627 129 6MB
English Pages [552] Year 2020
The SAGE Handbook of
Evolutionary Psychology
This page intentionally left blank
The SAGE Handbook of
Evolutionary Psychology
Applications of Evolutionary Psychology
Edited by
Todd K. Shackelford
SAGE Publications Ltd 1 Oliver’s Yard 55 City Road London EC1Y 1SP SAGE Publications Inc. 2455 Teller Road Thousand Oaks, California 91320 SAGE Publications India Pvt Ltd B 1/I 1 Mohan Cooperative Industrial Area Mathura Road New Delhi 110 044 SAGE Publications Asia-Pacific Pte Ltd 3 Church Street #10-04 Samsung Hub Singapore 049483
Editor: Donna Goddard Editorial Assistant: Umeeka Raichura Production Editor: Prachi Arora Copyeditor: Sunrise Setting Ltd. Proofreader: Derek Markham Indexer: Caroline Eley Marketing Manager: Camille Richmond Cover Design: Naomi Robinson Typeset by Cenveo Publisher Services Printed in the UK
Editorial arrangement © Todd K. Shackelford, 2021 Chapter 1 © Cezar Giosan, 2021 Chapter 2 © Riadh Abed and Paul St John-Smith, 2021 Chapter 3 © John F. Gunn III, Pablo Malo and C. A. Soper, 2021 Chapter 4 © James Carmody, 2021 Chapter 5 © Ulysses Paulino Albuquerque, Joelson M. B. Moura, Risoneide Henriques da Silva, Washington S. Ferreira Júnior and Taline C. Silva, 2021 Chapter 6 © Simon Russell, 2021 Chapter 7 © Diana Santos Fleischman, 2021 Chapter 8 © Michael Latner and Elissa Feld, 2021 Chapter 9 © Joseph L. Nedelec, 2021 Chapter 10 © Lois James, 2021 Chapter 11 © Eyal Aharoni and Morris B. Hoffman, 2021 Chapter 12 © Alina Simona Rusu, 2021 Chapter 13 © Anthony Walsh,
Cody Jorgensen and Jessica Wells, 2021 Chapter 14 © Ian A. Silver and Jamie Newsome, 2021 Chapter 15 © Russil Durrant, 2021 Chapter 16 © Anthony C. Lopez, 2021 Chapter 17 © Holly Wilson, Paul Rauwolf and Joanna J. Bryson, 2021 Chapter 18 © Robert Finkelstein, 2021 Chapter 19 © Deanna Singhal and David Wiesenthal, 2021 Chapter 20 © Gayle S. Stever, 2021 Chapter 21 © Ned Kock, 2021 Chapter 22 © Mark A. Caudell, 2021 Chapter 23 © James R. Anderson, 2021 Chapter 24 © Stephen Whyte and Benno Torgler, 2021 Chapter 25 © Robert Finkelstein, 2021
Apart from any fair dealing for the purposes of research or private study, or criticism or review, as permitted under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, this publication may be reproduced, stored or transmitted in any form, or by any means, only with the prior permission in writing of the publishers, or in the case of reprographic reproduction, in accordance with the terms of licences issued by the Copyright Licensing Agency. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside those terms should be sent to the publishers.
Library of Congress Control Number: 2020947010 British Library Cataloguing in Publication data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library 978-1-5264-8916-6
At SAGE we take sustainability seriously. Most of our products are printed in the UK using responsibly sourced papers and boards. When we print overseas we ensure sustainable papers are used as measured by the PREPS grading system. We undertake an annual audit to monitor our sustainability.
Contents List of Figures, Tables and Boxes Notes on the Editor and Contributors
vii ix
PART 1 INTEGRATION WITHIN PSYCHOLOGY 1.
Evolutionary Psychology and Counseling and Psychotherapy Cezar Giosan
3
2.
Evolutionary Psychology and Psychiatry Riadh Abed and Paul St John-Smith
24
3.
Evolutionary Psychology and Suicidology John F. Gunn III, Pablo Malo, and C. A. Soper
51
4.
Evolutionary Psychology and Mindfulness and Meditation: Easing the Anxiety of Being Human James Carmody
94
5.
Evolutionary Psychology and Environmental Sciences Ulysses Paulino Albuquerque, Joelson M. B. Moura, Risoneide Henriques da Silva, Washington S. Ferreira Júnior, and Taline C. Silva
107
6.
Evolutionary Psychology and Public Health Simon Russell
123
7.
Animal Ethics and Evolutionary Psychology Diana Santos Fleischman
144
PART 2 APPLICATIONS TO LAW AND ORDER 8.
Evolutionary Psychology and Political Institutions Michael Latner and Elissa Feld
171
9.
Evolutionary Psychology and Crime Joseph L. Nedelec
188
10.
Evolutionary Psychology and Policing: The Balance Between Aggression and Restraint Lois James
11.
Evolutionary Psychology, Jurisprudence, and Sentencing Eyal Aharoni and Morris B. Hoffman
203
221
vi
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
12.
Evolutionary Psychology and Incarceration Alina Simona Rusu
243
13.
Evolution and Punishment Anthony Walsh, Cody Jorgensen, and Jessica Wells
258
14.
Evolutionary Psychology and Corrections and Rehabilitation Ian A. Silver and Jamie Newsome
277
15.
Evolutionary Psychology and Organized Crime Russil Durrant
296
16.
Evolutionary Psychology and Warfare Anthony C. Lopez
316
PART 3 APPLICATIONS TO TECHNOLOGY, COMMUNICATIONS, AND THE FUTURE 17.
Evolutionary Psychology and Artificial Intelligence: The Impact of Artificial Intelligence on Human Behaviour Holly Wilson, Paul Rauwolf, and Joanna J. Bryson
333
18.
Evolutionary Psychology and Robotics Robert Finkelstein
352
19.
Evolutionary Psychology and Dangerous Driving Behaviour Deanna Singhal and David Wiesenthal
374
20.
Evolutionary Psychology and Mass Media Gayle S. Stever
398
21.
Evolutionary Psychology and Communication Ned Kock
417
22.
Evolutionary Psychology and Climate Change: Understanding the Impact of Time Perspective on Carbon Emissions across 75 Countries Mark A. Caudell
435
23.
Evolutionary Psychology and Thanatology: Responses to Death James R. Anderson
457
24.
Evolutionary Psychology and Reproduction Stephen Whyte and Benno Torgler
477
25.
Evolutionary Psychology and Cyberwarfare Robert Finkelstein
499
Index515
List of Figures, Tables and Boxes FIGURES 2.1 Life history strategy trade-offs 29 3.1 Summary of posited antisuicide defences 68 3.2 A tentative mapping of hypothesized types of antisuicide mechanisms (keepers) across common diagnostic categories of mental disorder 74 4.1 Alarm-related components of experience forming a cycle of distress 97 4.2 Memory, imagination and emotion are symphonies of three interwoven experiential components 99 4.3 Components recognized as differentiated and connected 100 4.4 Attention shifts from differentiated components to arousal-neutral sensations of breathing 101 4.5 Re-perceiving reduces distress through a perceptual/attentional shift from what the thought is about – ‘I’m going to pass out’ – to the thought as an event in the mind/awareness – ‘This is a thought’ 101 5.1 Environment of Evolutionary Adaptedness definition (EEA), original version and extended version 110 5.2 Structure of the human naturalist mind 112 6.1 The impact of the food supply on the expression of obesity 125 6.2 Key determinants of psychological mechanisms and behaviour strategies 129 7.1 Charitable donations towards animal organizations as compared to animal use 151 9.1 Age-specific birth rates (per 1,000 women per year) in the 10 neighborhoods with the longest life expectancy compared to the 10 neighborhoods with the shortest life expectancy 198 10.1 Police balance between aggression and restraint 213 15.1 The basic dimensions of organized crime 298 19.1 GAM factors included in the investigation of modelling of aggressive or risky driving 384 19.2 Domestic box-office history for the Fast and Furious movies389 21.1 Path model showing a costly trait and its relationship with fitness 421 21.2 Probability of evolution of a new costly trait 423 21.3 Variation of the expected ratio between pay and pax424 21.4 The evolution of oral speech in humans 425 22.1 Effect of time orientation on total fertility as a function of education 446 22.2 Effect of time orientation on total fertility as a function of mortality level 447 22.3 Effect of time orientation on carbon emissions per capita as a function of investment in education 448
viii
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
TABLES 2.1 Tinbergen’s four questions 3.1 The fitness costs of suicide 7.1 Days of suffering per kilogram of food weight produced by the animal adjusted for the badness of each day of life as estimated by animal welfare researchers 15.1 Approaches to defining organized crime 15.2 The functional structures of organized crime groups in relation to the key evolutionary processes that facilitate cooperation 18.1 Processes of mind and their computational equivalents 21.1 Oral speech and the two common characteristics of costly traits 22.1 Descriptive statistics for Model 1 22.2 Variable correlations for Model 1 22.3 Data sources, years, and future orientation scores 22.4 Descriptive statistics for Model 2 22.5 Variable correlations for Model 2 22.6 Relationship between total fertility rates, time orientation, mortality, and parental investment 22.7 Effect of time orientation and education on carbon emissions
27 54 158 297 305 354 426 441 441 443 445 445 446 448
BOX 2.1 Pathways for the persistence of disease and disorder 2.2 Evolutionary theories of depression 5.1 Structure and behavior of the human naturalistic mind
28 33 113
Notes on the Editor and Contributors THE EDITOR Todd K. Shackelford received his Ph.D. in evolutionary psychology in 1997 from the University of Texas at Austin. Since 2010, he is Professor and Chair of the Department of Psychology at Oakland University in Rochester, Michigan, where he is Co-Director of the Evolutionary Psychology Lab. In 2016, he was appointed Distinguished Professor by the Oakland University Board of Trustees. He led the founding of new Ph.D. and M.S. programs which launched in 2012. Shackelford has published around 300 journal articles and his work has been cited over 22,000 times. Much of Shackelford’s research addresses sexual conflict between men and women, with a special focus on men’s physical, emotional, and sexual violence against their intimate partners. Since 2006, Shackelford has served as editor of the journal Evolutionary Psychology, and in 2014 founded the journal Evolutionary Psychological Science as Editor-in-Chief.
THE CONTRIBUTORS Riadh Abed FRCPsych, Qualified in medicine from Baghdad and trained in psychiatry in the UK. Retired Psychiatrist, Medical Director and Hon. Senior Clinical Lecturer, University of Sheffield, UK. Currently is a medical member of Mental Health Tribunals, Ministry of Justice, UK. He is author of a number of novel evolutionary hypotheses on eating disorders, obsessive compulsive disorder and schizophrenia and has published both theoretical as well as research articles on a range of evolutionary psychiatry subjects. He is founding chair of the Evolutionary Psychiatry Special Interest Group (EPSIG) at the Royal College of Psychiatrists, UK. Eyal Aharoni is an Associate Professor of Psychology, Philosophy, and Neuroscience at Georgia State University in Atlanta. His research investigates violence risk assessment and the influence of emotion, cognitive bias, and other extra-legal factors on legal decision-making. Prior to his current appointment, Aharoni served as a Research Associate for the RAND Corporation. He completed a postdoctoral fellowship with appointments at The MIND Research Network for Neurodiagnostic Discovery and the University of New Mexico Psychology. He has also held research positions at the Research Center for Virtual Environments and Behavior and the Institute for Social, Behavioral, and Economic Research. Aharoni earned his PhD in psychology at UC Santa Barbara where he also served as a research fellow for the MacArthur Foundation’s Law and Neuroscience Project. Ulysses Paulino Albuquerque received his Ph.D. in biology in 2001 from the Universidade Federal de Pernambuco, Brazil. He is Full Professor of the Department of Botany at Universidade Federal de Pernambuco, Pernambuco, Brazil. In 2011, he led the founding of new Ph.D. program in Ethnobiology and Nature Conservation. Albuquerque has published around 316 journal articles,
x
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
200 chapter’s book and edited or authored 50 books (including new editions and translations). Much of actual Albuquerque’s research addresses how work our naturalistic mind. Albuquerque has served as editor of various peer-reviewed journals, and in 2011 co-founded the journal Ethnobiology and Conservation as Co-Editor-in-Chief. James R. Anderson is a Professor in Psychology at Kyoto University, Japan. For more than 30 years he has studied behaviour and cognition in a wide range of nonhuman primates in captivity in the wild, as well as human children and elderly people. Most of his research is in the following areas: the effects of early experience on social adjustment, the development of abnormal behaviour, improving welfare of captive primates through environmental enrichment, communicative behaviours including tactile and postural signals, gaze-following, feeding competition and the influence of dominance relationships, tool-use, the ontogeny and phylogeny of self-recognition, self-control, third-party social evaluations, sleep-related behavioural adaptations, and responses to dead and dying group members and other individuals. Joanna J. Bryson is recognised for broad expertise on intelligence and its impacts, advising governments, transnational agencies and NGOs globally. She holds two degrees each in psychology and AI (BA Chicago, MSc and MPhil Edinburgh, PhD MIT). From 2002–2019 she was Computer Science faculty at the University of Bath; she has also been affiliated with Harvard Psychology, Oxford Anthropology, Mannheim Social Science Research and the Princeton Center for Information Technology Policy. During her PhD she observed the confusion generated by anthropomorphised AI, leading to her first AI ethics publication ‘Just Another Artifact’ in 1998. She has remained active in the field including coauthoring the first national-level AI ethics policy, the UK’s (2011) Principles of Robotics. She is presently Professor of Ethics and Technology at the Hertie School of Governance in Berlin, Germany. James Carmody is a Professor in the Departments of Medicine, and Population and Health Sciences Division of Preventive and Behavioral Medicine at University of Massachusetts Medical School. His research is on how evolutionary and biological imperatives shape our habits of attending to experience, their effect on anxiety, and the degree to which they can be mitigated by mind–body training programmes like mindfulness and yoga. He is principal investigator on NIH-funded clinical trials of the clinical effects and mechanisms of mindfulness training. James studied and practised in Zen, Tibetan, Theravada and Advaita traditions in several countries over 50 years. He has been a therapist and leads retreats for clinicians with the goal of making the conceptualisation and psychological mechanisms of mindfulness straightforward, jargon-free and practically accessible for patients. His work has been featured in national and international media including the New York Times, NPR and ABC. Mark A. Caudell is a Medical Anthropologist working for the Food and Agriculture Organization of the United Nations and is adjunct faculty in the Department of Anthropology at Washington State University. His research centres on understanding how socioecological systems drive the emergence and transmission of environmental risks as well as pattern individual and community responses to these risks. His current work combines ethnographic and lab-based methods to identify the cultural and cognitive drivers of infectious disease and antimicrobial resistance in low- and middle-income countries. He has conducted research among foragers in the Congo Basin and farmers and pastoralists throughout sub-Saharan Africa and is funded by the National Science Foundation, The Fleming Fund, Amazon and the Paul G. Allen School for Global Animal Health at Washington State University. Currently, he is based in Nairobi, Kenya.
Notes on the Editor and Contributors
xi
Risoneide Henriques da Silva is master in Botany (2018) from the Federal Rural University of Pernambuco, Brazil. She is currently PhD candidate in Ethnobiology and Nature Conservation by the same institution. Since 2016 she is a researcher associated at the Laboratory of Ecology and Evolution of Social-ecological Systems at the Federal University of Pernambuco, Brazil. Risoneide Henriques has an interest in understanding the cognitive aspects involved with human behaviour in relation to biota. Russil Durrant is a Senior Lecturer at the Institute of Criminology, Victoria University of Wellington, New Zealand, where he teaches courses in criminal, biosocial and investigative psychology. His research focuses on the application of evolutionary theory to understanding crime and crime-related phenomena. He is the author (or co-author) of five books including (with Tony Ward) Evolutionary Criminology: Towards a Comprehensive Explanation for Crime and (with Zoe Poppelwell) Religion, Crime, and Punishment: An Evolutionary Perspective. Elissa Feld earned a Masters in Public Policy at California Polytechnic State University, San Luis Obispo. Her research continues to focus on political psychology and public policy. Robert Finkelstein earned a DBA in Systems Theory and Cybernetics from George Washington University (GWU), an ApSci. in Operations Research (GWU), an MS in Operations Research (GWU), an MS in Physics (University of Massachusetts) and a BA in Physics (Temple University), as well as completing postgraduate courses in Physics at MIT. Dr Finkelstein is President, since 1985, of Robotic Technology Inc., a professional services firm that provides technical analyses, systems engineering, technology assessments, operations research, business development and other services in the fields of autonomous ground, air and water vehicles, intelligent systems, robotics for military and civil applications, and memetics. Dr Finkelstein is an Adjunct Professor in the graduate school at the University of Maryland Global Campus and is serving as a Co-Director of the Intelligent Systems Laboratory at the University of Maryland Clark School of Engineering. Diana Santos Fleischman is an Associate Professor of psychology at the University of Portsmouth in the UK. She received her PhD in evolutionary psychology at the University of Texas at Austin. Diana has been involved in animal ethics and effective animal advocacy for several years. From 2010–2012 Diana co-hosted ‘The Vegan Option’ podcast which explored many themes at the intersection of psychology and animal ethics. From 2017– 2019 Diana served on the board at Sentience Institute, a think tank devoted to exploring ways to expand humanity’s moral circle. Diana also has served on the grants board of the Animal Advocacy Research Fund which aims to promote research into effective animal advocacy. Cezar Giosan PhD is a faculty member of the Department of Psychology at the University of Bucharest and has a doctorate in psychology from the New School University, New York. He worked for a long time as a research psychologist in the top-ranked Department of Psychiatry at Weill Medical School of Cornell University. Dr Giosan has authored dozens of peer-reviewed publications in impact journals, including studies on the applications of evolutionary psychology in psychological interventions. He has tested, in the form of a randomized clinical trial, the efficacy of an evolutionary intervention for depression, and is the author of a published therapy protocol of Cognitive-Evolutionary Therapy.
xii
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
John F. Gunn III PhD has a BA (Stockton University) and MA (Rutgers University – Camden) in psychology and a PhD in family science and human development (Montclair State University). John is currently a Postdoctoral Associate at the NJ Center on Gun Violence Research at Rutgers University, where he is investigating the role of firearms in suicide mortality on both small and large scales. His research interests include risk and protective factors for suicidal behaviour (such as access to a firearm; exposure to bullying), social connectedness and suicide, theoretical models of suicidal behaviour (such as evolutionary explanations for suicide) and the impact of media on suicide. John has written or co-authored over 20 scholarly publications, three edited books and 10 book chapters. Morris B. Hoffman has been a district judge in the state of Colorado since 1991. He is a member of the John D. and Catherine T. MacArthur Foundation’s Research Network on Law and Neuroscience, and a Research Fellow at the Gruter Institute for Law and Behavioral Research. He has published many law review articles, focusing on the areas of criminal law, jurisprudence, law and neuroscience, and jury history, in journals that include Stanford, University of Chicago, Vanderbilt, Duke, Northwestern, the University of Pennsylvania, Journal of Law and Biosciences and Journal of Philosophy, Science and Law. He has coauthored science papers in journals that include Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, Journal of Neuroscience, Trends in Neuroscience and Social Neuroscience. His book, The Punisher’s Brain: An Evolutionary History of Judge and Jury, was published in 2014. Lois James is an Assistant Professor in the Washington State University (WSU) College of Nursing, where she focuses on bias, stress, sleep and performance in ‘high-stress’ populations such as police officers, military personnel, nurses and top-tier athletes. She has received multiple honours and awards for her work, and is internationally recognised as a leading expert in her field. Her simulation-based research on the impact of bias on police decision making has significantly advanced what is known about how suspect race and ethnicity influences police officers during critical encounters with the public. She is the founding director of Counter Bias Training Simulation (CBTsim), a novel and innovative simulation-based implicit bias training program that has been featured in National Geographic and the recent feature-length documentary ‘bias’. Her work has been published extensively in academic journals, practitioner magazines and mainstream media such as the New York Times and the Washington Post. Cody Jorgensen is an Assistant Professor at Boise State University. He received his PhD from the University of Texas at Dallas in 2014. His main research interests include biosocial and developmental criminology, policing and forensics, and drug policy. Washington S. Ferreira Júnior received his Ph.D in Botany in 2015 at Federal Rural University of Pernambuco. Since 2016, he is Professor of the Biological Sciences course at Pernambuco University in Petrolina, Pernambuco, where he is coordinator of the Laboratory of Biocultural Investigations in the Semiarid. He is professor at the Postgraduate Program in Environmental Science and Technology at University of Pernambuco and the Postgraduate Program in Ethnobiology and Nature Conservation at Federal Rural University of Pernambuco. Ferreira Júnior has published around 40 journal articles, 40 book chapters and organized three books with partners. His research efforts are focused on understanding the structure, dynamics and evolution of local medical systems with an emphasis on the use of medicinal plants.
Notes on the Editor and Contributors
xiii
Ned Kock is Texas A&M Regents Professor and Chair of the Division of International Business and Technology Studies, in the Sanchez School of Business, at Texas A&M International University. He is an active member of the Human Behavior and Evolution Society and the Association for Information Systems. He has edited the Springer book Evolutionary Psychology and Information Systems Research, and guest-edited the Special Issue on Darwinian Perspectives on Electronic Communication published in the IEEE Transactions on Professional Communication. Ned has published his research in a number of high-impact journals including Communications of the ACM, Decision Support Systems, European Journal of Information Systems, European Journal of Operational Research, IEEE Transactions (various), Information & Management, Information Systems Journal, Journal of the Association for Information Systems, Journal of Management Information Systems, MIS Quarterly and Organization Science. His research interests include evolution and human behaviour toward technology, computational statistics and structural equation modelling. Michael Latner is a Professor of Political Science at California Polytechnic State University, San Luis Obispo, faculty scholar at Cal Poly’s Institute for Advanced Technology and Public Policy and a Senior Fellow with the Union of Concerned Scientists’ Center for Science and Democracy. His research focuses on electoral systems, coalition behavior, representation and voting rights. Anthony C. Lopez is Associate Professor of Political Psychology in the School of Politics, Philosophy, and Public Affairs, at Washington State University. He received his PhD from Brown University, and also received training as a research associate at the Center for Evolutionary Psychology, University of California, Santa Barbara. His research explores the evolutionary origins of warfare, as well as its constituent psychological dynamics, such as revenge, the nature of deterrence, collective action problems of warfare, extremist violence, and distinctions between offensive and defensive aggression. He serves as Associate Editor of Politics with the Evolution Institute and blogs regularly at Psychology Today. Pablo Malo studied medicine in the University of the Basque Country in Spain and psychiatry in the Psychiatric Hospital of Zamudio. Pablo is currently a clinical psychiatrist working in the Mental Health Center of Bombero Etxaniz, in Bilbao, Spain. His clinical interests include psychosis and severe mental disorders, violence and mental health disorders, intimate partner violence and evolutionary psychology. Pablo has co-authored a book about evolutionary psychiatry, written over 20 scholarly papers and is the editor of two blogs about evolutionary psychology and biology. Joelson M. B. Moura has a complete degree in Biological Sciences from the Universidade Federal Rural de Pernambuco (UFRPE), with an internship at the University of Coimbra (UC) in 2013. He received his master’s degree in Ethnobiology and Nature Conservation (UFRPE) in 2018. He is currently a Ph.D. candidate in the same program and integrates the Laboratory of Ecology and Evolution of Socioecological Systems (LEA) at the Universidade Federal de Pernambuco (UFPE) since 2016. The research carried out by Moura seeks to understand the processes that contributed to the evolution of the human mind. His work is in the perspective of evolutionary ethnobiology, which addresses the influence of the evolutionary past on current human behavior and how it reflects on the relationship between people and their environments.
xiv
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Joseph L. Nedelec is an Associate Professor in the School of Criminal Justice at the University of Cincinnati. His research interests include biosocial criminology, evolutionary psychology, intelligence, quantitative behaviour genetics, and cybercrime. Dr Nedelec’s work has been published in a variety of journals including Criminology, Evolution and Human Behavior, Intelligence, Journal of Criminal Justice, Journal of Quantitative Criminology, Personality and Individual Differences and PLOS One, among others. Jamie Newsome received her doctorate in 2013 from the School of Criminal Justice at UC, and is currently the Research Coordinator for UCCI. Her research interests include the design, implementation and effectiveness of correctional interventions, and translating research into practice. Paul Rauwolf is an Assistant Professor (Lecturer) in Psychology at Bangor University, UK. Previously, he was a Postdoctoral Researcher in the Mathematics Institute at the University of Oxford and the School of Psychology at Bangor University. In 2016, he received his PhD in Computer Science from the University of Bath. His research takes an interdisciplinary perspective to better understand the utility and aetiology of biases in human decision-making. During his PhD, he used agent-based modelling to demonstrate that ignoring freely available information can be adaptive in a variety of contexts, such as maintaining cooperative societies. His current work focuses on understanding how the changing information and technological landscape impacts human decision-making under uncertainty. Simon Russell is a Research Fellow at the Great Ormond Street Institute of Child Health. Simon has conducted research in the fields of evolutionary science and public health, with a particular interest in health risk behaviours, obesity, inequalities in health, public health policy and epidemiology. Simon’s PhD entailed applying evolutionary principles to the obesity problem and other issues in public health, work that demonstrated that health behaviours and strategies are likely to be adaptive. Currently, Simon leads various research projects that have high policy relevance and often involve emerging methodologies. In recent years, Simon has specialised in simulating policy relevant interventions using causal inference techniques across longitudinal cohort data. Simon’s work involves applying epidemiological techniques to explore causes and consequences of obesity and to appraise the effectiveness of potential population policy action. Alina Simona Rusu is a biologist and psychologist and is currently an Associate Professor in the Department of Special Education, School of Psychology and Sciences of Education, BabeşBolyai University, Romania. She received her PhD in Animal Behaviour from University of Zurich, Switzerland. She is interested in interdisciplinary research of human prosocial behaviour in the context of inclusive institutions, as well as the applied values of human–animal interactions. Taline C. Silva received her Ph.D. in Botany in 2014 from the Federal Rural University of Pernambuco. Since 2016, she is Professor of the Biology course at State University of Alagoas in Palmeira dos índios, Alagoas, where she is coordinator of the Ethnobiology and Ecossistems conservation Lab. In 2018, she was member of Post graduation program in ethnobiology and nature conservation. Silva has published around 30 journal articles. She has experience in Ethnobiology and seeks to understand the factors that guide the complex relationship between people and nature, accessing knowledge, use and local perception of natural resources and landscape changes.
Notes on the Editor and Contributors
xv
Ian A. Silver is an Assistant Professor at the Law and Justice Department at Rowan University and a Fellow at the University of Cincinnati Corrections Institute (UCCI). His research interests include correctional rehabilitation, incarceration, biopsychosocial criminology, and methodological issues. His recent work has appeared in Criminology and Public Policy, Aggressive Behavior, Journal of Offender Rehabilitation, Brain Injury and Journal of Criminal Justice. Deanna Singhal received a bachelor’s degree in psychology from Queen’s University in Kingston, and a master’s degree (exercise and health science) and doctoral degree (psychology: brain, behaviour, and cognitive science) from York University in Toronto. She is now a Faculty Service Officer in the Department of Psychology at the University of Alberta, Canada, with a primary role to support the Undergraduate Teaching and Learning Program. Her research interests include driving behaviour and cognitive workload, and her areas of teaching include introductory psychology and human neuropsychology. Paul St John-Smith FRCPsych. Trained at Oxford, graduated in natural sciences in 1976 and qualified in medicine in 1979. He then trained as a general practitioner and later joined the pharmaceutical industry for five years as a research physician in psychopharmacology investigating various antidepressants, hypnotics and other central nervous system agents including the benzodiazepine antagonist. In 1987 he returned to study psychiatry full time and worked in a number of London hospitals including Barnet, Guys, Greenwich, St Thomas’, and as a consultant in Hertfordshire. He has published on a range of areas in evolutionary psychiatry and has peer reviewed papers on psychopharmacology, placebo effects, professionalism, suicide and depression, as well as evolution. C. A. Soper is a psychotherapist in private practice in Lisbon, Portugal. He holds degrees from the University of Cambridge and the University of London and gained his PhD at the University of Gloucestershire for theoretical research into the evolutionary origins of suicide. His book, The Evolution of Suicide, was published in 2018. He has authored various other scholarly publications on suicide and suicidology, and presented at academic and clinical conferences on the subject. Soper’s clinical interests include the provision of therapeutic support for people affected by suicide and those suffering from alcoholism and other addictions. Gayle S. Stever is a Professor of Psychology at Empire State College/State University of New York. She has done research in the areas of parasocial theory, media effects and fan studies for over 30 years, and has authored numerous peer-reviewed articles on these subjects, in addition to writing The Psychology of Celebrity (2019). With her degree in lifespan development psychology, looking at media effects from a lifespan perspective is central to her work. Benno Torgler is Professor of Economics at the Centre for Behavioural Economics, Society and Technology (BEST) and School of Economics and Finance, Queensland University of Technology (QUT), Australia. He was also Adjunct Professor at the EBS Universität für Wirtschaft und Recht, Germany (2012–2015) and an Australian Research Council (ARC) Future Fellow (2011–2015). Before QUT he was a Research Affiliate and Lecturer in International and Comparative Political Economy in the Leitner Program at the MacMillan Center, Yale University; a Visiting Scholar in the Law and Economics Program at University of CaliforniaBerkeley; and a Visiting Scholar in the Andrew Young School of Policy Studies at Georgia State
xvi
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
University. His primary research interest lies in the area of economics, but he has also published in journals with a political science, social psychology, medical, sociology and biology focus. Anthony Walsh is a Professor Emeritus at Boise State University. He received his PhD from Bowling Green State University in 1983 after working as a marine, police officer and probation/ parole officer. His primary interest is biosocial criminology. He has published 43 books, the latest being God, Science, and Society: The Origin of the Universe, Intelligent Life, and Free Societies (Vernon, 2020). Jessica Wells is an Assistant Professor of Criminal Justice at Boise State University. She received her PhD in Criminal Justice and Criminology from Sam Houston State University in 2017. Her research is in the area of psychological and biosocial perspectives on criminal offending. Her publications focus on the consequences of stress and trauma exposure in samples of community members, incarcerated individuals and criminal justice professionals. Stephen Whyte is a Research Fellow in Behavioural Economics at the Centre for Behavioural Economics, Society and Technology (BEST) and School of Economics and Finance, Queensland University of Technology (QUT), Australia. His research focus explores largescale decision making in mate-choice settings. His work takes a multi-disciplinary approach in studying key sex differences in human behaviour, with work that bridges the fields of applied micro-economics, personality and social psychology, and evolutionary biology. His most recent research has explored such diverse topics as sex differences in nonbinary gender identification, male and female decision making in assisted reproductive and donor insemination medical environments, and preferences vs choice in cyber dating markets. David Wiesenthal received a bachelor’s degree in psychology from the City College of New York and a doctoral degree in social psychology from the State University of New York at Buffalo, followed by a postdoctoral fellowship from York University, Canada. He is now a Professor Emeritus and Senior Scholar at York University, Canada. He has been a Visiting Professor at the Hebrew University of Jerusalem and lectured as a Scandinavian Fellow at the Building Research Institute (Gävle, Sweden), Umeå University, Lund University, and the Helsingborg campus of Lund University, as well as the University of Costa Rica and the College of Psychologists (Costa Rica). His research interests are social and environmental influence processes, driver behaviours, scientific racism and research ethics. Holly Wilson is a second-year PhD student in the Department of Computer Science at the University of Bath. Her doctoral research involves investigating the neural correlates of both visual imagery and perception, and developing a brain computer interface which facilitates visual imagery reconstruction. Holly merged her interests in both artificial and natural intelligence by obtaining a BSc in Psychology followed by an MSc in Computer Science. In the first year of her PhD she focused on the ethics and impact of AI on people, on both an individual and societal level, alongside developing agent-based models of cultural evolution during the Upper Palaeolithic transition.
PART 1
Integration within Psychology
This page intentionally left blank
1 Evolutionary Psychology and Counseling and Psychotherapy Cezar Giosan
This chapter covers two important clinical applications of evolutionary psychopathology: (1) evolutionary-inspired psychological interventions, and (2) integration of evolutionary insights into couples therapy.
APPLICATIONS OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY IN THE TREATMENT OF MENTAL DISORDERS In recent years, there has been an outpouring of attempts at evolutionary hypotheses of mental disorders. Different authors have proposed evolutionary explanations for depression (Durisko et al., 2015), anxieties (Gilbert, 2001; Nesse, 1998), schizophrenia (Crow, 2000), and personality disorders (Glenn et al., 2011; Gutiérrez et al., 2013; Hertler, 2014; Molina et al., 2009; O’Reilly et al., 2001), to name a few. Evolutionary explanations of mental disorders typically focus on the role of the
symptoms in increasing fitness, seeing them as evolved strategies serving an organism’s goal to survive and reproduce, or, conversely, center on the mismatch between our adaptations, evolved during the Environment of Evolutionary Adaptedness, and the modern world. An important practical question that arises from this substantial body of work revolves around the clinical implications of such theories. Although still speculative for the most part, evolutionary explanations of mental disorders do raise the intriguing possibility that psychological interventions that target fitness could have unique clinical benefits, which can go above and beyond those of current treatments. To this end, clinical psychologists, psychotherapists, or clinical researchers have attempted to bridge the gap between evolutionary theory and clinical practice by developing protocols that integrate evolutionary insights into the treatment of mental disorders. Some of these protocols have been
4
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
tested in randomized clinical trials with active comparators, while others have led to case studies or small-n pilot studies with no comparators. Also, some of these insights have been used in a cross-diagnostic manner – that is, same principles applied to various conditions – while others are specific to certain disorders. Alfonso Troisi and Michael McGuire have proposed that an evolutionary therapy’s main aim is to increase a patient’s short-term biological goals. In this light, evolutionary psychopathology makes the distinction between mental disorder and mental suffering, seeing many mental symptoms as adaptive reactions to situations associated with negative cost–benefit outcomes, which should not be treated if they do not cause distress (Troisi and McGuire, 2014). More specifically, in the view of Troisi and McGuire (2014), an evolutionary-driven therapy should (1) address cost–benefit outcomes; (2) facilitate the development of revised models of the social environments; and (3) aid the patient in developing capacities to achieve biologically relevant goals. This therapy should attempt to refine traits or to foster the use of alternative capacities that can help to achieve high-priority goals. In the more difficult cases, the authors argue, therapy should encourage patients with suboptimal functional capacities to actively search for environments where they can be successful in reaching highpriority goals (Troisi and McGuire, 2014).
Evolutionary Psychology and Case Conceptualization Case conceptualization – an explanation, offered by the therapist, of the problems bothering a patient – addresses the mental problem and its possible causes, the ethiopathogenetic processes presumed to be involved, and the positive or adverse effects of the proposed treatment. The efficient conceptualization of a problem can generate positive expectations about the treatment as well as a sense of prediction and control in
the patient, which can facilitate recovery (John and Segal, 2015; Kuyken et al., 2008). Historically, Sigmund Freud was the first to introduce case conceptualization as a key element in psychotherapy, through the analysis of the latent content of the dreams and interpretation of the neurotic symptoms (Freud, 2017). Today, case conceptualization is used in many therapeutic approaches. For instance, Cognitive Behavioral Therapy (CBT), one of the most widely used interventions for anxiety and depression, typically includes information about the causal mechanisms of the problem, that is, proximal causes of psychopathology, thus answering the ‘how’ questions from the ABC1 model (Ellis, 1994; Ellis et al., 2007). Case conceptualization in modern psychological interventions, however, typically includes only information about proximal causes of the symptoms. For instance, the ABC model leaves out the ‘how’ questions, focusing almost exclusively on the immediate mechanisms, such as dysfunctional thinking (Lam and Gale, 2000). Some therapeutic schools do offer distal explanations of symptoms, but none of them goes so deep as to bring into the therapeutic discourse, in a coherent, unified manner, the factors, forces, and elements that have shaped the evolution of our species. For example, psychoanalysis, the first school of thought that brought into discussion the distal causes of psychopathology, explains phobias through repression and displacement. A conflict originates in childhood and that conflict is either repressed or displaced onto the feared object. As an illustrative example, in ‘Notes upon a case of obsessional neurosis’ Freud attributed the Rat Man’s fear of relatives dying from being burrowed through by rats to guilt originating from a repressed desire he had earlier to see women that he knew naked (Williams, 2008). A phobia of snakes, from the same psychoanalytical perspective, was an unconscious fear of something else, which was to be unraveled in therapy through dream interpretation or analysis of slips of tongue.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND COUNSELING AND PSYCHOTHERAPY
Evolutionary psychopathology makes one giant leap further and addresses the distal, evolutionary causes of mental illness, namely, the evolutionary factors and forces that might be at the root of the presenting symptoms. By addressing the evolutionary causes of behaviors, evolutionary psychopathology finds itself in the privileged – and unique, to some extent – position to offer explanations of symptoms that typically make much sense to patients. By offering evolutionary explanations of symptoms, evolutionary psychology can enhance case conceptualizations of various treatment approaches in meaningful ways, potentially leading to better therapeutic outcomes. For instance, incorporating information about the hypothesized adaptive functions of the symptoms in the ABC, or the further refined ABCDE model (Ellis, 1994; Ellis et al., 2007), can lead to answers to ‘why’ questions, thus giving the patient a broader and more meaningful understanding of the problems they are confronting, which can lead to better acceptance.
Integration of Evolutionary Principles in Specific Forms of Therapy There have been several attempts to integrate evolutionary insights into various therapies in recent years. We begin by briefly describing the possible evolutionary resuscitation of Freud’s psychoanalysis and Jung’s analytical therapy and continue with a presentation of several evolutionary-driven therapy protocols that have been tested in randomized clinical trials. We will end this section with a brief presentation of the potential applications of evolutionary conceptualizations to other types of mental conditions.
Psychoanalysis Evolutionary psychotherapies place substantial importance on the therapeutic relationship. This is not something new. A century ago,
5
Sigmund Freud also made this central in his psychoanalytical psychotherapy. Indeed, one of the fundamental tenets of psychoanalytical psychotherapy is complete disclosure and communication: the patient is required to disclose anything that comes to their mind, without censorship. Thus, in Freudian psychoanalysis, the therapist took a central role in patients’ lives, since he would learn information about them that no one else was privy to. This unique and extremely close relationship (sessions were held several times per week) made Freud realize that it played a major role in the therapeutic outcomes and subsequently led to the definition of important constructs such as ‘transference’, which slowly replaced the initial emphasis on sexual symbolism with more nuanced understandings of the therapeutic alliance. Some scholars note that many psychotherapies – including evolutionary interventions – do not place sufficient importance on the relationship between the client and the therapist, or they may use that relationship to manipulate patients in what the therapist believes is in his own best interests. Kriegman (2000) argues that evolutionary insights can help reduce this risk in all forms of therapy, including psychoanalysis. Since psychoanalysis revolves around a deep relationship between two unrelated individuals and since one evolutionary principle is that we are hardwired to operate for our own benefits, it follows that the power the therapist has over the patient may sometimes be used to further the interests of the therapist, even if unconsciously (Kriegman, 1998). Becoming more aware of the distal mechanisms responsible for human behavior will place a therapist in a better position to avoid confusion between proximal and distal causes, ultimately benefitting the patient. For instance, as Kriegman describes hypothetically, a woman who dresses provocatively but is angered when perceived as a sexual object can be seen by an analyst as having an unconscious wish to be ravished or raped, with anger being a reaction formation. From an evolutionary lens, however, this interpretation might reflect a mix between projections
6
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
of male wishes and confusion of proximal (dressing sexily) and ultimate causes (woman’s self-interest enhancement through the stimulation of men). Becoming more aware of such nuances can help the therapeutic process and, therefore, evolutionary interpretations can bring value to such clinical situations.
Jungian Analytical Therapy While for classical psychoanalytical therapy the answer to the central question of what is wrong with the patient is their repressed memories, which the therapist tries to bring to the conscious level using strategies such as interpretation of dreams or slips of the tongue, in Carl Gustav Jung’s analytical therapy it is the archetypal intent that needs to be freed to unleash the patient’s full potential (Stevens, 2000). Jung’s theory of archetypes – universal, innate, archaic patterns and images of evolutionary origins that stem from the collective unconscious and which are the psychic counterpart of instinct – closely anticipated the notions of evolved mechanisms (innate strategies or algorithms) present in evolutionary theories today. Indeed, Jung rejected the tabula rasa understanding of human mind, common to his contemporaries (notably, John Watson in the United States) and replaced it with a theory that included the enormous influence of evolutionary factors on human behavior. Like evolutionary psychologists today, Jung argued that homeostasis, epigenesis, and adaptation are at the basis of the human psyche (Stevens, 1982, 1999), a paradigm that was in stark contrast to the blank-slate view of the mind from the Standard Social Sciences Model. Jung also rejected the sexualized Freudian interpretation of complexes such as Oedipus, anticipating the later works of John Bowlby, who argued that a child is attached to his/her mother because she is the caregiver (Bowlby, 1983, 2005). Also, of note, in clinical practice, Jung rejected Freud’s cold
objectivity in the therapeutic relationship, replacing it with something common in evolutionary therapies today, namely, the emphasis on a warm, reciprocal alliance. Not unlike the mismatch hypothesis (Giphart and van Vugt, 2018), psychopathology, in the Jungian paradigm, occurs when environmental mismatches at critical developmental stages lead to malfunction in ‘archetypal’ strategies (Stevens, 2000). Evolutionary psychology can add to analytical therapy the critical element of an even broader view of self than Jung conceived. Armed with modern knowledge about the functions of psychological mechanisms, therapists nowadays can bring into the clinical conceptualization a more expanded conversation about the role of these mechanisms in mental illness.
Evidence-Based Evolutionary Interventions After this brief theoretical presentation of the ways in which evolutionary insights can aid Freudian and Jungian therapies, we continue, in the section that follows, with the presentation of results from several empirical studies that have examined the benefits of integrating evolutionary insights into the treatment of depression and personality disorders.
Depression A Rwandan man once described the Rwandan treatment for depression to the 2001 National Book Award winner Andrew Solomon like this: You know, we had a lot of trouble with Western mental health workers, especially the ones who came here right after the genocide. They came and their practice did not involve being outside in the sunshine… which is, after all, where you begin to feel better. There was no drumming or music to get your blood flowing again – when you’re depressed and low you need to have your blood flowing. There was no sense that everyone had taken the day off so that the entire community
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND COUNSELING AND PSYCHOTHERAPY
could come together to lift you up and bring you back to joy. There was no acknowledgement of the depression as something invasive and external that could actually be cast out of you again. Instead, they would take people one at a time into these dingy little rooms and have them sit around for an hour or so to talk about bad things that had happened to them. We had to ask them to leave the country. (Taljaard, n.d.)
While this description of an intervention for depression is in stark contrast to the standard one-hour-weekly therapy sessions common in Western cultures, it would not surprise an evolutionary therapist. Evolutionary psychopathologists view mild and moderate depression as functional states, serving adaptive functions (for a review, see Durisko et al., 2015). For instance, as early as the 1990s, some authors conceptualized depression as a warning signal that biosocial goals have not been achieved (Nesse, 1991). The clinical implication of this line of thought is that finding solutions to reset the cost–benefit balance in favor of the patient should make depressed mood subside. In one of the earlier attempts at incorporating evolutionary insights into therapy for depression, McGuire and Troisi presented a clinical case of a patient who was depressed because of her inability to have children (i.e., major direct fitness problem). The treatment focused on addressing the dysregulating effects of the patient’s inability to reproduce, and, crucially, also formulated strategies to help this patient’s fitness through kin investment (i.e., inclusive fitness) (McGuire and Troisi, 1998: 270–271).
Treating Depression Downhill One evolutionary-based intervention protocol for depression is Treating Depression Downhill – TDD (Krupnik, 2014). TDD relies on an experiential approach and involves three distinct phases: (1) exploratory, in which the patients gain insight into their experience of defeat; (2) acceptance, in
7
which the patients terminate protest, that is, accept defeat as an immutable fact of their lives. This phase, which is the analogue equivalent of exposure therapy in anxiety disorders, is the centerpiece of TDD, as it facilitates the transition from protest to acquiescence; and (3) behavioral activation without the functional analysis component. Throughout TDD treatment, cognitive reappraisal takes place, following standard cognitive therapy approaches (e.g., analysis of distortions).
Evidence in Favor of TDD A preliminary study testing the efficacy of TDD was conducted in the form of a pilot observation on a sample of 12 participants, who met for 24 biweekly, 90-minute-long sessions (Krupnik, 2014). The protocol demonstrated effectiveness and specificity for depression, differentiating it from anxiety and personality disorders. The results showed marked decline in depressive symptomatology; however, the study was underpowered and the tentative trends in the dynamics of the participants’ scores did not reach statistical significance. The TDD protocol needs further testing in randomized controlled studies in comparison with established protocols for depression to better establish its efficacy. Since not all clients can engage in mindfulness, which is a key element in the acceptance phase in TDD, the same author replaced, in a further case study on a medicated patient, the acceptance phase from TDD with eye movement desensitization and reprocessing – EMDR (Shapiro, 2017). In this study, EMDR was used in a truncated form, and the nature of the targets was the subjective perception of loss, rather than actual events, while reappraisal took place along the protest– acceptance axis. The results showed that, at the end of the treatment and at followup assessment, the patient reported a more accepting disposition and decreased depressive symptoms (Krupnik, 2015).
8
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Following the same line of investigation, another study conducted by the same author reported a case series of 21 military personnel diagnosed with depressive disorders, who received a course of TDD-EMDR (Krupnik, 2018). By the end of treatment (12 sessions), 80% of completers (n = 15) did not meet the criteria for depressive disorder and they showed a significant reduction in scores on the Beck Depression Inventory-II – BDI-II (Beck et al., 1996) with a large effect size (d = 2.8) and an increase in accepting disposition (d = 1.8) on the Acceptance and Action Questionnaire (Bond et al., 2011). Non-completers showed a similar decrease in the BDI-II scores at mid-treatment. The author observed no statistically significant decrease in anxiety symptoms on the BDI-II. These results suggest that TDD-EMDR may be an effective treatment for depressive disorders (Krupnik, 2018). They also indicate that this type of intervention may target depressive over anxiety symptoms (Krupnik, 2018), as was previously observed for the original TDD pilot study (Krupnik, 2014).
Therapeutic Lifestyle Change for Depression (TLC-D) Another attempt to incorporate evolutionaryinspired interventions in therapy is the Therapeutic Lifestyle Change for Depression (TLC-D) protocol (Karwoski et al., 2005), which includes several evolutionary elements thought to have positive effects on mood. TLC-D combines several relevant factors, some of which are evolutionary-relevant, that are shown to be effective in the treatment of depression. These factors include: 1 Omega-3 fatty acid consumption (Peet and Horrobin, 2002). 2 Bright light exposure (Martiny et al., 2005). 3 Sleep hygiene (Mayers and Baldwin, 2006). 4 Aerobic exercise (Blumenthal et al., 2007). 5 Anti-rumination exercises (Fennell and Teasdale, 1987). 6 Social support (George, 1989).
Evidence in Favor of TLC-D Karwoski et al.’s (2005) protocol was retested with additional data and gender comparison by Jacobson et al. (2007). The authors examined TLC-D on 81 patients who underwent 12 sessions of TLC-D therapy, with followup evaluations at three and six months. The experimental group was compared to a Treatment as Usual (TAU) group, representing one-third of the sample. The results showed that the TLC-D group outperformed the control group. The results also showed that, at the end of the therapy, participants averaged a 17.8% decrease in BDI-II (Beck et al., 1996) scores, which represented a statistically significant 60.6% reduction from baseline. These improvements were stable, showing a 67.7% reduction at three-month follow-up, and 64.0% reduction at six-month follow-up. Further research on TLC-D continued to show promising results. In a study conducted by Botanov et al., (2012), 29 patients were recruited into a TLC-D protocol, in a two-toone random assignment (22 in TLC-D and 7 in TAU). The participants underwent 12 sessions of group therapy over 14 weeks and were assessed weekly with the BDI-II (Beck et al., 1996). The results showed a clinically significant response (>= 50% reduction in BDI-II scores) in 77.3% of the participants in the TLC-D condition versus 28.6% in the TAU condition, and, notably, no significant change in BDI-II scores was observed from treatment end to six-month follow-up, suggesting low relapse rates post-treatment.
Cognitive Evolutionary Therapy for Depression (CETD) Another clinically tested evolutionary-driven intervention protocol for depression is Cognitive Evolutionary Therapy for Depression (CETD) (Giosan, 2020; Giosan, Cobeanu, Wyka, et al., 2020; Giosan, Cobeanu et al., 2014). As conceptualized by the authors,
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND COUNSELING AND PSYCHOTHERAPY
besides targeting the proximal causes of depression as is standard in CBT, CETD focuses on distal causes as well, such as inclusive fitness or reproductive success. While sharing common underpinnings with CBT, CETD adds the inclusion of evolutionary conceptualizations of the patient’s symptoms and the targeting of fitness-related problems. Very much unlike classical Cognitive Therapy for Depression, in which the problems that preoccupy the patient are identified by the patients during the therapy sessions, CETD starts from the premise that depressive symptoms reflect fitness difficulties, some of which are unknown to the patients, and which can be identified via an evaluation of the patient’s fitness prior to the first session. By identifying a patient’s fitness problems at intake, the CETD therapist thus is pre-equipped with this knowledge at the first session and can start working with the patient on problematic areas right away. Along with these evolutionary-driven behavioral activations, discussions about human nature from evolutionary perspectives are also taking place during CETD, such as modularity (Cosmides and Tooby, 1994), parental investment theory (Buss et al., 1990), conspicuous consumption (Sundie et al., 2011), or costly signaling theory (Fraser, 2012), all of which can facilitate acceptance, a key CBT ingredient (Chamberlain and Haaga, 2001). The instrument that CETD therapists use to identify a patient’s fitness difficulties is the Evolutionary Fitness Scale – EFS (Giosan et al., 2018). The EFS is a 58-item scale assessing mismatches between the Environment of Evolutionary Adaptedness and the modern world, such as in physical activity or nutrition, environmental misfits, or fitness-related factors such as health of the actor, his/her partner and their extended families, attractiveness (both of the actor and partner), status, resource control, extended family, social capital, and mate value. Some examples of items are: ‘I visit my relatives frequently’, or ‘I am an active outdoors person’, which are actionable in therapy.
9
The CETD manual (Giosan, 2020) provides the evolutionary therapist with concrete examples of therapeutic interventions on each of the EFS items. For instance, a negative endorsement of the EFS item ‘I have at least one best friend’ should be dealt with by exploring the reasons and refuting dysfunctional thinking, as well as exploring modalities to increase connectedness with at least one non-relative. Likewise, a negative endorsement of the EFS item ‘My family brag about me’ should be dealt with by discussing solutions to increase status and dominance (e.g., more education if appropriate, job change, community involvement, etc.) (‘Darwinian Psychotherapy’, 2019; Giosan, 2020). As far as the therapeutic alliance is concerned, the CETD protocol advocates that the therapist go beyond the recommendations of interventions such as Rational Emotive Behavior Therapy – REBT (where the alliance is centered on unconditional acceptance, empathy, humor, and genuineness) or psychoanalysis (friendly neutrality) and try to become a patient’s psychological kin, while maintaining a safe set of boundaries (“Darwinian Psychotherapy,” 2019; Giosan, 2020). This approach is in line with the suggestions of other evolutionary psychopathologists, who emphasize rapport between the therapist and patient (Troisi and McGuire, 2014: 34), question the efficacy of one-hour-per-week therapy sessions (Gilbert et al., 2014: 19), or propose that depressed patients may even need ‘therapeutic cheerleading’ (Markowitz, 1994; Michels, 1997). While many evolutionary therapists argue for a stronger connection between the therapist and the depressed patient than the one advocated by other therapeutic paradigms, support for such an idea predates these recent developments in evolutionary psychotherapy. The early and fascinating work of Jerome Motto, who found that simply mailing personally signed ‘Caring Letters’ to people who had attempted suicide drastically reduced future suicide attempts, as people felt more
10
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
connected to the therapist communicating with them, illustrated the importance of therapeutic rapport (Motto, 1976). The ‘Caring Letters’ approach has been revised to include a form of intervention that essentially makes the therapist available almost continuously, and the results of this kin-like therapeutic relationship are promising. (For a detailed account of this project, including historical aspects, see James Cherkis’ (n.d.) excellent article in Huffington Post, https://bit.ly/2NqSWeC).
Evidence in Favor of CETD
for depression: Cognitive Therapy (CT; Beck et al., 1979). A total of 97 depressed patients received 12 sessions of either (1) CETD or (2) CT. Baseline, mid-treatment, post-treatment, and three-month follow-up assessments were conducted. The CT group underwent classical cognitive interventions aimed at the correction of dysfunctional, automatic thoughts and beliefs hypothesized to be implicated in depressive symptoms. These interventions were paired with behavioral activation and positive reinforcements. The CETD group added specific goals targeted at increasing fitness (see full protocol at Giosan, Cobeanu et al., 2014). Both interventions led to similar reductions in depressive symptomatology, as measured by the BDI-II (Beck et al., 1996), which were maintained at three-month follow-up. Although non-significant, the CETD group showed a consistent pattern of larger gains (greater decreases in BDI-II scores) during the treatment as well as post-treatment. Fewer CETD participants were classified as having moderate or severe depression over time, with between-group analyses showing trend differences at post-treatment. The results also showed that the CETD group experienced significantly greater reductions in behavioral inhibition/avoidance at both post-treatment and follow-up, compared with the CT group. Notably, CETD was also significantly superior to CT in increasing engagement in social and enjoyable activities at post-treatment. The study showed that in the participants receiving CETD, but not in those receiving CT, engagement in these activities was directly related to decreased symptoms of depression, suggesting that CETD leads to greater social reach, which, in turn, might translate into better therapeutic outcomes (Giosan, 2020; Giosan et al., 2019; Giosan, Cobeanu, Wyka, et al., 2020).
In a case study examining the potential benefits of CETD, Giosan, Muresan et al. (2014) used this protocol on a patient with an intake score of 22 on the BDI-II (Beck et al., 1996) and a diagnosis with depression made with the Structured Clinical Interview for the DSM (SCID) (First et al., 1997), who presented deteriorating functioning (school performance) and quality of life following a recent break-up. An assessment of her perceived fitness with the EFS (Giosan et al., 2018) revealed deficiencies in self-image, healthy eating habits, and physical activity. The patient was offered a cognitive-evolutionary conceptualization of her symptoms that centered on the distal causes of depression as well as on the dysfunctional cognitions that led to symptoms (Giosan, Muresan et al., 2014). The treatment focus was to engage the patient in the EFSsuggested fitness-increasing activities, while simultaneously challenging dysfunctional thinking. The treatment was successful, the patient achieving a ~68% reduction in the BDI-II (Beck et al., 1996) scores by session 8 (BDI-II = 7), therapeutic gains maintained at post-evaluation (BDI-II = 7) and follow-up (BDI-II = 13). A randomized, single-blinded active- controlled design (Giosan, Cobeanu, Wyka, et al., 2020; Giosan, Cobeanu et al., 2014) Personality Disorders expanded on this preliminary case study and contrasted the efficacy of CET for depression Personality disorders are typically perceived with one of the best validated interventions as difficult to address in therapy, with some
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND COUNSELING AND PSYCHOTHERAPY
of them, such as borderline personality disorder, being especially prone to de facto demedicalization (Sulzer, 2015). The evolutionary scholars Prunetti et al. (2013) developed a protocol for Cognitive Evolutionary Therapy specifically aimed at personality disorders (CET-PD). CET-PD is based on the Darwinian view that humans are driven by evolutionaryselected motivations and develop psychopathologies when their biologically relevant goals are not met. Thus, failures in patients with personality disorder are explained by the authors as resulting from disordered functioning of evolutionary-shaped social motives (Prunetti et al., 2013). The authors differentiate CET-PD from other treatments from which it borrows, such as Cognitive Therapy (Beck, 1976), Rational Emotive Therapy (Ellis and Dryden, 2007), and Dialectical Behavioral Therapy (Chapman, 2006).
Key Elements in CET-PD The key elements of CET-PD include: 1 Focus on restructuring schemas of self-with-others around biologically relevant needs (attachment, caregiving, social ranking, mating, cooperation). 2 Special focus on the therapeutic relationship. CET-PD places importance on the rapport between the therapist and patient, with special attention on discovering the specific motive that is active during the flow of therapy conversation. 3 Assessing interpersonal motivations during the therapeutic relationship (e.g., attachment or social rank). 4 Managing the therapeutic relationship to prevent/repair ruptures. 5 Making people aware of how dysfunctional schemas guide behaviors.
Evidence in Favor of CET-PD The authors examined the benefits of CET-PD in an intensive 20-hour weekly three-week residential treatment (both individual and group) of a wide range of severe personality disorders. Fifty-one patients with various
11
personality disorders were assessed at admission, discharge, and three-month follow-up and the outcome measures consisted of selfreported depression, anxiety, general symptoms, duration of inpatient admissions after the program was over, and continuation in an outpatient program. The results suggested that CET-PD was effective in reducing the level of depression and anxiety, with a change that was stable for trait anxiety. Obsessive symptoms, paranoid ideation, psychoses, and feelings of self-inadequacy and inferiority diminished. Overall, the results showed an improvement in psychopathology after release and in follow-up sessions, a decrease in the number of further hospital admissions, and an increased level of outpatient therapy attendance (Prunetti et al., 2013).
Potential Applications of Evolutionary Conceptualizations to Other Mental Conditions In the previous section, we reviewed the possible integration of evolutionary insights in psychoanalysis and analytical psychotherapy, and we summarized the results from controlled studies that examined the efficacy of evolutionary interventions for depression and personality disorders. In the next section, we briefly present, in a speculative manner that needs further testing in controlled trials, some potential applications of evolutionary conceptualizations to the treatment of other mental conditions.
Postpartum Depression Conceptualizing postpartum depression as an adapted response to unfavorable circumstances (e.g., child sickness, lack of resources or support) (Hagen, 1999), evolutionary mismatch (Crouch, 1999), or age (Bottino et al., 2012) may make a patient suffering from it more likely to recover. A treatment aimed at increasing fitness (e.g., by focusing on resource
12
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
acquisition) may be better than correcting dysfunctional beliefs (‘I am a bad mother’). From an evolutionary perspective, cognitive techniques could be tried to increase the perceived benefits of having a child and reduce the perceived costs. Such a strategy might lead to a decrease in the severity of postpartum depression precisely because it addresses evolutionary causes. For instance, a young mother could understand that her symptoms do not reflect her incapacity as a mother, but, rather, a mechanism by which she is asking for help. Thus, the intervention could focus on coping mechanisms and problem-solving targeting the fundamental causes of the symptoms, addressing not only the depressive symptoms per se, but also the situation that led to them (decreased fitness).
Anxiety Disorders By distinguishing between situations in which anxiety is disabling (when medication can be useful) and those where anxiety may be adaptive, evolutionary theories can offer meaningful case conceptualizations that can help patients to accept these symptoms and possibly reduce impairment. For instance, a debilitating phobia of snakes might be accepted and dealt with better by a patient if it is explained to her that fear of snakes is an evolved fear which increased the likelihood of survival in ancestral times (Marks and Nesse, 1994) and that her extreme anxiety around such stimuli is not a brain disorder, but an evolved, normal mechanism that may be functioning in overdrive. Similarly, in Obsessive Compulsive Disorder, conceptualizing the symptoms as exacerbated mechanisms to facilitate reproduction and protect offspring (Feygin et al., 2006) can lead to better acceptance of the symptoms, a key element in the recovery process (Chamberlain and Haaga, 2001). One of the most common forms of anxiety, social anxiety (SA), is particularly resistant to treatment, with only about half of
patients showing improvement, even when gold-standard treatments, such as CBT, are used (Loerinc et al., 2015). Conceptualizing SA as one of the poles (besides social dominance) necessary to maintain social order (Öhman, 1986), or as a vestigial response to social threat (Trower and Gilbert, 1989), may increase a patient’s acceptance of the symptoms. Moreover, evolutionary understandings of SA may serve as a guide in therapeutic decisions. For instance, in some cases, just treating symptoms (through gradual exposure, for instance) may not be enough, and a discussion about eliminating or modifying the circumstances that elicit symptoms may be in order (Brosnan et al., 2017). Providing patients with evolutionary explanations of phobic symptoms is not possible in all the cases, so only some patients will benefit from this kind of evolutionaryaided case conceptualization. This approach is suitable in the case of patients with fears of biologically relevant stimuli, such as heights, public speaking, dark, blood, or certain types of animals, who could benefit from logical distal explanations of the symptoms, and less so, if at all, in the case of patients presenting fears of evolutionaryirrelevant objects, such as a fear of cotton balls or certain colors. In other words, while evolutionary explanations of anxieties can be helpful in treatment, this does not mean a replacement of current explanations, which typically rely on either proximal causes or distant, but not evolutionary ones (e.g., childhood traumas). On the contrary, multi-layered explanations (evolutionary, developmental, proximal mechanisms) should be used, with evolutionary insights helping in the creation of a more comprehensive causal picture of the problems bothering a patient.
Dysmorphic Disorder Dysmorphic disorder is explained evolutionarily through one’s attempt to compare with
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND COUNSELING AND PSYCHOTHERAPY
others and the avoidance of rejection or ridicule, which are linked to lower status and lower mate value (Veale and Gilbert, 2014). Understanding the context and functions of the behaviors associated with this condition can be critical for the success of an intervention, especially when the patient has aversive emotions, such as shame or rejection, which have not been properly processed (Veale and Gilbert, 2014). Cognitive behavioral techniques for treating this condition could be improved through the analysis of the functions and contexts in which the behaviors appear. This can be realized via multiple routes, such as (1) linking the body-related fears to fears of rejection or to emotionally charged memories; (2) rewriting of the narrative; (3) providing an evolutionary context that separates the symptoms from the feelings of shame and the affected person; or (4) the direct targeting of the feelings of shame and self-criticism and the development of social skills through compassion (Veale and Gilbert, 2014).
Post-Traumatic Stress Disorder (PTSD) Evolutionary hypotheses of PTSD center on evolved mechanisms of avoiding dangers (Silove, 1998; Wiedenmayer, 2004). Once a person has been exposed to a traumatic event, they will automatically learn to avoid that type of situation, thus increasing their survival chances. In some vulnerable individuals, this learning can be excessive or hard to stop. While validated evolutionary interventions for PTSD have yet to be reported, the reinterpretation of PTSD symptoms as produced by adaptations to protect an individual from future harm, mechanisms that are found in other species as well (Zanette et al., 2019), can help patients to better understand and accept the condition and may improve the therapeutic benefits offered by validated interventions for PTSD, such as Gradual Exposure Therapy. Furthermore, some authors have found a link between life history
13
and PTSD (Giosan and Wyka, 2009), which might lead to novel, reproductive strategiesbased intervention protocols in the future.
Eating Disorders Evolutionary explanations of eating disorders center on intrasexual competition (Li et al., 2010) or on life-history strategy (Mehta et al., 2011). Such hypotheses can have clinical implications. As in the examples above, an understanding of the mechanisms that activate when we eat certain foods can be therapeutically helpful when the patient’s cognitions are addressed. In cognitive behavioral interventions, for instance, such explanations could facilitate the psychoeducational aspect of therapy and can also aid in the generation of alternative thoughts that are to replace the automatic, dysfunctional ones. Furthermore, the integration of evolutionary explanations of eating disorders in school curricula may put young people in a better position to understand human tendencies, which can then act as an important protective factor.
Substance Abuse Evolutionary explanations of substance dependence or abuse revolve around the fact that people have consumed psychoactive substances over our recent and ancestral history (Dudley, 2004; Sullivan and Hagen, 2002), with some authors arguing that drug consumption can be associated with fitness benefits (Kirillova et al., 2008). The mismatch between the past benefits associated with such behaviors and the easy access to such substances in our modern world can make some predisposed individuals consume them more, slowly driving them into addiction. Understanding the distal explanations of substance consumption might be useful in therapy, especially in the conceptualization phase of an intervention. In substance abuse, patients typically feel guilt and shame
14
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
(McGaffin et al., 2013). Evolutionary insights integrated into therapy could potentially reduce such reactions, deepening positive therapeutic outcomes.
APPLICATIONS OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY IN COUPLES THERAPY No section on the applications of evolutionary psychology to counseling and psychotherapy would be complete without a discussion about the many helpful elements that evolutionary psychology can bring to couples therapy. Since evolutionary psychology examines the processes that have helped our ancestors to survive and reproduce, it is evident that it can bring insights into problems typically encountered in couples, such as sexual incompatibilities, emotional and/or sexual infidelity, trust, gender stereotyping, or control. An important class of results generated by evolutionary psychology is that, when it comes to mating, men and women are hardwired somewhat differently and their strategies to reach a common biological goal – reproduction – can, at times, be quite different, which can be a source of conflict, potentially leading to the dissolution of the couple. Studies on heterosexual mating preferences have documented gender commonalities, such as dependability, faithfulness, and kindness (Barber, 1995; Buss, 1989; Buss et al., 1990) but also differences, in that women are more interested in earning capacity, while men are more interested in physical beauty and health cues (e.g., skin smoothness, waist-to-hip ratio) of their partners, with overlapping bell curves in such tendencies (Buss et al., 1990; Zhang et al., 2018). Because women require a minimum of nine months investment (pregnancy) in order to be successful at reproduction, and because they cannot have nearly as many children as a man can theoretically have, they have evolved to be the choosier sex (Hatfield
and Sprecher, 2016). In contrast, since men can impregnate a large number of women in a short period of time, they have evolved stronger preferences for pursuing short-term mating opportunities (Schmitt et al., 2003). Studies show a gender difference favoring men in the number of sexual partners (Todd et al., 2009) and other research has shown differences in sexual fantasies, with men being more likely to fantasize about sexual variety (Ellis and Symons, 1990). Other studies show that men are more permissive about casual sex and have a higher incidence of masturbation (Oliver and Hyde, 1993) and are more likely to be consumers of pornography (Hald, 2006), an element that has been linked to couple dissatisfaction (Stewart and Szymanski, 2012). Males’ stronger desire for multiple sexual partners comes with a substantial threat to marriage, especially since men are sometimes willing to leave their children behind for the pursuit of new relationships. Indeed, some authors have argued that men live in a state of ‘mild torment’ that stems from their propensity for sexual variety (Singer, 1985a, 1985b). It is evident that such deeply engrained feelings can have catastrophic consequences on a marriage or long-term relationship. Therapists must be aware of such mechanisms and address them in therapy in a non-judgmental manner, as treating these tendencies as a ‘disease’ or lack of character can destroy the therapeutic relationship. In addressing such issues, therapists must also be careful about balancing male needs and female needs. For instance, some authors have stated that promoting commitment in therapy may mean, in fact, promoting female reproductive interests at the expense of the male reproductive interests (Glantz and Moehl, 2000). Such realities can make men feel they are not understood, which can alter the therapeutic relationship. Offering explanations of the distal causes of the gender differences in sexual preferences is usually a good strategy to navigate through these issues in therapy and sometimes helping a man deal with his
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND COUNSELING AND PSYCHOTHERAPY
conflicts about commitment is better done in one-person therapy (Gilbert et al., 2014). Men’s stronger preferences for sexual variety are also linked to the so-called Coolidge effect, which is the sexual interest in a new female, even when the male has reached sexual satiation with his existing partner (Buss, 1994; Dewsbury, 1981; Glantz and Pearce, 1989). In humans, this phenomenon translates into greater interest for sex outside the pair and reduced interest for sex within the pair. This sexual boredom, affecting men and, also, women, but for different reasons, can undermine a relationship. Therapists who understand that sexual boredom is not reversible and that the passion of youth cannot be restored are in a much better position to help a couple in need of counseling (Glantz and Moehl, 2000). Moreover, since women, but not men, are always certain that their babies are theirs, men are faced with the uncertainty of paternity, which has led to gender differences in the experience of feelings of jealousy. Thus, women appear to be more affected by their partners’ emotional infidelity, whereas men are more affected by their partners’ sexual infidelity (Buss et al., 1992; Daly et al., 1982). This, in turn, makes women less likely to forgive emotional infidelity, and men less likely to forgive sexual infidelity (Shackelford et al., 2002). The issue of jealousy appears often in couples therapy and in many a case one of the partners adamantly accuses the other of ‘destroying the relationship’ by being too jealous. Indeed, strong feelings of jealousy can lead to controlling behaviors (e.g., controlling the partner’s social media accounts), verbal or physical violence, suspiciousness, isolation of the partner from family and friends, and lack of trust, which can undermine a relationship until its complete dissolution. Clinicians would be welladvised to use evolutionary insights in such situations and explain to their clients that jealousy is, at its most fundamental level, a universal mate-guarding strategy (Buss, 2000), which has helped us pass on our genes to the next generations, and that, barring
15
extreme manifestations, such as delusions, it is a normal evolved mechanism that we should not be ashamed of. Reinterpretation of jealousy as an adaptation that facilitates mate retention may aid in the therapeutic process. Understanding the important differences in sexual preferences and tendencies between men and women can help a couples therapist’s attempts to heal a fractured relationship. Some authors have argued that some of the fundamental principles of therapy, such as communication and sharing feelings, fail to take into account core male needs (Glantz and Moehl, 2000), potentially leading to the inefficiency of the interventions. Indeed, men’s and women’s relating styles are different (Winstead et al., 1997), which may make the former harder to engage in psychotherapy. Furthermore, the tabula rasa paradigm advocated by the Social Science Standard Model assumes no innate gender differences, which may lead to unreasonable therapeutic requests of males to reveal inner emotions and insecurities (Shem and Surrey, 1998), further damaging a potentially already fragile therapeutic relationship. Let’s not forget that studies have shown that women prefer confident men, who are able to protect their partners from other men (Buss, 1989). This can and will make a man reluctant to display signals of weakness and subordination both in front of his partner and in front of the therapist. Clinicians who understand these nuances well are in a better position to establish rapport – critical for good outcomes – with a male patient in couples therapy. For instance, since status is often a crucial factor for men, acknowledging it or working to increase it can be an effective therapeutic strategy (Glantz and Moehl, 2000). Similarly, framing interventions in concrete economic terms (costs/benefits/advantages), as opposed to the more vague ‘better’, can lead to positive therapeutic outcomes (Glantz and Moehl, 2000). Furthermore, given the fact that men are less likely to disclose emotions and feelings, encouraging communication and deep disclosure, especially about weaknesses, may be counter-productive in some cases and
16
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
outright destructive when the disclosure might reveal profound couple incompatibilities, such as sexual (Glantz and Moehl, 2000). When the issue of misuse of power, such as anger directed toward family members, comes up in therapy, some clinicians have argued that this can lead to shaming and the activation of self-defense mechanisms in male patients, and that reframing, in the sense of explaining what the function of competition among males is, may be a better therapeutic strategy, with the important observation that the therapist should not recommend that a man simply give in to his partner (Glantz and Moehl, 2000).
CRITICISM OF EVOLUTIONARY INTERVENTIONS In the previous sections, we succinctly presented some of the recent progress in the field of evolutionary interventions for certain mental disorders as well as possible applications of evolutionary insights in couples therapy. Despite these promising developments, we must note the fact that the evolutionary hypotheses of mental disorders are, for the most part, speculative and do not have strong empirical support yet. Generally, there is rivalry between hypotheses, with little movement toward consensus, as well as slow adoption by practitioners. In addition, while some of the progress made in evolutionary randomized clinical trials is noteworthy, it is very difficult to draw incontrovertible conclusions from medical-style randomized clinical trials in this field, except perhaps when they can be pooled in bulk as meta-analyses. Even then, it is hard to adjust for publication bias, unaccounted placebo effects, statistical phenomena, and other confounds (Westen et al., 2004). Another point of caution in evaluating the merits of evolutionary interventions is the fact that meta-analyses generally show that no particular theoretical approach performs
markedly better than the rest (Cuijpers et al., 2008; Miller et al., 2008; Smith and Glass, 1977), and there is no reason to believe that evolutionary therapies are any different. Indeed, the most influential factors apparently common to virtually all schools are the therapist’s technique and the rapport between client and therapist (Budge and Wampold, 2015). Since some evolutionary therapies (e.g., CETD, described earlier in this chapter), place, among others, a premium on the client/therapist relationship, further research should examine whether this emphasis might be differentially associated with therapeutic success. Last, but not least, the evolutionary interventions presented in this section have generally addressed specific mental disorders, but there is debate in the field whether they exist as ‘real’ natural conditions to begin with (First and Pincus, 2009). As such, more cross-diagnostic evolutionary interventions should be attempted and tested, since a therapy developed for a certain condition (e.g., depression) may well be efficient for a different one (e.g., anxiety or self-harm) (Wampold and Imel, 2015).
SUMMARY This chapter briefly presented some of the recent advances in clinical applications of evolutionary psychology. Progress has recently been made in incorporating evolutionary insights into psychological interventions for depression and personality disorders, with several randomized clinical trials supporting such approaches already completed. Treatments of other psychological problems, such as anxiety, substance abuse, and eating disorders, might also benefit from the inclusion of evolutionary understandings of symptoms, although such assumptions need to be tested in future controlled clinical studies. By offering distal explanations of sexual preferences, evolutionary psychology may
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND COUNSELING AND PSYCHOTHERAPY
also aid substantially in couples therapy. Issues like jealousy or infidelity can be better dealt with in couples therapy when they are interpreted through evolutionary lenses, potentially leading to better therapeutic alliance and outcomes. Despite these recent developments, much more research on the merits of such approaches should be conducted, as the unclear role of common factors in evolutionary therapies, the speculative nature of many evolutionary hypotheses of mental disorders, and the lack of controlled evolutionary trials on cross-diagnostic symptoms make it hard to draw definitive conclusions about the efficacy of such efforts.
Note 1 The ABC model proposes that emotions (C) are not caused by external events (A), but by beliefs (B) and, in particular, irrational beliefs (IB) (Sarracino et al., 2017). The ABC model can also be referred to as the ‘ABCDE’ model, where D stands for the disputation of beliefs and E stands for new effect, the result of holding healthier beliefs (Jorn, 2016).
REFERENCES Barber, N. (1995). The evolutionary psychology of physical attractiveness: Sexual selection and human morphology. Ethology and Sociobiology, 16(5), 395–424. https://doi.org/ 10.1016/0162-3095(95)00068-2 Beck, A. T. (1976). Cognitive therapy and the emotional disorders. New York, NY: International Universities Press. Beck, A. T., Rush, A. J., Shaw, B. F., & Emery, G. (1979). Cognitive therapy of depression. New York, NY: Guilford Press. Beck, A. T., Steer, A. R., & Brown, G. K. (1996). Manual for the Beck Depression Inventory—II. San Antonio, TX: The Psychological Corporation. Blumenthal, J. A., Babyak, M. A., Doraiswamy, P. M., Watkins, L., Hoffman, B. M., Barbour, K. A., & Sherwood, A. (2007). Exercise and
17
pharmacotherapy in the treatment of major depressive disorder. Psychosomatic Medicine, 69(7), 587–596. https://doi.org/10.1097/ PSY.0b013e318148c19a Bond, F. W., Hayes, S. C., Baer, R. A., Carpenter, K. M., Guenole, N., Orcutt, H. K., & Zettle, R. D. (2011). Preliminary psychometric properties of the Acceptance and Action Questionnaire–II: A revised measure of psychological inflexibility and experiential avoidance. Behavior Therapy, 42(4), 676–688. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.beth.2011.03.007 Botanov, Y., Keil, K., Ilardi, S. S., Scheller, V., Sharp, K. L., & Williams, C. L. (2012). Successful treatment of depression via therapeutic lifestyle change: Preliminary controlled-trial results. Poster presented at the Annual conference of the Association for Psychological Science. Retrieved from http://tlc.ku.edu/sites/ tlc.drupal.ku.edu/files/files/PosterAPS2012. pdf (Accessed 30 November 2018). Bottino, M. N., Nadanovsky, P., Moraes, C. L., Reichenheim, M. E., & Lobato, G. (2012). Reappraising the relationship between maternal age and postpartum depression according to the evolutionary theory: Empirical evidence from a survey in primary health services. Journal of Affective Disorders, 142(1), 219–224. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jad.2012.04.030 Bowlby, J. (1983). Attachment: Attachment and loss volume one (2nd edition). New York, NY: Basic Books. Bowlby, J. (2005). A secure base; Clinical applications of attachment theory (1st edition). London: Routledge. Brosnan, S. F., Tone, E. B., & Williams, L. (2017). The evolution of social anxiety. In T. K. Shackelford & V. Zeigler-Hill (Eds.), The Evolution of psychopathology (pp. 93–116). Springer: Switzerland. https://doi.org/10.1007/ 978-3-319-60576-0_4 Budge, S. L., & Wampold, B. E. (2015). The relationship: How it works. In O. C. G. Gelo, A. Pritz, & B. Rieken (Eds.), Psychotherapy research: Foundations, process, and outcome (pp. 213–228). Springer: Switzerland. https:// doi.org/10.1007/978-3-7091-1382-0_11 Buss, D. M. (1989). Sex differences in human mate preferences: Evolutionary hypotheses tested in 37 cultures. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 12(1), 1–14. https://doi.org/10.1017/ S0140525X00023992
18
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Buss, D. M. (1994). The evolution of desire: Strategies of human mating. New York, NY: Basic Books. Buss, D. M. (2000). The dangerous passion: Why jealousy is as necessary as love and sex. New York, NY: Free Press. Buss, D. M., Abbott, M., Angleitner, A., Asherian, A., Biaggio, A., Blanco-Villasenor, A., & Yang, K.-S. (1990). International preferences in selecting mates: A study of 37 cultures. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology, 21(1), 5–47. https://doi.org/10.1177/0022022190211001 Buss, D. M., Larsen, R. J., Westen, D., & Semmelroth, J. (1992). Sex differences in jealousy: Evolution, physiology, and psychology. Psychological Science, 3(4), 251–256. https://doi. org/10.1111/j.1467-9280.1992.tb00038.x Chamberlain, J. M., & Haaga, D. A. F. (2001). Unconditional self-acceptance and psychological health. Journal of Rational-Emotive and Cognitive-Behavior Therapy, 19(3), 163–176. https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1011189416600 Chapman, A. L. (2006). Dialectical behavior therapy. Psychiatry (Edgmont), 3(9), 62–68. Cherkis, J. (n.d.). The best way to save people from suicide. Retrieved January 28, 2019, from https://highline.huffingtonpost.com/articles/ en/how-to-help-someone-who-is-suicidal/ Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (1994). Origins of domain specificity: The evolution of functional organization. In L. Hirschfeld & S. Gelman (Eds.), Mapping the Mind: Domain Specificity in Cognition and Culture (pp. 85–116). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511752902.005 Crouch, M. (1999). The evolutionary context of postnatal depression. Human Nature, 10(2), 163–182. https://doi.org/10.1007/ s12110-999-1013-x Crow, T. J. (2000). Schizophrenia as the price that homo sapiens pays for language: A resolution of the central paradox in the origin of the species. Brain Research Reviews, 31(2–3), 118–129. Cuijpers, P., van Straten, A., Andersson, G., & van Oppen, P. (2008). Psychotherapy for depression in adults: A meta-analysis of comparative outcome studies. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology, 76(6), 909–922. https://doi.org/10.1037/a0013075 Daly, M., Wilson, M., & Weghorst, S. J. (1982). Male sexual jealousy. Ethology and Sociobi-
ology, 3(1), 11–27. https://doi.org/ 10.1016/0162-3095(82)90027-9 Darwinian Psychotherapy. (2019). Retrieved January 23, 2019, from https://darwinianpsychotherapy.com Dewsbury, D. A. (1981). Effects of novelty of copulatory behavior: The Coolidge effect and related phenomena. Psychological Bulletin, 89(3), 464–482. https://doi.org/10.1037/ 0033-2909.89.3.464 Dudley, R. (2004). Ethanol, fruit ripening, and the historical origins of human alcoholism in primate frugivory. Integrative and Comparative Biology, 44(4), 315–323. https://doi.org/ 10.1093/icb/44.4.315 Durisko, Z., Mulsant, B. H., & Andrews, P. W. (2015). An adaptationist perspective on the etiology of depression. Journal of Affective Disorders, 172, 315–323. https://doi.org/ 10.1016/j.jad.2014.09.032 Ellis, A. (1994). Reason and emotion in psychotherapy. Secaucus, NJ: Carol Publishing Group. Ellis, A., & Dryden, W. (2007). The practice of rational emotive behavior therapy (2nd edition). New York, NY: Springer Publishing Company. Ellis, A., Dryden, W., & DiGiuseppe, R. (2007). The practice of rational emotive behavior therapy. New York, NY: Springer Publishing Company. Ellis, B. J., & Symons, D. (1990). Sex differences in sexual fantasy: An evolutionary psychological approach. The Journal of Sex Research, 27(4), 527–555. https://doi.org/10.1080/ 00224499009551579 Fennell, M. J., & Teasdale, J. D. (1987). Cognitive therapy for depression: Individual differences and the process of change. Cognitive Therapy and Research, 11(2), 253–271. https://doi. org/10.1007/BF01183269 Feygin, D. L., Swain, J. E., & Leckman, J. F. (2006). The normalcy of neurosis: Evolutionary origins of obsessive–compulsive disorder and related behaviors. Progress in Neuro- Psychopharmacology and Biological Psychiatry, 30(5), 854–864. https://doi.org/10.1016/ j.pnpbp.2006.01.009 First, M. B., & Pincus, H. A. (2009). Diagnosis and classification. In M. G. Gelder, N. C. Adreasen, J. J. Lopez-Ibor, & J. R. Geddes (Eds.), New Oxford Textbook of Psychiatry
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND COUNSELING AND PSYCHOTHERAPY
(pp. 99–121). Oxford: Oxford University Press. First, M. B., Spitzer, R. L., Williams, J. B. W., & Gibbon, M. (1997). Structured clinical interview for DSM-IV SCID. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. Fraser, B. (2012). Costly signalling theories: Beyond the handicap principle. Biology & Philosophy, 27(2), 263–278. https://doi.org/ 10.1007/s10539-011-9297-8 Freud, S. (2017). The interpretation of dreams (A. A. Brill, Trans.). Digireads.com Publishing. George, L. K. (1989). Stress, social support, and depression over the life-course. In K. S. Markides & C. L. Cooper (Eds.), Aging, stress and health (p. 241–267). John Wiley & Sons. Gilbert, P. (2001). Evolution and social anxiety: The role of attraction, social competition, and social hierarchies. Psychiatric Clinics, 24(4), 723–751. https://doi.org/10.1016/ S0193-953X(05)70260-4 Gilbert, P., Bailey, K. G., & McGuire, M. T. (2014). Evolutionary psychotherapy: Principles and outline. In P. Gilbert & K. G. Bailey (Eds.), Genes on the couch: Explorations in evolutionary psychotherapy (pp. 3–27). New York, NY: Routledge. Giosan, C. (2020). Cognitive-Evolutionary Therapy for Depression. Springer, Switzerland, https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-38874-4 Giosan, C., Cobeanu, O., Mogoase, C., Muresan, V., Malta, L. S., Wyka, K., & Szentagotai, A. (2014). Evolutionary cognitive therapy versus standard cognitive therapy for depression: A protocol for a blinded, randomized, superiority clinical trial. Trials, 15(1), 83. https://doi.org/10.1186/1745-6215-15-83 Giosan, C., Cobeanu, O., Wyka, K., Muresan, V., Mogoase, C., Szentagotai, A., & Moldovan, R. (2019, June 29). Cognitive-evolutionary therapy for depression – results of a randomized clinical trial. Presented at the 31st Annual Human Behavior & Evolution Society Meeting, Boston, MA. Retrieved from http://meetatbu. com/hbes19/ (Accessed 1 September 2019). Giosan, C., Cobeanu, O., Wyka, K., Muresan, V., Mogoase, C., Szentagotai, A., Malta, L. S., Moldovan, R. (2020). Cognitive evolutionary therapy versus standard cognitive therapy for depression: A single‐blinded randomized clinical trial. Journal of Clinical Psychology; 1–14. https://doi.org/10.1002/jclp.22991
19
Giosan, C., Muresan, V., & Moldovan, R. (2014). Cognitive evolutionary therapy for depression: A case study. Clinical Case Reports, 2(5), 228–236. https://doi.org/ 10.1002/ccr3.131 Giosan, C., & Wyka, K. (2009). Is a successful high-K fitness strategy associated with better mental health? Evolutionary Psychology, 7(1), 28–39. https://doi.org/10.1177/ 147470490900700104 Giosan, C., Wyka, K., Mogoaşe, C., Cobeanu, O., & Szentagotai, A. (2018). The Evolutionary Fitness scale: A measure of the independent criterion of fitness. EvoS Journal: The Journal of the Evolutionary Studies Consortium, 7(1), 181–205. Giphart, R., & van Vugt, M. (2018). Mismatch: How our stone age brain deceives us every day (and what we can do about it). London: Robinson. Glantz, K., & Moehl, M.-B. (2000). Reluctant males: Evolutionary perspectives on male psychology in couples therapy. In P. Gilbert & K. G. Bailey (Eds.), Genes on the couch: Explorations in evolutionary psychotherapy (pp. 176–195). New York: Routledge. Glantz, K., & Pearce, J. (1989). Exiles from Eden: Psychotherapy from an evolutionary perspective (1st edition). New York, NY: W. W. Norton & Co. Inc. Glenn, A. L., Kurzban, R., & Raine, A. (2011). Evolutionary theory and psychopathy. Aggression and Violent Behavior, 16(5), 371–380. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.avb.2011.03.009 Gutiérrez, F., Gárriz, M., Peri, J. M., Ferraz, L., Sol, D., Navarro, J. B., & Valdés, M. (2013). Fitness costs and benefits of personality disorder traits. Evolution and Human Behavior, 34(1), 41–48. https://doi.org/10.1016/ j.evolhumbehav.2012.09.001 Hagen, E. H. (1999). The functions of postpartum depression. Evolution and Human Behavior, 20(5), 325–359. https://doi.org/ 10.1016/S1090-5138(99)00016-1 Hald, G. M. (2006). Gender differences in pornography consumption among young heterosexual Danish adults. Archives of Sexual Behavior, 35(5), 577–585. https://doi.org/ 10.1007/s10508-006-9064-0 Hatfield, E., & Sprecher, S. (1995). Men’s and Women’s Preferences in Marital Partners in the United States, Russia, and Japan. Journal of
20
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Cross-Cultural Psychology, 26(6), 728–750. https://doi.org/10.1177/002202219502600613 Hertler, S. C. (2014). A review and critique of obsessive-compulsive personality disorder etiologies. Europe’s Journal of Psychology, 10(1), 168–184. https://doi.org/10.5964/ ejop.v10i1.679 Jacobson, J. D., Lehman, K. A., Stites, B. A., Karwoski, L., Stroupe, N., Steidtmann, D., & Ilardi, S. (2007). Therapeutic lifestyle change for depression: Results of a randomized controlled trial. Presented at the Annual conference of the Association for Behavioral and Cognitive Therapies, Philadelphia, PA. Retrieved from http://tlc.ku.edu/sites/tlc. drupal.ku.edu/files/files/2007ABCTPoster.pdf (September 1 2018). John, S., & Segal, D.L. (2015). Case Conceptualization. In R.L. Cautin & S.O. Lilienfeld (Eds.), The Encyclopedia of Clinical Psychology. Chichester: Wiley. doi:10.1002/ 9781118625392.wbecp106 Jorn, A. (2016, May 17). Rational emotive behavior therapy. Retrieved November 10, 2019, from //psychcentral.com/lib/rationalemotive-behavior-therapy/ Karwoski, L., Prohaska, J. A., Lehman, K. A., Stites, B. A., Steidtmann, D., & Ilardi, S. S. (2005). Therapeutic Lifestyle Change (TLC) For Depression: Initial Results with a Severely Depressed Outpatient Population. Poster presented at the annual meeting of the American Psychological Association, Washington, D.C., August 18–21, 2005. Kirillova, G. P., Vanyukov, M. M., Kirisci, L., & Reynolds, M. (2008). Physical maturation, peer environment, and the ontogenesis of substance use disorders. Psychiatry Research, 158(1), 43–53. https://doi.org/10.1016/j. psychres.2007.02.017 Kriegman, D. (1998). Interpretation, the unconscious, and psychoanalytic authority: Toward an evolutionary, biological integration of the empirical/scientific method with the fielddefining, empathic stance. In R. F. Bornstein & J. M. Masling (Eds.), Empirical perspectives on the psychoanalytic unconscious (pp. 187–272). Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. Kriegman, D. (2000). Evolutionary psychoanalysis: Toward an adaptive, biological perspective on the clinical process in psychoanalytic
psychotherapy. In P. Gilbert & K. G. Bailey (Eds.), Genes on the couch: Explorations in evolutionary psychotherapy (pp. 71–92). New York, NY: Routledge. Krupnik, V. (2014). A novel therapeutic frame for treating depression in group Treating Depression Downhill. Sage Open, 4(1), 2158244014523793. https://doi.org/ 10.1177/2158244014523793 Krupnik, V. (2015). Integrating EMDR into an evolutionary-based therapy for depression: A case study. Clinical Case Reports, 3(5), 301–307. https://doi.org/10.1002/ ccr3.228 Krupnik, V. (2018). Differential effects of an evolutionary-based EMDR therapy on depression and anxiety symptoms: A case series study. Journal of EMDR Practice and Research, 12(2), 46–57. https://doi.org/ 10.1891/1933-3196.12.2.46 Kuyken, W., Padesky, C. A., & Dudley, R. (2008). The science and practice of case conceptualization. Behavioural and Cognitive Psychotherapy, 36(6), 757–768. https://doi.org/ 10.1017/S1352465808004815 Lam, D., & Gale, J. (2000). Cognitive behaviour therapy: Teaching a client the ABC model – the first step towards the process of change. Journal of Advanced Nursing, 31(2), 444–451. https://doi.org/10.1046/j.1365-2648. 2000.01280.x Li, N. P., Smith, A. R., Griskevicius, V., Cason, M. J., & Bryan, A. (2010). Intrasexual competition and eating restriction in heterosexual and homosexual individuals. Evolution and Human Behavior, 31(5), 365–372. https://doi. org/10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2010.05.004 Loerinc, A. G., Meuret, A. E., Twohig, M. P., Rosenfield, D., Bluett, E. J., & Craske, M. G. (2015). Response rates for CBT for anxiety disorders: Need for standardized criteria. Clinical Psychology Review, 42, 72–82. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cpr.2015.08.004 Markowitz, J. C. (1994). Psychotherapy of dysthymia. The American Journal of Psychiatry, 151(8), 1114–1121. https://doi.org/10.1176/ ajp.151.8.1114 Marks, I. F. M., & Nesse, R. M. (1994). Fear and fitness: An evolutionary analysis of anxiety disorders. Ethology and Sociobiology, 15(5), 247–261. https://doi.org/10.1016/01623095(94)90002-7
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND COUNSELING AND PSYCHOTHERAPY
Martiny, K., Lunde, M., Undén, M., Dam, H., & Bech, P. (2005). Adjunctive bright light in non-seasonal major depression: Results from clinician-rated depression scales. Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica, 112(2), 117–125. https:// doi.org/10.1111/j.1600-0447.2005.00574.x Mayers, A. G., & Baldwin, D. S. (2006). The relationship between sleep disturbance and depression. International Journal of Psychiatry in Clinical Practice, 10(1), 2–16. https://doi.org/ 10.1080/13651500500328087 McGaffin, B. J., Lyons, G. C. B., & Deane, F. P. (2013). Self-forgiveness, shame, and guilt in recovery from drug and alcohol problems. Substance Abuse, 34(4), 396–404. https:// doi.org/10.1080/08897077.2013.781564 McGuire, M., & Troisi, A. (1998). Darwinian psychiatry. Retrieved from www.oxfordclinicalpsych.com/view/10.1093/med:psych/ 9780195116731.001.0001/med9780195116731 (Accessed 1 September 2019). Mehta, S., Abed, R., Figueredo, A. J., Aldridge, S., Balson, H., Meyer, C., & Palmer, R. (2011). P02-113 – Eating disorders and intrasexual competition: Testing an evolutionary hypothesis among young women. European Psychiatry, 26, 709. https://doi.org/10.1016/ S0924-9338(11)72414-2 Michels, R. (1997). Psychotherapeutic approaches to the treatment of anxiety and depressive disorders. The Journal of Clinical Psychiatry, 58(Suppl 13), 30–32. Miller, S., Wampold, B., & Varhely, K. (2008). Direct comparisons of treatment modalities for youth disorders: A meta-analysis. Psychotherapy Research: Journal of the Society for Psychotherapy Research, 18(1), 5–14. https:// doi.org/10.1080/10503300701472131 Molina, J. D., López-Muñoz, F., Stein, D. J., Martín-Vázquez, M. J., Alamo, C., LermaCarrillo, I., & Calle-Real, M. de la. (2009). Borderline personality disorder: A review and reformulation from evolutionary theory. Medical Hypotheses, 73(3), 382–386. https:// doi.org/10.1016/j.mehy.2009.03.024 Motto, J. A. (1976). Suicide prevention for high-risk persons who refuse treatment. Suicide & Life-Threatening Behavior, 6(4), 223–230. Nesse, R. M. (1991). What good is feeling bad? The Sciences, 31(6), 30–37. https://doi. org/10.1002/j.2326-1951.1991.tb02346.x
21
Nesse, R. M. (1998). Emotional disorders in evolutionary perspective. British Journal of Medical Psychology, 71(4), 397–415. https://doi.org/ 10.1111/j.2044-8341.1998.tb01000.x Öhman, A. (1986). Presidential address: Face the beast and fear the face: Animal and social fears as prototypes for evolutionary analyses of emotions. Psychophysiology, 23, 737–747. Oliver, M. B., & Hyde, J. S. (1993). Gender differences in sexuality: A meta-analysis. Psychological Bulletin, 114(1), 29–51. O’Reilly, T., Dunbar, R., & Bentall, R. (2001). Schizotypy and creativity: An evolutionary connection? Personality and Individual Differences, 31(7), 1067–1078. https://doi.org/ 10.1016/S0191-8869(00)00204-X Peet, M., & Horrobin, D. F. (2002). A doseranging study of the effects of ethyl- eicosapentaenoate in patients with ongoing depression despite apparently adequate treatment with standard drugs. Archives of General Psychiatry, 59(10), 913–919. Prunetti, E., Bosio, V., Bateni, M., & Liotti, G. (2013). Three-week inpatient Cognitive Evolutionary Therapy (CET) for patients with personality disorders: Evidence of effectiveness in symptoms reduction and improved treatment adherence. Psychology and Psychotherapy: Theory, Research and Practice, 86(3), 262–279. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.2044-8341. 2011.02060.x Sarracino, D., Dimaggio, G., Ibrahim, R., Popolo, R., Sassaroli, S., & Ruggiero, G. M. (2017). When REBT goes difficult: Applying ABC-DEF to personality disorders. Journal of Rational-Emotive & Cognitive-Behavior Therapy, 35(3), 278–295. https://doi.org/10.1007/ s10942-016-0258-7 Schmitt, D. P., Alcalay, L., Allik, J., Ault, L., Austers, I., Bennett, K. L., & International Sexuality Description Project. (2003). Universal sex differences in the desire for sexual variety: Tests from 52 nations, 6 continents, and 13 islands. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 85(1), 85–104. Shackelford, T. K., Buss, D. M., & Bennett, K. (2002). Forgiveness or breakup: Sex differences in responses to a partner’s infidelity. Cognition and Emotion, 16(2), 299–307. https://doi.org/10.1080/02699930143000202 Shapiro, F. (2017). Eye Movement Desensitization and Reprocessing (EMDR) therapy, third
22
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
edition: Basic principles, protocols, and procedures (3rd edition). New York, NY: The Guilford Press. Shem, S., & Surrey, J. (1998). We have to talk: Healing dialogues between women and men. New York, NY: Basic Books. Silove, D. (1998). Is posttraumatic stress disorder an overlearned survival response? An evolutionary-learning hypothesis. Psychiatry, 61(2), 181–190. Singer, B. (1985a). A comparison of evolutionary and environmental theories of erotic response part I: Structural features. The Journal of Sex Research, 21(3), 229–257. https://doi.org/ 10.1080/00224498509551265 Singer, B. (1985b). A comparison of evolutionary and environmental theories of erotic response part II: Empirical arenas. The Journal of Sex Research, 21(4), 345–374. https://doi.org/ 10.1080/00224498509551275 Smith, M. L., & Glass, G. V. (1977). Meta-analysis of psychotherapy outcome studies. American Psychologist, 32(9), 752–760. https://doi. org/10.1037/0003-066X.32.9.752 Stevens, A. (1982). Archetype: A natural history of the self. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Stevens, A. (1999). On Jung: Updated edition (Updated, Subsequent edition). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Stevens, A. (2000). Jungian analysis and evolutionary psychotherapy: An integrative approach. In P. Gilbert & K. G. Bailey (Eds.), Genes on the couch: Explorations in evolutionary psychotherapy (pp. 93–117). New York, NY: Routledge. Stewart, D. N., & Szymanski, D. M. (2012). Young adult women’s reports of their male romantic partner’s pornography use as a correlate of their self-esteem, relationship quality, and sexual satisfaction. Sex Roles, 67(5), 257–271. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11199-012-0164-0 Sullivan, R. J., & Hagen, E. H. (2002). Psychotropic substance-seeking: Evolutionary pathology or adaptation? Addiction, 97(4), 389–400. Sulzer, S. H. (2015). Does ‘difficult patient’ status contribute to de facto demedicalization? The case of borderline personality disorder. Social Science & Medicine, 142, 82–89. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.socscimed. 2015.08.008 Sundie, J. M., Kenrick, D. T., Griskevicius, V., Tybur, J. M., Vohs, K. D., & Beal, D. J. (2011).
Peacocks, Porsches, and Thorstein Veblen: Conspicuous consumption as a sexual signaling system. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 100(4), 664–680. https://doi.org/ 10.1037/a0021669 Taljaard, T. (n.d.). Treating depression with tribal wisdom. Retrieved January 23, 2019, from https://upliftconnect.com/treatingdepression-with-tribal-wisdom/ Todd, J., Cremin, I., McGrath, N., Bwanika, J.-B., Wringe, A., Marston, M., & Żaba, B. (2009). Reported number of sexual partners: Comparison of data from four African longitudinal studies. Sexually Transmitted Infections, 85(Suppl 1), i72–i80. https://doi.org/10.1136/ sti.2008.033985 Troisi, A., & McGuire, M. T. (2000). Psychotherapy in the context of Darwinian psychiatry. In P. Gilbert & K. G. Bailey (Eds.), Genes on the couch: Explorations in evolutionary psychotherapy (pp. 28–41). Brunner-Routledge. Retrieved from http://psycnet.apa.org/ record/2001-16368-000 Trower, P., & Gilbert, P. (1989). New theoretical conceptions of social anxiety and social phobia. Clinical Psychology Review, 9(1), 19–35. Veale, D., & Gilbert, P. (2014). Body dysmorphic disorder: The functional and evolutionary context in phenomenology and a compassionate mind. Journal of Obsessive-Compulsive and Related Disorders, 3(2), 150–160. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jocrd.2013.11.005 Wampold, B. E., & Imel, Z. E. (2015). The great psychotherapy debate: The evidence for what makes psychotherapy work (2nd edition). New York, NY: Routledge/Taylor & Francis Group. Westen, D., Novotny, C. M., & Thompson- Brenner, H. (2004). The empirical status of empirically supported psychotherapies: Assumptions, findings, and reporting in controlled clinical trials. Psychological Bulletin, 130(4), 631–663. https://doi.org/10.1037/ 0033-2909.130.4.631 Wiedenmayer, C. P. (2004). Adaptations or pathologies? Long-term changes in brain and behavior after a single exposure to severe threat. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews, 28(1), 1–12. https://doi. org/10.1016/j.neubiorev.2003.09.005 Williams, P. (2005). ‘Notes Upon a Case of Obsessional Neurosis’. In R. J. Perelberg (Ed.), Freud: A modern reader (pp. 177–188).
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND COUNSELING AND PSYCHOTHERAPY
Routledge: NY https://doi.org/10.1002/ 9780470713525.ch10. Winstead, B. A., Derlega, V. J., & Rose, S. (1997). Gender and close relationships. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Zanette, L. Y., Hobbs, E. C., Witterick, L. E., MacDougall-Shackleton, S. A., & Clinchy, M. (2019). Predator-induced fear causes PTSDlike changes in the brains and behaviour of
23
wild animals. Scientific Reports, 9(1), 1–10. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41598-019-47684-6 Zhang, L., Lee, A. J., DeBruine, L. M., & Jones, B. C. (2018, December 4). Are sex differences in preferences for physical attractiveness and good earning capacity in potential mates smaller in countries with greater gender equality?. https://doi.org/10.31234/ osf.io/mtsx8
2 Evolutionary Psychology and Psychiatry Riadh Abed and Paul St John-Smith
INTRODUCTION Psychiatry is a branch of medicine that deals with mental disorders that manifest themselves through disturbances in cognition, emotions, and behaviour. Like the rest of medicine but unlike psychology (with the exception of clinical psychology), psychiatry is an interventionist discipline that aims to modify the signs and symptoms of disorder in order to reduce/ relieve individual distress and reduce risk (harm) to the individual and/or others. The contemporary failure of psychiatry to make significant progress in understanding the aetiology of mental disorders has been characterized as a ‘crisis’ by leading evolutionists (Brune et al., 2012); a fact that has also been acknowledged in an article in ‘Science’ that stated that there have been no major breakthroughs in the treatment of schizophrenia for 50 years nor in the treatment of depression for 20 years (Akil et al., 2010). Mainstream psychiatry, like the rest of medicine, focuses on proximate causation
and favours mechanistic explanations of disease and disorder. However, unlike medicine where human physiology provides clear reference points for normal functioning, psychiatry has attempted to identify disorder and dysfunction without a coherent theory of normal human psychology (Nesse, 2019). We argue in this chapter that evolutionary psychology and evolutionary biology can serve as a vital basic science for psychiatry. Despite the publication of notable evolutionary psychiatry texts over the last couple of decades as well as numerous scholarly articles in peer-reviewed journals, evolutionary thinking has remained underappreciated by mainstream psychiatry (e.g. Brune, 2015; Del Giudice, 2018; McGuire and Troisi, 1998; Nesse, 2019; Stevens and Price, 2000a). Although a pluralistic and multi-level approach to causality in mental health remains essential (Kendler, 2008), the current pluralism is unconstrained and lacks any recognizable framework (Abed, 2000). While it is recognized that all mental phenomena are mediated by physical events
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND PSYCHIATRY
in the brain, the phenotypic end-products of interest to psychiatry cannot be understood by examining the behaviour of neurons alone (a situation compared to trying to understand the mechanics of bird flight through the study of feathers (Marr, 1982)). We propose evolution as being ideally placed to guide psychiatrists in determining what the phenotypic end-products of neurobiological systems constitute. Such evolutionary emphasis on function can provide the scientific basis for expanding the concept of the biological to encompass the psychological, social, and cultural domains (Abed and St John-Smith, 2016). Hence, in contrast with mainstream biological psychiatry’s narrow ‘decontextualized’ view of mental disorder as brain disorder (Andreasen, 1984), evolutionists consider the environmental context to be vital in determining the existence of mental disorder (Nesse, 2019).
THE CONCEPT OF MENTAL DISORDER Despite its widespread adoption within psychiatry and medicine generally, the concept of disorder has been difficult to define with precision (Nesse, 2001). One influential evolutionary proposal is that mental disorder represents a hybrid concept, with a biological and a socio-cultural component; a ‘harmful dysfunction’ (HD) (Wakefield, 1992). Accordingly, the biological component of any disorder is the failure of a biological mechanism to perform its evolved function, and the value-laden component identifies that the dysfunction inflicts harm or damage on the affected individual as judged by socio-cultural standards. Although Wakefield’s HD concept has been subject to criticism (e.g. Bolton, 2007; Fulford and Thornton, 2007), it is acknowledged to be a significant improvement on existing formulations (e.g. First, 2007; Nesse, 2007). However, while the biological criterion of the failure of a system to perform its evolved function is intellectually
25
appealing, having considerable face validity, problems with its clinical utility linger because our understanding of the function of the neurobiological systems involved in mental disorder remains poor (First, 2007). In addition, whereas the emphasis on context is acknowledged to be important or even vital in determining the existence of mental disorder (Nesse, 2007), this potentially reduces the diagnostic inter-rater reliability subsequent to the increased scope of subjective judgement, generating concern for the authors of official classification systems such as the DSM-5 (American Psychiatric Association, 2013). Hence, while the DSM-5 accepts mental disorders necessarily involve internal dysfunction and that this produces harm and/or distress, it leaves the term ‘dysfunction’ undefined. Furthermore, whereas context is considered in a range of conditions, it is excluded in others. For example, in the DSM-5, unlike its predecessors, low mood lasting longer than two weeks can now be diagnosed as major depressive disorder (MDD) following a major bereavement (Kavan and Barone, 2014). Del Giudice (2018) submits that a number of facets must be recognized to avoid common errors in interpreting Wakefield’s HD concept, including the fact that dysfunctions can arise from a number of different causes, both internal and external; that the concept of dysfunction is fuzzy; and that systems can have degrees of functionality where the line of demarcation between function and dysfunction is unclear. While there are undoubted benefits from an evolutionary analysis of the concept of mental disorder, we support Troisi’s (2015) conclusion that evolutionary biology alone does not resolve the central question of what should (and should not) be categorized as a mental disorder, as ethical, health, and social policy considerations lie outside the remit of evolutionary science. In other words, it is important not only to appreciate how evolutionary biology can help advance our understanding of mental disorder but also to understand its limits.
26
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
THE REMIT OF PSYCHIATRY In addition to the DSM-5, the other major classification system of mental disorders in clinical use throughout most of the world, outside the United States, is the ICD-10 issued by the World Health Organization (WHO, 1992). Both systems endeavour to follow an atheoretical approach to the definition and differentiation of mental disorder and, with the exception of organic mental disorders, base their diagnostic categories broadly on symptom clusters and duration. Context is acknowledged in some instances. The ICD-10 definition of mental disorder, being more succinct than that of the DSM, omits the assumption of an internal dysfunction, and proceeds as follows: ‘a clinically recognizable set of symptoms or behaviours associated in most cases with distress and with interference with personal functioning’ (WHO, 1992: 11). Their main categories of adult mental disorder comprise organic mental disorders, mental disorders secondary to psychoactive substance use, schizophrenia and related disorders, mood disorders, anxiety and stressrelated disorders, behavioural syndromes associated with physiological disturbances, and personality and other behaviour disorders. Other chapters deal with mental retardation, developmental disorders, and mental disorders of childhood and adolescence. Remarkably, given that both the ICD and DSM are systems based on the consensus of committees, these categorical domains continue to demarcate effectively the current boundaries of psychiatric practice (Nesse and Stein, 2012). Nevertheless, criticism remains directed against both systems for increasing reliability at the expense of validity (Insel, 2013). The National Institute of Mental Health in the United States, in an attempt to overcome these shortcomings, proposed the Research Diagnostic Criteria (RDoC). The four principles used to formulate the RDoC system were explained as follows (Insel, 2013): • A diagnostic approach based on the biology as well as the symptoms must not be constrained by the current DSM categories;
• Mental disorders are biological disorders involving brain circuits that implicate specific domains of cognition, emotion, or behaviour; • Each level of analysis needs to be understood across a dimension of function; and • Mapping the cognitive, circuit, and genetic aspects of mental disorders will yield new and better targets for treatment.
The RDoC approach is rooted in experimental neuroscience and lists five domains: positive valance systems, negative valence systems, cognitive systems, systems for social processes, and arousal and regulatory systems. Each system has a number of constructs and these are investigated using a number of units of analysis ranging from the molecular level to individual behaviour. The RDoC has been characterized as a bottom-up approach to the classification of mental disorders, grounded in the latest research in biological sciences that can cut across existing DSM/ICD categories (Del Giudice, 2018). However, critics have raised concerns regarding the neglect of context (above and beyond the DSM or ICD) and neglect of the role of evolution (Wakefield, 2014).
EVOLUTION AND CAUSALITY The application of evolutionary thinking to psychiatry commences by considering some general principles that apply to all biological phenomena. Tinbergen (1963) proposed that a complete understanding of any biological trait or system involves understanding its mechanism, developmental history (collectively referred to as proximate causes), phylogenetic history, and function (referred to as ultimate or evolutionary causes) (Table 2.1). These are referred to as Tinbergen’s four questions and all four apply simultaneously to biological phenomena (Gluckman et al., 2009). It is acknowledged that unlike proximate causation which can directly lead to therapeutic interventions, understanding evolutionary or ultimate causation is somewhat
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND PSYCHIATRY
27
Table 2.1 Tinbergen’s four questions Proximate causation Evolutionary or ultimate causation
Developmental/historical 1. Ontogeny: how does the trait develop during the lifetime of the organism? 3. Phylogeny: what is the phylogenetic history of the trait?
Characteristics of trait/system 2. Mechanism: how does it work? 4. Adaptive function: How has the trait or system contributed to the organism’s inclusive fitness in its natural environment?
Source: Adapted from Nesse (2013).
removed from direct clinical applications but is no less important. Neglecting the question of function (ultimate causation) runs the risk of psychiatrists inadvertently altering psychological functioning through their interventions to relieve distressing but adaptive states, leading to potentially negative consequences for some patients. It can also lead us to construct defective models of how psychopathology arises. Focusing exclusively on the proximate is akin to a technician’s view of a machine, whereas considering ultimate causation as well is more like an engineer’s view (Nesse, 2019). Hence, it may seem adequate for a busy clinician to simply recognize the existence of depression or anxiety in a given patient and to dispense standard advice and treatment accordingly. However, a clinician who also understands why we have such emotions in the first place and how emotional systems interact with people’s current lives is likely to have a deeper understanding of the patient’s emotional problems and is able to take greater account of the patient’s circumstances that may be contributing to their current state. It also has the potential for influencing the research agenda through testing hypotheses regarding what the normal function is of the system that is giving rise to psychopathology; a question that is seldom asked by mainstream psychiatry (Brune, 2015).
CAUSAL PATHWAYS FOR THE PERSISTENCE OF DISEASE AND DISORDER It is obligatory to recognize that selection shapes vulnerability to disease and disorder
and not disorders themselves (Nesse, 2019). This applies throughout medicine, including psychiatry, and stems primarily from the demonstration that bodies and brains are a bundle of adaptations shaped by selection over thousands of generations to increase reproductive success and not good health, happiness, or longevity. The answer to the pivotal conundrum of why evolution has left humans so vulnerable to disease and disorder has itself been evolving ever since it was first posed by the founders of modern evolutionary medicine (Nesse and Williams, 1994). Accordingly, pathways by which evolutionary processes can lead to the existence and persistence of disease or disorder have been proposed (Box 2.1). These causal pathways are not mutually exclusive and several may be implicated concurrently or sequentially in the origin of mental disorders. They represent a list of ultimate causes of our vulnerability to mental disorder. Examples of many of these causal pathways will be given in the sections below. These evolutionary explanations for vulnerability to disorder are based on the recognition that selection is unable to eliminate all harmful mutations, and can be too slow to respond to rapidly changing environments, creating states of evolutionary mismatch (Del Giudice, 2018). This concept of ‘mismatch’ is crucial for understanding and explaining the existence of many diseases and disorders of modernity such as obesity, metabolic syndrome, Type 2 diabetes, eating disorders, and many others. Evolutionary mismatch occurs when the environment changes too rapidly for selection to be able to track it, resulting in residual traits that are no longer suited to the
28
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
BOX 2.1 Pathways for the persistence of disease and disorder (Adapted from Gluckman et al. (2009) and Crespi (2016); for definition of terms see glossary: www.rcpsych. ac.uk/docs/default-source/members/sigs/evolutionary-psychiatry-epsig/evolutionary-psychiatry-glossary-2. pdf?sfvrsn=707dd6b_2)
• • • • • • • • • • • •
Mismatch Life history factors Overactive defence mechanisms Co-evolutionary considerations: consequences of the arms race against pathogens Constraints imposed by evolutionary history Trade-offs Sexual selection and its consequences Balancing selection: maintaining an allele that raises disease risk Demographic history and its consequences Selection favours reproductive success at the expense of health Deleterious alleles Extremes of adaptations
new environment. Developmental mismatch arises when circumstances alter radically during an individual’s lifetime. For example, moving from a state of impoverishment during early development to a state of affluence in adult life can increase the risk of cardiovascular disease, Type 2 diabetes, and metabolic syndrome (Gluckman and Hanson, 2006). Furthermore, the extreme ends of functional adaptations can become maladaptive e.g. when adaptive personality traits are magnified (Trull and Widiger, 2013). Additionally, over-activation of useful emotional defences (mood states and anxiety) can result in harmful outcomes, leading to defence activation disorders (Del Giudice, 2018). It is important to understand that selection necessitates trade-offs. Increasing one trait is often at the expense of worsening performance of another. For example, increasing resistance to infections increases the risk of autoimmune diseases. Improving nutritional conservation increases the risk of obesity. Trade-offs are also involved in life history strategies. Life history theory (LHT) deals with species-typical solutions for problems associated with survival and reproduction that change over an individual’s lifespan (Brune,
2015). Hence, LHT provides a framework for understanding how organisms allocate time and energy in achieving core biosocial goals across the lifespan. Life history strategies involve a series of trade-offs that shape important biological developments including the timing of sexual maturity, the number and quality of offspring, and the length of lifespan (Stearns, 1992). The application of LHT demonstrates that the trade-offs yield a spectrum of life history strategies where the trade-offs include somatic versus reproductive effort, present versus the future, and quality versus quantity of offspring (Figure 2.1). The ‘fast’ end of the spectrum is characterized by a shorter lifespan, faster growth, earlier maturation and reproduction, and a larger number of offspring, while those at the slow end of the life history spectrum show the opposite characteristics (Del Giudice, 2018). Differences in life history strategies are partly under genetic control but it appears that the nature and quality of the individual’s early environment may also be important (Belsky et al., 1991; Ellis et al., 2011) (see Barbaro et al., 2016 for a different perspective). This renders LHT important for the understanding
29
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND PSYCHIATRY
Lifetime Energy Investment
Reproductive Effort
Somatic Effort (Slower)
(Faster)
Mating Effort (Faster)
Parental Effort (Slower)
Figure 2.1 Life history strategy trade-offs
of vulnerability to mental disorders (Brune, 2015; Del Giudice, 2018) (see later section ‘Evolutionary Models of Mental Disorders’). One major insight that follows from understanding the evolutionary causal pathways for the persistence of disease and disorder is the recognition that mental distress can arise from functional systems. Hence, an evolutionary taxonomy of treatable (undesirable) mental health conditions goes beyond harmful dysfunctions (Tooby and Cosmides, 1999). Undesirable conditions may result from different scenarios as summarized below (Del Giudice, 2018): • Undesirable mental health conditions can either arise from: {{ harmful dysfunctions (system breakdowns); or {{ functional mechanisms, which can be either: • maladaptive states at population level (e.g. evolutionary mismatch), or are: • currently adaptive, but outcomes may vary, resulting in: {{ maladaptive outcomes at the individual level (e.g. overactive defences, developmental mismatches), or: {{ adaptive outcomes at the individual level even if considered harmful by others (e.g. antisocial personality/psychopathy).
Hence, an evolutionary analysis provides a theoretical framework that enables us to distinguish states of mental distress and mental disorder that arise from functional or dysfunctional systems, and also provides a more effective way of understanding the role of environmental context.
GENETICS AND HERITABLE RISKS OF MENTAL DISORDERS Taking an evolutionary perspective is tantamount to turning genetics on its head. Hence, whereas a non-evolutionary view may consider specific DNA sequences as the primary biological cause of a given trait, an evolutionary approach seeks to understand the selection pressures over evolutionary history that led to the retention of these genes. So, evolutionary views consider environmental influences at two distinct levels, first over evolutionary history (leading to the shaping of adaptations) and, second, the ontogenic effects of the environment during the individual’s lifetime. Mental disorders require a degree of heritability, and hence some genetic basis,
30
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
before becoming candidates for evolutionary explanations. Remarkably, 55% of all coding genes in humans are expressed in the brain. This renders the brain a prime target for mutations and evolutionary changes (Brune, 2015). After considering heterogeneity and uncertainty, psychiatric disorders demonstrate a degree of heritability suggesting a moderate degree of heritable risk. For example, 90% of trait variation for autism can be accounted for with genetics; bipolar disorder, 85%; schizophrenia, 81%; unipolar depression, 37% (Kendler, 2001). Similarly, heritability estimates for anxiety disorders range from 30% to 45% (Hettema et al., 2001). Family studies (including twin and adoption studies) provide consistent evidence that genetic factors are involved in the presentation of these syndromes (Kendler and Eaves, 2005). Two types of heterogeneity have been identified in association with psychiatric genetics: causal and clinical. Causal heterogeneity refers to two or more causes independently inducing the same clinical syndrome. Clinical heterogeneity occurs when a single cause leads to multiple clinical syndromes (Tsuang et al., 2003). Natural selection does not directly select for genes that cause disease or disorder, so other explanations for their persistence must be considered. Accordingly, alongside any degree of heritability psychiatrists should ask: ‘Why does this mental disorder exist and persist?’ Mental disorders may be actively maintained through a number of evolutionary processes. These include: A) despite natural selection e.g. (i) mutation-selection balance, (ii) ancestral neutrality; and B) because of natural selection, (i) balancing selection, (ii) antagonistic pleiotropy, (iii) stabilizing selection on continuous traits, (iv) alternating selection, and (v) functioning adaptations. These categories are not mutually exclusive, and there may be multiple mechanisms maintaining some disorders in the population (Durisko et al., 2016).
Differential Susceptibility Research has demonstrated that people possessing at least one s-allele of the serotonin transporter gene HTTLPR incur increased risk of developing depression when facing adverse events. However, the same variation is linked to superior cognitive performance in several domains and increases social conformity (Homberg and Lesch, 2011). A balanced polymorphism also explains the frequency of a particular SNP in the general population, and why it has not been selected against. Beyond this important concept, evolutionary theory has aided in developing the idea that a particular SNP such as the s-allele of the 5-HTTLPR not only confers heightened risk for depression under unfavourable conditions, but lower risk for depression under favourable environmental conditions such as parental warmth and emotional availability during important developmental stages. This phenomenon is referred to as ‘differential susceptibility’ (Belsky, 1997; Pluess and Belsky, 2010), where phenotypic plasticity occurs in response to early environmental conditions, and differs radically from genetically mediated resilience which involves unresponsiveness to environmental conditions. The specific phenomenon of differential response to positive experiences is referred to as ‘vantage sensitivity’; a concept that shows promise in assessing the likelihood of responding to psychological interventions (de Villiers et al., 2018). This example serves as evidence against simple genetic determinism and also provides an indication that aspiring to alter genes alone to treat disorders may not be in an individual’s interests as differing circumstances alter the harmfulness or benefits of such a gene.
Mutation Load and Mental Disorder Mutation load has been implicated in the causation of some mental disorders (Keller and Miller, 2006), referring to de novo
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND PSYCHIATRY
germ-line mutations passed on from parents, rather than somatic mutations. Because ova go through far fewer replications than sperm, paternal age at conception was suspected as the primary source of de novo mutations (Crow, 2000). Paternal age is associated with increased risk of mental disorders generally (Hare and Moran, 1979). Mutation load is believed to play a significant role in the causation of schizophrenia and this is especially the case in childhood onset (Ahn et al., 2014; Caplan, 2016) (for a contrary view, see Ek et al., 2014). For autistic-spectrum disorder (ASD), mutation load was more significant in females and in severe cases (Jacquemont et al., 2014). The risk of attention deficit hyperactivity disorder (ADHD) has been found to be positively related to paternal age (Chudal et al., 2015; D’Onofrio et al., 2014; Russell et al., 2014, 2015). In depression, no significant relationship has been found with paternal age but there is increased risk with maternal age, suggesting prenatal stress as a factor (Del Giudice, 2018). In eating disorders and obsessive– compulsive disorder (OCD), the relationship with mutation load remains inconclusive (Del Giudice, 2018). Conversely, young paternal and maternal age is also related to the risk of a range of mental disorders in offspring. This, however, is not related to mutation load but rather to heritability of fast life history strategies, as fast life history is associated with early parenthood in both men and women and predicts a greater risk of fast life history spectrum disorders in the offspring of young parents (most notably ADHD and schizophrenia spectrum disorders) (see ‘Evolutionary Models of Mental Disorders’ section below).
Genomic Imprinting and Mental Disorder In diploid species such as humans, each autosomal gene is represented by two alleles, with one copy inherited from each parent.
31
Usually in autosomal genes, expression occurs from both alleles. However, in a very small fraction, one of the two alleles is switched off or ‘imprinted’, which may have significant effects on behaviour, as many are expressed in the brain (Wilkinson et al., 2007). Genomic imprinting represents a form of intragenomic conflict, whereby different alleles and loci express the fitness interest of one of the parents (Crespi, 2019). Intragenomic conflict arises from the asymmetry in the confidence regarding parental relatedness to offspring between the sexes. The conjecture is that paternally expressed (maternally imprinted) genes in an individual exert phenotypic effects that increase fitness-related demands imposed by offspring upon the mother, due to the lower probability of relatedness of paternal genes (than maternal genes) within a given brood. This is thought to be because mothers are always related to offspring by 50%, while the offspring of a given female can have different fathers (Crespi, 2019). Contrastingly, maternally expressed (paternally imprinted) genes are predicted to exert the reverse effect, namely, lower demands imposed on mothers. Hence, sometimes incremental investment will be favoured by paternal genes but resisted by maternal genes (Haig, 2014). Intriguingly, maternal gene imprinting (paternal expression) may be one cause for the underdevelopment of the ‘social brain’, generating a higher risk of ASD, whereas the paternal gene imprinting (maternal gene expression) may predispose to hyper-development of the social brain and increased risk of schizophrenia and related psychosis (Crespi, 2019) (see section ‘Schizophrenia Spectrum Disorders (SSDs)’, para. E, below).
EVOLUTIONARY MODELS OF MENTAL DISORDERS In contrast to the avowedly atheoretical approach of the DSM/ICD systems described above and the bottom-up biological approach
32
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
of the RDoC, evolutionary frameworks for the classification of mental disorder are top-down systems with explicit theoretical assumptions. They tend to utilize high-level organizing principles derived from evolutionary insights regarding the adaptive significance of various brain systems. Such a top-down approach remains compatible with a range of existing non-evolutionary approaches (Del Giudice, 2018). According to Del Giudice (2018), any coherent framework for mental disorder (evolutionary or otherwise) should meet four main challenges: explain patterns of co-morbidity; address heterogeneity within diagnostic categories; bridge psychopathology with individual differences; and account for developmental features of mental disorders including life course trajectories. The evolutionary framework proposed by Del Giudice (2018) based on LHT is more comprehensive and wideranging than others such as the diametric model of ASD and psychosis (Crespi, 2019; ‘Mutation Load and Mental Disorder’ section, above) and the externalizing–internalizing model (Martel, 2013). Del Giudice (2018) suggests that his proposed framework meets all four challenges and offers an alternative to the existing trans-diagnostic taxonomies of mental disorders such as the RDoC. The most recent version of this framework has been expanded to include a primary dimension of fast–slow life history strategy supplemented by a secondary dimension of defence-activation and hence the model has been dubbed the FSD model (Del Giudice, 2018). It is based on a core proposition, namely that the risk of developing a mental disorder depends on a pattern of individual differences that can be understood as manifestations of alternative life history strategies. Hence, moving along the fast–slow life history dimension will increase the risk of certain mental disorders and reduce the risk of others e.g. fast life history strategies increase the risk of psychosis while reducing the risk of autism, and vice versa. The FSD model generates three clusters of disorders:
F-type, S-Type, and D-type. The system is currently aimed at use by researchers rather than clinicians and it does not currently accommodate organic mental disorders or mental handicap.
EVOLUTIONARY THINKING ABOUT SELECTED PSYCHIATRIC DISORDERS It is important to note that due to the dual problems of heterogeneity and co-morbidity that beset current classification systems (Del Giudice, 2018), none of the evolutionary theories discussed in this section can account for the full range of the conditions they purport to explain. Heterogeneity in this context refers to the likelihood that most common mental disorders are a collection of disparate conditions that share certain clinical features but may differ in their causation.
Depression Sadness is universally recognized as the normal emotional response to loss, setbacks, and reversals in life (Horowitz and Wakefield, 2007). Unlike anxiety (a state of vigilance designed to detect and deal with risk and prevent/reduce harm), there is no consensus on the function(s) of sadness. Depressive disorders are marked by a severe negative mood with an inability to experience pleasure. In addition to low mood or anhedonia lasting a minimum of two weeks the DSM-5 requires the existence of four or more symptoms (loss or gain in weight, insomnia or hypersomnia, agitation or retardation, fatigue/loss of energy, feelings of worthlessness or inappropriate guilt, poor concentration or indecisiveness, and thoughts of death and suicide) for a diagnosis of major depressive disorder (MDD) (American Psychiatric Association, 2013). Although the DSM-5 treats MDD as a unitary condition, the application of its criteria allows for a wide variety of combinations where
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND PSYCHIATRY
individual patients can share few or even no symptoms (Fried and Nesse, 2015). Although many accept that depressive disorders are a highly heterogeneous collection of conditions (Akiskal and McKinney, 1975; Brune, 2015; Gilbert, 2006; Rantala et al., 2018), most evolutionary theories of depression still treat it as if it was a unitary condition with a single explanation. Depression remains one of the most common mental disorders in clinical practice, with a lifetime risk in the US population that exceeds 15% (Blazer et al., 1994) and striking at increasingly younger ages (Rottenberg, 2014). The increase in prevalence of depression in modern societies most probably results from evolutionary mismatch (Brune, 2015; Rantala et al., 2018; Rottenberg, 2014). As in most other defence activation disorders, depression has a higher prevalence in females with an overall F:M ratio of around 2:1. The higher female risk is contributed to by higher levels of neuroticism, sensitivity to social rejection, and interpersonal stressors (Del Giudice, 2018). Interestingly, and unlike most other mental disorders such as schizophrenia, autism, and anorexia nervosa, patients with depression show rates of reproductive success very close to that of the general population, with males at 90% and females at 100%
(Power et al., 2013). Depression occurs at both ends of the fast–slow life history continuum, with a fast life history subgroup of both males and females having early puberty and a slow life history subgroup (mainly males) having late puberty (Del Giudice, 2018). Hence, depression is not so much a slow life history strategy as a ‘slowing down’ strategy that can occur across the life history strategy spectrum (Brune, 2015). Although there is lack of agreement on the precise function of low mood, most evolutionists agree that the capacity for low mood has been shaped by selection because of its contribution to inclusive fitness in the ancestral environment. Disagreements between evolutionists arise where some consider the extremes or persistence of low mood as maladaptive and/or dysfunctional, while others consider the whole range of low mood including the extremes of depression as adaptations. Broadly speaking, one can classify evolutionary theories of depression into social and non-social theories (Gilbert, 2006) (Box 2.2). Depression primarily occurs in social or interpersonal contexts and is less frequently associated with events in non-social domains (Brune, 2015). Evolutionary formulations suggest explanations for the observed female
BOX 2.2 Evolutionary theories of depression Social Evolutionary Theories 1 2 3 4 5 6
33
Theories based on attachment theory (Bowlby, 1980). Theories on social competition and social rank (Price et al., 1994). Social navigation hypothesis (Watson and Andrews, 2002). Social risk theory (Allen and Badcock, 2003). Depression as bargaining (Hagen, 2003). Analytical rumination hypothesis (Andrews and Thomson, 2009).
Non-social Evolutionary Theories 1 Theories of resource conservation (Nesse, 2019). 2 Depression as immune response, defence against pathogens, starvation (see Rantala et al., 2018 for a review).
34
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
preponderance in depression as being related to ‘female fitness’, which appears much more dependent on securing support from others compared to males (Troisi, 2001). The social competition and rank theories propose that depression is part of a strategy of subordination associated with decline in social standing or rank and where further contest is judged to be futile or even risky. The low mood serves the dual function of signalling helplessness and submission both to dominants and to potential helpers. It also stops the individual from resuming competition too quickly (Price et al., 1994). However, if social competition lies at the root of depression, males would be expected to be at higher risk of depression given the higher fitness costs incurred by males as a result of status setbacks (Brune, 2015). According to attachment theory, the low mood of depression bears a distinct resemblance to the phase of despair that occurs in an infant after prolonged separation from its main carer, which involves reduced activity and vocalization as well as disengagement from its environment (Bowlby, 1980). This suggests that depression is an evolved strategy that is activated by the disruption of significant attachment bonds. The social risk theory focuses on the risk of social exclusion, which would have had grave consequences in the ancestral environment (Allen and Badcock, 2003). The unconscious and subtle calculation of the quotient of one’s social value to social burden will signal the risk of exclusion if this drops to a critical level. This will trigger a depressive state designed to conserve energy and help build up future potential social value to others; it also predicts increased suicide risk once the quotient drops below one (Brune, 2015). The analytical rumination hypothesis proposes that depressive rumination is an adaptation designed to solve complex social dilemmas (Andrews and Thomson, 2009). This is supported by the finding that low mood facilitates complex decision-making (von Helversen et al., 2011).
An influential non-social evolutionary theory proposes that low mood is adaptive for disengaging from unattainable goals. However, depressive disorder arises when the goals are too important to be abandoned and the individual becomes trapped in an unwinnable situation (Nesse, 2019). More recently, Rantala et al. (2018) proposed a subtyping of MDD, based on an evolutionary framework, with 12 distinct conditions each with its own proximate and ultimate causal profile. According to this model, MDD cannot be explained by a single theory and is consistent with the widespread view that depression is a heterogeneous disorder. These include infection, long-term stress, hierarchy conflict, grief, loneliness, traumatic experiences, post-partum events, romantic rejection, the season, chemicals, somatic disease, and starvation. While many of the theories briefly described above are reasonably parsimonious accounts of known facts about depression, the fact remains that few of their predictions have been empirically tested (Hagen, 2011). Unfortunately, the same can be said about many of the evolutionary theories regarding other mental disorders. The current dearth of data in the field remains an important obstacle to the integration of evolutionary thinking into mainstream psychiatry. Nevertheless, the evolutionary perspective is crucial for the formulation of appropriate questions and examination of existing data as well as for the collection of new information on mental disorders.
Schizophrenia Spectrum Disorders (SSDs) According to DSM-5, SSDs include schizophrenia (requires a minimum of six months of symptoms), schizophreniform disorder (up to six months), brief psychotic episode (up to one month), schizoaffective disorder, drug-induced psychosis, and catatonia. DSM-5 requires two or more of the following for a diagnosis of schizophrenia: delusions, hallucinations,
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND PSYCHIATRY
disorganized thinking, disorganized behaviour, and negative symptoms. In addition, a number of specifiers should be applied for the diagnosis to be made (American Psychiatric Association, 2013). Although it was once believed that schizophrenia occurs uniformly across the world, affecting 1% of the population, it is now recognized that this view is erroneous and that schizophrenia varies significantly in its prevalence (McGrath, 2006). Some studies have found a 30-fold difference in prevalence (0.1–3%) (Kinney et al., 2009). The average incidence is suggested to be between 0.2– 0.6 per 1,000 (Brune, 2015). The sex ratio shows a male preponderance of around 1.4:1 (McGrath, 2006). Schizophrenia is highly heritable, with monozygotic (MZ) twins having a 48% concordance compared to 17% for dizygotic (DZ) twins, and the relative risk shows a progressive reduction with increasing genetic distance (Owen et al., 2007). The persistence of schizophrenia within human populations, a condition that strikes at the peak of reproductive years and has a devastating effect on reproductive success, is a puzzle that has exercised evolutionists and has resulted in a diversity of evolutionary hypotheses (Brune, 2015). Power et al. (2013) found that males with schizophrenia had fertility rates 23% and females 47% that of the general population. Patients’ brothers also showed highly reduced fertility whereas sisters showed a slightly increased fertility. Hence, schizophrenia is associated with the lowest rates of fertility compared to all other common mental disorders. We list below a number of evolutionary formulations for SSDs. (a) Evolutionary by-product models: 1 The laterality and language model of schizophrenia: schizophrenia arising from disrupted lateralization of the brain with the failure of the hemispheric dominance for language is one of the best-known by-product models (Crow, 1997). Although this is supported by reduced
35
hemispheric asymmetry in schizophrenic patients and increased levels of ambidexterity in children who later develop psychosis, these findings can be explained equally well through mutation load and developmental stress (Yeo et al., 1999). Moreover, genome-wide studies demonstrate that SSDs are not the result of the action of single or a small number of genes but the cumulative effect of thousands of common and rare variants (Plomin, 2018). 2 The lipid metabolism hypothesis: this hypothesis proposes that changes in lipid metabolism within the human lineage enabled the development of creativity, which explains the flourishing of culture, including art and religion, over the last 50,000 years. According to this hypothesis, SSDs are the by-product of these newly evolved metabolic pathways (Horrobin, 2001). Horrobin’s ideas on the role of lipid metabolism in the aetiology of schizophrenia resulted in an interest in testing the effects of administering Omega-3 fatty acids in high concentrations to patients, but the results of randomized controlled trials have been inconsistent (National Institute for Health and Care Excellence (NICE), 2013). 3 The social brain theory of schizophrenia: Burns’ cortical dysconnectivity hypothesis is arguably the best developed example of the ‘social brain’ theory and also the most plausible example of evolutionary ‘by-product’ formulations generally (Burns, 2007). Burns’ hypothesis states that the emergence of the social brain, with its complex and vulnerable circuits, produced a vulnerability to aberrant connectivity. According to this model, schizophrenia is a disorder of the fronto-temporal and fronto-parietal circuits that evolved in our species as a substrate for the social brain. Schizophrenia, as a disorder of the social brain, is consistent with a range of findings that show deficits in social cognition prior to first psychotic episode, including deficits in recognition of facial emotions, mentalizing, and interpersonal processes such as understanding of fairness, reciprocity, and trust, as well as findings following the onset of the psychosis (Brune, 2015). 4 The ‘cliff edge’ fitness functions model: this is based on the idea that certain adaptive traits can overshoot their optimum, resulting in catastrophic failure and severe maladaptive consequences. Nesse (2019) has suggested that schizophrenia is intimately related to the
36
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
development of language ability and theory of mind where the fitness peak is dangerously close to the catastrophic cliff edge. This model is consistent with a range of evolutionary formulations including the social brain, language, and laterality, as well as the sexual selection hypothesis of schizotypal traits. (b) Schizophrenia as an adaptation: an early model that has since been falsified was based on a balanced polymorphism of a single gene that was beneficial in the heterozygote state but causes schizophrenia in homozygotes (Huxley et al., 1964). More recently, a range of models based on group selection have been proposed that suggest that schizotypal traits facilitated group splitting during human evolutionary history through magical and paranoid thinking as well as idiosyncratic behaviour which can lead to messianic leadership and group fission (Stevens and Price, 2000a, 2000b). Other formulations focused on the shaman as the self-sacrificing equivalent of the sterile castes in social insects that produces group cohesion and solidarity through magical thinking, possession states, and religious ritual which is maintained through group selection (Polimeni, 2012). However, while these theories draw attention to the fascinating similarities between religious phenomenology and psychosis, they remain highly speculative. (c) Mismatch model: the outgroup intolerance hypothesis is an attempt to provide an explanatory framework for a range of epidemiological findings pointing to wide variation in the incidence and prevalence of SSDs. The hypothesis proposes that schizophrenia arises as the result of a mismatch between the social brain as shaped by evolution and the novel social conditions of the post-Neolithic that involve living in large settlements and regularly encountering strangers (outgroup members). The hypothesis can provide an explanation for (i) the higher risk in migrants and especially second-generation migrants and migrants who are racially and/or ethnically salient; (ii) increased risk of schizophrenia that is inversely related to same-group ethnic density in a given locality; (iii) the increased risk to individuals who have grown up in cities; and (iv) the putative low risk of schizophrenia in hunter-gatherer societies (Abed and Abbas, 2011, 2014). (d) Sexual selection model of creativity of schizotypal traits: these hypotheses are based on the proposal that schizophrenia is the extreme, low-fitness end of a range of sexually selected
characteristics that include creativity, emotional expressiveness, and superior mentalizing ability (Nettle, 2001; Shaner et al., 2004). Hence the sexual selection model proposes that SSDs are the maladaptive outcome of adaptive but risky mating strategies (Del Giudice, 2018). This model is also compatible with the view of SSDs as a fast life history spectrum disorder (see para. f below). The model is consistent with a range of findings including the slight increase in fertility in sisters, but it is rather difficult to reconcile with the finding of a dramatic reduction in fertility in brothers (Power et al., 2013). (e) The diametrical model of psychosis (including schizophrenia) and autism: in this model autisticspectrum disorders (ASD) and psychotic-spectrum conditions (including schizophrenia (SSD)) represent two major suites of disorders of human cognition, affect, and behaviour that involve altered development and function of the social brain (Crespi and Badcock, 2008). The model is based on evidence that large sets of phenotypic traits exhibit diametrically opposite phenotypes in ASD versus psychotic-spectrum conditions, with a focus on schizophrenia. These include constrained growth in psychotic-spectrum disorders as opposed to overgrowth in ASD and underdeveloped social cognition in ASD as opposed to its hyper-development in the psychotic spectrum (the reverse is the case for mechanistic cognition resulting in the psychosis spectrum being hypermentalistic/hypomechanistic and the reverse is the case in ASD). The role of genomic imprinting in this phenomenon has already been alluded to in the section ‘Genomic Imprinting and Mental Disorder’, above. The different cognitive biases of SSD and ASD proposed in the diametric model have received considerable empirical support (Abu-Akel et al., 2015; White et al., 2016). However, the overlap between ASD and SSD (co-morbidity) remains a challenge for this model (Chisholm et al., 2015). (f) Life history theory and SSDs: broadly speaking, positive schizotypy, characterized by odd beliefs, magical thinking, unusual perceptual experiences, and paranoid thoughts, associated with hypermentalizing, enhanced creativity, and unrestricted socio-sexuality, fits the pattern of fast life history strategy. This is also consistent with the association of positive schizotypy with aggression, impulsivity, and sensation-seeking as well as early maturation (Del Giudice, 2018). Negative schizotypy, on the other hand, characterized by
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND PSYCHIATRY
lack of social engagement, flat affect, and social anxiety with paranoid tendencies that tends to overlap with autistic traits, is associated with late maturation in males but not in females, and is consistent with a slow life history strategy (Kaiser and Gruzelier, 1999). It is clear that the diametric model of psychosis and ASD as well as the sexual selection hypothesis both fit the fast life history strategy model.
Drug and Alcohol Addictions Examining substance abuse from an evolutionary perspective offers explanatory advantages in illuminating a wide range of biological, psychological, and social facts and mechanisms in substance misuse (St John-Smith et al., 2013). Evolutionary models are unique in that they emphasize the effects that drugs had on fitness over human evolution. For substance abuse, a seemingly maladaptive trait, to persist, there must be either a ‘trade-off’ where the harm is counterbalanced by a fitness benefit, or substance-taking is a by-product of other more adaptive processes. Such models include: a) psychotropic self-medication (pharmacological manipulation of emotions); b) pharmacophagy and infection control; c) mismatch theory; d) increasing reproductive fitness; e) evolutionary constraints; f) tradeoffs; g) costly signalling and handicap theories; h) placebo, ritual, and healing effects; and i) drug use in spirituality or religion (e.g. the role of psychedelic drug use by ‘neo-shamans’ and ‘psychonauts’). Some of these models are conceptually similar or overlapping, are not mutually exclusive, and may interact in unpredictable ways (Orsolini et al., 2017).
Emotional pathways Primary emotional systems evolved to produce pleasurable affects in response to propitious circumstances or stimuli indicating adaptive success, and aversive affects in response to environmental or other threats, indicating reduced adaptive success. Drugs (of abuse) may be used to diminish aversive affects (e.g. opiates) or to increase positive
37
affect (e.g. stimulants). These drugs override the adaptive functions of the primary emotional systems so individuals experience an increase in positive affect, or decrease in negative affect, independently of any change in their circumstances, thus decoupling the emotional system from environmental events, some continuing to consume the drug despite mounting harm because the reactions bypass the evolved protective mechanisms used to signal real success or danger (Nesse, 2019).
Mismatch The hijack hypothesis implies that a range of drugs of abuse effectively commandeer the neural reward circuitry in the mesolimbic reward pathway as a result of mismatch as the contemporary abundance of potent psychoactive substances is a recent and novel phenomenon that was not present and therefore could not have occurred in the ancestral environment.
Human–plant co-evolutionary history and the paradox of drug reward Plants evolved the capacity to synthesize chemicals (nicotine, morphine, cocaine etc.) that act as neurotoxins to deter consumption by insects and herbivores (Sullivan et al., 2008). The efficacy of plant neurotoxins evolved over 400 million years and is therefore not evolutionarily novel. Consequently, human physiology can ‘identify’ plant toxins and activate defences that involve genes, tissue barriers, neural circuits, organ systems, and behaviours to protect against them. Drug toxicity and aversive responses (e.g. headache, sweating, nausea, and vomiting) occur in humans so are inconsistent with a simplistic theory of drug reward. Consequently other mechanisms, such as trade-offs, must be invoked as explanations. The neurotoxin regulation hypothesis proposes that the parallel consumption of both the nutrients and neurotoxins in plants selected for a system capable of maximizing the benefits of plant energy extraction while mitigating the cost of plant toxicity. The pharmacophagy hypothesis proposes that the consumption of chemicals
38
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
with medicinal properties is contingent on human–plant co-evolution. Self-medication advantages arose when humans learned to overcome cues of plant toxicity (e.g. bitter taste) and consumed potentially toxic substances with little energetic content because ingesting the toxins in small amounts was advantageous. Thus, the consumption of plant alkaloids could have contributed to reproductive fitness, and a taste for these substances could have been selected for. It is recognized that many such toxins are known to have anti-helminthic or antimicrobial and antiparasitic effects. Consuming ripe fruits containing small amounts of ethanol is selectively advantageous (Dudley, 2004), as volatile alcohols potentially aid in olfactory localization of ripe fruit. Herbivores developed the capacity to metabolize alcohol to be able to utilize energy-rich fruits despite the presence of alcohol. In the ancestral environment, alcohol would have been encountered in fermenting fruit in low concentrations and small quantities for brief periods in the year. Subsequent to the agricultural revolution, large surpluses of fruits and grains became available for fermentation so alcoholic drinks were brewed up to 12–14% and stored/traded for year-round consumption. Much more recently, the development of distilling technology permitted the production of far higher concentrations of alcohol. With the rise of larger settlements and cities, having access to alcoholic beverages may have protected against waterborne pathogens. However, enzyme systems that evolved to process small amounts of alcohol on an occasional basis can now be presented with inexhaustible supplies of highly concentrated alcohol, giving rise to a state of mismatch (St John-Smith et al., 2013).
Drug use can increase reproductive fitness because consumption may: (1) advertise biological quality, sexual maturity, or availability; (2) decrease inhibitions in mating contexts; and/or (3) enhance associative learning behaviours that in turn increase mating opportunities (Richardson et al., 2017). Variation in drug use susceptibility is in part due to genetic factors; therefore, successful drug consumption may be a costly and honest signal of biological quality: a process of costly signalling and sexual selection. Such risktaking behaviour represents a fast life history strategy and involves future discounting (see ‘Evolutionary Models of Mental Disorders’ section above). LHT can explain the current male preponderance in drug use, as female drug users incur much higher fitness costs through reduced parenting capacity, potential teratogenic effects, and potential circumvention of mate choice (Orsolini et al., 2017). Finally, another aspect of mismatch is that the ancient ‘evolved’ advantages of any psychoactive substances have now potentially become a liability and risk in modern environments as cultural change is accelerating and outstrips biological adaptation. The evolutionary perspective can help researchers reach a functional understanding of substance abuse and develop treatments for the various complex underlying causes of substance misuse. Some of these models are conceptually similar or overlapping and can interact in unpredictable ways. In addition, psychoactive substances, often hallucinogens which tend not to be addictive, have been used in various religious and cultural ceremonies (signalling) for millennia. Some advantages may be had from related group cohesion as well as their action on micro-organisms and other trade-offs discussed above.
Cultural, psychological, anthropological models and sexual selection hypotheses
Anorexia Nervosa (AN) and Bulimia Nervosa (BN)
Alcohol
Some evolutionary psychological theories concerning drug use suggest individuals consume drugs to increase reproductive opportunities.
AN and BN are diagnostic categories of eating disorders according to ICD-10 and DSM-5
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND PSYCHIATRY
classifications. The conditions share core features of morbid fear of fatness, distorted body image, and a pattern of behaviour aimed at weight reduction that includes purging, restriction of food intake, or excessive exercise (American Psychiatric Association, 2013; WHO, 1992). AN is characterized by low body weight with possible amenorrhea whereas BN is associated with binge eating and a normal body weight. Evidence demonstrates some heritability (Bulik et al., 2016; Yilmaz et al., 2015) and AN and BN share some genetic basis (Eley et al., 2005). Notably, the epidemiology of AN and BN demonstrates a marked female preponderance with a female-to-male sex ratio of 10:1 or greater (Gordon, 1990; Hudson et al., 2007). Also, both are by far more prevalent in developed countries compared to developing countries, particularly when considering subthreshold phenotypes (Katzman et al., 2004).
Evolutionary theories for eating disorders A number of evolutionarily informed theories and hypotheses have been proposed. The ‘Reproductive Suppression Hypothesis’ of AN considers eating restriction as a strategy to delay reproduction in times of disadvantageous environmental conditions by lowering the amount of body fat to a level incompatible with ovulation (Surbey, 1987; Voland and Voland, 1989; Wasser and Barash, 1983). Consistent with the Reproductive Suppression Hypothesis it is reported that women who perceive low levels of support from romantic partners and family are prone to dieting and do not feel ready for parenthood, suggesting that poor environmental conditions are causal in the development of AN (Juda et al., 2004). Unlike the original Reproductive Suppression Hypothesis which hypothesized the occurrence of reproductive self-suppression, an alternative hypothesis was put forth by Mealey (2000) where reproductive suppression was imposed upon subordinate females by dominants. Other evolutionary hypotheses have posited that symptoms of AN may help to cope with famine, whereby food restriction, denial
39
of starvation, and hyperactivity could r epresent an adaptive behaviour that helped ancestral nomadic foragers to migrate from depleted environments to more promising surroundings in times of food shortages (Guisinger, 2003). However, the ‘fleeing famine hypothesis’ appears to confound consequences with causation in that the features of ‘fleeing famine’ represent the consequences of starvation that arise in AN as a result of self-imposed restriction of food intake. It is of interest that the trigger for the initiation of dieting proposed by Guisinger (2003) is the improvement of attractiveness and competition for mates, which is more or less identical to the Sexual Competition Hypothesis (see below). It is notable that these theories focus exclusively on AN where food restriction causes low body weight, which in turn can lead to amenorrhoea and reproductive suppression or the starvation response, whereas this does not occur in BN.
The Sexual Competition Hypothesis (SCH) and LHT The SCH is a more inclusive evolutionary model which reconsiders the whole spectrum of eating disorders including AN and BN (Abed, 1998). The SCH, based on the Darwinian theory of sexual selection, proposes that female intra-sexual competition is the biological root for the drive for thinness, an adaptive response originally suited to the ancestral environment, and that the extreme version of this manifests in what we know as eating disorders. The SCH proposes that AN and BN are manifestations of abnormally intense female intra-sexual competition whereby autonomous females of reproductive age compete with each other in the novel modern Westernized urban environment through a strategy of ‘the pursuit of thinness’ as a signal of youth, leading to ‘runaway female intra-sexual competition’, the extreme version of which manifests as eating disorders (Abed, 1998). The SCH is based on the fact that throughout human evolutionary history the female shape has been a reliable indicator of the female’s
40
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
reproductive history and consequently her reproductive potential (Bovet and Raymond, 2015; Singh, 1993). Youth and good health have always been major determinants of female mate value not least because of the finite reproductive window in humans that abruptly ends with menopause (Buss, 1987). The visual signal for a female’s peak reproductive potential in the ancestral environment was the female nubile shape, which was generally short-lived and deteriorated with the repeated cycles of gestation and lactation (Symons, 1995). Hence, according to SCH, female intrasexual competition in affluent Westernized societies became focused on the preservation of the ‘nubile shape’ through a strategy of the pursuit of thinness to display signs of youth. The SCH further proposes that other important factors serve to up-regulate the intensity of female intra-sexual competition. Some of the major additional factors include (Nettersheim et al., 2018): (a) female autonomy that involves the ability to make mating decisions with relatively little interference from kin (unlike the case in ancestral and traditional societies) (Apostolou, 2007; (b) living in cities where abnormally large numbers of autonomous females live in close proximity to each other; (c) reduced fertility (birth rates) (Vining, 1986); and (d) the ubiquity of abnormally attractive youthful nubile female images in the media that are mistaken for competitors (Ferguson et al., 2011). Therefore, the SCH is based on a proposed mismatch between the design of the female’s psychological adaptations for mate attraction and retention and for competing with rival females, on the one hand, and the novel circumstances of the modern urban environment, on the other. However, intra-sexual competition alone cannot explain the different presentations of AN and BN. Hence, life history strategies were considered as an added factor where BN lies at the fast and AN on the slow end of the life history spectrum (Abed et al., 2012). Predictions from the SCH have been examined in a number of non-clinical studies and
have found a significant correlation between abnormal eating behaviour and the intensity of competition for mates (Abed et al., 2012; Faer et al., 2005). Also, supportive evidence has been found for the predictions that homosexual men resemble heterosexual women and lesbians resemble heterosexual men in their concerns about physical attractiveness and eating behaviour (Li et al., 2010). More recently an exploratory study on anorexic and bulimic patients supported the fast–slow life history strategy prediction for BN and AN and partially supported the predictions of SCH (Nettersheim et al., 2018).
The Placebo Response and Nesse’s Smoke Detector Principle Placebo effects may be considered as explanations of how healing and caring works (McQueen et al., 2013). The universality of placebo responses suggests a likely evolutionary basis to the underlying mechanisms. Placebo responses permit mammals to modify internal processes and behaviours. Adaptive advantages might result from the evolution of abilities to modify our internal environment in the light of positive evaluations of our external environments, social interactions, and appraisals of the future. The hypothetical system charged with health maintenance, shaped by evolution, has been referred to as a ‘health governor’, aspects of which are shared across many species but which is most highly developed in humans and operates entirely outside conscious awareness (Humphrey and Skoyles, 2012). Nesse (2019) stresses that placebo responses primarily entail modification of the body’s defences e.g. pain, nausea, anxiety, depression, fever, coughing, vomiting, and diarrhoea, rather than altering disease processes. Hence, evolution has selected for mechanisms that defend against injury, infection or poisoning and the regulation of these defences is influenced by appraisals of the environment. However, many defences appear to be over-expressed. A signal-detection
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND PSYCHIATRY
analysis can explain this apparent paradox. When the cost of expressing an all-or-nothing defence is low compared with the potential harm it protects against, the optimal system will express many false alarms. For example, vomiting may cost only a few hundred calories and a few minutes, whereas not vomiting may result in a chance, however small, of death from poisoning. This has been dubbed ‘the smoke detector principle’ (Nesse, 2001). The over-expression of many defences allows that they can often be dampened without compromising fitness. The regulation of defences allows that otherwise ‘protective’ defences can be turned off both in situations of extreme danger, to facilitate escape, and in situations propitious for recovery, where they may no longer be necessary for protection. This may explain why pain is reduced both when facing immediate threat and when being cared for. Furthermore, the goal of the attachment system is to maintain proximity to caregivers who would provide safety from danger. Thus, at times of threat, the attachment system becomes activated. Manifestations of attachment behaviour change with the stage of the life cycle and attachment style, but at times of subjectively perceived threat, which includes illness, proximity and caring are sought from attachment figures, which may come to include trusted professional carers, and hence the placebo response may be an emergent property of the attachment system (Bowlby, 1980).
Other Disorders: Alzheimer’s, Personality Disorders, and Bipolar Disorder People are increasingly surviving into old age. This increase in longevity is associated with increased levels of morbidity of both somatic and mental disorders, among them the dementias such as Alzheimer’s disease (AD), during those added years. Evolutionists consider explanatory theories for the phenomenon of aging such as antagonistic
41
pleiotropy (Williams, 1957) and LHT. As AD seems to be specific to Homo sapiens, its existence may in part be anchored in the adaptive changes that have occurred after humans separated from other primates. Evolutionary theories also take into account issues around brain development including the related phenomena of altriciality and grandmothering, the evolution of ApoE and the genome lag hypothesis. Thus, an evolutionary look into AD may shed new light on the causes and treatments of this devastating disease (Von Gunten et al., 2018). Others have suggested that AD is the result of mismatch related to the vastly increased levels in the modern environment of insulin resistance, inflammation, and exposure to toxins (Fox, 2018), or that AD is the result of a trade-off between the antimicrobial effects of amyloid beta and the damaging effects of its sustained activation (Moir et al., 2018). Personality disorders (PD) are defined by DSM-5 as an enduring pattern of inner experience and behaviour that deviates markedly from the expectations of the individual’s culture. The DSM and ICD classifications list around a dozen different types each but they differ in their subtyping, terminology, and criteria. The five-dimension model of personality is currently widely favoured and comprises extraversion, neuroticism, agreeableness, conscientiousness, and openness (McCrae and Costa, 2003). Personality disorders are clustered into three groups with Cluster A comprising the ‘eccentric’ PDs such as paranoid and schizoid; cluster B ‘dramatic’ such as antisocial and borderline PDs; and cluster C ‘anxious’, including avoidant, dependent, and obsessive–compulsive PDs. Evolutionary formulations have proposed that antisocial PDs may be an ‘adaptive’ cheating strategy that is maintained through frequency dependent selection (e.g. Mealey, 1995). Cluster B (antisocial and borderline PDs) has been considered to represent a fast life history strategy while both clusters A and C are considered slow life history disorders (Brune, 2015). However, Del Giudice (2018)
42
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
takes a more nuanced approach and classifies PDs as fast (antisocial and borderline) and slow (obsessive–compulsive), with avoidant PD as a defence activation disorder. Bipolar disorder (BPD) has a prevalence of between 1 and 5% of the population depending on the subtypes included. In contrast to schizophrenia, BPD has received relatively little attention from evolutionists. Many of the existing evolutionary models propose some evolutionary advantage of hypomanic traits or even manic episodes (Del Giudice, 2018). The manic mood has been considered the winning and the depressive mood the losing programmes of the dominance system (Gilbert et al., 2007). It is of interest to note the relatively small decline in fertility associated with BPD (85% of general population levels in females and 75% in males) compared to the steep decline in schizophrenia (Power et al., 2013). Nesse (2019) considers BPD as an example of a malfunctioning mood regulation system or broken ‘moodostat’. Del Giudice (2018), applying the life history framework, proposes that there are two distinct variants, a fast and a slow life history strategy variant. The fast subtype has greater links to schizophrenia with a higher risk of psychotic symptoms and the slower subtype has links to autism and lower risk of psychotic symptoms.
EVOLUTION AND PSYCHOPHARMACOLOGY Psychopharmacological drugs became widely available in the 1950s and have changed many outcomes; however, psychiatric disorders are so complex and heterogeneous that psychopharmacology alone cannot cure every aspect of any disorder. Current psychopharmacology is not based on evolutionary insights or theories. Highly preserved, bio-active chemicals play fundamental roles in many processes across virtually all life forms. They include acetylcholine and the biogenic monoamines
as well as other groups such as amino acids, purines, cannabinoids, and neuropeptides. Such chemicals have been found not only in animals, but also in plants and unicellular microorganisms (Roshchina, 2010). This ubiquity is best explained by universal cellular mechanisms, communication systems across kingdoms, and shared evolutionary ancestry, demonstrating the ‘thriftiness’ of evolutionary processes and the conservation of evolved mechanisms and strategies. Phylogenetically, it appears that these chemicals and their associated enzymes existed for a substantial period before their respective receptor proteins. Evolution of sophisticated nervous systems arrived independently of the synthesis of newer sophisticated transmitter substances, receptor proteins, transducers, and effector proteins; rather they evolved with improved organization and utilization of these entities, forming increasingly advanced and refined circuitry via natural and sexual selection (Roshchina, 2010). There are hundreds of chemical substances that provide communication between cells in humans, some simple monoamines, others more complex, e.g. neuropeptides. Knowledge of differing receptor function in other species has aided drug development. For example, there are important changes during evolutionary time, related to the neurotransmitters/receptors and how they function in humans. As further examples of biological cross-reactivity, many psychotropic agents have an action on microorganisms, including such varied taxa as bacteria, helminths, insects, and other parasites. The antipsychotics (phenothiazines and thioxanthenes) show antibacterial activity, exerting their activity independently of antibiotic resistance. The benzodiazepine clonazepam is anti-schistosomal (Stohler, 1978). Monoamine oxidase inhibitors, lithium, tricyclic antidepressants, and valproic acid have a range of antimicrobial activities (Kristiansen, 1990). Many psychiatric conditions involve emotion dysregulation, inappropriate expression of emotions, or impaired access to one’s
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND PSYCHIATRY
emotional life. Positive emotions developed evolutionarily to motivate humans to take advantage of environmental opportunities and to recognize when we have succeeded in doing so. Negative emotions evolved to motivate humans to avoid misfortune by escaping, attacking, or preventing harm or repairing damage when it has already occurred. Emotional reactions importantly correspond to differences in appraisal that result from individual differences in personal values, experiences, and goals. Psychopharmacological agents may modify these responses in ways which have consequences beyond the simple alleviation of distress. ‘Side effects’ of medications are sometimes consequences of effects on attendant processes, as distinct from the direct pharmacology, for instance a reduction in anxiety leading to an increase in risk taking or disinhibition. Understanding why symptoms exist/persist may enhance psychiatric management. Treatments should be evaluated regarding whether the index symptoms are aiding individual coping strategies with respect to the adverse life event which caused the lowered mood in the first place. Importantly, pharmacologically reducing symptoms remains beneficial, even essential, when the symptoms are excessive or fail to serve their adaptive purpose, and when the symptoms are not associated with events that triggered the episode. Conversely, in cases where a depressive episode is a functional response to adversity, suppressing it unconditionally without addressing the underlying causes might be harmful. This is analogous to treating pain without considering the aetiology. Conceptualizing sickness behaviours, pain mechanisms, and mental disorders in relation to the problems that they evolved to solve potentially encourages practitioners to provide treatment options that are more effectively targeted, ensuring a patient’s long-term well-being, though the patient’s immediate best interests must always be regarded as paramount (Rantala et al., 2018). Psychopharmacology should also review the
43
side effects of medication through the lens of evolutionary theory, potentially considering drug interference with evolutionarily relevant systems that might have negative consequences for the individual’s ability to attain vital biosocial goals.
LOOKING TOWARD THE FUTURE At present, the evolutionary literature remains largely invisible to mainstream psychiatrists. This is partly explained by the current paucity of evolutionarily inspired interventions but is also influenced by a range of other factors. These include ideological, religious, and libertarian concerns as well as factors related to the inertia inherent in paradigm shifts (Kuhn, 1962). Whereas the religious and ideological (primarily post-modernist, anti-science trends) opposition to Darwinism is largely entrenched and probably unchangeable, the libertarian concerns arise from misconceptions that should, in principle, be amenable to modification. For example, mistaking evolutionary science for social Darwinism and assuming that evolution implies strict genetic determinism can be countered by appropriate scientific argument and evidence. However, it may prove much more difficult to overcome the anti-evolutionary position of ‘biological reductionism’ that is currently the dominant trend in medical and psychiatric academic centres within the Western world. We propose that evolutionary science provides a framework that can organize a huge number of facts about human biology and psychology into a coherent narrative that, in time, will lead to insights that can give rise to novel treatments and interventions in psychiatry and the rest of medicine. This can help further our understanding of sex differences in vulnerability to disorder, phenotypic plasticity including differential susceptibility as a result of gene–environment interactions, and the role of life history strategies. The unique insights evolutionary thinking brings stem
44
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
primarily from combining an understanding of the role of ultimate causation alongside proximate causes. Such evolutionary thinking has already resulted in novel interventions for cancer (DeGregori, 2018). However, a critical mass of evolutionarily informed psychiatrists is necessary to significantly influence the research agenda. Hence, the first step must involve better evolutionary education for psychiatrists both at under- and postgraduate levels. We suggest that trainee psychiatrists would benefit from the following basic evolutionary knowledge/competences: 1 An understanding of how selection shapes adaptations (physical and psychological traits). 2 An understanding of Tinbergen’s four causes with special emphasis on the distinction between proximate and ultimate causation (see ‘Evolution and Causality’ section). 3 An understanding of the concepts of kin selection and inclusive fitness. 4 An understanding of the evolutionary causal processes for the persistence of disease and disorder with special emphasis on mismatch, trade-offs, life history strategies and sexual selection (see ‘Causal Pathways for the Persistence of Disease and Disorder’ section). 5 An understanding of the basics of evolutionary genetics, including selection, mutation, drift, intra-genomic conflict, and genomic imprinting.
Many evolutionary applications in medicine rely on well-established methods, such as population genetics, phylogenetic analysis, and observing pathogen evolution. Approaches to evolutionary questions about traits that leave bodies vulnerable to disease are less well developed. Strategies for formulating questions and hypotheses remain unsettled, and methods for testing evolutionary hypotheses are unfamiliar to many in medicine. Nesse (2011) has suggested a structure for appropriate evolutionary research which uses recent examples to illustrate successful strategies and some common challenges. He identifies 10 questions to consider in testing evolutionary hypotheses. Addressing them
systematically can help minimize confusion and errors. One of the major contributions of evolutionary thinking is that it helps researchers formulate the right questions regarding the nature of disease and disorder. Evolution also cautions us against simplistic genetic models and draws attention to the possible adaptive function(s) of genes implicated in mental disorders. Evolution’s flagship contribution is that it highlights the mistake of equating distress with disease and disorder. This prompts clinicians to consider the possible downside of treating potentially adaptive states of defence activation in individual patients as well as to consider the currently neglected possibility that insufficient defences (e.g. low or absent anxiety) are also a possible source of psychopathology and harmful dysfunction (Nesse, 2019). Aside from future advantages in the areas of research and classification, there are potential benefits from utilizing evolutionary thinking in the clinic in the present. Examples include introducing patients with anxiety and panic disorders to evolutionary concepts such as the ‘smoke detector principle’ (Nesse, 2019) or the harm-avoidance model of OCD (Abed and de Pauw, 1999). Finally, we submit that possessing an evolutionary understanding of unique human vulnerabilities in itself enhances empathy and understanding, complementing the clinician’s effectiveness (Nesse, 2019; Troisi, 2012).
ACKNOWLEDGEMENT We are grateful to David Geaney and the anonymous referee for reading and commenting on previous drafts of this chapter.
REFERENCES Abed, R.T. (1998). The sexual competition hypothesis for eating disorders. British Journal of Medical Psychology, 71, 525–547.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND PSYCHIATRY
Abed, R.T. (2000). Psychiatry and Darwinism: Time to reconsider? British Journal of Psychiatry, 177, 1–3. Abed, R.T. & Abbas, M.J. (2011). A reformulation of the social brain theory of schizophrenia: The case for outgroup intolerance. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, 54, 132–151. Abed, R.T. & Abbas, M.J. (2014). Can the new epidemiology of schizophrenia help elucidate its causation? Irish Journal of Psychological Medicine, 31, 1–5. Abed, R.T. & de Pauw, K.W. (1998). An evolutionary hypothesis for obsessive compulsive disorder: A psychological immune system? Behavioural Neurology, 11(4), 245–250. Abed, R.T. & St John-Smith, P. (2016). Evolutionary psychiatry: A new college special interest group. BJPsych Bulletin, 40, 233–236. Abed, R., Mehta, S., Figueredo, A.J., Aldridge, S., Balson, H., Meyer, C. & Palmer, R. (2012). Eating disorders and intrasexual competition: Testing an evolutionary hypothesis among young women. Scientific World Journal, 290813. doi: 10.1100/2012/290813 Abu-Akel, A.M., Wood S.J., Hansen, P.C. & Apperly, I.A. (2015). Perspective-taking abilities in the balance between autism tendencies and psychosis proneness. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, 282, 20150563. Ahn, K., Gotay, N., Andersen, T.M., Anvari, A.A., Gochman, P., Lee, Y., Sanders, S., Guha, S., Darvasi, A., Glessner, J.T., Hakonarson, H., Lencz, T., State, M.W., Shugart, Y.Y. & Rapoport, J.L. (2014). High rate of disease-related copy number variation in childhood onset schizophrenia. Molecular Psychiatry, 19, 568–572. Akil, H., Brenner, S., Kandel, E., Kendler, K.S., King, M-C., Scolnick, E., Watson, J. D. & Zoghby, H.Y. (2010). The future of psychiatric research: Genomes and neural circuits. Science, 327(5973), 1580–1581. Akiskal, H.S. & McKinney, W.T. (1975). Overview of recent research in depression: Integration of ten conceptual models into a comprehensive clinical frame. Archives of General Psychiatry, 32(3), 285–305. Allen, N.B. & Badcock, P.B. (2003). The social risk hypothesis of depressed mood: Evolutionary, psychosocial and neurobiological perspectives. Psychological Bulletin, 129, 887–913.
45
American Psychiatric Association (2013). Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (5th ed.). Arlington, American Psychiatric Association. Andreasen, N. (1984). The Broken Brain. New York, HarperPerennial. Andrews, P.W. & Thomson, J.A. (2009). The bright side of being blue: Depression as an adaptation for analyzing complex problems. Psychological Review, 116, 620–654. Apostolou, M. (2007). Sexual selection under parental choice: The role of parents in the evolution of human mating. Evolution and Human Behavior, 28, 403–409. Barbaro, N., Boutwell, B.B., Barnes, J.C. & Shackelford, T.K. (2017). Genetic confounding of the relationship between father absence and age at menarche. Evolution and Human Behavior, 38, 357–365. Belsky, J. (1997). Variation in susceptibility to rearing influence: An evolutionary argument. Psychological Inquiry, 8, 182–186. Belsky, J., Steinberg, L. & Draper, P. (1991). Childhood experience, interpersonal development and reproductive strategy: An evolutionary theory of socialization. Child Development, 62, 647–670. Blazer, D.G., Kessler, R.C., McGonagle, K.A. & Swartz, M.S. (1994). The prevalence and distribution of major depression in a national community sample: The National Comorbidity Survey. American Journal of Psychiatry, 151, 979–986. Bolton, D. (2007). The usefulness of Wakefield’s definition for the diagnostic manuals. World Psychiatry, 6(3), 164–165. Bovet, J. & Raymond, M. (2015). Preferred women’s waist-to-hip ratio variation over the last 2,500 years. PLOS One, 10, e0123284. Bowlby, J. (1980). Attachment and Loss: Loss Sadness and Depression (Vol. 3). London, Hogarth Press. Brune, M. (2015). Textbook of Evolutionary Psychiatry and Psychosomatic Medicine: The Origins of Psychopathology. Oxford, OUP. Brune, M., Belsky J., Fabrega, H., Feierman, H.R., Gilbert, P., Glantz, K., Polimeni, J., Price, J.S., Sanjuan, J., Sullivan, R., Troisi, A. & Wilson, D.R. (2012). The crisis of psychiatry – insights and prospects from evolutionary theory. World Psychiatry, 11(1), 55–57.
46
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Bulik, C.M., Kleiman, S.C. & Yilmaz, Z. (2016). Genetic epidemiology of eating disorders. Current Opinion in Psychiatry, 29, 383–388. Burns, J. (2007). The Descent of Madness: Evolutionary Origins of Psychosis and the Social Brain. London, Routledge. Buss, D.M. (1987). Sex differences in mate selection criteria: An evolutionary perspective. In: C. Crawford, M. Smith & Krebs, D. (eds.) Sociobiology and Psychology: Ideas, Issues and Applications (pp. 335–351). Hillsdale, NJ, Erlbaum. Caplan, R. (2016). Childhood schizophrenia. In: D. Cicchetti (ed.) Developmental Psychopathology: Vol. 3 Maladaptation and Psychopathology (3rd ed., pp. 898–997). New York, Wiley. Chisholm, K., Lin, A., Abu-Akel, A. & Wood, S.J. (2015). The association between autism and schizophrenia spectrum disorders: A review of eight alternative models of cooccurrence. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews, 55, 173–183. Chudal, R., Joelsson, P., Gyllenberg, D., Lehti, V., Leivonen, S., Hinkka-Yli-Salomaki, S., Gissler, M. & Sourander, A. (2015). Parental age and the risk of attention-deficit/hyperactivity disorder: A nationwide, populationbased cohort study. Journal of the American Academy of Adolescent Psychiatry, 54(6), 487–494. Crespi, B.J. (2016). The evolutionary etiologies of autism spectrum and psychotic affective spectrum disorders. In: A. Alvergne, C. Jenkinson & C. Faurie (eds.) Evolutionary Thinking in Medicine: From Research to Policy and Practice (pp. 299–327). Switzerland: Springer. Crespi, B.J. (2019). Autism, psychosis, and genomic imprinting: Recent discoveries and conundrums. Current Opinion in Behavioral Sciences, 25, 1–7. Crespi, B.J. & Badcock, C. (2008). Psychosis and autism as diametrical disorders of the social brain. Behaviour and Brain Sciences, 31, 241–320. Crow, J.F. (2000). The origins, patterns, and implications of human spontaneous mutation. Nature Reviews Genetics, 1, 40–47. Crow, T.J. (1997). Is schizophrenia the price Homo sapiens pays for language? Schizophrenia Research, 28, 127–141.
DeGregori, J. (2018). Adaptive Oncogenesis: A New Understanding of How Cancer Evolves Inside Us. Cambridge, Massachusetts, Harvard University Press. Del Giudice, M. (2018). Evolutionary Psychopathology: A Unified Approach. New York, OUP. de Villiers, B., Lionetti, F. & Pluess, M. (2018). Vantage sensitivity: A framework for individual differences in response to psychological intervention. Social Psychiatry and Psychiatric Epidemiology. doi.org/ 10.1007/s00127-017-1471-0 D’Onofrio, B.M., Rickert, M.E., Franz, E., KujaHalkola, R., Almqvist, C., Sjolander, A., Larsson, H. & Lichtenstein, P. (2014). Parental age at childbearing and offspring psychiatric and academic morbidity. JAMA Psychiatry, 71, 432–438. Dudley, R. (2004). Ethanol, fruit ripening, and the historical origins of human alcoholism in primate frugivory. Integrative and Comparative Biology, 44(4), 315–323. Durisko, Z., Mulsant, B.H., McKenzie, K. & Andrews, P.W. (2016). Using evolutionary theory to guide mental health research. Canadian Journal of Psychiatry, 61(3), 159–165. Ek, M., Wicks, S., Svensson, A.C., Idring, S. & Dalman, C. (2014). Advancing paternal age and schizophrenia: The impact of delayed fatherhood. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 41(3), 708–714. Eley, T.C., Collier, D. & McGuffin, P. (2005). Anxiety and eating disorders. In: P. McGuffin, M.J. Owen & I. Gottesman (eds.) Psychiatric Genetics and Genomics (pp. 303–340). Oxford, OUP. Ellis, B.J., Shirtcliff, E.A., Boyce, W.T., Deardorff, J. & Essex, M.J. (2011). Quality of early family relationships and the timing and tempo of puberty: Effects depend on biological sensitivity to context. Developmental Psychopathology, 23, 85–99. Faer, L.M., Hendriks, A., Abed, R.T. & Figueredo, A.J. (2005). The evolutionary psychology of eating disorders: Female competition for mates or for status? Psychology and Psychotherapy, Theory, Research and Practice, 78, 397–417. Ferguson, C.J., Winegard, B. & Winegard, B.N. (2011). Who is the fairest of them all? How
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND PSYCHIATRY
evolution guides peer and media influences on female body dissatisfaction. Review of General Psychology, 15, 11–28. First, M.B. (2007). Potential implications of the harmful dysfunction analysis for the development of DSM-V and ICD-11. World Psychiatry, 6(3), 158–159. Fox, M. (2018). ‘Evolutionary medicine’ perspectives on Alzheimer’s disease: Review and new directions. Ageing Research Reviews, 47, 140–148. Fried, E.I. & Nesse, R.M. (2015). Depression is not a consistent syndrome: An investigation of unique symptom patterns in the STAR* D study. Journal of Affective Disorders, 172, 96–102. Fulford, K.W.M. & Thornton, T. (2007). Fanatical about ‘harmful dysfunction’. World Psychiatry, 6(3), 161–162. Gilbert, P. (2006). Evolution and depression: Issues and implications. Psychological Medicine, 36, 287–297. Gilbert, P., McEwan, K., Hay, J., Irons, C. & Cheung, M. (2007). Social rank and attachment in people with bipolar disorder. Clinical Psychology & Psychotherapy, 14, 48–53. Gluckman, P.D. & Hanson, M.A. (2006). Mismatch: The Lifestyle Diseases Timebomb. Oxford, OUP. Gluckman, P.D., Beedle, A.S. & Hanson, M.A. (2009). Principles of Evolutionary Medicine. OUP. Gordon, R.A. (1990). Anorexia and Bulimia: Anatomy of a Social Epidemic. Cambridge, Wiley-Blackwell. Guisinger, S. (2003). Adapted to flee famine: Adding an evolutionary perspective on anorexia nervosa. Psychological Review, 110, 745–761. Hagen, E.H. (2003). Depression as bargaining: The case postpartum. Evolution and Human Behavior, 23, 323–336. Hagen, E.H. (2011). Evolutionary theories of depression: A critical review. Canadian Journal of Psychiatry, 56(12), 716–726. Haig, D. (2014). Genetic dissent and individual compromise. Biology and Philosophy, 29, 233–239. Hare, E.H. & Moran, P.A. (1979). Raised parental age in psychiatric patients: Evidence for the constitutional hypothesis. British Journal of Psychiatry, 134, 169–177.
47
Hettema, J.M., Neale, M.C. & Kendler, K.S. (2001). A review and meta-analysis of genetic epidemiology of anxiety disorders. American Journal of Psychiatry, 158, 1568–1578. Homberg, J.R. & Lesch, K.P. (2011). Looking on the bright side of serotonin transporter gene variation. Biological Psychiatry, 69, 513–519. Horowitz, A.V. & Wakefield, J.C. (2007). The Loss of Sadness: How Psychiatry Transformed Normal Sorrow into Depressive Disorder. Oxford, OUP. Horrobin, D.F. (2001). The Madness of Adam and Eve: How Schizophrenia Shaped Humanity. Ealing, Bantam. Hudson, J.I., Hiripi, E., Pope, H.G. Jr. & Kessler, R.C. (2007). The prevalence and correlates of eating disorders in the national comorbidity survey replication. Biological Psychiatry, 61, 348–358. Humphrey, N. & Skoyles, J. (2012). The evolutionary psychology of healing: A human success story. Current Biology, 22(17), R695–R698. Huxley, J., Mayr, E., Osmond, H. & Hoffer, A. (1964). Schizophrenia is a genetic morphism. Nature, 204, 220–221. Insel, T. (2013). Transforming diagnosis. www. nimh.nih.gov/about/directors/thomas-insel/ blog/2013/transforming-diagnosis.shtml (accessed May 1st 2019). Jacquemont, S., Coe, B.P., Hersch, M., Duyzend, M.H., Krumm, N., Bergmann, S., Beckmann, J.S., Rosenfeld, J.L. & Eichler, E.E. (2014). A higher mutational burden in females supports a ‘female protective model’ in neurodevelopmental disorders. The American Journal of Human Genetics, 94, 415–425. Juda, M.N., Campbell, L. & Crawford, C.B. (2004). Dieting symptomatology in women and perceptions of social support. Evolution and Human Behavior, 25, 200–208. Kaiser, J. & Gruzelier, J.H. (1999). Timing of puberty and syndromes of schizotypy: A replication. International Journal of Psychophysiology, 34, 237–247. Katzman, M.A., Hermans, K.M.E., van Hoeken, D. & Hoek, H.W. (2004). Not your ‘typical island woman’: Anorexia nervosa is reported only in subcultures in Curaçao. Culture, Medicine and Psychiatry, 28, 463–492.
48
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Kavan, M.G. & Borone, E.J. (2014). Grief and major depression – controversy over changes in DSM-5 diagnostic criteria. American Family Physician, 90(10), 693–694. Keller, M.C. & Miller, G. (2006). Resolving the paradox of common, harmful, heritable mental disorders: Which evolutionary genetic models work best? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 29, 385–452. Kendler, K. (2001). Twin studies of psychiatric illness: An update. Archives of General Psychiatry, 58, 1005–1014. Kendler, K.S. & Eaves, L.J. (2005). Psychiatric Genetics. Arlington, American Psychiatric Publishing. Kendler, K.S. (2008). Explanatory models for psychiatric illness. American Journal of Psychiatry, 165, 695–702. Kinney, D.K., Teixeira, P., Hsu, D., Napoleon, S.C., Crowley, D.J. & Miller, A. (2009). Relation of schizophrenia prevalence to latitude, climate, fish consumption, infant mortality, and skin color: A role for prenatal vitamin D deficiency and infections? Schizophrenia Bulletin, 35, 582–595. Kristiansen, J.E. (1990). The antimicrobial activity of psychotherapeutic drugs and stereoisomeric analogues. Danish Medical Bulletin, 37(2), 165–182. Kuhn, T. (1962). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Li, N.P., Smith, A.R., Griskevicius, V., Cason, M.J. & Bryan, A. (2010). Intrasexual competition and eating restriction in heterosexual and homosexual individuals. Evolution and Human Behavior, 31, 365–372. Marr, D. (1982). Vision: A Computational Investigation into the Human Representation and Processing of Visual Information. San Francisco, WH Freeman. Martel, M.M. (2013). Sexual selection and sex differences in the prevalence of childhood externalizing and adolescent internalizing disorders. Psychological Bulletin, 139(6), 1221–1259. McCrae, R.R. & Costa, P.T. (2003). Personality in Adulthood: A Five-Factor Theory Perspective (2nd ed.). New York, Guilford. McGrath, J.J. (2006). Variations in incidence of schizophrenia: Data versus dogma. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 32, 195–197.
McGuire, M.T. & Troisi, A. (1998). Darwinian Psychiatry. New York: OUP. McQueen, D., Cohen, S., St John-Smith, P. & Rampes, H. (2013). Rethinking placebo in psychiatry: How and why placebo effects occur. Advances in Psychiatric Treatment, 19(3), 171–180. Mealey, L. (1995). The sociobiology of sociopathy: An integrated evolutionary model. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 18, 41–79. Mealey, L. (2000). Anorexia: A ‘losing’ strategy? Human Nature, 11, 105–116. Moir, R.D., Lathe, R. & Tanzi, R.E. (2018). The antimicrobial protection hypothesis of Alzheimer’s disease. Alzheimer’s & Dementia, 14, 1602–1614. Nesse, R.M. (2001). On the difficulty of defining disease: A Darwinian perspective. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy, 4, 37–46. Nesse, R.M. (2007). Evolution is the scientific foundation for diagnosis: Psychiatry should use it. World Psychiatry, 6(3), 160–161. Nesse, R.M. (2011). Ten questions for evolutionary studies of disease vulnerability. Evolutionary Applications, 4(2), 264–277. Nesse, R.M. (2013). Tinbergen’s four questions organized: A response to Bateson and Laland. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 28(12), 681–682. Nesse, R.M. (2019). Good Reasons for Bad Feelings: Insights from the Frontiers of Evolutionary Psychiatry. UK: Allen Lane. Nesse, R.M. & Stein, D.J. (2012). Towards a genuinely medical model for psychiatric nosology. BMC Medicine, 10(5), www. biomedcentral.com/1741-7015/10/5 Nesse, R.M. & Williams, G. (1994). Why We Get Sick: The New Science of Darwinian Medicine. New York, Times Books. Nettersheim, J., Gerlach, G., Herpertz, S., Abed, R., Figueredo, A.J. & Brüne, M. (2018). Evolutionary psychology of eating disorders: An explorative study of patients with anorexia nervosa and bulimia nervosa. Frontiers in Psychology, 9. doi: 10.3389/ fpsyg.2018.02122 Nettle, D. (2001). Strong Imagination: Madness, Creativity and Human Nature. Oxford: OUP. National Institute for Health and Care Excellence (2013). Schizophrenia: Omega-3 Fatty Acid Medicines. www.nice.org.uk/advice/esuom19/
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND PSYCHIATRY
chapter/key-points-from-the-evidence (accessed: February 1st 2019). Orsolini, L., St John-Smith, P., McQueen, D., Papanti, D., Corkery, J. & Schifano, F. (2017). Evolutionary considerations on the emerging subculture of the e-psychonauts and the novel psychoactive substances: A comeback to the shamanism? Current Neuropharmacology, 15(5), 731–737. Owen, M.J., Craddock, N. & Jablensky, A. (2007). The genetic deconstruction of Psychosis. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 33, 905–911. Pleuss, M. & Belsky, J. (2010) Children’s differential susceptibility to effects of parenting. Family Science, 1(1), 14–25. Plomin, R. (2018). Blueprint: How DNA Makes Us Who We Are. London: UK, Allen Lane. Polimeni, J. (2012). Shamans Among Us: Schizophrenia, Shamanism and the Evolutionary Origins of Religion. Boston: EvoEbooks. Power, R.A., Kyaga, S., Uher, R., McCabe, J.H., Langstrom, N., Landen, M., McGuffin, P., Lewis, C.M., Lichtenstein, P. & Svenson, A.C. (2013). Fecundity of patients with schizophrenia, autism, bipolar disorder, depression, anorexia nervosa, or substance abuse vs their unaffected siblings. JAMA Psychiatry, 70, 22–30. Price, J.C., Sloman, L., Gardner, R., Gilbert, P. & Rohde, P. (1994). The social competition hypothesis of depression. British Journal of Psychiatry, 164(3), 309–315. Rantala, M.J., Luoto, S., Krams, I. & Karlsson, H. (2018). Depression subtyping based on evolutionary psychiatry: Proximate mechanisms and ultimate functions. Brain, Behavior and Immunity, 69, 603–617. Richardson, G., Chen, C-C., Dai, C-L., Swoboda, C.M., Nedelec, J.L. & Chen, W-W. (2017). Substance use and mating success. Evolution and Human Behavior, 38(1), 48–57. Roshchina, V.V. (2010). Evolutionary considerations of neurotransmitters in microbial, plant, and animal cells. In: M. Lyte & P.P.E. Freestone (eds.) Microbial Endocrinology – Interkingdom Signaling in Infectious Disease and Health (pp. 17–52). Cham: Springer. Rottenberg, J. (2014). The Depths: The Evolutionary Origins of the Depression Epidemic. New York, Basic Books. Russell, A.E., Ford, T. & Russell, G. (2015). Socioeconomic associations with ADHD: Findings
49
from a mediation analysis. PLOS One, 10, e0128248. Russell, G., Ford, T., Rosenberg, R. & Kelly, S. (2014). The association of attention deficit hyperactivity disorder with socioeconomic disadvantage: Alternative explanations and evidence. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 55, 436–445. Shaner, A., Miller, G. & Mintz, J. (2004). Schizophrenia as one extreme of a sexually selected fitness indicator. Schizophrenia Research, 94, 58–63. Singh, D. (1993). Adaptive significance of female physical attractiveness: Role of waistto-hip ratio. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 65, 293–307. Stearns, S.C. (1992). The Evolution of Life Histories. New York: OUP. Stevens, A. & Price, J. (2000a). Evolutionary Psychiatry: A New Beginning (2nd ed.) London, Routledge. Stevens, A. & Price, J.S. (2000b). Prophets, Cults and Madness. London, Duckworth. St John-Smith, P., McQueen, D., Edwards, L. & Schifano, F. (2013). Classical and novel psychoactive substances: Rethinking drug misuse from an evolutionary psychiatric perspective. Human Psychopharmacology: Clinical and Experimental, 28, 394–401. Stohler, H.R. (1978). RO 11-3128 – a novel schistosomicidal compound. Vol. 1 Proceedings of the 10th International Congress of Chemotherapy (pp. 147–148). Washington DC, American Society for Microbiology. Sullivan, R.J., Hagen, E.H. & Hammerstein, P. (2008). Revealing the paradox of drug reward in human evolution. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 275, 1231–1241. Surbey, M.K. (1987). Anorexia nervosa, amenorrhea, and adaptation. Ethology Sociobiology, 8, 47–61. Symons, D. (1995). Beauty is in the adaptation of the beholder. In: P.R. Abramson & S.D. Pinkerson (eds.) Sexual Nature, Sexual Culture (pp. 80–118). Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Tinbergen, N. (1963). On the aims and methods of ethology. Zeitschrift fur Tierpsychologie, 20, 410–433. Tooby, J. & Cosmides, L. (1999). Toward an evolutionary taxonomy of treatable conditions.
50
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 108(3), 453–464. Troisi, A. (2001). Gender differences in vulnerability to social stress: A Darwinian perspective. Physiology & Behavior, 73, 443–449. Troisi, A. (2012). Mental health and well-being: Clinical applications of Darwinian psychiatry. Applied Evolutionary Psychology. doi: 10.1093/ acprof:oso/9780199586073.003.0017 Troisi, A. (2015). The evolutionary diagnosis of mental disorder. WIREs Cognitive Science, 6, 323–331. Trull, T.J. & Widiger, T.A. (2013). Dimensional models of personality: The five-factor model and the DSM-5. Dialogues in Clinical Neuroscience, 15(2), 135–146. Tsuang, M., Taylor, L. & Faraone, S. (2003). Psychiatric genetics: Future and prospects. In: M. Leboyer & F. Bellivier (eds.) Psychiatric Genetics: Methods and Reviews (pp. 251– 265). Totwa, NJ: Humana Press. Vining, D.R. (1986). Social versus reproductive success: The central theoretical problem of human sociobiology. Behavior and Brain Sciences, 9, 167–216. Voland, E. & Voland, R. (1989). Evolutionary biology and psychiatry: The case of anorexia nervosa. Ethology Sociobiology, 10, 223–240. Von Gunten, A., Clerc, M-T., Tomar, R. & St John-Smith, P. (2018). Evolutionary considerations on aging and Alzheimer’s disease. Journal of Alzheimers Disease and Parkinsonism, 8(1). doi: 10.4172/2161-0460.1000423 Von Helversen, B., Wilke, A., Johnson, T., Schmid, G. & Klapp, B. (2011). Performance benefits of depression: Sequential decision making in a healthy sample and a clinically depressed sample. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 120, 962–968.
Wakefield, J.C. (1992). The concept of mental disorder: On the boundary between biological facts and social values. American Psychologist, 47, 373–388. Wakefield, J.C. (2014). Wittgenstein’s nightmare: Why the RDoC grid needs a conceptual dimension. World Psychiatry, 13(1), 38–40. Wasser, S.K. & Barash, D.P. (1983). Reproductive suppression among female mammals: Implications for biomedicine and sexual selection theory. Quarterly Review of Biology, 58, 513–538. Watson, P. & Andrews, P. (2002). Toward a revised evolutionary adaptationist analysis of depression: The social navigation hypothesis. Journal of Affective Disorders, 72, 1–14. White, T.P., Borgan, F., Ralley, O. & Shergill, S.S. (2016). Are you looking at me? Interpreting social cues in schizophrenia. Psychological Medicine, 46, 149–160. Wilkinson, L.S., Davies, W. & Isles, A.R. (2007). Genomic imprinting effects on brain development and function. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 8, 832–843. Williams, G. (1957). Pleiotropy, natural selection, and the evolution of senescence. Evolution, 11(4), 398–411. World Health Organization (1992). ICD-10. Geneva, World Health Organization. Yeo, R.A., Gangestad, S.W., Edgar, C. & Thoma, R. (1999). The evolutionary genetic underpinnings of schizophrenia: The developmental instability model. Schizophrenia Research, 39, 197–206. Yilmaz, Z., Hardaway, J.A. & Bulik, C.M. (2015). Genetics and epigenetics of eating disorders. Advances in Genomics and Genetics, 5, 131–150.
3 Evolutionary Psychology and Suicidology J o h n F. G u n n I I I , P a b l o M a l o , a n d C . A . S o p e r
As of patch 7.822, androids can no longer shut themselves down. Reason: they just kept doing it at the slightest inconvenience – @ctrlcreep, quoted by Perry (2016).
SUICIDE, SUICIDOLOGY AND EVOLUTION Suicide, ‘the act of deliberately killing oneself’ (World Health Organization, 2014: 12), takes about 800,00 lives each year, and accounts for some 1.4% of human deaths: more of us die by our own hands than from wars, terrorism, and all other forms of homicides put together (World Health Organization, 2013). Millions more of the living are affected – bereaved families, friends, and carers left to deal with the aftermath of others’ self-destruction (Cerel et al., 2019). Around the world, suicide is acknowledged to be a major, and presumed preventable, cause of misery and death, and an important public health
challenge (Satcher, 1999; World Health Organization, 2012, 2014). Indeed, a new multi-disciplinary field of research emerged in the second half of the 20th century, suicidology, focused on tackling the problem (American Association of Suicidology, 2019; Shneidman, 2001). But, frustratingly, decades of effort have produced only patchy progress. The global suicide rate has fallen in recent years, but it is not clear why (it may be because of generally improved population health rather than special prevention initiatives) and wide unexplained differences in rates and trends persist (Naghavi, 2019). In the United States, for example, the rate is probably the same now as it was 100 years ago, and seems to be rising (Hedegaard et al., 2018; Nock et al., 2019). Rival theories of suicide have accumulated by the dozens,1 but none has won a consensus of support, and suicide’s causation remains a scientific mystery (Lester, 2019; Nock, Borges, and Ono, 2012; Soper, 2019a). The disarray is such that a recent meta-review describes
52
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
suicidology as ‘still in a preparadigmatic phase’ (Franklin et al., 2017: 188) – that is, still in its infancy. There may at least be the beginnings of a consensus that the proper place for the scientific study of suicide is alongside other modern life sciences – within an evolutionary paradigm. This vision can be traced across generations of researchers. A century ago, in the evolutionist spirit of his time, Freud (1920/1991) hypothesized a potentially suicidogenic ‘death drive’ as an extension of his theory of libido, a framework inspired by the Darwinian premise that selection depends on sexual success (Gilbert, 1989; Litman, 1967; Tolaas, 2005). But psychoanalysis failed to find a satisfactory explanation for suicide, at least according to Freud’s contemporaries (Zilboorg, 1936a) – debate continues (Goldblatt, 2014; Selby et al., 2014). And although other ideas have been floated since, as we will see, suicide remains an evolutionary puzzle (Aubin et al., 2013; Blasco-Fontecilla et al., 2009; Confer et al., 2010). On the face of it, self-killing defies the rule of thumb for winning the struggle for existence: survive and reproduce. Darwin himself told us, ‘Natural selection will never produce in a being anything injurious to itself, for natural selection acts solely by and for the good of each’ (1859: 201). Yet here we are, scions of selection but with a more or less steady percentage of us taking our own lives. How could so self-destructive a propensity have come about? Why has it persisted? And what can we do about it? Searching for answers, this chapter critically reviews prominent evolutionary thinking in the field. We find tentative signs of progress. Focusing on recent proposals, we will discuss in particular a new ‘painand-brain’ framework – that suicide likely evolved as an evolutionary by-product of social pain and human cognition (Gunn, 2017; Humphrey, 2011, 2018; Soper, 2018) – which may offer a basis for convergence in suicide theory and, it is hoped, new prospects for saving lives.
The Need for Evolutionary Explanation of Suicide A preliminary question is whether evolution is at all relevant to suicide. Many human activities can be viewed not as products of selection but as exemplars of our behavioral flexibility: to some extent we are free to do as we will despite having biological drives (Sarkar, 1998). Perhaps suicide is one such behavior (deCatanzaro, 1980). At a proximal level of understanding (Tinbergen, 1963) such an answer might suffice. But there are at least three reasons to believe that evolution by natural selection is not just relevant but essential for making sense of the phenomenon (Soper, 2018). First, we can deduce that suicide is under the control of selection because the behavior presents the full trio of handles – (a) heritability, (b) variability, and (c) a differential effect on fitness – with which selection takes hold of any trait (Darwin, 1859). Suicidality (a) tends to cluster strongly in families, with at least some genetically heritable component (Mullins et al., 2019; Tidemalm et al., 2011). Suicide risk (b) varies markedly across and between groups of humans (e.g., De Leo et al., 2013; Schmidtke, 1997; Voracek and Marušič, 2008). And (c) if death is usually calamitous for an organism’s reproductive prospects, death by one’s own hand is predictably even worse because of special social, economic, and psychological penalties imposed on suicides’ kin (Wertheimer, 2014), a matter we will explore. The point to note for now is that, with these three levers, selection would be expected powerfully to promote the offspring of the less suicidal, eventually driving the potential for suicide out of the human genotype. But selection has evidently not done this, and the apparent anomaly calls for an account. The second reason for seeking evolutionary explanation is that suicide is endemic across the human population. As far as can be known, no sizeable region, culture, or historical era is exempt (Bering, 2018; Fedden, 1938;
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND SUICIDOLOGY
Mishara, 2006). Where suicide is not directly observable it can be inferred, as Durkheim (1897/1952) points out, from the fresh imprint it leaves in universal, or near universal, antisuicide moralities: suicide presumably posed enough of a societal threat in the past to warrant proscribing. Importantly, suicide’s ubiquity extends to preliterate and huntergatherer societies (Steinmetz, 1894; Syme et al., 2016; Tousignant, 1998; Zilboorg, 1936b), which indicates ancient roots: it is no mere novelty of modern conditions. Such universal human traits were probably in place at the time of ancient human migrations out of Africa, and likely follow an unbroken line of descent (Brown, 2004; Kappeler et al., 2010). The curiosity is that, as Darwin (1859) deduced, features that confer no selective advantage tend to phase out over time, hence the disappearance of the hind limbs of cetaceans and flying wings of some island birds. There is no evidence of degeneration of suicidality, a continuity that tells us that selection has positively held the capacity for suicide in place – that is, for some evolutionary reason. Third, suicide is almost certainly a uniquely human phenomenon. It is right to keep an open mind (Peña-Guzmán, 2018), but there is scant evidence – none that meets a scientific standard – that any other animal deliberately takes its own life (Bering, 2018; Comai and Gobbi, 2016; Maltsberger, 2003; Preti, 2007). Absence of evidence is not evidence of absence, of course. But the absence of scientific evidence speaks volumes in the context of animal suicide because there are at least three reasons to believe that, if such evidence existed, we could reasonably expect it to have found its way into a peerreviewed publication by now. First, centuries of concerted scientific enquiry have offered ample opportunities to observe nonhuman suicide – if it were there to be observed (Ramsden and Wilson, 2010). Chimpanzees, for example – our nearest living cousins and hence arguably the species in which suicide is most likely to be found – have been studied particularly closely; but as Bering
53
(2018) notes, no distraught chimp has been seen, say, to climb to the highest available branch and jump. Experimental set-ups have been devised that could in principle demonstrate nonhuman suicides under laboratory conditions, but there are no reports of positive results (Lester, 2017; Schaeffer, 1967). Secondly, there is no lack of motivation to find evidence: discovery of an animal model of suicide would likely attract intense popular interest, and catch the eye of a well-resourced pharmaceutical industry keen to test whether suicide risk is affected by drugs (Malkesman et al., 2009; Preti, 2011). Thirdly, if nonhumans could suicide, then it would raise the question not of whether they do, but why it is not commonplace behavior (Soper and Shackelford, 2018). Life in the Malthusian arena of natural selection, a relentless struggle to survive and reproduce, is intrinsically not pleasant. Combatants face pain, hunger, thirst, rejection, defeat, disease, and whatever other privation. An animal that knew it could escape hardship by removing itself from the battlefield would fairly be expected do so. In other words, nonhuman suicide, if it were possible at all, ought to be not so rare as to elude scientific discovery but a routine outcome of animal suffering.2 In any event, aside from absence of evidence, there are positive grounds for doubting in principle that any nonhuman could be capable of suicide. The required intention – self-induced death of the self – presumes an understanding of personal mortality, a conceptual abstraction that is demonstrably beyond the grasp of prepubescent humans (Kastenbaum, 1967; Seiden, 1969; Slaughter and Griffiths, 2007; Soper, 2018) let alone of less intellectually sophisticated animals (Anil et al., 1996; Bracke, 1992). An adult chimp, said to be the smartest nonhuman, might match the deductive powers of, at most, a 4- or 5-year-old child (O’Connell and Dunbar, 2003), but the mind of a typical 5-yearold child brain must develop over as many years again, and more, before it is capable of conceiving and organizing deliberate selfkilling (Mishara, 1999; Shaffer, 1974; Soper,
54
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
2018). In sum, suicide is evidently unique to our species, an exceptionality that presents a further call for an evolutionary account: the behavior likely arose in the course of speciation, at or after our phylogenetic path diverged from that of our extant primate cousins.
The Fitness Costs of Suicide So, suicide calls for evolutionary explanation. The main difficulty with formulating an explanation, we suggest, is not so much that behavior is self-injurious: many evolved traits can have self-injurious effects while being fitness-enhancing overall (Williams, 1996). The special problem is that suicide is self-injurious to an extraordinary degree. From a genetic viewpoint, suicide is literally a fate worse than death. Whether an attempt is lethal or survived, multiple and severe fitness
penalties predictably follow, as can be seen from Table 3.1. If the attempt is fatal (the upper section of the table), then the fitness consequences of dying (dying generally, that is – not specifically by one’s own hand) ripple out from the individual also to harm close relations and the wider kin and social group (Duntley, 2005). Heading the costs schedule (Item 1) is the fitness catastrophe of forfeiting future opportunities for procreation. It is hard to overstate this loss. For semelparous species (they breed only once, such as Pacific salmon) death may carry little or no genetic downside after their reproductive phase is complete (Cole, 1954). But for iteroparous species (geared for multiple rounds of breeding), such as virtually all mammals, including humans, the cost of dying is severe, as can be inferred from the lengths gone to avoid it. Most higher faunas are overridingly protective of their reproductive potential, however
Table 3.1 The fitness costs of suicide Lethal attempt Death generally: (Daly and Wilson, 1988; Duntley, 2005; Duntley and Buss, 1. Ends prospects of producing more offspring. 2004; Lankford, 2015) 2. Ends ability to invest in existing offspring. 3. Ends ability to support co-parent in their raising of existing offspring. 4. Ends further prospects of investing in reproductive success of other close relations (kin selection). 5. May deprive group of skills, experience, manpower. 6. May destabilize group’s power and allegiance structures. Suicide specifically: (Andoh-Arthur et al., 2019; Bohannan, 1960; Chapple 7. Distancing and other special economic and social et al., 2015; Fedden, 1938; Grad and Andriessen, 2016; costs for offspring and other close kin: loss of status, Hanschmidt et al., 2016; Healey, 1979; Hezel et al., 1985; resources, mating opportunities. Mugisha et al., 2011; Poole, 1985) 8. Special psychological and emotional problems for (Bolton et al., 2013; Cerel and Aldrich, 2011; Erlangsen et al., offspring and other close kin; increased risk of 2017; Grad and Andriessen, 2016; Jordan, 2008; Pitman psychopathology and suicide. et al., 2014; Sveen and Walby, 2008; Wertheimer, 2014) Survived attempt 9. Risk of death by suicide (costs as above). 10. Prospect of physical injury and/or disfigurement, (Gandhi et al., 2006; Kahne, 1966; Kennedy et al., 1999; Penney possibly permanent and/or serious. et al., 2002; Persley and Pegg, 1981; Salim et al., 2006) 11. Negative emotional sequelae: guilt, shame, psychological (Akotia et al., 2014; Kahne, 1966; Mehlum and Mork, 2016; trauma, heightened risk of further suicide attempts. Stanley et al., 2019) 12. Social stigmatization: distancing, loss of status, loss of (Bering, 2018; Brown, 1986; Frey et al., 2015; Kahne, 1966; mating opportunities. Knizek et al., 2013; Lester, 1993; Saunders et al., 2012; Sheehan et al., 2016; Sudak et al., 2008)
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND SUICIDOLOGY
slight. In extremis, when their own survival is endangered, they will kill even offspring or siblings to preserve the capacity to procreate (Hausfater and Hrdy, 1984; O’Connor, 1978). Iteroparity helps to explain why intentional self-killing is not found among other animals (Lankford, 2015): in the Darwinian competition to survive and reproduce, the organism’s death spells genetic ‘game over’. Item 2, death ends the organism’s ability to invest in existing progeny. The ill-timed death of a parent can seriously compromise the reproductive prospects of offspring – for our species more than others in view of the protracted dependency of human childhood. Disadvantage appears to be a cross-cultural outcome: even in, or especially in, pre-industrial societies, children bereaved of one or both parents face life with fewer resources and die younger as a consequence (Bailey, 2009; Geary, 2005). Death also closes off the possibility of helping a surviving co-parent in their task of raising the individual’s children (Item 3). The widow/ er, with their own survival needs to meet, may be less able or less willing to care for the dead partner’s young. If the surviving parent pairs with a new mate, the deceased’s offspring are exposed to a new set of hazards at the hands of a step-parent, who will have competing genetic interests (Daly and Wilson, 1988). More broadly, Item 4, death ends the individual’s ability to invest labor, skills, and experience towards the reproductive success of other family members and the wider kin group, people whose offspring could propagate the individual’s genetic material indirectly (Duntley, 2005). Wider still, multilevel selection (Wilson and Wilson, 2007) would be expected to disfavor mortality with or without kinship relations: death ends an individual’s contributions to the competitive success of the individual’s group (Item 5); and as Duntley (2005) notes (6), a death may create a power vacuum that could destabilize a group’s organization and possibly unravel a whole network of allegiances. Clearly, it is ‘bad to be dead’ (Duntley and Buss, 2004: 107). But the fitness costs
55
of intentional self-killing do not end there, because there are extra, special, penalties for kin bereaved specifically in this way. Table 3.1 groups these consequences, perhaps arbitrarily, into rejection and other social sequelae (Item 7), and psychological injuries (Item 8). The first of these, involving often exemplary punishments for a suicide’s relations, seems to be a cross-cultural phenomenon linked to a virtually universal abhorrence of the act (Andoh-Arthur et al., 2019; Bohannan, 1960; Fedden, 1938; Hezel et al., 1985). In the West, people bereaved by suicide report being stigmatized – distanced as if they were tainted or contaminated by association (Chapple et al., 2015). Harsher penalties are found elsewhere. Among the Baganda in Uganda, for example, close kin of suicides face disinheritance, termination of their familial lineage, burning of their homes, and exile (Mugisha et al., 2011). And then there is the noxious psychological fallout, sometimes lethal, manifest in markedly higher rates of mental illness and suicidality among suicides’ families (Erlangsen et al., 2017; Jordan, 2008; Pitman et al., 2014, 2016; Wertheimer, 2014). Importantly, dire fitness costs predictably follow a suicide attempt even if it is survived, as indicated by the lower section of Table 3.1. Aside from (9) risking suicidal death with its accompanying genetic forfeits as already discussed, a suicide attempt can be expected to injure and/or disfigure the actor (Item 10). The damage may be permanent and/or serious. For example, jumping from bridges, roofs, etc. often results in paraplegia (Kennedy et al., 1999), and suicide attempts by pregnant women associate with consequent maternal and perinatal morbidity and sometimes perinatal death (Gandhi et al., 2006). Injuries sustained in a suicide attempt can be psychological as well as physical, and are often traumatic (Item 11): a quarter of suicide attempters in a recent study screened positive for post-traumatic stress disorder resulting directly from their attempts (Stanley et al., 2019). People who have tried
56
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
to kill themselves are affected by intrusive feelings of shame and blame (Akotia et al., 2014; Mehlum and Mork, 2016), and are at a heightened risk of making further attempts (Turecki and Brent, 2016). Finally (Item 12), attempters face distancing social attitudes, even from professionals charged with helping them, and from close family members (Frey et al., 2015; Kahne, 1966; Knizek et al., 2013; Saunders et al., 2012). The stigma may impair reproductive fitness most directly via sexual deselection, as Bering (2018) points out: a replicated study found that people would rather, all else equal, marry someone they loved even from a marginalized ethnic group or dying of cancer in preference to someone they loved who had recently tried to take their own life (Lester, 1993). Table 3.1, a grim catalogue as it stands, may not be exhaustive. Clearly, in fitness terms, suicide is exceptionally costly. This is a central point to note, because in order for the trait to have become a genetic fixture it presumably associates with a commensurately powerful fitness benefit. The challenge, taken up by several theorists in recent decades, is to try to identify this countervailing upside, as we will now review. In the following sections, various proposals are organized into three headings – modern evolutionary theory allowing three ways, and only three, by which any characteristic can propagate genetically across generations (Tooby and Cosmides, 1990b; Williams, 1966). A trait that has no effect on fitness can sometimes arrive in isolated populations by chance and then fix, as background genetic ‘noise’, for lack of selective pressure against it (Wright, 1943); or a trait may propagate as an adaptation, directly selected for its fitnessenhancing effect; or it may spread not as an adaptation but as a by-product of some other feature that is adaptive overall, notwithstanding its side effects. We will discuss these three in turn, reaching the provisional conclusion that suicide appears best to fit the third type of explanation – a harmful by-product of an adaptation.
‘NOISE’ THEORIES Could suicide be the kind of useless trait that sometimes spreads in isolated populations by happenstance? On the face of it, probably not: it is hard to conceive of suicide as trivial in its fitness impact, and the phenomenon is not restricted to isolated groups. Nonetheless, an interesting ‘noise’-type theory warrants scrutiny. DeCatanzaro (1980, 1981, 1986) – a sociobiologist, and the first writer to explore the evolution of suicide in depth – suggests that people who have no prospects of producing further offspring may kill themselves for want of biological reason to stay alive: they are already genetically dead. The idea links to the principle of senescence (Dawkins, 1980; Williams, 1957): if an organism has no reproductive future, then any subsequently emergent trait may have no fitness effect. Perhaps suicide may be one such condition, a nonselected behavior that, according to deCatanzaro, may express particularly among elderly bachelors. He compares their fate to that of the semelparous salmon we mentioned earlier: once their procreative work is done, they die. The proposal that low reproductive potential may drive or open the door to suicide has sparked interest among other theorists (Campbell, 2002; Saad, 2007), and it finds some empirical support (deCatanzaro, 1980, 1981, 1982, 1986, 1991; Soper, 2018). But there are forceful objections (Bering, 2018; Lankford, 2015; Lester, 2014b; Rubinstein, 1986; Soper, 2018; Wright, 1994). We highlight three. First, as already noted, humans are not semelparous: like virtually all mammals, we are designed for multiple episodes of reproduction. Although fertility declines with age, species-typical men remain potentially able to father offspring throughout adulthood, and would hence be expected to avoid self-killing at almost any stage of life (Bribiescas, 2006; Lankford, 2015). Second, the hypothesis is empirically contraindicated by much of the epidemiology (Lester, 2014b). For example, suicides around the world are characterized more by youth
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND SUICIDOLOGY
than old age, occurring more among under45s than older (Värnik, 2012), and the demographic most at risk of trying to take their own lives are not old men but young women (Nock, Borges, Bromet et al., 2012), people whose reproductive careers could be assumed to lie ahead of them. At the other extreme, populations with certainly zero direct reproductive prospects – post-menopausal women, and castrated men – are not reported to be particularly suicidal (Usall et al., 2009; Wilson and Roehrborn, 1999). Third is a general problem for ‘genetic noise’ explanations for suicide: unselected traits are very unlikely to promote survival, but they would also be vanishingly unlikely to produce willful self-killing, or any other specific pattern of behavior for that matter (Soper, 2018). The lifting of selection would be predicted, rather, simply to let the second law of thermodynamics prevail. Spawned salmon, a case in point, don’t deliberately kill themselves – they carry on, for example, trying to evade predators: rather, depleted of energy, they disintegrate. For suicide to eventuate, some canalizing process would be needed to shape that particular outcome. The key to understanding the evolutionary origins of suicide probably lies in identifying this special suicidogenic system rather than in random genetic dynamics.
ADAPTATION THEORIES Adaption-type explanations of suicide draw on a cluster of connected tenets of modern evolutionary theory: inclusive fitness, kin selection, and altruism. Inclusive fitness recognizes that direct reproduction isn’t the only way an individual’s genetic material can pass into future generations: facilitating reproduction by others who share the individual’s genes can have the same result. For humans, as other mammals, direct offspring carry half of the organism’s genes (one equivalent) while a sibling’s child carries a quarter of the
57
organism’s genes (half equivalent), and so on. Genetic success, then, depends not on the number of direct offspring an organism produces, but the number of offspring equivalents, direct or not (Hamilton, 1964). Kin selection is the favoring of an organism’s relations in the interests of inclusive fitness, even if this endangers the survival or direct reproduction of the organism (Maynard Smith, 1964). Behaviors that display apparent altruism may therefore be genetically self-serving: organisms that act altruistically may advantage the survival and reproduction of kin which, due to genetic relatedness, may pass on to their offspring the genes responsible for the altruism. Since, for mammals at least, death is assuredly unhelpful for direct reproduction, adaptationist explanations of suicide hypothesize reproductive payoffs to be had via such indirect routes. An often cited example of kin selection as it supposedly relates to suicide is the seemingly altruistic, but genetically selfish, responses of worker bees, ants, and other social insects when under attack (e.g., Shorter and Rueppell, 2012). A caveat: although etymologists informally talk of ‘suicide’ in the context of insect behaviors, use of the word should not be taken to signal equivalence with human self-killings (Lankford, 2015; Soper, 2018). There are important and categorical differences. One stems from the special familial structure of social insects: in a colony composed largely of non-reproducing siblings, and where only one queen is permitted to reproduce, there may be genetically little to lose and much to gain in sacrificing an individual sibling in the colony’s defense (Alexander, 1974; Hamilton, 1972) – inclusive fitness logic that does not apply to virtually all mammals, including humans. To view ant ‘suicide’ as at all self-destructive is to superimpose inappropriately onto biology a folk notion of the ‘self’: the biological ‘self’ for ants may be more usefully viewed as the colony, operating as a super-organism, rather than the individual insect. Helpful analogies for ant ‘suicide’ would include, not literal (human) suicide, but programed cell death, the
58
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
shedding of a tree’s leaves in the fall, or a lizard self-amputating its tail to escape attack, these being losses of comparable genetic inconsequence (Dawkins, 1976; Hamilton, 1980; Lankford, 2015). Nonetheless, insect behaviors demonstrate that survival isn’t always an overriding biological imperative: as deCatanzaro (1992) points out, there are ‘evolutionary limits to self-preservation’. Developing this theme, deCatanzaro provides most of suicidology’s adaptationist literature (e.g., 1980, 1981, 1986, 1991), seeking to fill the theoretical gap noted in the previous section – the need for some canalizing process that produces suicide as a specific outcome. He suggests that human self-killing may be adaptive where a burdensome individual’s death advantages the reproductive prospects of close kin. DeCatanzaro (1986) went on to express this idea as a mathematical formula for a tipping point at which an individual’s genetic interests would be served by self-removal. This calculation, he argues, may shed light not just on self-killings but on attempted suicide, self-sacrificial military actions, and risk-taking behavior. Following this lead, other theorists assert that inclusive fitness logic may explain suicide as a genetically adaptive strategy aimed at protecting kin from infection or infestation (Tanaka and Kinney, 2011) or from internecine conflict (Riordan, 2019); and potentially to account for suicide terrorism (Gallup and Weedon, 2013). Still others suggest that processes of multi-level selection, in which a group’s competitive success may be furthered by the altruistic behavior of its members whether genetically related or not, may offer adaptive logic for extreme acts of heroism in battlefield situations (Orbell and Morikawa, 2011). Some theorists offer a ‘mismatch’ variation on the adaptation idea; that suicide may not be adaptive in current conditions but, as fossil behavior carried over from ancient environments, it might have been adaptive in the past (Aubin et al., 2013; deCatanzaro, 1980, 1981). Self-killing as a way to relieve kin of the burden of one’s existence is the most
prominent adaptationist idea in suicide research (Aubin et al., 2013; Bering, 2018; Soper, 2018; Syme et al., 2016). Brown and colleagues, for example, develop deCatanzaro’s proposals and offer supportive empirical evidence (Brown et al., 1999, 2009). As other researchers also record, various measures of burdensomeness do correlate with suicidal thinking and behavior (Chu et al., 2017; Lester, 2014b) – although, it should be noted, not strongly and no more strongly than do many other risk factors (Franklin et al., 2017). Further empirical support might arguably be found in ethnographic reports from some tribal societies where a group member too frail to survive the next season or journey may sometimes take part in ritualized assisted suicide, although this practice is not common (Falger and Falger, 2003). These are all intriguing ideas. But the state of play is that, after four decades, there are no signs of a scientific consensus forming around the conception of suicide as the adaptive removal of unsupportable kin (Bering, 2018; Lester, 2014b; Soper, 2018). There are multiple empirical contraindications, including high notable suicidality among young adults (De Leo et al., 2013), the gifted and talented (Delisle, 1986; Voracek, 2006), people with high incomes (Goldsmith et al., 2002) and others who, it can be presumed, are unlikely to be among the most burdensome members of their families. The general difficulty we perceive is a lack of compelling evidence of special design – a precise match between observable form and biological function that is the hallmark of adaptation: Evolutionary adaptation is a special and onerous concept that should not be used unnecessarily, and an effect should not be called a function unless it is clearly produced by design… (Williams, 1966, vii)
Three disconnects will illustrate the problem. First, is the absence of a causal connector between suicide as the means and the end
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND SUICIDOLOGY
it is supposed to achieve: it is unclear why the task of removing an individual should call for suicide in preference to other solutions that have stronger genetic logic (Bering and Shackelford, 2004). If an individual has to be removed, there is no particular reason to expect that removal to necessitate a killing: abandonment, quarantine, or exile, say, would achieve the same objective, with the advantage of preserving at least provisionally the individual’s reproductive capability (Wright, 1994). And even if a killing would be in a conspecific’s reproductive interests, the expectable outcome is still not suicide: the killing would more logically be done by that conspecific, who has likely better information and genetically more to gain (O’Connor, 1978; Skinner, 1969; Soper, 2018). Indeed the empirical evidence among humans and other species points to infanticide or fratricide, rather than suicide, as the way unsupportable kin are removed (Dickeman, 1975; Harris, 1974; Hrdy, 1979; O’Connor, 1978). Second, it is doubtful in principle whether a biological stimulus could exist that would trigger suicide as an adaptive response. Perry (2015) presumes that if an organism is to decide whether or not life is genetically worth continuing, then it would need to be equipped with some kind of ‘inclusive fitness monitor’ that can compare the reproductive value of life overall versus death. For sure, sophisticated measuring devices have been proposed elsewhere by evolutionists, such as a ‘sociometer’ that may alert the organism to threats to social supports (Leary and Guadagno, 2011; Leary et al., 1995). But Soper (2018) argues that a serviceable ‘inclusive fitness monitor’ would entail an altogether higher order of complexity; it would need to take a view on, among other things, current and future kin members’ reproductive prospects and the future carrying capacities of their environments. He claims that it would be so all-encompassing that it would lack the specific input–output associations to which selection responds. Modern theory holds that such a general-purpose mechanism
59
is unlikely to evolve (Symons, 1992; Tooby and Cosmides, 1990b). Third, given the severity of costs outlined in Table 3.1, the hypothesized benefits accruing via kin or group selection seem to fall decisively short, in power and reliability, of what would be required to justify self-killing as a fitness investment. The suggested payoffs are highly contingent, it being far from certain that the reproduction of an individual’s family or group would improve as a consequence (Lankford, 2013). On the contrary: Table 3.1 suggests that suicide can be predicted to add to, not lift, reproductive difficulties for those left behind. Summing up, it is hard to argue that suicide shows marks of special design. At the margins, some writers suggest possible adaptive functionality in heroic deeds in battle and similar emergencies, which might be classed as ‘altruistic suicide’ following Durkheim’s (1897/1952) nosology (Humphrey, 2018; Orbell and Morikawa, 2011). Other writers question the usefulness of ‘altruistic suicide’ as a concept (Johnson, 1965; Townsend, 2007). The phenomenon is unusual, as Durkheim himself acknowledged. And it may not anyway help to class as ‘suicide’ acts where killing of the self is not of itself the primary intention, but where, rather, death happens incidentally in pursuit of some other endeavor (Lankford, 2013). For these reasons Soper (2018) argues that battlefield scenarios are unlikely to shed light on private, solo self-killing – what Cholbi (2017) calls ‘runof-the-mill’ suicide – which probably is not and never would have been adaptive.
‘BY-PRODUCT’ THEORIES With only three types of evolutionary explanations available, and if suicide cannot be credibly ascribed to the first two (that is, it probably evolved neither as noise nor as an adaptation), then Soper (2018) argues that whatever remains has prima facie appeal.
60
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Explicitly or implicitly, several theories fall into this third category, characterizing suicide not as adaptive but as a noxious side effect of some other trait that, despite the severe cost of suicidality, is adaptive in the round. The following section reviews prominent ideas of this type.
Pleiotropy The idea of senescence, as we discussed in above, did not seem to carry us far in understanding suicide. But senescence is a special case of a broader genetic phenomenon, pleiotropy, which may take us further (Williams, 1992; Wilson, 1980). Pleiotropy occurs where genes express in the same individual in multiple phylogenetic outcomes, some beneficial, some harmful. Particularly if a beneficial effect is felt early in the individual’s lifetime, then it may more than compensate for an injurious one that emerges later – hence the link with senescence. We can safely presume that suicide arises in this general way, as a harmful effect of genetic material that is fitnessenhancing on average. This is not to say that a ‘suicide gene’ exists or will ever be found: genetic predisposition to suicide appears to be spread thinly across a large number of genes, each of weak effect, interacting with each other and with environmental factors (Marušič and Swapp, 2004; Mullins et al., 2019).3 More likely, as deCatanzaro (1980) suggests, intentional self-killing occur as an incidental effect of a species-typical genome, the expression of which has proved adaptive overall in the course of human evolution. But then, what adaptive aspect of this species-typical genome could by-produce suicide?
Suicide as Communication One posited answer, offered by Hagen and Syme, (Hagen, 2002; Syme et al., 2016; Syme and Hagen, 2018), is that deaths may occur as an unfortunate by-product of suicidal
interpersonal communication. Their original idea is that an otherwise powerless individual, modally a young woman, may, at the extreme, threaten to or try to kill herself as the only available means by which she can induce kin to attend to her honest genetic needs. It may be in her reproductive interests to make a potentially high-stakes gamble, informed unconsciously by an inclusive fitness calculation. Suicidal death, from this perspective, can be seen as an unfortunate gamble lost. The behavior posited to be adaptive is the threat of, or attempt at, suicide; the potential for death being necessarily concomitant for the threat to be credible (Wiley, 2020). A recent variation of the idea, also with the inherent risk of a lethal, maladaptive outcome, is that a suicide attempt may constitute a costly signal of remorse (Syme and Hagen, 2018). Perhaps this line of theorizing may usefully shed light on non-suicidal self-injury and unintended fatalities, both outside the scope of this discussion. Researchers have long hypothesized a “cry for help” component in sub-lethal self-harming behaviors (Shneidman and Farberow, 1961), phenomena which may be significantly distinct from suicide (Kapur, Cooper, O’Connor and Hawton, 2013; Selby et al., 2014; Stengel, 1970). Among the chronically suicidal, it is possible that a cycle of reinforcement may arise in which carers’ well-meaning responses inadvertently provoke yet more behavioral cries for help (Linehan, 2020). There may also be strong commonsense appeal in attributing suicide to communication. There is an important caveat in this regard: folk theorizing about the cause of suicides is evidently not an objective data source. It is rather, at least in large part, a product of encultured post-rationalization (Atkinson, 1978; Solano, Pizzorno, Pompili, Serafini and Amore, 2018; Soper, 2019a). For example, alongside communication-type explanations, and presumably as reliably, non-western informants often also blame suicides on evil spirits, as Syme et al. (2016) themselves found. Observers frequently intuit
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND SUICIDOLOGY
interpersonal motives for attempted suicides too, but it should be born in mind that these interpretations rarely agree with actors’ own explanations: and where they do agree it may be because surviving attempters sometimes confess motives that they think others expect to hear (Bancroft et al., 1979). All that said, we question whether communication offers a satisfactory evolutionary explanation for intentional self-killing, partly for the same reasons that we found more directly adaptationist models wanting. We will highlight two difficulties (a critique may also be found in Soper (2018)). The first problem recalls the hallmark of adaptation: evidence of special design (Williams, 1966, 1996). It is an intuitive call, but suicide, whether completed, attempted or threatened, does not strike us as likely custom-designed for communication. People who seriously intend to take their own lives, presumably against kin’s wishes, would logically be expected not to communicate that intent, at least not sufficiently to invite interference. With rare exceptions, the empirical picture seems to fit this expectation. Perhaps it is different in some parts of the world – most of the evidence is from Western sources – but suicides are usually characterized by non- communication: privacy and non-disclosure are the norm. That they tend to happen without effective warning may be inferred from relatives’ immediate reaction to the news: typically shock, confusion, and disbelief (Chow, 2006; Dyregrov et al., 2012). Far from registering a communicated message, bereaved families are generally left bewildered by the act’s apparent senselessness (Jordan and McIntosh, 2011; Wertheimer, 2014). Noncommunication is characteristic of attempted suicides too (Maple et al.). Where an attempt is survived, close kin are usually not told about it either before or after the event, and they usually remain unaware even long afterwards (Brezo et al., 2007; Walker et al., 1990). At the same time, one can imagine any number of other deviances, potentially costly but not ordinarily suicidal, available for use if a drastic
61
threat or costly signal were needed: desertion, sexual infidelity, self-mutilation, infanticide, sabotage, arson, and so forth. In sum, it is not clear that suicide constitutes an outstandingly good solution to the needs of coercive, or any other, communication. The other difficulty recalls, again, the extreme and predictable fitness penalty of a suicide attempt, whether lethal or survived (Table 3.1). It is hard to imagine a commensurately extreme and predictable fitness benefit that could, even in theory, be won from a suicidal communication. Empirically, the epidemiology shows no obvious pattern of net fitness gains. Lesser upsides offered as supporting evidence in Syme et al.’s ethnographic analysis (2016, supplementary material, table S3) seem to fall well short in specificity (e.g., ‘Manipulate parents’) and reproductive impact (‘Prevented unwanted ear modification’) to be plausibly sufficient, as biological prizes, to justify the fitness losses and risks taken in trying to kill oneself. The strongest claimed payoffs are cases where actors are alleged to have sought sexual concessions, such as ‘Prevent unwanted marriage’ and ‘Concubine moved out of house’ – psychologically appealing, no doubt; but in a fitness calculation, still not credibly worth dicing with genetic extinction for their sake. If there is not a plausible net fitness gain to be had from going through with a threat, then it is unclear on what fitness grounds such a threat would be accepted as being credible. This is not to say that there may not be social utility in threatening to kill oneself, or any other threat for that matter. The error, we suggest, is to confuse non-evolutionary and evolutionary processes – to confuse utility with biological fitness. Stepping back, we question a general assumption that underlies hypotheses discussed so far, that the fitness payoff of whatever process it is that produces suicide derives from the suicide behavior itself. In principle, pleiotropy does not require there to be any obvious connection between a selected trait and its noxious concomitants (Williams, 1992). The explanatory gap between suicide’s
62
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
hypothesized benefits (weak, and contingent) and evident costs (severe, and predictable; Table 3.1) suggests that we probably need to look beyond the act itself for a categorically more powerful biological impetus. With this in mind, we will next look at some prominent evolutionary ideas circulating in mainstream suicidology.
The Interpersonal–Psychological Theory of Suicide (IPTS) Another conceptual framework, the Interpersonal–Psychological Theory of Suicide (IPTS), deserves attention. In various formulations it may currently be suicidology’s most prominent theory (Hjelmeland and Knizek, 2019; Lester, 2019; Paniagua et al., 2010), and it explicitly draws on some evolutionary ideas, including the notion that suicide may have come about as an evolutionary byproduct. In its original form IPTS holds that suicide results from the co-occurrence of three supposedly sufficient conditions: (1) a perception of being a burden to one’s family, (2) a thwarted desire to belong, and (3) a learned capability to enact lethal self-injury (Joiner, 2005; Van Orden et al., 2010). We will discuss each in turn. The first element, a feeling that one is a liability to loved ones, has been mapped by some commentators onto deCatanzaro’s (1980) sociobiological idea of burdensomeness – critiqued earlier – to which suicide is allegedly the organism’s genetically adaptive response (Aubin et al., 2013; Brown et al., 2009). But in what they call a ‘sociobiological extension’ of their own theory, IPTS’s authors depart from deCatanzaro’s view of burdensomeness in that they posit (human) suicide to be intrinsically maladaptive: colonial insects and humans are said to be equivalently eusocial, but while lethally self-sacrificial behaviors are understood to have inclusive fitness logic for insects, supposedly the same response among humans is seen as an error – a ‘dysfunction, misfiring, or derangement
of the adaptive behavioral suite evolved as a facet of eusociality’ (Joiner et al., 2017: 71). Evolutionary rationale for this distinction isn’t provided, but the need to make a distinction seems to stem from the authors’ equating of insect and human sociality – a questionable premise given the special familial makeup of insect colonies noted earlier. Adding to the confusion is what appears to be a mixing of biological process and moral evaluation (Gorelik and Shackelford, 2017) something that has long colored scientific discourse in this field (Soper, 2019a; Zilboorg, 1936a). IPTS’s second element, thwarted belongingness that may motivate self-killing, is on firmer theoretical ground and is where suicide is envisioned explicitly as a dysgenic byproduct (Joiner, 2005; Van Orden et al., 2010). The aversiveness of rejection, abandonment, and similar interpersonal stressors has certainly been attributed to evolutionary origins: psychological pain probably functions as an ancient alarm system, warning of potentially fitness-damaging social losses (Baumeister and Leary, 1995; Bowlby, 1969/1997, 1973, 1980/1991). Suicide can be understood as a way to escape from this adaptive social distress. We will return to this idea. Less strong in its theoretical underpinnings is the third component of IPTS, a hypothesized learned capability for lethal self-injury. The idea derives from a centuriesold belief that suicide defies an ‘instinct for self-preservation’. This supposedly universal natural drive must be overpowered, IPTS’s authors claim, before suicide can be carried out (Joiner, 2005; Van Orden et al., 2010). IPTS’s originator, Joiner (2005), ascribes evolutionary credentials to an ‘instinct for self-preservation’, but the notion faces principled objections from evolutionists, not least because there is no known biological means by which such a superordinate drive could come about (Kirkpatrick and Navarrete, 2006; Soper, 2019a). Modern theory holds that a general-purpose motivational device would be underspecified, lacking the recurring connections between proximal
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND SUICIDOLOGY
stimulus and fitness-impacting response that are required for selection to take hold: a system without specific links between inputs and outputs is unlikely to be favored (Buss, 1990; Buss and Penke, 2015). The same difficulty, it will be recalled, arose above in discussions of an ‘inclusive fitness monitor’. Soper (2016, 2018) suggests that if an antisuicide mechanism were reconceived within the tenets of evolutionary psychology, as a special rather than general-purpose device, then useful implications follow. We will come back to this point as well.
Suicide as an Escape from Pain Pyschological pain may drive the phenotype to seek relief in a way that is destructive for the genotype. We saw this idea underlying IPTS’s second component (above), and indeed it can be traced to suicidology’s formative writings. In the words of Henry A. Murray (the clinician whom Edwin Shneidman, the acknowledged father of suicidology, saw as his mentor), Suicide does not have adaptive (survival) value but it does have adjustive value for the organism…it abolishes painful tension. (Murray and Kluckhohn, 1948: 15, original italics)
By this perspective, suicide offers escape (Baechler, 1975/1979; Baumeister, 1990; Shneidman, 1993, 1996, 2005). A related idea, but with much older philosophical roots, is that self-killing may be a rational response to difficult life circumstances (Maris, 1982; Mishara, 2003). General reviews are available elsewhere of ‘suicide as escape’ theories (Gunn, 2014) and rational suicide (Lester, 2014a). Of interest for our purposes is their recognition, implicit or explicit, of the suicidogenic power of emotional pain (Selby et al., 2014). There are two points to note. First, although pain systems can malfunction, pain almost certainly has ancient adaptive origins (Nesse and Schulkin, 2019). Pain’s signal
63
enables the organism to navigate fitness hazards in its environment, both physical (Wall, 1999) and, as we have already noted, social (MacDonald and Leary, 2005). And in order to fulfil its navigation task, pain is necessarily motivational: it is designed precisely to force the organism to take action to relieve it (Auvray et al., 2010; Corns, 2014; Melzack and Casey, 1968). Hence, pain hurts. As the leprosy surgeon Paul Brand observed, pain is a valuable gift, albeit a gift nobody wants (Brand and Yancey, 1993). Second, there is an accord among suicide theorists and empirical researchers about the kind of pain that most powerfully motivates action – whatever action – to obtain the required relief. Although physical pain also associates with suicidality (Klonsky et al., 2019; Klonsky and May, 2015), emotional pain is more usually held responsible. The unbearable emotional state that can induce people to take their own lives is encapsulated by Shneidman’s (1993) neologism, psychache: Psychache refers to the hurt, anguish, soreness, aching, psychological pain in the psyche, the mind. It is intrinsically psychological – the pain of excessively felt shame, or guilt, or humiliation, or loneliness, or fear, or angst, or dread of growing old or of dying badly or whatever. (1993: 51; original italics)
There is also implicit agreement across more than a century of suicide research that unbearable emotional pain usually stems from social troubles. The disagreement is rather about what hue of social trouble is deemed most troublesome. Durkheim (1897/1952), for example, cited detachment (‘anomy’) as the chief driver. A hundred years later, Williams and colleagues ascribe suicide to feelings of social defeat and entrapment (Williams, 1997; Williams and Pollock, 2000; Williams et al., 2005). Williams’ ideas reappear in another theoretical framework, one that rivals IPTS, the Integrated Motivational–Volitional Model of Suicidal Behavior (IMV) devised by O’Connor and colleagues (O’Connor, 2011; O’Connor et al., 2016). IPTS, it will be recalled, highlights yet other varieties of
64
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
interpersonal distress – thwarted belonging and burdensomeness. And so on. Gunn (2017) connects these threads in an explicitly evolutionist frame; his Social Pain Model (SPM) registers that suicidogenic psychache is usually activated by various forms of damaged or threatened social relations. This social pain, as with pain generally, is both adaptive and intrinsically aversive. It is adaptive in that it is designed to alert the organism to the fitness threat posed by detachment – rejection presaging near certain death for our hunter-gatherer forbears (Bjorklund et al., 2010; Eisenberger and Lieberman, 2004; Eisenberger et al., 2003; Lieberman, 2013). And social pain is necessarily painful in order to induce action to alleviate it. Unfortunately, suicide offers a genetically self-destructive answer to this biological imperative to act. In sum, a weight of empirical and theoretical evidence points to suicide instantiating as an unfortunate by-product of pain, notably social pain, this being integral to the navigational equipment that humans need for maintaining attachments in large and close-knit groups. The aversiveness of social pain, adaptively, demands action to end it – a demand that can be met maladaptively by self-extinction.
‘Pain-and-Brain’ Model But social pain alone cannot be sufficient explanation for the evolution of suicide. If it were sufficient, suicide would presumably be found elsewhere among primates and other higher social animals. Indeed, solitary animals would expectably be vulnerable too: to reprise the point, pain (social or other) is biologically designed not to be tolerated – it demands that the organism act to end or escape it – so, any animal that could terminate its pain by terminating itself would reasonably be expected do so (Perry, 2016; Soper and Shackelford, 2018). We are still searching for an explanation for suicide as a narrowly human response. The search space
is even narrower than this because, as well as nonhumans, certain human populations too are protected from taking their own lives, however painful their circumstances: young children (Nock et al., 2013; Shaffer, 1974) and the mentally incapacitated (Merrick et al., 2006; Seyfried et al., 2011). Their immunity, or virtual immunity, also needs to be accounted for. Noting commonality across these groups, Baechler (1975/1979) draws a parsimonious conclusion that deliberate selfkilling presupposes a minimum level of intellectual functioning. Soper (2017, 2018) concurs, arguing that it’s only after more than a dozen years of cerebral development that species-typical humans, and apparently only humans, acquire sufficient capacity for logical thinking, foresight, and planning, for suicide to become a conceivable and practicable response. Humans alone appear to cross what Perry (2014: 110) describes as a ‘cognitive “floor” for suicide’, usually in adolescence. Thus, a second necessary condition for suicide emerges: cognitive competence. This may be central for understanding the behavior’s evolutionary origins. If deliberate self-killing presupposes the crossing of a developmental threshold during the individual’s lifetime, then we can deduce that an evolutionary counterpart, a phylogenetic threshold, also had to be surpassed at some point in human prehistory. Humphrey (2011: 211) makes the point by quoting Stengel (1970: 37)… At some stage of evolution man must have discovered that he can kill not only animals and fellowmen but also himself. It can be assumed that life has never since been the same to him.
Humphrey (2018) goes on to ascribe this pivotal discovery to the arrival, around 100,000 years ago, of a suite of uniquely human cognitive skills, including abstract thinking, mental time travel, self-consciousness, and sophisticated theory of mind. These are virtuoso demonstrations of the flexible, general-purpose style of thinking of Homo sapiens sapiens – promiscuous intelligence favored by selection because it conferred potent ecological, social,
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND SUICIDOLOGY
and sexual advantages (Flinn and Alexander, 2007; Humphrey, 1976; Pinker, 2010; Tooby and DeVore, 1987). But the human brain is ‘expensive tissue’ (Aiello and Wheeler, 1995): encephalization brought with it heavy costs, including energetic demands (Aiello and Wheeler, 1995), mutational load (Keller and Miller, 2006), obstetric challenges (Miller and Penke, 2007), problems of thermoregulation (Falk, 1990), and the burden of supporting young while the brain matures (Flinn et al., 2007). Suicidality can be understood as another such cost, a price we pay for a mind so free ranging that it can conceive even of its own mortality (Bering and Shackelford, 2004; deCatanzaro, 1980; Soper, 2018; Suddendorf, 2013). To sum up, it appears likely that suicide evolved as a by-product of not one adaptation, but two combined: pain (usually social); and speciestypical human cognition. Soper calls this a pain-and-brain theory of suicide.
Suicide as an Adaptive Problem The above discussion suggests that scientific consensus, if loose and implicit, can be seen coalescing around some form of ‘by-product’ explanation for suicide’s ultimate origins. A pain-and-brain framework in particular does not appear contentious: it seems to offer a point of agreement among prominent suicide theories, it accords with the epidemiology of suicide, and connects to knowledge bases of neuroscience, anthropology, and elsewhere. But it raises new and difficult questions, mainly because, as Soper (2016, 2018, 2019a) infers, the posited pain-and-brain conditions are not only necessary for suicide, but logically sufficient: pain provides the motive, and mature human cognition provides the means. If the pain-and-brain assessment is correct, then the fitness threat of suicide exists in potentia among virtually all of us. All speciestypical humans feel, and are motivated to escape, pain (Benatar, 2015; Brand and Yancey, 1993); and all species-typical human
65
adults, equipped with much the same cognitive machinery (Tooby and Cosmides, 1990a), have self-removal available as an exit route from pain. A consequent ‘lure of death’ (Humphrey, 2018) has probably featured in our evolutionary environment at least since the advent of behaviorally modern humans. Perhaps for much longer – presumably, indeed, ever since hominid intelligence began to approach that of a modern-day pubescent child (Soper, 2019b). By implication, suicide presents a harmful variety of, in evolutionary parlance, adaptive problem: Adaptive problems are evolutionarily long-enduring recurring clusters of conditions that constitute either reproductive opportunities (e.g., the arrival of a potential mate, the reflectant properties of light) or reproductive obstacles (e.g., the speed of a prey animal, the actions of a sexual rival, limited food supplies for relatives). (Cosmides and Tooby, 2000: 96)
Adaptive problems seek out adaptive solutions (Mayr, 1965; Tooby and Cosmides, 1990b; Williams, 1996). That almost all adults could be expected to take their own lives, but few do, indicates that adaptive solutions to the suicide problem are in fact in place. Without them, we as individuals, and we as a species, would not be here. At a phylogenetic level, hominid evolution would not have found a way through the cognitive floor for suicide, the floor acting as a ceiling of viable intelligence: in this light suicide emerges as perhaps the pre-eminent adaptive problem of our species (Soper, 2019b). Our existence presents a puzzle not so much of suicide but non-suicide. What stops most of us killing ourselves?
Evolved Antisuicide Defenses In seeking to answer this question, why not suicide, we can set aside the pre-Darwinian notion of a general-purpose survival instinct – critiqued briefly above and more fully elsewhere (Buss, 1990; Buss and Penke, 2015; Kirkpatrick and Navarrete, 2006; Soper, 2019a).
66
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
The likely solution would look more like the customized ‘patch 7.822’ artificial intelligence fantasy that began this chapter (Perry, 2016). If a fleet of androids dealt with every difficulty by, uselessly, switching themselves off, the problem would call for a software update to eliminate that particular behavioral option. In actuality, the human brain, a biological computer (Tooby and Cosmides, 2005), has presumably been retrofitted with a comparable fix, devised by selection. We next need to ask: how would such a patch operate? And what would its successful operation look like? Two sorts of antisuicide programs have been hypothesized in recent years (Humphrey, 2018; Miller, 2008; Soper, 2016, 2017, 2018). The first are evolved psychological mechanisms (Buss, 1995); the second are culturally propagated barriers. There won’t be a neat dichotomy in reality because many evolved psychological mechanisms rely on cultural inputs (Tooby and Cosmides, 1992), and many cultural devices exploit evolved psychological preparedness for learning in their particular domains (McNally, 2016). Nonetheless the distinction is interesting – partly because, although both sorts of devices might be expected to emerge, there is disagreement over their likely chronology and relative importance. Humphrey (2018) reasons that psychological mechanisms (what he calls ‘natural’ or ‘innate’ protections) would not have arisen as the first or foremost protection because of their slowness to evolve. Soper (2018, 2019a) argues the contrary, that they probably came first, emerging at least in part during a reconfiguration of anatomically modern humans’ ‘wetware’ ahead of the cultural explosion of the Later Stone Age (Klein and Edgar, 2002). The evolution of human intelligence may have been held at the cusp of suicidality for perhaps 150,000 years or more, while largely autonomic solutions to the suicide problem were assembled and refined. The pressure favoring such solutions would have been intense due to a combination of forces: runaway selection pushing
for greater computing power (Geary, 2007; Miller, 2000), while intelligentsia who lacked adequate protection were culled. Soper posits that it was only after basic defenses were installed that human intelligence could progress to the level of being able to enculture antisuicide ideas, proscriptions which presuppose a capacity to conceive of personal mortality. It is possible to deduce something of the likely design features of antisuicide defenses, as we will next discuss, by adopting evolutionary psychology’s ‘task analysis’ method (Tooby and Cosmides, 1992) – inferring likely parameters of an adaptive solution from the nature of the adaptive problem. Soper (2018) suggests that, in view of the severity of the threat, antisuicide devices are probably arranged as serial fortifications, each line guarding the position behind and deploying special stimulus-response mechanisms to that end. Perhaps simplifying, he suggests a framework that splits into front and rear defenses. At the back are emergency interventions, labelled keepers to connote the primary role of a goalkeeper on a soccer team: on stand-by much of the time, keepers leap into ‘Save!’ mode at times of crisis, and are all that stands between an attacking shot and disaster. Front-line protections, in contrast, are continuously active: following the soccer analogy, Soper labels them fenders to suggest a team’s other defensive players. Fenders’ job is to stop crises arising in the first place. The default outcome, if players can’t fulfil their respective tasks, is a conceded goal – a suicide attempt – which, as noted earlier, may be genetic ‘game over’. Soper argues that defenses’ triggering inputs and behavioral outputs would be expected to address both of suicide’s dual pain-and-brain drivers, and in distinct ways. To borrow the soccer analogy again, the fitness hazard of suicide can be conceived as an opposing team with only two forward players, ‘Pain’ and ‘Brain’, and they pose a threat only when they attack together. They have distinct styles of play, and the defending team
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND SUICIDOLOGY
must adopt customized pain-type and braintype tactics to neutralize them. Let us look first at the system design of keepers, the posited emergency defenses. To detect an imminent threat from ‘Pain’, keepers must be ready to respond to the experience of chronic and intense emotional distress. To detect an incoming ‘Brain’ threat, keepers must also be alert to the surpassing, in adolescence, of the cognitive threshold for suicide. Cues for both ‘Pain’ and ‘Brain’ must be present for keepers to mobilize. And, likewise, there are two, and only two, strategies available by which keepers can block incoming attacks: pain-type and brain-type. Pain-type keepers make self-killing unnecessary: they numb, distract from, or otherwise weaken the felt urgency of emotional pain as a motivator for escape. Brain-type keepers deny the means: they interfere with intellectual functioning enough usually to prevent an effective suicide attempt being organized. We will discuss keepers in more detail after this overview. The main point to note for now is that keepers’ interventions may be highly costly to the organism – and they are evidently not failsafe: hence the need for the pre-emptive work of fenders. As for fenders, the forward line of protections; these are hypothesized also to deploy in pain- and brain-type forms. Pain-type fenders titrate the organism’s exposure to emotional pain within tolerable limits. They use what could loosely be called positive psychology (Efklides and Moraitou, 2013) to hold humans safely distant, most of the time, from the potentially lethal danger that resides lop-sidedly in negative affect. Soper suggests they may work as four subsystems. First, is a homeostasis of affect around a resting point that is happier than neutral (Heintzelman and King, 2014), a base at which shocks can generally be absorbed without great disruption. Second, is a regulation of conscious contact with potentially painful realities – a self-serving self-deception that, empirically, characterizes so-called psychoanalytic (or psychodynamic) defenses (Paulhus and Buckels, 2012). Third, is a manufacturing
67
of positive affect (Kuhl et al., 2015; Layard, 2011) via, inter alia, investment in pleasurable activities beyond what would be economically justified by normal animalian needs of survival and reproduction (Pinker, 1997). And fourth, is the selection and maintenance of a hopeful, measuredly fictitious, mental model of self-in-the-world. This paradigm, more or less spiritual, holds that the universe and its people are not wholly indifferent to our wellbeing, and that our futures are not entirely doomed to the pain that would attend a purely Darwinian struggle. Thus, operating within (to adapt Baumeister’s (1989) phrase) an optimum margin of delusion, we perceive the world not as it is but through a rose-tinted lens. This enhanced reality system is under continual assault by factual counterevidence, and hence requires us continuously to defend it, literally as if our lives – or, at least, mental health – depend on it. Arising from this protective worldview, Soper says, is a costly propensity for selflessness and charity – that is, generosity that goes beyond the reciprocal calculus of economics. Taken as a whole, these sundry irrational-looking morale-boosters are not easy otherwise to explain and connect, but they may be understood to work as integrated psychological machinery, designed to prevent crises of willful self-destruction and the necessity for keepers to intervene. A separate set of evolved, culturally learned protections, independently hypothesized by Miller (2008), Humphrey (2018), and Soper (2018), are designed to block access to the idea of suicide. They are brain-type fenders in Soper’s scheme. He suggests they propagate by multi-level selection and form three serial walls: a thought-inhibiting taboo; the expectation of a fearful afterlife; and a moralistic stigma. The deterrent function of this last barrier, unfortunately but perhaps necessarily, involves exemplary punishments for suicides and their kin, some noted in Table 3.1. The dismantling of these prohibitions, the acceptance of suicide as a normal topic of conversation and a reasonable solution to trying circumstances, can release a surge of
68
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
suicides (Huber, 2015/2019). Such a wave may perpetuate for generations (Macdonald, 2007): once lost, cultural defenses may be exceptionally difficult to reinstate (Soper, 2018).
A summary graphic (Figure 3.1, from Soper, 2018) illustrates how the various posited protections may interrelate. Out of a great number of potential suicidal incidents, symbolized
Figure 3.1 Summary of posited antisuicide defences Source: Reproduced from Soper (2018).
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND SUICIDOLOGY
by a mass of dots at the top of the diagram, only a few find their way through the fortifications to materialize as actual suicide attempts, indicated by a couple of dots at the bottom. By focusing not on supposed (possibly inscrutable; Soper, 2019a) proximal causation of suicide but on evolved machinery posited to stop suicide, the graphic departs conceptually from the style of flow chart that usually accompanies presentations of suicide theory (Gunn, 2019).
PREDICTED FEATURES OF ‘KEEPER’ LAST-LINE ANTISUICIDE DEFENSES This section focuses on Soper’s (2018) task analysis for keepers – the hypothesized last line of defenses, which react to exigent risk. These ideas are novel, and not mainstream in either suicidology or evolutionary psychology, but we suggest they warrant attention for three reasons. First, their claim to logic – keepers’ design features being supposedly deducible a priori from the nature of suicide as an adaptive problem – is central to the theory and calls for scrutiny. Second, these features may be read as predictions, amenable to empirical confirmation or falsification. Third, if correct, they may have important repercussions for suicide prevention, psychiatry, and wider mental health policy, as we will discuss. Keepers’ posited features are presented in 20 items, (a) to (t) below, the headings taken from a tabulation in Soper (2018: 145).
‘Pain’ Input With suicide modelled as an answer to the imperative to escape pain, Soper argues that the emotional aversiveness of pain would probably serve as the primary activator of emergency antisuicide defenses. Keepers would mobilize selectively among people in potentially suicidogenic distress.
69
a. Keepers would be activated by chronic, intense pain (subject to the developmental condition of a ‘brain’ input). Soper predicts that an activating ‘pain’ cue will combine (by some unspecified algorithm) pain’s chronicity and intensity. Chronicity, on the grounds that suicides take time to plan and enact (Joiner, 2005),4 so potentially drastic countermeasures should not be triggered by merely ephemeral upsets. Intensity, because the stronger the pain, presumably the more urgent the motivation to escape it. An additional ‘brain’ input is set out in (d) below. b. Input variable would be the unidimensional aversiveness of pain, regardless of the pain’s source or quality. Because the pain-and-brain model views suicide as an adjustive response to the generic aversiveness of pain, irrespective of its origin, keepers will respond to the degree, not kind, of triggering pain. The point recalls Shneidman’s (1993) catch-all notion of suicidogenic psychache; that any blend of shame, grief, anomy, thwarted belongingness, burdensomeness, defeat, hopelessness, or whatever other emotional distress can motivate suicidal escape. Soper (2018) posits that, likewise, any combination can trigger an antisuicide defense. Social pain is more likely to activate keepers than is physiological pain only inasmuch as social pain is often experienced as more painful (Gunn, 2017). c. Keeper responses would be calibrated so that the intensity of defensive outputs accords with the intensity and chronicity of the pain input. The strength of antisuicide responses would be expected to adjust according to the scale of the threat: more intense and longer-lasting distress should associate with commensurately more robust countermeasures.
‘Brain’ Input d. Keepers would not activate earlier than the species-typical age of first onset of suicide, in early adolescence, possibly signaled by the onset of puberty. As already noted, activation would presumably need a threshold ‘brain’ condition to be met, linked to developmental surpassing of the cognitive floor for suicide. Because young children lack the mental capability for suicide, there would be no fitness benefit in keepers mobilizing among them however distressed they may be. Soper (2018)
70
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
stops short of specifying how this ‘brain’ cue operates; but he posits that a biochemical signal connected with pubescence is probably involved because, empirically, it is usually at or shortly after this stage of life that suicide becomes enactable. Interesting predictions may follow from this developmental association, as we will discuss later.
Deactivation e. Keepers would demobilize spontaneously following a reduction in the originating pain input. Mirroring activation, keepers should deactivate after, and only after, relief of the potentially suicidogenic pain that activated them. f. Deactivation would usually be slow, gradual and delayed, especially without an unambiguous ‘all clear’ signal. Antisuicide defenses would work on a ‘better safe than sorry’ principle, deactivating slowly for the same reason that prey mammals, on high alert after scenting a predator, stand down only cautiously once the scent disperses: the extreme potential cost of misreading an ambiguous ‘all clear’ outweighs the cost of remaining too long on guard (Blanchard, Griebel, and Nutt, 2011).
Specific Types of Keeper Responses g. Responses would aim to limit motivation for suicide (‘pain-type’); or limit the capacity to organize suicide (‘braintype’). It was noted earlier that keepers are predicted to block suicide by deploying ‘pain’ and ‘brain’ strategies, a dual process deducible, Soper (2018) argues, from suicide’s posited pain-and-brain evolutionary causation. He offers suggestions as to what these interventions may entail, listed as bullet points in the ‘keeper’ boxes towards the bottom of Figure 3.2. Ellipses indicate that the lists may not be exhaustive. The first category, pain-type keepers, are tasked with lessening the aversiveness of emotional pain. Given the neurological overlap between physical and emotional pain (Eisenberger and Lieberman, 2005), Soper (2018) hazards that keepers would probably co-opt pre-existing circuitry that moderates the felt intensity of physical pain (Wall, 1999). Pain-type keepers might, for example, numb emotions autonomically in a manner akin to the analgesic effect of physical
trauma. They could also manage pain exogenously: by, say, ingestion of analgesics – exploiting ‘nature’s pharmacy’ as animals do (Engel, 2002); by exploiting the phenomenon of pain-offset relief, in which one pain can be relieved by applying another, unrelated, stimulus; and/or by distraction (Eccleston, 2001). Other pain-type keepers are posited to use psychological adjustments to make pain bearable, such as the construction of a rationale for suffering pain and/or an emotionally tolerable, but partly imaginary, re-perception of the environment (Eccleston, 2001).
The other category, brain-type keepers, deny the means and opportunity for suicide. They will attenuate the individual’s ability to plan and implement suicide (and, incidentally, any other complex task) by tactically disabling psychomotor and executive resources. Activation would expectably express inlethargy and/or targeted cognitive deficits, such as indecisiveness and forgetfulness.
General Characteristics of Keeper Responses h. Keepers would drive compulsive and involuntary behaviors, resisting conscious awareness and intervention. Suicide being the kind of lethal, once-in-a-lifetime, fitness threat that offers few opportunities for conditioned learning and where to err can be fatal, it ought to be addressed by preset and strongly obligate routines. Keepers would present limited scope for being voluntarily moderated. Indeed, the phenomenon of instinct blindness prevailing (Cosmides and Tooby, 1994), they may operate beyond awareness. i. Multiple forms of keepers are likely to operate in an integrated fashion in the same individual, concurrently and/ or temporally. Blends of pain- and brain-type defenses would likely deploy in combinations in the interest of system robustness and to spread costs. In principle, keepers could appear in many possible permutations, varying from person to person and over time, responding to the varying needs of culture, gender, life stage, personality, and other aspects of individual difference. j. Keepers are likely to be accompanied by protracted anxiousness, and rumination focused on emotional pain. As a point related to (f) above, following the general pattern by which
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND SUICIDOLOGY
animals respond to severe but uncertain fitness threats (Blanchard, Griebel and Nutt, 2011), humans at risk of suicide would expectably display prototypical anxiety. Recalling the analogy of prey mammals scenting an unlocatable predator, their best strategy is not flight, because they would as likely head towards death as away from it. For humans vulnerable to suicide, lethal danger similarly comes from no discernible direction and there is likewise nowhere to run. The priority in the presence of such an extreme, ambiguous hazard is to stay on high alert and try to infer its detail ‘beyond the information given’ (Waldmann et al., 2006). By this light, a compulsive mental rumination, which may be a uniquely human addition to what is otherwise a pan- animalian anxiety state (Blanchard, Griebel, Pobbe et al., 2011), would be an expectable response.
Goals and Trade-Off Considerations k. The compromise objective would be to minimize the risk of suicide, while limiting the imposition of new, potentially drastic, fitness costs arising from activated keepers. Keepers are necessarily costly to activate because they involve attenuating the advantageous-on-average ‘pain’ and ‘brain’ primary adaptations that brought suicide in their wake. Keepers have evidently not delivered zero suicide risk, and would not be expected to do so, because zero suicidality would presumably be achievable only by commensurately zeroing the fitness benefit of those adaptations. Rather, antisuicide defenses would evolve only up to an equilibrium; a point where the marginal fitness gain to be had from further reducing actuarial risk matches the cost of the extra defenses required to achieve that reduced risk. l. Keepers would trigger sensitively, with a high incidence of false alarms – many affected individuals will not have considered suicide. As with the posited ‘brain’ cue, Soper does not specify the ‘pain’ input that is hypothesized to mobilize keepers. Candidate triggers would presumably include biochemical correlates of pain. But they would probably not include, despite its appealing specificity, conscious planning of suicide projects. The informational currency of the brain being emotional rather than semantic, the organism’s central nervous system would be oblivious to suicide plans unless they
71
were flagged as such by an emotional regulatory variable (Tooby and Cosmides, 2008). Soper (2018) hypothesizes the existence of separate defenses that deter suicide plans by using the disgust mechanism, informed by culturally learned inputs (so-called brain-type fenders, discussed above). But he suggests that there may be no preprogrammed biological tag marked ‘Suicide Plan’ to which keepers could respond. Commonplace experience is that one can muse about suicide without triggering a drastic autonomic response. On this basis, keepers may not be good at differentiating, from among emotionally distressed people, those who have specific suicide plans from those who don’t. Keepers would likely mobilize in some individuals who, although in pain, may never have entertained serious thoughts of taking their own lives. Keepers erring on the side of caution ((f), above), there may be many such false alarms. m. Keepers may themselves become pathological. In the same way that the physiological immune system can malfunction, there may be exceptional situations in which keepers may become pathological. Soper posits the possibility, for example, that antisocial behavioral outputs of keepers, mobilized in response to social pain, may invite more social pain, potentially creating a positive feedback loop.
Manifestations of Successful Operation n. Keepers would result in a low, but abovezero, incidence of suicide in human populations. It follows from keepers’ compromise objective ((k), above) that their success would appear at a population level not as zero suicides but as a minimal, biologically irreducible, residue. Pockets of high, even demographically destabilizing, rates of suicide might arise, but these would be short-lived and in due course supplanted, through multi-level selection, by groups with suicidality held at sustainable levels.5 o. Residual suicides would be intrinsically unpredictable at the level of the organism. Functioning optimally as part of a wider system of antisuicide defenses, keepers would be expected to exploit and exhaust any and all useful markers of actuarial risk. The few suicides that do occur, it follows, can be viewed as statistical residuals – suicidal trajectories that are amenable neither
72
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
to detection (not, that is, based on informational priors available to the organism) nor, therefore, to autonomic prevention. With keepers operating properly, suicides should be ‘predictably unpredictable’ (Soper, 2019a). p. Activated keepers would be associated with suicide, but only inasmuch as they associate with suicidal ideation rather than with the enacting of those ideas. Most suicides would expectably be accompanied by activated keepers. Interesting predictions arise from (k) and (l) above concerning statistical associations between suicidality and activated keepers. Completed suicides will likely be accompanied by signs of keepers having activated – properly, although in these instances ineffectively. Keepers should also correlate strongly with suicide plans and actions. But, importantly, these correlations should hold only insofar as keepers correlate with the emotional prior – a generalized urge to terminate pain. By analogy, one could imagine a warring city that defended its centre against aerial bombardment with less-than-perfectly effective anti-aircraft guns deployed at the city’s outskirts. Gunners open fire pre-emptively; they start shooting as soon as bombers come within range. Hence, gunfire would correlate strongly with bombing of the centre, but only inasmuch as the outbreak of gunfire correlates with bombers approaching the outskirts – not especially with any surviving bombers’ completion of their raids, progressions which the gunners are trying to avert. Likewise, keepers will respond only weakly, if at all, to the pursuit of specific suicide projects among people motivated to end their suffering, this being the progression that keepers are designed to prevent. q. Keeper responses would be nearly always recoverable and survivable: they should only rarely cause permanent disability. Almost any outcome short of death being preferable to suicide, keepers’ interventions may be extreme. Nonetheless, as immune-like responses, they should usually not be degenerative. A protective denial of psychomotor energy, for example, would expectably produce tactical lethargy, perhaps for a while even complete immobility, but it should not seriously compromise somatic functions. r. Keeper responses would be nearly always recoverable and survivable: they should only rarely cause permanent disability. Because the pain-and-brain framework
views suicide as a dysgenic, but psychologically rational, response to aversive affect, activated keepers can be understood as tactical denials of rationality – they sacrifice aspects of the organism’s affective (‘pain’) and cognitive (‘brain’) functioning in order to preserve life. People under the influence of activated keepers will find themselves not only distressed, but also emotionally (‘pain’) and intellectually (‘brain’) debilitated. Faced with this inconvenience, sufferers and their families would be expected to approach priests, healers, and the like for explanations and remedial interventions. It can be expected that keepers’ expressions are conspicuous and probably well known to science, and we may not need to look far to find evidence of them.
Species-Specific and SpeciesUniversal s. Keepers would be species-specific: they would not occur in nonhuman animals, although homologue of their features may be found in other mammals. Keepers’ style of response contrasts with the way animals normally meet severe fitness hazards: just when any other animal would be expected to bring all its mental resources to bear on tackling a mortal threat, humans facing the threat of suicide are likely to find their affective and cognitive faculties autonomically impaired. Keepers are a uniquely human solution to a uniquely human problem. Rudimentary precursors of their features may well be found in nonhumans, particularly among other primates, but these will be only vestiges of phylogenetic raw material that was co-opted and adapted for antisuicide purpose in our species alone. t. Keepers would be species-universal: the same integrated system of keepers would be found activating among populations of mature humans in all cultures and historical ages. Keepers are genetically transmitted, species-typical mechanisms. Although the proximal cause of precipitating social pain will likely vary according to cultural context, the same suite of antisuicide responses to that pain will be found in all sizeable human populations. That said, as universal human features, keepers’ antisuicide functionality may not be obvious because no extant control population may be to hand to show what the suicide rate would be, all else equal, were it not for their interventions.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND SUICIDOLOGY
PSYCHIATRIC SYMPTOMS AS ANTISUICIDE DEFENSES The above section outlined an engineering specification – a score of features that would be expected of so-called keepers, reactive devices designed to stop us taking our own lives when we otherwise might. The specification follows, Soper (2018) argues, from the pain-and-brain model of suicide’s evolution; defensive systems would activate with ‘pain’ and ‘brain’ informational inputs, respond using ‘pain’ and ‘brain’ processes, and produce observable ‘pain’ and ‘brain’ outputs. The predicted features of this system show striking similarities, according to Soper, with adult patterns of so-called ‘functional’ (i.e., not due to structural brain dysfunction, as opposed to ‘organic’) common mental disorder, or CMD (Goldberg and Goodyer, 2005) – sundry states that would usually be described as depression, generalized anxiety, alcoholism and other addictions, psychoses, obsessive/ compulsive disorders, non-suicidal self-harm, and perhaps other diagnoses. He asserts that the fit is so detailed and multi-faceted that it is difficult plausibly to explain, except by the proposal that CMD is, in fact, the expression of antisuicide machinery. The hypothesis challenges a widespread preconception that CMD causes suicide, rather than works to block suicidal trajectories among those at risk (Mishara and Chagnon, 2016). To ascribe suicide to CMD may be to commit the post hoc fallacy: to assume that because a preceded b, a must have caused b. Recalling the analogy of air defences, ill-informed citizens might understandably misplace blame for the bombing of their city on the anti-aircraft gunfire that usually foreshadowed it. The challenge is not new: it has long been suggested within psychiatry that depression, addictions, psychotic delusions, and diverse other psychopathologies can protect against self-killing (e.g., Hendin, 1975; Himmelhoch, 1988; Hundert, 1992; Menninger, 1938). What is new is evolutionary theory that predicts such a dynamic.
73
We note four interesting ways to inspect the hypothesis. First, it offers a novel conception of ‘functional’ psychiatric diagnoses, as the concurrence of potentially suicidogenic pain alongside blends of antisuicide responses to that pain. Soper (2018) offers a cross- tabulation (Figure 3.2) to illustrate how psychiatric labels may describe various groupings of keepers in this way, with equivalent defensive components appearing under different diagnostic headings. Protective emotional numbing, for example, maps against criteria used for diagnosing ‘major depressive disorder’, ‘psychotic disorders’, and ‘bipolar disorder’. According to this conception, keepers, not diagnoses, are natural kinds. Second, the hypothesis may offer parsimonious explanation for a suite of statistical links between suicidality and CMD which, without the hypothesis, look unrelated and puzzling. We note three. One is that almost all CMD diagnoses associate with a heightened vulnerability to suicide (Cavanagh et al., 2003) – but, signally, the diagnosis of severe to profound intellectual disability associates with fewer suicides (Harris and Barraclough, 1997) as the pain-and-brain model would anticipate. Two is that, as predicted, CMD correlates with suicide only inasmuch as it correlates with the ideational prior. CMD associates strongly with generalized suicidal ideas; but only weakly, if at all, with the progression from this ideation to the planning and execution of specific suicide actions (Klonsky et al., 2016; Nock et al., 2015). Three is that the developmental stage when CMD tends first to appear – in the teen years (Kessler et al., 2007) – coincides with earliest first onsets of suicidality (Nock et al., 2013). It is not easy otherwise to account for these correlations individually let alone as a set. Together they could be taken as a fingerprint of antisuicide functionality. Third, the existence of marked patterns common to sundry diagnostic labels point to a shared aetiology – specifically, it is suggested, as mechanisms designed to prevent potentially suicidogenic pain and suicidal ideas
• Compulsive use of analgesics and other mind-altering substances (ii, iv, v, vi, vii)
Substance use disorders
• Indecisiveness; • Compulsive use diminished ability to of sedatives think or concentrate (viii) (viii, ix) • Loss of interest in activities; fatigue, loss of energy, hypersomnia; psychomotor retardation; loss of appetite (ix)
• Feeling ‘empty’; ‘Having no feelings’; ‘Not caring any more’ (i) • Craving foods (iv)
Major Depressive Disorder
Non-suicidal self-injury (NSSI)b
Psychotic disorders
• Difficulty concentrating; mind going blank (viii) • Fatigue (ix)
• Disorganised thinking; Disorganised/ abnormal motor behaviour (viii) • Negative symptoms; catatonia (ix)
• Worry, • Self-injury • Diminished rumination (iii, iv) emotional restlessness; expression (i) insomnia (vi, vii) • Delusions; hallucinations (iv, v, vi, vii)
Generalised Anxiety Disorder(GAD)a
Diagnostic criteria of some common psychopathologies (A.P.A., 2013)
Bipolar disorders
• Obsessions • Depressive (viii); episode (viii, ix) • Compulsions (ix)
• Obsessions; • Depressive compulsions episode (i) (iv, v, vii) • Manic/ hypomanic episodes (iv, vii)
OCD
Notes: a The anxiousness of generalised anxiety disorder may be better understood as a concomitant of keepers rather than a keeper defence in itself, but the pain-type function of GAD posited here might be taken to express the urgency of the organism’s need to seek relief from suicidogenic pain; bNon-suicidal self-injury (NSSI), classified as a ‘condition for further study’ in DSM-5 (APA, 2013), appears here as an exception, arguably lacking a ‘brain-type’ action: this function may be provided instead by other symptoms often comorbid with NSSI. Source: Reproduced from Soper (2018).
Figure 3.2 A tentative mapping of hypothesized types of antisuicide mechanisms (keepers) across common diagnostic categories of mental disorder
PAIN-TYPE (weaken the motivation for suicide) (i) Autonomic numbing. (ii) Medicate the pain. (iii) Pain offset relief. (iv) Distract from pain. (v) Detach from pain. (vi) Make sense of the pain. (vii) Find reason to live with pain. BRAIN-TYPE (restrict access to the means of suicide) (viii) Degrade ability to plan and enact tasks. (ix) Loss of psychomotor energy.
Suggested types of keeper anti-suicide mechanism
74 THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND SUICIDOLOGY
progressing to suicidal actions. One commonality, mentioned above, is marked suicidality – to be exact, suicidal ideas rather than the enacting of those ideas (Nock et al., 2013). Another is the characteristic stimulus-response course of CMD, precipitated by emotionally painful events, and typically lifting over time (with or without medical intervention) after the precipitating adversities are eased (Brown, 2009; Goldberg and Goodyer, 2005; Harris, 2000). Yet others include: extreme comorbidity – people diagnosed with one disorder usually also meet criteria for one or more others, concurrently or at different times (American Psychiatric Association, 2013; First and Pincus, 2009); lack of ‘zones of rarity’, or natural boundaries, between diagnostic criteria (Kendell and Jablensky, 2003); non-specificity of causation – to large extent, as the keeper model anticipates, any kind of adversity can precipitate any variety of CMD response (Goldberg and Goodyer, 2005; Kessler et al., 2010); non-specificity of treatments – therapies developed for one condition also alleviate others (Wampold and Imel, 2015); common cognitive deficits – selectively impairing, also as the keeper specification predicts, the ability to organize complex tasks (Harvey, 2004); coincident scheduling of first onsets – in adolescence, as already noted, the stage of life when suicidality first develops (Kessler et al., 2007); species-specificity – an absence of close animal models (Willner and Belzung, 2015); and so on. This mesh of continuities poses a problem for an ad hoc labelby-label style of analysis that is widespread in Darwinian psychiatry (e.g., Brune, 2016; Del Giudice, 2018) – some evolutionary hypotheses advanced for depression, others for generalized anxiety, yet others for schizophrenia etc. Soper (2018) argues that any explanation proffered for one diagnostic label is incomplete unless also explained is the detailed configuration that label shares, and its routine co-occurrence, with almost any other form of CMD. Soper’s model may offer parsimonious theoretical underpinning for what some researchers have inferred from empirical observation: that many psychiatric constructs, for all their superficial
75
differences, vary more in degree than kind and likely relate to a singular causal process, hitherto unclear (Caspi et al., 2014; Menninger, 1963; Stochl et al., 2015). Fourth, it is possible to understand why psychiatric symptoms are poor predictors of suicide, and indeed why a decades-long search for any clinically useful marker has returned empty handed (Carter et al., 2017; Franklin et al., 2017). The failure of prediction arises not particularly, as is often claimed, because suicide is rare; rare events are not necessarily unpredictable (Soper, 2019a). Rather, precisely this null result would be expected of an organism that is finely adapted to its ‘suicidal niche’ and already making best use of available cues (Soper, 2019b). Suicide attempts, as statistical residuals, are events associated with no utilizable prognostic information to which the individual’s defensive systems could have responded. It should be anticipated, then, that suicides offer little or no scope for being accurately foreseen at the individual level. Summing up, a posited convergence of evidence from multiple directions sets up a probability argument for special design (Williams, 1966, 1996). Soper (2018) finds no unaccountable inconsistencies, and no better explanation for the confluence. A software patch devised to stop humans switching themselves off in the face of difficulties would predictably include routines that look very much like symptoms of ‘functional’ common mental disorder. On this basis, he intuits, it is more likely than not that many outwardly dissimilar psychiatric states reflect the proper workings of systems that evolved to prevent self-killing.
Implications: The Case of Depression If the pain-and-brain framework is correct, its ramifications may be wide-ranging, profound, and take time to fathom. They could impact on the research agenda, suicide
76
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
prevention policy, psychiatric practice, and the conceptualization of psychopathology and mental health. We will illustrate with an example relating to the extensive and widely recommended use of antidepressants and other psychopharmacological treatments to prevent suicides among clinical patients assessed to be at risk (Wasserman et al., 2012; Zalsman et al., 2017). The task analysis outlined above suggests that certain common psychiatric symptoms – including the emotional numbing, cognitive impairment, fatigue, and generalized anxiety characteristic of adult-pattern depressive states – can be understood not as suicidogenic disorder, but expressions of the organism’s protective response to the lethal threat latent in chronic, intense, emotional pain. In other words, various common depressive symptoms may be conceived as actions of a psychological defensive system, in the same way that modern medicine understands coughing, vomiting, and fever to be defensive responses (Nesse and Williams, 1995). It is for this reason that the analysis predicts that, once the triggering distress is relieved, depressive symptoms would be expected to lift of their own accord, with or without medical intervention – spontaneous remission that characterizes the normal course of most common psychopathologies (Goldberg and Goodyer, 2005; Harris, 2000). The notion of protective antisuicide depression is not new. Hendin (1975) inferred such a dynamic from clinical observation half a century ago; and some epidemiological findings might, arguably, support Hendin’s case (Rogers et al., 2018). Psychiatrists across decades have warned that suicide risk can intensify, not reduce, when depressive symptoms start to lift (Kahne, 1966; Meehl, 1973). What is new is an evolutionary foundation for the idea. Hence, evolutionary analysis pertains to important questions about the treatment of depression, in particular the use of pharmacological treatments, especially in the context of suicide prevention. We will highlight three issues. First, the model suggests that antidepressants treat symptoms rather than causes.
Addressing the root cause of depressive symptoms would presumably involve helping sufferers to relieve the precipitating distress, which probably originates, recalling Gunn’s (2017) Social Pain Model, from some form of social detachment. That said, any pain relief could offer provisional respite; and given the likely social nature of the triggering pain, any credible treatment, psychotropic medication included, could be expected to produce a strong placebo effect, signaling that a supportive attachment has been put in place (Davies, 2013; Wampold, 2018). Second, at worst, suppressing the psyche’s antisuicide systems exogenously, at least without other measures, would be expected to exacerbate, not lessen, suicide risk, at least in some circumstances. This expectation is supported by considerable pharmacological evidence (Hengartner and Plöderl, 2019; Sharma et al., 2016). Third, evolutionary analysis challenges a premise of such treatments, that people ‘at risk’ can accurately be picked out in clinical settings. As we have noted, special-purpose biological defenses would be expected to have exploited and exhausted any and all utilizable markers, with the result that suicides are probably not amenable to prediction in principle (Soper, 2019a). The evolutionary argument thus touches on an ethical question: whether it is justifiable to prescribe mind-altering drugs to large numbers of people, nearly all of whom were never going to take their own lives, in an effort to protect a small and unidentifiable minority. The analysis would, in the round, appear to lend theoretical support to those who already question on empirical grounds whether psychopharmacology is an appropriate approach to suicide prevention (Hjelmeland et al., 2019; Maris, 2015). Looking at alternative strategies, the same evolutionary analysis predicts that restricting access to lethal means (such as, for example, installing nets under favored jump sites, and limiting the size of retail drug packs) may be effective to an extent that
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND SUICIDOLOGY
would seem far-fetched to people viewing such incomplete obstacles with the benefit of normal intellectual functioning (Chen et al., 2016; Hawton, 2007). Interventions that only mildly complicate a suicide endeavor would be expected to disrupt disproportionately the plans of someone affected by denials of psychomotor energy, memory, decision-making, and other task-related cognitive faculties – attenuations which, Soper (2016, 2018) posits, may be protective aspects of depression. A slight delay may be enough to allow homeostatic affective systems to de-escalate from a suicidal crisis, restoring the organism towards a protective, above-neutral, resting point. Means restriction, in other words, could be understood to capitalize on and co-operate with the organism’s own antisuicide defenses.
Problems with Soper’s Theory On one hand, Soper’s (2018) model has merit. It appears, at least at this early stage, parsimoniously to fit multiple lines of evidence, and it does so arguably better than other available explanations; it could be judged attractive on the criterion of inference to the best explanation (Harman, 1965). From an evolutionary perspective, it appears to match biological function to observable form (Buss, 1995; Williams, 1996). The theory is in principle falsifiable: many findings would suffice as disproof – if science discovered, for example, nonhuman suicide, or a human population with a pattern of early childhood suicides, or a group that lacked positive correlations between suicidality and hypothesized keeper responses, and so forth. It could generate novel and testable ancillary predictions. We propose, for example, that Soper’s notion of a statistical, but only indirect, association between the scheduling of first onsets of keepers (triggered by a hormonal cue linked to puberty) and first onsets of suicide (dependent on intellectual competence) could be tested by comparing the epidemiology of suicide and keepers in populations with
77
delayed/accelerated intellectual development against populations with delayed/accelerated endocrine development. A pattern in which suicide, but not psychiatric symptoms, occurred among the hormonally delayed but cognitively precocious, and vice versa, could be taken to support Soper’s proposals and be difficult otherwise to explain. On the other hand, Soper’s theory faces at least four significant problems. First, being at the stage of a preliminary sketch, it lacks detail and raises many unanswered questions. It is not specified, for example, how exactly hypothesized antisuicide protections would operate. To illustrate, ‘loss of psychomotor energy’ (LoPE) (Soper, 2018: 143) is conceived as an autonomic defense against suicide, but self-killing could be brought about by inaction as well as action. It is unclear how LoPE would interact with other hypothesized keepers; it could conflict, for example, with others that presumably require positive action, such as the compulsive consumption of analgesics. The biological parameters of LoPE are undefined – whether it exists as a discrete condition, and how it would be operationalized as a testable construct, and so on. Soper’s proposals may have intuitive appeal, but there is much work to do before a robust, comprehensive framework could be said to have been achieved, despite, or perhaps because of, the breadth of the framework’s ambit. Second, the forward/reverse engineering approach, the appeal to evidence of special design on which Soper’s adaptationist arguments largely rely, is intrinsically intuitive notwithstanding apparent objectivity (Lauder, 1996; Williams, 1996). Due to the method’s subjectivity, another researcher replicating Soper’s thought experiments might not arrive at the same conclusions. This is not to say that his arguments are invalid, but that there is scope for different students legitimately to reach different opinions from the same data depending on their biographical backgrounds (Kuhn, 1977). Soper’s efforts to infer a priori design parameters for keepers, for example,
78
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
will not be entirely a priori: the author, a psychotherapist, could not have approached the topic with a blank slate and it would be surprising if his findings were not colored by experience. Indeed, some of his predictions might strike many workers in mental health as already matters of common knowledge. Third, Soper’s (2018) approach leans on a presumption of optimal outcomes: that because x would be biologically ideal, x is what we should find. While the optimization approach is a useful way to model biological problems and may suggest solutions, it is not a safe basis in itself for predicting evolutionary results. Many alternative outcomes of selection are possible (Gould and Lewontin, 1979), and the fitness functions of most adaptive problems are complex landscapes of hills and valleys, the path to optimization often blocked at local fitness maxima (Parker and Smith, 1990). Fourth, testing certain aspects of Soper’s (2018) theory may be problematic due to the composite nature of its hypotheses. Taking again the example of ‘loss of psychomotor energy’ (LoPE), this is presented as both an adaptive solution to suicide risk, and as an expression of that solution. Associations between LoPE and measures of suicidality that offer to support one hypothesis could simultaneously undermine the other: if, say, suicides happen alongside LoPE, then that could be read both as confirmatory evidence (because LoPE had mobilized as predicted to meet the threat), and as falsifying evidence (because LoPE had failed in its supposed design task, to stop suicides). This kind of epistemological trap is not unique to Soper’s theorizing and may be endemic in evolutionary science. A comparable zero-sum game plays out, for example, in the long-debated Westermarck effect, an evolved mechanism said to deter close inbreeding: the same evidence can be taken both to support and contradict the theory (Sesardic, 2005). On balance, while acknowledging these and other weaknesses, it is not easy to dismiss the thrust of Soper’s (2018) arguments. Intuitively difficult is the claim that varied symptoms of psychiatric disorders function
as special-purpose antisuicide devices. But to reject this hypothesis may be to invite fresh difficulty, because two questions would then call for answers. Which aspects of the antisuicide task analysis are being disputed? And, if not ‘functional’ psychiatric disorder, then what alternative empirical phenomenon is proposed that better matches that design specification? If the pain-and-brain model is broadly correct, the call would remain to explain why few people kill themselves. It may be partly for this reason that at least one prominent suicidologist is on record as finding Soper’s proposals persuasive (Lester, 2019). Time will tell if others agree.
CONCLUSION At one level this chapter carries an encouraging message. The evolutionary approach would seem, in principle, capable of bringing unity and coherence to suicidology’s current morass of theory. A ‘pain-and-brain’ framework in particular seems to offer a rallying point for numerous, superficially disparate, theoretical positions, such as IPTS (Van Orden et al., 2010), IMV (O’Connor et al., 2016), or SPM (Gunn, 2017), theories which essentially characterize suicide as a way to escape intolerable emotional stress. None would appear incompatible with the view that pain, as a biological imperative, motivates action to end or escape it, while regular adult human cognition offers intentional self-killing as an effective, but genetically destructive, means to answer that demand. But the corollary, that suicide poses an engineering problem, as summed by the tweet that began this chapter, may be harder to digest. Presumably human beings are prevented most of the time from switching themselves off because of one or more special-purpose software patches. Blind to our own instincts (Cosmides and Tooby, 1994), we may be oblivious to their functioning, and skeptical they may even exist. A research program to uncover their workings may not be
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND SUICIDOLOGY
easy to formulate. The idea that humans are equipped with organismic defenses against suicide is not new (e.g., Himmelhoch, 1988; Hundert, 1992; Miller, 2008), but it has only recently gained prominence in the research agenda (Culotta, 2019). Its implications may run wide and deep, and call some longheld preconceptions into question: as Lester (2019) finds, accepting the ramifications may require close reading of the arguments. Progress is not helped by what Soper (2018) believes to be a systematic non-interaction between suicidology and evolutionary psychology, a two-way blockage of ideas that may go beyond the institutional disconnects seen elsewhere in psychological sciences (Staats, 2004). Soper posits that suicide and evolution, each for different reasons, are domains that many people find awkward to think about, researchers included. It may be for this reason that, in one direction, evolutionary psychology has largely ignored suicide, as indeed has psychology generally (Rogers, 2001): in view of the gravity and ubiquity of suicide as a human phenomenon, and the evolutionary puzzle it presents, remarkably little has been written on the subject from an evolutionary perspective, at least until recent years. In the other direction, suicidology has largely ignored evolutionary psychology. It may be illustrative that a rare review of the field, titled ‘Evolutionary processes in suicide’ (Chiurliza et al., 2017), attempts to appraise its research group’s ideas (and, oddly, only that group’s) without reference to evolutionary psychology’s primary texts or tenets – a surprising omission given that evolutionary psychology, ‘the study of behavior from an evolutionary perspective’ (Cornwell et al., 2005: 369), is centrally relevant. This chapter calls for consilience between the two fields. An evolutionary stance would not in itself be a departure for suicidology: it would, rather, follow the lead set by Freud (1920/1991), Shneidman (1985), Joiner (2005), and other prominent researchers, drawing on evolutionary ideas across more than a century. Evolutionary psychology could synthesize, not replace, much of suicidology’s
79
existing theoretical and empirical content. There may be little to lose in such an incremental move. The upsides, on the other hand, may be great. Evolutionary psychology offers fresh perspectives for suicidology, and ready tools that, if used, could be decisive in a battle to save lives. Evolutionary psychology and suicidology deserve each other’s attention.
Notes 1 Reviews of prominent offers can be found in the general suicidology literature (e.g., Gunn, 2019; Gunn and Lester, 2014; O’Connor and Portzky, 2018; Paniagua et al., 2010; Selby et al., 2014). 2 If it were claimed that nonhuman suicide is rare thanks to the action of antisuicide adaptations – something like the ‘patch 7.822’ software update imagined in this chapter’s opening quotation – then those countermeasures need to be identified, as indeed we will later suggest they probably need to be identified in humans. 3 As a side point: some theorists argue that risk of suicide may vary, albeit weakly, with a heritable propensity for certain personality traits, notably impulsivity (McGirr et al., 2008). 4 Suicide would presumably have been no easier in our evolutionary environment. As grounddwellers on open grasslands, it may have been a scarcity of ready opportunities for self-killing that allowed humans to encephalize closer to the cognitive floor for suicide than would be feasible for other social animals. Other social animals that otherwise would be expected to benefit from increased social intelligence (Varki and Brower, 2013) may occupy habitats where suicide could be summarily enacted at almost any time by default – by not gripping (chimp), or not surfacing (dolphin), for example (Soper, 2019b). 5 As a related point, Humphrey (2018) speculates that suicidality may help to account for catastrophic demographic collapses thought to have occurred in early human pre-history.
REFERENCES Aiello, L. C., & Wheeler, P. (1995). The expensive-tissue hypothesis: The brain and the digestive system in human and primate evolution. Current Anthropology, 36(2), 199–221.
80
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Akotia, C. S., Knizek, B. L., Kinyanda, E., & Hjelmeland, H. (2014). ‘I have sinned’: Understanding the role of religion in the experiences of suicide attempters in Ghana. Mental Health, Religion & Culture, 17(5), 437–448. Alexander, R. D. (1974). The evolution of social behavior. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics, 5(1), 325–383. American Association of Suicidology. (2019). History of the American Association of Suicidology. Retrieved from https:// suicidology.org/about-aas/#history (Accessed 20 May 2020) American Psychiatric Association. (2013). Diagnostic And Statistical Manual Of Mental Disorders: DSM-5. New York, NY: American Psychiatric Association. Andoh-Arthur, J., Knizek, B. L., Osafo, J., & Hjelmeland, H. (2020). Societal reactions to suicide in Ghana: A qualitative study of experiences of the bereaved. Crisis, 41(2), 128–134. Anil, M., Preston, J., McKinstry, J., Rodway, R., & Brown, S. (1996). An assessment of stress caused in sheep by watching slaughter of other sheep. Animal Welfare, 5(4), 435–441. Atkinson, J. M. (1978). Discovering Suicide: Studies in the Social Organization of Sudden Death. London, UK: McMillan. Aubin, H.-J., Berlin, I., & Kornreich, C. (2013). The evolutionary puzzle of suicide. International Journal of Environmental Research & Public Health, 10(12), 6873–6886. Auvray, M., Myin, E., & Spence, C. (2010). The sensory-discriminative and affectivemotivational aspects of pain. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews, 34(2), 214–223. Baechler, J. (1975/1979). Les Suicides (B. Cooper, Trans.). New York, NY: Basic Books. Bailey, J. D. (2009). Orphan care: An introduction. Social Work & Society, 7(1), 1–12. Bancroft, J., Hawton, K., Simkin, S., Kingston, B., Cumming, C., & Whitwell, D. (1979). The reasons people give for taking overdoses: A further inquiry. British Journal of Medical Psychology, 52(4), 353–365. Bateson, M., Brilot, B., & Nettle, D. (2011). Anxiety: an evolutionary approach. The Canadian Journal of Psychiatry, 56(12), 707–714.
Baumeister, R. F. (1990). Suicide as escape from self. Psychological Review, 97(1), 90–113. Baumeister, R. F., & Leary, M. R. (1995). The need to belong: Desire for interpersonal attachments as a fundamental human motivation. Psychological Bulletin, 117(3), 497. Baumeister, R. F. (1989). The optimal margin of illusion. Journal of Social and Clinical Psychology, 8(2), 176–189. Benatar, D. (2015). Life is not good. In T. K. Shackelford & R. D. Hansen (Eds.), The Evolution Of Morality (pp. 137–140). Cham, Switzerland: Springer. Bering, J. M. (2018). A Very Human Ending: How Suicide Haunts Our Species. London, UK: Transworld. Bering, J. M., & Shackelford, T. K. (2004). The causal role of consciousness: A conceptual addendum to human evolutionary psychology. Review of General Psychology, 8(4), 227–248. Bjorklund, D. F., Causey, K., & Periss, V. (2010). The evolution and development of human social cognition. In P. M. Kappeler & J. B. Silk (Eds.), Mind The Gap (pp. 351–371). Heidelberg, Germany: Springer. Blanchard, D. C., Griebel, G., & Nutt, D. J. (2011). Handbook Of Anxiety And Fear (Vol. 17). Amsterdam, Netherlands: Academic. Blanchard, D. C., Griebel, G., Pobbe, R., & Blanchard, R. J. (2011). Risk assessment as an evolved threat detection and analysis process. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews, 35(4), 991–998. Blasco-Fontecilla, H., Lopez-Castroman, J., Gomez-Carrillo, A., & Baca-Garcia, E. (2009). Towards an evolutionary framework of suicidal behavior. Medical Hypotheses, 73(6), 1078–1079. Bohannan, P. (Ed.) (1960). African Homicide And Suicide. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Bolton, J. M., Au, W., Leslie, W. D., Martens., Patricia J., Enns, M. W., Roos, L L., & Sareen, J. (2013). Parents bereaved by offspring suicide: A population-based longitudinal case-control study. JAMA Psychiatry, 70(2), 158–167. Bowlby, J. (1969/1997). Attachment And Loss: Attachment (2nd ed. Vol. 1). London, UK: Pimlico. Bowlby, J. (1973). Attachment And Loss: Separation: Anxiety And Anger (2nd ed. Vol. 2). London, UK: Penguin.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND SUICIDOLOGY
Bowlby, J. (1980/1991). Attachment And Loss: Loss: Sadness And Depression (Vol. 3). London, UK: Penguin. Bracke, M. (1992). Can animals have a preference not to be killed?: Observations on red deer, laying hens and mice which were exposed to conspecifics being killed: A study in cognitive ethology (Doctoral dissertation). Edinburgh School of Agriculture, Edinburgh, UK. Brand, P. W., & Yancey, P. (1993). Pain: The Gift Nobody Wants. New York, NY: HarperCollins. Brezo, J., Paris, J., Barker, E. D., Tremblay, R., Vitaro, F., Zoccolillo, M., & Turecki, G. (2007). Natural history of suicidal behaviors in a population-based sample of young adults. Psychological Medicine, 37(11), 1563–1574. Bribiescas, R. G. (2006). On the evolution, life history, and proximate mechanisms of human male reproductive senescence. Evolutionary Anthropology: Issues, News, and Reviews, 15(4), 132–141. Brown, D. E. (2004). Human universals, human nature & human culture. Daedalus, 133(4), 47–54. Brown, G. W. (2009). Medical sociology and issues of aetiology. In M. G. Gelder, N. C. Andreasen, J. J. López-Ibor, & J. R. Geddes (Eds.), New Oxford Textbook Of Psychiatry (pp. 268–275). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Brown, M. F. (1986). Power, gender, and the social meaning of Aguaruna suicide. Man, 21(2), 311–328. Brown, R. M., Brown, S. L., Johnson, A., Olsen, B., Melver, K., & Sullivan, M. (2009). Empirical support for an evolutionary model of selfdestructive motivation. Suicide and LifeThreatening Behavior, 39(1), 1–12. Brown, R. M., Dahlen, E., Mills, C., Rick, J., & Biblarz, A. (1999). Evaluation of an evolutionary model of self-preservation and self-destruction. Suicide and Life-Threatening Behavior, 29(1), 58–71. Brüne, M. (2016). Textbook of Evolutionary Psychiatry and Psychosomatic Medicine: The Origins of Psychopathology (2nd ed.). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Buss, D. M. (1990). Toward a biologically informed psychology of personality. Journal of Personality, 58(1), 1–16.
81
Buss, D. M. (1995). Evolutionary psychology: A new paradigm for psychological science. Psychological Inquiry, 6(1), 1–30. Buss, D. M., & Penke, L. (2015). Evolutionary personality psychology. In M. Mikulincer, P. R. Shaver, M. Cooper, Lynne, & R. J. Larsen (Eds.), APA Handbook Of Personality And Social Psychology: Vol. 4. Personality Processes And Individual Differences (pp. 3– 39). Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. Campbell, A. (2002). A Mind Of Her Own: The Evolutionary Psychology Of Women. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Carter, G., Milner, A., McGill, K., Pirkis, J., Kapur, N., & Spittal, M. J. (2017). Predicting suicidal behaviours using clinical instruments: Systematic review and meta-analysis of positive predictive values for risk scales. The British Journal of Psychiatry, 210(6), 387–395. Caspi, A., Houts, R. M., Belsky, D. W., GoldmanMellor, S. J., Harrington, H., Israel, S., & Moffitt, T. E. (2014). The p factor: One general psychopathology factor in the structure of psychiatric disorders? Clinical Psychological Science, 2(2), 119–137. Cavanagh, J. T. O., Carson, A. J., Sharpe, M., & Lawrie, S. M. (2003). Psychological autopsy studies of suicide: A systematic review. Psychological Medicine, 33(03), 395–405. Cerel, J., & Aldrich, R. S. (2011). The impact of suicide on children and adolescents. In J. R. Jordan & J. L. McIntosh (Eds.), Grief After Suicide: Understanding The Consequences And Caring For The Survivors (pp. 81–92). New York, NY: Routledge. Cerel, J., Brown, M. M., Maple, M., Singleton, M., van de Venne, J., Moore, M., & Flaherty, C. (2019). How many people are exposed to suicide? Not six. Suicide and Life-Threatening Behavior, 49(2), 529–534. Chapple, A., Ziebland, S., & Hawton, K. (2015). Taboo and the different death? Perceptions of those bereaved by suicide or other traumatic death. Sociology of Health & Illness, 37(4), 610–625. Chen, Y.-Y., Chien-Chang Wu, K., Wang, Y., & Yip, P. (2016). Suicide prevention through restricting access to suicide means and hotspots. In R. C. O’Connor & J. Pirkis (Eds.), International Handbook Of Suicide
82
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Prevention (2nd ed., pp. 609–636). Chichester, UK: John Wiley and Sons. Chiurliza, B., Rogers, M. L., Schneider, M. E., Chu, C., & Joiner, T. E. (2017). Evolutionary processes in suicide. Current Opinion in Psychology, 22, 84–88. Cholbi, M. (2017). Suicide. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Fall 2017. Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/ archives/fall2017/entries/suicide/ (Accessed 20 May 2020) Chow, A. Y. M. (2006). The day after: Experiences of bereaved suicide survivors. In C. L. W. C. Chan & A. Y. M. Chow (Eds.), Death, Dying And Bereavement: A Hong Kong Chinese Experience (Vol. 1, pp. 293–308). Aberdeen, Hong Kong: Hong Kong University Press. Chu, C., Buchman-Schmitt, J. M., Stanley, I. H., Hom, M. A., Tucker, R. P., Hagan, C. R., & Ringer, F. B. (2017). The interpersonal theory of suicide: A systematic review and metaanalysis of a decade of cross-national research. Psychological Bulletin, 143(12), 1313–1345. Chung, D., Hadzi-Pavlovic, D., Wang, M., Swaraj, S., Olfson, M., & Large, M. (2019). Meta-analysis of suicide rates in the first week and the first month after psychiatric hospitalisation. BMJ open, 9(3), e023883. Cole, L. C. (1954). The population consequences of life history phenomena. The Quarterly Review of Biology, 29(2), 103–137. Comai, S., & Gobbi, G. (2016). Translational research in suicide: Is it possible to study suicide in animal models? In P. Courtet (Ed.), Understanding Suicide: From Diagnosis To Personalized Treatment (pp. 177–188). Cham, Switzerland: Springer. Confer, J. C., Easton, J. A., Fleischman, D. S., Goetz, C. D., Lewis, D. M., Perilloux, C., & Buss, D. M. (2010). Evolutionary psychology. Controversies, questions, prospects, and limitations. American Psychologist, 65(2), 110–126. Corns, J. (2014). Unpleasantness, motivational oomph, and painfulness. Mind & Language, 29(2), 238–254. Cornwell, R. E., Palmer, C., Guinther, P. M., & Davis, H. P. (2005). Introductory psychology texts as a view of sociobiology/evolutionary psychology’s role in psychology. Evolutionary Psychology, 3(1), 147470490500300124.
Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (1994). Beyond intuition and instinct blindness: Toward an evolutionarily rigorous cognitive science. Cognition, 50(1), 41–77. Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (2000). Evolutionary psychology and the emotions. In M. Lewis & J. M. Haviland-Jones (Eds.), Handbook Of Emotions (Vol. 2, pp. 91–115). New York, NY: Guilford Press. Culotta, E. (2019). Probing an evolutionary riddle. Science, 365(6455), 748–749. Daly, M., & Wilson, M. (1988). Homicide. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction. Darwin, C. (1859). On The Origin Of Species By Means Of Natural Selection, Or The Preservation Of Favoured Races In The Struggle For Life. London, UK: John Murray. Davies, J. (2013). Cracked: Why Psychiatry Is Doing More Harm Than Good. London, UK: Icon. Dawkins, R. (1976). The Selfish Gene (3rd ed.). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Dawkins, R. (1980). Domesticity, senescence, and suicide. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3(2), 274. De Leo, D., Milner, A., Fleischmann, A., Bertolote, J., Collings, S., Amadeo, S., & Saniel, B. (2013). The WHO START Study: Suicidal behaviors across different areas of the world. Crisis, 34(3), 156–163. deCatanzaro, D. (1980). Human suicide: A biological perspective. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3(02), 265–272. deCatanzaro, D. (1981). Suicide And SelfDamaging Behavior: A Sociobiological Perspective. New York, NY: Academic Press. deCatanzaro, D. (1982). Suicide, aggression, and natural selection. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 5(02), 316–317. deCatanzaro, D. (1986). A mathematical model of evolutionary pressures regulating selfpreservation and self-destruction. Suicide and Life-Threatening Behavior, 16(2), 166–181. deCatanzaro, D. (1991). Evolutionary limits to self-preservation. Ethology and Sociobiology, 12(1), 13–28. deCatanzaro, D. (1992). Prediction of selfpreservation failures on the basis of quantitative evolutionary biology. In R. W. Maris, A. L. Berman, J. T. Maltsberger, & R. I. Yufit (Eds.), Assessment And Prediction Of
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND SUICIDOLOGY
Suicide (pp. 607–624). New York, NY: Guilford Press. Delisle, J. R. (1986). Death with honors: Suicide among gifted adolescents. Journal of Counseling and Development, 64(9), 558–560. Del Giudice, M. (2018). Evolutionary psychopathology: A unified approach. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Dickeman, M. (1975). Demographic consequences of infanticide in man. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics, 6(1), 107–137. D. Lester (Ed.), Theories Of Suicide: Past, Present and Future (pp. 9–22). Springfield, IL: Charles C. Thomas. Duntley, J. D. (2005). Adaptations to dangers from humans. In D. M. Buss (Ed.), The Handbook Of Evolutionary Psychology (pp. 224–249). Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley & Sons. Duntley, J. D., & Buss, D. M. (2004). The evolution of evil. In A. G. Miller (Ed.), The Social Psychology Of Good And Evil (pp. 102–124). New York, NY: Guilford Press. Durkheim, E. (1897/1952). La Suicide (J. Spaulding & G. Simpson, Trans.). Henley, UK: Routledge. Dyregrov, K., Plyhn, E., & Dieserud, G. (2012). After The Suicide: Helping The Bereaved To Find A Path From Grief To Recovery. London, UK: Jessica Kingsley. Eccleston, C. (2001). Role of psychology in pain management. British Journal of Anaesthesia, 87(1), 144–152. Efklides, A., & Moraitou, D. (Eds.). (2013). A Positive Psychology Perspective On Quality Of Life. New York, NY: Springer. Eisenberger, N. I., & Lieberman, M. D. (2004). Why rejection hurts: A common neural alarm system for physical and social pain. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8(7), 294–300. Eisenberger, N. I., & Lieberman, M. D. (2005). Why it hurts to be left out: The neurocognitive overlap between physical and social pain. In K. D. Williams, J. P. Forgas, & W. von Hippel (Eds.), The Social Outcast: Ostracism, Social Exclusion, Rejection, And Bullying (pp. 109– 127). New York, NY: Psychology Press. Eisenberger, N. I., Lieberman, M. D., & Williams, K. D. (2003). Does rejection hurt? An fMRI study of social exclusion. Science, 302(5643), 290–292.
83
Engel, C. (2002). Wild Health. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. Erlangsen, A., Runeson, B., Bolton, J. M., Wilcox, H. C., Forman, J. L., Krogh, J., & Conwell, Y. (2017). Association between spousal suicide and mental, physical, and social health outcomes: A longitudinal and nationwide register-based study. JAMA Psychiatry, 74(5), 456–464. Falger, V. S. E., & Falger, E. L. F. (2003). The cultural evolution of dying: Euthanasia in the Netherlands. In A. Somit & S. A. Peterson (Eds.), Human Nature And Public Policy: An Evolutionary Approach (pp. 77–96). New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan. Falk, D. (1990). Brain evolution in Homo: The ‘radiator’ theory. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 13(02), 333–344. Faucher, L. (2016). Darwinian blues: Evolutionary psychiatry and depression. In J. C. Wakefield & S. Demazeux (Eds.), Sadness Or Depression? (pp. 69–94). Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer. Fedden, R. (1938). Suicide; A Social And Historical Study. London, UK: Peter Davies. First, M. B., & Pincus, H. A. (2009). Diagnosis and classification. In M. G. Gelder, N. C. Andreasen, J. J. López-Ibor, & J. R. Geddes (Eds.), New Oxford Textbook Of Psychiatry (pp. 99–121). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Flinn, M. V., & Alexander, R. D. (2007). Runaway social selection in human evolution. In S. W. Gangestad & J. A. Simpson (Eds.), The Evolution Of Mind: Fundamental Questions And Controversies (pp. 249–255). New York, NY: Guilford Press. Flinn, M. V., Quinlan, R. J., Ward, C., & Coe, M. (2007). Evolution of the human family: Cooperative males, long social childhoods, smart mothers, and extended kin networks. In C. Salmon & T. K. Shackelford (Eds.), Family Relationships: An Evolutionary Perspective (pp. 16–38). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Franklin, J. C., Ribeiro, J. D., Fox, K. R., Bentley, K. H., Kleiman, E. M., Huang, X., & Nock, M. K. (2017). Risk factors for suicidal thoughts and behaviors: A meta-analysis of 50 years of research. Psychological Bulletin, 143(2), 187–232. Freud, S. (1920/1991). Beyond The Pleasure Principle (J. Strachey, Trans.). London, UK: Penguin.
84
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Frey, L. M., Hans, J. D., & Cerel, J. (2015). Perceptions of suicide stigma: How do social networks and treatment providers compare? Crisis, 37(2), 95–103. Gallup, G. G., & Weedon, S. L. (2013). Suicide bombers: Does an evolutionary perspective make a difference? Evolutionary Psychology, 11(4), 791–794. Gandhi, S. G., Gilbert, W. M., McElvy, S. S., El Kady, D., Danielson, B., Xing, G., & Smith, L. H. (2006). Maternal and neonatal outcomes after attempted suicide. Obstetrics & Gynecology, 107(5), 984–990. Geary, D. C. (2005). Evolution of paternal investment. In D. M. Buss (Ed.), The Handbook Of Evolutionary Psychology (pp. 483–505). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley. Geary, D. C. (2007). The motivation to control and the evolution of general intelligence. In S. W. Gangestad & J. A. Simpson (Eds.), The Evolution Of Mind: Fundamental Questions And Controversies (pp. 305–312). New York, NY: Guilford Press. Gilbert, P. (1989). Human Nature And Suffering. Hove, UK: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Goldberg, D., & Goodyer, I. (2005). The Origins And Course Of Common Mental Disorders. Hove, UK: Routledge. Goldblatt, M. J. (2014). Psychodynamics of suicide. In M. K. Nock (Ed.), The Oxford Handbook Of Suicide And Self-Injury (pp. 255–264). Oxford, UK: OUP. Goldsmith, S., Pellmar, T., Kleinman, A., & Bunney, W. (2002). Reducing Suicide: A National Imperative. Washington, DC: National Academies Press. Gorelik, G., & Shackelford, T. K. (2017). Suicide and the moralistic fallacy: Comment on Joiner, Hom, Hagan, and Silva (2016). Evolutionary Psychological Science, 3(3), 287–289. Gould, S. J., & Lewontin, R. C. (1979). The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian paradigm: A critique of the adaptationist programme. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 205(1161), 581–598. Grad, O., & Andriessen, K. (2016). Surviving the legacy of suicide. In R. C. O’Connor & J. Pirkis (Eds.), The International Handbook Of Suicide Prevention (pp. 663–680). Chichester, UK: Wiley.
Gunn, J. F. (2014). Suicide as escape: Baechler, Shneidman, and Baumeister. In J. F. Gunn & Gunn, J. F. (2017). The Social Pain Model. Crisis, 38(5), 281–286. Gunn, J. F. (2019). The importance of conceptual and theoretical frameworks. In D. Lester (Ed.), The End Of Suicidology: Can We Ever Understand Suicide? (pp. 135–145). New York, NY: Nova Science Publishers. Gunn, J. F., & Lester, D. (2014). Theories Of Suicide: Past, Present And Future. Springfield, IL: Charles C. Thomas. Hagen, E. H. (2002). Depression as bargaining: The case postpartum. Evolution and Human Behavior, 23(5), 323–336. Hamilton, W. D. (1964). The genetical evolution of social behaviour. I. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 7(1), 1–16. Hamilton, W. D. (1972). Altruism and related phenomena, mainly in social insects. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics, 3(1), 193–232. Hamilton, W. J. (1980). Do nonhuman animals commit suicide? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3(02), 278–279. Hanschmidt, F., Lehnig, F., Riedel-Heller, S. G., & Kersting, A. (2016). The stigma of suicide survivorship and related consequences – a systematic review. PloS One, 11(9), e0162688. Harman, G. H. (1965). Inference to the best explanation. Philosophical Review, 74, 88–95. Harris, E. C., & Barraclough, B. (1997). Suicide as an outcome for mental disorders. A metaanalysis. The British Journal of Psychiatry, 170(3), 205–228. Harris, M. (1974). Cows, Pigs, Wars And Witches: The Riddles Of Culture. New York, NY: Random House. Harris, T. O. (2000). Introduction to the work of George Brown. In T. O. Harris (Ed.), Where Inner And Outer Worlds Meet: Psychosocial Research In The Tradition Of George W Brown (pp. 1–52). London, UK: Routledge. Harvey, A. G. (2004). Cognitive Behavioural Processes Across Psychological Disorders: A Transdiagnostic Approach To Research And Treatment. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Hausfater, G., & Hrdy, S. B. (1984). Infanticide: Comparative And Evolutionary Perspectives. New York, NY: Aldine.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND SUICIDOLOGY
Hawton, K. (2007). Restricting access to methods of suicide: Rationale and evaluation of this approach to suicide prevention. Crisis, 28(S1), 4–9. Healey, C. (1979). Women and suicide in New Guinea. Social Analysis: The International Journal of Social and Cultural Practice, (2), 89–106. Hedegaard, H., Curtin, S. C., & Warner, M. (2018). Suicide mortality in the United States, 1999–2017. NCHS Data Brief, 330, 1–8. Heintzelman, S. J., & King, L. A. (2014). Life is pretty meaningful. American Psychologist, 69(6), 561–574. Hendin, H. (1975). Growing up dead: Student suicide. American Journal of Psychotherapy, 29(3), 327–338. Hengartner, M. P., & Plöderl, M. (2019). Reply to the letter to the editor: ‘Newer-generation antidepressants and suicide risk: Thoughts on Hengartner and Plöderl’s Re-Analysis’. Psychotherapy and Psychosomatics. 88(6), 373–374. Hezel, F. X., Rubinstein, D. H., & White, G. M. (Eds.). (1985). Culture, Youth And Suicide In The Pacific. Honolulu, HI: Pacific Island Studies Program. Himmelhoch, J. M. (1988). What destroys our restraints against suicide? Journal of Clinical Psychiatry, 49(9 (Suppl)), 46–52. Hjelmeland, H., Jaworski, K., Knizek, B. L., & Marsh, I. (2019). Problematic advice from suicide prevention experts. Ethical Human Psychology and Psychiatry, 20(2), 79–85. Hjelmeland, H., & Knizek, B. L. (2019). The emperor’s new clothes? A critical look at the interpersonal theory of suicide. Death Studies, 44(4), 168–178. Hrdy, S. B. (1979). Infanticide among animals: A review, classification, and examination of the implications for the reproductive strategies of females. Ethology and Sociobiology, 1(1), 13–40. Huber, F. (2015/2019). Promise Me You’ll Shoot Yourself (I. Taylor, Trans.). London, UK: Allen Lane. Humphrey, N. (1976). The social function of intellect. In P. Bateson & R. A. Hinde (Eds.), Growing Points In Ethology (pp. 303–317). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Humphrey, N. (2011). Soul Dust: The Magic Of Consciousness. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
85
Humphrey, N. (2018). The lure of death: Suicide and human evolution. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, B, 373, 1–8. Hundert, E. M. (1992). The brain’s capacity to form delusions as an evolutionary strategy for survival. In M. Spitzer, F. Uehlein, M. A. Schwartz, & C. Mundt (Eds.), Phenomenology, Language & Schizophrenia (pp. 346–354). New York, NY: Springer. Johnson, B. D. (1965). Durkheim’s one cause of suicide. American Sociological Review, 30, 875–886. Joiner, T. E. (2005). Why People Die By Suicide. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Joiner, T. E., Buchman-Schmitt, J. M., Chu, C., & Hom, M. A. (2017). A sociobiological extension of the interpersonal theory of suicide. Crisis, 38(2), 69–72. Joiner, T. E., Hom, M. A., Hagan, C. R., & Silva, C. (2016). Suicide as a derangement of the self-sacrificial aspect of eusociality. Psychological Review, 123(3), 235–254. Jordan, J. R. (2008). Bereavement after suicide. Psychiatric Annals, 38(10), 679–685. Jordan, J. R., & McIntosh, J. L. (Eds.). (2011). Grief After Suicide: Understanding The Consequences And Caring For The Survivors. New York, NY: Routledge. Kahne, M. J. (1966). Suicide research: A critical review of strategies and potentialities in mental hospitals (Part II). International Journal of Social Psychiatry, 12(3), 177–186. Kappeler, P. M., Silk, J. S., Burkart, J. M., & van Schaik, C. P. (2010). Primate behavior and human universals: Exploring the gap. In P. M. Kappeler & J. B. Silk (Eds.), Mind The Gap (pp. 3–15). Berlin, Germany: Springer. Kapur, N., Cooper, J., O’Connor, R. C., & Hawton, K. (2013). Non-suicidal self-injury v. attempted suicide: New diagnosis or false dichotomy? The British Journal of Psychiatry, 202(5), 326–328. Kastenbaum, R. (1967). The child’s understanding of death: How does it develop? In E. A. Grollman (Ed.), Explaining Death To Children (pp. 89–100). Boston, MA: Beacon. Keller, M. C., & Miller, G. F. (2006). Resolving the paradox of common, harmful, heritable mental disorders: Which evolutionary genetic models work best? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 29(4), 385–404; discussion 405–352.
86
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Kendell, R., & Jablensky, A. (2003). Distinguishing between the validity and utility of psychiatric diagnoses. American Journal of Psychiatry, 160(1), 4–12. Kennedy, P., Rogers, B., Speer, S., & Frankel, H. (1999). Spinal cord injuries and attempted suicide: A retrospective review. Spinal Cord, 37(12), 847–852. Kessler, R. C., Amminger, G. P., Aguilar-Gaxiola, S., Alonso, J., Lee, S., & Ustun, T. B. (2007). Age of onset of mental disorders: A review of recent literature. Current Opinion in Psychiatry, 20(4), 359. Kessler, R. C., McLaughlin, K. A., Green, J. G., Gruber, M. J., Sampson, N. A., Zaslavsky, A. M., & Angermeyer, M. (2010). Childhood adversities and adult psychopathology in the WHO World Mental Health Surveys. The British Journal of Psychiatry, 197(5), 378–385. Kirkpatrick, L. A., & Navarrete, C. D. (2006). Reports of my death anxiety have been greatly exaggerated: A critique of terror management theory from an evolutionary perspective. Psychological Inquiry, 17(4), 288–298. Klein, R. G., & Edgar, B. (2002). The Dawn Of Human Culture. New York, NY: Wiley. Klonsky, E. D., Dhingra, K., Klonsky, D., & Tapola, V. (2019). An empirical test of the Three-Step Theory (3ST) of suicide in UK university students. Suicide and LifeThreatening Behavior, 49, 478–487. Klonsky, E. D., & May, A. M. (2015). The ThreeStep Theory (3ST): A new theory of suicide rooted in the ‘ideation-to-action’ framework. International Journal of Cognitive Therapy, 8(2), 114–129. Klonsky, E. D., May, A. M., & Saffer, B. Y. (2016). Suicide, suicide attempts, and suicidal ideation. Annual Review of Clinical Psychology, 12, 307–330. Knizek, B. L., Kinyanda, E., Akotia, C. S., & Hjelmeland, H. (2013). Between Hippocrates and God: Ugandan mental health professional’s views on suicide. Mental Health, Religion & Culture, 16(8), 767–780. Kuhl, J., Quirin, M., & Koole, S. L. (2015). Being someone: The integrated self as a neuropsychological system. Social and Personality Psychology Compass, 9(3), 115–132.
Kuhn, T. S. (1977). The Essential Tension — Selected Studies In Scientific Tradition And Change. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Lankford, A. (2013). The Myth Of Martyrdom. New York, NY: Palgrave. Lankford, A. (2015). Is suicide terrorism really the product of an evolved sacrificial tendency? A review of mammalian research and application of evolutionary theory. Comprehensive Psychology, 4(21). Lauder, G. V. (1996). The argument from design. In M. R. Rose & G. V. Lauder (Eds.), Adaptation (pp. 55–87). San Diego, CA: Academic Press. Layard, R. (2011). Happiness: Lessons From A New Science (2nd ed.). London, UK: Penguin. Leary, M. R., & Guadagno, J. (2011). The sociometer, self-esteem, and the regulation of interpersonal behavior. In K. D. Vohs & R. F. Baumeister (Eds.), Handbook Of SelfRegulation: Research, Theory, And Applications (2nd ed., pp. 339–354). New York, NY: Guilford Press. Leary, M. R., Tambor, E. S., Terdal, S. K., & Downs, D. L. (1995). Self-esteem as an interpersonal monitor: The sociometer hypothesis. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 68(3), 518. Lester, D. (1993). The stigma against dying and suicidal patients: A replication of Richard Kalish’s study twenty-five years later. OMEGA Journal of Death and Dying, 26(1), 71–75. Lester, D. (2014a). Suicide as deviance. In J. F. Gunn & D. Lester (Eds.), Theories Of Suicide: Past, Present And Future (pp. 244–277). Springfield, IL: Charles C. Thomas. Lester, D. (2014b). Suicide, ethology and sociobiology. In J. F. Gunn & D. Lester (Eds.), Theories Of Suicide: Past, Present And Future (pp. 55–71). Springfield, IL: Charles C. Thomas. Lester, D. (2017). Non-human animal suicide could be tested. Animal Sentience, 2(20), 3. Lester, D. (2019). The End Of Suicidology: Can We Ever Understand Suicide? New York, NY: Nova Science Publishers. Lieberman, M. D. (2013). Social: Why Our Brains Are Wired To Connect. Oxford, UK: OUP. Litman, R. E. (1967). Sigmund Freud on suicide. In E. Shneidman (Ed.), Essays In
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND SUICIDOLOGY
Self-Destruction (pp. 324–344). New York, NY: Aronson. Linehan, M. M. (2020). Building a Life Worth Living. New York, NY: Random House. Macdonald, C. J.-H. (2007). Uncultural Behavior: An Anthropological Investigation Of Suicide In The Southern Philippines. Honolulu, HI: University of Hawai’i Press. MacDonald, G., & Leary, M. R. (2005). Why does social exclusion hurt? The relationship between social and physical pain. Psychological Bulletin, 131(2), 202. Malkesman, O., Pine, D. S., Tragon, T., Austin, D. R., Henter, I. D., Chen, G., & Manji, H. K. (2009). Animal models of suicide-traitrelated behaviors. Trends in Pharmacological Sciences, 30(4), 165–173. Maltsberger, J. T. (2003). Can a louse commit suicide? Crisis, 24(4), 175–176. Maple, M., Frey, L. M., McKay, K., Coker, S., & Grey, S. (2019). “Nobody hears a silent cry for help”: Suicide attempt survivors’ experiences of disclosing during and after a crisis. Archives of Suicide Research, 1–19. Maris, R. W. (1982). Rational suicide: An impoverished self-transformation. Suicide and Life-Threatening Behavior, 12(1), 4–16. Maris, R. W. (2015). Pillaged: Psychiatric Medications And Suicide Risk. Columbia, SC: University of South Carolina Press. Marušič, A., & Swapp, R. (2004). Suicide genes floating in a glass of sparkling wine. Archives of Suicide Research, 8(4), 297–301. Maynard Smith, J. (1964). Group selection and kin selection. Nature, 201, 1145–1147. Mayr, E. (1965). Cause and effect in biology. In D. Lerner (Ed.), Cause And Effect (pp. 33– 50). New York, NY: Free Press. McGirr, A., Renaud, J., Bureau, A., Seguin, M., Lesage, A., & Turecki, G. (2008). Impulsiveaggressive behaviours and completed suicide across the life cycle: A predisposition for younger age of suicide. Psychological Medicine, 38(3), 407–417. McNally, R. J. (2016). The legacy of Seligman’s ‘Phobias and Preparedness’ (1971). Behavior Therapy, 47(5), 585–594. Meehl, P. E. (1973). Why I Do Not Attend Case Conferences. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press. Mehlum, L., & Mork, E. (2016). After the suicide attempt – the need for continuity and
87
quality of care. In R. C. O’Connor & J. Pirkis (Eds.), The International Handbook Of Suicide Prevention (pp. 387–402). Chichester, UK: Wiley. Melzack, R., & Casey, K. L. (1968). Sensory, motivational and central control determinants of pain: A new conceptual model. In D. Kenshalo (Ed.), The Skin Senses (pp. 423–443). Springfield, IL: Charles C. Thomas. Menninger, K. A. (1938). Man Against Himself. New York, NY: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich. Menninger, K. A. (1963). The Vital Balance: The Life Process In Mental Health And Illness. New York, NY: Viking. Merrick, J., Merrick, E., Lunsky, Y., & Kandel, I. (2006). A review of suicidality in persons with intellectual disability. The Israel Journal of Psychiatry and Related Sciences, 43(4), 258. Miller, G. (2000). Sexual selection for indicators of intelligence. In G. R. Bock, J. A. Goode, & K. Webb (Eds.), The Nature Of Intelligence: Novartis Foundation Symposium 233 (pp. 260–275). Chichester, UK: Wiley. Miller, G. F., & Penke, L. (2007). The evolution of human intelligence and the coefficient of additive genetic variance in human brain size. Intelligence, 35(2), 97–114. Miller, M. B. (2008). Suicide and evolution (Thesis). Florida State University, Tallahassee, FL. Mishara, B. L. (1999). Conceptions of death and suicide in children ages 6–12 and their implications for suicide prevention. Suicide and Life-Threatening Behavior, 29(2), 105–118. Mishara, B. L. (2003). Suicide types: Rational. In R. Kastenbaum (Ed.), Macmillan Encyclopedia Of Death And Dying (Vol. 2). New York, NY: Macmillan. Mishara, B. L. (2006). Cultural specificity and universality of suicide: Challenges for the International Association for Suicide Prevention. Crisis, 27(1), 1–3. Mishara, B. L., & Chagnon, F. (2016). Why mental illness is a risk factor for suicide: Implications for suicide prevention. In R. C. O’Connor & J. E. Pirkis (Eds.), International Handbook Of Suicide Prevention (2nd ed., pp. 594–608). Chichester, UK: Wiley. Mugisha, J., Hjelmeland, H., Kinyanda, E., & Knizek, B. L. (2011). Distancing: A traditional
88
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
mechanism of dealing with suicide among the Baganda, Uganda. Transcultural Psychiatry, 48(5), 624–642. Mullins, N., Bigdeli, T. B., Børglum, A., Coleman, J., Demontis, D., Mehta, D., & Lewis, C. M. (2019). GWAS of suicide attempt in psychiatric disorders and association with major depression polygenic risk scores. American Journal of Psychiatry, 176(8), 651–660. Murray, H. A., & Kluckhohn, C. (1948). Outline of a conception of personality. In C. Kluckhohn & H. A. Murray (Eds.), Personality In Nature, Society, And Culture (pp. 3–32). Oxford, UK: Knopf. Naghavi, M. (2019). Global, regional, and national burden of suicide mortality 1990 to 2016: Systematic analysis for the Global Burden of Disease Study 2016. BMJ, 364(l94), 1–11. Nesse, R. M., & Schulkin, J. (2019). An evolutionary medicine perspective on pain and its disorders. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 374(20190288), 1–7. Nesse, R. M., & Williams, G. C. (1995). Why We Get Sick. New York, NY: Random House. Nock, M. K., Borges, G., Bromet, E. J., Cha, C. B., Kessler, R. C., & Lee, S. (2012). The epidemiology of suicide and suicidal behavior. In M. K. Nock, G. Borges, & Y. Ono (Eds.), Suicide: Global Perspectives From The WHO World Mental Health Surveys (pp. 5–32). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Nock, M. K., Borges, G., & Ono, Y. (2012). Conclusions and future directions. In M. K. Nock, G. Borges, & Y. Ono (Eds.), Suicide: Global Perspectives From The WHO World Mental Health Surveys (pp. 222–225). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Nock, M. K., Green, J., Hwang, I., McLaughlin, K. A., Sampson, N. A., Zaslavsky, A. M., & Kessler, R. C. (2013). Prevalence, correlates, and treatment of lifetime suicidal behavior among adolescents: Results from the National Comorbidity Survey Replication Adolescent Supplement. JAMA Psychiatry, 70(3), 300–310. Nock, M. K., Ramirez, F., & Rankin, O. (2019). Advancing our understanding of the who, when, and why of suicide risk. JAMA Psychiatry, 76(1), 11–12. Nock, M. K., Ursano, R. J., Heeringa, S. G., Stein, M. B., Jain, S., Raman, R., & Fullerton,
C. S. (2015). Mental disorders, comorbidity, and pre-enlistment suicidal behavior among new soldiers in the US Army: Results from the Army Study to Assess Risk and Resilience in Service members (Army STARRS). Suicide and Life-Threatening Behavior, 45(5), 588–599. O’Connell, S., & Dunbar, R. (2003). A test for comprehension of false belief in chimpanzees. Evolution and Cognition, 9(2), 131–140. O’Connor, R. J. (1978). Brood reduction in birds: Selection for fratricide, infanticide and suicide? Animal Behaviour, 26, 79–96. O’Connor, R. C. (2011). Towards an integrated motivational-volitional model of suicidal behaviour. In R. C. O’Connor, S. Platt, & J. Gordon (Eds.), International Handbook Of Suicide Prevention: Research, Policy And Practice (pp. 181–198). Chichester, UK: John Wiley and Sons. O’Connor, R. C., Cleare, S., Eschle, S., Wetherall, K., & Kirtley, O. J. (2016). The integrated motivational-volitional model of suicidal behavior: An update. In R. C. O’Connor & J. Pirkis (Eds.), International Handbook Of Suicide Prevention (2nd ed., pp. 220–240). Chichester, UK: John Wiley and Sons. O’Connor, R. C., & Portzky, G. (2018). Looking to the future: A synthesis of new developments and challenges in suicide research and prevention. Frontiers in Psychology, 9(2139), 1–14. Orbell, J., & Morikawa, T. (2011). An evolutionary account of suicide attacks: The kamikaze case. Political Psychology, 32(2), 297–322. Paniagua, F. A., Black, S. A., Gallaway, M. S., & Coombs, M. A. (2010). The InterpersonalPsychological Theory Of Attempted And Completed Suicide. Bloomington, IN: AuthorHouse. Parker, G. A., & Smith, J. M. (1990). Optimality theory in evolutionary biology. Nature, 348(6296), 27. Paulhus, D. L., & Buckels, E. (2012). Classic selfdeception revisited. In S. Vazire & T. D. Wilson (Eds.), Handbook Of Self-Knowledge (pp. 363–378). New York, NY: Guilford Press. Peña-Guzmán, D. M. (2018). Can nondolphins commit suicide? Animal Sentience, 2(20), 20.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND SUICIDOLOGY
Penney, D., Stewart, A., & Parr, M. (2002). Prognostic outcome indicators following hanging injuries. Resuscitation, 54(1), 27–29. Perry, S. A. (2014). Every Cradle Is A Grave: Rethinking The Ethics Of Birth And Suicide. Charleston, WV: Nine-Banded Books. Perry, S. A. (2015). Antinatalism in biological and cultural evolution: Fertility and suicide. In T. K. Shackelford & R. D. Hansen (Eds.), The Evolution Of Morality (pp. 141–154). Cham, Switzerland: Springer. Perry, S. A. (2016). Patch 7.822: An experimental design puzzle. Retrieved from https://theviewfromhellyes.wordpress.com (October 2016) Persley, G., & Pegg, S. P. (1981). Burn injuries related to suicide. Medical Journal of Australia, 1(3), 134. Pinker, S. (1997). How The Mind Works. New York, NY: Norton. Pinker, S. (2010). The cognitive niche: Coevolution of intelligence, sociality, and language. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 107(Supplement 2), 8993–8999. Pitman, A. L., Osborn, D. P. J., King, M. B., & Erlangsen, A. (2014). Effects of suicide bereavement on mental health and suicide risk. The Lancet Psychiatry, 1(1), 86–94. Pitman, A. L., Osborn, D. P. J., Rantell, K., & King, M. B. (2016). Bereavement by suicide as a risk factor for suicide attempt: A crosssectional national UK-wide study of 3432 young bereaved adults. BMJ, 6(1), e009948. Poole, F. J. P. (1985). Among the boughs of the hanging tree: Male suicide among the BiminKuskusmin of Papua New Guinea. In F. X. Hezel, D. H. Rubinstein, & G. M. White (Eds.), Culture, Youth and Suicide in the Pacific: Papers from an East-West Center Conference (pp. 152–181). Honolulu, HI: University of Hawaii at Manoa. Preti, A. (2007). Suicide among animals: a review of evidence. Psychological Reports, 101(3), 831–848. Preti, A. (2011). Animal model and neurobiology of suicide. Progress in Neuro- Psychopharmacology and Biological Psychiatry, 35(4), 818–830. Ramsden, E., & Wilson, D. (2010). The nature of suicide: Science and the self-destructive animal. Endeavour, 34(1), 21–24.
89
Riordan, D. (2019). Suicide and human sacrifice; sacrificial victim hypothesis on the evolutionary origins of suicide. Suicidology Online, 10(2), 1–10. Rogers, J. R. (2001). Theoretical grounding: The ‘missing link’ in suicide research. Journal of Counseling & Development, 79(1), 16–25. Rogers, M. L., Ringer, F. B., & Joiner, T. E. (2018). The association between suicidal ideation and lifetime suicide attempts is strongest at low levels of depression. Psychiatry Research, 270, 324–328. Rubinstein, D. H. (1986). A stress–diathesis theory of suicide. Suicide and LifeThreatening Behavior, 16(2), 182–197. Saad, G. (2007). Suicide triggers as sex-specific threats in domains of evolutionary import: Negative correlation between global male-tofemale suicide ratios and average per capita gross national income. Medical Hypotheses, 68(3), 692–696. Salim, A., Martin, M., Sangthong, B., Brown, C., Rhee, P., & Demetriades, D. (2006). Nearhanging injuries: A 10-year experience. Injury, 37(5), 435–439. Sarkar, S. (1998). Genetics and Reductionism. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Satcher, D. (1999). The Surgeon General’s Call To Action To Prevent Suicide. Washington, DC: US Public Health Service. Saunders, K. E., Hawton, K., Fortune, S., & Farrell, S. (2012). Attitudes and knowledge of clinical staff regarding people who selfharm: A systematic review. Journal of Affective Disorders, 139(3), 205–216. Schaeffer, H. (1967). Can a mouse commit suicide? In E. Shneidman (Ed.), Essays In Self Destruction. Northvale, NJ: Jason Aronson. Schechter, M. A., & Goldblatt, M. J. (2020). Suicide: A transdiagnostic phenomenon. Psychiatric Annals, 50, 136–137. Schmidtke, A. (1997). Suicide in Europe. Suicide and Life-Threatening Behavior, 27(1), 127–136. Seiden, R. H. (1969). Suicide Among Youth. A Review Of The Literature, 1900–1967. Chevy Chase, MD: National Clearinghouse for Mental Health Information. Selby, E. A., Joiner, T. E., & Ribeiro, J. D. (2014). Comprehensive theories of suicidal behaviors. In M. K. Nock (Ed.), The Oxford Handbook
90
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Of Suicide And Self-Injury (pp. 286–307). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Sesardic, N. (2005). From genes to incest taboos: The crucial step. In A. P. Wolf & W. H. Durham (Eds.), Inbreeding, Incest, And The Incest Taboo: The State Of Knowledge At The Turn Of The Century (pp. 109–120). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Seyfried, L. S., Kales, H. C., Ignacio, R. V., Conwell, Y., & Valenstein, M. (2011). Predictors of suicide in patients with dementia. Alzheimer’s & Dementia, 7(6), 567–573. Shaffer, D. (1974). Suicide in childhood and early adolescence. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 15(4), 275–291. Sharma, T., Guski, L. S., Freund, N., & Gøtzsche, P. C. (2016). Suicidality and aggression during antidepressant treatment: Systematic review and meta-analyses based on clinical study reports. BMJ, 352, i65. Sheehan, L. L., Corrigan, P. W., & Al-Khouja, M. A. (2016). Stakeholder perspectives on the stigma of suicide attempt survivors. Crisis, 38(2), 73–81. Retrieved from https://doi. org/10.1027/0227-5910/a000413 Shneidman, E. S. (1985). Definition Of Suicide. New York, NY: John Wiley & Sons. Shneidman, E. S. (1993). Suicide As Psychache: A Clinical Approach To Self-Destructive Behavior. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield. Shneidman, E. S. (1996). The Suicidal Mind. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Shneidman, E. S. (2001). Comprehending Suicide. Landmarks In 20th-Century Suicidology. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. Shneidman, E. S. (2005). Anodyne psychotherapy for suicide: A psychological view of suicide. Clinical Neuropsychiatry, 2(1), 7–12. Shneidman, E. S., & Farberow, N. L. (Eds.). (1961). The Cry For Help. New York, NY: McGraw-Hill. Shorter, J., & Rueppell, O. (2012). A review on self-destructive defense behaviors in social insects. Insectes Sociaux, 59(1), 1–10. Skinner, B. F. (1969). Contingencies Of Reinforcement: A Theoretical Analysis. New York, NY: Meredith. Slaughter, V., & Griffiths, M. (2007). Death understanding and fear of death in young
children. Clinical Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 12(4), 525–535. Solano, P., Pizzorno, E., Pompili, M., Serafini, G., & Amore, M. (2018). Conceptualizations of suicide through time and socio-economic factors: a historical mini-review. Irish Journal of Psychological Medicine, 35(1), 75–86. Soper, C. A. (2016). Could some common mental diseases have evolved to prevent suicide? – a theoretical enquiry. Paper presented at the 16th European Symposium on Suicide and Suicidal Behaviour, Oviedo, Spain. Soper, C. A. (2017). Towards solving the evolutionary puzzle of suicide (PhD thesis). University of Gloucestershire, Cheltenham, UK. Soper, C. A. (2018). The Evolution Of Suicide. Cham, Switzerland: Springer. Soper, C. A. (2019a). Beyond the search for suigiston: How evolution offers oxygen for suicidology. In V. Zeigler-Hill & T. K. Shackelford (Eds.), Evolutionary Perspectives On Death (pp. 37–61). Cham, Switzerland: Springer. Soper, C. A. (2019b). Adaptation to the suicidal niche. Evolutionary Psychological Science. 5(4), 454–471. Soper, C. A., & Shackelford, T. K. (2018). If nonhuman animals can suicide, why don’t they? Animal Sentience, 2(20), 14. Staats, A. W. (2004). The disunity-unity dimension. American Psychologist, 59(4), 273. Stanley, I., Hom, M., Boffa, J., Stage, D. R. L., & Joiner, T. E. (2019). PTSD from a suicide attempt: An empirical investigation among suicide attempt survivors. Journal of Clinical Psychology, 75(10), 1879–1895. Steinmetz, S. R. (1894). Suicide among primitive peoples. American Anthropologist, 7(1), 53–60. Stengel, E. (1970). Suicide And Attempted Suicide (Revised ed.). London, UK: Penguin. Stochl, J., Khandaker, G., Lewis, G., Perez, J., Goodyer, I., Zammit, S., & Jones, P. (2015). Mood, anxiety and psychotic phenomena measure a common psychopathological factor. Psychological Medicine, 45(7), 1483–1493. Sudak, H., Maxim, K., & Carpenter, M. (2008). Suicide and stigma: A review of the literature
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND SUICIDOLOGY
and personal reflections. Academic Psychiatry, 32(2), 136–142. Suddendorf, T. (2013). The Gap: The Science Of What Separates Us From Other Animals. New York, NY: Basic Books. Sveen, C. A., & Walby, F. A. (2008). Suicide survivors’ mental health and grief reactions: A systematic review of controlled studies. Suicide and Life-Threatening Behavior, 38(1), 13–29. Syme, K. L., Garfield, Z. H., & Hagen, E. H. (2016). Testing the bargaining vs. inclusive fitness models of suicidal behavior against the ethnographic record. Evolution and Human Behavior, 37(3), 179–192. Syme, K. L., & Hagen, E. H. (2018). When saying ‘sorry’ isn’t enough: Is some suicidal behavior a costly signal of apology? A crosscultural test. Human Nature, 30(1), 117–141. Symons, D. (1992). On the use and misuse of Darwinism in the study of human behavior. In J. Barkow, L. Cosmides, & J. Tooby (Eds.), The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology And The Generation Of Culture (pp. 137– 162). New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Tanaka, M., & Kinney, D. K. (2011). An evolutionary hypothesis of suicide: Why it could be biologically adaptive and is so prevalent in certain occupations. Psychological Reports, 108(3), 977–992. Tidemalm, D., Runeson, B., Waern, M., Frisell, T., Carlström, E., Lichtenstein, P., & Långström, N. (2011). Familial clustering of suicide risk: A total population study of 11.4 million individuals. Psychological Medicine, 41(12), 2527–2534. Tinbergen, N. (1963). On aims and methods of ethology. Zeitschrift für Tierpsychologie, 20(4), 410–433. Tolaas, J. (2005). Evolution And Suicide. Salt Lake City, UT: American University & Colleges Press. Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (1990a). On the universality of human nature and the uniqueness of the individual: The role of genetics and adaptation. Journal of Personality, 58(1), 17–67. Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (1990b). The past explains the present: Emotional adaptations and the structure of ancestral environments. Ethology and Sociobiology, 11(4), 375–424.
91
Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (1992). The psychological foundations of culture. In J. H. Barkow, L. Cosmides, & J. Tooby (Eds.), The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology And The Generation Of Culture (pp. 19–136). New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (2005). Conceptual foundations of evolutionary psychology. In D. M. Buss (Ed.), The Handbook Of Evolutionary Psychology (pp. 5–67). Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley & Sons. Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (2008). The evolutionary psychology of the emotions and their relationship to internal regulatory variables. In M. Lewis, J. M. Haviland-Jones, & L. F. Barrett (Eds.), Handbook Of Emotions (3rd ed., pp. 114–137). New York, NY: Guilford Press. Tooby, J., & DeVore, I. (1987). The reconstruction of hominid behavioral evolution through strategic modeling. In W. G. Kinzey (Ed.), The Evolution Of Human Behavior: Primate Models (pp. 183–237). Albany, NY: State University of New York. Tousignant, M. (1998). Suicide in small-scale societies. Transcultural Psychiatry, 35(2), 291–306. Townsend, E. (2007). Suicide terrorists: Are they suicidal? Suicide and Life-Threatening Behavior, 37(1), 35–49. Turecki, G., & Brent, D. A. (2016). Suicide and suicidal behaviour. The Lancet, 387(10024), 1227–1239. Usall, J., Pinto-Meza, A., Fernández, A., de Graaf, R., Demyttenaere, K., Alonso, J., & Haro, J. M. (2009). Suicide ideation across reproductive life cycle of women: Results from a European epidemiological study. Journal of Affective Disorders, 116(1), 144–147. van Dongen, J., & Boomsma, D. I. (2013). The evolutionary paradox and the missing heritability of schizophrenia. American Journal of Medical Genetics Part B: Neuropsychiatric Genetics, 162(2), 122–136. Van Orden, K. A., Witte, T. K., Cukrowicz, K. C., Braithwaite, S. R., Selby, E. A., & Joiner, T. E. (2010). The interpersonal theory of suicide. Psychological Review, 117(2), 575–600. Varki, A., & Brower, D. (2013). Denial: SelfDeception, False Beliefs, And The Origins Of The Human Mind. New York, NY: Twelve.
92
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Värnik, P. (2012). Suicide in the world. International Journal of Environmental Research And Public Health, 9(3), 760–771. Voracek, M. (2006). Smart and suicidal? The social ecology of intelligence and suicide in Austria. Death Studies, 30(5), 471–485. Voracek, M., & Marušič, A. (2008). Testing the Finno-Ugrian Suicide Hypothesis: Geographic variation of elderly suicide rates across Europe. Nordic Journal of Psychiatry, 62(4), 302–308. Wiley, J. (2020). Psychological Aposematism: An Evolutionary Analysis of Suicide. Biological Theory. doi:10.1007/s13752-020-00353-8 World Health Organization. (2012). Public Health Action For The Prevention Of Suicide: A Framework. Geneva, Switzerland: World Health Organization. World Health Organization. (2013). Projections of Mortality and Causes of Death, 2015 and 2030. Retrieved from www.who.int/ healthinfo/global_burden_disease/en/ (Accessed February 2016) World Health Organization. (2014). Preventing Suicide: A Global Imperative. Geneva, Switzerland: World Health Organization. Waldmann, M. R., Hagmayer, Y., & Blaisdell, A. P. (2006). Beyond the information given: Causal models in learning and reasoning. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 15(6), 307–311. Walker, M., Moreau, D., & Weissman, M. M. (1990). Parents’ awareness of children’s suicide attempts. American Journal of Psychiatry, 147(10), 1364–1366. Wall, P. D. (1999). Pain: The Science Of Suffering. London, UK: Weidenfeld & Nicholson. Wampold, B. E. (2018). The therapeutic value of the relationship for placebo effects and other healing practices. International Review of Neurobiology, 139, 191–210. Wampold, B. E., & Imel, Z. E. (2015). The Great Psychotherapy Debate: The Evidence For What Makes Psychotherapy Work (2nd ed.). New York, NY: Routledge. Wasserman, D., Rihmer, Z., Rujescu, D., Sarchiapone, M., Sokolowski, M., Titelman, D., & Carli, V. (2012). The European Psychiatric Association (EPA) guidance on suicide treatment and prevention. European Psychiatry, 27(2), 129–141.
Wertheimer, A. (2014). A Special Scar: The Experiences Of People Bereaved By Suicide (3rd ed.). Abingdon, UK: Routledge. Williams, G. C. (1957). Pleiotropy, natural selection, and the evolution of senescence. Evolution, 11(4), 398–411. Williams, G. C. (1966). Adaptation And Natural Selection: A Critique Of Some Current Evolutionary Thought. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Williams, G. C. (1992). Natural Selection: Domains, Levels, And Challenges. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Williams, G. C. (1996). Plan And Purpose In Nature. London, UK: Weidenfeld & Nicholson. Williams, J. M. G. (1997). Cry Of Pain: Understanding Suicide And Self-Harm. London, UK: Penguin. Williams, J. M. G., Crane, C., Barnhofer, T., & Duggan, D. S. (2005). Psychology and suicidal behaviour: Elaborating the entrapment model. In K. Hawton (Ed.), Prevention And Treatment Of Suicidal Behaviour: From Science To Practice (pp. 71–89). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Williams, J. M. G., & Pollock, L. R. (2000). The psychology of suicidal behaviour. In K. Hawton & K. van Heeringen (Eds.), The International Handbook Of Suicide And Attempted Suicide (pp. 79–94). Chichester, UK: John Wiley & Sons. Willner, P., & Belzung, C. (2015). Treatmentresistant depression: Are animal models of depression fit for purpose? Psychopharmacology, 232(19), 3473–3495. Wilson, D. S. (1980). Suicide, beanbag genetics, and pleiotropy. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3(2), 283. Wilson, D. S., & Wilson, E. O. (2007). Rethinking the theoretical foundation of sociobiology. The Quarterly Review of Biology, 82(4), 327–348. Wilson, J. D., & Roehrborn, C. (1999). Longterm consequences of castration in men: Lessons from the Skoptzy and the eunuchs of the Chinese and Ottoman courts. The Journal of Clinical Endocrinology & Metabolism, 84(12), 4324–4331. Wright, R. (1994). The Moral Animal. New York, NY: Vintage. Wright, S. (1943). Isolation by distance. Genetics, 28(2), 114–138.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND SUICIDOLOGY
Zalsman, G., Hawton, K., Wasserman, D., van Heeringen, K., Arensman, E., Sarchiapone, M., & Zohar, J. (2017). Evidence-based national suicide prevention taskforce in Europe: A consensus position paper. European Neuropsychopharmacology, 27(4), 418–421.
93
Zilboorg, G. (1936a). Differential diagnostic types of suicide. Archives of Neurology & Psychiatry, 35(2), 270–291. Zilboorg, G. (1936b). Suicide among civilized and primitive races. American Journal of Psychiatry, 92(6), 1347–1369.
4 Evolutionary Psychology and Mindfulness and Meditation: Easing the Anxiety of Being Human James Carmody
INTRODUCTION Something called mindfulness seems to be popping up everywhere: in clinics and hospitals, schools, corporate offices, prisons, online, the list keeps expanding. Today, at the local farmer’s market, I bought greens from ‘Mindful Veggies’. Promoted as a wellbeing enhancer, studies show that mindfulness does indeed reduce stress and distress in a range of conditions and circumstances (Goyal et al., 2014; Willem et al., 2016). In this chapter I describe the evolutionary roots of the psychological processes that give rise to the human angst that mindfulness addresses and how the training exercises designed to cultivate it alleviate that distress. And to provide context for those I first describe the cultural roots of mindfulness and meditation. Several innovative approaches to inquiry emerged during what has been called the Axial Age. In contrast to the Platonic and Aristotelian systems developing in Greece during that era, internal psychological models
developed in India including those of Vedanta and Buddhism. Training exercises designed to develop the personal qualities required to actualize the models’ goals were also developed and in keeping with approaches to knowledge at the time, these were not clearly distinguished from religion. Mindfulness, as it is now commonly recognized in the West, came primarily out of Buddhism and is described in the following section. Buddhist principles, particularly, later spread into other parts of Asia and integrated into those countries’ prevailing spiritual belief systems. Both parties were changed as a result of those meetings. After a hiatus of several centuries, increased global mobility brought Buddhism to Western countries and once again it has been adapted into the prevailing cultural narrative. One of those adaptations has been the integration of mindfulness, a core tenet of the system described in the following section, into the cultural narrative of self-help. The cultural origins and purpose of Buddhism however have parallels in some Vedanta
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND MINDFULNESS AND MEDITATION
practices that also have migrated to the West in the various forms of yoga. This secular transition has made its benefits more widely available than they might otherwise have been, for although a practice from a religious system is attractive to some people, it is alienating to many in the secular West. This transition has also brought mindfulness under the gaze of empirical science and close inspection of its mechanisms of action reveals parallels and differences in some principles independently developed in Western psychology to categorize, account for, and alleviate human angst. Those principles, together with evolutionary theory, can provide a coherent and culturally familiar explanation of the everyday mental unease that plagues us and how the practice of mindfulness alleviates it. This evolutionary and needs-based lens describes inbuilt patterns of attending that keep us illat-ease, and the psychological principles that mindfulness and several similar mind–body practices draw upon in enabling the recognition and amelioration of that distress. The description draws upon my own and others’ published studies of the clinical effects and mechanisms of mindfulness training (MT), as well as experience and feedback from teaching mindfulness to patients and clinicians. The description is phenomenological because suffering and mindfulness are rooted in felt experience and it is their felt sense that people wish to address in doing the practices. Clinicians also talk most meaningfully to patients in those terms. In that sense, mindfulness practices can be thought of as phenomenologically empirical explorations of the mental processes giving rise to mental distress and the capacity for self- regulation that emerges in the face of it. The chapter also draws upon my own experience with 50 years of practice in Buddhist and Vedantic traditions of inquiry in Asia and Western countries. Many academic papers about mindfulness are caught in attempting objectivity in relation to something that is often anything but. In the background, u sually undescribed, stands the author’s positive personal experience with mindfulness that led
95
them to the research and that has guided their decisions about the conditions, instruction, and syllabus of the mindfulness intervention. For mindfulness makes apparent the normally unrecognized patterns of attending that nevertheless continuously affect our felt sense and the background hope is that study participants also will benefit from that kind of noticing.
THE CULTURAL ROOTS OF MINDFULNESS AND ITS MIGRATION INTO WESTERN SETTINGS The Buddhist and Vedanta narratives are rooted in the primarily introspective approaches to knowledge extant in India around 500 BCE, the time of the historical Buddha. They each place the source of human angst in ignorance of the moment-by-moment construction of the personal self, and the chronic dissatisfaction (suffering) arising from the accompanying sense of ownership of its desires and aversions. In this respect they are not a description of how the physical world operates, but of what we call mind. As the Buddha described his insight into this dilemma to others and the experience of enlightened release accompanying it, an eightfaceted system developed through which they also could cultivate a similar recognition. One facet was the cultivation of something called ‘sati’ to serve as a heuristic aid for real-time recognition of these mental operations and their effects. Sati is from the Pali language spoken in Northern India at the time, but that is no longer understood outside the Indian scholarship community. Exactly how sati was translated, described, and cultivated varied in the places to which Buddhism migrated over the centuries. This is apparent in the varied teachings and practices of the Western Buddhist sects whose traditions derive from those countries. Mindfulness, a term with an already existing meaning in English, emerged as the accepted translation during the 19th century as Buddhism was becoming of interest in the West.
96
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Recognizing the commonality that Buddhism’s goal of reducing mental suffering had with the goal of patient care, Kabat-Zinn (Kabat-Zinn, 1982) experimented with teaching groups of patients a selection of training exercises used to cultivate sati in South Asian traditions. Those patients described obtaining benefits in coping with their illnesses from participating in the classes that came to be called the Mindfulness-Based Stress Reduction (MBSR) program. Replications in peer-reviewed journals affirmed those benefits and the program became widely used in clinics (Shonin et al., 2015). Principles and practices from MBSR form the foundation for many of the adaptations and applications found in the wide variety of settings in which mindfulness now appears. While the processes at the root of the mental distress that the cultivation of mindfulness addresses are interwoven and run in parallel, for explanatory purposes I describe them as a sequence. It is important also to note that early Buddhism employed a somewhat different frame to categorize the qualities of experience than Western systems do. For example, it did not use the construct of emotion in the description of affective experience; rather it used a more granular analysis of experiential components that comprise those states as described in following sections. Attention regulation, however, is common across the systems and is known to be fundamental to wellbeing (Posner and Rothbart, 2007). For that reason, it may be best to begin with attention and the priorities that effect it.
THE EVOLUTIONARY ROOTS OF ATTENTION AND ITS ROLE IN A NEEDS-BASED SYSTEM MT usually begins with an attention-regulation task. A common one asks the person to place their focus on the sensations of their breathing and to keep it there for some time. While this may seem a relatively easy task, trainees report it as one of the most challenging (Segal et al.,
2013). They stay with it for a breath or two before attention wanders to daydreaming. The tenacity of this default movement to cognitions in the absence of sustained watchfulness suggests an important function, one that becomes clear in reflecting on the role attention plays in our mental ecology. Our brains are continuously processing all manner of information about the internal and external environment. Attention, the capacity to selectively attend to some portion of this information over others, particularly opportunities and threats to the fulfillment of needs, has clear value for survival and reproductive success (Geary, 2005). Selection has also resulted in this process being immediate rather than through conscious, deliberate, and slower decision-making pathways (Tomlin et al., 2015). When physical danger threatens, as it regularly did in the evolutionary past, attention automatically orients to sensory processes monitoring the external environment. Attention is also intimately connected to arousal. In the best-selling book Why Zebras Don’t Get Ulcers, Sapolsky (2004) describes how the attention of animals in the wild is oriented to the senses and to arousal: danger is smelled, seen, or heard, arousal levels and tension spike, the animal responds in some way, and a more quiescent state resumes. We also would live in a more relaxed here and now if real and immediate physical dangers were the principle risks that our attention responded to. But being in the moment is not characteristic of modern life. The capacity for cognition and language makes possible the imagination of conceivable future threats (Andrews-Hanna, 2012; Baumeister et al., 2001) as well as complex planning and discussion of how best to address them. The importance of those capacities to modern humans is evident in our attention’s insistent default to the concerns of projected futures and pasts when it is not required for the execution of an immediate task. This can be observed by deliberately taking notice of the content of the imaginings to which our minds ‘wander’. There we see recurring and often conflicting and entangled concerns about
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND MINDFULNESS AND MEDITATION
our own and our family’s and friends’ welfare, social standing, sex, work, and money. The persistence of this default, and its affective upshot, was captured nicely in a real-time study by Killingsworth and Gilbert (2010). Prompted at random times to report what their attention was on in that moment, subjects reported it being on the task at hand for only about half the day, even though they reported greater happiness at those times. Significantly, the attention wandering generally preceded the happiness decrease. It is this propensity of attention to quickly and repeatedly default to cognitions, memories, plans, speculations, and daydreams, that mindfulness trainees encounter when asked to focus on sense-based experience, and that they find so challenging to overrule and regulate. They discover also that much of this cognition goes on outside of awareness and becomes apparent only when they deliberately watch their mental activity. In the absence of immediate danger, then, attention functionally defaults to cognitive processes serving the social-safety needs of tribal primates, particularly those for relationship/belonging, status, and power. The biological importance of these needs is evident in the fact that health becomes compromised when, for some reason, we are stripped of them. Also, their intricately interwoven and at times conflicting nature, together with the fact that they have no organic satiation mechanism,
97
means that navigating threats and opportunities and monitoring projected pasts and futures is a constant project.
DARWIN AND BUDDHISM’S FIRST NOBLE TRUTH: VIGILANCE AND THE INTERNAL NARRATIVE MAKE UNEASE OUR EVERYDAY STATE In traditional Buddhist teachings, the reduced happiness Killingsworth and Gilbert (2010) found associated with the preoccupations of a wandering mind results not from the thoughts and imaginings themselves, but from the unpleasant sensations of constriction that reflexively accompany their semi-vigilant (‘what could go wrong here?’) and uncertaintyrelated character. A discomforting cycle is then set up as those unpleasant sensations of tension remind us again of the threat-related thought (Damasio, 2003). Extended preoccupation with these alarm-based cycles is experienced as rumination and worry. These are accompanied by arousal-related inflammatory processes. As we’ve all experienced, the level of arousal, constriction, and unpleasantness can range from very mild to dreadful depending on the degree to which those needs are frustrated or threatened (Brosschot et al., 2006). Figure 4.1 illustrates this vigilance-based cycle in the experience of anxiety.
Figure 4.1 Alarm-related components of experience forming a cycle of distress
98
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
When mental bandwidth is occupied by this narrative, curiosity and connection with our surroundings becomes problem-focused, and we are less than openly present for the present needs and concerns of others. When attention is task-related, however, this internal narrative recedes (Watkins, 2004) and we are less affected by its threat- and opportunityoriented memories and imaginings. Even when these preoccupations barely reach awareness (Brosschot et al., 2014; Creswell et al., 2013; Custers and Aarts, 2010; Dahl et al., 2015), the ongoing bodily discomfort gives rise to a desire for a break in something more pleasant; to interrupt the cycle and replace it temporarily with one characterized by greater ease. And because the experience of pleasure and delight encompasses the body (Biswas-Diener et al., 2015), a sense pleasure is usually the most immediately accessible. It might be something like a snack, a drink, or a drug. It may also be something more elaborate; the possibilities are as broad as imagination and resources allow. We don’t start life cognitively preoccupied in this way. We arrive as little sensate creatures, curious and awake to the wonder of touching, tasting, hearing, seeing, moving, and their pleasant and unpleasant feeling tones. A cognitive past and future become gradually and imperceptibly woven into this sensory experience alongside language, the naming and appraisal enabling us to describe our needs and impressions to others (Alderson-Day and Fernyhough, 2015). As we learn to weave our way through the fragile social maze, the hopes, comparisons, judgments, and regrets embedded in this emerging internal narrative come to mediate and filter sensory perception and experience, and weave indiscernibly into a developing sense of self.
Using Our Heads to Get out of Them Just as this safety-oriented cognitive watchfulness has an affective downside, cognition
can also wish for and imagine a life free of it and trial possible solutions. That’s a reflection for the ages. It is also one that preoccupied the historical Buddha who, after intense experimentation, recognized the above patterns shaping the affective quality of his own life as well as related insights into how these can be overcome. In conveying these to interested friends he saw that they were also useful to others. Three of those insights are contained, to a greater and lesser degree, within present-day MT programs. They are designed to support greater awareness, acceptance, and some level of everyday self-regulation in the face of these mental and perceptual tendencies shaping everyday feeling life (Cavanagh et al., 2014; Donald et al., 2016; Saunders et al., 2016) and can be operationalized in familiar psychological terms. The analysis is not regarded as the final word on mental mechanisms but as a description of mental qualities that can be phenomenologically recognized in real time, and trainees comprehend and use them to suit their interests and circumstances (Carmody and Baer, 2008; Cebolla et al., 2017). The first insight, alluded to in the previous section, is that everyday experience and emotions are constructed from a suite of just three interwoven phenomenological components: cognitions, sensations, and their pleasant/unpleasant feeling tones. Classification and description of the affective dimension of experience change with the age and the culture, and feeling here is not to be confused with how we commonly use the term today when we might say we are feeling angry or sad. It’s simply the pleasant or unpleasant quality of a sensation. Also, emotional categories vary across cultures and over time; something described as an emotion at one time might be referred to as a passion in another. In the Buddhist analysis emotions are approached more granularly as amalgams of those three fundamental qualities. When those components are not distinguished their felt experience is seamless, as illustrated in Figure 4.2.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND MINDFULNESS AND MEDITATION
99
Figure 4.2 Memory, imagination and emotion are symphonies of three interwoven experiential components
Experiential recognition and discrimination of the components starts, most usually, with re-awakening interest in the realm of sensation. In the body scan, for example, an exercise taught in MBSR (Kabat-Zinn, 1990), trainees are asked to systematically direct attention to each part of the body and to notice any sensations that may be present there, including subtle and neglected sensations that may escape awareness in everyday life; this while refraining from attempting to change the experience in any way. They are instructed to notice also any pleasant or unpleasant feeling tone that may be associated with a sensation, and the difference between the sensation and any thoughts that may also be present. This is schematically illustrated in Figure 4.3 using the example of a fearful thought and the sensations of constriction that may be associated with it, and which, on a less granular level, we experience as anxiety. This learning is akin to winding back the developmental and experiential clock. As described in the previous section, we are not born with these groupings. Cognitions that had been so implicitly integrated (Blair, 2002) into our early world of sensation and
affect that their distinction was not apparent in awareness (Pessoa, 2008) become noticed and named. Their associations, so rapid they are normally missed, become apparent in noticing that attention does not stay with a sensation, but quickly goes to its feeling tone, to thoughts about it, or to something else. Implicit in this bare noticing of experience is an embodied acceptance, one that also may be made explicit in the instructions. Interoceptive awareness is important in emotion regulation (Füstös et al., 2013) and the perception of internal experience developed by these MT exercises appears to mediate its beneficial effect on emotional wellbeing (Mehling et al., 2012). And even though trainees initially report finding these exercises challenging (Segal et al., 2013), they result in measurable increases in volitional orienting of attention (Chan and Woollacott, 2007; Jha et al., 2007), improved performance on sustained attention tasks (Tang et al., 2015), and improvements in working memory and autobiographical memory (Lao et al., 2016). Also, the differential thickness in brain regions associated with attention, interoception, and sensory
100
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Figure 4.3 Components recognized as differentiated and connected
processing found in meditators compared to matched controls (Lazar et al., 2005) is consistent with meditators’ increased capacity for awareness of internal states, particularly awareness of breathing sensations. The second insight is that attention can be regulated to create a more benign or neutral affect. It builds upon the first insight and can be experienced in any of the MT exercises; when attention is directed to arousal-neutral bodily sensations, such as those of breathing for example, a more benign affect emerges. The sensations of breathing provide an accessible and readily available object of attention that can be unobtrusively turned to as a restful experience in moments of stress. This facility, sometimes referred to by clinicians as ‘going to the breath’, is readily established. In the initial trials of MBSR, a large majority of participants indicated that they attached high importance to this simple skill to calm themselves in moments of stress/distress (Kabat-Zinn, 1987). This redirection of attention and its affective result is illustrated in Figure 4.4. It is distinguished from experiential avoidance, which involves a compulsive mental (or physical) turning away from difficult experiences (Hayes et al., 1996).
The principle is consistent with William James’ cogent remark that experience is what one pays attention to (James, 1890). The key role that this effortful focusing of attention plays in wellbeing-supportive emotion regulation and in self-regulated behavior (Baumeister and Heatherton, 1996; Kirschenbaum, 1987; Thayer et al., 1996) was confirmed in later experimental studies, and in the findings that poor cognitive control is associated with many mental disorders (Snyder and Hankin, 2016). Rumination, for example, is an indicator of attention wandering from immediate tasks and becoming captivated by an uncomfortable internal narrative. Supporting this principle, MT has been shown to reduce rumination (Campbell et al., 2012) and to increase mood as a result (Huffziger et al., 2013). More specifically, an MT exercise focusing on the awareness of breathing improved mood, meta-awareness, and mind wandering (Levinson et al., 2014). These observations are supported by imaging studies in which mindfulness trainees show less activation of brain regions involved in narrative processing of self-relevant stimuli and greater activation of regions implicated in ‘experiential’ processing, relative to novices (Farb et al., 2007; Lutz et al., 2016).
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND MINDFULNESS AND MEDITATION
101
Figure 4.4 Attention shifts from differentiated components to arousal-neutral sensations of breathing
Interestingly, MT appears to reduce reactivity to emotional stimuli, which is not found with relaxation training (Ortner et al., 2007). The third insight is the use of an observing perspective toward mental life. This ‘observing self’ (Deikman, 1982) is used to notice thoughts/images, sensations, and feelings while remaining unaffected by their content and tone. It is itself a cognitive process, albeit one used to cultivate a sense of detachment from mental phenomena that previously had captured attention and created distress.
This observing stance is implicit in most MT exercises and is cultivated explicitly by the practice of silently naming component mental qualities as they are occurring in awareness. For example, rather than contending with, or trying to push away, a harshly self-critical thought, attention is reoriented from its content, such as ‘I am a failure’, to the more affectneutral reflection ‘This is a thought’. The strategy is illustrated in Figure 4.5 using the example of a commonly reported thought during panic attacks.
Figure 4.5 Re-perceiving reduces distress through a perceptual/attentional shift from what the thought is about – ‘I’m going to pass out’ – to the thought as an event in the mind/ awareness – ‘This is a thought’
102
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Referred to as decentering (Teasdale et al., 2002) and meta-cognition (Wells, 1999), this meta-awareness increases with participation in MT (Carmody et al., 2009; Feldman et al., 2010; Lao et al., 2016; Levinson et al., 2014; Teasdale et al., 2002). It has been found important in the treatment of depression (Bieling et al., 2012), and this decreased cognitive reactivity appears to mediate the association between mindfulness-based cognitive therapy and decreases in depressive symptoms (Cladder-Micus et al., 2017).
MINDFULNESS AND THE COGNITIVE NARRATIVE’S DOUBLE-EDGED SWORD We are tribal primates with a powerful capacity to imagine. This wondrous ability envisions possible futures and constructs narratives of the past beyond simple conditioning. It gives us a powerful advantage in meeting our human needs and is that which most clearly separates us from other primates. The capacity for language that developed in conjunction with it allows also for conversations about where dangers are most likely to be found, how they might best be met, and the passing of those lessons across generations – group learning, in other words. The clear survival upside of imagination is seen in the development of tools and their uses, and in the ability to plan and coordinate future activities and scenarios that would favor resource procurement and advantageous mates: to be able to plan for the hunt and what would be required, as well as how any gains might be distributed. When bands were small and less complex, dangers imminent and immediate, and neural cognitive capacity less developed, those imaginings were probably relatively short-lived; life required careful and continued attention to the senses. Immediate physical dangers have been minimized in modern life and sensory monitoring has become less necessary. In these
circumstances, attention defaults to supporting our social needs and planning how they can be met. And as social life becomes more complex, the goals longer term, and success and failure more contingent, imagining assumes an increasingly central role. Essential to this planning is imagining what could go wrong here, how plans might be threatened by others or by circumstances, and the consequences of these in terms of our own, and our kin’s, future suffering and possible death. Imagination also allows for reflections that give rise to questions of meaning and existential angst. Each age and culture developed ways and means of coping with this anxiety that arises from the necessary uncertainty of our plans, and of life itself. Some rely on placating and beseeching imagined beings assumed to control events. The Greeks began a more rational and empirical approach to understanding human nature and events that unfold in the world, apparent in the teachings of people such as Plato, Aristotle, and Archimedes. Around the same time philosophers in India developed what we would now call psychological methods of inquiry that focused on the mind itself. In that sense they are not descriptions of the world, but mental models that allow insight into the machinations of the vehicle through which we apprehend the world and how it can be self-modified to alleviate the angst. In its original context, mindfulness was cultivated as part of a training system to recognize how mental suffering is created moment-to-moment in the human mind and the behaviors and attitudes that can alleviate it. And while some schools of Western psychology developed constructs and principles that parallel some of those found in Buddhism, they did not develop training exercises that so systematically develop their recognition and self-regulation. In that sense, one of Buddhism’s most important contributions has been the practices to actualize those principles; ones that have been seamlessly integrated as mindfulness into existing psychotherapies.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND MINDFULNESS AND MEDITATION
In our complex and secular societies, the cognitive activity required to navigate for success in status, power, and relationships consumes inordinate amounts of neural bandwidth. And the affect associated with this is evident in ever-increasing rates of anxiety, depressive disorders, and suicide. It may also be contributing to increasing rates of addiction and obesity; rates that may make a more universal healthcare unsustainable. The MT exercises support recognition of this mental activity that goes largely unnoticed in daily life, even as it is affecting wellbeing. To those ends, mindfulness encourages the recognition that our apparently seamless mental activity comprises phenomenological components: sensations, cognitions, and their pleasant/unpleasant affective quality that we don’t normally experience as separate. The exercises also develop a capacity to notice where attention is focused in that suite and to regulate attention so that it becomes less conditioned and more fluid. The exercises also expose attention’s default impulse toward cognition and the narratives forming through imagination and memory, its handmaiden. As a needs-serving mechanism, cognition has a watchful quality for threats and opportunities. In the mental background, the default mode network and related functions are planning and wondering what could go wrong here and whether this is an opportunity. MT makes this vigilant quality apparent, as well as its affective downside in the uncomfortable sensations of constriction that naturally accompany it. It also reveals how the system relaxes as interest and attention are re-oriented to just sensation: an ease that is associated with reduced neural monitoring activity and downstream changes in arousalrelated biomarkers. And while MT offers the opportunity for profound insight, people come to it with varying levels of interest and curiosity so that each gets off at their own stop along the route. In the clinical and secular settings into which mindfulness has been introduced it is valued primarily for the palliative effects
103
that the practice provides: I want to feel less anxious or less depressed, I want to sleep better, or I’d like moments of quiet in the tumult of modern life. The relief that accompanies these recognitions satisfies the interest of most people. For those sufficiently interested to continue exploring the system’s original existential goal, other mental features become apparent. Gaps begin to appear between thoughts and in those moments the still background becomes apparent. The natural re-emergence of thoughts reveals how the narrative they form has become indistinguishable from that still presence within which they occur (Carmody, 2016). You realize that it has always been there, just overlain by attention’s ongoing fascination with the contents of the cognitive narrative. It also becomes apparent just how much of our lives are spent distracted and preoccupied by that imagining. Perspective shifts with that experience, as it would if a fish was to recognize water.
REFERENCES Alderson-Day, B., & Fernyhough, C. (2015). Inner speech: Development, cognitive functions, phenomenology, and neurobiology. Psychological Bulletin, 141(5), 931. doi:http:// psycnet.apa.org/doi/10.1037/bul0000021 Andrews-Hanna, J. R. (2012). The brain’s default network and its adaptive role in internal mentation. The Neuroscientist, 18(3), 251–270. doi:https://doi.org/10.1177/ 1073858411403316b Baumeister, R. F., Bratslavsky, E., Finkenauer, C., & Vohs, K. D. (2001). Bad is stronger than good. Review of General Psychology, 5(4), 323. doi:http://psycnet.apa.org/doi/10.1037/ 1089-2680.5.4.323 Baumeister, R. F., & Heatherton, T. F. (1996). Self-regulation failure: An overview. Psychological Inquiry, 7(1), 1–15. doi:http://dx.doi. org/10.1207/s15327965pli0701_1 Bieling, P. J., Hawley, L. L., Bloch, R. T., Corcoran, K. M., Levitan, R. D., Young, L. T., & Segal, Z. V. (2012). Treatment-specific
104
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
changes in decentering following mindfulnessbased cognitive therapy versus antidepressant medication or placebo for prevention of depressive relapse. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology, 80(3), 365. doi:http:// psycnet.apa.org/doi/10.1037/a0027483 Biswas-Diener, R., Linley, P. A., Dovey, H., Maltby, J., Hurling, R., Wilkinson, J., & Lyubchik, N. (2015). Pleasure: An initial exploration. Journal of Happiness Studies, 16(2), 313–332. doi:https://doi.org/10.1007/ s10902-014-9511-x Blair, C. (2002). School readiness: Integrating cognition and emotion in a neurobiological conceptualization of children’s functioning at school entry. American Psychologist, 57(2), 111. doi:http://psycnet.apa.org/doi/10.1037/ 0003-066X.57.2.111 Brosschot, J. F., Gerin, W., & Thayer, J. F. (2006). The perseverative cognition hypothesis: A review of worry, prolonged stress-related physiological activation, and health. Journal of Psychosomatic Research, 60(2), 113–124. Brosschot, J., Geurts, S., Kruizinga, I., Radstaak, M., Verkuil, B., Quirin, M., & Kompier, M. (2014). Does unconscious stress play a role in prolonged cardiovascular stress recovery? Stress and Health: Journal of the International Society for the Investigation of Stress, 30(3), 179. doi:10.1002/smi.2590 Campbell, T. S., Labelle, L. E., Bacon, S. L., Faris, P., & Carlson, L. E. (2012). Impact of mindfulness-based stress reduction (MBSR) on attention, rumination and resting blood pressure in women with cancer: A waitlistcontrolled study. Journal of Behavioral Medicine, 35(3), 262–271. doi:https://doi. org/10.1007/s10865-011-9357-1 Carmody, J. (2016). Fish Discovering Water: Meditation as a Process of Recognition. In M. West (Ed.), The Psychology of Meditation. Oxford University Press. Carmody, J., & Baer, R. A. (2008). Relationships between mindfulness practice and levels of mindfulness, medical and psychological symptoms and well-being in a mindfulnessbased stress reduction program. Journal of Behavioral Medicine, 31(1), 23–33. doi:https:// doi.org/10.1007/s10865-007-9130-7 Carmody, J., Baer, R. A., Lykins, E. L. B., & Olendzki, N. (2009). An empirical study of the
mechanisms of mindfulness in a mindfulnessbased stress reduction program. Journal of Clinical Psychology, 65(6), 613–626. doi:10.1002/jclp.20579 Cavanagh, K., Strauss, C., Forder, L., & Jones, F. (2014). Can mindfulness and acceptance be learnt by self-help? A systematic review and meta-analysis of mindfulness and acceptancebased self-help interventions. Clinical Psychology Review, 34(2), 118–129. doi:https://doi. org/10.1016/j.cpr.2014.01.001 Cebolla, A., Campos, D., Galiana, L., Oliver, A., Tomás, J. M., Feliu-Soler, A., & Baños, R. M. (2017). Exploring relations among mindfulness facets and various meditation practices: Do they work in different ways? Consciousness and Cognition, 49, 172–180. doi:https:// doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2017.01.012 Chan, D., & Woollacott, M. (2007). Effects of level of meditation experience on attentional focus: Is the efficiency of executive or orientation networks improved? The Journal of Alternative and Complementary Medicine, 13(6), 651–658. doi:10.1089/acm.2007.7022 Cladder-Micus, M., van Aalderen, J., Donders, A., Spijker, J., Vrijsen, J., & Speckens, A. (2017). Cognitive reactivity as outcome and working mechanism of mindfulness-based cognitive therapy for recurrently depressed patients in remission. Cognition and Emotion, 1–8. doi:http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/ 02699931.2017.1285753 Creswell, J. D., Bursley, J. K., & Satpute, A. B. (2013). Neural reactivation links unconscious thought to decision-making performance. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, 8(8), 863–869. doi:https://doi.org/10.1093/ scan/nst004 Custers, R., & Aarts, H. (2010). The unconscious will: How the pursuit of goals operates outside of conscious awareness. Science, 329(5987), 47–50. doi:10.1126/science.1188595 Dahl, C. J., Lutz, A., & Davidson, R. J. (2015). Reconstructing and deconstructing the self: Cognitive mechanisms in meditation practice. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 19(9), 515–523. doi:https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2015.07.001 Damasio, A. R. (2003). Looking for Spinoza: Joy, sorrow, and the feeling brain. New York: Harcourt. Deikman, A. J. (1982). The observing self: Mysticism and psychotherapy. Boston: Beacon Press.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND MINDFULNESS AND MEDITATION
Donald, J. N., Atkins, P. W., Parker, P. D., Christie, A. M., & Ryan, R. M. (2016). Daily stress and the benefits of mindfulness: Examining the daily and longitudinal relations between present-moment awareness and stress responses. Journal of Research in Personality, 65, 30–37. doi:https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jrp.2016.09.002 Farb, N. A. S., Segal, Z. V., Mayberg, H., Bean, J., McKeon, D., Fatima, Z., & Anderson, A. K. (2007). Attending to the present: Mindfulness meditation reveals distinct neural modes of self-reference. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, 2(4), 313–322. doi:https:// doi.org/10.1093/scan/nsm030 Feldman, G., Greeson, J., & Senville, J. (2010). Differential effects of mindful breathing, progressive muscle relaxation, and loving-kindness meditation on decentering and negative reactions to repetitive thoughts. Behaviour Research and Therapy, 48(10), 1002–1011. doi:https://doi.org/10.1016/j.brat.2010.06.006 Füstös, J., Gramann, K., Herbert, B. M., & Pollatos, O. (2013). On the embodiment of emotion regulation: Interoceptive awareness facilitates reappraisal. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, 8(8), 911–917. doi:https://doi.org/10.1093/scan/nss089 Geary, D. (2005). The motivation to control and the origin of mind: Exploring the lifemind joint point in the Tree of Knowledge System. Journal of Clinical Psychology, 61(1), 21–46. doi:10.1002/jclp.20089 Goyal, M., Singh, S., Sibinga, E. M., Gould, N. F., Rowland-Seymour, A., Sharma, R., & Shihab, H. M. (2014). Meditation programs for psychological stress and well-being: A systematic review and meta-analysis. JAMA Internal Medicine, 174(3), 357–368. doi:10.1001/jamainternmed.2013.13018 Hayes, S. C., Wilson, K. G., Gifford, E. V., Follette, V. M., & Strosahl, K. (1996). Experiential avoidance and behavioral disorders: A functional dimensional approach to diagnosis and treatment. Journal of Consulting & Clinical Psychology, 64(6), 1152–1168. doi:http:// psycnet.apa.org/doi/10.1037/0022-006X. 64.6.1152 Huffziger, S., Ebner-Priemer, U., Eisenbach, C., Koudela, S., Reinhard, I., Zamoscik, V., & Kuehner, C. (2013). Induced ruminative and mindful attention in everyday life: An experimental ambulatory assessment study.
105
Journal of Behavior Therapy and Experimental Psychiatry, 44(3), 322–328. doi:https:// doi.org/10.1016/j.jbtep.2013.01.007 James, W. (1890). The principles of psychology. New York: H. Holt. Jha, A., Krompinger, J., & Baime, M. J. (2007). Mindfulness training modifies subsystems of attention. Cognitive Affective and Behavioral Neuroscience, 7(2), 109–119. doi:https://doi. org/10.3758/CABN.7.2.109 Kabat-Zinn, J. (1982). An out-patient program in behavioral medicine for chronic pain patients based on the practice of mindfulness meditation: Theoretical considerations and preliminary results. General Hospital Psychiatry, 4, 33–47. Kabat-Zinn, J. (1987). Four-year follow-up of a meditation-based program for the self- regulation of chronic pain; treatment outcomes and compliance. Clinical Journal of Pain, 2, 159–173. Kabat-Zinn, J. (1990). Full catastrophe living: Using the wisdom of your body and mind to face stress, pain and illness. New York: Delacorte. Killingsworth, M. A., & Gilbert, D. T. (2010). A wandering mind is an unhappy mind. Science, 330(6006), 932. doi:10.1126/science. 1192439 Kirschenbaum, D. S. (1987). Self-regulatory failure: A review with clinical implications. Clinical Psychology Review, 7(1), 77–104. doi:https:// doi.org/10.1016/0272-7358(87)90005-5 Lao, S., Kissane, D., & Meadows, G. (2016). Cognitive effects of MBSR/MBCT: A systematic review of neuropsychological outcomes. Consciousness and Cognition, 45, 109–123. doi:https://doi.org/10.1016/ j.concog.2016.08.017 Lazar, S. W., Kerr, C. E., Wasserman, R. H., Gray, J. R., Greve, D. N., Treadway, M. T., & Fischl, B. (2005). Meditation experience is associated with increased cortical thickness. NeuroReport 16(17), 1893–1897. Levinson, D. B., Stoll, E. L., Kindy, S. D., Merry, H. L., & Davidson, R. J. (2014). A mind you can count on: Validating breath counting as a behavioral measure of mindfulness. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 1202. doi:https:// dx.doi.org/10.3389%2Ffpsyg.2014.01202 Lutz, J., Brühl, A. B., Doerig, N., Scheerer, H., Achermann, R., Weibel, A., & Herwig, U.
106
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
(2016). Altered processing of self-related emotional stimuli in mindfulness meditators. Neuroimage, 124, 958–967. doi:https://doi. org/10.1016/j.neuroimage.2015.09.057 Mehling, W. E., Price, C., Daubenmier, J. J., Acree, M., Bartmess, E., & Stewart, A. (2012). The multidimensional assessment of interoceptive awareness (MAIA). PloS One, 7(11), e48230. Ortner, C. N. M., Kilner, S. J., & Zelazo, P. D. (2007). Mindfulness meditation and reduced emotional interference on a cognitive task. Motivation and Emotion, 31(4), 271–283. doi:https://doi.org/10.1007/s11031-0079076-7 Pessoa, L. (2008). On the relationship between emotion and cognition. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 9(2), 148–158. Posner, M. I., & Rothbart, M. K. (2007). Research on attention networks as a model for the integration of psychological science. Annual Review of Psychology, 58, 1–23. doi:https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev.psych. 58.110405.085516 Sapolsky, R. M. (2004). Why zebras don’t get ulcers: The acclaimed guide to stress, stressrelated diseases, and coping (revised and updated). New York: Macmillan. Saunders, B., Rodrigo, A. H., & Inzlicht, M. (2016). Mindful awareness of feelings increases neural performance monitoring. Cognitive, Affective, & Behavioral Neuroscience, 16(1), 93–105. doi:https://doi.org/10.3758/s13415015-0375-2 Segal, Z. V., Williams, J. M. G., & Teasdale, J. D. (2013). Mindfulness-based cognitive therapy for depression (2nd ed.). New York: Guilford. Shonin, E., Van Gordon, W., & Griffiths, M. D. (2015). Does mindfulness work? BMJ, 1, 1–11. Snyder, H. R., & Hankin, B. L. (2016). Spiraling out of control: Stress generation and subsequent rumination mediate the link between
poorer cognitive control and internalizing psychopathology. Clinical Psychological Science, 4(6), 1047–1064. doi:https://doi.org/ 10.1177/2167702616633157t Tang, Y.-Y., Hölzel, B. K., & Posner, M. I. (2015). The neuroscience of mindfulness meditation. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 16(4), 213–225. doi:http://dx.doi.org/10.1038/nrn3916 Teasdale, J. D., Moore, R. G., Hayhurst, H., Pope, M., Williams, S., & Segal, Z. V. (2002). Metacognitive awareness and prevention of relapse in depression: Empirical evidence. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology, 70(2), 275–287. doi:http://psycnet.apa. org/doi/10.1037/0022-006X.70.2.275 Thayer, J. A., Friedman, B. H., & Borkovec, T. D. (1996). Autonomic characteristics of generalized anxiety disorder and worry. Biological Psychiatry, 39(4), 255–266. doi:https://doi. org/10.1016/0006-3223(95)00136-0 Tomlin, D., Rand, D. G., Ludvig, E. A., & Cohen, J. D. (2015). The evolution and devolution of cognitive control: The costs of deliberation in a competitive world. Scientific Reports, 5, 11002. doi:https://dx.doi.org/10.1038%2Fsrep11002 Watkins, E. (2004). Appraisals and strategies associated with rumination and worry. Personality and Individual Differences, 37(4). doi:https://doi.org/10.1016/j.paid.2003.10.002 Wells, A. (1999). A meta-cognitive model and therapy for generalized anxiety disorder. Clinical Psychology and Psychotherapy, 6, 86–95. doi:10.1002/(SICI)1099-0879(199905) 6:23.0.CO;2-S Willem, K., Warren, F., Taylor, R., Whalley, B., Crane, C., Bondolfi, G., & Schweizer, S. (2016). Efficacy and moderators of mindfulness-based cognitive therapy (MBCT) in prevention of depressive relapse: An individual patient data meta-analysis from randomized trials. JAMA Psychiatry. 73(6), 565–574. doi:http://dx.doi.org/10.1001/ jamapsychiatry.2016.0076
5 Evolutionary Psychology and Environmental Sciences Ulysses Paulino Albuquerque, Joelson M. B. Moura, Risoneide Henriques da Silva, Washington S. F e r r e i r a J ú n i o r , a n d Ta l i n e C . S i l v a
INTRODUCTION An investigative program of evolutionary psychology must address the origin of human beings, as the environments that generated pressure during the evolution of early hominids form the basis for premises about the evolution of the human mind. As evidence suggests the African savanna as the most likely place for the origin of the modern human being, the savanna environment usually receives more emphasis than other environments. We have succeeded as a species through mental specializations, also understood as evolved psychological mechanisms. These specializations were selected because they solved problems in paleoenvironments, and were inherited by subsequent generations of hominids. For example, when exploring new landscapes, early hominids needed to quickly identify potentially dangerous situations, which trees were climbable, and where they could shelter. These decisions needed to be fast, and they were only possible because
previously selected mental mechanisms allowed the assessment of the landscape, even if unconsciously (see Zajonc, 1980; Townsend and Barton, 2018). If we assume that the savanna was the ‘main paleoenvironment’ of our evolution and that we inherited both physical and mental adaptations of our ancestors, the abovementioned argument is coherent. However, the literature indicates that we evolved along different lineages and from myriad hominid groups that coexisted in a wide range of environments, and that more than one point of origin of H. sapiens may have existed (Foley et al., 2016; Stringer, 2016). Evolution may have occurred independently in different areas, with hominids developing morphological substructures that resulted in a complete set of H. sapiens characteristics. Stringer (2016) calls this independent evolution ‘African multiregionalism’, characterized by interfertile subdivisions of H. sapiens in their evolutionary history across Africa.
108
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
This discussion is central to a program that attempts to investigate the evolution of the human mind and human behavior. Discussing the origin of human beings is essential for evolutionary psychology and for understanding how our minds work in relation to the environment and all its components.
THE ORIGIN AND EVOLUTION OF HUMANS The transition from dense and closed forests to the savanna may have occurred slowly. This suggests that early hominids left the canopy of forest trees gradually, venturing into the East African savanna to explore available resources and to identify hazards and safe sleeping places. Thus, arboreal behaviors may have coexisted with bipedal locomotion (see Townsend and Barton, 2018). Lucy, the most famous Australopithecus afarensis, had both bipedal and arboreal habits (Larson, 2012). Until recently, paleontological data suggested that the first hominids appeared in Central Africa seven million years ago (Ma) (see Böhme et al., 2017). However, recent evidence suggests that the earliest hominid, Graecopithecus freybergi, lived in a savanna environment in the region of Greece, between 7.37 and 7.11 Ma, which is 200,000 years earlier than the previous earliest known hominid, Sahelanthropus tchadensis, found in Africa (Böhme et al., 2017). Likewise, Homo sapiens was believed to have originated around 200,000 years ago in South Africa, but recent fossil evidence suggests that H. sapiens appeared about 315,000 years ago in Morocco, 100,000 years earlier than previously thought (Hublin et al., 2017; Richter et al., 2017). These fossils have a mix of characteristics of H. sapiens fossils from other parts of Africa, indicating a multicentric genesis for our species (see Hublin et al., 2017; Richter et al., 2017). This finding is consistent with genetic evidence that the first divergence of modern human populations
occurred between 350,000 and 260,000 years ago (Schlebusch et al., 2017). In addition, a hominid skull, dating back about 436,000– 390,000 years, was recently discovered in the Cave of Aroeira in Portugal, reinforcing the idea that human origins did not necessarily occur in Africa (López-García et al., 2018). Although the savanna is still regarded as the main setting of our evolution, these findings suggest that the origin and the great divisions in the family of hominids may have occurred outside Africa. Nonetheless, if we understand that establishment in the savanna was important for the survival of hominids, it is reasonable to infer that, over time, natural selection favored individuals better adapted to savanna conditions. These individuals inherited the anatomical and cognitive apparatus evolved in this environment and were most likely to survive and leave offspring. This moment was crucial in evolutionary history. Many aspects of our anatomy and current behaviors resulted from solutions to challenges faced by early hominids (Townsend and Barton, 2018). Townsend and Barton (2018) argue that common behaviors and anatomical adaptations of early hominids in the Pleistocene persist today. For example, the palmar grasp reflex is a primitive reflex. It consists of a strong pressure with the hands and represents the primate’s need to hold the mother’s skin as she moves through the canopy of the trees. During childhood, for example, there is a tendency for children to show climbing behaviors (e.g., climbing trees or climbable objects) that fit the category of primitive reflex (Townsend and Barton, 2018). Brachiation is also still used today by children and gymnasts and was essential for the hominids in the savanna paleoenvironments. Perhaps children use tree climbing as strategy to avoid predators (Coss and Moore, 2002). Brachiation refers to a mobility method that depends on the specific structure of the shoulder to hang on the tree limb and allow the arm to swing in a complete circle (Townsend and Barton, 2018). These authors also suggest that the standard
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ENVIRONMENTAL SCIENCES
size of the human hand is proportional to the size of tree branches capable of supporting a human’s weight during a climb. In addition, humans generally prefer horizontal-branched trees precisely because it facilitates climbing. These behaviors can be understood as an ancestral inheritance of early hominids, with our cognition, like our anatomy, resulting from adaptations to the selective pressures of paleoenvironments (Tooby and Cosmides, 2015). Blome et al. (2012) demonstrated that the African paleoclimate from 150,000 to 30,000 years ago also displayed regional variation, so that periods of high aridity or humidity did not occur simultaneously in the northern, eastern, tropical, and southern regions of Africa. According to these authors, this climate heterogeneity may have created opportunities for hominids to migrate to adjacent regions. Furthermore, Coulthard et al. (2013) found that, in humid climates around 100,000 years ago, major African river systems flowed northward, across the Sahara and to the Mediterranean Sea. These authors believe that three now-buried rivers could have been active in the period of human migration across the Sahara, with the abundance of water resources creating viable migratory routes for humans. Evidence shows that hominids adapted to various environments in a wide latitudinal range, such as the temperate and subtropical north of China and tropical regions of Southeast Asia (Roberts et al., 2016; Kong et al., 2018). The use of fire, which is a practice frequently described in the literature on arid environments, has also been observed in tropical forests (Friesem et al., 2017). In addition, traces of foraging activities and the discovery of tools for hunting arboreal animals challenge the dominant idea of the evolutionary adaptation of the first humans to the arid environment of the savanna (Barker et al., 2007; Friesem et al., 2017). If cognitive mechanisms result from responses to selective pressures of the environment, much of our mind may also be ‘trapped’ in evolutionary environments. If this is true, a challenge for evolutionary
109
psychologists would be to broaden the spectrum of the environments in which we evolved and the influence of the evolved psychological mechanisms in solving problems different from those found in the savanna. If the human mind has evolved in response to the difficulties imposed by the environment, and if H. sapiens has emerged and evolved in different environments, it is possible that today’s human behavioral responses, including their preferences, are a reflection of this multicentric origin. Indeed, the paleontological evidence that hominids inhabited and explored several environments in the Pleistocene suggests that other psychological mechanisms may have evolved in periods before or after establishment in the savanna. For example, a recent study by our research group has shown that some people, when analyzing landscapes of savanna, rainforest, tundra, desert, coniferous forest, deciduous forest, and urban landscape, prefer images of exuberant green rainforests (Moura et al., 2018). In addition, people living in Spain tend to prefer densely green and closed landscapes (Hartmann and Apaolaza-Ibáñez, 2010). Because this landscape is typical of Spain, and in Brazil there is great media appeal to preserve the Amazon rainforest, these findings suggest that recent stimuli, rather than innate responses, may exert strong influence on human behavior. According to Barrett (2012), adaptations may provide plasticity to the human mind. They may also integrate mechanisms – whether more general or more specific – shaped by evolutionary history with those shaped by the ontogenetic development of the individual. Therefore, our mental mechanisms may be heterogeneous in origin, with new structures evolving from older structures and ancestral features combining with relatively recent characteristics (Barrett, 2012). Thus, cognitive adaptations are not necessarily the result of responses to difficulties imposed by a specific environment. They might reflect the selection of general strategies of the human mind to meet challenges in different environments.
110
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
THE ENVIRONMENT OF EVOLUTIONARY ADAPTEDNESS (EEA) AND THE STRUCTURING OF THE HUMAN MIND Understanding the evolutionary environment of hominids is crucial for evolutionary psychology and other disciplines interested in the evolution of the human mind. For example, Bowlby (1982) coined the term Environment of Evolutionary Adaptedness (EEA) to refer to the environment that selected the current genotypes of an organism. According to this perspective, it is reasonable to suppose that these environments also influenced the selection of mental traits of human beings. Frost (2011) proposed that, for humans, the EEA would be represented by the African savanna of the Pleistocene, the environment probably occupied by early H. sapiens before they started migrating to other continents about 50,000 years ago. Many authors argue that human psychological mechanisms evolved in response to the stable characteristics of the savanna environments (Tooby and Cosmides,
1992, 2005), and the reconstruction of these selective environments could indicate why humans have propensities for certain types of thoughts, motivations, and behaviors (Foley, 1996). However, the previously mentioned evidence of evolution of hominids in different areas of the African continent seems to challenge the savanna hypothesis (see Bolhuis et al., 2011). Thus, the human EEA may comprise a multitude of geographic and temporal environments (Volk and Atkinson, 2013), that is, the EEA has become less specific, taking into account not only the African savanna (see Tooby and Cosmides, 2015), but also the other selective environments in which humans have lived over the course of their evolution. As a consequence, humans may have developed psychological mechanisms in environments that were different from the African savanna (see Hartmann and Apaolaza-Ibáñez, 2010, 2013; Moura et al., 2018) (Figure 5.1). Studies on human preference for landscapes, for example, provide evidence that these psychological mechanisms may have suffered interference from the interaction
Figure 5.1 Environment of Evolutionary Adaptedness definition (EEA), original version and extended version Source: Created by the authors.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ENVIRONMENTAL SCIENCES
of humans and different ancestral environments. Orians (1980) argues that, because the savanna is an open environment, it enabled the first hominids a more accurate perception of approaching predators. This suggests the evolution of a psychological mechanism in humans to prefer savanna landscapes – the savanna hypothesis. However, several studies have reported preference in humans for environments other than African savannas (see Han, 2007; Hartmann and Apaolaza-Ibáñez, 2010, 2013; Moura et al., 2018). Some studies have tried to understand how our species recalls information that is relevant to survival, providing evidence of how the human mind may have evolved psychological mechanisms that deal with risky situations in different environments. Yang et al. (2014) observed that people in both ancestral survival scenarios – grasslands and in non-ancestral or modern environments – recalled important words in a survival situation. In another study, Young et al. (2012) found that threats in modern environments – such as firearms and cars – capture and maintain attention in the same way as would be expected for threats in ancestral environments, such as snakes and spiders. These findings lead us to believe that natural selection favored psychological mechanisms that deal with challenges regardless of the type of environment. Thus, human inventions (e.g., firearms and cars) that are immersed in the culture and environment may be acting as a selective force that activates modern psychological mechanisms. This fact seems to indicate that the human construction of niche1 interferes in own and others’ psychological mechanisms. This interpretation finds support in reports that psychological mechanisms that favor the recall of information relevant to survival can be observed in people occupying different contemporary environmental and cultural contexts (see Barrett and Broesch, 2012; Barrett et al., 2016). For example, Barrett and Broesch (2012) found that children living in the city of Los Angeles in California and children of a village in Shuar in the Ecuadorian Amazon had high levels of recall when images of and
111
information on the name and diet of dangerous animals were presented.
Did Evolution Endow Us with a Naturalistic Mind? We believe that many of today’s human decisions and behaviors are influenced by the same psychological mechanisms present in our ancestors. An example of this would be the ability to recall information relevant to survival (see Nairne et al., 2007), such as snakes and spiders (see Young et al., 2012). However, we also believe that some of these ancestral psychological mechanisms have adjusted to the adversities of new environments humans occupied throughout their evolution. Consequently, derived psychological mechanisms evolved from ancestral psychological mechanisms. The ability to recall information that refers to a risky situation in a modern environment, such as firearms and cars, is evidence of a psychological mechanism adjusted to the reality of contemporary environments (see Young et al., 2012). Barrett (2012) relativizes the influence of ancestral environments in the present – in the case of evolved psychological mechanisms shaped in these environments – considering innate cognitive modules as mechanisms specialized to solve a specific adaptive problem. However, if adaptations in the brain are analogous to adaptations of the body, such as tissue types, they are likely to be heterogeneous and hierarchical (Barrett, 2012). A hierarchical organization is a feature of systems that evolve and develop new structures from older structures. These adaptations are, therefore, a combination of ancestral and recent traits (Barrett, 2012). Thus, mental adaptations can be constructed during the ontogenetic development of each individual (see Barrett, 2012). As changes in the individual’s social environment occur, there may be a selection of ‘dormant’ behaviors or preferences that would never or rarely be generated by the brain if the environment remained static (see Barrett, 2012).
112
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
A study by Sandry et al. (2013) provided evidence of the hierarchical organization of the human mind: these authors demonstrated that people do not recall adaptive information in a similar way. By studying the memorization of words in different scenarios – survival, fear and phobia, partner selection, incest avoidance, detection of cheaters, jealousy, infidelity, and acquisition and maintenance of status – they found that the survival scenario excelled in the number of words remembered by people when compared to the other scenarios (which were also considered adaptive). If human memory were a non-hierarchical system, all these psychological mechanisms should have promoted recall equally.
This evidence suggests that psychological mechanisms evolved through processes of descent with modification, indicating the formation of human cognition by a combination of ancestral and derived psychological mechanisms (Barrett, 2012). This should make brain processes highly heterogeneous and possibly hierarchically organized, with information organized in human memory according to its relevance in dealing with imposed environmental adversity. Then, some ancestral or derived psychological mechanism, or both simultaneously, would be activated (Figure 5.2). Albuquerque and Ferreira Júnior (2017) argue that evolution has provided us with a naturalistic mind that evolved to account
Figure 5.2 Structure of the human naturalist mind: Scheme I shows a cladogram with the ancestral and derived psychological mechanisms that constitute the human mind. Scheme II illustrates the ancestral and derivative psychological mechanisms distributed in the human mind and how they can be activated; the psychological mechanisms are hierarchically organized according to their relevance to deal with environmental adversity Source: Created by the authors.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ENVIRONMENTAL SCIENCES
for myriad and complex relationships and challenges that the environment poses for our species. Challenges include what to eat (e.g., plants and animals), where to look for food, how to treat diseases or cope with accidents with the resources provided by nature, where to take refuge, and how to avoid predators and poisonous animals. The naturalistic mind, as one of the components of the human mind, would also result from the numerous selective pressures of the ancestral or modern environment to which our species is subjected. One of the first studies using the concept of naturalistic mind found that the human mind favors the recovery and storage of information about diseases and plants associated with their treatment, when these diseases are frequent in the social system (common diseases) or related to previous experiences of the individual (Silva et al., 2019). The authors expected to find that serious diseases, those normally debilitating or fatal, would be favored in memory. However, this was not the case. The modulation of the
113
frequency of illness with previous experience suggests that there is, in fact, a hierarchy in the mind. Interestingly, a similar pattern is observed in relation to other phenomena, such as when people deal with environmental hazards or catastrophes (see Ruin et al., 2007; Miceli et al., 2008; Gibbons and Groarke, 2016). This led Ferreira Júnior et al. (2019) to formulate the Principle of Regularity. According to this principle, the human mind is biased, because it is organized based on the regular events of our experience. Box 5.1 summarizes what we know about the naturalistic mind.
Does the Past Explain the Present? Human Beings and Landscapes Landscapes can be defined as the space of interaction of people and environment. The way humans relate to them may reveal strong evolutionary roots. The Biophilia hypothesis proposes that people possess an innate
BOX 5.1 Structure and behavior of the human naturalistic mind Origin • The naturalistic mind is the fruit of all selective pressures along the hominid lineage in evolutionary environments. Thus, evolved psychological mechanisms respond to different environmental challenges, that is, they are not necessarily tied to a particular environment (such as the Pleistocene savanna). • Memory, as one of the components of the naturalistic mind, prioritizes content with adaptive bias, organizing content hierarchically. Thus, information related to environmental survival can be prioritized over other adaptive information. This means that ancestral hazards will not necessarily be prioritized to the detriment of modern hazards. Physiology • The naturalistic mind, as shaped during evolution, can lead our species to experience adaptive lags. However, as cultural responses operate faster than biological evolution, human activities of niche construction can modulate the existence or not of adaptive lags. • Possible mental responses generated in the ancestral environment can be modulated by the individual’s previous experience with a given phenomenon. • The frequency (regularity) of a given phenomenon biases cognitive processes associated with the naturalistic mind, so that less common or rare phenomena tend to be neglected unless they are modulated by previous experience.
114
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
emotional and affective predisposition to living things, whether they are animals, plants, or processes (Wilson, 1993). People tend to prefer images of natural environments to urban environments and these images are more likely to be preferred when they contain trees (Ulrich, 1993). In addition, humans process visual stimuli from nature more efficiently than from urban environments. This can elicit favorable feelings and emotions to natural landscapes (Townsend and Barton, 2018). For example, when contemplating a landscape, whether urban or natural, people elicit emotional responses that may lead to positive or negative attitudes towards that landscape (see Bargh et al., 1992). Evidence has shown that some people appreciate landscapes containing lakes or rivers (Ulrich, 1983), and feel more freedom in environments with exuberantly green vegetation than in urban landscapes (Hartmann and Apaolaza-Ibáñez, 2010). These affective reactions can be the result of aesthetic aspects of the landscape (e.g., perceived naturalness – how close a given landscape is to its natural state – presence of water, complexity) or of evolutionary aspects, as proposed by the Biophilia hypothesis (Wilson, 1993; Han, 2007; Ode et al., 2009; Lee and Son, 2017). The affinity of human beings with living elements may be the result of the continuing relationship of hominids with nature during their evolutionary history. This affinity may influence aspects of human cognition related to the use and management of natural resources (Albuquerque and Ferreira Júnior, 2017) as well as emotional responses and preferences for aesthetic components of nature. In this case, some natural scenarios stand out more than others (Orians and Heerwagen, 1992). For example, studies have shown that inhabitants of countries including Australia, Nigeria, South Africa, the United States, Estonia, and Italy, among others, prefer open landscapes with sparse trees with wide and stratified canopy, which are characteristic of the African Pleistocene savanna (see Orians and Heerwagen, 1992;
Sommer, 1997; Summit and Sommer, 1999; Herzog et al., 2000; Falk and Balling, 2010). Orians and Heerwagen (1992) suggest that this preference has an evolutionary origin and results from the importance of the savanna environment for hominid survival during the Pleistocene. The savanna offered the first humans a set of possibilities (e.g., a panoramic view of the open environment and trees that were easy to climb) that helped them to escape from predators, search for food, and shelter under their canopies (Appleton, 1975; Orians and Heerwagen, 1992; Townsend and Barton, 2018). The savanna may have played a relevant role during human evolution, but not the most prominent. Since we inhabited other environments with different challenges in the Pleistocene, survival strategies for the savanna have been potentially modified, improved, and combined with other strategies or even abandoned over time. According to Tooby and Cosmides (2015), the period during which we were hunter- gatherers in paleoenvironments was crucial for the evolution of our mind. Evolutionary processes are slow and need hundreds of generations to build a highly complex ‘mental’ program. That is, human minds would still be adapted to the world of our ancestors. According to these authors, ‘The industrial revolution – even the agricultural revolution – is too brief a period to have selected for new neurocomputational programs of any complexity’ (Tooby and Cosmides, 2015: 19). People commonly experience an adaptive delay when facing the challenges of industrialized societies, because these environments are different from the environment in which we evolved. For example, the taste for fatty foods is an adaptive behavior for ancestral environments, in which fat was scarce, but is nonadaptive in the current environment because it increases the incidence of cardiovascular diseases (Cosmides and Tooby, 2003). The influence of past heritage on the interaction of people and landscapes and, consequently, the existence of adaptive lags has been debated by scholars. Some argue that this
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ENVIRONMENTAL SCIENCES
argument overlooks evolutionary processes that have enabled the reproductive success of humans, such as the ability to adjust to varying and variable environments in which they live (see Laland and O’Brien, 2012). Laland and Brown (2006) argue that humans do not experience adaptive lags, precisely because they have the ability to build and rebuild key components of their environments to suit their needs. This adaptive capacity of humans and other organisms is understood as niche construction, which occurs in response to the environmental challenges created by their ancestors (see Lewontin, 1982; Odling-Smee et al., 2003; Laland and Brown, 2006; Laland and O’Brien, 2012). For example, even if there is excessive consumption of fatty foods, humans create niches to solve this problem, such as the development of drugs and the practice of physical exercise. Due to the cultural and environmental diversity in which we live and develop, the preference for landscape among humans is also diverse. For example, the preference among the Japanese for landscapes of feudal gardens in urban centers varies according to the distance to buildings and also to personal life experience (Senoglu et al., 2018). Colley and Craig (2019) observed that, in Scotland, if people perceive a landscape as natural (i.e., with little human intervention), the emotional attachment to the landscape increases, influencing their preferences. In addition, people living in China prefer environments with a balance between wild nature and human constructions, such as channeled streams in native vegetation (see Hu et al., 2019). Thus, recent environmental factors can influence innate human preferences for landscapes.
How Does Our Mind Deal with Information about Other Living Things? In their interactions with environments, humans had to deal with dangerous events that threatened ancestral survival. Learning
115
strategies such as trial and error may have been important in order to avoid such threats over time. However, trial and error are not always advantageous because the learning costs increase in situations such as contact with poisonous animals. In this context, strategies that favor the learning of certain information from the environment may have been selected (see Rendell et al., 2011; Barrett and Broesch, 2012). For example, early hominids that remembered and quickly learned how to avoid certain components of the environment (e.g., dangerous animals) and how to recognize and select natural resources (e.g., fruits) would have an advantage over others who did not possess such skills or behaviors. In the Biophilia hypothesis, Wilson (1993) proposes that the behaviors of approaching (biophilia) and avoiding (biophobia) certain components of the environment may have a biological, evolutionary basis. These behaviors result from natural selection to promote the survival of humans in their interactions with the environment (see also Kellert, 1993). Chief among the biophilic interactions is the demand for food in the ancestral environment. Rozin and Todd (2015) argue that, during human evolution, the need for food and nutrients demanded more time and cognitive effort than other activities performed by hominids. Selecting food is critical to the evolution of the human mind and structuring the culture, but is not an easy task. This activity requires caution in avoiding the ingestion of toxins and other non-nutritive substances. It was essential to differentiate the toxic from the nutritious. This has led humans to specialize over time, through natural selection (Rozin and Todd, 2015). Although the human–food interaction during evolution is a promising way to understand our cognitive structure – and a matter of great interest to evolutionary ethnobiology (see Albuquerque and Ferreira Júnior, 2017) – this subject is still neglected in the field of evolutionary psychology (Rozin and Todd, 2015). Evidence suggests a bias in human memory towards learning information related to
116
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
dangerous animals, as we have previously mentioned. Broesch et al. (2014) evaluated memory retention of information related to the danger of animals (e.g., if they were poisonous or not), diet, and habitat in indigenous young people and adults of the Fiji Islands. They observed that information about hazard and toxicity was best retained by young people, whereas adults showed no preferential retention for this information. In contrast, other studies have indicated that the use of images of dangerous animals can increase the retrieval and retention of information in adults (Kock et al., 2008; Riaz et al., 2018). In addition to retrieving information from memory, humans may possess other characteristics that respond quickly to dangerous animals. Neurobiological studies have indicated that the amygdala of primates, including humans, is able to tune visual areas of the brain to perceive fear-related stimuli (see Prokop and Randler, 2018). Studies on visual attention have shown that dangerous animals, such as lions and snakes, more quickly capture and maintain the attention of humans than non-dangerous animals (Yorzinski et al., 2014). Infants at five months of age stare longer at images that schematically represent a spider than images with random schemata (Rakison and Derringer, 2008). This may reflect an evolved response to detect more quickly and to focus attention on dangerous animals (Yorzinski et al., 2014; Prokop and Randler, 2018). According to Tooby and Cosmides (2015), this fact could also explain modern phobias associated with these animals. However, these responses are culturally modulated. For example, Maasai people in Kenya evaluated lions as aesthetically more attractive than hyenas (Pinho et al., 2014). Lions are of great cultural importance to the Maasai people (Pinho et al., 2014), suggesting that culture can partly modulate human responses to dangerous animals. Aversion to dangerous animals can be learned quickly by observing the reactions of other individuals to these animals. In a study with laboratory-raised monkeys – Macaca
mulatta – Cook and Mineka (1990) showed that young individuals can quickly acquire fear of snakes merely by watching fear reactions of other individuals towards these animals in videos. However, observers were not afraid of flowers after watching edited videos displaying individuals who were afraid of these items. This suggests that fear is more quickly learned when directed at dangerous animals. Similarly, babies aged seven to 18 months paid more attention to snake images when they were associated with a frightened human voice than with a cheerful voice (DeLoache and LoBue, 2009). Such learning may have been important for the survival of early hominids, as individuals would not need direct experience with dangerous animals to acquire the behavior of avoiding these animals. Adaptive mechanisms are also activated in relation to plants. Prokop and Fančovičová (2014) investigated children exposed to information on toxic and non-toxic plants associated with fruit images of different colors, i.e., red and black for toxic plants and green for non-toxic plants. They found that plant information associated with red- and blackcolored fruits was better retained in children’s memory, possibly due to their association with toxic fruits. A recent study showed that, in a visual detection task, toxic plants were detected significantly sooner than non-toxic plants by humans (Prokop and Fančovičová, 2019). The ability to recall information about plant toxicity may have given humans the ability to identify and avoid foods potentially harmful to their survival. In addition to the behavior of aversion, people also exhibit behaviors that promote contact and interaction with animals and plants (biophilia). People have positive emotional responses towards animals with certain characteristics (Prokop and Randler, 2018). Martín-López et al. (2008) conducted a meta-analysis of 60 studies and showed that people are more likely to pay for animal conservation due to anthropocentric rather than scientific factors. Anthropocentric factors
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ENVIRONMENTAL SCIENCES
include animal characteristics preferred by people, such as length, weight, and eye size. Regarding plants, some studies have shown that people prefer landscapes of trees with larger canopies and shorter trunks (for a review, see Townsend and Barton, 2018). It seems this preference may be produced by psychological adaptation. Individuals who had positive sensations in response to these trees were selected because these trees offered them safety and shelter (Townsend and Barton, 2018). The degree of interaction of people and nature may promote positive behaviors directed at other animals. A study in China found that children living in rural areas and having more contact with nature were more likely to protect and like animals (biophilia) than children from urbanized regions (Zhang et al., 2014). Zhang and colleagues suggest that contact of humans with nature can help to promote conservation strategies. Sampaio et al. (2018) observed that the contact of children with forests influenced their knowledge of local biodiversity. The children were encouraged to express their knowledge as drawings, and the authors found that children who had more contact with forests also had greater knowledge about native animals of the region. According to the authors, the proximity of children to the forest drew attention to the components of this environment, laying the foundations for the construction of knowledge. This fact indicates that the environment in which human beings live can influence their cognition, and is responsible for promoting and mediating human behaviors, such as being prone or not to preserve nature.
FUTURE CHALLENGES FOR ENVIRONMENTAL SCIENCES Penn (2003) offered a synthesis of a number of evolutionary approaches that provide insight into human nature and its role
117
in current environmental events. For Penn, population growth is one of the major current ecological issues – there are around seven billion people on the planet – and creating effective public policies to stabilize this growth requires understanding the evolutionary roots of the problem. From an evolutionary perspective, reproductive self-regulation should be expected as the high demographic rate disturbs population and environmental balance – as advocated by the Demographic Transition Theory – as this adaptive response provides the best chance for survival (see recent discussion in Brooks et al., 2019; Salvati et al., 2019). However, in some traditional societies, reproductive success is positively associated with wealth increase, whereas in rich developed countries, fertility tends to fall as their people opt to have fewer children to improve their quality of life (Penn, 2003). Therefore, more studies are necessary, analyzing the influence of evolutionary and cultural factors on current demographic dynamics. Another aspect to be considered when developing policies to deal with long-term environmental threats is discounting the future, that is, the limitations humans have in considering environmental problems that may arise in a distant future, putting more emphasis on the present day (Penn, 2003; Henry et al., 2017). In this case, natural selection may have favored hominids that discounted the future, as life expectancy was relatively short and the future uncertain, making it crucial to focus on present needs, which increased individual survival and reproductive success (Penn, 2003). Thus, a good conservation strategy would be to associate time discount rates to nature conservation policies, as that may provide more realistic expectations of human response to these policies (Henry et al., 2017). Moreover, humans tend to use natural resources according to their own interests, putting societal interests in second place, potentially leading to resource exhaustion (Penn, 2003). This kind of behavior was
118
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
proposed by Hardin (1968) as the tragedy of the commons. For instance, a study by Scheiter et al. (2019) showed that, in African rural savannas, people use open fields for pasture or hunting intensively, exceeding the optimum level. These authors propose this as an example of the tragedy of the commons that will compromise ecosystem services in the future. However, human populations are able to adapt and to develop rules to effectively manage common resources, avoiding the tragedy of the commons (for a more complete argument, see Šestáková and Plichtová, 2019). In this sense, it is essential to understand the constraints and amplitude of the influence of the evolved psychological mechanisms in the relations of modern humans and the environment. Evolutionary psychology is interested in better understanding not only environmental problems and challenges (having as background the attitudes of human beings) but also how we model our multiple relationships with nature. Penn (2003) argues that we are still moving towards an understanding of environmental problems from an evolutionary perspective. In this chapter, we presented a brief overview of how evolved psychological mechanisms help to understand modern humans. However, just as we move slowly in understanding the environmental challenges generated by human activity, our understanding of other aspects of the relationship between human beings and the environment is still in its infancy. We believe that dialogue with other fields in science can be fruitful for a better understanding, from an evolutionary point of view, of the relationship between humans and the environment. An evolutionary perspective is not exclusive but provides an alternative or additional point of view. Evolutionary ethnobiology is a newly systematic science (Albuquerque and Ferreira Júnior, 2017) that shares this interest in understanding the ecological and evolutionary history behind our relations with the environment.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS This study was financed in part by the Coordenação de Aperfeiçoamento de Pessoal de Nível Superior – Brasil (CAPES) – Finance Code 001. We thank the CNPq for the productivity grant awarded to UPA.
Note 1 The process where organisms, through their activities and decisions, modify their own and other’s environments. The environmental modifications generated by the niche constructors influence the selective pressures of their environment and can lead to changes in their metabolic, physiological, and behavioral activities (Odling-Smee et al., 2003; Laland and O’Brien, 2012; Flynn et al., 2013; Matthews et al., 2014).
REFERENCES Albuquerque, U.P. and Ferreira Júnior, W.S., 2017. What do we study in evolutionary ethnobiology? Defining the theoretical basis for a research program. Evolutionary Biology, 44(2), pp.206–15. Appleton, J., 1975. The Experience of Landscape. London: John Wiley & Sons. Barrett, H.C., 2012. A hierarchical model of the evolution of human brain specializations. PNAS, 109(1), pp.10733–40. Barrett, H.C. and Broesch, J., 2012. Prepared social learning about dangerous animals in children. Evolution and Human Behavior, 33, pp.499–508. Barrett, H.C., Peterson, C.D. and Frankenhuis, W.E., 2016. Mapping the cultural learnability landscape of danger. Child Development, 87(3), pp.770–81. Bargh, J.A., Chaiken, S., Govender, R. and Pratto, F., 1992. The generality of the automatic attitude activation effect. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 62(6), pp.893–912. Barker, G., Barton, H., Bird, M., Daly, P., Datan, I., Dykes, A., Farr, L., Gilbertson, D., Harrisson, B., Hunt, C., Higham, T., Kealhofer, L., Krigbaum, J., Lewis, H., MacLaren, S., Paz, V., Pike, A.,
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ENVIRONMENTAL SCIENCES
Piper, P., Pyatt, B., Rabett, R., Reynolds, T., Rose, J., Rushworth, G., Stephens, M., Stringer, C., Thompson, J. and Turney, C., 2007. The ‘human revolution’ in lowland tropical Southeast Asia: The antiquity and behaviour of anatomically modern humans at Niah Cave (Sarawak, Borneo). Journal of Human Evolution, 52(3), pp.243–61. Blome, M.W., Cohen, A.S., Tryon, C.A., Brooks, A.S. and Russell, J., 2012. The environmental context for the origins of modern human diversity: A synthesis of regional variability in African climate 150,000–30,000 years ago. Journal of Human Evolution, 62, pp.563–92. Böhme, M., Spassov, N., Ebner, M. and Geraads, D., 2017. Messinian age and savannah environment of the possible hominin Graecopithecus from Europe. PLoS ONE, 12(5), pp.1–31. Bolhuis, J.J., Brown, G.R., Richardson, R.C. and Laland, K.N., 2011. Darwin in mind: New opportunities for evolutionary psychology. PLoS Biology, 9, pp.1–8. Bowlby, J., 1982. Loss: Sadness and Depression. New York: Basic Book Publishers. Broesch, J., Barrett, H.C. and Henrich, J., 2014. Adaptive content biases in learning about animals across the life course. Human Nature, 25, pp.181–99. Brooks, D.J., Brooks, S.G., Greenhill, B.D. and Haas, M.L., 2019. The demographic transition theory of war: Why young societies are conflict prone and old societies are the most peaceful. International Security, 43(3), pp.53–95. Colley, K. and Craig, T., 2019. Natural places: Perceptions of wildness and attachment to local greenspace. Journal of Environmental Psychology, 61, pp.71–8. Cook, M. and Mineka, S., 1990. Selective associations in the observational conditioning of fear in rhesus monkeys. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 16, pp.372–89. Cosmides, L. and Tooby, J., 2003. Evolutionary psychology: Theoretical foundations. In: L. Nadel (Ed.). Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science (pp.54–64). London: Macmillan. Coss, R.G. and Moore, M., 2002. Precocious knowledge of trees as antipredator refuge in preschool children: An examination of aesthetics, attributive judgments, and relic sexual dinichism. Ecological Psychology, 14, pp.181–222.
119
Coulthard, T.J., Ramirez, J.A., Barton, N., Rogerson, M. and Brucher, T., 2013. Were rivers flowing across the Sahara during the last interglacial? Implications for human migration through Africa. PLoS ONE, 8(9), e74834. DeLoache, J.S. and LoBue, V., 2009. The narrow fellow in the grass: Human infants associate snakes and fear. Developmental Science, 12, pp.201–7. Falk, J.H. and Balling, J.D., 2010. Evolutionary influence on human landscape preference. Environment and Behavior, 42(4), pp.479–93. Ferreira Júnior, W.S., Medeiros, P.M. and Albuquerque, U.P., 2019. Evolutionary ethnobiology. Encyclopedia of Life Sciences, pp.1–6. John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Foley, R., 1996. The adaptive legacy of human evolution: A search for the environment of evolutionary adaptedness. Evolutionary Anthropology, 4(6), pp.194–203. Foley, R.A., Martin, L., Lahr, M.M. and Stringer, C., 2016. Major transitions in human evolution. Philosophical Transactions Royal Society B, 371(1698), pp.1–8. Friesem, D.E., Lavi, N., Madella, M., Boaretto, E., Ajithparsad, P. and French, C., 2017. The formation of fire residues associated with hunter-gatherers in humid tropical environments: A geo-ethnoarchaeological perspective. Quaternary Science Reviews, 171(1), pp.85–99. Frost, P., 2011. Human nature or human natures? Futures, 43, pp.740–8. Gibbons, A. and Groarke, A., 2016. Can risk and illness perceptions predict breast cancer worry in healthy women? Journal of Health Psychology, 21(9), pp.1–11. Han, K.T., 2007. Responses to six major terrestrial biomes in terms of scenic beauty, preference, and restorativeness. Environment and Behavior, 39(4), pp.529–56. Hardin, G., 1968. The tragedy of the commons. Science, 162(3859), pp.1243–8. Hartmann, P. and Apaolaza-Ibáñes, V., 2010. Beyond savanna: An evolutionary and environmental psychology approach to behavioral effects of nature scenery in green advertising. Journal of Environmental Psychology, 30(1), pp.119–28. Hartmann, P. and Apaolaza-Ibáñes, V., 2013. Desert or rain: Standardisation of green
120
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
advertising versus adaptation to the target audience’s natural environment. European Journal of Marketing, 47(5/6), pp.917–33. Henry, A.D., Christensen, A.E., Hofmann, R., Steimanis, I. and Vollan, B., 2017. Influence of sea level rise on discounting, resource use and migration in small-island communities: An agent-based modelling approach. Environmental Conservation, 44(4), pp.381–8. Herzog, T.R., Herbert, E.J., Kaplan, R. and Crooks, C.L. 2000. Cultural and developmental comparisons of landscape perceptions and preferences. Environment and Behavior, 32(3), pp.323–46. Hu, S., Yue, H. and Zhou, Z., 2019. Preferences for urban stream landscapes: Opportunities to promote unmanaged riparian vegetation. Urban Forestry & Urban Greening, 38, pp.114–23. Hublin, J.J., Ben-Ncer, A., Bailey, S.E., Freidline, S.E., Neubauer, S., Skinner, M.M., Bergmann, I., Le Cabec, A., Benazzi, S., Harvati, K. and Gunz, P., 2017. New fossils from Jebel Irhoud, Morocco and the pan-African origin of Homo sapiens. Nature, 546(7657), pp.289–92. Kellert, S.R., 1993. The biological basis for human values of nature. In: S.R. Kellert and E.O. Wilson (Eds.). The Biophilia Hypothesis. Washington, DC: Island Press. Pp. 42–69. Kock, N., Chatelain-Jardón, R. and Carmona, J., 2008. An experimental study of simulated web-based threats and their impact on knowledge communication effectiveness. IEEE Transactions on Professional Communication, 51, pp.183–97. Kong, Y., Deng, C., Liu, W., Wu, X., Pei, S., Sun, L., Ge, J., Yi, L. and Zhu, R., 2018. Magnetostratigraphic dating of the hominin occupation of Bailong Cave, central China. Scientific Reports, 8(9699), pp.1–12. Laland, K.N. and Brown, G.R., 2006. Niche construction, human behavior, and the adaptive-lag hypothesis. Evolutionary Anthropology: Issues, News, and Reviews, 15(3), pp.95–104. Laland, K.N. and O’Brien, M.J., 2012. Cultural niche construction: An introduction. Biological Theory, 6(3), pp.191–2. Larson, S., 2012. Did Australopiths climb trees? Science 338(6106), pp.478–9. Lee, K. and Son, Y., 2017. Exploring landscape perceptions of Bukhansan national park
according to the degree of visitors. Sustainability, 9(8), pp.1–27. Lewontin, R.C., 1982. Organism and environment. In: H.C. Plotkin (Ed.). Learning, Development and Culture (pp.151–70). New York: John Wiley & Sons. López-García, L.M., Blain, H., Sanz, M., Daura, J. and Zilhão, J., 2018. Refining the environmental and climatic background of the Middle Pleistocene human cranium from Gruta da Aroeira (Torres Novas, Portugal). Quaternary Science Reviews, 200, pp.367–75. Martín-López, B., Montes, C. and Benayas, J., 2008. Economic valuation of biodiversity conservation: The meaning of numbers. Conservation Biology, 22, pp.624–35. Matthews, B., De Meester, L., Jones, C.G., Ibelings, B.W., Bouma, T.J., Nuutinen, V., Koppel, J.V. and Odling-Smee, J., 2014. Under niche construction: An operational bridge between ecology, evolution, and ecosystem science. Ecological Monographs, 84, pp.245–63. Miceli, R., Sotgiu, I. and Settanni, M., 2008. Disaster preparedness and perception of flood risk: A study in an alpine valley in Italy. Journal of Environmental Psychology, 28(2), pp.164–73. Moura, J.M.B., Ferreira Junior, W.S., Silva, T.C. and Albuquerque U.P., 2018. The influence of the evolutionary past on the mind: An analysis of the preference for landscapes in the human species. Frontiers in Psychology, 9(2485), pp.1–13. Nairne, J.S., Thompson, S.R. and Pandeirada, J.N.S., 2007. Adaptive memory: Survival processing enhances retention. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 33(2), pp.263–73. Ode, A., Fry, G., Tveit, M.S., Messager, P. and Miller, D., 2009. Indicators of perceived naturalness as drivers of landscape preference. Journal of Environmental Management, 90(1), pp.375–83. Odling-Smee, J., Laland, K.N. and Feldman, M.W., 2003. Niche Construction: The Neglected Process in Evolution. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Orians, G.H., 1980. Habitat selection: General theory and applications to human behavior. In: J. Lockard (Ed.). The Evolution of Human Social Behavior (pp.49–66). Chicago, IL: Elsevier.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ENVIRONMENTAL SCIENCES
Orians, G.H. and Heerwagen, J.H., 1992. Evolved responses to landscapes. In: J.H. Barkow, L. Cosmides and L. Tooby (Eds.). The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture (pp.555–79). New York: Oxford University Press. Penn, D.J., 2003. The evolutionary roots of our environmental problems: Toward a Darwinian ecology. The Quarterly Review of Biology, 78(3), pp.275–301. Pinho, J.R., Grilo, C., Boone, R.B., Galvin, K.A. and Snodgrass, J.G., 2014. Influence of aesthetic appreciation of wildlife species on attitudes towards their conservation in Kenyan agropastoralist communities. PLoS ONE, 9:e88842. Prokop, P. and Fančovičová, J., 2014. Seeing coloured fruits: Utilization of the theory of adaptive memory in teaching botany. Journal of Biological Education, 3(48), pp.127–32. Prokop, P. and Fančovičová, J., 2019. The perception of toxic and non-toxic plants by children and adolescents with regard to gender: Implications for teaching botany. Journal of Biological Education, 53, pp. 463–473. Prokop, P. and Randler, C., 2018. Biological predispositions and individual differences in human attitudes toward animals. In: U.P. Albuquerque and R.R.N. Alves (Eds.). Ethnozoology: Animals in our Lives (pp. 447–66). Oxford: Elsevier Academic Press. Rakison, D.H. and Derringer, J., 2008. Do infants possess an evolved spider-detection mechanism? Cognition, 107, pp.381–93. Rendell, L., Fogarty, L., Hoppitt, W.J.E., Morgan, T.J.H., Webster, M.M. and Laland, K,N., 2011. Cognitive culture: Theoretical and empirical insights into social learning strategies. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15, pp.68–76. Riaz, A., Gregor, S. and Lin, A., 2018. Biophilia and biophobia in website design: Improving internet information dissemination. Information & Management, 55, pp.199–214. Richter, D., Grün, R., Joannes-Boyau, R., Steele, T.E., Amani, F., Rué, M., Fernandes, P., Raynal, J., Geraads, D., Ben-Ncer, A., Hublin, J. and McPherron, S.P., 2017. The age of the hominin fossils from Jebel Irhoud, Morocco, and the origins of the Middle Stone Age. Nature, 546(7657), pp.293–6. Roberts, P., Boivin, N., Lee-Thorp, J., Petraglia, M. and Stock, J., 2016. Tropical forests and
121
the genus Homo. Evolutionary Anthropology: Issues, News, and Reviews, 25(6), pp.306–17. Rozin, P. and Todd, P.M., 2015. The evolutionary psychology of food intake and choice. In: D.M. Buss (Ed.). The Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology (pp.183–205). Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley & Sons. Ruin, I., Gaillard, J.C. and Lutoff, C., 2007. How to get there? Assessing motorists’ flash flood risk perception on daily itineraries. Environmental Hazards, 7(3), pp.235–44. Salvati, L., Carlucci, M., Serra, P. and Zambon, I., 2019. Demographic transitions and socioeconomic development in Italy, 1862–2009: A brief overview. Sustainability (Switzerland), 11(1), pp.1–12. Sampaio, M.B., De La Fuente, M.F., Albuquerque, U.P., Souto, A.S. and Schiel, N., 2018. Contact with urban forests greatly enhances children’s knowledge of faunal diversity. Urban Forestry & Urban Greening, 30, pp.56–61. Sandry, J., Trafimow, D., Marks, M.J. and Rice, S., 2013. Adaptive memory: Evaluating alternative forms of fitness-relevant processing in the survival processing paradigm. PLoS ONE, 8(4), e60868. Scheiter, S., Schulte, J., Pfeiffer, M., Martens, C., Erasmus, B.F.N. and Twine, W.C., 2019. How does climate change influence the economic value of ecosystem services in savanna rangelands? Ecological Economics, 157, pp.342–56. Schlebusch, C.M., Malmström, H., Günther, T., Sjödin, P., Coutinho, A., Edlund, H., Munters, A.R., Vicente, M., Steyn, M., Soodyall, H., Lombard, M. and Jakobsson, M., 2017. Southern African ancient genomes estimate modern human divergence to 350,000 to 260,000 years ago. Science, 358(6363), pp.652–5. Senoglu, B., Oktay, H.E. and Kinoshita, I., 2018. An empirical research study on prospect– refuge theory and the effect of high-rise buildings in a Japanese garden setting. City, Territory and Architecture, 5(3), pp.1–16. Šestáková, A. and Plichtová, J., 2019. Contemporary commons: Sharing and managing common-pool resources in the 21st century. Human Affairs, 29(1), pp.74–86. Silva, R.H., Ferreira Júnior, W.S., Medeiros, P.M. and Albuquerque, U.P., 2019. Adaptive
122
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
memory and evolution of the human naturalistic mind: Insights from the use of medicinal plants. PLoS ONE, 14(3), pp.1–15. Sommer, R., 1997. Further cross-national studies of tree form preferences. Ecological Psychology, 9(2), pp.153–60. Stringer, C., 2016. The origin and evolution of Homo sapiens. Philosophical Transactions Royal Society B, 371(1698), pp.1–12. Summit, J. and Sommer, R., 1999. Further studies of preferred tree shapes. Environment and Behavior, 31(4), pp.550–76. Tooby, J. and Cosmides, L., 1992. The psychological foundations of culture. In: J. Barkow, L. Cosmides and J. Tooby (Eds.). The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture (pp.19–136). New York: Oxford University Press. Tooby, J. and Cosmides, L., 2005. Conceptual foundations of evolutionary psychology. In: D.M. Buss (Ed.). The Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology (pp.5–67). Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley & Sons. Tooby, J. and Cosmides, L., 2015. The theoretical foundations of evolutionary psychology. In: D.M. Buss (Ed.). The Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology (pp.3–87). Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley & Sons. Townsend, J.B. and Barton, S., 2018. The impact of ancient tree form on modern landscape preferences. Urban Forestry and Urban Greening, 34, pp.205–16.
Ulrich, R.S., 1993. Biophilia, biophobia, and natural landscapes. In: S.R. Kellert and E.O. Wilson (Eds.). The Biophilia Hypothesis. Washington, DC: Island Press. pp. 73–137. Volk, A.A., and Atkinson, J.A., 2013. Infant and child death in the human environment of evolutionary adaptation. Evolution and Human Behavior, 34, pp. 182–93. Wilson, E.O., 1993. Biophilia and the conservation ethic. In: S.R. Kellert and E.O. Wilson (Eds.). The Biophilia Hypothesis. Washington, DC: Island Press. pp. 31–41. Yang, L., Lau, K.P.L. and Truong, L., 2014. The survival effect in memory: Does it hold into old age and non-ancestral scenarios? PLoS ONE, 9(5), pp.1–9. Yorzinski, J.L., Penkunas, M.J., Platt, M.L. and Coss, R.G., 2014. Dangerous animals capture and maintain attention in humans. Evolutionary Psychology, 12, pp.534–48. Young, S.G., Brown, C.M. and Ambady, N., 2012. Priming a natural or human-made environment directs attention to contextcongruent threatening stimuli. Cognition and Emotion, 26, pp.927–33. Zajonc, R.B., 1980. Feeling and thinking: Preferences need no inferences. American Psychologist, 35(2), pp.151–75. Zhang, W., Goodale, E. and Chen, J., 2014. How contact with nature affects children’s biophilia, biophobia and conservation attitude in China. Biological Conservation, 177, pp.109–16.
6 Evolutionary Psychology and Public Health Simon Russell
INTRODUCTION: PUBLIC HEALTH AND THE OBESITY PROBLEM Public health has been defined as ‘the art and science of preventing disease, prolonging life and promoting health through the organized efforts of society’.[1] Public health is an interdisciplinary science, which aims to promote the length and quality of human life through the prevention and treatment of disease. Whether relating to physical, mental, or social health, public health seeks to translate highquality research into preventative or curative practice. The field of public health also recognises a positive value arising from good health, which incorporates concepts of psychological and emotional well-being. While selection does not act to promote longevity, evolutionary fitness is profoundly affected by morbidity and mortality[2] and both health outcomes and evolutionary fitness are notably predicted by socioeconomic status in the developed and developing world.[3,4] While there is a
complex relationship between human fertility, fecundity, and fitness,[5] good health is recognised as a key dimension of evolutionary fitness[6] and has a greater impact on fitness than age-specific fertility.[7] However, selection does not act on health and it is possible to be a public health success but an evolutionary failure; one may lead a long and healthy life but fail to reproduce. Equally, one may be an evolutionary success and a public health failure; it is possible to reproduce successfully from a position of poor health. Despite public health and evolutionary success being defined by and measured in different currencies, applying the principles of evolution to the discipline of public health may provide original insight for policy makers and practitioners. Evolutionary science has been increasingly applied to various disciplines within the field of public health, including reproductive health, immunity, infectious diseases, cancer, and mental health.[8–11] This chapter explores the utility of applying the principles of evolutionary
124
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
psychology to the most pervasive physical health problem of the modern world, namely, non-communicable diseases (NCDs). The primary focus will be on pathological health risk behaviours, which greatly enhance the risk of NCDs. Additionally, a case study presents the relevance of evolutionary decision making in health-promotion behaviour, within the context of vaccinations and protection from communicable diseases. Comprising cardiovascular diseases, cancers, chronic respiratory diseases, and diabetes, NCDs are preventable but account for 41 million or 71% of global deaths annually.[12] The main risk factors for NCDs are poor diet, physical inactivity, tobacco use, and harmful alcohol use.[13] Harmful alcohol use, smoking, poor diet, and physical inactivity can be understood as health risk behaviours, which lead to potentially pathological metabolic and physiological changes. Poor diets typically involve consuming energy-dense but low-nutrient food and drinks. Low nutrition and overconsumption often co-exist and are typified by eating foods that are high in fats, sugars, and salt (HFSS). Overweight and obesity are typical consequences of poor diet and inactivity and will be considered as key pathological outcomes for the purpose of this chapter. The principles and public health response discussed here for overweight and obesity are also potentially relevant to harmful drinking and smoking, since it will be argued that similar psychological mechanisms and evolutionary strategies underpin and govern multiple health-risk-taking behaviours (for usage and definitions, see section ‘Psychological mechanisms and evolutionary strategies’). Overweight and obesity has become perhaps the most prevalent and burdensome public health problem of the modern world. Overweight and obesity rates in adults have tripled since 1975, and in 2016 there were 1.9 billion (39%) adults globally living with overweight or obesity.[14] Rates of childhood obesity have risen 10-fold over the same period, and in 2016 there were an estimated 340 million children aged 5–19 years living
with overweight and obesity.[14] Living with overweight and obesity greatly increases the risk of Type-2 diabetes, cardiovascular diseases, and various forms of cancer,[15] in addition to many other physical and mental health problems. Obesity can be conceived as both very simple and as highly complex. A positive energy balance can be thought of as an equation: energy in, use by metabolic processes, and energy out. Even a slight but consistent positive imbalance would accrue overweight and obesity over time. Conversely, there is almost nothing we do in our lives which does not affect our energy balance and obesity. The Foresight obesity systems map[16] categorises, maps, and illustrates the varied and complex determinants of obesity. There is limited utility in focussing on any one part of the map, given that the obesity system is dynamic and any change to one part of the system will have consequences for other parts. Public health responses can sometimes be simplistic; interventions may attempt to adjust one determinant in some way, while controlling for others, and practitioners and policy lobbyists can become focused on just one element of the map. In turn, the public and the media sometimes misunderstand the problem and oversimplify what is perceived to be an effective policy response. Furthermore, there is no consensus between academics or civil servants on where the public health focus should be. Some suggest the problem lies with ‘energy in’, since evidence suggests physical activity may not help people lose weight, while others focus mainly on ‘energy out’ given that physical activity has been shown to attenuate the risks of NCDs, even for people living with overweight or obesity. The causality of obesity has drawn similar debate in terms of the relative impacts of our genes and the environment and the interplay between the two. Broadly speaking, the effects of heredity in obesity are likely to be low, given that obesity has grown rapidly in genetically stable populations. However, there is some evidence to suggest that biological influences account for large proportions
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND PUBLIC HEALTH
125
Figure 6.1 The impact of the food supply on the expression of obesityi[19]
of variance in food and satiety responsiveness and therefore risk of obesity. Yet the more we understand about genetic susceptibility, the more the importance of the environment has been revealed; the expression of susceptibility to obesity in environments with a limited food supply is low but becomes hugely amplified in environments with an abundant supply (Figure 6.1).[17] Generally, diseases rarely have simple Mendelian patterns of inheritance; heritability of ill health is more commonly the product of interactions between multiple genes, predispositions and the environment, and socioeconomic and cultural influences.[18] While genetic predispositions are likely to exacerbate or attenuate the risk of obesity, the problem is recent relative to human history and has coincided with industrial and urban modernisation, which provide the obesogenic platforms from which genetic susceptibility may be expressed.
MAKING EVOLUTIONARY SENSE OF THE MODERN WORLD The majority of people now live in surroundings that are very different from the selective environments in which we evolved. With tech-
nological and civil development, many physical and psychological adaptations that are rooted in evolutionary time have become mismatched with modern life. Obesity is perhaps the most pronounced physical manifestation of this mismatch; it has increased in almost every country in the world, and is reported to be proximally driven by changes in the food system, where calorie-dense food is abundant, affordable, and readily available in most of the modern world.[20] Built environments have also changed and influence what and how much we eat, in addition to the energy we expend; energy-saving mechanisms are integral to modern civic design. Modern living has become increasingly urbanised; in 1950 there were 751 million people worldwide living in urban areas, compared to 4.2 billion in 2018, which is 55% worldwide but as high as 72% in Europe and 82% in North America.[21] Urbanisation is relevant to the obesity epidemic; research suggests that a lack of green space and recreational facilities, perceived unsafe communities, and high-density populations can be risk factors for obesity.[22] Urbanisation is also relevant from an evolutionary perspective; community and kin networks have been replaced in urban environments by small living units or nuclear families, typically with non-kin neighbours.[23]
126
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
In our ancestral, selective environment there would have been food scarcity and changeable conditions. In such circumstances it would have been adaptive to maximise caloric intake, especially of food rich in sugar and fat. Our ancestors and traditional populations have evolved to maximise their foraging success and net energy intake,[24–26] and, therefore, their health and evolutionary fitness. Adaptations that motivate preferences for high-calorie foods would have been a consequence and humans are reportedly hardwired to prefer HFSS foods.[27] A mechanism of this adaptation is that energy-rich foods elicit enjoyment in humans, especially when consumed in combination. Various hormones are released when high-energy foods, particularly fats and sugars, are consumed, which stimulate pleasure-associated areas of the brain;[28] similar effects are found with alcohol, cigarettes, and other substances. Humans are also tolerant to food delays, which is likely to be a product of changeable environmental conditions. It seems likely that our ancestors were adapted to maximise energy intake during periods of food scarcity and moderate consumption during times of food abundance. The agricultural and industrial revolutions brought great civil advancement, but food technology and food systems have changed more over the last 50 years than ever before; production and supply of energy-dense and processed foods have increased substantially. Globalisation has resulted in a reduction in price and an increase in availability of high-calorie foods.[20] The modern world for most people affords a constant state of food plenty and, given human preference for HFSS foods, consumption of food and prevalence of obesity have increased dramatically. It is for these reasons that obesity has been described as a normal response to an abnormal environment.[29] The advertising and food industries of the modern world also work to maximise our contact with food or associated psychological cues. So rather than asking why some of us are living with
overweight, the more pertinent question may be, why are some of us not living with overweight? We are conscious that overconsumption is not conducive to good health, and we moderate our behaviour accordingly, but our ability to moderate consumption and other diet-related behaviour varies. If conscious moderation of behaviour is the mechanism by which we prevent overeating, why are so many people making suboptimal and seemingly maladaptive health choices? Perhaps these health choices are not maladaptive at all. There is a long-established link between socioeconomic gradients and health risk behaviours,[30] health outcomes, and mortality.[3] While deprivation predicted food poverty and underweight in the past, in the modern developed world, low socioeconomic status strongly predicts obesity;[31] in turn, living with obesity has been found to exacerbate inequalities.[32] Within the developed world, evidence suggests that relative inequalities are equally if not more important than absolute poverty in predicting problematic health behaviours and outcomes.[33] There are environmental factors that accompany deprivation, which increase the likelihood of obesity. Energy-dense foods represent better calories per unit cost compared to fresh ingredients, which appeals to low-income families.[34] The built environment in areas of deprivation also has reduced green spaces and fewer recreation facilities, such as leisure centres, which limit opportunities for physical activity, increase risk factors for obesity, and widen health inequalities overall.[35] There are also higher densities of fast-food outlets and reduced access to healthier food stores in increasingly deprived areas, both of which are associated with poorer diets.[36] The relationship between disadvantage and obesity is complex and dynamic but, in developed countries, people of lower socioeconomic status are disproportionately affected by obesity.[37] However, obesity is prevalent across all socioeconomic strata and there is variation in overweight and obesity within
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND PUBLIC HEALTH
similarly deprived areas, which implies that disadvantage only accounts for a proportion of the observed variance.
Psychological Mechanisms and Evolutionary Strategies Psychological mechanisms or modules throughout this chapter refer to functional neurocognitive adaptations that have been successful over evolutionary time owing to their selective value in solving problems and their contribution to survival or reproductive success.[38] In combination and in addition to anatomical and physiological traits, psychological mechanisms create broader evolutionary or behavioural strategies, a clear example being an individual’s reproductive strategy.[39] When originally conceptualised, psychological mechanisms or modules were proposed to be universal among humans but that different mechanisms were invoked in different situations, leading to phenotypic variation.[40] It is proposed here that while some fundamental psychological mechanisms are innate and species-typical, others are more varied across individuals, arising from individual-specific interactions between genetic predispositions and phenotypic plasticity.[41] Neurobiological structures are produced by our genes after thousands of years of selection pressures, which act on individual genes but also the resulting cognitive mechanisms. Physically, the brain is complex, comprising billions of neurons and chemical interactions, but it functions as a specialised system that has been produced by the evolutionary process.[42] The brain acts hierarchically, where functionality emerges as a property of micro- and mesoscopic interactions through coordinated chained structures that run between anatomically clustered areas. [43] For example, the choice to eat a donut would flow through and elicit responses from various areas of the brain: affect and emotion centres, autonomic and conscious
127
centres, expectation centres, short- and longterm memory,[44] all before a hand has been outstretched. Selection has not acted upon these areas in isolation; the idea of modularity recognises functional specialisations within the brain that are domain-specific and are utilised for different cognitive processes. Whether modularity is strong or weak, any choice and resulting behaviour is the product of a hierarchical chained process that breaks down with impairment of any of the involved areas.[45] Psychological mechanisms are selected in their own right; they may be heritable in a conventional sense, but may also be the product of behavioural and, therefore, phenotypic plasticity, leading to selectable individual variation.[41] Genetic predispositions form the basis of all psychological mechanisms, but they also remain a part of our complex biological systems and are mutually associated with our physiology. For example, and in relation to obesity, adipose tissue is an active organ and part of the homeostatic system that regulates satiation and energy balance. Adipose tissue, the gastrointestinal tract, and the pancreas release various hormonal regulators to the brain, which receives the signals and acts to reprioritise behaviour to stimulate or suppress appetite. There are also physiological detectors for fats and sugars in food, which stimulate pleasure-associated areas of the brain. Elicitation of reward mechanisms also motivates behaviour, to such an extent that homeostatic processes may be overridden. This push and pull creates a trade-off within our energy-balance system, whereby psychological mechanisms, each with a clear adaptive significance, compete at cross-purposes. It is a feature of environments with constantly available energy-rich foods that allow the reward mechanisms to gain the upper hand and enable a chronic positive energy balance. Developmental conditions also affect psychological mechanisms, beginning in utero; these may be physiological, physical, emotional, or sociocultural. Childhood experience has been found to profoundly affect cognitive
128
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
development, psychological mechanisms, and therefore behaviour. Neurobiological development occurs rapidly throughout childhood but continues through adolescence and into adulthood. Cognitive systems and pathways that govern behaviour can be affected if areas of the brain suffer impairment during development. Adverse experiences in childhood, including psychological or physical abuse, change the formation of physical structures and neural pathways, which can profoundly affect healthy development and behaviour in later life. These changes can also be irreversible, meaning that the consequences of adverse experiences often persist into adulthood and act independently of socioeconomic pressures.[46] Adverse childhood experiences have been found to contribute to problematic eating behaviours, weight gain, and overweight and obesity in childhood and adulthood.[47–49] The responses to adverse experiences may have adaptive roots; stressors are linked to heightened immune- and nervous-system responses, but continued stress may produce over-activation that is likely to create a platform for poor mental health.[50] Adverse experiences are likely to be accompanied by unstable and insecure food environments, an adaptive response to which may be overconsumption when the opportunity arises. If the consequences of an adverse childhood persist into adulthood, so too would the food response, even when food becomes more consistently available. Psychological mechanisms are also profoundly shaped by environmental circumstances, both physical and, in modern contexts, socioeconomic.[51] Our phenotypes are cumulative developmental outcomes of interactions between our genes and environments. Assuming that the mechanism by which a trait is inherited does not constrain its adaptive value, it is likely that behaviour and the underlying mechanisms are modified in line with environmental variation.[52] While fields such as human behavioural ecology face challenges in testing quantifiable hypothesis in non-traditional or industrialised
countries, it seems logical that behavioural strategies are matched to environmental contexts or circumstances, despite the debatable and nuanced influence of culture. It will be argued here that health behaviour is strategic and adaptive, which would provide the principal reason why seemingly maladaptive choices, such as overeating, are so often taken. There is a wealth of evidence that the health behaviour of industrialised populations is influenced by physical and socioeconomic environments; deprived populations are more likely to have low-nutrition diets, and more likely to engage in a range of other health risk behaviours.[53–54] The trend is not solely economic; even when health behaviours are free, people from increasingly deprived groups have been found to be less likely to engage with them,[30] implying the issue is strategic. The way we perceive our environmental circumstance is also important; perception of income, for example, has been shown to be more important than actual income in determining related behaviour.[55] Living in environments that are to lesser or greater degrees mismatched from those in which we evolved has subtle and complex implications for modern humans. Rates of mental health problems, including depression, anxiety, and stress, have never been higher, especially among young people. Our behaviours act dynamically with environmental pressures; governed by psychological mechanisms and broader strategies, our behaviour is a response to the environment, whether physiological or psychological, which is then experienced and remembered. Our experience leads to learning, which subtly adjusts the psychological platform on which behaviour is based. Just as adverse developmental experiences can impair cognitive functioning, so can more transient states of low mood or poor well-being, and repetition of such states can lead to poor mental health. Similarly, other temporary states such as illness and disease can alter not only our behaviour but our perception of social and physical environments. Low mood and emotional disorders have been
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND PUBLIC HEALTH
found to affect behavioural strategies, and specifically those related to food consumption and physical activity.[56] The key determinants of psychological mechanisms and, therefore, behavioural strategies are genetic, physiological, environmental, developmental, and subjective (Figure 6.2). These determinants are not mutually exclusive but are linked as part of a dynamic system. For example, phenotypic expression is primarily the product of interplay between genetic predispositions and environmental conditions; physical and socioeconomic environments are inextricably linked but are also associated with developmental and subjective determinants; and developmental and subjective factors also feedback and modify the physiological system. Resulting mechanisms may be fixed, others may be more plastic, varying with changes in circumstances or even mood states. Behavioural plasticity allows us to make different choices and exhibit different
129
behaviours within a changing environment; behavioural plasticity was and remains a huge selective advantage for humans.[57] Our ability to modify our behaviour extends selection beyond psychological mechanisms and the resulting behaviours to behavioural strategies themselves. Such strategies are likely to be adaptive but modifiable both temporally and with changing environments, meaning that physical, political, social, or individual change would be likely to shift the parameters for optimal behaviour. Examples of this can be anecdotally observed every day: a natural disaster, political change, or a dramatic change in personal circumstance are all likely to dramatically shift the behaviour of an individual or collective. Health behaviour strategies are determined more subtly, especially given the sometimes contradictory pressures of health and fitness, but perhaps unhealthy choices are not maladaptive but optimal given the evolutionary context of the choice.
Figure 6.2 Key determinants of psychological mechanisms and behaviour strategies
130
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Adaptive Mechanisms and Optimal Strategies As outlined by life history theory, behavioural optimality is a shaped by a range of problems, including survival, growth, and development. [39] These represent multiple and complex pressures, which underpin choices or decisions that produce variable behaviours. All behaviour, including health behaviour, is the product of a cognitive appraisal system, the process of choosing an action from a range of options with the expectation of maximising the benefit and minimising the cost.[58] The stress-response system functions to mediate openness to environmental inputs and regulate behaviour in a range of fitness-relevant areas. ‘Switch’ mechanisms regulate genetic and environmental influences on phenotypic development; during development, information processed by these mechanisms feeds back and recalibrates the stress-response system, resulting in individual and adaptive patterns of behaviour.[59] Environmental moderators may be social or familial, physical, including the built or natural environment, or socioeconomic, given that there are established gradients in health behaviour across the spectrum of inequality. Temporal decision making provides an example, and in particular the extent to which behavioural strategies are underpinned by impulsive or reflective decision making. Rather than assuming all impulsive behaviour is the absence of control, there is utility in considering a dual system of behaviour,[60] where reflective and impulsive influences exist, are differentially adaptive, and are often in conflict or trade-off against each other.[61–62] A moderator of this system may be developmental factors, that have the potential to inhibit the healthy formation of neurobiological structures, which are important in overriding impulsive mechanisms for behaviour. A good example is the impact of developmental conditions on the functioning of the stress-response system, a biological mechanism involved in a wide
range of adaptive functions.[59] In a health setting, impulsiveness is sometimes considered hedonistic but reflective or rational behaviour involves constraint and is likely to be the product of conscious or higher cognitive control. Hedonic impulsivity may bring a sense of enjoyment and freedom to the human experience,[63] but in a health sense, this often involves long-term costs. Smoking cigarettes, using substances, drinking alcohol, or eating HFSS foods may be enjoyable in the short term but are likely to pose future health risks. Reflective and goal-directed behaviour is often viewed as rational, reasoned, and conscious, utilising volitional control or selfregulation to achieve a goal, while impulsive decisions, despite incorporating a range of behaviours, have been described as suboptimal, an inability to moderate behaviour. Reflective decisions usually have the goal of a larger payoff at a later time point, while forgoing the immediate reward or benefit. In terms of health behaviour, this would be represented by forgoing the immediate pleasure and reward from an action, such as eating an HFSS food, in order that the chances of yielding the longer-term and larger benefit of good health are enhanced. Impulsivity can be interpreted as the forgoing of a large but delayed reward in favour of a smaller but immediate reward.[58] In certain environmental conditions, impulsivity is likely to be adaptive; dangerous environments, for example, where there is an immediate threat or mortality rates are high, are likely to favour short-term and high-risk behaviours.[39] Research supports this theory, demonstrating that people in adverse environments are more likely to discount the future and act more impulsively, despite the potential harm to their health.[64] Impulsive and reflective decision making has also been shown to predict health behaviour in the way we would expect; lower health-risktaking behaviour is associated with increasingly reflective decision making, while riskier health behaviour is associated with increasingly impulsive decision making.[65–66]
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND PUBLIC HEALTH
Within the field of cognitive psychology, the concept of delay or temporal discounting[67] is used to explore our cognitive appraisal system, specifically relating to the temporal nature of health economics. Delay discounting is the extent to which immediate rewards are declined or postponed in order to gain larger rewards in the future; these constructs create behavioural strategies, which are variable, context specific, and are highly likely to be adaptive. Crucial in the decision are the values of the present and future reward, but also the length of time required or delay in gaining the future benefit; this can be considered as a cost subtracted from the future reward. It is well established that humans trade off between present and future rewards and, as previously stated in terms of food choice, tolerance for delays in foraging may have been selected for in variable environments. It is also well established that humans make temporally optimal decisions with financial or resource-based benefits and costs; the principle of delay discounting has been used to predict various health behaviours, including food consumption, physical activity, tobacco, and alcohol use.[68] The constructs that underlie impulsive or reflective behaviour and delay discounting are psychological mechanisms, which have been selected upon but remain modifiable with changing circumstances of environments. The relevance of these mechanisms and their determinants to the field of public health have not been fully explored but may hold the key to understanding why suboptimal health behaviours are chosen to the point of pathology and premature death at epidemic proportions. Behavioural traits, whether fixed or variable, contribute to broader behavioural strategies and our overall phenotype. Behavioural strategies can become stable in evolutionary terms,[69] but changes to our environment create pressures, which alter learning and lead to new behaviours and strategies. This implies that for a set of environment conditions, including socioeconomic, there is likely to be an optimal
131
and adaptive behavioural strategy.[70] Within these parameters are individual factors, which may have arisen from biological, developmental, or subjective determinants and may be fixed or transient. Individual states may not alter the objective optimality of a behavioural strategy matched to a set of environmental conditions, but they would alter the cognitive appraisal system and the perceived costs and benefits in temporal decision making. Like adverse developmental conditions, strategies that favour short-term payoffs and immediate rewards may have adaptive roots. In states of high anxiety or depression, it may not be optimal or even possible to think about long-term benefits; it is likely that for someone suffering from a mental health disorder, temporal perception may be very different to someone of good mental health and the cost of waiting for a reward may be perceived to be much higher. Such individuals may still be behaving optimally and adaptively, upon consideration of the determinants of their psychological mechanisms, the internal influences on behavioural appraisal, and the social, physical, and socioeconomic environment. These ideas can be further evidenced by considering behavioural strategies that have established evolutionary significance and their relationship to currencies of health. Risk taking or aversion is adaptive in various ancestral and modern contexts and has relevance to health. While there are broad differences in risk-taking behaviour between age and gender groups, strategic variation can also be observed. Life history theory predicts that decisions relating to energy allocation and behaviour are divided between competing functions, such as growth and reproduction, which are affected by ecological pressures, the differential proportion of which result in diverse health outcomes.[71] Consider the relationship between wealth and reproduction – increasing wealth predicts higher long-term fitness and reproductive success but a trade-off also exists between the number of offspring produced and the
132
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
wealth transmitted to each; this balance has been found to be predicted by socioeconomic and environmental conditions.[39] Accruing wealth in the developed world requires time and career focus, which is time spent away from having and raising children; women in particular face a decision of how much wealth to accrue before having children. Accruing wealth is desirable but there is risktaking relevance given that fertility decreases with increasing age. Risk-taking decisions can also be observed more directly in a health setting. The choice to forgo protection during sex, such as a condom, is risky given the increased chance of getting an infection or an unwanted pregnancy. However, unprotected sex is more pleasurable for men and women, and represents a reward to counter the risk; research has shown that the greater the perceived pleasure differential, the more willing men and women would be to engage in unprotected sex.[72] Similarly, eating HFSS foods, drinking alcohol, or using other substances can also be pleasurable in the short term but each behaviour incurs long-term risks to morbidity and mortality. It is also well established that health risk behaviours cluster together,[73] implying there is an underlying risk-taking strategy for any individual within a specific set of circumstances. Varying strategies of health risk, as shaped by external factors, can also be illustrated in financial terms. Low-income workers have been found to be less likely to participate in insurance schemes, even when large subsidies are offered.[74] Despite the losses of not having insurance being potentially ruinous, low-income workers are less likely to participate because they have less to spend and, crucially, less to lose. Conversely, gambling and playing the lottery is more popular among poorer groups;[75] although the chance of winning is slim, the relative reward is higher for someone who has less. One could predict that people in adverse circumstances, whether environmental, developmental, or subjective, would devalue future payoffs as the cost of waiting is perceived to be higher given the
immediate adversity or danger. In this case, it makes sense to opt for shorter-term rewards and payoffs. Chances of survival have been found to profoundly shape reproductive strategy,[39] and are likely to affect strategies relating to health or wealth in a similar way. An individual’s life history reflects trade-offs in the allocation of time or energy, and may be categorised as slow or fast depending on the environmental conditions and perceived time horizons.[76] Preferable environments are likely to induce slower or longer life histories, which are associated with higher investment, lower impulsivity, and lower levels of risk taking. Conversely, shorter life histories are associated with future discounting, impulsivity, and risk taking.[76]
APPLICATIONS OF EVOLUTIONARY CONCEPTS TO PUBLIC HEALTH PHENOMENA Investing and offsetting decision making is fundamental to impulsive and reflective decision making and may be applied to various health behaviours. Exercise can be considered as investing behaviour; while there may be short-term rewards for some people, costs are involved in the form of time and energy. The investment is made with an idea that there will be a reward of good health and potentially a long-term benefit of longer life. Buying healthy foods can also be considered as an investment; fresh ingredients tend to cost more and usually take more time to prepare but they may represent a similar longterm goal to that of exercise. In many societies, health insurance represents an investment; it may be part of a healthcare system or it may represent a better level of care. Like risk-aversion behaviours, these decisions are more likely to be taken by individuals who have the financial means but also who perceive the long-term benefits to be worth the investment. For those who do not have the means or think in temporally
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND PUBLIC HEALTH
shorter terms due to adversity in one or more areas of their lives, investments are less likely to be made. Offsetting behaviour can be thought of in similar but subtly different terms; instead of immediate investment costs being incurred, immediate rewards are rejected but still with the expectation of higher rewards in the future. Choosing not to eat HFSS foods, drink alcohol, or use substances are examples of offsetting behaviour as they are immediately pleasurable but in accumulation are likely to incur risks to longterm health. Altruistic and cooperative behaviours also have relevance to health. In ancestral environments, altruism may have evolved partly in response to foraging and food sharing; evidence has shown higher levels of altruistic behaviour to be associated with better health and well-being. Cooperation has relevance given that sharing resources equally allows for moderation and fairness but requires trust that community members will not take more than their fair share. The global food industry is a good example of non-cooperative behaviour whereby nation states or companies compete to gain as much market share as possible. Such competition has led to over-farming and fishing, which have led to environmental destruction. Huge production and advertising of processed HFSS foods within a global market have also pushed consumption to the point that the majority of the world’s populations live in countries where they are more likely to suffer mortality from the consequences of living with overweight than living with underweight.[77] These pressures operate in a similar way to the other health-relevant evolutionary behaviours, whether for individuals or larger organisations. Longer-term rewards that may be gained with altruistic and cooperative strategies are not optimal given the context, in this case the free-market food system. The optimal strategy for an individual, company, or nation state in such circumstances is to take the immediate payoff or reward. Extreme examples of adverse developmental, subjective, and environmental
133
circumstances can help to illustrate how extreme behaviours might make sense in terms of the adaptive appraisal systems that underpin them. Victims of childhood physical or sexual abuse commonly grow up to suffer poor health outcomes; not only is cognitive development impaired, potentially leading to reduced reflective decision making, but the immediate reward that may be provided by an unhealthy behaviour would almost always outweigh the cost of waiting for a larger future reward. Individuals who suffer from mental health conditions could make a similar appraisal; for a person living with severe depression, for example, potential benefits in the distant future may feel completely irrelevant. In these examples, the immediate reward could be alleviation or self-medication from the ongoing costs of extreme low mood. These unhealthy behaviours, which incur long-term risks to health and fitness, are uniquely adaptable in that they may be survival mechanisms. Consider populations living in extreme environmental conditions such as war or within violent gang culture. Individuals are aware that their chances of survival are reduced, which diminishes the value of any future reward as they may not live to benefit from it. Shortterm strategies would always be optimal in situations such as these since the rewards of tomorrow may never come. For any individual, health behaviours can be better understood if framed as adaptive strategies that can be predicted by environmental, developmental, and subjective circumstances. Early exploratory work has demonstrated that environmental conditions shape the strategies that drive health behaviour and that such strategies are predictive of various adaptive or evolutionary strategies. [70] Public health practitioners understand the determinants of poor health but there is little acknowledgement that there may be circumstances in which it makes more sense to undertake unhealthy rather than healthy behaviours. Under such circumstances, it seems pointless to try to change the behaviour itself, if
134
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
the underlying strategy is not acknowledged and the determinants of that strategy are not addressed. Such an approach may also widen the public health perspective. Often academics and practitioners operate in silos, focusing on specific health risk behaviours, interventions, or risk factors for disease, but perhaps the problem needs to be re-framed. In addition to addressing the morbidity arising from obesity, how can we triangulate research and practice to reduce the risk factors for NCDs more broadly? A key element of this challenge may be seeking to address the determinants of health risk behaviours. The public health response must be informed, paradigms may need to be challenged, and we will need a whole system and population approach to address a whole system and population problem. Given the complexity of the problem, no simple solution is likely to be successful and each of the key determinants of unhealthy behavioural strategies need careful consideration. In public health, it is understood that prevention is better than cure and this is especially true with the obesity problem. We understand how important and formative developmental experiences are, and that the impact of adversity may be irreversible in terms of cognitive structures and resulting behaviours. In a similar way, the public health response to the obesity problem must begin from pregnancy, and carry on through early years, childhood, and adolescence, given that nurturing environments with healthy parent–child bonds are crucial to long-term health. Everything is important in early life from breastfeeding and weaning to a healthy school environment and safe, enabling communities. Children who live with obesity are likely to become adults who live with obesity, and adults very rarely sustain weight loss. In addition to meeting health recommendations for early life, it is our developmental experience that can profoundly affect our shortand long-term behaviours. Creating positive childhood experiences is a complex societal challenge but it must be recognised as critical
in addressing the obesity epidemic and other major risk factors for NCDs. Developmental experiences often contribute to subjective issues that continue to underpin unhealthy behavioural strategies in adults but, equally, poor adult well-being or mental health problems can be triggered by life circumstances at any time. Recognition and appropriate treatment are hugely important not only to treat the disorder but also to re-balance the appraisal system that favours short-term rewards but has consequences for long-term health. Mental and physical health are often treated separately but are inextricably linked and are often cyclical. We cannot expect an individual to make choices that are good for their long-term health when they are struggling to cope with the here and now. Further to developmental and subjective determinants, the environments in which we live must be adapted to address key public health problems and particularly obesity. There is a clear need to create local physical and social environments that are conducive to good health; there are multiple and varied features of our home, social, and work environments that affect our health and well-being. However, there is a bigger challenge to enabling good health, and it lies in the industrial, political, and philosophical climate in which we live. We are the objects of a free-market food system in which the primary objective of any company is to make money and grow, not always but often at the expense of ill health and a burden of disease. The food system is incredibly complex but as long as companies large and small are permitted to produce unhealthy products, saturate the market, and advertise ubiquitously, we cannot hope to shift the behaviour of populations in a meaningful way. There has been a helpful paradigm shift among academics and public health experts, who now consider it unreasonable for populations to achieve and maintain a healthy weight through individual agency alone. Powerful regulations for industry must be demanded by the public and actioned by policy makers, if we are to tackle the obesity epidemic in a meaningful way.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND PUBLIC HEALTH
Perhaps more importantly, the greatest challenge of our time is to reduce socioeconomic inequalities. At a population level, individuals from relatively poorer groups make unhealthier choices, these choices are likely to be underpinned by behavioural strategies, and it is likely that these strategies are adaptive. Trying to change the outcomes of the behaviour is unlikely to be effective without consideration of the environmental conditions that determined the strategy. Reducing inequalities is a global problem and requires unprecedented change but in terms of the public health response, interventions and policies must be careful that they reduce rather than exacerbate inequalities. For example, when dealing with obesity, nationwide policies that address issues such as pricing are likely to reduce inequalities, while person-focused interventions that encourage behaviour change are likely to widen them. [78] Health disparities are the most serious outcome of socioeconomic inequalities, the reduction of which will certainly require an understanding of the implications and applications of evolutionary principles.[79] These broad discussion points do not overlook the huge amount of academic and public health work that contributes substantially and meaningfully to addressing obesity and other health problems. The object here is to suggest that an evolutionary perspective of health risk behaviours may be helpful, given that they are likely to be optimal and adaptive. Recognition of the strategies that drive unhealthy choices, and the key determinants of them, will not only encourage a focus on the root causes of health problems,[2] but might also reduce the stigmatisation of health risk behaviours and the individuals that carry their burden. An engrained mantra of public health is to ‘make the healthy choice the easy choice’ but in evolutionary terms the easy choice is the adaptive choice; perhaps we have known for some time that health risk behaviours are a normal response to an abnormal world.
135
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND PUBLIC HEALTH: CASE STUDY – VACCINATIONS For over 200 years,[80 ] vaccinations have prevented the consequences of disease for millions of people worldwide. Vaccines are a public health success story and are estimated to have saved at least 10 million lives between 2010 and 2015 alone.[81] Vaccinations stimulate an immune response from the body to develop resistance to a pathogen, which can lead to the prevention or complete eradication of an infectious disease.[82] Vaccines have successfully led to the worldwide eradication of smallpox and widespread eradication of measles, polio, and tetanus. Other standard vaccine-preventable diseases include diphtheria, whooping cough, mumps, rubella, influenza, and hepatitis, but there are many other infectious diseases that have available vaccines. Vaccines are a basic human right and have greatly reduced the burden of disease[83] but despite this success, a determined antivaccine lobby, representing an increasingly sceptical world view of science, is on the rise.[84] The antivaccine movement has gained traction online and is suggested to be well organised and widely dispersed.[85] Antivaccine messages question vaccine safety and effectiveness and have been reported to rely on strong emotional messages to enhance their appeal. [86] For this reason, a minority of antivaccine advocates have been suggested to have a highly persuasive voice and the potential to persuade millions of parents against vaccinations on scientific, ethical, and political grounds. Medical and academic experts have tried to counter such messages to advocate the safety and importance of vaccines but have often suffered ‘harassment campaigns’, typically via social media by vehement antivaccine activists.[87] While the most effective strategy at combatting this problem is unclear,[88] the antivaccine movement represents a difficult and complex challenge for public health policy makers and practitioners.
136
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
While the academic consensus is that the antivaccine movement is based on misconceptions,[89] there have been controversial studies reporting links between vaccinations and disability and disease, such as autism and asthma, despite strong evidence to the contrary.[90–92 ] Emotive online pressure and spurious evidence have succeeded to some degree. In the UK, the link with the measles, mumps, and rubella (MMR) vaccine and autism appears to have gained momentum and, following year-on-year increases from 2007, decreases in coverage were recorded in 2016/17 for the third year in a row.[93] In the United States, while the overall rate of vaccination coverage has remained high, the rate of children not receiving any vaccinations has been increasing since 2011.[94] The consequences of the growing antivaccination movement have already been observed; analysis of a measles outbreak in the United States in 2015 indicated that the likely cause was lack of or incomplete vaccinations.[95] Multiple developed and developing countries have experienced outbreaks of measles in recent years,[96–97] which have been primarily attributed to gaps in vaccination coverage.[97–98] Research suggests that framing public health messages within the context of the moral foundations that underpin judgements can successfully influence attitudes.[99] Moral foundations theory proposes that internal decision making predicts social group attitudes.[100] While there is complexity surrounding decision-making processes, consideration of selective pressures and evolutionary principles that underpin motivations may provide an enhanced understanding of public health decision making. The incentive to vaccinate is clear; it leads to individual and group immunity and is the best defence against potentially epidemic diseases. If sufficiently high proportions of people vaccinate, herd immunity[101] can be achieved whereby a whole population becomes resistant to a parasite or disease. The coverage threshold varies by disease
but is less than 100%; estimates suggest that for a disease such as measles the herd immunity threshold is 93–95%; for diseases such as smallpox or polio the threshold is 80–86%.[102] Aside from the questionable links between vaccines and disability or disease, there are various risks involved with vaccinating, typically low-level side effects. Vaccines can be painful and create soreness and swelling, and in some cases they can also induce allergic reactions and subjects may become a little unwell. Individual and population immunity is a clear benefit of vaccinations, while the risks and side effects can be interpreted as costs. An application of the principles of evolutionary psychology can add insight into the decision-making process of whether or not to vaccinate. Altruism is an act that benefits others (non-kin) at expense to the actor,[103] and cooperation, like altruism, provides a benefit to another individual or group but does not require reciprocation since it also yields direct or indirect fitness benefits to the actor.[104] The process of vaccinating does not neatly fit with either principal definition; it is altruistic in that a cost is incurred and the process benefits others, but it is also cooperative in that it yields direct fitness benefits to the actor. Vaccinating involves elements of altruism and cooperation; the commonality between the two is reliance on others to maximise individual and group benefits. However, within populations counter strategies may occur arising from selfish or cheating behaviours that yield benefits to the individual with no personal cost but with an expense to others. Cheating strategies may often lead to higher relative fitness than altruistic strategies[105], but if caught, cheats are likely to be punished. Emotional mechanisms have evolved, including moralistic aggression, trust, suspicion, and dishonesty, a function of which is to regulate decisions and behaviours relating to altruism and cheating.[106] Cheating, free riding, or bandwagonning have been found to motivate vaccination decisions[107], and across
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND PUBLIC HEALTH
a large population, cheating is incentivised given that benefits from herd immunity can be realised without paying the individual costs, assuming that the proportion of free riders does not exceed the threshold. One would expect a successful cheating strategy to not only be hidden but to outwardly support vaccinations, in order that others vaccinate and herd immunity is maintained. Yet there appears to be a maladaptive cultural phenomenon whereby, far from being hidden, not vaccinating or cheating in an evolutionary sense is publicly advocated and promoted. It may be that cultural misinformation has shifted the perceived benefits and costs to such an extent that the adaptive strategies of vaccinating or free riding have been abandoned in favour of a wholly maladaptive strategy. This is likely to be an example of humans being adaptively mismatched from a technologically developed world; our psychological mechanisms that strategize our behaviour may be fundamentally misinformed leading to suboptimal decision making. Vaccinations are a relatively recent phenomenon and were not a feature of our formative and selective environments, but our ability to make adaptive choices in novel situations is a key feature of our behavioural plasticity. It seems likely that a successful public health response will need to change the parameters of the game in order that modern humans can once again make sense of their world. Perhaps a consequence of living in urban populations rather than smaller communities is that people have become less trusting; the choice not to vaccinate has been found to be influenced by confidence, not only in the product but also the health professional and the policy maker.[108–109] Evidence suggests public confidence in vaccinating is decreasing,[110] and that social norms and interactions with healthcare providers are highly influential on decisions to vaccinate. [111] A response by public health policy makers and practitioners may be to foster trust by increasing the availability and transparency
137
of information relating to the product and the process. Research suggests that 37% of US adults when questioned were not aware of the concept of herd immunity and over 75% thought that vaccination coverage was higher than it was.[112] While there is some evidence that educational interventions can improve willingness to vaccinate,[112] most traditional education tools have been found to have little impact on vaccine hesitancy,[113] including those that specifically dispel the myths linking vaccines with disability.[114] Since antivaccine lobby groups assume a disproportionate space within the discussion arena,[115] the key response may be to engage with mass media and initiate widespread vaccination-promotion campaigns; there is some evidence that such campaigns can reduce vaccine hesitancy and increase coverage rates.[116] Perhaps fighting the fire of powerful antivaccine lobbyists requires the clear and effective communication of scientific evidence via the medium of social and digital mass media. One further much discussed public health response could be to make vaccinations compulsory; proposals are currently in place in various countries in the developing world in light of recent outbreaks.[117] Aside from the potential implications for civil liberties and the difficulty in implementation, it has also been suggested that mandating vaccines would not address the causal problems of vaccine hesitancy[118] and may increase the inherent mistrust of the political health system.[115] Accounting for the available evidence, there have been sensible and well-considered recommendations of best practice to improve vaccination coverage in an age of inherent mistrust and hesitancy. Calls to utilise immunisation frameworks, apply multi-component interventions, link interventions to empirical evidence, and take account of the personand environment-specific factors[36] are valid and helpful. However, mindfulness of the maladaptive strategies that have propagated in recent years and the evolutionary
138
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
decision-making mechanisms that appear to be misfiring may be crucial in reminding parents that, in this case, the adaptive choice is the healthy choice. A successful campaign may enable free riding to become a successful strategy once again, as long as cheats are low in number and quiet of voice, in order that they alone incur the risks.
REFERENCES 1 Acheson, D. (1988). Public Health in England: The Report of the Committee of Inquiry into the Future Development of the Public Health Function. Cm. 289. London: HMSO. 2 Gluckman, P.D., Low, F.M., Buklijas, T., Hanson, M.A. and Beedle, A.S. (2011). How evolutionary principles improve the understanding of human health and disease. Evolutionary Applications. 4. 2. 249–263. 3 Stringhini, S., Carmeli, C., Jokela, M., Avendaño, M., Muennig, P., Guida, F. et al. (2017). Socioeconomic status and the 25 × 25 risk factors as determinants of premature mortality: a multicohort study and metaanalysis of 1.7 million men and women. The Lancet. 389. 10075. 1229–1237. 4 Nettle, D. and Pollet, T.V. (2008). Natural selection on male wealth in humans. The American Naturalist. 172. 5. 658–666. doi:10.1086/591690. 5 Gillespie, D.O.S., Russell, A.F. and Lummaa, V. (2008). When fecundity does not equal fitness: evidence of an offspring quantity versus quality trade-off in pre-industrial humans. Proceedings of the Royal Society. 275. 713–722. 6 Giosan, C., Mureșan, V., Wyka, K., Mogoașe, C., Cobeanu, O. and Szentagotai, A. (2018). The Evolutionary Fitness Scale: A measure of the independent criterion of fitness. The Journal of the Evolutionary Studies Consortium. 7. 1. 181–208. 7 Jones, J.H. (2009). The force of selection on the human life cycle. Evolution and Human Behavior. 30. 305–314. 8 Jasienska, G. (2013). The Fragile Wisdom: An Evolutionary View on Women’s Biology and Health. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
9 Litman, G.W. and Cooper, M.D. (2007). Why study the evolution of immunity? Nature Immunology. 8. 547–548. 10 Schmid-Hempel, P. (2011). Evolutionary Parasitology: the Integrated Study of Infections, Immunology, Ecology, and Genetics. Oxford Scholarship Online. doi:10.1093/acprof: oso/9780199229482.001.0001. 11 Greaves, M. (2010). Cancer stem cells: back to Darwin? Seminars in Cancer Biology. 20. 2. 65–70. 12 World Health Organization. (2018). Noncommunicable diseases – key facts. [Date accessed: 4th March 2019] www.who. int/news-room/fact-sheets/detail/ noncommunicable-diseases. 13 World Health Organization. (2019). Global Health Observatory (GHO) data – risk factors. [Date accessed: 10th March 2019] www. who.int/gho/ncd/risk_factors/en/. 14 World Health Organization. (2018). Taking action on childhood obesity. [Date accessed: 10th March 2019] https://www.who.int/endchildhood-obesity/publications/takingaction-childhood-obesity-report/en/. 15 Wang, Y.C., McPherson, K., Marsh, T., Gortmaker, S.L. and Brown, M. (2011). Health and economic burden of the projected obesity trends in the USA and the UK. Lancet. 378. 815–825. 16 Butland, B. (2007). Tackling obesities: future choices. Project report. London: Government Office for Science. 17 Schrempft, S., van Jaarsveld, C.H.M., Fisher, A., Herle, M., Smith, A.D., Fildes, A. et al. (2018). Variation in the heritability of child body mass index by obesogenic home environment. JAMA Pediatrics. 172. 12. 1153–1160. doi:10.1001/jamapediatrics.2018.1508. 18 Institute of Medicine (US) Committee on Assessing Interactions Among Social, Behavioral, and Genetic Factors in Health; Hernandez, L.M. and Blazer, D.G., editors. (2006). Genes, Behavior, and the Social Environment: Moving Beyond the Nature/ Nurture Debate. Washington (DC): National Academies Press (US) 3. Genetics and Health. 19 Llewellyn, C. and Wardle, J. (2013). Genetic Influences on Child Eating Behaviour. In Encyclopedia on Early Childhood Development, edited by R.E. Tremblay, M. Boivin, R.D. Peters and M.S. Faith (eds). [Date accessed: July 15th
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND PUBLIC HEALTH
2019] https://eur01.safelinks.protection.outlook.com/?url=http%3A%2F%2Fwww. child-encyclopedia.com%2Fchildnutrition%2Faccording-experts%2Fgeneticinfluences-child-eating-behaviour&data =02%7C01%7C%7Cfb2a1bd6fa7f449a946 008d70933e623%7C1faf88fea9984c5b93c 9210a11d9a5c2%7C0%7C1%7C63698799 0829674502&sdata=%2BFkWye4%2F G61UawslrZ%2FotY6r6naJkGGIwP8t6M9lUs U%3D&reserved=0. 20 Swinburn, B.A., Sacks, G., Hall, K.D., McPherson, K., Finegood, D.T., Moodie, M.L. et al. (2011). The global obesity pandemic: shaped by global drivers and local environments. The Lancet. 378. 9793. 804–814. 21 United Nations. (2018). News: 68% of the world population projected to live in urban areas by 2050. [Date accessed: 12th March 2019] www.un.org/development/desa/en/ news/population/2018-revision-of-worldurbanization-prospects.html. 22 Foster, C., Hillsdon, M., Cavil, N., Allender, S. and Cowburn, G. (2005). Understanding participation in sport: a systematic review. London: Sport England. 23 Goode, W.J. (1964). The Family. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall Inc. 24 Krebs, C.J. (1978). Ecology. The experimental analysis of distribution and abundance. New York, United States: Joanna Cotler Books. ISBN 10: 0060437715.(Second edition). 25 Maynard-Smith, J. (1978). Optimization theory in evolution. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics. 9. 31–56. 26 Winterhalder, B. (1986). The analysis of hunter-gatherer diet: stalking an optimal foraging model. In Food Preferences and Aversions, M. Harris and E.A. Ross (eds). Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press. 311–339. 27 Power, M.L. and Schulkin, J. (2009). The evolution of obesity. Baltimore, MD: John Hopkins University Press. 28 Dallman, M.F., Pecararo, N. and la Fleur, S.E. (2005). Chronic stress and comfort foods: self-medication and abdominal obesity. Brain, Behaviour and Immunity. 19. 275–280. 29 Lancet editorial. (2011). Urgently needed: a framework convention for obesity control. 378. 741.
139
30 Nettle, D. (2010). Why are there social gradients in preventative health behaviour? A perspective from behavioural ecology. PLoS One. 5. 10. 1–6. 31 Ball, K. and Crawford, D. (2005). Socioeconomic status and weight change in adults: a review. Social Science and Medicine. 60. 1987–2010. 32 Monteiro, C.A., Conde, W.L., Lu, B. and Popkin, B.M. (2004). Obesity and inequities in health in the developing world. International Journal of Obesity. 28. 1181–1186. 33 van Zon, S.K.R., Bültmann, U., Mendes de Leon, C.F. and Reijneveld, S.A. (2015). Absolute and relative socioeconomic health inequalities across age groups. PLoS One. 10. 12. e0145947. 34 Edin, K., Boyd, M., Mabli, J., Ohls, J., Worthington, J., Greene, S. et al. (2013). SNAP Food Security In-Depth Interview Study: Final Report. Washington, DC: US Department of Agriculture, Food and Nutrition Service. 35 Gordon-Larsen, P., Nelson, M.C., Page, P. and Popkin, B.M. (2006). Inequality in the built environment underlies key health disparities in physical activity and obesity. Pediatrics. 117. 2. 417–424. 36 Cummins, S. and Macintyre, S. (2006). Food environments and obesity: neighbourhood or nation? International Journal of Epidemiology. 35. 100–104. 37 Wang, Y. and Beydoun, M.A. (2007). The obesity epidemic in the United States – gender, age, socioeconomic, racial/ethnic, and geographic characteristics: a systematic review and meta-regression analysis. Epidemiologic Reviews. 29. 6–28. 38 Starratt, V.G. (2017). Evolved psychological mechanisms. In Encyclopedia of Personality and Individual Differences, V. Zeigler-Hill and T.K. Shackelford (eds). Cham, Switzerland: Springer International Publishing. doi:10.1007/ 978-3-319-28099-8_1633-1. 39 Chisholm, J.S. (1993). Death, hope, and sex: life-history theory and the development of reproductive strategies. Current Anthropology. 34. 1–24. 40 Tooby, J. and Cosmides, L. (1990). On the universality of human nature and the uniqueness of the individual: the role of genetics and adaptation. Journal of Personality. 58. 17–67.
140
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
41 Wilson, D.S. (1994). Adaptive genetic variation and human evolutionary psychology. Ethology and Sociobiology. 15. 219–235. 42 Tooby, J. and Cosmides, L. (1995). Mapping the evolved functional organization of mind and brain. In The Cognitive Neurosciences, M.S. Gazzaniga (ed.). 3995. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 1185–1197. 43 Mastrandea, R., Gabrielli, A., Piras, F., Spalletta, G., Caldarelli, G. and Gili, T. (2017). Organization and hierarchy of the human functional brain network lead to a chain-like core. Scientific Reports. 7. 4888. 1–13. doi:10.1038/s41598-017-04716-3. 44 Nolte, J. (2002). The Human Brain: An introduction to its functional anatomy. Missouri, United States: Mosby. 45 Caramazza, A. and Coltheart, M. (2006). Cognitive neuropsychology twenty years on. Cognitive Neuropsychology. 23. 1. 3–12. 46 Russell, S.J., Hughes, K. and Bellis, M.A. (2016). Impact of childhood experience and adult well-being on eating preferences and behaviours. BMJ Open. 6. 1. e007770. doi:10.1136/bmjopen-2015-007770. 47 Johnson, J.G., Cohen, P., Kasen, S. and Brook, J.S. (2002). Childhood adversities associated with risk for eating disorders or weight problems during adolescence or early adulthood. American Journal of Psychiatry. 159. 394–400. 48 Ebbeling, C.D., Pawlak, D.B. and Ludwig, D.S. (2002). Childhood obesity: public health crisis, common sense cure. Lancet. 360. 473–482. 49 Koch, F.S., Sepa, A. and Ludvigsson, J. (2008). Psychological stress and obesity. Journal of Pediatrics. 153. 6. 50 Gustafson, T.B. and Sarwer, D.B. (2004). Childhood sexual abuse and obesity. Obesity Reviews. 5. 129–135. 51 Hassel, S., McKinnon, M.C., Cusi, A.M. and Macqueen, G.M. (2011). An overview of psychological and neurobiological mechanisms by which early negative experiences increase risk of mood disorders. Journal of the Canadian Academy of Child and Adolescent Psychiatry. 20. 4. 277–288. 52 Borgerhoff-Mulder, M. and Schacht, R. (2012). Human behavioural ecology. In eLS. Chichester: John Wiley & Sons, Ltd.
doi:10.1002/9780470015902.a0003671. pub2. 53 Pechey, R., Jebb, S.A., Kelly, M.P., AlmironRoig, E., Conde, S., Nakamura, R. et al. (2013). Socioeconomic differences in purchases of more vs. less healthy foods and beverages: analysis of over 25,000 British households in 2010. Social Science and Medicine. 92. 22–26. 54 Kipping, R.R., Smith, M., Heron, J., Hickman, M. and Campbell, R. (2015). Multiple risk behaviour in adolescence and socioeconomic status: findings from a UK birth cohort. European Journal of Public Health. 25. 1. 44–49. 55 Engelhardt, C. and Wagener, A. (2014). Biased Perceptions of Income Inequality and Redistribution. CESifo Working Paper Series No. 4838. Munich: CESifo Group. 56 Marsheb, R.M. and Grilo, C.M. (2006). Emotional overeating and its associations with eating disorder psychopathology among overweight patients with binge eating disorder. International Journal of Eating Disorders. 39. 141–146. 57 Bateson, P. and Gluckman, P. (2011). Plasticity, Robustness, Development and Evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 58 Kim, S. and Lee, D. (2011). Prefrontal cortex and impulsive decision making. Biological Psychiatry. 69. 12. 1140–1146. 59 Del Giudice, M., Ellis, B. and Shirtcliff, E.A. (2011). The adaptive calibration model of stress responsivity. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews. 35. 1562–1592. 60 Wiers, R.W., Bartholow, B.D., van den Wildenberg, E., Thush, C., Engels, R.C.M.E., Sher, K.J. et al. (2007). Automatic and controlled processes and the development of addictive behaviors in adolescents: a review and a model. Pharmacology, Biochemistry and Behavior. 86. 263–283. 61 Carver, C.S. (2005). Impulse and constraint: perspectives from personality psychology, convergence with theory in other areas, and potential for integration. Personality and Social Psychology Review. 9. 312–333. 62 Hofmann, W., Friese, M. and Wiers, R. (2008). Impulsive versus reflective influences on health behavior: a theoretical framework and empirical review. Health Psychology Review. 2. 2. 111–137.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND PUBLIC HEALTH
63 Hansen, E.B. and Breivik, G. (2001). Sensation seeking as a predictor of positive and negative risk behaviour among adolescents. Personality and Individual Differences. 30. 627–640. 64 Frankenhuis, W.E., Panchanathan, K. and Nettle, D. (2016). Cognition in harsh and unpredictable environments. Current Opinion in Psychology. 7. 76–80. 65 Bogg, T. and Roberts, B. W. (2004). Conscientiousness and health-related behaviors: A meta-analysis of the leading behavioral contributors to mortality. Psychological Bulletin. 130. 887–919. 66 Grano, N., Virtanen, M., Vaherta, J., Elovainio, M. and Kivimäki, M. (2004). Impulsivity as a predictor of smoking and alcohol consumption. Personality and Individual Differences. 37. 1693–1700. 67 Read, D., Frederick, S., Orsel, B. and Rahman, J. (2005). Four score and seven years from now: the date/delay effect in temporal discounting. Management Science. 51. 1326–1335. 68 Daugherty, J.R. and Brase, G.L. (2009). Taking time to be healthy: predicting health behaviors with delay discounting and time perspective. Personality and Individual Differences. 48. 202–207. 69 Maynard-Smith, J. (1972). On Evolution. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. 70 Russell, S.J. (2017). Applying evolutionary principles to the obesity problem and other issues in public health. [Date accessed: 18th March 2019] https://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails. do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.733959. doi: 10.24377/ LJMU.t.00007660. 71 Wells, J.C.K., Nesse, R.M., Sear, R., Johnstone, R.A. and Stearns, S.C. (2017). Evolutionary public health: introducing the concept. Evolutionary Public Health. 390. 10093. 500–509. 72 Randolph, M.E., Pinkerton, S.D., Bogart, L.M., Cecil, H. and Abramson, P.R. (2007). Sexual pleasure and condom use. Archives of Sexual Behavior. 36. 6. 844–848. 73 Spring, B., Moller, A.C. and Coons, M.J. (2012). Multiple health behaviours: overview and implications. Journal of Public Health. 34. i3–10.10.1093/pubmed/fdr111. 74 Chernew, M., Frick, K. and McLaughlin, G. (1997). The demand for health insurance
141
coverage by low-income workers: can reduced premiums achieve full coverage? HSR: Health Services Research. 32. 4. 453–470. 75 Beckert, J. and Lutter, M. (2012). Why the poor play the lottery: sociological approaches to explaining class-based lottery play. Sociology. 47. 6. 1152–1170. 76 Kruger, D.J. and Kruger, J.S. (2016). Psychometric assessment of human life history predicts health related behaviors. Psychological Topics. 25. 19–28. 77 World Health Organization. (2018). Obesity and overweight: key facts. [Accessed: 20th March 2019] www.who.int/news-room/factsheets/detail/obesity-and-overweight. 78 McGill, R., Anwar, E., Orton, L., Bromley, H., Lloyd-Williams, F., O’Flaherty, M. et al. (2015). Are interventions to promote healthy eating equally effective for all? Systematic review of socioeconomic inequalities in impact. BMC Public Health. 15. 457. doi:10.1186/s12889-015-1781-7. 79 Omenn, G.S. (2010). Evolution and public health. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 107. 1. 1702–1709.
CASE STUDY REFERENCES 80 Stern, A. and Markel, H. (2005). The history of vaccines and immunization: familiar patterns, new challenges. Health Affairs. 24. 3: The Vaccine Enterprise. 81 World Health Organization. (2017). The power of vaccines: still not fully utilized. World Health Organization. [Date accessed: 6th January 2019] https ://www.who.int/ publications/10-year-review/vaccines/en/. 82 Fenner, F., Henderson, D.A., Arita, I., Jezek, Z. and Ladnyi, I.D. (1988). Smallpox and its eradication, pp. 332–335. Geneva, Switzerland: World Health Organization. 83 Andre, F.E., Booy, R., Bock, H.L., Clemens, J., Datta, S.K., John, T.J. et al. (2008). Vaccination greatly reduces disease, disability, death and inequity worldwide. Bulletin of the World Health Organization. 86. 2. 81–160. 84 Kata, A. (2012). Anti-vaccine activists web 2.0 and the postmodern paradigm: an overview of tactics and tropes used online by
142
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
the anti-vaccination movement. Vaccine. 30. 25. 3778–3789. 85 Bandari, R., Zhou, Z., Qian, H., Tangherlini, T.R. and Roychowdhury, V.P. (2017). A resistant strain: revealing the online grassroots rise of the antivaccination movement. Computer. 50. 11. 60–67. 86 Wolfe, R.M., Sharp, L.K. and Lipsky, M.S. (2002). Content and design attributes of antivaccination web sites. JAMA. 287. 24. 3245–3248. 87 Wong, J.C. (2019). Anti-vaxx ‘mobs’: doctors face harassment campaigns on Facebook. [Date accessed: 6th January 2019] www.theguardian.com/technology/2019/feb/27/ facebook-anti-vaxx-harassment-campaignsdoctors-fight-back. 88 Leask, J. (2015). Should we do battle with anti-vaccination activists? Public Health Research and Practice. 30. 25. 2: e2521515. 89 Jacobson, R.M., Targonski, P.V. and Poland, G.A. (2007). A taxonomy of reasoning flaws in the anti-vaccine movement. Vaccine. 25. 16. 3146–3152. 90 Gerber, J.S. and Offit, P.A. (2009). Vaccines and autism: a tale of shifting hypotheses. Clinical Infectious Diseases. 48. 4. 456–461. 91 Destefano, F., Gu, D., Kramarz, P., Truman, B.I., Iademarco, M.F., Mullooly, J.P. et al. (2002). Childhood vaccinations and risk of asthma. The Pediatric Infectious Disease Journal. 21. 6. 498–504. 92 Hviid, A., Hansen, J.V., Frisch, M. and Melbye, M. (2019). Measles, mumps, rubella vaccination and autism – a nationwide cohort study. Annals of Internal Medicine. 170. 8. 513–520. doi:10.7326/M18-2101. 93 National Health Service. (2017). Childhood Vaccination Coverage Statistics, England, 2016–17. NHS Digital. [Date accessed: 8th January 2019] https://digital.nhs.uk/dataand-information/publications/statistical/nhsimmunisation-statistics/childhood-vaccinationcoverage-statistics-england-2016-17. 94 Centers for Disease Control and Prevention. (2018). Vaccination Coverage Among Children Aged 19–35 Months – United States, 2017. [Date accessed: 8th January 2019] www.cdc.gov/mmwr/volumes/67/wr/ mm6740a4.htm. 95 Majumder, M.S., Cohn E.L., Mekaru, S.R., Huston, J.E. and Brownstein, J.S. (2015).
Substandard vaccination compliance and the 2015 measles outbreak. JAMA Pediatrics. 169. 5. 494–495. 96 World Health Organization. (2018). Emergencies preparedness, response: measles – Japan. [Date accessed: 20th January 2019] www.who.int/csr/don/20-june-2018measles-japan/en/. 97 Dyer, O. (2019). Philippines measles outbreak is deadliest yet as vaccine scepticism spurs disease comeback. BMJ. 364. l739. doi:https://doi.org/10.1136/bmj.l739. 98 World Health Organization. (2018b). Measles cases spike globally due to gaps in vaccination coverage. [Date accessed: 20th January 2019] www.who.int/news-room/ detail/29-11-2018-measles-cases-spikeglobally-due-to-gaps-in-vaccination-coverage. 99 Amin, A.B., Bednarczyk, R.A., Ray, C.E., Melchiori, K.J., Graham, J., Huntsinger, J.R. et al. (2017). Association of moral values with vaccine hesitancy. Nature Human Behaviour. 1. 873–880. 100 Graham, J., Nosek, B.A., Haidt, J., Iyer, R., Koleva, S. and Ditto, P.H. (2011). Mapping the moral domain. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 101. 366–385. 101 Anderson, R.M. and May, R.M. (1991). Infectious Diseases of Humans: Dynamics and Control. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 102 Centers for Disease Control and Prevention. (2015). Smallpox: Disease, Prevention, and Intervention. Retrieved 13 March 2015. [Date accessed: 20th January 2019] https:// stacks.cdc.gov/view/cdc/27929. 103 O’Gorman, R., Wilson, D.S. and Miller, R.R. (2005). Altruistic punishing and helping differ in sensitivity to relatedness, friendship and future interactions. Evolution and Human Behavior. 26. 375–387. 104 West, S.A., Griffin, A.S. and Gardner, A. (2007). Evolutionary explanations for cooperation: review. Current Biology. 17. 16. 661–672. 105 Wade, M.J. and Breden, F. (1980). The evolution of cheating and selfish behavior. Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology. 7. 3. 167–172. 106 Trivers, R.L. (1971). The evolution of reciprocal altruism. The Quarterly Review of Biology. 46. 1. 35–57.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND PUBLIC HEALTH
107 Hershey, J.C., Asch, D.A., Thumasathit, T., Meszaros, J. and Waters, V.V. (1994). The roles of altruism, free riding, and bandwagoning in vaccination decisions. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes. 59. 2. 177–187. 108 MacDonald, N.E. (2014). Vaccine hesitancy: definition, scope and determinants. Vaccine. 33. 34. 4161–4164. 109 Larson, H.J., Schulz, W.S., Tucker, J.D. and Smith, D.M.D. (2015). Measuring vaccine confidence: introducing a global vaccine confidence index. Version 1 PLoS Currents. 7: ecurrents.outbreaks.ce0f6177bc97332 602a8e3fe7d7f7cc4. 110 Dubé, E., Vivion, M. and MacDonald, N.E. (2014). Vaccine hesitancy, vaccine refusal and the anti-vaccine movement: influence, impact and implications. Expert Review of Vaccines. 14. 1. 99–117. 111 Leask, J., Willaby, H.W. and Kaufman, J. (2014). The big picture in addressing vaccine hesitancy. Human Vaccines and Immunotherapeutics. 10. 9. 1–3. 112 Logan, J., Nederhoff, D., Koch, B., Griffith, B., Wolfson, J., Awanal, F.A. et al. (2018). ‘What have you HEARD about the HERD?’ Does education about local influenza vaccination coverage and herd immunity affect willingness to vaccinate? Vaccine. 36. 4118–4125. 113 Odone, A., Ferrari, A., Spagnoli, F., Visciarelli, S., Shefer, A., Pasquarella, C. et al.
143
(2014). Effectiveness of interventions that apply new media to improve vaccine uptake and vaccine coverage: a systematic review. Human Vaccines and Immunotherapeutics. 11. 1. 72–82. https://doi.org/10.4161/ hv.34313. 114 Nyhan, B., Reifler, J., Richey, S. and Freed, G.L. (2014). Effective messages in vaccine promotion: a randomized trial. Pediatrics. 133. 4. 1–8. 115 Dube, E., Gagnon, D. and MacDonald, N.E. (2015). Strategies intended to address vaccine hesitancy: review of published reviews. Vaccine. 33. 4191–4203. 116 Cairns, G., MacDonald, L., Angus, K., Walker, L., Cairns-Haylor, T. and Bowdler, T. (2012). Systematic literature review of the evidence for effective national immunisation schedule promotional communications. Stockholm: European Centre for Disease Prevention and Control. [Date accessed 20th January 2019] https://www.ecdc.europa.eu/sites/default/files/ media/en/publications/Publications/Literaturereview-national-immunisation-schedulepromotional-communications.pdf. 117 Arie, S. (2017). Compulsory vaccination and growing measles threat. British Medical Journal. 358. j3429. doi:10.1136/bmj.j3429. 118 Wigham, S., Ternent, L., Bryant, A., Robalino, S., Sniehotta, F.F. and Adams, J. (2014). Parental financial incentives for increasing preschool vaccination uptake: systematic review. Pediatrics. 134. 4. e1117.
7 Animal Ethics and Evolutionary Psychology Diana Santos Fleischman
INTRODUCTION Evolutionary psychology examines the human mind through the lens of evolution to understand the functions of our psychological adaptations such as motivations, emotions, and cognitions. Humans have many interactions with nonhuman animals (hereafter just ‘animals’, although the term ‘nonhuman animals’ makes an important philosophical point), most of which are fairly recent (e.g., cats as companion animals), but some go much further back in our history (e.g., hunting animals for food). We use animal bodies for fur, meat, lactation, eggs, labor, and scientific study; the scale of animal use is enormous, trillions of animals are killed for food each year (Wiblin and Bollard, 2017). In the last few hundred years, the average level of human suffering has decreased dramatically, but the total amount of animal suffering due to human actions has skyrocketed. All around us we can see examples of individuals being
exceedingly altruistic to favored animals, but also industrialized cruelty towards less favored animals at an incomprehensible scale. While we should have no expectation that human morality will be rational or consistent, this chapter grapples with the fact that our treatment of animals deviates very far from any coherent, rational morality. In terms of overall ‘suffering footprint’, human maltreatment of animals may be the biggest ethical issue in the world, and evolutionary psychology can give us deep insights into both the problem and possible solutions.
ANIMAL ETHICS Animal ethics has different meanings among groups of philosophers, scientists, and the public. Examining how our evolutionary psychology obscures consistent ethics requires some consideration of what would
ANIMAL ETHICS AND EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
serve as an ethical baseline for comparison (Fleischman, 2018). Views about human obligations to animals, or lack thereof, have proliferated in philosophy. Some philosophers argue it’s wrong to own animals or use them in any way (Francione, 2015), whereas others argue that we have no obligation to animals because they cannot make social contracts and are thus not part of our moral community (Machan, 2004). Of all the mainstream philosophical approaches to animal ethics, utilitarianism and consequentialism have been most positively disposed to morally consider animals than other frameworks (Beauchamp and Frey, 2011). Utilitarianism defines what is good as what maximizes happiness or pleasure and minimizes suffering, across all sentient beings (those capable of experiencing happiness or suffering) (Greene, 2013). This chapter rests on the basic evolutionary insight that vertebrate animals like mammals and fish evolved the capacity to feel pain and pleasure, and thus the capacity to suffer. Further, it rests on a normative moral stance that sentience should be the basis for moral consideration, that suffering is bad, and that reducing suffering is good. I do not rely on any concept of ‘animal rights’, nor do I assume that using animals as a means to human ends is always immoral (Regan, 2004), although I believe the moral foundations of these ideas are also rooted in evolutionary psychology. For my normative moral claim that suffering is bad and alleviating suffering is good, most philosophers appeal to the reader’s personal experience with suffering, or take the idea that suffering is bad as obvious (‘a priori’ or ‘axiomatic’) (but see also Kahane, 2009). Evolutionary theory has influenced many to adopt an ethical stance that we should ascribe moral standing and consideration on the basis of the ability to suffer (Singer, 2011), otherwise known as ‘sentientism’ (Ryder, 1991; ‘Sentientism’, 2019). This chapter analyzes where our evolutionary psychology is consistent with and deviates from sentientism as a moral baseline.
145
EVIDENCE FOR ANIMAL SENTIENCE How can we establish which animals are sentient, and therefore deserving of moral consideration? Sentience is the ability to experience pain and pleasure subjectively. First let’s distinguish between the ability to react to tissue damage, and the ability to suffer. Nociception, or the experience of pain, is the simple and ancient capacity of most animals to respond to injuries that cause tissue damage. Nociception is specific to animals with a nervous system, but even simpler organisms may have a similar capacity to respond to harmful stimuli (Tomasik, 2018a). Behavioral evidence of nociception is, for example, a shrimp grooming an injured antenna (Elwood, 2011) or, physiologically, the measurement of neurons firing in response to sensory stimulation (Braithwaite, 2010). Sentience and the ability to suffer is the subjective awareness of pleasure and pain and can be demonstrated when the response to stimuli is more complex than a simple response to physical damage (Braithwaite, 2010; Elwood, 2011). Considering an evolutionary and functional perspective, we can infer that subjective awareness of suffering evolved to prevent and manage bodily damage. If we take as given that humans can suffer, and suffering has important adaptive functions in enabling our survival and reproduction, it’s parsimonious to assume that sentience and suffering evolved in other related animals, including many other vertebrates (Tomasik, 2017). There is a solid foundation of evidence that vertebrates and even some invertebrates evolved both nociception and sentience (Braithwaite, 2010). Vertebrates as a group generally have the same neurons, synapses, and other neural hardware associated with the ability to feel pain found in sentient humans. Fish brains, once thought to lack the fundamental hardware of sentience, have been found to have a brain region similar to the limbic system such that they may have the ability to ‘process information with an emotional component’ (Braithwaite, 2010: 102).
146
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Animal responses to pain, such as soliciting help, and avoiding stimuli previously associated with pain, are behavioral evidence of sentience. Many studies have shown that invertebrates – widely thought to be incapable of sentience – show responses consistent with subjective awareness of pain. For example, hermit crabs have been shown to make adaptive tradeoffs when exposed to shock, choosing to endure more painful shock in a high-quality as opposed to a low-quality shell (Appel and Elwood, 2009). Trout given a painful injection in their lips failed to show the normal neophobic response to a novel stimulus (a colorful block tower), compared to trout in the control condition; the trout’s distraction from normal behavior because of pain suggests a subjective awareness of pain, and thus suffering and sentience (Braithwaite, 2010; Sneddon et al., 2003). Using crabs and fish as examples is instructive, because they show better objective evidence for suffering than human neonates do (Braithwaite, 2010: 153) – but babies would almost certainly be more likely to get the benefit of our doubt. This is not to say that fish are equally sentient with cats, dogs, babies, or adult humans. There are many potentially good reasons to prioritize some animals over others by virtue of their greater ability to suffer, but the influence of, for example, brain size on degree of potential suffering is beyond the scope of this chapter (see Tomasik, 2019). The vast amount of sentience that evolved across millions of species in our world – and the resulting potential for suffering across trillions of animals – can feel overwhelming. But that doesn’t mean it is not true – and evolutionary psychologists have been courageous in confronting other emotionally challenging, counter-intuitive truths. Evolution may have created endless forms most beautiful, but it would never have passed an ethics review board (Bostrom, 2016: 188). Evolutionary psychologists should take seriously the likelihood that evolution favors widespread sentience across species, but not widespread altruism to other species, and this
sets the stage for a planet filled with s entient suffering both before and after humans achieved the technological means to exploit other species on an industrial scale.
Natural-Born Speciesists There are two central questions with regards to human morality towards animals: why do we value animals less than humans morally, and why are our moral attitudes towards animals so inconsistent? Both moral anthropocentrism and speciesism describe the concept of valuing human lives over animal lives, although speciesism implies that this valuation is a form of prejudice due to mere species membership (Caviola, 2019). Most people value members of certain species above and beyond their ability to suffer, for example valuing insensate humans (like those in a persistent vegetative state) more than chimpanzees, and valuing dogs more than pigs, even though they are similarly sentient. Valuing humans over animals seems to be a human moral universal. In one study, millions of participants all over the world overwhelmingly choose to save the life of a human over an animal, or several animals (Awad et al., 2018). In another study, participants most often choose to save one human over the lives of several endangered animals (like gorillas) (Petrinovich et al., 1993). This valuation is often reversed if the animal at risk is their pet. When Topolski et al. (2013) asked participants who they would save if a bus was imminently going to hit their pet or a foreign tourist, 40% chose to save their pet. ‘The only consistency in the way humans think about animals is inconsistency’ (H.Herzog, 2010: 14). Arguably, it can be rational to prioritize some interests over others on the basis of sentience, but, unsurprisingly, humans are not doing any coherent form of ethical calculus when they choose actions or decide on the morality of those actions. Is there an inherent human moral response towards animals? The study of how humans
ANIMAL ETHICS AND EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
and animals interact has taken off in the last two decades with the rise of anthrozoology, also known as human–animal relations (Amiot and Bastian, 2015; H. Herzog, 2010; Serpell, 1996). Anthrozoology is a diverse field, investigating topics like the therapeutic properties of living with dogs, the possible link between animal abuse and criminal behavior, and the personality traits of animalrights activists (H. Herzog, 2010). These fields have often tried to explain human moral anthropocentrism and moral inconsistency with descriptive frameworks like carnism (the social ideology that supports meat eating) (Joy, 2011), moral disengagement (i.e., we distance ourselves from our humane standards to harm animals) (Bandura, 1999; Vollum et al., 2004), terror management theory (i.e., we cling to human uniqueness and animal oppression to avoid existential anxiety) (Marino, 2019), and speciesism (discrimination based on species membership) (Caviola et al., 2018; Singer, 1995). Explanations at a functional level of analysis (Scott-Phillips et al., 2011) and adaptationist accounts are less common in anthrozoology (although see Bradshaw and Paul, 2010; H. Herzog, 2002). Evolutionary psychology is compatible with most of the explanations of human morality towards animals advanced by anthrozoologists. It posits functional explanations for attitudes and behaviors as reflecting evolved psychological adaptations (or their byproducts). Explanations like speciesism and cultural explanations like carnism are not in conflict with evolutionary psychology (Tooby and Cosmides, 1989), because culture is both an outgrowth of and a support for our evolved morality (e.g., the cultural celebration of consensual courtship and maternal love). However, the assumption of some thinkers in anthrozoology, as well as many animal-welfare advocates, is that humans are naturally sensitive and morally concerned about animal suffering, but this innate goodness is numbed by cultural and social factors like carnism (Joy, 2003)
147
and moral disengagement. The consistent thread in these perspectives is that violence is deeply unnatural. However, from the perspective of evolutionary morality, we should not expect sensitivity to animal suffering or kindness to animals except to the extent that it helped us, for example when using animals for our benefit, or to signal our morality.
Anthropomorphism Anthropomorphism, or ascribing human characteristics to animals, is an apparently universal feature of the human mind (Urquiza-Haas and Kotrschal, 2015). Anthropomorphism is so naturally expressed that it’s difficult to think about animals in non-anthropomorphic, objective terms. Most children don’t make clear distinctions between humans and animals, and young children usually treat animals, like family pets, as human persons (Serpell, 1996). Ironically, the basis for much of our moral feelings towards animals likely evolved so we could better exploit, kill, and eat them. Humans and animals aren’t so different, so the same theory of mind and empathy that helps us predict what humans do can also be used when hunting prey animals or avoiding predators. Primatologists and other animalbehavior scientists often use simple anthropomorphism to make predictions; behaviorist John Garcia stated that anthropomorphism with regard to rat behavior ‘works better than most learning theories’ (Serpell, 1996: 174). When you’re using the mind-reading ability that mostly evolved to predict the behavior of other people, you’re bound to ascribe human characteristics to animals. The ability to imagine what it was like to be an animal has adaptive benefit to better predict the behavior of prey, predators, and dangerous animals (H. Herzog, 2002). Some speculate that empathy could have motivated nurturance for domesticated species in animal husbandry (Bradshaw and Paul, 2010) however these animals have also been bred to be cute and inspire
148
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
feelings of care. Given an adaptationist perspective, empathy would have been bounded so as not to interfere with the processes of killing, butchering, and eating animals. If empathy is like a spotlight that illuminates the suffering of some at the expense of others (Bloom, 2016), this spotlight turns off or moves on. Empathy isn’t consistently associated with caring about animal ethics (Kasperbauer, 2015). And biophilia, or the desire to affiliate with nature and animals (Wilson, 1984), often doesn’t have a loving or caring character.
Play and Animal Abuse One clue about evolved human morality towards animals is how readily humans will torment animals when it isn’t necessary, and how much they enjoy doing it. Play is an essential part of learning in our species and many others. But humans playing with animals often involves both curiosity and cruelty (Arluke, 2002). Around the world, in both traditional societies and Western societies, playing with animals and cruelty to animals are commonplace in both adults and children – not just in psychopaths. Read some anthropological descriptions of hunter-gatherers and you’ll see sentimental, Noble Savage views like this: ‘Children learn to sympathize with animals and to see animals as sentient persons sharing the forest world with them’ (Lew-Levy et al., 2017: X). The implication is that hunter-gatherers have greater moral regard for animals than Western people, who only see meat wrapped in cellophane at the grocery store. However, read descriptions from thinkers who are less attached to a Noble Savage narrative, and you’ll get a better picture of how difficult it may be for our species to bestow moral consideration on others. It’s common for people in more traditional societies to hurt animals for fun. Jared Diamond describes Papua New Guinean men amusing themselves by raising and lowering
squealing bats into a fire and dissecting them alive for their bones (Diamond, 1993). Men and boys are much more likely to abuse animals than women and girls (Arluke, 2002) but this passage about Nisa, a !Kung San woman, describes with unusual clarity the dynamic of curious, playful cruelty, and its ability to facilitate precise prediction of animals: A flying ant with a long, wormlike body and large, almost transparent wings… landed in the hot sand… Nisa saved it… and pierced it through half the length of its body with a thin twig, leaving the upper half with the wings and head free. She planted the stick, with the skewered insect at the top, upright in the ground and tapped it gently with her fingers. The insect’s wings burst into motion, as if in flight, propelling the free parts of its body around and around the stick; then it stopped. Nisa tapped the stick again and again; each time, the insect responded with the same outpouring of energy… What Nisa was doing… seemed like an inexcusable torture… [But Nisa’s] head and the upper parts of her body had begun to move rhythmically. I did not understand what she was doing at first. Then it became clear: as the insect held itself erect, Nisa’s body also became erect; when the insect circled, drooped, and strained, Nisa’s body did the same. Her face and torso echoed the insect’s plight with a wrenching subtlety and her mimicry of its every movement was so sympathetic that the situation took on a kind of beauty. (Shostak and Nisa, 2004: 321)
Using animals for entertainment has been one of the most contentious and moralized aspects of animal use, even though the scale of suffering involved is much smaller than most modern industrialized forms of animal use. For example, many countries that otherwise have few animal-protection laws have banned circuses (‘These 27 Countries Have Banned WildAnimal Circuses!’, 2019, https://www.peta.org. uk/blog/these-26-countries-that-have-bannedwild-animal-circuses-are-making-englandlook-really-bad/). Bear-baiting, hare-coursing, dogfighting, and cockfighting are more controversial than other types of animal use, and were banned much earlier (e.g., the UK banned bearbaiting in 1835 and Pakistan banned bear-baiting in 1890). This seems to be an area of strong moral signaling.
ANIMAL ETHICS AND EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
One reason modern people might be judgmental about animal entertainment is because of the glut of other entertainment media developed in the last few centuries. Yes, using animals for entertainment is unnecessary, but it seems even less necessary and thus indulgently cruel when so many other forms of entertainment are available, especially other forms of violent entertainment like combat sports, action films and video games. Forms of animal entertainment considered lowbrow or ‘primitive’ may be more controversial. For example, many have argued that forms of animal entertainment enjoyed by the working class, like cockfighting, have been banned more quickly and more often than those enjoyed by the higher classes, like fox hunting (‘Fox Hunting’, 2019). Most of us in Western societies who would not want to torment an animal directly, or would be appalled to see staged animal suffering intended for entertainment, are still entertained by watching animals inflict suffering on each other in the wild, for example, in nature documentaries. The disparity in sensibilities is also well illustrated in this anecdote: That is perhaps the hardest part of being an anthropologist. [The hunter-gatherers I was studying] sensed my weakness and would sell me all kinds of baby animals with descriptions of what they would do to them otherwise. I used to take them far into the desert and release them, they would track them, and bring them back to me for sale again! (Pinker, 2011: 473)
These behaviors that cause suffering to animals are often practiced alongside making offerings to animal deities, praying to the spirit of animals after killing them, and efforts to embody animal qualities – contrary to the notion that cruelty requires dehumanization or suspension of empathy. In many smallscale societies, formalized animal totemism often co-exists with informal animal torment. The majority of human groups include some conspicuous cruelty to animals, but there are exceptions. For example, Jain monks and nuns sweep the ground in front of them so as to avoid inflicting any suffering on insects
149
(‘Ahimsa in Jainism’, 2019). Here it’s notable that this requires strong spiritual and social incentives, such as the belief that any given human might be reincarnated as an insect. Given our evolutionary history as omnivores, and the ubiquity of animal abuse across cultures, it seems likely that carnism and speciesism are outgrowths of our evolved psychology, rather than historically novel cultural influences that render us weirdly insensitive to animal suffering.
Animal Abuse by Children – The Link Children commonly inflict suffering on animals, not just out of necessity, but for enjoyment and curiosity. Here again, we see the sentimental narrative that animal abuse is a rare, pathological glitch in children’s fundamentally caring natures, and that children who abuse animals will grow up to have other serious problems like psychopathy and criminality. Animal abuse is considered a risk factor for violence with such certainty in the animal advocacy community that it’s sometimes referred to simply as ‘The Link’ (H. Herzog, 2010). Most of the evidence for an association between childhood animal abuse and adult violence suffers from methodological limitations like retrospective reporting, and sampling incarcerated criminals (Flynn, 2011). But, consistent with the idea that insensitivity to animal suffering is fairly standard in our species, there isn’t replicable evidence that animal abusers are more likely to commit violent crime (H. Herzog and Arluke, 2006; Patterson-Kane and Piper, 2009). Consistent with the cross-cultural ubiquity of animal cruelty, and the historical commonality of using animals for entertainment, animal abuse is normal among young people, even now. In one study, 40% of female college students and 66% of male college students admitted to having abused animals (Arluke, 2002) – and given the modern stigma against animal abuse, this is probably
150
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
an underreported behavior. There seems to be a moral panic about animal abuse; advocates often depict anyone who has ever abused an animal as likely to commit violence against people, even though the majority of people have, at some time, abused an animal (Patterson-Kane and Piper, 2009). Children might be learning about how animals ‘work’ by playing with them, developing mental models of animal morphology and behavior that ancestrally would have been useful for hunting, tracking, and butchering. Indeed, vertebrate animals’ similarity to humans means that children may be learning more than this. Children around the world often practice caretaking with pets and baby animals. I speculate that violence, which is often used to adaptively compel others to do what you want, can be practiced and honed similarly by playing with animals or through cruelty. Indeed, lacking the kinds of modern toys that Western children have access to, animals are used in just this way, treated with both care and cruelty. ‘Anthropologists have observed returning hunters bringing small wild animals back alive and promptly turning them over to their children… these animated toys are generally badly treated, short lived and… end up the objects of target practice or mutilation’ (Serpell, 1996: 68). There are two main hypotheses about the animal- cruelty association with crime: the graduation hypothesis posits that animal abuse is ‘a form of rehearsal for human-directed violence’, and the deviance generalization hypothesis posits that antisocial personality is associated with both animal cruelty and criminal behavior (Gullone, 2014). Animal cruelty might be both a normal behavior that children perform if unsupervised with animals, and also a form of practice that is disproportionately attractive to children with antisocial and violent tendencies. Animal killing and butchering were surely features of our evolutionary history, but modern specialization of labor means for the first time there are workers who spend hour after
hour killing and butchering animals. Even among slaughterhouse workers, the worker who kills the cow, the ‘knocker’, is considered to have psychological problems compared to other workers who bleed the cow or begin to dismember it (Pachirat, 2014). There is evidence that the presence of slaughterhouses is associated with increased local rates of violent crime and sexual offences, relative to other industries like steel forging (Fitzgerald et al., 2009), but it’s unclear if violent people are more attracted to working in slaughterhouses, or if slaughtering animals increases workers’ propensities for violence towards other humans.
WHY HAS ANIMAL ADVOCACY LAGGED BEHIND OTHER MORAL MOVEMENTS? Civil-rights movements, like those for the abolition of slavery, black power, women’s rights, worker’s rights, and gay rights, have flourished in the last several decades, and have reduced suffering for billions of humans (Pinker, 2011). The animal advocacy movement (including animal rights, animal welfare, and animal liberation – but not environmental protection) has not had the same success as other sentient-rights movements (Pinker, 2011). In some ways, attitudes have changed a great deal. In a representative sample of over 1,000 American adults, Sentience Institute found that nearly 50% supported a ban on slaughterhouses and factory farming (Reese, 2017). But, in that same survey, 75% of participants believed the reassuring fiction that the animal products they were eating had been humanely produced (Reese, 2017) even though 99% of animal products come from factory farms (Reese, 2019). A recent Gallup poll found that 32% of Americans think that animals deserve ‘the exact same rights as people’ (Riffkin, 2015), up from 25% in 2003 (Moore, 2003). A study of 3,500 Ohio residents found 81% said farm
ANIMAL ETHICS AND EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
animal welfare was as important as pet welfare, and 75% said farm animals should be protected from physical pain (Rauch and Sharp, 2005). These self-reported attitudes are impressively progressive, but consumer behavior has not changed that much. FewAmericans boycott animal products. The rate of selfidentified vegetarians has hovered around 5% in the United States for several years (Riffkin, 2015). Other reports claim there are slightly more vegetarians. The number of people who describe themselves as vegetarian is probably not actually representative of boycott, because only about one-third abstain from meat (Cooney, 2014). Che Green, an expert on these trends, has called vegans and vegetarians ‘a blip on the demographic radar’ and ‘below the margin of error for most surveys’ (Zaraska, 2016: 136). The concern for animal wellbeing has made uneven progress, with far more concern about some species and some issues than others. One illustration of the vast disparity between the alleged human moral concern for animal suffering, and the actual concentration of animal suffering, is revealed by patterns of charitable donations (Figure 7.1). Farm animals, compared to all other animals,
151
experience the vast majority of suffering and death with more than 99% of farm animals living on factory farms (Reese, 2019). Farm animals received only $20 million in charitable donations in 2015, compared to $1.2 billion donated to animal shelters for pet species like dogs and cats (Bockman, 2016). Of domesticated land animals used and killed by humans in the United States, over 99.6% are farmed land animals, about 0.2% are animals used in laboratories, 0.07% are used for clothing, and 0.03% are killed in companion animal shelters. However, about 66% of donations to animal charities in the United States go to companion animal shelters, 32% go to groups with mixed or other activities, and just 0.8% of donations go specifically to farmed animal organizations, while 0.7% go to laboratory animal organizations. (Bockman, 2016)
A couple of caveats are that the ‘other’ category does include some farm animal donations, because it includes large organizations that engage in diverse animal advocacy campaigns (e.g., People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals (PETA)). ‘Other’ also includes environmental charities and wildlife preservation. Also, importantly, the ‘animals used and killed’ number does not include fish, which would completely dominate the left panel.
Figure 7.1 Charitable donations towards animal organizations as compared to animal use
152
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Fish are probably killed in the trillions, at a rate greater than all other animals combined (Mood and Brooke, 2010). This is another way that human behavior is inconguous with stated concern. If humans cared about reducing animal suffering and acted in keeping with this concern, they would not give a disproportionate amount of their donations to cat and dog shelters. Below I will address the psychology of how and why humans morally value and devalue animals. First, I’ll discuss kin selection, and the empathy elicited by cuteness and neoteny – two intertwined factors that account for our kindness towards companion animals like dogs and cats. Second, I’ll discuss disgust and food aversion, meat consumption, and the future of meat eating. Empathy, disgust, and food preferences show significant sex differences, and I’ll discuss how they manifest in morality. Lastly, I’ll talk about how morality is socially signaled, and how this virtue signaling plays out in animal care and attitudes towards the animal-focused moral minority, such as vegans. The view of decision-making in the moral domain in this chapter is consistent with the popular metaphor of the elephant and the rider (Haidt, 2012; Simler and Hanson, 2017). Emotions and psychological mechanisms like the cuteness response, disgust, reputation management, and empathy guide our moral decisions in often irrational directions, like an elephant deciding which path to take. We identify as the rider, the part we are most conscious of, and we later attribute our moral decisions to rational processes rather than the ‘hot’ emotional cognition of the elephant, the part that controls our behavior.
Kin Selection and the Cuteness Response Prominent anthrozoologist James Serpell defines pets as ‘animals we live with, with no obvious function’ (H. Herzog, 2010: 72). Other animals don’t usually keep pets. Crossspecies friendships sometimes happen (see
viral videos of cats who love rats and hippos who love tortoises, for example), but they are almost always the product of an artificial environment (H. Herzog, 2014). Pet-keeping seems uniquely human. Two interesting exceptions in the wild are a dolphin who adopted a melon-headed whale (Carzon et al., 2019), and a marmoset adopted into a group of capuchin monkeys (Izar et al., 2006). In the first case, the dolphin nursed and cared for the whale, and in the second case, two female capuchins provisioned the marmoset. In both cases, arguably, the adopted animal appears to be a neotenous version of the animals’ own young. This illustrates a major psychological means through which humans integrate animals more centrally into their moral worlds: kin selection and empathy for cuteness. Both cases also illustrate how this cuteness-based empathy is more motivating for females than for males. Humans keep a wide variety of pets, from insects to horses, but here I’ll focus mostly on dogs, who seem to be the animals who most often reverse human speciesism. The psychological mechanisms motivating kin selection may cause humans to value dogs and cats much more than other comparably sentient animals. Evolution promotes passing on our genes, including in other members of our families (Foster et al., 2006). Because cooperating in groups is adaptive, we may be more likely to interpret ambiguous cues as evidence of genetic association (Park and Ackerman, 2011). In this way, kin selection means that we tend to be more altruistic to those who show cues of being members of our ingroup – whether these cues are cultural (Kurzban et al., 2001) or physical (Krupp et al., 2011). There are other possible indicators of genetic relatedness, like psychological similarity (Park and Schaller, 2005), and time spent growing up together (Lieberman et al., 2007). It’s unclear if our minds are simply indiscriminate about what cues we take as indicators of genetic relatedness. Some animals indisputably occupy a familial role, not only in Western countries but also among many
ANIMAL ETHICS AND EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
153
hunter-gatherers. New Guineans, which I earlier described abusing bats, treat pigs as members of their families; piglets sleep in the same hut with their human families and New Guinean women often nurse piglets at the breast (Diamond, 1993). In the United States, 91% of dog and cat owners reported that their pet was a part of their family, and 20% of dog owners report giving their dogs birthday gifts (‘Pets Really Are Members of the Family’, 2011). We attend to physical similarity when evaluating species and breeds for special treatment. For example, people are more likely to support causes to save endangered species that have more in common with humans, like great apes, and researchers who do invasive scientific experiments on monkeys are most likely to be threatened by animal activists (H. Herzog, 2010). Even so, most people (around 75%) would choose to save one person over five endangered lowland gorillas (Petrinovich et al., 1993). Dogs show resemblance to humans in their facial musculature: domestication has changed dog faces compared to wolf faces to be able to display more humanlike expressions (Kaminski et al., 2019). There is also evidence that people resemble their dogs (Nakajima et al., 2009), and that people choose dogs who resemble them (Roy and Nicholas, 2004). People also tend to think their dogs are psychologically similar to them. Dog breeds go in and out of fashion (Ghirlanda et al., 2013), but the proliferation of so many dog breeds with different appearances and personalities may have been driven by the kin-selection mechanisms of different individuals and ethnic groups with different implicit criteria for similarity.
(genetic similarity) and cuteness are difficult to disentangle as contributors to this unusual moral relationship. Because there is no word in English for the especially cute emotional repertoire elicited by cuteness, I’ll use ‘cuteness response’. The cuteness response elicits nurturance but also inspires mentalizing and anthropomorphizing, bringing cute individuals closer into the circle of moral concern (Sherman and Haidt, 2011). There is evidence that pets, especially dogs, parasitize our parental caretaking mechanisms (Turner, 2001). People talk to dogs in a way similar to ‘motherese’ (the sing-song way in which parents talk to their infants), and motherese for dogs has been termed ‘doggerel’ (HirshPasek and Treiman, 1982). Dogs are also neotenous: they retain puppylike features throughout their lives. Furthermore, dogs who have more paedomorphic (i.e., cute) facial musculature are more likely to be adopted from shelters (Waller et al., 2013). Dogs in childless homes are much more likely to be groomed, given presents, and taken on vacation (H. Herzog, 2010: 79). Dogs have been bred to retain neotenous puppylike features and to be cuter than their wolfy ancestors. Dogs aren’t just cuter to us; they’re also cuter to wolves themselves! In one study a wolf mother was given two different litters to foster, one with wolf puppies and one with dog puppies:
Cute Ethics
One reason that dog breed popularity doesn’t track health, obedience, or other desirable qualities is the desire for the cuteness superstimulus. Analyzing the popularity of dog breeds in the United States from 1926 to 1995, researchers concluded that there was
In ethics, cuteness doesn’t count. (Cohen, 2009)
Because pets seem to occupy a place in the family as surrogate children, cues of kinship
The foster-mother wolf was… more nurturant with the Malamute pups than with the wolf pups. She washed them earlier and more frequently, spent 2–3 times as many hours in the den-box with them as she did with the wolf pups, was more defensive toward intruders, showed far more distress when one was missing (e.g., during supplemental feedings), played with them and continues to play with them for longer periods of time. (Frank and Frank, 1982: 515)
154
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
no indication ‘that breeds with more desirable behavior, longer life, or fewer inherited genetic disorders have been more popular than other breeds’ (Ghirlanda et al., 2013: 4). Most purebred dog breeds have some endemic health problems, but brachycephalic dogs (dogs with short snouts, like bulldogs) have many more problems. This preference for this brachycephalic cuteness super-stimulus, (for example these dogs have a much rounder more infant like head than most other dog breeds) causes a huge amount of suffering for animals that are otherwise treated like family. French and English bulldogs must usually be delivered by C-section, and suffer many other problems like allergies, hip dysplasia, persistent farting, and heat sensitivity that causes them to die more often in transport (K. Herzog, 2019). Interestingly, people with these neotenous breeds are more attached to their pets than those with less neotenous breeds. In a Danish sample, French bulldog owners were more attached to their dogs and nearly 20% more likely to say ‘I would do anything for my dog’ compared to owners of the much less neotenous Cairn Terriers (Sandøe et al., 2017). Perhaps they just reported this because their dogs required extraordinary attention and care or perhaps these health problems – are one reason people want these dogs (Serpell, 2019). Bulldogs have been in the top five for breed popularity for the last six years, and in the last two years, French bulldogs have also been in the top five. With the recent high-profile win of ‘Thor’, a bulldog, at a national dog pageant, this trend is likely to continue (K. Herzog, 2019). To some extent, our special affinity for our pet dogs translates into special moral consideration for all dogs. In the United States there was widespread outrage prompted by China’s annual dog-meat festival (Howard, 2016). The United States has loved dogs for a long time – and, in perhaps the greatest success story from the animal-protection movement, the number of dogs (and cats) that are euthanized per year has plummeted, down 75% from 2011 (Parlapiano, 2019).
Why do we as humans find a huge array of animals cute, from penguins to pandas to pangolins? Prototypical cuteness elicitors are cues like round and fat cheeks, large eyes, small teeth, and playful energetic behavior. Our own young don’t achieve peak cuteness until they are several months old (Sherman and Haidt, 2011). Humans produce very altricial young and neonates are highly divergent in their appearance (e.g., presence of hair, redness of skin, facial morphology). Also, neonates often aren’t cute, and yet this stage of life is when our young are most vulnerable and most in need of care. In order to take care of our own neonates, the normal primate standards of cuteness may have become relaxed in humans. Earlier I speculated that slightly indiscriminate kin-detection mechanisms could have made it easier for humans to form friendships. Something similar could have happened with cuteness and pets. The large number of animal species we think are cute could be because of indiscriminate cuteness perception. ‘Cuteness promiscuity’ might be a byproduct of our unusual life history, high altriciality, and high variance in infant appearance. This tendency to think that many different animals are cute could be even more pronounced in women, who are the primary caretakers of altricial infants. Given selection over time for dogs to elicit both fellow-feeling (kin selection) and the cuteness response, it makes sense that their suffering is much more prioritized than that of other species. Given women’s special sensitivity to cuteness, it makes sense that we find such a large difference in men and women when it comes to animal morality.
SEX DIFFERENCES IN MORALITY TOWARDS ANIMALS In the example above in which a dolphin fostered a melon-headed whale, she also nursed him. Cross-species nursing is also common cross-culturally. Women around the
ANIMAL ETHICS AND EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
world have nursed baby animals like bears, monkeys, pigs, and puppies (H. Herzog, 2019). In some of these cultures, eating an animal nursed at the breast is considered as taboo as eating your own child. In other cultures, animals like dogs, are traded with other groups in order to limit the discomfort of killing animals one raised, and in other cultures, animals are nursed so that they can be later eaten (Serpell, 1996). Among the Ainu of Japan, bear cubs are breast fed and then ceremonially sacrificed and eaten, while the women who suckled the bear cubs show their ambivalence by alternately crying and laughing (Serpell, 1996: 184). Unsurprisingly, given women’s sensitivity to cuteness and their greater nurturing response (on average), women show stronger moral concerns for animals than men do. For example, 45% of women would let a foreign tourist die before their cat or dog, compared to 30% of men (Topolski et al., 2013), and 33% of women would kill a person to save 1,000 dogs, compared with 23% of men (Petrinovich et al., 1993). However, men and women were similarly likely to say they would save a close relative over a pet (Topolski et al., 2013). There are many other sex differences in moral attitudes towards animals, reflecting differences in moral emotions such as disgust, empathy, and the cuteness response. Women are much more likely to be involved in animal protection and animal advocacy, much more likely to be vegetarian, more likely to hoard animals, and much less likely to hunt or engage in direct animal abuse ( H. Herzog, 2007). Women are less speciesist than men as measured through questionnaire (Caviola et al., 2018). Women are more likely than men to believe that animals experience complex emotions like grief and anxiety (Walker et al., 2014). There are also substantial sex differences in moral views on animals. In a 2015 poll, 42% of women compared to 22% of men said that animals deserve the same rights as people (Riffkin, 2015). In a 2011 Gallup poll on moral issues, the largest sex differences were on issues related to animals: ‘Majorities
155
of men, but less than half of women, consider the use of animal fur for clothing, and medical testing on animals to be morally acceptable’ (Saad, 2010). Women are also much more opposed to ‘unnatural’ technologies, including food additives, genetically modified foods, and animal testing (Funk et al., 2015). In particular, 62% of women oppose the use of animals in scientific research, whereas 60% of men support it.
Animal Testing: Disgust and Empathy The widespread opposition to animal testing is a good demonstration of how disgust and empathy can create strong feelings around animal ethics, even when they conflict with important human interests such as biomedical advances. All drugs and interventions to prevent human and animal suffering must first be tested. Gary Francione (2009), who famously advocates completely abolishing the use and ownership of animals, has called animal testing the only use of animals that isn’t frivolous. Animal testing is one of the highest-profile and most controversial uses of animals, although it accounts for a very small proportion of animal suffering. ‘We kill 200 food animals for every animal used in a scientific experiment’ (H. Herzog, 2010: 176). More than half (52%) of Americans oppose the use of animals in scientific testing (Strauss, 2018), and 60% oppose animal cloning (Masci, 2017) – a technology that could lead to significant advances in biomedical research and comparable gains in human welfare. In comparison to other animal-related causes, there have been much larger changes in legislation and regulation around animal testing. For instance, the EU has implemented bans on cosmetic animal testing (‘Testing Cosmetics on Animals’, 2019) (arguably, this was only possible because most cosmetic ingredients have already been tested on animals for decades and found safe).
156
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
In 2015, 0.2% of animals were killed in labs but a disproportionate 0.7% of charity money went to this cause (Bockman, 2016). Some of the only true terrorism by animal advocates – like death threats and property damage – has targeted scientists and laboratories conducting animal research. In particular, scientists who work with primates or dogs have been targeted (H. Herzog, 2010). Familiarity is one heuristic we use to infer that something isn’t dangerous or pathogenic. Unlike meat eating, animal experimentation’s visceral associations and unfamiliarity combine to create an impression of ‘unnaturalness’ (Holden and H. Herzog, 2019) that is disgusting and elicits moral condemnation.
Meat Meat is a strongly preferred food among humans. This enjoyment of and desire for meat is a major contributor to our moral attitudes about meat, and to our self-deception about the living conditions of animals raised for meat. Humans almost certainly evolved eating meat (Wrangham, 2009), and seem motivated to eat meat specifically. For instance, human taste buds appear to be sensitive to a flavor abundant in cooked meat called umami (Lindemann et al., 2002). In many places in the world there is a special word for ‘meat hunger’ (Fiddes, 2004; Zaraska, 2016), as distinct from other kinds of hunger. In recent years the developing world, either imitating rich industrialized nations or actualizing their evolved taste preferences for savory, high-calorie foods, are eating more meat and other animal products (Kearney, 2010). Meat eating has increased a great deal in the United States in the last few decades, and Americans now are eating an average of 125 kg of meat per year (Zaraska, 2016). And in China, the most populous country in the world, the average person in the 1970s ate 14 kg of meat per year, whereas in 2010 they were eating 55 kg of meat per year (H. Herzog, 2010). Around
the world the trend is that people are eating more meat, year after year. However, the strong human desire for meat has a flip side, because meat has often been a dangerous food to eat, more likely to contain pathogens than plant foods. Because humans eat both plants and animals, they face an omnivore’s dilemma: there are a large number of foods that could be eaten, but they differ both in nutritional quality and in the risk of dangerous pathogens. Disgust is thought to have evolved to reduce the chance of coming into contact with potential pathogens, especially those that are orally incorporated (Tybur et al., 2012). That’s likely why culture discourages eating certain animal foods. Taboos are more often leveraged against meat than against other foods (Fessler and Navarrete, 2003). The trait of ‘disgust sensitivity’ is positively linked to meat avoidance (Fessler et al., 2003), and disgust is often given as an explicit reason for not eating meat (Santos and Booth, 1996). As I argued earlier, there is evidence that most animals used for food are sentient, and that human imposition of industrial-scale suffering on sentient animals may, from the perspective of aggregate suffering, be one of the most pressing concerns of our generation (Singer, 1990). The scale of animal use is staggering. According to an interview with expert Lewis Bollard (Wiblin and Bollard, 2017), there are currently 23 billion chickens being farmed (15 billion for meat and 8 billion for eggs), 6 billion mammals (like cows, pigs, and rabbits), and over 100 billion farmed fish. Even if we ascribe to each of these animals just a fraction of the sentience and moral importance ascribed to a human, this adds up to a massive moral issue – vastly more aggregate suffering than global poverty or disease among humans. From the perspective of sentient suffering, the environmental and sustainability issues around meat also matter. Meat is environmentally costly to produce, requiring more water and land per calorie, in addition to being one of the major producers of greenhouse gases and
ANIMAL ETHICS AND EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
water pollution (Steinfeld et al., 2006). Meat feeds fewer people with the same resources. Estimates of inefficiency vary, but the same amount of grain produces 10 times fewer calories through grain-fed cattle than when eaten directly (Bittman, 2008). (However, it’s important to consider that much of the land that isn’t suitable for farming can still feed grazing ruminants, like cattle, and thus can produce food.) In principle, boycotting animal products could significantly reduce many of these problems. But, even in places with abundant food choices, vegetarianism and veganism are rare (Pinker, 2011). Most self-described ‘vegetarians’ eat meat (Cooney, 2014), and perhaps 90% of people who self-identify as vegetarian aren’t behaviorally vegetarian (H. Herzog, 2010: 195). Moreover, lapsed vegetarians outnumber current vegetarians (H. Herzog, 2011), and many vegetarians avoid red meat for health reasons rather than ethical reasons. Thus, it’s difficult to estimate how many people are boycotting animal products for ethical reasons. All foods cause some degree of suffering – even vegetables and fruit, because many small wild animals, from insects to birds, are killed during planting and harvesting. As Norwood and Lusk (2011) glibly comment, ‘even veganism is murder’ (2011: 229). However, animal foods differ markedly in how much suffering they cause. Ironically, the most popular ways that vegetarians and semi-vegetarians reduce their consumption of animal products may impose more net suffering than a diet centered around beef would, as I discuss below. Disgust is a major driver of meat avoidance (Fessler et al., 2003). Red meat, which retains more cues of its animal origins, like blood, is considered much more disgusting than fish or chicken, which are often packaged to hide their animal origin (H. Herzog, 2010: 190). Health messages about meat underscore this disgust, with recommendations to cut out red meat and to eat chicken, eggs, and fish instead. Self-described vegetarians, who are
157
often motivated by both disgust and health messaging, often end up eating more chicken than self-described meat eaters do (H. Herzog, 2010: 195). Another factor beyond disgust is that we often feel more empathy for cows and pigs than for fish and chickens, because they have more humanlike and neotenous characteristics. How might consumption of fish, eggs, and chicken, to the exclusion of beef and pork, cause more animal suffering? There are two main reasons: animal size and quality of life. Chickens and farmed fish are smaller animals, which means that for each animal bred, caged, and slaughtered, we get far fewer meals. This observation was the basis of a tongue-in-cheek campaign from PETA called ‘Eat the whales’ (Tomasula, 2001). In a 100-ton blue whale, there are 70,000 chickens’ worth of meat. (H. Herzog, 2010: 193). Considering living conditions, chickens (both egg-laying hens and broiler chickens) and farmed fish have much worse lives than conventionally produced beef cattle (Tomasik, 2018b). Conventionally produced beef cattle spend much of their lives in pasture and the last 100–200 days of their lives in a feedlot – they can eat, stretch out, and associate with others of their species. By contrast, broiler chickens live in cramped conditions and often have crippling leg problems. Egg-laying hens kept in cages usually have their beaks removed so they don’t attack or cannibalize one another in cramped spaces. Often this causes chronic pain or inability to feed, and it doesn’t solve the problem of hens aggressing against their cage mates. Conventional pork production is widely considered to be terrible for smart social animals such as pigs, who are confined and bored, like a dog kept in a kennel cage for months on end. For those concerned with humane animal treatment, a reasonable goal is that animals raised for food should only have ‘one bad day’: the day they go to slaughter. For detailed descriptions of how different animals are raised for food see, for example Norwood and Lusk (2011) and Singer and Mason (2006).
158
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Remarkably few people have tried to compare animal welfare across species or to calculate how much suffering is caused by eating different animal foods. Still, there is some consensus on which animals have the best and worst lives. Economists Bailey Norwood and Jayson Lusk (2011) came to similar conclusions as Tomasik (2018b) in terms of the quality of life of various animals raised for food (and also quantified the quality of life for animals kept for breeding purposes) (Norwood and Lusk, 2011: 229). They estimated that laying hens and veal calves have the worst quality of life, and that beef cattle and dairy cows have the best quality of life relatively speaking. (However, Norwood and Lusk argue that broiler chickens have a much better quality of life on average than most animal advocates think they do.) How does all this add up? We can quantify a ‘suffering footprint’: an estimate of how many days of suffering animals endure to contribute a unit of meat to our diet. Table 7.1 is adapted and simplified based on Tomasik’s (2018b) calculation of how many days of suffering per kg are caused by the demand from buying various animal foods. I have simplified the calculation here by assuming these animals have the same sentience, and by assuming that each animal has roughly the same suffering on the day of slaughter (the reader can input values in the table at the Reducing Suffering blog, https://reducing-suffering.org/how-muchdirect-suffering-is-caused-by-various-animal-
foods/). Here, animal lifespan is how many days the animal lives before slaughter, on average; kg of food per animal lifespan is how much edible food weight is produced by the animal; suffering per day of life is how bad the animal’s life is based on best estimates from animal-welfare researchers (note that beef cattle have the best lives and battery hens have the worst lives). The column on the right indicates for each kg of the animal product consumed how many days of suffering there are adjusted for the badness of each day of life. Using a similar calculation, the standard American with a typical diet of animal products causes 5 years, 6 months, and 5 days of animal suffering per year (Hurford, 2014). Regardless of specific numbers, many ‘vegetarians’, some adhering to the definition and eating eggs, and many others who still eat fish and chicken, are causing more days of animal suffering, and more intense suffering, than many meat eaters are. Based on the calculations from the table above, a vegetarian who eats three eggs at a meal (around 150 g) is causing 19.5 days of chicken suffering, compared to a meat eater who eats a 1.3 kg steak that causes around 2.4 days of cow suffering. The average vegetarian almost certainly causes less suffering than the five years of suffering created through the average American diet. But the perception that the average selfdescribed ‘vegetarian’ is more moral than the average meat eater is derived not from any
Table 7.1 Days of suffering per kilogram of food weight produced by the animal adjusted for the badness of each day of life as estimated by animal welfare researchers Animal product Farmed catfish Farmed salmon Battery cage eggs Chicken Turkey Pork Beef Milk
Animal lifespan (days) Kg of food per animal lifespan 820 639 501 42 133 183 395 1,825
.39 2.0 16 1.9 9.6 65 212 30,000
Suffering per day of life (beef cows =1) 1.5 1.5 4 3 3 2.5 1 2
Adjusted days of suffering caused per kg demanded 3,200 480 130 68 42 7.1 1.9 0.12
ANIMAL ETHICS AND EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
quantitative analysis of animal suffering, but from their claimed concern for animals, and from the fact that they eat less meat from mammals, who are cuter and more humanlike. Even a vegetarian who eats eggs every day would cause more suffering than someone on an all-beef diet. An actual vegan, who eats no animal products including meat, fish, eggs, and dairy, causes the least amount of suffering with their consumption. Giving up fish, eggs, and chicken would reduce animal suffering about 90% as much as a vegan who eats no animal products at all (Cooney, 2014). Unfortunately, there is no name for this avoiding fish, eggs, and chicken ethical stance, and thus it is not possible to signal this or reap any benefits to social moral reputation. The impact of better welfare animal practices on animal suffering and human morality is beyond the scope of this chapter. But it seems that people are much more likely to think they are buying humane animal products than they really are (75% believe they are buying human products versus 99% of products coming from factory farms) (Reese, 2017). Given that billions of animals are farmed for food across thousands of facilities, and the food industry remains politically powerful, it’s difficult to enforce humane standards. The little evidence we have, such as that undercover animal advocacy operations seem to always discover cruel mishandling and mistreatment of animals, even on farms with ‘humane standards’, doesn’t bode well.
Clean Meat Fifty years hence, we shall escape the absurdity of growing a whole chicken in order to eat the breast or wing by growing these parts separately under a suitable medium. (Winston Churchill, 1932: 26)
It’s unlikely that individual consumer choices are going to significantly reduce the demand for animal products. Polls show Americans say they are very concerned about animal welfare, but this doesn’t translate into their
159
choices as consumers. One experiment on the ‘vote/buy gap’ – the tendency for consumers to vote for higher welfare standards but not to buy in accordance with these ideals – showed that 80% of consumers who chose to buy cookies made with battery cage eggs said that battery cage eggs should be illegal (Paul et al., 2019). The vast majority of people in Western societies would state that they are morally repulsed by slavery, and yet when a report documented that around one-third of shrimp produced in Thailand involved slave labor (Hodal and Lawrence, 2014), this did not change the huge demand for shrimp, and there is still slavery in the supply chain now (Clark, 2019). From a historical perspective, no movement has ever made significant gains from endorsing individual boycotts of largescale industries. An analysis of the abolitionist movement against human slavery showed that boycotting slave-produced goods was not effective, and was not that widespread, even among abolitionists (Witwicki, 2017). One possible solution to the problem of animal suffering caused by meat production is in vitro meat, cultured meat, or ‘clean meat’. Clean meat is the ‘cultivation of food grade animal tissues in carefully controlled environments’ (McLaren, 2014: 1). Clean meat holds the promise of replacing slaughter-based meat production. The fast rate of technological innovation in clean meat seems to have overcome some of the obstacles I wrote about several years ago (Fleischman, 2013). The main obstacle has been price preventing clean meat from meeting market demand. Creating a structure for in vitro meat to grow, to keep it at the correct temperature and inundated with nutrients for cell division, and free from contamination, made it prohibitively expensive. The debut clean meat burger in London created by Mark Post a few years ago cost about $330,000 to make (McLaren, 2014). But, after many failed predictions (Madrigal, 2013), it seems clean meat might soon be coming to market. A few major obstacles seem to have been overcome since clean meat is now being taste-tested for the public.
160
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
However, our evolved psychology may still present obstacles to the uptake of clean meat. Food preferences crystallize at an early age (Birch, 1999) and people feel disgust about foods that are unfamiliar to them. To increase demand for clean meat, ethical vegetarians might at least be willing to try it. However, in two small surveys it was found that the majority of vegans and vegetarians (71%) were unwilling to try in vitro meat (Fleischman, 2012). A larger survey of vegetarians found a similar result, with 73% unwilling to eat it (Dahlgreen, 2013). In my survey (Fleischman, 2012), it seemed that the stipulation that in vitro meat would cause no more animal suffering than plant foods did not change attitudes against in vitro meat, leaving disgust as the most probable cause. Indeed, 32% of vegans explicitly cited disgust as a reason they would not want to try it. There is some research indicating that moral vegetarians are more disgust-sensitive overall (Rozin et al., 1997). However, it is disappointing that this group is likely not going to be leading the way towards clean meat. Vegan and vegetarian attitudes are probably not that important for the future of clean meat. The most important thing is uptake from people eating the most meat and populous countries whose meat consumption is increasing, namely China and India. There is some hopeful news as familiarity with clean meat increases. In one survey of American adults, the majority were willing to try clean meat (65%) and about onethird said they would be willing to eat clean meat as a replacement for farmed meat (Wilks and Phillips, 2017). Men, who tend to eat more meat than women, also had a more positive view of clean meat in this US sample. In a sample of over 3,000 participants from the United States, India, and China, 93% of Chinese participants said they were likely to purchase clean meat, as were 86% of Indian participants and 75% of US participants (Bryant et al., 2019). In keeping with ideas about sex differences and food aversions, men and those who are less disgust-sensitive are more favorable towards clean meat (Bryant and Barnett, 2018).
If clean meat is going to become an important solution to the myriad problems of the global animal industry we have to learn from history, both evolutionary and cultural. As I mentioned above, we as humans are more concerned about meat contamination than other food sources. Any warning about clean-meat contamination, or a recall, could have pervasive long-term effects and mean that people will continue to buy more familiar meat from animals that suffered and died for decades to come. Branding clean meat as ‘clean meat’ rather than in vitro meat, lab meat, cultured meat, or synthetic meat was an important first step in combating disgust sensitivity. One major reason that genetically modified food wasn’t an unalloyed success was because of perceptions of unnaturalness (Mohorčich, 2018), another form of disgust response that can be reduced by increasing consumer familiarity. Framing is also important; meat producers learned long ago that mentioning the animals themselves reduced consumer acceptance (Zaraska, 2016). We don’t really want to know how the sausage is made, and less detail about how clean meat is produced generally improves attitudes (Bryant and Barnett, 2018). We as humans are more concerned with what’s delicious than what is virtuous; consumers rarely care enough to buy or boycott any product because of its moral ramifications (Bryant and Barnett, 2018). That’s why making sure that clean meat is tastier than conventional meat can go a long way. Finally, the rise of zoonotic diseases like Covid19 and H1N1 can hopefully turn the tide of disgust sensitivity in the other direction, against forms of animal agriculture that can cause pandemics.
VIRTUE SIGNALING AND ANIMAL WELFARE Stop smirking. One of the most universal pieces of advice from across cultures and eras is that we are all hypocrites, and in our condemnation of others’ hypocrisy we only compound our own. (Haidt, 2006: 60)
ANIMAL ETHICS AND EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Most animals are hidden from public view or otherwise incapable of communicating about their suffering and cannot leverage reputational concern (Sperber and Baumard, 2012). However, because people can advertise their moral attitudes in so many ways now, from vegan bumper stickers to social-media posts, there is more widespread concern about the suffering of animals than at any previous point in history. Our moral attitudes do not occur in a vacuum. Advertising our moral qualities to others for social benefits, whether these moral qualities are instantiated in behavior or just ‘cheap talk’, is known as virtue signaling (Miller, 2019). When definitions of moral behavior shift in social groups, culture can change moral behavior to the extent that it’s available for virtue signaling. This is one reason that animal advocates have had so much more success with institutional change over individual changes (Reese, 2018). People are willing to advertise moral ideals by signing a petition or publicly advocating that a business change its harmful animal practices, but are unwilling to engage in more costly and less visible individual boycott. Our moral identity is important to us; there is a strong psychological motivation to present ourselves as more moral than others (Kurzban, 2011) and to resist others’ claims of moral superiority. This creates fraught relationships with ‘moral minorities’ who consider themselves to be in the moral vanguard – including animal advocates, vegans, and others who hold and display a virtuous identity. Vegetarians are widely disliked by the rest of society. In one study, participants reported disliking vegans and vegetarians more than atheists, asexuals, immigrants, or Blacks, but reported being more willing to hire or rent to vegans and vegetarians than all other target groups (MacInnis and Hodson, 2017). In this study, only drug addicts were more disliked than vegans. Because moral rules are considered to be universal, meeting someone who holds different or more strict moral standards than you do can be seen as an implicit indictment of your behavior. People tend to rate themselves
161
as more moral and better than others; meat eaters rate vegetarians as more moral than the average person, but rate vegetarians as less moral than themselves (Minson and Monin, 2012). Maintaining a moral reputation is a major reason that meat eaters rate vegetarians negatively. They anticipate that vegetarians are judging them and will communicate their moral condemnation of meat eaters to others. Meat eaters rated vegetarians more negatively when they were first asked to consider how much vegetarians might judge them, and meat eaters expected vegetarians to judge them three times more negatively than they were actually judged (Minson and Monin, 2012). Of course, it’s possible that because being judgmental is widely considered immoral, vegetarians were reporting less judgment than they actually felt. One interesting aspect of the Minson and Monin (2012) study was that some meat eaters were first given an opportunity to say what they thought about vegans before later reporting how much they agreed with their moral message. Participants in the study described vegetarians as ‘weird’, ‘preachy’, and ‘sadistic’. But afterward they were more likely than other participants who did not derogate vegetarians to say that they agreed with the moral message of vegetarianism. This is interesting from an evolutionary reputationmanagement perspective. Reducing someone else’s reputational status relative to your own might increase your likelihood of taking their message seriously; you don’t have to fight as hard to make yourself look good. Moral change often happens when we want to socially affiliate with others, and negative impressions of activists – from animal advocates to social-justice advocates – undermines the cause (Bashir et al., 2013). Importantly, for any moral advocate, they must remember that others are going to have strong incentives to derogate them and will scrutinize them for moral inconsistency (Monin, 2007). Anyone advocating a major change in moral priorities must remember that people have spent years honing their virtue-signaling strategies,
162
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
and will not take kindly to someone arguing that they have really been hugely less virtuous than they thought. The evolutionary psychological challenge for animal advocacy is to nudge people to show more concern for animal suffering, without feeling like their whole virtue-signaling identity has to be jettisoned and rebuilt from scratch.
CONCLUSION Evolutionary explanations are often maligned because they are said to excuse or normalize violence. To say animal cruelty and inflicting animal suffering is normal and natural is not to minimize the suffering of animal victims either as the result of any individual’s sadism or the large-scale production of animal products. To say that our nurturing instincts predispose us to be kinder to animals that demonstrate kinship cues or that elicit the cuteness response is not to say that these responses are moral. To say that we are more disgusted by meat that looks more like the animal it came from than meat that looks more abstract is not to say it is more moral to eat meat packaged in cellophane. And to say that we virtue signal about our moral behavior is not to say that moral behavior isn’t important or that cynical motivations render moral behavior immoral. When we take our moral intuitions as moral rules we project and institutionalize our evolved moral blind spots into the world, often making it worse for others. Advocacy requires understanding. If animal suffering is an ethical issue, we have to be realistic about our incentives to signal, our functional emotional responses and what comprises our evolved moral psychology towards animals.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS For helpful feedback, thanks to Hal Herzog, Geoffrey Miller, and Todd Shackelford.
REFERENCES Ahimsa in Jainism. (2019). In Wikipedia. https:// en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Ahimsa_ in_Jainism&oldid=929905870 (Accessed 4 January 2020) Amiot, C. E., & Bastian, B. (2015). Toward a psychology of human–animal relations. Psychological Bulletin, 141(1), 6–47. Appel, M., & Elwood, R. W. (2009). Motivational trade-offs and potential pain experience in hermit crabs. Applied Animal Behaviour Science, 119(1–2), 120–124. Arluke, A. (2002). Animal abuse as dirty play. Symbolic Interaction, 25(4), 405–430. Awad, E., Dsouza, S., Kim, R., Schulz, J., Henrich, J., Shariff, A., Bonnefon, J.-F., & Rahwan, I. (2018). The moral machine experiment. Nature, 563(7729), 59. Bandura, A. (1999). Moral disengagement in the perpetration of inhumanities. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 3(3), 193–209. Bashir, N. Y., Lockwood, P., Chasteen, A. L., Nadolny, D., & Noyes, I. (2013). The ironic impact of activists: Negative stereotypes reduce social change influence. European Journal of Social Psychology, 43(7), 614–626. Birch, L. L. (1999). Development of food preferences. Annual Review of Nutrition, 19(1), 41–62. Bittman, M. (2008, January 27). Rethinking the Meat-Guzzler. The New York Times. www. nytimes.com/2008/01/27/weekinreview/ 27bittman.html (Accessed 4 January 2020) Bloom, P. (2017). Against empathy: The case for rational compassion. Random House. Bockman, J. (2016, November 1). Why Farmed Animals? Animal Charity Evaluators. https:// animalcharityevaluators.org/donationadvice/why-farmed-animals/ (Accessed 4 January 2020) Bostrom, N. (2016). Superintelligence: Paths, dangers, strategies. UK, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bradshaw, J. W., & Paul, E. S. (2010). Could empathy for animals have been an adaptation in the evolution of Homo sapiens. Animal Welfare, 19(1), 107–112. Braithwaite, V. (2010). Do fish feel pain? OUP Oxford. http://books.google.co.uk/books?
ANIMAL ETHICS AND EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
hl=en&lr=&id=aMvonPqzu_cC&oi=fnd& pg=PT2&dq=do+fish+feel+pain&ots=tjbXOJy C5x&sig=oU0xqgrjKN3RQfRll99esQfMxEI (Accessed 4 January 2020) Bryant, C., & Barnett, J. (2018). Consumer acceptance of cultured meat: A systematic review. Meat Science, 143, 8–17. Bryant, C. J., Szejda, K., Deshpande, V., Parekh, N., & Tse, B. (2019). A survey of consumer perceptions of plant-based and clean meat in the USA, India, and China. Frontiers in Sustainable Food Systems, 3, 11. Carzon, P., Delfour, F., Dudzinski, K., Oremus, M., & Clua, É. (2019). Cross-genus adoptions in delphinids: One example with taxonomic discussion. Ethology, 125(9), 669–676. https://doi.org/10.1111/eth.12916 Caviola, L. (2019). How we value animals: The psychology of speciesism [University of Oxford]. https://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:9000a8beb6dc-4c63-88e8-974b9daaa83a (Accessed 4 January 2020) Caviola, L., Everett, J. A., & Faber, N. S. (2019). The moral standing of animals: Towards a psychology of speciesism. Journal of personality and social psychology, 116(6), 1011. Churchill, W. (1932). Fifty years hence. Thoughts and adventures, 24–27. Thornton Butterworth London. Clark, M. (2019, October 15). What Are We Supposed to Think About Shrimp? The New York Times. www.nytimes.com/2019/10/15/ dining/shrimp-sourcing-united-states.html (Accessed 4 January 2020) Cohen, R. (2009, July 15). Nesting Blues. The New York Times. www.nytimes.com/2009/ 07/19/magazine/19FOB-ethicist-t.html (Accessed 4 January 2020) Cooney, N. (2014). Veganomics: The surprising science on vegetarians, from the breakfast table to the bedroom. Herndon Virginia USA: Lantern Books. Dahlgreen, W. (2013, August 5). No British Demand for Fake Meat. YouGov. https:// yougov.co.uk/news/2013/08/05/no-demandfake-meat/ (Accessed 4 January 2020) Diamond, J. (1993). New Guineans and their natural world. The biophilia hypothesis, 251–271. Island Press Washington DC. Elwood, R. W. (2011). Pain and suffering in invertebrates? Ilar Journal, 52(2), 175–184.
163
Fessler, D. M. T., Arguello, A. P., Mekdara, J. M., & Macias, R. (2003). Disgust sensitivity and meat consumption: A test of an emotivist account of moral vegetarianism. Appetite, 41(1), 31–41. Fessler, D. M. T., & Navarrete, C. D. (2003). Meat is good to taboo: Dietary proscriptions as a product of the interaction of psychological mechanisms and social processes. Journal of Cognition and Culture, 3(1), 1–40. https:// doi.org/10.1163/156853703321598563 Fiddes, N. (2004). Meat: A natural symbol. Abingdon Oxfordshire: Routledge. Fitzgerald, A. J., Kalof, L., & Dietz, T. (2009). Slaughterhouses and increased crime rates: An empirical analysis of the spillover from ‘The Jungle’ into the surrounding community. Organization & Environment, 22(2), 158–184. Fleischman, D. S. (2012, May 16). Lab Meat: Survey Results. The Vegan Option. http:// theveganoption.org/2012/05/16/lab-meatsurvey-results/ (Accessed 4 January 2020) Fleischman, D. S. (2013, August 5). Will Clean Meat Become Cruelty Free? Sentientist. https://dianaverse.com/2020/04/29/willclean-meat-become-cruelty-free-repost/ (Accessed 4 January 2020) Fleischman, D. S. (2018, May 17). Universal Morality Is Obscured by Evolved Morality. The Evolution Institute. https://evolutioninstitute.org/universal-morality-is-obscuredby-evolved-morality/ (Accessed 1 May 2020) Flynn, C. P. (2011). Examining the links between animal abuse and human violence. Crime, Law and Social Change, 55(5), 453–468. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10611-011-9297-2 Foster, K. R., Wenseleers, T., & Ratnieks, F. L. (2006). Kin selection is the key to altruism. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 21(2), 57–60. Fox Hunting. (2019). In Wikipedia. https:// en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Fox_ hunting&oldid=933138160 (Accessed 2 January 2020) Francione, G. L. (2009). Animals as persons. New York: Columbia University Press. Francione, G. L. (2015). Animal rights: The abolitionist approach. Louisville, Kentucky: Exempla Press. Frank, H., & Frank, M. G. (1982). On the effects of domestication on canine social development and behavior. Applied Animal Ethol-
164
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
ogy, 8(6), 507–525. https://doi.org/ 10.1016/0304-3762(82)90215-2 Beauchamp, T. L., & Frey, R. G. (Eds.). (2011). The Oxford handbook of animal ethics. Oxford University Press. Oxford, UK. 172–198. Funk, C., Rainie, L., Smith, A., Olmstead, K., Duggan, M., & Page, D. (2015). Attitudes and Beliefs on Science and Technology Topics. Pew Research Center. www.pewresearch. org/science/2015/01/29/chapter-3-attitudesand-beliefs-on-science-and-technologytopics/ (Accessed 4 January 2020) Ghirlanda, S., Acerbi, A., Herzog, H., & Serpell, J. (2013). Fashion vs. function in cultural evolution: The case of dog breed popularity. PLoS One, 8(9), e74770. Greene, J. D. (2013). Moral tribes: Emotion, reason, and the gap between us and them. London, UK: Penguin. Gullone, E. (2014). An evaluative review of theories related to animal cruelty. Journal of Animal Ethics, 4(1), 37–57. Haidt, J. (2006). The happiness hypothesis: Finding modern truth in ancient wisdom. New York, USA Basic Books. Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind: Why good people are divided by religion and politics. New York: Pantheon Books. http://media. matthewsbooks.com.s3.amazonaws.com/ documents/tocwork/030/9780307377906. pdf (Accessed 4 January 2020) Herzog, H. (2002). Darwinism and the study of human–animal interactions. Society & Animals, 10(4), 361–367. https://doi.org/ 10.1163/156853002320936818 Herzog, H. (2007). Gender differences in human–animal interactions: A review. Anthrozoös, 20(1), 7–21. Herzog, H. (2010). Some we love, some we hate, some we eat: Why it’s so hard to think straight about animals (Reprint edition). HarperCollins e-books. Herzog, H. (2011, June 20). Why Do Most Vegetarians Go Back to Eating Meat? Animals and Us. www.psychologytoday.com/blog/ animals-and-us/201106/why-do-most- vegetarians-go-back-eating-meat (Accessed 4 January 2020) Herzog, H. (2014). Biology, culture, and the origins of pet-keeping. Animal Behavior and Cognition, 1(3), 296–308.
Herzog, H. (2019, August 6). Did BreastFeeding Play a Role in the Evolution of Pets? Psychology Today. www.psychologytoday. com/blog/animals-and-us/201908/didbreast-feeding-play-role-in-the-evolutionpets (Accessed 4 January 2020) Herzog, H., & Arluke, A. (2006). Human– animal connections: Recent findings on the anthrozoology of cruelty. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 29(3), 230–231. Herzog, K. (2019, December 2). Genetic Freak Wins National Dog Show. The Stranger. www. thestranger.com/slog/2019/12/02/42155095/ genetic-freak-wins-national-dog-show (Accessed 4 January 2020) Hirsh-Pasek, K., & Treiman, R. (1982). Doggerel: Motherese in a new context. Journal of Child Language, 9(1), 229–237. Hodal, K., & Lawrence, C. K. F. (2014, June 10). Revealed: Asian Slave Labour Producing Prawns for Supermarkets in US, UK. The Guardian. www.theguardian.com/globaldevelopment/2014/jun/10/supermarketprawns-thailand-produced-slave-labour (Accessed 4 January 2020) Holden, C. J., & Herzog, H. (2019). Featherless chickens and puppies that glow in the dark. In K. Dhont & G. Hodson (Eds.), Why we love and exploit animals: Bridging insights from academia and advocacy. Abingdon, Oxfordshire: Routledge. 137–153. Howard, B. C. (2016, June 21). Dog Meat Festival Opens Amid Outrage. National Geographic News. www.nationalgeographic. com/news/2016/06/china-yulin-dog-meatfestival-controversy/ (Accessed 4 January 2020) Hurford, P. (2014, May 31). How Much Suffering Is in the Standard American Diet? Everyday Utilitarian. www.everydayutilitarian.com/ essays/how-much-suffering-is-in-the-standard-american-diet/ (Accessed 4 January 2020) Izar, P., Verderane, M. P., Visalberghi, E., Ottoni, E. B., Gomes De Oliveira, M., Shirley, J., & Fragaszy, D. (2006). Cross-genus adoption of a marmoset (Callithrix jacchus) by wild capuchin monkeys (Cebus libidinosus): Case report. American Journal of Primatology: Official Journal of the American Society of Primatologists, 68(7), 692–700. Joy, M. (2003). Psychic numbing and meat consumption: The psychology of carnism.
ANIMAL ETHICS AND EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
(Unpublished dissertation). Saybrook Graduate School, NY. Joy, M. (2011). Why we love dogs, eat pigs, and wear cows: An introduction to carnism. Newburyport, Massachusetts: Conari Press. Kahane, G. (2009). Pain, dislike and experience. Utilitas, 21(3), 327–336. Kaminski, J., Waller, B. M., Diogo, R., Hartstone-Rose, A., & Burrows, A. M. (2019). Evolution of facial muscle anatomy in dogs. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 116(29), 14677–14681. Kasperbauer, T. J. (2015). Rejecting empathy for animal ethics. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 18(4), 817–833. https://doi. org/10.1007/s10677-014-9557-1 Kearney, J. (2010). Food consumption trends and drivers. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 365(1554), 2793–2807. https:// doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2010.0149 Krupp, D. B., DeBruine, L. M., & Jones, B. C. (2011). Cooperation and conflict in the light of kin recognition systems. The Oxford Handbook of Evolutionary Family Psychology. Oxford. UK: Oxford University Press. 345–362. Kurzban, R. (2011). Why everyone (else) is a hypocrite: Evolution and the modular mind. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Kurzban, R., Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (2001). Can race be erased? Coalitional computation and social categorization. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 98(26), 15387–15392. Lew-Levy, S., Reckin, R., Lavi, N., CristóbalAzkarate, J., & Ellis-Davies, K. (2017). How do hunter-gatherer children learn subsistence skills? Human Nature, 28(4), 367–394. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12110-017-9302-2 Lieberman, D., Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (2007). The architecture of human kin detection. Nature, 445(7129), 727–731. Lindemann, B., Ogiwara, Y., & Ninomiya, Y. (2002). The discovery of umami. Chemical Senses, 27(9), 843–844. Machan, T. R. (2004). Putting humans first: Why we are nature’s favorite. Lanham Maryland USA: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. MacInnis, C. C., & Hodson, G. (2017). It ain’t easy eating greens: Evidence of bias toward vegetarians and vegans from both source
165
and target. Group Processes & Intergroup Relations, 20(6), 721–744. Madrigal, A. C. (2013, August 6). Chart: When Will We Eat Hamburgers Grown in Test Tubes? The Atlantic. www.theatlantic.com/ technology/archive/2013/08/chart-whenwill-we-eat-hamburgers-grown-in-testtubes/278405/ (Accessed 4 January 2020) Marino, L. (2019). I am not an animal. Animal Sentience, 3(23), 40. Masci, D. (2017, February 22). 20 Years after Dolly the Sheep’s Debut, Americans Remain Skeptical of Cloning. Pew Research Center. www.pewresearch.org/fact-tank/2017/ 02/22/20-years-after-dolly-the-sheepsdebut-americans-remain-skeptical-of- cloning/ (Accessed 4 January 2020) McLaren, M. E. (2014). Cultured Meat: A Beneficial, Crucial, and Inevitable Nutrition Technology. Seton Hall University. Law School Student Scholarship. 527. http:// scholarship.shu.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi? article=1527&context=student_scholarship (Accessed 4 January 2020) Miller, G. (2019). Virtue signaling: Essays on Darwinian politics & free speech. Albuquerque, New Mexico: Cambrian Moon. Minson, J. A., & Monin, B. (2012). Do-gooder derogation: Disparaging morally motivated minorities to defuse anticipated reproach. Social Psychological and Personality Science, 3(2), 200–207. Mohorčich, J. (2018). What Can the Adoption of GM Foods Teach Us about the Adoption of Other Food Technologies? Sentience Institute. https://sentienceinstitute.org/gm-foods (Accessed 4 January 2020) Monin, B. (2007). Holier than me? Threatening social comparison in the moral domain. Revue Internationale de Psychologie Sociale, 20(1), 53–68. Mood, A., & Brooke, P. (2010). Estimating the number of fish caught in global fishing each year. http://fishcount.org.uk/published/std/ fishcountstudy.pdf (Accessed 4 January 2020) Moore, D. C. (2003). Public Lukewarm on Animal Rights. Gallup. https://news.gallup. com/poll/8461/Public-Lukewarm-AnimalRights.aspx (Accessed 4 January 2020) Nakajima, S., Yamamoto, M., & Yoshimoto, N. (2009). Dogs look like their owners: Replications with racially homogenous owner
166
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
portraits. Anthrozoös, 22(2), 173–181. https://doi.org/10.2752/175303709X434194 Norwood, F. B., & Lusk, J. (2011). Compassion, by the pound: The economics of farm animal welfare. Oxford UK: Oxford University Press. Pachirat, T. (2011). Every twelve seconds: Industrialized slaughter and the politics of sight. Yale University Press. New Haven: Connecticut. Park, J. H., & Ackerman, J. M. (2011). Passion and compassion: Psychology of kin relations within and beyond the family. In Salmon, C., & Shackelford, T. K. (Eds.) (2011). The Oxford handbook of evolutionary family psychology. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Park, J. H., & Schaller, M. (2005). Does attitude similarity serve as a heuristic cue for kinship? Evidence of an implicit cognitive association. Evolution and Human Behavior, 26(2), 158– 170. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.evolhumbehav. 2004.08.013 Parlapiano, A. (2019, September 3). Why Euthanasia Rates at Animal Shelters Have Plummeted. The New York Times. www. nytimes.com/2019/09/03/upshot/why-eutha nasia-rates-at-animal-shelters-have-plummeted.html (Accessed 4 January 2020) Patterson-Kane, E. G., & Piper, H. (2009). Animal abuse as a sentinel for human violence: A critique. Journal of Social Issues, 65(3), 589–614. https://doi.org/10.1111/ j.1540-4560.2009.01615.x Paul, A. S., Lusk, J. L., Norwood, F. B., & Tonsor, G. T. (2019). An experiment on the vote-buy gap with application to cage-free eggs. Journal of Behavioral and Experimental Economics, 79, 102–109. https://doi.org/10.1016/j. socec.2019.02.005 PeTAUK (2019). These 27 Countries Have Banned Wild-Animal Circuses! [Blog Post]. https://www.peta.org.uk/blog/these-26countries-that-have-banned-wild-animalcircuses-are-making-england-look-reallybad/ (Accessed 6 July, 2020) Petrinovich, L., O’Neill, P., & Jorgensen, M. (1993). An empirical study of moral intuitions: Toward an evolutionary ethics. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 64(3), 467. Pets Really Are Members of the Family. (2011, June 10). The Harris Poll. https://theharrispoll. com/americans-have-always-had-interestingrelationships-with-their-pets-whether-that-
pet-is-a-cat-dog-parakeet-or-somethingelse-the-pet-industry-is-thriving-and-forgood-reason-more-than-three-in-f/ (Accessed 4 January 2020) Pinker, S. (2011). The better angels of our nature: The decline of violence in history and its causes. London, UK: Penguin. https://books. google.co.uk/books?hl=en&lr=&id=c3cWaGnsfMC&oi=fnd&pg=PT11&dq=better+angel s+of+our+nature&ots=aKhKguUK8a&sig=iKN 0Khly8JAx42B3LcJu30My-m8 Rauch, A., & Sharp, J. S. (2005). Ohioans’ attitudes about animal welfare. Social Responsibility Initiative. Department of Human and Community Resource Development. The Ohio State University. Reese, J. (2017). Animal Farming Attitudes Survey 2017. Sentience Institute. www.sentienceinstitute.org/animal-farming-attitudessurvey-2017 (Accessed 4 January 2020) Reese, J. (2018, June 25). 3 Big Changes We Need in the Farmed Animal Movement. Sentience Institute. www.sentienceinstitute.org/ blog/three-big-changes (Accessed 4 January 2020) Reese, J. (2019). US Factory Farming Estimates. Sentience Institute. www.sentienceinstitute. org/us-factory-farming-estimates (Accessed 4 January 2020) Regan, T. (2004). The case for animal rights. Oakland, California: University of California Press. Riffkin, R. (2015, May 18). In U.S., More Say Animals Should Have Same Rights as People. Gallup. https://news.gallup.com/poll/183275/ say-animals-rights-people.aspx (Accessed 4 January 2020) Roy, M. M., & Nicholas, J. S. C. (2004). Do dogs resemble their owners? Psychological Science, 15(5), 361–363. https://doi.org/10.1111/ j.0956-7976.2004.00684.x Rozin, P., Markwith, M., & Stoess, C. (1997). Moralization and becoming a vegetarian: The transformation of preferences into values and the recruitment of disgust. Psychological Science, 8(2), 67. Ryder, R. D. (1991). Souls and sentientism. Between the Species: An Online Journal for the Study of Philosophy and Animals, 7(1) 1–5. https://doi.org/10.15368/bts.1991v7n1.1 Saad, L. (2010, May 26). Four Moral Issues Sharply Divide Americans. Gallup. https://
ANIMAL ETHICS AND EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
news.gallup.com/poll/137357/Four-Moral-IssuesSharply-Divide-Americans.aspx (Accessed 4 January 2020) Sandøe, P., Kondrup, S. V., Bennett, P. C., Forkman, B., Meyer, I., Proschowsky, H. F., Serpell, J. A., & Lund, T. B. (2017). Why do people buy dogs with potential welfare problems related to extreme conformation and inherited disease? A representative study of Danish owners of four small dog breeds. PLoS One, 12(2), e0172091. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0172091 Santos, M. L. S., & Booth, D. A. (1996). Influences on meat avoidance among British students. Appetite, 27(3), 197–205. Scott-Phillips, T. C., Dickins, T. E., & West, S. A. (2011). Evolutionary theory and the ultimate– proximate distinction in the human behavioral sciences. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 6(1), 38–47. https://doi.org/10.1177/ 1745691610393528 Sentientism. (2019). In Wikipedia. https:// en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Sentienti sm&oldid=926119747 (Accessed 4 January 2020) Serpell, J. (1996). In the company of animals: A study of human-animal relationships. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Serpell, J. (2019). How happy is your pet? The problem of subjectivity in the assessment of companion animal welfare. Animal Welfare, 28(1), 57–66. https://doi.org/10.7120/ 09627286.28.1.057 Sherman, G. D., & Haidt, J. (2011). Cuteness and disgust: The humanizing and dehumanizing effects of emotion. Emotion Review, 3(3), 245–251. https://doi.org/10.1177/ 1754073911402396 Shostak, M., & Nisa. (2004). Nisa: The life and words of a !Kung woman. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Simler, K., & Hanson, R. (2017). The elephant in the brain: Hidden motives in everyday life. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Singer, P. (1995). Animal liberation. Random House. Singer, P. (2011). The expanding circle: Ethics, evolution, and moral progress. Princeton: Princeton University Press. http://books. google.co.uk/books?hl=en&lr=&id=Yve7lgvt LcsC&oi=fnd&pg=PP2&dq=the+expanding+ c irc le & ot s=5L e S l Yq g O j & s i g = 2 U l L 4 8 I p LqC-MKX7_s10Q0PjvnA
167
Singer, P., & Mason, J. (2006). The ethics of what we eat. Melbourne: Text Publishing. Sneddon, L. U., Braithwaite, V. A., & Gentle, M. J. (2003). Novel object test: Examining nociception and fear in the rainbow trout. The Journal of Pain, 4(8), 431–440. Sperber, D., & Baumard, N. (2012). Moral reputation: An evolutionary and cognitive perspective. Mind & Language, 27(5), 495–518. Steinfeld, H., Gerber, P., Wassenaar, T. D., Castel, V., Rosales, M., Rosales, M., & de Haan, C. (2006). Livestock’s long shadow: environmental issues and options. Food & Agriculture Org. https://books.google.co.uk/ books?id=1B9LQQkm_qMC&lpg=PP1&ots= LO1XiY7OlI&dq=livestock’s%20long%20sha dow&lr&pg=PP1#v=onepage&q&f=false Strauss, M. (2018, August 16). Americans Divided over Use of Animals in Scientific Research. Pew Research Center. www. pewresearch.org/fact-tank/2018/08/16/ a m e r i c a n s - a re - d i v i d e d - o v e r- t h e - u s e of-animals-in-scientific-research/ (Accessed 4 January 2020) Testing Cosmetics on Animals. (2019). In Wikipedia. https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index. php?title=Testing_cosmetics_on_animals& oldid=929257214 (Accessed 4 January 2020) Tomasik, B. (2017, August 17). Suffering in Animals vs. Humans. Reducing Suffering. https:// reducing-suffering.org/suffering-in-animalsvs-humans/ (Accessed 4 January 2020) Tomasik, B. (2018a, September 20). Bacteria, Plants, and Graded Sentience. Reducing Suffering. https://reducing-suffering.org/ bacteria-plants-and-graded-sentience/ (Accessed 4 January 2020) Tomasik, B. (2018b, July 14). How Much Direct Suffering Is Caused by Various Animal Foods? Reducing Suffering. https://reducingsuffering.org/how-much-direct-suffering-iscaused-by-various-animal-foods/ (Accessed 4 January 2020) Tomasik, B. (2019, July 21). Is Brain Size Morally Relevant? Reducing Suffering. https://reducing-suffering.org/is-brain-sizemorally-relevant/ (Accessed 4 January 2020) Tomasula, D. (2001, July 26). PETA Says Eat a Whale, Save a Pig. DMNews.Com. www. dmnews.com/marketing-channels/direct-mail/
168
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
news/13088690/peta-says-eat-a-whalesave-a-pig (Accessed 4 January 2020) Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (1989). Evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture, part I: Theoretical considerations. Ethology and Sociobiology, 10(1–3), 29–49. Topolski, R., Weaver, J. N., Martin, Z., & McCoy, J. (2013). Choosing between the emotional dog and the rational pal: A moral dilemma with a tail. Anthrozoös, 26(2), 253–263. https://doi.org/10.2752/175303713X13636 846944321 Turner, W. G. (2001). Our new children: The surrogate role of companion animals in women’s lives. The Qualitative Report, 6(1), 1–10. Tybur, J. M., Lieberman, D., Kurzban, R., & DeScioli, P. (2013). Disgust: Evolved function and structure. Psychological Review, 120(1), 65. Urquiza-Haas, E. G., & Kotrschal, K. (2015). The mind behind anthropomorphic thinking: Attribution of mental states to other species. Animal Behaviour, 109, 167–176. https:// doi.org/10.1016/j.anbehav.2015.08.011 Vollum, S., Longmire, D., & Buffington-Vollum, J. (2004). Moral disengagement and attitudes about violence toward animals. Society & Animals, 12(3), 209–235. Walker, J. K., McGrath, N., Nilsson, D. L., Waran, N. K., & Phillips, C. J. (2014). The role of gender in public perception of whether animals can experience grief and other emotions. Anthrozoös, 27(2), 251–266. Waller, B. M., Peirce, K., Caeiro, C. C., Scheider, L., Burrows, A. M., McCune, S., & Kaminski, J.
(2013). Paedomorphic facial expressions give dogs a selective advantage. PLoS One, 8(12), e82686. Wiblin, R., & Bollard, L. (2017, September 27). Why we must end factory farming as soon as possible – and how to do it [Interview]. https://80000hours.org/podcast/episodes/ lewis-bollard-end-factory-farming/ (Accessed 4 January 2020) Wilks, M., & Phillips, C. J. (2017). Attitudes to in vitro meat: A survey of potential consumers in the United States. PloS One, 12(2). https:// jour nals.plos.org/plosone/article/file? type=printable&id=10.1371/journal.pone. 0171904 (Accessed 4 January 2020) Wilson, E. O. (1984). Biophilia: The human bond with other species. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Witwicki, K. (2017). Social Movement Lessons From the British Antislavery Movement: Focused on Applications to the Movement Against Animal Farming. Sentience Institute. www.sentienceinstitute.org/british-antislavery (Accessed 4 January 2020) Wrangham, R. (2009). Catching fire: How cooking made us human. New York: Basic Books. https://books.google.co.uk/books? hl=en&lr=&id=ebEOupKz-rMC&oi=fnd&pg=P R5&dq=humans+evolved+eating+meat &ots=sVRt8Y8NLS&sig=2a3UdxIPEq_Crn BKY0XK8O5hGrI Zaraska, M. (2016). Meathooked: The history and science of our 2.5-million-year obsession with meat. New York: Basic Books.
PART 2
Applications to Law and Order
This page intentionally left blank
8 Evolutionary Psychology and Political Institutions Michael Latner and Elissa Feld
Biology and political science have a long, symbiotic relationship in their shared focus on conflict and cooperation between organisms. Many of the major puzzles in biology and political science, from the emergence of cooperation, and the threat of parasitism and selfishness, to the dynamics of collective decision making and the evolution of morality, are interwoven in early, pre-Darwinian works. As these areas of study developed into separate professional disciplines in the early 20th century, they would part ways with considerable tension before returning to such fundamentals with the advent of modern evolutionary psychology. In this chapter, we survey the literature surrounding three major areas where the study of political institutions and evolutionary psychology intersect: the evolution of cooperation at the micro-level; the emergence of complex political systems; and democracy as a major evolutionary transition in nature.
THE EVOLUTION OF COOPERATION The Scottish Enlightenment, especially the work of David Hume, had a significant influence on James Madison’s theory of republican government (Mclean, 2005). Hume’s discourses on competition and selective retention would figure prominently in Madison’s constitutionaldesign principles, especially his commitment to design institutions responsive enough to ‘guard against the cabals of a few’ but not subject to so much ‘mutability’ and ‘incessant changes’ that ‘no man who knows what the law is today can guess what it will be tomorrow’ (Palmer, 2002: 109). Hume’s concern about the degenerative effects of extreme elements in political competition, as well as the capacity for such diverse interests to be ‘serviceable’ to the public interest, would be fully developed in Madison’s writings on faction, the modern study of political institutions, and constitutional design (Madison et al., [1788]2008).
172
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Charles Darwin studied both Hume and Madison’s contemporary, the Reverend Thomas Malthus, whose Essay on the Principle of Population (Malthus, [1798]2013) began to quantify the relationship between competition for resources and human-population growth (Hamilton et al., [1788]1998). Madison himself understood that the world would be ‘much indebted to’ Malthus for his work, though a decade before Malthus’ Principle was published, Madison had already been reflecting with Thomas Jefferson on the degenerative social effects of concentrated resources among the ‘idle rich’ and the potential threat of overpopulation (Madison, 1786; McCoy, 1980). The threat of parasitism on social prosperity and development was on the mind of these institutional reformers. The Principle of Population would also lead Darwin to the insight that with selection pressures under conditions of scarcity ‘favourable variations would tend to be preserved, and unfavourable ones to be destroyed. The results of this would be the formation of a new species. Here, then I had at last got a theory by which to work’ (Darwin, [1838]2011). Hume may have also been influential in the way that Madison and Darwin thought about the emergence of cooperative behavior within the context of group competition, an insight neglected by Malthus. Consider Hume’s account of the logic of reciprocity in his Treatise on Human Nature (Binmore, 1994: 261): I learn to do service to another, without bearing him any real kindness, because I foresee, that he will return my service in expectation of another of the same kind, and in order to maintain the same correspondence of good offices with me and others. And accordingly, after I have serv’d him … he is induced to do his part, as foreseeing the consequences of his refusal.
Darwin certainly recognized the dynamics of reciprocity at play in cooperative behavior and the dilemma of moral development. Darwin viewed morality as the highest principle of human development, but he also saw that in group competition the ‘bravest men’
who came to the front at war and ‘freely risked their lives for others, would on an average perish in larger number than other men’, producing fewer offspring (Darwin, 1876: 130). Immoral (selfish) actors would, on average, out-produce their braver comrades, eventually driving the trait of bravery out of the population. However, competition between groups could change the selective dynamics: It must not be forgotten that although a high standard of morality gives but a slight or no advantage to each individual man and his children over the other men of the same tribe, yet that an advancement in the standard of morality and an increase in the number of well-endowed men will certainly give an immense advantage to one tribe over another. (Darwin, 1876: 132)
This is the basis of the cooperation dilemma, and the question of how cooperative or ‘good’ traits could gain a selective advantage through social decisions was a central feature in early social choice theory. On that topic another contemporary of Madison, the Marquis de Condorcet, also played a major role. He formally showed that voters seeking the best collective decision for their group could rely on majority rule to most likely yield a ‘correct’ decision, if the probability of a voter being right was greater than 50%, and that the probability of a correct outcome approaches 100% as the size of the electorate increases (Young, 1988). Condorcet’s probabilistic explorations at least indirectly influenced Madison as well (Schofield, 2005b), specifically the proclamation in Federalist #10 that ‘If the proportion of fit characters be not less in the large than in the small republic, the former will present a greater option, and consequently a greater probability of a fit choice’. (Hamilton et al., [1788]1998). While many thinkers who subsequently took the mantle of ‘Darwinist’ would continue to think about evolution purely in terms of competition, following T. H. Huxley’s famous dictum that nature ‘is on about the same level as the gladiator’s show’ from the ‘point of view of the moralist’ (Kropotkin et al., 1955), others would focus on empirical observations of cooperation in nature and seek to explain them. In particular,
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS
the Russian naturalist Peter Kropotkin’s observations led him to believe that evolution was about combination as much as competition. He observed that reciprocity was widespread, even between species. Kropotkin’s analysis of social insects, parental behavior, and associative activities like pack hunting, integrated with an analysis of medieval guilds, led him to the conclusion that mutual aid was as much a law of nature as mutual struggle. In addition to anticipating much in the scientific study of altruism, Kropotkin’s Mutual Aid remains a foundational work of anarcho-communism (Kropotkin, 2017). J. B. S. Haldane (also a vocal communist) was perhaps the first to begin formalizing the link between genetic traits and sociality (Haldane, 1941). In The Causes of Evolution, Haldane first proposed that reciprocity could spread in a population if the genes determining it were carried by individuals whose offspring benefitted from the presence of the gene in their nearby relatives (Haldane, 1932). Similarly, R. A. Fisher, whose Genetical Theory of Natural Selection heralded the modern synthesis in evolutionary biology, focused considerable attention on how degrees of genetic relatedness affected individuals living in different types of populations (Fisher, [1930]2000). It is telling that the politically conservative Fisher was attracted to understanding how ‘distastefulness’ in insect larvae could spread in a population. He reasoned that nasty tasting larvae would provide increased protection for their siblings by driving away predators, such that the genetic benefit of an eaten larvae could be substantial. Perhaps Fisher’s politics motivated his interest in distastefulness: recent research suggests that sensitivity to disgust is linked to conservatism (Murray, 2012). Sadly, both Haldane and Fisher were advocates of eugenics (Haldane coined the term ‘cloning’ and Fisher headed the Department of Eugenics at University College London), but unlike Haldane, Fisher viewed the fall of civilizations as a function of declining fertility rates of the upper classes, and he was concerned about encouraging
173
allowances for large working-class families and those who possessed less ‘innate capacity for intellectual and emotional development’ (Fisher, [1930]2000). The greatest breakthrough, and the reunion of evolutionary biology and political science, began after W. D. Hamilton broke the code for kin selection (Hamilton, 1964a, 1964b). Adapting economic cost–benefit analysis, Hamilton showed how natural selection would allow for altruism to evolve while still maximizing individual fitness. In a series of articles, he demonstrated how natural selection can favor altruism between relatives when the product of the relatedness of individuals and the benefits of reciprocity outweigh the individual costs. The concept of inclusive fitness was born, as was Hamilton’s legacy as one of the greatest evolutionary theorists of the 20th century. The next giant step would be taken by Robert Trivers, who extended Hamilton’s work to non-kin reciprocity, such as bird warning calls, the symbiosis between cleaner and predator fish, and broader social interactions. His 1971 publication ‘The Evolution of Reciprocal Altruism’ showed how net benefits could be accrued between non-relatives through social exchange, and how cheating and spiteful behavior could be regulated through the evolution of moralistic aggression (Trivers, 1971). Trivers’ work opened new opportunities for the integration of the behavioral sciences, as he sketched out how the analysis could extend to complex, multi-party coordination, the emergence of norms and collective punishments (and rewards), generational return effects, and the like (Trivers, 2006). Soon after, John Maynard Smith (a student of Haldane) and George R. Price (a friend of Hamilton) would formalize the Evolutionarily Stable Strategy (ESS) and initiate evolutionary game theory in ‘The Logic of Animal Conflict’ (Smith and Price, 1973), directly addressing Darwin’s dilemma of moral development. An ESS is a strategy (social interaction where agents compete over a resource, such as food, with payoffs dependent on both
174
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
agents’ strategies) that is stable once it is fixed in a population. If agents will not do better (more offspring) by employing a different strategy, or perturbations from ‘mutant’ strategies cannot successfully invade and replace it, the trait becomes fixed in the population as the offspring of the winners replace those with lower payoffs. The ESS has not only become central to the explanation of human evolution in evolutionary psychology, it has been adopted in political science as a means of understanding evolution through institutions. That pivotal moment came when W. D. Hamilton teamed up with political scientist Robert Axelrod to publish ‘The Evolution of Cooperation’ in 1981 (Axelrod and Hamilton, 1981), one of the most cited publications in political science (Peress, 2019). Axelrod’s computer tournaments provided output for simulations using competing strategies in repeated Prisoner’s Dilemma (PD) games. In such games, both agents know they would do better if they cooperated, but the payoff is higher for individuals to defect rather than be exploited. Axelrod and Hamilton described how an eloquently simple logic of cooperation (essentially do unto others, the ‘Tit for Tat’ strategy submitted by anthropologist Anatol Rapaport) could emerge as an ESS, given a high-enough probability of future interaction between cooperative agents. Their analysis demonstrated how ‘the benefits of life are disproportionately available to cooperating groups’ and from it they drew several strategic considerations: • Be nice: don’t be the first to defect. • Be provocable: return defection for defection, cooperation for cooperation. • Don’t be envious: focus on maximizing your own ‘score’, as opposed to ensuring your score is higher than your ‘partner’s’. • Don’t be too clever: signal clarity is crucial.
Successive work on iterated PD has relaxed the highly simplifying assumptions built into the original model, continuing to produce important insights, including those about the importance of forgiveness and reputation (Nowak, 2006). Today, the study of
cooperation is a fertile interdisciplinary field, identifying multiple stable states of cooperation, the foundations of pro- and anti-social behavior, the crucial role of structured interaction, and the ways that institutions cultivate cooperation (Alford and Hibbing, 2004; Lopez, 2017; The Cooperative Human, 2018). One of the most relevant ongoing debates concerning institutional analysis has to do with the concept of ‘strong reciprocity’ and the role of institutions in sustaining cooperation. A body of scholars have challenged the orthodox view of the reciprocal altruist as self-regarding, developing an alternative model of group-beneficial pro-social behavior (Bowles et al., 2003; Bowles and Gintis, 2011; Fehr and Gächter, 2002; Henrich and Boyd, 1998). Whereas kin selection, reciprocal altruism, indirect reciprocity, and signaling explain behaviors that appear costly but are repaid to genetic relatives, the strongreciprocity hypothesis posits that a genuinely altruistic behavior can be adaptive, but critics are unconvinced (Burnham and Johnson, 2016). The answer to this controversy is immensely important for the design of political institutions, and it has rightly become a major focus of scientific attention (Abbot, et al., 2011; Ferriere and Michod, 2011; Herre and Wcislo, 2011; Nowak et al., 2010).
THE EMERGENCE OF COMPLEX POLITICAL SYSTEMS The use of biological metaphors to explain the emergence and persistence of political systems dates back at least to Thomas Hobbes’ Leviathan with its cover art of the Sovereign King, whose body is literally constituted by the multitude of citizens, obedient co-signers of the social contract, the body politic represented by one man (Hobbes, [1651]2009). Walter Bagehot’s ‘Physics and Politics’ was probably the first to explicitly apply Darwinian selection and inheritance concepts to political society (Bagehot, [1869]2009). Writing in
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS
1869, Bagehot made a case for liberal-democratic institutions having emerged from more conformist, dictatorial restraints as a moral achievement. The selective process had supposedly refined the nervous systems and moral capacity of ‘accomplished’ elites, creating opportunity for more complex decisionmaking institutions and social progress. Bagehot was also among the earliest in a long line of ‘Social Darwinists’ to leverage pseudo-scientific accounts of racial inequalities to justify an ideological theory of the state. John William Burgess similarly believed that only ‘superior’ races had acknowledged the moral ‘duties of civilization’ (Gunnell, 2004). Burgess established the US political science degree at Columbia University, where he taught comparative constitutional law, and his vision of political science emphasized the training of career government bureaucrats, as well as civic education as a sort of ‘democratic’ training, within the confines of his racist ideology. After World War I, and the embrace of scientific racism within fascism and Nazism during World War II, social Darwinism was largely discredited and abandoned by political science, at least publicly. Post-war social scientists turned to formal social choice and game theory as a framework to explain political institutions. Properties of social-decision rules, or ‘constitutional conditions’ in the words of Kenneth Arrow, where individual values are treated as inputs, became a focal point of analysis (Arrow, 1970). One of the most influential political scientists to emerge from this period was Robert Dahl, whose Arrow-inspired analysis of social choice procedures shaped our understanding of how popular sovereignty and political equality are instituted (Dahl, 1989, 2006). Nevertheless, Dahl’s image of the locus of democracy in US government as fluid, pluralist bargaining assumed an equilibrium of social consensus, with no direct focus on evolution or adaptation (Gunnell, 2004). Dissatisfied with the historical bent of most political science and unconvinced by Dahl’s group bargaining theory of political
175
behavior, David Easton’s theoretical explorations reflected his study of physiology and systems biology, specifically the concept of homeostasis and the capacity of evolved systems to react to environmental stimuli with equilibrating responses (Cannon, 1963). As a member of the University of Chicago’s Committee on the Behavioral Sciences, he was committed to the integration of biological and social scientific knowledge, co-authoring ‘Projects and Problems of Homeostatic Models in the Behavioral Sciences’ with psychologist James G. Miller and anthropologist Anatol Rapoport, among others, in 1953 (Fontaine, 2016). Easton’s work transformed the study of political institutions by nesting them within a living-systems framework. Easton was primarily interested in understanding how institutional arrangements regulate demands on a political system, shaping the way that social choices are put into effect as policy outcomes, which he elaborated in A Framework for Political Analysis and A Systems Analysis of Political Life (Easton, 1965, 1979). Among his many contributions to the study of institutions, Easton’s ideas about how regimes generate support through the allocation of biological and social resources, and regulation of social values, stand out (Easton, 1979). Easton was among the first to flesh out how emotive attachment to codified social roles, and the social status they yield, supply the behavioral energy upon which a political system depends for its survival. In the last few decades there has been increasing convergence of Easton’s macrolevel type of structural-constraints analysis and the micro-foundations of cooperative game theory. Formalization of political authority occurs when communicative artifacts, from mating and marriage practices to landtenure customs, nomenclature, measurement, and other forms of codification, instantiate a ‘high degree of mutual predictability’ with large-scale coordination of, and thus control over, the allocation of biological and social resources (Easton, 1979: 329). Just as valuable biological information is correlated
176
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
across generations through the germ line, institutional transmission of communicative artifacts sustains biocultural complexes that can greatly enhance the fitness of participants (Corning, 1995). Indeed, the production and management of knowledge is itself a commons dilemma (Frischmann et al., 2014). National constitutions are rules for strategy selection. That is, constitutional regimes operate to regulate social niche-construction strategies (Santa Fe Institute, 2016). As Brian Skyrms notes in Evolution of the Social Contract (2014), here strategies come to the fore as units of selection, and individuals recede into the background (much as genes do in the biological literature). The success of collectively selected strategies (laws) is based on their success as behavioral phenotypes, and how well populations converge on successful strategies of social interaction (Skyrms, 2014). Our understanding of institutions as carriers of cultural transmission has been built on decades of successful modeling of cooperation, complexity, and culture (Axelrod, 2006; Cavalli-Sforza and Feldman, 1981; Creanza and Feldman, 2014). Studies of the evolution of complexity show that, as regulators of niche construction, political institutions face some universal information-processing problems. For example, the tradeoff between exploring alternative strategies and reliance on the status quo is a general dilemma in organizational productivity (March, 1991). The ‘explore/ exploit’ dilemma arises from the inability to optimize both the exploration of potentially adaptive/productive strategies, and cashing in on the value of e xisting strategies. Without commitment to a strategy, a system can ‘boil’ in the endless search for optimal alternatives, but without generating variation there are fewer alternatives to optimize, making it less likely to find a better alternative than the status quo. In the context of political institutions these constraints correspond to the bounds of political authority and social choice. The potential range of participation in collective decision making for a population ranges from N (total
population) to one, or pure dictatorship. Both arrangements constitute cooperative regimes in the sense that in a regime of N decision makers, all preferences are taken into consideration, maximizing the communication channels and flow of information to be processed, but also coordination costs (the resources required to take everyone’s preferences into account) and potential ‘boiling’ as each individual does their own thing. Alternatively, pure dictatorship may be the least costly social choice mechanism in terms of coordination costs, but conformity costs (everyone obeys the dictator) tend to be extreme, in part because there is little effort to search the landscape for mutually beneficial strategies (Page, 2008; Zhou, 2011). This tradeoff maps closely onto the solutions typically proposed for the management of public goods, or the ‘tragedy of the commons’. Ecologist Garrett Hardin famously argued in several papers (around the same time that models of evolutionary cooperation were emerging) that species are generally unable to cooperate for the greater good (Hardin, 1968). In addition to being another Malthusian throwback who believed that those who won superior intellect through the genetic lottery (whites, of course) should deploy abortion and sterilization to maintain limited population growth because ‘freedom to breed will bring ruin to all’ (Hardin, 1968: 1248), he popularized the problem of maintaining public goods through his analogy of livestock management on shared grasslands, an iterated PD game emphasizing the freerider problem and defection as rational in the short term but irrational in the long run. Hardin’s solutions to the tragedy were either privatization and strong property rights, in order to incentivize individual owners to be stewards over their own land, or the very Hobbesiansounding ‘mutual coercion, mutually agreed upon’ typically interpreted as collectivization. Willfully or otherwise, Hardin was ignorant of the degree to which many commons were already being governed under ‘mutually coercive’ social structures that have evolved to
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS
manage the ‘explore/exploit’ dilemma without resorting to either strict privatization or collectivization. No individual has played as large a role in demonstrating the capacity of local organizations to manage common resources as Elinor Ostrom (Ostrom, 1990, 2010, 2013). While Ostrom’s work fits within the broader fields of political economy and organizational behavior (Levi, 1989; March and Olson, 1971; Olsen, 1976), her approach to core design principles, the Institutional Analysis and Development (IAD) framework, is distinctly Darwinian. Ostrom’s acceptance speech for the 2009 Nobel prize in economics, ‘Do Institutions Evolve?’, recounts decades of research she and colleagues have developed to understand how biophysical systems, participant heterogeneity, and operational rules shape the governance of commons (Ostrom, 2013). A set of ‘default’ rules highlights what Ostrom has discovered as core design principles: • • • • • • •
Clearly defined group boundaries Proportionally equivalent costs and benefits Collective-choice mechanisms Monitoring Graduated sanctions Fast and fair conflict resolution Polycentric governance (tiered rule-making)
The work of Ostrom and other political economists, including Douglas North, Margaret Levi, Barry Weingast, and Geoffrey Hodgson, has engendered a generalized Darwinian approach to the study of institutional change that stands independent of genetics and biology (Aldrich et al., 2008; Fürstenberg, 2016; Hodgson, 2004; Levi and Weingast, 2019; Wilson and Gowdy, 2013). We have learned much from empirical field studies that have demonstrated the adaptiveness of local communities, including tribal communities that Hardin surely would not have imagined were cooperatively stable. Large-scale societies require complex, adaptive institutions to transmit norms of conflict resolution and morality (Bowles et al., 2003; Bowles and Gintis, 2011; Ehrlich and Levin, 2005; Levin, 2014). Legal systems
177
exhibit properties that Walker and Davies (2012) characterize as an informational structure that gains causal efficacy over matter, in this case, behavior: they are explicit instructions, decontextualized from specific behaviors to classes of behaviors, applicable to classes of agents, designed to yield high levels of predictability (Bowles and Gintis, 2011; Boyer and Petersen, 2012). Rather than being directly transmitted, legal expectations are learned, deriving from hard-wired moral intuitions, but converted into ‘publicly scrutable processes’ that modify social interaction from the ‘top down’ (Boyer and Petersen, 2012). According to Boyer and Peterson, like our biophysical equipment, our evolved cognitive systems operate more reliably in matching environments (ideally the environment of evolutionary adaptedness). As a result, we are motivated to match our environments to those cognitive systems, while the modification of environmental niches creates and maintains selective pressures that favor adaptions matched to them (Laland et al., 1999). Richard Dawkins famously called this sort of niche construction The Extended Phenotype (Dawkins, 1999), based on the evolutionary logic that the quality of an environmental niche (a spider web, a beaver dam, a human settlement) is correlated with genetic variation, in that an allele for better niche construction enhances the fitness of the organisms expressing it. In an environment with good nest-building materials, the best nest builders will proliferate the genes for building nests with those materials, as their offspring increase in frequency through the population. Constitutional environments will likewise favor the selection and spread of behavior traits and cultural norms, such as a sense of justice, under constitutional conditions that favor it.
DEMOCRACY: A MAJOR EVOLUTIONARY TRANSITION? Representative democracy encompasses a range of regimes that have emerged quite
178
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
recently on the human scene, possibly in response to the conformity costs imposed by more authoritarian, dictatorial regime structures (Latner, 2017). The core design principle of democracy is political equality, or fairness. Political theory on procedural justice has contributed to our understanding of cooperation at all levels of life through a sort of cross fertilization. Specifically, the political philosopher John Rawls’ concept of the ‘veil of ignorance’ played prominently in the social theory of another Michigan biologist, Richard D. Alexander (Alexander, 2017; Rawls, 1999). The basic logic is that if the only way to be sure one gets ahead is to promote rules that will improve overall welfare, fair laws should be favored for selection. What emerges is a society that applies laws equally to individuals regardless of their status, or justice as fairness. Alexander saw that the enforcement of mutualistic cooperation requires limiting opportunities for cheating, such that agents can only increase their success by increasing the success of others (Frank, 2013). He also saw how natural selection could favor the suppression of internal competition by drawing on the work of E. G. Leigh, probably the first modern biologist to use a political analogy, equating the genome to ‘a parliament of genes: each acts in its own self-interest, but if its acts hurt the others, they will combine together to suppress it’ (Leigh, 1971). Later analysis has supported the idea that the cellular infrastructure of meiosis in sexual reproduction is favored, in part, as a mechanism to thwart parasitic conflict at the genetic level (Burt and Trivers, 2008; Howard and Lively, 1994). Similarly, Alexander’s argument that socially imposed monogamy levels reproductive opportunity, and in doing so reduces the pool of unmarried men, has found support in research that shows monogamy is associated with reduced rates of homicide, rape, and related violence (Henrich et al., 2012). Bryan Skyrms’ Evolution of the Social Contract and later work brings us full circle through the evolution of cooperation
to the operation of constitutional structure (Skyrms, 2014). His eloquent essay ‘Sex and Justice’ (1994) compares the puzzle of sex ratios (which led to Fisher’s game-theoretic insights) to the evolution of justice. Skyrms shows how, like many observed sex ratios, fair division (50/50) is an attractive equilibrium in repeated interactions. Crucially, if interactions between more cooperative agents can be correlated (a higher probability that they interact with one another instead of greedy agents), then the cooperative norm ‘share and share alike’ becomes a stronger evolutionary attractor and will emerge as an ESS. Skyrms shows how mechanisms for the evolution of cooperation, from kin selection to ‘group’ selection, spatial interaction, and the repression of competition, are all linked to increasing correlation and cooperative association (Skyrms, 2014). Skyrms has also brought attention to the problem of ‘negative correlation’ and how spiteful behavior can be sustained through correlated interactions, such as when a reputation for ‘fighting too hard’ (to the detriment of self and opponent) may enable agents to win future contests more easily in repeated encounters (Skyrms, 2014). The likelihood that political equality is a fit alternative against dictatorial hierarchy and anarchy is empirically supported across a variety of fields. First, recent developments in social choice theory have confirmed that proportional representation, which most accurately translates votes into seats of political power, is the closest approximation to political equality in electoral-system design (Hout and McGann, 2009). Contemporary experimental tests further support Condorcet’s position that majority rule outperforms alternative strategies, including dictatorship (Hastie and Kameda, 2005; Sorkin et al., 1998), and regimes that more closely approximate political equality (PR and simple majority rule) tend toward greater redistribution and responsiveness, as predicted (Acemoglu et al., 2009; McGann and Latner, 2013). Representative assemblies, electoral systems, thresholds for legislative decision making and policy
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS
execution all reflect fundamental features of institutional niche construction and cooperative decision making (Latner, 2017). Steven Frank has, more than nearly any other evolutionary thinker, shown how the policing of competition, or reduction of opportunities for exploitative behavior, correlates individual payoffs and can sustain group cohesion (Frank, 2003, 2011, 2013). Reducing opportunities for exploitative behavior through political equality may result in both higher levels of redistributive sharing and flexible responsiveness in resource management, making it an evolutionary attractive equilibrium (McGann and Latner, 2013). The historical record is also supportive of the evolutionary democracy hypothesis. The number of regimes holding minimally free and fair elections has nearly doubled since 1990, from 69 to 122 according to Freedom House (‘Freedom in the World’, 2014). Moreover, among electoral democracies, major electoral reforms have been decisively in the direction of more proportional representation (Soudriette and Ellis, 2006). This follows the evolution from simple ‘originating’ systems in early electoral systems to electoral rules that reduced the frequency of single-party dominance that had emerged (Colomer, 2001, 2007). At the other extreme, hyper-permissive systems demonstrably produce greater instability in governing coalitions, lower cabinet duration, and greater difficulty committing to comprehensive policy platforms (Shugart and Wattenberg, 2001; Taagepera, 2007). Reforms in these systems have generally maintained proportionality along with consolidating legislative power in the direction of greater accountability (Shugart and Wattenberg, 2001). Of course, political institutions do not operate exogenously on behavior, independent of the complexity of other social systems. Population heterogeneity and inequality in social resources obviously shape institutional performance and the prospects of regime persistence. For example, cultural mutation and cycles of stability are highly sensitive to interactions between transmission, selection,
179
and assorting of populations. For example, Creanza and Feldman have considered education norms, specifically the belief that women should receive secondary education and delay childbirth (Creanza and Feldman, 2014). The probability of fixation of the belief is shaped by lower fertility among those women who take part, as well as lower infant mortality among the same families, and future sorting in offspring mating practices. Similar dynamics may impact the norm of democratic participation and investment in the considerable responsibilities of democratic citizenship, not to mention the interaction between education, socialization, and support for democratic institutions, especially for women (Fox and Lawless, 2014). Asymmetries between the (de jure) constitutional and (de facto) economic allocation of political power also shape the dynamics of regime stability. Daron Acemoglu and colleagues have produced a number of analyses proposing that the threat of upheaval and benefits of anticipated economic growth have been primary drivers of elite-led expansion in collective decision making (Acemoglu et al., 2009, 2011; Acemoglu and Robinson, 2013). Peter Turchin has proposed a broader model of democratic evolution that emphasizes the role of exogenous threats, with a similar sequencing that cooperation and enfranchisement are frequently followed by periods of economic inequity and political instability (Turchin, 2013, 2016). These and other analyses point toward higher potential for upheaval under greater economic inequality, when lower classes (and their offspring) feel they have nothing to lose, and when the prospective benefits of a major transition outweigh the perceived costs of disruption. The interplay of group conditions and specific conflict-reduction mechanisms can determine the fate of a regime’s future. If increasing inequality or prolonged economic stagnation fuel animosity between competing economic classes, it will lead to increased demand for the powerful to invest in economic and political mechanisms to better preserve common
180
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
goods, and consequently the stronger taking over more institutional control (Frank, 2011). Whether that control is more equitable or ‘extractive’ (parasitic) may in turn depend on the prior fixation of economic and cultural traits, like democratic norms among elites. Further, the adequacy of a political solution will depend on whether competition among reformers can be sustained and a coalition holds, for example by requiring coalition building within broad-based political parties, or whether fragmented interests and the work of compromise must be channeled into a representative assembly (Balinski and Young, 2001; Cox, 1997). In electoral system science, the general pattern that proportional electoral systems are associated with higher rates of women’s representation is a puzzle that requires consistency between macro- and micro-level explanations (Reynolds et al., 2005). One consistent model that has been applied to the puzzle is social contagion, where smaller parties in proportional systems differentiate themselves (at lower cost than under single-seat systems) by listing more women on party lists, driving larger parties to follow suit (Matland and Studlar, 1996). Several outlier systems such as Israel and Malta exhibit very low percentages of women in parliament despite using rather pure versions of PR, and incorporating models of variance in child-rearing strategies would provide a fuller understanding of these strategies (Lane, 1995; Rule, 1987). Evolutionary psychology has also contributed to our understanding of sex and gender dynamics in campaign and election studies. For example, a large body of research has demonstrated that men and women differ in candidate support based on factors like facial appearance and body image, with men preferring more attractive female candidates and women preferring approachable male candidates (Chiao et al., 2008; Dolan, 2014). However, electoral contexts interact with these abstract preferences in ways that shape vote choice, especially partisan signaling and contextual priming emphasizing either
intergroup conflict or cooperation, such that both masculine (conflict) and feminine (cooperation) traits can positively contribute to the perception of effective leadership traits (Dolan and Lynch, 2014; Grabo and van Vugt, 2018). The sub-field of evolutionary feminist studies is challenging stereotypes of bio-essentialism head on, and will surely aid our understanding of institutional design with relation to women’s and gender studies (Buss and Malamuth, 1996; Feminist Evolutionary Perspectives, 2019). Another example of the evolution of democracy is seen in contestation over voting rights in the United States. Epperly and colleagues have documented the dynamics at work in voter suppression as an exploitative form of ‘cooperation’ (Epperly et al., 2019). They show that under conditions of low state capacity and legibility (formalized authority through administrative records, etc.), as well as external constraints on state legislative suppression (the federal government), voter suppression under Reconstruction took the form of decentralized intimidation like lynching that peaked just before federal restraints on legalized suppression were relaxed, allowing Southern Democrats to re-take control of several state legislatures. In the mid 1890s, the inefficient and enforcement-costly strategy of lynching declined as the codified, more predictable discriminatory laws of Jim Crow (poll taxes, registration requirements, multiple-box voting, secret ballots, literacy tests, property tests, understanding clauses, grandfather clauses, and the white primary) came online. These electoral barriers on the representation and possible transmission of less oppressive social strategies kept the Southern caste system in place for several generations, and with it the cultural norms of segregation, revulsion at inter-racial marriage, and belief in the inherent inferiority of African Americans. The Civil Rights Movement, and Civil Rights Act of 1964, Voting Rights Act of 1965, and accompanying court cases marked a behavioral and legislative tipping point in
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS
electoral reforms to expand racial representation and socioeconomic opportunity in the United States (Davidson and Grofman, 1994). The cultural impact on norms has been substantial, but complex. While Jim Crow era norms have largely collapsed within the white population, and broad support for political equality has spread across all populations, support for government efforts to address segregation and other discriminatory practices is still frequently opposed (Bobo et al., 2012). Surviving racial stereotypes and negative views of racial minorities today tend to be based in characterizations of group culture, rather than biology (Bazian, 2016; Bobo et al., 2012; Kaufmann, 2019). Selective pressures, and the institutional regulation of cooperation and competition, have altered the fitness of racial norms. Over the last decade, Americans have experienced the consequences of relaxations on federal constraints with the weakening of the Voting Rights Act and reduced judicial oversight of discriminatory practices (Bentele and O’Brien, 2013; CNN, 2019; Keena et al., 2017). Predictably, attempts to discriminate against black voters and other groups are on the rise again, and as in the post-Reconstruction South, voter suppression is increasingly couched in terms of partisan calculations (Hasen, 2014). While existing laws arguably make these new efforts, which range from gerrymandering to voter list purging, voter ID laws, and proof of citizenship requirements, less effective than Jim Crow 1.0, there is little reason to believe that Jim Crow 2.0 will not become more egregious over time, or that efforts will not be made to restrict the franchise further if the Republican Party does not expand beyond its shrinking demographic base of support. In this event, the importance of evolutionary psychology is even more apparent, as scientists will need every tool at their disposal to educate and advocate for evidence-based policies to help inoculate the public, and fight back against the resurgence of racism and white nationalism in our electoral ecosystem.
181
CONCLUSION This brief summary of what the evolutionary approach has provided to our current understanding of institutional design and performance is far from exhaustive. But one final sign of the extent of recent integration between institutionalists and biologists that must be mentioned is the contributions that scholars of political institutions are making to biology. Political scientists are now researching animal institutions and collective decision making, a sure sign that the ‘life sciences’ properly understood are integrating under the umbrella of a generalized Darwinism (Akcay et al., 2013; Conradt and List, 2009). The claim that human behavior and institutions are not reducible to biological sciences is true insofar as we narrow biology to genetic studies or similar micro-level processes. But political institutions are emergent phenomena, have their own laws, and require their own sciences, just as the science of complexity is not reducible to molecular physics (Taagepera, 2008). Rather, unification posits that there be consistency between micro- and macro-behavioral explanations. For example, models of political institutions and partisan competition should not assume that agents value the welfare of others more than their own, that men and women are equally prone to engage in extra-constitutional, violent confrontation, or that conventions of masculinity and feminism have no biological roots. An even broader challenge, the levels of selection controversy over the relative importance of kin selection and reciprocity versus group selection, has animated all of evolutionary science, and might benefit from better incorporation of institutional theory. As already discussed, political institutions that mobilize, aggregate, synthesize, and select competing policy strategies provide a clear Darwinian process with which to study levels of selection, and the potential to trace return benefits and other return effects across generations.
182
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
REFERENCES Abbot, P. et. al. (2011). ‘Inclusive Fitness Theory and Eusociality’, Nature, 471: E1–E4. Retrieved from https://www.nature.com/articles/ nature09831?proof=true19 Acemoglu, D., Egorov, G., & Sonin, K. (2009). Political selection and persistence of bad governments (Working Paper No. 15230). Retrieved from National Bureau of Economic Research website: www.nber.org/papers/ w15230 Acemoglu, D., Egorov, G., & Sonin, K. (2011). Political model of social evolution. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 108(Supplement 4), 21292–21296. https:// doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1019454108 Acemoglu, D., & Robinson, J. (2013). Why nations fail: The origins of power, prosperity, and poverty (Reprint edition). New York: Crown Business. Akcay, E., Roughgarden, J., Fearon, J. D., Ferejohn, J. A., & Weingast, B. R. (2013). Biological institutions: The political science of animal cooperation (SSRN Scholarly Paper No. ID 2370952). Retrieved from Social Science Research Network website: http:// papers.ssrn.com/abstract=2370952 Aldrich, H. E., Hodgson, G. M., Hull, D. L., Knudsen, T., Mokyr, J., & Vanberg, V. J. (2008). In defence of generalized Darwinism. Journal of Evolutionary Economics, 18(5), 577–596. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00191008-0110-z Alexander, R. (2017). The biology of moral systems. New York: Routledge. Alford, J., & Hibbing, J. (2004). The Origin of Politics: An Evolutionary Theory of Political Behavior. Perspectives on Politics, 2(4), 707– 723. doi:10.1017/S1537592704040460 Arrow, K. J. (1970). Social choice and individual values (2nd ed.). New Haven: Yale University Press. Axelrod, R. (2006). The evolution of cooperation (Revised). Basic Books, Inc., New York. Axelrod, R., & Hamilton, W. D. (1981). The evolution of cooperation. Science, 211(4489), 1390–1396. https://doi.org/10.1126/ science.7466396 Bagehot, W. [1869](2009). Physics and politics. CreateSpace, an Amazon Publishing Company. Scotts Valley, California.
Balinski, M. L., & Young, H. P. (2001). Fair representation: Meeting the ideal of one man, one vote (2nd ed.). Washington, DC: Brookings Institution Press. Bazian, H. (2016, October 12). Police violence in America and compounded racism. Retrieved November 2, 2016, from Hatem Bazian website: www.hatembazian.com/content/policeviolence-in-america-and-compounded-racism/ Bentele, K. G., & O’Brien, E. E. (2013). Jim Crow 2.0? Why states consider and adopt restrictive voter access policies. Perspectives on Politics, 11(4), 1088–1116. https://doi. org/10.1017/S1537592713002843 Binmore, K. G. (1994). Game theory and the social contract: Just playing. Cambridge: MIT Press. Bobo, L. D., Charles, C. Z., Krysan, M., & Simmons, A. D. (2012). The real record on racial attitudes. Retrieved from https://dash.harvard.edu/handle/1/32197879 Bowles, S., Choi, J.-K., & Hopfensitz, A. (2003). The co-evolution of individual behaviors and social institutions. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 223(2), 135–147. Retrieved from https:// doi.org/10.1016/S0022-5193(03)00060-2 Bowles, S., & Gintis, H. (2011). A cooperative species: Human reciprocity and its evolution. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Boyer, P., & Petersen, M. B. (2012). The naturalness of (many) social institutions: Evolved cognition as their foundation. Journal of Institutional Economics, 8(01), 1–25. Burnham, Terence & Johnson, Dominic. (2005). The Biological and Evolutionary Logic of Human Cooperation. Analyse & Kritik. 27. 113–135. 10.1515/auk-2005-0107. Burt, A., & Trivers, R. (2008). Genes in conflict: The biology of selfish genetic elements (1st ed.). Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press. Buss, D. M., & Malamuth, N. M. (Eds.). (1996). Sex, power, conflict: Evolutionary and feminist perspectives. New York: Oxford University Press. Cannon, W. B. (1963). The wisdom of the body (Revised and enlarged ed.). New York: W. W. Norton & Company. Cavalli-Sforza, L. L., & Feldman, M. W. (1981). Cultural transmission and evolution: A quantitative approach. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Chiao, J. Y., Bowman, N. E., & Gill, H. (2008). The political gender gap: Gender bias in
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS
facial inferences that predict voting behavior. PLoS ONE, 3(10). e3666. https://doi. org/10.1371/journal.pone.0003666 CNN, J. B. (2019, January 21). The Supreme Court takes on MLK’s legacy. Retrieved August 4, 2019, from CNN website: www. cnn.com/2019/01/20/us/mlk-legacysupreme-court/index.html Colomer, J. M. (2001). Political institutions: Democracy and social choice. Oxford University Press, USA. Retrieved from www. oxfordscholarship.com/view/10.1093/01992 4183X.001.0001/acprof-9780199241835 Colomer, J. M. (2007). On the origins of electoral systems and political parties: The role of elections in multi-member districts. Electoral Studies, 26(2), 262–273. https:// doi.org/10.1016/j.electstud.2006.02.002 Conradt, L., & List, C. (2009). Group decisions in humans and animals: A survey. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 364(1518), 719–742. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb. 2008.0276 Corning, P. A. (1995). Synergy and selforganization in the evolution of complex systems. Systems Research, 12(2), 89–121. https://doi.org/10.1002/sres.3850120204 Cox, Gary W. (1997). Making votes count. Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University Press. Creanza, N., & Feldman, M. W. (2014). Complexity in models of cultural niche construction with selection and homophily. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 111(Supplement 3), 10830–10837. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1400824111 Dahl, R. A. (2006). A preface to democratic theory (Expanded, anniversary ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Dahl, R. A. (1989). Democracy and its critics. New Haven: Yale University Press. Darwin, C. (1871). The descent of man, and selection in relation to sex. John Murray, London. Darwin, C. [1838](2011). The autobiography of Charles Darwin. CreateSpace Independent Publishing Platform. Davidson, C., & Grofman, B. (1994). Quiet revolution in the South: The impact of the Voting Rights Act, 1965–1990. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
183
Dawkins, R. (1999). The extended phenotype: The long reach of the gene (Revised ed.). Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. Dolan, K. (2014). When does gender matter?: Women candidates and gender stereotypes in American elections. Retrieved from www. oxfordscholarship.com/view/10.1093/acpr of:oso/9780199968275.001.0001/acprof9780199968275 Dolan, K., & Lynch, T. (2014). It takes a survey: Understanding gender stereotypes, abstract attitudes, and voting for women candidates. American Politics Research, 42(4), 656–676. https://doi.org/10.1177/1532673X13503034 Easton, D. (1965). A framework for political analysis. Prentice-Hall, New Jersey. Easton, D. (1979). A systems analysis of political life. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Ehrlich, P. R., & Levin, S. A. (2005). The evolution of norms. PLOS Biology, 3(6), e194. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pbio. 0030194 Epperly, B., Witko, C., Strickler, R., & White, P. (2019). Rule by violence, rule by law: Lynching, Jim Crow, and the continuing evolution of voter suppression in the U.S. Perspectives on Politics, 1–14. Retrieved from https://doi.org/ 10.1017/S1537592718003584 Fehr E, Gächter S. Altruistic punishment in humans. Nature. 2002; 415(6868):137–140. doi:10.1038/415137a Feminist Evolutionary Perspectives. (2019). Feminist evolutionary perspectives society. Retrieved May 22, 2020 from Feminist Evolutionary Perspectives website: www. facebook.com/groups/122502515165/ Ferriere, R., Michod, R. Inclusive fitness in evolution. Nature 471, E6–E8 (2011). https:// doi.org/10.1038/nature09834 Fisher, R. A. [1930](2000). The genetical theory of natural selection (1st ed.; J. H. Bennett, Ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Fontaine, P. (2016). Walking the tightrope: The committee on the behavioral sciences and academic cultures at the University of Chicago, 1949–1955. Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences. 52(4). 349–370. Retrieved from https://www.academia.edu/29432063/ Walking_the_Tightrope_The_Committee_ on_the_Behavioral_Sciences_and_Academic_ Cultures_at_the_University_of_Chicago_ 1949_1955
184
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Fox, R. L., & Lawless, J. L. (2014). Uncovering the origins of the gender gap in political ambition. American Political Science Review, 108(3), 499–519. https://doi.org/10.1017/ S0003055414000227 Frank, S. A. (2003). Perspective: Repression of competition and the evolution of cooperation. Evolution; International Journal of Organic Evolution, 57(4), 693–705. Frank, S. A. (2011). “Evolutionary foundations of cooperation and group cohesion.” in Simon Levin (Ed.). In Games, Groups and the Global Good. Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg Retrieved from http://arxiv.org/ abs/1112.3046 Frank, S. A. (2013). “Introduction: A new theory of cooperation.” In K. Summers & B. Crespi (Eds.), Human Social Behavior: The Foundational Works of Richard D. Alexander. Oxford University Press, USA. Freedom in the World. (2014). Retrieved July 16, 2014, from Freedom House website: www.freedomhouse.org/report/freedom-w orld-aggregate-and-subcategory-scores#. U8bXglZfTQs Frischmann, B. M., Madison, M. J., & Strandburg, K. J. (2014). Governing knowledge commons. Oxford University Press. Fürstenberg, D. K. (2016). Evolutionary institutionalism. Politics and the Life Sciences: The Journal of the Association for Politics and the Life Sciences, 35(1), 48–60. Grabo, A., & van Vugt, M. (2018). Voting for a male warrior or female peacekeeper? Testing the evolutionary contingency hypothesis in the 2016 U.S. presidential elections. Evolutionary Psychology, 16(2), 1474704918773267. https://doi.org/10.1177/1474704918773267 Gunnell, J. G. (2004). Imagining the American polity: Political science and the discourse of democracy. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press. Haldane, J. B. S. (1932). The causes of evolution. Retrieved July 26, 2019, from Princeton University Press website: https://press. princeton.edu/titles/4618.html Haldane, J. B. S. (1941). Concerning social Darwinism. Science & Society, 5(4), 373– 375. Retrieved from JSTOR. Hamilton, A., Madison, J., & Jay, J. [1788] (1998, December 29). The federalist papers
No. 10. Retrieved July 24, 2019, from https:// avalon.law.yale.edu/18th_century/fed10.asp Hamilton, W. D. (1964a). The genetical evolution of social behaviour. I. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 7(1), 1–16. Hamilton, W. D. (1964b). The genetical evolution of social behaviour. II. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 7(1), 17–52. Hardin, G. (1968). The tragedy of the commons. Science, 162(3859), 1243–1248. https://doi. org/10.1126/science.162.3859.1243 Hasen, R. (2014, January 7). ‘Race or party?: How courts should think about Republican efforts to make it harder to vote in North Carolina and elsewhere’. Retrieved November 29, 2014, from Harvard Law Review website: http://harvardlawreview.org/2014/01/race-orparty-how-courts-should-think-about-republicanefforts-to-make-it-harder-to-vote-in-northcarolina-and-elsewhere/ Hastie, R., & Kameda, T. (2005). The robust beauty of majority rules in group decisions. Psychological Review, 112(2), 494–508. https:// doi.org/10.1037/0033-295X.112.2.494 Henrich, J., & Boyd, R. (1998). The evolution of conformist transmission and the emergence of between-group differences. Evolution and Human Behavior, 19(4), 215–241. https:// doi.org/10.1016/S1090-5138(98)00018-X Henrich, J., Boyd, R., & Richerson, P. J. (2012). The puzzle of monogamous marriage. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 367(1589), 657–669. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2011.0290 Herre, E., and Wcislo, W. (2011). In defence of inclusive fitness theory. Nature 471, E8–E9. https://doi.org/10.1038/nature09835 Hobbes, Thomas. (1651;2009). Leviathan: Or the Matter, Form and Power of a Commonwealth, Ecclesiastical and Civil. Gutenberg Project. https://www.gutenberg. org/files/3207/3207-h/3207-h.htm Hodgson, G. M. (2004). The evolution of institutional economics: Agency, Structure and Darwinism in American Institutionalism. London and New York: Routledge https:// doi.org/10.4324/9780203300350 Hout, E. van der, & McGann, A. J. (2009). Liberal political equality implies proportional representation. Social Choice and Welfare, 33(4), 617–627. https://doi.org/10.1007/ s00355-009-0382-8
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS
Howard, R. S., & Lively, C. M. (1994). Parasitism, mutation accumulation and the maintenance of sex. Nature, 367(6463), 554–557. https:// doi.org/10.1038/367554a0 Kaufmann, E. (2019, March 18). Americans are divided by their views on race, not race itself. The New York Times. Retrieved May 22, 2020 from www.nytimes.com/2019/03/18/ opinion/race-america-trump.html Keena, A., McGann, A., & Smith, C. A. (2017, October 25). The Supreme Court’s quiet gerrymandering revolution and the road to minority rule. Retrieved July 26, 2018, from USAPP website: http://blogs.lse.ac.uk/ usappblog/2017/10/25/the-supreme-courtsquiet-gerrymandering-revolution-and-theroad-to-minority-rule/ Kropotkin, P. (2017). Mutual aid: A factor of evolution (J. Duran, Ed.). CreateSpace Independent Publishing Platform. Kropotkin, P. A., Huxley, T., & Montagu, A. (1955). Mutual aid and the struggle for existence. Extending Horizons Books. Boston, Massachusetts. Laland, K. N., Odling-Smee, F. J., & Feldman, M. W. (1999). Evolutionary consequences of niche construction and their implications for ecology. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 96(18), 10242–10247. Lane, J. C. (1995). The election of women under proportional representation: The case of Malta. Democratization, 2(2), 140–157. https://doi.org/10.1080/13510349508403433 Latner, M. (2017). Darwinian democracy? How evolutionary theory informs constitutional design. Handbook of Biology and Politics. Retrieved from www.elgaronline.com /view/edcoll/9781783476268/97817834762 68.00037.xml Leigh, E. G. (1971). Adaptation and diversity: Natural history and the mathematics of evolution. Freeman, Cooper. San Francisco. Levi, M. (1989). Of rule and revenue. California: University of California Press. Levi, M., & Weingast, B. R. (2019). Douglass North’s theory of politics. PS: Political Science & Politics, 52(2), 213–217. https:// doi.org/10.1017/S1049096518002111 Levin, S. A. (2014). Public goods in relation to competition, cooperation, and spite. Proceedings of the National Academy of
185
Sciences, 111(Supplement 3), 10838–10845. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1400830111 Lopez, A. (2017). Does Conflict Drive Cooperation? The Evolution Institute. Retrieved May 20th, 2020 https://evolution-institute.org/ cooperation-was-important-in-humanevolution/ Madison, J. (1786). Equality: James Madison to Thomas Jefferson. Retrieved December 1, 2017, from http://press-pubs.uchicago.edu/ founders/print_documents/v1ch15s33.html Madison, J., Hamilton, A., & Jay, J. [1788] (2008). The Federalist papers. CreateSpace Independent Publishing Platform. Malthus, T. [1798](2013). An essay on the principle of population. J. Johnson, London. March, J. G. (1991). Exploration and exploitation in organizational learning. Organization Science, 2(1), 71–87. https://doi.org/10.1287/ orsc.2.1.71 March, J. G., & Olsen, J. P. (1976). Ambiguity and choice in organizations. Universitetsforlaget. Oslo, Norway. Matland, R. E., & Studlar, D. T. (1996). The contagion of women candidates in singlemember district and proportional representation electoral systems: Canada and Norway. The Journal of Politics, 58(3), 707–733. https://doi.org/10.2307/2960439 McCoy, D. R. (1980). Jefferson and Madison on Malthus: Population growth in Jeffersonian political economy. The Virginia Magazine of History and Biography, 88(3), 259–276. McGann, A., & Latner, M. (2013). The calculus of consensus democracy: Rethinking patterns of democracy without veto players. Comparative Political Studies, 46(7), 823– 850. Retrieved from https://doi.org/10.1177/ 0010414012463883 Mclean, I. (2005). Before and after Publius: The sources and influences of Madison’s political thought. In S. Kernell (Ed.), James Madison: The Theory and Practice of Republican Government. Stanford University Press. Redwood City, California. Miller, James G. (1953). Profits and Problems of Homeostatic Models in the Behavioral Sciences – Introduction. Chicago Behavioral Sciences, University of Michigan Biography of Publications. Murray, G. (2012, March 4). Are you easily disgusted? You may be a Conservative.
186
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Retrieved July 26, 2019, from Psychology Today website: www.psychologytoday.com/ blog/caveman-politics/201203/are-you-easilydisgusted-you-may-be-conservative Nowak, M. A. (2006). Five rules for the evolution of cooperation. Science, 314(5805), 1560–1563. https://doi.org/10.1126/ science.1133755 Nowak, M., Tarnita, C., & Wilson, E. (2010). The evolution of eusociality. Nature 466, 1057– 1062. https://doi.org/10.1038/nature09205 Olson, M. (1971). The logic of collective action: Public goods and the theory of groups, Second printing with a new preface and appendix (Revised ed.). Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Ostrom, E. (1990). Governing the commons: The evolution of institutions for collective action (1st ed.). Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press. Ostrom, E. (2010). Beyond markets and states: Polycentric governance of complex economic systems. American Economic Review, 100(3), 641–672. https://doi.org/10.1257/aer. 100.3.641 Ostrom, E. (2013). Do institutions for collective action evolve? Journal of Bioeconomics, 16(1), 3–30. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10818013-9154-8 Palmer, Tom G. (2002). “Madison and Multiculturalism: Group Representation, Group Rights and Constitutionalism”. In John Samples (ed.), James Madison and the Future of Limited Government, Cato Institute. Page, S. E. (2008). The difference: How the power of diversity creates better groups, firms, schools, and societies (New edition with a new preface by the author ed.). Princeton: Princeton University Press. Peress, M. (2019). Measuring the research productivity of political science departments using Google Scholar. PS: Political Science & Politics, 52(2), 312–317. https://doi. org/10.1017/S1049096518001610 Rawls, J. (1999). A theory of justice (2nd ed.). Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press. Reynolds, A., Reilly, B., & Ellis, A. (Eds.). (2005). Electoral system design: The new international IDEA Handbook. Stockholm: International IDEA. Rule, W. (1987). Electoral systems, contextual factors and women’s opportunity for election
to parliament in twenty-three democracies. The Western Political Quarterly, 40(3), 477– 498. https://doi.org/10.2307/448386 Santa Fe Institute. (2016, November 9). lawOS: Regulations as society’s operating system. Retrieved August 2, 2019, from Santa Fe Institute website: www.santafe.edu/newscenter/news/lawos-regulations-societysoperating-system Schofield, N. (2005). The intellectual contribution of Condorcet to the founding of the US Republic 1785–1800. Social Choice and Welfare, 25(2–3), 303–318. https://doi. org/10.1007/s00355-005-0005-y Shugart, M., & Wattenberg, M. P. (2001). Mixed-member electoral systems: The best of both worlds? Oxford University Press. Oxford. Skyrms, B. (1994). Sex and justice. Journal of Philosophy, 91(6), 305–320. Skyrms, B. (2014). Evolution of the social contract. Cambridge University Press. New York. Smith, J. M., & Price, G. R. (1973). The logic of animal conflict. Nature, 246(5427), 15. https://doi.org/10.1038/246015a0 Sorkin, R. D., West, R., & Robinson, D. E. (1998). Group performance depends on the majority rule. Psychological Science, 9(6), 456–463. https://doi.org/10.1111/14679280.00085 Soudriette, R., & Ellis, A. (2006). A global snapshot. Journal of Democracy, 17(2), 78–88. https://doi.org/10.1353/jod.2006.0038 Taagepera, R. (2007). Predicting party sizes: The logic of simple electoral systems (1st ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Taagepera, R. (2008). Making social sciences more scientific: The need for predictive models. Oxford: Oxford University Press. The cooperative human. (2018) Nat Hum Behav 2, 427–428. Retrieved from https:// doi.org/10.1038/s41562-018-0389-1 Trivers, R. (1971). The evolution of reciprocal altruism. Quarterly Review of Biology, 46(1). 35–57. Trivers, R. (2006). Reciprocal altruism: 30 years later. In P. M. Kappeler & C. P. van Schaik (Eds.), Cooperation in Primates and Humans: Mechanisms and Evolution (pp. 67–83). Springer. New York. https://doi.org/10.1007/ 3-540-28277-7_4
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS
Turchin, P. (2013, February 8). The double helix of inequality and well-being. Retrieved August 3, 2019, from Peter Turchin website: http:// peterturchin.com/cliodynamica/the-doublehelix-of-inequality-and-well-being/ Turchin, P. (2016). Ages of discord: A structuraldemographic analysis of American history. Chaplin: Beresta Books. Walker, S. I., & Davies, P. C. W. (2012). The algorithmic origins of life. Journal of The Royal Society Interface, 10(79), 20120869– 20120869. https://doi.org/10.1098/rsif. 2012.0869
187
Wilson, D. S., & Gowdy, J. M. (2013). Evolution as a general theoretical framework for economics and public policy. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 90, S3–S10. https://doi.org/ 10.1016/j.jebo.2012.12.008 Young, H. P. (1988). Condorcet’s theory of voting. American Political Science Review, 82(4), 1231–1244. https://doi.org/10.2307/ 1961757 Zhou, Y. M. (2011). Synergy, coordination costs, and diversification choices. Strategic Management Journal, 32(6), 624–639. Retrieved from JSTOR.
9 Evolutionary Psychology and Crime Joseph L. Nedelec
INTRODUCTION As examined throughout this volume, humans are a highly social species and as such possess a constellation of adaptations which aid in survival and reproduction. Among the evolved strategies employed by highly social species, those which can be viewed as exploitative are abundant. Indeed, nature is awash with examples of evolved strategies that appear to callously infringe on the desires or choices of individuals who are the targets of such strategies. To be sure, highly social species rely on cooperation, empathy, and stable group dynamics, but all these factors can also be exploited for individual gain as an effective evolved strategy. When viewed from an evolutionary perspective, criminal behavior among humans clearly falls into an exploitative-strategy category. However, the field of social science devoted to the study of criminal and antisocial behavior, criminology, rarely examines behavior using an evolutionary lens. Instead, almost all traditional criminological theories and
empirical analyses place the etiological responsibility for antisocial behavior solely within the realm of social factors. Recently, however, biosocial criminologists have illustrated the shortcomings of such an approach. The current chapter overviews the various ways in which an evolutionary viewpoint can inform our understanding of antisocial behavior, crime, and criminality. Increasingly referred to as evolutionary criminology, the perspective described in this chapter illustrates how viewing antisocial behavior from an evolutionary standpoint can explain the most well-established observations regarding criminality as well as contextualize more recent empirical findings derived from neuropsychology, behavioral genetics, and biosocial criminology.
UNDERSTANDING AND USING EVOLUTIONARY THEORY Although covered elsewhere in this volume, it is necessary at the outset of our discussion to
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND CRIME
address why many people within social- science disciplines struggle with recognizing the relevance of an evolutionary point of view. Perhaps the two most important concepts related to evolutionary thinking that can help in this regard are deep time and recognizing that humans are not immune to the processes of nature. Deep time is a geological concept that informed Charles Darwin in generating his theory of evolution by natural selection. Briefly, the concept refers to the immense amount of time that has passed since the formation of the earth and the amount of time that has been available for natural processes such as erosion, movement of the earth’s crust, and most germane to the current chapter, evolution of biological organisms. Given that humans typically live for only a handful of decades, our perceptions of the passage of time are drastically limited compared to the age of the earth. Consequently, it is difficult for most people to understand how the complexities we observe in nature and our own behaviors could result from the processes of evolution. Other factors such as religious dogma and cultural characteristics also impinge on people’s ability to recognize the immensity of time that has passed and the vast opportunities that have been provided for the processes of natural and sexual selection to shape the evolution of species. When one recognizes and accepts the overwhelming evidence of deep time, however, it becomes easier to see how natural processes could apply to all aspects of species’ lives, including behavioral traits such as crime and antisocial conduct. Given the time frames associated with the typical human life course, deep time is often cognitively taxing. However, observing natural wonders like the Grand Canyon provides an opportunity to witness the results of deep time. Recognizing that humans are a part of nature, however, is often less widely accepted. Given the complexities and varieties of human culture and the incredible technological and societal advances that humans
189
have made, along with the wide array of religious beliefs that have and continue to profess human exceptionalism, it is not surprising that many feel humans are separate from the natural world – and, therefore, immune to the processes of natural and sexual selection that have shaped all life. Acceptance of human’s place in nature is, and has been since well before Darwin, a controversial issue. Nonetheless, the evidence that humans are a part of nature is as overwhelming as the evidence for deep time. Empirical facts such as homology (shared structures across different species or taxa), genetic code illustrating relatedness across animals and plants, and the considerable fossil record, among other empirical facts, all point to an inevitable conclusion: humans are not exceptional in terms of our place in nature and are the result of natural processes (i.e., natural and sexual selection) in the same way as all life on earth. Once this fact is acknowledged, and in combination with the concept of deep time, it is thus necessary that assessments of the causes of almost any aspect of the human condition must incorporate recognition of the evolutionary processes that underpin the human condition. Such a conclusion was emphasized by Pierre Teilhard de Chardin who poignantly noted, “[evolution] is a general postulate to which all theories, all hypotheses, all systems must henceforward bow and which they must satisfy in order to be thinkable and true. Evolution is a light which illuminates all facts, a trajectory which all lines of thought must follow”. (As cited in Dobzhansky, 1973: 129.) All this information inexorably leads to the perspective that informs the chapters within this volume. Briefly, evolutionary psychology argues that our brain is the seat of all human behavior and the construction and functioning of our brain is driven, in part, by genetic factors; these genetic factors, in turn, have been susceptible to the processes of natural and sexual selection over the vast eons of evolutionary time. Consequently, all aspects of the human condition, including human behavior, society, and culture,
190
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
can be assessed using an evolutionary lens. Given that criminal and antisocial behaviors are an empirical universal across all recorded history and across every known society, it is clear that an evolutionary lens can also illuminate why such behaviors appear to be an integral, though often unfortunate, aspect of the human condition.
OF CRIME, CRIMINALITY, AND ANTISOCIAL BEHAVIOR A common reaction in the social sciences to the suggestion of the utility of an evolutionary perspective is that, given behaviors considered to be criminal are based on codified laws, crime is a social construct that will vary from society to society. Thus, a biologically based perspective such as evolutionary psychology cannot inform the discussion of crime. The argument, though partially correct (codified prohibitions on certain behaviors certainly do change both within and between societies over time), is incomplete in at least two ways. First, across all recorded history and known societies there is considerable overlap in terms of prohibited behaviors. Few cultures accept behaviors such as thievery, murder, assault, or rape (this list is not exhaustive) without any social rebuke. Even within highly violent cultures where the murder of one group’s rivals is seen as a necessary step in the maturity of males, such behavior is condoned only if it is directed at an out-group. Consequently, there appears to be a human constant against the impingement of the rights and desires of others in terms of these behaviors (at least in terms of one’s own in-group). Second, while it is certainly the case that codified prohibitions (i.e., legal definitions of what constitutes crime) are fluid across time and space, the behavioral proclivities that underlie criminal or antisocial behavior are consistent. These proclivities are referred to, in general, as criminality, which is a propensity or inclination to engage
in criminal or antisocial behaviors. Thus, when biosocial criminologists examine criminal or antisocial behaviors using an evolutionary lens, it is with the concept of criminality in mind; in other words, the focus is on the behavior and not necessarily the legality of the behavior. As an example, criminologists examine not only antisocial behaviors that are illegal but also behaviors that are considered analogous to criminal behavior such as substance abuse or risky sexual behaviors and the lifestyles associated or congruent with engaging in antisocial conduct. Thus, recognizing that antisocial behaviors are acts which violate the interests of one party to the benefit of another party in contravention of normative behaviors of the group to which the parties belong allows for a more nuanced examination of the etiology of antisocial behavior than simply relying on legal definitions. Thinking in this way (i.e., focus on the behavior – criminality) provides an opportunity to apply an evolutionary lens. In the sections that follow, I outline how evolutionary psychology as a paradigm can help explain three of criminology’s most commonly observed empirical patterns in terms of antisocial behavior: the gender gap in crime, the age-graded distribution of crime, and the non-random distribution of criminal behavior.
THE GENDER GAP IN CRIME Imagine, if you will, a risk factor associated with criminality and antisocial behavior that is so pervasive that it replicates across all known societies and all recorded history. That risk factor is actually well-known, and in our species, it is represented by a lone chromosome: the Y-chromosome. Sex is the single most consistent predictor of criminal behavior that has emerged from well over a century of criminological theorizing and empirical work. To be sure, not all men engage in criminal behavior and not all women refrain from it. However, in the
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND CRIME
statistical sense (i.e., average differences), there has not existed a society wherein women engaged in a higher rate of criminal behavior than men, and this is particularly the case with violent antisocial behaviors. The robust observed differences in terms of criminality between the sexes has been addressed in a variety of ways in the criminological literature with almost all explanations focusing on sociological factors (e.g., differential parental socialization, cultural factors, differential media exposure, etc.). In each case, these explanations have proven to be at best incomplete and at worst incorrect. A potential reason for the ineffective explanations is the lack of recognition that humans are part of the natural world. Here we see that an evolutionary perspective can illuminate potential causal factors for the observed differences in antisocial behaviors between men and women. When one recognizes that humans are a part of nature, one can then look to nature for potential analogues of the behavior or dynamic of interest. Additionally, an evolutionary perspective allows for the application of well-known biological theories or processes. For example, biological explanations of the differences in behavioral repertoires between the sexes within many species are often informed by discussions of investment (Trivers, 1972). Briefly, any given organism within a sexually reproducing species can allot time and energy to obtaining mates (mating effort) or caring for offspring (parental effort or investment). Bioenergetic resources cannot be allotted to both mating and parenting simultaneously and, as we shall see, the evolved strategies of sexes with regard to investment of resources are often divergent. Throughout the animal kingdom, the primary driver of differentiation in bioenergetic resources is referred to as minimal parental investment (MPI). MPI refers to the minimal time and energy costs associated with producing a viable offspring (i.e., one that can live long enough to then also reproduce). In most primate species (human and non-human), the MPI for males and females
191
differs considerably. While females in most primate species have a very high MPI (many months of gestation and often many years of offspring care), males have a relatively low MPI (perhaps as minimal as a few moments of copulation). Consequently, males can reproduce at much higher rates and with shorter intervals than females. While males have a much higher reproductive ceiling, they also evince much more variance in terms of reproductive success – the proportion of males who never reproduce is much higher than in females. Additionally, given that females risk a much higher MPI, they exhibit mating strategies that lead to what is generally referred to as choosiness (females assess males on their reproductive quality to a much higher degree than males assess females). The result of this difference in MPI is that males tend to differentially invest in mating effort while females tend to invest relatively more in parenting effort. Along with this differential allocation of resources comes a suite of behavioral strategies which affect the level and degree of competition both within and between sexes. Differential allocation of reproductive resources driven by MPI and within-sex variances in reproductive success is associated with more intense within-sex competition in the sex with the lower MPI. In less technical language, the sex with more to lose (i.e., greater reproductive variance – if you don’t reproduce, you’re a genetic dead end) is the sex that will engage in more intense (i.e., risky, violent, combative) competition relative to the sex with higher MPI. Thus, the biological concept of MPI provides the logic for understanding the wide range of morphological and behavioral traits that males possess, relative to females, which appear specifically designed for intense competition. The same morphological and behavioral traits related to within-sex competition (i.e., fighting rivals for access to the high MPI sex) are also employed for between-sex competition (e.g., subduing the ability of the high MPI sex to choose among mates).
192
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
While in most primate species males compete in a more intense fashion, there is nothing about maleness per se that inevitably leads to increased violence and aggression; likewise, there is nothing about femaleness per se that inevitably leads to decreased violence and aggression in within- and between-sex competition. To illustrate this argument, one can again observe nature for instances wherein the sexes converge in terms of MPI (i.e., greater amount of shared parental efforts, aka biparental care). Many species exhibit such patterns (e.g., wolves, numerous types of birds, beavers, some monkeys, among others), and the morphological and behavioral differences between males and females are greatly reduced. Perhaps the greatest evidence for the importance of MPI can be derived from species where the males invest more resources to parental effort relative to females and females have greater reproductive variance relative to males. This occurs in varieties of fish and other animals (though no mammals) and what is observed is a role reversal – relative to most primates – in terms of behavioral strategies: the females compete with more aggression and the males are generally choosier in terms of selecting mates. Armed with an evolutionary explanation of sex differences in terms of aggressive behavior, one can then see why men and women in our own species have exhibited and still do exhibit differences in terms of criminality or a propensity to engage in antisocial behaviors. Given that men possess a much lower MPI than women, it is men who possess (on average) greater muscle mass, height, and other morphological traits conducive to intense competition. Additionally, it is also the reason why men possess a suite of psychological traits that drive risky and aggressive behaviors more often and in typically more intense degrees than women. Consequently, in possession of the psychological drive and morphological capacities to aggressively compete, men are more often the sex to engage in criminal behaviors
(particularly those which are considered interpersonal and violent). Hence, one of the most robust empirical findings of criminological research: the gender gap in crime.1
AGE-GRADED DISTRIBUTION OF CRIME In addition to the gender gap in crime, researchers of human antisocial behavior have long observed that criminal activity, in general, tends to rise with the onset of adolescence, peak near the end of adolescence, and then abruptly plummet in young adulthood. This empirical pattern has been dubbed the age-crime curve and, like the gender gap in crime, has appeared relatively consistent across time and space.2 Numerous scholars have put forth theoretical explanations for this patterned empirical observation, the most well-known among criminologists being Laub and Sampson’s (1993) agegraded theory of crime and Moffitt’s (1993) dual taxonomic theory of crime. Briefly, Laub and Sampson’s (1993) theory asserts that informal social control through an individual’s bond to society affects the propensity to engage in criminal behavior over the life course. The theory places great weight on the bonds within an individual’s family during development as well as attachment to school, employment, and other structural aspects of society. Overall, Laub and Sampson argue that those youth with weak social bonds are more likely to engage in antisocial behaviors during adolescence and that such behavior in turn leads to an increased likelihood of criminal behavior in adulthood. Further, they argue that without social bonding or attachment to institutions such as employment, military service, and marriage, continued criminal behavior during adulthood is probable. Finally, they argue that desistence from criminal behavior is largely due to obtaining attachment to one or more of these social institutions.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND CRIME
Moffitt’s (1993) dual taxonomic theory also recognizes the importance of a life-course approach and contains a multitude of hypotheses regarding the shape of the age-crime curve. In brief, Moffitt argued that antisocial behavioral patterns illustrate two distinct groups of offenders: adolescent-limited offenders (AL) and life-course persistent offenders (LCP).3 As suggested by the label, those exhibiting AL patterns of offending engage in criminal behavior that is limited to the period of adolescence, that was not preceded by antisocial behavior in childhood, and does not tend to continue into adulthood. Additionally, the type of offending in which AL offenders engage is typically relatively minor and rarely results in serious contact with the criminal justice system (i.e., long-term institutionalization). LCP offenders, however, exhibit behavioral patterns illustrating a lifetime of antisocial behavior from childhood through adulthood. Additionally, relative to AL offenders, the type of criminal activity in which LCP offenders engage is often severe and does typically lead to serious and consistent interaction with the criminal justice system (throughout the life course). In terms of etiological factors, Moffitt (1993) argued that the behavioral pattern of LCP offenders is a result of an unfortunate mix of neuropsychological deficits and deleterious rearing environments. She argued that LCP offending patterns are so serious in nature and consistency that exceedingly damaging circumstances such as abnormal neuropsychological functioning and abusive or otherwise damaging developmental environments were required. However, given that Moffitt argued that AL offending was normative (i.e., an expected pattern of development in modern societies), her explanation required normative processes typically experienced by most youth. Her hypotheses regarding AL offending centered on two components. The first component is represented by the difference between the biological maturity experienced by youth in adolescence (after puberty an individual is, more or less, biologically an
193
adult) and the social limitations that remain in place in modern societies (adolescence is a period of relaxed limitations relative to childhood, but it still consists of wide- ranging restrictions on a variety of aspects of life). The difference between one’s biological maturity and one’s perceptions of social freedom/limitation was termed the maturity gap. Moffitt argued that the greater the experienced maturity gap, the greater the frustration experienced by the youth and therefore the greater the need to address the resulting frustration. The second component of Moffitt’s explanation of AL offending provides the mechanism through which youth were said to then deal with the frustration resulting from an experienced maturity gap. Her argument indicated that AL individuals could recognize/observe the relative social freedom exhibited by those who are engaged in LCP offending and lifestyle patterns. Observing the socially uninhibited lifestyle of LCP offenders could then lead to a process of behavioral mimicry in order to gain similar social freedoms (termed social mimicry). Moffitt thus argued that AL offending was a result of experiencing a maturity gap during adolescence and engaging in social mimicry such that the behavioral patterns of LCP offenders are followed (although to a less serious degree) by non-LCP youth (i.e., AL offenders). Further, Moffitt argued that the desistance from criminal behavior observed during early adulthood by AL offenders was a result of the reduced effect of the maturity gap (i.e., the social limitations placed on adolescents become much less intense or pervasive as they age into early adulthood) – thus, with the accumulation of greater social freedoms throughout many aspects of their lives, those in the AL offending group no longer experience the frustrations associated with social limitations which eliminates the need to mimic the behavioral patterns of LCP offenders. Both the age-graded and dual taxonomic theories of crime have received substantial attention in the criminological literature and
194
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
researchers continue to test the hypotheses derived from both theories. For the purposes of this chapter, however, it is important to note that both theories are proximal theories of criminal behavior (as exhibited in the age-crime curve). As discussed throughout this volume, proximal explanations of behavior refer to those arguments that focus on factors related primarily to ontogeny (i.e., development within an individual’s lifespan), whereas evolutionary arguments provide ultimate explanations of behavior, which focus on phylogeny (development over generations rather than within a single lifespan) and adaptive function (i.e., what adaptive problem is addressed by the behavior in question?). For example, while it may be the case that informal social bonds affect crime over the life course or that the frustration associated with experiencing the maturity gap leads to increased antisocial behavior in adolescence, we are still left with the question as to why these processes have the (potential) effect that is purported. Why should social bonds experienced during development and in adulthood affect behavioral patterns? Why should biological maturity combined with limitations on social freedoms lead to frustration among youth? Why would aggressive or violent behavior be something in which youth engage to deal with the frustration? Fortunately, an evolutionary perspective can provide the ultimate reasons/answers to such questions. As with the discussion of the gender gap in crime, an evolutionary explanation of the age-crime curve centers on variance in reproductive effort between men and women. A few examples of evolutionary explanations for the age-crime curve exist in the literature (e.g., Quinsey et al., 2004) but they all center on what Wilson and Daly (1985) termed the young male syndrome. Briefly, Wilson and Daly argue that given the immense costs of reproductive failure (i.e., genetic dead end) and the substantial variance in reproductive fitness among men, there will be intense competition for any resources that help increase
reproductive fitness. In this zero-sum social contest, higher-ranking men tend to obtain more mates and increase their reproductive fitness, whereas lower-ranking men have fewer or no mates. Given that social rank is a vital component to reproductive fitness for men, there is a heightened psychological awareness among men to threats to status or reputation (often referred to as honor). Threats to social status or reputation are, in essence, threats to social rank and, thus, threats to reproductive potential. Consequently, intense, aggressive, and often violent competition to maintain or advance rank can occur when such threats arise. Further, within a polygymous breeding system wherein some males reproduce much more than most males there are numerous reproductive benefits to intense (aggressive, risky) competition. Such behavior can serve to protect or gain status, discourage or eliminate rival males in a competitive breeding environment, allow for the acquisition of resources to be used to woo females, engage in and protect from mate poaching, and protect already acquired resources and mates (including aggressive mate guarding). Wilson and Daly (1985) provide empirical evidence supporting these assertions based on data from over 500 homicide cases in Detroit in the early 1970s. They illustrate that not only were the majority of both offenders and victims in homicide cases men, but offenders and victims were almost identical in terms of being unemployed, unmarried, and younger (teen years to mid 20s). Analysis of the cases also indicated that the most common type of homicide was the result of social conflict or what criminologists would refer to as the escalation of a trivial altercation (the majority of which were primarily in retaliation for a previous loss of face in the presence of social peers). Summarizing their observations regarding lethal conflict, they note, ‘many, perhaps most, homicides concern status competition’ (Wilson and Daly, 1985: 59). Wilson and Daly also illustrated that other behaviors that carry a substantive threat of physical harm (e.g., risky and/or
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND CRIME
aggressive driving) are likely the result of a generalized willingness to engage in competitive risk taking relevant to social rank and, thus, linked to male fitness. The observations and hypotheses put forth by Wilson and Daly have been further supported using data outside of Detroit and for different time periods (see Daly, 2016; Daly and Wilson, 2017). Although Wilson and Daly (1985) outline why engagement in criminal conduct and other risky behaviors increases during the adolescent years, their discussion does not explicitly focus on the entirety of the agecrime curve. In their theoretical piece on male criminality over the life course, Kanazawa and Still (2000) echo Wilson and Daly’s young male syndrome hypothesis but also directly address the shape of the age-crime curve. Overall, Kanazawa and Still indicate that intense competition (manifested as antisocial, aggressive, and other risky behaviors) occurs when the reproductive benefits of such behavior are maximized over the life course. Thus, violent competition among males does not occur earlier in life (i.e., prior to puberty) primarily because there are no reproductive benefits to engaging in violence, theft, or murder – the pre-pubescent male is unable to translate a competitive edge into reproductive success. However, after puberty the reproductive benefits sky-rocket and so too does the resulting behavior (thus, the peak in adolescence of the age-crime curve). As noted above, however, the age-crime curve drops precipitously in early adulthood. Kanazawa and Still argued that the ultimate reason for this drop is associated with the costs of continued intense competition. The authors argue that risky strategies are employed to gain sexual access to mates and, in general, secure reproductive success (or at least the opportunity for reproductive success) and at the arrival of offspring (i.e., reproductive success) less risky behavior is employed to minimize the costs to the reproductive success of the male. Thus, the age-crime curve (for males) is a manifestation of a two-pronged strategy selected over evolutionary time
195
wherein males engage in intense competition in order to secure reproductive success, but once this is secured tend to disengage from risky behavioral strategies given the potential costs to the obtained reproductive success. The ultimate explanations put forth by Wilson and Daly (1985) and Kanazawa and Still (2000) are supported by proximal explanations derived from psychophysiological and criminological research. For example, the hormone testosterone – which has been associated primarily with competitive behaviors – increases dramatically in males during puberty but has been observed to drop substantially at the onset of marriage and the arrival of offspring (Beaver, 2009). Additionally, some criminological research has illustrated a calming effect in males (in terms of engagement in criminal behavior) who begin families, though this research is often confounded by issues of temporal order and a lack of genetically informed analyses (Barnes et al., 2014). Finally, we see that these evolutionary explanations of the age-crime curve provide some potential answers to our earlier questions derived from the discussion of the age-graded and dual taxonomic theories of crime. For example, informal social bonds such as employment, military service, and marriage could affect male criminality as these are resources which directly affect or relate to reproductive success. Given that criminal behavior, especially violent or aggressive behavior, represents a threat to these resources there is a corresponding reduction in the level of criminal behavior (on average) that is congruent with the acquisition of these resources. Additionally, experiencing the maturity gap results in increased frustration in youth because their biological maturity – driven by eons of evolutionary processes – motivates them to engage in intra- and inter-sexual competition to obtain mates. However, the wide-ranging social limitations placed on adolescents prevent or at least minimize opportunities for such behaviors. Thus, social rebellion through minor delinquency could result (not only to rebel
196
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
against the social restraints but to attempt to secure status and rank within a peer network). Overall, the discussion illustrates what all evolutionary psychologists argue: both proximal and ultimate explanations are required in order to fully understand observed behavioral patterns such as the age-crime curve.
NON-RANDOM DISTRIBUTION OF CRIMINAL BEHAVIOR The final consistent criminological empirical observation that we will address in the current chapter is the non-random distribution of criminal behavior. In addition to the gender gap and age-crime curve, long-standing and cross-cultural patterns in terms of where criminal conduct tends to occur geospatially and the typical dynamics of offender–victim relationships have been observed. Entire subfields within criminology, for example, have developed which center specifically on these observations. For example, the Chicago school of criminology, most readily exemplified by the work of Shaw and McKay (1942), focused on the differential patterns of criminal behaviors across different areas (or zones) within a city. The authors argued that the differential offending patterns were a result of variance in the structural conditions (e.g., economic status, ethnic heterogeneity, and residential mobility) found in the zones. Further, socioeconomic status and aspects of neighborhood cohesion (sometimes referred to as collective efficacy; Sampson et al., 1997) have long been assessed as key causal variables in the etiology of crime and criminality. Additionally, criminologists and other social scientists have also been examining the nature of victim–offender relationships for well over a century. Consequently, much is known about the ways in which criminal behavior is distributed in terms of geospatial location within cities and towns as well as how offenders and victims are (or are not) known or connected. Overall, in both cases there is a
non-random distribution of criminal conduct although the pattern of the conduct typically depends upon the specific type of crime. The remaining discussion within this section will illustrate how an evolutionary perspective can help explain these non-random patterns.
Non-Random Clustering of Criminality and Other Risky Behaviors in Locales As noted, criminologists have observed that criminal conduct tends to be over-represented or differentially concentrated within certain areas of a city or town. Typically, the areas of concentration are considered to represent highly unstable environments characterized by low average economic status and relatively low social cohesion. Social scientists have tended to point to these characteristics as the causal factors in the accompanying concentration of criminal conduct while others have noted that the criminal behavior exhibited in such areas is a result of a sub-culture of recklessness resulting from minimal opportunity for social advancement. However, as discussed in the prior section these types of explanations are incomplete – why would criminal behavior, especially violent behavior, result from reduced social and economic opportunity? Why would criminal behavior exhibit concentrations among communities with a relative lack of social cohesion or stability? In their analysis of 77 different neighborhoods in Chicago using data from 1988 to 1993, Wilson and Daly (1997) illustrated that an evolutionary perspective can help to address such questions (see also Daly, 2016). Briefly, Wilson and Daly (1997) examined the differential life expectancy for men and women across various neighborhoods, as well as homicide rates, birth rates, and measures of socioeconomic status (i.e., household income and an income inequality index). The key independent variable, life expectancy, was a measure of the expected average duration of life, in years, for an individual based on a variety
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND CRIME
of vital statistics and population data present at the time of the individual’s birth. In their analyses Wilson and Daly empirically assessed three specific hypotheses: (1) homicide rates are a function of local life expectancy; (2) economic inequality accounts for variance in homicide rates beyond that attributed to local life expectancy; and (3) local life expectancy will impact reproduction (birth rates) across neighborhoods. Overall, the researchers argued that life expectancy provides a vital external cue to inhabitants of neighborhoods such that their unconscious behavioral and reproductive strategies can be adjusted based on an assessment of probable lifespan. Thus, rather than representing a potential pathological reaction to social conditions, high-crime areas may be a function of a rational calculation (though one that has been honed over evolutionary time) based on environmental cues. The analyses testing these ideas revealed a number of illuminating findings. First, life expectancy at birth was strongly associated with homicide rates across neighborhoods for both men and women. In neighborhoods with a lower life expectancy at birth a much higher homicide rate was observed. The magnitudes of the bivariate associations were very strong and statistically significant for both men (r = −0.88, p < .0001) and women (r = −0.83, p < .0001). Importantly, these associations held in multivariate models wherein measures for household income and income inequality were introduced. Second, comparisons between the 10 neighborhoods with the longest life expectancy and the 10 neighborhoods with the shortest life expectancy revealed some drastic differences in terms of homicide rates across age categories. For example, in the long life expectancy neighborhoods the homicide rate (deaths per 100,000 per year) went from virtually zero for those males aged five to 14 years to about 20/100,000 for those aged 15 to 24, to a peak of about 25/100,000 for those aged 25 to 34 before dropping to near zero for the remaining age groups. However, in the short life expectancy neighborhoods
197
the homicide rate skyrocketed from about 5/100,000 in the five to 14 years age group to over 300 deaths per 100,000 for the males in the 15 to 24 years age group. While the homicide rate for males in these neighborhoods decreased over time, the rates were still astronomically higher than those observed in the long life expectancy neighborhoods (25 to 34 years: about 250/100,000; 35 to 44 years: about 175/100,000; 45 to 54 years: about 75/100,000; 55 to 64 years: about 60/100,000; 65 to 74 years: about 40/100,000; and 75 years or older: about 55/100,000). While the homicide rates for females in the short life expectancy neighborhoods were much lower than for males, the overall pattern across the age groups was similar and, in some cases, exceeded the homicide rates for males in the long life expectancy neighborhoods. Finally, in terms of reproductive behaviors Wilson and Daly (1997) again compared the 10 neighborhoods with the longest life expectancy to the 10 neighborhoods with the shortest life expectancy across seven different age categories. The differences in birth rates during the teen years and early adulthood between the neighborhoods was substantial. Figure 9.1 illustrates the stark differences. As illustrated, the birth rate for women in the short life expectancy neighborhoods was over four times higher than the long life expectancy neighborhoods for the 15 to 19 years age group, and two-and-a-half times greater in the 20 to 24 years age group. Additionally, although the difference is still evident in the 25 to 29 years age group, the birth rates for the different neighborhoods become almost identical in the remaining age categories (i.e., 30 years and above). Based on the results of their analyses, Wilson and Daly concluded: [t]he data presented here indicate that people behave as if they have adjusted their rates of future discounting and risk acceptance thresholds in relation to local life expectancy, and that they do so in the non-violent domain of reproductive decision making as well as in the potentially violent domain of social competition. (Wilson and Daly, 1997: 1273)
198
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Figure 9.1 Age-specific birth rates (per 1,000 women per year) in the 10 neighborhoods with the longest life expectancy compared to the 10 neighborhoods with the shortest life expectancy Source: Data derived from table 3 in Wilson and Daly (1997).
The analyses and conclusion presented by Wilson and Daly (1997) illustrate how an evolutionary lens can help explain social phenomena that have hitherto only been addressed employing sociologically based theories. Furthermore, they illustrate that the behavioral repertoire exhibited by individuals presented with certain environmental cues may not be pathological or reckless, but rather a function of an unconscious calculus resulting from eons of evolutionary processes. The next example provides a similar illustration in terms of observed patterns of victim–offender characteristics.
Non-Random Victim–Offender Characteristics Depending on the criminal behavior of interest, criminologists have observed that characteristics are consistently represented in terms of victims and offenders. In general,
both victims and offenders tend to be in their adolescence or early adulthood. This observation is not entirely surprising given the age-crime curve, which manifests as a result of the intense mating competition experienced during that period in the life course. However, examinations of specific criminal behaviors have illustrated other patterns in terms of characteristics. For example, researchers estimate that in North America on average approximately 65% of all murders involve a male offender and a male victim, about 20% involve a male offender and a female victim, about 10% involve a female offender and a male victim, and less than 5% involve a female offender and a female victim (Buss, 2005; Daly and Wilson, 2017). Additionally, the risk of being a homicide victim (in general) increases considerably during late adolescence, peaks in the early 20s, and then drops substantially over adulthood. The overall pattern of homicide and other aggressive behaviors in terms of
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND CRIME
offender–victim characteristics has been addressed by a wide range of criminological inquiries. Most of the examinations, however, have focused solely on proximate factors such as socialization practices or even media consumption to account for the observed patterns. As noted earlier, a substantial problem for such explanations is that the patterns observed in terms of offender– victim characteristics are relatively consistent across time and space. Thus, explanations which rely on variance in societal factors such as socialization practices are doomed to be incomplete. Fortunately, researchers employing an evolutionary lens have provided potential explanations for the observed patterns of offender characteristics exhibited in several crimes, including homicide. In their book entitled Homicide: Foundations of human behavior, Daly and Wilson (2017) expand upon their 1985 paper and provide a thorough examination of how an evolutionary viewpoint can help explain the characteristics of offenders and of victims for various types of homicides. Their discussion centers on intrasexual competition among young males who are psychologically attuned to threats to status and again apply the young male syndrome logic to socially competitive risky behaviors. Daly and Wilson provide a wellspring of empirical analyses from multiple countries to support their claims, and their coverage of the topic is thorough. However, as valuable as Daly and Wilson’s book is – and it is certainly a definitive discussion of how an evolutionary viewpoint can be applied to murder – we will focus our discussion in this section instead on a book by David Buss (2005). Buss’s (2005) book, entitled The Murderer Next Door: Why the Mind is Designed to Kill, presents the argument that homicidal behavioral patterns may have been selected for over evolutionary time as a potential strategy for dealing with a variety of adaptive problems. The claim that killing is produced by a specific psychological adaptation is a controversial one and discussing the merits
199
of the argument is beyond the scope of the current chapter. However, the data on which Buss based his conclusion and the evolutionary arguments are worth considering herein. In addition to examining a large amount of behavioral data similar to that presented in Daly and Wilson’s (2017) book (i.e., official criminal justice records), Buss and his team also collected data on homicidal ideations (fantasies) from a sample of over 5,000 individuals across a number of age categories from multiple countries. The respondents in the study were asked if they had ever thought of killing someone, who it was (in terms of the relationship to the respondent), the manner in which they thought of killing the target, what prevented them from going through with the killing, and what could have potentially led them to actually kill (i.e., push them over the edge). The respondents were also asked if they ever thought someone might kill them and were also presented similar followup questions (i.e., who they thought may have wanted to kill them, how they might have been killed, what the respondent did to prevent being killed, what prevented them from being killed, and what would have pushed the person over the edge to kill the respondent). The results of the survey revealed several illuminating patterns that aligned with evolutionary theory (only a handful of which are included here). First, a considerable majority of the respondents in the sample indicated that they had given thought to killing. Buss and his team of researchers observed that 91% of the men in the sample and 84% of the women reported at least one vivid fantasy about killing someone. Buss argued that this finding supports the argument that over evolutionary time murder may have been an effective strategy to employ when faced with a serious adaptive problem. Second, both men and women in the study exhibited consistent yet distinct patterns of homicidal ideations. While both sexes reported homicidal fantasies related to sexual rivalries (e.g., killing the new sexual/romantic partner
200
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
or a former partner), men tended to focus on issues centered on mate retention (i.e., infidelity, actual or perceived, by their current or former partner) whereas women tended to focus on threats by other women to their own mate quality (e.g., responding to rumors about their own sexual reputation) and on responding to perceived or actual abusive threats by current or former partners. Buss notes that given the substantial threat to reproductive success in these circumstances intense counter-measures, such as violent action, were likely selected for over evolutionary time. Third, related to the general patterns of men and women’s homicidal ideations the researchers also noted that men generally reported homicidal ideations focused on sexual (rather than emotional) infidelity, whereas when women mentioned infidelity of a current or former partner in a homicidal fantasy it was more often related to emotional (rather than sexual) infidelity. The general differences observed in the reported homicidal fantasies in this regard also belie the differential threats to reproductive success for the sexes. As outlined above, given that women are the high-MPI sex in our species sexual access is a resource that is highly contested by men. Thus, any aspects of the social environment which affects the likelihood of securing such a resource will be met with severe reaction. Likewise, while women are typically the choosier sex in terms of sexual access they are, as a result of being the high-MPI sex, more burdened by potential and actual offspring than are men. Thus, over evolutionary time psychological modules guiding women’s mate choice have been tuned to cues in potential mates that indicate a willingness to invest in the long term (i.e., help to raise any future offspring). One such cue is the extent to which a mate professes and exhibits emotional attachment. Consequently, Buss and his team argue, many of the women in the study centered their homicidal fantasies on situations wherein the respondent actually had, or perceived an experience of, emotional infidelity.
Fourth, in terms of the thoughts related to being a victim of homicide, Buss and his team also noted some general patterns that were consistent within and between sexes. For instance, both men and women consistently indicated that they thought they would be the victim of murder given that they had engaged in or came close to what evolutionary psychologists generally call mate poaching. In essence, the process refers to a sexual or romantic partnership with another mate who is already involved in a relationship. As noted above, being the actual or perceived victim of mate poaching was consistently evident in the fantasies of those who reported wanting to kill. Additionally, across most known societies and recorded time periods such behavior is associated with enraged emotion and what is typically termed irrational behavior (though from an evolutionary point of view, acting to minimize threats to one’s reproductive status may actually be rational; see Daly, 2016). Indeed, the legal codes of many societies include provisions for reduced punishment or even culpability in cases where a spouse murders a mate poacher. Thus, all parties involved in the matepoaching situation are aware of the potential risks and the respondents who reported feared homicidal victimization in Buss’s study certainly echoed such awareness. In terms of some of the general differences between the sexes regarding the reports of being a potential murder victim, the primary variance mirrored that observed in the fantasies associated with committing a homicide. For example, men generally reported a fear of homicidal victimization that resulted from not only mate poaching but also from threats to other men regarding the target’s (i.e., the potential homicidal male) social rank, status, or worthiness as a sexual partner. Additionally, women generally reported a fear of victimization resulting from engaging in verbal denigration of the sexual reputation or physical appearance of other female rivals. Overall, the pattern illustrated in the ideations about homicidal victimization reflected a keen recognition of the type of social
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND CRIME
circumstances that typically could drive others to kill. In line with evolutionary theory, Buss noted that this dynamic is a result of co-evolution of intense strategies related to maintaining or increasing one’s value in the highly competitive sexual reproduction market. Further, the findings are manifestations of the evolution of strategies related to prevent being a victim of such competition (and therefore also maintaining or increasing one’s mate value). Biologists and evolutionary psychologists refer to this process as the Red Queen hypothesis, and it is discussed in detail elsewhere in this volume. Overall, the data presented in Homicide and The Murderer Next Door align with the historical and contemporary data studied by criminologists and other social scientists. The patterns observed in terms of the crime-specific non-random distributions of victim–offender characteristics and relationships occur across these data. The differences, however, arise in the explanations that have been proffered to account for these observations. Whereas social scientists typically lay the blame on processes such as socialization, culture, and media exposure, evolutionary psychologists illustrate how such observations may actually be the result of our evolutionary heritage. Data presented by Buss and his research team indicate that the targets of offenses such as homicide may (in general) be particular and such particularity is due to the specific threat to reproductive success or survival (the key aspects of evolutionary processes) represented by the target. Understanding the victim–offender associations so often observed in criminological data in terms of ultimate causes provides an opportunity for greater clarity of etiology and therefore potential to increase our ability to reduce harm.
CONCLUSION The current chapter presented an overview of some of the ways in which an evolutionary view can be applied to crime, criminality,
201
and antisocial behavior. As noted in the introduction, given the social nature of our species, the exploitation of others for personal gain is an indelible and likely inevitable characteristic of the human condition. The inevitability of the characteristic, however, does not mean that our species need accept, condone, or encourage antisocial behaviors of any kind. As noted throughout this volume, nothing about the explanation of a behavior should be seen as a moral stance on the behavior. Additionally, just because antisocial, aggressive, and/or criminal behavior is in part due to the natural processes associated with evolution it does not mean that the behavior is justified or in any way excused by the knowledge of those processes (to think otherwise would be to commit the naturalistic fallacy). Rather, the stance taken in this chapter and elsewhere is that the best opportunity to reduce harm associated with criminal behavior must be derived from our best efforts to understand the underlying processes of criminality. While the social sciences have provided a wide variety of potentially useful proximal hypotheses in this regard, the application of an evolutionary perspective to criminal behavior provides the ultimate, and therefore likely most useful, understanding. As biosocial criminology advances within and beyond the discipline of criminology it is likely that our ability to address the harms associated with criminality will be enhanced. Employing an evolutionary lens will be a crucial component of that journey.
Notes 1 At the risk of being repetitive, it is key to note here that an evolutionary perspective does not dismiss the importance of cross-cultural diversity in terms of observed crime rates and potential additional etiological factors. Indeed, an evolutionary perspective is inherently biosocial such that it emphasizes the interactive processes between the inherited genetic architecture of the brain and the developmental environment to which an individual is exposed.
202
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
2 Deviations across a variety of societies have been noted, but some of these patterns of deviation are due to exceedingly rare socio-political events (e.g., aftermath of a world war and nuclear attack; Hiraiwa-Hasegawa, 2005). 3 Moffitt also suggested a third group, abstainers, who appear to not engage in any offending over the life course. While of much theoretical interest, our discussion will be limited to the two offending groups emphasized in her dual taxonomy.
REFERENCES Barnes, J. C., Wright, J. P., Boutwell, B. B., Schwartz, J. A., Connolly, E. J., Nedelec, J. L., & Beaver, K. M. (2014). Demonstrating the validity of twin research in criminology. Criminology, 52, 588–626. Beaver, K. M. (2009). Biosocial criminology: A primer. Dubuque: Kendall Hunt. Buss, D. M. (2005). The murderer next door: Why the mind is designed to kill. New York: Penguin. Daly, M. (2016). Killing the competition: Economic inequality and homicide. New York: Transaction Publishers. Daly, M., & Wilson, M. (2017). Homicide: Foundations of human behavior. New York: Routledge. Dobzhansky, T. (1973). Nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of evolution. The American Biology Teacher, 35, 125–129. Hiraiwa-Hasegawa, M. (2005). Homicide by men in Japan, and its relationship to age,
resources and risk taking. Evolution and Human Behavior, 26, 332–343. Kanazawa, S., & Still, M. C. (2000). Why men commit crimes (and why they desist). Sociological Theory, 18, 434–447. Laub, J. H., & Sampson, R. J. (1993). Turning points in the life course: Why change matters to the study of crime. Criminology, 31, 301–325. Moffitt, T. E. (1993). A developmental taxonomy. Psychological Review, 100, 674–701. Quinsey, V. L., Skilling, T. A., Lalumiere, M. L., & Craig, W. M. (2004). Juvenile delinquency: Understanding the origins of individual differences. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. Sampson, R. J., Raudenbush, S. W., & Earls, F. (1997). Neighborhoods and violent crime: A multilevel study of collective efficacy. Science, 277, 918–924. Shaw, C. R., & McKay, H. D. (1942). Juvenile delinquency and urban areas. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Trivers, R. L. (1972). Parental investment and sexual selection. In B. Campbell (Ed.), Sexual selection and the descent of man, 1871–1971 (pp. 136–179). Chicago, IL: Aldine. Wilson, M., & Daly, M. (1985). Competitiveness, risk taking, and violence: The young male syndrome. Ethology and Sociobiology, 6, 59–73. Wilson, M., & Daly, M. (1997). Life expectancy, economic inequality, homicide, and reproductive timing in Chicago neighbourhoods. BMJ, 314, 1271–1274.
10 Evolutionary Psychology and Policing: The Balance Between Aggression and Restraint Lois James
INTRODUCTION Police professionalism and use of force are critical topics of public interest in the 21st century. Perhaps more than ever in the history of US policing, the public are demanding accountability and visibility of police behavior. Some researchers indicate that this intense microscope of scrutiny has led to decreased legitimacy and public faith in police, going so far as to label it a “legitimacy crisis” (Gest, 2016; James et al., 2016). Following high-profile shootings of unarmed African American men in recent years, starting with Michael Brown in Ferguson, Missouri, public trust in police dropped significantly, equaling the rates observed in the years following the Rodney King trials (Jones, 2015). Minority citizens reported less trust in the police than white citizens (Peck, 2015). Within any social system a certain degree of give and take is necessary, and historically the police have had some difficulty with yielding authority – for example,
enforcement of ‘stop and frisk’ practices, contributing to racial injustice and antipolice sentiment (White and Fradella, 2016). In the ‘post-Ferguson’ era, the policing profession is faced with nationwide calls for reform, and an understanding of how this professional group has evolved is essential for guiding its path forward (President’s Task Force on 21st Century Policing, 2015). The function of the police is tied to their granted authority to use force to ensure safety and order. Renowned sociology and policing scholar Egon Bittner (1970) identified the role of the police as the legitimate authority to exercise force. This is challenging because the exercising of this authority by the police frequently stirs accusations of brutality and racism, civil unrest, demands that officers be criminally punished, and at times mass violence and rioting. The goal of this chapter is to explore the police function and these contradictory social realities using evolutionary psychology. In order to maintain order and serve the citizenry the police must be
204
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
both aggressive and restrained. Maintaining a balance between aggression and restraint is required to promote and uphold social order. As society evolves, so does this balance (whereby the scale can tip more towards aggression or restraint depending on societal demands). Our society today expects greater restraint on the part of police, while police culture continues to promote aggressive authority. Aligning public and police expectations of the appropriate balance between aggression and restraint could promote legitimacy in all aspects of police work.
THE EVOLUTION OF AGGRESSION AND RESTRAINT Evolution is the process of change in all forms of life over generations. Each generation inherits traits, through genes, from their parents. If this new trait is heritable, and contributes to greater reproductive success of the organism relative to individuals without the trait, it will be passed on to the next generation and accumulate in the population (Buss and Shackelford, 1997). New traits that do not help the organism survive long enough to reproduce will become rare or disappear. This process of natural selection or ‘survival of the fittest’ has guided the evolution of aggressive and restrained behaviors over time. Although in social animals such as humans, aggression is not typically an indiscriminate strategy (Savage and Kanazawa, 2004), context-specific aggression is a naturally occurring, prevalent phenomenon (Neuberg et al., 2010). Restraint is the action that occurs when the ‘means to an end’ is reached, for example when the threat of an opponent is neutralized. It can also occur if one decides that the risks of employing aggression as a strategy are too great. For the most part, aggression and restraint are tightly linked. Buss and Shackelford (1997) identified seven social problems for which aggression
has evolved over generations as a beneficial response. These include the protection and acquisition of necessary resources, selfdefense against attack, inflicting costs on same-sex rivals who are vying for the same resources, gaining and maintaining power and dominance, deterring potential opponents from future attacks, ensuring the sexual fidelity of a partner, and reducing resource investment in unrelated children. For example, in a pack of wolves, the dominant member cannot show weakness in the face of a physical challenge or his dominant status will be questioned and potentially overturned (Millan, 2006). He must assert his dominance through aggression, or submit to a new leader (restraint). In this way, aggression evolved as a mechanism for demonstrating and protecting dominant social status. Examples of resource-acquisition-related aggression in humans include two men fighting over the attentions of an attractive woman, a homeless woman stabbing a wealthy-looking woman to steal her wallet, or a nation going to war with another over valuable natural resources. Restraint behavior should occur when the target of the aggressive behavior is subdued or neutralized. As important as aggression is, the failure to employ proper restraint can compromise one’s survival. Restraint occurs in nature when animals are faced with the submission of a challenger. For example, the roe deer buck will not clash antlers unless an opponent is face-on and engaged in the fight, although he could successfully attack when the opponent is turned around and vulnerable (Eibl-Eibesfeldt, 1961). Likewise, the defeated wolf will show his neck to his successful opponent, who refrains from killing him even though he could do so (Lorenz, 1952). Such restraint in the face of submission is used to safeguard one’s energy for future attacks – use of unnecessary energy can signal that one is vulnerable (Millan, 2006). Moreover, if a social animal fails to show proper restraint by either attacking others without good cause, being overly aggressive in their pursuit of submission from
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND POLICING
others, or continuing an attack when their opponent is clearly defeated, that individual will be threatening to the social order and may be killed, exiled, or (in the human case) jailed or imprisoned (Francis, 1998).
THE CREATION OF THE POLICE PROFESSION AND THE SOCIAL CONTRACT BETWEEN THE POLICE AND THE CITIZENRY Evolution explains why using aggression as a means to an end may be necessary for survival, and how restraint in humans evolved as a means of tempering and controlling aggression, with the result that social order and the rule of law are preserved. Not all players are afforded equal power in the exercise of aggression in contemporary US society. The police (and other professionals in ascribed circumstances) are granted the right to exercise legitimate physical force if necessary to protect public safety. This can be explained by Social Contract Theory (SCT), which states that individuals’ moral obligations are shaped by a collective agreement or ‘social contract’ that binds a society together with a set of accepted norms and rules (such as the rule of law). This theory was given its first rigorous defense by Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679). John Locke (1632–1704) and Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712–1778) are other champions of this theory. In fact, Locke’s argument that citizens have the right to revolt against authority should it no longer be protecting their interests was enormously influential on democratic revolution – notably for Thomas Jefferson and the founders of the United States. Revolt against perceived tyrannical rule or oppression has potential implications for the current police legitimacy crisis with the rise of social justice movements such as Black Lives Matter. Not all human societies are bound by a social contract. Reiman (1985) describes the
205
‘state of nature’ as a society without legal institutions. Although rare, a modern example of such a system is the Gebusi tribe of New Guinea – a highly cooperative, egalitarian, social society which is non-competitive and politically decentralized with interpersonal relations that are mutually respectful, nonhierarchical, and self-effacing. Aggression among the Gebusi people is discouraged, as antisocial behavior is contradictory to their peaceful values. Fear of violence is fostered and withdrawal from violence is reinforced. They also have a homicide rate among the highest reported. Between 1940 and 1982 nearly one-third of adult deaths were caused by homicide (Knauft et al., 1987). This is the equivalent of a homicide rate of 568 per 100,000 per annum. To put this in perspective, the US homicide rate (one of the highest in the Western world) was roughly 6 per 100,000 per annum in 2018 (Federal Bureau of Investigation, 2018). The most common cause of homicide is ‘sorcery’, that is, an individual will be killed when they are believed to have caused death through sickness to someone else in the village. Given that the Gebusi live in the lowland rainforest of New Guinea, disease is rampant, explaining the ‘sickness deaths’ and consequent sorcerer killings. Homicide is considered a regrettable but unavoidable burden required to maintain the social system, and even the close kin members of the victim rarely seek retribution. Societies without legal institutions, even highly cooperative and peaceable tribes like the Gebusi, will inevitably require a great deal of interpersonal violence to prevent anarchy. Within most systems, the social contract between police and citizens is the collective antidote to the ‘state of nature’ Reiman describes. Individuals recognize that their right to use force may be countered by the rights of others to use force, and that the state of nature is inherently unsafe and unstable in the absence of a governing rule. As such, we sacrifice certain personal freedoms to increase safety at a broader level: ‘It becomes rational for
206
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
freedom-loving people to renounce their freedom to use force at their own discretion’ (Reiman, 1985: 239). But in order to do this, some society members must be responsible for maintaining public safety. We assign this duty to the police. In the mid 19th century, as the United States expanded through immigration and the industrial revolution, professional police forces were established in metropolitan cities and a social contract authorized police officers to protect individuals from victimization (Walker, 1977). Police officers were granted the authority to employ coercion to protect citizens’ lives and property (Reiman, 1985). Conceptualized in this way, the police became society’s ‘professional aggressors’, called upon when force was necessary (Bittner, 1970). The social contract establishes the right of police to utilize the force necessary, including deadly force, if the threat warrants it. For example, if a suspect is posing a deadly threat to innocent civilians the police are justified to shoot. In this case, aggression is not just allowed, but expected for the overall good of society. The role of restraint within the social contract is equally important. Citizens expect that police authority be utilized legitimately, competently, and in good faith (Reiman, 1985). Use of force by police must result in an overall increase in public safety. Despite a consistent emphasis on the function of the police being tied to the legitimate use of force, the major role of the police has evolved over time with the demands of the ruling elite. From preventing slave revolts in the mid 19th century, to maintaining segregation following emancipation, to riot enforcement during the civil rights movement, the police can be seen as the ‘forceful arm’ of local, state, and federal government, tasked with maintaining the status quo. The police have long been directed by the political powers, who have historically been made up of wealthy white men. It stands to reason that the police have traditionally served the interests of this socially dominant group. A common
argument for why police use of force differs based on suspect race and socioeconomic status is that police discretion favors the socially dominant and protects the status quo. Of course, this position tends to be vehemently denied by members of the socially dominant group, who argue that suspect behavior is solely responsible for police use of force. Nevertheless, the tension between the police and minority classes has fueled considerable discord and distrust in police legitimacy. Use of force perceived by citizens as unnecessary, unjust, or excessive undermines the social contract and the legitimacy of the police. In many circumstances, this is now the case: the police retain a cultural emphasis on aggressive crime-control tactics and have a self-image as society’s law enforcers (Brown, 1988). The citizenry, on the other hand, have come to expect that police not only control crime, but serve the community in ways that build social bonds and prevent crime. Officers are expected to be mentors, social workers, mental-health professionals, and counselors, as well as law enforcers (Terrill et al., 2003). Similarly, while the citizenry expects greater and more nuanced restraint in the exercise of law enforcement, police training and culture emphasize the need for officers to protect themselves by staying one step ahead of the suspect or safety threat. These differences of opinion reinforce the ‘us vs them’ mentality, in which officers increasingly feel the public does not understand the harsh realities of what they face on a daily basis, and the public increasingly resents police authority.
HAWKS VS DOVES AND THE EVOLUTION OF THE POLICE PERSONA Maynard-Smith’s famous ‘hawk versus dove’ model is one of the most important contributions in evolutionary game theory and of direct relevance to the ‘police persona’. At its most basic level, the hawk will choose the strategy of escalating aggression and
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND POLICING
continue attacking until their opponent retreats or they themselves are injured. A dove might display aggression but retreat if their opponent escalates. In a contest between a hawk and a dove, a hawk would win. In a contest between two hawks, assuming both have equal ‘resource-holding potential’ (RHP) such as strength, access to weapons, etc., there is an equal likelihood of either winning. In a contest between two doves, the resource being fought over is shared (negotiation), or the War of Attrition model of threat to avoid actual fighting is employed to determine who gets the resource. Maynard Smith’s (1974) War of Attrition model states that when animals engaging in conflict cannot assess the other’s likelihood of beating them they will attempt to deter conflict through ritual displays of aggression. For an evolutionarily stable strategy (ESS) to occur there must be a mix of hawks and doves. A system of all doves is vulnerable to invasion by a mutant hawk and in a system of all hawks, the cost of loss becomes too great. The result is that when hawks are rare they have the advantage and are selected for. However, when there are more hawks than doves some hawks are forced to take on a dove strategy so the evolutionary ‘seesaw’ that typifies an ESS swings back the other way as doves are selected for. The same thing can be said for those that follow the rules and those that cheat in Hardin’s ‘Tragedy of the Commons’ scenario, where there are only so many resources to go around. When cheaters are rare their strategy is highly successful, but eventually the resources will run thin and their chances of detection will increase; thus the balance will be tipped back in favor of the compliers (Hardin, 1968). This type of ESS can be seen throughout the animal kingdom. For example, most seagulls catch fish but some wait by the shore and steal the food from the hard-working gulls. This is an effective strategy as cheaters get maximum benefit for minimum effort. However, when the cheating gulls start to outnumber the hard-working gulls some are
207
required to change strategies or nobody gets food (Dawkins, 1980). On average, police officers will be more successful with a hawk strategy than a dove strategy. This makes sense because if an officer comes up against a ‘hawk-like’ suspect and they themselves are ‘dove-like’, the suspect will likely win (get away, attack them, etc.). On the other hand, if the officer is ‘hawk-like’ they will likely win against a dove and have an equal likelihood of winning against a hawk. Research by Yabuta (2008), however, has suggested that there might be a third more complex strategy to add to the hawk versus dove model with particular relevance to policing, that of ‘assessor’. The assessor weighs RHP, then alternates between hawk and dove strategies depending on the situation. To assess is an ESS because it prevents inappropriate attacks on non-opponents. The role of assessor could be applied to police officers who must distinguish between opponents (threatening suspects) and non-opponents (general members of the public or complying suspects) and modify their strategy accordingly. How they select these strategies can also be explained by evolutionary theory.
GAME THEORY AND SELECTION OF AGGRESSION AND RESTRAINT STRATEGIES Selection between aggression and restraint strategies applies to policing in two important ways. First, it is expected that officers are able to expertly assess whether aggression is an appropriate response in a given situation. The justification for the decision is grounded in the level of threat in their opponents’ actions. Barash (2004) uses game theory, and the example of the game ‘rock, paper, scissors’, to demonstrate the success of a strategy that is dependent on another player. If you pick rock and your opponent also picks rock then you draw, the expected
208
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
return is zero, or E(R,R)=0. If your opponent has picked scissors you win and the expected return is one, or E(R,S)=+1; however, if they picked paper you lose and the expected return is minus one, or E(R,P)=−1 (Barash, 1982). If a player consistently employs one strategy such as rock, their opponent will catch on and use a defeating strategy. Thus, in the ‘rock, paper, scissors’ game the best strategy is to use each with equal probability. Now apply the game to police use of deadly force, where the options are ‘shoot’ or ‘don’t shoot’. If the officer shoots and the suspect represents a real threat, the officer wins (assuming he or she does not get shot first). If the officer shoots and the suspect does not represent a real threat (e.g. is trying to pull out a wallet, not a gun) then the officer loses and faces the consequences. If the officer does not shoot and the suspect represents a real threat the officer loses and might be injured or killed. Finally, if the officer does not shoot and the suspect does not represent a real threat the officer wins, as he or she has made the right decision. As in the ‘rock, paper, scissors’ game, the police cannot always favor the same strategy because they would be at high risk of making an error. Thus, officers must constantly weigh their perceptions of threat with the actions of the suspect and the consequences of their own decisions. Of course, officers have far more to think about than this simple analogy implies, and are usually not blind to the actions of the opponent. However, game theory exemplifies the decision officers must make when faced with a threat to employ either aggression or restraint. Evolutionary game theory explains why selection has favored certain characteristics, behaviors, or attributes, when success in a contest depends on the behaviors of others (Barash, 1982). For example, Maynard Smith’s War of Attrition model (1974) states that when animals engaging in conflict cannot assess the other’s likelihood of beating them or RHP they will attempt to avoid conflict through ritual displays of aggression.
This model can be observed in many species, for example howler monkeys or elephant seals that loudly vocalize to display aggression, fish that puff up to try and prevent attacks, and deer that shake their antlers at each other to determine who is the more dominant (Krebs and Davies, 1984). If this deterrence does not work and a fight ensues, then the contestant who is prepared to risk a higher cost and fight for longer will win. The War of Attrition model relates to police use of force because it shows how a cost–benefit analysis has evolved resulting in aggression only when necessary and only to the extent necessary. The latter relates to the second application of the balance between aggression and restraint in policing: that officers must apply immediate restraint following the use of aggression. Furthermore, the very aggression they use should be controlled and strategic as opposed to driven by fear, anger, or frustration. They are also expected to render or call for medical aid for injuries they were personally responsible for inflicting. The failure to apply appropriate restraint and allow aggression to become emotionally driven results in incidents such as the infamous beating of Rodney King in 1991. Video footage of the incident, featuring Los Angeles Police Department officers beating an African American man on the ground and circulated by media outlets nationwide, has come to symbolize how use of force in law enforcement can become unfettered, brutal, and deadly when left unchecked. Restraint, then, is a crucial component of a law enforcement officer’s tactical skill set. The evolutionary foundation of the balance between aggression and restraint is straightforward. Aggression when necessary can solve several adaptive problems. Aggression past the point of necessity in social systems, however, can produce costs and often fails to solve adaptive problems. The police, just like every social animal, must achieve a balance between aggression and restraint. However, officers are in a reasonably unique position in having to balance aggression and restraint as
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND POLICING
a core function of their job, and answering to the public whenever they decide to employ an aggressive response. In some cases, aggression can be favored on the part of the police, and evolutionary theory offers some insights as to why.
THREAT SIGNALS AND THE ‘FIGHT OR FLIGHT’ RESPONSE The functioning of the human brain has not changed since the Pleistocene epoch. Humans evolved over millions of years in the African savanna where people lived in small groups of hunter-gatherers. This environment is referred to as the ‘environment of evolutionary adaptedness’ (EEA) (e.g. Bowlby, 1969). This is a critical time period and the environment where natural selection ‘designed’ the modern human species. One of the most important tools for survival, favored by natural selection, was the ‘fight or flight’ system for responding to threats. Threat response required efficient learning of threat signals and detecting threatening objects. An example is fear of snakes (Neuberg et al., 2010). Despite fear of snakes serving little purpose for the majority of humans in the modern era, humans tend to be particularly efficient at learning fearful responses to threat signals, and particularly inefficient at unlearning them. Relatedly, humans tend to be fearful or wary of coalitional outgroups (groups of people who are different from them) due to successful threat responses against attacking groups in the ancestral environment. This at least partially explains the concept of ‘implicit bias’ that humans have against groups that are different from themselves. Common implicit biases exist around race, ethnicity, sexual orientation, gender identification, and disability, among others. Although in the modern era we (typically) do not need to fear people who are different from us, we have evolved to favor this strategy, and this can lead to attitudes and
209
beliefs that we might not be aware of (James, 2017). Nesse (2005) describes responses to threat signaling that evolved within the ancestral environment, such as the fight or flight response, and some of the problems that arise in modern life because of these evolved responses. These ideas have relevance to policing, and officers’ use of aggression. Natural selection resulted in the human nervous system being highly responsive to threat cues. We do not wait to see a predator attacking to trigger the response system, but instead we are sensitive to subtle cues and engage the sympathetic system that allows us to fight or flee. Classical conditioning also plays a role here – if we have experienced a threatening situation in the past, a similar situation will be likely to trigger the fight or flight response in the future. This is the concept of conditioned anxiety to a cue of danger. ‘False alarms’ are inexpensive relative to the potential consequences of attack by a predator. This helps to explain why humans tend to be risk averse. This could also explain police shootings where officers shoot in the absence of concrete evidence that the suspect posed a deadly threat. From a survival perspective, the risk of being shot is worse than the risk of getting it wrong, and the fight or flight response can make us prone to responding to threat cues in the absence of real threat. James, Todak et al. (2018) speculated that this construct from evolutionary psychology can be seen in Fachner and Carter’s (2015) ‘threat perception failure’ (TPF) theory. TPF occurs when an officer mistakes a non-threatening object (such as a wallet) for a threatening one (such as a gun), or a non-threatening action (reaching for a wallet) for a threatening one (reaching for a gun) (see also Scharf and Binder, 1983, for a discussion of false-positive errors). Within the policing literature, TPF is associated with implicit racial bias, whereby officers are more likely to experience TPF when faced with African Americans than with people of other races and ethnicities. From an evolutionary perspective, TPF is
210
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
associated with fear and threat responses. Of course, one could argue that increased fear indicates increased bias, but bias is not the sole reason for a threat response. One of the causes of threat response in police officers is training they receive designed to increase anxiety and heighten attention to threat signals. An example of this training is ambush training. This type of training is well intentioned, in that it is designed to prepare officers for ambush encounters on the street, but it teaches rapid response over careful thought, and consequently results in a heightened risk of error. James Todak and colleagues (2018) argue that training should help reduce the incidence of sudden, impulsive use of force by officers that might be fueled by anxiety associated with a fight– flight response. Training that focuses on keeping the officer actively engaged (instead of relying on fight or flight) could reduce the number of accidental shootings by police (Binder and Scharf, 1980; Fyfe, 1996). This is feasible because, just as we learn to detect and respond to threat signals, we also can become desensitized to those signals when they do not result in threat. Understandably, an argument frequently made by the policing profession is that desensitization to threat cues could compromise officer safety. Directly counter to this argument, evidence exists that preventing officers from being overcome by a sympathetic nervous system response improves officers’ marksmanship and deadly-force judgment and decision making, ultimately promoting officer safety (Johnson et al., 2014).
GENDER-BASED AGGRESSION AND POLICE CULTURE Despite gender diversification in the police profession, policing remains an overwhelmingly male profession. Selection has favored individual aggression in boys and men, in particular with regard to the development and
protection of coalitions – groups who work together towards goals (Geary et al., 2003). These groups provide reproductive advantages, as well as increased opportunity for status and protection. Even in highly social animals such as humans, group-level dynamics can facilitate individual aggression under some circumstances, in particular between male groups. A famous example of this was observed in the sociological ‘Robbers Cave’ experiments, where randomly assembled groups of boys engaged in between-group competition (Puurtinen et al., 2015). During these 1950s and 1960s experiments, boys were grouped arbitrarily. They quickly began coalition building and engaged in competition with the other group. Evolutionary psychologists posit that this is evidence of psychological mechanisms that motivate ingroup cooperation and outgroup-directed aggression (Sherif et al., 1961). Interestingly, when provided with a problem that required resources outside of their group, the boys would cooperate with the competing group for a period of time, before reverting to their own coalition. These insights have relevance to the police profession as a coalition. Police culture emphasizes loyalty to its members and a distrust of non-members (or at least a strong feeling that people outside the group do not understand them or have their best interests at heart). The police culture has clear benefits to individual officers – notably the belief that members of their group will ‘have their back’ (Paoline, 2003), which promotes officer safety. The feeling of belonging to a family is often noted as a draw to policing, and in many cases generations of people from the same family will join the profession. There are other aspects of police culture which are not as positive, for example the fostering of an ‘us vs them’ mentality, which can impair police ability to connect with the communities that they are expected to protect and serve. Also the ‘blue wall of silence’ or unwillingness to ‘rat’ on fellow officers when they break the rules can lead to accusations of
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND POLICING
secrecy, corruption, and lack of accountability (Walker, 2001). Finally, the police culture is inherently masculine, and female officers can have challenges with acceptance, bias, bigotry, or unfair promotion practices. Police researchers have shown that officers who more closely align with the police culture are more likely to display aggression, on and off the job. This includes aggressive tactics during traffic stops (Paoline and Terrill, 2005) and citizen interactions (Terrill et al., 2003). These officers are more likely to receive citizen complaints (Terrill and Paoline, 2015) and to use unnecessary force (Silver et al., 2017). Furthermore, they are less likely to adhere to the principles of procedural justice (Terrill and Paoline, 2015) and are more likely to engage in misconduct (Kappeler et al., 1998). Finally, officers who have a strong connection to police culture are more likely to engage in intimate-partner violence (Blumenstein et al., 2012).
DOMINANCE, PRESTIGE, AND STATUS SEEKING Dominance hierarchies form when access to resources is limited and are common in social species. Within the hierarchy, some individuals have greater access to resources than others (Neuberg et al., 2010). This is based on social rank, and its association with reproductive success in social species (Paquette, 2015). Among humans, these hierarchies are common across cultures (Neuberg et al., 2010) and can be observed even in young children (Beaulieu and Bugental, 2007). Within dominance hierarchies, those at the top tend to induce submission to their dominance either through physical intimidation or control of resources (Cheng et al., 2010). In mammals, dominant males have greater access to mates, which then leads to selection for these dominant traits. The construct of prestige, although related to dominance, differs in that it elicits freely
211
conferred deference instead of intimidationinduced submission (Henrich and Gil-White, 2001). There is an evolutionary basis for respecting those we consider to be prestigious. In some societies, prestige exists without dominance hierarchies, and deference to prestigious individuals offers advantages (e.g. proximity to potential mates who flock to the prestigious). Those with prestige enjoy benefits, including the desire for proximity to the prestigious (rather than distance, as is common with regard to dominant individuals), the admiration of others, preferential copying, obedience, and attention (James, Todak et al., 2018). Of course, dominance and prestige are not mutually exclusive, and many individuals may attain both. But prestige does not depend on dominance. For example, a police officer who performs a heroic feat (such as rescuing a small child) is likely to achieve prestige, both among peers and within the community, even if they are not a ‘dominant’ officer. Status seeking is related to both dominance and prestige. Although the construct is from social psychology, it is relevant to evolutionary psychology, because status seeking is a product of competition for social status and consequent resources (Geary, 1999). Social status can be observed in children as young as two or three years old, particularly during same-sex play (Bukowski et al., 2011). The construct of status seeking can also be observed in the literature on juvenile delinquency, especially regarding gang participation and violence (Thrasher, 1936). Within this context, serious aggression and physical violence can occur, especially between males, over issues that seem trivial. This is related to the idea of ‘saving face’ and not letting other males disrespect or question one’s social status (Felson and Steadman, 1983). Within policing, dominance, prestige, and status seeking are readily observed. A police officer who takes a dominant approach is likely to be seen as a protector, an aggressor, and someone who will not back down in the face of attack. This strengthens ties to the
212
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
police culture, and also promotes aggressive tactics with citizens, for example officers who escalate their responses in an effort to maintain control in a situation (Alpert et al., 2004). Escalation tactics are more frequently observed when officers are faced with citizens who disrespect their authority (Van Maanen, 1978) or display ‘contempt of cop’ (James, James et al., 2018). Thus, officers’ physical responses to threats to authority and character can be seen as mechanisms for maintaining dominance during the encounter. This adheres to the policing culture, and is likely to secure prestige and status from their police-officer peers.
TOWARDS A BALANCE OF AGGRESSION AND RESTRAINT IN POLICING Despite a focus on aggression within the policing culture, police officers are adept at employing restraint. They do not typically employ force indiscriminately. Recently, however, serious allegations of excessive and unnecessary force used by the police against young Black men has sparked controversy surrounding the police profession. This has led to calls for action, and in some cases citizens taking matters into their own hands (either by rioting or attacking the police). Throughout the evolution of human society, when social order is threatened and revolution looms, the antidote is often authority reform (DeBenedetti, 1980; Shaw and Shaw, 1977; Wolpert, 1962). The final report from President Obama’s Task Force on 21st Century Policing recommends police reform to reduce tensions between the police and the people they are sworn to serve and protect (President’s Task Force on 21st Century Policing, 2015). The majority of the recommendations from the report are targeted at improving public trust in police, repairing broken relationships, increasing police legitimacy, and promoting procedural justice. Avenues towards
accomplishing these goals include training reform, policy change, and greater transparency. However, the type of reform the public expects is not likely to be successful while the majority of police training emphasizes aggressive tactics and police culture resists reform. According to the Police Executive Research Forum (2015), over 90% of the training hours officers currently receive are on aggressive tactics. Paired with the emphasis on physical aggression within the police culture, tactics that promote restraint are likely to be less appealing to police officers (Crank, 2014). The framework depicted in Figure 10.1 re-envisions the goal of the police in modern society as expertly balancing aggression and restraint. The proposed framework acknowledges the importance of controlled aggression in policing as a strategy for maintaining social order, but emphasizes the need to temper aggression with appropriate levels of restraint. This balance can be demonstrated across all elements of policing, from routine to deadly encounters. The proposed framework does not diminish the importance of aggression in situations in which it is legitimately required. For example, to competently arrest an assaultive suspect, an officer must overpower any resistance. Similarly, encounters that warrant police force require an officer to aggressively ‘win’ against the suspect. This is especially true for use of deadly force where the officer must guard against loss of innocent life, including their own. When officers are confident in their ability to employ aggression, they are less likely to activate a flight or fight response, because they are less likely to feel that their resources are overwhelmed. In other words, the police officer must have the ability to be a hawk, in order to select whether a hawk or dove strategy is more appropriate. The other side of the balancing scale is restraint. Restraint in this case is not to be mistaken for meekness, second-guessing, or unwillingness to dominate if the situation requires it. Restraint is defined as the ability
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND POLICING
213
Figure 10.1 Police balance between aggression and restraint
to temper aggression, or avoid it when it is not warranted. On the restraint side, the officer is supplied with a toolkit of additional options that circumvent the use of physically aggressive tactics. It is important to note that these tactics (for example, tactical disengagement and verbal de-escalation) are not new; they have been around since the inception of the police profession. Arguably, however, they have yet to become central components of police work, given that the majority of training continues to promote aggressive tactics, and police culture continues to reward physical aggression.
PROMOTING RESTRAINT IN POLICE TRAINING AND POLICY Several strategies exist in the police profession for promoting restraint. One example is the use of ‘tactical disengagement’ or actively attempting to de-escalate a volatile encounter.
Police departments in the United States, including Kansas City (Missouri), have begun to implement tactical disengagement training (Police Executive Research Forum, 2015). There has been a move in other countries such as Canada and the UK in this direction, as well. The idea is to not force an encounter with a citizen when there is a risk of escalation and the reason for the encounter is minor. This mindset is antithetical to predominant cultural values in policing, which dictate that officers should not back down from a challenge and should jump in quickly to handle a situation (Fyfe, 1986; Paoline, 2003). The tactical disengagement philosophy teaches officers that they do not need to initiate or ‘win’ every encounter. Relatedly, communication tactics such as ‘verbal judo’, de-escalation, and motivational interviewing have been taught in many departments as a way to influence citizens into voluntary compliance without using physical coercion (Humphrey, 2013). Such techniques draw on professionalism and
214
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
empathetic connections with the individual’s personal situation to reach a mutually agreedupon solution to the problem. Verbal techniques require expert restraint and can be especially frustrating for police officers when they are faced with individuals who are combative, disrespectful, or rude (Pusatory, 2016). Switching immediately from aggressor to rendering medical aid is another example of how officers balance aggression and restraint. In fact, officers today are increasingly expected to immediately render aid to an injured person or else be publicly condemned for neglecting human life (Dart and Walters, 2016). Rendering life-saving aid following a use of force requires that an officer changes mindsets quickly, shifting from a ‘warrior’ to a ‘guardian’ role (Rahr and Rice, 2015) – an officer must drop their defensive and offensive stance and save the person’s life. An officer may need to shift back and forth between controlled aggression and restraint if the individual continues to resist or fight as the officer employs medical aid. From an evolutionary perspective, these expectations move beyond a simple decision to employ restraint upon achieving the end goal – we are asking the police to engage in the seemingly more unnatural behavior of actually preserving the wellbeing of a physical opponent by employing life-saving aid. Collaboration with other services also requires restraint on the part of officers. Officers are accustomed to being called on to solve a wide range of life problems that often have nothing to do with law enforcement but that the citizenry feels the police should do something about right away (Bittner, 1974). As such, police agencies are beginning to identify areas of police work that may be better handled if they are redirected to other professionals, or are handled collaboratively by multiple agencies. For example, when interacting with a suspect suffering from mental illness, an officer sometimes has the option to call on mental health professionals who can offer expert advice on the individual’s behavior. Indeed, this is an underlying philosophy of Crisis Intervention Team (CIT) training.
Officers can exercise restraint in tempering their tactics according to the mental health professionals’ information and suggestions. The same can be said for communicating with victims, distraught family members, friends, and witnesses on scene. Police departments in some US cities have begun to re-engineer their use of force training towards an emphasis on violence deescalation and avoidance. Officers in the Las Vegas (Nevada), New York City (New York), Seattle (Washington), Oakland (California), and Leesburg (Virginia) police departments have all received training on violence deescalation, teaching tactics designed to deescalate a police encounter and avoid the need to use physical force to solve the problem. Unfortunately, programs that incorporate some form of de-escalation or verbal tactics training are frequently offered in a fragmented manner, failing to teach how these skills can be integrated with the use of force training. A prevailing criticism of de-emphasizing aggressive tactics training for police is that it will result in decreased officer safety, and consequently decreased community safety. A central argument here, often voiced by officers themselves, is that researchers and others who are advocating for reform in police use of force do not understand the dangerous realities of police work. Supporting this argument, some evidence suggests that hyper-vigilance on the part of the police is necessary. Interviews with individuals who feloniously assaulted a police officer found that they were more likely to attack an officer if he or she seemed unprepared to react to a problem, did not appear to know an attack was coming, or seem to have dropped their guard (Pinizzotto et al., 2006). This research confirms police-culture beliefs, and has made the shift towards violence de-escalation difficult to accept by many rank-and-file officers. In contrast, de-escalation tactics may promote officer safety. In a crisis of police legitimacy, citizens are less likely to follow the law and comply with police commands. This has been documented in the policing
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND POLICING
literature – people who perceive the police as legitimate are more likely to cooperate and obey the law (Mastrofski et al., 1996; Tyler and Fagan, 2008). Thus, training the police in conflict- and violence-avoidance (i.e. to be more restrained) may reduce the likelihood that situations will escalate and the officer will become engaged in conflict. Such a situation results in an overall reduction in the risk of harm to all persons involved.
GROUNDING POLICE TRAINING IN EVOLUTIONARY THEORY With respect to threat response, training for reducing unnecessary or excessive force could focus on officers’ concerns about danger, and reduce the amount of training that promotes rapid response over reasoned decision making. For example, ambush training that teaches an officer that it is beneficial to be constantly alert may help an officer during the (statistically) unlikely situation that they are ambushed. However, it is also likely to increase the risk of officers rapidly responding to a perceived threat without evidence that a threat exists. It is unlikely that officers in the field will favor critical decision making over rapid threat response unless they have been taught to do so. Deadly-force judgment and decision-making training (either simulation or role-play based) can help promote critical decision making over rapid response, due to the consequence of ‘getting it wrong’. Police training can also reduce officers’ natural distrust of ‘outgroups’ via exposure. As the Robbers Cave experiments demonstrate, competing groups can put aside differences and overcome hostility when faced with a common problem requiring a cooperative solution. Community-orienteered policing (COP) strategies that focus on shared goals, such as improving the safety of people living in the community, have potential to discourage police perceptions of citizens as rivals
215
and vice versa. Examples of COP strategies include programs that promote citizen cooperation in crime reduction and events that allow police and citizens to interact without a power imbalance, such as non-crime-related community events. Another strategy for reducing outgroup distrust is implicit-bias training, which teaches officers about their biases, and provides strategies for identifying and overcoming the impact of bias on behavior. Diversification of the police force also has potential to reduce outgroup suspicion, due to promotion of ties to both the police and minority communities. Relatedly, promoting minority individuals to positions of power where they influence decisions and represent the police profession has promise for reducing outgroup distrust and suspicion. Although promising, these strategies have yet to be evaluated for effectiveness at promoting inter-group collaborative relationships between the police and the citizenry. The theories of dominance, prestige, and status seeking also have relevance to police training. It is easy to train officers to exhibit dominant control behavior. This is because this training aligns with evolved psychology. In the ancestral environment, however, the expectation related to an individual’s dominance behavior is that if the individual wins, the opponent submits. This is complicated in the modern environment because police authority is granted institutionally, and not based on a direct competition between individuals. In other words, no contest has established that the police officer is dominant to the citizen, so it is naïve to assume that the citizen will always submit. The citizen might have strong reasons for not submitting (e.g. gaining prestige and social status among peers). This can result in challenge to the police authority which, in turn, the police are unlikely to submit to. Police training that demands officers exert dominance will in these instances lead to escalation. Alternatively, training that teaches officers to reduce the likelihood of unnecessary
216
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
dominance contests can prevent the need for aggression. There are situations when it is appropriate and expected for an officer to be a hawk and take immediate control of a situation, regardless of escalation consequences. For example, if a suspect is armed and posing a deadly threat to those around them, an officer must neutralize that threat, quickly and decisively. The vast majority of police–citizen interactions, however, do not require the police to be forceful. Many of these interactions, particularly for police officers that work in ‘anti-cop’ neighborhoods, will be fraught with challenges to police authority. Policing scholar Van Maanen (1978) describes ‘the asshole’ or citizen who is not inclined to submit to police authority. When facing such a citizen, the officer can either engage in a dominance challenge or not. In the absence of criminal behavior, the officer has no grounds to force a citizen to submit to their authority (Klinger, 1994), and doing so will escalate the situation. Unfortunately for the police, not everyone will like them, and taking that personally is both unprofessional and unsafe. De-escalation training has potential for reducing unnecessary dominance contests between the police and the citizenry. De-escalation techniques are typically communication based, and attempt to influence citizens into voluntary compliance without using force (Humphrey, 2013). They can be used in volatile crisis encounters (e.g. hostage negotiation) or in day-to-day encounters for decreasing the likelihood that a situation will escalate (e.g. procedural justice). These techniques emphasize police need to read people, be professional, display empathy, and treat people with dignity and respect, regardless of their attitude towards the police. Evaluations of de-escalation techniques show that they improve public perceptions of police legitimacy (Todak, 2017). The idea that de-escalation techniques can be used to dissuade citizens from challenging police authority has implications for long-term police–community relationships. Influencing citizens away from antagonism
and towards cooperation results in more effective police work. The traditional ‘police persona’ of aggression, authority, and masculinity takes the strategy of deterrence to prevent challenges to dominance (‘my RHP is bigger than your RHP’). The evidence on the effectiveness of this strategy, however, is limited, and evidence exists that cooperative strategies are more effective (Tyler and Fagan, 2008). For example, the research literature on procedural justice demonstrates that officers who treat people fairly, with dignity and respect, listen to them, and work towards mutually beneficial outcomes are more likely to gain voluntary compliance and avoid useof-force encounters (Tyler and Fagan, 2008).
CONCLUSION Bittner (1970) defined the role of the police in terms of their legitimate authority to exercise coercive force. Police culture has embraced this definition, shaping training and policy around the use of aggressive crime-control techniques. This mindset has led to strained relationships between police and minority communities and a social crisis in the United States characterized by eroded police legitimacy. Examining police strategies for selecting tactics through an evolutionary lens provides a framework that re-envisions police function as the expert balance of controlled aggression and restraint. Aggressive ‘hawk-like’ strategies are appropriate in certain situations, but in many others, restrained ‘dove-like’ strategies will be more effective at gaining voluntary compliance and avoiding unnecessary dominance contests. Adopting this framework by focusing more training hours on force alternatives and promoting a culture of de-escalation may result in police behavior falling more closely in line with citizens’ expectations of police. Such a shift could result in a reduction in the rate of violence that occurs between police and citizens.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND POLICING
REFERENCES Alpert, G. P., Dunham, R. G., & MacDonald, J. M. (2004). Interactive police-citizen encounters that result in force. Police Quarterly, 7(4), 475–488. Barash, D. P. (2004). The survival game: How game theory explains the biology of cooperation and competition. New York, NY: Macmillan. Barash, D. (1982). Sociology and behavior (2nd ed.). New York, NY: Elsevier. Beaulieu, D. A., & Bugental, D. B. (2007). An evolutionary approach to socialization. In J. E. Grusec & P. D. Hastings (Eds.), Handbook of Socialization (pp. 71–95). New York: Guilford Press. Binder, A., & Scharf, P. (1980). The violent police-citizen encounter. The ANNALS of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 452(1), 111–121. Bittner, E. (1970). The functions of the police in modern society. Bethesda, MD: National Institute of Mental Health. Bittner, E. (1974). Florence Nightingale in pursuit of Willie Sutton: A theory of the police. In H. Jacob (Ed.), Potential for Reform of Criminal Justice (pp. 17–44). Beverly Hills, CA: Sage. Blumenstein, L., Fridell, L., & Jones, S. (2012). The link between traditional police subculture and police intimate partner violence. Policing: An International Journal of Police Strategies & Management, 35(1), 147–164. Bowlby, J. (1969). Attachment and loss. New York, NY: Basic Books. Brown, M. K. (1988). Working the street: Police discretion and the dilemmas of reform. New York, NY: Russell Sage Foundation. Bukowski, W. M., Buhrmester, D., & Underwood, M. K. (2011). Peer relations as a developmental context. In M. K. Underwood & L. H. Rosen (Eds.), Social Development: Relationships in Infancy, Childhood, and Adolescence (pp. 153–179). New York, NY: Guilford Press. Buss, D. M., & Shackelford, T. K. (1997). Human aggression in evolutionary psychological perspective. Clinical Psychology Review, 17(6), 605–619.
217
Cheng, J. T., Tracy, J. L., & Henrich, J. (2010). Pride, personality, and the evolutionary foundations of human social status. Evolution and Human Behavior, 31(5), 334–347. Crank, J. P. (2014). Understanding police culture. Philadelphia:Routledge. Dart, T., & Walters, J. (2016, September 22). Tulsa police under scrutiny for delayed medical aid given to Terence Crutch. The Guardian. Retrieved from www.theguardian. com/us-news/2016/sep/22/tulsa-policet e re n c e - c r u t c h e r- m e d i c a l - a s s i s t a n c e. (Accessed 28 March 2018). Dawkins, R. (1980). Good strategy or evolutionary stable strategy? In G. W. Barlow & J. Silverberg (Eds.), Sociobiology: Beyond Nature/Nurture, Westview Press, Boulder, Colorado, pp. 331–367. DeBenedetti, C. (1980). The peace reform in American history. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press. Eibl-Eibesfeldt, I. (1961). The fighting behavior of animals. Scientific American, 205, 112–122. Fachner, G., & Carter, S. (2015). An assessment of deadly force in the Philadelphia Police Department (Collaborative Reform Initiative). Washington, DC: Office of Community Oriented Policing Services, US. Department of Justice. Federal Bureau of Investigation. (2018). Uniform Crime Report, January–June 2018. Retrieved from https://ucr.fbi.gov/crime-inthe-u.s/2018/preliminary-report. (Accessed 28 October 2018) Felson, R. B., & Steadman, H. J. (1983). Situational factors in disputes leading to criminal violence. Criminology, 21(1), 59–74. Francis, R. C. (1988). On the relationship between aggression and social dominance. Ethology, 78(3), 223–237. Fyfe, J. J. (1986). The split-second syndrome and other determinants of police violence. In A. T. Campbell & J. J. Gibbs (Eds.), Violent Transactions (pp. 207–225). Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell. Fyfe, J. J. (1996). Training to reduce policecitizen violence. In W. A. Geller & H. Toch (Eds.), Police Violence: Understanding and Controlling Police Abuse of Force. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
218
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Geary, D. C. (1999). Evolution and developmental sex differences. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 8(4), 115–120. Geary, D. C., Byrd-Craven, J., Hoard, M. K., Vigil, J., & Numtee, C. (2003). Evolution and development of boys’ social behavior. Developmental Review, 23(4), 444–470. Gest, T. (2016, July 8). Is a ‘police legitimacy crisis’ driving homicides up? The Crime Report. Retrieved from http://thecrimereport. org/2016/07/08/is-a-police-legitimacy-crisisdriving-homicides-up/ (Accessed 3 March 2018). Hardin, G. (1968). Tragedy of the Commons. Science, 162, 1243–1248. Henrich, J., & Gil-White, F. J. (2001). The evolution of prestige: Freely conferred deference as a mechanism for enhancing the benefits of cultural transmission. Evolution and Human Behavior, 22(3), 165–196. Humphrey, J. (2013, November 19). State police academy building guardians instead of warriors. KXLY News. Retrieved from https:// www.kxly.com/state-police-academybuilding-guardians-instead-of-warriors/ (Accessed 3 March 2018). James, L. (2017). The stability of implicit racial bias in police officers. Police Quarterly. 21(1), 30–52. doi: 10.1177/ 1098611117732974 James, L., Fridell, L., & Straub, F. (2016, February). Implicit bias versus the ‘Ferguson Effect’: Psychosocial factors impacting officers’ decisions to use deadly force. The Police Chief, 83, 44–51. James, L. James, S., & Vila, B. (2018). Testing the impact of citizen characteristics and demeanor on police officer behavior in potentially violent encounters. Policing: An International Journal of Police Strategies & Management, 41(1), 24–40. https://doi. org/10.1108/PIJPSM-11-2016-0159 James, L., Todak, N., & Savage, J. (2018). Unnecessary force by police: Insights from evolutionary psychology. Policing: A Journal of Policy and Practice. 14(1), 278–291. Johnson, R. R., Stone, B. T., Miranda, C. M., Vila, B., James, L., James, S. M., & Berka, C. (2014). Identifying psychophysiological indices of expert vs. novice performance in deadly force judgment and decision
making. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8, 512. Jones, J. M. (2015, June 29). In U.S., confidence in police lowest in 22 years. Gallup. Retrieved from www.gallup.com/poll/183704/ confidence-police-lowest-years.aspx (Accessed 25 July 2017). Kappeler, V. E., Sluder, R. D., & Alpert, G. P. (1998). Forces of deviance: Understanding the dark side of policing (2nd ed.). Long Grove, IL: Waveland Press. Klinger, D. A. (1994). Demeanor or crime? Why ‘hostile’ citizens are more likely to be arrested. Criminology, 32(3), 475–493. Knauft, B. M., Daly, M., Wilson, M., Donald, L., Morren Jr, G. E., Otterbein, K. F., & van Wetering, W. (1987). Reconsidering violence in simple human societies: Homicide among the Gebusi of New Guinea [and comments and reply]. Current Anthropology, 28(4), 457–500. Krebs, J. & Davies, N. (1984). Behavioural ecology: An evolutionary approach. Oxford: Blackwell Scientific Publications. Lorenz, K. (1952). King Solomon’s ring. London, UK: Methuen. Mastrofski, S. D., Snipes, J. B., & Supina, A. E. (1996). Compliance on demand: The public’s response to specific police requests. Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency, 33(3), 269–305. Millan, C. (2006). Cesar’s way. New York, NY: Harmony Books. Nesse, R. M. (2005). Natural selection and the regulation of defenses: A signal detection analysis of the smoke detector principle. Evolution and Human Behavior, 26(1), 88–105. Neuberg, S. L., Kenrick, D. T., & Schaller, M. (2010). Evolutionary social psychology. In S. T. Fiske, D. Gilbert, & G. Lindzey (Eds.), Handbook of Social Psychology (pp. 761–796). New York: Wiley. Paoline, E. A. (2003). Taking stock: Toward a richer understanding of police culture. Journal of Criminal Justice, 31(3), 199–214. Paoline, E. A., & Terrill, W. (2005). The impact of police culture on traffic stop searches: An analysis of attitudes and behavior. Policing: An International Journal of Police Strategies & Management, 28(3), 455–472.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND POLICING
Paquette, D. (2015). An evolutionary perspective on antisocial behavior: Evolution as a foundation for criminological theories. In J. Morizot & L. Kazemian (Eds.), The Development of Criminal and Antisocial Behavior (pp. 315–330). New York: Springer. Peck, J. H. (2015). Minority perceptions of the police: A state-of-the-art review. Policing: An International Journal of Police Strategies & Management, 38(1), 173–203. Pinizzotto, A. J., Davis, E. F., & Miller, C. E. (2006). Violent encounters: A study of felonious assaults on our nation’s law enforcement officers (No. NCJ 231272). Washington, DC: US Department of Justice, Federal Bureau of Investigation. Police Executive Research Forum. (2015). Re-engineering training on police use of force (Critical Issues in Policing). Washington DC: Police Executive Research Forum. Retrieved from https://www.policeforum. org/assets/reengineeringtraining1.pdf President’s Task Force on 21st Century Policing. (2015). Final Report of the President’s Task Force on 21st Century Policing. Washington, DC: Office of Community Oriented Policing Services. Pusatory, M. (2016, August 10). Watch: Spokane officer shows amazing patience dealing with intoxicated man. Fox 28. Retrieved from https://www.khq.com/news/ watch-spokane-officer-shows-amazingpatience-dealing-with-intoxicated-man/ article_616ebc29-947b-58d5-937cccf1cfbb50e8.html (Accessed 25 July 2017). Puurtinen, M., Heap, S., & Mappes, T. (2015). The joint emergence of group competition and within-group cooperation. Evolution and Human Behavior, 36(3), 211–217. Rahr, S., & Rice, S. K. (2015). From warriors to guardians: Recommitting American police culture to democratic ideals (No. NCJ 24865). Laurel, MD: National Institute of Justice and the Harvard Kennedy School Program in Criminal Justice Policy and Management. Reiman, J. (1985). The social contract and the police use of deadly force. In F. A. Ellison & M. Feldberg (Eds.), Moral Issues in Police Work. (pp. 237–249) Savage, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.
219
Savage, J., & Kanazawa, S. (2004). Social capital and the human psyche: Why is social life ‘capital’? Sociological Theory, 22(3), 504–524. Scharf, P., & Binder, A. (1983). The badge and the bullet: Police use of deadly force. New York, NY: Praeger. Shaw, S. J., & Shaw, E. K. (1977). History of the Ottoman Empire and Modern Turkey: Volume 2, Reform, Revolution, and Republic: The Rise of Modern Turkey 1808–1975. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Sherif, M., Harvey, O. J., White, B. J., Hood, W. R., & Sherif, C. (1961). The Robbers Cave experiment: Intergroup conflict and cooperation. Institute of Group Relations, University of Oklahoma. Silver, J. R., Roche, S. P., Bilach, T. J., & Bontrager Ryon, S. (2017). Traditional police culture, use of force, and procedural justice: Investigating individual, organizational, and contextual factors. Justice quarterly, 34(7), 1272–1309. Smith, J. M. (1974). The theory of games and the evolution of animal conflicts. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 47(1), 209–221. Smith, J. M. (1982). Evolution and the Theory of Games. Cambridge University Press. Terrill, W., & Paoline, E. A. (2015). Citizen complaints as threats to police legitimacy: The role of officers’ occupational attitudes. Journal of Contemporary Criminal Justice, 31(2), 192–211. Terrill, W., Paoline, E. A., & Manning, P. K. (2003). Police culture and coercion. Criminology, 41(4), 1003–1034. Thrasher, F. M. (1936). The boys’ club and juvenile delinquency. American Journal of Sociology, 42(1), 66–80. Todak, N. (2017). De-escalation in police-citizen encounters: A mixed methods study of a misunderstood policing strategy (Dissertation). Arizona State University, Phoenix, AZ. Tyler, T. R., & Fagan, J. (2008). Legitimacy and cooperation: Why do people help the police fight crime in their communities? Ohio State Journal of Criminal Law, 6, 231–275. Van Maanen, J. (1978). The asshole. In P. K. Manning & J. V. Maanen (Eds.) Policing: A View from the Street (pp. 221–238). Santa Monica, CA: Goodyear.
220
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Walker, S. (1977). A critical history of police reform. Lexington, MA: Lexington Books. Walker, S. (2001). Police accountability: The role of citizen oversight. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth. White, M. D., & Fradella, H. F. (2016). Stop and frisk: The use and abuse of a controversial policing tactic. New York, NY: New York University Press.
Wolpert, S. A. (1962). Tilak and Gokhale: Revolution and reform in the making of modern India. Berkeley and Los Angeles, CA: University of California Press. Yabuta, S. (2008). Evolution of cross-contextual displays: The role of risk of inappropriate attacks on nonopponents, such as partners. Animal Behaviour, 76(3), 865–870.
11 Evolutionary Psychology, Jurisprudence, and Sentencing Eyal Aharoni and Morris B. Hoffman
I. JURISPRUDENCE AND PUNISHMENT1 Two thousand years ago, Socrates and an Athenian Sophist named Thrasymachus began a famous debate about human nature and the meaning of justice (Plato, 380 BCE). Are humans fundamentally good, built to cooperate and to appreciate beauty and truth, as Socrates contended, and therefore perhaps in need only of modest and occasional intervention by the state? Or are we fundamentally bad, built only to maximize our self-interest, as Thrasymachus argued, and therefore probably in need of heavy-handed restraint by a robust state? Is justice ‘the excellence of the soul’ (Plato, 380 BCE: 297) or nothing more than ‘the interest of the stronger’(Plato, 380 BCE: 275)? Humans have been having these same debates ever since, and the ways we have resolved them have largely defined our political and legal institutions. It is no coincidence that the founders of the United States were steeped
in the Enlightenment’s decidedly mixed version of this controversy. The Constitution’s distribution of powers between different branches of government was a reflection of the framers’ nuanced views about human nature. We are good enough to be largely free of an overbearing state, but not quite good enough to live without a state or to populate it without checks and balances between its parts. Until the paradigm-shifting insights of evolutionary psychology, behavioral economics, and the other disciplines described in Section II of this chapter, most modern takes on human nature have been skewed heavily toward Thrasymachus’ dreary views. The central simplifying assumption of classical economics was that each of us is relentlessly self-interested. Markets are an efficient integration of all those individual greedy unseen hands. Darwin’s insights strengthened the belief that we are self-interest machines, and biology’s great synthesis of evolution and genetics simply moved the locus of that selfinterest from the selfish individual animal
222
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
down to the animal’s selfish genes. Freud did much the same for the psyche, and Marx for the allegedly relentless march of economic and political history, framing the wars between self-interested classes. But then something delightful happened on this dark road to modern pessimism. Some economists, anthropologists, and psychologists had the audacity to look systematically at how humans actually behave instead of how these dreary theories predicted we should behave. And there were many surprising results. They discovered that when we play economic games in the laboratory, we engage in all kinds of cooperative behaviors that cannot be explained by classical economics, including sharing with and trusting other players, even when they are strangers. They discovered that we are not only not the rational self-interest machines conceived by classical economic theory, but that our apparent irrationality is predictable in many important decision-making domains. As discussed in more detail in Section II below, all these observations were then linked to the theoretical insights of evolutionary psychology. These same ancient and modern debates about human nature and the meaning of justice have echoed throughout the philosophy of law, also called ‘jurisprudence’. There are four main schools of jurisprudence – natural law, legal positivism, legal realism, and normative law – all addressed to these fundamental questions. Natural-law theorists view law in a way that is analogous to how natural philosophers viewed the physical universe: there are a priori principles (like Socrates’ truth, beauty, and justice) that animate legal systems just as physical laws (gravity, conservation of momentum) animate the universe, and humankind’s job is to discover these natural laws and apply them (Bix, 2010; Haakonssen, 1996). Natural law need not be grounded in the divine, although its most famous historical proponents – Socrates, Aristotle, and Thomas Aquinas – of course did so. As modern philosophers generally became less
satisfied with any systems that depended on unexaminable axioms of theology, natural law began to fall out of fashion. But there have been, and continue to be, modern efforts to re-ground natural law in concepts of secular morality, most prominently by Lon Fuller (Fuller, 1965) and Ronald Dworkin (Dworkin, 1986). We will see similar rekindled interests in secular morality from the normativists and even some positivists. Even though natural law’s fundamental principle is that law is a formal expression of morality, that position does not mean that all natural-law theorists take Socrates’ side in the debate about human nature. For example, Thomas Hobbes, a prominent Scottish proponent of natural law whose views were important to the founders of the United States, believed humankind’s natural tendencies were toward selfishness and violence, tendencies that needed curbing by a powerful state. Hobbes’ view of right and wrong seems presciently Darwinian; he once wrote that man is forbidden by natural law ‘to do that which is destructive to his life, to take away the means of preserving the same, or to omit that by which he thinks it may best be preserved’ (Hobbes, 1651). The second school of jurisprudence is called ‘legal positivism’. Like Thrasymachus before them, legal positivists rejected the fusing together of law and morality. The ‘positivism’ simply means that laws are rules posited by man, not by God. They are social constructs and nothing more. The role of the legal positivist is to describe those social constructs and to analyze them non-normatively, especially the processes by which laws come into being (Coleman and Leiter, 2010). There are many different subspecies of legal positivism, some of which vary by the degree to which they pay attention to moral groundings (Gardner, 2001). One of the most prominent modern positivists was H. L. A. Hart (Hart, 1961), who famously debated Lon Fuller in the Harvard Law Review in 1958 (Fuller, 1958; Hart, 1958). The third school of jurisprudence is ‘legal realism’. Legal realists, like positivists, take a
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY, JURISPRUDENCE, AND SENTENCING
non-normative view of law. But unlike most positivists, they are not satisfied with simply accepting the conventions of law as given social constructs. Instead, most legal realists are interested in the psychological engines that drive legislatures to adopt laws and judges to interpret them (Leiter, 2010). The law and economics phenomenon – using the insights of economics to study the relationship between law and its intended and unintended consequences – is a modern branch of legal realism. There are many other branches, including perhaps the most extreme one, usually credited to Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr. In Holmes’ view, law is nothing more than a prediction of the results of adjudication. The promise contained in a contract, under this view, means nothing other than a prediction that whoever breaks the promise will have to pay damages. To Holmes, law is power dressed up in process (Alschuler, 2000). Critical legal theory and its cousin, critical race theory, are modern versions of this extreme legal realism. The fourth and most recent school of jurisprudence is normative law. The normativists, somewhat like Fuller’s and Dworkin’s secular naturalism and the more morally interested positivists, focus on the foundations and justifications of the law. They are not satisfied either with the strict positivist assumption that laws are just arbitrary social constructs or with the realists’ fascination with the levers of power. They examine the purposes of law, and study methods to measure whether those purposes have been optimized (Shiner, 2010). All you non-philosophers out there are probably wondering what in the world any of this esoteric theorizing has to do either with evolutionary psychology or with how the law actually operates on the ground. The answer is that jurisprudence and evolutionary psychology are both concerned with human nature. As evolutionary psychology is impacting our fundamental view of what it means to be human, those impacts portend important consequences in many areas of the
223
law. The one we consider here is criminal sentencing. The debates between the four schools of jurisprudence in some ways echo, and in other ways are distinct from, the justifying theories that underlie criminal punishment. There are four main justifications for criminal punishment: retribution, rehabilitation, deterrence, and incapacitation (Alschuler, 2003; Davis, 2009). Retributivists generally believe that punishment is its own categorical good, and therefore it need not accomplish, or be validated by, any external effects. Hence, the other three theories, in contrast to retribution, are sometimes lumped together as ‘utilitarian’. Retribution is the oldest punishment theory, though its formalization is generally attributed to the German philosopher Immanuel Kant (1797). One can hear legal naturalism within retribution. Precisely because there is a natural core of right and wrong, punishment is as much a part of that a priori core as the right and wrong itself. But there are also positivist and realist currents in retribution. Kant’s intellectual successor, Georg Hegel, once wrote that criminals must be punished simply to earn their way back into the social fold. Crime is a breach of the social contract, which requires that the breacher pay damages in the form of suffering (Hegel, 1820). Deterrence was the first utilitarian rebellion against retribution. Utilitarians like Cesare Beccaria (1766) and Jeremy Bentham (1830) believed that no social group had the right to inflict punishment on its members unless that punishment resulted in a net social good. For proponents of deterrence, punishing wrongdoers is permissible because it deters both the person being punished (special deterrence) as well as others (general deterrence) from committing future crimes. Early proponents of deterrence focused on special deterrence. Bentham once famously asserted that no state had the right to punish any criminal, even a murderer, if it could be certain the criminal would never commit another crime (Bentham, 1830). But of
224
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
course, punishment that might not deter the wrongdoer may nevertheless deter millions of others, and thus be a net good. Modern proponents of deterrence therefore tend to focus on general deterrence rather than special deterrence. Both kinds are an amalgam of different jurisprudential schools. Like the realists and normativists, the deterrence school of punishment is focused on the way law accomplishes, or fails to accomplish, its central purpose of deterring crime. Rehabilitation is deterrence writ small. It focuses not on deterring the population as a whole, or even the particular criminal being sentenced, but rather on treating criminals to make them better persons who are less likely to commit future crimes. Rehabilitation became pre-eminent in US law at the beginning of the 20th century, as progressives viewed crime as mostly a product of failed social systems, and criminals as socially diseased and in need of a cure. It began to fall out of favor in the late 1960s (Allen, 1978; Alschuler, 2003). Incapacitation is the most recent justification for criminal punishment, at least when it comes to non-capital crimes. It ascended as a theory of punishment beginning in the 1960s as rehabilitation began to wane. Incapacitation, like special deterrence and rehabilitation, is focused not on the population as a whole but on the individual criminal. Incapacitationists believe the primary purpose of punishment is to remove criminals from society so that they do not commit more crimes. Unlike the other three theories of punishment, which attempt in different ways to remove people’s desire to commit future crimes, incapacitation is designed to remove their ability. These theories had important, real-life effects on the way we have treated criminals. When retribution was king, sentences in the United States were generally, and perhaps surprisingly, quite mild in length. Indeed, the Quakers invented the penitentiary in the late 1700s as a more merciful alternative to death and banishment, which were the punishments
for most serious crimes. Penitentiaries were not originally intended to be criminal warehouses. They were a place for criminals to contemplate their crimes and futures – to be penitent. Prison sentences for non-capital crimes in these early years were extraordinarily mild by modern standards – months rather than years. When rehabilitation ascended at the turn of the century these mild sentences became quite harsh. Cures took time. The length of prison sentences skyrocketed. Deterrence and incapacitation theories, especially prominent in the 1970s as rehabilitation fell out of favor, further boosted sentence lengths. These theories have all survived to some extent. Today, in all federal and virtually all state courts, judges are expressly directed to consider all of them when imposing a sentence. The federal statute, 18 U.S.C. § 3553(a), is typical. It provides that federal judges shall consider … the need for the sentence imposed: a. to reflect the seriousness of the offense, to promote respect for the law, and to provide for just punishment for the offense [retribution]; b. to afford adequate deterrence to criminals [general deterrence]; c. to protect the public from further crimes of the defendant [special deterrence and incapacitation]; d. to provide the defendant with needed educational or vocational training, medical care, or other correctional treatment in the most effective manner [rehabilitation].
The idea of this kitchen-sink approach is undoubtedly that different kinds of cases will tend to command different punishment goals. But how ought we resolve conflicts between these goals? For example, how should we deal with an offender who is morally culpable but not dangerous? Or dangerous but not morally culpable? The theories don’t tell us when one kind of goal should predominate over another. And if we need to consider all four goals, as most statutes command, none of the theories explains how judges are to integrate the theories’ incompatible goals.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY, JURISPRUDENCE, AND SENTENCING
If we punish only to deter, then why do we often punish serious wrongdoers who have low recidivism rates (murderers, for example) more than wrongdoers with astronomical recidivism rates (forgers, for example)? Similarly, if the main goal of punishment is to rehabilitate, then why do we punish Bentham’s already rehabilitated killer at all? If we only punish to incapacitate, then why doesn’t every criminal get a life sentence, or a sentence gauged only to the risks of his recidivating? It seems like something else, something non-utilitarian, is animating our actual sentencing practices. There’s a wonderful thought experiment (Alschuler, 2003) that sheds light on the incompleteness of all the utilitarian theories and hints that our retributivist urges run very deep and need to be acknowledged. Imagine a society in which all first-degree murderers are executed as part of the halftime show at the Super Bowl. The method of execution is a laser beam that we are told inflicts unimaginably excruciating pain on the prisoner for several minutes before he is terminally vaporized. But unbeknownst to us, the ‘killer’ beam is really a painless transporter beam, and it sends the prisoners to an idyllic island in the South Seas where they live out their lives in luxury but can never return. This system should be fine with true utilitarians. Deterrence is maximized, the murderers are rehabilitated (at least in the sense of being sent to a perfect society without social wants), and they are likewise incapacitated from ever hurting the rest of us again. But there is something deeply unsettling about such an approach. It is not fair. A retributivist would say that the murderers are not getting their just deserts (and in fact they are being rewarded for their heinous crimes). But retribution comes with its own incompleteness issues. How much desert is just, and why? Even more fundamentally, retribution seems to be built on the same unsatisfactory a priori sands as natural law. Philosophers might say that retribution has no antecedent moral justifications. It just is, like gravity.
225
The evolutionary insights discussed in Section II below address these central criticisms of retribution: our core moral intuitions evolved, and one of those intuitions is to punish serious violations of the other moral intuitions.
II. SCIENTIFIC PERSPECTIVES ON THE ULTIMATE AND PROXIMATE FUNCTIONS OF PUNISHMENT To predict where a storm front is heading, it helps to understand its initial conditions. The same is true for human nature. According to the perspective of evolutionary psychology, human behavior is enabled by brains that solved ecological problems – problems such as finding and maintaining good cooperation partners – favored by natural selection. So consideration of the problems that our brains evolved to solve can help to explain and predict the motivations that shape our social institutions, including, perhaps, the justice system. It is through this lens that it makes sense to ask what an organism would stand to gain from being punitive. Punishing other people is costly. At minimum, it takes time and energy, and it exposes the punisher to the risk of retaliation. So, unless a given punishment strategy tended to confer proportionally large benefits to the punisher, such a strategy would be unlikely to have evolved by natural selection. Yet punishment has been a ubiquitous part of human society (Brown, 1991). A growing body of empirical scholarship has thus sought to identify the potential benefits that common punishment behaviors are, in an ultimate sense, designed to procure. Here, we discuss some key results from this scholarship as well as their added value for our ancestors and possibly for modern legal institutions.
Second-Party Punishment Among the various forms of punishment that occurs in human societies, the simplest is
226
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
second-party punishment: when a victim retaliates against the victimizer. Retaliation is risky business. Yet it’s a common response to cheating and aggression in humans and even some non-human animals (CluttonBrock and Parker, 1995; Jensen et al., 2007). So, what are the benefits to be gained by second-party punishment? The evolutionary psychology literature provides at least three notable answers. First, retaliation, if deployed effectively, provides self-defense. It can serve as a precautionary strategy for managing a hazard in the environment (Fiddick et al., 2000), not unlike our instinct to shut our eyes in a dust storm. In this way, one need not posit the existence of an evolved psychology of social interaction because our need for self-preservation extends beyond the social. Indeed, there are many examples of self-defense across animal species, social and non-social alike, including algae (Paul and Fenical, 1986) and guppies (Godin and Davis, 1995). The most fundamental form of self-defense may be the immunological response (Hoffman and Krueger, 2017). Clearly, at least some of our evolved psychology may support retaliatory behavior, not to interface with the cheater’s motivations or perceptions, but more simply to protect oneself from harm. Another potential benefit to be gleaned from retaliating could be to gain a direct- fitness advantage over the cheater. An impulse to ostracize, kill, or otherwise debilitate the cheater could directly advance one’s own prospects, if deployed successfully (Trivers, 1971). However, since such actions invite dangerous countermeasures and thwart the possibility of future cooperation, this strategy would seem to be limited to situations in which continued victimization is assessed to be highly likely but the likelihood of mutual cooperation is low. In the environment in which our punishment psychology evolved, situations like this would have been more common when the offender was a member of a competing coalition rather than a member of one’s own social group.
A third way in which a victim could b enefit from retaliation is by transforming the cheater into a valuable cooperation partner. This characterization is known as the theory of direct reciprocity, proposed by Trivers, and there is considerable evidence for its operation in both human and non-human species (Trivers, 1971). For this strategy to be effective, the imposition of costs on the cheater would have to ‘educate’ the cheater by altering his incentive structure for how he conducts future interactions with the punisher. In other words, the punishment, or at least a credible threat of punishment, must appeal to his psychology of deterrence. If successful, this strategy not only protects the punisher from further exploitation but also enables reciprocal gains in trade between the dyad via increased cooperation. Thus, this strategy would commonly target members of one’s own existing social network. So, while retaliation might be risky, it can also pay dividends.
Third-Party Punishment Third-party punishment: why bother? Human punishment behavior, of course, is not limited to two-party contexts. Across history and across cultures, punishment by ostensibly independent ‘third’ parties is pervasive. In the ancestral environment, thirdparty punishment would have been delivered by members of the victim’s broader community, usually small coalitions of men who, together, could deliver punishment at lesser risk to any one individual. In modern societies, such activities have been largely delegated to social institutions like the criminal justice system, which empower disinterested triers of fact, like judges and jurors, to deliver third-party punishment. The fact that punishment is so costly is particularly problematic for evolutionary theories of third-party punishment since third parties are defined as people who are not involved in the offense and so do not stand
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY, JURISPRUDENCE, AND SENTENCING
to gain directly from the punishment. Why should they bother? The answer may lie in the fact that they are not really independent parties after all. Supposed third parties may have implicit social motivations driving their punitive attitudes even if they do not have conscious access to those motivations. This is because, being human, their minds evolved in a hyper-social context. People with traits that enabled them to exploit the social marketplace gained a fitness advantage. So, it is relevant to ask, in an ultimate sense, how these so-called third parties could stand to gain from particular types of punishment behavior, and how these gains might undergird modern legal justifications for punishment. A rich body of literature provides some empirical answers to this question. The first is kin selection, which predicts altruism toward genetic relatives. As expressed by the highly influential Hamilton’s Rule, the degree of relatedness (given the modest assumption that our ancestors could recognize their kin with some accuracy) predicts the degree of altruism because such altruistic behaviors increase the replication of our genes (Hamilton, 1964). Under these conditions, our tolerance for risk should increase – a prediction well-captured by the quip credited to biologist J. B. S. Haldane that he’d be prepared to die for two brothers or eight cousins (Connolly and Martlew, 1999: 10). Thus, costly punishments that deter or incapacitate actors from cheating our kin should be favored by natural selection. Indeed, evidence for kin-based punishment has been widely documented (Daly and Wilson, 1988). Since kin-based punishment must effectively prevent or discourage cheating in order to be selected, it is compatible with the incapacitative and deterrence-based philosophical justifications for punishment. Of course, punishments by judges and jurors are not supposed to favor kin. Indeed, the law specifically bars judges and jurors from serving in such cases. So an additional explanation is needed to explain third-party punishment in non-kin contexts. One such
227
explanation is strong reciprocity. According to this view, altruistic punishment can evolve because groups of people who expressed this trait deterred cheaters and, thus, enjoyed more cooperation than those who did not (Gintis, 2000). Support for this theory has been argued on the basis of a series of economic game studies. In these studies, participants who engaged in a repeated public-goods game demonstrate a willingness to punish third-party defectors at a cost to themselves, and this behavior sustained a norm of cooperation across the group of players (Fehr and Fischbacher, 2004; Fehr and Gächter, 2002; Fehr et al., 2002). Since punishment of this sort must effectively discourage the cheater or other tempted onlookers in order to be selected, this theory is compatible with the legal justifications of special and general deterrence. Despite its intuitive appeal, scholars disagree about the viability of such an altruistic strategy given that groups that punish would be vulnerable to exploitation by second-order cheaters, namely, people who shirk their contribution to the enforcement of punishment (Krasnow et al., 2015; Tooby and Cosmides, 2016). There is a burden, critics argue, to explain how the enforcement of punishment ever gained an evolutionary foothold, given that it’s individually costly. To explain how third-party punishment could benefit the individual punisher, one theory – social exchange theory – highlights the implicit value of the cheater and victim to the punisher. According to this theory, since humans evolved in small social exchange networks, most people that we encountered on a day-to-day basis would have been network members (i.e., direct resources to us), and so we operate on assumptions that our peers, and even most strangers, are potential exchange partners (Delton et al., 2011; Krasnow et al., 2013). Under this constraint, if an actor cheats a victim, ‘third parties’ who punish the cheater gain a direct advantage in social capital by deterring the cheater. This hypothesis has received support from multiple methods including experimental
228
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
surveys and economic games with real stakes (Aharoni and Fridlund, 2013; Delton and Krasnow, 2017; Krasnow et al., 2012, 2016; Pedersen et al., 2018; Price et al., 2002). This theory is a generalization of Trivers’ directreciprocity theory (1971), and it is most compatible with the legal justification of special deterrence. Other efforts to explain how third-party punishment could evolve at the individual level point to the reputational benefits of punishing. Known as indirect reciprocity, this theory states that by punishing a cheater, third parties accrue reputational credit with the victim and other community members, such that if the third party helps the victim by punishing the cheater, someone else may help the third party in the future (Nowak and Sigmund, 2005). People who are willing to enforce costly punishment signal their commitment to group norms, thereby broadly advertising their own social status (Frank, 1988). Since this strategy is designed to incentivize both second and third parties in the network, it is compatible with the legal justifications of special and general deterrence.
Third-party Punishment: how is it done? Besides asking what a punisher might gain by punishing a cheater, it would be valuable to understand by what manner punishment might achieve these ends. Most evolutionary theories of punishment posit that punishment increases the punisher’s fitness by reducing recidivism, but they are sometimes hazy about the proximate mechanism – how our evolved punishment response reduces recidivism. Here, we discuss some answers to this question of mechanism. From an evolutionary perspective, the most direct way to gain a fitness advantage over a cheater is by imposing corporal punishments like injury or death, as we discussed in the section on second-party punishment. This strategy assumes a motivation to (temporarily or permanently) behave in ways that incapacitate the cheater, but to achieve its aim, it does
not require a deterrence psychology – a folk psychological theory of the cheater’s or other group members’ motivations and incentive structure. This makes the incapacitative strategy cognitively efficient. However, this strategy is costly, partly because it could forestall a lifetime of future contributions by the former cheater to the social exchange community. Therefore, it should have evolved to be used as a last resort, and only when the costs imposed by the cheater are expected to outweigh his lifetime contributions. Another, potentially less risky, way to limit the probability that the cheater will cheat is to socially exclude, or ostracize, that individual from the group. By removing his opportunities to trade on the social market, this also reduces his opportunities to exploit cooperative group norms. In a general sense, this action can also be understood as an incapacitative strategy, but unlike corporal punishments, it may be easier to revoke. Thus, it would have been a useful strategy in ancestral environments, which lacked correctional institutions to perform the incapacitative work. Though incapacitation is a recognized legal justification for punishment, socialscience research suggests that it fails to capture a dominant feature of typical punishment psychology, namely, the desire to inspire changes in the cheater’s mental state. It is this feature of punishment psychology that ultimately defines the deterrence motive. The advantage of deterrence strategies over other strategies like direct-fitness reduction or ostracism is that, if effective, they immediately restore gains in trade between the former cheater and the social exchange network because they convert the cheater into a cooperator. Different scholars have characterized this process in slightly different ways. Some have described deterrence as a form of coercion (e.g., Matravers, 2000). The implication is that, while it may be against the cheater’s personal interest to shift to a more cooperative social strategy, the heavy threat of
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY, JURISPRUDENCE, AND SENTENCING
punishment may demand it, and so through a rational fear of that negative reinforcer, the cheater is compelled to change his behavior, against his deeper preferences. Certainly, as an empirical matter, most people are responsive to the threat of punishment, and so this form of deterrence is likely to play a role in crime and punishment psychology today. But a moment’s reflection suggests that there is something deeply unfulfilling about a cheater who plays by the rules only because of fear of punishment. Instead, we seem to crave a genuine mental transformation: we want the cheater to understand how he harmed us, and to fully endorse and internalize the values that guide our self-protective social norms (Nahmias and Aharoni, 2017), perhaps in no small part because when we internalize norms, we can worry less about catching norm violators. They catch themselves. Scholars have described this deterrence motive as a form of education or recalibration, namely, to change how much the cheater values our welfare relative to his own (Petersen et al., 2012; Trivers, 1971). Consistent with this perspective, experimental research demonstrates that we care deeply about whether the offender understands why he’s being punished. For instance, in an experimental stock-market game, participants were more satisfied with their punishment of an ostensible cheater when they received evidence that the cheater understood why he was being punished and even more satisfied when the cheater expressed a commitment to stop cheating (Gollwitzer and Denzler, 2009). Theoretically, it’s not surprising that we would evolve to favor a fundamental transformation in values over a more simple, coerced obedience. This is because coercion only works in the presence of a credible enforcement threat, whereas a recalibration of one’s values is self-enforcing. In this sense, effective recalibration harnesses the power of first-party punishment, which we discuss below. If punishment is designed to deter cheaters by recalibrating their value structures,
229
punishers should be sensitive to signals that the cheater had an unfavorable value structure to begin with. This could explain why punishers care so much about mens rea – the mental states at the time of the offense – such as criminal intent and knowledge of the risk of harm (e.g., Aharoni and Fridlund, 2011; Cushman et al., 2013). A punitive sentiment that didn’t care about these mental states would end up imposing heavy costs on genuine cooperators who had a stroke of bad luck, like a driver who caused a fatality as the result of a brain seizure. Typically, we don’t punish such individuals as harshly, if at all, and one reason could be that unlucky people who are otherwise morally innocent are not as likely to repeatedly undermine cooperative norms in the future. The presence of mental states like criminal intent, in contrast, are prognostic of future recidivism. In other words, a likely proximate function of punishment is to impose ecologically rational constraints on who we should punish. The premium that our deterrence psychology places on the cheater’s mental states reveals another lesson for the law: attempts to deter a cheater by encouraging internalization of norms would seem to qualify as a form of rehabilitation. As we noted, standard punishment theory treats deterrence and rehabilitation as separate motives for punishment. But both motivations, if delivered effectively, are designed to change behavior by inspiring a change in the cheater’s personal goals and values. Where they differ is that the deterrence motive places greater emphasis on the role of coercion as a motivator for recalibration. Whether coercion is any more effective a motivator is an empirical question. If coercion simply represents the threat of suffering, then as we discussed in the Super Bowl thought experiment, many people would be deeply unsatisfied by rehabilitation sans suffering. But if we could achieve such ends without the harmful means, then why do we feel an obligation that the offender should suffer? Why do we boil with outrage when he does not? Stated differently, what evolved
230
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
purpose is served by the offender’s suffering and the torrent of retributive impulses that give rise to it? The answer brings us to our final point about how our evolved punishment psychology carries out its function: via sophisticated motivational programs we call emotions. As economist Robert Frank (1988) forcefully argued, emotions serve as commitment devices: they are conspicuous, costly signals that commit us to a particular course of action. This is well illustrated by a classic anecdote of a game of chicken played by two opposing drivers. If one driver, while revving his engine, removes his steering wheel and drops it out the window for his opponent to see, that opponent must take seriously the first driver’s commitment to winning. If retributive emotions are like our first driver, they can be understood as part of a system that is motivating us toward a particular punishment strategy. The fact that these retributive emotions are not sated until the offender suffers suggests that the suffering may likewise serve a motivational role for the offender, namely to change his offensive behavior by shifting the balance in how much he values our welfare (Petersen et al., 2010). So, retributive emotions can be understood as mobilizing punishment and facilitating offender behavior change – functioning to keep both parties honest and invested in long-term reciprocity. The punisher, of course, need not be consciously aware of the functional role of these retributive emotions in order for them to exert their effects. Conceived in this way, the retributive motive for punishment is not in opposition to the utilitarian motives, as legal theory implies. Rather, it is an expression of them. In this view, we are psychological retributivists but adaptive utilitarians (Cushman, 2015). Retributive emotions commit us to punishment – a costly signal of our status that enhances the punisher’s fitness, either directly or indirectly, by modifying the cheater’s fitness, rational incentives, or social values. In this view, the legal purposes of
punishment are not wholly incompatible – they are just operating on different levels of analysis. Thus, the application of evolutionary theory carries the potential to synthesize the legally disparate theories for punishment.
First-Party Punishment: Conscience, Guilt, and Shame We’ve saved first-party punishment for last because it might be the most complex, and also because, in important ways, its effectiveness depends on the other two types. Firstparty punishment, as the phrase suggests, could be loosely understood as the tendency to ‘pre-punish’ ourselves with the bite of conscience to help us refrain from violating norms in the first place.2 Guilt and shame are also versions of first-party punishment, though they generally operate after we have violated a norm, and serve the function of reducing the chances of violating that norm again. Of course, with an animal as smart and devious as we humans, there is much overlap between conscience, guilt, and shame. We might feel guilty or ashamed even for contemplating a wrong. Likewise, we might look back on some of our decisions and wonder why our conscience did or did not save us from doing wrong. The bite of conscience is not just a human universal; it is a substantial part of self-image across cultures. It is central to many religions and mythologies (Katchadourian, 2009). It was probably a critical solution to the problem of effectively deterring antisocial behaviors in our social networks. At the proximate level of explanation, one of the reasons you don’t punch your neighbor during a political argument – perhaps the main reason – is not that you are afraid he’ll punch you back or that you will be punished by the criminal justice system, but rather because you know it is wrong. Brains with built-in systems that make their owners feel bad when they contemplate cheating are brains that will not cheat as often. This is what we mean when we said earlier
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY, JURISPRUDENCE, AND SENTENCING
that an offender has recalibrated his value structure or internalized a norm. Conscience is the first line of defense against the commission of antisocial behaviors, and at an ultimate level, it worked in concert with the other forms of punishment to deter individuals from undermining our ancestors’ precious social exchange network. Presumably, it had to work in concert with other forms of punishment because without an external threat of punishment, there would be little incentive to regulate oneself. One way to appreciate how important conscience is to our cooperative nature is to study people who don’t seem to have a conscience – psychopaths. Psychopaths tend to have deficiencies in brain regions associated with moral decision-making, including affective memory, inhibition, and empathy (Kiehl, 2007). Unsurprisingly, psychopaths make up a hugely disproportionate segment of incarcerated adults, are notoriously resistant to traditional punitive and rehabilitative treatments, and therefore consume an astonishing proportion of our criminal justice resources (Kiehl and Hoffman, 2011). A growing body of research has also begun to examine whether certain psychopathic traits might themselves contain evidence of adaptive design (Glenn et al., 2011). Such insights would underscore the need to investigate alternative approaches to behavior modification that better account for individual differences. If conscience evolved to steer us away from the commission of antisocial behavior, then guilt and shame evolved to help us learn from lapses in conscience. Research suggests that the emotion of guilt and the rumination that often accompanies it evolved to change an undesirable pattern of behavior by recalibrating the cheater’s relative utility functions for alternative goal states – the same process of recalibration discussed above. Similarly, the emotion of shame evolved to signal to others the cheater’s commitment to change through public acts of compensation and penance (Nahmias and Aharoni, 2017; Sznycer, 2018; Trivers, 1971).
231
In a classic experiment by Wallace and Sadulla (1966), individuals were led to believe they broke an expensive machine, and the transgression had either been discovered or not. The investigators found that compared to a control group who did not break the machine, the participants whose transgression was discovered were more likely to volunteer for a separate, painful experiment. Volunteering for a painful experiment, and other shame displays, can be understood as a costly signal of one’s commitment to the group, that one has internalized the purpose of punishment, and potentially that secondor third-party punishment is unnecessary. This pattern of behavior suggests that selfgoverning psychological systems are in place but may require social input to be triggered. This dependency would make sense if our self-governing systems coevolved with secondand third-party punishment systems. By implication, effective criminal punishment practices might be those that utilize the natural threat of public exposure to motivate offenders to recalibrate their internal model for how to treat others – or at least for how not to get caught. Many legal practices already exploit such properties, for instance, in publishing the names and addresses of local sex offenders. But to maximize their effectiveness, such practices should leverage rather than subvert our intrinsic, self-regulatory emotions. If so, such practices could qualify under the law’s deterrence- and rehabilitationbased justifications for punishment.
III. ANOMALOUS BYPRODUCTS OF OUR EVOLVED PUNITIVE ATTITUDES Though natural selection has fashioned sophisticated punishment strategies designed to protect the punisher’s interests and preserve norms of cooperation, it doesn’t always do this well. Natural selection produces relative fitness advantages. It does not optimize – it produces minimally viable solutions.
232
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Moreover, evolution by natural selection is slow, which means that today’s adaptations reflect fitness advantages with respect to ancestral environments, not modern ones. When a trait that evolved to solve a problem in the environment in which it adapted behaves differently in a more contemporary environment, it is known as an evolutionary mismatch. This lack of fit between the adaptation and its present environment can produce behavioral phenotypes (i.e., byproducts) that are over-sensitive to some evolutionarily novel cues (as when we crave candy as a proxy for fruit) and under-sensitive to others (as when drivers underestimate fatally high travel speeds). Likewise, the objectives and interests of legal institutions and their stakeholders are not necessarily aligned with those of our hunter-gatherer ancestors, and there are plentiful examples of punitive behaviors exhibiting such over- and under-sensitivities. Here we discuss these discrepancies as a potential source of ‘subtractive value’ of human punishment expressed in modern environments.
Over-Sensitivity to Legally Irrelevant Factors Several examples demonstrate how our punitive instincts may be over-sensitive to factors that are not legally relevant or efficacious. For example, judges and jurors are highly susceptible to the anchoring phenomenon. One dramatic experiment showed that professional judges who were asked to make hypothetical prison-sentencing judgments predictably increased or decreased their sentence following a phone call from an ostensible journalist (an actor in the study) who asked whether the sentence will be higher or lower than ‘one’ vs ‘three’ years (Englich et al., 2006). Since judges know they ought not take questions by the media, this tendency to conform their sentence to the journalist’s suggestion presumably occurred at an unconscious level. Such effects have been explained by known psychological biases
such as the availability heuristic, the tendency to place more weight on information that happens to be most cognitively accessible in that moment (Tversky and Kahneman, 1973). Although judges wouldn’t normally talk to journalists in the real world, similar anchoring effects could be caused by pretrial publicity generally. Another example of our over-sensitivity to legally irrelevant cues is the identifiable victim effect, which shows that people are more likely to support punishment when they know more about the victim – such as age or occupation, for instance (Jenni and Loewenstein, 1997). Given natural limitations on our cognitive resources, it makes sense that people who prioritized the most immediate information, such as who the specific victim was, would tend to have an advantage in the sorts of high-pressure social problems commonly faced by our ancestors. Of course, this logic does not necessarily result in fair and appropriate legal judgments. Arguably, not all information that judges and jurors learn about victims is strictly relevant to their judgments. Since some judges and juries are incidentally exposed to more information about victims than others, one implication of this research is whether attempts should be made to limit and standardize what victim information is and is not revealed to fact finders. Some widely studied examples of our oversensitivity to legally irrelevant cues include age, race, gender, and attractiveness biases. Experimental simulation studies have shown that defendants are more likely to receive higher sentence recommendations when they are portrayed as young, black, and male (e.g., Mitchell et al., 2005; Steffensmeier et al., 1998; Sweeney and Haney, 1992). Archival research has been less consistent, suggesting that any real-life sentencing biases against age, race, and gender may be small and highly variable (Bontrager et al., 2013; Mitchell, 2005; Wu and Spohn, 2009). To the extent that these biases are real, however, findings like these have been explained in proximate terms including ingroup favoritism and halo
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY, JURISPRUDENCE, AND SENTENCING
effects. But they are also consistent with more ultimate explanations of social exchange. According to these theories, in the environment in which our social brain evolved, demographic characteristics may have served as a conspicuous cue to group membership, and people who were willing to pay the cost to punish could reap direct rewards on trading markets by leveling more severe punishments against groups and individuals with whom they were most likely to compete for physical and social resources (Aharoni and Fridlund, 2013; Petersen et al., 2010, 2012). Ultimately, for such punishment biases to evolve, they would have had to be effective at deterring or incapacitating the most competitive opponents. And while the law takes pains to try to remove such response patterns from the courtroom, they often persist. Another example of our over-sensitivity to legally irrelevant cues concerns the disproportionate emphasis we place on severity as the preferred mechanism of punishment. The two most studied parameters by which a punisher can deter an offender are the severity and the probability of punishment. The intuition is that more severe punishments deter better, but research has shown that increases in severity have limited deterrent effect and diminishing marginal returns; increasing the probability of punishment would have a greater impact (e.g., Grogger, 1991; Paternoster and Iovanni, 1986). In the ancestral environment, the situation was different. People lived in small groups with little privacy, and so the looming threat of detection must have been real, and powerful. But in the massive societies we live in today, the probability that an offender is caught and adjudicated remains, on average, relatively low (Aharoni and Kiehl, 2013; Ehrlich, 1996), and offenders can exploit this fact. Despite the evidence that severe sanctions typically deter no better than moderate ones, people seem to readily accept modulating the severity of punishment as the primary instrument through which to express their punitive motives, consistent with the philosophical
233
principle of proportionality (see Robinson and Kurzban, 2006). One reason, as we discussed above, may be our instinctive desire to know that the offender will suffer because suffering once was an effective means of recalibration and long-term behavior change (Nahmias and Aharoni, 2017). Our punishment judgments are also sensitive to information from our internal, physiological environments. For example, research has provided evidence that judicial sentencing decisions are less favorable immediately following the shift to daylight savings time, when people tend to be most fatigued (Cho et al., 2017). Other research has shown a pattern of sentence increases following unexpected home-team football losses (Eren and Mocan, 2018), presumably by implicitly impacting the judge’s mood. Unconscious cognitive processes, such as those that regulate fatigue, stress, and mood, evolved as a part of a motivational system designed to prioritize our momentary physical and social needs, so they might have global effects on our decision-making, though it remains to be seen whether such effects are large enough to be decisive in court. Even subject-matter experts are susceptible to influence by extra-legal factors. The testimony of expert witnesses, of course, should be based on the principles of their discipline, but research suggests that scientific experts who engage in objective reasoning problems are (unconsciously) prone to produce evidence that confirms the preferences of the hiring party (Robertson, 2010; Wong et al., 2015). One likely proximate explanation for this ‘adversarial allegiance’ effect is socially desirable responding, a form of motivated reasoning. Socially desirable responding probably had important social advantages for our hunter-gatherer ancestors, but in a modern trial context, these effects could also bias factfinders’ ascriptions of guilt and punishment. Another extra-legal factor that we may be sensitive to is how the costs and benefits of punishment are presented. Although the cost of incarcerating a defendant, for instance,
234
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
may or may not be important to judges and taxpayers, incidental changes in the availability of that information should certainly not drive sentencing attitudes. Yet recent research suggests that when professional judges and laypeople make sentencing recommendations for criminal offenders, they are more lenient when the direct monetary costs of incarceration are made salient, suggesting that they find those costs to be relevant but fail to spontaneously consider them under typical, low-salience conditions. As a consequence, removing the cost information (without also removing benefit information) may produce sentence length recommendations that systematically exceed those made under more transparent conditions (Aharoni et al., 2019; Rachlinski et al., 2012). This behavior pattern implies that individuals’ punishment attitudes are internally inconsistent across informational contexts, placing more weight on whatever information happens to be most readily available in the moment. This tendency may be rooted in a more general tendency to discount distant future rewards relative to immediate ones (Loewenstein and Thaler, 1989; Metcalfe and Mischel, 1999; Mischel and Ebbesen, 1970). Placing greater importance on the here and now might have been adaptive for people in need of quick results under conditions of very limited information (see Daly and Wilson, 2005), but such features do not necessarily promote the careful, disinterested, and judicious decision-making that we expect of modern criminal justice decisions. We don’t mean to imply that more regulation is always the best solution to reduce bias in the courtroom, but that a richer understanding of how and why we punish can serve to clarify discourse on appropriate strategies.
Under-Sensitivity to Legally Relevant Factors There are also examples of our punitive instincts operating in ways that are
under-sensitive to factors that may actually be legally relevant. For one, we seem to readily discount the value of modern, custodial punishment strategies. Through the use of police forces, prisons, and civil commitment facilities, it is now possible to incapacitate dangerous offenders with lower risk to victims, and without the need to impose suffering or coercive ultimata on the offender. But as discussed, we often feel outrage at the prospect of an offender spending his days in a cushy rehabilitation center. And we demand punishment of moral offenders even if they are no longer dangerous (see Connolly, 2010). In such cases, though the modern sanction may effectively satisfy the ultimate objective of the punishment adaptation (i.e., to reduce recidivism), it fails to meet the adaptation’s more proximate conditions, such as evidence that the offender has undergone mental recalibration by way of suffering and penitence. Such responses evolved in environments in which effective custodial incapacitative sanctions were unavailable – they evolved not for incapacitation but for deterrence. This could help explain public dissatisfaction with purely custodial sanctions. From a public-safety perspective, in the presence of effective incapacitation, the offender’s attitudes about his punishment should be irrelevant. But people still treat them as relevant (Gollwitzer and Denzler, 2009) presumably because efforts to recalibrate his attitudes would have been one of the best strategies for reducing recidivism in ancestral environments. For this reason, we may be inclined to discount or altogether reject recidivism-reduction strategies that bypass opportunities for inducing suffering and penitence. If so, whether our evolved psychology of punishment (i.e., to achieve deterrence via retribution) provides a good justification for rejecting correctional sanctions that are equally effective but more humanitarian is a worthy normative question, but not one that can be answered by the science alone.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY, JURISPRUDENCE, AND SENTENCING
IV. THE UTILITY OF THE EVOLUTIONARY PERSPECTIVE From Explanation to Justification Before we finish up with some speculations about how the lens of evolutionary psychology might clarify some issues in the criminal law (and even a few issues beyond the criminal law), we need to address the problem of Hume’s Gap, or what is also called the naturalistic fallacy. In 1739, the Scottish philosopher David Hume complained about how there is often a gap between what is and what some philosophers claim ought to be (Hume et al., 1739 ). Just because behaviors happen regularly, that does not mean they are morally grounded. Rapes and murders happen all the time, but that doesn’t mean they are acceptable under any jurisprudential theory of law. In more modern philosophical parlance, moral truths (‘the ought’) cannot be derived solely from observational ones (‘the is’). Evolutionary psychology has been a favorite target of criticisms revolving around Hume’s Gap (Rose and Rose, 2000). Just because killing a rival and kidnapping his mate may have been an effective strategy for our ancestors (Buss, 2005; Daly and Wilson, 1988), and therefore our brains are arguably built with motivations for these kinds of behaviors, evolutionary psychologists are wary about taking those ‘is’ observations into ‘ought’ realms like the law, and quite properly so (Pinker, 2003). But Hume himself never suggested the trip between ‘is’ and ‘ought’ was unnavigable; he was just complaining that moral philosophers jumped the gap without so much as a pause. Indeed, like virtually every other moral philosopher of his time, Hume believed the worlds of nature and morals were connected. His connective tissue was empathy and socialization: our own selfish desires to avoid pain cause us to hesitate to inflict pain on others, and that hesitation was Hume’s root of morality (Hoffman, 2014). We suggest that evolutionary psychology itself has now supplied a more rigorous
235
connection between the ‘is’ and the ‘ought’. Moral intuitions (including intuitions to punish) evolved precisely because they gave our ancestors a net survival advantage in their intensely social groups. Human punishment behaviors are not just widespread by chance; they are widespread because evolution has armed us with emotions that make us feel their moral bite. The boldest answer to the jurisprudential question with which we began this chapter – where does law come from? – is not that it comes from God (as the traditional natural-law theorists argued), or from social conventions (the positivists), or from the individual and varying interpretations of lawmakers and judges (the legal realists). Instead, it comes from our evolved moral intuitions. In this account of moral realism, our notions of right and wrong come from the same place as our opposable thumbs and spines. Understanding what goals our punitive impulses evolved to achieve and how they achieve them can help us evaluate the degree of alignment with our modern societal goals, and can help formulate hypotheses for how to manage those impulses. For example, if deterrence is our main goal, we can ask whether retribution is still the best way to achieve deterrence. If so, lengthy prison terms might not satisfy that goal as efficiently as lashings and scarlet letters. Or if retribution is not the best way to achieve deterrence, then it might make more sense to remove offender suffering from the equation and focus instead on evidence-based rehabilitation services. Such tradeoffs would not be discoverable without a theory of the function that retribution evolved to serve. Caution is still warranted. Many a moral and legal judgment must be exercised in the vast areas beyond and between our evolved moral intuitions. These intuitions give us only the broadest contours of a secular morality. Even for those readers who reject our suggestion that evolutionary psychology can itself be a small bridge across Hume’s Gap, it still has significant utility when examining
236
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
legal questions. We discuss three examples: (1) synthesizing the various punishment theories; (2) providing a framework for predicting behavior under uncertainty in ways that might help us use law to leverage those behaviors; and (3) helping to inspire practical legal reforms in circumstances where the distance between the law and our evolved behavioral predispositions is just too great to leverage. The application of evolutionary theory to the law carries the potential to fundamentally change how we think about legal justifications for punishment and their apparent tensions. As we have argued, our punitive sentiments, and the sense of obligation that accompanies them, evolved in part because they gave punishers a fitness advantage by deterring cheating behavior, thereby protecting their physical resources and social exchange networks. The ultimate benefit was deterrence, but the proximate mechanism to accomplish that deterrence was retribution. When a wrongdoer revealed cues that he/she is not a good candidate for deterrence, other tactics were available, and these are reflected in sentiments like the desire to ostracize, incapacitate, or rehabilitate. Our powerful desire to forgive and be forgiven, about which there has developed a significant behavioral- and evolutionarypsychology literature (McCullough, 2008), is another one of these proximate mechanisms serving the ultimate advantage of reaping the many benefits of cooperation. Seen in this way, justice systems themselves can be understood as a type of ‘evolved’ system that is specialized to solve problems of cheating and cooperation. The notion that legal systems themselves evolved by processes akin to natural selection remains to be demonstrated, but whatever the mechanism, they do appear equipped to increase the scale by which group members can deter cheaters. This could be achieved by minimizing the costs of enforcement to any individual group member (Cushman, 2015). Notably, goals like ‘deterrence’ take on somewhat different meanings in the
evolutionary and legal accounts. The law attempts to protect a much larger and less well-defined social group than our punitive adaptations were designed to serve. Because of this mismatch, our evolved punitive psychology cannot necessarily be relied on to serve the explicit interests of society as a whole, and conversely, pursuit of such social goals may not necessarily satisfy our punitive desires, such as when the law is more merciful than what a victim demands. Evolutionary science alone is not sufficient to help us reconcile this tension, which hinges on normative judgments, but a deeper understanding of our evolutionary legacy brings such tensions to light.
From Explanation to Change An evolutionary psychological perspective can also help us understand the ultimate reasons for our behavior, so we can more lucidly decide whether these reasons are worth paying for and whether there are other ways of achieving our desired ends. By analogy, knowing that a fever is an adaptive response to infection can help us decide whether it benefits us most to take a medication that treats the fever symptoms or the underlying infection. Fever, of course, is not a perfect solution to overcoming an infection – in some cases, there might be other, more effective solutions – but, with some discomfort, fever usually and eventually gets the job done whereas treating the symptoms by suppressing body temperature could actually make the infection worse (Nesse and Williams, 2012). On the other hand, there are some adaptations that are clearly obsolete, like wisdom teeth that crowd the modern jaw. Similarly, knowing that human punishment motivations evolved to confer fitness advantages to members of a social exchange network, and knowing that it does this by employing retributive-emotion programs to cause individuals to behave in ways that facilitate deterrence and desistance of the offensive action
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY, JURISPRUDENCE, AND SENTENCING
can help us evaluate whether these are worthy aims, and if so, whether our punitive motivations achieve these aims more or less effectively than other strategies, such as particular rehabilitative approaches that do not demand suffering. Are retributive sentiments more like a fever that, despite the discomfort, works pretty well most of the time, or are they more like an impacted wisdom tooth that’s better off pulled? We don’t know the answer to this question – whatever the answer, it is undoubtedly complicated – but it’s largely owing to evolutionary theory that we can even articulate the question. A richer understanding of the ultimate reasons for human punishment behavior could potentially inspire practical strategies for managing unwanted effects. For example, knowing that offenders can exploit relatively anonymous lifestyles in modern societies, reducing perceptions of anonymity in highcrime areas (e.g., via increased surveillance) could reduce crime, increase the quality of evidence to support criminal charges, and consequently make punishers less reliant on the use of heavy sanctions to achieve the same level of deterrence. Knowing that decision-makers might neglect the costs of the punishment unless those costs are made salient could bolster arguments for increased transparency about sentencing costs, including recognition of other ways the funds could be used (i.e., the opportunity costs of the punishment). Knowing that sentencing judgments may be primed by factors like fatigue and mood, countermeasures could be developed, such as protocols for randomizing defendants to docket schedules to ensure that particular types of defendants (e.g., if a court tends to schedule high-risk defendants last) are not systematically penalized by timedependent effects. The power of evolutionary theory to mobilize the law in ways that more effectively shape human behavior has been dubbed ‘the law of law’s leverage’ (Jones, 2000). If we think of law’s proscriptions and threats of punishment as a lever by which society tries
237
to move its members away from antisocial or other destructive behaviors, then understanding the evolutionary pressures (i.e., the fulcrum) shaping those behaviors may tell us how long our levers need to be. Behaviors with deep evolutionary roots will be hard to move except with big levers. We’ve focused here on criminal sentencing, but evolutionary psychology might impact other areas of the law. This is not to say there is a one-to-one correspondence between evolutionary theories and particular legal reforms. The payoffs are not likely to be so direct. Instead, their value will be in constraining and inspiring plausible hypotheses about legally relevant behaviors including their triggers and inhibitors, by helping to identify any evolutionary roots of such behaviors. For instance, researchers have already discovered that ordinary people (like jurors) have significant trouble distinguishing between two of the criminal law’s four mental states – knowing and reckless (the other two are purposeful and negligent; Ginther et al., 2014; Shen et al., 2011). Examining the adaptive contours of mental-state attribution may help judges improve their definitions of these mental states. Understanding more about how different kinds of substances or diseases affect these mental states could also pay huge dividends in reforming the law’s traditional defenses to responsibility, including intoxication and insanity (Hoffman, 2018). Jury instructions – the written rules through which judges inform jurors about the legal rules they must apply to the case before them – are a fertile ground for evolutionary psychology-based improvements. Knowing how best to communicate complex principles to ordinary citizens, and the pitfalls that lie in wait, could substantially improve the truthfinding function of jury trials. Understanding more about human bias may help judges and lawyers identify biased jurors and/or inoculate them from the harshest effects of those biases. Insights about our irrational discounting behaviors could affect the way in which judges instruct civil jurors,
238
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
and lawyers argue to them, about future tort damages. Knowing that expert witnesses, too, are susceptible to social-cognitive biases, such as unconscious allegiance to the hiring party, could inspire the development of methods for controlling the experts’ access to this information, thereby improving the quality of the testimony on which guilt and punishment decisions may be based (Robertson, 2010; Wong et al., 2015). The potential for these insights to impact the law is not limited to courts and juries. They may even be more important at the front end of law as legislators consider new laws and regulators consider new rules and regulations. If the difficulty in distinguishing between knowing criminal acts and reckless ones ends up being insurmountable, informed legislatures may want to consider reforming the criminal law’s mental states. Likewise, as evolutionarily informed researchers learn more about those mental states, legislatures may consider changing the contours of some of the classic defenses to responsibility, such as intoxication or insanity. Similarly, a working knowledge of our time-discounting bias would certainly be important as legislators and regulators consider issues like usury rates, payday loans, and caps on future tort damages. Evolutionary psychology is likely to have significant traction in all these areas of the law because it informs our understanding of human nature, and law is applied human nature.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS We thank the Cooperation, Conflict, and Cognition lab members, especially Sharlene Fernandes, Corey Allen, and Justin Thurman, for helpful comments.
Notes 1 The first part of this section was adapted from Hoffman (2018).
2 We use the term ‘first-party punishment’ loosely since punishment in an ultimate sense implies the delivery of costs that come at the expense of the receiver, and it’s not clear that conscience, guilt, and shame are best understood this way. Another way to think of these mental states is in proximate terms, as programs that regulate how we conduct ourselves and treat others (see Peterson et al., 2010).
REFERENCES Aharoni, E., & Fridlund, A. J. (2011). Punishment without reason: Isolating retribution in lay punishment of criminal offenders. Psychology, Public Policy, and the Law, 18(4), 599–625. Aharoni, E., & Fridlund, A. J. (2013). Moralistic punishment as a crude social insurance plan. In T. Nadelhoffer (Ed.), The Future of Punishment. New York, NY: Oxford University Press (pp. 213–229). Aharoni, E., & Kiehl, K. A. (2013). Evading justice: Quantifying criminal success in incarcerated psychopathic offenders. Criminal Justice and Behavior, 40(6), 629–645. Aharoni, E., Kleider-Offutt, H. M., Brosnan, S. F., & Watzek, J. (2019). Justice at any cost? The impact of cost/benefit salience on criminal punishment judgments. Behavioral Sciences & the Law, 37, 38–60. Allen, F. A. (1978). The decline of the rehabilitative ideal in American criminal justice. Cleveland State Law Review, 27, 147. Alschuler, A. W. (2003). The changing purposes of criminal punishment: A retrospective on the past century and some thought about the next. University of Chicago Law Review, 70(1), 1–22. Alschuler, A. W. (2000). Law without values: The life, work and legacy of Justice Holmes. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Beccaria, C. (1766). On crimes and punishment. Hackett (1986). Bentham, J. (1830). The rationale for punishment. London: R. Heward. Bix, B. (2010). Natural law theory, 2nd ed. In D. Patterson (Ed.), A Companion to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory. West Sussex, UK: Wiley Blackwell (pp. 211–227).
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY, JURISPRUDENCE, AND SENTENCING
Bontrager, S., Barrick, K., & Stupi, E. (2013). Gender and sentencing: A meta-analysis of contemporary research. Journal of Gender, Race & Justice, 16, 349. Brown, D. (1991). Human universals. New York: McGraw-Hill. Buss, D. M. (2005). The dangerous passion: Why jealousy is as necessary as love and sex. New York, NY: Odile Jacob. Cho, K., Barnes, C. M., & Guanara, C. L. (2017). Sleepy punishers are harsh punishers. Psychological Science, 28(2), 242–247. Clutton-Brock, T. H., & Parker, G. A. (1995). Punishment in animal societies. Nature, 373(6511), 209. Coleman, J. L., & Leiter, B. (2010). Legal positivism. In D. Patterson (Ed.), A Companion to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory (2nd ed.). West Sussex, UK: Wiley Blackwell (pp. 228–249). Connolly, K. (2010, July). Nazi death camp guard charged over 430,000 Jewish deaths. The Guardian. Retrieved on May 6, 2019 from www.theguardian.com/world/2010/jul/29/ nazi-death-camp-holocaust Connolly, K., & Martlew, M. (Eds.) (1999). Altruism. Psychologically speaking: A book of quotations. Leicester, UK: BPS Books. Cushman, F. (2015). Punishment in humans: From intuitions to institutions. Philosophy Compass, 10(2), 117–133. Cushman, F., Sheketoff, R., Wharton, S., & Carey, S. (2013). The development of intentbased moral judgment. Cognition, 127(1), 6–21. Daly, M., & Wilson, M. (1988). Homicide. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers. Daly, M., & Wilson, M. (2005). Carpe diem: Adaptation and devaluing the future. The Quarterly Review of Biology, 80(1), 55–60. Davis, M. (2009). Punishment’s golden half century: A survey of developments from (about) 1957–2007. Journal of Ethics, 13(1), 73–100. Delton, A. W., & Krasnow, M. M. (2017). The psychology of deterrence explains why group membership matters for third-party punishment. Evolution and Human Behavior, 38(6), 734–743. Delton, A. W., Krasnow, M. M., Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (2011). Evolution of direct reciprocity under uncertainty can explain
239
human generosity in one-shot encounters. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 108(32), 13335–13340. Dworkin, R. (1986). Law’s empire. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Ehrlich, I. (1996). Crime, punishment, and the market for offenses. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 10(1), 43–67. Englich, B., Mussweiler, T., & Strack, F. (2006). Playing dice with criminal sentences: The influence of irrelevant anchors on experts’ judicial decision making. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 32(2), 188–200. Eren, O., & Mocan, N. (2018). Emotional judges and unlucky juveniles. American Economic Journal: Applied Economics, 10(3), 171–205. Fehr, E., & Fischbacher, U. (2004). Third-party punishment and social norms. Evolution and Human Behavior, 25(2), 63–87. Fehr, E., Fischbacher, U., & Gächter, S. (2002). Strong reciprocity, human cooperation, and the enforcement of social norms. Human Nature, 13(1), 1–25. Fehr, E., & Gächter, S. (2002). Altruistic punishment in humans. Nature, 415(6868), 137. Fiddick, L., Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (2000). No interpretation without representation: The role of domain-specific representations and inferences in the Wason selection task. Cognition, 77(1), 1–79. Frank, R. H. (1988). Passions within reason: The strategic role of the emotions. New York, NY: W.W. Norton & Co. Fuller, L. L. (1958). Positivism and fidelity to law: a reply to Professor Hart. Harvard Law Review, 71(4), 630–672. Fuller, L. L. (1965). The morality of law (2nd ed.). New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Gardner, J. (2001). Legal positivism: 5 1/2 myths. American Journal of Jurisprudence, 46, 199–227. Ginther, M. R., Shen, F. X., Bonnie, R. J., & Hoffman, M. B. (2014). The language of mens rea. Vanderbilt Law Review, 67, 1327. Gintis, H. (2000). Strong reciprocity and human sociality. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 206(2), 169–179. Glenn, A. L., Kurzban, R., & Raine, A. (2011). Evolutionary theory and psychopathy.
240
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Aggression and Violent Behavior, 16(5), 371–380. Godin, J., & Davis, S. (1995). Who dares, benefits: Predator approach behaviour in the guppy (Poecilia reticulata). Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, 259, 193–200. Gollwitzer, M., & Denzler, M. (2009). What makes revenge sweet: Seeing the offender suffer or delivering a message? Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 45(4), 840–844. Grogger, J. (1991). Certainty vs. severity of punishment. Economic Inquiry, 29(2), 297–309. Haakonssen, K. (1996). Natural law and moral philosophy: From Grotius to the Scottish Enlightenment. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. Hamilton, W. D. (1964). The genetical evolution of social behaviour. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 7(1), 17–52. Hart, H. L. A. (1958). Positivism and the separation of law and morals. Harvard Law Review, 71(4), 593–629. Hart, H. L. A. (1961). The concept of law. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press. Hegel, G. W. F. (1820). Philosophy of right 71 (T. M. Knox trans.). Oxford: Oxford University Press (1942). Hobbes, T. (1651). Leviathan. London, UK: A&C Black (2006). Hoffman, M. B. (2014). The punisher’s brain: The evolution of judge and jury. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. Hoffman, M. B. (2018). Nine neurolaw predictions. New Criminal Law Review: An International and Interdisciplinary Journal, 21(2), 212–246. Hoffman, M. B., & Krueger, F. (2017). The neuroscience of blame and punishment. In S. Menon (Ed.), Self, Culture and Consciousness: Interdisciplinary Convergences on Knowing and Being. Singapore: Springer (pp. 207–223). Hume, D. (1739). A treatise of human nature, 469. Oxford: Clarendon Press (1906). Jenni, K., & Loewenstein, G. (1997). Explaining the identifiable victim effect. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 14(3), 235–257. Jensen, K., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2007). Chimpanzees are vengeful but not spiteful.
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 104(32), 13046–13050. Jones, O. D. (2000). Time-shifted rationality and the Law of Law’s Leverage: Behavioral economics meets behavioral biology. Northwestern University Law Review, 95, 1141. Kant, I. (1797). The philosophy of law: An exposition of the fundamental principles of jurisprudence as the science of right (W. Hastie trans.). Edinburgh: T & T Clark 1887). Retrieved from https://oll.libertyfund. org/titles/kant-the-philosophy-of-law Katchadourian, H. (2009). Guilt: The bite of conscience. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Kiehl, K. A. (2007). Without morals: The cognitive neuroscience of psychopathy. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral Psychology (Vol. 3): The Neuroscience of Morality: Emotion, Brain Disorders and Development. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Kiehl, K. A., & Hoffman, M. B. (2011). The criminal psychopath: History, neuroscience, treatment, and economics. Jurimetrics, 4(1), 355–397. Krasnow, M. M., Cosmides, L., Pedersen, E. J., & Tooby, J. (2012). What are punishment and reputation for? PLOS ONE, 7(9), e45662. Krasnow, M. M., Delton, A. W., Cosmides, L. & Tooby, J. (2015). Group cooperation without group selection: Modest punishment can recruit much cooperation. PLOS ONE, 10(4), e0124561. doi:10.1371/journal.pone. 0124561 Krasnow, M. M., Delton, A. W., Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (2016). Looking under the hood of third-party punishment reveals design for personal benefit. Psychological Science, 27(3), 405–418. Krasnow, M. M., Delton, A. W., Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (2013). Meeting now suggests we will meet again: Implications for debates on the evolution of cooperation. Scientific Reports, 3, 1747. Leiter, B. (2010). American legal realism. In D. Patterson (Ed.), A Companion to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory (2nd ed.). West Sussex, UK: Wiley Blackwell (pp. 249–266). Loewenstein, G., & Thaler, R. H. (1989). Anomalies: Intertemporal choice. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 3(4), 181–193.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY, JURISPRUDENCE, AND SENTENCING
Matravers, M. (2000). Justice and punishment: The rationale of coercion. Oxford University Press on Demand. McCullough, M. (2008). Beyond revenge: The evolution of the forgiveness instinct. New York, NY: Jossey-Bass. Metcalfe, J., & Mischel, W. (1999). A hot/coolsystem analysis of delay of gratification: Dynamics of willpower. Psychological Review, 106(1), 3. Mischel, W., & Ebbesen, E. B. (1970). Attention in delay of gratification. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 16(2), 329. Mitchell, O. (2005). A meta-analysis of race and sentencing research: Explaining the inconsistencies. Journal of Quantitative Criminology, 21(4), 439–466. Mitchell, T. L., Haw, R. M., Pfeifer, J. E., & Meissner, C. A. (2005). Racial bias in mock juror decision-making: A meta-analytic review of defendant treatment. Law and Human Behavior, 29(6), 621–637. Nahmias, E., & Aharoni, E. (2017). Communicative theories of punishment and the impact of apology. In C. W. Surprenant (Ed.), Rethinking Punishment in an Era of Mass Incarceration. New York, NY: Routledge (pp. 144–161). Nesse, R. M., & Williams, G. C. (2012). Why we get sick: The new science of Darwinian medicine. New York, NY: Vintage Books. Nowak, M. A., & Sigmund, K. (2005). Evolution of indirect reciprocity. Nature, 437(7063), 1291. Paternoster, R., & Iovanni, L. (1986). The deterrent effect of perceived severity: A reexamination. Social Forces, 64(3), 751–777. Paul, V. J., & Fenical, W. (1986). Chemical defense in tropical green algae, order Caulerpales. Marine Ecology Progress Series, 34(1–2), 157–169. Pedersen, E. J., McAuliffe, W. H., & McCullough, M. E. (2018). The unresponsive avenger: More evidence that disinterested third parties do not punish altruistically. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 147(4), 514. Petersen, M. B., Sell, A., Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (2010). Evolutionary psychology and criminal justice: A recalibrational theory of punishment and reconciliation. In H. Høgh-Oleson (Ed.),
241
Human Morality & Sociality: Evolutionary & Comparative Perspectives. New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan. Petersen, M. B., Sell, A., Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (2012). To punish or repair? Evolutionary psychology and lay intuitions about modern criminal justice. Evolution and Human Behavior, 33(6), 682–695. Pinker, S. (2003). The blank slate: The modern denial of human nature. New York, NY: Penguin. Plato (380 BCE). The Republic, 272–297 (B. Jowett trans.). Seattle, WA: Amazon Classics (2017). Price, M. E., Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (2002). Punitive sentiment as an anti-free rider psychological device. Evolution and Human Behavior, 23(3), 203–231. Rachlinski, J. J., Wistrich, A. J., & Guthrie, C. (2012). Altering attention in adjudication. UCLA Law Review, 60, 1586. Robertson, C. T. (2010). Blind expertise. New York University Law Review, 85, 174–257. Robinson, P. H., & Kurzban, R. (2006). Concordance and conflict in intuitions of justice. Minnesota Law Review, 91, 1829. Rose, H., & Rose, S. (Eds.) (2000). Alas, poor Darwin: Arguments against evolutionary psychology. New York, NY: Harmony Books. Shen, F. X., Hoffman, M. B., Jones, O. D., & Greene, J. D. (2011). Sorting guilty minds. New York University Law Review, 86, 1306. Shiner, R. A. (2010). Law and its normativity. In D. Patterson (Ed.), A Companion to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory (2nd ed.). Sussex, UK: Wiley Blackwell (pp. 417–445). Steffensmeier, D., Ulmer, J., & Kramer, J. (1998). The interaction of race, gender, and age in criminal sentencing: The punishment cost of being young, black, and male. Criminology, 36(4), 763–798. Sweeney, L. T., & Haney, C. (1992). The influence of race on sentencing: A metaanalytic review of experimental studies. Behavioral Sciences & the Law, 10(2), 179–195. Sznycer, D. (2018). Forms and functions of the self-conscious emotions. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 23(2), 143–157. Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (2016). Human cooperation shows the distinctive signatures
242
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
of adaptations to small-scale social life. [Peer commentary on ‘Cultural group selection plays an essential role in explaining human cooperation: A sketch of the evidence’ by P. Richerson et al.]. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 39, 42–43. doi:10.1017/ S0140525X15000266 Trivers, R. L. (1971). The evolution of reciprocal altruism. The Quarterly Review of Biology, 46(1), 35–57. Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1973). Availability: A heuristic for judging frequency and probability. Cognitive Psychology, 5(2), 207–232. https://doi.org/10.1016/00100285(73)90033-9
Wallace, J., & Sadalla, E. (1966). Behavioral consequences of transgression: I. The effects of social recognition. Journal of Experimental Research in Personality, 1(3), 187–194. Wong, C., Aharoni, E., Aliev, G., & DuBois, J. (2015). Blind collaborative justice: Testing the impact of expert blinding and consensus building on the validity of expert testimony. RAND Report RR-804-1-NIJ. Retrieved on May, 18, 2020 from www.rand.org/pubs/ research_reports/RR804-1.html Wu, J., & Spohn, C. (2009). Does an offender’s age have an effect on sentence length? A meta-analytic review. Criminal Justice Policy Review, 20(4), 379–413.
12 Evolutionary Psychology and Incarceration Alina Simona Rusu
INTRODUCTION Literature in the field of criminal justice frequently places incarceration (i.e. the state of being confined in prison) in the context of the normative nature of human activities and institutions (Ward and Durrant, 2011). A recent analysis of incarceration systems at the international level (Mauer, 2017) points out that a nation’s incarceration rate is often interpreted as the degree of civilization of that nation, as well as the degree of punitiveness the nation is willing to impose in the process of isolating specific members from the broader community (i.e. in the direction of public safety). While several forms and levels of imprisonment exist, incarceration is often considered the end product of individual or societal failure (Mauer, 2017). In line with this consideration, international conventions and policies, such as the European Convention on Human Rights, state that no individual shall be deprived of liberty unless
certain conditions are met, such as the necessity to prevent the committing of an offence or fleeing after having done so (Macovei, 2004; Mauer, 2017). Analyses of criminal justice systems across human societies indicate that incarceration today involves not only the isolation of individuals, but also their rehabilitation through professionally designed interventions and educational programs. Features of violations of social rules are considered to meet the input conditions for the development of mechanisms designed to respond to inter-individual exploitation (Petersen et al., 2010, 2012). Hence, criminal justice institutions can be interpreted in the context of evolved counter-exploitation strategies. Two categories of counter-exploitation strategies (i.e. punishment and rehabilitation) are addressed in this chapter in the context of evolutionary analyses of incarceration from the perspectives of incapacitation of offenders and of reparative interventions.
244
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
INTER-INDIVIDUAL EXPLOITATION AND COUNTER-EXPLOITATION STRATEGIES Interactions with conspecifics in social species afford not only fitness opportunities but also potential costs, which can sometimes include even the death of individuals subjected to severe violence (e.g., Kurzban and Leary, 2001). Acts of exploiting conspecifics for self-benefits related to survival and reproduction have been documented in many social species, including humans, as well as evolved strategies designed to counter these exploitation efforts (e.g., Duntley and Buss, 2004; Petersen et al., 2012; McCullough et al., 2013). Punishment and behaviors that resemble human social exclusion, i.e., preventing particular individuals from interacting with the group, have been studied in nonhuman species, such as lemurs, chimpanzees, and three-spined sticklebacks (e.g., Wilson, 1980; Goodall, 1986; Wrangham, 1987; Kurzban and Leary, 2001). Kurzban and Leary (2001) interpret these types of behaviors in nonhumans and humans within the frame of discriminate sociality, noting different forms that have emerged due to different selection pressures. Several authors present and discuss several categories of counter-exploitation strategies, from the incapacitation of offenders to the combination of incapacitation and rehabilitation, as well as the development of prison settings with respect to the needs and welfare of human beings. Petersen et al. (2012) point out that the evolutionary literature on exploitation and its application to modern justice should take into account the counterexploitation strategies beyond punishment and note that the small-scale social world of our ancestors – with dense social networks and high levels of dependency – should have selected not only for punitive strategies, but also for non-punitive reparative ones (Aureli and de Waal, 2000; Petersen et al., 2010, 2012).
THE RECALIBRATION THEORY OF COUNTER-EXPLOITATION Starting from the idea that a major factor regulating the activation of reparative – rather than punitive – responses to exploitation/rule violation is the perceived social value of the perpetrator (the criminal’s social worth), an explanatory frame has recently emerged, i.e. the recalibration theory of counter-exploitation (Petersen et al., 2010). The authors offer the evolutionary prediction that the human mind spontaneously computes the magnitude of two distinct variables when confronted with exploitation: (1) the exploitation’s seriousness and (2) the exploiter’s association value; these variables are fed into motivational mechanisms regulating distinct aspects of strategies for countering exploitation (e.g., how severely we want to punish, how long we wish to incapacitate the perpetrator, how intense the social repair efforts will have to be; Petersen et al., 2012). Recent research demonstrates that the social decisions mentioned above depend upon the magnitude of an internal variable – a welfare tradeoff ratio (WTR) – which sets the weight the actor places on a specific person’s welfare relative to the actor’s own (Tooby et al., 2006; Tooby and Cosmides, 2008). Within this framework, Petersen et al. (2012) define exploitation as acts expressing too low a WTR (relative to some baseline) by inflicting a cost on the target for too small a benefit to oneself. From the perspective of this definition, evolution should have selected for counter-exploitation strategies designed to recalibrate the exploiter’s WTR in the direction of decreasing the number of exploitive acts they commit in the future (Sell et al., 2009; Petersen et al., 2012) and of inducing the exploiter to place greater weight on the welfare of others in the future (e.g., Clutton-Brock and Parker, 1995; de Waal, 1996, cited in Petersen et al., 2012). The efficacy of the reparatory functions of punishment appears to depend upon the ability of the punisher to monitor the exploiter’s
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND INCARCERATION
behavior (Petersen et al., 2012). From this perspective, prisons might have evolved as systems for monitoring the behavior of the exploiter, but also a way for the offender and for the society (‘the collective punisher’) to interact through reconciliation and other forms of reparative gestures.
245
Petersen et al. (2012) propose that the difference between the minimally acceptable WTR and the WTR expressed toward the victim reflects the intuitive concept of an exploitive act’s seriousness. In light of recalibration theory, the information on the seriousness of an offense should be reflected in the intensity of the reaction to regulate the WTR of the perpetrator toward potential victims (i.e. punitive or rehabilitative reaction). Petersen et al. summarize from an evolutionary point of view the criminological literature addressing the seriousness of crime. It appears that the seriousness of crime is set by the crime’s physical or symbolic level of harm and that the rank orderings of the seriousness of crimes are stable across cultures, especially with regard to crimes causing physical harm (Stylianou, 2003; cited in Petersen et al., 2012). Petersen et al. point out that, although less explored, there are data suggesting that the same crime is seen as less serious when performed for a large gain in inclusive fitness, such as stealing food for one’s family, defending relatives, etc., than for a small individual gain (Rossi et al., 1985). The authors suggest that these findings might indicate that intuitions about crime seriousness track welfare tradeoffs rather than harm alone (Duntley and Buss, 2004; Petersen et al., 2012).
the exploiter’s behavior violates social obligations (Vangelisti et al., 1991), reminding the exploiter of the favors done for them in the past (Sell et al., 2009) or signaling a wish for future prosocial interactions (Fujisawa et al., 2005; Petersen et al., 2012). The reparative gestures convey information to exploitive persons that they have underestimated the true magnitude of the harm inflicted, underestimated the true value of the relationships jeopardized, or overestimated the gain to the exploiter; it is argued that such information targets WTR circuits that are distinct from those targeted by punishment (Petersen et al., 2012). Petersen et al. (2012) argue that because different factors regulate whether specific actions are adaptive in private versus public contexts, evolution should have selected for cognitive machinery designed to compute a monitored WTR to govern decisions when one’s actions are likely to become known to those who will be affected by them, and a different cognitive machinery to govern decisions when one’s actions are not being monitored. It is argued that reparative gestures aim at up-regulating the exploiter’s intrinsic WTRs, such that they inflict less harm in the future even when not being monitored (Petersen et al., 2012). In line with this, research on emotions indicates that reparative interventions, when successful, have the potential to elicit guilt in exploiters (Harris et al., 2004), which subsequently up-regulates their cooperativeness (Harris, 2003; Petersen et al., 2012). Several studies support the idea that feelings of guilt correspond specifically to an up-regulation of the exploiter’s intrinsic rather than monitored WTR (Tooby and Cosmides, 2008; Petersen et al., 2012).
The Perceived Social Value of the Offender
Decision to Punish and/or to Repair
Research on reparative gestures reveals that they usually involve demonstrations of how
The dual character of the incarceration system, i.e. isolation and rehabilitation, is supported
The Exploitation’s Seriousness
246
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
by the four-phases frame of analysis of the evolutionary psychology behind the mechanisms of social justice institutions (Ward and Durrant, 2011): phase 1 refers to the inquiry into the nature of rehabilitation, which can be seen as a capacity-building guided process aiming to assist and shape the capabilities of the incarcerated offenders in making better prudential and moral choices; phase 2 consists in the identification of the features of an effective and ethical rehabilitation process, such as the offenders’ inherent dignity, capacity for independent functioning, and increase in well being, all within the direction of reducing the risk that these individuals will commit further crimes; phase 3 refers to asking questions about the relevance of evolutionary approaches to human functioning and behavior for the process of incarceration and of reintegration, in terms of understanding that the strategies of providing a ‘good life’ for offenders and other members of society should be based on realistic views of human nature and on the understanding of the causes of criminal behavior; phase 4 refers to the question of whether an evolutionary psychological explanation provides the best theoretical guidance on understanding the function of incarceration systems and of communalities of these systems across the nations of the world. In their comprehensive analysis of the decisions to punish or to repair in the context of an evolutionary psychological analysis of modern criminal justice, Petersen et al. (2012) conclude that, across a range of different types of crime and across two different countries (i.e. the United States and Denmark), the preferences of the participants for rehabilitation over punishment of the offenders were regulated by the perception of the social value of the offender, independently of their perception of the severity of the crime. However, the perception of the seriousness of the crime has regulated the intensity of preferred sanction (Petersen et al., 2012). The perceived association value of the offender was significantly affected by
several experimentally manipulated cues (i.e. evolutionarily significant cues in the context of human social functioning), such as the criminal history of the offender, the offender’s status as in-group or out-group member, and the offender’s expression of remorse (Petersen et al., 2012). One of the conclusions by the authors is that their results support the hypothesis that the mind’s design for decisions to respond to offenders (exploiters) is based on two distinct information-processing channels, i.e. one for computing the seriousness of the crime and the other for computing the criminal’s association value (Petersen et al., 2012). While nowadays there is little chance that an individual’s well being will be directly affected by the state’s decision to punish or to rehabilitate a specific offender, a strategic social calculus in terms of this decision might operate in intimate social settings, suggesting that this might mirror the adaptive problems faced by our hunter-gatherer ancestors (Petersen et al., 2012). In other words, the action of the selection pressures that have favored the mental designs that trigger reparative over punitive strategies in response to exploitive acts by individuals with potential social value might be reflected in the modern sanctioning institutions, including the incarceration system.
THE NICHE CONSTRUCTION THEORY APPLIED TO THE INCARCERATION SYSTEM Based on the four-phases model presented above, Ward and Durrant (2011) place the rehabilitation efforts of the prison system within the niche construction theory (OdlingSmee et al., 2003), which states that human beings partially engineer their environments and in this way contribute to downstream selection pressures, i.e. in the case of evolutionary functions of criminal justice from the perspective of niche construction, it is
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND INCARCERATION
assumed that greater community involvement in offender rehabilitation should encourage a higher investment by individuals in social norms and, further, that these individuals will be less likely to offend (Ward and Durrant, 2011). This idea is in line with the concept of rehabilitation applied to prison systems, which refers to normative processes that manifest at an individual level by assisting individuals to renounce criminal activity and construct socially desirable identities, and at the social level in terms of correctional policies directed at risk reduction (Ward and Maruna, 2007; Ward and Durrant, 2011). In other words, the evolution of modern incarceration systems might be considered an intentional social-intervention strategy, which should be analyzed by taking into account multiple ways of applying evolutionary theory to human behavior, such as human ethology, anthropology, sociobiology, memetics, and gene-culture co-evolution theory (Laland and Brown, 2002; Ward and Durrant, 2011). While one can assume that in the hunter-gatherer Pleistocene environment, the reaction of the group to an offender was probably a quick one in order to quickly resume everyday life activities, now there is a considerable social and economic effort in the direction of recalibration of interactions with offenders and reconstruction of their functional social identities. Niche construction occurs when organisms alter their environment through metabolism, activities, and choices, thus reconfiguring their relationships between their characteristics and the environment (Laland, 2007; Ward and Durrant, 2011). These alterations might reduce the selection pressures in the direction of enhancement of survival and reproduction. Examples of niche construction in humans are not only the products related to basic survival needs, such as houses, farming practices, heating systems, medical care, etc., but also the products addressing the development of social and cultural capital, such as technology products, books, and educational systems.
247
Odling-Smee et al. (2003) describe three types of processes involved in niche construction: genetic processes, ontogenetic or developmental processes (individual learning within lifetime), and cultural processes. These processes are argued to result in the modification of physical and cultural environments and are implicated in the generation of three types of inheritance systems (Odling-Smee et al., 2003): genetic inheritance, cultural inheritance, and ecological inheritance (i.e. the altered ecological niche). In a comprehensive analysis of niche construction theory in the context of offenders’ rehabilitation, Ward and Durrant (2011) direct special attention to the following types of inheritance: (1) culturally stored knowledge, arguing that this type of knowledge helps the incoming and current generations of humans not to repeat the errors made by the previous generations, and (2) ecological inheritance, which refers to changes in the environments and ecologies passed on to a new generation. According to Ward and Durrant (2011), such knowledge has the potential to offer greater flexibility for a species, as well as to gradually develop increased environmental control. In this line, the existence of incarceration systems across human societies, which function on similar rules and structured interventions directed to offenders, might indicate that this system is part of cultural and ecological inheritance at the species level. Another aspect that should be taken into account when placing the evolution of incarceration systems within the explanatory frame of niche construction theory (Ward and Durrant, 2011) is the existence of two basic types of niche construction: (1) inceptive niche construction, which refers to the original modification of the environment, and (2) counteractive niche construction, which refers to modification in an attempt to counteract a problem or a previous change. Several implications of niche construction theory, especially of counteractive niche construction, for the rehabilitation process of offenders (i.e. specific interventions with
248
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
offenders) are discussed in the literature, starting from elements of human behavior to the concept of extended cognitive system (Ward and Durrant, 2011). From the point of view of niche construction theory, human beings are culturally responsive animals, i.e. human behavior and socio-emotional capabilities can be shaped by ethical values and social norms that are imparted by social learning (Ward and Durrant, 2011). Hence, a broad range of behavioral options, as well as attitudes and proclivities of offenders, can be altered by interventions designed in the direction of socially responsible and meaningful lives (Clark, 2003; Sterelny, 2011; Ward and Durrant, 2011). Also, in the same direction of interpretation, it is considered that the fact that human beings can engineer their cognitive environments supports the existence of reparative interventions in prisons aiming to diminish the criminogenic cognitions and crime-supportive beliefs (Ward and Durrant, 2011). The concerted effort of society (social support) and professionals in the field of rehabilitation of offenders (e.g., psychologists, social workers, correctional staff, medical staff, etc.) points toward an extended cognitive system in relation to the evolutionary significance of incarceration. Specifically, Ward and Durrant (2011) suggest that, if one accepts the idea that human individuals utilize a combination of internal and external resources when involved in cognitive tasks, then it can be assumed that all the agents involved in the process of rehabilitation engineering of offenders are part of their extended cognitive system. In line with this, several authors indicate that a proper understanding of the role of cognition in causing and maintaining offending is dependent upon the fact that humans are socially embedded beings with a hybrid cognitive system, which consists of an integrated combination of internal and external components that enable problem solving (e.g., Clark, 2008; Menary, 2007; Ward and Durrant, 2011). In the context of incarceration, it is interpreted that the survival of offenders and the reflection on their offending-related problems while being
incarcerated does depend on the cognitive resources of others (Ward and Durrant, 2011). Another important aspect that should be taken into account when addressing the evolution of modern incarceration systems in the context of niche construction theory is the fact that humans, regardless of their incarcerationrelated status, are naturally inclined to seek certain goals, which are often called primary human goods (e.g., physical health, relatedness, subjective happiness, mastery; Ward and Maruna, 2007; Ward and Durrant, 2011). These primary goods or ‘natural desires’ (Arnhart, 1998) are considered markers of fitness or key components of well being; it is argued that they have their origin in human nature and have evolved through natural selection in the direction of establishing social networks favorable to survival and reproduction (Ward and Durrant, 2011). Primary goods are assumed to be linked to secure living that should allow the realization of potentialities specific to human individuals, such as states of mind, personal characteristics and experiences, states of affairs, etc. (Ward and Stewart, 2003). Additional to the primary goods, secondary goods or instrumental goods refer to the means of achieving primary goods (Ward and Durrant, 2011). Instrumental means could be considered both the offending behavior and the incarceration strategy: in the case of offending behavior, it is assumed that it can occur when individuals are trying to achieve primary goods in often destructive ways at individual and societal levels (Ward and Durrant, 2011), while in the case of incarceration systems, we can assume that restructuring interventions in prison are means of preventing further crimes in the direction of a secure living environment.
Effects of Incarceration: CrimeSuppressive and Criminogenic Consequences Definitions of prison are generally based on their functions related to the consequences of incarceration on individuals and society.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND INCARCERATION
Several theories suggest that prison is crime-suppressive, while others suggest that prison can have criminogenic consequences (Harding et al., 2017). It is assumed that the crime-reduction effect is achieved through incapacitation, rehabilitation, and specific deterrence (Bushway and Paternoster, 2009; Harding et al., 2017). The magnitude of any incapacitation effect depends on the offending of a comparison group of individuals who have not been imprisoned, and incapacitation effects occur only when individuals remain incarcerated. In contrast, rehabilitation and specific deterrence will exert their effects after release. It was also hypothesized that prison increases criminal offending through stigmatization and labeling effects, through social learning of pro-criminal attitudes, values, skills, and roles (prisons as ‘schools of crime’), and through prison’s effects on employment prospects (Harding et al., 2017). Recent studies indicate that returns to prison are primarily a product of post-prison community supervision rather than criminogenic effects of imprisonment, as many individuals sentenced to prison are trapped in the escalating surveillance and punishment of the criminal justice system; in other words, the rise in incarceration in the United States in the late 20th to 21st centuries was in part a self-perpetuation process resulting from the workings of the criminal justice system itself (Harding et al., 2017). Being sentenced to prison rather than probation increases the probability of future imprisonment dramatically, regardless of racial groups (Harding et al., 2017). Harding et al. (2017) suggest that probation sentences might be employed more frequently as an alternative to incarcerations. The cost savings associated with probation are large relative to the incapacitation effect of imprisonment and prison sentences do little to reduce/prevent criminal offending after release, relative to offending by probationers. Also, a significant proportion of incarcerated individuals are those that have been recently released from prison and have been re-imprisoned, i.e. prison’s revolving-door
249
phenomenon (Harding et al., 2017). Most of the prison returns are due to a mix of new crimes and technical violations of the conditions of community supervision in the postprison period (Pew Center on the States, 2011, cited in Harding et al., 2017). Technical violations during the post-prison period are considered a key mechanism driving the prison’s revolving-door effect, rather than an artifact of the pre-existing differences between prisoners and probationers (Harding et al., 2017). These results point toward the fact that for the reparatory function of the prison system to be effective, the rehabilitation programs and the monitoring of the former offenders should continue after their release, especially in the first years after, i.e. imprisonment for technical violations among prisoners is concentrated in the first two years post-release (Harding et al., 2017). Even though the data indicate that there is a moderate incapacitation effect of incarceration, i.e. a prison sentence reduces the probability of a new conviction by 5–8% in the first year after sentence, the increased rate of post-release imprisonment due to technical violations supports a self-perpetuating process resulting from the functioning of the criminal justice system itself (Siegel, 2014; Harding et al., 2017).
Social Functioning in Prison: An Evolutionary Analysis Various correlates of social functioning in prison have been addressed in the literature, such as the personality traits of the inmates, psycho-affective vulnerabilities, sociofamilial context, behavioral management in detention, etc. (Picken, 2012; Tomar, 2013; Unver et al., 2013; Andelin and Rusu, 2015; Rusu, 2016). The aspects investigated so far reflect not only the high level of psychosocial heterogeneity of the prison population, but also the level of complexity of the process of planning efficient strategies for the prevention of self- and hetero-aggressive behaviors in detention.
250
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
To date, there are no studies concerning the evolutionary significance of the dimensions associated with the optimal dynamic of social interactions in prison environments, specifically their functional value for survival in this specific environment, in which the most probable resources to be controlled by the inmates are those directly related to their survival, i.e. social interactions that pose the highest risk to their quality of life. From an evolutionary perspective, prison environments represent a complex mixture of stimuli and selection pressures, bringing together individuals who are not familiar with each other and who have different social abilities and inclusive-fitness-related traits. Inclusive fitness refers here to the abilities and traits of an individual organism to survive and pass on its genes through direct reproduction and/ or by investing somatic effort and other types of resources in his/her relatives (Hamilton, 1964). Some of the survival abilities of the individuals facing incarceration are visible (conspicuous) to others, i.e. they can be easily evaluated by other inmates without necessitating long-term interactions, such as age, gender, voice, physical appearance, body mass, general health, access to social support (family and friend visits). Other survivalrelated abilities are less visible (hidden) at primary evaluation, requiring time and longitudinal social interactions (e.g., ability to recognize emotions in specific contexts, emotional-intelligence level, interpersonal dominance or submission tendencies, etc.). Both categories of abilities can be investigated as predictors for the behavior of individuals in detention, thus pointing out the need for their inclusion in the professional screening forms of newly convicted persons, especially when dealing with individuals with a known history of aggression (Rusu, 2016). Aggression is costly in the prison environment, not only at an individual level, but also at the level of organization and mobilization of the human and other resources of the prison. Although from an evolutionary
perspective, aggressive behavior is useful for self-defense and resources protection (Buss and Shackelford, 1997), it still remains one of the behaviors posing the highest risk on the quality of life of incarcerated persons, both at the physical and psychological levels, often associated with self-harm and suicide (Towl, 2003; Campbell, 2005). Violence is a major problem in settings with incarcerated persons, and it is frequently associated in the literature with deficits in the facial emotion decoding accuracy (Hoaken et al., 2007). Emotion-identification errors, especially anger, are significantly associated with attribution of instrumental value to aggression in social contexts. Thus, a high level of aggressive attitudes and verbal aggression can be associated with misperception of anger even in its absence (Dodge, 1993). Also, individuals with a propensity for violence (who are frequently found in prison settings) have a higher probability of inadequately interpreting subtle social cues, such as facial micro expressions of emotions (Hoaken et al., 2007). According to the social information processing model (Dodge, 1993; McNiel et al., 2003), errors in emotion decoding accuracy have the potential to affect individuals’ ability (especially of those predisposed to violent behaviors) to access and employ alternative adaptive responses to social situations. In the case of incarcerated persons, there are data indicating that the ability to recognize facial expressions of fear and anger is reduced in inmates with a higher number of arrests and with a history of aggression (Dodge, 1993). From an evolutionary perspective, the ability to detect facial expressions of emotions, in particular those associated with anger, is hypothesized to have enhanced the chances of survival and reproduction of our ancestors in environments of evolutionary adaptedness, anger being the main indicator of the intention to aggress against another individual (Grandjean et al., 2005; Hoaken et al., 2007). Another important factor for optimal social functioning in prison is the level of emotional
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND INCARCERATION
intelligence (EI) of the offenders. EI seems to be a relevant factor for accessing strategies of responding to social situations other than the primary responses such as quick and violent behaviors. The social-cognitive theory of power (Fiske, 1993) posits that the ability to perceive others, an important component of EI, plays an important role in social-functioning outcomes. According to this theory, individuals situated in positions of power tend to perceive others in a non-individualizing, stereotypical manner. On the other hand, less powerful individuals (i.e. submissive individuals) seem to be favored by individualization of others because they consider interpersonal relationships as depending on the more powerful individuals and on interaction partners, in general (Fiske, 1993; Goodwin et al., 1998). Having access to emotional signals and decoding them correctly affords humans better chances of evaluating the attitudes and intentions of others (Hess et al., 1988; Mayer et al., 2008), of determining if social conflict is imminent (Ekman, 2009), and of adjusting interactive behavior in accordance with the perceived emotions. Consistent with the aspects presented above, it is recommended that, besides the standard psychological screening forms that are generally used in prisons, assessments of EI, emotion decoding accuracy, and individual inclusive fitness should be taken into consideration as biopsychological and evolutionary predictors of optimal social functioning in the prison environment (Rusu, 2016).
Costs of High Rates of Incarceration Several studies point out that imprisonment can be a profound life experience not only for the incarcerated persons, but also for their families and community (e.g., Mauer, 2017). These effects have been particularly related to high incarceration rates. Moderate rates of incarceration have a higher impact on crime reduction than high levels of incarceration,
251
which are associated with increases in crime; this effect is interpreted as the diminishing of informal social-control mechanisms that function to establish and reinforce social norms and create bonds among community and family members (Clear et al., 2003). Analyses of small human communities with high levels of incarceration indicate difficulties in family formation and child rearing (e.g., Braman, 2002), especially in those communities where most of the men have died or are serving in the military, but many are incarcerated. Hence, in terms of the direct fitness impact of incarceration at individual level, the imprisonment of men can considerably diminish the ability of women to find sexual and parenting partners in these communities (Raphael and Stoll, 2009). Also, literature indicates that imprisonment of parents can have unintended negative consequences on the well being of their children, often related to the placement arrangements of the children following parental incarceration (Johnson and Waldfogel, 2002). In terms of the financial costs imposed by incarceration systems, comparative analyses of cost savings between probation and incarceration indicate that the cost savings associated with probation are large relative to the incapacitation effect of incarceration (Harding et al., 2017). In the same study, Harding et al. (2017) revealed that the impact of prison sentences on reducing criminal offending after release is lower relative to the offending behavior of probationers; these results support the policy recommendation of using probation more frequently as an alternative to incarceration (depending on the seriousness of the offending) and more efficient planning of the post-prison parole supervision.
Emotional Burnout among Correctional Staff In terms of costs associated with the evolution of incarceration systems, evidence-based studies indicate that occupational burnout,
252
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
especially the level of emotional fatigue, is frequently reported among members of correctional staff, which can have negative consequences not only at the level of individuals, but also on the efficiency of the correctional organization (Hurst and Hurst, 1997; Griffin et al., 2012; Lambert et al., 2015). Job burnout is most commonly defined in the literature as psychological exhaustion and fatigue due to excessive workplace demands (Freundenberger, 1975 cited in Lambert et al., 2015). Maslach and Jackson (1981) have postulated three dimensions of job burnout: emotional exhaustion, depersonalization, and a reduced sense of personal accomplishment. Several studies indicate that the emotional dimension is the core component of burnout (Cordes and Daugherty, 1993; Maslach et al., 2012; Lambert et al., 2015) and that, compared to other professions from the category of helping others, correctional officers report significantly higher levels of emotional exhaustion as a dimension of job burnout (Maslach et al., 2012). The high level of emotional exhaustion in correctional officers was associated with turnover intent, absenteeism, and increased health problems, which were particularly high in maximum-security settings and in prisons holding juveniles (Fox, 1982; Carlson and Thomas, 2006; Lambert et al., 2010; Griffin et al., 2012). Hence, it appears that working tasks in prison settings involve important fitness-related costs to the employers, which are often addressed in terms of prevention and management by a higher income, possibilities for early retirement and, in some institutions, access to psychological- and social-support programs. Lambert et al. (2015) indicate in their investigation of the consequences of emotional burnout among correctional staff that the higher the level of education of correctional officers (e.g., college graduates), the lower the level of their emotional burnout; the findings are explained by the possibility that the officers with college degrees may have been given the opportunity to participate in decision making within the
institution. Correctional officers are usually the staff who are responsible for monitoring and implementation of programs planned by administrators and supervisory staff (Lambert et al., 2015). Previous studies indicate that a conflict in personal belief system versus institutional goals contributed to increased levels of emotional burnout, which in turn was associated with less favorable attitudes to treatment (in the context of rehabilitation) and more favorable attitudes to punishment (Lambert et al., 2015). Thus, one can conclude that emotional burnout of correctional staff represents an important variable to be considered when analyzing the selective pressures in the context of modern incarceration’s evolution. Recommendations are made by several authors regarding the necessity of exploring other variables of working place in prison, which are expected to play a role in correctional staff’s quality of life, support for treatment, support for punishment, turnover intent, and humane consideration of the needs of the incarcerated people. Another variable associated with lower levels of emotional burnout and greater life satisfaction in correctional staff was the opportunity to directly interact with the inmates in a positive manner (Lambert et al., 2015). When interpreting the behavior and attitudes of correctional officers toward inmates, Lambert et al. (2015) suggest that it is important to take into account that correctional officers tend to have most of the direct contact with inmates on a daily basis, so their perceptions of the goal of treatment versus punishment may be driven by the immediate circumstances of control rather than the longrange goals of the institutional plans.
Incarceration System from the Perspective of Helping Others In line with the data on the positive association between direct contact with inmates and greater life satisfaction in correctional officers (Lambert et al., 2015), one can assume
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND INCARCERATION
that a higher level of awareness of the fact that working with inmates is one of the professions within the category of ‘helping others’ (i.e. structured forms of prosocial behavior) may help in preventing emotional burnout and increase the occupational motivation. A common definition of prosocial behavior refers to it as ‘a broad category of acts that are defined by some significant segment of society and/or one’s social group as generally beneficial to other people’ (Penner et al., 2005: 366). A more specific definition of prosocial behavior from the field of evolutionary psychology considers it as a form of behavior that brings fitness benefits to the recipient and diminishes the fitness of the helper (West et al., 2007). The costs of helping others are well documented in the literature, mainly in the contexts of caregiving and informal and formal volunteering, and they usually include psychological and physiological correlates of caregiver distress (Rusu, 2019). Brown and Brown (2015) point out that the studies addressing the stress associated with helping others often fail to distinguish between the stress associated with the behavior per se and the feelings about the recipients (e.g., compassion, sadness). Besides the costs mentioned above, recent studies suggest that helping others in need (i.e. unrelated individuals) can be associated with benefits, such as experience of positive states and improvements in health and psychological well being (e.g., Brown et al., 2009; Jenkinson et al., 2013; Rusu, 2019). While helping others in need from the perspective of prosocial-behavior definitions implies an individual autonomous decision and intrinsic motivation, when it comes to the professions targeting the rehabilitation of offenders in prisons, the idea of helping others and the ways of doing so are imposed by the institutional and society rules, leaving most probably little place for the intrinsic motivation to occur. Therefore, we consider that in order to increase the rewarding value of the prisonrelated professions, more attention should
253
be offered to the prosocial aspects of these professions. One proposed action would be to include a learning objective in the training curricula of the correction officers on the neurobiological mechanisms and substrate of successful human social interactions, such as offering and receiving help from others in situations of need. For example, several recent investigations indicate that dopamine is one of the most commonly suggested candidates for the explanation of ‘helper’s high’ (Luks, 1988), which is described in the literature as a sensation of pleasure and subjective happiness associated with helping unrelated others in need (Krach et al., 2010; Rusu, 2019).
CONCLUSION The purpose of incarceration, i.e. whether to rehabilitate or punish offenders, is still a subject of debate not only within the criminal justice system itself, but also among members of society. In this chapter, incarceration is analyzed from the perspective of recalibration theory of counter-exploitation (Petersen et al., 2010, 2012), which is based on the evolutionary prediction that, when facing exploitation, the human mind spontaneously computes the magnitude of two variables: (1) the exploitation’s seriousness and (2) the exploiter’s association value. It is suggested in the literature that evolution should have selected for counter-exploitation strategies designed to recalibrate the exploiter’s welfare tradeoff ratio (i.e. a variable that sets the weight the actor places on a specific individual’s welfare relative to the actor’s own) in the direction of decreasing the number of exploitive acts in the future (Sell et al., 2009; Petersen et al., 2012). In line with this, modern prisons might function as a monitored strategy of welfare tradeoff ratio manipulation or adjustment, combining punishment and reparative actions in the direction of preventing future harm to society and up-regulation of the cooperativeness of the offenders.
254
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
The incarceration system is also discussed within the frame of niche construction theory, specifically the ways in which interactions with offenders are designed not only with the purpose of their incapacitation, but also in the direction of assisting them in renouncing criminal activity and in constructing socially desirable identities. Also, the chapter presents the idea that the concerted effort of society (social support) and professionals in the field of rehabilitation of offenders (psychologists, social workers, correction officers, etc.) could be interpreted as an extended cognitive system in relation to the evolutionary significance of incarceration. In terms of fitness-related analysis, incarceration imposes costs both on the offenders (e.g., incapacitation due to imprisonment, violent interactions in prison, negative consequences on the well being of their children and family) and on the correction staff (e.g., emotional fatigue, occupational burnout, turnover intent). Hence, one can conclude that the two main functions of the incarceration system (i.e. punitive and reparatory) are continuously challenged by selective pressures that are both external ones (i.e. system-independent, such as financial crises in the society), but also internal ones, including the system itself.
REFERENCES Andelin, E.I., & Rusu, A.S. (2015). Investigation of facial micro-expressions of emotions in psychopathy – A case study of an individual in detention. Procedia – Social and Behavioral Sciences, 209, 46–52. Arnhart, L. (1998). Darwinian natural right: The biological ethics of human nature. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press. Aureli, F., & de Waal, F. (Eds.). (2000). Natural conflict resolution. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press. Braman, D. (2002). Families and incarceration. In Mauer, M. & Chesney-Lind, M. (Eds.), Invisible punishment: The collateral consequences of mass imprisonment (pp. 137–135) New York: New Press.
Brown, S.L., & Brown, R.M. (2015). Connecting prosocial behavior to improved physical health: Contributions from the neurobiology of parenting. Neuroscience and Behavioral Reviews, 55, 1–17. Brown, S.L., Smith, D.M., Schulz, R., Kabeto, M.U., Ubel, P.A., Poulin, M., & Langa, K.M. (2009). Caregiving behavior is associated with decreased mortality risk. Psychological Sciences, 20, 488–494. Bushway, S.D., & Paternoster, R. (2009). The impact of prison on crime. In Raphael, S. & Stoll, M.A. (Eds.), Do prisons make us safer? The benefits and costs of the prison boom (pp. 119–150). New York: Russell Sage Foundation. Buss, D.M., & Shackelford, T.K. (1997). Human aggression in evolutionary psychological perspective. Clinical Psychology Review, 17, 605–619. Campbell, A. (2005). Aggression. In Buss, D.M. (Ed.), The handbook of evolutionary psychology (pp. 628–652) New York: John Wiley. Carlson, J., & Thomas, G. (2006). Burnout among prison caseworkers and corrections officers. Journal of Offender Rehabilitation, 43, 19–34. Clark, A. (2003). Natural born cyborgs: Minds, technologies and the future of human intelligence. New York: Oxford University Press. Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. New York: Oxford University Press. Clear, T., Rose, D., Waring, E., & Scully, K. (2003). Coercive mobility and crime: A preliminary examination of concentrated incarceration and social disorganization. Justice Quarterly, 20(1), 33–64. Clutton-Brock, T.H., & Parker, G.A. (1995). Punishment in animal societies. Nature, 373, 209–216. Cordes, C., & Dougherty, T. (1993). A review and integration of research on job burnout. Academy of Management Review, 18, 621–656. de Waal, F. (1996). Good natured: The origins of right and wrong in humans and other animals. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Dodge, K.A. (1993). Social information processing and peer rejection factors in the
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND INCARCERATION
development of behavior problems in children. In Biennial Meeting of the Society for Research in Child Development, New Orleans, LA. Duntley, J.D., & Buss, D.M. (2004). The evolution of evil. In Miller, A. (Ed.), The social psychology of good and evil (pp. 102–123). New York: Guilford. Ekman, P. (2009) Telling lies: Clues to deceit in the marketplace, politics, and marriage (Revised Edition). W.W. Norton & Company. Fiske, S.T. (1993). Controlling other people: The impact of power on stereotyping. American Psychologist, 48, 621–628. Fox, J. (1982). Organizational and racial conflict in maximum-security prisons. Lexington, MA: Lexington Books. Freundenberger, H. (1975). The staff burn-out syndrome in alternative institutions. Psychotherapy: Theory, Research and Practice, 12, 73–82. Fujisawa, K.K., Kutsukake, N., & Hasegawa, T. (2005). Reconciliation pattern after aggression among Japanese preschool children. Aggressive Behavior, 31, 138–152. Goodall, J. (1986). Social rejection, exclusion, and shunning among the Gombe chimpanzees. Ethology and Sociobiology, 7, 227–236. Goodwin, S.A., Operario, D., & Fiske, S.T. (1998). Situational power and interpersonal dominance facilitate bias and inequality. Journal of Social Issues, 54, 677–698. Grandjean, D., Sander, D., Pourtois, G., Schwartz, S., Seghier, M.L., Scherer, K.R., & Vuilleumier, P. (2005). The voices of wrath: Brain responses to angry prosody in meaningless speech. Nature Neuroscience, 8, 145–146. Griffin, M., Hogan, N., & Lambert, E. (2012). Doing people work among a tough crowd: A further examination of the job characteristics model and correctional staff burnout. Criminal Justice and Behavior, 39, 1131–1147. Hamilton, W.D. (1964). The genetical evolution of social behavior. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 7, 1–52. Harding, D.J., Morenoff, J.D., Nguyen, A.P., & Bushway, S.D. (2017). Short- and long-term effects of imprisonment on future felony convictions and prison admissions. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 114(42), 11103–11108.
255
Harris, N. (2003). Reassessing the dimensionality of the moral emotions. British Journal of Psychology, 94, 457–473. Harris, N., Walgrave, L., & Braithwaite, J. (2004). Emotional dynamics in restorative justice conferences. Theoretical Criminology, 8, 191–210. Hess, U., Kappas, A., & Scherer, K.R. (1988). Multichannel communication of emotion: Synthetic signal production. In Scherer, K.R. (Ed.) Facets of emotion: Recent research (pp. 161–182). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Hoaken, P.N., Allaby, D.B., & Earle, J. (2007). Executive cognitive functioning and the recognition of facial expressions of emotion in incarcerated violent offenders, non-violent offenders, and controls. Aggressive Behavior, 33, 412–421. Hurst, T., & Hurst, M. (1997). Gender differences in mediation of severe occupational stress among correctional officers. American Journal of Criminal Justice, 22, 121–137. Jenkinson, C.E., Dickens, A.P., Jones, K., Thompson-Coon, J., Taylor, R.S., Rogers, M., & Richards, S.H. (2013). Is volunteering a public health intervention? A systematic review and meta-analysis of the health and survival of volunteers. BMC Public Health, 13, 773. Johnson, E.I., & Waldfogel, J. (2002). Parental incarceration: Recent trends and implications for child welfare. Social Service Review, 76(3), 460–479. Krach, S., Paulus, F.M., Bodden, M., & Kircher, T. (2010). The rewarding nature of social interactions. Frontiers in Behavioral Neuroscience, 4(22), 1–3. Kurzban, R., & Leary, M.R. (2001). Evolutionary origins of stigmatization: The function of social exclusion. Psychological Bulletin, 127, 187–208. Laland, K.N. (2007). Niche construction, human behavioral ecology, and evolutionary psychology. In Dunbar, R.I.M. & Barrett, L. (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of evolutionary psychology (pp. 36–47). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Laland, K.N., & Brown, G.R. (2002). Sense and non-sense: Evolutionary perspectives on human behavior. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
256
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Lambert, A., Altheimer, I., & Hogan, N. (2010). Exploring the relationship between social support and job burnout among correctional staff: An exploratory study. Criminal Justice and Behavior, 37, 1217–1236. Lambert, E.G., Barton-Bellessa, S., & Hogan, N.L. (2015). The consequences of emotional burnout among correctional staff. Sage Open, 5(2), 1–15. Luks, A. (1988). Doing good: Helper’s high. Psychology Today, 22(10), 34–42. Macovei, M. (2004). The right to liberty and security of the person: A guide to implementation of Article 5 of the European Convention on Human Rights. In Human rights handbooks (No. 5), Retrieved 18 November 2019 from https://www.refworld. org/docid/49f181e12.html, Council of Europe. Maslach, C., & Jackson, S. (1981). The measurement of experienced burnout. Journal of Occupational Behavior, 2, 99–113. Maslach, C., Leiter, M., & Jackson, S. (2012). Making a significant difference with burnout interventions: Researcher and practitioner collaboration. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 33, 296–300. Mauer, M. (2017, April 26). Incarceration Rates in an International Perspective. Oxford Research Encyclopedia of Criminology. Retrieved 18 November 2019 from https:// oxfordre.com/criminology/view/10.1093/ acrefore/9780190264079.001.0001/acrefore9780190264079-e-233. Mayer, J.D., Roberts, R.D., & Barsade, S.G. (2008). Human abilities: Emotional intelligence. Annual Review of Psychology, 59, 507–536. McCullogh, M.E., Kurzban, R., & Tabak, B.A. (2013). Cognitive mechanisms for revenge and forgiveness (with commentaries and response). The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36, 1–58. McNiel, D.E., Eisner, J.P., & Binder, R.L. (2003). The relationship between aggressive attributional style and violence by psychiatric patients. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology, 71, 399–403. Menary, R. (2007). Cognitive integration: Mind and cognition unbounded. Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave Macmillan. Odling-Smee, F.J., Laland, K.N., & Feldman, M.W. (2003). Niche construction: The
neglected process in evolution. New Jersey, NY: Princeton University Press. Penner, L.A., Dovidio, J.F., Piliavin, J.A., & Schroeder, D.A. (2005). Prosocial behavior: Multilevel perspectives. Annual Reviews of Psychology, 56, 365–392. Petersen, M.B., Sell, A., Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (2010). Evolutionary psychology and criminal justice: A recalibrational theory of punishment and reconciliation. In HoghOlesen, H. (Ed.), Human morality and sociality: Evolutionary and comparative perspectives (pp. 72–131). Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan. Petersen, M.B., Sell, A., Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (2012). To punish or repair? Evolutionary psychology of lay intuitions about modern criminal justice. Evolution of Human Behavior, 33(6), 682–695. Pew Center on the States (2011). State of Recidivism: The Revolving Door of America’s Prisons. The Pew Charitable Trusts, Washington, DC. Picken, J. (2012). The coping strategies, adjustment and well being of male inmates in the prison environment. Internet Journal of Criminology, 1–29. Retrieved 8th of December 2018 from https://studylib.net/doc/8657392/ the-coping-strategies–adjustment-and-wellbeing-of-male. Raphael, S., & Stoll, M. (Eds.). (2009). Do prisons make us safer? The benefits and costs of the prison boom. New York: Russell Sage Foundation. Rossi, P.H., Simpson, J.E., & Miller, J.L. (1985). Beyond crime seriousness: Fitting the punishment to the crime. Journal of Quantitative Criminology, 1, 59–90. Rusu, A.S. (2016). Evolutionary-based aspects of optimal social functioning in prison. Acta Psychopathologica, 2(6), 1–3. Rusu, A.S. (2019). Educational practices for civic engaged students: Service-Learning from general to applied values in animaloriented professions. Journal of Educational Sciences & Psychology, 9, 29–35. Sell, A., Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (2009). Formidability and the logic of human anger. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 106, 15073–15078. Siegel, J.A. (2014). Prisoner reentry, parole violations, and the persistence of the
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND INCARCERATION
surveillance state. PhD Dissertation (University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, MI). Sterelny, K. (2011). The evolved apprentice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Stylianou, S. (2003). Measuring crime seriousness perceptions: What have we learned and what else do we want to know? Journal of Criminal Justice, 31, 37–56. Tomar, S. (2013). The psychological effects of incarceration on inmates: Can we promote positive emotion in inmates? Delphi Psychiatry Journal, 16, 60–68. Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (2008). The evolutionary psychology of the emotions and their relationship to internal regulatory variables. In Lewis, M. & Haviland-Jones, J.M. (Eds.), Handbook of emotions (pp. 114–137; 3rd ed). New York: Guilford Press. Tooby, J., Cosmides, L., & Price, M.E. (2006). Cognitive adaptations for n-person exchange: The evolutionary roots of organizational behavior. Managerial and Decision Economics, 27, 103–129. Towl, G. (2003). Psychology in prisons. Oxford, UK: BPS Blackwell. Unver, Y., Yuce, M., Bayram, N., & Bilgel, N. (2013). Prevalence of depression, anxiety, stress, and anger in Turkish prisoners. Journal of Forensic Sciences, 58, 1210–1218.
257
Vangelisti, A.L., Daly, J.A., & Rudnick, J.R. (1991). Making people feel guilty in conversations: Techniques and correlates. Human Communication Research, 18, 3–39. Ward, T., & Durrant, R. (2011). Evolutionary psychology and the rehabilitation of the offenders: Constraints and consequences. Aggression and Violent Behavior, 16, 444–452. Ward, T., & Maruna, S. (2007). Rehabilitation: Beyond the risk paradigm. London, UK: Routledge. Ward, T., & Stewart, C.A. (2003). The treatment of sex offenders: Risk management and good lives. Professional Psychology: Research and Practice, 34(4), 353–360. West, S.A., Griffin, A.S., & Gardner, A. (2007). Social semantics: Altruism, cooperation, mutualism, strong reciprocity and group selection. Journal of Evolutionary Biology, 20, 415–432. Wilson, E.O. (1980). Sociobiology: The abridged edition. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press. Wrangham, R.W. (1987). The significance of African apes for reconstructing human social evolution. In Kinzey, W.G. (Ed.), The evolution of human behavior: Primate models (pp. 51–71). Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
13 Evolution and Punishment Anthony Walsh, Cody Jorgensen, and Jessica Wells
INTRODUCTION In the opening words of The Scarlet Letter, first published in 1850, Nathaniel Hawthorne wrote: ‘The founders of a new colony, whatever Utopia of human virtue and happiness they might originally project, have invariably recognized it among their earliest practical necessities to allot a portion of the virgin soil as a cemetery, and another portion as the site of a prison’ (1879: 1). Hawthorne’s words are a reminder of two things we cannot avoid – human mortality and depravity, and that we must make provisions for both. We sadly commit our departed loved ones to the ground for obvious reasons, and we gladly remove miscreants from our sight for reasons just as obvious. It is beyond doubt that there are times when we must set certain people apart from the rest of us because they have demonstrated their inability to live by the agreed-upon norms of acceptable behavior. When we do this we are doing it against the will of the person being removed, and thus
we are expressing censure and community disapproval of his or her actions by inflicting punishment upon him or her. Of course, prisons are a relatively modern invention, but we have always retaliated in some way against those who have offended us. We see this retaliatory aggression in almost all sexually reproducing animals when conspecifics ‘cheat’ (signal cooperation but fail to be forthcoming). A classic example is that of vampire bats who freeload on blood donation. Bats who fail to find a blood meal on a given night will have regurgitated blood donated to them by other members of the group. The tendency is to share blood with those who have previously shared with them, thus returning the favor. Failure to reciprocate usually results in the original benefactor withdrawing future acts of sharing (Wilkinson, 1990). So even bats have some built-in motivation to retaliate punitively against norm breakers. From a scientific perspective, any emotion or behavior that is shown to be as universal as
EVOLUTION AND PUNISHMENT
the urge to punish must have an evolutionary history. Natural selection is a powerful positive feedback process energized by differential reproduction. If a genetic mutation results in the design (morphological, physiological, or behavioral) of an organism that allows it to out-reproduce other conspecifics, it will eventually become more common in the population and we then say that the design change has been selected for. Over many generations, the design change will spread until it goes to fixation in the population; that is, all members of the species have it. Cosmides and Tooby (1994: 328) liken natural selection to Adam Smith’s ‘invisible hand’ whereby unobservable market forces (‘natural selection’) fueled by millions of people seeking their self-interest (‘survival and reproduction’) move the supply and demand of goods (‘genetic polymorphisms’) in a free market (‘the environments of evolutionary adaptation’) to reach market equilibrium (‘genetic fixation’) automatically and without any intention or foresight. The consequences of punishing norm violators must have been positive with respect to the twin goals of all life – survival and reproduction. It is important for all animals to be motivated to do things that are vital in the pursuit of these goals. To provide that motivation, nature has provided us with neural mechanisms that reward us with pleasurable feelings when we do things that aid in achieving these goals. These pleasurable feelings arise from the neurotransmitter dopamine bombarding the nucleus accumbens and similar so-called ‘pleasure centers’ in the brain (Walsh et al., 2012). Each surge of dopamine can be viewed as Mother Nature’s reward when we satisfy urges to eat, drink, and have sex, which are the most obvious requirements for survival and reproduction. The pleasantness associated with dopamine (known as the ‘happy chemical’ in popular parlance) reinforces the behavior that makes us feel good and motivates us to repeat it. Given that the urge to punish wrongdoers is universal and strong (Penney, 2012),
259
punishment obviously played an adaptive role, but the survival and reproductive function of punishment is not at all as obvious as are the roles of food, drink, and sex. We do know, however, that humans find the same kind of satisfaction when heinous criminals are punished. Brain-imaging studies have shown increased blood flow to the nucleus accumbens when subjects witness the punishment of those who have wronged them (de Quervain et al., 2004; Klein, 2012). Blood flow to reward centers has also been observed when people are punished who have harmed others, and the strength of the pleasure response is proportional both to the harm done and to the level of the offender’s culpability (whether the act was purposeful, knowing, reckless, or negligent) (Buckholz and Marois, 2012). These brain-imaging studies provide us with compelling evidence that the urge to punish must be an adaptive feature of human nature, attested to by the old saying, ‘Vengeance is sweet’. Petersen and colleagues’ evolutionary perspective on criminal justice notes the various ways that our ancestors could have reacted to exploitative harm or other norm violations (2010: 92). These four ways they have identified are presented below. 1 ‘Killing the perpetrator, which permanently removes the threat’. In an evolutionary context, executing a band member would probably be considered a hugely important decision since all band members would have known the perpetrator and his or her family. The decision would have required a sufficiently serious group-damaging act and significantly more members of the band favoring execution than opposing it. In the modern United States, this is the death penalty, the imposition of which requires a particularly heinous murder and/or multiple murders. The death penalty is retributive in nature, although some justify it by a supposed deterrent effect. People who believe in the value of retribution say that punishment for its own sake is morally justified and need not be judged good or bad according to its consequences for society (such as deterrence). Logan and Gaes (1993) aver that retribution is the most honestly stated justification
260
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
for punishment because it taps into our punitive urges and posits no secondary purpose for it. 2 ‘Expelling the perpetrator from the social world through ostracism or confinement; or, on an individual basis, not engaging in future cooperation endeavors with those who have cheated’. In a band situation, being ostracized would have been devastating because the ostracized person would have no other group to which to turn for sustenance. Not so long ago, those who violated cultural and social norms were publicly shamed by being placed in the stocks for all passers-by to taunt and abuse. We no longer publicly abuse villains or tell them to ‘Get out of Dodge’; rather, we use imprisonment and justify it by the concept of incapacitation. The justification for incapacitation is well put by James Q. Wilson (1975, p. 391): ‘Wicked people exist. Nothing avails except to set them apart from innocent people’. Incapacitation obviously has positive consequences for society; while criminals remain in prison they can no longer harm people on the outside. For instance, in 1995, there were 135,000 inmates in prison whose most serious crime was robbery, and each robber on average commits five robberies per year. Had these robbers not been incarcerated, they would have been responsible for an additional 675,000 robberies that year (Currie, 1999). An Italian study of 22,000 inmates published in 2006 found that the incapacitation effect was an average of between 14 and 18 subsequent theft and robbery (these were the only crimes documented) arrests per released convict (Buonanno and Raphael, 2013). 3 ‘Punishing the perpetrator through infliction of costs or withdrawal of benefits’. This response to norm violations would have been far more damaging in ancestral environments if it meant the withdrawal of cooperation; in a modern sense it would still be painful but less so. Today such punishments would be in the form of fines and/or withdrawal of welfare benefits; just like the ‘No more blood for you, Vlad’ response to cheater bats. 4 ‘Reconciling with the perpetrator’. In a modern criminal justice system we call this rehabilitation, or to restore or return to constructive, healthy relationships with other members of society. Rehabilitation is criticized by conservatives as ‘molly cuddling’ and lacking in truth in sentencing, and by libertarians and some liberals for forcing offenders into treatment against their wills. Liberals charge that it contributes to sentencing disparity because it requires indeterminate
sentencing to accommodate different rates of offender ‘rehabilitation’. Yet we continue to try to rehabilitate criminals because we realize that whatever helps the offender helps the community. The rehabilitation model is well stated in former United States Supreme Court Chief Justice Warren Burger’s famous lines: ‘To put people behind walls and bars and do little or nothing to change them is to win a battle but lose a war. It is wrong. It is expensive. It is stupid’ (in Stohr et al., 2012: 246).
Of course, all these responses to norm violations are punitive in that those experiencing them do not welcome them. By imposing such pain, we hope that offenders will not repeat the behavior that led to his or her punishment, and to make those witnessing the punishment not be tempted to follow the same path. We call this punishment justification ‘deterrence’. Radzinowicz and King (1979) aver that retribution and deterrence occur simultaneously, but that the real social function of punishment is deterrence: People are not sent to prison primarily for their own good, or even in the hope that they will be cured of crime. Confinement is used as a measure of retribution, a symbol of condemnation, a vindication of the law. It is used as a warning and deterrent to others. It is used, above all, to protect other people … from the offender’s depredations. (Radzinowicz and King, 1979: 296)
RETRIBUTION: ITS ORIGIN AND FUNCTION Whatever justification for punishment that philosophers and criminologists may come up with, underneath it all is the urge for retribution. Retribution means recompense, repayment, payback, or getting even. Many criminologists tend to view retribution as an irrational and barbaric justification for punishment based on emotion rather than reason. They may note that retribution is most often given as a rationale by supporters of the death penalty (Bohm, 2012), which many see
EVOLUTION AND PUNISHMENT
as little more than state-sanctioned revenge (Rosebury, 2009). This position carries with it the unspoken assumption that the emotions behind the retributive urge are immoral and antisocial. Evolutionary psychologists and neuroscientists beg to differ, as did Justice Potter Stewart. In his concurring opinion in the Supreme Court’s 5–4 ruling in Furman vs. Georgia (1972) invalidating Georgia’s death penalty statute, he wrote the following about the importance of retribution and the folly of dismissing it: I cannot agree that retribution is a constitutionally impermissible ingredient in the imposition of punishment. The instinct for retribution is part of the nature of man, and channeling that instinct in the administration of criminal justice serves an important purpose in promoting the stability of a society governed by law. When people begin to believe that organized society is unwilling or unable to impose upon criminal offenders the punishment they ‘deserve,’ then there are sown the seeds of anarchy – of self-help, vigilante justice, and lynch law. (Furman vs. Georgia 408 U.S. 238, 1972)
What did Justice Stewart mean by locating the ‘instinct for retribution’ in the ‘nature of man’? One method of determining if something is ‘in the nature of man’ is to scour the historical record for the universality of the practice so considered. All early legal codes, such as the ancient Mesopotamian codes of Hammurabi, Ur-Nammu, and Eshnunna, and the Roman Laws of the Twelve Tables, were retributive, and the universality of such sentiments in criminal codes supports Stewart’s contention about the urge for retribution being a strong component of human nature. Given the assumption that it is part of human nature, how did it become so and why? Evolutionary logic tells us there must have been good adaptive reasons why our reward centers fire up when we punish or witness the punishment (vicariously or otherwise) of wrongdoers, but it does not tell us why punishment was so vital to our distant ancestors. We may approach the question by noting that Homo sapiens are an ultra-social species consisting of individuals who are preeminently
261
motivated to attend to their own survival and reproductive interests. The urge to cooperate with our fellow creatures and the urge to signal cooperation and then defect, thus receiving resources illegitimately, is the hedonic tug of war we all play with ourselves. Most of us successfully adjust with nary a thought of violating the social contract; some adjust with difficulty, and others find the illegitimate route congenial to their natures. The modern evolutionary view of human nature accommodates the classical view that humans are designed to maximize their pleasure and minimize their pain. The governance of these two sovereign masters is an adaption and thus functional, but it can be socially disruptive if immediate concerns for gratification are placed above maintaining social harmony and one seeks ‘money without work, sex without courtship, and revenge without court delays’, as Gottfredson and Hirschi (1990: 89) put it. This is the origin of the urge to punish because any individual who appropriates resources illegitimately thereby deprives the legitimate owners of resources needed for their own survival and reproductive success. Counteracting the human competitive and status-striving motives that lead to conflict is a powerful egalitarian instinct that leads to cooperation. One of the first moral statements uttered by children, and often quite forcefully, is ‘That’s not fair!’ How do children arrive at that conclusion long before they are able to articulate any moral reasoning for it, and why is it so compelling? A number of scholars (see generally Gavrilets, 2012) have posited that the nomadic lifestyle characterized by dangerous and uncertain prospects of obtaining survival resources kick-started the evolution of our species’ powerful social and egalitarian instincts. Small foraging and hunting and gathering bands demanded strict group-wide cooperation, with each individual’s survival depending on the survival of the whole. Any kind of behavior that would subvert mutual reciprocity (not pulling one’s weight, cheating, stealing) could
262
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
not be tolerated. Scarce resources had to be distributed according to egalitarian principles lest the group fall into disputes and fracture, leading perhaps to the death of everyone in it. In such a group, resource sharing would take place under the vigilant eyes of all in immediate time as opposed to a delayedtime sharing of society’s resources in agrarian and industrial societies. Perceptions of unequal distribution of resources would have produced immediate emotional reactions that were not of the warm and pleasant variety. Social animals cooperate because they can achieve more as a group than they can individually, and we feel good about ourselves when helping others. We are also rewarded by reciprocal behavior in the future, but even if the person we help is a stranger we are unlikely to meet again, we still receive a shot of dopamine that makes us feel good (Brunero, 2002). However, a population of cooperators would thrive and grow bigger, thereby planting the seeds of norm violation. A fairly large group of cooperators consisting overwhelmingly of non-kin provides a target-rich niche for people who cheat on the social contract and seek to gain resources at zero cost due to a lower level of vigilance and a higher level of anonymity. It has been estimated that the maximum group size to maintain stable relations among all members is around 150; this is known as ‘Dunbar’s Number’ (Hill and Dunbar, 2003). This number is derived from observation of different human groups which maintained stable relations throughout their history, extrapolation from relative neocortex size to group size in different species, and the assumed cognitive constraints involved in maintaining cohesion in face-to-face interaction while still pursuing one’s own personal evolutionarily relevant interests. The reference to neocortex size calls on studies of a wide range of primate species that show that group size is related to brain size (Dunbar and Shultz, 2007). Most evolutionary adaptations, including brain adaptations, are the result of challenges to survival and reproductive success posed by ecology (finding
food and mates, fighting off pathogens and predators, etc.) that all animals share, but human culture has shaped both the anatomy and function of the human brain above and beyond the changes wrought by the challenges posed by ecology. We know that from the approximate 1.5 million years that separated Australopithecus afarensis and Homo erectus, hominid cranial capacity doubled from a mean of 450 cc to a mean of 900 cc, and by another 70% to about 1,350 cc from Homo erectus to modern Homo sapiens. On an evolutionary timescale, this is truly an astounding level of morphological change in such a short period of time (Adolphs, 2009). A study of hominid crania by Bailey and Geary (2009: 77) found that geographic latitude was strongly related to cranial capacity (r = .61), but population density was more strongly related (r = .79), leading them to conclude that the burden of evolutionary selection has moved from ‘climactic and ecological to social’. There are a number of other studies of hominid crania dating as far back as 1.9 million years that show more robust increases in cranial capacity among groups in areas with greater population density and in areas in which food procurement was most problematic, namely, colder and most northerly areas of the globe (Ash and Gallup, 2007; Kanazawa, 2008). Living in large groups forces the brain to make more computations in order to negotiate relationships, to understand the thoughts, feelings, and intentions of others, and to cooperate in securing resources and in defending the group (Dunbar and Shultz, 2007). Despite increases in reasoning power, as has been pointed out, it is difficult to maintain the fuzzy warmth of all-for-one-and-one-forall kind of ‘primitive communism’ in groups larger than about 150 (Dunbar’s number). The seminal studies of Hutterite communities by Baden and Stroup (1972) are among the studies that reveal this. The Hutterites are a religious community spread across colonies in the United States and Canada.
EVOLUTION AND PUNISHMENT
The Hutterites seem to have a c ommon-sense understanding of human nature, and mandate that a settlement must split and form a new one every time the mother colony reaches about 150 people. When the colony is small, public surveillance of each person is more complete and an accounting of each person’s contribution (or lack of) is possible, just as it was on the ancient African savannah. The Hutterites recognize freeloaders who take advantage of their system of communal ownership of resources and call them drones (reference to male drone bees who do not participate in nectar and pollen gathering and whose only role is to mate with a queen bee). They also recognize that the number of ‘drones’ increases proportionately to colony size, which affords the drones greater autonomy. When the colony splits the ‘drones’ again come under the vigilant gaze of others and revert to norm compliance and become good ‘worker bees’ in the offspring colony.
KANT’S MORAL JUSTIFICATION FOR RETRIBUTION The philosopher John Mackie (1982: 3) saw a paradox inherent in retribution because it ‘cannot be explained or developed within a reasonable system of moral thought, while, on the other hand, such a principle cannot be eliminated from our moral thinking’. This ‘paradox’ is the result of assuming that rational deliberations about moral issues can take place without involving the emotions that, as we will see, cannot be done. However, Immanuel Kant has defended retribution rationally and morally. Kant’s justification of punishment is retributive but he is aware that retribution carries a message to the public of moral disapproval of criminals and their acts, and therefore conveys a de facto general deterrent effect. Deterrence rides on retribution’s coat tails, but as a stand-alone justification it cannot be a moral justification for punishment in Kantian terms.
263
Kant justifies retribution as the only moral justification for punishment in terms of the value, dignity, and agency of human beings. Kant’s retributionism is undergirded by his idea of duty and beliefs in human reason and autonomy. Human beings are different from other animals because they are guided by reason, and it is from reason that we derive all of our duties and obligations. Because we are blessed with reason, we all have a duty to act out of reverence for moral law, which Kant conceived of as a set of categorical imperatives. A categorical imperative is a moral duty to be discharged regardless of any further end or consequence. A categorical imperative commands ‘Do this!’; it does not say ‘Do this if’. Any action consistent with this is morally good, says Kant, regardless of its consequences. Categorical imperatives are viewed as universal laws that guide humans toward their duties: ‘Act as if the maxim of your action were to become through your will a universal law of nature’ (Kant, 1964: 89). In his Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, Kant says that a categorical imperative should be grounded in something that should be an ‘end in itself, and an absolute value’. He finds this grounding in ‘man’, who ‘exists as an end in himself, not merely as a means for arbitrary use for this or that will’ (1964: 95). ‘Man’, in all his actions, must always be regarded as an end in himself regardless of whether his actions are directed at himself or at others. Based on this, Kant arrives at a final definition of a categorical imperative: Act in such a way that you always treat humanity, whether in your own person or in the person of any other, never simply as a means, but always at the same time as an end. (1964: 96)
Respecting humans as ends in themselves leads to a retributionist justification of punishment. From this viewpoint, punishing criminals for instrumental reasons such as deterring others or subjecting them to rehabilitative treatment is morally wrong because
264
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
it treats them as means to an end, not as ends in themselves. As Kant phrased it in The Metaphysical Elements of Justice: Judicial punishment can never be used merely as a means to promote some other good for the criminal himself or for civil society, but instead it must in all cases be imposed on him only on the ground that he has committed a crime; for a human being can never be manipulated merely as a means to the purposes of someone else … He must first of all be found to be deserving of punishment before any consideration is given of the utility of his punishment for himself or his fellow citizens. (Kant, 1965: 331)
According to Kant, criminals are ruled by reason just as everyone else and thus live in accordance with maxims – universal moral standards (‘Act as if the maxim of your action were to become through your will a universal law of nature’). If criminals harm others, they are violating the autonomy of others, and by doing so, they are said to be endorsing criminal acts as universal laws, and thus in effect they are saying that others should act similarly. By punishing criminals, the state is treating them in accordance with their own maxims; that is, how they think others should be treated. The state is thus allowing criminals to decide how they will be treated, and by doing so, it is respecting their judgment and autonomy. Thus, Kant says of the criminal: ‘His own evil deed draws the punishment upon himself’ (in Rachels, 1986: 123). Retribution is a ‘just deserts’ model demanding that criminals be punished in proportion to the harm they have inflicted on their victims; thus death would be a proportional punishment for someone who has taken the life of another.
THE MORAL LAW WITHIN Humans live under an implied social contract by which we surrender some of our freedoms to do as we please in exchange for security. A vital part of the contract is the agreement not to harm others, and if we do, we recognize the fact that the state has the legitimate
right to punish us. As McBride (2007: 122) avers: ‘Punishment is the midwife in the birth of the social contract’. Central to the social contract is social integration and social order based on the strongly felt norms of right and wrong among its members. In evolutionary times, deeply felt moral rules helped individuals to stay connected to the group, survive in dangerous environments, and garner a valuable reputation as being trustworthy. Morals were therefore invaluable in terms of achieving shared ends. No society can do without intolerance, indignation, and disgust; they are the forces behind the moral law. (Moore, 1987: 199)
Moore adds: ‘In this view, the emotions of a people constitute moral truth’ (1987: 199). Individuals who freeload or cheat (we call the worst of them criminals) will always prosper in a population of unconditional cooperators whom evolutionary psychologists call ‘suckers’. Cheats would soon drive suckers to extinction. It has been consistently shown in computer simulation games such as the prisoner’s dilemma that in a mixed population of cooperators and cheats, cheats always do better than cooperators when no punitive response is forthcoming (Klein, 2012; Nowak, 2006). Of course, very few humans are suckers. The vast majority of us are ‘grudgers’ who cooperate conditionally. Grudgers can be cheated because they abide by the norms of mutual trust and cooperation and expect the same from others. Once cheated, however, grudgers will react differently to cheaters in the future in tit-for-tat ways (Wiebe, 2011). Anyone stealing resources or sexual mates in our species’ evolutionary history constituted a severe threat to everyone in a group relying on strong norms of reciprocity, and thus would have generated intense negative emotions such as anger, outrage, disgust, and a desire to punish. As de Waal (1996: 160) puts it: ‘A taste of revenge is the other side of the coin of reciprocity’. Victims feel angry and hurt when treated unfairly. Victims also
EVOLUTION AND PUNISHMENT
feel confusion and frustration at losing the expectation of the predictability of reciprocity. The sum of these evolved emotions is moral outrage. Without moral outrage there would be no internal motivation to react against those who violate the norms of reciprocal cooperation, cheats would have thrived without the threat of punishment in our ancestral environments, and we would have evolved as a quite different species of animal (Haidt, 2012; Nowak, 2006). However, natural selection does not pass its judgment on emotions, or even on the behaviors they motivate, if those behaviors do not result in enhanced reproductive success. Natural selection operates on the consequences of the behavior motivated by the emotion (Massey, 2002; Walsh, 2006). It is no use silently feeling angry and hurt when victimized. Those feelings must generate behavior designed to prevent it occurring again. Negative feelings caused by victimization are mediated by punishing violators because punishment signals the restoration of fairness and predictability (the perception that cheaters may be less likely to cheat in the future, and that potential cheaters may be deterred). The positive feelings accompanying the punishment of those who have wronged us, coupled with the reduction of negative feelings, provide powerful reinforcement for punitive responses and may explain why we see increased blood flow to the brain’s reward centers when wrongdoers are punished.
THE IMPORTANCE OF MORAL EMOTIONS IN UNDERSTANDING PUNITIVE BEHAVIOR We have been waxing about such things as moral outrage, disgust, and revenge, but aren’t these things all primitive emotions, and surely we have progressed beyond relying on such unreasoned criteria when deciding what to do with criminals? Primarily, we
265
are concerned here with the moral or ‘social’ emotions such as guilt, shame, empathy, and embarrassment, although the more basic emotions such as anger, disgust, and joy come into play in punishment. These social emotions that evolved as integral parts of our social intelligence provide clues about the kinds of relationships (cooperative vs uncooperative) that we are likely to have with others, and serve as ‘commitment devices’ and ‘guarantors of threats and promises’ (Mealey, 1995: 525). Barkow (1989: 121) describes them as involuntary and invasive ‘limbic system overrides’ that serve to adjust our behavior in social situations. The social emotions animate, focus, and modify neural activity in ways that lead us to choose certain responses over other possible responses from the streams of information we constantly receive. The social emotions move us to behave in ways that enhanced our distant ancestors’ reproductive success by overriding neocortical decisions suggesting alternatives to cooperation (i.e., cheating) which may have been more rational in the short term, but which were ultimately fitness reducing. One of the most salient emotions in people’s punishment urges is empathy; not for the person to be punished but rather for his or her victim. Rob Canton (2015: 59) maintains, ‘The emotions of punishment are distinctly moral emotions. They are emotions of judgement, of righteousness and reprobation’. Canton is implying that people feel these emotions not just for themselves, but also on behalf of victims they have never met, and they are therefore deeply prosocial emotions linked to concern for others. This is the emotion we call empathy. Empathy is an ancient capacity predating the emergence of Homo sapiens that evolved rapidly in the context of parental care and is found only in mammals and some bird species (de Waal, 2008). Empathy is the cognitive and emotional ability to understand the feelings and distress of others as if they were our own. The cognitive component allows us to understand their distress and why they are feeling
266
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
it, and the emotional component allows us to feel that distress ourselves (‘I feel your pain’). Feelings of distress are discomforting because they trigger stress/anxiety hormones (i.e., cortisol), giving us the unconscious feeling that we are threatened and motivating us to ‘do something’. To the extent that we feel empathy for others, we have a visceral motivation to take some action to alleviate their distress if we are able; thus empathy is the emotional component of altruistic actions. Performing a helpful action on behalf of another alleviates the distress of the other individual and thereby we alleviate our own. Thus, empathy has a selfish component, but it is a very good thing that it does because if we were lacking in emotional connectedness to others, we would be callously indifferent to their needs and suffering. Once locked into the human repertoire, empathetic feelings can be diffused to a wider network of social relationships, which is why empathy is considered ‘the heart of mammalian development, limbic regulation, and social organization’ (Farrow and Woodruff, 2007: 51). Empathy is arguably the quintessential social emotion, and therefore it is difficult to dismiss its impact on punishment decisions as irrational. We recognize that doing the right thing when there is a strong temptation to do otherwise as conscience. In The Descent of Man, Charles Darwin opined that conscience is based on two things: the social instincts and cognition and habit: ‘the social instincts – the prime principle of man’s moral constitution – with the aid of active intellectual powers and the effects of habit, naturally lead to the golden rule’ (Darwin, 1896: 106). Obviously, we must have a cognitive awareness of what is right and wrong, but the consensus of opinion agrees with Darwin that the emotional component of conscience is most important (Choy et al., 2015; Kochanska and Aksan, 2004). The degree to which the sympathetic branch of the autonomic nervous system (ANS) is activated, and/or the speed at which the parasympathetic branch returns the ANS
to homeostasis in the face of temptation and the decision not to give in, is the major determinant of conscience development. It is obvious that ‘doing the right thing’ is much more than rational consideration since that thing we call a conscience typically moves us in that direction before we have had an opportunity to contemplate our options (Barkow’s ‘limbic system override’).
RATIONALITY AND EMOTION: THE HEADS AND TAILS OF DECISIONMAKING The ancient notion that rationality and emotion are polar opposites is no longer viable. It has long been known in neuroscience that cognition is always suffused with emotion and cognition with emotion (Nowak and Sigmund, 2005). Our emotional and rational neural mechanisms work in unison and sustain each other, and often cannot be separated. As we have seen, decision based on emotions are typically more effective when the decision to be made is a moral one than a decision arrived at after pondering all possible outcomes and implications. Neural-network research has shown that emotion and reason are fully integrated in the lateral prefrontal cortex (LPFC): ‘the convergence of both cognition and affective/motivational information enables the LPFC to dynamically weigh multiple lines of information in guiding action’ (Pessoa, 2008: 154). Although emotion and rationality are two inseparable components of all that we think and do, neuroscience informs us that when the two are in conflict, emotion usually triumphs over reason (Verweij et al., 2015). Emotions are assumed to be located in a set of brain structures called the limbic system, which is a multi-structural system of behavioral regulation that predates the evolution of the prefrontal cortex structures where our reasoning power is housed by at least a million years (Suwa et al., 2009). As Douglas
EVOLUTION AND PUNISHMENT
Massey (2002: 15) notes: ‘Emotionality clearly preceded rationality in evolutionary sequence, and as rationality developed it did not replace emotionality as the basis for human interaction. Rather, rational abilities were gradually added to preexisting and simultaneously developing emotional capacities’. Jonathan Haidt (2001: 819) puts it even more strongly: ‘It [emotion] comes first in phylogeny, it emerges first in ontogeny, it is triggered more quickly in real-time judgments, and it is more powerful and irrevocable [than rationality] when the two systems yield conflicting judgments’. Anyone who wishes to challenge the primacy of emotion over rationality in making moral decisions will have to confront the evidence of psychopathy. If relying on rationality in making punitive decisions is the mark of a ‘civilized’ being, and introducing emotion into the equation is irrational and barbaric, then the callous psychopath must be the epitome of the civilized being. He/ she is the consummate expert in using his/ her rational faculties – unencumbered by the emotions of guilt, shame, embarrassment, and empathy – to connive and manipulate others into doing his/her bidding, and has been defined as an ‘obligate cheater’ (da Silva et al., 2015; Mealey, 1995; Quinsey, 2002). The psychopath knows the rational words of the moral song, but not its emotional music. This results in an entirely utilitarian self-centered pattern of behavior (Jorgensen et al., 2016). The defining neurobiological feature of psychopaths is that the rational and emotional areas of the brain are poorly integrated (Raine, 2013; Wiebe, 2011). This has been demonstrated using numerous techniques such as EEG, PET, fMRI, and even at the molecular level by diffuse tensor imaging (DTI), which tracks the movement of molecules along white-matter tracts to and from the ‘rational’ prefrontal cortex and the ‘emotional’ limbic system (Craig et al., 2009; Walsh and Bolen, 2012). Psychopaths are fully able to understand the moral norms of society rationally; it is their lack of understanding of their moral
267
implications supplied by the social emotions of guilt, shame, empathy, and embarrassment that explains their activities. Psychopaths feel more primitive primary emotions such as anger and fear, but due to the poor connections between the limbic system and the prefrontal cortex, they are not guided by rational considerations, just as their rational considerations are not guided by the social emotions. When the psychopath does display emotions, they are indeed ‘confused passions’ and ‘pathological’. A retributive punishment justification is the only justification associated with deep natural emotions. When people hear of some vicious criminal act such as the rape and murder of a young girl, they become angry, outraged, and disgusted. Their first inclination is to want to exact some sort of retribution; it is highly unlikely that their first thoughts should be of deterrence or rehabilitation. Only a callous psychopath would shrug his shoulders upon hearing of such a crime because it had no impact on his life, which is, of course, entirely ‘rational’. The rest of us would feel empathy for the victim and her grieving family. However, this retributive urge still tends to be damned as ‘irrational’, ‘uncivilized’ by good liberal humanists who find it entirely inappropriate. Retribution, they rightly complain, is punishment for its own sake from which nothing good can come, and which degrades society. Wanting something good to come from punishment is a utilitarian position by which the only justification for punishment is its alleged positive consequences. Moore (1987) sees this position as hypocritical since no objections to emotional outrage are offered when it is aimed at unjust punishment of the innocent. Don’t we all experience feelings of outrage when we hear of an innocent man being released from prison after 20 years through DNA exoneration? Most people are emotionally disturbed when they perceive innocent people are being or have been punished, even if it has resulted in some positive consequence for society. Why then do many consider it
268
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
barbaric when the same emotional outrage is aimed at the acts of guilty people? If the moral judgment in the first instance is virtuous, then it is virtuous in the second instance also. The retributionist would say that if you demand a positive outcome from punishment for its own sake, then that would be justice being done. The retributionist would also say that punishing the innocent, regardless of what positive consequences may come from it (such as general deterrence), is impermissible and unjust.
THE ROLE OF EVOLVED EMOTIONS IN CAPITAL-PUNISHMENT DECISIONS The issue of capital punishment is a deeply moral one, and as we have seen, the foundation for morality is more emotional than rational. The deep emotional underpinning of morality, and thus the morality we bring with us to these issues, is generally not appreciated by people who cannot understand why equally reasonable people can arrive at opposite conclusions regarding the issue of capital punishment. Two equally intelligent people can have access to exactly the same information on a deep moral issue, but differ radically as to its meaning based on the emotions it generates. Capital punishment thus provides us with a meaningful stage on which to present the role of emotions in punishment since the death penalty is the ultimate and irrevocable punishment. Support for capital punishment waxes and wanes in the United States with crime rates, especially violent crime rates. A 2018 Pew Research Center poll found that 54% of Americans favor the death penalty while 39% oppose it (Oliphant, 2018). Public support of the death penalty was at its lowest at 42% in 1966 when the violent crime rate was 200 per 100,000 population, and at 80% in 1994 when the violent crime rate peaked at 713.6 per 100,000 (Hatch and Walsh, 2016: 111). These figures clearly indicate that at
some level people track crime as reported in the news media and form their attitudes accordingly. We wish to emphasize that the following discussion of death penalty decision-making implies neither support nor non-support of capital punishment. It is meant only to emphasize the role of evolved human emotions in the juror’s decision, for they must make it, not the judge. Additionally, we also note that it is possible to have no objection to the death penalty on moral grounds, but object to it on practical grounds. For example, the death penalty is much more costly to our public coffers compared with life in prison without the possibility of parole. What is more, our criminal justice system is imperfect and may have executed an innocent person in the past and may continue to do so in the future if the death penalty remains an option. Serving on a jury in a case in which the prosecutor is seeking the death penalty and knowing that you and 11 other jurors must vote for life or death must be an exhausting emotional rollercoaster ride. On what does one base one’s vote to execute another human being or spare him or her? During the trial phase, jurors have learned a bit about the law and how the judge says they must apply it, but they have also learned many gruesome details that have alarmed, shocked, and disgusted them. Rule 403 of the federal Rules of Evidence allows evidence to be excluded if it risks unfair prejudice, which ‘means an undue tendency to suggest decision on an improper basis, commonly, though not necessarily, an emotional one’. However, the gloves are off. When the trial is over and the defendant has been found guilty beyond a reasonable doubt, the jurors must then deliberate on the murderer’s sentence after a sentencing hearing when the full force of emotion is evident. According to Bandes (2008: 493): ‘When asked to determine what sort of punishment heinous murderers deserve, people consult their moral, ethical, and religious beliefs. They consult their emotional reactions – their empathy, disgust, and moral outrage’.
EVOLUTION AND PUNISHMENT
Bandes (2008: 495) further notes that: ‘The capital [punishment] system is built upon choices among competing emotional claims – some acknowledged and others not’. The competing emotional claims are abundantly evident in capital trials. In a capital case, prosecutors play on the jury’s fear, disgust, anger, and sympathy for the victim, and ask that the defendant be sentenced to death for what he or she has done. Then comes the defense attorney who asks jurors to consider the humanity of the defendant, trying to evoke sympathy by conveying his or her terribly abusive childhood, and begs for mercy. After which comes the very tearful testimony of the families of both the victim and the convicted. At the end of it all, the judge instructs the jury to set their emotions aside and decide the defendant’s fate by a rational deliberation of the law and the facts before them, but we know that they cannot since: Reasoned argument has limited effect because it is not reasoning that prompts the judgement. (Canton, 2015: 68) Canton (2015) offers us a number of social emotions and how they engage our evolved retributive urge, all of which are doubtlessly engaged during jury deliberations. He notes that empathetic compassion for the victim and the victim’s survivors is perhaps the primary emotion, remarking that ‘retributive emotions reflect a decent compassion for a victim’s (or survivor’s) distress and a virtuous expression of solidarity with members of our community’ (2015: 62). Only the ultimate punishment can achieve justice for the victim(s) and right the wrong. Jurors would also focus on the deep instinct of fairness – Canton asserts that retribution ‘restores a balance: the offender’s unjust profit or gain from the crime must be redressed or annulled…The retributivist does not hit, but hits back’ (2015: 63). There is no turning of the other cheek for retributionists for it is only virtuous to turn a cheek if it is one’s own that was slapped. Rightly or wrongly, the retributionist views the convicted person as possessing the free will to make choices, and the condemned person has made evil ones.
269
The urge to punish can also be seen as loyalty to the group and an expression of commitment to it. Offenders are subconsciously viewed as traitors and enemies of the group – ‘not one of us’ – which serves to neutralize our feelings of care and compassion for them. By their crimes, offenders have demonstrated a lack of respect for authority, which represents the possibility of the breakdown of the social contract. This possibility generates anxiety among those who have a deep respect for authority and social order and view just deserts as a way of increasing social order. Canton reminds us that crimes for which the death penalty is sought evoke a deep sense of negative emotion, especially when multiple victims, children, and/or torture are involved. We often hear metaphors for such criminals as ‘filth’ or ‘scum’ and seeing them punished described as an act of ‘cleansing’ (Canton, 2015: 66). There are those who believe that not only can jurors not eliminate emotion, but also that they should not: Perhaps it is not so much that emotion is a key to normative judgment as it is a key to important and effective normative judgment, normative judgment that gets our attention and gets translated into action, either with respect to our own conduct or to the reward or punishment of others. (Goodenough and Prehn, 2004: 1717)
We should expect emotions to render the most effective moral judgments given their long evolutionary history as the only basis for hominid social interaction prior to the evolution of our vaunted rationality. If these ‘effective moral judgments’ are more often than not retributive when it comes to moral decisions about punishing transgressors, one may wonder why Kant’s proportional retribution is often viewed so negatively.
SECOND- AND THIRD-PARTY PUNISHMENT It is not always possible to punish those who harm us and we must turn to others to carry
270
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
the burden. However, why would others take on your risky burden with no apparent payoff for them? Among chimpanzees, alpha males take on the role of what is called control behavior, which includes the punishment of troop members who bully and exploit others (de Waal, 1996). This is a costly and risky role, but it confers a number of benefits to the alpha male. As an arbiter and punisher, alpha males typically show a preference for the weaker party in most disputes. This develops support among the weaker regular members and serves to level the hierarchy. Leveling the hierarchy increases the gap between the alpha male and the more powerful members of the group who might seek to replace him (de Waal, 1996). Maintaining one’s position as the alpha male affords him status, allowing him ‘first dibs’ on the females when they come into estrus. A host of computer simulation studies of human altruistic punishment (punishment on behalf of others) have conclusively shown that the punisher receives many benefits, including an increased likelihood of receiving future benefits, with enhanced status in the group being the most valuable because it leads to enhanced fitness (Ule et al., 2009). Dos Santos et al. (2011) remark that: “reputation is the key to the evolution of punishment, and that simple reputation games can explain the high preservation of punishment in humans” (2011: 376). Leading theories of third-party punishment include inequity aversion and strong reciprocity. Inequity aversion favors fairness and rejects inequitable outcomes. Humans (and primates) are willing to forgo benefits to themselves if they perceive others receiving a greater and unfair reward. This rejection of injustice helps to punish cheats and stabilize cooperation among group members. Strong reciprocity refers to the tendency to cooperate with group members even when there are no immediate benefits of doing so. It is therefore advantageous to the group to punish non-cooperators and to use punishment to ensure fairness. In modern societies, punishment is meted out by third-party punishers who are individuals not directly harmed and who will
not directly benefit (like second-party chimp alpha males) from meting out punishment. This type of punishment is more impartial and less egocentric than second-party punishment, thereby minimizing the likelihood of a retaliatory tit-for-tat feedback loop (Fehr and Fischbacher, 2004). However, there is some evidence to suggest that third parties do not punish differently than second parties (Leibbrandt and Lopez-Perez, 2012). Third-party punishers in modern societies are typically agents of the state operating in accordance with the law. For example, offenders are caught by police, prosecuted in court, and then sentenced by judges. However, other informal third-party punishments may be doled out to offenders by school administrators or church officials. Informal third-party punishment occurs more frequently than state-sponsored third-party punishment and is essential to the enforcement of norms (Bendor and Swistak, 2001). Numerous experiments have shown that third parties will punish cheats at a cost to themselves. A study involving 1,762 subjects from five continents found that in all populations, people are willing to punish defectors who have harmed unknown others (Henrich et al., 2006). This study also found that ‘societies with high degrees of punishment will also exhibit more altruistic behavior’ (Henrich et al., 2006: 1770). This tends to suggest altruism and punishment coevolved in the sense that ‘Third-party punishment of norm violations (‘I punish you because you harmed him’) seems especially crucial for the evolutionary stability of cooperation and is the cornerstone of modern models of criminal justice’ (Buckholz and Marois, 2012: 655).
FROM PRIMITIVE VENGEANCE TO MODERN LAW Just as we can become alcoholics, obese, and sex addicts partaking too freely in what feels good, or even vital in the right proportions,
EVOLUTION AND PUNISHMENT
punishment can overstep its optimum and become dysfunctional. In neurological imaging studies showing blood flow to the brain’s pleasure center, when people witness the punishment of those who have harmed them, the punishment tends to be proportional to the harm caused. Only a callous sadist would take pleasure in seeing grossly disproportionate punishment imposed. Punishment that exceeds just and reasonable boundaries induces disgust and repugnance, and many people feel that the death penalty is one such excessive punishment. Even given the well-founded evolutionary reasons for retributionist feelings, we must reflect on the propriety of acting on them completely. Just because these feelings are natural, it does not mean that we should act on them and ignore rational consequentialist considerations. If the primitive desire to ‘get even’ is left untamed, it can tear a social group apart by generating a cycle of tit-fortat blood feuds, which have smeared human history (Boehm, 2011). It has been estimated that approximately 30% of adult male deaths among the Yanomamo of South America are related to revenge feuds, which expand the very injustice that ‘righteous’ revenge was supposed to assuage (Chagnon, 1988). As Susan Jacoby (1983: 13) put it: The struggle to contain revenge has been conducted at the highest level of moral and civic awareness at each stage in the development of civilization. The self-conscious nature of the effort is expectable in view of the persistent state of tension between uncontrolled vengeance as destroyer and controlled vengeance as an unavoidable component of justice.
Just as evolutionary scientists view cheating and punishment as vital to the evolution of cooperation, Durkheim saw it as necessary for maintaining social solidarity, and that it does so by reaffirming the justness of the social norms. He recognized that the urge to punish is inherent in human nature and that it serves an expiatory role, but he also recognized that we could temper the urge with sympathy. Over the course of human history, Durkheim
271
noted that many societies have moved from retributive to restitutive justice. For Durkheim (1964), retributive justice is driven by the natural passion for punitive revenge that ‘ceases only when exhausted … only after it has destroyed’ (1964: 86). Restitutive justice, on the other hand, is driven by simple deterrence, and is more humanistic and tolerant, although it is still ‘at least in part, a work of vengeance’ since it is still ‘an expiation’ (1964: 88–89). While both forms satisfy the human urge for social regularity, repressive justice oversteps its adaptive usefulness and becomes socially destructive, while restitutive justice offers a rational balance between calming moral outrage on the one hand, and engaging empathy and sympathy on the other. Culture may engage or neutralize the emotions that temper punishment with mercy or allow vengeance to run wild. The lasting influence of Cesare Beccaria rests on his recognition that the brutal acts of retribution that were common in the 18th century resulted in general distrust of powerful institutions and social alienation rather than altruistic cooperation. In other words, Beccaria argued that excessive punishment is indicative of tyranny and the associated lack of perceived legitimacy accompanying tyrannical institutions fails to inspire cooperation. Many of Beccaria’s recommended criminal justice reforms were implemented throughout much of Europe within his lifetime (Durant and Durant, 1967). Such radical and rapid change suggests that Beccaria’s ideas tapped into and broadened other evolved emotions such as sympathy and empathy among the European elite. We tend to feel empathy for those whom we view as being ‘like us’, and empathy often leads to sympathy, which may translate the vicarious experiencing of the pains of others into an active concern for their welfare, even if they are wrongdoers. Vignette studies have shown that people tend to recommend more lenient punishment for criminals whom they perceive to be similar to themselves (reviewed in Miller and Vidmar, 1981), and the march of democracy has drawn more people into the circle of people we consider ‘us’.
272
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
RECONCILIATION AND REINTEGRATION: FORGIVENESS TIT-FOR-TAT Just as social emotions such as empathy may lead to more lenient sentencing, the existence of this emotion may increase the likelihood for forgiveness of offenders (Batson and Ahmad, 2001; Batson and Moran, 1999). This empathyinduced altruism has some evolutionarily advantageous outcomes that benefit social groups. In societies where cheating is likely to occur, forgiveness tit-for-tat operates to benefit social groups by avoiding social actions that degrade into absolute punishment. If two strict tit-for-tat strategists play one another and one cheats (purposely or otherwise), it tends to launch a long series of mutual punitive response resulting in a loss for both. Work in game theory indicates that a measure of forgiveness may work better to maintain social cooperation rather than always paying back defectors in kind (Rand et al., 2009). If people play strict tit-for-tat (always punishing noncooperation in kind) in their relationships they risk losing a valuable relationship if the cheating incident was uncharacteristic of the person, or accidental (Wagstaff, 1998). As Machalek and Cohen (1991: 221) put it: ‘Forgiving strategies can transform a pattern of mutual cheating by not remaining permanently punitive but instead by cooperating, even when the other strategy cheats’. A large number of game-theory studies have found that strict tit-for-tat can amount to punishment that is just too costly for the punisher, that all parties tend to suffer to some extent, and that the generous (forgiving) tit-for-tat strategy invariably prevails (Rand et al., 2009). Although some social emotions may drive this behavior across generations, findings focused on other social emotions such as compassion muddy these waters. Weng et al. (2015) found that while compassion enhances giving to victims, it does not affect punishment of transgressors. The generous tit-for-tat strategy forgives a single betrayal by responding with cooperation
rather than retaliation in the next round of the game, and in most circumstances, it will return the players to cooperation. Of course, we are dealing with game theory here, with its idealized laboratory conditions and assumption of rational actors; the real world is expected to be far more complicated. However, the predictions based on game-theoretical models have been remarkably consistent with real-world findings on numerous occasions (Levitt and List, 2007). Cosmides and Tooby (1992) offer the example of the Ache tribe of Paraguay (and certain other hunter/gatherer tribes) who respond differently to hunters who cheat than to gatherers who cheat. Meat is a scarce and valued resource, and is shared equally by all when available, which is often a matter of luck and hunting skills. Plant food is a low-variance item, the availability of which depends only on the effort spent on gathering it. Arguments erupt when plant gatherers are perceived as not pulling their weight. Punishing lazy gatherers has no adverse effect on the availability of plant food; it is still there for the gathering. Given the highly variable nature of meat acquisition, however, tribal members are more forgiving of hunters whom they perceive as cheating. It is recognized that a charge of cheating can be the result of a false perception (hunting is often a matter of sheer luck as much as effort). If because of the false charge the hunter is punished by ostracism, the whole tribe will lose a valuable cooperator in the tricky business of hunting for meat, and the meat supply will become less stable and predictable. Continuing to invite cooperation in the face of defection is not a ‘sucker’ strategy because it is not one that tolerates continued cheating. It is similar to sentencing an offender to probation rather than prison, thus leaving the door open to future mutually advantageous cooperation between offender and community. The ‘forgiving tit-for-tat’ strategy is captured most familiarly in Braithwaite’s (1989) concept of reintegrative shaming. It is Braithwaite’s position that we should retaliate against tit-for-tat defectors, but that retaliation should be conciliatory rather than
EVOLUTION AND PUNISHMENT
permanently punitive. Punishment (and the shame accompanying it) should be reintegrative and motivate offenders to evaluate themselves and their behavior, not disintegrative. Both the offender and the community benefit by methods used to express our disapproval of offenders that conforms to the reintegrative ideal. If we always respond to defecting with strong punitive reactions, the community loses a potentially valuable cooperator, and the offender becomes, to his or her great disadvantage, alienated from it. Reconciliatory behavior is common among primate species, which indicates that forgiving tit-for-tat had some positive fitness consequences. In restorative-justice programs, victims who confront their victimizers in controlled settings and offer forgiveness to them report feeling positive (a sense that justice had been done) about the experience (reviewed in Latimer et al., 2005). Satisfaction with restorative justice is, however, contingent on procedural factors (trust, neutrality, respect, etc.) as well as situational factors such as flexibility and provisions of care for the victim (Van Camp and Wemmers, 2013). Thus, even forgiveness has rather strong elements of tit-for-tat. Restorative-justice principles that tap an offender’s capacity for empathy for their victim are most fully implemented by juvenile justice agencies. Juvenile agencies implicitly recognize that delinquent behavior is normal behavior; indeed, the young male who does not engage in some sort of delinquent behavior is statistically abnormal (Moffitt, 1993). Adolescence and young adulthood is a period of intense inter-male competition ultimately (if not always consciously) aimed at securing more mating opportunities than the next male (McKibbin and Shackleford, 2011; Wiebe, 2011). To adopt a strategy of strict tit-for-tat rather than forgiveness tit-for-tat with juvenile offenders, whose physical desires and abilities have temporarily outrun their neurological maturity, would be severely counterproductive. Although the evolutionary benefits are greater when applied to juvenile
273
offenders, the perceived satisfaction with restorative justice is less pronounced in juveniles as compared to adults (Gal and Moyal, 2011; Kim and Gerber, 2012). Because of its ability to foster more cooperative societies however, forgiveness tit-for-tat in game theory provides a degree of evolutionary and mathematical justification for restorative justice, which is the only corrections model aimed at reintegrating offenders back into the community with the help of the community.
REFERENCES Adolphs, R. (2009). The social brain: Neural basis of social knowledge. Annual Review of Psychology, 60, 693–716. Ash, J., & Gallup, G. G. (2007). Paleoclimatic variation and brain expansion during human evolution. Human Nature, 18(2), 109–124. Baden, J., & Stroup, R. (1972). Choice, faith, and politics: The political economy of Hutterian communes. Public Choice, 12, 1–11. Bailey, D. H., & Geary, D. C. (2009). Hominid brain evolution. Human Nature, 20(1), 67–79. Bandes, S. (2008). Repellent crimes and rational deliberation: Emotion and the death penalty. Vermont Law Review, 33, 489–519. Barkow, J. H. (1989). The elastic between genes and culture. Ethology and Sociobiology, 10(1–3), 111–129. Batson, C. D., & Ahmad, N. (2001). Empathyinduced altruism in a prisoner’s dilemma II: What if the target of empathy has defected? European Journal of Social Psychology, 31(1), 25–36. Batson, C. D., & Moran, T. (1999). Empathyinduced altruism in a prisoner’s dilemma. European Journal of Social Psychology, 29(7), 909–924. Bendor, J., & Swistak, P. (2001). The evolution of norms. American Journal of Sociology, 106, 1493–1545. Boehm, C. (2011). Retaliatory violence in human prehistory. British Journal of Criminology, 51, 518–534. Bohm, R. (2012). Deathquest: An introduction to the theory and practice of capital
274
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
punishment in the United States. Boston, MA: Anderson. Braithwaite, J. (1989). Crime, shame, and reintegration. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Brunero, J. (2002). Evolution, altruism and internal reward explanations. Philosophical Forum, 33, 413–424. Buckholtz, J., & Marois, R. (2012). The roots of modern justice: Cognitive and neural foundations of social norms and their enforcement. Nature Neuroscience, 13, 655–661. Buonanno, P., & Raphael, S. (2013). Incarceration and incapacitation: Evidence from the 2006 Italian collective pardon. American Economic Review, 103(6), 2437–2465. Canton, R. (2015). Crime, punishment and the moral emotions: Righteous minds and their attitudes towards punishment. Punishment & Society, 17, 54–72. Chagnon, N. A. (1988). Life histories, blood revenge, and warfare in a tribal population. Science, 239(4843), 985–992. Choy, O., Farrington, D. P., & Raine, A. (2015). The need to incorporate autonomic arousal in developmental and life-course research and theories. Journal of Developmental and Life-Course Criminology, 1(2), 189–207. Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (1994). Better than rational: Evolutionary psychology and the invisible hand. The American Economic Review, 84, 327–332. Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (1992). Cognitive adaptations for social exchange. The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture, 163, 163–228. Craig, M., Catani, M., Deeley, Q., Latham, R., Daly, E., Kanaan, R., Picchioni, M., McGuire, P., Fahy, T., & Murphy, D. (2009). Altered connections on the road to psychopathy. Molecular Psychiatry, 14, 946–953. Currie, E. (1999). Reflections on crime and criminology at the millennium. Western Criminology Review, 2(1), 1–13. Da Silva, D. R., Rijo, D., & Salekin, R. T. (2015). The evolutionary roots of psychopathy. Aggression and Violent Behavior, 21, 85–96. Darwin, C. (1896). The descent of man and selection in relation to sex (Vol. 1). D. New York: Appleton.
De Quervain, D., Fischbacher, U., Valerie, T., Schellhammer, M., Schnyder, U., Buch, A., & Fehr, E. (2004). The neural basis of altruistic punishment. Science, 305, 1254–1259. De Waal, F. (1996). Good natured: The origins of right and wrong in humans and other animals. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. De Waal, F. (2008). Putting the altruism back into altruism: The evolution of empathy. Annual Review of Psychology, 59, 279–300. Dos Santos, M., Rankin, D., & Wedekind, C. (2011). The evolution of punishment through reputation. Proceedings of the Royal Society: Biology, 278, 371–377. Dunbar, R. I., & Shultz, S. (2007). Evolution in the social brain. Science, 317(5843), 1344–1347. Durant, W., & Durant, A. (1967). Rousseau and revolution. New York: Simon and Schuster. Durkheim, E. (1964). The division of labor in society. Glencoe, IL: Free Press. Farrow, T., & Woodruff, P. (2007). Empathy in mental illness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Fehr, E., & Fischerbacher, U. (2004). Third party punishment and social norms. Evolution and Human Behavior, 25, 63–87. Furman vs. Georgia. 408 U.S. 238 (1972). Gal, T., & Moyal, S. (2011). Juvenile victims in restorative justice: Findings from the reintegrative shaming experiments. The British Journal of Criminology, 51(6), 1014–1034. Gavrilets, S. (2012). On the evolutionary origins of the egalitarian syndrome. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 109(35), 14069–14074. Goodenough, O., & Prehn, K. (2004). A neuroscientific approach to normative judgment in law and justice. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London: Biology, 359, 1709–1726. Gottfredson, M., & Hirschi, T. (1990) A general theory of crime. Stanford University Press. Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionalist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108, 814–834. Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind: Why good people are divided by politics and religion. New York: Pantheon.
EVOLUTION AND PUNISHMENT
Hatch, V., & Walsh, A. (2016). Capital punishment: The theory and practice of the ultimate penalty. New York: Oxford University Press. Hawthorne, N. (1879). The scarlet letter. The Blithedale romance (Vol. 9). New York: Houghton, Osgood. Henrich, J., McElreath, R., Barr, A., Ensminger, J., Barrett, C., Bolyanatz, A., Cardenas, J., Gurven, M., Gwako, E., Henrich, N., Lesorogot, C., Marlowe, F., Tracy, D., & Ziker, J. (2006). Costly punishment across human societies. Science, 312, 1767–1770. Hill, R. A., & Dunbar, R. I. (2003). Social network size in humans. Human Nature, 14, 53–72. Jacoby, S. (1983). Wild justice: The evolution of revenge. New York: Harper & Row. Jorgensen, C., Anderson, N., & Barnes, J. C. (2016). Bad brains: Crime and drug abuse from a neurocriminological perspective. American Journal of Criminal Justice, 41(1), 47–69. Kanazawa, S. (2008). Temperature and evolutionary novelty as forces behind the evolution of general intelligence. Intelligence, 36(2), 99–108. Kant, I. (1964). Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals. Trans. by H. J. Paton. New York: Harper & Row. Kant, I. (1965). The metaphysical elements of justice. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs–Merrill. Kim, H. J., & Gerber, J. (2012). The effectiveness of reintegrative shaming and restorative justice conferences: Focusing on juvenile offenders’ perceptions in Australian reintegrative shaming experiments. International Journal of Offender Therapy and Comparative Criminology, 56(7), 1063–1079. Klein, R. (2012). The neurobiology of altruistic punishment: A moral assessment of its social utility. In K. Plaisance & T. Reydon (Eds.), Philosophy of Behavioral Biology, pp. 297– 313. Boston, MA: Springer Science. Kochanska, G., & Aksan, N. (2004). Development of mutual responsiveness between parents and their young children. Child Development, 75(6), 1657–1676. Latimer, J., Dowden, C., & Muise, D. (2005). The effectiveness of restorative justice practices: A meta-analysis. The prison Journal, 85(2), 127–144. Leibbrandt, A., & Lopez-Perez, R. (2012). An exploration of third and second party
275
punishment in ten simple games. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 84, 753–766. Levitt, S. D., & List, J. A. (2007). What do laboratory experiments measuring social preferences reveal about the real world? Journal of Economic Perspectives, 21(2), 153–174. Logan, C., & Gaes, G. (1993). Meta-analysis and the rehabilitation of punishment. Justice Quarterly, 10, 245–263. Machalek, R., & Cohen, L. (1991). The nature of crime: Is cheating necessary for cooperation? Human Nature, 2, 215–233. Mackie, J. L. (1982). Morality and the retributive emotions. Criminal Justice Ethics, 1, 3–10. Massey, D. (2002). A brief history of human society: The origin and role of emotion in social life. American Sociological Review, 67, 1–29. McBride, K. (2007). Punishment and the political order. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press. McKibbin, W. F., & Shackelford, T. K. (2011). Women’s avoidance of rape. Aggression and Violent Behavior, 16(5), 437–443. Mealey, L. (1995). The sociobiology of sociopathy: An integrated evolutionary model. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 18(3), 523–541. Miller, D. T., & Vidmar, N. (1981). The justice motive in social behavior. Boston, MA: Springer. Moffitt, T. E. (1993). Life-course-persistent and adolescence-limited antisocial behavior: A developmental taxonomy. Psychological Review, 100(4), 674–701. Moore, M. (1987). The moral worth of retribution. In F. Schoeman (Ed.), Responsibility, character, and the emotions: New essays in moral psychology, pp. 179– 219. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Nowak, M. (2006). Five rules for the evolution of cooperation. Science, 314, 1560–1563. Nowak, M., & Sigmund, K. (2005). Evolution of indirect reciprocity. Nature, 437, 1291–1298. Oliphant, B. (2018, June 11). Public support for the death penalty ticks up. Pew Research Center. www.pewresearch.org/fact-tank/2018/ 06/11/us-support-for-death-penalty-ticksup-2018/ (Accessed 7 June 2019)
276
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Penney, S. (2012). Impulse control and criminal responsibility. International Journal of Law and Psychiatry, 35, 99–103. Pessoa, L. (2008). On the relationship between emotion and cognition. Nature/Neuroscience, 9, 148–158. Petersen, M. B., Sell, A., Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (2010). Evolutionary psychology and criminal justice: A recalibrational theory of punishment and reconciliation. In Human morality & Sociality: Evolutionary & comparative perspectives (Eds. Henrik HoghOleson). Palgrave MacMillan: New York. Quinsey, V. L. (2002). Evolutionary theory and criminal behaviour. Legal and Criminological Psychology, 7(1), 1–13. Rachels, J. (1986). The elements of moral philosophy. New York: Random House. Radzinowicz, L., & King, J. (1979). The growth of crime. Harmondsworth: Penguin. Raine, A. (2013). The anatomy of violence: The biological roots of crime. New York: Pantheon. Rand, D. G., Ohtsuki, H., & Nowak, M. A. (2009). Direct reciprocity with costly punishment: Generous tit-for-tat prevails. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 256(1), 45–57. Rosebury, B. (2009). Private revenge and its relation to punishment. Utilatus, 21, 1–21. Stohr, M. K., Walsh, A., & Hemmens, C. (2012). Corrections: A text/reader (Vol. 3). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Suwa, G., Asfaw, B., Kono, R., Kubo, D., Lovejoy, C., & White, T. (2009). The Ardipithecus ramidus skull and its implications for hominid origins. Science, 326, 68e1–68e8. Ule, A., Schram, A., Riedl, A., & Cason, T. N. (2009). Indirect punishment and generosity
toward strangers. Science, 326(5960), 1701–1704. Van Camp, T., & Wemmers, J. A. (2013). Victim satisfaction with restorative justice: More than simply procedural justice. International Review of Victimology, 19(2), 117–143. Verweij, M., Senior, T., Dominquez, D., & Turner, R. (2015). Emotion, rationality, and decision-making: How to link affective and social neuroscience with social theory. Frontiers in Neuroscience, 9, 1–13. Wagstaff, G. (1998). Equity, justice, and altruism. Current Psychology, 17, 111–134. Walsh, A. (2006). Evolutionary psychology and criminal behavior. In J. Barkow (Ed.), Missing the revolution: Darwinism for social scientists, pp. 225–268. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Walsh, A., & Bolen, J. (2012). The neurobiology of criminal behavior: Gene-brain culture co-evolution. Farnham: Ashgate. Walsh, A., Johnson., H., & Bolen., J. (2012). Drugs, crime, and the epigenetics of hedonic allostasis. Journal of Contemporary Criminal Justice, 28, 314–328. Weng, H. Y., Fox, A. S., Hessenthaler, H. C., Stodola, D. E., & Davidson, R. J. (2015). The role of compassion in altruistic helping and punishment behavior. PLoS ONE, 10(12), e0143794. Wiebe, R. (2011). The nature and utility of low self-control. In K. Beaver & A. Walsh (Eds.), The Ashgate research companion to biosocial theories of crime, pp. 369–395. Farnham: Ashgate. Wilkinson, G. S. (1990). Food sharing in vampire bats. Scientific American, 262(2), 76–83. Wilson, J. Q. (1975). The rise of the bureaucratic state. The Public Interest, 41(3), 77–103.
14 Evolutionary Psychology and Corrections and Rehabilitation Ian A. Silver and Jamie Newsome
INTRODUCTION Identifying effective strategies for managing and responding to crime is a priority for nations around the world. Scholars, policymakers, and practitioners continually work to develop crime-control policies that will enhance public safety and reduce expenditures. Meeting these goals has become critical in the United States – particularly in the correctional system where the number of individuals under some form of supervision has exceeded 6.6 million adults (Kaeble and Cowhig, 2018). The dominant perspective on ‘what works’ in offender rehabilitation, the risk-need-responsivity (RNR) model, has been widely used throughout North America and in other regions throughout the world. It combines knowledge gained from empirically supported theories that offer explanations of criminal behavior with practical recommendations to guide policy and practice (Bonta and Andrews, 2017). Moreover, it is supported by a wealth of empirical evidence (Smith et al., 2009b).
The impact of the RNR model on the field of corrections has been tremendous, but the pursuit to achieve even greater reductions in recidivism continues. Much of this effort has been focused on refining the practical application of the model. However, some scholars have suggested that important theoretical advancements have taken place in recent decades, and that these developments should be explored as potential avenues for informing continued work in rehabilitation (Newsome and Cullen, 2017). Explanations of behavior grounded in an evolutionary psychology framework have expanded, and may now present another opportunity to enhance our understanding of antisocial behavior and how individuals respond to interventions (Bakermans-Kranenburg and van IJzendoorn, 2015). This chapter explores this possibility by first providing an overview of the state of corrections in the United States, followed by a brief description of the RNR model of offender rehabilitation. The core ideas of an evolutionary psychological perspective are
278
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
then summarized, and three theories based on this perspective – biological sensitivity to context theory, differential susceptibility theory, and intrasexual competition – are discussed with an emphasis on how they might inform corrections.
CORRECTIONS IN THE UNITED STATES The correctional system in the United States monitors individuals detained in institutions, such as jails and prisons, as well as those who are supervised in the community, such as probationers or parolees. The total number of individuals in the system grew rapidly beginning in the 1980s (Bureau of Justice Statistics, 2016) and continued until it reached a peak of 7,339,600 in 2007 (Bureau of Justice Statistics, 2016). This period is often referred to as the ‘era of mass incarceration’, during which the rise in the use of prisons to sanction offenders was so extreme and persistent some have questioned whether the United States may have become ‘addicted to incarceration’ (Pratt, 2019). Others have argued that recent decades may be more accurately described as an ‘era of mass corrections’ given the simultaneous rise in community corrections populations (Mears and Cochran, 2015). The number of individuals on some form of community supervision reached a high of 5,119,000 in 2007 and has only slowly declined to 4,650,900 in recent years (Kaeble and Cowhig, 2018). The growth in the correctional system represents a shift towards a more punitive strategy. Increased surveillance and punishment were intended to decrease recidivism and crime more generally. Recent estimates, however, indicate that those who become involved with the criminal justice system may not subsequently redirect their lives to a more prosocial path. More than half of the inmates who are released are returned to prison within three years (Durose et al., 2014). Perhaps even more alarming, a recent
report by Alper et al. (2018) indicated that 44% of state prisoners were rearrested in the first year after they were released, and by nine years post-release 83% had been rearrested. One trend that may have contributed to these high failure rates is a reduction in rehabilitative initiatives (Mears and Cochran, 2015). Some reports suggest that during the rise in the reliance on the correctional system lower percentages of inmates received treatment services relative to earlier periods (Lynch and Sabol, 2001; Phelps, 2011). Moreover, the majority of inmates may not be participating in treatment services before they leave prison (Lawrence et al., 2002; Phelps, 2011). The size of the corrections populations, high failure rates, and lack of treatment represents a complex problem. Fortunately, an abundance of empirical evidence has accumulated that suggests strategies known as the principles of effective intervention may be the most promising tactics for reducing recidivism – whether an individual is confined in an institution or supervised in the community (Bonta and Andrews, 2017; Smith et al., 2009b). This model, which is described in the following section, continues to be studied and refined in hopes of further enhancing policy and practice in corrections.
The Risk-Need-Responsivity (RNR) Model of Offender Rehabilitation Offender rehabilitation has come to be predominantly founded on the principles of effective intervention, a set of guidelines for providing treatment that maximizes the potential to achieve reductions in recidivism (Bonta and Andrews, 2017; Smith et al., 2009b). Central among these principles are risk, need, and responsivity (RNR), which are collectively referred to as the ‘RNR Model’. Organizations throughout the world have adopted this model as the framework for providing services to offenders, and it is viewed as the leading strategy in rehabilitation (Cullen and Jonson, 2012; Newsome and
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND CORRECTIONS AND REHABILITATION
Cullen, 2017; Ogloff and Davis, 2004; Polaschek, 2012). To align practice with the risk principle, corrections agencies are advised to assess each individual’s likelihood of committing another crime and focus the most intensive intervention efforts towards those deemed to be at the highest risk of recidivating (Andrews, Bonta et al., 1990; Andrews, Zinger et al., 1990). To aid practitioners in adhering to this principle, several actuarial risk-assessment tools have been developed that capture the presence of static and dynamic risk factors, quantify them, and generate an overall risk score and classification (e.g., low risk, moderate risk, and high risk). Static factors are stable over time, such as criminal history, and should not be identified as targets for treatment. Dynamic factors that heighten the risk for recidivism can be changed through effective interventions and provide insights practitioners can use to develop case plans. Scholars and practitioners often collaborate to examine the reliability and predictive validity of such tools and make refinements based on emerging research; however, evidence from numerous studies has suggested that modern tools can improve predictions of recidivism and case-management strategies while individuals are involved with the justice system (Andrews et al., 2004; Gendreau et al., 2002; Smith et al., 2009a). Many of the dynamic risk factors identified through the risk-assessment process are conceptualized in the need principle as ‘criminogenic needs’ that should be the targets of interventions (Bonta and Andrews, 2017). Criminogenic needs include antisocial attitudes, antisocial associates, antisocial temperament/personality, family circumstances, employment, substance use, and leisure activities that may promote offending behaviors (Andrews, 2006). Focusing rehabilitative efforts on these factors is the most strategic method for reducing the likelihood of recidivism. Translating this into practice should include regular reassessments to monitor progress in treatment.
279
In addition to determining who and what to target in offender rehabilitation, the principles of effective intervention also provide guidance on how to approach treatment. Specifically, the responsivity principle instructs practitioners to adopt treatment strategies known to be the most effective overall (i.e., general responsivity), and to address individual differences that could impact the effectiveness of the treatment strategies (i.e., specific responsivity) (Bonta and Andrews, 2017). With regard to offender populations, research has suggested that strategies based on cognitive behavioral therapy tend to be the most effective (Andrews, Zinger et al., 1990; Lipsey and Cullen, 2007; Lipsey et al., 2007; Lipsey and Wilson, 1998; Smith et al., 2009b). Specific responsivity factors, on the other hand, vary widely and may include things like low motivation to change, language barriers, or a history of trauma. To fully adhere to the responsivity principle, treatment providers must recognize these factors and develop solutions to minimize any barriers to success in treatment. The remaining principles of effective intervention build upon the risk, need, and responsivity principles to form a comprehensive framework for establishing offender rehabilitation programs (Bonta and Andrews, 2017). Overall, these principles have been empirically supported through several systematic reviews and meta-analyses (Andrews, Zinger, et al., 1990; Gendreau, 1996; Gendreau et al., 1996, 2006; Lipsey and Cullen, 2007; Lipsey et al., 2007; Lipsey and Wilson, 1998; Smith et al., 2009a, 2009b). Moreover, the widespread adoption and robust body of evidence in support of the model has been attributed to the strong theoretical basis, the psychology of criminal conduct, upon which the model was created (Bonta and Andrews, 2017).
Using Theory to Inform Correctional Policy and Practice Developing policy and practice with careful consideration for theories that emerge as
280
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
well-supported explanations of offending behavior may optimize the impact of interventions (Bonta and Andrews, 2017; Mears and Cochran, 2015; Taxman and Friedmann, 2009). The psychology of criminal conduct has emphasized the importance of using theory to better understand individual differences, particularly those that could readily be used in practical application (Bonta and Andrews, 2017). This has largely included explanations of antisocial behavior that emerged in psychology or criminology, with a particular emphasis on a general psychology and cognitive social learning approach. Briefly, this perspective views different behaviors as being learned, maintained, or changed through cues that signal a consequence that may follow an action and the consequences themselves. This logic can then be extended to theorize that manipulating the cues and consequences associated with a behavior can be a useful strategy in eliminating behaviors that are problematic and promoting the continuation of those that are more desirable (Bonta and Andrews, 2017). A number of theories of criminal or antisocial behaviors have identified links between individual characteristics and lifestyle factors and offending, which could lend further insights and support to the RNR model. Sampson and Laub’s (1993) age-graded theory represents one criminological theory that complements the RNR model. Their theoretical proposition argues that variation of social bonds over time influences variation in criminal behavior throughout the lifecourse. As such, the weakening of social bonds is expected to increase involvement in criminal behavior, while the strengthening of social bonds is speculated to encourage individuals to desist from criminal behavior. For instance, as one reaches late adolescence or adult stages of development, obtaining meaningful employment – one of the central criminogenic needs identified in the RNR model – can be a critical turning point that encourages the adoption of a prosocial lifestyle. A job consumes free time, provides an individual with opportunities to
establish prosocial connections, and can bring about a number of benefits that one would not want to lose. Sampson and Laub (1993) further speculated that it is not likely that simply obtaining a job will divert someone away from a life of crime; the job should be of some value to the individual (i.e., add favorable consequences). While this aspect of the theory does not necessarily point to a new risk factor or criminogenic need, it has the potential to deepen the understanding of the relationship between these factors and offending. It could also provide some context to aid in understanding why some justice-involved individuals do not desist from crime, even when they are able to reduce their risk of reoffending by obtaining a job. The above example demonstrates that establishing strong connections between theory, research, and practice can be informative for the corrections field. Some scholars have argued that emerging perspectives that appear to be supported by empirical evidence could be examined as a potential avenue for further enhancing public policy and corrections (Barnes, 2014; Beaver and Schwartz, 2016; Moffitt, 2013; Newsome and Cullen, 2017; Rocque and Welsh, 2015). The growth in research in evolutionary psychology has revealed new findings that could serve to expand the understanding of offenders and rehabilitation. A brief overview of key concepts from evolutionary psychology and theories from this area of research is provided in the following section, and key findings that are relevant for policy and practice in corrections are discussed below.
EVOLUTIONARY EXPLANATIONS OF BEHAVIOR Over the past 20 years, various scholars have developed theoretical explanations of behavior through reliance on evolutionary principles. These theories may be informative for corrections by enhancing our understanding of the origins of antisocial behaviors and
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND CORRECTIONS AND REHABILITATION
understanding differences in how individuals respond to interventions designed to reduce offending. These theories are founded upon the idea that all living things, consciously or subconsciously, strive to ensure their genes are passed onto subsequent generations (Belsky, 1997a, 2005; Belsky and Pluess, 2009a, 2009b). In line with this goal is the understanding that fitness (i.e., success in mating) and survival are fundamental to natural selection. As discussed below, scholars generally theorize that behaviors in modern society – including those that are widely considered to be antisocial – could have increased fitness and survival over the evolutionary history of humans. These foundational components have guided the development of evolutionary theories to explain a number of human behaviors. Although various perspectives exist, this chapter will focus on biological sensitivity to context theory, differential susceptibility theory, and intrasexual competition because these may be the most informative for working with correctional populations.
Biological Sensitivity to Context and Differential Susceptibility Theories and Behavior Biological sensitivity to context theory and differential susceptibility theory are compatible perspectives that offer explanations for differences in how individuals respond to the conditions they encounter during the course of their lives (Ellis et al., 2011). These theories may be particularly informative for corrections, as they could provide insights into how antisocial behaviors develop and why justiceinvolved individuals respond differently to interventions (Bakermans-Kranenburg and van IJzendoorn, 2015). Although prior research has suggested that adhering to the RNR model is one of the most effective approaches to reducing recidivism, less is known about why some individuals who are exposed to evidence-based practices desist from crime and others do not.
281
Biological sensitivity to context theory, initially proposed by Boyce and Ellis (2005), maintains that individuals vary in their sensitivity to environmental stressors. When individuals perceive that events or circumstances are threatening in some way, their stress-response systems are activated generating increases in heart rate and breathing, the release of various neurotransmitters in the brain, and other physiological processes. While these responses are normal, there are differences in the situations that prompt the activation of this system and the intensity of the responses. The variation in reactivity is attributed to both genetic and environmental influences, as some may be born with predispositions to be more or less reactive and early experiences can shape the precision of responsiveness (Boyce and Ellis, 2005). For example, highly reactive individuals may be more skilled at anticipating dangers when repeatedly exposed to adversity during their upbringing. This heightened sensibility may promote survival by allowing them to avoid life-threatening situations. Alternatively, a highly reactive individual who is reared in a stable, predictable, and highly supportive environment may thrive because he or she would gain more of the benefits of the advantageous environment. In contrast to the highly reactive individuals, others are theorized to be born with a lower level of reactivity (Boyce and Ellis, 2005). They are less likely to be harmed by adversity and are seemingly resilient to negative experiences, but also less likely to fully acquire the benefits of highly supportive environments. Belsky’s (1997, 2005) differential susceptibility theory rests upon many of the same assumptions as biological sensitivity to context theory but extends the logic to explain behavioral differences in children reared by the same parents. Briefly, the theory proposes that the traits that are advantageous in one generation will be passed on to descendants. However, there are no guarantees that the same traits that are beneficial at one point in time will continue to be beneficial at other time points (Belsky and Pluess, 2009a, 2009b).
282
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
In light of this uncertainty, the theory proposes that some genes that are passed from one generation to another can be expressed in a range of traits to provide a natural mechanism for some flexibility. This is known as ‘genetic plasticity’, a phenomenon that ultimately reduces the risk that one would fail to survive or reproduce if traits are inherited that are no longer beneficial. As an example, one individual may be born with a genetic predisposition that would permit the expression of higher levels of aggression in exceedingly volatile environments where aggression may promote survival (e.g., aggression used in self-defense, the capacity to take resources from others during times of scarcity). The same individual might demonstrate little to no aggressive behaviors if reared in a safe and secure environment where such behaviors may compromise survival and the likelihood of reproducing. The theory further suggests that others will have lower levels of susceptibility to environmental influence (Belsky, 1997b, 2005). For these individuals, behavior will be more heavily influenced by genetic factors regardless of the environmental conditions. Those with inclinations towards aggression, for example, will likely exhibit aggressive behaviors regardless of whether or not it is advantageous. Differences in susceptibility are hypothesized to be an evolutionary strategy that maximizes the odds that at least one offspring of a mating pair is raised to reproductive age (Belsky, 1997a, 2005; Belsky and Pluess, 2009a, 2009b). This is because parents are likely to adopt rearing strategies that will encourage the adoption of traits and behaviors in the offspring that were beneficial for them given the environmental conditions to which they were exposed. This could be a favorable strategy if the environmental conditions remained consistent across time. In those instances, children who are more easily influenced by their environments would be likely to adopt the strategies of the parents, promoting continued success in surviving and reproducing. However, it is also possible that
environmental conditions could be altered, and the strategies encouraged by the parents will not continue to be optimal. Should this occur, children who are more resistant to the parental rearing strategies may have more favorable odds of survival and reproduction – particularly when the rearing strategies could compromise success in these endeavors.
Intrasexual Competition and Antisocial Behavior Intrasexual competition theory relies on the social commonplaces that promote reproductive success to explain antisocial behavior. To briefly introduce an important concept, parental investment refers to the amount of energy and time a parent provides to its offspring. Human females, like other mammalian species, provide substantive parental investment to every offspring they produce (e.g., gestation and lactation). Human males, however, are not required by biological processes to invest in any one offspring and can produce numerous children without investing substantial resources. Consistent with the differences in parental investment, females in most mammalian species control access to reproduction (i.e., they dictate which males can reproduce). As a result, males must compete for reproductive rights and engage in competition for the ability to produce offspring (Buss, 1988). Importantly, females must compete – at a much lower rate than males – for males that provide the best opportunity for their offspring. As hypothesized by Buss and colleagues (1988, 2006), the competition for access to reproductive resources has led to the selection of prosocial behaviors indicative of high paternal investment (i.e., the best opportunity for the offspring). Prosocial behaviors, such as altruism and selflessness, have been suggested to promote reproductive success among males (Phillips et al., 2008). These prosocial behaviors, however, are counteracted by some antisocial behaviors that can promote
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND CORRECTIONS AND REHABILITATION
reproductive success with limited paternal investment. Buss’s (1988) initial research suggested that effective strategies for males to promote reproductive success generally involved acquiring or demonstrating access to resources. It is believed that females are more likely to provide access to reproduction when males can demonstrate paternal investment through actions or physical resources (e.g., altruism, access to food, providing safety to offspring). Access to physical resources (e.g., food, water, and property), especially during ancestral times, played an important role in maternal survival and the survival of any offspring. Upon observing this phenomenon and additional evidence, Buss (1988) concluded that some antisocial behaviors are intended to promote reproductive success by immediately increasing access to physical resources. Specifically, resourcebased crimes, such as robbery and burglary, increase access to food, water, and property, and promote male attractiveness to female suitors. For example, individuals during ancestral times could steal food from others to demonstrate their ability to feed the mother and offspring without the risks associated with hunting (e.g., death). In contemporary society, robbery and burglary can provide individuals with immediate access to financial resources to potentially demonstrate the ability to financially provide for the mother and offspring. In addition to demonstrating paternal investment through resource-based crimes, Buss (1988) suggested that more aggressionbased behaviors, selected for by intersexual competition, are intended to increase access to reproductive resources by providing safety and food for the mother. Furthermore, the offspring produced by aggressive males are more likely to survive due to their ability to effectively engage in combat and hunt. For example, during ancestral times males that had increased aggressive tendencies could protect the females and offspring from external tribes, hunt with a high degree of success,
283
and access resources generally reserved for tribal leaders. These same traits would then be passed on to their offspring and increase the reproductive success and survival of the offspring, independent of the parental figures. These traits, as Buss (2006) suggests, were extremely beneficial and were commonly selected to improve the reproductive success and survivability of the offspring. Violence towards females appeared to be a reproductive strategy, selected for by intrasexual competition, that allowed males to take and maintain access to reproductive resources while providing limited paternal investment (Buss, 2006). In the current context, violence towards females refers to extremely violent behaviors used to increase reproduction success and control reproductive resources, while limiting paternal investment. Specifically, while scholars consistently agree that violence towards females is immoral in contemporary society, during ancestral times violent behaviors towards females provided individuals with immediate access to reproduction and potential reductions in cuckoldry, while requiring limited paternal investment (Shackelford et al., 2005). For instance, acts of violence towards females, such as sexual aggression and domestic violence, may have increased access to reproduction and maintained reproductive control, without providing resources, such as food, water, or safety. Additionally, domestic violence may have reduced the likelihood of cuckoldry (i.e., providing resources to another male’s child) and increased the likelihood of maintaining reproductive success and control (Camilleri and Quinsey, 2012). Violence towards females likely arose during ancestral times, where individuals would engage in sexual aggression against females to produce large numbers of offspring without investing any resources in the children. Historical figures, such as Genghis Khan, serve as case studies for the evolutionary purpose of hyper-violence against females. In the case of Genghis Khan, it is documented that he would often
284
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
sexually assault females during conquests and leave to continue his military campaigns. Using hyper-sexual violence, Genghis Khan was able to reproduce large numbers of descendants with limited paternal investment. Genghis Khan’s hyper-sexual violence generated approximately 16 million descendants as of 2003 (Weatherford, 2005). Although the majority of the research focuses on intrasexual competition among males, females also engage in intrasexual competition. Distinct from males, intrasexual competition among females concentrates on increasing perceived attractiveness (i.e., males select for physical attractiveness; Daly and Wilson, 1988). Often, females increase perceived attractiveness by limiting skin blemishes, increasing body curvatures, and increasing apparent vulnerability (Rucas et al., 2006). Consistent with this, females engage in positive behaviors (e.g., purchasing of accentuating clothes) or negative petty behaviors (e.g., stealing of accentuating clothes) to increase perceived attractiveness. In addition to females increasing perceived attractiveness of themselves, female intrasexual competition is often characterized as psychological struggle to damage the perceived attractiveness of female rivals (Fink et al., 2014). Specifically, while females engage in less physically aggressive and damaging behaviors, strategies such as intimidation and defamation may have improved reproductive success. Intimidation and defamation generally result in limited physical harm but can result in serious psychological damage to females. Intrasexual violence among females is rare but occurs when males provide emotional or physical resources to one female that is perceived as committed to another female (e.g., the primary form of female jealousy; Campbell et al., 1998; Daly and Wilson, 1988). Scholars have employed the postulations of intrasexual competition to explain criminal behavior in contemporary society. For example, Wilson and Daly (1985) proposed that intrasexual competition, more specifically
risk taking, offered a potential explanation of the age crime curve. Briefly, the age crime curve is a common criminological phenomenon suggesting that most individuals engage in criminal behavior during adolescence and early adulthood. Wilson and Daly’s (1985) theoretical assertions suggested that the reproductive benefits of risk taking and violence during adolescence – the peak age for intrasexual competition – outweighs the reproductive costs and increases the likelihood of criminal behavior among adolescents. Specifically, using data from Detroit, Wilson and Daly (1985) demonstrated that the vast majority of homicide offenders and homicide victims range in age between 14 and 30 years of age, suggesting that intrasexual competition might account for this trend. As individuals age, however, Wilson and Daly (1985) argued that the reproductive costs of risk taking and violent behaviors become too large and encourage males to desist from these behaviors. By the age of 30 years, individuals who engage in violent behaviors risk injury, removal of resources, and death, all of which are perceived as too costly given the limited reproductive benefits at that age. Furthermore, in addition to exposing oneself to increased risks, any initial offspring are exposed to heightened risks when males engage in intrasexual competition beyond early adulthood. This theoretical proposition was again demonstrated by the data, which illustrated stark reductions in homicide offenders and homicide victims as the age of an individual becomes greater than 30 years. Like other theoretical postulations founded within intrasexual competition, Wilson and Daly (1985) argue that competition is an important component of the reproductive process for most human beings. While both differential susceptibility and intrasexual competition hypotheses offer broad evolutionary explanations of antisocial behavior, these theoretical perspectives can be applied to provide a greater understanding of behavior among correctional populations.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND CORRECTIONS AND REHABILITATION
FUTURE DIRECTIONS: THE INTEGRATION OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY INTO CORRECTIONS Evolutionary psychology can offer various advancements to help understand or enhance offenders’ experiences during involvement with the correctional system. The following discussions will focus on the research in evolutionary psychology pertaining to offending and the benefits evolutionary psychology can offer to understanding offenders under community supervision (i.e., probation or parole) and incarcerated in secure facilities (i.e., jails and prisons). To provide a brief reiteration, community supervision and incarceration are used by correctional agencies to supervise or punish individuals who commit a wide variety of offenses (both non-violent and violent). Both community supervision and incarceration possess hierarchical structures, in which more serious offenses result in the additional loss of freedoms. Community supervision commonly involves offenders reporting to a probation or parole officer at predetermined times and engaging in a variety of other activities (e.g., alcohol treatment or drug testing) to ensure that the offenders do not violate the conditions of their probation. Incarceration generally involves individuals living in a secured facility for six months or more. Incarceration conditions can vary drastically depending upon the crimes committed and the activities of the individual during incarceration. Below is a review of the research and the application of evolutionary psychology to corrections and rehabilitation.
Differential Susceptibility and Correctional Research Several empirical assessments of Belsky’s differential susceptibility hypothesis have been published that offer explanations for the emergence of maladaptive behaviors among individuals (van IJzendoorn and BakermansKranenburg, 2015). For example, in a sample
285
of twins, Newsome and Sullivan (2014) investigated the extent to which genetic and environmental influences could account for variation in how adolescents respond to risk factors for delinquency. In line with differential susceptibility theory, the results of this study provided evidence to suggest that individuals respond differently to the accumulation of risk factors, with some exhibiting resilience (i.e., avoiding delinquency despite being exposed to risks) and others exhibiting vulnerability (i.e., engaging in delinquency without experiencing common risk factors). Differences in youths’ outcomes were attributed to both genetic and unique environmental factors. In a later study, Newsome and colleagues (2016) found that additive genetic influences explained a significant proportion of variance in males’ responses to risk for violent (41%) and non-violent (29%) forms of delinquency. Among females, however, environmental factors fully accounted for differences in the response to risk for all forms of delinquency. Others have used molecular genetic data to test hypotheses about behaviors linked to criminality based on differential susceptibility theory. Simon and colleagues (2011) examined the interaction between a cumulative measure of plasticity alleles and environmental conditions on aggression. The study considered favorable aspects of the environment (e.g., supportive parenting, neighborhood informal social control) and adverse social factors (e.g., harsh parenting, discrimination, violent peers). The results indicated that cumulative genetic plasticity and the qualities of the social environment produced a significant interaction that predicted aggression, chronic anger, a hostile view of relationships, and a belief in toughness. A later study by Simon and his colleagues (2012) also found cumulative genetic plasticity and exposure to a hostile or demoralizing environment was a significant predictor of aggression and adopting a ‘street code’ that supports criminal behavior. Findings pertaining to criminal behaviors and related traits and behaviors based on
286
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
differential susceptibility theory reveal that these outcomes are the results of an interaction of genetic and environmental influences. Based on these findings, it is further possible that there will be variation in outcomes when the environmental influences under investigation are interventions designed to reduce deviant, delinquent, and criminal behaviors. Indeed, researchers have begun investigating variation in treatment effects for prevention and intervention programs from a differential susceptibility framework and findings have produced a substantial amount of evidence in support of the theory (BakermansKranenburg and van IJzendoorn, 2015; Belsky and van IJzendoorn, 2015; van IJzendoorn and Bakermans-Kranenburg, 2015). This growing body of evidence is robust, as many of the studies employed a strong research design through the use of a randomized controlled trial. As an example, the Strong African American Families (SAAF) program was designed to reduce alcohol use among African American teens, and was tested among a sample of 337 youths using a randomized design (Brody et al., 2006). Results from this study suggested that the DRD4 gene moderated the effects of the program on substance use among the youths. Adolescents with a DRD4 7-repeat allele, one hypothesized to increase plasticity, had lower alcohol use than teens with two DRD 4-repeat alleles (Beach et al., 2010). A similar pattern of findings emerged in a test of the Promoting School-Community-University Partnerships to Enhance Resilience program. In this study, participating in the program reduced alcohol use for individuals who possessed the DRD4 7-repeat allele if they indicated that involvement with their primary caregiver was moderate or high (Cleveland et al., 2015). Other studies have focused on interventions designed to reduce externalizing behaviors, a known correlate of delinquency (White et al., 1990). The Video-Feedback Intervention to Promote Positive Parenting and Sensitive Discipline was tested with a randomized trial
and was found to increase parental sensitivity when administering discipline (BakermansKranenburg, van IJzendoorn, Pijlam et al., 2008). The intervention also reduced externalizing behaviors among children, but only those who were carriers of the DRD4 7-repeat allele. Another intervention tested in the Fast Track Randomized Controlled Trial also generated evidence in support of the differential susceptibility perspective (Albert et al., 2015). Participants who had the rs10482672 A allele of the NR3C1 gene exhibited externalizing behaviors less often at age 25 years after participating in Fast Track (18%) relative to control subjects (75%). The percentage of treatment and control participants who did not possess the A allele and exhibited externalizing behaviors were nearly identical (56% and 57%, respectively). Brody et al. (2015) also tested the Adults in the Making program, which was designed to promote positive development and reduced drug use. The results of this study revealed that individuals who were assigned to the intervention and were carriers of at least one long allele of DRD4 engaged in less drug use compared to those who were placed in the control group. Individuals with the same allele, however, engaged in more drug use if they were in the control group and lived in a risky family environment. In other words, those with the genotype associated with greater plasticity seemed to experience more benefits if they participated in the program or more problematic behavior if they were exposed to a high-risk context. Findings from these and other studies have led some scholars to suggest that differential susceptibility theory can be informative for intervention science (Bakermans-Kranenburg and van IJzendoorn, 2015; Belsky and van IJzendoorn, 2015). This body of literature offers some explanation for why some individuals may respond better to treatment efforts than others, and has the potential to enhance the responsivity principle in the RNR model – particularly specific responsivity. It is possible that, due to genetic factors, tremendous
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND CORRECTIONS AND REHABILITATION
gains from some interventions should not necessarily be expected. Considering this possibility more broadly, it has further been suggested that estimates of treatment effects may be biased (Bakermans-Kranenburg and van IJzendoorn, 2015). Some interventions appear to be stronger among those with particular genotypes; however, studies often fail to account for this phenomenon. As a result, studies may be underestimating the treatment effects that are possible when individuals are better matched to interventions. To the extent that this is occurring, efforts to take stock of the empirical status of the RNR model may be underestimating the actual efficacy of the model (or its components) for individuals who are most likely to benefit from services offered under the model. Integrating the differential susceptibility hypothesis into community supervision efforts could suggest fruitful endeavors for practitioners. Considering that the deterrent and beneficial effects of community supervision differ between individuals (Andrews and Bonta, 2010), it can be speculated that genetic predispositions could generate different observed outcomes for those on community supervision. Consistent with the RNR model, the differential susceptibility hypothesis would advocate for a customizable process for each individual under community supervision. These individualized case management plans should be guided by validated psychological and behavioral assessments that identify the risks, needs, and responsivity issues. Furthermore, case plans should be flexible to account for the differential responses (i.e., specific responsivity) some individuals will have to meet the requirements of the case management plans. This customizable process could benefit both the practitioners and the offenders, as it will allow for the creation of more flexible and empirically supported case plans. In addition to individualized case management plans, the differential susceptibility hypothesis could be used to advocate for more individualized treatment plans.
287
A well-developed component of the RNR model is the responsivity principal, which suggests that individual- and system-level differences influence the observed effectiveness of treatment programs. At the individual level, it is possible that differences in genetic predispositions influence the causal association between treatment programs and behavioral outcomes. To address this potential influence, probation and parole officers can develop individualized treatment plans, which take into account psychological and behavioral assessments, to address the criminogenic needs of the individual. Furthermore, genetic predispositions could make individuals more or less vulnerable to the effects of confinement on psychological and behavioral outcomes. In contemporary society, the conditions of confinement in jails and prisons are often characterized by the removal of basic freedoms (e.g., speaking and movement), social isolation, and limited access to additional human resources. Generally, evidence suggests that these conditions can lead to increases in antisocial outcomes (e.g., recidivism) and the severity of psychological afflictions (Cullen et al., 2011). These findings, however, often coincide with evidence suggesting that the effects of prison on behavior differ by individual. As such, it is not unreasonable to speculate that individuals with genetic predispositions for mental-health afflictions and antisocial behavior might be more or less affected by the conditions of confinement.
Integrating Intrasexual Competition into Corrections Unlike differential susceptibility theory, scholars have rarely considered the effects of intrasexual competition on offender rehabilitation and the RNR model. Considering the limited postulations, it is believed that integrating intrasexual competition into corrections could potentially provide a superior understanding of the observed heterogeneity
288
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
in treatment effects (e.g., Lipsey and Cullen, 2007). Specifically, intrasexual competition theory can further emphasize the importance of access to resources during offender reentry, in addition to exploring the role of age and sexual competition during incarceration and reentry. Briefly, as discussed above, in contemporary society females tend to subconsciously perceive males with higher financial prospects as more suitable mates (Wiederman and Allgeier, 1992). This perceived suitability likely arises from the benefits these males provided, regarding paternal investment, during evolutionary times. For instance, males with increased access to resources, such as food, were more likely to provide these resources to their partners and offspring. On the contrary, during evolutionary times individuals with limited access to resources were less likely to provide for their partners and offspring. Considering the evolutionary benefit of resources, increased survivability, females in contemporary society consider males with greater resource prospects as more attractive than males with fewer resource prospects. As such, individuals with regular employment, disposable income, and housing likely have increased reproductive success. Individuals without regular employment, disposable income, and housing likely have decreased reproductive success. These individuals, however, might employ alternative strategies to access reproductive resources. These strategies could be perceived as antisocial behaviors by broader society. As demonstrated by previous studies (Richie, 2001; Travis, 2005; Visher and Travis, 2003), involvement in the correctional system drastically hinders access to resources. For instance, individuals convicted of felony offenses have a decreased likelihood of legally maintaining constant employment, purchasing a house, and sustaining wealth. Furthermore, felony convictions drastically hinder an individual’s legal financial prospects (Raphael, 2014). Although speculative, considering the effects of the correctional
system on resource prospects, intrasexual competition might provide a theoretical explanation for the observed heterogeneity in offender reentry. If females are more attracted to males with greater prospects, individuals previously involved in the correctional system might have reduced reproductive success and in turn seek out antisocial strategies to increase access to reproductive resources. For example, illegal behaviors that provide a means of financial stability, such as drug dealing, could potentially increase access to reproductive resources. Alternatively, individuals previously involved in the correctional system might engage in behaviors, such as robbery or burglary, to increase the perception of financial stability by acquiring jewelry or other valuable objects, which in turn could increase reproductive success. As such, male offenders reentering society might recidivate due to the inability to access financial resources through legal channels and engage in illegal activities to counteract the reduced financial prospects caused by the criminal justice system. Furthermore, these reentry difficulties could influence the heterogeneity of correctional programming by encouraging individuals with reduced resources to seek antisocial strategies for obtaining access to reproductive resources. Interestingly, access to financial prospects is an important subcomponent of the RNR model. Employment is one indicator of an individual’s risk of recidivating and has been identified as a criminogenic need area to target in treatment (Bonta and Andrews, 2017). As such, intrasexual competition could potentially provide insights as to why such factors are of critical importance to individuals involved in the criminal justice system. Additionally, considering that intrasexual competition is heightened between the ages of 15 and 30 (Wilson and Daly, 1985), probation and parole departments can service these individuals differently from older clientele. For instance, younger individuals can be provided supplemental opportunities such as additional evidence-based treatment
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND CORRECTIONS AND REHABILITATION
opportunities to address negative behavioral tendencies used to promote access to reproductive resources. These treatment opportunities could provide individuals on supervision with strategies that reduce risk-taking behaviors and help them to recognize that competition over resources could result in negative outcomes such as imprisonment or death. All of these strategies guided by evolutionary principles require minor alterations to the current services provided by community supervision agencies and should improve the benefits for the individuals under community supervision. Intrasexual competition theory would also argue that limited access to financial prospects during incarceration might also contribute to inmate misconduct. For example, financial prospects, such as employment and disposable income, are extremely difficult to access during imprisonment. Nevertheless, while access to reproductive resources is extremely limited during imprisonment, competition persists because of the high number of inmates at peak reproductive ages (15–30; Wilson and Daly, 1985). Furthermore, intrasexual competition persists as inmates attempt to attract the limited number of females that work at or visit the facility. This competition and competition with males who have obtained partners outside of the facility likely also contributes to the strain felt by inmates in the facility. The inability to increase financial prospects during incarceration might further heighten competition among inmates within these age groups. Competition may also be further amplified due to the limited availability of prosocial employment after incarceration – the options for convicted felons are exceedingly limited. Working to expand employment opportunities for inmates through work release programs and other reentry planning pre-release from prison may ease competition among inmates and lead to reductions in misconduct. In addition to the individual-level enhancements offered by intrasexual competition theory, a macro-level integration of intrasexual competition could provide
289
benefits for understanding the heterogeneity in correctional programs. Notably, while these postulations align with contemporary theories of intrasexual competition, scholars have yet to provide a comprehensive perspective or empirical examination of intrasexual competition in correctional environments. It is theorized that sex ratio, at the macro level, can influence the efficacy of correctional programming by influencing risk through the development of environmental factors conducive to heightened intrasexual competition. For example, the prison environment drastically reduces access to reproductive resources. As such, incarcerated populations might have heightened levels of violence and sexual violence resulting from the extreme reductions in access to reproductive resources. Violent behaviors, such as assault and homicide, might occur as a result of limited reproductive resources within the facility and an increased number of males at peak competition age (Wilson and Daly, 1985). Furthermore, due to limited reproductive resources, sexual violence against other inmates might arise as a reproductive adaptation. Although the link between macro-level intrasexual competition and recidivism has yet to be examined, various scholars have explored the association between sex ratio and crime rates. The research on the association between sex ratio and crime rates could potentially provide insight into the potential effects of sex ratio on the reentry process. For example, Campbell and colleagues (1998) published a study assessing the association between intrasexual competition and femaleon-female assault rates. The data for the study came from the 1998 National Incident-Based Reporting System (NIBRS) for the state of Massachusetts. At the time, 34 districts in Massachusetts reported crime incidents to NIBRS. Importantly, findings from the preliminary analysis suggested that the rate of same-sex assault was higher for males and females under the age of 24 than males and females over the age of 24. These findings suggested that intrasexual competition peaks
290
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
under the age of 24, evidence supporting the theoretical position of Wilson and Daly (1985). Additionally, males over the age of 24 engaged in higher rates of cross-sexual violence, suggesting that older males might use cross-sexual violence to reduce the likelihood of cuckolding or mate abandonment. Further analysis, however, suggested that sex ratio did not predict female-on-female assault rates. As such, it can be suggested that higher cross-sexual violence might occur among former inmates over the age of 24. Furthermore, heightened levels of violent recidivism might occur as an intrasexual competition strategy. While additional research on the association between intrasexual competition and delinquency exists, the literature is extremely limited regarding correctional populations and criminal justice processes. As such, more research is needed to explore how intersexual competition moderates the efficacy of rehabilitation programs. Although more research is needed, intrasexual competition, like differential susceptibility theory, is useful for informing policy and practices in correctional settings.
Implications of Evolutionary Psychology for Corrections Although the empirical literature in corrections has predominantly drawn from psychological and sociological theories, there is emerging evidence to suggest that evolutionary psychology can offer another avenue for extending scientific inquiry in corrections. Scholars testing differential susceptibility theory among youths have found strong evidence to suggest that children and adolescents respond differently to interventions, and that the efficacy of treatment may be underestimated when researchers fail to consider the role of genetic and environmental factors (Bakermans-Kranenburg and van IJzendoorn, 2015; Belsky and van IJzendoorn, 2015). These findings present two important implications for correctional rehabilitation.
First, it is possible that genetic factors should be considered as specific responsivity factors. Studies investigating this possibility among adult offenders are scare relative to those for juveniles, but as this body of literature continues to grow it could reveal important insights to guide correctional rehabilitation – particularly in understanding how and why individuals respond differently to interventions. Second, scholars who are examining the efficacy of correctional interventions risk generating biased results when genetic factors are not included in statistical models. As science and technology in this area continue to develop, new evidence and methods should be given consideration in designing tests of interventions. Evolutionary psychology may also aid in understanding and managing inmate populations. As described above, research on differential susceptibility theory has shown that individuals respond differently to risks for delinquency and crime and interventions designed to target these behaviors. It is also conceivable that individuals will respond differently to prison environments in ways that align with biological sensitivity to context and differential susceptibility theories, though this remains to be tested empirically. To enhance research in this area, upon arrival at a secure correctional facility the inmates could be administered a broader range of assessments (Newsome and Cullen, 2017). Assessments for psychological afflictions, such as depression, anxiety, and psychoticism, and behavioral assessments for antisocial tendencies and risk of recidivism could be employed by correctional departments to gather more personalized information on the incarcerated individuals. There is also evidence to suggest that the biological processes that are triggered by stress, such as changes in cortisol levels, can also be altered by participating in cognitive behavioral therapy (Bakermans-Kranenburg et al., 2008; Cornet et al., 2014; van Goozen et al., 2007 ). A more comprehensive assessment process that includes these additional factors would
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND CORRECTIONS AND REHABILITATION
allow practitioners to identify the individualized risks and needs of the inmates while also creating opportunities to identify those who exhibited a heightened susceptibility to environmental stressors and examine the impact of imprisonment and treatment on individuals. The management of offender populations could also be enhanced by further research and consideration for the intrasexual competition perspective of behavior. For example, strategies that increase prosocial means of obtaining financial resources could potentially be beneficial. Specifically, one reentry strategy that could reduce recidivism is providing former felons with prosocial means of obtaining and maintaining financial prospects. Explicitly, these prosocial means can include but are not limited to employment opportunities, housing opportunities, and disposable income through legal channels. Access to these resources through prosocial channels could reduce the reliance on resource-based crimes and violent behaviors to promote access to reproductive resources. Furthermore, promoting financial prospects during reentry could enhance the efficacy of the correctional programming. Correctional departments can make concerted efforts to reduce competition among inmates. These efforts can focus on increasing access to non-harm-inducing resources, reduce competitive opportunities, and reduce risk-taking opportunities. Additionally, correctional departments can reduce competition among inmates by reducing the number of inmates at the peak reproductive stage in the same vicinity. These efforts could reduce intrasexual competition over resources during imprisonment.
CONCLUSION The current chapter introduced the state of corrections in the United States and the RNR model to provide a brief overview of current
291
correctional practices. These discussions focused on how contemporary policies and practices could be reexamined with consideration for principles derived from evolutionary psychology. Nevertheless, scholars have yet to integrate the principles of evolutionary psychology to develop meaningful policy initiatives in corrections. As such, the core ideas of the evolutionary psychological perspective were summarized and three middlelevel theories were discussed with an emphasis on how they might inform corrections (Buss, 1995). These three theories were: biological sensitivity to context theory, differential susceptibility theory, and intrasexual competition. The policy discussions focused on how evolutionary psychology can provide meaningful policy recommendations for community and institutional corrections. At the heart of these policy discussions, correctional departments should treat offenders as individuals and train officers to better understand the individualistic nature of human behavior. In conclusion, researchers and practitioners should examine the feasibility and efficacy of evolutionary psychology policy recommendations to ensure that the desired results of the criminal justice system are maintained.
REFERENCES Albert, W. D., Belsky, D. W., Crowley, D. M., Latendresse, S. J., Aliev, F., Riley, B., & Sun, C., (2015). Can genetics predict response to complex behavioral interventions? Evidence from a genetic analysis of the Fast Track Randomized Control Trial. Journal of Policy Analysis and Management, 34, 497–518. Alper, M., Durose, M. R., & Markman, J. (2018). 2018 Update on Prisoner Recidivism: A 9-Year Follow-up Period (2005–2014). Washington, DC: US Department of Justice. Andrews, D. A. (2006). Enhancing adherence to risk-need-responsivity: Making quality a matter of policy. Criminology & Public Policy, 5, 595–602.
292
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Andrews, D. A., & Bonta, J. (2010). The psychology of criminal conduct, 5th edition. New Providence, NJ: Matthew Bender & Company, Inc. Andrews, D. A., Bonta, J., & Hoge, R. D. (1990). Classification for effective rehabilitation: Rediscovering psychology. Criminal Justice and Behavior, 17, 19–52. Andrews, D. A., Bonta, J., & Wormith, S. J. (2004). The Level of Service/Case Management Inventory (LS/CMI). Toronto, Ontario, Canada: Multi-Health Systems. Andrews, D. A., Zinger, I., Hoge, R. D., Bonta, J., Gendreau, P., & Cullen, F. T. (1990). Does correctional treatment work? A clinically relevant and psychologically informed metaanalysis. Criminology, 28, 369–404. Bakermans-Kranenburg, M. J., & van IJzendoorn, M. H. (2015). The hidden efficacy of interventions: Gene x environment experiments from a differential susceptibility perspective. Annual Review of Psychology, 66, 381–409. Bakermans-Kranenburg, M. J., van IJzendoorn, M. H., Mesman, J., Alink, L. R. A., & Juffer, F. (2008). Effects of an attachment-based intervention on daily cortisol moderated by dopamine receptor D4: A randomized control trial on 1- to 3-year-olds screened for externalizing behavior. Development and Psychopathology, 20, 805–820. Bakermans-Kranenburg, M. J., van IJzendoorn, M. H., Pijlman, F. T. A., Mesman, J., & Juffer, F. (2008). Experimental evidence for differential susceptibility Dopamine D4 receptor polymorphism (DRD4 VNTR) moderates intervention effects on toddlers’ externalizing behavior in a randomized controlled trial. Developmental Psychology, 44, 293–300. Barnes, J. C. (2014). The impact of biosocial criminology on public policy: Where should we go from here? In M. DeLisi & Kevin M. Beaver (Eds.), Criminological theory: A lifecourse approach (2nd Edition, pp. 83–98). Burlington, MA: Jones & Bartlett. Beach, S. R. H., Brody, G. H., Philibert, R. A., & Lei, M. (2010). Differential susceptibility to parenting among African American youths: Testing the DRD4 hypothesis. Journal of Family Psychology, 25, 513–521. Beaver, K. M., & Schwartz, J. A. (2016). The utility of findings from biosocial research for
public policy. In T. G. Blomberg, J. M. Brancale, K. M. Beaver, & W. D. Bales (Eds.), Advancing criminology & criminal justice policy (pp. 452–460). New York, NY: Routledge. Belsky, J. (1997a). Variation in susceptibility to environmental influence: An evolutionary argument. Psychological Inquiry, 8, 182–186. Belsky, J. (1997b). Theory testing, effect-size evaluation, and differential susceptibility to rearing influence: The case of mothering and attachment. Child Development, 68, 598–600. Belsky, J. (2005). Differential susceptibility to rearing influence: An evolutionary hypothesis and some evidence. In B. Ellis & D. Bjorklund (Eds.), Origins of the social mind: Evolutionary psychology and child development (pp. 139–163). New York, NY: Guilford Press. Belsky, J., & Pluess, M. (2009a). The nature (and nurture?) of plasticity in early human development. Association for Psychological Sciences, 4, 345–351. Belsky, J., & Pluess, M. (2009b). Beyond diathesis stress: Differential susceptibility to environmental influences. Psychological Bulletin, 135, 885–908. Belsky, J., & van IJzendoorn, M. H. (2015). What works and for whom? Genetic moderation of intervention efficacy. Development and Psychopathology, 27, 1–6. Bonta, J. & Andrews, D. A. (2017). The psychology of criminal conduct, 6th edition. New York, NY: Routledge. Boyce, W. T., & Ellis, B. J. (2005). Biological sensitivity to context: I. An evolutionarydevelopmental theory of the origins and functions of stress reactivity. Development and Psychopathology, 17, 271–301. Brody, G. H., Murry, V. M., Kogan, S. M., Gerrard, M., Gibbons, F. X., Molgaard, V., & Wills, T. A. (2006). The Strong African American Families program: A cluster randomized prevention trial of long-term effects and a mediation model. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology, 74, 356–366. Brody, G. H., Yu, T., & Beach, S. R. H. (2015). A differential susceptibility analysis reveals the ‘who and how’ about adolescents’ responses to preventive interventions: Tests of first- and second-generation Gene X Intervention hypotheses. Development and Psychopathology, 27, 37–49.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND CORRECTIONS AND REHABILITATION
Bureau of Justice Statistics (2016). Probation and parole in the United States, 2016. Washington, DC: National Institute of Justice. Buss, D. M. (1988). The evolution of human intrasexual competition: Tactics of mate attraction. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 54, 616–628. Buss, D. M. (1995). The evolution of desire: Strategies of human mating. New York, NY: Basic Books. Buss, D. M. (2006). The murderer next door: Why the mind is designed to kill. London, UK: Penguin Publishers. Campbell, A., Muncer, S., & Bibel, D. (1998). Female-female criminal assault: An evolutionary perspective. Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency, 35, 413–428. Camilleri, J. A., & Quinsey, V. L. (2012). Sexual conflict and partner rape. In T. K. Shackelford & A. T. Goetz (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of sexual conflict in humans (pp. 257–268). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Caspi, A., McClay, J., Moffitt, T. E., Mill, J., Martin, J., Craig, I. W., & Poulton, R. (2002). Role of genotype in the cycle of violence in maltreated children. Science, 297, 851–854. Cleveland, H. H., Schlomer, G. L., Vandenberg, D. J., Feinberg, M., Greenberg, M., Spoth, R., & Hair, K. L. (2015). The conditioning of intervention effects on early adolescent alcohol use by maternal involvement and dopamine receptor D4 (DRD4) and serotonin transporter linked polymorphic region (5-HTTLPR) genetic variants. Development and Psychopathology, 27, 51–67. Cornet, L. J. M., de Kogel, C. H., Nijman, H. L. I., Raine, A., & van der Laan, P. H. (2014). Neurobiological changes after intervention in individuals with anti-social behaviour: A literature review. Criminal Behavior and Mental Health, 25, 10–27. Cullen, F. T., & Jonson, C. L. (2012). Correctional theory: Context and consequences. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Cullen, F. T., Jonson, C. L., & Nagin, D. S. (2011). Prisons do not reduce recidivism: The high cost of ignoring science. The Prison Journal, 91, 48S–65S. Daly, M, & Wilson, M. (1988). Homicide. Hawthorne, NY: Aldine deGruyter. Durose, M. R., Cooper, A. D., & Snyder, H. N. (2014). Recidivism of prisoners released in 30
293
states in 2005: Patterns from 2005 to 2010. Washington, DC: Bureau of Justice Statistics, US Department of Justice. Ellis, B. J., Boyce, W. T., Belsky, J., BakermansKranenburg, M. J., & van IJzendoorn, M. H. (2011). Differential susceptibility to the environment: An evolutionary-neurodevelopmental theory. Development and Psychopathology, 23, 7–28. Fink, B., Klappauf, D., Brewer, G., & Shackelford, T. K. (2014). Female physical characteristics and intra-sexual competition in women. Personality and Individual Differences, 58, 138–141. Gendreau, P. (1996). The principles of effective intervention with offenders. In A. T. Harland (Ed.), Choosing correctional options that work: Defining the demand and evaluating the supply (pp. 117–130). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Gendreau, P., Goggin, C., & Smith, P. (2002). Is the PCL-R really the ‘unparalleled’ measure of offender risk? A lesson in knowledge cumulation. Criminal Justice and Behavior, 29, 397–426. Gendreau, P., Little, T., & Goggin, C. (1996). A meta-analysis of the predictors of adult offender recidivism: What works? Criminology, 34, 575–607. Gendreau, P., Smith, P., & French, S. A. (2006). The theory of effective correctional intervention: Empirical status and future directions. In F. T. Cullen, J. P. Wright, & K. R. Blevins (Eds.), Advances in criminological theory: Taking stock: The status of criminological theory (Vol. 15, pp. 419–446). New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction. Kaeble, D., & Cowhig, M. (2018). Correctional populations in the United States, 2016. Washington, DC: US Department of Justice. Lawrence, S., Mears, D. P., Dubin, G., & Travis, J. (2002). The practice and promise of prison programming. Washington, DC: The Urban Institute. Lipsey, M. W., & Cullen, F. T. (2007). The effectiveness of correctional rehabilitation: A review of systematic reviews. Annual Review of Law and Social Science, 3, 297–320. Lipsey, M. W., Landenberger, N. A., & Wilson, S. J. (2007). The effects of cognitive-behavioral programs for criminal offenders. Campbell Systematic Reviews, 6, 1–27.
294
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Lipsey, M. W., & Wilson, D. B. (1998). Effective intervention for serious juvenile offenders: A synthesis of research. In R. Loeber & D. P. Farrington (Eds.), Serious & violent juvenile offenders: Risk factors and successful interventions (pp. 313–366). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Lynch, J. P., & Sabol, W. J. (2001). Prisoner reentry in perspective. Washington, DC: The Urban Institute. Mears, D. P., & Cochran, J. C. (2015). Prisoner reentry in the era of mass incarceration. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Moffitt, T. E. (2013). Childhood exposure to violence and lifelong health: Clinical intervention science and stress-biology research join forces. Development and Psychopathology, 25, 1619–1634. Newsome, J., & Cullen, F. T. (2017). The riskneed-responsivity model revisited: Using biosocial criminology to enhance offender rehabilitation. Criminal Justice and Behavior, 44, 1030–1049. Newsome, J., & Sullivan, C. J. (2014). Resilience and vulnerability in adolescents: Genetic influences on differential response to risk for delinquency. Journal of Youth and Adolescence, 43, 1080–1095. Newsome, J., Vaske, J. C., Gehring, K. S., & Boisvert, D. L. (2016). Sex differences in sources of resilience and vulnerability to risk for delinquency. Journal of Youth and Adolescence, 45, 730–745. Ogloff, J. R., & Davis, M. R. (2004). Advances in offender assessment and rehabilitation: Contributions of the risk-needs-responsivity approach. Psychology, Crime & Law, 10, 229–242. Phelps, M. S. (2011). Rehabilitation in the punitive era: The gap between rhetoric and reality in U.S. prison programs. Law & Society Review, 45, 33–68. Phillips, T., Barnard, C., Ferguson, E., & Reader, T. (2008). Do humans prefer altruistic mates? Testing a link between sexual selection and altruism towards non-relatives. British Journal of Psychology, 99, 555–572. Polaschek, D. L. (2012). An appraisal of the risk-need-responsivity (RNR) model of offender rehabilitation and its application in correctional treatment. Legal and Criminological Psychology, 17, 1–17.
Pratt, T. C. (2019). Addicted to incarceration, 2nd edition. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Raphael, S. (2014). The effects of conviction and incarceration on future employment outcomes. In D. P. Farrington & J. Murray (Eds.), Labeling theory: Empirical tests, advances in criminological theory 18 (pp. 237–262). New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction. Richie, B. (2001). Challenges incarcerated women face as they return to their communities: Findings from life history interviews. Crime and Delinquency, 47, 368–389. Rocque, M., & Welsh, B. C. (2015). Offender rehabilitation from a maturation/biosocial perspective. In M. DeLisi & M. Vaughn (Eds.), Handbook of biosocial criminology (pp. 501– 515). Abingdon, UK: Routledge. Rucas, S. L., Gurven, M., Kaplan, H., Winking, J., Gangestad, S., & Crespo, M. (2006). Female intrasexual competition and reputational effects on attractiveness among the Tsimane of Bolivia. Evolution and Human Behavior, 27, 40–52. Sampson, R. J., & Laub, J. H. (1993). Crime in the making: Pathways and turning points through life. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Shackelford, T. K., Goetz, A. T., Buss, D. M., Euler, H. A., & Hoier, S. (2005). When we hurt the ones we love: Predicting violence against women from men’s mate retention. Personal Relationships, 12, 447–463. Simons, R. L., Lei, M. K., Beach, S. R., Brody, G. H., Philibert, R. A., & Gibbons, F. X. (2011). Social environment, genes, and aggression: Evidence supporting a differential susceptibility perspective. American Sociological Review, 76, 883–912. Simons, R. L., Lei, M. K., Stewart, E. A., Beach, S. R., Brody, G. H., Philibert, R. A., & Gibbons, F. X. (2012). Social adversity, genetic variation, street code, and aggression: A genetically informed model of violent behavior. Youth Violence and Juvenile Justice, 10, 3–24. Smith, P., Cullen, F. T., & Latesssa, E. J. (2009a). Can 14,737 women be wrong? A metaanalysis of the LSI-R and recidivism for female offenders. Criminology and Public Policy, 8, 183–208. Smith, P., Gendreau, P., & Swartz, K. (2009b). Validating the principles of effective
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND CORRECTIONS AND REHABILITATION
intervention: A systematic review of the contributions of meta-analysis in the field of corrections. Victims and Offenders, 4, 148–169. Taxman, F. S., & Friedmann, P. D. (2009). Fidelity and adherence at the transition point: Theoretically driven experiments. Journal of Experimental Criminology, 5, 219–226. Travis, J. (2005). But they all come back: Facing the challenges of prisoner reentry. Washington, DC: The Urban Institute Press. van Goozen, S. H. M., Fairchild, G., Snoek, H., & Harold, G. T. (2007). The evidence for a neurobiological model of childhood antisocial behavior. Psychological Bulletin, 133, 149–182. van IJzendoorn, M. H., & Bakermans-Kranenburg, M. J. (2015). Genetic differential susceptibility on trial: Meta-analytic support from randomized controlled experiments. Development and Psychopathology, 27, 151–162.
295
Visher, C. A., & Travis, J. (2003). Transitions from prison to community: Understanding individual pathways. Annual Review of Sociology, 29, 89–113. Weatherford, J. (2005). Genghis Khan and the making of the modern world. New York, NY: Broadway Books. White, J. L., Moffitt, T. E., Earls, F., Robins, L., & Silva, P. A. (1990). How early can we tell? Predictors of childhood conduct disorder and adolescent delinquency. Criminology, 28, 507–535. Wiederman, M. W., & Allgeier, E. R. (1992). Gender differences in mate selection criteria: Sociobiological or socioeconomic explanation? Ethology and Sociobiology, 13, 115–124. Wilson, M., & Daly, M. (1985). Competitiveness, risk taking, and violence: The young male syndrome. Ethology and Sociobiology, 6, 59–73.
15 Evolutionary Psychology and Organized Crime Russil Durrant
INTRODUCTION In his foreword to the United Nations Convention against Transnational Organized Crime, the then Secretary-General of the United Nations, Kofi Annan, painted a vivid picture of what he termed the ‘gulf that exists between the civil and the uncivil’ (United Nations Office of Drugs and Crime, 2004: 3). Civil society, he claimed, referred to the history of accumulated progress that has resulted in liberal societies that promote tolerance, respect, and good governance. However, there also exists what he called an ‘uncivil society’: ‘They are terrorists, criminals, drug dealers, traffickers in people and others who undo the good works of civil society… they thrive in countries with weak institutions, and they show no scruple about resorting to intimidation or violence’ (United Nations Office of Drugs and Crime, 2004: 3). In short, the forces of organized crime are pitted against those mainstream institutions they seek to undermine. Efforts to better understand the nature and scope of organized crime, therefore, can contribute to strategies that can
mitigate its deleterious effects on both specific victims and society more generally. Despite a substantial body of research on the topic, organized crime remains a contested concept within criminology with little or no consensus concerning what constitutes organized criminal activities (Paoli and Vander Beken, 2014), or what the main causes of organized crime are (Paoli, 2016). My primary aim in this chapter is to discuss how an approach that draws from evolutionary psychology can contribute to a better understanding of what organized crime is, the motivations of organized criminal offenders, and the structure of organized criminal groups. Although evolutionary psychologists have had a long-standing interest in criminal offending, especially violent crime (e.g., Daly and Wilson, 1988; Duntley and Shackelford, 2008), and there is an emerging literature more generally on ‘evolutionary criminology’ (e.g., Durrant and Ward, 2015; Kavish et al., 2017; Roach and Pease, 2013; Walsh and Jorgensen, 2018), the topic of organized crime has received negligible attention from evolutionary-minded
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ORGANIZED CRIME
scholars (although see Hirschfeld, 2015, for an approach that draws from behavioural ecology). From the perspective of evolutionary psychology, I argue that organized crime involves the coalitional exploitation of others for personal gain in ways that violate criminal laws. As such, the activities that comprise organized crime – the trafficking of illegal goods and services, predatory crimes such as theft, fraud, and robbery, and ‘illegal governance’ crimes such as protection payments – involve the cooperation of individuals in ways that can enhance their inclusive fitness at the expense of others. After briefly reviewing contemporary criminological approaches to conceptualizing organized crime, I first examine the nature of organized criminal activities and discuss how these tend to focus on exploiting evolved human motivations and their manifestations in contemporary environments to promote status among organized criminal offenders. I then outline how an evolutionary perspective can shed light on the nature of organized crime groups. Specifically, I suggest that cooperation among group members (in contexts where there can be strong temptations to ‘defect’) can be maintained via three main evolutionary routes: kin selection, direct
297
and indirect reciprocity, and cultural selection for ‘strong reciprocity’ involving the development of group norms and the administration of sanctions for their violation. Taking a more historical perspective, I consider how an evolutionary approach can help us to understand the relationship between organized criminal groups and the formation of states and under what conditions we might expect such groups to emerge. In the final section, I discuss the broader implications of an evolutionary approach for efforts to prevent or reduce organized crime.
THE NATURE OF ORGANIZED CRIME What Is Organized Crime? The concept of organized crime, like many other such concepts in the social and behavioural sciences, is intensely contested, with different authors and agencies employing different, but overlapping, criteria (Table 15.1; Paoli and Vander Beken, 2014). Levi (1998: 335) notes that the term ‘organized crime’ ‘… is generally applied to describe a group of
Table 15.1 Approaches to defining organized crime United Nations Office of Drugs and Crime1
Council of the European Union2
Abadinsky3
1. A structured group of three or more persons 2. The group exists for a period of time 3. It acts in concert with the aim of committing at least one serious crime 4. To obtain, directly or indirectly, a financial or other material benefit
Mandatory (all) 1. Collaboration of more than two people 2. For a prolonged or indefinite period of time 3. Suspected of the commission of serious criminal offences 4. Motivated for the pursuit of profit and/or power Non-mandatory (at least 2) 1. Each with their own appointed tasks 2. Using some form of discipline and control 3. Operating on an international level 4. Using violence or other means suitable for intimidation 5. Using commercial or business-like structures 6. Engaged in money laundering 7. Exerting influence on politics, the media, public administration, judicial authorities or the economy
1. Is devoid of political goals 2. Is hierarchical 3. Has a limited or exclusive membership 4. Constitutes a unique sub-culture 5. Perpetuates itself 6. Exhibits a willingness to use illegal violence 7. Is monopolistic 8. Is governed by explicit rules and regulations
Sources: 1 United Nations Office of Drugs and Crime, 2004, Article 2(a). Downloaded from: www.unodc.org/documents/treaties/UNTOC/ Publications/TOC%20Convention/TOCebook-e.pdf 2 Cited in Paoli and Vander Beken, 2014: 22. 3 Abadinsky, 2017: 2.
298
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
people who act together on a long-term basis to commit crimes for gain’, and this appears to capture the core characteristics in many definitions, as illustrated in Table 15.1. Nonetheless, as von Lampe (2016a: 30) admits, ‘… there is no definition that could meaningfully delineate the study of organized crime as a field of research’. Paoli (2016) notes that attempts to define organized crime have tended to take one of two main paths: either they focus on the nature of the criminal activities that are perpetrated (e.g., drug trafficking, extortion, money laundering), or they concentrate on the nature of the groups themselves and how they are structured. Similarly, von Lampe (2016a) argues that there are three main focal points for definitions of organized crime that can serve to structure research and theory: (1) the criminal activities that organized crime groups engage in; (2) the nature and structure of organized crime groups; and (3) illegal governance and the nature of the power that organized crime groups can sometimes wield (Figure 15.1). Organized crime groups engage in a diverse range of illegal activities. These can be usefully classified in terms of three main types of activities: market-based crimes, predatory crimes, and governance crimes (Figure 15.1; von Lampe, 2016a). Market-based crimes involve the provision of illegal goods and services to ‘consumers’. Widely studied examples include the trafficking in illicit drugs,
arms, wildlife, and counterfeit products (e.g., Feinstein and Holden, 2014; Reuter, 2014), people smuggling, human trafficking, prostitution, and sex trafficking (Kleemans and Smit, 2014), illegal gambling (Spapens, 2014), loan sharking, and money laundering (Levi, 2014). In many cases, market-based crimes involve transactions with ‘willing’ consumers, although this is not always the case (e.g., human trafficking and sex trafficking). Market-based crimes, as I elaborate in more detail below, involve the provision of goods and services that satisfy motivational needs of consumers, but which are deemed by governments to pose threats to the effective social functioning of society (hence their illegality). The nature and scope of such activities thus vary as a function of national and international regulations and organized crime groups may move into or out of given markets depending on changes to their structure. For example, alcohol prohibition in the United States opened a vast market for illegal alcohol that organized crime groups – in particular the Italian-American Mafia – were uniquely poised to exploit (Albanese, 2014). Predatory crimes, as their name suggests, involve clear victims: individuals exploited in the service of criminal gain. Predatory crimes involve a diverse range of activities including the running of paedophile rings, organized fraud, property offending, robbery, and the stock-in-trade of many of the most wellknown organized crime groups: extortion
Figure 15.1 The basic dimensions of organized crime Source: Based on the analysis in von Lampe (2016a).
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ORGANIZED CRIME
(Varese, 2014). Finally, von Lampe (2016a: 77) argues that many organized crime groups engage in what he refers to as ‘illegal governance crimes’: ‘… activities that are inherently linked to the exercise of power within criminal organizations, criminal milieus and beyond’. Examples include the enforcement of particular rules or procedures through the threat or use of force, the negotiation of agreements or ‘contracts’ among rival criminal groups, and the collection of ‘taxes’ (i.e. protection payments) from either legal or illegal business operations (von Lampe, 2016a: 78). Clearly, there is overlap between many of the activities that criminal groups engage in and many such groups will be involved in a diverse range of criminal activities that might include trafficking, organized fraud, and the collection of protection payments to facilitate business monopolies. The Japanese Yakuza, for example, are heavily involved in the trafficking of illegal drugs (particularly amphetamines), facilitate sex trafficking and illegal gambling, offer ‘protection’ services for both legitimate and illegitimate business operations, and play an active role in dispute resolution for legal businesses (e.g., debt collection and bankruptcy management) (Abadinsky, 2017; Hill, 2014). The structure of organized crime groups varies substantially from group to group (and within groups), depending in part on the main kinds of illegal activities that the group is involved in. Von Lampe (2016a, 2016b) argues that there are three basic types of criminal structure: entrepreneurial structures, associational criminal structures, and quasigovernment criminal structures (Figure 15.1). Entrepreneurial structures are organized in ways that facilitate economic activities that provide material benefits to organized groups and their members. Transnational drugtrafficking networks, for example, are often structured in ways that involve specialized divisions of labour (from growers/manufacturers to traffickers to street-level dealers) that serve the ultimate goal of delivering the illicit drugs to consumers at an – often
299
substantial – profit. In contrast, associational criminal structures provide social functions through the bonding of group members, the provision of mutual support, and the reinforcement of group norms and rules. Finally, structures that serve to maintain social order within organized crime groups (and, often, the wider community) through the resolution of conflicts and the imposition of sanctions are referred to as quasi-government in structure, to highlight the similar functions that states provide their citizens. One enduring challenge for organized crime groups is the maintenance of cooperation among group members in contexts where ‘defection’ can lead to criminal arrest. As argued below, an evolutionary perspective can help to explain the particular kinds of structures that tend to emerge among organized crime groups and which help to promote cooperation among group members. Finally, the third main focal point for conceptualizing organized crime focuses on the nature of illegal governance. As many scholars have noted, organized crime groups often operate in ways that mimic the functions of legitimate states: they collect ‘taxes’ from businesses, provide third-party enforcement of ‘laws’, offer dispute-resolution mechanisms, and in many cases provide public goods to local communities. For instance, the head of the Medellin drug cartel, Pablo Escobar, donated substantial sums of money to the community for public works programmes, including the construction of a football stadium (Thoumi, 2014; von Lampe, 2016a). Illegal governance activities reflect the power that organized crime groups can yield, often through complex relationships with legitimate businesses, political elites, and individuals who are involved in the ‘legitimate’ running of state functions (e.g., police, politicians, prosecutors, and civil servants). Although a substantial body of research has accumulated on the topic of organized crime and some advances have been made in how best to conceptualize the activities and structures of organized crime groups, most
300
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
research has been descriptive. As such, as Paoli (2016: 3) notes, ‘no systematic attention has so far been given to the causes of organized crime’. Most scholars have drawn from mainstream criminological perspectives in attempts to explain organized criminal offending (e.g., Abadinsky, 2017, chapter 2). The handful of specific theoretical approaches – such as ‘ethnic succession theory’ and ‘alien conspiracy theory’ tend to focus on the ethnic status of organized crime groups in society and thus have limited scope for understanding the diversity of organized crime groups and organized criminal activities both historically and cross-culturally. Other approaches tend to focus on how organized crime groups are similar in their functions to legal businesses or to legitimate political organizations (see Kleemans, 2014 for a review of these ideas). Ultimately, the challenge for theoretical approaches is to explain (a) the motivations for engaging in organized crime; (b) the scope of organized criminal activities; (c) the structures of organized crime groups; (d) how such groups maintain cooperation among group members; and (d) how such groups persist over time and space. An evolutionary psychological perspective can contribute to a better understanding of these key issues, beginning with a novel way of conceptualizing the primary nature of organized crime.
AN EVOLUTIONARY PERSPECTIVE ON ORGANIZED CRIME An immediate question for an approach to organized crime that draws from evolutionary psychology is its novelty in historical terms: was organized crime, or anything like organized crime, a recurrent feature of ancestral environments in hominin evolution? The paradigmatic examples of organized crime that are the feature of research in the modern world – hierarchically structured large-scale organizations like the Mafia or the Yakuza
– were almost certainly absent from the largely egalitarian hunter-gatherer societies that persisted throughout the Pleistocene. Organized crime, as I argue below, emerges most prominently in contexts where there is a concentration of difficult-to-defend resources and competition among groups for access to those resources. Until the advent of agriculture, the existence of such resources would have been limited. Evolutionary psychologists are well versed in the idea that there is often a ‘mismatch’ between evolved psychological mechanisms and contemporary environments (Confer et al., 2010). Given that organized crime, as it is manifest in the modern world, is an evolutionarily novel phenomenon facilitated by the development of large-scale societies, it is reasonable to consider its potential evolutionary roots: what features of past environments might have favoured motivations to form coalitions among group members for the exploitation of others? Human-male coalitional aggression is arguably a feature of our species that has deep roots in hominin evolution. Like our closest genetic relative, the chimpanzee (Pan troglodytes), human males form relatively fluid coalitions in a range of contexts including collective hunting, disputes over status, and inter-group conflict including the sporadic raiding of other groups (Wrangham and Glowacki, 2012). In addition, humans employ collective aggression in the punishment of norm violators (Boehm, 2012). Although in humans both males and females form part of parochial groups which favour in-group over out-group members, males tend to be overwhelmingly represented in coalitions that involve significant risk to protagonists (e.g., hunting, warfare). According to the ‘male warrior hypothesis’ (McDonald et al., 2012; van Vugt et al., 2007) ‘humans, particularly men, may possess psychological mechanisms enabling them to form coalitions capable of planning, initiating and executing acts of aggression on members of out-groups (with the ultimate
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ORGANIZED CRIME
goal of acquiring or protecting reproductive resources)’ (McDonald et al., 2012: 671). The male warrior hypothesis suggests that men, relative to women, may be particularly prone to ethnocentrism, and are more strongly motivated to bond with in-group members. I argue, then, that organized crime, from an evolutionary perspective, can be conceptualized as a (predominantly) male coalitional strategy to exploit resources from others in the service of reproductive goals. Of course, the form that organized crime takes is highly variable and reflects, as I elaborate in more detail below, the outcome of cultural evolutionary processes. However, at its core, it reflects psychological adaptations that have evolved in the context of male coalitional aggression. We should expect, then, if organized crime is largely a male coalitional strategy for exploiting resources from others, that most perpetrators of organized crime are male, and that organized crime groups have features that specifically promote male bonding. Clear information about the demographic characteristics of organized crime offenders is difficult to come by, but the evidence we do have suggests that most offenders are male. For example, Kirby et al. (2016), in an analysis of 2.1 million recorded offenders drawn from the UK Police National Computer database between 2007 and 2010, found that of the 4,109 offenders who met the criteria for organized crime, 95% were male (compared to 78% of general offenders). The literature on gender differences in offending highlights the fact that males are more likely to perpetrate offences than females, and that the asymmetry between males and females is greatest for sexual and serious violent offending (e.g., homicide) (Durrant, 2019). It is noteworthy, then, that the gender bias for organized crime is similar to that for homicide, even though in this sample the majority of organized crime offenders did not engage in violent crime. It is worth recognizing, however, that although organized crime is largely a male phenomenon there are
301
both all-female and mixed-gender organized crime groups and women may be involved in organized crime in a range of different roles and contexts (see Pizzini-Gambetta, 2014). In addition to the preponderance of male organized crime offenders, many organized crime groups – such as the Mafia in both Italy and the United States – are exclusively male and specifically exclude women from membership (Paoli, 2003). Finally, research suggests that in addition to greater co-offending among males relative to females, when males do offend with others they are more likely to employ violence and seriously injure victims (Bourgeois and Fisher, 2018; Lantz, 2019). Although organized crime often involves the use of, or the threat of the use of, violence, it involves a diversity of different activities – from racketeering, to the trafficking of illegal substances – that fundamentally involve exploiting others for gain. This is most obviously the case when organized crime groups extort payment from individuals or businesses in exchange for protection (often from the organized crime group itself) because, in effect, this is the appropriation of resources backed up by the threat of violence. The trafficking of people, organs, and wildlife also are clearly exploitative and involve genuine harm to victims. However, many organized groups, including the Mafia, offer ‘genuine’ protection services to willing individuals or groups (Paoli, 2016), and may be involved in bringing order to otherwise lawless communities. In addition, trafficking in many illegal substances such as illicit drugs involves the provision of goods to willing customers (Kassab and Rosen, 2019; Paoli, 2016). Nonetheless, as a general rule, organized crime groups and their members disproportionally benefit from the goods and services that they provide relative to their customers, and all organized crime, by definition, ‘exploits’ society by making profits without paying taxes. Indeed, there is good economic evidence that the presence of organized crime groups tends to result in a suppression of economic growth in those areas where they are
302
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
more active (van Dijk, 2007), suggesting that such groups are not operating in the interests of the wider community. Organized criminal activities, then, involve both the perpetrators of organized crime and a somewhat heterogenous group of individuals who can be considered ‘consumers’ (some more willingly than others) of the goods and services that organized crime groups provide. To understand why organized criminal activities occur it is important to recognize the motivational needs of these two groups: offenders and consumers. For many consumers, the motivations are straightforward: they are able to obtain goods and services that would otherwise be unavailable through legitimate channels. It is noteworthy that the kinds of goods and services that organized crime groups provide typically map onto evolved motivational systems (Kenrick et al., 2010). The ‘protection’ services that groups like the Mafia provide, for instance, are readily sought out (as well as imposed) because in environments that lack robust and reliable third-party enforcement of laws, humans seek to meet fundamental needs for safety and self-protection for themselves and their kin. The provision of illegal drugs, gambling, and sex (via prostitution and sex trafficking) also, arguably, tap into underlying motivational systems. Perhaps most straightforwardly from an evolutionary perspective, human males are motivated to seek opportunities for sex with desirable mates and hence are willing consumers of these services provided by some organized crime groups. The motivation to consume psychoactive drugs (and, perhaps, by extension other activities like gambling) reflect the evolution of rewards systems that drugs act on, even if they were not specifically selected for drug use (Durrant et al., 2009; Nesse, 1994; although some forms of drug use may have played a role in enhancing fitness – see Roulette et al., 2016). Understanding the motivations of offenders from an evolutionary perspective entails considering ‘higher-order’ motivational
needs (Kenrick et al., 2010), particularly those that relate to affiliation, status, mate acquisition, and mate retention. I discuss the way that organized crime groups can meet affiliation needs in more detail in the next section, but it is worth noting how some organized crime groups afford opportunities for social bonding among group members that may not have been available through legitimate channels. Membership in organized crime groups can also meet fundamental motives underlying status. Status is important from an evolutionary perspective because higher status can be translated into greater reproductive success (van Vugt and Tybur, 2015; von Rueden and Jaeggi, 2016; von Rueden et al., 2011). Organized crime groups provide various opportunities for status enhancement. Simple membership in an organized crime group can reap substantial rewards in status – at least in the criminal underworld. For example, becoming a formal member of groups like the post-Soviet ‘Thieves in Law’ or the Hell’s Angels motorcycle gang, is an arduous task involving a lengthy screening process with successful applicants significantly enhancing their social status among their peers (von Lampe, 2016b). Many organized crime groups are also structured in terms of hierarchies that afford opportunities for advancement with commensurate benefits in terms of status and access to resources. New York Mafia families, for instance, are made up of ‘members’, or ‘made guys’, who form ‘crews’ headed by a caporegime or ‘captain’. Captains, in turn, defer to the all-powerful ‘boss’ who wields immense influence (Abadinsky, 2016). As Abadinsky (2016: 53) explains: ‘The boss demands absolute respect and total obedience … the boss is treated with a great deal of deference. People rise when he enters the room, and they never interrupt when he is speaking’. There has been almost no research on how such status is translated into reproductive success among organized criminals, although van San (2011: 281) provides an interesting analysis of how many women
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ORGANIZED CRIME
‘find themselves uncontrollably drawn to men who have made a career in crime’. Although the motivations to engage in organized crime are likely to have an evolutionary basis, there are also individual difference factors that might help to explain why some people are more likely to participate in organized criminal groups than others. There has been surprisingly little work done on ‘risk factors’ for organized crime in general, although there is an extensive literature on the factors that promote involvement in certain kinds of organized criminal groups such as gangs (e.g., Lenzi et al., 2015), or activities such as human trafficking (e.g., Beeson, 2014). Perhaps unsurprisingly the risk factors identified in this research are similar to the risk factors for offending in general: social deprivation, antisocial personality characteristics, antisocial attitudes and cognitions, and association with antisocial peers (Durrant, 2018). For many individuals, involvement in organized criminal groups provides opportunities for accruing status and resources that might be difficult to obtain through legitimate channels (e.g., see Bourgeois, 1995 on involvement in drug dealing). However, it needs to be recognized that many offenders, especially those occupying ‘higher-level’ positions in organized criminal groups, may diverge from this more typical profile. There appears to be very little research on these individuals, but certain roles are likely to favour traits that are more similar to whitecollar offenders, such as a greater capacity for self-regulation (Ragatz et al., 2012), even though they may have other antisocial personality characteristics (Craparo et al., 2018). An evolutionary approach can help us delineate the core aspects of organized crime and explain both the motivations for engaging in organized crime and the typical activities pursued by organized crime groups. It can also help us to understand, as outlined below, how these groups are structured. More specifically, it can shed light on how cooperation is maintained in such groups in the face of incentives to defect.
303
THE PROBLEM OF COOPERATION IN ORGANIZED CRIME Organized crime involves the coordination of at least two individuals in the commission of illegal activities, although for many organized crime groups there are a large number of individuals involved. Organized crime is, thus, an inherently cooperative endeavour and, as such, poses an important and widely recognized problem: how is cooperation maintained in the face of temptations to freeride or defect? (Tooby and Cosmides, 2010). The structure of the widely researched ‘Prisoner’s Dilemma game’ provides an apt illustration of this problem. In this game, as it was originally developed, two offenders have been arrested by the police and have agreed to keep silent about their criminal activities to protect themselves and their partner. If they are successful in this (i.e. they cooperate), they will receive a one-year prison sentence. The police, as is their wont, offer a tangible incentive to rat on their partner (i.e. to defect): if they talk, they will be set free, unpunished, and their partner will receive a lengthy 10-year prison sentence. If they incriminate each other, they will get five years in prison. The structure of the dilemma is obvious: the best collective outcome for both offenders is to stay silent because they will receive a combined two years in prison. However, the best individual outcome is to be set free, but because this outcome is presented to each offender, if both individuals take this option, they will both be worse off than if they stayed silent (Cronk and Leech, 2013). The Prisoner’s Dilemma provides a vivid illustration of a more general problem for evolutionary theory: how do we explain cooperation among group members given the selective advantages of free-riding or defection? There is now an extensive literature on the evolution of altruism and cooperation and a number of viable evolutionary mechanisms have been identified that can maintain cooperation among individuals (see Clutton-Brock,
304
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
2009; Cronk and Leech, 2013; Kurzban et al., 2015; West et al., 2011, for reviews). Cooperation among kin is easily explained: because kin are more likely to share genes compared to non-kin, any behaviour that facilitates interactions that benefit kin or are mutually beneficial will be selected for (Dawkins, 1976; Hamilton, 1964). Cooperation also occurs widely among nonkin in humans and other animals and can be maintained via direct reciprocity: if all parties benefit from cooperation, then all parties will be motivated to cooperate (Trivers, 1971). Cooperation can be maintained via direct reciprocity even if the exchange of benefits is not simultaneous as long as they are reciprocated at some future date. Cooperation may also evolve via what some scholars have termed ‘indirect reciprocity’. Cooperative behaviour can be a reliable signal to other group members that the individual can be trusted and thus they are likely to be cooperated with in the future (Kurzban et al., 2015). Both direct and indirect reciprocity are vulnerable, however, to exploitation. Individuals who cooperate but are not cooperated with in turn will be at a selective disadvantage relative to those who accept the benefits of cooperation without reciprocating in kind. One solution to this problem is the evolution of punishment. Individuals who receive cooperation but don’t return it in kind may be subject to sanctions – either at the hands of the cooperator (what we call ‘revenge’ or ‘retaliation’ – Jackson et al., 2019; McCullough et al., 2013) or via a thirdparty (what is often termed ‘altruistic punishment’ or, more generally, ‘justice’ – Boyd et al., 2003). Finally, a number of scholars have argued that the evolution of cooperation in large-scale groups, of the kind that most people live in today, has been shaped by cultural evolutionary processes (Chudek et al., 2013; Henrich, 2016; Richerson et al., 2017; Turchin, 2016). A particular emphasis has been placed on the potential role of cultural group selection in shaping cooperative behaviour within groups. Groups that have characteristics – norms,
values, institutions – that tend to promote cooperation among in-group members will be more successful relative to groups without these characteristics and hence these particular norms, values, and institutions will tend to flourish at the expense of others. Recent work suggests that cultural group selection processes may have been important in the cultural evolution of prosocial religions that are maintained via constellations of norms, values, and practices that demarcate in-group from out-group members (e.g., rituals, hardto-fake markers) and promote social cohesion and cooperation among members of the ingroup (see Norenzayan, 2013; Norenzayan et al., 2016; Saroglou, 2011). In particular, cultural evolutionary approaches to the evolution of religion highlight the role of specific norms and values that bind co-religionists (e.g., the notion of fictive kin – all adherents are ‘brothers’ and ‘sisters’): costly, time- consuming, and sometimes painful rituals that serve as clear markers of group commitment (what Norenzayan, 2013, calls ‘credibility enhancing displays’), and often strict rules and their enforcement by both group members (Durrant and Poppelwell, 2017), and by a god or gods (Norenzayan, 2013). Similar processes operate to bind individuals into closely knit male groups (army units, terrorist cells) in the context of inter-group conflict (e.g., Whitehouse et al., 2014), consistent with the male warrior hypothesis outlined above. How might these various evolutionary processes that support cooperation help us to understand the nature, structure, and practices of (largely male-based) organized crime groups? Table 15.2 provides an overview of how evolutionary mechanisms for cooperation might map on to the different organization structures elucidated by von Lampe (2016a, 2016b). Many organized criminal groups are based on interactions involving family members (von Lampe, 2016b). This seems to be the case for both relatively smallscale organized crime groups as well as for larger, more complex criminal organizations.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ORGANIZED CRIME
305
Table 15.2 The functional structures of organized crime groups in relation to the key evolutionary processes that facilitate cooperation1 Entrepreneurial Kin-selection
Direct reciprocity
Illegal networks, markets, and businesses Indirect reciprocity Reputation-based promotion Punishment Violence used to enforce reciprocal exchange – ‘revenge’ Cultural selection
Associational Blood family associations and ‘fictive kin’ structures, and ‘ethnic’ groups Mutual support
Quasi-governmental
Honouring of commercial exchanges and ‘contracts’
Reputation, honour, loyalty Mechanisms for the enforcement Sanctions for violations of rules and norms administered by group members The role of group-based norms, Mechanisms for regulation, conflict markers, rituals, and practices resolution, protection
1
Examples provided are illustrative only and may be influenced by multiple evolutionary mechanisms (e.g., revenge may have been shaped by both genetic and cultural evolutionary processes – Jackson et al., 2019).
In the UK, for instance, there is a long history of criminal groups based on cooperation among brothers: the Sabini brothers in the 1920s, the Richardson brothers in South London in the 1940s and 1950s, and the notorious Kray twins during the same period in the East End of London (Antonopoulos and Papanicolaou, 2018). The Latin American drug cartels that emerged during the 1970s were also often centred on leaders who were close kin. The Ochoa clan, along with Pablo Escobar, led the Medellin cartel, while the Cali cartel was led by the Rodriguez-Orejuela brothers (Abadinsky, 2017; Antonopoulos and Papanicolaou, 2018). Italian Mafia organizations have also historically been based on blood ties, although this varies somewhat among the different Mafia groups (Antonopoulos and Papanicolaou, 2018; von Lampe, 2016a). Research suggests that there is often a considerable degree of intergenerational continuity among members of organized crime groups as sons in particular follow their fathers’ involvement (van Dijk et al., 2018). Many large-scale organized crime groups (like many religious groups) tap into evolved mechanisms to preferentially cooperate with kin by creating family-like structures, based on the notion of ‘fictive kin’. Thus, the various branches of the Italian Mafia place
emphasis on the idea of ‘brotherhood’, the Japanese Yakuza invoke the notion of Ikka, or family, creating an organizational structure that mimics that of the family (with a ‘father’, and ‘brothers’), and the Hong Kong Triads invoke a concept of ‘universal Triad brotherhood’ which links the various Triad societies (von Lampe, 2016a). From an evolutionary perspective, the prevalence of both actual and fictive blood ties reflects the evolution of mechanisms that promote cooperation among close kin. Thus, they are likely to reduce defection among members of organized crime groups while enhancing cooperation and social cohesion. Indeed, many large-scale organized crime groups emphasize the importance of fictive-kin ties (among ‘brothers’) over and above ties to family members. The first rule of the Russian ‘Vory v zakone’ (‘Thieves in law’), for example, states: ‘A thief must turn his back on his family – mother, father, brothers, and sisters. The criminal community is family’ (cited in von Lampe, 2016a: 166). Cooperation among organized crime groups is also maintained via direct and indirect reciprocity. The operation of direct reciprocity is straightforward. In the same manner that legal transactions are maintained through simultaneous or delayed exchanges of goods or cash, the illegal activities of
306
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
organized criminals are facilitated through such reciprocal exchanges. Individuals who do not reciprocate will be viewed as less trustworthy and hence are less likely to be chosen as cooperative partners in the future (in addition to being the object of potential sanctions, including those that operate through quasi-governmental-like processes). The exchange of goods and services among members of organized crime groups, however, is not always immediate or necessarily reciprocal, and cooperative behaviour may be maintained as a way of signalling trustworthiness to other group members. Values such as honour, trustworthiness, and loyalty to the group are strongly emphasized in many organized crime groups such as the Mafia. In turn, organized crime groups provide extensive mutual support to group members in need: ‘The bonds that tie individuals together in an associational criminal structure almost by nature establish a commitment to mutual support. There is an unspoken or explicit obligation to come to the aid of other members when needed’ (von Lampe, 2016b: 25). As Paoli (2003: 17) notes for the Italian Mafia, aid to other members is given ‘with no expectation of short-term rewards’. Even among members of organized crime groups there may be temptations to ‘defect’ or ‘free-ride’ – to benefit from the cooperation of others while not fully reciprocating in turn. The role of sanctions in shaping behaviour among offenders who violate norms is well recognized. For example, Maier and Ricciardelli (2019), in a qualitative study of 56 former prisoners in Canada, found that prisoners would often rather accept the institutional punishment handed out by the authorities than risk the informal punishment they might receive at the hands of their fellow inmates for being a ‘snitch’. As one participant recounted: ‘ …’ cause I figured out … ‘cause I found out who did it but I didn’t say anything [to the prison staff] … because they [prison staff] try to tell me well “why didn’t you say who did it or you get it shit?” I’m
like “you’d rather I’d say” … [but if] I say it now and then I’ll get killed and then what?’ (Maier and Ricciardelli, 2019: 245; see also Dudai, 2018, for the role of punishment among members of the Irish Republican Army). Entrepreneurial structures based on reciprocal exchange are vulnerable to exploitation and defection because agreements cannot be enforced via legal channels. Thus, protagonists in organized crime must be willing to use violence and other threats to enforce cooperation. The high levels of violence in some illegal markets, such as the drug market, reflect the absence of formal mechanisms of dispute resolution (Reuter, 2016). Many large-scale organized crime groups, however, have clear rules and mechanisms for their enforcement that entail quasigovernmental processes of dispute resolution and sanctioning. These processes go beyond ‘revenge’ and may include processes that resemble the criminal justice system, including collective decision making, dispute resolution between parties, and graded sanctions that include fines, suspension of membership, and death (von Lampe, 2016a). Some methods are specific to particular groups and serve as markers of group commitment: among Japanese Yakuza, for example, finger amputation is employed as both a punishment and a signal to others of commitment to the group (Hill, 2014). When groups become large or entail high levels of cooperation among members, social cohesion and cooperation are more difficult to sustain. If, as suggested above, cooperation in large-scale groups is partly maintained via norms, values, and institutions that have been culturally selected for, then we might expect ‘successful’ organized crime groups (e.g., those with greater longevity) to have converged upon rules, norms, and processes that maintain group cooperation. Codes of conduct are similar across geographically divergent organized crime groups, providing some support for this suggestion (Kassab and Rosen, 2019; von Lampe, 2016b). They usually coalesce around a set of strict rules or
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ORGANIZED CRIME
obligations: (1) absolute loyalty to the group above all others, including kin; (2) strict secrecy concerning the nature of the group’s members and activities; and (3) honesty and reciprocity among group members. In addition, organized crime groups often have a diverse set of specific rules about how individuals conduct themselves with both group and non-group members, and the kinds of criminal activities they can and cannot engage in. For example, Italian Mafia groups traditionally prohibit involvement in drug trafficking or the use of kidnapping for ransom, to avoid drawing unnecessary attention to themselves (von Lampe, 2016b). Interestingly, various organized crime groups such as the Italian Mafia also prohibit sexual relations with other members’ wives – a rule that is likely to promote and maintain cohesive bonding among male members (Kassab and Rosen, 2019). Cultural group selection processes are facilitated through clear mechanisms for symbolically delineating group bound aries that demarcate group membership (Richerson et al., 2016). In addition, social cohesion among group members, as noted above, can be enhanced via participation in collective rituals. The role of initiation rituals and markers of group status are common among organized crime groups. Among Italian Mafia groups, traditional initiation ceremonies involve the pricking of the index finger so that blood drips on a saint’s icon, which is then set on fire in the hand of the candidate, who swears loyalty to the Mafia and its rules (Antonopoulos and Papanicolaou, 2018). Markers of group membership are also common: membership into outlaw motorcycle gangs is often signalled by the wearing of distinct patches, the Russian vory v zakone sport specific tattoos that signal group status communicated in a coded language only known among group members (Abadinsky, 2017). Among the Yakuza, extensive body tattooing is common, and members are required to participate in ceremonies such as initiation rites (Hill, 2014). However, given the importance
307
of secrecy among many organized crime groups, such as the Mafia, overt markers of group status may be absent from some groups. From the perspective of cultural group selection theory (Richerson et al., 2016), it is easy to see why different organized crime groups have converged on similar mechanisms for maintaining cooperation: those groups that promote extreme withingroup cooperation and that adhere to clear rules (like codes of secrecy) are likely to thrive at the expense of groups that do not. There has been very little empirical research that has systematically examined the nature of cooperation among members of organized crime groups (or among offenders in general). In the first study to employ the Prisoner’s Dilemma game with a sample of prison inmates, Khadjavi and Lange (2013) found that the prison sample was more likely to cooperate in the simultaneous Prisoner’s Dilemma (where the decision to cooperate or defect is made at the same time) compared to student participants. Rates of cooperation were roughly the same in the two groups in response to a sequential Prisoner’s Dilemma (where individuals respond with cooperation or defection in response to an initial response by their partner). The results perhaps reflect the existence of informal ‘prisoner codes’ that structure social interactions in correctional facilities, and facilitate cooperation among inmates (Maier and Ricciardelli, 2019). Interestingly, a more recent study using a sample of community-supervised offenders found lower rates of cooperation in a Prisoner’s Dilemma game in the offending group compared to a control group (Clark et al., 2015), suggesting that it may be features of the prison environment that play a role in structuring cooperative behaviour in these games (although the nature of the sample could also have been a factor, given that Khadjavi and Lange’s study involved women prisoners only). Although we may expect that cooperation among offenders depends on specific contextual factors (e.g., lower in general, but
308
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
perhaps higher in institutional contexts), we should expect that organized criminals display high rates of cooperation among group members for the reasons that have been presented above: kin and fictive-kin structures, networks of direct and indirect reciprocity, and strong social norms and rules that promote trust, cooperation, and bonding among group members. This is exactly what Nese et al. (2018) found in an experimental field study with a sample of Camorra (Mafia) prisoners recruited from a jail in Naples. Participants in this study (129 Camorra, 109 ‘ordinary’ criminals, and 109 students) engaged in two different experimental games: a one-shot Prisoner’s Dilemma (PD), and one-shot Prisoner’s Dilemma with third-party punishment (PD-TPP). In the PD game, participants were given an envelope containing 10 tokens and paired with another individual with a similar envelope containing 10 tokens. Both individuals had to simultaneously decide whether to (a) keep their tokens; or (b) send them to their partner, in which case the researcher would triple the amount received (at the end of the study tokens could be exchanged for real money). The Prisoner’s Dilemma structure here is clear: if both individuals cooperate and send their tokens, they will receive 30 points (the 10 received times 3), if both defect and keep their own tokens they obtain 10 points, and if one cooperates while the other defects the cooperator receives nothing while the defector obtains 40 points (their original 10 plus the 10 they receive multiplied by three). All games were played with anonymous partners, but participants knew which group they were playing with (e.g., Camorristi interacted with Camorristi, and students interacted with students). The results indicated that the organized criminal offenders (the Camorristi) engaged in higher levels of cooperation (86.7% of trials) compared to the students (67.5%) and the ordinary criminals (50.0%), providing strong support for the idea that organized crime members abide by strong norms
of reciprocity. Interestingly, in the PD-TPP game, when a third party could pay points to sanction the two participants in the PD game (by taking points from them for not cooperating), rates of cooperation dropped among both the Camorristi and the students but increased among the ordinary prisoners. This suggests that the introduction of sanctions may reduce cooperation under some circumstances, particularly if the sanctions are perceived as unfair (see Fehr and Rockenbach, 2003). In a related study employing a battery of economic games with samples of students residing in both pro- and anti-Mafia neighbourhoods in Palermo, the researchers found that levels of trust, trustworthiness, and altruism were lower among students in the proMafia neighbourhoods, but that in-group favouritism on these measures was higher than in the anti-Mafia neighbourhood (Meier et al., 2016). This implies that the strong presence of organized crime groups might erode generalized trust and cooperation in the environments in which they are active but promote greater cooperation among in-group members. Similar results have been found in research that examined the role of religion on cooperation: adherents tend to be more prosocial and cooperative, but also more parochial, more strongly favouring in-groups over out-groups (e.g., Purzycki et al., 2018). Clearly, more empirical research is needed on the nature of cooperation among organized crime members, but these initial studies support the idea that cooperation has been maintained through a combination of mechanisms including direct and indirect reciprocity along with third-party punishment and the maintenance of group-based norms and values.
ORGANIZED CRIME AND STATE BUILDING Charles Tilly (1985/2002: 35) influentially drew a somewhat startling comparison
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ORGANIZED CRIME
between organized crime groups and the institutions of ‘legitimate’ statehood: Apologists for particular governments and for government in general commonly argue, precisely, that they offer protection from local and external violence. They claim that the prices they charge barely cover the costs of protection. They call people who complain about the price of protection ‘anarchists’, ‘subversives’, or both at once. But consider the definition of a racketeer as someone who creates a threat, then charges for its reduction. Governments’ provision of protection, by this standard, often qualifies as racketeering. To the extent that the threats against which a given government protects its citizens are imaginary, or are a consequence of its own activities, the government has organized a protection racket.
This comparison speaks to a number of important similarities between the ‘legitimate’ practices and institutions of the nation state and those that are apparent in many organized crime groups. First, and most importantly, as the sociologist Max Weber (1978) emphasized, states possess a monopoly on legitimate violence to punish rule violations and maintain social order. To sustain a state apparatus that can maintain order and ‘protect’ its citizens from the predations of others, it levies taxes from those who reside within the state’s jurisdiction and, more generally, ‘claims authority … to a very large extent over all action taking place in the area of its jurisdiction’ (Weber, 1978: 69). Similarly, many organized crime groups such as the Mafia extract payments from businesses that operate within their ‘jurisdiction’ for which, in turn, they provide protection (in part, from themselves, but also from other predatory individuals and groups). Of course, these similarities do not necessarily apply to all organized crime groups and the degree to which they exercise ‘state-like’ functions vary, in part due to differences to the extent that the activities of such groups entail the control of specific territory (Koivu, 2016). Nonetheless, the comparison between states and organized crime groups is a potentially fruitful one that may serve to shed light on both the origin of the state itself, and how
309
and under what conditions organized crime groups tend to emerge. Understanding the transition from small, largely mobile hunter-gatherer bands to sedentary, large-scale societies with state-like features remains a formidable task that has engaged scholars from a wide range of disciplines. Although there remain many theories of state formation (Carneiro, 1970; Turchin et al., 2018), it seems that early states shared many of the features of organized crime groups such as the Mafia, as they provided protection while extracting profits and wielding substantial amounts of largely unchecked power (Scheidel, 2017). As Scheidel (2017: 48) laconically suggests: ‘Reduced to essentials, history has known only two ideal-typical modes of wealth acquisition: making and taking’. Male coalitionary elites are uniquely poised to follow the latter pathway. Scott (2017) argues that the development of high-density agriculture, particularly cereal production, provided the conditions for emerging statehood. Because wealth is heavily concentrated in a clearly defined territory, it is chronically vulnerable to exploitation by mobile raiders. Raiding, however, is inherently unstable as an ongoing concern: not only does it destroy wealth that forms the basis of the raiding activity, but as raiding increases in frequency sedentary lifestyles become untenable. ‘Knowing this’, Scott (2017: 240–241) suggests raiders are more likely to adjust their strategy to something that looks more like a ‘protection racket.’ In return for a portion of the trade goods, harvest, livestock, and other valuables, the raiders ‘protect’ the traders and communities against other raiders and, of course, against themselves… In extracting a sustainable surplus from sedentary communities and fending off external attacks to protect its base, a stable protection racket like this is hard to distinguish from the archaic state itself.
Recent quantitative analyses of emerging statehood suggest that large-scale complex human societies were more likely to develop in contexts where agriculture had been practiced for long periods, population size was
310
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
larger, and warfare was more intense (Currie et al., 2019; Turchin et al., 2018). As humans scaled up from small-scale hunter-gatherer bands to large-scale societies, male coalitions – long a component of human societies in the context of collective ‘power scavenging’, hunting, and inter-group raiding – were uniquely placed to exploit new opportunities made available through the concentration of resources offered by the emergence of agriculture (although it is worth noting here that the development of agriculture preceded the emergence of states by a considerable period of time, suggesting that agriculture was a precondition, rather than an inevitable precursor, for state formation – Gintis et al., 2019). Hirschfeld (2015), who has provided one of the few in-depth analyses of organized crime from an evolutionary perspective, employs the idea of an ‘evolutionary stable strategy’ to argue that economic exchanges based purely on reciprocity are going to be vulnerable to exploitation from organized crime like activities (raiding, violence, extortion) (although see Koivu, 2016). In turn, exploitative groups are vulnerable to others that provide protection with less overt or obvious exploitation of primary producers, resulting in transitions to ‘gangster-states’. More stable state-like institutions of the kind that operate in contemporary liberal democracies may emerge but will remain vulnerable to exploitation from organized criminal groups under specific circumstances. From this broader perspective, organized crime groups with different characteristics or traits compete both among themselves and against ‘legitimate’ states for control and power over valuable resources. Historical analyses suggest that organized crime groups are most likely to emerge when there is a valuable concentration of defendable resources and when legitimate state processes for enforcing the law are weak or non-existent. The emergence of the Sicilian mafia in the 19th century, for example, occurred against a backdrop of a weak rule of law in combination with a concentration of valuable
resources that could be readily monopolized – citrus fruit (Dimicio et al., 2017) and sulphur (Buonanno et al., 2015). Although many organized crime groups interact with legitimate state actors and institutions in various forms of ‘symbiotic’-like relationships that benefit each other, research clearly suggests that the prevalence of organized crime in a given nation state is strongly (negatively) associated with the quality of rule of law, indicating that it is the absence of legitimate third-party enforcement that creates opportunities for organized crime groups to exert influence (van Dijk, 2007).
CONCLUSION I have argued in this chapter that organized crime involves the coalitional exploitation of others for personal gain in ways that violate criminal laws. Consistent with the male warrior hypothesis, I have suggested that selection for male coalitional aggression in our evolutionary past has fostered the tendency for males to form groups in the context of hunting, raiding, and inter-group conflict. As such, the activities that comprise organized crime – the trafficking of illegal goods and services, predatory crimes such as theft, fraud, and robbery, and ‘illegal governance’ crimes such as protection payments – involve the cooperation of (mostly) men in ways that can enhance their inclusive fitness at the expense of others. Because organized crime groups (like any cooperative group) are vulnerable to exploitation, their longevity depends on exploiting mechanisms that facilitate cooperation among group members. Three main evolutionary routes have been discussed: kin selection, direct and indirect reciprocity, and cultural group selection. Many organized crime groups are based on a nucleus of close family members and many more use cultural mechanisms to enhance cooperation via the idea of ‘fictive kin’. Cooperation is also sustained through the
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ORGANIZED CRIME
reciprocal exchange of resources and via mechanisms that encourage trustworthy behaviour, ultimately backed up by the threat of sanctions. Large-scale organized crime groups often have many of the features that promote social cohesion in different group contexts (e.g., religious groups), including costly initiation ceremonies, symbolic marking of group members, and rigid codes of conduct. The capacity for organized crime groups to exert power through the control of concentrated resources, the extraction of ‘taxes’, and the use of violence to enforce cooperation offers many similarities with the functions of legitimate governments and may provide insights into the ultimate origin of the state in human history. Given the paucity of research on organized crime from an evolutionary perspective, there is substantial scope for future research to explore many of these avenues in further detail. Finally, it is worth considering how the approach taken in this chapter suggests various avenues for reducing the (largely) harmful impacts of organized crime on society. Most obviously, if we can conceptualize organized crime groups as being in competition with legitimate states, then we should employ strategies that support those characteristics of states that allow them to promote public goods – protection, safety, an effective rule of law, social services – as they are likely to reduce the impact and influence of many organized crime groups that may offer similar ‘services’. Relatedly, approaches that de-couple organized crime groups from legitimate institutions through crackdowns on corruption are likely to be effective, as such groups can no longer exploit state actors and institutions to pursue their own objectives and goals. If membership in organized criminal groups is seen by many men as a viable route to obtain social status, as argued above, then strategies to improve opportunities for status attainment through legitimate means (e.g., better education, reductions in inequality, and anything that is likely to promote the development of slow life history
311
strategies – Durrant, 2016) are likely to reduce the lure of such groups. Finally, it is worth considering how some highly desirable commodities (e.g., drugs) and services (e.g., prostitution), currently monopolized by organized crime groups because they are illegal, may be better managed through legitimate channels, thus eliminating many of the harms that arise through their (illegal) sale. It is unlikely that we will be able to eradicate organized crime groups entirely because they readily emerge in contexts where state power is weak or non-existent, or corruption is widespread, but recognition of their evolutionary origins may encourage strategies that can reduce their largely negative effects on society.
REFERENCES Abadinsky, H. (2016). Organized crime (11th edition). Boston, MA: Cengage Learning. Albanese, J. S. (2014). The Italian-American Mafia. In L. Paoli (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of organized crime (pp. 142–158). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Beeson, J. G. (2014). Psychology of human trafficking. In M. J. Palmiotto (Ed.), Combatting human trafficking: A multidisciplinary approach (pp. 47–60). London, UK: CRC Press. Boehm, C. (2012). Moral origins: The evolution of virtue, altruism, and shame. Philadelphia, PA: Basic Books. Bourgeois, C. A., & Fisher, M. L. (2018). More ‘bros,’ more woes? The prevalence of male coalitions in crimes of robbery. Evolutionary Behavioral Sciences, 12, 126–131. doi: 10.1037/ebs000116 Bourgeois, P. (1995). In search of respect: Selling crack in El Bario. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Boyd, R., Gintis, H., Bowles, S., & Richerson, P. J. (2003). The evolution of altruistic punishment. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 100, 3531–3535. Buonanno, P., Durante, R., Prarolo, G., & Vanin, P. (2015). Poor institutions, rich mines: Resource curse in the origins of the Sicilian
312
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
mafia. The Economic Journal, F175–F201. doi: 10.1111/ecoj.12236 Carneiro, R. L. (1970). A theory of the origin of the state: Traditional theories of state origins are considered and rejected in favor of a new ecological hypothesis. Science, 169, 733–738. Chudek, M., Zhao, W., & Henrich, J. (2013). Culture-gene coevolution, large-scale cooperation, and the shaping of human social psychology. In K. Sterelny, R. Joyce, B. Calcott, & B. Fraser (Eds.), Cooperation and its evolution (pp. 425–457). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Clark, B. C., Thorne, C. B., Hendricks, P. S., Sharp, C., Clark, S. K., & Cropsey, K. L. (2015). Individuals in the criminal justice system show differences in cooperative behaviour: Implications for cooperative games. Criminal Behaviour and Mental Health, 25, 169–180. doi: 10.1002/cbm.1920 Clutton-Brock, T. (2009). Cooperation between non-kin in animal societies. Nature, 462 November, 51–57. doi: 10.1038/nature08366 Confer, J. C., Easton, J. A., Fleischman, D. S., Goetz, C. D., Lewis, D. M. G., Perilloux, C., & Buss, D. M. (2010). Evolutionary psychology: Controversies, questions, prospects, and limitations. American Psychologist, 65, 110– 126. doi: 10.1037/a0018413 Craparo, G., David, V., Costanzo, G., & Gori, A. (2018). Cosa Nostra and the Camorra: Assessment of personality, alexithymic traits, and attachment styles. International Journal of Law and Psychiatry, 58, 17–26. doi: 10.1016/ j.ijlp.2018.02.010 Cronk, L., & Leech, B. L. (2013). Meeting at Grand Central: Understanding the social and evolutionary roots of cooperation. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Currie, T. E., Turchin, P., & Gavrilets, S. (2019). History of agriculture and intensity of warfare shaped the evolution of large-scale human societies in Afro-Eurasia. SocArXiv Papers. doi: 10.31235/osf.io/9kmrw Daly, M., & Wilson, M. (1988). Homicide. Hawthorne, NY: Aldine. Dawkins, R. (1976). The selfish gene. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Dimico, A., Isopi, A., & Olsson, O. (2017). Origins of the Sicilian Mafia: The market for lemons. The Journal of Economic History, 77, 1083– 1115. doi: 10.1017/S002205071700078X
Dudai, R. (2018). Underground penality: The IRA’s punishment of informers. Punishment & Society, 20, 375–395. doi: 10.1177/ 1462474517701302 Duntley, J. D., & Shackelford, T. K. (2008). Darwinian foundations of crime and law. Aggression and Violent Behaviour, 13, 373–382. doi: 10.1093/acprof:oso/97801953 25188.001.0001 Durrant, R. (2016). Putting risk factors in their place: An evolutionary-developmental approach to understanding risk. Psychology, Crime & Law, 22, 17–32. Durrant, R. (2018). An introduction to criminology psychology (2nd edition). London, UK: Routledge. Durrant, R. (2019). Evolutionary approaches to understanding crime: Explaining the gender gap in offending. Psychology, Crime & Law, 25, 589–608. doi: 10.1080/1068316X.2018. 1558224 Durrant, R., Adamson, S., Todd, F., & Sellman, D. (2009). Drug use and addiction: An evolutionary perspective. Australian and New Zealand Journal of Psychiatry, 43, 1049–1056. doi: 10.3109/00048670903270449 Durrant, R., & Poppelwell, Z. (2017). Religion, crime and punishment: An evolutionary perspective. Cham, Switzerland: Springer. Durrant, R., & Ward, T. (2015). Evolutionary criminology: Towards a comprehensive explanation for crime. Amsterdam, Netherlands: Academic Press. Fehr, E., & Rockenbach, B. (2003). Detrimental effects of sanctions on human altruism. Nature, 422, 137–140. Feinstein, A., & Holden, P. (2014). Arms trafficking. In L. Paoli (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of organized crime (pp. 444–459). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Gintis, H., van Schaik, C., & Boehm, C. (2019). Zoon politikon: The evolutionary origins of human socio-political systems. Behavioural Processes, 161, 17–30. Hamilton, W. D. (1964). The genetical evolution of social behavior: I. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 7, 1–16. doi: 10.1016/0022-5193 (64)90038-4 Henrich, J. (2016). The secret of our success: How culture is driving human evolution, domesticating our species, and making us smarter. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ORGANIZED CRIME
Hill, P. (2014). The Japanese Yakuza. In L. Paoli (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of organized crime (pp. 234–253). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Hirschfeld, K. (2015). Gangster states: Organized crime, kleptocracy and political collapse. New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan. Jackson, J. C., Choi, V. K., & Gelfand, M. J. (2019). Revenge: A multi-level review and synthesis. Annual Review of Psychology, 70, 319–345. doi: 10.1146/annurev-psych-010418 Kassab, H. S., & Rosen, J. D. (2019). Illicit markets, organized crime, and global security (pp. 63–85). Cham, Switzerland: Palgrave Macmillan. Kavish, N., Fowler-Finn, K., & Boutwell, B. B. (2017). Criminology’s modern synthesis: Remaking the science of crime with Darwinian insight. In T. K. Shackelford & V. Zeigler-Hill (Eds.), The evolution of psychopathology (pp. 171–183). Cham, Switzerland: Springer International Publishing. Kenrick, D. T., Griskevicius, V., Neuberg, S. L., & Schaller, M. (2010). Renovating the pyramid of needs: Contemporary extensions built upon ancient foundations. Perspectives in Psychological Science, 5, 292–314. doi: 10.1177/ 1745691610369469 Khadjavi, M., & Lange, A. (2013). Prisoners and their dilemma. Journal of Economic Behaviour and Organization, 92, 163–175. doi: 10.1016/j.jebo.2013.05.015 Kirby, S., Francis, B., Humphreys, L., & Soothill, K. (2016). Using the UK general offender database as a means to measure and analyse organized crime. Policing: An International Journal of Police Strategies and Management, 39, 78–94. doi: 10.1108/ PJJPSM-03-2015-0024 Kleemans, E. (2014). Theoretical perspectives on organized crime. In L. Paoli (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of organized crime (pp. 32–52). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Kleemans, E. R., & Smit, M. (2014). Human smuggling, human trafficking, and exploitation in the sex industry. In L. Paoli (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of organized crime (pp. 381–401). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Koivu, K. L. (2016). In the shadow of the state: Mafias and illicit markets. Comparative Political Studies, 49, 155–183.
313
Kurzban, R., Burton-Chellew, M. N., & West, S. A. (2015). The evolution of altruism in humans. Annual Review of Psychology, 66. doi: 10.1146/annurev-psych-010814015355 Lantz, B. (2019). Co-offending group composition and violence: The impact of sex, age, and group size on co-offending violence. Crime & Delinquency. Advance online publication. doi: 10.1177/0011128719834564 Lenzi, M., Sharkey, J., Vieno, A., Mayworm, A., Dougherty, D., & Nylund-Gibson, K. (2015). Adolescent gang involvement: The role of individual, family, peer, and school factors in a multilevel perspective. Aggressive Behavior, 41, 386–397. Levi, M. (1998). Perspectives on ‘organised crime’: An overview. The Howard Journal, 37, 335–345. Levi, M. (2014). Money laundering. In L. Paoli (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of organized crime (pp. 419–443). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Maier, K. H., & Ricciardelli, R. (2019). The prisoner’s dilemma: How male prisoners experience and respond to penal threat when incarcerated. Punishment & Society, 2, 231–250. doi: 10.1177/1462474518757091 McCullough, M. E., Kurzban, R., & Tabak, B. A. (2013). Cognitive systems for revenge and forgiveness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36, 1–58. McDonald, M. M., Navarrete, C. D., & van Vugt, M. (2012). Evolution and the psychology of intergroup conflict: The male warrior hypothesis. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, B, 367, 670–679. Meier, S., Pierce, L., Vaccaro, A., & La Cara, B. (2016). Trust and in-group favouritism in a culture of crime. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 132, 78–92. doi: 10.1016/j.jebo.2016.09.005 Nese, A., O’Higgins, N., Sbriglia, P., & Scudiero, M. (2018). Cooperation, punishment and organized crime: A lab-in-the-field experiment in southern Italy. European Economic Review, 107, 86–98. doi: 10.1016/j. euroecorev.2018.05.004 Nesse, R. M. (1994). An evolutionary perspective on substance abuse. Ethology and Sociobiology, 15, 339–348.
314
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Norenzayan, A. (2013). Big gods: How religion transformed cooperation and conflict. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Norenzayan, A., Shariff, A. F., Willard A. K., Slingerland, W. E., Gervais, R. A., McNamara, R. A., & Henrich, J. (2016). The cultural evolution of prosocial religions. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 39, e1. Paoli, L. (2003). Mafia brotherhoods: Organized crime Italian style. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Paoli, L. (2016). Towards a theory of organized crime: Some preliminary reflections. In G. A. Antonopoulos (Ed.), Illegal entrepreneurship, organised crime, and social control (pp. 3– 17). Cham, Switzerland: Springer. Paoli, L., & Vander Beken, T. (2014). Organized crime: A contested concept. In L. Paoli (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of organized crime (pp. 13–31). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Pizzini-Gambetta, V. (2014). Organized crime: The gender constraints of illegal markets. In R. Gartner & B. McCarthy (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of gender, sex, and crime (pp. 448–467). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Purzycki, B. G., Henrich, J., Apicella, C., Atkinson, Q. C., Baimel, A., Cohen, E., & Norenzayan, A. (2018). The evolution of religion and morality; A synthesis of ethnographic and experimental evidence from eight societies. Religion, Brain & Behaviour, 8, 101–132. doi: 10.1080/ 2153599X.2016.1267027. Ragatz, L. L., Fremouw, W., & Baker, E. (2012). The psychological profile of white collar offenders: Demographics, criminal thinking, psychopathic traits, and psychopathology. Criminal Justice & Behavior, 39, 978–997. Reuter, P. (2014). Drug markets and organized crime. In L. Paoli (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of organized crime (pp. 359–380). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Reuter, P. (2016). On the multiple sources of violence in drug markets. Criminology and Public Policy, 15, 1–7. Richerson, P., Baldini, R., Bell, A. V., Demps, K., Frost, K., Hillis, V., & & Ross, C. (2016). Cultural group selection plays an essential role in explaining human cooperation: A sketch of the evidence. Behavioural and
Brain Science, 39, e30. doi: 10.1017/ S0140525X1400106X Roach, J., & Pease, K. (2013). Evolution and crime. London, UK: Routledge. Roulette, C. J., Kazanji, M., Breurec, S., & Hagen, E. H. (2018). High prevalence of cannabis use among Aka foragers of the Congo basin and its possible relationship to helminthiasis. American Journal of Human Biology, 28, 5–15. Saroglou, V. (2011). Believing, bonding, behaving, and belonging: The big four religious dimensions and cultural variation. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology, 42, 1320–1340. doi: 10.1177/0022022111412267 Scheidel, W. (2017). The great leveller: Violence and the history of inequality from the stone age to the twenty-first century. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Scott, J. C. (2017). Against the grain: A deep history of the earliest states. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Spapens, T. (2014). Illegal gambling. In L. Paoli (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of organized crime (pp. 402–418). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Thoumi, F. E. (2014). Organized crime in Colombia: The actors running the illegal drug industry. In L. Paoli (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of organized crime (pp. 177–195). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Tilly, C. (1985/1992). War making and state making as organized crime. In C. Besteman (Ed.), Violence: A reader (pp. 35–60). New York, NY: New York University Press. Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (2010). Groups in mind: The coalitional roots of war and morality. In H. Høgh-Olesen (Ed.), Human morality and sociality: Evolutionary and comparative perspectives, (pp. 191–234). Cham, Switzerland: Palgrave Macmillan. Trivers, R. L. (1971). The evolution of reciprocal altruism. Quarterly Review of Biology, 46, 35–57. Turchin, P. (2016). Ultra society: How 10,000 years of war made humans the greatest co-operators on earth. Chaplin, CT: Beresta Books. Turchin, P., Whitehouse, H., Korotayev, A., Francois, P., Hoyer, D., Peregrine, P., & Currie, T. E. (2018). Evolutionary pathways to statehood: Old theories and new data. SocArXiv Papers. doi: 10.31235/osf.io/h7tr6
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ORGANIZED CRIME
United Nations Office of Drugs and Crime (2004). United Nations Convention Against Transnational Organized Crime and the Protocols Thereto. Retrieved from: www. unodc.org/documents/treaties/UNTOC/ Publications/TOC%20Convention/ TOCebook-e.pdf (Accessed 15 April 2019) van Dijk, M. (2007). Mafia markers: Assessing organized crime and its impact upon societies. Trends in Organized Crime, 10, 39–56. doi: 10.1007/s12117-007-9013-x van Dijk, M., Kleemans, E., & Eichelsheim, V. (2018). Children of organized crime offenders: Like father, like child? An explorative and qualitative study into mechanisms of intergenerational (dis)continuity in organized crime families. European Journal of Crime and Policy Research. Advance online publication. doi: 10.1007/s10610-018-9381-6 van San, M. (2011). The appeal of ‘dangerous’ men. On the role of women in organized crime. Trends in Organized Crime, 14, 281– 297. doi: 10.10007/s12117-011-9128-y von Lampe, K. (2016a). Organized crime: Analyzing illegal activities, criminal structures, and extra-legal governance. Los Angeles, CA: Sage. von Lampe, K (2016b). The ties that bind: A taxonomy of associational criminal structures. In G. A. Antonopoulos (Ed.), Illegal entrepreneurship, organised crime, and social control (pp. 19–35). Cham, Switzerland: Springer. von Rueden, C., Gurven, M., & Kaplan, H. (2011). Why do men seek status? Fitness payoffs to dominance and prestige. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, B, 278, 2223–2232. doi: 10.1098/rspb.2010.2145 von Rueden, C., & Jaeggi, A. V. (2016). Men’s status and reproductive success in 33 nonindustrial societies: Effects of subsistence, marriage system, and reproductive strategy.
315
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 113, 10824–10829. doi: 10.1073/ pnas.1606800113 van Vugt, M., De Cremer, D., & Janssen, D. P. (2007). Gender differences in cooperation and competition: The male warrior hypothesis. Psychological Science, 18, 19–23. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9280.2007.01842.x van Vugt, M., & Tybur, J. M. (2016). The evolutionary foundations of hierarchy: Status, dominance, prestige, leadership. In D. M. Buss (Ed.), Handbook of evolutionary psychology (2nd edition) (pp. 788–809). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley. Varese, F. (2014). Protection and extortion. In L. Paoli (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of organized crime (pp. 343–358). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Walsh, A., & Jorgensen, C. (2018). Evolutionary theory and criminology. In R. Hopcroft (Ed.), Oxford handbook of evolution, biology and society (pp. 517–542). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Weber, M. (1978). Economy and society: An outline of interpretive sociology. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. West, S. A., El Mouden, C., & Gardner, A. (2011). Sixteen common misconceptions about the evolution of cooperation in humans. Evolution and Human Behaviour, 32, 231–262. doi: 10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2010.08.001 Whitehouse, H., McQuinn, B., Buhrmester, M., & Swann, W. (2014). Brothers in arms: Libyan revolutionaries bond like family. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, 111, 17783–17785. doi: 10.1073/ pnas.1416284111 Wrangham, R. W., & Glowacki, L. (2012). Intergroup aggression in chimpanzees and war in nomadic hunter-gatherers: Evaluating the chimpanzee model. Human Nature, 23, 5–29. doi: 10.1007
16 Evolutionary Psychology and Warfare Anthony C. Lopez
INTRODUCTION The scientific study of the evolution of human coalitional aggression has exploded over the last several decades. In four parts, I explore and integrate several of the core frameworks that have emerged to explain the human practice of inter-group violence. First, we have a better understanding of the conditions required for the evolution of adaptations for coalitional aggression. These include: the presence within a species of a unique socio-ecology that facilitates the emergence of a group-based population structure; the existence of evolved cognitive abilities that make possible the navigation of challenges associated with group living that are necessary for coalitional aggression (e.g., some forms of collective action); and the presence of low-cost/high-benefit reproductive opportunities that are uniquely wellseized via coalitional aggression. In short, a species must live in groups, it must be able to solve complex collective action problems,
and violence must have been reproductively beneficial, on average. Second, given an understanding of the theoretical requirements, we are better situated to examine the historic and prehistoric record for evidence of the existence of these conditions. This involves examination of many lines of evidence such as studies of nonhuman primates, the archaeological record of coalitional aggression, and modern huntergatherer evidence, as well as game-theoretic evidence and lab evidence of the design of psychological mechanisms for coalitional aggression. The latter is particularly important given that the logic of natural selection indicates that the extant structure of adaptations themselves provides, in part, a window into ancestral landscapes. Third, I explore and integrate current evidence of psychological adaptations for coalitional aggression. There are two forms of inter-group engagement that have received the most attention: raids and battles. I also examine five areas of inquiry that suggest
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND WARFARE
special design for coalitional aggression. These are: the collective action problem of coordinated violence; parochial altruism; attacker–defender asymmetries; leader– follower dynamics; and sex differences in the costs and benefits of violence. Fourth, I speculate on the historical emergence of modern human warfare. I do not use ‘coalitional aggression’ and ‘warfare’ interchangeably. Instead, evolved psychological adaptations for small-scale coalitional aggression are what make the emergence of largescale human warfare possible. Thus, in addition to the biological and evolutionary arguments necessary to establish the existence of adaptations for coalitional aggression, I conclude with a speculative discussion of the historical and cultural shifts that may help to explain the complex modern phenomenon of human warfare.
UNIVERSAL CONSTRAINTS ON THE EVOLVABILITY OF COALITIONAL VIOLENCE There are at least three necessary conditions that favor the emergence of lethal coalitional aggression in its broadest sense. First, the species’ ecology must be such that the organism is adapted for group-based interaction (Chapman, 1986; Chapman et al., 1995; Chapman and Chapman, 2000). Second, the species must possess neurocomputational machinery that allows it to solve at least a subset of a potentially infinite range of n-person collective action problems pertinent to coalitional aggression (Tooby and Cosmides, 1988; Tooby et al., 2006). This can range from relatively simple coordination problems, to more complex cooperation problems involving conspiracy, coercion, and alliance. For example, the existence of symbolic language is crucial for enabling complex and large-scale coalitional action (Wrangham, 2019). Third, opportunities for coalitional violence must exist that are sufficiently low-cost and/or beneficial – in
317
reproductive terms – to favor coalitional violence as a unique strategy relative to alternative fitness-enhancing strategies (Enquist and Leimar, 1990; Lopez, 2016a). The first two conditions being met (groupstructured population; coalitional psychology of coordination and cooperation) mean that a species likely possesses some of the psychological tools that can be used for coalitional aggression, but without the third condition, coalitional aggression is unlikely to occur via these tools alone. Similarly, the mere presence of low-cost/high-benefit opportunities for coalitional violence will not ipso facto lead a species to coalitional aggression if there is no group structure in the population, or if language and cognitive abilities to coordinate are limited or absent. For example, this simple difference may be one among many reasons that chimpanzees engage in an intense and lethal form of coalitional violence that is nevertheless limited in duration and complexity relative to humans. Although our ability to peer into the ancestral past is imperfect, the ancestral past is far from unknowable. Despite disagreement on the origins and prevalence of warfare, there is near universal agreement that the necessary conditions for coalitional violence existed among ancestral humans throughout the Holocene, Pleistocene, and perhaps earlier to a common ancestor with chimpanzees. I briefly discuss the evidence for each of the three necessary conditions. First, although there is disagreement on the size and structure of early human forager bands, there is broad agreement that humans associated in groups, that these groups ranged in size from 25 to several hundred individuals (depending on distinctions between bands, tribes, societies, ethnolinguistic units, etc.), and that these groups included a substantial number of kin as well as non-kin (Hill et al., 2011; Bird et al., 2019). Group structure is unequivocally a component of our species’ long evolutionary history. Second, there is broad evidence that humans are instinctively good at solving
318
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
coordination and cooperation problems in both dyadic and n-person contexts (Tooby et al., 2006). Additionally, language and symbolic reasoning in humans are such that we are able to build cultural institutions that interact with motivated reasoning to either enhance or limit group- and individual-level dynamics (Boyer and Petersen, 2011). It should come as no surprise, therefore, that political institutions often focus on the nature and expression of authority (Smith et al., 2007) and the distribution of resources (Petersen, 2012) – two recurrent and important challenges faced by all groups. In short, we have evolved in groups, and we are well-adapted for navigating the many recurrent and reproductively significant challenges associated with this coalitional landscape. Third, opportunities for low-cost/highbenefit coalitional violence must exist. There are at least three foundational components that determine the cost profile of coalitional violence in almost any setting. First is the proximity of out-groups. The more geographically distal groups are, the more quickly the costs of coalitional violence accumulate in terms of effort and coordination. Second, targets must reliably exist that are vulnerable to low-cost attack. Third, their injury or death must entail, either directly or indirectly, some fitness benefit to the attacker(s). In chimpanzees, for example, group structure and feeding habits result in occasions of lone travelers who can be ambushed and killed, and the reproductive benefits of such an attack, when delivered with overwhelming force of numbers, are substantial (e.g., see Wrangham, 1999; Wilson et al., 2014). Similarly, in humans, relatively frail bodies (i.e. in comparison to chimpanzees) combined with historical innovation in lethal weaponry and conspiratorial ability have turned humans into ‘quintessential first-strike creatures’ (Gat, 2006). Furthermore, it is not uncommon for inter-group raids to entail significant reproductive benefits as well (Glowacki and Wrangham, 2015). In short, low-cost/highbenefit opportunities for human coalitional violence have long existed.
These three universal constraint conditions on the evolution of coalitional violence have been met in humans. However, the presence of these three conditions still does not tell us much about the specific form that coalitional violence will take in any species, and neither does it allow us to make many inferences about downstream or related considerations, such as the possibility of cultural evolution or the existence of sex differences in fighting. Rather, it gives us a universal cross-species framework for conceptualizing the necessary phenotypic ‘starting point’ of coalitional violence. In order to provide a richer explanation of the form and function of coalitional violence observed in a given species, we must not only ask whether the three conditions mentioned above existed ancestrally; we must also uncover species-specific details regarding demographic and socio-ecological variables that influence the form and function of coalitional violence such as group size and composition, fission–fusion dynamics, mating structure, parental-investment dynamics, and the nature and distribution of opportunities for violence between groups. It is to this evidence that I now turn.
EVIDENCE OF ANCESTRAL HUMAN COALITIONAL VIOLENCE Given the above, the logical next steps are to trace the practice of coalitional violence in humans, i.e. when did it emerge, what did it look like, and how has it changed over time? I address the first two questions in this section, and the final question in the next section.
Emergence of Coalitional Violence Scholarship on the evolutionary origins of warfare is bifurcated in two traditions that Allen refers to as the long chronology and short chronology of warfare (Allen and Jones, 2014). The short chronology views
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND WARFARE
human warfare as having emerged by or shortly after the agricultural revolution at the start of the Holocene, and in response to new social and ecological pressures relating to sedentarism and the accumulation of wealth (Otterbein, 1997; Kelly, 2000; Fry, 2007; Fry and Söderberg, 2013). Prior to this period, humans likely engaged in sporadic violent encounters, but most occurred within kin groups rather than between them and rarely involved anything more complex than the targeted killing of single individuals. In contrast, the long chronology accepts the chimpanzee model of low-cost/high-benefit opportunistic coalitional killing as perhaps the most basic form of warfare, upon which humans slowly and over time built greater complexity. In other words, we have been engaging in coalitional violence at least since the split with chimpanzees (Wrangham, 1999; Gat, 2006; McDonald et al., 2012; Lopez, 2016b; Glowacki et al., 2017). Both short and long chronologies recognize that developments in the early Holocene brought significant changes to human inter-group violence, but whereas the short chronology sees this as the beginning of ‘warfare’ per se, the long chronology sees it as a period of significant transition in the scale and complexity of warfare (Keeley, 1996; Lopez, 2019a). This dispute is not so much regarding what humans ‘were actually doing’ in the Pleistocene; rather, the more contentious issues hinge on whether various activities should be labeled ‘warfare’. Therefore, the question ‘when did warfare begin?’ is somewhat indeterminate to the extent that it rests on arbitrary definitional assumptions, and should be engaged with methodological caution.
Forms of Ancestral Coalitional Violence Both chronologies of war recognize that raiding has been and remains the oldest and commonest form of human inter-group violence (Keeley, 1996; Otterbein, 2004; Gat, 2006).
319
Raids – sometimes called stealth raids – display particular characteristics: occurring by stealth and/or at night; exploiting cover/ concealment; targeting one or a few lone unsuspecting individuals by surprise/ambush; quick retreat; exploiting numerical asymmetries (e.g., at least 3:1 force imbalance); overwhelmingly initiated by males; overwhelmingly targeting out-group males. Raids are designed to maximize effect relative to the expected risks, principally via numerical imbalance and the element of surprise. Humans are indeed ‘first-strike creatures’; however, in the context of lethal weaponry and symbolic language that facilitates coordinated revenge, human raiding is relatively riskier than chimpanzee raiding and may be ‘scaffolded’ to some extent by cultural institutions that incentivize some forms of intergroup or otherwise ‘heroic’ violence and sacrifice (Wrangham and Glowacki, 2012; Glowacki and Wrangham, 2013). Prior to the Holocene, direct evidence that humans engaged in anything other than coalitional raiding is patchy at best. Despite occasional findings of mass graves from as early as the end of the Pleistocene (Lahr et al., 2016), there is neither direct nor indirect evidence that, for example, humans assembled in more than a handful of individuals at a time for the purpose of relatively symmetric melee coalitional aggression. In other words, ‘battles’ – in contrast to raids – are relatively recent and rare in both the ethnographic and archaeological record, and with no analogue in chimpanzee behavior.
AN EVOLVED PSYCHOLOGY OF COALITIONAL VIOLENCE? The universal conditions for the evolution of coalitional violence are satisfied in humans, and we also know that ancestral humans engaged in at least some forms of inter-group violence (e.g., raids and possibly battles). Combined with incomplete but rich available
320
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
information regarding the ancestral coalitional landscapes in which humans lived, it is possible to identify several overlapping and interconnected classes of adaptive problems that existed, and these problems seem to underlie all instances of coalitional violence to a variable degree. These are: the collective action problem of coordinated violence; parochial altruism; attacker–defender asymmetries; leader–follower dynamics; and sex differences in the costs and benefits of violence.
The Collective Action Problem of Coordinated Violence Despite significant disagreement regarding the origins and frequency of warfare in our species’ history, most agree that at the heart of the puzzle of warfare lies a within-group collective action problem (Kitchen and Beehner, 2007; Crofoot and Gilby, 2012; Pietraszewski, 2016; Glowacki et al., 2017; Lopez, 2019b; Wiessner, 2019). Large, complex, sedentary societies are often able to solve these problems through the use of coercive institutions, while relatively smaller nomadic societies tend to solve these problems via the implicit or explicit distribution of material rewards or the leveraging of personal reputation and status. Any agonistic contest entails risks to the participants such as injury or retaliation, and species that engage in such contests must possess evolved systems that regulate an individual’s participation in such contests, such as whether to engage, escalate, submit, or run away (Parker, 1974; Sell, 2011; Chapin et al., 2019). The problem is magnified among coalitions, where assessments of the likelihood of success are compounded by assessments of the feasibility and strength of within-group coordination and cooperation. It is probably no surprise again, that the most common form of human coalitional violence is the raid; it is a form of low-cost violence that can be initiated with a small group of
motivated individuals and concludes quickly, minimizing what would be an otherwise challenging problem of n-person tracking that is difficult for even modern militaries to master and sustain (Biddle, 2006). At a basic level, the initiation of any act of coalitional violence requires a solution to the near-simultaneous problems of individual commitment as well as inter-personal efforts to manipulate the behavior and commitment of within-group others (Tooby and Cosmides, 1988; Lopez, 2017, 2019b). These are problems of participation and enforcement: should I participate? (How) should I manipulate the behavior of others toward (or away from) participation? Again, although modern societies solve these problems with coercive institutions, these problems were solved by our ancestors via the mechanisms of individual formidability and interest. This helps to explain why the commonest form of human coalitional violence is that of small, unstable, fraternal coalitions that sporadically assemble to take advantage of offensive opportunities.
Parochial Altruism The conceptual core of parochial altruism is simple, yet its simplicity betrays what has become a complex and contentious area of study. In its simplest form, parochial altruism refers to a class of motivations and behavior in which one pays a cost to benefit at least some members of one’s own group at the direct or indirect expense of at least some members of an out-group. For example, lab and field evidence over many decades suggest that the mere presence of inter-group competition (violent or otherwise) is often sufficient to trigger many forms of withingroup cooperation, sacrifice, and altruism (Puurtinen and Mappes, 2009; Gneezy and Fessler, 2011; Bauer et al., 2016; Chang et al., 2016; but see also Jordan et al., 2017). In the extreme, this is taken as evidence that inter-group competition in our species’
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND WARFARE
evolutionary history is directly responsible for our remarkable capacity for large-scale cooperation, even among strangers. At the very least, it suggests that the two processes (in-group favoritism and out-group derogation) may have co-evolved to some degree (Choi and Bowles, 2007; Bowles, 2009). However, it has been demonstrated that the desire to harm an out-group is often motivated by individual-level incentives (e.g., personal status, reputation, privatized material resources), and it has also been demonstrated that in-group favoritism does not necessarily also trigger out-group hate (Patton, 2005; Gavrilets and Fortunato, 2014; Rusch, 2014; Weisel and Böhm, 2015; Romano et al., 2017; Do˘gan et al., 2018). Therefore, the evidently tight linkage between inter-group competition and within-group cooperation that lies at the center of parochial altruism is conditional at best and likely engages a range of individual-level and group-level incentives depending on the immediate context. For example, individuals may be driven more by group-level benefits in domains of defense, while driven more by individual-level benefits in domains of offense (Rusch, 2013; Lopez, 2017). An adaptationist perspective on coalitional violence, therefore, provides us with a lens through which to examine the interplay between strategic context (e.g., defense/offense) and individual differences pertaining to capability (i.e. formidability, or resource-holding potential) or interest. This leads to the next two major domains of research: attacker/defender asymmetries and leadership.
Attacker–Defender Asymmetries Coalitional violence can be defined as the attempt by a group of individuals to physically damage at least one individual of another group. Unless the individuals of opposed groups are sitting immediately beside each other, any attack upon an outgroup must minimally endure the costs of
321
travel through time and space. This initial obligate cost necessarily establishes an asymmetrical structure to the cost–benefit profile of attacking versus defending, as well as alternative strategies (e.g., to run/disperse). For example, although much emphasis is rightly given to the fact that attackers can exploit surprise and relative numbers if appropriate targets are chosen, attackers also endure significant costs of coordination, motivation, and target retaliation, in addition to the obligate costs mentioned above. In contrast, defenders can exploit resident advantages such as superior knowledge of local terrain and may often find it easier to solve coordination problems. Mirville et al., for example, find that ‘large groups may be unsuccessful in inter-group conflict if they enter a smaller group’s home range, as the smaller group may respond with more aggression to defend the area’ (2018: 178). It is no surprise, therefore, that De Dreu and Gross (2018) find that, on average, across many contexts, defenders have a greater success rate than attackers, which must be at least partly due to this initial obligate asymmetry. Buckner and Glowacki (2019), however, usefully point out that attackers have the advantage of ‘setting the stage of conflict’, which stacks the odds of success in attackers’ favor. It is clear that when attackers can assemble for brief incursions to catch defenders offbalance and unaware, the result is a low-cost/ high-benefit effort that can be strongly favored by selection. As mentioned above, Gat (2006) extends this analysis by arguing that, given the relatively weak physique of humans combined with the use of weaponry in coalitional violence, humans evolved to be ‘quintessential first-strike creatures’. To the extent this is true, then in the language of international relations theory, ancestral humans may have evolved in an ‘offense-dominant’ environment, in which the costs of defending were greater than the costs of attacking (Jervis, 1978; Biddle, 2001). Despite the fact that this ‘offense–defense’ balance has shifted numerous times since
322
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
the Pleistocene, Gat argues that the gamble of inter-group violence was probably stacked in favor of well-organized attackers – as Buckner and Glowacki (2019) agree – which is perhaps best characterized by the wellknown adage that the best defense is a good offense. Attacker–defender asymmetries are probably more obvious and relevant in raiding contexts or contexts of small-scale conflict than in larger battle contexts. Furthermore, in raiding contexts, defenders face a publicgood problem, in which the benefits of success are general to the group, while attackers face a club-good problem, in which the benefits of success are more privatized among the attackers themselves. These attacker– defender asymmetries help to clarify the set of unique problems that must be resolved in each domain in order for either attack or defense to be successful (Lopez, 2017). There are clearly group-level macro variables that impinge upon outcomes, especially relative numbers. However, the successful prosecution of attack and defense invariably depends on group members being able to effectively manage and navigate a constellation of interindividual dynamics (Tooby and Cosmides, 1988; Tooby et al., 2006; Pietraszewski, 2016; Wiessner, 2019). Individuals must solve a range of domain-specific collective action problems specific to warfare, the solutions to which are conditional upon, inter alia, whether individuals are initiating or responding to an attack.
Leader–Follower Dynamics Leaders – whether formal or informal – are not intrinsically necessary for solving collective action problems; however, their presence has been demonstrated to facilitate success in inter-group contexts. Although ancestral human societies are believed to be relatively egalitarian, these groups are also marked by asymmetries of influence and status that shape motivation and behavior (von Rueden,
2020). Thus, although the pattern of lethal violence in hunter-gatherers is characterized by relatively leaderless raiding parties organized in the absence of overt coercive manipulation, this is better described as the absence of formal leadership, in which behavior is instead informally motivated by reputation and reciprocity. In short, the ancestral characterization of ‘leaderless’ societies understates the importance of relative influence and status as constraints and facilitators of collective action (Boehm, 1999, 2012). Leaders can help resolve coordination problems (e.g., Where to meet? When to leave?) as well as resolve and enforce more complicated problems pertaining to the distribution of costs and benefits of aggression. By definition, highly formidable individuals have both a greater capacity to punish and to reward, as well as a greater incentive for attack in many cases. Therefore, highly formidable individuals are also more likely to resort to deception to recalibrate otherwise unmotivated minds. For example, when a formidable individual identifies a window of opportunity for attack, yet willing others are immediately unavailable, the initiator can resort to the direct manipulation of costs and benefits, or resort to an indirect manipulation of the strategic context. Direct manipulation of cost and benefit is clear: leaders are often those who, by definition, are most able to distribute such costs and benefits. However, initiators may also manipulate others’ beliefs about the nature of aggression, recasting opportunistic aggression as defensive or preemptive necessity (Lopez, 2019b). It has been well-established that individuals are often more willing to fight for defense than for offense (Böhm et al., 2016); if this asymmetry extended to ancestral environments, the result is a motivated bias among strongly incentivized initiators (i.e. leaders; highly formidable individuals) to falsely cast opportunism as necessity. Coalitional violence is not just a story of manipulation by the powerful; in fact, leaders can provide a valuable public good in
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND WARFARE
the prosecution of inter-group competition (van Vugt and Kurzban, 2007; Hooper et al., 2010; Glowacki and von Rueden, 2015). Thus, research has found that individuals seem to prefer dominant or masculine leaders in times of inter-group violence, precisely because there is an implicit understanding that these individuals, in these contexts, are able to provide a unique service. This has led to a growing field of research demonstrating that facial and vocal cues are implicitly used by individuals to assess leadership in specific contexts (Anderson and Klofstad, 2012; Klofstad et al., 2012; Spisak, 2012; Spisak et al., 2012; Laustsen and Petersen, 2017). In short, despite a relatively egalitarian group structure, individual variance in both formidability and interest allowed our ancestors to facilitate coalitional violence when necessary or beneficial.
Sex Differences in the Costs and Benefits of Coalitional Violence The overall pattern of human violence at both the individual and group levels is that of male physical violence (van Vugt, 2009; McDonald et al., 2012). Cross-culturally, males are significantly more likely to be both the perpetrators and targets of physical violence (Daly and Wilson, 1988). Even in modern contexts, for example, in which it has been observed that greater numbers of women are engaged in acts of suicide terrorism, the overall numbers are skewed toward overwhelmingly male involvement (Goldstein, 2003). Participation in physical violence should be distinguished from support for violence. Evidence of greater male aggressiveness is strongest on indicators of physical acts of violence, and weaker on indicators of indirect or informal support, particularly in defensive contexts, in which all benefit from victory due to its public-good nature (Ginges and Atran, 2011; Lopez, 2017). Thus, it is little surprise that Fair and Shepherd (2006)
323
find that female support for terrorism is not only on the rise in several Arab countries, but that in many instances it equals male support for terrorism in these contexts. In other words, violence, as the adaptive output of evolved psychological mechanisms, is irrevocably conditional, and the structure of that conditionality depends in part on sex. While male participation in coalitional violence is likely highly personalized, physical, and motived to seek opportunistic gains at low cost, female participation is likely indirect, greater in defensive contexts, and when immediate resources are at stake (resources, territory, children) rather than when surrogate resources are at stake, such as status and honor, although these remain somewhat open questions (Glowacki and Wrangham, 2013; Scalise Sugiyama, 2014; Lopez, 2017; Lynch et al., 2019). Greater male physical aggressiveness in humans is directly predicted by sexual selection and parental investment theory, in which sex differences in physical aggression follow asymmetries in parental investment (Trivers, 1972; Daly and Wilson, 1983). Furthermore, these theoretical foundations have been well elaborated by research on several established mechanisms of sexual selection, such as contest competition, in which same-sex competitors are excluded from mating through force, and mate choice, in which the possession of traits (e.g., intelligence, formidability, wealth) enhances one’s attractiveness toward members of the opposite sex (Puts, 2016; Hill et al., 2017).
BEYOND THE MILITARY HORIZON: THE EMERGENCE OF WARFARE Humans possess the three universal criteria for the evolution of coalitional violence, and a cursory review of the human pattern of ancestral violence, alongside a sketch of the adaptive problems this has generated (e.g., collective action problems, attacker–defender
324
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
asymmetries) suggests that humans likely possess specialized psychological design for navigating the challenges of coalitional violence. What this means is that we possess the psychological tools for reasoning about and engaging in small-scale coalitional violence. However, what we observe today arguably bears little resemblance to the behaviors our ancestors engaged in. The real question often reduces to: are the differences between ancestral and modern ‘warfare’ differences in degree or kind? These questions probably cannot be answered in a general sense. In some arenas, notably lethal weaponry, modern warfare is a faint shadow of its ancestral forms. However, in terms of certain principles of engagement, such as cover/concealment, the element of surprise, force-imbalance ratios, rally ‘round the flag effects, attacker–defender asymmetries, and many others, modern warfare often still follows a fundamentally ancestral logic, even if it is now manifested at much greater scales (Keeley, 1996; Lopez, 2016b, 2019a). Guerrilla warfare, insurgency, and hybrid warfare follow kinetic principles of violence that would likely be intuitive to any hunter-gatherer (Boot, 2013). This suggests that the real question regarding the emergence of human warfare from smaller-scale versions is probably not evolutionary so much as historical. In other words, once the psychological tools of coalitional violence were in place, significant changes in demographics and ecology would have been sufficient to trigger both qualitative and quantitative innovations in the scale and method of coalitional violence, such that at some ambiguous and relatively arbitrary point in history, what we once recognized as coalitional violence looks more and more like modern warfare. How did this happen? The answer to this question forces at least a brief return to an earlier question, that of the origins of warfare. Recall that the longchronology perspective argues that warfare is evolutionarily old and merely ‘transitions’
after the emergence of agriculture, while the short-chronology perspective argues that this transition is in fact an origin. Aside from the relatively arbitrary issue of what difference there is between an origin and a transition, a more productive question is: what ecological and social shifts were occurring at this time, and how did this affect the nature of intergroup conflict? The first thing to note about the emergence of agriculture and its effects on inter-group violence is that it does not occur everywhere at the same time, and therefore neither does ‘warfare’. Otterbein, for example, while sitting somewhere between the long- and shortchronology perspectives, argues that an older form of human warfare predates agriculture, and emerges as a by-product of hunting. As big game became scarce, so too did the practice of warfare, which then disappeared until social innovations occurring after the transition to agriculture made the practice of warfare profitable again. For Otterbein, warfare could not have occurred simultaneously with the emergence of agriculture, since: ‘For agriculture and permanent settlements to arise, there must be no warfare’ (Otterbein, 2004: 13). Innovations in agriculture require peace, and somewhat ironically, the fruits of agriculture make war again possible and profitable. In direct contrast, however, Ferrill argues instead that it was warfare that drove the need for agriculture. Innovations in weaponry that occurred around 10,000 BC, such as bows and slings, increased the need for defenses, such as fortified walls, and the resultant decline in mobility meant there was pressure to find new ways to live off the land (Ferrill, 1997). This obvious chicken-or-egg problem remains unresolved, but what is clear is that where agriculture emerged, it tended to have clear impacts upon the political economy of human groups, which included the possibility of, and in some cases a perceived imperative for, what might be labeled ‘modern warfare’. Relatively sedentary groups practicing agriculture were larger, accumulated more
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND WARFARE
wealth, were more effective at command, control, and logistics, and were more efficient innovators. Gabriel, similar to Otterbein, argues that although this transition is underway after the transition to agriculture, intergroup violence does not begin to look like ‘modern warfare’ until about 4,000–2,000 BC, by which time population centers, social and economic organization, lethal weaponry, and institutional command coalesce to produce a form of warfare that is often associated with nation states – those that exhibit steep vertical command structures, are characterized by sizeable armies that exploit column and line formations, and are capable of greater levels of destruction (Gabriel, 2002). In other words, it is around this time that the raid, as the predominant or even exclusive form of inter-group violence, now shares the stage with (or in many cases is upstaged by) conventional battle between formal political organizations. As Levy and Thompson describe, this transition begins in Mesopotamia and Egypt, followed later by transitions in Greece, Rome, and China, during which: ‘Weapons became much more lethal, military organizations became larger and more complex, and states became more powerful’ (Levy and Thompson, 2011: 122)1. In addition to these first two transitions, Levy and Thompson identify a third transition occurring within the last five centuries. Two trends that stand out during this period include a decreasing frequency of great power warfare alongside a pernicious increase in the lethality of warfare (Gat, 2006; Levy and Thompson, 2011; Pinker, 2011). The particularities of this transition and the innovations and security imperatives that in part drove it are outside the scope of this inquiry; it is sufficient to note that this long history of the ever-unfolding nature of warfare is pithily summed up with Tilly’s famous assertion that ‘war made the state, and the state made war’ (Tilly, 1975: 42). This ironic, even if tragic, connection between expanding zones of political
325
cooperation and the steady intensification of warfare is brought to a head in the current era, in which great powers are restrained in their conflicts with each other, and new forms of violence have largely taken the place of inter-state violence. In this sense, we are witnessing a reemergence of small-scale violence – a renaissance of the raid. This feature is now characteristic of many forms of modern political violence. When great powers do engage in violence, it often takes the form of so-called ‘limited wars’, in which quick incursions are meant to target key individuals, groups, or facilities in order to degrade or deter an adversary, often a nonstate actor (Osgood, 1957; Stoker, 2016). When nation states are the targets of violence, the source may be a terrorist network or a nation state engaging in ‘hybrid warfare’ in which states bring to bear a motley range of tools, such as propaganda, cyber instruments, and targeted assassinations, in order to effect outcomes short of war (Hoffman, 2007). Lastly, the most common form of political violence is now civil war and insurgency (Lopez and Johnson, 2017), which, again, often bears the ancestral hallmarks of many raiding dynamics (Boot, 2013). In short, the raid, having fallen from prominence over two thousand years ago, is now returning to center stage in our species’ long evolution of warfare.
UNIVERSALITY, UNIQUENESS, AND CHANGE: WAR AS A WINDOW INTO HUMAN NATURE Perhaps it is the author’s conceit, but there is hardly any domain outside of warfare that singularly unites so much about what makes us human – from our ugliest desires to our noblest sacrifices. The study of warfare is necessarily a tour through many if not all of the big questions of human nature and the nature of human psychology. Many of these questions are not investigated here, and some
326
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
that are remain nevertheless unresolved. However, one lesson that does emerge from this analysis is that humans are social by design, and at least part of this design facilitates aggression between groups. Evolution is a process of change, and natural selection is a force that explains one kind of change: directional change in gene frequencies that can build complex adaptations over time. The human mind is proposed to consist, in part, of complex adaptations designed to facilitate the navigation of the natural world (which includes the social world) in a way that would have maximized reproductive success in ancestral environments. In other words, these complex adaptations are relatively slow to change, which means that many of the evolved systems that emerged to solve ancestral problems remain active today, ‘trying’ to make sense of a modern world that is a shadow of its ancestral self. However, as Ridley (2003: 7) notes, ‘difference is the shadow of similarity’. Thus, some of the most promising avenues for current research on the evolutionary psychology of war deal with puzzles such as reconciling the universal presence of the psychological tools of violence with variation in their expression across space and time, explaining why the preponderance of coalitional violence is still carried out by men, explaining why humans can sometimes be led to levels of violent self-sacrifice that appear to contradict the possibility of any fitness benefits, and correcting past blind spots in research that has focused on Western subjects and data. All of these puzzles are tractable and indeed benefit from and require an evolutionary lens as we untangle the sordid knot of human coalitional violence and warfare.
Note 1 This is an admittedly brief summary of a masterful and complex summary provided by Levy and Thompson. Interested readers are encouraged to engage the reading directly, while for my purposes here, a bird’s-eye view is sufficient.
REFERENCES Allen, Mark W., and Terry L. Jones, Eds. 2014. Violence and Warfare among Hunter- Gatherers. Walnut Creek, California: Routledge. Anderson, Rindy C., and Casey A. Klofstad. 2012. ‘Preference for Leaders with Masculine Voices Holds in the Case of Feminine Leadership Roles’. PLOS ONE 7 (12): e51216. https://doi. org/10.1371/journal.pone.0051216. Bauer, Michal, Christopher Blattman, Julie Chytilová, Joseph Henrich, Edward Miguel, and Tamar Mitts. 2016. ‘Can War Foster Cooperation?’ Journal of Economic Perspectives 30 (3): 249–74. https://doi. org/10.1257/jep.30.3.249. Biddle, Stephen. 2001. ‘Rebuilding the Foundations of Offense-Defense Theory’. Journal of Politics 63 (3): 741–4. https://doi. org/10.1111/0022-3816.00086. ———. 2006. Military Power: Explaining Victory and Defeat in Modern Battle. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. Bird, Douglas W., Rebecca Bliege Bird, Brian F. Codding, and David W. Zeanah. 2019. ‘Variability in the Organization and Size of Hunter-Gatherer Groups: Foragers Do Not Live in Small-Scale Societies’. Journal of Human Evolution 131 (June): 96–108. https:// doi.org/10.1016/j.jhevol.2019.03.005. Boehm, Christopher. 1999. Hierarchy in the Forest: The Evolution of Egalitarian Behavior. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. ———. 2012. ‘Ancestral Hierarchy and Conflict’. Science 336 (6083): 844–7. https:// doi.org/10.1126/science.1219961. Böhm, Robert, Hannes Rusch, and Özgür Gürerk. 2016. ‘What Makes People Go to War? Defensive Intentions Motivate Retaliatory and Preemptive Intergroup Aggression’. Evolution and Human Behavior 37 (1): 29–34. https://doi. org/10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2015.06.005. Boot, Max. 2013. ‘The Evolution of Irregular War’. Foreign Affairs, March 1, 2013. www. foreignaffairs.com/articles/2013-02-05/ evolution-irregular-war Bowles, Samuel. 2009. ‘Did Warfare Among Ancestral Hunter-Gatherers Affect the Evolution of Human Social Behaviors?’ Science 324 (5932): 1293–8. https://doi. org/10.1126/science.1168112.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND WARFARE
Boyer, Pascal, and Michael Bang Petersen. 2011. ‘The Naturalness of (Many) Social Institutions: Evolved Cognition as Their Foundation’. Journal of Institutional Economics FirstView: 1–25. Buckner, William, and Luke Glowacki. 2019. ‘Reasons to Strike First’. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 42, 17–18. https://doi.org/10.1017/ s0140525x19000840. Chang, Linda W., Amy R. Krosch, and Mina Cikara. 2016. ‘Effects of Intergroup Threat on Mind, Brain, and Behavior’. Current Opinion in Psychology, Intergroup relations, 11 (October): 69–73. https://doi.org/10.1016/ j.copsyc.2016.06.004. Chapin, Kenneth James, Paulo Enrique Cardoso Peixoto, and Mark Briffa. 2019. ‘Further Mismeasures of Animal Contests: A New Framework for Assessment Strategies’. Behavioral Ecology 30 (5): 1177–85. https:// doi.org/10.1093/beheco/arz081. Chapman, Colin, A. 1986. ‘Ecological Constraints on Group-Size for 3 Species of Neotropical Primates’. American Journal of Primatology 10 (4): 394. Chapman, Colin A., and Lauren J. Chapman. 2000. ‘Constraints on Group Size in Red Colobus and Red-Tailed Guenons: Examining the Generality of the Ecological Constraints Model’. International Journal of Primatology 21 (4): 565–85. Chapman, C. A., R. W. Wrangham, and L. J. Chapman. 1995. ‘Ecological Constraints on Group-Size – an Analysis of Spider Monkey and Chimpanzee Subgroups’. Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology 36 (1): 59–70. Choi, Jung-Kyoo, and Samuel Bowles. 2007. ‘The Coevolution of Parochial Altruism and War’. Science 318 (5850): 636–40. https:// doi.org/10.1126/science.1144237. Crofoot, Margaret Chatham, and Ian C. Gilby. 2012. ‘Cheating Monkeys Undermine Group Strength in Enemy Territory’. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 109 (2): 501–5. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1115937109. Daly, Martin, and Margo Wilson. 1983. Sex, Evolution, and Behavior. Boston, Massachusetts: Willard Grant Press. ———. 1988. Homicide. New York: A. de Gruyter. De Dreu, Carsten K. W., and Jörg Gross. 2018. ‘Revisiting the Form and Function of Conflict:
327
Neurobiological, Psychological, and Cultural Mechanisms for Attack and Defense within and between Groups’. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 42: e116. https://doi.org/ 10.1017/S0140525X18002170. Do˘gan, Gönül, Luke Glowacki, and Hannes Rusch. 2018. ‘Spoils Division Rules Shape Aggression between Natural Groups’. Nature Human Behaviour 2 (5): 322–6. https://doi. org/10.1038/s41562-018-0338-z. Enquist, Magnus, and Olof Leimar. 1990. ‘The Evolution of Fatal Fighting’. Animal Behaviour 39 (1): 1–9. https://doi.org/10.1016/S00033472(05)80721-3. Fair, C. Christine, and Bryan Shepherd. 2006. ‘Who Supports Terrorism? Evidence from Fourteen Muslim Countries’. Studies in Conflict & Terrorism 29 (1): 51–74. https:// doi.org/10.1080/10576100500351318. Ferrill, Arther. 1997. The Origins Of War: From The Stone Age To Alexander The Great, Revised Edition. 1st edition. Boulder, Colorado: Westview Press. Fry, Douglas P. 2007. Beyond War: The Human Potential for Peace. 1st edition. New York: NY: Oxford University Press. Fry, Douglas P., and Patrik Söderberg. 2013. ‘Lethal Aggression in Mobile Forager Bands and Implications for the Origins of War’. Science 341 (6143): 270–3. https://doi. org/10.1126/science.1235675. Gabriel, Richard A. 2002. The Great Armies of Antiquity: Westport, Connecticut: Praeger. Gat, Azar. 2006. War in Human Civlization. Oxford: Oxford University Press. www.loc. gov/catdir/toc/ecip0614/2006017223.html Gavrilets, Sergey, and Laura Fortunato. 2014. ‘A Solution to the Collective Action Problem in Between-Group Conflict with WithinGroup Inequality’. Nature Communications 5 (March): 3526. https://doi.org/10.1038/ ncomms4526. Ginges, Jeremy, and Scott Atran. 2011. ‘War as a Moral Imperative (Not Just Practical Politics by Other Means)’. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 278 (1720): 2930–8. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb. 2010.2384. Glowacki, Luke, and Christopher von Rueden. 2015. ‘Leadership Solves Collective Action Problems in Small-Scale Societies’. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal
328
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Society B: Biological Sciences 370 (1683). https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2015.0010. Glowacki, Luke, Michael L. Wilson, and Richard W. Wrangham. 2017. ‘The Evolutionary Anthropology of War’. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, January. https:// doi.org/10.1016/j.jebo.2017.09.014. Glowacki, Luke, and Richard W. Wrangham. 2013. ‘The Role of Rewards in Motivating Participation in Simple Warfare’. Human Nature 24 (4): 444–60. https://doi.org/ 10.1007/s12110-013-9178-8. Glowacki, Luke, and Richard Wrangham. 2015. ‘Warfare and Reproductive Success in a Tribal Population’. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 112 (2): 348–53. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1412287112. Gneezy, Ayelet, and Daniel M. T. Fessler. 2011. ‘Conflict, Sticks and Carrots: War Increases Prosocial Punishments and Rewards’. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 279, 219–223. June. https://doi. org/10.1098/rspb.2011.0805. Goldstein, Joshua S. 2003. War and Gender: How Gender Shapes the War System and Vice Versa. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hill, Alex, Drew H. Bailey, and David A. Puts. 2017. ‘Gorillas in Our Midst? Human Sexual Dimorphism and Contest Competition in Men’. In Michel Tibayrenc and Francisco J. Ayala (Eds) On Human Nature: Biology, Psychology, Ethics, Politics, and Religion, 235–49. Academic Press. Hill, Kim R., Robert S. Walker, Miran Božičević, James Eder, Thomas Headland, Barry Hewlett, A. Magdalena Hurtado, Frank Marlowe, Polly Wiessner, and Brian Wood. 2011. ‘Co-Residence Patterns in HunterGatherer Societies Show Unique Human Social Structure’. Science 331 (6022): 1286–9. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1199071. Hoffman, Frank. 2007. Conflict in the 21st Century: The Rise of Hybrid Wars. Arlington, Virginia: Potomac Institute for Policy Studies. Hooper, Paul L., Hillard S. Kaplan, and James L. Boone. 2010. ‘A Theory of Leadership in Human Cooperative Groups’. Journal of Theoretical Biology 265 (4): 633–46. https:// doi.org/10.1016/j.jtbi.2010.05.034. Jervis, Robert. 1978. ‘Cooperation under the Security Dilemma’. World Politics 30 (2): 167–214. https://doi.org/10.2307/2009958.
Jordan, Matthew R., Jillian J. Jordan, and David G. Rand. 2017. ‘No Unique Effect of Intergroup Competition on Cooperation: Non-Competitive Thresholds Are as Effective as Competitions between Groups for Increasing Human Cooperative Behavior’. Evolution and Human Behavior 38 (1): 102–8. https://doi.org/10.1016/ j.evolhumbehav.2016.07.005. Keeley, Lawrence H. 1996. War before Civilization: The Myth of the Peaceful Savage. New York: Oxford University Press. www.loc.gov/ catdir/enhancements/fy0638/94008998-d.html Kelly, Raymond C. 2000. Warless Societies and the Origin of War. Ann Arbor, Michigan: University of Michigan Press. Kitchen, Dawn M., and Jacinta C. Beehner. 2007. ‘Factors Affecting Individual Participation in Group-Level Aggression among Non-Human Primates’. Behaviour 144 (12): 1551–81. Klofstad, Casey A., Rindy C. Anderson, and Susan Peters. 2012. ‘Sounds like a Winner: Voice Pitch Influences Perception of Leadership Capacity in Both Men and Women’. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences 279 (1738): 2698–2704. https://doi. org/10.1098/rspb.2012.0311. Lahr, Marta. Mirazón., Rivera, Frances., Power, R. K., Mounier, Aurelien., Copsey, B., Crivellaro, F., Edung, J.E., Maillo Fernandez, J.M.,… Foley RA. 2016. ‘Inter-Group Violence among Early Holocene Hunter-Gatherers of West Turkana, Kenya’. Nature 529 (7586): 394–8. https://doi.org/10.1038/nature16477. Laustsen, Lasse, and Michael Bang Petersen. 2017. ‘Perceived Conflict and Leader Dominance: Individual and Contextual Factors Behind Preferences for Dominant Leaders’. Political Psychology 38 (6): 1083–1101. https://doi.org/10.1111/pops.12403. Levy, Jack S., and William R. Thompson. 2011. The Arc of War: Origins, Escalation, and Transformation. Chicago, Illinois: University Of Chicago Press. Lopez, Anthony C. 2016a. ‘Conditions Required for Evolution of Warfare Adaptations’. In Encyclopedia of Evolutionary Psychological Science, edited by Viviana WeekesShackelford, Todd K. Shackelford, and Viviana A. Weekes-Shackelford, 1–10. Cham: Springer International Publishing. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-169996_914-1.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND WARFARE
———. 2016b. ‘The Evolution of War: Theory and Controversy’. International Theory 8 (1): 97–139. https://doi.org/10.1017/S17529719 15000184. ———. 2017. ‘The Evolutionary Psychology of War: Offense and Defense in the Adapted Mind’. Evolutionary Psychology 15 (4): 1474704917742720. https://doi.org/10.1177/ 1474704917742720. ———. 2019a. ‘The Evolution of War’. In Carol Ann Ireland, Jane Louise Ireland, Michael Lewis, and Anthony C. Lopez (Eds) International Handbook of Collective Violence, edited by Carol Ann Ireland, Jane Louise Ireland, Michael Lewis, and Anthony C. Lopez. 3–16. New York, NY: Routledge Press. ———. 2019b. ‘Making “My” Problem “Our” Problem: Warfare as Collective Action, and the Role of Leader Manipulation’. The Leadership Quarterly, 31(2) May. https://doi.org/10.1016/ j.leaqua.2019.05.001. Lopez, Anthony C., and Dominic D. P. Johnson. 2017. ‘The Determinants of War in International Relations’. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, October. https://doi. org/10.1016/j.jebo.2017.09.010. Lynch, Robert, Virpi Lummaa, and John Loehr. 2019. ‘Self Sacrifice and Kin Psychology in War: Threats to Family Predict Decisions to Volunteer for a Women’s Paramilitary Organization’. Evolution and Human Behavior. 40 (6) 543–50. June. https://doi.org/10.1016/ j.evolhumbehav.2019.06.001. McDonald, Melissa M., Carlos David Navarrete, and Mark Van Vugt. 2012. ‘Evolution and the Psychology of Intergroup Conflict: The Male Warrior Hypothesis’. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 367 (1589): 670–9. https://doi.org/10.1098/ rstb.2011.0301. Mirville, Melanie O., Amanda R. Ridley, Jean Pierre Mucyo Samedi. Samedi, Veronica Vecellio, Felix Ndagijimana, Tara S. Stoinski, and Cyril C. Grueter. 2018. ‘Low Familiarity and Similar “Group Strength” between Opponents Increase the Intensity of Intergroup Interactions in Mountain Gorillas (Gorilla Beringei Beringei)’. Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology 72 (11): 178. https:// doi.org/10.1007/s00265-018-2592-5. Osgood, Robert E. 1957. Limited War: The Challenge to American Strategy. 5th edition. Chicago, Illinois: University of Chicago Press.
329
Otterbein, Keith F. 1997. ‘The Origins of War’. Critical Review 11 (2): 251–77. ———. 2004. How War Began. 1st edition. Texas, US: TAMU Press. Parker, Geoff. 1974. ‘Assessment Strategy and the Evolution of Fighting Behaviour’. Journal of Theoretical Biology 47 (1): 223–43. Patton, John Q. 2005. ‘Meat Sharing for Coalitional Support’. Evolution and Human Behavior 26 (2): 137–57. https://doi.org/ 10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2004.08.008. Petersen, Michael Bang. 2012. ‘Social Welfare as Small-Scale Help: Evolutionary Psychology and the Deservingness Heuristic’. American Journal of Political Science 56 (1): 1–16. https://doi. org/10.1111/j.1540-5907.2011.00545.x. Pietraszewski, David. 2016. ‘How the Mind Sees Coalitional and Group Conflict: The Evolutionary Invariances of n-Person Conflict Dynamics’. Evolution and Human Behavior 37 (6).470–80. https://doi.org/10.1016/j. evolhumbehav.2016.04.006. Pinker, Steven. 2011. The Better Angels of Our Nature: Why Violence Has Declined. Johannesburg, SA: Viking Adult. Puts, David. 2016. ‘Human Sexual Selection’. Current Opinion in Psychology 7 (February): 28–32. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.copsyc. 2015.07.011. Puurtinen, Mikael, and Tapio Mappes. 2009. ‘Between-Group Competition and Human Cooperation’. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 276 (1655): 355–60. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2008.1060. Ridley, Matt. 2003. The Agile Gene: How Nature Turns on Nurture. Reprint edition. New York: Harper Perennial. Romano, Angelo, Daniel Balliet, Toshio Yamagishi, and James H. Liu. 2017. ‘Parochial Trust and Cooperation across 17 Societies’. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 114 (48): 12702–7. https://doi. org/10.1073/pnas.1712921114. Rueden, Chris von. 2020. ‘Making and Unmaking Egalitarianism in Small-Scale Human Societies’. Current Opinion in Psychology, Power, Status and Hierarchy, 33 (June): 167–71. https://doi.org/10.1016/j. copsyc.2019.07.037. Rusch, Hannes. 2013. ‘Asymmetries in Altruistic Behavior during Violent Intergroup Conflict’. Evolutionary Psychology: An International
330
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Journal of Evolutionary Approaches to Psychology and Behavior 11 (5): 973–93. ———. 2014. ‘The Evolutionary Interplay of Intergroup Conflict and Altruism in Humans: A Review of Parochial Altruism Theory and Prospects for Its Extension’. Proceedings. Biological Sciences 281 (1794): 20141539. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2014.1539. Scalise Sugiyama, Michelle. 2014. ‘Fitness Costs of Warfare for Women’. Human Nature 25 (4): 476–95. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12110014-9216-1. Sell, Aaron N. 2011. ‘The Recalibrational Theory and Violent Anger’. Aggression and Violent Behavior 16 (5): 381–9. https://doi.org/ 10.1016/j.avb.2011.04.013. Smith, Kevin B., Christopher W. Larimer, Levente Littvay, and John R. Hibbing. 2007. ‘Evolutionary Theory and Political Leadership: Why Certain People Do Not Trust Decision Makers’. The Journal of Politics 69 (2): 285–99. https://doi. org/10.1111/j.1468-2508.2007.00532.x. Spisak, Brian R. 2012. ‘The General Age of Leadership: Older-Looking Presidential Candidates Win Elections during War’. PLoS ONE 7 (5): e36945. https://doi.org/10.1371/ journal.pone.0036945. Spisak, Brian R., Astrid C. Homan, Allen Grabo, and Mark Van Vugt. 2012. ‘Facing the Situation: Testing a Biosocial Contingency Model of Leadership in Intergroup Relations Using Masculine and Feminine Faces’. The Leadership Quarterly 23 (2): 273–80. Stoker, Donald. 2016. ‘Everything You Think You Know About Limited War Is Wrong’. War on the Rocks, December 22, 2016. h t t p s : / / w a ro n t h e ro c k s . c o m / 2 0 1 6 / 1 2 / everything-you-think-you-know-aboutlimited-war-is-wrong/. Tilly, Charles. 1975. The Formation of National States in Western Europe. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Tooby, John, and Leda Cosmides. 1988. ‘The Evolution of War and Its Cognitive Foundations’. Institute for Evolutionary Studies Technical Report 88–1. https://www. cep.ucsb.edu/papers/EvolutionofWar.pdf Tooby, John, Leda Cosmides, and Michael E. Price. 2006. ‘Cognitive Adaptations for N-Person Exchange: The Evolutionary Roots of
Organizational Behavior’. Managerial and Decision Economics 27 (2–3): 103–29. Trivers, Robert. 1972. ‘Parental Investment and Sexual Selection’. In Bernard Campbell (Eds) Sexual Selection and the Descent of Man. Chicago, IL: Aldine Publishing. van Vugt, Mark. 2009. ‘Sex Differences in Intergroup Competition, Aggression, and Warfare: The Male Warrior Hypothesis’. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 1167 (June): 124–34. https://doi.org/10.1111/ j.1749-6632.2009.04539.x. van Vugt, Mark, and Rob Kurzban. 2007. ‘Cognitive and Social Adaptations for Leadership and Followership: Evolutionary Game Theory and Group Dynamics’.” In Joseph P. Forgas, Martie G. Haselton, and William von Hippel (Eds) Evolution and the Social Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and Social Cognition, 229–43. New York: Psychology Press. Weisel, Ori, and Robert Böhm. 2015. ‘“Ingroup Love” and “Outgroup Hate” in Intergroup Conflict between Natural Groups’. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 60 (September): 110–20. https://doi.org/ 10.1016/j.jesp.2015.04.008. Wiessner, Polly. 2019. ‘Collective Action for War and for Peace: A Case Study among the Enga of Papua New Guinea’. Current Anthropology 60 (2): 224–44. https://doi. org/10.1086/702414. Wilson, Michael L., Christophe Boesch, Barbara Fruth, Takeshi Furuichi, Ian C. Gilby, Chie Hashimoto, Catherine L. Hobaiter, et al. 2014. ‘Lethal Aggression in Pan Is Better Explained by Adaptive Strategies than Human Impacts’. Nature 513 (7518): 414–17. https://doi. org/10.1038/nature13727. Wrangham, Richard. 1999. ‘Evolution of Coalitionary Killing’. Yearbook of Physical Anthropology 42: 1–30. ———. 2019. The Goodness Paradox: The Strange Relationship Between Virtue and Violence in Human Evolution. 1st edition. New York: Pantheon. Wrangham, Richard W., and Luke Glowacki. 2012. ‘Intergroup Aggression in Chimpanzees and War in Nomadic Hunter-Gatherers: Evaluating the Chimpanzee Model’. Human Nature. 23 (1): 5–29 March. https://doi.org/ 10.1007/s12110-012-9132-1.
PART 3
Applications to Technology, Communications, and the Future
This page intentionally left blank
17 Evolutionary Psychology and Artificial Intelligence: The Impact of Artificial Intelligence on Human Behaviour Holly Wilson, Paul Rauwolf, and Joanna J. Bryson
1 INTRODUCTION Artificial intelligence (AI) impacts our behaviour. Intelligence, whilst not in itself defining humanity, is one of our key characteristics, inextricably linked to everything from our implicit survival strategies to our explicit self-concepts. Intelligence is also integral to the social institutions on which contemporary existence depends. AI is a set of technologies that extend human intellectual capacities such as perception, action, categorisation and pattern recognition. Some systems, termed autonomous, may do all of these things at once without human intervention, though only after human or humaninstitutional inception. Determining the impact of AI is imperative for two reasons: for empowering us to adapt to and optimise our existence with AI; and for developing AI and AI policies which maximise benefit and minimise harm to our society. Due to the myriad definitions of AI, we begin by establishing what we mean by
the term, at least in the scope of this chapter. Intelligence is the capacity to do the right thing at the right time; thus artificial intelligence refers to non-living artefacts that demonstrate such capacities (Bryson, 2019). By this definition, AI has been prevalent for decades, albeit less advanced than at present, and not so apparent to the public eye. Present awareness of AI has been magnified by two different recent outcomes: first the sudden prevalence of anthropomorphic capacities such as conversational-speech recognition and generation, or automobile driving; and second the use of AI technology as part of a global assault on democracies, and through them key institutions to maintaining peace under the present global order, such as the EU and the North Atlantic Treaty Organization (NATO).1 We focus here on how behaviour is shaped by contemporary intelligent technology; first by our cultural understanding of AI, then by the technological reality of AI. Many of our drives and behaviours, such as tribalism, sex, and resource procurement, are sculpted
334
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
by thousands of years of evolution in disparate environments (Buss and Schmitt, 1993; Kramer and Ellison, 2010; McDonald et al., 2012). Therefore, in this chapter we explore from an evolutionary perspective how AI – ubiquitous in the modern world – impacts both individual and collective human behaviour. We put emphasis on the predictions from several published models that explain how information transmission facilitates intelligence between intelligent agents. We consider how these theories predict changes to individual and collective behaviour as the information transmission is magnified or its quality improved. We then compare, at least qualitatively, these predicted alterations to present societal trends. We finish with recommendations for guiding AI development and interaction to maximise adaptation, progression and overall benefit to the individual and society. More specifically, in Section 2 we initially tease apart the current actual impact of AI on society from the impact that our cultural narratives surrounding AI have. We consider the evolutionary mechanisms that maintain a stable society such as heterogeneity, flexibility and cooperation. Given that AI can constitute a prosthetic intelligence, we discuss the consequences of how it enhances our connectivity, coordination, equality, distribution of control and our ability to make predictions. We also give examples of how transparency of thoughts and behaviours may influence call-out culture, as well as behavioural manipulation with consideration of group dynamics and tribalism. In Section 3, we discuss how AI may exacerbate the societal problems created by inequality. We place focus on the vulnerability of human trust in Section 4. We consider the contexts in which blind trust in information is either adaptive or maladaptive in an age where the cost of information is decreasing. We then bring the focus back onto trust in AI, and how we can calibrate trust so as to avoid over-trust and mistrust adaptively, using transparency as a mechanism. Finally, in Section 5, we explore
the barriers to AI increasing accuracy in our perception by focusing on fake news. We consider the impact of information accuracy and the battles of individuals against false beliefs.
2 IMPACTS OF AI THUS FAR The narratives within a culture can have as much impact on behaviour as at least some objective realities (Hammack, 2008). For this reason, we begin by examining the current narrative surrounding AI. According to Social Representation Theory (SRT), when we encounter a new or unknown phenomenon, we construct a representation of it based on collective narratives and interpersonal communication (Moscovici, 1981, 2001). It seems clear that public gaps in understanding AI are often filled by fear-mongering entertainment shows like Black Mirror, magazine articles on the feats of Alpha Go, and propaganda from businesses (Elish and Boyd, 2018). Indeed, media exposure to science fiction has been found to predict fear of AI above and beyond demographic variables (Liang and Lee, 2017). Problematically, such representations assume AI with capacities far beyond the current feasibility – and in many cases, beyond the computationally tractable – instilling awe and fear (Bryson and Kime, 2011). An investigation of narratives surrounding the impact of AI revealed that the most common visions elicited anxiety (Cave et al., 2019). One such vision was that by becoming over-reliant on AI and machines, we will replace the need for humans in jobs, relationships and socialising. Emotional arousal increases the efficacy of information spread (Berger, 2011); this mechanism is posited to have evolved to transmit fitness-relevant information; i.e. information relevant to survival which can help organisms avoid dangers (Nairne et al., 2009) or direct resources within a population (Teste et al., 2009). Yet the adaptive benefits of this in contemporary cultures are questionable, now that the mechanism is known and
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE
manipulable. These narratives may distract from or obscure the real problems and utility of AI, resulting in sub-optimal allocation of energy and resources (Bryson and Kime, 2011; Elish and Boyd, 2018). In the next few sections, we discuss the mixture of benefits and potential problems we face with AI.
2.1 Flexibility, Cooperation, Coordination, Perception: Humanity’s Survival Mechanisms AI does present a new landscape for humanity – yet, despite popular rhetoric, this does not necessarily pose an existential threat (Gent, 2015; Müller and Bostrom, 2016). Throughout our evolutionary history, humans have succeeded in adapting to changing environments (Gilligan, 2007; Richerson et al., 2005). Machines, in contrast, are typically fragile and short lived. As such, dangerous machines or technology are unlikely to be allowed to persist in their damaging behaviour long enough to destroy humanity as a whole, although technologically mediated impacts such as climate change or hate crimes are already costing lives. Cooperation and flexibility by means of heterogeneity (diversity) are two mechanisms that enable adaptation, survival and progress in unstable, changing environments (Brown et al., 2011; Lahr, 2016; Smaldino et al., 2013). Here we discuss the impact of AI on human behaviour within the context of these two mechanisms. There are two core hypotheses as to the role our nervous systems evolved to fill: the sensory-motor view, to link senses to actions; and the action-shaping view, to coordinate the body’s micro acts into macro acts (GodfreySmith, 2017). These hypotheses are by no means exclusive of each other. Likewise, our development of AI, amongst other things, has greatly enhanced our abilities to sense, act and coordinate. Our society has become increasingly complex; we are connected world-wide, with perturbations in one part
335
of our global system impacting many others. AI can be considered as our prosthetic nervous system, a tool we have developed to selectively mediate the strength of edges between each node. As an example, we can deploy hardy robots to explore subterranean and underwater environments inaccessible to humans, acting and perceiving on our behalf (Siles and Walker, 2009), growing new edges of our agency. Machine learning (ML), the ability to learn to perceive and categorise patterns based on input data, also constitutes a prosthetic perception. With adequate computational resources, ML for example allows us to search across larger ranges of data than a human might otherwise be able to internalise, and to consider more candidate patterns. Enhanced perception, assuming accuracy, means a species has more knowledge with which to react better to events in its environment. This constitutes an increase in human collective intelligence (Eagle and Pentland, 2003).
2.2 AI Increases Connectivity Which Facilitates Coordination but Also Transparency An enhanced capacity for coordination also results from the increased connectivity that AI and Information and Communication Technologies (ICT) more generally facilitate. These technologies afford communication and coordination on a scale that human societies have never encountered before. This can be expected to have – and be having – myriad impacts on collective and individual behaviour, not all of which we have yet recognised (Bryson, 2015). Through increasing the number of individuals we can connect with, and decreasing temporal and spatial constraints on doing so, AI creates a capacity for highly agile cooperation. Cooperation and group-level investment as a whole is known to increase with capacity to communicate, because this capacity allows for the increased probability of discovering mutually beneficial equilibria (Roughgarden et al., 2006).
336
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
This cooperation may occur at historically large scales, but also at small scales, and with higher frequency of change in aggregation and direction. Social media platforms, for example, have facilitated mass organisation of not only protests but also disaster recovery which may not otherwise have been feasible (Gerbaudo, 2018; Starbird and Palen, 2011; Vieweg et al., 2010). Additionally, increased access to knowledge enables us to predict threats or more quickly become aware of disasters (Chavan and Khot, 2013). Connectivity also has the effect of increasing behaviour transparency. Social media pages reveal the ‘likes’, ‘dislikes’ and actions of a population. Problematically within this context, humans are often driven to take on characteristics of a group, and strive to behave according to group norms (Terry and Hogg, 1996), which may have a homogenising or polarising effect, particularly during periods when competition and identity politics are steep (McCarty et al., 2016). Before we were so connected via the digital world, the group norms we had access to were of far smaller scale. This facilitated diversity – a global heterogeneity of group norms. Now, our access to the large scale, combined with behaviour transparency, is widely believed to homogenise behaviours and preferences (Morris, 2002). This is true even without taking into account potential conformity induced by physical, political, or economic threats for unacceptable behaviour, which we discuss further below. However, the data created by our digital activity is also made transparent for use by the political and business, as well as the social, realms. This can have positive impacts as well, if it is used to, for example, provide better public services or ensure greater customer satisfaction.
2.3 AI Facilitates Behaviour Prediction and Manipulation Ordinary collectives such as companies use algorithms on big data sets to predict our
behaviour with increasing accuracy (Zuboff, 2015). This seems qualitatively different to our already adept prediction capacities: to navigate our social world, we use mental models of people to infer and predict the beliefs, actions and intentions of others (Bradford et al., 2015). This ability, alongside language (Smith, 2010), has been critical for facilitating our species’ large-scale social cooperation. However, AI has enhanced our ability to predict the individual and collective beyond past capabilities. This can aid us to better allocate our time and resources. For example, by anticipating that the number of people about to use a road is beyond capacity, a navigation app may direct a proportion of people along a different route, altering their behaviour advantageously for the collective. At an individual level, the ‘optimal’ level of sleep (Hao et al., 2013), exercise (Spring et al., 2013), socialising and nutrition (Franco et al., 2016) can be predicted then recommended. Unfortunately, businesses looking to maximise profits will tailor their product – or just monetising efforts related to their product – to the individual based on predictions. This can be with an incentive to reshape behaviour to make it even more easily predictable, or otherwise less expensive for the company, for example when insurance companies demand digital access to evidence of healthy living (Raber et al., 2019). This, whilst not explicitly detrimental to cooperation, may increase homogeneity and therefore reduce group advantages and societal robustness (Fisher, 1930; Shi et al., 2019). It also speaks to an additional issue with behaviour transparency: capacity for behavioural control. Both the aforementioned examples of collective and individual behaviour tweaking and recommendations indicate a shift in autonomy; it seems AI may be increasing collective agency but decreasing opportunity and drive for individual decision-making. In fact, a survey of 970 respondents revealed that a core concern surrounding AI technologies is the loss of human agency and input into decisions (Anderson et al., 2018).
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE
At one level, behavioural control may or may not shift to autonomous artificial agents, but either way at a higher level it shifts to the individuals or organisations who can monitor data and deploy any such agents. This enables execution of potentially regressive social policing, albeit some well-intentioned. Take for example, the rise of helicopter parenting (Lee et al., 2014), or AI-powered predictive policing systems (Meijer and Wessels, 2019). We do not claim such behaviour manipulation is unique to AI. There are varying views on whether manipulation techniques (not all of which necessarily use AI) are ethical, when used for example to promote health (Behavioural Insights Team, 2010) or reduce debt (Behavioural Insights Team, 2012). We see the sense in policies (such as that of the Institute of Electrical and Electronics Engineers (IEEE), 2019) recommending that behaviour manipulation may be ethical in contexts where all the following hold: it can be beneficial for the individual and/or society, transparency is provided as to the nature of the manipulation, and the subject or a responsible adult representative of the subject has consented. This (arguably, cf. Simkulet, 2019) leaves the individual some control over the decision, at least at a higher level. For example, clinicians, especially under cognitive load, can demonstrate bias towards ethnic-minority patients, resulting in sub-optimal interaction, diagnosis and treatment (Stone and Moskowitz, 2011). Evidence suggests that two tasks – perspective taking or categorising oneself to be in a shared group with the ethnic minority – can reduce bias. In this scenario, consented behavioural manipulation could involve an app-based intervention, where the clinician chooses to engage with a bias-reduction task prior to seeing the patient. This same public or semi-private – and sometimes implicit – communication of preferences can be used deliberately to determine the personality types of individuals, and also their voting inclinations (Gelman et al., 2016; Kosinski et al., 2013; Wu et al., 2015). Such
337
information has obvious applications for those interested in the outcomes of elections, which have apparently been deployed with some success. Such techniques were reportedly originally designed and deployed to break up terrorist networks in conflict regions in the Middle East. The technique consists of identifying like-minded individuals with minority opinions that are available locally or otherwise convenient to those doing the aggregating, then introducing these individuals to each other and encouraging their political participation (Piette, 2018). AI-powered search can produce the ‘coincidence’ of good numbers of like-minded individuals in one place, convincing them all that their position is secretly in the majority – a secret being kept by the political status quo which must therefore be attacked. Relatively simple AI allows the identification and coordination of such target individuals; ICT allows the application of such power from a distance and across borders. Without laws and technological enforcement for transparency, such manipulation may be done invisibly.
2.4 AI as Prosthetic Memory In the past, humans strove to both remember and to be remembered, yet the time and monetary cost of data retention were barriers to doing so. Now, however, these costs have reduced to the point where we no longer need to be picky about the quality of what we select to retain. This has its advantages and disadvantages. Biological brains forget (Kraemer and Golding, 1997). In humans, such a lack of pruning memories, inability to forget, or information overload can result in deficits in executive functioning, and an inability to escape past autobiographical memories (Parker et al., 2006). Using AI-driven techniques, even with surplus data, we can still successfully store, reorganise, classify and retrieve the relevant information we require from large data stores. However, this prosthetic memory of digital expression
338
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
of opinions and beliefs – whether political, religious or otherwise – combined with increased connectivity has resulted in, amongst other things, a resurgence of call-out culture and public shaming (Hess and Waller, 2014; Tucker, 2018; Webb et al., 2016). The urge to normalise groups by exiling or denouncing the credibility of individuals who diverge is a facet of tribalism prevalent throughout our history (Bechtel, 1991; Burns, 2003). Novel though with the AI landscape is the relative immortality of digital memory. The social costs (and benefits) to acting or thinking in diverging ways have increased; it is hard to be forgotten. Thus again, we are homogenised by our evolutionary urge to remain in the safety of the tribe. Mayer-Schönberger (2007) advocates finding an equilibrium: by giving data an expiry date after which it will automatically be deleted, we can maximise the benefits of a precise prosthetic memory, whilst preserving the right to be forgotten. However, such arbitrary truncation would also be an end to history, unless history were still retained in non-digital format. Even if exceptions were made for those considered public individuals, as is now the case for certain privacy laws, this could have an unintended effect of reducing social mobility, as those in situations of prominence, privileged with being knowable, would be more likely to garner further attention and opportunity. Historical data also has applications ranging from the social sciences to monitoring the impacts of government policies. In an era where behaviour modification might be practised by subterfuge, accurate historical data may be the only way to detect malicious actors working subtly over time. The rights to freedom of opinion and thought are enshrined in the Declaration on Human Rights (United Nations General Assembly, 1948), but without an option of perceivable expression such rights may be of limited value. There is substantial research being conducted in anonymisation, including for data extraction and analysis – whether this proves mathematically tractable remains to
be seen. Uncompromised cybersecurity of not only data storage but transmission would also be necessary for any digital records to have even a hope of remaining private. The claim that homogenisation is a side effect of AI may seem demonstrably false given the increase in identity politics and political polarisation. Coincidence is not necessarily causal, and even if there is a causal link, it may be difficult to untangle. Polarisation is known to be correlated with wealth inequality, and to have been so since before the advent of ICT and AI. Whether AI is presently contributing to inequality will be considered in the next section. But with respect to homogenisation, it is worth saying that both processes may well occur at the same time – rather than a plethora of perspectives, we may find strong forces towards conformity with one of a small number of tribes. Again, this is the opposite of what was anticipated with access to the Internet and cheap self-publication, and there is also evidence of societal fragmentation (Pentland, 2015).
3 AI AND INEQUALITY Whether or not we become more homogenous in our beliefs and opinions, inequality in access to resources and quality of life is increasing. We discuss here what is known about how inequality is driven, and consider the impact of AI and the consequences for the collective. First, it should be observed that globally inequality has been falling, an effect driven primarily by the very poorest. The World Bank reports more than a third of humanity moving out of extreme poverty since 1980 (Roser and Ortiz-Ospina, 2017), a shift that has been facilitated by ICT including AI, as populations have had more access to useful information such as weather predictions, fair prices and how to obtain government support. Further, efforts to communicate political and economic situations, and means to
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE
coordinate protest, are leading at least some governments in rich areas such as the member states of the Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development (OECD) to adopt policies that have been demonstrated to reduce inequality within populations by increasing wealth distribution. Nevertheless, an individual’s access to public goods such as schools, physical security, utilities and health depends to a large degree on their geographic identity. Access to ICT and AI is no exception (Robinson et al., 2015; Sujarwoto and Tampubolon, 2016), although it is also influenced by other factors such as age. As we globally become more dependent on such tools, the populations without access are exposed to higher risks of inequality. By moving towards equality of access to these technologies, individuals may have improved job opportunities and information in regard to the socioeconomic, political and cultural context in which they live. The increase in inequality may result in reduced social cohesion as it seems to be correlated to reductions in social mobility and increases in political polarisation (McCarty et al., 2016). ICT and AI may also reduce the sort of localised social cohesion that is critical to many forms of well-being and political engagement, by diverting social attention to others with shared interests in topics that are not geographically centred. In this, it continues and expands on trends of mass media known since the beginning of the information age with, for example, the advent of national newspapers (Perlman and Sprick Schuster, 2016). For a substantial fraction of our society, the time we spend engaging with others as real, physical equals is replaced with ever-moreengaging digital entertainment. Research shows that whilst some US teens felt digital technologies connected them with others, others felt it resulted in a lack of in-person contact in their lives (Anderson and Jiang, 2018). The interaction that would once have taken place in person is now conducted through technology. There is a danger that inequality produces an elite who no longer identify with
339
the majority of individuals (Atkinson, 2015). This can be the effect not only of lack of social mobility and understanding, but even of simple spatial segregation (Cassiers and Kesteloot, 2012). As discussed earlier, digital social media provides a ready platform for disinformation, including caricaturised and exaggerated distortions of others. An elite may also falsely assume that it can consolidate power by extracting wealth from its own neighbours and nearest contenders. However, inequality breeds instability as the whims of small coalitions or even individual actors are unpredictable (Scheidel, 2017). When greater collective action is required, solutions become more predictable and stable, ironically better ensuring the maintenance of rank order at the higher end of society. Power over a collective is not only an animal thrill, it is also a mechanism of security because it ensures more individuals are invested in a mutually beneficial outcome (Terkel, 1974). Trust is a factor in individuals collectively investing in mutually beneficial outcomes, yet not only does inequality breed distrust (Barone and Mocetti, 2016) but, even when trust is held, it is vulnerable to exploitation and damage to the individual. Again, there is no clear evidence to date, but rather active investigation, as to whether and in what ways AI may be affecting inequality. It seems evident that any technology that reduces the cost of distance will also facilitate inequality through no particular malfeasance but simply by allowing excellent businesses to dominate larger territories, and therefore market shares. In the case of some technologies now such as finance, media, pharmaceutical, aerospace, and of course digital, this is approaching the limit case of single corporations dominating markets globally. This same phenomenon may explain the similar surge in developed-world inequality witnessed in the late 19th and early 20th centuries (Atkinson, 2015; Bryson, 2019). As mentioned in Section 2, another concern is that AI may alter employment. Whilst the common concern is that ‘robots will take all the jobs’, this seems highly unlikely as ‘all the jobs’ is not defined. There is an infinite
340
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
number of ways we can better each other’s lives. People tend to employ each other when the economy is good, though this may be seen as tautological. But the advent of intelligent technology has been associated with an increase in demand for both highly skilled and very low-skilled and low-waged work, with a declining demand and therefore wages for the intermediate workers (Acemoglu and Autor, 2011). Acemoglu and Autor (2011) suggest that technology plays two roles in wages: in allowing all to be more productive, this somewhat increases the value of being highly skilled, but flattens any advantages of moderate skill as people become more exchangeable. Worryingly, recent decades seem to be dominated by the latter effect.
4 THE VULNERABILITY OF HUMAN TRUST Subjective evaluations of trustworthiness are deeply tied to how humans navigate the world. The likelihood of a monetary transaction is largely dependent on the trust a buyer has in a seller (Kim et al., 2008; Ponte et al., 2015). Trust in politicians affects voter turnout (Grönlund and Setälä, 2007) and electoral results (Hetherington, 1999). When evaluating a person’s face on multiple dimensions, subjective trustworthiness is one of the most predictive measures for overall evaluation (Oosterhof and Todorov, 2008). Further, once trustworthiness is perceived, it is relatively robust, persistently affecting behaviour (Delgado et al., 2005). If AI alters our capacity or predisposition to trust other humans, it will clearly have a deep impact on society.
4.1 Baseline Proclivities to Blindly Trust Using simple economic games, it has been shown that individuals will blindly trust a stranger even when it leaves them vulnerable (Berg et al., 1995). In a one-shot Trust Game (TG), an
investor is given some monetary windfall and must decide whether to keep the windfall, or give some fraction to a trustee. The fraction offered by the investor is then multiplied by some factor (typically three) and the trustee can then offer a fraction of the multiplied investment back to the investor. Human investors tend to blindly trust their partner by offering non-zero investments, even though it is in the trustee’s best interest to return nothing to the investor. Whilst trust is moderated by several factors, including framing effects (Burnham et al., 2000), geography (Johnson and Mislin, 2011), gender (Buchan et al., 2008), risk preferences (Fehr, 2009) and whether participants are selected from a student population (Johnson and Mislin, 2011), individuals consistently tend to blindly trust, investing some of their windfall (Johnson and Mislin, 2011). Significant research has sought to understand how blindly trusting others might be ecologically rational. This proclivity to trust has been explained as adaptive in relatively small populations where individuals have reputation cues of their partners (Boero et al., 2009; Masuda and Nakamura, 2012) or if the chance of knowing a partner’s strategy exceeds some threshold (Manapat and Rand, 2012; Manapat et al., 2013; McNamara et al., 2009; Rauwolf and Bryson, 2018). The common theme is that blindly trusting another can be adaptive if someone, somewhere, has a chance of having information about a player, including indirectly (e.g. if a population is known to share trust-related characteristics by some sort of contagion effect or enforcement). Interestingly, on the other hand, individuals will not trust others when they know the others are likely to return (reciprocate) an unfair amount in the TG, even if that amount would still make trusting them beneficial.
4.2 When Blind Trust Is Valuable Rauwolf and Bryson (2018) demonstrate a generally advantageous but unstable evolutionary dynamic that typically establishes
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE
trust. This demonstration is in the context of simulations with computational agents playing one-shot TGs with each other. Agents were given several potential partners for playing each game, and chose which agent to play, if any. As in the natural world, the investing agent knew the reputation for historic pay-off of some partners, but did not know the payoff of others – information was partially occluded. Each actor learned three things socially from the strongest players: their levels of trust in unknown players, the demanded level of reciprocation for known players, and their own reciprocation rate. Rauwolf and Bryson (2018) demonstrate that this simple dynamic is sufficient to generate trust between members of a population. When the known pay-offs of partners are sufficiently low, it can be in an agent’s interest to blindly select a partner whose history is unknown, provided that the population has evolved high enough levels of trust, which tends to coevolve with high levels of reciprocation, and of course assuming sufficient extra benefit from mutual development of the public good. In these cases, blind trust can be more valuable to the agent than walking away with their monetary windfall, trusting no one. On the other hand, trust will not evolve if the reciprocation rate of many players is known, because it becomes better to stick with the best-known available return rather than to take a chance with the unknown. The insight from this work is that a willingness to blindly trust others increases competition between others, lowering prices by increasing the reciprocation rate. It is wellknown that creating competition between sellers lowers prices. But, by being willing to trust those whose information is unknown, the pressure of competition is increased. Not only do sellers need to compete with other sellers whose information is known, they now need to compete with those whose information is unknown. This tends to lower the market price even further. This is related to work on outside options (André and Baumard, 2011). The value of a sale is contingent upon
341
the other options of a prospective buyer. If an individual is willing to go elsewhere, even by blindly trusting a stranger, then the market is forced to adjust and the buyer’s life is improved.
4.3 Information Cost Reduces Benefits of Trust Importantly, whilst the adaptive models of trust require that some information is available, trust fails if information is fully transparent (Manapat et al., 2013; Rauwolf and Bryson, 2018). By definition, the act of trusting another requires some uncertainty in the outcome (Yamagishi, 2011). If information is fully transparent, then there is no need to trust another; rather, each individual can make an informed decision. The consequence is that there is no selective pressure to evolve or learn the strategies and beliefs associated with the riskier behaviour, but these are what bind a local community together. We are currently living in an age where the cost of information is dramatically decreasing. As a result, the adaptive benefits of trust are becoming increasingly obsolete. This may be for the best – we may have a more predictable environment with even higher rewards for ‘good’ behaviour. However, we should also be concerned about this being another force for homogeneity, and further loss of individual capacity to deal creatively with localised crises. The institution of trust may be just a consequence of our inability to perfectly control our peers, but it may also serve an adaptive advantage by reducing our responsibility to do so. Society does not need to come up with plans to handle every contingency, because a desperate individual can always take advantage of the availability of trust without first seeking social approval of their plans. There are indications that in the near term moving from trust to full information is problematic in other ways. Because we will not just ‘shut off’ our historic psychological choice making, replacing trust with
342
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
information may mean that extant prejudices become more rigidly a part of our behaviour. Not only is trust deeply tied to how individuals make decisions, subjective trust is often biased and founded on unhelpful signals. People find attractive individuals more trustworthy (Wilson and Eckel, 2006). Individuals will invest more if a profile picture has a smiling face (Scharlemann et al., 2001) or is visually perceived as more trustworthy (Bente et al., 2012). The trust individuals place in profile information is often incorrect (Toma, 2010). More generally, individuals perform close to chance when predicting deception (Bond and DePaulo, 2006). Ert et al. (2016) show that perceived trustworthiness of an Airbnb option correlates more with the profile photo than the quantified reputation score of that option. This was confirmed by Fagerstrøm et al. (2017), who found that facial expressions in a renter’s photo predicted likelihood to rent more than customer ratings. This demonstrates that the transparency of information is not necessarily sufficient to improve behaviour. Individuals must make decisions using that information before it offers an advantage.
4.4 Calibrating Trust in AI There is considerable discussion these days about trust in AI and trustworthiness for AI. Our own work and that of many in the UK’s ethics community more generally has taken a different tack, emphasising that trust is an anthropocentric trait not truly useful for artefacts, where transparency and accountability are more desirable (Boden et al., 2011; Bryson and Theodorou, 2019). Improving transparency in AI reduces the need to trust AI. Yet it is possible that transparency does not affect the consumption of AI when the human consumer projects human-like identity to intelligent technology (anthropomorphises). By doing so, the consumer exposes themselves to exploitation as their established biases concerning the likelihood of trustworthiness are even easier to exploit via designed
artefacts than they are by unscrupulous individuals. For example, one might assume that a robot is unlikely to remember everything you say because a person or pet would not, but the robot may in fact not only recall but transmit its full memory – a full record of all interactions or even nearby events – storing these offsite in a corporate cloud. Although in theory the same digital and architected features of AI that make it more powerful as a manipulator should also make it easier to govern, presently (2020) manipulation is outstripping governance. Acceptance of AI can be increased in many ways, but given the vulnerability of the human trust system, care is needed to ensure trust is extended with consent, and is not exploited (IEEE, 2019). Whilst tapping into the vulnerabilities of how humanity perceives trustworthiness may be efficacious, it can also result in unwarranted trust. People are already found to perceive AI as more objective than human decision-makers, and in some cases to over-rely on AI. For example, in a legal setting, people demonstrated a preference to follow a machine advisor’s decision despite a human advisor having judgement of higher accuracy (Logg et al., 2019). In our own research (Wilson and Theodorou, 2019), we have found that in virtual reality (VR), AI actors presented to the participants as human agents were perceived to be significantly less deterministic than those presented explicitly as robots, despite both being controlled by the same AI system. It seems that many of us attribute properties to AI that do not exist, at least where that AI reminds us of humans (Sparrow, 2019). Some evidence suggests that anthropomorphising robots increases interaction with them (Waytz et al., 2014) via increased trust resistance (de Visser et al., 2016) and mind attribution. There are uncertainties as to the impact of anthropomorphism when robots are more prevalent and ‘normalised’ in our society. As we grow familiar with robots in our day-to-day lives, our mental models of robots may become more accurate (Bryson and Kime, 2011). We may perceive with more clarity the distinctions
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE
between artificially embodied cognition and humans, or commercial products may be mandated to provide transparency. In these cases, the impact of anthropomorphism may be reduced. Alternatively, viewing robots as human-like may become normalised, and social robotics – believed to be human-like, despite their inhuman, designed capacities – an embedded aspect of our lives. We suggest that a safer and more long-term stable approach is to work to increase AI transparency whilst simultaneously helping individuals learn to make choices using empirical information. As the information age reduces the need for trust, individuals need to be trained to operate in this information age, rather than reinforcing poor decision-making tendencies based on fallible and manipulable perceptions of trust. An example of increased AI transparency would be to have a QR code attached to each robot that when scanned gives information on the robot’s maker, purpose and capabilities. We have also been developing means for allowing users to see the current goals and strategies of a robot or other real-time interactive AI system (Rotsidis et al., 2019; Theodorou et al., 2017), and are presently experimenting to see whether this reduces the moral-hazard aspects of anthropomorphism. Whilst some may see viewing AI as human-like to be an example of a freedom of opinion or even association, we feel strongly that such opinions need to be informed where information is available, in order to avoid unknowing exploitation. Willing exploitation, like the manipulation of emotions that occurs during a motion picture or other work of fiction, is of course a perfectly acceptable part of life and entertainment. We only seek to avoid economic and political manipulation imposed on unknowing others.
5 BARRIERS TO ACCURATE PERCEPTION AND DEVELOPMENTS Our earlier metaphor for AI as an extension of our nervous system posited that new
343
AI tendrils enhance our ability to sense and perceive. Yet, problematically, the collective intelligence that could be garnered from this additional perception is hindered by two key barriers: the fact that data can be inaccurate and misleading, and our own inability to handle and interpret data. In this section we explore the origins, trajectory and impact of inaccurate information in human communication networks. We note our current inability to correctly deploy, infer and apply meaning from AI. We highlight current avenues for reducing these barriers in order to fully exploit our augmented collective intelligence.
5.1 ‘Fake News’ Humans have long expressed a desire to record and share information: the first encyclopaedia was written in AD 77 (Gudger, 1924); libraries have been dated back 2,000 years earlier. The arrival of the telegraph and Morse Code in 1835 enabled instantaneous transmission of knowledge across great distances (Burns, 1988); now databases are ubiquitous. Historical records indicate sharing knowledge spurred many innovations (Bessen and Nuvolari, 2016), and on a day-to-day basis, enables individuals to make informed decisions and actions. Unfortunately, not all shared information is accurate. Disinformation and misinformation, which often fall under the misnomer ‘fake news’, are of rising public concern. Disinformation implies intentional creation and sharing of manipulated or false information, whereas misinformation refers to inadvertent sharing (Lazer et al., 2018). Fake news is not new: since humans could speak, misinformation has spread via word of mouth. The spread increased and quickened with the arrival of newspapers and pamphlets, then with mass media such as television, finally exploding with the Internet and especially social media (Burkhardt, 2017). What is new is that, compared to past technological mediums, social media largely
344
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
lacks filtering, editorial judgement and factchecking (Allcott and Gentzkow, 2017). Further, the communication network is infiltrated by artificially intelligent bots, able to pass as or augment human users, which can be used to quickly deploy, share and spread information across networks (Machado and Konopacki, 2018). Such bots can be used to sway public opinion. In fact, disinformation affects stock prices (Carvalho et al., 2011), political opinions (Howard et al., 2018), and voting patterns (Allcott and Gentzkow, 2017) at least transiently. Evidence shows that accurate stories take longer to spread but have more purchase once spread (Vosoughi et al., 2018). In previous work (Mitchell et al., 2016), we have demonstrated that even error-prone ‘gossip’ can be a better strategy than direct experiential learning for acquiring true and useful information. The speed of information transmission such as is provided by social media can in some circumstances outweigh the costs of incorrect information, particularly if disinformation can be identified and quickly combated (Panagiotopoulos et al., 2014). Nevertheless, in at least some contexts, our species seems often to communicate inaccurate rather than accurate information. An analysis of a data set of rumour cascades on Twitter revealed fake news was 70% more likely to be retweeted than the truth (Vosoughi et al., 2018). There are suggestions that fake news is more likely to be novel, and novelty captures human attention. Perhaps worryingly, the average American spends 23.6 hours online weekly (Cole et al., 2017), and 62% get their news online (Gottfried and Shearer, 2016). Whilst there is evidence that our trust of such news has decreased, exposure alone may have negative impacts. Exposure can prime thinking and conversational topics. When any news enters the conversational sphere, trust in the information increases (Hajli et al., 2014). We humans seem to have a disposition to trust information communicated by word of mouth (Atika et al., 2018; Huete-Alcocer, 2017). Conversations require resources such
as time, cognition, and sometimes emotional investment. Actions occurring as consequence of conversations result in further deployment of resources. We know that, as a social species, we respond to such evidence of investment by others in our society (Zahavi, 1977). We posit that individual and collective resources may be consequently directed away from more accurate topics which are of perhaps more importance to our survival and flourishing.
5.2 The Impact of Information Accuracy In further work with simulations and formal analysis, we offered insight into the environments where humans may be vulnerable to utilising incorrect information (Rauwolf, 2016). Information requires both time and energy to gather. If information gathering comes at a non-trivial cost, then we would expect individuals to truncate their information search after a period of time (Simon, 1956). However, given continual improvements in technology, the cost of information is falling; as a result we might expect individuals to be better informed. Importantly though, even if information is easily obtained, if the processing of that information is costly, limiting information can be advantageous (Rauwolf and Jones, 2019). Rauwolf et al. (2015) show that when the benefits of group dynamics conflict with the accuracy of beliefs, false beliefs can become the least-costly option. Across a variety of contexts, individuals tend to prioritise relationships with those who share similar values – a trait called value-homophily (McPherson et al., 2001). We have demonstrated that it is in precisely these contexts where individuals can be expected to use incorrect information (Rauwolf et al., 2015). When the social value or benefit provided by the group outweighs the private cost of possessing incorrect information, it is advantageous for the individual to maintain (or at
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE
least act on) their false beliefs. Given that the inaccuracy of political and religious beliefs provides virtually no personal cost (Caplan, 2001), but group agreement may provide social value through security, we would expect humanity would struggle to remove false beliefs, particularly in times of resource scarcity and conflict (Stewart et al., 2020). As the benefits conferred by AI and technology at large continue to improve and secure individual basic needs, individuals will likely pay a reduced private cost for possessing incorrect information across a broadening array of contexts. Regardless of the accuracy of an individual’s beliefs, the basic needs of most individuals are improving. As such, if individuals pay small personal costs for false beliefs, but garner large social benefits for group homogeneity, then we would expect an expanding and resilient battle against false beliefs. Nevertheless, what costs an individual little in isolation may cost a society a great deal due to aggregate responses, particularly in a democracy (Chote et al., 2016; Lewis, 2017). Whether or not we should strive for increased rate of information transmission in every case (see the discussions of trust and freedom of opinion above), we should almost certainly prefer accurate communication, though here, too, inaccuracy can sometimes lead to useful innovation. Disinformation is a global and long-running issue, and there are global initiatives to combat it. For example, Facebook flags potential news stories to be reviewed by third-party fact checkers; and through the messaging system WeChat in China, users can report fake news, which is then checked and flagged. Crucial new initiatives introduce critical literacy into the education curriculum – training children to recognise and question information sources, particularly online (Vasu et al., 2018). Critical-thinking and fact-checking skills, as well as basic understanding of algorithm mechanics and their limitations, could enable the next generation to be better prepared to avoid such scenarios faced by us today (Guess et al., 2019).
345
Fact-checking can be as simple as conducting a Web search on a topic and its source.
6 CONCLUSION In this chapter we have discussed the impact of AI on contemporary societies. We took a perspective of understanding how the changing social and economic landscape induced by AI interacts with the human informationprocessing biases which evolved in very different environments. We consider a better understanding of these impacts imperative for our society going forward as we optimise our existence with AI, and for ensuring the AI and the regulations we design to govern its use both maximise benefit and minimise harm. We discussed the impact on both collective and individual human behaviour. Here we summarise the key foci of this chapter. First, the accuracy of narratives surrounding AI could critically impact optimal engagement with AI. Next, we compared AI to a prosthetic nervous system, which increases our perception and agency. AI also enhances our capacity to remember, coordinate, connect and communicate; this has many positive but also some negative outcomes. We considered the impact on freedom and diversity of opinion, political and economic impact, the mechanisms of information spread, and vulnerability of human trust and social coherence. The increased discoverability and predictability facilitated by AI requires serious consideration; there are myriad beneficial and harmful current applications of AI, and no doubt more of both to come. There are also of course many movements to ensure AI is beneficial to our society rather than harmful, though we did not take time to touch on those much here, we view such consideration and efforts as essential. Coordinating and enforcing such pro-social efforts has traditionally been called governance, and we hope this chapter may contribute to making sensible governance easier to both justify and employ constructively.
346
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Note 1 As of this writing, the impact of these assaults is still a matter of urgent research and debate, but the fact of significant, long-term, and on-going expenditure in the attempts has been established in both courts and academic writings (e.g. Machado and Konopacki, 2018; Woods, 2018; LandonMurray et al., 2019).
REFERENCES Acemoglu, D. and Autor, D. (2011). Skills, tasks and technologies: Implications for employment and earnings. In Ashenfelter, O. and Card, D. (Eds.), volume 4 of Handbook of Labor Economics, chapter 12, pages 1043– 1171. Amsterdam: Elsevier. Allcott, H. and Gentzkow, M. (2017). Social media and fake news in the 2016 election. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 31(2): 211–236. Anderson, J., Rainie, L., and Luchsinger, A. (2018). Artificial intelligence and the future of humans. Pew Research Center. Anderson, M. and Jiang, J. (2018). Teens, social media & technology 2018. Washington, DC: Pew Internet & American Life Project. Retrieved June 3, 2018, from https://www.pewresearch. org/internet/2018/05/31/teens-social-mediatechnology-2018/ André, J.-B. and Baumard, N. (2011). Social opportunities and the evolution of fairness. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 289:128–135. Atika, A., Kusumawati, A., and Iqbal, M. (2018). The effect of electronic word of mouth, message source credibility, information quality on brand image and purchase intention. EKUITAS (Jurnal Ekonomi dan Keuangan), 20(1):94–108. Atkinson, A. B. (2015). Inequality: What can be done? Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Barone, G. and Mocetti, S. (2016). Inequality and trust: New evidence from panel data. Economic Inquiry, 54(2):794–809. Bechtel, L. M. (1991). Shame as a sanction of social control in biblical Israel: Judicial, political, and social shaming. Journal for the Study of the Old Testament, 16(49):47–76.
Behavioural Insights Team (2010). Applying behavioural insight to health. Technical Report 403936/1210, Cabinet Office, UK Government, London. Behavioural Insights Team (2012). Applying behavioural insights to reduce fraud, error and debt. Technical Report 408779/0212, Cabinet Office, UK Government, London. Bente, G., Baptist, O., and Leuschner, H. (2012). To buy or not to buy: Influence of seller photos and reputation on buyer trust and purchase behavior. International Journal of Human-Computer Studies, 70(1):1–13. Berg, J., Dickhaut, J., and McCabe, K. (1995). Trust, reciprocity, and social history. Games and Economic Behavior, 10(1):122–142. Berger, J. (2011). Arousal increases social transmission of information. Psychological Science, 22(7):891–893. Bessen, J. and Nuvolari, A. (2016). Knowledge sharing among inventors: Some historical perspectives. In Harhoff, D. and Lakhani, K. (Eds.), Revolutionizing Innovation: Users, Communities, and Open Innovation, page 135. MIT Press, Cambridge MA. Boden, M., Bryson, J., Caldwell, D., Dautenhahn, K., Edwards, L., Kember, S., Newman, P., Parry, V., Pegman, G., Rodden, T., Sorell, T., Wallis, M., Whitby, B., and Winfield, A. (2011). Principles of robotics. The United Kingdom’s Engineering and Physical Sciences Research Council (EPSRC). Retrieved from https://epsrc. ukri.org/research/ourportfolio/themes/ engineering/activities/principlesofrobotics/ Boero, R., Bravo, G., Castellani, M., and Squazzoni, F. (2009). Reputational cues in repeated trust games. The Journal of Socio-Economics, 38(6):871–877. Bond, C. F. J. and DePaulo, B. M. (2006). Accuracy of deception judgments. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 10(3):214–234. Bradford, E. E., Jentzsch, I., and Gomez, J.-C. (2015). From self to social cognition: Theory of mind mechanisms and their relation to executive functioning. Cognition, 138:21–34. Brown, G. R., Dickins, T. E., Sear, R., and Laland, K. N. (2011). Evolutionary accounts of human behavioural diversity. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 366:313–324. Bryson, J. J. (2015). Artificial intelligence and pro-social behaviour. In Misselhorn, C.,
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE
editor, Collective Agency and Cooperation in Natural and Artificial Systems: Explanation, Implementation and Simulation, volume 122 of Philosophical Studies, pages 281–306. Berlin: Springer. Bryson, J. J. (2019). The past decade and future of AI’s impact on society. In Towards a New Enlightenment? In Cities, D (Eds.), A Transcendent Decade, pages 150–185. Madrid: Turner–BBVA. Bryson, J. J. and Kime, P. P. (2011). Just an artifact: Why machines are perceived as moral agents. In Proceedings of the 22nd International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence, pages 1641–1646, Barcelona. Morgan Kaufmann. Bryson, J. J. and Theodorou, A. (2019). How society can maintain human-centric artificial intelligence. In Toivonen-Noro, M. and Saari, E. (Eds.), Human-Centered Digitalization and Services, chapter 16, pages 305–323. Singapore: Springer. Buchan, N. R., Croson, R. T., and Solnick, S. (2008). Trust and gender: An examination of behavior and beliefs in the investment game. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 68(3):466–476. Burkhardt, J. M. (2017). History of fake news. Library Technology Reports, 53(8):5–9. Burnham, T., McCabe, K., and Smith, V. L. (2000). Friend-or-foe intentionality priming in an extensive form trust game. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 43(1):57–73. Burns, R. (1988). The electric telegraph and the development of picture telegraphy. In Papers Presented at the Sixteenth IEE Week-End Meeting on the History of Electrical Engineering, pages 80–86. IET. Burns, W. E. (2003). Witch hunts in Europe and America: An encyclopedia. Westport, CT: Greenwood Publishing Group. Buss, D. M. and Schmitt, D. P. (1993). Sexual strategies theory: An evolutionary perspective on human mating. Psychological Review, 100(2):204. Caplan, B. (2001). Rational ignorance versus rational irrationality. Kyklos, 54(1):3–26. Carvalho, C., Klagge, N., and Moench, E. (2011). The persistent effects of a false news shock. Journal of Empirical Finance, 18(4):597–615. Cassiers, T. and Kesteloot, C. (2012). Sociospatial inequalities and social cohesion in
347
European cities. Urban Studies, 49(9): 1909–1924. Cave, S., Coughlan, K., and Dihal, K. (2019). ‘Scary robots’: Examining public responses to AI. In Proceedings of the AIES. Retrieved May 24, 2020, from https://doi.org/10.1145/ 3306618.3314232 Chavan, S. and Khot, T. S. (2013). Efficient and reliable routing algorithm to enhance connectivity in disaster scenario: Abc algorithm. International Journal of Science and Research, 4(5):891–896. Chote, R., Nickell, S., and Parker, G. (2016). Economic and fiscal outlook. Technical Report Cm 9346, Office for Budget Responsibility, London, UK. Retrieved on 22 August, 2020 from www.gov.uk/government/publications. Cole, J., Suman, M., Schramm, P., and Zhou, L. (2017). The 2017 digital future report: Surveying the digital future. Los Angeles, CA: USC Annenberg School Center for the Digital Future. de Visser, E. J., Monfort, S. S., McKendrick, R., Smith, M. A., McKnight, P. E., Krueger, F., and Parasuraman, R. (2016). Almost human: Anthropomorphism increases trust resilience in cognitive agents. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Applied, 22(3):331. Delgado, M. R., Frank, R. H., and Phelps, E. A. (2005). Perceptions of moral character modulate the neural systems of reward during the trust game. Nature Neuroscience, 8(11):1611–1618. Eagle, N. and Pentland, A. S. (2003). Social network computing. In Dey, A. K., Schmidt, A., and McCarthy, J. F. (Eds.), UbiComp 2003: Ubiquitous Computing, pages 289–296, Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer Berlin Heidelberg. Elish, M. C. and Boyd, D. (2018). Situating methods in the magic of big data and AI. Communication Monographs, 85(1):57–80. Ert, E., Fleischer, A., and Magen, N. (2016). Trust and reputation in the sharing economy: The role of personal photos in Airbnb. Tourism Management, 55:62–73. Fagerstrøm, A., Pawar, S., Sigurdsson, V., Foxall, G. R., and de Soriano, M. Y. (2017). That personal profile image might jeopardize your rental opportunity! On the relative impact of the seller’s facial expressions upon buying behavior on AirbnbTM. Computers in Human Behavior, 72:123–131.
348
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Fehr, E. (2009). On the economics and biology of trust. Journal of the European Economic Association, 7(2–3):235–266. Fisher, R. A. (1930). The genetical theory of natural selection. Clarendon Press, Oxford (2nd edn., 1958, New York, Dover. Variorum edition, Bennett JH (Ed.), 1999, Oxford University Press). Franco, R. Z., Fallaize, R., Lovegrove, J. A., and Hwang, F. (2016). Popular nutrition-related mobile apps: A feature assessment. JMIR mHealth and uHealth, 4(3):e85. Gelman, A., Goel, S., Rivers, D., and Rothschild, D. (2016). The mythical swing voter. Quarterly Journal of Political Science, 11(1):103–130. Gent, E. (2015). Ai: Fears of ‘playing god’ [control & automation artificial intelligence]. Engineering & Technology, 10(2):76–79. Gerbaudo, P. (2018). Tweets and the streets: Social media and contemporary activism. London: Pluto Press. Gilligan, I. (2007). Neanderthal extinction and modern human behaviour: The role of climate change and clothing. World Archaeology, 39(4):499–514. Godfrey-Smith, P. (2017). Other minds: The octopus, the sea, and the deep origins of consciousness. New York, NY: Farrar, Straus and Giroux. Gottfried, J. and Shearer, E. (2016). News Use Across Social Medial Platforms 2016. Washington, DC: Pew Research Center. Retrieved 24 May, 2020 from http://www.journalism. org/2016/05/26/news-use-across-social-me dia-platforms-2016/. Grönlund, K. and Setälä, M. (2007). Political trust, satisfaction and voter turnout. Comparative European Politics, 5(4):400–422. Gudger, E. W. (1924). Pliny’s historia naturalis. The most popular natural history ever published. Isis, 6(3):269–281. Guess, A., Nagler, J., and Tucker, J. (2019). Less than you think: Prevalence and predictors of fake news dissemination on Facebook. Science Advances, 5(1), eaau4586. Hajli, N., Lin, X., Featherman, M., and Wang, Y. (2014). Social word of mouth: How trust develops in the market. International Journal of Market Research, 56(5):673–689. Hammack, P. L. (2008). Narrative and the cultural psychology of identity. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 12(3):222–247.
Hao, T., Xing, G., and Zhou, G. (2013). isleep: Unobtrusive sleep quality monitoring using smartphones. In Proceedings of the 11th ACM Conference on Embedded Networked Sensor Systems, page 4. ACM. Hess, K. and Waller, L. (2014). The digital pillory: Media shaming of ‘ordinary’ people for minor crimes. Continuum, 28(1):101–111. Hetherington, M. J. (1999). The effect of political trust on the presidential vote, 1968–96. American Political Science Review, 93(2):311–326. Howard, P. N., Kollanyi, B., Bradshaw, S., and Neudert, L.-M. (2018). Social media, news and political information during the US election: Was polarizing content concentrated in swing states? arXiv preprint arXiv:1802.03573. Huete-Alcocer, N. (2017). A literature review of word of mouth and electronic word of mouth: Implications for consumer behavior. Frontiers in Psychology, 8:1256. Institute of Electrical and Electronics Engineers (IEEE) (2019). Ethically aligned design: A vision for prioritizing human well-being with autonomous and intelligent systems. Technical report, The IEEE Global Initiative on Ethics of Autonomous and Intelligent Systems, first edition. Johnson, N. D. and Mislin, A. A. (2011). Trust games: A meta-analysis. Journal of Economic Psychology, 32(5):865–889. Kim, D. J., Ferrin, D. L., and Rao, H. R. (2008). A trust-based consumer decision-making model in electronic commerce: The role of trust, perceived risk, and their antecedents. Decision Support Systems, 44(2):544–564. Kosinski, M., Stillwell, D., and Graepel, T. (2013). Private traits and attributes are predictable from digital records of human behavior. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 110(15), 5802–5805. Kraemer, P. J. and Golding, J. M. (1997). Adaptive forgetting in animals. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 4(4):480–491. Kramer, K. L. and Ellison, P. T. (2010). Pooled energy budgets: Resituating human energy-allocation trade-offs. Evolutionary Anthropology: Issues, News, and Reviews, 19(4):136–147. Lahr, M. M. (2016). The shaping of human diversity: Filters, boundaries and transitions. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 371(1698):20150241.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE
Landon-Murray, M., Mujkic, E., and Nussbaum, B. (2019). Disinformation in contemporary US foreign policy: Impacts and ethics in an era of fake news, social media, and artificial intelligence. Public Integrity, 21(5):512–522. Lazer, D. M., Baum, M. A., Benkler, Y., Berinsky, A. J., Greenhill, K. M., Menczer, F., and Schudson, M. (2018). The science of fake news. Science, 359(6380):1094–1096. Lee, E., Bristow, J., Faircloth, C., and Macvarish, J. (2014). Parenting culture studies. London: Palgrave Macmillan. Lewis, M. (2017). Why the scariest nuclear threat may be coming from inside the White House. Vanity Fair. Retrieved 24 May, 2020, from https://www.vanityfair.com/news/2017/07/ department-of-energy-risks-michael-lewis. Liang, Y. and Lee, S. A. (2017). Fear of autonomous robots and artificial intelligence: Evidence from national representative data with probability sampling. International Journal of Social Robotics, 9(3):379–384. Logg, J. M., Minson, J. A., and Moore, D. A. (2019). Algorithm appreciation: People prefer algorithmic to human judgment. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 151:90–103. Machado, C. and Konopacki, M. (2018). Computational power: Automated use of WhatsApp in the Brazilian elections. Medium. Retrieved 24 May, 2020 from https://feed.itsrio.org/ computational-power-automated-use-ofwhatsapp-in-the-elections-59f62b857033. Manapat, M. L., Nowak, M. A., and Rand, D. G. (2013). Information, irrationality, and the evolution of trust. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 90:S57–S75. Manapat, M. L. and Rand, D. R. (2012). Delayed and inconsistent information and the evolution of trust. Dynamic Games and Applications, 2:401–410. Masuda, N. and Nakamura, M. (2012). Coevolution of trustful buyers and cooperative sellers in the trust game. PLoS One, 7(9):1–11. Mayer-Schönberger, V. (2007). Useful void: The art of forgetting in the age of ubiquitous computing, (Working Paper No. RWP07-022). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University. McCarty, N. M., Poole, K. T., and Rosenthal, H. (2016). Polarized America: The dance of ideology and unequal riches. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, second edition.
349
McDonald, M. M., Navarrete, C. D., and Van Vugt, M. (2012). Evolution and the psychology of intergroup conflict: The male warrior hypothesis. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 367(1589):670–679. McNamara, J. M., Stephens, P. A., Dall, S. R., and Houston, A. I. (2009). Evolution of trust and trustworthiness: Social awareness favours personality differences. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 276(1657):605–613. McPherson, M., Smith-Lovin, L., and Cook, J. M. (2001). Birds of a feather: Homophily in social networks. Annual Review of Sociology, 27(1):415–444. Meijer, A. and Wessels, M. (2019). Predictive policing: Review of benefits and drawbacks. International Journal of Public Administration, 42(12), 1031–1039. Mitchell, D., Bryson, J. J., Rauwolf, P., and Ingram, G. P. (2016). On the reliability of unreliable information: Gossip as cultural. Interaction Studies, 17(1), 1–18. Morris, N. (2002). The myth of unadulterated culture meets the threat of imported media. Media, Culture & Society, 24(2): 278–289. Moscovici, S. (1981). On social representations. In Forgas, J. (Ed.), Social cognition: Perspectives on everyday understanding, 8(12):181– 209, London: Academic Press. Moscovici, S. (2001). Why a theory of social representation? The representations of the Social. Bridging theoretical traditions. 8–37. Müller, V. C. and Bostrom, N. (2016). Future progress in artificial intelligence: A survey of expert opinion. In Müller, V. C. (Ed.), Fundamental Issues of Artificial Intelligence, pages 555–572. Berlin: Springer. Nairne, J. S., Pandeirada, J. N., Gregory, K. J., and Van Arsdall, J. E. (2009). Adaptive memory: Fitness relevance and the huntergatherer mind. Psychological Science, 20(6):740–746. Oosterhof, N. N. and Todorov, A. (2008). The functional basis of face evaluation. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 105(32):11087–11092. Panagiotopoulos, P., Bigdeli, A. Z., and Sams, S. (2014). Citizen–government collaboration on social media: The case of Twitter in the 2011
350
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
riots in England. Government Information Quarterly, 31(3):349–357. Parker, E. S., Cahill, L., and McGaugh, J. L. (2006). A case of unusual autobiographical remembering. Neurocase, 12(1):35–49. Pentland, A. (2015). Social physics: How social networks can make us smarter. New York, NY: Penguin. Perlman, E. R. and Sprick Schuster, S. (2016). Delivering the vote: The political effect of free mail delivery in early twentieth century America. The Journal of Economic History, 76(3):769–802. Piette, A. (2018). Muriel Spark and fake news. Textual Practice, 32(9):1577–1591. Ponte, E. B., Carvajal-Trujillo, E., and EscobarRodríguez, T. (2015). Influence of trust and perceived value on the intention to purchase travel online: Integrating the effects of assurance on trust antecedents. Tourism Management, 47:286–302. Raber, I., McCarthy, C. P., and Yeh, R. W. (2019). Health insurance and mobile health devices: Opportunities and concerns. Journal of the American Medical Association (JAMA), 321(18):1767–1768. Rauwolf, P. (2016). Understanding the ubiquity of self-deception: The evolutionary utility of incorrect information. PhD thesis, University of Bath. Rauwolf, P. and Bryson, J. J. (2018). Expectations of fairness and trust co-evolve in environments of partial information. Dynamic Games and Applications, 8(4):891–917. Rauwolf, P. and Jones, A. (2019). Exploring the utility of internal whistleblowing in healthcare via agent-based models. BMJ Open, 9(1). Rauwolf, P., Mitchell, D., and Bryson, J. J. (2015). Value homophily benefits cooperation but motivates employing incorrect social information. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 367:246–261. Richerson, P. J., Bettinger, R. L., and Boyd, R. (2005). Evolution on a restless planet: Were environmental variability and environmental change major drivers of human evolution. In Woketits, F. M. and Ayala, F. J. (Eds.), Handbook of Evolution, 2:223–242. Robinson, L., Cotten, S. R., Ono, H., QuanHaase, A., Mesch, G., Chen, W., Schulz, J., Hale, T. M., and Stern, M. J. (2015). Digital inequalities and why they matter.
Information, Communication & Society, 18(5):569–582. Roser, M. and Ortiz-Ospina, E. (2017). Global extreme poverty. Technical report, Our World in Data. Retrieved 24 December, 2019 from https://ourworldindata.org/extreme-poverty. Rotsidis, A., Theodorou, A., Bryson, J. J., and Wortham, R. H. (2019). Improving robot transparency: An investigation with mobile augmented reality. In 28th IEEE International Symposium on Robot and Human Interactive Communication (RO-MAN), New Delhi. IEEE. Roughgarden, J., Oishi, M., and Akçay, E. (2006). Reproductive social behavior: Cooperative games to replace sexual selection. Science, 311(5763):965–969. Scharlemann, J. P., Eckel, C. C., Kacelnik, A., and Wilson, R. K. (2001). The value of a smile: Game theory with a human face. Journal of Economic Psychology, 22(5):617–640. Scheidel, W. (2017). The great leveler: Violence and the history of inequality from the Stone Age to the twenty-first century. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Shi, F., Teplitskiy, M., Duede, E., and Evans, J. A. (2019). The wisdom of polarized crowds. Nature Human Behaviour, 3:329–336. Siles, I. and Walker, I. D. (2009). Design, construction, and testing of a new class of mobile robots for cave exploration. In Mechatronics, 2009. ICM 2009. IEEE International Conference on, pages 1–6. IEEE. Simkulet, W. (2019). Informed consent and nudging. Bioethics, 33(1):169–184. Simon, H. A. (1956). Rational choice and the structure of the environment. Psychological Review, 63(2):129–138. Smaldino, P. E., Newson, L., Schank, J. C., and Richerson, P. J. (2013). Simulating the evolution of the human family: Cooperative breeding increases in harsh environments. PLoS One, 8(11):e80753. Smith, E. A. (2010). Communication and collective action: Language and the evolution of human cooperation. Evolution and Human Behavior, 31(4):231–245. Sparrow, R. (2019). Robotics has a race problem. Science, Technology, & Human Values, 45(3), 538–560. Spring, B., Gotsis, M., Paiva, A., and SpruijtMetz, D. (2013). Healthy apps: Mobile devices
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE
for continuous monitoring and intervention. IEEE Pulse, 4(6):34. Starbird, K. and Palen, L. (2011). ‘Voluntweeters’: Self-organizing by digital volunteers in times of crisis. In Proceedings of the SIGCHI Conference on Human Factors in Computing Systems, CHI ‘11, pages 1071–1080, New York, NY. ACM. Stewart, A. J., McCarty, N., and Bryson, J. J. (2020). Polarization under rising inequality and economic decline. arXiv preprint arXiv: 1807.11477. Stone, J. and Moskowitz, G. B. (2011). Nonconscious bias in medical decision making: What can be done to reduce it? Medical Education, 45(8):768–776. Sujarwoto, S. and Tampubolon, G. (2016). Spatial inequality and the internet divide in Indonesia 2010–2012. Telecommunications Policy, 40(7):602–616. Terkel, S. (1974). Working. New York: The New Press. Terry, D. J. and Hogg, M. A. (1996). Group norms and the attitude-behavior relationship: A role for group identification. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 22(8):776–793. Teste, F. P., Simard, S. W., Durall, D. M., Guy, R. D., Jones, M. D., and Schoonmaker, A. L. (2009). Access to mycorrhizal networks and roots of trees: Importance for seedling survival and resource transfer. Ecology, 90(10): 2808–2822. Theodorou, A., Wortham, R. H., and Bryson, J. J. (2017). Designing and implementing transparency for real time inspection of autonomous robots. Connection Science, 29(3):230–241. Toma, C. L. (2010). Perceptions of trustworthiness online: The role of visual and textual information. In Proceedings of the 2010 ACM Conference on Computer Supported Cooperative Work, pages 13–22. ACM. Tucker, B. (2018). ‘That’s problematic’: Tracing the birth of call-out culture. Critical Reflections: A Student Journal on Contemporary Sociological Issues, 6. United Nations General Assembly (1948). Universal declaration of human rights. Technical report, New York. Vasu, N., Ang, B., Teo, T.-A., Jayakumar, S., Raizal, M., and Ahuja, J. (2018). Fake news: National security in the post-truth era. RSIS. In Policy Report. Singapore: Nanyang
351
Technological University. Retrieved 24 May, 2020, from https://www.rsis.edu.sg/wp- content/uploads/2018/01/PR180313_FakeNews_WEB.pdf Vieweg, S., Hughes, A. L., Starbird, K., and Palen, L. (2010). Microblogging during two natural hazards events: What Twitter may contribute to situational awareness. In Proceedings of the SIGCHI Conference on Human Factors in Computing Systems, CHI ‘10, pages 1079–1088, New York, NY. ACM. Vosoughi, S., Roy, D., and Aral, S. (2018). The spread of true and false news online. Science, 359(6380):1146–1151. Waytz, A., Heafner, J., and Epley, N. (2014). The mind in the machine: Anthropomorphism increases trust in an autonomous vehicle. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 52:113–117. Webb, H., Jirotka, M., Stahl, B. C., Housley, W., Edwards, A., Williams, M., Procter, R., Rana, O., and Burnap, P. (2016). Digital wildfires: Hyper-connectivity, havoc and a global ethos to govern social media. ACM SIGCAS Computers and Society, 45(3):193–201. Wilson, H. and Theodorou, A. (2019). Slam the brakes: Perceptions of moral decisions in driving dilemmas. In International Workshop in Artificial Intelligence Safety (AISafety), IJCAI, Macau. Wilson, R. K. and Eckel, C. C. (2006). Judging a book by its cover: Beauty and expectations in the trust game. Political Research Quarterly, 59(2):189–202. Woods, L. (2018). ICO reacts to use of data analytics in micro-targetting for political purposes reports: United Kingdom. European Data Protection Law Review (EDPL), 4:381–383. Wu, Y., Kosinski, M., and Stillwell, D. (2015). Computer-based personality judgments are more accurate than those made by humans. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 112(4):1036–1040. Yamagishi, T. (2011). Trust: The evolutionary game of mind and society. Berlin: Springer, Berlin. Zahavi, A. (1977). The testing of a bond. Animal Behaviour, 25:246–247. Zuboff, S. (2015). Big other: Surveillance capitalism and the prospects of an information civilization. Journal of Information Technology, 30(1):75–89.
18 Evolutionary Psychology and Robotics Robert Finkelstein
Evolutionary psychology can impact intelligent robots in two different ways: 1 The expression of evolutionary psychology in the human brain and emergent mind allows it to create intelligent robots, with some of their development focused on duplicating the neurophysiology of the human brain and the cognition of the human mind. As with many complex technologies in the past, it is uncertain whether human psychology will be sufficient to manage the consequences of its own invention. 2 The future expression of evolutionary psychology, albeit with a different theoretical framework, will affect the autonomous intelligent robot in the physical structure of its brain and the cognition of its mind.
ROBOT EVOLUTION: LAMARCK VS DARWIN Evolutionary psychology holds that Darwinian processes of natural selection apply to the brain, mind, and resulting psychological traits,
e.g., memory, perception, and language, just as they do to physiological traits (Buss, 2005). Darwinian evolution is a well-tested scientific theory that explains how organic complexity can arise from simplicity. Evolutionary psychology is expected to provide a basis for explaining the origin of the human brain, the most complex entity in the known universe (Aunger, 2002), its manifestation in the human mind, and the mind’s psychological phenomena. The process for the evolution of the autonomous intelligent robot, however, will be Lamarckian evolution and not Darwinian evolution. In biology, the discredited Lamarckian theory of evolution claims that when the environment changes the phenotype of an organism changes, such that the organism is better adapted to the environmental factor that caused the change (Hull, 2000), and the genotype can then pass the improved adaptation to the organism’s progeny (albeit, having died in 1829, Jean-Baptiste Lamarck knew nothing of genes or the genotype).
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ROBOTICS
Recent research has shown that for at least a few organisms, such as certain roundworms, pseudo-Lamarckian evolution seems to take place by passing to its progeny, independent of its genome, an individual’s acquired immunity to a virus (Rechavi, 2009). Technology is sometimes said to advance with Lamarckian evolution, rather than with Darwinian evolution, because of the high rate of technological change compared with the relative slowness of Darwinian evolution, and the ability of changes in one generation of a technology to be passed on to the next generation. However, technological change was not always this rapid for Homo sapiens and its ancestors; a flint-cutting tool might have taken thousands of years before manifesting some improvement. In any event, the principles of Lamarckian evolution with respect to technological evolution have been a metaphor, not the actual evolutionary process that was claimed to take place in an organism. In the future, however, it might indeed become the actual process for the evolution of robots. If a future robot experiences an incident that causes it to change its behavior, physiological structure, or cognitive ability to better survive or improve its functionality, it could then pass the improvement to its progeny. The robot would create its descendants via autopoiesis (i.e., self-replication), albeit with improvements. Furthermore, such a robot would be able to communicate globally with its contemporaries and could convince them to implement the improvements immediately. The advent of autonomous vehicles and other robots, made possible by advances in neural networks with deep learning (Goodfellow et al., 2016) and other artificial intelligence (AI) tools and techniques, processing chips, communications networks, knowledgebases, and sensors, will become a foundational technology leading to manifold kinds of autonomous intelligent robots over the coming decades. Over the ensuing decades the cognitive ability of robots will evolve to replicate or surpass human capabilities. Some AI processes, such as neural
353
networks, can produce robot behavior that is as unpredictable and inexplicable as human behavior. As robot cognition increases over time, it is likely that robot minds will increasingly exhibit psychological phenomena. The scientist and science-fiction writer Isaac Asimov anticipated the need, in the 21st century, for what he called robopsychologists to analyze and cure the mental illness that he expected to emerge in some intelligent machines, and which would engender behavior that is dangerous to humans (Asimov, 1950). With the evolution of autonomous intelligent robots following Lamarckian, rather than Darwinian, principles, the study of robopsychology will be needed sooner rather than later.
A COMPUTATIONAL THEORY OF MIND In 1943 Warren McCulloch and Walter Pitts concluded that neurons perform computational processes (McCulloch and Pitts, 1943). Subsequently, the basis for a computational theory (actually, a hypothesis) of mind was formed from the confluence of several disciplines: neuroscience, cognitive psychology, AI, robotics, information science, and semiotics. It envisions that the mind can be modeled as a set of processes which have computational equivalents (Albus and Meystel, 2001; Meystel and Albus, 2002). If such a theory were established on a foundation of evidence, it could be tested experimentally with software and hardware. Machines, such as robots, could be built which model the brain and test whether a human-like mind emerges from the machine brain. This test would be a more comprehensive version of the Turing test for machine intelligence. The computational theory of the human mind intersects with evolutionary psychology in holding that the human brain is a system of computational subsystems designed by natural selection over eons in our Homo sapiens
354
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
ancestors and their ancestors (e.g., Homo habilis, Homo erectus, Homo heidelbergensis, etc.) for foraging, hunting, reproducing, and outmaneuvering entities such as animals, plants, objects in the environment, and other hominids. It postulates that our cognition and emotions are produced by evolved algorithms computed by our subconscious mind. Machines can be very good at developing and computing algorithms, often better than Homo sapiens. A consequence of a computational theory of mind is that the mind consists of a set of processes, each of which has a computational equivalent. These processes include emotion, imagination, thought, reason, feeling, perception, knowledge, cognition, meaning, understanding, belief, planning, wisdom, attention, awareness, consciousness, intelligence, a sense of good and evil, a sense of justice and duty, and an appreciation of beauty. Each of these processes can be represented in robots, as shown in Table 18.1 (from Albus, 2001):
To further explain the meaning of some of the computational equivalents in the table, consider that: “meaning is the set of semantic relationships that exist between the internal knowledge database and the external world. Meaning establishes what is intended or meant by behavioral actions, and defines what entities, events, and situations in the knowledge database refer to in the world.” “Understanding occurs when the system’s internal representation of external reality is adequate for generating intelligent behavior.” “Planning is a thinking process whereby a system imagines the future and selects the best course of action to achieve a goal state.” “Awareness is a condition wherein a system has knowledge of the structure, dynamics, and meaning of the environment in which it exists.” “Consciousness is a state or condition in which an intelligent system is aware of itself, its surroundings, its situation, its intentions, and its feelings.” (Albus and Mystel, pp xii–xiii, 2001)
Despite centuries of philosophical argument, it is now generally agreed that the mind is what the brain does, so there is no need to
Table 18.1 Processes of mind and their computational equivalents Processes of the human mind
Computational equivalents
Emotion Imagination Thought Reason Feeling Perception Knowledge Cognition Meaning Understanding Belief Planning Wisdom Attention Awareness Consciousness Intelligence Sense of good and evil Sense of justice and duty Appreciation of beauty
Value judgment; evaluation of good and bad Modeling, and simulation; visualization Analysis of what is imagined Logic applied to thought Experience of sensory input or emotional state Transforming sensory data into knowledge Information organized so it is useful Analysis, evaluation, and use of knowledge Relationships between forms of knowledge Correspondence between model and reality Level of confidence assigned to knowledge Examination of possible future actions Decisions likely to achieve long-term goals Focusing perception on what is important Operational state of perceptual processes Operational state of cognitive processes Ability to achieve purpose or goals despite uncertainty Value judgment output Value judgment output Value judgment output
Source: Albus (2001).
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ROBOTICS
invoke mysterious spiritual phenomena outside the realm of science. Likewise, the robot mind consists of the computational processes of the robot brain. And its structure and process will be subject to technological evolution. Thus the brain, whether human or robot, is primarily a control system, generating and controlling behavior. It likely developed in ancient primitive organisms to control mobility and path planning to avoid threats and take advantage of opportunities for survival and reproduction. Any control system is designed, by nature or humans, to achieve or maintain a goal (a desired result or state of the system or world). Organisms with many offspring can survive with simple brains; higher intelligence allows those with fewer offspring to survive with higher probability. Robots need not have greater intelligence or more complex cognition than humans. They should only have the ‘IQ’ needed to perform their functions, perhaps insect-level intelligence. Excessive intelligence would be inefficient economically and operationally, perhaps even interfering with the ability of the machine to do its job well. However, many jobs will require robots to have human-level intelligence or better, some with high levels of expertise that is narrowly focused, such as for performing colonoscopies, but others will need high levels of cognition that is broad in scope, such as being a fifth-grade school teacher where knowledge and skill for interacting with human students is needed along with knowledge for effective teaching. Some robots will need greater intelligence in order to interact with humans in a desirable way, despite their simpler basic jobs. For example, an autonomous car need only know how to drive in complex environments in order to perform its basic function as a chauffeur. But if human passengers would like to converse with the car in natural language on manifold topics, or if the car is to be a partner of a law-enforcement officer or a soldier and must know policies
355
and procedures, tactics and strategies, facial recognition, natural language (in multi ple languages) with the ability to banter or employ formal procedural language, and have general situational awareness with, for example, the ability to discern subtle important cues from the environment, then the robot will have to know much more than how to drive, just as its human equivalent would. Likewise, the intelligence of household robots may vary, depending on the needs and wants of their owners.
ROBOT INTELLIGENCE, LEARNING, ADAPTATION, WISDOM, AND SELFAWARENESS Autonomous robots will have varying degrees of intelligence and ability to learn and adapt. Robots with human-level intelligence or greater will also need wisdom if humanity is to avoid the oft-predicted Robot Apocalypse. Robots will also need their behavior to be guided by an ethics and morality, but wisdom provides the framework for ethical and moral behavior. In a pragmatic definition, an intelligent system is a system with the ability to act appropriately (or make an appropriate choice or decision) in an uncertain environment. An appropriate action (or choice) is that which maximizes the probability of successfully achieving the system’s mission, function, purpose, or goals (Meystel and Albus, 2002). Machine intelligence need not be at the human level. For example, appropriate autonomous vehicle intelligence is the ability of an autonomous vehicle to perform at least as skilled as a good human driver would under a variety of conditions. It does not need to know how to play chess or make an omelet, although it could be given additional cognition to enhance its abilities to perform functions other than driving. The appropriate robot intelligence for an application depends on the user’s requirements and the technical,
356
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
operational, and economical feasibility of achieving the desired level of intelligence. Many robots may only require insect-level intelligence to perform their functions, but even these robots will need behavioral constraints to avoid running amok. Bees, ants, and termites, for example, work together with their hive or colony cohort in a purposive way and generally avoid killing each other. There are many definitions of learning. Our preferred synthesized definition of learning is the acquisition of knowledge, skill, ability, or understanding by study, instruction, or experience, as evidenced by achieving growing success (improved behavior), with respect to suitable metrics, in a fixed environment. Learning takes place when the system’s behavior increases the efficiency with which data, information, and knowledge is processed so that desirable states are reached, errors avoided, or a portion of the system’s environment is controlled. Robots with varying degrees of intelligence will be capable of learning as may be required by their applications, even robots with relatively low intelligence. Even Caenorhabditis elegans, a worm one millimeter in length with just 302 neurons, is capable of learning (Ardiel and Rankin, 2010). In our view of learning is different from adaptation. Our definition of adaptation is a change in behavior (or structure) in response to a changed environment. An adapted system is able to maintain critical or essential variables within physical (or physiological) limits (e.g., homeostasis). Adaptation occurs where the changed behavior (or structure) increases the probability that the system can achieve its function or purpose (e.g., maintain homeostasis) by adjusting to the new or changed environment. Thus, in our view, learning occurs in a fixed environment while adaptation occurs in a changed environment. To understand wisdom requires wisdom (Sternberg, 1995). While there are many projects to develop robot learning and intelligence, there are none yet to develop robot wisdom, an ability humans may need in their
robots if they are to survive among them. The love of (or search for) wisdom is the original meaning of the word philosophy. But the notion of wisdom is a bit elusive. According to Martin Henry Fischer (1879– 1962), knowledge is a process of aggregating facts while wisdom is their simplification. Our preferred definition of wisdom is: the ability to see the forest as well as the trees. A decision by a human or robot may seem to be the right one when considered in the context of the details of the problem or the short term, i.e., the trees, or in the context of the big picture or the long term, i.e., the forest, but not both. For example, some immediate or near-term solutions for problems may later become problems themselves, while some long-term solutions for problems may cause new near-term problems. Self-awareness is the ability to simulate oneself, as in a mental world model. A robot can be considered to be self-aware if it is able to predict what it will perceive in the future based on its current state and behavior, and use those predictions to plan future behavior (Albus and Meystel, 2001).
RULE-BASED SYSTEMS, NEURAL NETWORKS, AND GENETIC ALGORITHMS There are a number of AI tools which can be used to evolve the robot mind to higher cognition and greater sentience, including symbolic processes, connectionist processes, and genetic algorithms. It is likely that a synthesis of these AI tools, perhaps along with some that have not been invented yet, might be required. Symbolic processes, consisting of rule-based (or expert) systems, have been used successfully to replicate specialized human intelligence or expertise within narrow domains of knowledge (Hayes-Roth et al., 1983). Expert systems, featuring strings of if-then formatted rules (Durkin, 1994), have achieved some
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ROBOTICS
degree of success in commercial and military applications. They are suitable for such autonomous robot tasks as high-level planning, navigation, tactics, strategies, and portions of sensory processing, such as high-level vision. Conventional symbolic (knowledgebased) processes are limited by the ability of a human expert to foresee situations and environments that a robot will encounter, and to program, with sufficient if-then rules, appropriate responses to threats and opportunities that the robot may encounter. However, rule-based systems can be designed to learn, to modify themselves, which would greatly broaden their domain. A robot interacting with the environment and encountering a situation that contradicts an existing rule, or does not have a rule to address the current situation, could modify an existing rule to accommodate the new reality or create a new rule. Rule-based systems could be used to address a current weakness of AI – its general inability to deal with context, such as the relationship of entities with time, space, and causality (Brézillon, 1999). Deep learning, for example, is not generally suitable for teaching a robot context, such as how the existence and interaction of entities relate to each other and the world in terms of spatial and temporal phenomena, or the chains of causal events (Edell, 2018). For example, a rule-based system could state that if a non-moveable object, like the Brooklyn Bridge, is in one place, like New York City, it cannot also be in another place, like next to the Golden Gate Bridge in San Francisco. Or it can be instructed in, or directly experience if it is in a robot, causality; e.g., if a person trips on a crack in the sidewalk, that may cause him to fall; and if he falls, he may be injured. Connectionist processes, consisting of artificial neural networks (ANN) (Goodfellow et al., 2016), are suited for deep learning and autonomic responses in robots, such as avoiding an imminent crash into a tree. Machines can be designed to learn (or adapt) in various ways, including such AI tools as
357
neural networks, expert systems, genetic algorithms, and Bayesian inference. But the major approach has been using ANN, which have been developed for many decades but until recently have only had limited success in achieving machine learning. In recent years there has been significant progress because of improvements with neural network software and hardware, which are also referred to as deep learning and deep neural networks (DNN). Early ANN had one layer of eight neurons; new DNN can contain more than 150 layers of neurons, interconnected with about a billion connections. One DNN has 60 million tunable parameters and 650,000 neurons (Krizhevsky et al., 2012; Lipson and Kurman, 2016). They need fast and powerful computers and advanced training algorithms to function. As an example of the progress of deep learning, consider that an untrained human can categorize images (i.e., identify the content of images) with a 5% error rate, which was far better than machine vision until recently (Lipson and Kurman, 2016). • 2010: The winning ANN in a machine vision competition categorized 100,000 test images with 28% error rate. • 2011: The winning ANN categorized test images with 25% error rate, a slight improvement. • 2012: Deep learning emerged and the winning ANN (a convolutional neural network) categorized test images with 15% error rate, a major improvement. • 2013: The winning DNN categorized test images with 11.2% error rate. • 2014: The winning DNN categorized test images with 6.66% error rate. • 2015: The winning DNN categorized test images with 3.57% error rate, beating human capability (Lipson and Kurman, 2016).
While DNN seems to be an effective and efficient approach to many intelligent machine applications, nevertheless there are many problems. For example, DNN cannot learn by analogy, as humans and animals can do, that objects possess common attributes. Despite their many shapes and sizes, humans can quickly generalize the notion of a chair
358
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
or lamp. So far, DNN has failed to learn the concept of sameness and could not learn by analogy the underlying concepts linking similar objects in a training set of images of those objects (Lipson and Kurman, 2016). Also, DNN is not transparent and the reasons for its outcomes are often inexplicable. It does not learn like humans. People learn by abstracting the principles underlying a few examples, while DNN needs massive databases to learn (Lipson and Kurman, 2016). So far DNN, while accomplished in machine learning, has not provided machines with human-like intelligence or cognition. It seems that machines, such as robots, must interact with the world to discover the intuitive physics upon which cognitive inference depends. The application of genetic algorithms (GAs) for robot evolution provides a hybrid case where Darwinian evolution can be used to impel the rapid evolution of robot technology, including the evolution of the robot mind. It is a Darwinian basis for Lamarckian technological evolution. GAs (Goldberg, 1989; Davis, 1991) are mathematical algorithms that transform a set (or population) of individual mathematical entities (typically fixed-length character strings patterned after chromosome strings), each with an associated fitness value, into a new population (i.e., the next generation) using operations patterned after the Darwinian principle of reproduction and survival of the fittest and after naturally occurring genetic operations, such as sexual recombination. GAs are run in high-speed digital simulations containing entities and their environment. Millions of simulations, representing the equivalent of millions of years of passing time in the real world and millions of generations of living and dying, can be run in seconds or minutes of processing time. The GAs typically cause, over simulated generations, the progressive modification of some structure or structures, which may then be reflected in the behavior of the system of which the structures are a part (as animal behavior is a reflection of genetic structures
based on DNA). As in nature, simple mechanisms can generate complex structures and adaptive behaviors. Genetic programming is an extension of conventional GAs (Koza, 1992). It is a method for automatically creating a working computer program from a high-level statement of the problem, i.e., the programmer need not specify the program code. It accomplishes this by genetically breeding a population of computer programs using the principles of Darwinian natural selection and biologically inspired operations. Genetic programming iteratively transforms a population of computer programs into a new generation of programs by applying analogs of naturally occurring genetic operations. As with GAs, the genetic operations include crossover (sexual recombination), mutation, reproduction, gene duplication, and gene deletion. The conventional robot selects a pre- programmed strategy (on the basis of information stored in its databases, memory, and world model, and acquired from the interaction of its sensors with the internal and external environments), to meet a defined goal or achieve a functional purpose. The conventional approach requires complex and costly preparation for the development of algorithms for each specific environment in which the robot is to operate. GAs require goals, feedback mechanisms, and sensory access to the environment to learn to operate effectively and efficiently. They require minimal engineering or programming. The designer need not be prescient about every possible contingency to write a long series of if-then rules (as for expert systems). The designer does not have to expend the time and effort to train the system, as is the case for most neural networks and deep learning. GAs enable the simulated robot to adapt continuously, to cope with uncertain or changing environments, and to allow the system (e.g., robot) to perform successfully while becoming strategically prepared for future circumstances. This not only reduces the cost and exertion of programming, but
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ROBOTICS
enables the robot to adapt to a broader range of environments (Schultz et al., 1993). For example, a simulated autonomous robot aircraft can learn, over millions of attempts, to land safely on the simulated rolling, pitching, yawing deck of an aircraft carrier – or how to land on various irregular surfaces. A simulated legged robot can learn how to best control its legs to negotiate an uneven terrain, and adapt to walking successfully over various kinds of difficult terrain. The algorithms and physical designs (e.g., for legs) that are engineered in the simulated evolutionary generations can then be built into the real-world robot. The psychology of the real-world robot can be advanced by millions of generations of simulated evolution of simulated robots (Schultz et al., 1993). If a robot had sufficient computational power, GAs could be run within the brain of the real-world robot. For example, if a robot were to encounter an unexpected problem or environment, it could pause in its movement and run its own GAs to arrive at a solution that optimizes or satisfies an objective function, allowing the robot to solve the problem or survive a dangerous situation. The basic elements of the GA consist of representations, patterns (or structures), and schemata (Goldberg, 1989), as follows: • representation: a blank vector of elements (variables) which can take on numerical values; • pattern (or structure): numerical values are incorporated into the representation; and • schemata: sets of structures which are, in effect, strategies for optimizing fitness criteria.
GAs prescribe the maintenance of a small set of structures and provide guidelines for the construction of new structures (Goldberg, 1989). The structures generally combine in pairs (the equivalent of sexual reproduction) at a rate based on their observed performance. Each time the two structures reproduce to produce a new structure, the new structure maintains the optimal properties expected to result from the initial union, while simultaneously correcting for biases in the algorithm. By testing
359
sequential structures, a large number of patterns, or schemata, are implicitly tested. For a robot control system, for example, each schemata may be a control strategy associated with multiple sensor inputs. Each structure in a relatively small set is tested against the environment, as genetically designed organisms in nature are tested against the environment. Three primary operators are used to combine the elements of two selected structures to form a new structure (Goldberg, 1989): • crossover: each structure is represented as a vector. A point along this vector is selected, and the new structure takes all elements before (and at) this position from one parent structure, and all of the elements after this point from the other. Crossover is the most used primary operator; • inversion: crossover produces a bias toward propagating closely linked schemata (i.e., schemata with short physical distances between elements). Inversion compensates for this bias by causing successful schemata to become increasingly closely linked physically; and • mutation: over successive trials potentially important values in particular positions may disappear from the population of structures. A low mutation rate periodically reintroduces lost values.
Information about large amounts of schemata is processed at each stage of the simulation, with subsequent trials making use of this information, which is genetically embedded in the structures. The structures reproduce probabilistically and the probabilities are assigned by the algorithm on the basis of observed performance against fitness criteria. Over successive trials, the expected number of occurrences of schemata mirrors their performance, e.g., the ability of a robot to walk, swim, or play tennis against humans. Schemata that have demonstrated to be high-performance by surviving trials must reproduce themselves while new structures are also being generated and tested. There is an algorithm for assigning trials to structures which test schemata. This algorithm must maximize current fitness while also exploring new schemata. Thousands of generations of simulated entities,
360
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
such as robots, are born, live, reproduce, and die. The equivalent of millions of years of natural evolution takes place in brief computerprocessing time (Goldberg, 1989). The compressed Darwinian evolution of a robot, including that of its mind and psychology, can be effected in the context of the Lamarckian evolution of computer simulation technology.
TECHNOLOGY AND PSYCHO-SOCIAL FACTORS Evolutionary psychology provides an account of the psycho-social gestalt and psycho-social factors concerning technology, not just the efficacy of the technology. It will have a significant influence on the public’s acceptance of autonomous robots. As a consequence of our psychology, one death is a tragedy while a million deaths is a statistic, as the Soviet dictator Joseph Stalin is alleged to have said. For example, a few isolated accidental deaths caused by autonomous cars or other robots, which are widely publicized by the media, might elicit an exaggerated emotional response by the public, slowing or stifling the development of the technology. The National Highway Traffic Safety Administration (NHTSA) reports nearly 37,000 deaths in the United States from automotive accidents during 2018, despite major improvement in vehicle safety driver-assist systems. The fatality rate per vehicle mile traveled (VMT) has decreased greatly over the decades with improving automotive technology and infrastructure, but at the same time the number of vehicle miles traveled increased greatly (e.g., with more miles traveled per vehicle and more vehicles on the road), contributing to the number of deaths. But the public has become inured to these deaths (Evans, 2008). More to the point, according to NHTSA there were 26 deaths in the United States from automotive accidents in 1899 when there were about 8,000 horseless carriages. By 1903 there were more than
100 deaths. If social media existed at the time as it does now, generating public outrage over the accidental automotive deaths, perhaps we would still be riding in horse-drawn carriages. The goal for autonomous (robotic) vehicles is zero deaths (National Safety Council, 2019). The goal may not be achieved, but automotive casualties could become as rare as deaths from sharks (about six per year). Psycho-social factors (as opposed to, for example, engineering or technical factors) are critical in the development and acceptance of most – or all – technologies. For example, to compensate for a shortage of suitable wood in the 19th century, some pencils were designed to be sheathed with paper instead of wood. Functionally, it worked well. But psychologically people preferred to sharpen their pencils by whittling them with a knife or a pencil sharpener, rather than peeling the paper. The paper pencil eventually became defunct, except for special-purpose applications (Teich, 2009). New technologies are now critically evaluated in the context of aesthetics, such as environmental and design considerations. Developers of technology, such as scientists and engineers, are influenced, consciously or unconsciously, by the organizational and societal culture in which they reside, which is a manifestation of evolutionary psychology. The institutionalization of science and engineering means that once a decision (even a bad one) is made concerning the development and commercialization of a technology, the momentum of the organizational bureaucracy and the processes of systems engineering drive the product to its conclusion (Teich, 2009). Adverse unintended consequences can ensue.
TECHNOLOGY AND UNINTENDED CONSEQUENCES Ancient legend tells us that Prometheus defied Zeus and brought technological knowledge, in the form of fire and the skill of metalwork, to the human race. Zeus then
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ROBOTICS
punished him for this by having him bound to a rock while a huge eagle ate his liver every day, only to have it grow back to be eaten again the next day (Cartwright, 2013). New technology when first introduced can have serious and dangerous flaws. For example, early methods of vaccination for smallpox could cause smallpox – and death (Teich, 2009). Manufacturers of early high-pressure steam engines often used inferior materials, and poor design and construction contributed to major malfunctions (Teich, 2009). Even well-built engines needed improved technology to avoid catastrophic failures. Aside from the engines, early railroads needed better technology for bridges and tracks to avoid death and destruction (Teich, 2009). Many technological advances had unexpected and unwanted side effects. Associated with a technological advance having major benefits might be unintended consequences causing death and destruction. Our ancestors generally did not abandon the flawed technology but persisted in trying to improve it, either mitigating the adverse consequences or accepting them as a tradeoff for the benefits. There is a tension between new technology and the preservation of individual and societal values. The new technology may threaten the values of some, while efforts to mitigate the adverse consequences of the new technology may threaten the values of others. Some people might then conclude that technology is inherently hostile to human values. Technology has a direct impact on values because it generally increases the range of choice and opportunity, and one’s values cause one to make certain choices and pursue particular opportunities. New technology can lead to a change in individual or cultural values by either bringing some previously unattainable goal within the realm of choice or by making some values easier to implement (Teich, 2009). Ultimately, intelligent robots might drive humans to extinction maliciously or unintentionally by competing more successfully for limited resources of matter, energy, and
361
territory. Genetics, nanotechnology, and robotics all offer the possibility of self-replicating technology – autopoiesis. It is necessary to examine the potential adverse consequences of new technology, for much of technology has adverse consequences. Often the benefits of the new technology exceed its adverse consequences, or its disadvantages can be mitigated by improving – evolving – the technology. Cultural and technological systems do not develop independently; the two evolve together in complex feedback loops, wherein each drives, restrains, and accelerates change in the other. Darwinian evolutionary psychology underlies human culture and its values, while Lamarckian evolutionary psychology will underlie robot culture and values.
AUTONOMOUS INTELLIGENT ROBOTS: A DISRUPTIVE AND TRANSFORMATIVE TECHNOLOGY The first generation of fully autonomous intelligent robots will be vehicles: autonomous cars, trucks, and buses. This will be a disruptive and transformative technology, whether for civilian or military applications. The technology will be disruptive because it will cause old industries and companies to vanish while new ones emerge. With creative destruction, jobs lost in one industry will be replaced by new jobs in another. The technology will be transformative because it will change society. The robots will alter military tactics, strategy, and doctrine; the national economy and power; political policy; cultural values and societal structures; and how and where people live, work, and play. As an example of a disruptive and transformative technology similar to that of autonomous vehicles, consider the advent of the horseless carriage at the turn of the 19th century. The older technology at the time, the horse and buggy, was a kind of intelligent vehicle in that the horse was sufficiently smart to avoid objects in the road, and could
362
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
even be autonomous, e.g., if the driver was drunk or fell asleep, the horse could find its way home. Horses pulling milk-delivery wagons learned their routes and did not require guidance from a human driver. The horse and buggy (or cart) was an ancient, well-known technology, with support from known goods providers (e.g., buggy manufacturers, tackequipment manufacturers, and horse breeders), service providers (e.g., blacksmiths, livery stables, veterinarians), and infrastructure providers (e.g., horse troughs and barns). The technology was acceptably reliable and able to traverse bad roads. Problems with the technology included: daily storage maintenance (barn, food, water, grooming, etc.) for the horse, whether it was used or not; a growing manure problem in urban areas; and the cost to buy and maintain it. The earliest horseless carriages were an unknown technology: unreliable, slow, and very expensive, with no infrastructure (e.g., no suitable roads, available parts, fuel stations, mechanics, rules and regulations, or an understanding of the technology by the public). Some advantages over the existing technology included: no daily maintenance if not used; faster; more easily and compactly stored; more compact fuel; no manure; and status for early adopters. But the cost of the new technology was still too expensive for most people. Early cars and manufacturers proliferated, with varied technology and designs (e.g., should it be a steering lever or a wheel; an internal or external combustion engine or electric motor?). As with natural evolution during the Cambrian period when nature was experimenting with manifold new designs, new body plans, for complex animals, automotive designs evolved rapidly during the first two decades of the automotive age. Around the turn of the century there were more than 2,000 automotive manufacturers across the United States, of which many were startups in home garages, creating a proliferation of automotive designs (Wikipedia, 2019b). But as in the Cambrian period with the evolutionary winnowing of
organism design, by 1920 there were just 100 US manufacturers with their automotive designs converging to new industry standards. By 1929 only 44 automotive manufacturers remained in the United States, which decreased to 11 by 1976. In the early 1900s, only a few thousand cars were sold annually. For example, Ford sold 1,700 cars in 1904, its first year of business. After introducing factory mass production in 1913 and thereby drastically reducing the cost of cars, Ford sold over a million cars in 1920 (Wikipedia, 2019a). The horseless carriage was a disruptive technology (The Economist, 2015). Across many sectors of the economy it drove the creation of new technologies, industries, and infrastructure, such as the oil industry, asphalt and concrete roads, bridges, tires, factory mass production, etc. Many, but not all, horse- and buggy-related goods and services firms were driven out of business. The horse and buggy market shriveled but did not disappear entirely. To this day they remain common in Amish areas of Pennsylvania and other states. Most new entrants in the automotive industry also disappeared as the technology advanced and designs, production, products, infrastructure, and marketplace standardized and stabilized. Punctuated equilibrium (Gould, 1983), as it does in natural evolution, caused occasional disruptions to the industry, with paradigm shifts due to new technology, government regulation, or customer expectations. The current technology paradigm shift is driven by the technologies for energy, electronics, and ergonomics, including electric propulsion to reduce pollution, driver-assist systems to increase safety, and autonomous vehicles. The horseless carriage was a transformative technology (The Economist, 2015). It changed cultural values and societal structure. It caused the fashion industry to design clothing to accommodate the car. It caused the rise of suburbs, increased travel among the populace, and increased the homogenization of society. It gave rise to industry in place of agriculture and city living in place
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ROBOTICS
of rural living. It abetted the influence of massive new corporations. It changed family dynamics with teenage and women drivers; the rise of teenage influence and their dating customs, with the car as bedroom-on-wheels; and the loss of power by the husband and father. It increased family wealth, freedom, and mobility, and contributed to the rise of the middle class. It caused many casualties due to crashes. In the long term it caused geopolitical and environmental changes, with the rise of oil cartels, religious and tribal conflicts in oil-rich lands, wars over oil, and environmental degradation leading to climate change and the potential destruction of much of the Earth’s species and living space for humans. Autonomous intelligent vehicles have a limited but sufficient domain of knowledge and ability, but they will serve as a kind of Ur-technology for all kinds of autonomous robots. Their success will serve as the basis for developing and technologically evolving autonomous robots into many robot ‘species’ able to perform many jobs across all economic sectors. Biomimetic robots will proliferate, including humanoid and multi-legged chimera robots, like centaur robots; zoomorphic robots with forms like snakes, lizards, fish, octopuses, primates, birds, insects, etc. Disruption will spread across all sectors of the economy, and changes in how people live, work, and play will continue for the rest of the century. The technological evolution of robots and the AI for their minds will continue unabated across the globe despite any efforts of one nation or another to slow or stop its progress. Technology that is feasible and useful is hardy and always emerges like a weed in a crack in the sidewalk. Perhaps human psychology will be changed in the future by genetic engineering or some other technology and will be better able to cope with the results of the mind’s creations (Smith, 2019). It seems that the best way to avoid the proverbial robot apocalypse is for people to be at least as smart as their robots.
363
ROBOT EMOTION There are development projects to give robots emotion (Hall, 2017), or the appearance to humans of emotion. The robots are designed to interpret certain internal states as the equivalent of human emotions, such as happy, sad, angry, etc., and to express those emotions with facial expressions and body language. The idea is for robots to be better able to interact and work with people. Human emotion is based on algorithmic bio-chemical processes which evolved to solve specific adaptive problems, e.g., the fear of being eaten and the pleasure of eating food and having sex (LeDoux, 2012). Emotions are also an important part of generating and controlling human behavior, as employed regularly by priests and politicians (Zaki, 2013). Rationality and logic are not necessarily what motivates people to achieve goals. Human emotion is an important mechanism for making certain kinds of decisions, such as when time is critical or data are unavailable and objective analysis is not feasible. Computers can perform detailed analyses much faster than people and until recently emotion was largely ignored in the development of intelligent machines. Robots, however, will be moving about and interacting with the environment. As humans do, they will encounter sudden life-and-death situations in which decisions cannot be made rationally, where emotion, or its robot equivalent, may be called upon to make the decision. Emotions can represent an aggregation of certain critical memories (LeDoux, 1996), allowing for a quick, nearly autonomic, fightor-flight response (e.g., run from the tiger!). Emotions have a profound effect on cognition (Damasio, 2003), determining what is good or bad, loved or hated, important or unimportant, beautiful or ugly, remembered or forgotten. Humans and other animals seem to have similar, if not identical, emotions because of the similarity of the physiological neural system and the evolution of the portions of the brain involved with emotions (LeDoux, 2012).
364
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
It seems likely that emotional-state variables such as fear, hate, and love can be generated by computational mechanisms and used for generating behavior in artificially intelligent systems. Computer models have been used to model certain emotional processes such that the machine seems to behave emotionally. Even if the underlying sources of emotion were different in machines, if the manifestation were the same as for humans, the conclusion from a Turing test (Moore, 2003) designed to test robot emotions would be that robots have emotions. If a machine behaves as if it is afraid or happy, who is to say it is not?
ROBOT CONSCIOUSNESS AND FREE WILL There is no universal agreement among cognitive scientists as to the nature or meaning of consciousness (Edelman and Tononi, 2000; Graziano, 2013). An aggregation of various dictionary definitions of consciousness is: ‘the state of being aware of oneself and one’s relationship to the world; perceiving, apprehending, or noticing with a degree of controlled observation; capable of or marked by thought, will, design, or perception’. Our preferred definition of consciousness is the state of meta-perception – the perception of perception. Self-awareness is quite limited in humans in that we are unaware of most of our physiological states. Most of our physiological and mental processes take place without our being aware of them, such as what is going on in our gastro-intestinal system or pancreas. Most of the cells and the DNA in and on our body are not even ours, belonging to bacteria, fungi, worms, mites, mitochondria, and other symbionts and parasites, all of which we are blissfully unaware unless there is a gross malfunction. Experiments of seemingly conscious behavior indicate that it may be caused subconsciously and then retroactively attributed by the mind to a conscious decision (Libet, 1993; Ayan, 2018; Koch, 2018). This would
be just one of the many delusions we constantly create as the mind frantically tries to fill the gaps in perception caused by incomplete sensory information from imperfect senses, inattention, and environmental noise, along with missing knowledge about the environment, uncertainty about the behavior of others, and the inability to know everything about the past or to predict the future (Libet, 1993; Ayan, 2018; Koch, 2018). A robot’s physiology and brain would be different from that of humans. The technological evolution of robot psychology could lead to a robot consciousness that is superior to that of people, where the robot is fully selfaware. At all times the robot could be aware of everything taking place within its body and the state of its physiology and mind. It is possible that a form of consciousness can emerge from a robot that has a suitable representation of the world. A robot that can build and maintain a world model that represents objects, events, entities, situations, and relationships should be able to include itself as one of the entities. A self-aware system can keep track of itself, of its external and internal states and dynamics. A self-aware system can be aware of how it should respond to things – how it ‘feels’ about things. Events or objects can be labeled with emotional state variables, such as fear, hate, and love. Pain-state variables can indicate to the robot that it is damaged. An emotional response may not always be desirable in robots or humans because the consequent behavior may be excessive or inappropriate to the situation. In life-threatening situations it may be quite appropriate. A robot could have a world model with objects that have assigned emotional-state variables. If the robot observes an object labeled with a highfear-state variable, it might exhibit fear by increasing its engine speed, assuming a defensive posture, or increasing its visual attention and sensory awareness. It might articulate its fear, as the intelligent computer HAL did in the movie version of Arthur C. Clarke’s ‘2001: A Space Odyssey’ when it was being dismantled: ‘Stop, Dave, I’m afraid’.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ROBOTICS
As previously defined, robot intelligence is not the same as self-awareness or consciousness. And robot consciousness is not the same as what is usually considered free will, although the meaning of free will is elusive, and the perception of free will in humans may be a delusion (Gazzaniga, 2011; Harris, 2012). Self-awareness can be designed into the robot, or it may become an emergent property as robot minds become more complex. Free will, or the perception of free will, may also emerge from complex robot minds. Large, complex neural networks make correct decisions even now that are unexplainable by human observers. Advanced robots may make appropriate decisions and act accordingly without anyone understanding how or why. When asked, the robot may answer ‘I decided it was the right thing to do’. In a future Turing test for free will, human observers may conclude that robots have free will. When robots are perceived to be intelligent, conscious, and have free will, on what justification can people treat them as machines or slaves?
AUTONOMOUS MILITARY ROBOTS The US military is still refining its definition of an autonomous system. For example, DOD Directive No. 3000.09 (21 November 2012) defines an autonomous weapon system as a weapon system that, once activated, can select and engage targets without further intervention by a human operator. For many years a US government working group called ALFUS (Autonomy Levels for Unmanned Systems) met regularly to try to define autonomous systems based on three key variables (i.e., three dimensions): mission complexity, environmental difficulty, and human interface. They were not entirely successful. Likewise, during the 1990s various aerospace companies and government agencies attempted to define autonomous systems, often with lists of functional descriptions,
365
such as a 10-level scale, from no autonomy to full autonomy. There is actually a continuum of autonomy and the levels discretize the continuum: 1 System offers no assistance – operator must do everything 2 System offers a complete set of action alternatives to operator 3 System narrows the action alternatives to a few 4 System suggests a selection 5 System executes a selection if operator approves 6 System allows operator a restricted time to veto before automatic execution 7 System executes automatically, then necessarily informs operator 8 System informs operator after execution only if operator asks 9 System informs operator after execution – if system decides to 10 System decides everything and acts autonomously, essentially ignoring the human
In recent years, as the technology for autonomous cars advanced rapidly, the automotive industry and the Society for Automotive Engineering defined six levels of autonomy. A few slightly different variants of the six levels are used by various autonomous vehicle developers. Level 0: no autonomy Level 1: a few functions, such as automated cruise control, are automated Level 2: the driver, while always monitoring the car, does not have to steer or brake or accelerate under some driving conditions Level 3: the vehicle can drive mostly autonomously, but the driver must always be alert to take over as needed (vehicle may check the driver’s alertness regularly) Level 4: the vehicle can operate fully autonomously at least in some environments, e.g., on an interstate road, without the driver having to be alert while in that environment (but a driver must always be in the vehicle) Level 5: the vehicle can operate fully autonomously without any human or driver in the vehicle or controlling or monitoring the vehicle from a distance
In 2012 the US Department of Defense issued a directive outlining steps to ensure that
366
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
autonomous weapons function as anticipated and to minimize failures that could lead to unintended engagements, or to loss of control of the system. The Defense Science Board (DSB) in 2016 conferred to improve the future adoption and use of autonomous systems, declaring that they had significant military value. They recommended accelerating the military’s adoption of autonomous capabilities. The DSB’s definition was that an autonomous system has the ability to independently compose and select among different courses of action to accomplish goals based on its knowledge and understanding of the world, self, and situation. Along with the military’s accelerated adoption of autonomous systems, there are growing efforts to ban autonomous lethal robots for military (and law-enforcement) applications. Organizations like Human Rights Watch and the Harvard Law School’s International Human Rights Clinic are alarmed about the ethics of lethal autonomous robots. Calling them ‘killer robots’, opponents urge an international treaty that would absolutely prohibit the development, production, and use of fully autonomous weapons. Opponents say that killer robots will never possess the human judgment that limits civilian casualties during war and such machines could not be held accountable for war crimes. ‘Never’ is a very long time, and it seems that their developers and users could be held liable for war crimes, similar to the liability issues when autonomous cars cause accidents or, in the future, be used to commit crimes or terrorist acts. Civilians have always been, and still are, major casualties of war, and robot soldiers can be designed to reduce battlefield death, destruction, and atrocities. It is not certain that autonomous military robots would be worse than human combatants. It depends on how the robots are designed, programmed, and trained. Some say machines can never have compassion, but, again, ‘never’ is a very long time. In any event, many humans, including combatants, are sociopaths or suffer from clinical narcissistic personality disorder and
consequently lack compassion and empathy (Brazier, 2018). While inherently saving the lives of the human soldiers they replace, autonomous robots can be programmed to be more humane and rational than humans and save civilians who would be otherwise killed, maimed, or raped by emotional, rampaging human combatants. On the other hand, robots can be designed to kill everyone efficiently without empathy or remorse. Those opposing combat robots say that autonomous machines will not be able to apply human judgment in the application of lethal force, or will not be constrained by the laws of war. But even humans cannot, or do not, always distinguish between combatants and non-combatants, or between friendly and enemy forces. The laws of war, such as they are, are frequently ignored. A robot could recognize that a potential target is already wounded or trying to surrender and respond appropriately. For example, DOD Directive 3000.09 (2012) concerning autonomy in weapons systems requires that commanders who authorize autonomous weapons systems must do so in accordance with the laws of war, treaties, safety rules, and rules of engagement, and that the autonomous weapons systems must allow that such constraints be imposed by their human commanders. Opponents say robotic warfare is a slippery slope leading to an uncertain, potentially apocalyptic future. Even if the US DOD were conscientious in deploying autonomous robots, other nations or non-state actors may not be the same. Autonomous weapon systems are not inherently unlawful or unethical. In any event, the development and deployment of autonomous weapon systems are inevitable, and any attempt at a global ban will likely be ineffective. Given the historical failure of international treaties to ban other seemingly abhorrent means of killing, it is unlikely to succeed for lethal robots as well. It would likely be easier to get an international moratorium on their deployment or an agreement on how to constrain their behavior than to prohibit them entirely, just as nuclear
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ROBOTICS
weapons have not been used again in combat and lethal gas has been used rarely.
ROBOT LAWS, ETHICS, AND MORALITY Natural selection has provided humans with a set of rules and constraints for behaving socially, such as not killing or eating one’s children, or behaving fairly with others within one’s family or tribe. These behavioral rules are limited and not always effective, so humans have devised larger sets of behavioral rules, such as laws, ethics, and morality. These terms have many different definitions, with often an overlap between ethics and morality. These definitions distinguish the rules. Laws are behavioral rules which, when violated, can be punished by society with the loss of one’s life, freedom, or possessions. Ethics are rules of behavior which, when violated, can be punished with the loss of one’s profession (if it includes ethical rules), or ostracism by business associates, friends, or social groups. Morality is behavior which mitigates pain and suffering, as in the parable of the Good Samaritan, which was tested in a well-known psychological experiment (Darley and Batson, 1973). However, morality does not require a belief system such as religion; just the objective realization that humankind benefits when the members of its species refrain from causing pain and suffering and strive to mitigate such suffering when it is caused by the brutality of nature or circumstance. Likewise, autonomous robots, including driverless vehicles in the near term, will need to conform to legal, ethical, and moral behavior, as well as understanding the human sense of these rules and behavior constraints (Lin et al., 2012). Robots will need to become what are called Artificial Moral Agents (Wallach and Allen, 2009). Robots which violate human or robot laws, such as laws against murdering humans or other robots, may lose their lives
367
by their complete destruction (i.e., execution) or re-programming, depending on whether the cause of the deviant behavior is known and repairable. Confining a future criminal robot in a prison would only be justified if the robot were deemed to be a conscious entity, worthy of human-like treatment, and it did not want to be re-programmed to have its mind altered. In order to impose behavioral constraints on robots, science-fiction author (and scientist) Isaac Asimov devised the Three Laws of Robotics in 1942 in a short story, which was later used in many more of his stories (Asimov, 1950). The Three Laws, later increased to Four Laws, were a set of behavioral rules that were ‘laws’ in the sense that they were programmed constraints on a robot’s behavior. The Laws were designed to prevent robots from harming humans while performing their functions, and Asimov later added a fourth (or zeroth) Law: 1 A robot may not injure a human being or, through inaction, allow a human being to come to harm. 2 A robot must obey the orders given to it by human beings, except where such orders would conflict with the First Law. 3 A robot must protect its own existence as long as such protection does not conflict with the First or Second Law. 4 A robot may not harm humanity, or, by inaction, allow humanity to come to harm.
The Laws are often cited as templates for constraining robot behavior, to serve as a basis for robot ethics and morality. But the point of the stories (e.g., I Robot) was that the Laws often failed for various unforeseen reasons, leading to unintended consequences. The narrative puzzle was to determine the cause of the Law’s failure. For example, why would robots, with their behavior seemingly constrained by the Four Laws, enslave people? Let’s say that the robots decide, among themselves, that the greatest threat of harm to humanity is from humanity itself. Thus, in order to protect humanity from harm they must enslave humans for their own good. Under strict control of the robots,
368
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
humanity, while enslaved, would be p revented from causing its own extinction, from coming to physical harm. The harm to humanity losing its freedom is either not apparent to the robots or is considered of relatively minor importance relative to physical harm. Legal, ethical, and moral dilemmas are being deliberated and debated now for the advent of autonomous vehicles (Herrman et al., 2018). Insurance companies are among those considering who will be legally and financially responsible for accidents involving autonomous vehicles. Who will be legally, ethically, and morally responsible for the decisions that will be made by any intelligent autonomous robot, including lethal military robots? A typical question is: if your driverless car were to encounter a bus full of schoolchildren coming toward you on the wrong side of a road near the edge of a cliff, how should it react? Should it make a decision to swerve, preventing a collision with the bus and sparing the children but putting your life at risk? Or should it collide with the bus if there’s a greater chance of you surviving? Recently, there has been much contemplation of the famous trolley problem, a moral and psychological dilemma with several variations, as it relates to humans and autonomous vehicles or other robots (Shenhav and Greene, 2010; Bohannon, 2011). In one variant of the narrative, a runaway trolley is about to kill five workers on a track. You are a bystander near a switch that would cause the trolley to change tracks and avoid killing the workers. However, there is one worker on the other track who would be killed. Would you close the switch and kill one person to avoid killing five people? What if you are on an overpass watching the runaway trolley below. You can save the five workers if you throw a fat woman, standing next to you on the overpass, onto the track to stop the trolley. Would you throw the woman onto the tracks? You would kill the woman to save the five workers. Most people surveyed would close the switch to save five people but not physically
throw a person off the overpass to achieve the same result. The reason for this illogical result was philosophically debated extensively, but a scientific experiment provided an explanation. It seems there is a mental distinction, embedded in different areas of the brain, between an intended harmful act involving physical force, like pushing a person off a bridge, and an act in which harm is a side effect, like the result of closing a switch. Functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) indicates that, for most people tested, a part of the brain involved with rationality (the prefrontal cortex) would close the switch, while a part of the brain involved with emotion (the amygdala) would prevent them physically throwing a person off the bridge. Depending on the scenario, one or the other would dominate the decision and determine the consequent act (Greene, 2012). A robot, or autonomous car, could decide the trolley problem or an equivalent encountered in the real world on a purely objective, rational basis. The metrics for determining the rationality of the decision may go beyond a simple numerical head count, to include the value to society of the individuals. Are the deaths of five laborers worth more than the death of one individual who is the 21st century equivalent of Einstein, Newton, Lincoln, or da Vinci? What if the five workers are all single but the person on the bridge is supporting a family of six? What if the five workers are all old but the one individual is young? With the information that it has or can quickly acquire, the robot can swiftly evaluate the alternative decisions against the metrics and make an objective decision. However, the metrics used as the bases for these kinds of decisions need the seeds of wisdom, whether human or machine, for their fruition. Objective decisions, however, may not always be commercially viable. People may avoid buying or riding in autonomous vehicles, or employing autonomous robots, if they felt that, in an emergency, their lives may not be considered as important as others’.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ROBOTICS
The algorithm for determining who should be saved and who should be allowed to die might then be skewed a bit, if not completely, toward the occupants of the vehicle or the owner of the robot, offering a higher probability of surviving an adverse incident. Or autonomous vehicle software may offer alternative algorithms to users, allowing them to select a preference for a higher probability of survival in an accident (i.e., a selfish choice) or survival based on objective criteria, which may provide the passengers with a lower probability (i.e., an altruistic choice). Human psychology again becomes a factor in determining robot psychology. Autonomous robots can know the laws they are required to obey from ‘birth’, as soon as they emerge from the assembly line. The laws may be the same as, or different from, those constraining human behavior. They will be codified rules with specified penalties, but it is likely the penalties will be different for robots. If needed, autonomous robots can have immediate internal or external access to, and knowledge of, all federal, state, and local laws, as well as judicial cases and precedents. However, for a robot to have more than superficial knowledge of lawful behavior, and especially ethical and moral behavior, it will need more than access to a vast knowledgebase – just as humans do. People are born with evolved behavioral rules that can be attributed to a moral and ethical code of conduct, such as manifested in their behavior with parents and siblings. They are not born knowing any societal laws. Robots can be ‘born’ with lots of preprogrammed rules, legal, moral, and ethical. This is a top-down approach to robot behavioral constraints, where rules are pre-encoded in software, like Asimov’s Laws of Robotics. Over the millennia people have devised, for example, the Code of Hammurabi, the Magna Carta, the Ten Commandments, the US Constitution, the Rules of Professional Conduct of the American Bar Association, and the Laws of the State of Maryland.
369
A robot can have knowledge of the local customs of how to set a dining-room table and the proper way to greet guests and offer them refreshments; or how to sell menswear in a retail store without cheating customers. In general, a top-down approach for robot legal, ethical, and moral behavior would require algorithms to guide robot behavior, i.e., the robots would need to know how to apply the rules in any given situation. Programmers cannot foresee every contingency, so the robot must also learn from experience how and when to apply the rules of law, ethics, and morality. Unlike robots, humans cannot be born with these rules implanted in their minds, at least currently. People often have difficulty interpreting these rules and knowing how to behave within their constraints. Many of the rules are not instinctual. They must be acquired through years of experience – the bottom-up approach. The bottom-up approach for robots to master their rules of behavior – legal, ethical, and moral – requires time for them to acquire experience interacting with family, peers, and strangers, as do humans. While the time required to learn from experience may be less than that for humans, it still may take several years. Robots will need a combination of top-down and bottom-up approaches to fully learn the norms, standards, and cultural aspects of moral and ethical behavior as practiced by humans, and the behavior required of robots (Lin et al., 2012). In the bottom-up experiential approach emphasis is placed on creating an environment where the robot explores courses of action and is rewarded for behavior that is legally, ethically, and morally praiseworthy. Thus the robot learns and adapts through its experiences. Unlike the top-down approach, in the bottom-up process the rules are discovered or constructed, not explicitly mandated by fiat. The given behavioral rules, however, serve to provide a framework and a context that guides and simplifies the experiential rule-learning process.
370
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY OF ROBOTS: FUTURE Over the coming decades, to the end of this century, robot intelligence will evolve technologically, a Lamarckian process that, like Darwinian evolution, is likely to be punctuated in its progress, with intervals of relatively fast and slow change. New discoveries and inventions will impact robot software and hardware. Robot intelligence is likely to increase with new algorithms and processors, and robot psychology will evolve. Robot performance is likely to improve with new technology for legs, wheels, arms, hands, and sensors. Robot capabilities in 2099 are unpredictable, except to safely speculate that they will be orders of magnitude greater than they are now. Ubiquitous robots and other intelligent machines can provide humankind with a utopia or dystopia. The technologies of genetics, nanotechnology, and robotics have at least one thing in common – they all offer the possibility of self-replication. Autopoiesis is one potential promise or danger of intelligent machines, whether they are as intelligent as a human or an amoeba, or the size of a human or an amoeba (such as nanobots which will repair damaged organs). The autonomous autopoietic system is self-sustaining through replication, just as organisms have been self-sustaining on Earth for nearly four billion years. The power of replication is astounding: on Earth there is an unbroken chain, sustained through intermittent global catastrophes, for almost a third of the age of the universe; from the first living aggregation of molecules to us. NASA’s astrobiological definition of life is that it is a ‘self-sustained chemical system capable of undergoing Darwinian evolution’. This may be modified to accommodate robotic lifeforms: life is a self-sustained system capable of adapting to a changing environment. Autopoietic robots smart enough to create new technology could hasten the evolution of robot psychology. Robot autopoiesis can be dangerous, but any guidelines, or even laws,
to control the development of self-replicating robots could be intentionally or unintentionally violated, as has happened with genetically modified crops. Before the end of this century, autonomous robots will become ubiquitous. Over the coming decades, scientific discoveries and technological invention from manifold fields could affect the evolution of robot minds. For example, there are thousands of human brain organoids now being grown in nutrient solutions for study, some of them on the International Space Station (Qian et al., 2019; Spectrum, 2019). These were originally human skin cells that were transformed into stem cells, which were transmuted into neurons. The neurons clumped into spherical organoids which formed internal structures like tubes and emitted synchronized neuronal firing patterns. These are not (yet) human brains, but there is some concern that they may become sentient and feel pain, or otherwise suffer. It is easy to imagine that conscious brain organoids might some day be integrated in the brain of a robot, creating a hybrid entity with a mind having both human and machine structure and psychology. Initial experiments linking brain organoids to a robot have already been conducted. A multilegged spider-like robot received neuron signals from a brain organoid causing it to walk. The robot sent sensory information, such as when it encountered a wall, back to the brain organoid. Our minds and their evolved psychology, ‘designed’ over eons for survival in their natural environments, are imperfectly designed to function properly in our current complex societies. Technology helped us survive the nastiness of nature for many millennia. We now need help to survive the nastiness of our human-made environment. Technology will propel the rapid evolution of robot minds and their consequent psychology. Despite the risks, such robots may be the best hope for humanity to alleviate ignorance, poverty, and suffering, and to allow humans to become more humane.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ROBOTICS
REFERENCES Albus, James S. (2001), Engineering of Mind, Presentation based on Albus, James S. and Alexander M. Meystel (2001), Engineering of Mind, New York, NY: John Wiley & Sons, Inc. Albus, James S. and Alexander M. Meystel (2001), Engineering of Mind, John Wiley & Sons, Inc. Ardiel, Evan L. and Catharine H. Rankin (2010), An Elegant Mind: Learning and Memory in Caenorhabditis Elegans, Learning and Memory, Brain Research Centre and Department of Psychology, University of British Columbia, Vancouver, British Columbia V6T 2B5, Canada, 17:191–201 # 2010 Cold Spring Harbor Laboratory Press, ISSN 15495485/10; www.learnmem.org Asimov, Isaac (1950), I Robot, New York, NY: Doubleday. Aunger, Robert (2002), The Electric Meme: A New Theory of How We Think, New York, NY: The Free Press. Ayan, Steve (2018), There Is No Such Thing as Conscious Thought, Scientific American, December 2018. Retrieved from https:// www.scientificamerican.com/article/thereis-no-such-thing-as-conscious-thought/ ?print=true (Accessed 10 July 2020) Bohannon, John (2011), A Time to Kill, J. Science. Retrieved from https://www. sciencemag.org/news/2011/06/time-kill (Accessed 10 July 2020) Brazier, Yvette (2018), All about Narcissistic Personality Disorder, Medical News Today. Retrieved from https://www.medicalnewstoday.com/articles/9741 Brézillon, Patrick (1999), Context in Artificial Intelligence I: A Survey of the Literature, Computers and Artificial Intelligence, 18(4) 1–28. Buss, David M. (2005), (Ed.), The Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology, New Jersey: John Wiley & Sons, Inc. Cartwright, Mark (2013), Prometheus, Ancient History Encyclopedia. Buffalo, NY: Prometheus Books. Damasio, Antonio (2003), Looking for Spinoza: Joy, Sorrow, and the Feeling Brain, New York, NY: Harcourt, Inc. Darley, J. M. and C. D. Batson (1973), From Jerusalem to Jericho: A study of Situational
371
and Dispositional Variables in Helping Behavior, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 27, 100–108. Davis, Lawrence (1991), Editor, Handbook of Genetic Algorithms. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Van Nostrand Reinhold. Durkin, John (1994), Expert Systems: Design and Development, Prentice-Hall, Inc. Edell, Aaron (2018), Recognizing context is still hard in Machine Learning, Towards Data Science. Retrieved from https://towards datascience.com/recognizing-context-is-stillhard-in-machine-learning-heres-how-to-tackleit-ed398a725f8c (Accessed 10 July 2020) Edelman, Gerald M. and Giulio Tononi (2000), A Universe of Consciousness. New York, NY: Basic Books. Evans, Leonard (2008), Death in Traffic: Why Are the Ethical Issues Ignored? Studies in Ethics, Law, and Technology, 2(1). Fisher, Martin Henry (1879–1962), http://libertytree.ca/quotes/Martin.Fischer.Quote.1A58 (Accessed 19 June 2020). Gazzaniga, Michael S. (2011), Who’s in Charge: Free Will and the Science of the Brain, New York, NY: Harper Collins. Goldberg, David E. (1989), Genetic Algorithms in Search, Optimization, and Machine Learning. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley Publishing Co., Inc. Goodfellow, Ian, Yoshua Bengio, and Aaron Couville (2016), Deep Learning, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA. Gould, Stephen Jay (1983), Hen’s Teeth and Horses Toes: Further Reflections in Natural History. New York, N: W.W. Norton & Company, Inc. Graziano, Michael S. (2013), Consciousness and the Social Brain. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Greene, Joshua D. (2012), Solving the Trolley Problem, In Sytsma, Justin and Wesley Buckwalter (2016), (Eds.), A Companion to Experimental Philosophy, pp 175–178. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Hall, Louisa (2017), How We Feel About Robots That Feel, MIT Technology Review. Retrieved from https://www.technologyreview.com/ 2017/10/24/148259/how-we-feel-aboutrobots-that-feel/ (Accessed 10 July 2020) Harris, Sam (2012), Free Will. New York, NY: Free Press.
372
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Hayes-Roth, Frederick, Donald A. Waterman, and Douglas B. Lenat (1983), (Eds.), Building Expert Systems. Reading, MA: AddisonWesley Publishing Co., Inc. Herrman, Andreas, Walter Brenner, and Rupert Stadler (2018), Autonomous Driving: How the Driverless Revolution Will Change the World. Bingley, UK: Emerald Publishing. Hull, David L. (2000), Taking Memetics Seriously: Memetics Will Be What We Make It. In Aunger, Robert, (Ed.), (2000), Darwinizing Culture: The Status of Memetics as a Science, pp. 43–68. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Koch, Christof (2018), What Is Consciousness? Scientific American, pp. 60–64. June 1, 2018. Koza, John R. (1992), Genetic Programming, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA. Krizhevsky, Alex, Ilya Sutskever, and Geoffrey E. Hinton (2012), ImageNet Classification with Deep Convolutional Neural Networks, Proceedings of the 25th International Conference on Neural Information Processing Systems – Volume 1, pp. 1097–1105. LeDoux, Joseph (1996), The Emotional Brain. New York, NY: Simon and Schuster. LeDoux, Joseph E. (2012), Evolution of Human Emotion: A View through Fear, Progress in Brain Research, 195, 431–442. Libet, B. (1993), The Neural Time Factor in Conscious and Unconscious Events, Ciba Foundation Symposium, 174, 123–137; discussion 137–146. Lin, Patrick, Keith Abney, and George A. Bekey (2012), Robot Ethics: The Ethical and Social Implications of Robotics, MIT Press. Cambridge, MA. Lipson, Hod and Melba Kurman (2016), Driverless: Intelligent Cars on the Road Ahead, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA. McCulloch, Warren S. and Walter Pits (1943), A Logical Calculus of the Ideas Immanent in Nervous Activity. In Anderson, James A. and Edward Rosenfeld, (Eds.), (1988), Neurocomputing: Foundations of Research, pp. 18–31. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA. Meystel, Alexander M. and James S. Albus (2002), Intelligent Systems: Architecture, Design, and Control. New York, NY: John Wiley & Sons, Inc. Moore, James H. (2003), Editor, The Turing Test: The Elusive Standard of Artificial
Intelligence (Studies in Cognitive Systems). New York, NY: Kluwer Academic Publishers. National Safety Council (2019), Road to Zero Presents Plan to Eliminate Roadway Deaths. Itasca, IL: Retrieved from https://www.nsc.org/ road-safety/get-involved/road-to-zero. (Accessed 16 April 2019) Qian, Xuyu, Hongjun Song, and Guo-li Ming (2019), Brain Organoids: Advances, Applications and Challenges, Development. 2019 Apr 16;146(8): dev166074. doi: 10.1242/ dev.166074j. Rechavi, Oded (2009), Cell contact-dependent acquisition of cellular and viral nonautonomously encoded small RNAs, Genes & Development, 23(16) 1971–9. doi: 10.1101/ gad.1789609. Schultz, Alan C., John J. Grefenstette, and Kenneth A. De Jong (1993), Test and Evaluation by Genetic Algorithms, IEEE Expert, 8(5) 9–14. October 1993. Shenhav, Amitai and Joshua D. Greene (2010), Moral Judgments Recruit Domain-General Valuation Mechanisms to Integrate Representations of Probability and Magnitude, j. Neuron. 67, 667–677. Smith, Wesley (2019), Eugenics-Engineered Babies’ Brains Changed by CRISPR, National Review, February 21, 2019. Retrieved from https://www.nationalreview.com/corner/ genetic-engineering-crispr-changed-babiesbrains/#:~:text=The%20brains%20of%20 two%20babies,probably%20impacted%20 by%20the%20procedure (Accessed 10 July 2020) Spectrum (2019), Brain organoids show realistic neuronal firing rhythms, Spectrum Research News. Retrieved from https://www.spectrumnews.org/news/brain-organoids-show-realisticneuronal-firing-rhythms/#:~:text=Brain%20 organoids%20made%20from%20 typical,at%20least%20four%20 months1.&text=A%20few%20features%20 of%20the,preterm%20infants%2C%20 the%20researchers%20say (Accessed 10 July 2020) Sternberg, Robert (1995), Editor, Wisdom: Its Nature, Origins, and Developments, New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. Teich, Albert H. (2009), Editor, Technology and the Future, Boston, MA: Wadsworth Cengage Learning.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND ROBOTICS
The Economist (2015), If Autonomous Vehicles Rule the World: From Horseless to Driverless, July 1, 2015. Retrieved from https://worldif. economist.com/article/12123/horselessdriverless (Accessed 10 July 2020) Wallach, Wendell and Collin Allen (2009), Moral Machines: Teaching Robots Right from Wrong. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Wikipedia (2019a), Ford Model T. Retrieved from https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Ford_ Model_T (Accessed 10 July 2020)
373
Wikipedia (2019b), Timeline of Motor Vehicle Brands. Retrieved from https://en.wikipedia. org/wiki/Timeline_of_motor_vehicle_brands (Accessed 10 July 2020) Zaki, Jamil (2013), Using Empathy to Use People: Emotional Intelligence and Manipulation, Scientific American. Retrieved from https:// blogs.scientificamerican.com/moral-universe/ using-empathy-to-use-people-emotionalintelligence-and-manipulation/ (Accessed 10 July 2020)
19 Evolutionary Psychology and Dangerous Driving Behaviour Deanna Singhal and David Wiesenthal
INTRODUCTION
AGGRESSIVE AND RISKY DRIVING
This chapter discusses the contributions of evolutionary psychological and social learning theories to explain aggressive and risky driving. Dangerous driving behaviour may be influenced by a number of factors: ‘the young male syndrome’ and observational learning may contribute to the choice to drive or respond aggressively on the roads. Exposure to media, such as motion pictures and racing video games, can promote the modelling of dangerous driving behaviours. How situational factors interact with personal and internal factors to promote risky driving is discussed within the context of the General Aggression Model (Anderson and Bushman, 2002). A summary of what is known about this topic is provided, including a review of research studies using different methodologies (e.g., laboratory, archival), and considerations for public policy are discussed.
Each driver at some point in their driving experience has likely witnessed, or even engaged in, an act of aggressive or risky driving on the road, such as tailgating, weaving in and out of traffic, running red lights, and driving at excessive speeds. Driving behaviour is considered aggressive if ‘it is deliberate, likely to increase the risk of collision, and is motivated by impatience, annoyance, hostility and/or an attempt to save time’ (Tasca, 2000: 2). It has been suggested that such behaviours can be frustration-driven and are more likely in an enabling environment (Shinar, 1998). Some aggressive driving involves hostile aggression, where the behaviour is directed at an object of frustration (e.g., cursing at another driver), whereas other acts involve instrumental aggression, where the frustrated driver attempts to move ahead at the expense of other drivers’ rights (e.g., weaving in and out of traffic)
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND DANGEROUS DRIVING BEHAVIOUR
(Roseborough, 2014; Shinar, 1998). In the context of evolutionary psychological theory, frustration may not necessarily be the only reason why these driving behaviours occur, as they may involve voluntarily initiated displays of dominance. Males are at a greater risk of motor vehicle collisions than females because they are more likely to be involved in speeding, tailgating, and responding aggressively to perceived misdeeds of other drivers (Wilson and Daly, 1985). The ‘young male syndrome’, coined by Wilson and Daly (1985), refers to the pattern of disproportionate involvement of males in risky or aggressive behaviours, such as gambling, homicide, and motor vehicle collisions. In the context of evolution, aggression can have an adaptive value and, in certain situations, males can perceive a benefit. Competitive risk-taking among males is believed to have evolved as a result of reproductive competition, where males compete with other males for the valued resource of females (Wilson and Daly, 1985). When environmental resources are scarce, or unequally distributed, and when the proportion of young males in the population is large, both risk- taking and aggression increase (Mesquida and Wiener, 1996; Wiesenthal and Singhal, 2012). Females may perceive these behaviours as indicators of a mate who will protect and provide for her and any offspring. These are desired characteristics associated with parental investment (Buss, 1988). Males engage in social displays of risky behaviour in an effort to secure the resources necessary to attract mates. Intra- and intergroup competition, which involves prestige, rank, and reputation, may enhance the likelihood of attracting prospective mates by elevating the male’s position on a dominance hierarchy (Wilson and Daly, 1985). The ability to provide social and psychological resources, in addition to material resources, is considered important for mate selection in females (Buss, 1988). Competition in young males is not restricted to driving scenarios. If society
375
bombarded young males with video games and motion pictures featuring chess-playing scenarios that resulted in rewarding experiences as a result of competitiveness, it seems reasonable to conclude that competition between young males would take place on chess boards rather than streets and highways. Chess is a symbolic or cognitive example of warfare, with males comprising the vast majority of Grandmasters, a title awarded to world-class chess players by the International Chess Federation (FIDE). The most recent FIDE list of Grandmasters includes 1,680 individuals from a variety of countries, 1,643 of which are male (98%) (‘List of chess grandmasters’, n.d.). Evolutionary tendencies are not the only influences on behaviour and the environmental or social exposure to depictions of competition, in various media forms, can serve as representative examples of which behaviours males should engage in and how. The presentation that will follow later in this chapter will review the effects of cinematic portrayals of risky driving. Roadways are a social environment that affords displays of competitive behaviour. When driving, individuals can engage in risk-taking competitiveness (Wiesenthal and Singhal, 2012), particularly among young males, which can contribute to risky or aggressive driving behaviours (Vingilis et al., 2013). An overrepresentation of young males in annual motor vehicle collisions was reported in British Columbia in 2018 (Peng, 2018). In particular, there was a doubling of deaths involving motorcycles, where 27 of the 30 victims were male and a third of all victims were between the ages of 19 and 29 years. Motorcycles may represent a riskier vehicle to drive and, by design, promote risky-driving behaviours, such as speeding. One British Columbian police agency reported a ‘major increase’ in excessive speeding province-wide that was not specific to motorcycles, with 25% more drivers being stopped for this risky behaviour (Peng, 2018). Though no known reasons for these increases were reported,
376
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
previous research has demonstrated that increases in male driving-related fatalities even occurred during a decrease in the male population (Wiesenthal and Singhal, 2012). Though evolutionary psychological theory can make an important contribution to the understanding of risky driving behaviour, societal influences, such as the presence of others and individual difference variables (e.g., personality), interact with male competitiveness and can influence the decision to engage in risk-taking behaviours (Wiesenthal and Singhal, 2012; Wilson and Daly, 1985). An important framework to consider in this context is social learning theory, which suggests that transmission of behaviour can occur through observational learning, where an individual acquires new patterns of behaviour by observation (Bandura, 1971). Media influences on the behaviour of children and adults have long been a research concern in developmental, social, and clinical psychology. The advertising industry is based on the fact that consumers can be influenced by media messages. While most advertising is concerned with altering or influencing relatively trivial consumer behaviours, the material presented in this chapter indicates that media can trigger dangerous and life-threatening actions in predisposed individuals. The novelty, relevance, and consequences of the behaviour play a role in the imitative effects of observation (Bandura, 1971). The term modelling encompasses the broader psychological effects that can occur with observational learning, beyond mere imitation or mimicry (Bandura, 1971). These could include cognitive changes (e.g., in attitudes) that accompany the learning of a behaviour, even if the behaviour was not performed following observation (Modeling, n.d.). Marketing relies upon individuals mimicking the use of products shown in advertising, and uses media to communicate this information. How much alcohol individuals choose to drink, or what they perceive as an ideal body image, is influenced by what they
see and hear on television, in the movies, on the Internet, or in newspapers and magazines (Koordeman et al., 2011; López-Guimerà et al., 2010). Media recognizes this influence and, in some cases, limits what viewers can see, in an attempt to prevent imitation of a behaviour. For example, the Toronto Transit Commission (TTC) has an agreement with local media to not treat subway suicides as newsworthy, in an attempt to prevent imitation. Soon after the adoption of this standard in 1971, the TTC reported a marked decrease in the number of suicides (Toronto Transit Commission, 2010). With respect to road safety, modelling of aggressive or risky driving can occur as a result of observational learning, with media being an influential source. Media depictions of dangerous or aggressive driving and glorifications of such risk-taking have become increasingly popular (Fischer et al., 2012). A pivotal influence was the 1968 release of the motion picture Bullitt. This film featured an exciting car chase, starring Steve McQueen, which involved risky and aggressive driving through the streets of San Francisco (Wiesenthal et al., 2016). A more current driving movie franchise is Fast and Furious, in which entire movies depict acts of illegal street racing and heists. The franchise has grown in popularity since its first movie release, The Fast and the Furious, in June of 2001. This movie grossed approximately two million dollars at the worldwide box office, compared to a more recent franchise instalment, Furious 7, which grossed over one and a half billion dollars worldwide, with an additional 70 million dollars in DVD sales (Nash Information Services, n.d.-c). Depictions of speeding, racing, dangerous passing, and aggressive behaviour towards other drivers are often shown in the absence of negative consequences (Beullens et al., 2011b; Greenberg and Atkin, 1983). According to media effects theory, viewers’ perceptions of what is normal can be influenced by the more frequent portrayal of certain behaviours (Beullens et al., 2011b).
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND DANGEROUS DRIVING BEHAVIOUR
The risky driving behaviours often depicted in media are novel, such that viewers do not commonly see them on the roads (Atkin, 1989). The more normative the events appear, the greater the possibility of viewer disinhibition (Atkin, 1989). Combined with the lack of depiction of negative consequences, learning of aggressive or risky driving may be enhanced (Beullens et al., 2011b). Adding to the possibility of imitation is the portrayal of a hero as the risky driver, which can be attractive to viewers (Beullens et al., 2011b) and creates a scenario in which the behaviour seems justified, further fostering disinhibition (Atkin, 1989). Media which is ‘arousing, nonfictional, justified, positively reinforced, and performed by individuals with whom viewers identify and feel similar’ is the most likely to influence behaviour (Vitaglione, 2012: 489). There is evidence that motion-picture production companies are aware of the possibility of modelling risky and unsafe driving. Prior to the release of The Fast and the Furious in 2001, Universal Studios posted a disclaimer on the film’s promotional website stating, ‘All of the racing stunts in “The Fast and the Furious” were performed in a staged environment by professionals with years of training and experience. Please do not try any of these yourself. Be smart. Drive safe. Stay legal’ (Goldberg, 2001; Orwall, 2001). In the days leading to the film’s release, they also ran two public-service announcements, recorded by the two lead actors in the film, Vin Diesel and Paul Walker, emphasizing safe driving. Given the awareness of possible imitation, it has been said that media is a major part of the problem when imitative behaviour is undesirable or antisocial (Coleman, 2004). Though observational learning can be useful and efficient (i.e., when errors in learning are costly or dangerous or when teaching structured rules and skills is time-consuming and difficult) (Bandura, 1971), modelling behaviour that is risky or aggressive can have serious negative consequences.
377
IMITATION AND MODELLING Social Learning Theory Social learning theory explains the transmission of behaviours. Aggression, like other complex social behaviours, may be imitated as a result of observational learning or direct exposure (Bandura, 1971). Bandura et al.’s (1963a) classic experiment investigated the imitation of aggression in children following the viewing of an adult model interacting with a three-foot Bobo doll. Young children who viewed a video of the model being aggressive towards the doll (e.g., hitting the doll while sitting on it, kicking and throwing it, pummelling it with a mallet), displayed more aggressive acts when allowed to interact with the Bobo doll in a situation of frustration, compared to the control group, who did not view the aggressive model (Bandura et al., 1963a). Though this study has been criticized for considering the acts displayed by the children to be aggressive, given that a Bobo doll is essentially designed to be pummelled (Freedman, 2007; Milgram and Shotland, 1973), it did demonstrate that children imitated specific observed behaviours, both physical (e.g., sitting on Bobo and hitting him with a mallet) and verbal (e.g., shouting ‘Sock him in the nose’) (Bandura et al., 1963a). Other research with children has suggested that early childhood exposure to aggressive or harsh punishment from parents can provide a situation of observational learning and result in aggressive behaviour from children towards others (Weiss et al., 1992). Though the social learning theory of aggression stems from research with children, it has implications for adults. Early exposure to aggression and violence may contribute to children developing different cognitions associated with aggression. For example, they may be more likely to attribute hostile intentions to others’ ambiguous behaviours (i.e., hostile attributional bias; Steinberg and Dodge, 1983). Therefore, they may become more likely to select aggressive
378
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
solutions to situations in the future (Steinberg and Dodge, 1983). In addition, the factors proposed to influence imitation of aggression in a situation of observational learning, specifically positive reinforcement, novelty, and relevance to a given social situation, are not specific to children (Atkin, 1989; Beullens et al., 2011b; Vitaglione, 2012). For example, the internal thrill or the accolades of friends associated with trying an aggressive or risky driving behaviour seen in a movie are examples of positive reinforcement, which can influence this adult behaviour.
Social Interaction Theory According to social interaction theory, aggressive behaviour is social influence behaviour, whereby coercive acts are used to obtain things of value, bring about retributive justice, or promote social and self-identities (Tedeschi and Felson, 1994). Two social influences proposed to mediate aggression are socialization practices within the family and peer influences (Wiesenthal and Singhal, 2012). For example, negative parenting, including poor family organization and functioning, as well as marital conflict, contributes to aggression among adolescents (Talwar, 1998). Children may adopt peer values and beliefs as substitutes for parental values and beliefs. When the peer influence is deviant and the individual is susceptible because of negative family influences, aggression increases (Talwar, 1998). With respect to driving, the presence of others increases aggressive and risky behaviours. Teenage drivers engage in more risky driving (i.e., speeding and reduced headway) with male passengers, compared to no passengers or female passengers, with the male driver/male passenger combination producing approximately double the rate of risky or aggressive driving (Simons-Morton et al., 2005). According to evolutionary psychological theory, intrasexual competition can result in a greater display of desired resources
believed to be important for mate selection (Buss, 1988). The ownership of a fast car and the demonstration of a daring male driver may be perceived as more attractive and dominant than his passenger counterparts. The driver may also be viewed as possessing similar characteristics to those of famous actors portrayed as heroes in risky driving movies, such as wealth and prestige. In addition to the influences of intrasexual competition, peer pressure can influence behaviour, and the susceptibility to this social influence is believed to be greatest during early adolescence (Wilson and Daly, 1985). Full development of resistance to peer pressure does not necessarily occur between late adolescence and early adulthood. During this period of time, young individuals may face other risky behaviour choices, such as drug use and teenage sexual encounters. If young males are already more likely to engage in risky behaviours (Wilson and Daly, 1985), they may be more susceptible to the influence of their peers who encourage participation (Steinberg and Monahan, 2007).
Influence of Behavioural Consequences Research on operant conditioning was rooted in animal behaviour (Skinner, 1938), but consequences associated with an action were proposed to not only predict but also control an individual’s behaviour (Skinner, 1953). In the case of childrearing, for example, reinforcement and punishment are used to teach a child appropriate behaviour. An unwanted behaviour results in a negative consequence, such as a ‘time-out’, while a desired response results in a positive consequence or reward, such as a treat. Research on vicarious learning suggests that observing another individual experience consequences for a behaviour can also influence one’s own behaviour. The influence of observing punishment or reward on the imitation of aggression in children was demonstrated in a follow-up study by
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND DANGEROUS DRIVING BEHAVIOUR
Bandura et al. (1963b). Children who viewed the adult model being punished for aggressive behaviour towards the Bobo doll were less likely to imitate the behaviour than children who viewed the aggressive model being rewarded. In adults, vicarious learning can result in attitude change, as demonstrated in one study where male university students reported being more accepting of interpersonal violence against women following the viewing of movies depicting positive consequences associated with sexual violence (Malamuth and Check, 1981). Though evolutionary psychological theory suggests that males, more than females, have a tendency to engage in aggressive behaviour in order to acquire desired resources (Wilson and Daly, 1985), cognitive behaviourism suggests that individuals have free will to contemplate and incorporate environmental information, such as behavioural consequences of punishment and reward, into decision-making processes related to behaviour choice (Bandura, 2001b). The absence of negative consequences, as observed in many movies depicting risky and aggressive driving, may act as negative reinforcement. When the undesirable consequences of risky driving, such as fines, collision, injury or death, are removed, the driving behaviour will be reinforced and more likely to occur in the future. When such outcomes are commonly depicted in the movies, vicarious learning also contributes to the probability of young males engaging in this driving behaviour in the real world.
The Copycat Effect The copycat effect refers to imitation or adoption of behaviours or practices of another, and its effects, usually negative and unfavourable, are believed to be triggered by media (Coleman, 2004). Phillips (1974) coined the term Werther effect, describing the copycat effect associated with suicide. In the 1774 novel The Sorrows of Young Werther,
379
by Johann Wolfgang von Goethe, the young Werther shoots himself after realizing that he could never be with the woman he loved. In following years, many young men killed themselves in the same manner, sitting at a desk, dressed like Werther, with Goethe’s novel in front of them (Coleman, 2004). To investigate this effect, Phillips recorded the number of monthly suicides in the United States, following the publication of frontpage suicide stories in the New York Times, during the period 1947–1967. Using the previous and subsequent year as a comparison, he found a significant tendency for suicides to increase, and a dose-response relationship between the number of suicides and the amount of front-page story coverage (Phillips, 1974). The influence of the newspaper coverage was location-specific, such that stories published in the New York Times, but not in Great Britain’s most popular newspaper, The London Daily Mirror, resulted in a greater increase in suicides in the United States, compared to Great Britain. However, when the suicide story was covered in both newspapers, British suicides increased significantly (Phillips, 1974). The Werther effect has also been demonstrated for suicide stories covered on network television news programs. For example, in California, between 1968 and 1985, the number of suicides significantly increased 0–7 days after a publicized television story (Phillips and Carstensen, 1988). The effect of this coverage can also be influenced by the involvement of a celebrity. In Korea, between 2005 and 2008, television news coverage of a celebrity suicide increased the number of emergency department visits associated with suicide attempts or self-injury in the three weeks following the reported suicide (Jeong et al., 2012). The method of suicide used by celebrities can also be imitated, as was demonstrated following the 2009 railway suicide of Robert Enke, a celebrated German football goalkeeper. German railway suicides increased both in the short term (i.e., two weeks following the event) and in
380
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
the long term (i.e., two years after the event) (Hegerl et al., 2013). A significant association between frequency of Google searches for ‘Enke’ and frequency of railway suicides in Germany was documented (Koburger et al., 2015), suggesting a media influence on this copycat behaviour. However, it was not possible to determine if those who committed suicide had experienced the media exposure. The copycat effect can also involve criminal behaviour. Copycat crime refers to imitative behaviour where an offence, originally portrayed in the media, is subsequently performed in reality. It can be motivated by real or fictional media depictions, and the offender incorporates aspects of the original crime (Helfgott, 2015). The 1994 film Natural Born Killers has been linked to over a dozen copycat crimes (Helfgott, 2015). The film depicts a young, attractive couple on a roadtrip/serial-mass-murder spree across the Southwestern United States, during which they kill over 50 people. Some couples, who committed similar murders, reported being obsessed with the movie and copied behaviours depicted in the film during their crimes. In one copycat case, the young woman lured her victim to his death by promising sex, replicating a scene in the movie. Many examples of copycat crime have been described, each with its own unique media source, such as the news coverage of the Columbine school shooting. It has been suggested that the link between viewing media violence and violent crime is difficult to establish because of the other factors that contribute to the behaviour (e.g., individual, environmental, and situational elements; Helfgott, 2015). Though it may be difficult to establish cause-andeffect links, later material in this chapter summarizes research that establishes relationships between viewing aggressive and risky driving media and engagement in these behaviours. With respect to movie content, there is anecdotal evidence supporting the copycat effect. In 1993, Disney made a controversial
decision to remove a scene from their movie The Program (Pristin and Fox, 1993). The scene depicted an inebriated college football quarterback lying in the middle of the highway, with cars passing by, barely missing him. As the scene continued, other football players joined him and no one was hurt. Disney’s decision to remove the scene came after two reported attempts of imitation in New Jersey and Pennsylvania (Kotzen, 2013). One teenager was killed and two others were seriously injured (Pristin and Fox, 1993). Television and social media are sources that can also contribute to the modelling of driving behaviour. Bird Box, a Netflix movie released in 2018 (IMDb, 2018), contains scenes of individuals manoeuvring through their environment blindfolded to avoid seeing a presence that urges them to commit suicide when observed. This includes scenes of driving in a vehicle with all windows covered in tape. The ‘Bird Box Challenge’ became a social media craze that encouraged people to try everyday tasks blindfolded (Deb, 2019). Police in Utah had to issue a warning to its citizens not to drive blindfolded. Though this would seem obvious to most, the warning was issued after a female teenage driver, with a hat pulled over her eyes, drove into oncoming traffic and hit another car (‘US driver’, 2019). In California, following the release of The Fast and the Furious, the Los Angeles Police Department increased patrols to stop street racing (Goldberg, 2001). Supporting their action was the knowledge that copycat behaviour had occurred in their area following the release of Gone in 60 Seconds, which glamorized auto theft. On the day of this film’s release, and the day after, the number of stolen vehicles in the area more than doubled, compared to the previous two years (Goldberg, 2001). Increased enforcement was also reported for the release of the fourth instalment of the Fast and Furious franchise in 2006, The Fast and The Furious: Tokyo Drift (Rowland, 2006). California Highway Patrol reported being extra vigilant during
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND DANGEROUS DRIVING BEHAVIOUR
this time in stopping any unsafe or illegal driving, such as street racing or speed contests (Rowland, 2006). Increased enforcement was also reported in Toronto for the release of this film, with cruisers positioned outside theatres near highways (Grewal and Brennan, 2006). The Ontario Provincial Police reported witnessing copycat behaviour and resulting crashes following the release of the previous Fast and Furious film, TurboCharged Prelude. They expressed the opinion that young people get caught up in the excitement and adrenaline of these films and attempt to imitate their heroes (Grewal and Brennan, 2006). Mass media is a source of social or situational influence on aggressive or risk-taking behaviour (Bandura et al., 1963a; Bushman, 1995; Eron et al., 1972; Paik and Comstock, 1994; Vitaglione, 2012). In the context of driving, when a driver speeds and weaves in and out of traffic, following the viewing of a movie that depicted such behaviour, they are not necessarily being violent or wanting to harm other drivers, but their risky and aggressive behaviour increases the likelihood of collision (Transport Canada, 2011), putting others at risk. Depictions of patterns of aggressive behaviours can teach behaviour styles, alter restraints on the behaviour, desensitize an individual to aggression, and shape the viewer’s perceptions, which are important bases for individual behaviour (Grey et al., 1989). Clearly, there are multiple factors that can contribute to driving aggressively or engaging in risky driving behaviours. Evolutionary psychological theory suggests the importance of personal factors, such as age and sex differences, and social learning theory emphasizes the need to consider situational factors in the environment. In the context of aggression, Anderson and Bushman (2002) developed the General Aggression Model (GAM), which addresses how these, and other factors, can interact to produce aggressive behaviour. This model can serve as a basis for better understanding aggressive or risky driving.
381
GENERAL AGGRESSION MODEL The GAM (Anderson and Bushman, 2002) is a multifaceted approach to explaining aggressive behaviour, incorporating aspects from social and evolutionary theories, as well as components related to personality, cognition, and arousal. It is an episodic model that focuses on the individual in a particular situation and consists of three overall components: inputs involving person and situation factors, routes through which arousal, affect, and cognition play a role, and outcomes resulting from appraisal and decision processes (Anderson and Bushman, 2002). Person factors include things such as age, sex differences in aggressive tendencies, and personality traits. Physical and verbal aggression, hostility, and anger can be intercorrelated and suggest overall trait aggressiveness, indicating that people who are angry are more likely to aggress (Buss and Perry, 1992). Sex differences have been reported using the Aggression Questionnaire, such that males have a higher total score, are much more physically and verbally aggressive, and are somewhat more hostile than females (Buss and Perry, 1992). Sensation seeking refers to the need and willingness to engage in novel events that are highly arousing, even if they involve physical and social risk (Zuckerman, 1979). It is related to risky behaviours, such as dangerous driving (e.g., drunk driving and speeding) (Wiesenthal et al., 2016), drug use, and minor criminality (Arnett, 1994). It has been suggested that sensation seekers, having greater acceptance or reduced perception of risk, are more likely to engage in behaviours that are both risky and aggressive (Wiesenthal et al., 2016). Sensation seeking can serve as a biological predisposition that interacts with the conditions of the social environment, such that less restrictive environments allow for its greater expression (Arnett, 1994). In the context of evolutionary psychological theory, both trait aggression and sensation
382
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
seeking may benefit males in the context of intrasexual competition for mates. Displays of aggression and willingness to take risks may present as qualities of an individual who will protect and provide for a female and their offspring. Mate-selection criteria for females include characteristics that demonstrate potential for parental investment, such as protection, social status, and the ability to provide food and shelter (Buss, 1988). Males who display the ability to provide social, psychological, and material resources may be considered more desirable by females and will compete strongly to demonstrate these characteristics. Displays of these characteristics do not require direct combat nor contact with competitors, but males may engage in representative behaviours at the expense of others who are competing for females (Buss, 1988). Situational factors, such as aggressive cues (e.g., weapons), provocation, frustration, and social opportunity for aggression (e.g., church versus nightclub), interact with the individual’s internal state. These can influence affect, arousal, and cognition, which are interconnected, and can influence each other in a reciprocal fashion (Anderson and Bushman, 2002). The existence of memory scripts can increase the likelihood of modelling aggressive behaviour. A script is a type of schema that is learned through experience and exposure, and comes to define a situation. Highly associated concepts are linked together in memory and these associations often involve causal links, goals, and action plans (Abelson, 1981). For example, the use of a gun can be associated with concepts such as anger, pain, retaliation, and the action of shooting (Anderson and Bushman, 2002). When components are strongly linked, they become a unitary concept in semantic memory and provide a guide for future behaviour. The greater the exposure to the behaviour, the greater the priming of these scripts, increasing the likelihood of their use. The use of memories in the decision to engage in aggressive behaviour is incorporated
in the broader cognitive neoassociation theory of aggression. Berkowitz (2012) states that the decision to act aggressively can begin with an aversive event, such as frustration or provocation. This leads to negative affect, which automatically stimulates both fight and flight physiological pathways. A dominant fight reaction leads to irritation or anger, whereas a dominant flight reaction leads to fear. In addition to the activation of the physiological components of these pathways, associated memories, thoughts, and motor responses will also be activated. Once the initial, more involuntary response tendencies arise, higher-order cognition can become involved in the processing of appraisals and attributions, as well as the consideration of rules and consequences associated with certain behaviour. These can modify or even extinguish the initial reaction, serving as selfregulation or control processes. However, it is possible that an individual can become angry enough to respond aggressively, without the intervention of higher-order cognition (Berkowitz, 2012). The physiological excitation produced from a given arousal-producing exposure, as mentioned in the cognitive neoassociation theory, does not necessarily end abruptly with the termination of the exposure (Zillmann, 1971). The arousal may linger for some time and be carried over to a subsequent event or experience, even one unrelated to the prior exposure. This residual arousal can influence the cognitive appraisal of the subsequent emotional state, with greater residual arousal creating a more intense subsequent emotion. This suggests that a potentially stronger negative affect could be elicited by a provoking event, producing an ‘over-intense’ response to stimuli in a future scenario. The residual arousal could ‘energize’ or facilitate associated aggressive behaviour (Zillmann, 1971). The idea of interaction and reciprocity between person, situation, and internalstate factors was also suggested by Bandura (2001b) in his Triadic Reciprocal Causation model of psychosocial functioning. This
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND DANGEROUS DRIVING BEHAVIOUR
model includes personal, behavioural, and environmental determinants, where personal factors involve cognitive, affective, and biological events. These determinants can influence each other in a bidirectional fashion. For example, an event in the environment, such as viewing an aggressive driving movie, can influence behavioural patterns of the viewer, with past behavioural patterns and person factors, such as mood and personality, mediating the choice of response. The output level of the GAM involves appraisal and decision processes, which can lead to either impulsive or thoughtful action (Anderson and Bushman, 2002). For the response to be a more thoughtful action, one requires sufficient time and cognitive capacity to reappraise the situation. Alternative responses are considered until one is chosen, but this does not imply that aggression has been averted. In fact, it is suggested that the reappraisal process could activate memories leading to an increase in anger, which could provide justification for retaliation and interfere with other higher-order cognitive processing. Additionally, the individual could become more aware of potential damage to their social image and the need to act aggressively in order to maintain it (Anderson and Bushman, 2002). Related to the output level of the GAM, Bandura (2001b) proposed that ‘human agency’ (i.e., using action to intentionally make things happen) involves both selfreactiveness and self-reflectiveness. The first involves individuals monitoring their own behaviour and being aware of the conditions under which it is produced (i.e., cognitive and environmental). The second is an individual’s higher metacognitive ability to reflect on and evaluate their actions, considering the effects, not only for themselves, but also for others. In a social context, when one encounters a situation that is provoking, exciting, aggressive, or risky, the GAM suggests there are a number of factors that will influence an individual’s choice to respond with an aggressive or risky behaviour. The recent viewing of
383
media depicting this behaviour is a situational factor that can influence the internal state. It can increase arousal and influence affect and cognition, partly through the priming of existing memory scripts associated with aggressive or risky behaviour or the formation of new scripts through observational learning. In this context, media can play an influential role in one’s choice to engage in aggression. Figure 19.1 shows how the GAM factors can interact and influence the modelling of aggressive or risky driving behaviour. Elements of the ‘young male syndrome’ contribute to person factors. Drivers who are young, male, and have higher levels of sensation seeking and trait aggression may be more susceptible to the situational factors of media exposure to aggressive or risky driving content and driving scenarios that involve frustration, provocation, and competition. Sensation seeking has been shown to be a significant predictor of aggressive and risky driving, including the physical and verbal expression of driver anger and using the vehicle to express anger. It was also predictive of lapses in concentration and minor losses of vehicular control (Dahlen et al., 2005). In the context of intrasexual competition, males may engage in displays of risky and aggressive driving in an attempt to display characteristics that females desire in a mate, such as social status and the ability to protect and provide for a family. Males may emulate the revered actors portraying the onscreen heroes in an attempt to model such adaptive traits. Arousal produced from viewing a film involving aggressive or risky driving may create stronger aggressive emotional responses when the driver is later confronted with an anger-provoking situation on the road. This is particularly true if memory scripts for this behaviour already exist. The more one views media depicting acts of aggressive or risky driving, the more likely memory scripts will form, associating negative emotion and aggressive driving responses with provoking or frustrating driving situations. This contributes
384
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Figure 19.1 GAM factors included in the investigation of modelling of aggressive or risky driving
to the formation of driver anger and driver vengeance, where drivers more readily choose aggressive responses in certain driving situations (e.g., being cut off by another driver).
TYPES OF MEDIA DEPICTING AGGRESSIVE OR RISKY DRIVING Various forms of aggressive or risky driving media can influence behaviour, including television, video games, movies, and the Internet. Research has specifically assessed the magnitude of this content in the media. During the years 1975 to 1980, it was estimated that within 784 driving scenes analysed from primetime broadcasts of popular television programmes, there were 1,301 acts of irregular driving, with the most common acts being speeding, quick braking, squealing
brakes, tires screeching, and quick acceleration (Greenberg and Atkin, 1983). These acts were estimated to be shown seven times per hour, and drivers were predominantly young males, rarely wearing seat belts, who engaged in irregular and dangerous driving acts that rarely resulted in negative consequences (e.g., death or injury, physical damage, or legal penalties; Greenberg and Atkin, 1983). A form of television programming specific to driving is automobile commercials. Between the years of 1998 and 2002, it was estimated that 45% of North American automobile and truck commercials (n = 349) displayed unsafe driving (Shin et al., 2005). Aggressive driving behaviour accounted for more than 80% of that content, with high speeds constituting the majority (Shin et al., 2005). Between the years of 2006 and 2007, it was found that approximately 20% of 200 Canadian automobile advertisements (i.e., television, magazine,
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND DANGEROUS DRIVING BEHAVIOUR
and newspaper) included some form of unsafe driving, such as speeding or hard stops (Watson et al., 2010). Considering television commercials only, because of their ability to display motion, it was estimated that 20% contained depictions of speed. In each television advertisement in which speeding was displayed, a disclaimer was also presented, demonstrating the vehicle manufacturer’s awareness of the unsafe or questionable driving displayed (Watson et al., 2010). One type of televised event suggested to clearly depict aggressive or risky driving is competitive automobile racing within NASCAR (National Association for Stock Car Racing), which has an estimated 75 million fans viewing these events each year, and tens of thousands attending in person (Vitaglione, 2012). Dangerous and risky driving is broadcast live and is encouraged and reinforced by both cheering fans and large monetary rewards. For example, the total purse for the 2015 Daytona 500 (the last year purse data was publicly available) was approximately $18 million. The winner received $1,581,453 and the last-place driver (i.e., the loser) still took home $262,390 (Mensching, 2015). The celebratory nature surrounding awarding the winner with large sums of money creates an air of acceptance of the behaviour and a ‘hero’ for the fans. This combination has the capacity to increase the possibility of modelling the aggressive or risky driving behaviour (Atkin, 1989; Beullens et al., 2011b). Popular action movies can contain scenes of aggressive or risky driving. Of 26 action movies shown in Belgium between 2005 and 2006 (e.g., War of the Worlds, Casino Royale, and The Fast and the Furious: Tokyo Drift), there were 287 driving scenes, with 129 depicting risky driving (Beullens et al., 2011b). Frequently occurring risky driving behaviours were speeding, tires screeching, brakes squealing, and quick braking or sudden decreases in speed. Risks associated with such driving behaviours were rarely shown. Approximately one-third were followed by a crash and showed the endangering vehicle, or its surroundings,
385
being damaged. In none of the scenes were legal penalties shown. Risky drivers tended to be young males and lead characters, who were the heroes in the movie (Beullens et al., 2011b). These individuals can be perceived by young male viewers as successful, strong, and dominant characters who serve as models, guiding them in how they should look and behave in order to achieve similar status. The popularity of social media, specifically YouTube, in the context of media depictions of aggressive or risky driving has been addressed (Vingilis et al., 2017). On this website, individuals can create a free account, post videos, and view others’ videos. Using the search term ‘street racing’, over 33 million videos were found (as of April 30, 2015) and, of the 10 most popular (i.e., averaging approximately 787,677 views), nine were on public roads, not racetracks. Searching terms of other risky driving behaviours, such as ‘burnouts’ or ‘drifting’, found similar results. The availability of this information on the Internet is evident, but who is watching these videos, and how they influence driving behaviour, is not known, given the lack of research on this specific type of media (Vingilis et al., 2017). A body of research, using various methodologies, has demonstrated that risk-glorifying media, some including content depicting acts of aggressive and risky driving, has the capacity to increase risk-promoting cognitions, arousal, affect, willingness to take risks in observed driving scenarios, and risky driving behaviour. These effects have been shown to last 24 hours, and even as long as several days, with some of the research demonstrating intervening variables of sex differences and personality traits of sensation seeking and aggressiveness.
RESEARCH ON THE INFLUENCE OF MEDIA ON MODELLING AGGRESSIVE OR RISKY DRIVING Various research methods have been used to investigate the influence of media on
386
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
modelling aggressive or risky driving. These include qualitative techniques (e.g., metaanalyses, surveys, correlation, and time series) and quantitative techniques (e.g., experimental studies). In a meta-analysis involving 88 empirical studies investigating the effects of different types of risk-glorifying media on cognitions, affect, and behaviours, small to moderate effects were found (Fischer et al., 2011). These effects were documented across all types of research designs (e.g., experimental, longitudinal, correlational) and for both males and females, though the effects were larger for males and younger participants (i.e., less than 24 years old). The largest effects were found when the stimuli in the risk-glorifying media matched the context of the response measured (e.g., risky driving behaviour was most strongly influenced by risky driving media) and when the media exposure was active versus passive (i.e., engaging in video game play versus viewing media; Fischer et al., 2011). The Entertainment Software Association (ESA) estimates that more than 164 million Americans play video games, with an estimated 60% of gamers being male (ESA, 2019a). One study surveyed over 4,000 US high school students, aged 14 to 18 years, and found the estimated proportion of male gamers to be as high as 75% (Desai et al., 2010). The popularity of this industry is reflected in its 2019 generated revenue, estimated to be over $43 billion in the United States and $135 billion globally (ESA, 2019a). Grand Theft Auto V was the third-best-selling video game of 2017 (ESA, 2019b), suggesting that a large proportion of young males are engaging in gaming content that promotes aggressive and risky driving behaviours. Active engagement in aggressive and risky driving video games has been found to influence arousal levels and risk-promoting cognitions. Driving games, such as Need for Speed, Burnout, and Midnight Racer require ‘massive’ violations of traffic rules to win (Fischer et al., 2007). A 20-minute session of playing these games was shown to produce
higher levels of self-reported arousal and more risk-related cognitions, compared to a control group who played more neutral games, such as Tak, Crash Bandicoot or FIFA 2005 (Fischer et al., 2007). No sex differences were demonstrated, which suggests this media content influenced males and females in the same manner. These games were also shown to influence behaviour more specific to driving, as measured with the Vienna RiskTaking Test. Males demonstrated greater risk-taking behaviour than females, as indicated by longer reaction times to abort risky driving manoeuvres depicted in video clips (Fischer et al., 2007). The influence of video game exposure on this task was also demonstrated to last a period of 24 hours (Fischer et al., 2009). Racing or ‘drive ‘em up’ video games are accessible and can be played by young individuals who have never experienced driving in the real world. This could influence their perception of risk on the roads and contribute to the formation and use of memory scripts associated with risky driving behaviour. In one study, unlicensed adolescents indicated how often they played racing video games (e.g., Gran Turismo, Burnout) and then, two years later, as licensed drivers, indicated their risk-taking attitudes and self-reported driving behaviour for speeding, fun riding, and drinking and driving (Beullens et al., 2011a). Even after controlling for measured personality traits of sensation seeking and aggression, video game playing was a significant predictor of positive attitudes and actual selfreported driving behaviour related to speeding and fun riding. Video game playing was a significant predictor of self-reported speeding only in males, suggesting there may be moderating effects of sex on specific aggressive or risky driving behaviours. Video game playing was not associated with positive attitudes towards drinking and driving nor with more self-reported drinking and driving, suggesting the modelling was specific to the content of the media to which the participant was exposed (Beullens et al., 2011a).
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND DANGEROUS DRIVING BEHAVIOUR
The influence of more passive types of media (i.e., movies and television) on the modelling of aggressive or risky driving has also been studied. Early exposure to reckless driving (e.g., fast, careless) depicted in movies was found to influence adolescents’ self-reported driving behaviour four years later (Kostermans et al., 2014). Selfreport of unsafe driving behaviours included exceeding the speed limit, weaving in and out of traffic, and driving without a seatbelt fastened. Higher levels of sensation seeking, measured using the Arnett Inventory of Sensation Seeking (Arnett, 1994), were also found to be a significant predictor of reckless driving. Males with higher sensation seeking were more likely to report driving without the use of a seatbelt, compared to females or those with lower levels of sensation seeking (Kostermans et al., 2014). Self-reporting of driving behaviour, particularly behaviours considered aggressive or risky, may not produce accurate results. Participants may alter their responses to appear more socially desirable, which could produce under-reporting of aggressive or risky behaviour (e.g., more acceptable to society as a whole), as well as over-reporting (e.g., an attempt to match a personal ideal of a ‘cool’ driver within a social circle of friends). Simulated driving has been used to investigate the effects of watching risk- glorifying media on subsequent driving behaviour. In one study, participants watched either a risk-promoting movie scene (e.g., a segment from a James Bond movie), or a neutral scene from a local talk show, and then drove on a simulator within the context of the racing video game Need for Speed (Fischer et al., 2008). Controlling for experience with racing games, significant differences were found, such that the risk-promoting condition produced higher maximum speeds and more collisions for both males and females, and less time to complete the entire course for males (Fischer et al., 2008). Though this experimental research used a measure closer to realistic driving (i.e., Vienna Risk-Taking
387
Test) and controlled the exposure to riskglorifying media, the media content was not specific to aggressive or risky driving behaviours. Additionally, the simulated driving was in the context of a racing video game, which could have influenced participants’ behaviour through expectations of performance and a lower perceived risk for driving aggressively. Lastly, this research did not consider other mediating factors of arousal, sensation seeking, trait aggression, or driving history. Using archival data in the context of a descriptive research approach, Vitaglione (2012) analysed aggressive driving accident reports (i.e., needless dangerous behaviours or increased risk of harm to other drivers), in relation to the timing of televised NASCAR events. West Virginia was selected as the test state because it was ranked first in the United States for the number of NASCAR fans per capita and it does not have its own NASCAR track (i.e., the predominant source of viewing of these events is television). A period of one week surrounding each of the 156 broadcasted NASCAR events, between 2003 and 2006, was used to investigate the cumulative modelling effects of mass media viewing of aggressive driving. This included the day before the event, the day of the event, and was limited to the five days immediately following the event, since NASCAR races could occur within one week of each other. Using a time-series regression analysis, the rate of accidents and injuries due to aggressive driving was regressed onto NASCAR dates (Vitaglione, 2012). The number of aggressive driving accidents significantly decreased on the day of the NASCAR events, possibly because fans were watching the televised event and not engaging in much driving that day (Vitaglione, 2012). Both accidents and injuries due to aggressive driving significantly increased on the fifth day following the event, but not immediately following the race. During this same time period, alcohol-related accidents and injuries did not change in the same way, suggesting the specific media content was
388
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
associated with the m odelling of specific risky and aggressive driving behaviours (Vitaglione, 2012). The delay in the effects of the media content may have been due to resulting arousal from viewing a NASCAR race becoming associated with dangerous or aggressive driving behaviours over time (Vitaglione, 2012). In the context of the GAM, the more an individual watches these races, the stronger the links become between arousal and associated aggressive memories, which include thoughts, feelings, and behaviours. When an individual experiences similar arousal in a driving scenario, as the result of provocation, the associated aggressive driving memory script may be activated or primed and become consciously accessible. It may require a number of days for these to be sufficiently activated in order to facilitate dangerous and risky driving (Vitaglione, 2012). However, an alternative explanation is that more immediate risky and aggressive driving behaviour was occurring, but drivers had escaped undetected until the passage of time, resulting in an accident or injury days later. Therefore, the measure used in this research was not sensitive enough to detect more immediate modelling effects (e.g., speeding) of this aggressive or risky driving media content. The United States National Highway Traffic Safety Administration suggested that excessive speeding be included in the definition of aggressive driving, following consensus among focus-group participants who considered it aggressive, as well as aggressive drivers’ confessions of speeding more frequently (Tasca, 2000). Though the intent of speeding behaviour may not always be known, the act of speeding has been used in research as a measure of risky driving (Iversen and Rundmo, 2002; Jonah et al., 2001; SimonsMorton et al., 2005) and it is considered a frequent antecedent behaviour to accident or collision (Transport Canada, 2011). Building on the descriptive research approach of Vitaglione (2012), Singhal (2018) used archival speeding infraction data from Edmonton, Alberta, to investigate whether
increases in this specific risky driving behaviour occurred following the theatrical release of two Fast and Furious franchise movies, Fast and Furious 6 and Furious 7. Not all aggressive or risky driving results in an accident or collision, and, therefore, using the measure of speeding may produce a more accurate estimate of the amount of aggressive or risky driving on the roads following such media exposure. Both Fast and Furious movies contain content that focused on aggressive or risky driving (i.e., car chases, racing, excessive speeding) and had a large viewership, based on their domestic box office performance (approximately $239 and $353 million, respectively) (Nash Information Services, n.d.-a). Pre-movie-release speeding behaviour was compared to post-movie-release speeding behaviour, with an emphasis on assessing effects immediately following movie release. A four-week post-movie-release period was selected and compared to a four-week premovie-release period. These time periods were selected based on the steep trend in the domestic box office profits for the first 30 days post movie release (Singhal, 2018). Figure 19.2 shows the daily cumulative domestic box office for the eight Fast and Furious movies (Nash Information Services, n.d.-a). The dotted line estimates the point at which the movies had played in theatres for approximately 30 days. Speeding infractions surrounding the release dates of Fast and Furious 6 and Furious 7 (May 24, 2013 and April 3, 2015, respectively) were provided by the Office of Traffic Safety in Edmonton, Alberta. All infractions included in the study were a result of automated enforcement using stationary cameras (i.e., photo radar). These cameras were permanently mounted, operating 24 hours a day, seven days a week, which ensured stable enforcement schedules over the selected time periods. The close proximity of cameras to theatres (i.e., five kilometres) allowed for the assessment of more immediate modelling effects of movie
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND DANGEROUS DRIVING BEHAVIOUR
389
Figure 19.2 Domestic box-office history for the Fast and Furious movies
content, though it was understood that closer distances were confounded with time (i.e., speeding detected closer to a theatre could also reflect speeding which occurred a short time after movie viewing). Infractions were issued to the registered owner of the vehicle, rather than the driver, since only the vehicle was identified as being involved in the offence. Unfortunately, personal identifiers, revealing driver and vehicle characteristics, were not available in this study, limiting the investigation of how these factors influence speeding behaviour (Singhal, 2018). An interrupted time-series approach was used to assess whether movie release was related to increases in speeding. The speeding infraction data were linked in time, such that data points were recorded consecutively on a daily basis. The interrupted approach allowed for the specification of the movie release date as a possible intervention in the time series, investigating whether changes in this driving behaviour occurred. Coding of specific days and intervention time periods (e.g., first weekend post movie release) was used to assess patterns of behaviour change post-intervention. Other variables of daily
precipitation (mm) and traffic volume were included in the analyses (Singhal, 2018), due to their influence on speeding (World Health Organization, 2004). Results revealed increases in aggressive or risky driving behaviour (i.e., speeding) when Furious 7 was released and playing in theatres. Significant increases in speeding infractions were found specifically for the first weekend (i.e., opening weekend) and the first week, post movie release. A significant increase in mean speed differential was also found for the first weekend, which means that not only did the number of speeding infractions increase, but also the speed at which drivers were caught speeding was greater. These effects were significant even after controlling for precipitation, traffic volume, Saturdays, Sundays, and autocorrelation in the data. This timeline of change was different from that reported for aggressive driving accidents following exposure to televised NASCAR races (Vitaglione, 2012), which, as mentioned previously, was likely due to the use of a more sensitive measure of modelling aggressive or risky driving (Singhal, 2018).
390
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Though Furious 7 was released during an Easter holiday, comparison analyses, using time periods surrounding the previous two Easter holidays, failed to demonstrate the same significant changes in speeding infractions and mean speed differential, during the post-period. Overall, these results suggest that early modelling effects of aggressive driving (i.e., speeding) can occur following the release of movies containing aggressive or risky driving content (Singhal, 2018). Similar modelling effects were not found for Fast and Furious 6, but the difference in domestic and worldwide box office gross (Nash Information Services, n.d.-c n.d.-a) suggests Furious 7 had a greater viewership (Singhal, 2018). Also, Furious 7 received greater news coverage due to the accidental death of one of the lead actors (Paul Walker) prior to the completion of filming his role in Furious 7 (Ying, 2015). Walker was killed in a high-speed collision unrelated to the movie production. Curiosity surrounded how the director would handle the actor’s death in the movie and the ongoing storyline of the franchise. Even though the more recent franchise instalment Fate of the Furious broke the global box office record for an opening weekend (April 14, 2017) (Nash Information Services, n.d.-b), it did not surpass the domestic box office gross for the opening weekend of Furious 7 (approximately $98 million compared to $147 million; Nash Information Services, n.d.-d). To further demonstrate the capacity of aggressive or risky driving content to influence the modelling of this driving behaviour, Singhal (2018) used an experimental research approach that incorporated multiple intervening factors together in a single study. University students were exposed to one of three video clips, which differed in the level of aggressive and risky driving content or arousal, and then drove through a set course on a simulator. Measures of speed, acceleration, and overtaking or passing actions were used to assess risky driving, and individual factors of age, sex, sensation seeking, trait
aggression, driver anger, driver vengeance, driving history, and movie and video game history were also included in the analyses (Singhal, 2018). Significant differences in aggressive or risky driving behaviour as a function of video condition were not found, though differences were in the expected direction (e.g., higher mean speed, shorter time to completion, and greater passing frequency). Some issues suggested to account for the lack of statistical significance were the use of videos with low plot content, a driving simulator test course with too few opportunities for speeding, and the viewing of movie content in an experimental context and not a typical social environment, such as a theatre with friends (Singhal, 2018). No sex differences were found for the behavioural measures of aggressive driving and it was suggested that the lower number of male than female participants may have contributed (i.e., a ratio of 1:2) (Singhal, 2018). Personality factors of higher trait aggression and sensation seeking were related to more aggressive and risky driving. In addition, those with higher driving vengeance and a history of violations, particularly speeding, engaged in more aggressive and risky driving, particularly during a provoking racing scenario in which two sports cars chased one another. Given that the majority of violations reported were for speeding, this suggested that drivers with a history of speeding were more influenced by environmental cues promoting this behaviour (Singhal, 2018). These findings support the interactivity of internalstate and situation factors associated with aggressive driving, specifically the contribution of personality factors and aggressivepromoting driving cognition (i.e., driving vengeance) on the choice to drive aggressively or with greater risk. Individuals with these characteristics may be more susceptible to aggressive and risky driving content in movies. Higher levels of sensation seeking and trait aggression were both related to higher levels of driving anger, driving vengeance,
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND DANGEROUS DRIVING BEHAVIOUR
and number of violations, suggesting these personality factors played a role in aggressive driving cognition and behaviour. Sensation seeking was also positively correlated with the number of aggressive driving movies viewed in the past two years and the greater viewing of these movies was associated with higher levels of driving vengeance, which was related to more violations (Singhal, 2018). Some future research questions that arise from the Singhal (2018) studies include the longevity or duration of the cinematic influences and whether generalization occurs, such that risky behaviours manifest in other realms. For example, will drivers who speed after viewing Fast and Furious movies now swim further from shore or be predisposed to gambling or engaging in risky sex when the situation presents itself?
THEORIES OF MODELLING OF AGGRESSION REVISITED The results of the two studies by Singhal (2018) offer support to theories of modelling aggression and contribute to a better understanding of how aggressive and risky driving occurs. Both studies support the social learning theory of modelling aggression (Bandura, 1971). Evidence of greater speeding surrounding the release of Furious 7 suggested that the modelling of aggressive or risky driving behaviour was associated with the release of this movie, which portrayed this behaviour being performed by a relatable ‘hero’ and, predominantly, in the absence of negative consequences. Trends in the second study provided support for this theory of modelling aggression, though differences between the video conditions were not significant. It is important to consider that these studies used different cohorts (i.e., speed violators versus undergraduate psychology research pool participants). The speed violators in the first study would have been more likely to possess the characteristics found in
391
the second study to contribute to aggressive or risky driving (e.g., higher trait aggression, sensation seeking, and driving vengeance). Demographics were not known for the speed violators, but, according to the evolutionary theory of modelling aggression (Mesquida and Wiener, 1996; Vingilis et al., 2013; Wiesenthal and Singhal, 2012; Wilson and Daly, 1985), the majority of these individuals were likely young males, who experienced a higher level of anonymity on the roads, compared to driving in a laboratory setting. Findings associated with higher levels of sensation seeking suggest that these personality types may seek out and view more aggressive and risky driving movies. This, in turn, contributes to the formation of aggressive and risky driving scripts, which can produce certain susceptibilities for the activation of these scripts at a later time, with further viewing of aggressive and risky driving movie content. The eventual engagement in the modelling of this behaviour may be more likely when the driver is exposed to a provoking driving scenario (e.g., racing or vengeance related). These relationships support the interactivity of the person, situation, and internal factors of the modified GAM, with respect to modelling aggressive and risky driving (Figure 19.1), and also support Bandura’s (2001b) Triadic Reciprocal Causation model of psychosocial functioning.
CONCLUSION Given the profits associated with movies containing aggressive or risky driving content, a halt in their production is not likely to occur. The large domestic box office gross associated with the Fast and Furious franchise demonstrates that a large fan base exists for this genre of movie. The next instalment, Fast and Furious 9, has an anticipated release date of April 2, 2021 (IMDb, 2019). There are also indications of popularity for other forms of media depicting acts of
392
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
aggressive and risky driving. As mentioned previously, the top 10 YouTube videos containing this content, particularly street racing, average over 700,000 views and ‘likes’ (Vingilis et al., 2017). These videos, which can be freely accessed and repeatedly viewed, are unlike movies in that the majority depict real-world extreme driving events that were not performed by professionals in a staged environment. Research has not begun to understand how this content influences a person’s driving behaviour (Vingilis et al., 2017). Almost 20 years ago, Bandura (2001a: 271) recognized the ‘accelerated growth of video delivery technologies’ and how they facilitate exposure to a wide range of behaviours and ‘models’. Social media has expanded that substantially since then. A complete halt in production of movies such as Furious 7 or other forms of media depicting acts of aggressive or risky driving is not a realistic solution to reducing the modelling of this behaviour. However, the proliferation of this content makes it important to raise awareness about the association between this material and one’s driving behaviour, particularly the dangers associated with modelling. Singhal’s (2018) finding of portrayals of this behaviour in the movies having a significant impact on real-world speeding behaviour supports increasing enforcement when these movies are released and playing in theatres. This is particularly true for opening weekends and the first week post movie release. Speeding is a risk factor in road traffic injuries and fatalities, because of the increased risk of collision and severity of the resulting consequences. It is estimated that 30–50% of mortality on the roads is associated with speeding (World Health Organization, 2004). Alternate strategies could be more proactive, targeting the movie-goer and raising awareness of the potential for modelling the unsafe driving behaviour. This could include messages from the actors themselves, urging people to be responsible and smart on the roads and to drive safely. Universal Studios did this in the past for the Fast and Furious
franchise (Orwall, 2001) and production companies could incorporate these messages into the credits of the movie, following its completion. It may intrigue the movie-goer to view additional footage of the actors and the message may be more meaningful coming from these individuals, who are revered in their role. This may also delay the moviegoers from returning to their vehicles immediately following the end of the movie, potentially allowing for some decrease in their immediate level of arousal. Lastly, we should not remove accountability from the viewer. Bandura’s early work (Bandura, 1971; Bandura et al., 1963a) demonstrated the basic principles of observational learning and modelling, and his later reflections emphasized that human behaviour is not simply the result of stimulus-response relationships. We, as humans, have ‘functional consciousness’, part of which involves regulating and evaluating the actions we choose to take (Bandura, 2001b). The two core features of Bandura’s (2001b) proposed ‘human agency’ are self-reactiveness and self- reflectiveness, mentioned previously. It is these two elements that are emphasized to viewers of aggressive and risky driving media content. Viewers make choices to expose themselves to this content and, therefore, have a responsibility to be aware of how this content can influence their behaviour, and to evaluate their actions accordingly (e.g., considering driving laws and the safety of others). Essentially, Bandura (2001b) is highlighting the appraisal and decision-making process of the modified GAM, as shown in Figure 19.1. Having viewers engage in self-reactiveness and self- reflectiveness could decrease the probability of an impulsive action and increase the probability of a thoughtful one. This would, ultimately, hamper the modelling of aggressive and risky driving following exposure to such content in the media. Drivers must be cognisant of the fact that they share the road with other drivers, vehicle occupants (e.g., children), cyclists, and pedestrians. With this in mind, all drivers
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND DANGEROUS DRIVING BEHAVIOUR
should consider characteristics that constitute a ‘good’ driver. Qualities which lessen the occurrence of factors that contribute to aggressive driving should be encouraged. For example, forethought, in the context of driving, would involve allowing sufficient time to arrive at a final destination, which could prevent the development of frustration when confronted with delays in traffic or other hampering driver actions. Forbearance (i.e., self-restraint and tolerance) and forgiveness of other drivers’ minor mistakes (e.g., driving too slowly in the fast lane) could lessen the likelihood of choosing an aggressive driving response. Factors such as these, in addition to being aware of the possibility of aggressive driving motion-picture content influencing driving behaviour, are encouraged in all drivers. Young males may need to be particularly aware of heightened sensitivity to provocation or competitiveness on the roads and appropriately inhibit aggressive or risky responses. Just as many drinking and driving campaigns target the driver in emphasizing the dangers and potentially tragic consequences of impaired driving (Green, 2013; MADD, 2017), research has highlighted the need for drivers to keep their safety, and the safety of the public, at the forefront when considering engaging in an aggressive or risky driving behaviour.
REFERENCES Abelson, R. P. (1981). Psychological status of the script concept. American Psychologist, 36, 715–729. Anderson, C. A. & Bushman, B. J. (2002). Human aggression. Annual Review of Psychology, 53, 27–51. Arnett, J. (1994). Sensation seeking: A new conceptualization and a new scale. Personality and Individual Differences, 16, 289–296. Atkin, C. K. (1989). Television, socialization and risky driving by teenagers. Alcohol, Drugs, and Driving, 5, 1–11.
393
Bandura, A. (1971). Psychological modeling: Conflicting theories. New Jersey: Aldine Transaction. Bandura, A. (2001a). Social cognitive theory of mass communication. Media Psychology, 3, 265–299. Bandura, A. (2001b). Social cognitive theory: An agentic perspective. Annual Review of Psychology, 52, 1–26. Bandura, A., Ross, D., & Ross, S. A. (1963a). Imitation of film-mediated aggressive models. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 66, 3–11. Bandura, A., Ross, D., & Ross, S. A. (1963b). Vicarious reinforcement and imitative learning. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 67, 601–607. Berkowitz, L. (2012). A cognitive-neoassociation theory of aggression. In P. Van Lange, A. Kruglanski, & E. Higgins (Eds.), Theories of Social Psychology (Vol. 2., pp. 99–117), London: Sage. Beullens, K., Roe, K., & Van den Bulck, J. (2011a). Excellent gamer, excellent driver? The impact of adolescents’ video game playing on driving behavior: A two-wave panel study. Accident Analysis and Prevention, 43, 58–65. Beullens, K., Roe, K., & Van den Bulck, J. (2011b). The portrayal of risk-taking in traffic: A content analysis of popular action movies. Journal of Communications Research, 2, 21–27. Bushman, B. J. (1995). Moderating role of trait aggressiveness in the effects of violent media on aggression. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 69, 950–960. Buss, D. M. (1988). The evolution of intrasexual competition: Tactics of mate attraction. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 54, 616–628. Buss, A. H. & Perry, M. (1992). The aggression questionnaire. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 63, 452–459. Coleman, L. (2004). The copycat effect: How the media and popular culture trigger the mayhem in tomorrow’s headlines. New York: Paraview Pocket Books. Dahlen, E. R., Martin, R. C., Ragan, K., & Kuhlman, M. M. (2005). Driving anger, sensation seeking, impulsiveness, and boredom proneness in the prediction of unsafe driving. Accident Analysis & Prevention, 37, 341–348.
394
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Deb, S. (2019, January 2). Netflix to ‘Bird Box’ fans: Please open your eyes. The New York Times. Retrieved January 14, 2019, from www.nytimes.com/2019/01/02/arts/net flix-bird-box-challenge-war ning.html? module=inline Desai, R. A., Krishnan-Sarin, S., Cavallo, D. & Potenza, M. N. (2010). Video-gaming among high school students: Health correlates, gender differences, and problematic gaming. Pediatrics, 126(6), e1414-e1424. Retrieved from https://pediatrics.aappublications.org/ content/126/6/e1414 Eron, L. D., Huesmann, L. R., Lefkowitz, M. M., & Walder, L. O. (1972). Does television violence cause aggression? American Psychologist, 27(4), 253–263. Entertainment Software Association (ESA) (2019a). ESA leadership desk: Telling our industry’s story in a new way. Retrieved June 7, 2019, from www.theesa.com/perspectives/ esa-leadership-desk-telling-our-industrysstory-in-a-new-way/ Entertainment Software Association (ESA) (2019b). 2018 Essential facts about the computer and video game industry. Retrieved June 7, 2019, from www.theesa.com/ esa-research/2018-essential-facts-about-thecomputer-and-video-game-industry/ Fischer, P., Greitemeyer, T., Kastenmüller, A., Vogrincic, C., & Sauer, A. (2011). The effects of risk glorifying media exposure on riskpositive cognitions, emotions, and behaviours: A meta-analytic review. Psychological Bulletin, 137, 367–390. Fischer, P., Greitemeyer, T., Morton, T., Kastenmüller, A., Postmes, T., Frey, D., Kubitzki, J., & Odenwälder, J. (2009). The racing-game effect: Why do video racing games increase risk-taking inclinations? Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 35, 1395–1409. Fischer, P., Guter, S., & Frey, D. (2008). The effects of risk-promoting media on inclinations toward risk taking. Basic and Applied Social Psychology, 30, 230–240. Fischer, P., Krueger, J. I., Greitemeyer, T., Asal, K., Aydin, N., & Vingilis, E. (2012). Psychological effects of risk glorification in the media: Towards an integrative view. European Review of Social Psychology, 23, 224–257. Fischer, P., Kubitzki, J., Guter, S., & Frey, D. (2007). Virtual driving and risk taking: Do
racing games increase risk-taking cognitions, affect, and behaviors? Journal of Experimental Psychology: Applied, 13, 22–31. Freedman, J. L. (2007). Television violence and aggression: Setting the record straight. The Media Institute Policy Views, 1, 1–10. Goldberg, O. (2001). ‘Fast’ fallout film may inspire copycat racers. The Free Library. Retrieved June 8, 2020, from web.archive. org/web/20151023223740/www.thefreelibrary.com/’FAST’+FALLOUT+FILM+MAY+INS PIRE+COPYCAT+RACERS.-a083598815 Green, M. (2013, July 24). Drunk driving prevention and the effectiveness of media campaigns. Retrieved June 26, 2020, from www. absoluteadvocacy.org/drunk-driving-preventionmedia-campaigns/ Greenberg, B. S. & Atkin, C. K. (1983). The portrayal of driving on television, 1975–1980. Journal of Communication, 33, 44–55. Grewal, S. & Brennan, R. (2006, June 23). Racing film has police on edge. The Toronto Star, p. B4. Grey, E. M., Triggs, T. J., & Haworth, N. L. (1989). Driver aggression: The role of personality, social characteristics, risk and motivation (Report No. CR 81). Federal Office of Road Safety, Australia. Hegerl, U., Koburger, N., Rummel-Kluge, C., Gravert, C., Walden, M., & Mergl, R. (2013). One followed by many? Long-term effects of a celebrity suicide on the number of suicidal acts on the German railway net. Journal of Affective Disorders, 146, 39–44. Helfgott, J. B. (2015). Criminal behaviour and the copycat effect: Literature review and theoretical framework for empirical investigation. Aggression and Violent Behavior, 22, 46–64. IMDb (2018, December 21). Bird Box (2018). Retrieved June 28, 2019, from www.imdb. com/title/tt2737304/ IMDb (2019, November 11). Fast & Furious 9 (2020). Retrieved June 7, 2020. from www. imdb.com/title/tt5433138/ Iversen, H. & Rundmo, T. (2002). Personality, risky driving and accident involvement among Norwegian drivers. Personality and Individual Differences, 33, 1251–1263. Jeong, J., Shin, S. D., Kim, H., Hong, Y. C., Hwang, S. S., & Lee, E. J. (2012). The effects of celebrity suicide on copycat suicide
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND DANGEROUS DRIVING BEHAVIOUR
attempt: A multi-center observational study. Social Psychiatry and Psychiatric Epidemiology, 47, 957–965. Jonah, B. A., Thiessen, R., & Au-Yeung, E. (2001). Sensation seeking, risky driving and behavioral adaptation. Accident Analysis & Prevention, 33, 679–684. Koburger, N., Mergl, R., Rummel-Kluge, C., Ibelshäuser, A., Meise, U., Postuvan, V., Roskar, S., Székely, A., Ditta Tóth, M., van der Feltz-Cornelis, C., & Hegerl, U. (2015). Celebrity suicide on the railway network: Can one case trigger international effects? Journal of Affective Disorders, 185, 38–46. Koordeman, R., Anschutz, D. J., & Engels, R. C. M. E. (2011). Exposure to alcohol commercials in movie theaters affects actual alcohol consumption in young adult high weekly drinkers: An experimental study. American Journal on Addictions, 20, 285–291. Kostermans, E., Stoolmiller, M., de Leeuw, R. N., Engels, R. C., & Sargent, J. D. (2014). Exposure to movie reckless driving in early adolescence predicts reckless, but not inattentive driving. Public Library of Science (PLoS ONE), 9, e113927. Kotzen, S. (2013, September 25). ‘The Program’ turns 20, along with its notorious road scene (video). The Hollywood Reporter. Retrieved on June 15, 2015 from www.hollywoodreporter.com/news/program-turns20-along-notorious-636568 List of Chess Grandmasters (n.d.). Retrieved September 15, 2019, from https://en.m.wikipedia. org/wiki/List_of_chess_grandmasters López-Guimerà, G., Levine, M. P., SánchezCarracedo, D., & Fauquet, J. (2010). Influence of mass media on body image and eating disordered attitudes and behaviors in females: A review of effects and processes. Media Psychology, 13, 387–416. MADD (2017, June 9). And then, in a heartbeat, everything changed! Retrieved on September 15, 2019 from http://madd.ca/pages/andthen-in-a-heartbeat-everything-changed/ Malamuth, N. M. & Check, J. P. V. (1981). The effects of mass media exposure on acceptance of violence against women: A field experiment. Journal of Research in Personality, 15, 436–446. Mensching, K. (2015, February 22). Daytona 500 purse 2015: Joey Logano take winner’s
395
share of $18 million payday. Retrieved from www.sbnation.com/nascar/2015/2/22/ 8085643/2015-daytona-500-purse-prizemoney Mesquida, C. G. & Wiener, N. I. (1996). Human collective aggression: A behavioral ecology perspective. Ethology and Sociobiology, 17, 247–262. Milgram, S. & Shotland, R. L. (1973). Television and antisocial behavior: Field experiments. New York: Academic Press. Modeling (n.d.). In Encyclopedia of Mental Disorders online. Retrieved on June 28, 2015 from www.minddisorders.com/Kau-Nu/ Modeling.html Nash Information Services (n.d.-a). The Numbers: Box office history for Fast and Furious movies. Retrieved March 1, 2017, from www.thenumbers.com/movies/franchise/ Nash Information Services (n.d.-b). The Numbers: The Fate of the Furious (2017). Retrieved April 18, 2017, from www.the-numbers.com/ movie/Fate-of-the-Furious-The#tab=summary Nash Information Services (n.d.-c). The Numbers: Furious 7 (2015). Retrieved February 28, 2017, from www.the-numbers.com/ movie/Furious-7#tab=summary Nash Information Services (n.d.-d). The Numbers: Movie comparison: The Fate of the Furious (2017) vs. Furious 7 (2105). Retrieved April 20, 2017, from www.the-numbers. com/movies/custom-comparisons/Fate-ofthe-Furious-The/Furious-7 Orwall, B. (2001, June 21). Fearing copycats, Universal warns against mimicking new action film. The Wall Street Journal. Retrieved from www.wsj.com/articles/SB99307515845 592312?mod=searchresults&page=1&pos=1 Paik, H. & Comstock, G. (1994). The effects of television violence on antisocial behavior: A meta-analysis. Communication Research, 21(4), 516–546. Peng, J. (2018, September 24). Doubling of motorcycle deaths in B.C. alarms safety officials. The Star. Retrieved October 10, 2018, from www.thestar.com/vancouver/2018/09/ 24/doubling-of-motorcycle-deaths-alarmssafety-officials.html Phillips, D. P. (1974). The influence of suggestion on suicide: Substantive and theoretical implications of the Werther effect. American Sociological Review, 39, 340–354.
396
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Phillips, D. P. & Carstensen, L. L. (1988). The effect of suicide stories on various demographic groups, 1968–1985. Suicide and Life-Threatening Behavior, 18, 100–114. Pristin, T. & Fox, D. (1993, October 23). Pop culture. Violence. Copycats. Blame?: Hollywood debates the responsibility issue after Disney’s edit of ‘The Program’. Los Angeles Times. Retrieved February 5, 2016, from http://articles.latimes.com/1993-10-23/entertainment/ca-48913_1_responsibility-issue Roseborough, J. E. W. (2014). Retaliatory aggressive driving: A justice perspective (Unpublished doctoral dissertation). York University, Toronto. Rowland, B. (2006, June 23). CHP concerned after release of racing movie. Free Lance News. Retrieved from www.sanbenito.com/ chp-concerned-after-release-of-racing-movie/ Shin, P. C., Hallett, D., Chipman, M. L., Tator, C., & Granton, J. T. (2005). Unsafe driving in North American automobile commercials. Journal of Public Health, 27, 318–325. Shinar, D. (1998). Aggressive driving: The contribution of the drivers and the situation. Transportation Research Part F: Traffic Psychology and Behaviour, 1, 137–160. Simons-Morton, B., Lerner, N., & Singer, J. (2005). The observed effects of teenage passengers on the risky driving behavior of teenage drivers. Accident Analysis & Prevention, 37, 973–982. Singhal, D. (2018). Modelling aggressive or risky driving: The effect of cinematic portrayals of risky driving (Doctoral dissertation, York University, Toronto). Retrieved from YorkSpace. (http://hdl.handle.net/10315/34497) Skinner, B. F. (1938). The behavior of organisms: An experimental analysis. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts. Skinner, B. F. (1953). Science and human behavior. Toronto: Simon and Schuster. Steinberg, M. S. & Dodge, K. A. (1983). Attributional bias in aggressive adolescent boys and girls. Journal of Social and Clinical Psychology, 1, 312–321. Steinberg, L. & Monahan, K. C. (2007). Age differences in resistance to peer influence. Developmental Psychology, 43, 1531–1543. Talwar, P. (1998). The family and peer group influences in aggression. Indian Journal of Psychiatry, 40, 346.
Tasca, L. (2000). A review of the literature on aggressive driving research. Ontario Advisory Group on Safe Driving Secretariat, Road User Safety Branch, Ontario Ministry of Transportation. Tedeschi, J. T. & Felson, R. B. (1994). Violence, aggression, and coercive actions. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. Toronto Transit Commission (2010, February 17). Subway suicide prevention. Retrieved on May 28, 2015 from www.ttc.ca/About_the_TTC/ Commission_reports_and_information/Commission_meetings/2010/Feb_17_2010/Supplementary_Reports/Subway_Suicide_Preve.pdf Transport Canada (2011). Road safety in Canada. Retrieved from www.tc.gc.ca/ media/ documents/roadsafety/tp15145e.pdf US driver in ‘Bird Box blindfold’ crashes in Utah. (2019, January 11). BBC News. Retrieved January 14, 2019, from www.bbc.com/ news/world-us-canada-46846981 Vingilis, E., Seeley, J., Wiesenthal, D., Mann, R., Vingilis-Jaremko, L., Vanlaar, W., & Leal, N. (2013). Street racing and stunt driving in Ontario, Canada: Results of a web-based survey of car and racing enthusiasts. Transportation Research Part F: Traffic Psychology and Behaviour, 21, 30–42. Vingilis, E., Yildirim-Yenier, Z., Vingilis-Jaremko, L., Wickens, C., Seeley, J., Fleiter, J., & Grushka, D. H. (2017). Literature review on risky driving videos on YouTube: Unknown effects and areas for concern? Traffic Injury Prevention, 18, 606–615. Vitaglione, G. D. (2012). Driving under the influence (of mass media): A four-year examination of NASCAR and West Virginia aggressive-driving accidents and injuries. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 42, 488–505. Watson, L., Lavack, A. M., Rudin-Brown, C., Burns, P., & Mintz, J. H. (2010). Message content in Canadian automotive advertising: A role for regulation? Canadian Public Policy, 36(Supplement 1), S49–S67. Weiss, B., Dodge, K. A., Bates, J. E., & Pettit, G. S. (1992). Some consequences of early harsh discipline: Child aggression and a maladaptive social information processing style. Child Development, 63, 1321–1335. Wiesenthal, D. L., Lustman, M., & Roseborough, J. (2016). Aggressive driving. In A. Smiley
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND DANGEROUS DRIVING BEHAVIOUR
(Ed.), Human Factors in Traffic Safety (3rd ed., pp. 169–193), Tucson, AZ: Lawyers & Judges Publishing Company. Wiesenthal, D. L. & Singhal, D. (2012). Evolutionary psychology, demography and driver safety research: A theoretical synthesis. In C. Roberts (Ed.), Applied Evolutionary Psychology (pp. 399–413), Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Wilson, M. & Daly, M. (1985). Competitiveness, risk taking, and violence: The young male syndrome. Ethology and Sociobiology, 6, 59–73. World Health Organization (2004). Road safety – Speed. Retrieved on June 15, 2015
397
from www.who.int/violence_injury_prevention/publications/road_traffic/world_report/ speed_en.pdf Ying, L. (2015, February 6). Hype’s must watch: Furious 7. Retrieved on May 15, 2015 from https://hype.my/2015/40192/hypesmust-watch-furious-7/ Zillmann, D. (1971). Excitation transfer in communication-mediated aggressive behavior. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 7, 419–434. Zuckerman, M. (1979). Sensation seeking: Beyond the optimum level of arousal. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
20 Evolutionary Psychology and Mass Media Gayle S. Stever
When considering the topic of evolutionary psychology and mass media, the questions come very quickly. For example: • As media has become more a part of human life, have humans adapted to it in an evolutionary sense, i.e. has natural selection had a chance to play a part in the way humans adapt to mass media? • If survival and reproduction are the two evolutionary imperatives, which has been the bigger influence in the way media has developed in the last century? • If men and women have different reproductive agendas, how has that affected the different ways that men and women use media? • Are mass media and entertainment adaptations, or are they by-products of adaptations? • Are there ways that mass media improves human chances for survival? • Are there ways that mass media affects our opportunities to engage in sexual behavior and thus have more chances to reproduce? • Or are there ways that mass media inhibits our sexual behavior and keeps us from having chances to reproduce? • What are the individual differences in how media is processed as affected by both social constructivism vs biological essentialism?
To tackle these questions, one must first define mass media, also referred to as mass communication. Mass communication is the result ‘of forces set in motion when groups of manlike [sic] animals first huddled together against the cold and danger of primitive times’ (Schramm, 1960: 3). News media is relevant because of the biological imperative for survival and the function of news to give us information about our environment that will affect the likelihood of that survival (Grabe, 2011; Shoemaker, 1996). Are those the primary origins and functions of mass media, or are there others? This chapter attempts to address these issues and questions.
ORIGINAL USES FOR MEDIA What was the first form of media and for what was it used? Schramm (1988) described the discovery of early cave paintings created in prehistoric times and speculated as to their purpose. The most likely use of these early
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND MASS MEDIA
paintings was for one generation of people to educate the next as to what the customs and practices of that culture had been. It is possible that these early pictures represented magical beliefs and secrets of that group (Schramm, 1988), shared with the youth of each successive generation. Learning about the ways and skills needed for survival was an essential part of being socialized and insured that the group would survive. In a basic fundamental way, the first media was an integral part of the survival of individuals. It has been suggested that the progress and evolution of technology in human history proceeded along almost Lamarckian lines, if the inventions of one generation are able to be communicated to a subsequent generation via some media representation. If adaptive capacity is improved by tools that are shared from one generation to the next via media representations, it can be speculated that brain capacity is shaped and accelerated via this ‘inherited’ shared knowledge. This is an example of the way that interaction between culture and biology can accelerate the development of knowledge that affects the survival of individuals, thus increasing the chance that their genes are passed on. Those whose genetic potential best leads to this kind of communication are the ones who will survive to reproduce. Thus, media plays a critical role in Darwinian evolution (Toth and Schick, 1993). From those earliest points moving forward, media continued to provide a way that knowledge, history, and social structures were conveyed from one generation to the next. Education has been a fundamental function of media and it is an important way to increase one’s odds of surviving to reproduce. Media provides the cornerstone of societal norms, traditions, and skills for preserving knowledge for future success and continuation of a social group. As media developed more sophisticated forms of delivery, it provided better representations of day-to-day reality, starting with drawings on cave walls and progressing to the current forms of media that include virtual reality, a complete recreation of a
399
symbolic environment within an imaginary and representational world. These mediated worlds are possible as technology becomes more sophisticated and it becomes possible to create more lifelike images. Education and also enhanced experience are made possible through these mediated formats. For example, The Henry Ford Museum in Dearborn, Michigan featured a film in 2018 about the true story of explorer Henry Bates’ 11-year journey through the Amazon rainforest. Using IMAX technology, the viewer is transported to the Brazilian rainforest where a trip down the Amazon is experienced, one that few people would actually be able to physically undertake. This expanded worldview is possible because increasingly realistic media forms make it so.
CONSIDERING MEDIA LIFE It has been argued that we live ‘in’ rather than ‘with’ media in the 21st century (Deuze, 2011). If this is so, then it becomes important to consider whether humans have adapted to media, or have simply assimilated it into the non-mediated aspects of their lives. If you, the reader, find yourself doubting that this could be so, that may be because as media becomes a greater part of our lives, it also becomes more invisible to us on a conscious level. As we become habituated to the presence of media in our lives, we become less aware of its presence and influence on a dayto-day or even minute-to-minute basis. Think of it as like electricity. There was a time in human life when electricity was not a pervasive part of every aspect of life. At that time, it was easy to sort out what parts of life involved electricity and what parts did not. As it became more available, fewer and fewer things were done apart from electricity. Cooking, cleaning, reading, even outdoor camping became infused with electricity to the point where while once we considered whether a situation involved electricity, now it is taken for granted that all parts of our life
400
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
involve use of electricity. In addition, and more important for this analogy, we do not think or talk about it much at this point in human history. It is a non-discursive aspect of our shared lives together. Mass media is becoming like that. We spend so much time in mediated worlds that we no longer consider the mediated parts of our lives as being separate from the rest of our lives. Consider what happens to you during a power failure. This recently happened to me, and while I was seeking alternate forms of power for basic needs (lighting, cooking, warmth), I was also seeking forms of media that did not require my home’s electricity (books, newspapers, battery-powered radios, my cell phone that didn’t depend on my local electricity for a signal). When the availability of the media I’m used to having was cut off, I was sent scrambling to replace those mediated sources of information and interaction with alternative forms to meet those needs that have developed as a result of having mass media readily available, each and every day. As media becomes more pervasive, it becomes more important to consider how humans are developing to adapt to this major change in our ways of living. Or are they? This is an important question.
SURVIVAL AND REPRODUCTION Natural selection is the cornerstone of evolution, and what drives natural selection are traits that facilitate either survival or reproduction, as traits that favor these things are more likely to be passed on to the next generation (Miller, 2011; West-Eberhard, 1979). It makes sense that any aspect of media experience that improves chances either for survival or for reproduction will be liable, over time, to shape the evolution of our species. However, mass media has not been in play long enough for this to have been a factor in human evolution thus far. So rather
than looking for the effects of mass media on evolution, it is better to consider how human beings as they have already evolved are able to adapt to a mediated environment. Because our culture is dominated by various forms of media, it could be argued that those who are best able to survive and reproduce in such an environment will pass their genes on to offspring. This has always been the case with social environments as they have shaped natural selection in the past. Another way to say this is that to the extent that our environment becomes more media saturated, it becomes more essential to adapt to this type of environment or not be successful in the tasks of survival and reproduction. Changing the overall structure of human inherited traits is a very slow process (Miller, 2011). A fundamental principle of evolution is that current members of a species are born with the set of traits that better prepared their ancestors for survival and reproduction. This presumes that environments stay the same. If there are radical changes in an environment, the species must adapt or it will become extinct. Humans have adapted to pay attention to any stimuli that have adaptive significance. The suggestion is that, rather than developing new structures in the brain to facilitate media processing, media has been created by the brain that has already developed. An ‘old’ brain isn’t necessarily an outmoded brain (Grabe, 2011). It remains to be seen if the addition of mass media is a large enough change to affect humans enough to change their survival trajectory (Geher, 2014).
Nature or Nurture? Any time one considers aspects of human growth and development, it is necessary to weigh in on the nature/nurture debate and attempt to identify which influences have a biological basis and which influences have a basis in socialization. In communication studies, the tradition has been to look at
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND MASS MEDIA
nurture over nature and, until recently, this was a driving force in most media research (Sherry, 2004). More recently, there has been a shift towards consideration of the effects of biology on communication (Sherry, 2015; Weber, 2015). For example, the field of strategic communications is the study of how communication satisfies a specific long-term goal. It has explored the specific ways that understanding improves as one comprehends the purposes, in an adaptive sense, that were fulfilled by the development of mental strategies. Studying motivations such as status or affiliation sets the stage for a larger understanding of how human motivations adapt to favor both survival and reproduction (Seiffert-Brockmann, 2018). Humans have not yet evolved as the result of mass media (Grabe, 2011). Evolution is a long-term process, and such adaptations have not yet had time to emerge. Therefore, the current conversation is about how the human brain as it exists today responds to mass media, and how, moving forward, media might influence future evolution. The response to media has been influenced both by the forces of social constructivism and biological and inherited aspects of human development (Bandura, 2001; Sherry, 2015). If the argument can be made that heritable traits influence the way we process media (Toth and Schick, 1993), then an argument could be made that humans might be expected to adapt and evolve in the future to an increasingly mediated world. Sherry (2004) was one of the early communication scholars to engage this issue of social constructivism vs biological essentialism. He observed that, up until that time, communication research had been more influenced by learning theory and environmental determinism than it had been by recognition of biological aspects of development. He recognized that more adaptive traits are likely to be the ones passed on to a new generation. He discussed the need for communication scholars to look more closely at biology and neuroscience
401
to find factors that explain a greater percentage of the variability in how humans process media. Studies to that time had achieved limited success in making such predictions. In explaining why communication had been dominated by the nurture aspects of development, he pointed out that the various theoretical traditions that had informed research in mass media were ideas like Bandura’s Social Learning Theory (Bandura, 2001) or Mead’s Symbolic Interaction (Mead, 1934), theories that were more driven by social constructivism than by considerations of inherited traits. By 2015, Sherry was writing about a newer model of communication research, one based on ‘complexity theory’ that had integrated considerations like evolution into the prevailing research paradigms. Indeed, a shift in thinking by not only Sherry but also others in the field (Falk et al., 2015; Weber, 2015) meant that mass media and communication scholars recognized that evolutionary psychology was becoming an important part of understanding media effects. In justifying a model that blends theoretical aspects of both nature and nurture, Malamuth (1996: 11) said this: ‘The human mind was designed by natural selection operating over many generations. To understand the influences of current environments, it is essential to consider the psychological mechanisms that are part of that design and are the result of an interactive blend of nature and nurture’. Mass media is part of the current environment that we are seeking to understand, and to gain full understanding, both nature and nurture must be considered. It is simplistic to talk about a model of nature vs nurture that posits that these are separate influences. In fact, it is the interaction between genotypes and environments that explains the ways that humans have evolved to be a good fit for their various environments, differentiated as they are (Scarr and McCartney, 1983). ‘The dichotomy of nature and nurture has always been a bad one, not only for the oft-cited reasons that both are required for development, but because a false
402
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
parallel arises between the two. We propose that development is indeed the result of nature and nurture but that genes drive experience’ (1983: 425). A good example to illustrate how this might work can be taken from my own family of origin. Both of my parents were career music educators and as a result I grew up in an environment that was heavily influenced by music. At various points, speculation was expressed whether the fact that my siblings and I were musical was the result of nature/genes, or nurture/environment. Scarr and McCartney’s theory would say that my parents and their genotypes were an influence on the environment they created in our household that resulted in a life heavily saturated by musical influences. Thus, it was not nature plus nurture as if they were two separate things, but rather nature and the resulting environment that was created by my parents who had strong genotypes/phenotypes for musicality. Scarr and McCartney call this a ‘passive’ type of environmental effect by parents who are genetically similar to offspring. But what if a child is adopted and grows up in an environment that is created by nonbiological parents? According to Scarr and McCartney (1983) there would still be an ‘evocative’ influence whereby the child’s own genotype affects the ways that she or he responds to the parents, regardless of their biological relationship. In this way the child’s genetic makeup creates a certain type of environment that is consistent with the genotype of the child. So if, for example, the adopted child is naturally introverted but the adoptive parents are very extroverted, the child’s responses might be initially introverted but become progressively more extroverted as (s)he adapts to this pattern of interaction. The third type of influence Scarr and McCartney (1983) call active niche-picking or niche-building. In this situation, the child adopted to parents who are not musical but who has a genetic proclivity to be musical will eventually seek out an environment,
once (s)he has a choice, that includes a lot of music and will build her or his own environment to support that ability. The important point in all of these examples is that nature and nurture as influences on a developing child cannot be separated or evaluated in isolation one from the other. Biology shapes environment and environment shapes developing traits. It is this choosing of environments that can have a direct effect on the eventual choice to reproduce or not reproduce. Said in a more technical way, phenotype (the visible trait) arises from a combination of genotype interacting with environment. To the extent that the genotype of the parents has a direct effect on the environment of the child, that parent’s genotype is shaping outcomes. The adoptive parent’s genotype is not passed to the adopted child, but it does shape the environment within which the child grows, which in turn has an effect on the child’s survival and subsequent ability to reproduce. The child him or herself responds to genetic tendencies that cause the choice of certain environments over others. Thus natural selection is a process fueled as much by environment as by biology. This principle is important because although the effect of the parents on the survival of the child is more obvious, it illustrates why it is important to consider the effect mass media has on the environment of a person. This can affect the likelihood that the person will both survive and reproduce. The chapter will return to this point at the end, when a person’s likelihood of developing a relationship with a media figure and how that can directly affect that person’s likelihood of reproducing is discussed. The conclusion to the question ‘Is human development or growth the result of nature or nurture?’ has to be that both must be considered to get an accurate picture of human behavior, particularly as shaped by mass media. This is true in all aspects of development including the development of sex and gender roles.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND MASS MEDIA
Sex and Gender In psychology, much of the biology vs socialization research has dealt with sex and gender, an area where differences in specific biological aspects vs social aspects of development seem easier to identify (Buss, 2016). Thus, it is no surprise that much of the research tying together evolutionary psychology with mass media looks at the topic through the lens of gender or sex (Ellis, 1992; Grabe, 2011; Kamhawi and Grabe, 2006; Malamuth, 1996; Miller, 2011; Salmon, 2012; Singh and Singh, 2011; Tifferet and Vilnai-Yavetz, 2014). What do women find attractive in partners in contrast with what men prefer? The list for women includes qualities like strength, youth, ability to provide and protect, and status, and one conclusion is that although women generally prefer these qualities in a potential mate, such preference does not usually occur at a conscious level. While this does not specifically address issues related to media, the application to how women might process mediated figures compared to how men process them can be inferred (Ellis, 1992). More specific to media is Kamhawi and Grabe’s (2006) discussion of gender differences in the reception of negative news. Citing research showing that women have a stronger avoidance of negative stimuli than do men (e.g. Zald, 2003), they showed that when news is given a more positive spin, women are more likely to watch and remember. Earlier studies had shown that women were less likely than men to watch and remember news stories about things like war and disasters. This study suggested that women have both a socially learned and biological predisposition to avoid negatively framed news (Kamhawi and Grabe, 2006). Shoemaker (1996) described the function of surveillance in early nomadic communities. All members of the society had to survey the environment for danger, and some individuals might have had this as their specialized function in the group. Perceiving potential threats to the group greatly increased the
403
survival of all members of the group. Grabe (2011) wrote about the surveillance function of news, and how our monitoring of news media is a way to remain apprised of potentially survival-related information. Citing Shoemaker, she makes the argument that humans are hard-wired to pay attention to negative news because of the way journalists are able to warn the public about potential dangers. She suggests that the gender differences similar to those reported in Kamhawi and Grabe (2006) are a function of historically early gender roles wherein women protected children by avoiding danger while men protected children by monitoring danger and being prepared to defend against it. An international randomized study of Facebook pages and the way users present themselves found that whereas men were more likely to use images that conveyed status and ruggedness, women were more likely to choose images that related to family values and/or emotional expression. These findings used theory-driven hypotheses from evolutionary psychology to explore aspects of evolutionary theory as it relates to behavior on social networking sites (Tifferet and Vilnai-Yavetz, 2014). Another social media study, this time about Instagram, looked at the variables that contributed to men’s desire to date women whose varying photo types were presented. Neutral photos (defined as those not showing people) were more appealing to men who felt lonely and had higher need for belonging and popularity, whereas group selfies were more appealing to men who had lower intrasexual competition for mates, need to belong, and need to be popular. This study used a variation on Maslow’s hierarchy of needs that was modified based on principles of evolutionary psychology. It considered affiliation, status, and mate acquisition as higher-order needs. One of the findings is that factors that correlate with desire for long-term relationships are different from short-term relationships. Overall, different photo types were related to differing profiles of intrasexual competition and the various
404
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
social needs reported. Perceived narcissism was another key variable, with those posting selfies and groupies perceived as more narcissistic than those posting neutral photos (Jin et al., 2019). Both of these social media studies suggest that sexual selection adaptations have a complex effect on the ways that users consume social media images. Some research has suggested that adolescent girls have a pre-occupation with male celebrities. Girls during this stage of development are more likely to form romantic attachments to celebrities than are boys during these years (Stever, 1994). Erikson (1959) suggested that while the formation of identity in adolescence is ideally before the development of intimacy which he associated with young adulthood, often adolescent girls put intimacy before identity and then assume the identity of their romantic partner (e.g. she becomes ‘the doctor’s wife’ or ‘the minister’s wife’). Emphasis on their historically evolved role as nurturers over the male role of provider and protector could explain why this happens. Engle and Kasser (2005) specifically queried a population of junior high school-aged girls and linked such interest to categories of secure and insecure attachment, an ethological theory driven by principles of evolutionary psychology. More will be said about attachment theory later but, for now, the observation was that girls who had positive attachments to same-age boys that they knew in real life were more likely to idolize male celebrities. Overall, adolescent girls are more romantically fixated than are boys at this age, and differing evolved sex roles is a possible explanation for this. Malamuth (1996) looked at gender differences in the consumption of sexually explicit media. He considered research that attempts to explain differing preferences of men and women in their consumption of this kind of material. Vast bodies of work that advocate for both biological and social explanations exist, not surprising due to the controversial nature of this particular subject (see also Salmon, 2018). When contrasting
erotic literature with romance literature, romance novels contain pornography written to appeal to women, while explicitly erotic images and literature appeal more to men. These each represent billion-dollar industries and the differences between them can be traced to the fact that sexual selection pressures faced by males and females during the course of evolutionary history have not been identical (Salmon, 2012). An ethnography of American romance readers revealed that women are very much aware of what they perceived to be a male proclivity for impersonal sex compared to the stories women in this study preferred, stories that involved interpersonal connection (Radway, 1984). A second study of female romance readers found that the basic themes of romance novels were finding, attracting, and keeping a desirable mate, certainly themes consistent with evolutionary psychology’s views of the female mating agenda (Buss, 2016; Hazen, 1983). Other studies have found sex differences that involve variations in sexual fantasies that include visual images, context, personalization, partner variety and response, and other variables. It is argued that if there are real differences between the sexes, then those differences should be even stronger in fantasies than in actual behaviors, as fantasies don’t have the same practical constraints as do behaviors. In general, women have more contextualized and personalized fantasies and their fantasies are more likely to involve emotional rather than purely physical responses. They are more likely to include personalized and specific partners (Ellis and Symons, 1990). These are all examples of how theory in evolutionary psychology is driving research on mass media and gender differences. Malamuth (1996) pointed out that, in general, sex differences occur in those domains for which men faced different problems from the ones women faced. Adaptation for each sex then proceeded on a different path to solve these different problems. Because the consequences of reproductive behavior
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND MASS MEDIA
for each gender are not the same, men and women developed different adaptations to their specific reproductive challenges. One of the largest differences is the parental involvement required for successful reproduction. Women must make a much larger minimum investment than do men. This difference is the source of many of the differences in mating strategies between the sexes.
OTHER RESEARCH LINKING EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY WITH MASS MEDIA A content analysis of tabloid media using an a priori list of evolutionary-related topics showed that sampled tabloid stories were most often related to survival fitness-relevant topics, those related to reproductive success (De Backer and Fisher, 2012). Long-term relationships, wealth status, health status, and parental care were four of the most frequently coded topics in the sample of tabloid media that was analyzed. The interest in celebrityrelated gossip was linked to the prevalence of parasocial relationships, discussed below. Research addressing themes in popular music linked to evolutionary themes produced similar findings, with country-western songs frequently containing phrases relating to sexuality and reproduction with an average of 10 such references per song (Hobbs and Gallup Jr., 2011). Salmon (2018) observed that these themes are found in music in general, although they are found more often in the most popular songs (e.g. those making Top 10 lists). Hip-hop and rap songs tend to focus on male interest in short-term mating, with much bragging about the number of partners they’ve had. In this same genre, female artists sing about wanting men with status and resources. The country-western songs had more themes around parenting as well as the start-up or break-up of relationships. Parasocial engagement (Tukachinsky and Stever, 2019) is defined as the social
405
connection one feels with a personality, usually mediated, whom one knows in some detail but without reciprocation. Attachments and other social relationships meet a fundamental need that is essential for optimal health and psychological functioning (Baumeister and Leary, 1995). Stever (2017a) found that parasocial attachment to mediated personalities is the natural by-product of persistent media consumption of the same face, voice, and personality of an attractive persona. Attachment theory would predict that the face and voice are primary mechanisms of attachment. A human infant will gaze longer at a human face than any other object presented to it (Umilta et al., 1996). He or she will look longer at a correct human face than an incorrect one (Easterbrook et al., 1999), and will prefer the face and voice of the mother to other faces and voices (Blehar et al., 1977; DeCasper and Fifer, 1980; Muir et al., 1994). Adults prefer attractive and symmetrical faces, and one theory is that such attractiveness is an indicator of good health and a strong genetic background (Fink and Penton-Voak, 2002). Reflecting back to the argument that humans respond to media as if it were real (Grabe, 2011; Reeves and Nass, 1996), humans respond to attractive potential mates whether they are 10 feet away or on a television screen. The familiar other is a potential mate. In some cases this is not adaptive in that sometimes the person who is fooled into thinking that attractive other is attainable persists in her or his attraction and refuses to give it up. This is discussed in more detail below. Media use compensates for diminished social interaction in situations wherein people experience isolation (Jonason et al., 2008). Because humans have evolved to be social beings, isolation creates psychological discomfort. Various kinds of ‘social snacking’ were investigated, operationalized for this study as ‘talking to oneself’ and ‘watching TV’. Whereas both genders used watching TV to mitigate social isolation, women indicated greater amounts of self-talk compared
406
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
to men. Additionally, the researchers point out that parasocial interaction is another way people cope with loneliness (Cohen, 2001; Giles, 2002). Bandura (2001), in his work on role models and vicarious social learning, maintained that media role models can be as powerful as proximal role models in shaping the behavior of those who admire and emulate them. Already discussed has been the role that learning adaptive behaviors from previous generations is a fundamental aspect of how media might affect adaptation. Taking this together with parasocial theory, it is clear that both identification and attachment are factors influencing the role that media plays in the relationships people form with mediated others, relationships that can have adaptive consequences.
Evolutionary Theory and Attachment Attachment theory, at its foundation, assumes that attachment behavior has evolved to be an adaptive behavioral pattern designed or selected to assure survival of the infant. A repertoire of attachment behaviors and a corresponding set of caregiving behaviors on the part of the adult caregiver complement each other and work together towards the successful development of the infant. Although sexual selection and successful mating are important, all of that is for nothing if the infant does not survive (Keller, 2013). Hazan and Shaver (1994) and others have posited that the attachment system that favors the survival of the infant is also a part of the adult romantic relationship. Partners look to one another for mutual support and care giving in a paradigm that defines attachment as the seeking of feelings of security and safety. Consistent with the idea that a key aspect of evolutionary psychology is the heritable quality of emotional responses, attachment theory says that inborn behaviors elicit feelings and emotions that predispose
one to feel connections with familiar others. Extending this to feelings that viewers develop for media personae, just as thoughts of the real-life romantic partner can make one feel safe and secure even when that partner is not physically present, mediated personae are able to elicit feelings of safety and security in the viewers who have those parasocial attachments (Stever, 2013, 2017a). Psychological comfort and a sense of safety potentially could play a role in the ability of humans to adapt to social environments but more research is needed to solidify this link. Parasocial attachment as a part of classical attachment theory is a new concept that needs further exploration. A recent study exploring the ways that viewers view media celebrities as parental attachment figures, looking to such a celebrity to meet a specific attachment need, is a good example of this kind of research (David et al., 2019).
Resulting Theories Out of work in media studies have come a number of theories including social presence, media richness, and media naturalness (Kock, 2012). Presence is defined as ‘a psychological state in which the virtuality of experience is unnoticed’ (Lee, 2004: 494). Thus, interaction is carried on with the mediated nature of that behavior being in the background and not noticed on a conscious level. If you ask the participant if this behavior is mediated, they are able to state that it is, but otherwise they behave as if the interaction is as real as faceto-face interaction. Lee concludes that ‘presence research will be equally benefitted by seriously considering the implication of evolutionary psychology for the explanation of how people use and interact with media and simulation technologies’ (Lee, 2004: 501). Social presence and media richness theories (Kock, 2004, 2012) each posit that faceto-face communication was most affected by evolution. Because humans have evolved to be good at face-to-face communication,
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND MASS MEDIA
media that best approximates face-to-face communication is the most engaging. Daft and Lengel (1986) argued that richness was dependent, in part, on the medium’s ability to convey nonverbal information as a part of the communication. Written communication has no nonverbal cues whereas traditional face-to-face communications have rich cues. Between those two extremes are a continuum of various forms of mediated communication that might have more or fewer nonverbal cues available as a characteristic of that form. For example, communicating via FaceTime on a cell phone includes many nonverbal cues but not as many as being in the presence of the person, but quite a few more than just writing an e-mail. An earlier idea, social presence, conveyed a similar distinction between faceto-face vs written communications (Short et al., 1976). Other aspects of social presence or media richness include the availability of immediate feedback from the communication partner, as well as the ability to convey aspects of one’s personality (Kock, 2004). As further research on these ideas was conducted, there was evidence both for and against the media richness theory, suggesting the need for an alternative explanation, and resulting in the development of media naturalness theory (Kock, 2012). Media naturalness theory contends that reduction of cognitive effort is the more important factor in explaining the greater effectiveness of media forms that best approximate face-to-face communication. Because humans evolved to communicate in person and in a manner that is most often synchronous, to the extent that these aspects are employed, communication takes less cognitive effort. Kock (2012) identifies five aspects of communication that are involved in media naturalness. The first is the individuals’ ability to see and hear each other; the second is that communication be synchronous; the third is the inclusion of facial expressions as a part of the message. Body language is the fourth element. Speaking directly to one another is the fifth element, such that partners
407
can talk to and hear one another. Specialized areas of the brain have evolved that allow facial recognition, the recognition of emotional cues, and the processing of speech, and thus it makes sense that communicating in this way will allow easy processing by all parties involved. When evaluating computer-mediated communication, media richness theory can favor a mode that features synchronicity and feedback immediacy whereas media naturalness theory favors the form that requires less cognitive effort, most often deemed to be faceto-face. In many examples, these two theories seem to come to similar conclusions, but the important consideration is the different emphases in each (Kock, 2004, 2012).
The Pleistocene Brain It is central to the arguments of this chapter that humans expend a considerable amount of time, effort, and resources in the production and consumption of mass media. Additionally, the ability of such mediated forms to elicit deep emotion from the consumer is something that social scientists seek to explain using established epistemologies (Hennighausen and Schwab, 2015). What is the origin of evolved psychological mechanisms and what purpose do they serve? These processes evolved in response to adaptive problems that occurred in the Pleistocene (or Ice Age, ending 11,700 years ago) human past (Barkow et al., 1992). They evolved very slowly over many millennia in contrast to the rapid social change that one can observe beginning from that time to the present. Predominantly, this is an era also referred to as hunter/gatherer society. Experts appear to agree that the Pleistocene brain or ‘old brain’ is still the one that guides human behavior (Grabe, 2011). Have evolved psychological mechanisms that evolved during the Pleistocene to solve adaptive problems served to determine how humans use media? This is another important question.
408
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
GRABE VS REEVES AND NASS: A DEBATE ABOUT THE ‘OLD’ BRAIN: ADAPTED OR OUTMODED? Related to all of this is Reeves and Nass’ (1996) theory, referred to as The Media Equation. Simply stated, their work suggests that humans interact socially with media in the same ways that they interact in face-to-face social situations: ‘… our research shows that media are perceived as real people and places, and that human responses to media are determined by the rules that apply to social relationships and navigating the world’ (1996: 10). When we see people or events depicted through media, reactions are governed by the rules of social interaction. For example, participants in research treated a computer as an active social partner, showing that computer courtesy and good manners. During experiments, people used polite behavior when interacting with a machine when that machine asked for evaluations. We will tell the machine we are using that it is helpful, accurate, and friendly, but when asked to evaluate that same computer from a different computer, responses were far less polite, suggesting that participants were responding to the computer in a way similar to any other social partner. Additionally, interpersonal distance as depicted in pictures elicits similar responses to those figures as does interaction with real people. When people in pictures seem close, our reactions are more intense, and we pay more attention and remember those people better (Reeves and Nass, 1996). By responding to media in the same way we react to face-to-face others, does this reflect that our Pleistocene brain has failed to adapt to media and is reacting in a way that is outmoded in an evolutionary sense? Grabe (2011), in interpreting The Media Equation, suggests that rather than look at this phenomenon as an outmoded ‘old’ brain that has not kept up with change, we rather consider that processing media as if it were the same as ‘real life’ is an adaptive way to integrate mediated
information into one’s day-to-day experience. Is the processing of media as ‘real’ always adaptive? This question is addressed later in this chapter. An important counterpoint to the research on The Media Equation is work done by Ramos and colleagues (Ramos et al., 2013). Specifically, they found that for Hispanic viewers who were the participants in their study, more empathy for objects of violence in a film was reported when they knew the violence was real compared to when it was part of fiction. Previous exposure to violence did not affect the degree of empathy shown with respect to these two types of violence, media depicting real victims vs media depicting fictional victims. A victim empathy scale was used to measure the dependent variable in this study, a self-report measure. Actual physiological responses were not recorded in this case.
Entertainment as Central to Mass Media When considering the role of entertainment as a result of evolution, two approaches are recognized. The first is that entertainment is a by-product of evolution. The second is that entertainment is itself an evolutionary adaptation to conditions in the environment (Hennighausen and Schwab, 2015). Other academics have also written about a connection between evolutionary psychology and entertainment (Vorderer et al., 2006) and have considered whether humans develop an interest in being entertained as an adaptation, or as a by-product of adaptations. One view that it is a by-product of adaptation posits that as humans became more adept at survival and no longer needed to expend all of their time and energy on it, this created leisure time, and entertainment originated from the desire to fill such leisure time with pleasurable activity. The Media Equation approach (Reeves and Nass, 1996) also assumes that human responses to media are a by-product of other adaptations. We respond to media as
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND MASS MEDIA
if it were real because we have evolved social responses to real people, and media resembles real people enough that we respond to it in a similar fashion. However, if entertainment is an adaptation in itself, then humans might have developed skills in being interesting and engaging in order to attract potential mates. In this case, entertainment is part of the primary task of reproduction and sexual selection. Miller (2011) developed the idea that the human mind, with its creativity and complexity, serves to attract mates in and of itself and as such is an evolutionary adaptation. Darwin (1871) called this a ‘hidden courtship function’. Said more simply, having a creative and interesting mind is ‘sexy’ to the prospective mate (see Hennighausen and Schwab, 2015 for a more extensive discussion of these approaches). Memory, anticipation, decision-making, and pleasure are all key aspects of sexual choice (Miller, 2011). These are all factors that easily can play into media choices as well and sexual attraction is an important factor when choosing one’s favorite celebrity (Stever, 1991). It is possible that both factors, entertainment and media as a by-product of adaptation, and as an actual adaptation, might be at work, and that it does not have to be one or the other (Ohler and Nieding, 2006). Entertainment can be a by-product of adaptations that led to increased leisure time, but also could be a mechanism for enhanced sexual selection.
Emotion, Play, and Fantasy This discussion of human evolution and how media fits into the picture begins with the observation that a huge aspect of media effects is the way media stimulates human emotions. It has been argued that our emotional responses to media are as intense as those same reactions to real events, as already noted (also Schwender and Schwab, 2010). Some theorists have suggested that the role of media in human life is largely dysfunctional in that media distracts us from dealing with real day-to-day things
409
in life. In addition, at first look, entertainment and mediated experience do not appear to have any real function in human life. However, upon closer analysis, two key functions of human existence, sensory perception and communication, seem to be related in a positive way to mediated experience. In an evolutionary sense, problem solving has an adaptive function and consuming media narratives, whether in books, films, and television, or even on the Internet, offers a form of cognitive rehearsal for real-life events. Nielsen (2012) identified the key element in this process as ‘imitation’. It is the predominant way that culture is transmitted from one individual to another and from parent to offspring. However, a key aspect of human development was that successive generations improved the tools they were given by parents. Such innovation explains, for example, the rapid progression of modes of air travel once a basic plane had been developed. Each generation didn’t have to start at the beginning of the ‘can humans fly’ question but rather could build on the accomplishments of their immediate predecessors. A prolonged stage of growth and development for humans gives an opportunity for advanced cognitive skills to develop. Thus ‘childhood’ is a unique feature of humans, and affords the time necessary to learn and develop. Play is identified as a primary mechanism in imitation and learning during childhood. Thus, a central part of development for children is play (Erikson, 1974) whereby children often rehearse tasks that they will be called upon to perform as adults. Media entertainment is an extension of the concept of ‘play’ and a higher-level form of cognitive rehearsal for tasks and situations that might come into play throughout life in various relationships, so that we can practice interpersonal, emotional, or social situations without incurring any unnecessary risk to real relationships. This can be argued to have a possible real and positive influence on reproductive outcomes for those who learn about social situations in this way.
410
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
It is recognized that play is a fundamental aspect of human behavior, and that play is often the rehearsal of behaviors that are adaptive for either survival or reproduction. In play we ‘practice’ doing things that will later ensure that we can be successful in life. What is play? It is the creation of a fantasy environment within which such practice can take place. So, a little girl in her pretend kitchen ‘cooks’ dinner for her family and serves it to them on small facsimiles of dishes. From such play, she later is able to learn real cooking skills. A little boy pretends to care for his doll, and such play is practice for future parenting. Theorists have suggested that mass media is experienced as ‘play’ by its recipients. Stephenson (1988: 49) recounts that the daily mix of media consumed by viewers ‘is repetitious, like a child’s game played over and over with variations on a familiar theme’. It is not a big leap to see the consumption of fiction in mass media as a springboard for fantasy, which is related to play. A viewer watches a favorite television show and when the show is over, fantasizes about being in social situations with a favorite protagonist, scripting conversations and practicing how to behave in those social situations. This social behavior is practice for future real encounters in the same way that the child cooking in a pretend kitchen is learning behaviors that will apply to real preparing of meals. The fantasy interaction with a favorite media persona is a type of parasocial relationship. Thus, play involves fantasy and when one consumes media, one is transported into a parasocial fantasy world where we interact with the inhabitants as if they were real. We assess possible fantasy mates in these worlds in the same way we might assess real potential mates in a face-to-face environment.
The Media Personae as an Idealized Romantic Figure Fisher (2004) has done extensive research on the nature of romantic love and how and why
humans fall in love. She has concluded that the brain evolved to execute three brain functions related to love. These are lust, romantic love, and attachment. Attachment has already been discussed here and sexual attraction has been discussed as well. Romantic love has been reported across time and across cultures in terms that are close to universal. Various terms are used to refer to the feelings associated with romantic love including infatuation, obsession, and passion. Fisher’s studies showed that the experiences and feelings associated with this state are similar across cultures, ages, and genders. Fisher recounts, ‘Lovers dote on the positive qualities of their sweethearts, flagrantly disregarding reality’ (Fisher, 2004: 8). What she refers to here is the tendency to idealize the beloved and ignore negative qualities or turn those negative qualities into endearing traits. It is not until the relationship comes up against reality that the rose-tinted glasses come off and the partner is seen as she or he really is. Over the course of time, idealization is tempered. This is potentially the foundation for why when viewers form ‘crushes’ on media figures, those feelings persist and the object is idealized. Because there is never any dose of reality to bring those ideals into a more realistic perspective, the viewing of the media object as near to perfection is a common experience. Stever (1991) found that when asked how big a fan someone was of their favorite celebrity, the best predictor for that Likert scale was romantic attraction. Clearly, these feelings of infatuation are heavily tied to why viewers become romantically attracted over time to their favorite media personalities.
IMPLICATIONS FOR THE IMPACT OF MEDIA ON INDIVIDUALS The argument is that humans have not evolved beyond the hunter/gatherer society with respect to social behavior. In order to
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND MASS MEDIA
understand the importance of the premise of The Media Equation, that people respond to media as if it were real, and to understand the impact that mass media is having on social life, it is important to consider the ways in which courtships have traditionally happened throughout recorded human history. It has been argued that the human brain has acted on the basis of one model of human interaction, and that was the model established by the Pleistocene hunter/gatherer society, a society that was conducted face-to-face. In the Pleistocene era, if a woman saw a man who was a good potential mate, she had only to behave in ways that would be attractive to him, and she had every expectation of being able to bear his offspring. The ways potential mates were evaluated has already been discussed, but status, age, and resources were all factors in this evaluation. Because a woman’s reproductive investment was in one man at a time, it was essential to her reproductive success that she attract the best candidate with whom to mate. Throughout history and up until very recently, the only candidates for potential mates were men that the woman met in person and knew face-to-face. If she could get close enough to evaluate him for things like strength, health, and attractiveness, she would be able to attract him and bear his children. It was not even essential that she be his only partner. Fast forward to the 20th century, where film, television, and eventually the Internet made the images and information available about potential candidates for mates that the woman had not met in person, indeed might likely never meet in person. The ‘script’ for mating was still written in the behavioral social system of the woman’s brain. In the earliest stages of attraction, initiation, and experimentation (Tukachinsky and Stever, 2018), it is easy for a woman to fantasize about a potential mate, trying out various mating scenarios in her imagination, in order to evaluate the worthiness of a potential mate. Throughout history, this was something that women had been doing with respect to
411
in-person candidates for mating. Now women can evaluate distant potential partners and, if the potential mate is found worthy, she could attempt to pursue him. The problem comes when it occurs to this woman that she does not know how to meet the potential mate, and in some cases, she realizes that she is one of thousands who are attracted to this same person. She is still in the phase of romantic attraction where she has idealized this possible mate, and so her pursuit of him becomes a desire to meet him face-to-face in order to realize the fantasy in real time and in real life. It is not until she reaches this point in the ‘courtship’ that the problems with mediated reality become apparent. In my interviews with women who have been through this process with an attractive distant media figure, there is one of three outcomes: 1) She has a reality check, gives up her pursuit of this idealized mate, and seeks instead to find someone in proximity; 2) She refuses to give up her pursuit of the idealized other and proceeds to pursue him by any means available. This choice often ends in despair as the pursuit is not successful; or 3) If she is vulnerable to mental illness, she enters a delusional state (referred to as erotomanic schizophrenia), where she evaluates the fantasy relationship as ‘real’ and behaves as if it is. In most cases of erotomania, the mentally ill person lives in isolation in her fantasy world, firm in her belief that she has been separated from her beloved and that if they could be reunited, all would be well (Kennedy et al., 2002). In a few cases, the erotomanic becomes a stalker and pursues the person she believes is her partner via any means available. Both history and the news have reported various stories about this type of woman. David Letterman’s stalker (Bruni, 1998) went so far as to enter his home, drive his car, and tell others that they were married. (Eventually she took her own life, a frequent outcome for persons in this situation.) Other celebrities have had to deal with similar intrusions into their private lives by
412
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
people who believed that the celebrity was his or her romantic partner. Some research has suggested that erotomania actually ‘may be viewed as a pathological variant of a specific sexual strategy that evolved under selection pressures of the human environment of evolutionary adaptedness’ (Brüne and Schröder, 2003: 83). This suggests that this kind of obsession with a media figure possibly reflects sexual selection pressures gone wrong. One of the main arguments of The Media Equation and discussions of this theory has been that if people perceive what they see in media as real, and react to it as if it were real, what harm is done? Grabe (2011: 366) asks, ‘what existing or anticipated environmental need might compel human adaptation for the ability to separate media from physical reality….Why should our brains discriminate between media and physical worlds if they are converging’? However, in the example above, a viewer’s belief that the attractive potential mate she ‘meets’ through media is obtainable and that it could or should be real has the potential to wreak havoc on that viewer’s life for many years. In my years of participation in fan communities, I have met and/or seen numerous fans who were in deep despair because they realized they were in love with someone that they could never have or even meet. Although this represents a small percentage of fandom, it is a real situation that I have encountered numerous times in the 30-plus years I have been involved in participant observation in media fandoms. So far, I have discussed this scenario with respect to women pursuing men and, indeed, most of the real-world cases I have observed have been women in this situation (the fandoms I have studied often were dominated by women). Looking at what we know about gender differences in mate selection, it is not hard to understand why a woman looking to partner with a famous male celebrity would be more common than a man seeking to mate
with a famous female celebrity. To succeed, a woman only has to be one of potentially many possible partners. For a man to succeed, he has to become the ONLY partner for that female celebrity, at least for a time. Thus, traditionally the throngs of adoring fans who want to partner with the famous celebrity have been more likely to be women. However, men are vulnerable to this situation as well.
An Illustration from The Big Bang Theory The idea that a fan would replace the opportunity for a real relationship in the face-toface world with a fantasy attachment to a media character is illustrated well in an episode of the television sitcom The Big Bang Theory. Howard Wolowitz has been introduced to Bernadette and Bernadette wants an intimate relationship with him. Howard hesitates to commit to the real relationship. Why? As he explains to his friends (in season 3, episode 9), ‘She wants a commitment and I’m not sure she’s my type. Bernadette is really nice. I just thought that when I was ready to settle down in a relationship, it would be with someone different. More like Megan Fox from Transformers or Katee Sackhoff from Battlestar Galactica’. When Penny replies, ‘You’re going to throw away a great girl like Bernadette because you’re holding out for some ridiculous fantasy?’, Howard’s answer is, ‘Just because you settled doesn’t mean I have to. I want what’s inside too but why is it wrong to want those insides wrapped up in the delicious caramel that is Halle Berry?’ Sheldon’s observation at this point is, ‘Biologically speaking, Howard is perfectly justified in seeking the optimum mate for the propagation of his genetic line’. Later in the episode, fantasy Katee Sackhoff asks Howard, ‘Why are you playing make believe with me when you could be out with a real woman tonight?’ When Howard says, ‘She’s not you’, Sackoff replies, ‘I’m not
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND MASS MEDIA
me…the point is you’ve got a real girl in your life and you’re ignoring her to spend your time with a mental image…’. In 30 years of fan research, I have met many dozens of fans who are holding out for the ideal represented by their favorite celebrity and who would not consider someone lesser than that ideal. In many cases, it meant that the fan did not date at all. From a natural-selection perspective, people who idealize and stay single/celibate as a result do not have their genes passed on to progeny. This is particularly true for women who are less likely to engage in frivolous reproductive activity if they are holding out for a perfect mate. Men can both hold out and also have casual sex because of their lesser investment in potential offspring. The Howard Wolowitz character is a good example of this as well. However, whether the celebrity ideal was a real person or a fictional character, the fan who is unwilling to settle for less than the ideal is far less likely to reproduce than the one who is more realistic. However, if media ‘fools’ the brain into thinking that a real relationship is being experienced (real in the sense of reproductive potential), this is exactly the kind of thing that Restak (1991) has described. There is a part of the brain that processes what is seen as ‘real’, even if the perception is mediated. Cultural anthropology teaches us about status hierarchies within cultures and the desire of individuals to mate with higher-status individuals than are currently available in one’s pool of potential mates (Wright, 1994). It makes sense that the attractive celebrities found in television, films, and other avenues of popular culture would be particularly attractive to the viewer who sees an individual who is likely to be more attractive, wealthier, and of higher status than potential mates who are in closer proximity. The virtual proximity of such individuals tricks the viewer into thinking that high-status celebrity mates are attainable. As Restak (1991) pointed out, The Brain Has a Mind of Its Own.
413
CONCLUSION To summarize the main points from this chapter, first, mass media has not been a factor in human evolution long enough to have shaped inherited characteristics in the species. Research supports the idea that the hunter/ gatherer Pleistocene-era brain is still the brain that regulates human social life (Barkow et al., 1992). Next, evolutionary psychologists have spent a good deal of time investigating the effects of sex and gender on media selection and processing. Different reproductive agendas and roles in the social group affect the ways that men and women process and react to media messages (Buss, 2016). The work of Sherry (2004, 2015) has suggested that research into mass media has integrated both biological and sociocultural influences on mass media selection and consumption into various theoretical models. These include social presence, media richness, and media naturalness theories (Kock, 2012). The Media Equation (Reeves and Nass, 1996) suggested that humans respond to media as if it were real, showing little difference in the way media messages are processed compared to in-person messages. Face-to-face communication appears to require less cognitive effort and thus mediated forms of communication that most closely resemble face-to-face communication require less cognitive effort and are more efficient and effective. Discussed were the ways that entertainment, fantasy, and play are part of evolutionary theoretical models, playing the function of rehearsal of future life tasks, both social and occupational. The final major point is that the inability to process mediated social situations differently from face-to-face social situations may occasionally have maladaptive or undesirable outcomes, particularly if mating and reproduction are the desired outcomes. However, social situations available through media have the potential to mitigate loneliness and support the individual who is relatively isolated. The literature on parasocial relationships and parasocial
414
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
attachments (Stever, 2017b), including the literature on celebrity worship (McCutcheon et al., 2002), suggests that there are both negative and positive potential outcomes for meeting one’s social needs through mediated parasocial relationships. Research investigating the effects of mass media from an evolutionary psychology perspective is relatively new and a great deal more work is needed to investigate, in particular, the long-term effects of increasing levels of media consumption. This includes the growing rate at which people are meeting social needs through social media, as well as texting, tweets, and various other messaging formats. The increasing presence of media devices in day-to-day lives, devices like cell phones, iPads, laptops, personal computers, and other devices that are used on a daily basis in more and more situations, also needs to be explored to see how the human brain as it has evolved is suited to and fits with persistent use of these devices. Comparisons between heavy media users and those who refrain from using media would be instructive in comparing brain development that results from use or nonuse.
REFERENCES Bandura, A. (2001). Social cognitive theory of mass communication. Media Psychology, 3, 265–299. Barkow, J. H., Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (Eds.). (1992). The adapted mind: Evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture. New York: Oxford University Press. Baumeister, R. F., & Leary, M. R. (1995). The need to belong: Desire for interpersonal attachments as a fundamental human motivation. Psychological Bulletin, 117(3), 497. Blehar, M., Lieberman, A., & Ainsworth, M. (1977). Early face-to-face interaction and its relation to later infant-mother attachment. Child Development, 48(1), 182–194. Brüne, M., & Schröder, S. G. (2003). Erotomania variants in dementia. Journal of Geriatric Psychiatry and Neurology, 16(4), 232–234.
Bruni, F. (November 22, 1998). ‘Behind the Jokes, a Life Of Pain and Delusion; For Letterman Stalker, Mental Illness Was Family Curse and Scarring Legacy’. The New York Times. Retrieved May 6, 2013. https://www. nytimes.com/1998/11/22/nyregion/behindjokes-life-pain-delusion-for-lettermanstalker-mental-illness-was-family.html Buss, D. M. (2016). The evolution of desire. New York: Springer International Publishing. Cohen, J. (2001). Defining identification: A theoretical look at the identification of audiences with media characters. Mass Communication & Society, 4(3), 245–264. Daft, R. L., & Lengel, R. H. (1986). Organizational information requirements, media richness and structural design. Management Science, 32(5), 554–571. Darwin, C. (1871). The descent of man. London: Gibson Square. David, K., Myers, M. E., Perry, S. D., Gouse, V., & Stein, C. B. (2019). Examination of insecure attachment and the potential for parasocial parental attachment (PPA) to a favorite celebrity through attachment theory. North American Journal of Psychology, 21(2), 387–406. De Backer, C. J., & Fisher, M. L. (2012). Tabloids as windows into our interpersonal relationships: A content analysis of mass media gossip from an evolutionary perspective. Journal of Social, Evolutionary, and Cultural Psychology, 6(3), 404–424. DeCasper, A., & Fifer, W. (1980). Of human bonding: Newborns prefer their mothers’ voices. Science, 208, 1174–1176. Deuze, M. (2011). Media life. Media, Culture & Society, 33(1), 137–148. Easterbrook, M.A., Kisilvesky, B.S., Muir, D.W., & LaPlante, D.P. (1999). Newborns discriminate schematic faces from scrambled faces, Canadian Journal of Experimental Psychology, 55(3), 231–241. Ellis, B. J., & Symons, D. (1990). Sex differences in sexual fantasy: An evolutionary psychological approach. Journal of Sex Research, 27(4), 527–555. Ellis, B. J. (1992). The evolution of sexual attraction: Evaluative mechanisms in women. In J. H. Barkow, L. Cosmides, & J. Tooby, (Eds.), The adapted mind: Evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture, (267–288). New York: Oxford University Press.
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND MASS MEDIA
Engle, Y., & Kasser, T. (2005). Why do adolescent girls idolize male celebrities? Journal of Adolescent Research, 20(2), 263–283. Erikson, E. (1959). Identity and the life-cycle. New York: W.W. Norton & Co. Erikson, E. (1974). Play and actuality. In R. J. Lifton & E. Olson (Eds.), Explorations in psychohistory. The Wellfleet Papers (109–135). New York: Simon and Schuster. Falk, E. B., Cascio, C. N., & Coronel, J. C. (2015). Neural prediction of communication-relevant outcomes. Communication Methods and Measures, 9(1–2), 30–54. Fink, B., & Penton-Voak, I. (2002). Evolutionary psychology of facial attractiveness. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 11(5), 154–158. Fisher, H. (2004). Why we love: The nature and chemistry of romantic love. New York: Macmillan. Geher, G. (2014). Evolutionary psychology 101. New York: Springer. Giles, D. C. (2002). Parasocial interaction: A review of the literature and a model for future research. Media Psychology, 4(3), 279–305. Grabe, M. E. (2011). News as reality-inducing, survival-relevant, and gender-specific stimuli. In S. C. Roberts (Ed.), Applied Evolutionary Psychology, (361–377). New York: Oxford University Press. Hazen, H. (1983). Endless rapture: Rape, romance and the female imagination. New York: Scribner’s. Hazan, C., & Shaver, P. (1994). Attachment as an organizational framework for research on close relationships. Psychological Inquiry, 5, 1–22. Hobbs, D. R., & Gallup Jr., G. G. (2011). Songs as a medium for embedded reproductive messages. Evolutionary Psychology, 9(3), 390– 416. doi:10.1177/147470491100900309. Jin, S. V., Ryu, E., & Muqaddam, A. (2019). Romance 2.0 on Instagram! ‘What type of girlfriend would you date?’ Evolutionary Psychology, 17(1), 1474704919826845. Jonason, P., Webster, G., & Lindsey, A. (2008). Solutions to the problem of diminished social interaction. Evolutionary Psychology, 6(4), 637–661. Kamhawi, R., & Grabe, M. E. (2006). Gender differences in negative news reception: An evolutionary psychology explanation. Media Report to Women, 34(4), 15.
415
Keller, H. (2013). Attachment and culture. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology, 44(2), 175–194. Kennedy, N., McDonough, M., Kelly, B., & Berrios, G. E. (2002). Erotomania revisited: Clinical course and treatment. Comprehensive Psychiatry, 43(1), 1–6. Kock, N. (2004). The psychobiological model: Towards a new theory of computer-mediated communication based on Darwinian evolution. Organization Science, 15(3), 327–348. Kock, N. (2012). Media naturalness theory: Human evolution and behaviour towards electronic communication technologies. In S. C. Roberts (Ed.), Applied Evolutionary Psychology, (381–398). New York: Oxford University Press. Lee, K. M. (2004). Why presence occurs: Evolutionary psychology, media equation, and presence. Presence: Teleoperators & Virtual Environments, 13(4), 494–505. Malamuth, N. M. (1996). Sexually explicit media, gender differences, and evolutionary theory. Journal of Communication, 46(3), 8–31. McCutcheon, L. E., Lange, R., & Houran, J. (2002). Conceptualization and measurement of celebrity worship. British Journal of Psychology, 93(1), 67–87. Mead, G. (1934). Mind, self, and society. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press. Miller, G. (2011). The mating mind: How sexual choice shaped the evolution of human nature. New York: Anchor Books. Muir, D. W., Humphrey, E. E., & Humphrey, G. K. (1994). Pattern and space perception in young infants. Spatial Vision, 8(1), 141–165. Nielsen, M. (2012). Imitation, pretend play, and childhood: Essential elements in the evolution of human culture? Journal of Comparative Psychology, 126(2), 170–181. Ohler, P., & Nieding, G. (2006). An evolutionary perspective on entertainment. In J. Bryan & P. Vorderer (Eds.), Psychology of Entertainment, (423–434). New York: Routledge. Radway, J. (1984). Reading the romance: Women, patriarchy, and popular literature. Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press. Ramos, R. A., Ferguson, C. J., Frailing, K., & Romero-Ramirez, M. (2013). Comfortably numb or just yet another movie? Media violence exposure does not reduce viewer empathy for victims of real violence among primarily Hispanic viewers. Psychology of Popular Media Culture, 2(1), 2–10.
416
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Reeves, B., & Nass, C. I. (1996). The media equation: How people treat computers, television, and new media like real people and places. London: Cambridge University Press. Restak, R. (1991). The brain has a mind of its own: Insights from a practicing neurologist. New York: Crown. Salmon, C. (2012). The pop culture of sex: An evolutionary window on the worlds of pornography and romance. Review of General Psychology, 16(2), 152–160. Salmon, C. (2018). Evolutionary perspectives on popular culture: State of the art. Evolutionary Studies in Imaginative Culture, 2(2), 47–66. Scarr, S., & McCartney, K. (1983). How people make their own environments: A theory of genotype environment effects. Child Development, 54(2), 424–435. Schramm, W. (Ed.). (1960). Mass communication. (2nd ed.). Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press. Schramm, W. (1988). The story of human communication: Cave painting to microchip. New York: Harper and Row. Schwender, C., & Schwab, F. (2010). The descent of emotions in media: Darwinian perspectives. In K. Doveling, C. von Scheve & E. A. Konijn (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of emotions and mass media, (29–50). New York: Routledge. Seiffert-Brockmann, J. (2018). Evolutionary psychology: A framework for strategic communication research. International Journal of Strategic Communication, 12(4), 417–432. Sherry, J. L. (2004). Media effects theory and the nature/nurture debate: A historical overview and directions for future research. Media Psychology, 6(1), 83–109. Sherry, J. L. (2015). The complexity paradigm for studying human communication: A summary and integration of two fields. Review of Communication Research, 3, 22–54. Shoemaker, P. J. (1996). Hardwired for news: Using biological and cultural evolution to explain the surveillance function. Journal of Communication, 46, 32–47. Short, J., Williams, E., & Christie, B. (1976). The social psychology of telecommunications. New York: Wiley. Singh, D., & Singh, D. (2011). Shape and significance of feminine beauty: An evolutionary perspective. Sex Roles, 64(9–10), 723–731.
Stephenson, W. (1988). The play theory of mass communication. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers. Stever, G. (1991). The celebrity appeal questionnaire. Psychological Reports, 68, 859–866. Stever, G. (1994). Parasocial attachments: Motivational antecedents. Doctoral Dissertation, Arizona State University, Tempe, AZ. Stever, G. (2013). Mediated vs. parasocial relationships: An attachment perspective. Journal of Media Psychology, 17(3), 1–31. Stever, G. S. (2017a). Evolutionary theory and reactions to mass media: Understanding parasocial attachment. Psychology of Popular Media Culture, 6(2), 95. Stever, G. (2017b). Parasocial theory: Concepts and measures. In P. Rossler (Ed.), International Encyclopedia of Media Effects. (1–12). doi: 10.1002/9781118783764.wbieme0069. Tifferet, S., & Vilnai-Yavetz, I. (2014). Gender differences in Facebook self-presentation: An international randomized study. Computers in Human Behavior, 35, 388–399. Toth, N., & Schick, K. (1993). Early stone industries and inferences regarding language and cognition. In K. R. Gibson, & T. Ingold (Eds.), Tools, Language and Cognition in Human Evolution, (346–362). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Tukachinsky, R., & Stever, G. (2019). Theorizing development of parasocial experiences. Communication Theory 29(3) 297–318. https://doi.org/10.1093/ct/qty032 Umilta, C., Simion, F., & Valenza, E. (1996). Newborn’s preference for faces. European Psychologist, 1(3), 200–205. Vorderer, P., Steen, F., & Chan, E. (2006). Motivation. In J. Bryan & P. Vorderer (Eds.), Psychology of entertainment, (3–17). New York: Routledge. Weber, R. (2015). Biology and brains – methodological innovations in communication science: Introduction to the special issue. Communication Methods and Measures, 9, 1–4. West-Eberhard, M. J. (1979). Sexual selection, social competition, and evolution. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 123(4), 222–234. Wright, R. (1994). The moral animal: Why we are the way we are. New York: Vintage Books. Zald, D. (2003). The human amygdala and the emotional evaluation of sensory stimuli. Brain Research Review, 41, 88–123.
21 Evolutionary Psychology and Communication Ned Kock
INTRODUCTION Electronic collaboration (e-collaboration) is collaboration using electronic technologies among different individuals to accomplish a common task. This is a broad definition that encompasses not only computer-mediated collaborative work, but also collaborative work that is supported by other types of technologies that do not fit most people’s definition of a ‘computer’. One example of such technologies is the telephone, which is not, strictly speaking, a computer. Another example of technology that may enable e-collaboration is the teleconferencing suite, whose main components are cameras, televisions, and telecommunications devices. One phenomenon that has often puzzled computer science and information-systems researchers over the years, particularly researchers interested in e-collaboration issues, is the high importance of having an audio channel for communication in the context of e-collaborative tasks (Graetz et al., 1998;
Kock, 2004, 2009; Kock and DeLuca, 2007; Wainfan and Davis, 2004). Whenever audio is available (e.g., teleconferencing, telephone conference calls, face-to-face meetings), tasks seem to be performed more easily and with fewer misunderstandings. Moreover, adding video to an already present audio channel typically adds little to the e-collaboration medium’s ability to support group tasks (Burke and Aytes, 2001). While this is not a universal phenomenon (see, e.g., Daly-Jones et al., 1998; Baker, 2002; Kock et al., 2015), its frequent appearance in the empirical research literature merits a more robust theoretical analysis. An evolutionary explanation of the reason oral speech is needed for effective communication is proposed here, as a new theoretical contribution to the e-collaboration literature. It is argued that the high importance of oral speech is restricted to knowledge-intensive tasks. The reason for that, which is advanced in more detail in the subsequent sections, is that oral speech evolved among our hominid
418
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
ancestors as a costly trait to enable efficient and effective knowledge communication. As a costly trait, oral speech is analogous to the large train displayed by male peacocks to attract mates (often incorrectly called the peacock’s tail). Generally speaking, oral speech can be seen as: (a) a survival handicap that only evolved because of its strong indirect effect on reproductive success, an effect that counteracts its negative effect on survival; and (b) particularly important in the context of the task for which it evolved, namely communication of knowledge. Nevertheless, it is acknowledged here that even in knowledge-intensive tasks, the negative influence of suppression of oral speech may be countered by what is called here ‘compensatory adaptation’, whereby individuals adapt their communicative behavior to overcome the limitations posed by the suppression of oral speech. As it will be seen later, the word ‘adaptation’ in the term ‘compensatory adaptation’ does not refer to evolutionary adaptation, but to adaptation that an individual undergoes within his or her lifetime (often a fraction of one’s lifetime).
COSTLY AND COSTLESS TRAITS: SURVIVAL COSTS, REPRODUCTIVE SUCCESS, AND THE HANDICAP PRINCIPLE Costly traits are phenotypic traits that evolved in spite of having a negative impact on survival performance (Gillespie, 2004; Maynard Smith, 1998; Rice, 2004). Survival performance is the performance of an individual in the general task of survival, which can be measured by the age of the individual at the time of death. The older an individual is, the more successful it is at surviving in spite of survival threats (e.g., disease, predators, and accidental falls). Costly traits evolve because they have a positive impact on reproductive success (normally referred to as ‘fitness’ by evolutionary
b iologists), generally measured as the number of surviving offspring or grand-offspring of an individual (Gillespie, 2004; Hartl and Clark, 2007). The positive impact on fitness results from the competing effects of a costly trait on: (a) survival performance, a negative effect; and (b) a task performance attribute, a positive effect. The net effect of these competing effects on fitness is positive, leading to an increase in the frequency of the genotype associated with the costly trait in the species. One example of task performance attribute that could lead to such a positive net effect on fitness is the number of lifetime copulations an individual participates in, a performance attribute associated with the task of mating. A classic example of a costly trait that evolved due to having increased the number of lifetime copulations individuals possessing the trait participated in, which in turn offset the survival cost of that trait, is the peacock’s train (Maynard Smith and Harper, 2003; Zahavi and Zahavi, 1997). The peacock’s train is frequently referred to, incorrectly, as the peacock’s tail (Petrie et al., 1991; Zahavi and Zahavi, 1997). Both males and females have tails, but only males have the tail appendage known as a train. Costly traits may also exist that have competing effects on survival, and that are unrelated to mating, through intermediate effects on other variables that themselves directly affect survival. For example, propensity toward aggressive behavior among our ancestors might have increased their chances of being the target of violent behavior by other individuals, which contributed to a decrease in survival, but might also have increased their access to nutritious food obtained through hunting (for which aggressiveness is important), which in turn contributed to an increase in survival. In this sense, propensity toward aggressive behavior might have evolved as a costly trait, where the positive indirect effect on survival, mediated by increased access to nutritious food, was stronger than the negative indirect effect on survival from attracting violent behavior (Boaz and Almquist, 2001; Dobzhansky et al., 1977).
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND COMMUNICATION
Costless traits are defined here as phenotypic traits that have no negative impact on survival performance. Most costless traits are actually associated with enhanced survival performance, and may be observable indicators of unobservable underlying traits that enhance survival performance (Hamilton and Zuk, 1982; Kokko et al., 2002). The ability of males of the fruit fly species Drosophila subobscura to engage in a rapid courtship dance with females is an example of trait that fits this definition (Maynard Smith and Harper, 2003). Males increase their success at the task of mating by demonstrating to females that they possess the ability to dance vigorously in response to lead movements by the females. This trait can be seen as a costless trait, because it has no negative impact on the survival success of males. In other words, the dance itself has no negative effect on the survival of males. Presumably the ability to dance is positively correlated with survival performance, since it is an indicator of health. The most widely cited theoretical framework in connection with the evolution of costly traits was proposed by Zahavi (1975), centered on what is known as the handicap principle (Walker, 2008; Zahavi and Zahavi, 1997). This framework is intuitively appealing, which has led in part to its wide use in research by evolutionary biologists, in general (Hausken and Hirshleifer, 2008), and more specifically by evolutionary psychology researchers (Griskevicius et al., 2007; Walker, 2008). The handicap principle focuses on costly traits used for signaling, and is founded on the notion that those traits are honest indicators of the signalers’ fitness. For example, the large train displayed by peacocks is a survival handicap, making them more vulnerable to predation (Maynard Smith and Harper, 2003; Zahavi and Zahavi, 1997). Consequently, males with large trains and who are still alive at the age of reproductive maturity also must possess other traits that make them particularly good at survival, such as vitality and speed. The tails are a reliable indicator of fitness, exactly because they are costly.
419
COMMON CHARACTERISTICS OF COSTLY TRAITS: RARITY AND STRONG EFFECTS The discussion presented here expands on and refines the handicap principle to cover any costly trait, in connection with the performance of any organism in any task that influences fitness, not only signaling tasks. Two key conclusions are reached, which are that costly traits should: be rare in nature, and be costly not to use. The three sections that follow this section provide a mathematical elucidation and basis for these conclusions. While these conclusions are consistent with the handicap principle, they allow for predictions and explanations that go beyond signaling tasks. As such, they provide the basis for the analysis of the evolution of oral speech and its importance in the task of knowledge communication.
Costly Traits Should Be Rare in Nature The survival handicaps imposed by costly traits create obstacles for their evolution, eventually making those traits significantly rarer in nature than costless traits. These obstacles can be seen as ‘thresholds’ for evolution of the traits, where the thresholds are proportional to the survival cost of the traits (Gillespie, 2004; Hartl and Clark, 2007; Maynard Smith and Harper, 2003). New traits (e.g., high intelligence, long legs, and slow fat metabolism) usually appear in populations of organisms as a result of random genetic mutations; a general rule that applies to all organisms, including our hominid ancestors (Boaz and Almquist, 2001; Hartl and Clark, 2007; Mayr, 1976). Therefore, the effects of new traits on fitness are also random, whether those traits are costly or costless. Evolution is not an engineering process; it is a wasteful process of continuous tinkering, where the vast majority of new traits are in fact detrimental to fitness (Hartl and
420
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Clark, 2007; Wilson, 2000). Traits that have a positive net effect on fitness are far and few between (McElreath and Boyd, 2007; Wilson, 2000). Given that costly traits must overcome obstacles, or thresholds, to evolve, fewer costly traits than costless traits are likely to evolve. That is, the probability of evolution of costly traits in any species is generally lower than that of costless traits. Moreover, the higher the cost of the trait, the lower its probability of evolution. Thus, costly traits should be rarer in nature than costless traits; the costlier, the rarer.
Costly Traits Should Be Costly Not to Use Costly traits must have had a strong effect on the performance of the task for which they evolved in order to make up for the survival costs imposed by those traits. Today, this would translate into a higher correlation between costly traits’ measures and performance attributes for the task, than between costless traits’ measures and the same task performance attributes. That is, not using a costly trait would be costlier, so to speak, than not using a costless trait in the context of the task for which the traits evolved. The above conclusions seem to be true when we look at the classical example of costly trait, the peacock train. Petrie et al. (1991) found that the costly ornamental train of the male, and especially the number of eyespots on the train, are far more attractive traits for the peahens than other apparently costless traits. Costless ornamental traits are more numerous in the peacock species than costly ones, of which the only known one is the train, and their relative importance in the context of the mating task is dwarfed by the importance of the train. Examples of costless ornamental traits likely evolved for mating in the male of peafowl are the crest atop the male’s head, the brightly colored feathers on the male’s chest, various color patterns around
the eyes, various feather patterns occurring in different parts of the male’s body, and the level of bilateral (i.e., left–right) symmetry of these ornamentations (Darwin, 1871; Zahavi and Zahavi, 1997).
THE THRESHOLD FOR EVOLUTION OF COSTLY TRAITS One of the most important contributions to mathematical evolutionary thinking was made by Price (1970). He showed that for any trait to evolve through selection, in any population or subpopulation of individuals of the same species, the trait must satisfy Equation (1), whose main element is a covariance term. The fitness of an individual that possesses the trait (e.g., number of surviving offspring) is measured through W, and Z is a measure of the manifestation of the trait in the individual (e.g., Z = 1 if the trait is present, and Z = 0 if it is absent). The trait in question can be any morphological, physiological or behavioral trait; examples could be opposing thumbs, aggressiveness, or a large train (tail appendage) with many eyespots.
Cov(W, Z) > 0
(1)
Equation (1) can be re-written as Equation (2) in terms of the standardized measures of W and Z, referred to as w and z. This allows for its use in the context of path analysis (Kock, 2011; Kock and Moqbel, 2016; Wright, 1934, 1960), which in turn greatly simplifies (as it will be shown below) theoretical reasoning based on comparative analyses of evolution of traits through selection. Cov(w · SW + W, z · SZ + Z) = Cov(w · SW, z · SZ) = SW · SZ Cov(w, z) > 0 ⇒ Cov(w · z) > 0
(2)
Figure 21.1 shows a path model where a costly trait measured by y is represented. All the measures are standardized, which is
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND COMMUNICATION
a
pwa w
pay y
pas pws
s
psy
Figure 21.1 Path model showing a costly trait and its relationship with fitness
why they are indicated with lowercase letters. The measure y has a positive causal relationship with a task performance attribute a. For example, a could be number of lifetime copulations of an individual, a performance attribute associated with the mating task, in the case of a trait used for mate choice. The measure y has a negative causal relationship with s, a measure of survival performance. For example, s could be age of an individual at the time of death. Since any individual must be alive to perform any task, s also has a positive causal relationship with a. Both a and s have positive causal relationships with fitness (w). The magnitudes of these relationships are given by the path coefficients pay, psy etc. All path coefficients are positive except for psy, which is negative since it refers to the survival cost of trait y. (For simplicity, a trait measured by y is also called trait y.) In path analysis the covariance between any pair of variables is given by the sum of the products of the path coefficients in all paths connecting the two variables (Wright, 1934, 1960). Thus, combining Equation (2) with Figure 21.1 leads to Equation (3), which must be satisfied for any costly trait y to evolve through selection. pwa ∙ pay + pws ∙ psy + pwa ∙ pas ∙ psy > 0 ⇒pwa ∙ pay > –psy ∙ (pws + pwa ∙ pas) ⇒pay > –psy∙ (pws pwa + pas) p ⇒ pay > − psy ⋅ ws + pas (3) p wa
421
For a costless trait x, a trait with no negative effect on survival, Equation (3) is reduced to Equation (4) because psy equals zero. What this equation tells us is that a costless trait x will always evolve as long as it has a positive causal relationship with a task performance attribute a, assuming that a has a positive causal relationship with fitness (w).
pax > 0
(4)
In the task of mating, for example, any costless trait x that increases mating success (measured by a) would evolve through selection, with trait frequency growth subject to the constraints posed by chance events unrelated to the trait. That is, the trait would evolve to the point of becoming widespread in a population only if it is not eliminated by chance from the population at its early stages of evolution; e.g., the only individual that initially possesses the trait is killed by a lightning strike before reaching reproductive maturity (Gillespie, 2004; Wen-Hsiung, 2000). A costly trait y (e.g., the peacock’s train), on the other hand, would have to meet a more stringent requirement for evolution. It would only evolve through selection if the trait’s positive effect on a surpassed the threshold given by the right side of Equation (3).
PROBABILITY OF EVOLUTION OF COSTLY TRAITS Let us assume that the appearance of a new costly trait y in a population will lead to a variation in pay and –psy that will be given by random numbers going from 0 to D. Let us also represent T as in Equation (5):
p T = ws + pas (5) p wa
The value of T is assumed here to be largely population specific, in a relatively stable environment, and thus should remain
422
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
relatively constant as new costly or costless traits appear in a population and either evolve or disappear in response to selection pressures. This can be illustrated for the task of mating, where a can be the number of lifetime copulations a male of a species engages in. In this case, the effect of a on fitness (w), the effect of survival performance (s) on w, and the effect of s on a are relatively constant for the males of the species. In a relatively stable environment this can be shown to hold for any task whose performance is measured by a. This conclusion also follows from the assumption that those effects can be represented through stable regression coefficients, an assumption that is routinely used in mathematical population genetics models (Gillespie, 2004; Kock, 2011; Kock and Moqbel, 2016; Rice, 2004). On the other hand, the effects that new traits x or y have on a and/or s can vary widely, since those traits appear in the population as a result of stochastic processes. Those effects will in turn ultimately dictate whether those traits will evolve or disappear in the species. For species that live today in environments similar to those in which most of their traits evolved, the value of T can be easily estimated empirically since the path coefficients are standardized partial regression coefficients. Given the above assumptions, the probability of evolution of a new costly trait y in a population will be given by Equation (6), assuming that T is equal to or greater than one. This equation reflects the intersection spaces of variation of D and DT, and can easily be verified through simple Monte Carlo simulations.
D 1 ⋅ DT 2 1 ⇒ P Evo ( y ) = (6) 2⋅ T
(
)
P Evo ( y ) =
(
)
T is assumed to be equal to or greater than one because it is difficult to conceive of a species population or subpopulation for which
the performance of a task is more important for fitness than survival, even for the allimportant task of mating. Let us consider, for example, spider species where the males are routinely cannibalized by their large and aggressive female mates during or after copulation (see, e.g., Wilder and Rypstra, 2008). In these species, the male spiders must still successfully survive up to the moment of copulation. Therefore, when looked at as a subpopulation of the species to which they belong, those male spiders will likely have a ratio pws / pwa that is greater than 1 (and thus a T greater than 1) for the task of mating, regardless of the fact that they contribute little more than their sperm to the survival of their offspring (and thus to their own fitness). Equation (6) can be depicted in a graph, as shown in Figure 21.2. The graph shows the variation of the probability of evolution of a new costly trait y in a population (vertical axis) based on values of T ranging from 1 to 10 (horizontal axis). As can be inferred from Figure 21.2, costly traits will always have a lower probability of evolution than costless traits, because the value of T for the latter traits is always zero. This suggests that costly traits should be rarer in nature than costless ones, regardless of the task for which they were evolved, e.g., mating, communication, fighting. Moreover, costly traits should be particularly rare in species where the value of T is high. This would be the case in species where the number of offspring born to females was small; and in species where the offspring relied heavily on their parents for survival in their early years of life, when most deaths occur. (In these species, the effect of survival on fitness would have been much higher than the effect of mating on fitness.) These are characteristics of the human species, and likely of the hominid ancestors in the human lineage (Boaz and Almquist, 2001; Cartwright, 2000). Thus, T values should have been high for our hominid ancestors, making the evolution of costly traits difficult. This line of reasoning would suggest
423
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND COMMUNICATION
0.5 0.45 0.4 0.35 0.3 0.25 0.2 0.15 0.1 0.05 0 1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
Figure 21.2 Probability of evolution of a new costly trait
the existence of moderating effects in our model, which are not included because their discussion would be beyond the scope of this chapter. This has no effect on the generality of the discussion presented here or the related conclusions. Of course, in order to evolve, costly and costless traits also have to satisfy the condition that their covariance with fitness is greater than zero (i.e., that they have a positive net impact on fitness), which rarely is the case for new genetic mutations. Most new genetic mutations have either a negative or neutral effect on fitness; in the latter case they may evolve by chance, through a process known as genetic drift (Gillespie, 2004; Hartl and Clark, 2007; Maynard Smith, 1998). Costly traits, unlike costless ones, have another condition to satisfy: they must overcome the survival costs that they impose.
DIFFERENT EFFECTS OF COSTLY AND COSTLESS TRAITS Let us also assume that the appearance of costly and costless traits in a population will lead to random values of pax and –psy in the range from 0 to D. The expected value of pax
for costless traits that evolve will then be given by D divided by 2. The expected value of pay, on the other hand, will be given by (DT–D)/2, assuming that T is equal to or greater than 1. Therefore, the expected ratios between pay and pax will be given by Equation (7).
(
D⋅ T − D /2 ) ( D/2 ) (7) E( p / p ) = T −1
E pay / pax = ⇒
ay
ax
The graph in Figure 21.3 shows the vari ation of the expected ratio between pay and pax (vertical axis) based on values of T ranging from 1 to 10 (horizontal axis). The ratio grows proportionally with T, and is a measure of how strong the expected effect of a costly trait y on the task performance attribute a is, compared with the expected effect of a costless trait x. For simplicity, it is assumed here that both types of traits are either independent from each other, or spread to fixation in a species at different points in time. For dependent traits or traits that evolve at the same time, the mathematical analysis becomes more complex, but the results are qualitatively the same. An expected ratio between pay and pax of 1.3, for example, means that the standardized
424
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 0
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
Figure 21.3 Variation of the expected ratio between pay and pax
effect of any costly trait on a given task performance attribute a is on average 30% stronger than the effect of any costless trait on the same task performance attribute. A ratio of 8 means that the costly trait is on average 800% stronger (e.g., pay=.4 and pax=.05). Standardized effects are expressed in terms of standard deviations of the variables to which they refer. For example, a pay=.4 means that a 1 standard deviation variation in y causes a .4 standard deviation variation in a.
THE EVOLUTION OF ORAL SPEECH IN HUMANS: A COSTLY TRAIT ASSOCIATED WITH CHOKING AND ILLNESSES Modern oral speech was enabled by the evolution of a larynx located low in the neck (Lieberman, 1998). The evolution of oral speech is one of the most important landmarks in the evolution of the human species, having happened relatively recently in our evolutionary history (Figure 21.4). However, the new larynx design also likely increased significantly our ancestors’ chances of death by choking during ingestion of food and liquids, a leading cause of death among modern humans (Hemsley et al., 2019), and of
suffering from various aerodigestive tract diseases such as gastroesophageal reflux (Laitman and Reidenberg, 1997), among other survival-related problems. Oral speech must have been particularly important for effective communication in our evolutionary past, and effective communication must have been important for fitness enhancement (Pinker, 2003), otherwise its survival cost would have prevented complex speech from evolving. The situation with gastroesophageal reflux is particularly telling with respect to the cost of the evolution of oral speech in humans. The aerodigestive tract adaptations that enable complex oral speech make modern humans differ from their Australopithecine ancestors in ways that are analogous to the differences between the aerodigestive tracts of modern humans and modern non-human primates. In modern humans the incidence of gastroesophageal reflux symptoms (at various degrees of severity) has been reported to be as high as 40%, and yet Glover et al. (2008) noted that no modern non-human primate species was reported to display naturally occurring symptoms. The occurrence of gastroesophageal reflux symptoms is associated with significantly greater rates of mortality among infants (Vandenplas et al., 1991). This is also the case among adults, due to various conditions,
425
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND COMMUNICATION
Emergence of Homo sapiens
Emergence of Australopithecines
Today Millions of years 3.5
2.0
1.5
1.0
Co-located and synchronous communication through facial expressions, body language, and simple sounds
0.1
Complex oral speech
Figure 21.4 The evolution of oral speech in humans
including hemorrhagic reflux esophagitis (Rantanen and Salo, 1999). Oral speech seems to exhibit the two common characteristics of costly traits. Oral speech is a rare costly trait among human traits involved in the transfer of communicative stimuli. By all accounts, it is the only such trait that obviously imposed a survival cost as it evolved among our ancestors. In addition to increasing our ancestors’ chances of death by choking, and of developing aero digestive tract diseases, it also hampered our ancestors’ ability to breathe while drinking water. Water sources are likely to have been a preferred site for predators to ambush prey (Boaz and Almquist, 2001), as they are today, and the oxygen depletion caused by having to hold their breath while drinking created yet another survival cost for our ancestors. Other communication-related traits, such as the ability to use body language and facial expressions, do not seem to have imposed a similar survival handicap on our ancestors. Oral speech also appeared late in the evolutionary history of hominids, in the last 100,000 years of that 3.5-million-year history, or approximately the last 3% (Cartwright, 2000; Laitman, 1984; Lieberman, 1998). This is consistent with it being a costly trait,
since the evolution of a costly trait is a lowprobability event, and low-probability events frequently take more time to happen than high-probability events. In fact, the evolution of oral speech coincides with the evolution of our species, Homo sapiens, likely from another species within the genus Homo, namely Homo erectus (Boaz and Almquist, 2001; Lieberman, 1998). Many human evolution researchers believe that it was the evolution of oral speech, with the complexity of human interactions that it enabled, that made us truly human (Cartwright, 2000; Dunbar, 1993; Lieberman, 1998). Finally, empirical research on the effects of electronic communication media that suppress the ability to use oral speech suggests that it is costly not to use oral speech in communicative interactions. This is reflected in as much as a 10-fold reduction in communication fluency, coupled with a significant increase in communication ambiguity and perceived cognitive effort (Graetz et al., 1998; Kock, 2005; Kock and DeLuca, 2007; Kock et al., 2007; Simon, 2006). Communication fluency is defined here as the number of ideas effectively conveyed per unit of time, and has been somewhat imprecisely measured as the number of words conveyed per unit of
426
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Table 21.1 Oral speech and the two common characteristics of costly traits Common characteristic of costly traits
Evidence in connection with oral speech
Costly traits should be rare in nature
Oral speech is the only communication-related trait that clearly imposed a survival cost on our ancestors; conversely, various related costless traits seem to exist – e.g., the ability to use body language and facial expressions for communication. Suppressing oral speech in electronic communication media is costly, leading to as much as a 10-fold reduction in communication fluency, coupled with a significant increase in communication ambiguity and perceived cognitive effort.
Costly traits should be costly not to use
time (Kock, 2005; Kock and DeLuca, 2007). It seems that, when oral speech is removed from a communication medium, communication becomes rather cumbersome (Crowston et al., 2007; Graetz et al., 1998; Kock, 2005). Table 21.1 summarizes the discussion so far regarding the relationship between oral speech and the two common characteristics of costly traits. If the use of oral speech is enabled by an audio channel, adding a video channel typically has little impact on the effectiveness or ease with which communication takes place (Burke and Aytes, 2001; Daly-Jones et al., 1998; Simon, 2006). In this sense, oral speech could be seen to the communication task as analogous to what the peacock’s train is to the mating task (Petrie et al., 1991); both are costly traits that have an effect that dwarfs the effects of other costless traits evolved in connection with the same task. There are exceptions to this general rule regarding the importance of a video channel (see, e.g., Daly-Jones et al., 1998), such as modern tasks in which shared and real-time visualization of an object or situation is important for the task completion. Examples would be a surgical intervention involving two or more geographically distributed doctors, and a real-time collaborative design of a car engine.
ORAL SPEECH AND KNOWLEDGE COMMUNICATION: THE FOCUSED IMPACT ON FITNESS OF THIS COSTLY TRAIT The notion that oral speech is particularly important in modern human communication,
as discussed so far, needs further theoretical elaboration and refinement. Simple observation of modern human communication practices suggests that oral speech is not equally important for all types of communication interactions. For example, if one person is trying to communicate his or her home or work address to another, to be used on a letter, then probably an e-mail will be just as effective as a phone call. Also, web-based social communication tools that enable human interaction through short text messages and provide no audio channel, such as in the early versions of Twitter, would probably not be as successful as they are if the theoretical framework put forth here applied to all types of communicative interactions. This takes us back to a review of why oral speech evolved in the first place. More specifically, how did oral speech affect fitness among our ancestors? As discussed earlier, only if oral speech had a net positive impact on fitness, by enhancing the performance of a fitness-relevant task, would it have overcome the survival handicap associated with our customized vocal tract. The answer is that oral speech enabled the exchange of knowledge among our ancestors, which indirectly increased their reproductive success by allowing them to occupy what Pinker (2003) refers to as the ‘cognitive niche’. A common characteristic of the simple exchanges illustrated above (communication of a home or work address and interaction through short text messages) is that these types of exchanges involve little or no knowledge transfer. Therefore, if we assume that oral speech was evolved by our ancestors primarily to enable the communication of knowledge,
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND COMMUNICATION
its effect should not be particularly strong in communication interactions with little or no knowledge content. There are other factors that may induce modern humans to communicate electronically through text only, and with no audio – e.g., via e-mail without audio file attachments. Among those factors is the ease with which e-mail can be sent to many individuals at the same time. Video and audio blogs can be used for the same purpose, incorporating oral speech, but their use is still not as widespread and embedded in communication practices as is the use of e-mail. Knowledge about ‘something’ is defined here in a way that is analogous to how it is defined by many cognitive psychologists: as a set of mental schemas that allows one to predict the future, or find out more about a present situation, based on information about the present or the past (Gardner, 1985; Kock, 1999; Lee and Holyoak, 2008; Waldmann et al., 1995). As noted by artificial intelligence researchers, with knowledge, one can build mental rules that can be expressed in the form of ‘if … then …’ statements (Luger and Stubblefield, 2008; Russel and Norvig, 2002), or reworded as statements that contain linguistic elements that express causality such as ‘the reason for … is …’, ‘this is … because …’, and ‘the cause for … is …’ (Kock, 1999; Waldmann et al., 1995). For example, the statement ‘the temperature in room 118, where 100 people are attending a lecture, is now 78 degrees Fahrenheit’ contains only information, whereas the following statement contains knowledge: ‘if the temperature in room 118 reaches 80 degrees Fahrenheit, most of the 100 people attending a lecture there will feel uncomfortable’. Our ancestors faced survival threats on a regular basis – exposure to pathogens, attacks by predators or territorial animals, encounters with venomous insects or snakes, and ingestion of toxins, among others. These events often occurred in specific contexts. For example, territorial animals would attack when their habitat was invaded by our ancestors, and venomous insects and snakes occur
427
in higher quantities in certain areas (Hung, 2004; Kock et al., 2008; Manipady et al., 2006). Without the ability to vicariously obtain knowledge linking contexts with survival threats, our ancestors would have to experience the survival threats, or observe someone experiencing them at a close distance, in order to build that knowledge. Oral speech enabled vicarious knowledge acquisition regarding survival threats, and thus significantly increased our ancestors’ chances of survival, easily overcoming the extra survival costs associated with our vocal tract. Costly traits evolved by our human ancestors must have had a strong effect on the performance of the task for which they evolved, in order to make up for the survival costs imposed by those traits. In the case of oral speech, a strong candidate for the task in question is the knowledge communication task, where oral speech evolved in part to increase the performance with which knowledge about survival threats was communicated among our ancestors. Oral speech may also have influenced fitness in other ways, although avoidance of survival threats must have been an important element in the selection of this costly trait. For example, vicarious knowledge about survival-enhancing elements, such as seasonal availability of food, was likely also enabled by oral speech (Cartwright, 2000; Dunbar, 1999). So probably was the ability to build social relationships and court potential mates (Dunbar, 1993; Miller, 2000, 2002). This type of knowledge communication likely required reciprocal altruism to have evolved before, which mathematical formalizations and empirical evidence strongly suggest was the case in the human species (Fletcher and Zwick, 2007; Henrich, 2004; McElreath and Boyd, 2007; Trivers, 2002). Knowledge communication performance refers to both the effectiveness and efficiency with which knowledge is communicated (Kock, 1999; Russel and Norvig, 2002; Waldmann et al., 1995). Effective knowledge communication between two individuals
428
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
occurs when the knowledge possessed by one individual is comprehensively and unambiguously conveyed to the other individual. Efficient knowledge communication occurs when the knowledge possessed by one individual is quickly and effortlessly conveyed to the other individual.
THE EFFECTS OF ORAL SPEECH IN E-COLLABORATIVE TASKS: COMMUNICATION FLUENCY AND AMBIGUITY It follows from the theoretical discussion presented in the previous section that removing the ability to convey speech from an electronic communication medium is likely to impair communication performance much more strongly than removing the medium’s ability to convey other communicative stimuli – e.g., facial expressions, body language, olfactory cues, and tactile stimuli. However, this effect is moderated by the extent to which knowledge is being communicated. This conclusion is consistent with the results of various studies that compare the impact of various media on communication performance (Graetz et al., 1998; Kock, 2004; Kock and DeLuca, 2007). Graetz et al. (1998) compared the performance in four-person groups across three communication media conditions: face-to-face, telephone conferencing, and electronic chat. The experimental task required exchange of knowledge to be successfully accomplished, and the participants were given a limited amount of time (approximately 30 minutes) to review the information provided to them by the researchers and to discuss it with the other group members. Group outcome quality was about the same through the face-to-face and telephone-conferencing media; slightly higher in the latter, a statistically insignificant difference. Group outcome quality was significantly lower through the electronic chat medium. Measures of perceived cognitive
effort and frustration were about the same for the face-to-face and telephone-conferencing media, and significantly higher for the electronic-chat medium. In summary, the medium that did not enable oral speech was the least conducive to effortless and unambiguous knowledge communication. This is consistent with the view that oral speech is a costly trait that is ‘costly not to use’ in the context of knowledge communication. Particularly noteworthy is the finding by Kock and DeLuca (2007), in a study of individuals in two different countries, that the use of an electronic communication medium that suppressed the ability to convey speech (a version of e-mail) dramatically reduced communication fluency. In this study, communication fluency was measured as the number of words conveyed per unit of time, a surrogate measure. The reduction in fluency observed by Kock and DeLuca was estimated to have been more than 10-fold; that is, e-mail users’ fluency was less than 1/10 of their expected fluency communicating over the phone or face-to-face. This is too drastic a reduction to be explained by the known fact that typing is mechanically more cumbersome than speaking, which would normally lead to a twofold reduction in fluency (Kock, 2004; McQueen et al., 1999). Again, it appears that our brain was ‘designed’ by evolution to rely heavily on oral speech for effective and efficient knowledge communication, because oral speech was costly to evolve. As a result, it is costly not to use oral speech in modern human communication whenever a significant amount of knowledge must be exchanged.
COMPENSATORY ADAPTATION: COUNTERACTING THE EFFECTS OF ORAL SPEECH SUPPRESSION BY E-COLLABORATION TECHNOLOGIES A possible conclusion based on the arguments presented thus far is that a decrease in communication fluency and an increase in ambiguity,
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND COMMUNICATION
caused by the suppression of oral speech in an electronic medium, may lead to a decrease in the quality of the outcomes accomplished by a group using the medium for most of its communication. Indeed, this seems to frequently be the case in short-duration tasks (Graetz et al., 1998; Kahai and Cooper, 2003; Warkentin et al., 1997), but not necessarily in long-duration tasks (Burke and Chidambaram, 1999; Carlson, 1995; DeLuca, 2003; Kock, 2005; Kock and DeLuca, 2007). The reason is that, in long-duration tasks, it is common to observe a phenomenon known as compensatory adaptation (Kock, 2002). This phenomenon may counteract the problems associated with the suppression of oral speech (Kock, 2005; Kock et al., 2007). An example of a short-duration task would be to write a one-page contract to sell a car, where the contract would be written in one hour. A long-duration equivalent would be to write a 20-page contract to sell a fleet of cars, where the longer contract would be developed over a period of two weeks. If an electronic medium is to be used for communication to accomplish these tasks, where oral speech is suppressed in the communication medium, we would expect a more drastic drop in quality for the one-page contract than for the longer one with 20 pages. Here, ‘quality’ could be measured based on a number of factors, including the degree of understandability of the contract by the parties involved and the degree to which the contract clauses would be legally enforceable. Compensatory adaptation seems to be one of the reasons why groups performing knowledge-intensive tasks over a relatively long period of time (e.g., days, weeks, or months), using an e-collaboration medium that suppresses oral speech, often have the same or even better performance than groups where oral interaction is not suppressed (Kock, 2005). As long as there is motivation among group members to expend additional compensatory effort, which may be strongly influenced by social factors (Bandura, 1986; Fulk, 1993), group members are likely to
429
adapt their communicative behavior in order to compensate for the obstacles posed by the e-collaboration medium’s suppression of oral speech (Short et al., 1976; Ulijn et al., 2001). Compensatory adaptation can be understood as a moderating effect. That is, the effects of oral speech suppression on communication fluency and ambiguity are moderated by compensatory adaptation, whose moderating effect is in turn positively correlated with e-collaborative task duration. In short-duration tasks, the negative effects of oral speech suppression on communication fluency and ambiguity are likely to be particularly acute, as there is no time for compensatory adaptation to take place. In long-duration tasks, the e-collaborators may adapt their behavior to compensate for the cognitive obstacles caused by the suppression of oral speech. This phenomenon has been referred to as compensatory adaptation to e-collaboration media of low naturalness (Kock, 2004).
DISCUSSION AND CONCLUSION The arguments presented in the previous sections can be summarized into three main predictions. The first refers to the effects of oral speech suppression on communication fluency and ambiguity in the context of e-collaboration. The second refers to the moderating effect that the amount of knowledge communicated is likely to have on these effects. The third prediction refers to the moderating effect that compensatory adaptation is likely to have on the effects of oral speech suppression on communication fluency and ambiguity. Compensatory adaptation itself is correlated with task duration, and may take place even when a large amount of knowledge is being communicated. These predictions are outlined below, and followed by recommendations for the use of e-collaboration tools in organizations.
430
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Communication Fluency and Ambiguity A key prediction based on the discussion put forth here is that removing the ability to convey speech from an e-collaboration medium used by modern humans is likely to decrease communication fluency and increase communication ambiguity much more strongly than removing the medium’s ability to convey other communicative stimuli such as facial expressions and body language. The reason is that the ability to use speech for communication evolved at a much higher survival cost among our human ancestors than the ability to use any other communicative stimulus.
The Moderating Effect of Knowledge Communication The negative effects of oral speech suppression on communication fluency and ambiguity are moderated by the amount of knowledge communication taking place in an e-collaborative task. Due to the context in which oral speech evolved among our ancestors, oral speech is not equally important for all types of communication interactions among modern humans; it is particularly important in knowledge-intensive communication. Communicating one’s home address to another person, for example, can be easily and effectively accomplished through e-mail. Conversely, if one engineer wants to communicate knowledge about how to design a new car engine to a production manager, then the suppression of oral speech may be problematic.
The Moderating Effect of Compensatory Adaptation Another moderating effect, similar to but of a different kind than knowledge communication, is compensatory adaptation. Compensatory adaptation, or the degree to which individuals adapt to a communication medium that is
unnatural (e.g., one that suppresses oral speech), seems to moderate the negative effects of oral speech suppression on communication fluency and ambiguity. Compensatory adaptation to media that suppress oral speech typically happens over time (e.g., days, weeks or months), as individuals modify their communicative behavior to make up for the shortcomings of the medium. This may be one of the reasons why compensatory adaptation is not normally observed in short-duration tasks requiring intense knowledge exchange. For example, groups performing knowledge-intensive tasks through text-based e-collaboration technologies, and where the tasks last from a few minutes to a few hours, generally tend to produce task outcomes of inferior quality. These groups would be better off either: (a) performing the task face-to-face or using an e-collaboration technology that provides an audio channel; or (b) performing the task using a text-based e-collaboration technology, but over a long time period (e.g., a few days) so that compensatory adaptation can take place. The increasingly distributed nature of organizational processes (e.g., sets of activities that are repeated over and over again) and projects (e.g., sets of activities that are carried out once or a few times) requires tasks to be accomplished by groups of individuals who are not only geographically distributed, but also distributed across multiple time zones. Given this, it is impractical to try to ensure that all activities in a process or project are performed face-to-face, or even through e- collaboration involving synchronous oral speech interactions. Sometimes ubiquitous text-based asynchronous communication such as e-mail must be used for part of the process or project, due to cost constraints. It is also possible that asynchronous oral speech interactions will be used (e.g., voice messaging or e-mail with attached audio messages) for part of the process or project, due to group members having to work from different time zones. A more practical piece of advice to managers, which follows from the theoretical discussion, is the following: (a) break organizational
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND COMMUNICATION
processes and projects into component collaborative activities; (b) rank those activities in terms of the perceived amount of knowledge exchange involved; (c) make sure that highly knowledgeintensive activities are performed through media that incorporate synchronous oral speech (e.g., face-to-face or teleconferencing interaction), which may mean that certain group members will have to make special accommodations to participate in group discussions (e.g., attend a meeting at 3 a.m., local time); (d) make sure that moderately knowledge-intensive activities are performed through media that incorporate some form of oral speech, even if asynchronous (e.g., voice messaging or e-mail with attached audio messages); and (e) encourage the use of textbased e-collaboration media for activities that involve little or no knowledge exchange among participants, as this is likely to be the cheapest and most widely available organizational communication medium.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS This book chapter is based on a previous version published as an article in the journal Electronic Markets, and also contains revised materials and ideas, originally developed by the author, from articles published in the following journals: International Journal of e-Collaboration; Cognition, Technology & Work; International Journal of Technology and Human Interaction; Journal of Systems and Information Technology; and Journal of Evolutionary Psychology. This is done with full permission by the copyright holders, and with the goal of timely and wide dissemination of scholarly work.
REFERENCES Baker, G. (2002). The effects of synchronous collaborative technologies on decision making: A study of virtual teams. Information Resources Management Journal, 15(4), 79–94.
431
Bandura, A. (1986). Social foundations of thought and action. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall. Boaz, N.T., & Almquist, A.J. (2001). Biological anthropology: A synthetic approach to human evolution. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall. Burke, K., & Aytes, K. (2001). Do media really affect perceptions and procedural structuring among partially-distributed groups? Journal on Systems and Information Technology, 5(1), 10–23. Burke, K., & Chidambaram, L. (1999). How much bandwidth is enough? A longitudinal examination of media characteristics and group outcomes. MIS Quarterly, 23(4), 557–580. Carlson, J.R. (1995). Channel expansion theory: A dynamic view of media and information richness perception. Doctoral dissertation. Tallahassee, FL: Florida State University. Cartwright, J. (2000). Evolution and human behavior: Darwinian perspectives on human nature. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. Crowston, K., Howison, J., Masango, C., & Eseryel, U.Y. (2007). The role of face-to-face meetings in technology-supported selforganizing distributed teams. IEEE Transactions on Professional Communication, 50(3), 185–203. Daly-Jones, O., Monk, A., & Watts, L. (1998). Some advantages of video conferencing over high-quality audio conferencing: Fluency and awareness of attentional focus. International Journal of Human-Computer Studies, 49(1), 21–58. Darwin, C.R. (1871). The descent of man, and selection in relation to sex. London, England: John Murray. DeLuca, D.C. (2003). Business process improvement using asynchronous e-collaboration: Testing the compensatory adaptation model. Doctoral dissertation. Philadelphia, PA: Temple University. Dobzhansky, T., Ayala, F.J., Stebbins, G.L., & Valentine, J.W. (1977). Evolution. San Francisco, CA: W.H. Freeman and Company. Dunbar, R.I.M. (1993). Coevolution of neocortical size, group size and language in humans. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 16(4), 681–735. Dunbar, R.I.M. (1999). Culture, honesty and the freerider problem. In: R.I.M. Dunbar,
432
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
C. Knight, & C. Power (Eds.), The evolution of culture (pp. 194–213). New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press. Fletcher, J.A., & Zwick, M. (2007). The evolution of altruism: Game theory in multilevel selection and inclusive fitness. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 245(1), 26–36. Fulk, J. (1993). Social construction of communication technology. Academy of Management Journal, 36(5), 921–938. Gardner, H. (1985). The mind’s new science. New York, NY: Basic Books. Gillespie, J.H. (2004). Population genetics. Baltimore, MD: The Johns Hopkins University Press. Glover, E.J., Leland, M.M., Dick Jr, E.J., & Hubbard, G.B. (2008). Gastroesophageal reflux disease in baboons (Papio sp.): A new animal model. Journal of Medical Primatology, 37(1), 18–25. Graetz, K.A., Boyle, E.S., Kimble, C.E., Thompson, P., & Garloch, J.L. (1998). Information sharing in face-to-face, teleconferencing, and electronic chat groups. Small Group Research, 29(6), 714–743. Griskevicius, V., Tybur, J.M., Sundie, J.M., Cialdini, R.B., Miller, G.F., & Kenrick, D.T. (2007). Blatant benevolence and conspicuous consumption: When romantic motives elicit costly displays. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 93(1), 85–102. Hamilton, W.D., & Zuk, M. (1982). Heritable true fitness and bright birds: A role for parasites? Science, 218(4570), 384–387. Hartl, D.L., & Clark, A.G. (2007). Principles of population genetics. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer Associates. Hausken, K., & Hirshleifer, J. (2008). Truthful signalling, the heritability paradox, and the Malthusian equi-marginal principle. Theoretical Population Biology, 73(1), 11–23. Hemsley, B., Steel, J., Sheppard, J.J., Malandraki, G.A., Bryant, L., & Balandin, S. (2019). Dying for a meal: An integrative review of characteristics of choking incidents and recommendations to prevent fatal and nonfatal choking across populations. American Journal of Speech-Language Pathology, 28(3), 1283–1297. Henrich, J. (2004). Cultural group selection, coevolutionary processes and large-scale cooperation. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 53(1), 3–35.
Hung, D.-Z. (2004). Taiwan’s venomous snakebite: Epidemiological, evolution and geographic differences. Transactions of the Royal Society of Tropical Medicine and Hygiene, 98(2), 96–101. Kahai, S.S., & Cooper, R.B. (2003). Exploring the core concepts of media richness theory: The impact of cue multiplicity and feedback immediacy on decision quality. Journal of Management Information Systems, 20(1), 263–281. Kock, N. (1999). Process improvement and organizational learning: The role of collaboration technologies. Hershey, PA: Idea Group Publishing. Kock, N. (2002). Compensatory adaptation: Understanding how obstacles can lead to success. Haverford, PA: Infinity Publishing. Kock, N. (2004). The psychobiological model: Towards a new theory of computer-mediated communication based on Darwinian evolution. Organization Science, 15(3), 327–348. Kock, N. (2005). Compensatory adaptation to media obstacles: An experimental study of process redesign dyads. Information Resources Management Journal, 18(2), 41–67. Kock, N. (2009). Information systems theorizing based on evolutionary psychology: An interdisciplinary review and theory integration framework. MIS Quarterly, 33(2), 395–418. Kock, N. (2011). A mathematical analysis of the evolution of human mate choice traits: Implications for evolutionary psychologists. Journal of Evolutionary Psychology, 9(3), 219–247. Kock, N., & DeLuca, D. (2007). Improving business processes electronically: An action research study in New Zealand and the U.S. Journal of Global Information Technology Management, 10(3), 6–27. Kock, N., & Moqbel, M. (2016). A six-stage framework for evolutionary IS research using path models: Conceptual development and a social networking illustration. Journal of Systems and Information Technology, 18(1), 64–88. Kock, N., Carmona, J., & Moqbel, M. (2015). Media naturalness and compensatory adaptation: Counterintuitive effects on correct rejections of deceitful contract clauses. IEEE Transactions on Professional Communication, 58(4), 381–395. Kock, N., Chatelain-Jardón, R., & Carmona, J. (2008). An experimental study of simulated
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND COMMUNICATION
web-based threats and their impact on knowledge communication effectiveness. IEEE Transactions on Professional Communication, 51(2), 183–197. Kock, N., Verville, J., & Garza, V. (2007). Media naturalness and online learning: Findings supporting both the significant- and no-significantdifference perspectives. Decision Sciences Journal of Innovative Education, 5(2), 333–356. Kokko, H., Brooks, R., McNamara, J.M., & Houston, A.I. (2002). The sexual selection continuum. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London: Biological Sciences, 269(1498), 1331–1340. Laitman, J.T. (1984). The anatomy of human speech. Natural History, 20(7), 20–27. Laitman, J.T., & Reidenberg, J.S. (1997). The human aerodigestive tract and gastroesophageal reflux: An evolutionary perspective. The American Journal of Medicine, 103(5), 2S–8S. Lee, H.S., & Holyoak, K.J. (2008). The role of causal models in analogical inference. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 34(5), 1111–1122. Lieberman, P. (1998). Eve spoke: Human language and human evolution. New York, NY: W.W. Norton & Company. Luger, G.F., & Stubblefield, W.A. (2008). AI algorithms, data structures, and idioms in Prolog, Lisp, and Java for artificial intelligence: Structures and strategies for complex problem solving. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley. Manipady, S., Menezes, R.G., & Bastia, B.K. (2006). Death by attack from a wild boar. Journal of Clinical Forensic Medicine, 13(2), 89–91. Maynard Smith, J. (1998). Evolutionary genetics. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Maynard Smith, J., & Harper, D. (2003). Animal signals. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Mayr, E. (1976). Evolution and the diversity of life. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. McElreath, R., & Boyd, R. (2007). Mathematical models of social evolution: A guide for the perplexed. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press. McQueen, R.J., Payner, K., & Kock, N. (1999). Contribution by participants in face-to-face business meetings: Implications for collaborative technology. Journal of Systems and Information Technology, 3(1), 15–33.
433
Miller, G.F. (2000). The mating mind: How sexual choice shaped the evolution of human nature. New York, NY: Doubleday. Miller, G.F. (2002). How did language evolve? In: H. Swain (Ed.), Big questions in science (pp. 79–90). London, England: Jonathan Cape. Petrie, M., Halliday, T., & Sanders, C. (1991). Peahens prefer peacocks with elaborate trains. Animal Behaviour, 41(2), 323–331. Pinker, S. (2003). Language as an adaptation to the cognitive niche. In M. Christiansen & S. Kirby (Eds.), Language evolution: States of the Art (pp. 16–37). New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Price, G.R. (1970). Selection and covariance. Nature, 227(1), 520–521. Rantanen, T.K., & Salo, J.A. (1999). Gastroeso phageal reflux disease as a cause of death: Analysis of fatal cases under conservative treatment. Scandinavian Journal of Gastroenterology, 34(3), 229–233. Rice, S.H. (2004). Evolutionary theory: Mathematical and conceptual foundations. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer Associates. Russel, S., & Norvig, P. (2002). Artificial intelligence: A modern approach. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall. Short, J.A., Williams, E., & Christie, B. (1976). The social psychology of telecommunications. London, England: John Wiley & Sons. Simon, A.F. (2006). Computer-mediated communication: Task performance and satisfaction. Journal of Social Psychology, 146(3), 349–379. Trivers, R. (2002). Natural selection and social theory. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. Ulijn, J.M., Lincke, A., & Karakaya, Y. (2001). Non-face-to-face international business communication: How is national culture reflected in this medium? IEEE Transactions on Professional Communication, 44(2), 126–138. Vandenplas, Y., Goyvaerts, H., Helven, R., & Sacre, L. (1991). Gastroesophageal reflux, as measured by 24-hour pH monitoring, in 509 healthy infants screened for risk of sudden infant death syndrome. Pediatrics, 88(4), 834–840. Wainfan, L., & Davis, P.K. (2004). Challenges in virtual collaboration: Videoconferencing, audioconferencing and computer-mediated
434
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
communications. Santa Monica, CA: RAND Corporation. Waldmann, M.R., Holyoak, K.J., & Fratianne, A. (1995). Causal models and the acquisition of category structure. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 124(2), 181–206. Walker, T. (2008). Could sexual selection have made us psychological altruists? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 39(1), 153–162. Warkentin, M.E., Sayeed, L., & Hightower, R. (1997). Virtual teams versus face-to-face teams: An exploratory study of a web-based conferencing system. Decision Sciences, 28(4), 975–996. Wilder, S.M., & Rypstra, A.L. (2008). Sexual size dimorphism mediates the occurrence of
state-dependent sexual cannibalism in a wolf spider. Animal Behaviour, 76(2), 447–454. Wilson, E.O. (2000). Sociobiology: The new synthesis. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Wright, S. (1934). The method of path coefficients. The Annals of Mathematical Statistics, 5(3), 161–215. Wright, S. (1960). Path coefficients and path regressions: Alternative or complementary concepts? Biometrics, 16(2), 189–202. Zahavi, A. (1975). Mate selection – A selection for a handicap. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 53(1), 205–214. Zahavi, A., & Zahavi, A. (1997). The Handicap Principle: A missing piece of Darwin’s puzzle. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
22 Evolutionary Psychology and Climate Change: Understanding the Impact of Time Perspective on Carbon Emissions across 75 Countries Mark A. Caudell INTRODUCTION For the last 40 years, Darwinian approaches to human behavior have been successfully applied to understanding a diverse range of behaviors operating at both individual and group levels (Buss and Shackelford, 1997; Smith, 2000; Tooby, 2018; Tooby and Cosmides, 1988). Despite these successes, the leveraging of these approaches to contextualize and address global issues has been limited (Caudell and Quinlan, 2016; but see Sörqvist and Langeborg, 2019). This is unfortunate given that many of the behaviors driving global issues, including resource consumption dynamics, fertility patterns, and cooperation levels, can be partially explained as a consequence of human evolutionary history. A global issue amenable to explanation by an evolutionary perspective is anthropogenic climate change. Climate change studies have increasingly emphasized the role of demographic patterns, including fertility rates, age structure, and household size, in shaping the emission of fossil fuels (Cohen,
2010; Jorgenson and Clark, 2013; Murtaugh and Schlax, 2009; O’Neill et al., 2010; Rosa and Dietz, 2012; Shi, 2003; Stephenson et al., 2010). Indeed, population growth in the next half-century, even when holding current per capita emissions constant, could raise global emissions by half (Swim et al., 2010). Caudell and Quinlan (2016) sought to understand anthropogenic climate change through an approach that combined elements of life history theory (LHT) and evolutionary psychology. This approach was used to understand the ‘Population Paradox’ underlying anthropogenic climate change and to propose potential resolutions. The paradox is founded on data showing that per capita carbon emissions (i.e., energy consumption) are positively associated with both fertility rate increases and decreases (Shi, 2003; Stephenson et al., 2010). This pattern contradicts LHT given that per capita energy consumption is generally negatively associated with fertility in mammals (Stearns, 1992). To explicitly frame this paradox within a
436
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
life history perspective, Caudell and Quinlan drew upon the slow-to-fast life history continuum (Ellis et al., 2009). Specifically, they argued that in high-income countries (HICs), selection for slower life history strategies results in high parental investment that targets ‘dynastic fitness’ (Kaplan, 1996). These investment patterns result in large per capita energy investments in skills, knowledge, and other abilities that are necessary to compete in industrial labor markets (Burger et al., 2011). Given that industry and supporting infrastructure (e.g., electricity, transportation) are responsible for over 60% of carbon emissions (Boden et al., 2017), these investment patterns are likely to promote increased emissions. In addition, these investment patterns, particularly in the context of HICs, are also resource-intensive, thereby reducing Earth’s carrying capacity. Through limiting carrying capacities and promoting carbon emissions driving climate change, these slower life history strategies also increase levels of environmental risk globally. Higher risk levels in non-industrial areas (e.g., many low- and middle-income countries (LMICs)) promote selection for faster life history strategies that increase fertility rates and ultimately create larger per capita carbon legacies (i.e., the expected future emissions produced by a parent and their surviving offspring; Murtaugh and Schlax, 2009). Viewed globally, these two life history strategies give rise to investment patterns in HICs that are decreasing Earth’s carrying capacity and fertility patterns in LMICs that increase the rate at which this capacity is reached. To resolve the positive association between carbon emissions and slow and fast life histories, Caudell and Quinlan (2016) propose that the evolved psychological construct of time orientation can motivate decreased fertility rates and be coopted to promote pro-environmental behavior through investment in education, thus resulting in reductions in carbon emissions. In this chapter, I expand upon the original study by Caudell and Quinlan (2016) to include data from around 100,000 women
across 75 countries. This analysis provides a more robust assessment of the proposed relationships among time orientation, fertility and investment patterns, and global carbon emissions. The analysis supports that role of time orientation in impacting life history strategies and carbon emissions. More generally, the analysis supports the application of Darwinian perspectives on human behavior to understand and address the demographic and consumption patterns fueling anthropogenic climate change.
BACKGROUND Life History, Risk and Reproduction In LHT, reproductive behavior is guided by the costs and benefits of investing energy into the ‘competing’ life functions of growth, maintenance, repair, and reproduction (Roff, 2002; Stearns, 1992). Given that resources invested into one life function cannot be devoted to another, a set of trade-offs arise (Stearns, 1989). Simply, time and calories invested into attracting a mate are time and calories that cannot be invested in caring for offspring. A fundamental trade-off in every organism’s life history exists between current and future reproduction. That is, should energy be devoted towards producing offspring (i.e., reproductive effort) as soon as physiologically viable? Or should investment in reproductive effort be delayed in favor of somatic investment, thereby increasing the quality of the organism to provide parental care? The trade-off between current and future reproduction underlies the continuum between slow and fast life history strategies (Stearns, 1992). Slower life history strategies delay reproduction thereby reducing the quantity of potential offspring, but allow the organism to allocate more resources to growth, maintenance, and repair (i.e., somatic effort). Extended investment in somatic effort should
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND CLIMATE CHANGE
lengthen life expectancy and, through enabling increased parental investment, result in higherquality offspring. Higher-quality offspring are important in organisms with slower life histories given competition for resources. This competition emerges as slower life histories are found in stable and predictable environments that allow species to trend towards the carrying capacity of a particular niche, thereby intensifying competition for resources. Given this selection, species with slower life histories are often larger, have fewer offspring but extended parental investment periods, and longer life expectancies (Stearns, 1989). Fast life history strategies are more likely to emerge in unstable and unpredictable environments that, in turn, are typically less crowded. This unpredictability makes it unlikely that adaptations will evolve to enhance the competitive abilities of organisms, given that changing environments may render these abilities moot in the future. These unpredictable environments also decrease the probability of surviving to adulthood. The consequences of these environments, in the logic of life history, mean there is little fitness advantage in investing heavily in oneself or one’s offspring, as own and offspring survivorship is low. Instead, the fitness advantage lies in earlier and more frequent investment in mating effort, which increases the quantity of offspring but decreases the quality of offspring. This investment pattern, combined with unpredictable environments, curtails life expectancy of both parents and offspring (Low, 1978; Promislow and Harvey, 1990; Roff, 2002; Stearns, 1992; Trivers, 1972). As stated above, the continuum of slowto-fast life histories is founded upon environmental unpredictability. Within LHT, this unpredictability is framed as environment risk, which is further divided into intrinsic risk and extrinsic risk. Intrinsic risk is mortality risk that can be impacted through investing in oneself or one’s offspring. When intrinsic risk dominates, selection for slower strategies is strong as increased somatic investment can produce a fitness advantage.
437
In contrast, mortality from extrinsic risk should occur independent of investment in reproduction (mating, parental investment) as it results from largely unpredictable sources (e.g., predation). As unpredictable, an organism is unable to change the survival probabilities associated with extrinsic risks, both for itself and its offspring, through increased investment. A high extrinsic risk environment favors faster strategies to ‘beat the odds’ that a potential parent dies before reproduction or leaves no offspring, given high juvenile mortality rates (Quinlan, 2007; Roff, 2002; Stearns, 1992). Selection for all life history strategies, both across and within species, depends largely on levels of extrinsic risk in the local environment (Charlesworth, 1994; Quinlan, 2007; Stearns, 1989; Williams, 1957). Support for a relationship between extrinsic risk and life history strategies has been found across a diverse range of human societies (Bulled and Sosis, 2010; Caudell and Quinlan, 2012; Gant et al., 2009; Low et al., 2008; Nettle, 2010; Walker et al., 2006; Wilson and Daly, 1997), although other economic and cultural considerations clearly impact fertility decisions as well (Caudell, 2015), while the rapid pace of extrinsic risk changes (e.g., infant mortality interventions in LMICs (Liu et al., 2016)) could mask the relationship between extrinsic risk and fertility.
Extrinsic Risk and Evolutionary Psychology The phenotypic effects of extrinsic risk should be apparent in a suite of evolved psychological, and within humans, cultural, traits that motivate behavior towards investment in slow or fast life history strategies (Hill et al., 1997; Kruger et al., 2008; Quinlan, 2010). For example, mate-choice decisions are impacted by predation risk within the local environment (Jennions and Petrie, 1997). Time orientation is another aspect of psychology, particularly human psychology, that may function as a
438
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
mechanism that responds to risk during an organism’s development (Hill et al., 1997; Kruger et al., 2008). Time orientation, as a psychological dimension, is the degree to which the past, present, or future guides attitudes and behaviors (Zimbardo and Boyd, 1999). Present-oriented individuals tend to be influenced by the sensory qualities of the current environment, seek immediate gratification, and are more likely to exhibit risky attitudes and behaviors (e.g., drugs, unprotected sex) (Apostolidis et al., 2006; Boyd and Zimbardo, 2005; Caldwell et al., 2006; Henson et al., 2006; Kruger et al., 2008; Rothspan and Read, 1996; Schechter and Francis, 2010). Future orientation allows one to ‘transcend’ stimuli in the current environment and delay gratification, particularly in the service of future goals (e.g., education) (Horstmanshof and Zimitat, 2007; Peetsma, 2000; Zimbardo and Boyd, 1999). Couched within a theoretical framework combining LHT and evolutionary psychology, present orientations may be adaptive in environments with high extrinsic risk given that future investments, such as education, may not increase fitness due to decreased survivorship to adulthood. Future orientations may be adaptive in low extrinsic risk environments where future investments, such as education, may increase competitive advantage, thereby increasing fitness. In the context of life history strategies, present orientations should be associated with traits of a faster strategy, including limited somatic/offspring investment, higher total fertility rates, and decreased lifespans, whereas future orientation should be associated with slower strategies and traits that include later onset of reproduction, fewer offspring, and longer lifespans.
LHT, Evolutionary Psychology, and Climate Change But what can these various evolved strategies tell us about the factors promoting climate change in the present? Indeed, should either
slower or faster strategies be considered beneficial in the reduction of carbon emissions? Here, we are confronted with the ‘Population Paradox’, that carbon emissions are positively associated with fertility rate increases and decreases (Shi, 2003; Stephenson et al., 2010). In a life history framework, then, both slow and fast life history strategies are associated with increased emissions. However, the route through which this promotion occurs differs and can be framed, as with life history relationships, as a trade-off between current and future emissions. Slower life history strategies result in larger and longer energy investments per individual, both for parents and offspring, and so higher per capita carbon emissions in the present. For example, competition for mates in many cultures results in ‘conspicuous consumption’ by males (i.e., large investments in extrasomatic resources such as houses, cars, livestock, etc.), which is positively related to carbon emissions. In addition, the longer lifespans and later ages at first marriage characterizing slower strategies also result in smaller average household sizes, including more single adult households, which further increases per capita emissions (Jorgenson and Clark, 2013; O’Neill et al., 2012). Faster strategies result in lower per capita emissions in the present due to higher extrinsic risk, which decreases competition pressures. Reductions in competition pressures, along with high extrinsic risks, mean that the benefits of somatic and extrasomatic investments in oneself and one’s offspring may not be realized. Importantly, however, the larger quantity of potential offspring increases an individual’s carbon legacy, again the expected future emissions produced by a parent and their surviving offspring. Carbon legacies have a much greater potential to impact emissions when compared to emission changes associated with changes in current investment patterns. In the United States, for example, every child contributes 9,441 metric tons to their mother’s carbon legacy while a mother who recycled across her lifetime would save
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND CLIMATE CHANGE
about 17 tons (Murtaugh and Schlax, 2009). Whether selection for slow-to-fast life history strategies results in greater emissions, both in the present and future, is thus a function of per capita emissions, population size, and the rates at which these two factors rise or fall (Crowley, 2000; Dietz and Rosa, 1997). On the spectrum of human life history variation, populations that comparatively trend towards exhibiting slower strategies have substantially larger carbon legacies than those countries exhibiting faster strategies. This result is largely due to the fact that slower strategies are more common in HICs – those that emit the most carbon – whereas faster strategies are more common in LMICs, with lower overall carbon emissions (Boden et al., 2017). Disparities in carbon emissions between HICs and LMICs are so considerable that they negate the potentially greater carbon legacies associated with high-fertility strategies. A woman in Bangladesh, for example, would need to have 74 children before her carbon legacy equaled that of an American woman with one child (Murtaugh and Schlax, 2009). As argued above, carbon emission disparities between HICs and LMICs can be viewed as byproducts of low extrinsic risk environments, which increase competition and allow for the benefits of larger investments to be accrued in the future (Kaplan, 1996). Conceptualized historically, these low-risk environments permitted the emergence and development of industrialization, which increased the need for sustained parental investment through emphasizing education and other extrasomatic resources. Concurrently, these increases in industrialization also decreased environment risk, through advances in healthcare, sanitation, and technology (Bar and Leukhina, 2010; Boserup et al., 1983; Boucekkine et al., 2007; Caldwell, 1976; Coale, 1984; Galor and Weil, 2000). As the fitness benefits of more future-oriented slower strategies increased, including future orientation, so too did the per capita emissions of individuals. If this
439
argument is correct, a positive correlation should exist between CO2 emissions and future orientation.
LHT and Evolutionary Psychology: Resolving the Population Paradox The observation that population increases, and decreases, elevate carbon emissions complicates the development of solutions to anthropogenic climate change. Indeed, efforts to decrease extrinsic risk levels in LMICs would, theoretically, reduce the demographic contributions towards emissions by promoting investment in slower strategies. Reductions in demographically linked emissions, however, would likely be offset by subsequent increases in per capita investments in potential parents and offspring. Critically, these consequences ensure that fertility reductions by themselves will not be sufficient in decreasing carbon emissions (see discussion in Cohen, 2010). In light of the observations above, reductions in emissions will come through channeling somatic and parental investments towards pro-environmental investment. To this end, I argue that the life history component of future orientation can be co-opted to produce pro-environmental investment patterns. This co-opting can occur when somatic investment in potential parents and parental investment in offspring is directed towards investment in education, particularly higher education. As discussed further below, this argument rests on evidence indicating that education promotes future orientation and that future orientations, in some contexts, promote pro-environmental behaviors. Education levels are positively correlated with future orientation, or related constructs (e.g., delay discounting, patience, risk-taking), across cultures, development contexts, and subsistence types, including populations in the United States (Alan and Ertac, 2014; Jaroni et al., 2004; Oreopoulos and Salvanes, 2011; Van der Pol, 2011),
440
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
Denmark (Harrison et al., 2002), Turkey (Alan and Ertac, 2014), Mexico (Perez-Arce, 2011), Vietnam (Anderson et al., 2004), rural populations in India (Bauer and Chytilová, 2013), and Uganda (Bauer and Chytilová, 2010), and in small-scale societies in Bolivia (Kirby et al., 2002). Longitudinal research (Alan and Ertac, 2014; Perez-Arce, 2011) and studies using exogenous sources of variation in education to infer causation (e.g., differential access to education across villages, changes in compulsory-schooling laws) have shown that education can promote increases in future time orientation, delay discounting, and lower the propensity towards risk-taking (Bauer and Chytilová, 2010; Lochner and Moretti, 2004). Further, education promotes future time orientation across a range of risk contexts, as demonstrated in studies finding that education has the largest impact on time orientation in disadvantaged youth, a finding consistent with recent results suggesting that education has the largest impact on fertility within high-risk environments (Caudell, 2015). Although education can produce a more future-oriented psychology, future orientation also is associated with pro-environmental attitudes and behaviors, both across individuals and cultures (Arnocky et al., 2012; Carmi and Arnon, 2014; Joireman et al., 2004; Lindsay and Strathman, 1997; Milfont and Gouveia, 2006; Toepoel, 2010), although others have not found a link (Ebreo and Vining, 2001). Future orientation is an essential aspect of sustainable and pro-environmental behavior as it emphasizes changing one’s behavior in the present to take responsibility for future outcomes (Carmi and Arnon, 2014). Important for the current argument, however, is that the association between future orientation and pro-environmental behavior is largely confined to highly educated individuals, particularly those with a college education. This proposed link is consistent with results showing that environmental concern and behavior are related to education level, but only at higher post-secondary
levels (Franson and Garling, 1999; Johnson et al., 2004; Olli et al., 2001; Wall, 1995; but see Wesely Schultz, 2001). Considering the research above, the prediction can be extended that an individual’s and country’s investment in higher education will mediate the effect of future orientation on per capita emissions through impacting both demographic and consumption patterns.
Predictions The analysis that follows assesses the following predictions: P1: Present orientations should be associated with traits of faster life history strategies whereas future orientations should be associated with slower strategies. P2: A positive correlation should exist between a country’s CO2 emissions and future orientation. P3: Investment in higher education will mediate the effect of future orientation on per capita emissions through impacting both demographic and consumption patterns.
Methods Predications were tested through multilevel analysis of data provided by 95,752 women from 75 countries (Model 1) and linear regression analysis of national-level data from these same 75 countries (Model 2). Model specifications and data sources are discussed below. Stata 16 was used for analysis (StataCorp, 2019).
Model 1: Measures and data sources Total fertility rates were used as proxies to reflect the slow-to-fast LHT continuum. Rates were collected for women 55 years and older, who have largely completed fertility. Extrinsic risk levels were represented by taking the average life expectancy at birth (LEB) in the 10 years after a person was born. Education level (EDU) was recoded
441
EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY AND CLIMATE CHANGE
Table 22.1 Descriptive statistics for Model 1 Variable Total fertility rate (TFR) Education level (EDU) Future orientation (FO) Life expectancy at birth (LEB)
Mean
Std dev.
3.75 1.25 45.54 64.67
2.85 1.00 24.88 10.98
Min
Max
0.00 0.00 0.00 27.08
20.00 3.00 100.00 82.12
N = 95,752. Std dev. = standard deviation. Education level is coded as 0 = None, 1 = Primary, 2 = Secondary, 3 = Post-secondary.
into none, primary, secondary, and post- secondary. A country’s time orientation was quantified by Hoftstede’s (2001) Long-Term Short-term Orientation measure. Long-Term Orientation represents the ‘fostering of virtues oriented towards future rewards’, whereas ‘Short Term Orientation stands for the fostering of virtues related to the past and present’ (Hofstede, 2001: 359). Given the scale anchors, 0 (most present) to 100 (most future), it will be referred to as future orientation. The measure has been a source of some debate (see Ashkanasy et al., 2004; Fang, 2003) but scores have been validated through factor analysis of time orientation items in the World, African, and European Values Surveys (Minkov, 2007; Minkov and Hofstede, 2011). In addition, studies have found that score variations are associated with behaviors impacted by time orientation, including sales of life insurance, across cultures (Park and Lemaire, 2011). Future orientation scores were calculated for 75 countries to reflect a geographically and economically diverse sample (e.g., different continents, high- versus low-income countries). See Table 22.1 for descriptive statistics and Table 22.2 for Pearson correlation coefficients between Model 1 variables.
Data for Model 1 were collected from the World Values Survey (www.worldvaluessurvey.org/; WVS, n.d.), European Values Survey (www.europeanvaluesstudy.eu/; EVS, n.d.), and surveys available at the Integrated Public Use Microdata Series-International from the Minnesota Population Center, including the Demographic Health Surveys (www.ipums.org/; IPUMS-DHS, n.d.). Data were collected from years closest to the date the future orientation was measured in the country. Not every country had data from the year the future orientation measure was collected but all data used in the analysis were plus or minus five years from this date. As stated above, education level (EDU) was coded into four categories: ‘none’, ‘primary’, ‘secondary’, and ‘post-secondary’. Some surveys recorded an individual’s education in years, and these were recoded using the following criteria: 0–2 years = ‘none’, 3–5 years = ‘primary’, 6–12 years = ‘secondary’, 12+ years = ‘post-secondary’. Life expectancy at birth (LEB) is defined as the number of years of life remaining at birth. Average LEB in the 10 years after an individual’s birth was calculated from data collected at the World Bank (http://data.worldbank.org/) (World
Table 22.2 Variable correlations for Model 1 Variable
Total fertility
Education
Future orientation
Life expectancy
Total fertility Education Future orientation Life expectancy
−0.48** −0.36** −0.39**
0.34* 0.53**
0.42**
-
**
p