 137-38 Patru, 299
160
Pellisson, 261
Milton, 5 Minim Order, 16
Peripateticism and Peripatetics, 56, 59, 72, 81, 107, 109-10, 297
Molesworth, 143 n.
Molinism and Molinists, Monadology, 246-50 Montaigne,
Pascal, Blaise, 51, 92-93, 126-38, 228,
2 34>
141
2,
15, 98,
2, 6,
132,
Perrot d'Ablancourt, 299
295
Peter of Spain, 240 n. 135,
294,
Peter the Great, 229
296 Montesquieu, 220
Pflaum, 161 n.
Montmor, 16
Philo the Jew, 187
More, Henry, 284 Morin, 50, 86
Picot,
Moriniere, Lefort de, 220
Pharisees, 298
Plato,
50 14, 32-33,
66, 72-73, 94,
112,
200, 219, 231, 246, 252, 272
Moses, 151, 155-56, 187
Platonism and Platonists, 65, 1 12-14, 169, 246, 248, 271, 276, 283-84
Nazarenes, 285 Neo-Platonism and Neo-Platonists, 26, 56, 64, 136, 160-61, 165, 173, 241-
Pliny, 26-28, 41
240
n.,
14,
68-69,
II2 >
J 65,
219,
241, 247-48, 254, 284
Poiret, 190-91
42,249
Newton, 42-43,
Plotinus,
88, 93, 126, 220, 229,
2 37> 2 39, 301
Newtonians, 258, 284-85
Polignac, Melchior de, 221
Pomponazzi, 297 Port Royal and Port-Royalists, 220, 260
Nicholas of Cusa, 225 Nicole, 1, 8, 9, 108
Pre-established
Nietzsche, 152
Proclus, 219, 242
Nihusius, 300
Protagoras, 80
harmony, 250-51
7, 14,
INDEX
312
Protestants, 2-4, 17,
no, 147 n.,
151,
Shaftesbury, 286 Shaftesbury, Earl of, 267
261, 292-93, 299
Puritans, 268
Siger of Brabant, 107
Pyrrhonians and Pyrrhonism, 132-33
Simon, Richard, 187 Simple and complex
Pythagoreans, 25, 57
ideas, 274-81
Skeptics, 71-72, 117, 136, 258
Raey, Jean de, 108
Smith, John, 284
Ramus, 54 Rauh, R, 188
Socinianism
and Socinians,
Rawley, 40 Reformation, 4
5-6,
81,
101,
Sophia, Charlotte, 257
Regius, 51, 79, 81 Regis, 108, 1 16-17, 190, 213-14, 218,
Sophists, 33
220 Remonstrants, 6
Spinoza, Baruch, 15, 27
Spedding, 27 n. n.,
145, 155-89, 200, 218, 229-30, 233,
Renaissance, 1-2, 8-9, 14, 17, 26, 31, 65, 136, 156, 219, 241,
Renaud
2,
157 Socinus, Faustus (Sozzini), 6
245, 273, 284, 294; concept of
166-69; freedom and eternal
284
human
178-86;
d'Elissagaray, 219
Improvement
Revius, 51 Richelieu, 7 Roberval, 16, 50, 93, 239 Rochot, 16 n.
of
ing, 160-66; life 59;
the passions,
and
politics,
nature,
the
God, life,
169-75;
Understand-
and works, 155175-78; religion
186-89
Spinozism, Spinozists, and anti-Spi-
Roche, 220 Rodocanachi, 268 n.
nozists, 168, 241, 189-91
Roemer, 87
Steno, N., 96, 97 n. Stoicism and Stoics, 26, 31, 105, 112,
Rohault, Jacques, 108-9, 201 Rosicrucians, 47, 228, 254
135-36, I75> 206, 252, 259-60, 270
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 220 Rufin, 293
Suarez,
21
1,
Swammerdam, 254
Sadducees, 298 St. Augustine, 70-71, 108, 114, 199,
Sydenham, 268 Synod of Dort,
6,
157
221, 252, 295 St.
Bonaventure, 199
St.
Cyron, 7
St.
Talbot, 21
Tannery,
Thomas Aquinas,
and
Scholastics, 8, 25,
64, 206, 230, 256-57, 279,
284
Schoot, 51
Seeing
all
things in God, 211-19
Thomism and
Seneca, 14
Seventeenth century, characteristics
Thomas, David, 268 Thomas, J., 34 n. Thomas, St., see St. Thomas Aquinas Thomasius, 228, 231 Thomassin, 219, 284
Semblancay, 299
1-17
16 n.
Theodicy, 251-54 Theophrastus, 31
Saturn, 65 Saurat, Denis, 5 n.
Scholasticism
Mme Paul,
Terrasson, 221
25, 107
of,
295, 297
Thucydides, 141
Thomists, 33, 63, 77,
313
INDEX Simon
Toland, 283, 285 Tonnies, 146 n.
Vries,
Tyrell, 268-69
Waard, C. de, 16 n. Wahl, Jean, 80 n.
Vailly, Mile, 219
Wallis, John, 142
Van
Dale, 301, 303 Verse, Aubert de, 190
Weigel, Erhard, 231 Weigel, Valentin, 225-26, 228
Vloten, van, 27 n.
Werenfels, 118
Voet, Gisbert, 51 Voiture, 300
William of Ockham, 240 William of Orange, 268
Voider, 243
Witt, Jan de, 158, 189
Voltaire, 42, 191, 245
Wittich, 108, 190
de, 157, 159
n.