492 34 32MB
English Pages [286] Year 1965
THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY
THE MIDDLE A AND THE RENAISSANCE BY
EMILE BREHJER
TRANSLATED BY WADE BASKIN
B77 THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO CHICAGO AND LONDON
361S82
£5 PRESS ^
Originally published in 1931 as Histoire de la philosophic: le Moyen Age. Ill: Le Moyen Age ® 1931, Presses Universitaires de France
L'Antiquite et et la Renaissance.
The present bibliography has been revised and enlarged to include recent publications. These have been
supplied by the translator and Joseph Betz
SBN:
226-07218-^ (clothbound); 226-oj2ig-^ (paperbound)
The University of Chicago Press, Chicago 60637 The University of Chicago Press, Ltd., London ® 1 965 by The University of Chicago All rights reserved. Published 1965
Fourth Impression
1
970
Printed in the United States of America
1% CONTENTS The Early Middle Ages
I
II
The Tenth and Eleventh III
IV
V
VI
i
Centuries
The Twelfth Century
46
Philosophy in the East
88
The
Thirteenth Century
The Fourteenth Century VII
The Renaissance INDEX
265
215
113
183
27
THE EARLY MIDDLE AGES DURING THE FIFTH CENTURY the Unity o£ the Mediterranean civiHzation was shattered just shattered.
invasions
With came
as
poHtical
its
the destruction of towns that
marked
unity was
the barbarian
the disappearance of traditional centers of culture
throughout the West, and with the destruction of urban civilization
came
the collapse of the sophistical instruction that
had imposed
unity on the last part of the age of antiquity.
its
How
was
possible for instruction to continue
under the de-
plorable conditions that existed until the time of
Charlemagne?
it
Here we must age: attention
one general
recall
was directed
less
characteristic of the late
toward
than toward the development of the spiritual
need was met not by the
Museum
of
Alexandria, but by
the Therapeutae of Philo,
life,
and the universal
chairs of sophistry or of science,
gradually became philosophical schools.
Roman
intellectual training per se
modeled on
conventicles
spiritual
that
They had sprung up among
Lake Mareotis, described
in the writings of
and countless Pythagorean, Hermetic, and Platonic com-
munities flourished even within pagan
though the
spiritual Hfe
was
still
circles.
Furthermore,
need for rational organization paramount in certain stance,
among
Plotinians), in others
it
tended
respect a mystery cult with a set of formulas,
Thus
it
was not by
clination that all the
al-
pre-eminently intellectual and the
to
circles (for in-
become
rites,
in every
and sacraments.
violent revolution but through natural in-
remnants of
intellectual life
were preserved
2
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
in the Christian communities, particularly in monasteries, after the
West had solidly embraced Christianity. Almost imperceptibly, therefore, a remarkable change came about: intellectual life was completely subordinated to religious life; philosophical problems were studied against the background of man's destiny as conceived by Christianity. religious life
The
period during which the
remained dominant marked the boundaries
—
—which are
somewhat vague of the intellectual Middle Ages. The modern age began with acceptance of the autonomy of intellectual methods and problems a revolution so profound that even today we can scarcely comprehend all its consequences. naturally
—
I
Orthodoxy and Heresies
in the
Fourth and Fifth Centuries
On
this
point
we must
the East
we
detect the
West from
carefully separate
great religious controversies that
marked
East. In the
the end of antiquity in
same metaphysical preoccupation, the same
concern with determining the intelligible structure of things as in
Neo-Platonism of the same Christological
question— that
All of
era.
and the
Trinitarian question
them concern
is,
either the
of hypostases or the
interrelations
the relation between the
a divine hypostasis
and Jesus Christ
appeals to authority
and
man.
as a
And
to Scripture the divergences
Word
as
in spite of
between theo-
logians seem to be mainly philosophical.
On
the one
hand
modalists feared that
there were
making
the
the
heretics.
Word
the
Sabellius
Son
of
and the
God would
and Arius, in the same spirit, reversed the argument and accepted the Son of God as a person only on condilead to polytheism,
tion that
he be made the
first
of
all
God's creatures "but without
being eternal or coeternal with the Father, for
The whole Antioch but a
man
is
his principle."
^
school refused to see in Jesus Christ anything
perfected by divine grace,
combinations of
God
God and man, an
and
it
rejected metaphysical
idea that permeated Christianity
^Quoted by Harnack, Lehrbuch der Dogmengeschichte (3d
ed.), H,
191, n. 2.
THE EARLY MIDDLE AGES
3
following Nestorius and spread even to the Far East. All such opinions bore the stamp of the same rationaUstic inspiration directed
toward
classifying, avoiding confusion,
making
distinctions.
was orthodox dogma which sought
tering the heresies
Coun-
to reconcile
theocentrism (which eliminates any possibility of difference within divine unity) and the distinctions indispensable to the very existence
and the Council
of Christianity. Athanasius
Trent confronted
of
Arius with the argument of the unity of substance in
God
together
with the diversity of the three persons, and Cyril of Alexandria and the Council of Ephesus
human and
that the duality of
prevent
Mary from being
Conflicts
condemned Nestorius by arguing
(433)
abounded
divine natures in Christ did not
the Theotokos, the
in the
West
as well
Mother
of
God.
during the same
but
era,
they were of a different order. All issued, directly or indirectly, from
Church and
the need for the institution of the
was true Africa,
of Donatism,
and which had been
debate presided over by true of Pelagianism,
The Church
in
tion of divine grace
The
hierarchy. This
which
Augustine combated
St.
in
when
the
It
was
also
all
his
life.
in existence for a century
Augustine took place in 411.
St.
an institution necessary for the dispensa-
role as
its
its
which originated and almost prevailed
was incompatible with both of
these heresies.
Donatists held that the validity of a sacrament depended on
the spiritual state of the priest
meant
rejecting the
objective rules,
Church
who
and exposing
it
for stability,
and
is
it
it.
This would have
grounded on
to all the
appraisal of the morality of priests.
ment
conferred
as a society
strict, practical,
hazards of a subjective
Formalism
is
no more necessary
the prime requirefor the
jurist
As
who
decides
what
for Pelagianism,
is
right to be personally just.
the starting point of the conflict
attempt on the part of the form.
To
who Roman
one
confers the sacraments to be a saint at heart than for the
refute Christians
was an
monk Pelagius to promote monastic rewho used the weakness of the flesh as
an excuse for not complying with divine law, he preached that
man
has the strength to do good
powers of
human
nature.
He
if
he so wills and pointed to the
insisted "that the soul should not be
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
4
remiss or hesitant in the pursuit of virtue simply because
impotent and
is
ignorant of
with
to Stoicism
its
own
potential."
confidence in virtue; but
its
us the sin of another;
work
of a
and not it
presents Christ's
it
model teacher or
as the
work
a
model
of a victim
the negation of
is
it
God
original sin transmitted by heredity, since
feels
it
His view goes back
-
cannot impute to
work
as if
it
were the
doctor, such as a saintly Cynic,
whose merits
justify
denies that the vehicles of grace, the sacraments
man;
finally,
which the Church
provides for the faithful, are of any importance.
To
counteract such notions
St.
Augustine cited the personal ex-
perience of his conversion and the effective reality of the Church.
Pelagius were right,
If
man would
not have to ask through prayer
when he
be freed from temptation or to pray
to
The
erred.^
Pelagians strove to identify our good with that part of us which
not of God;
is
they granted that good will
if
was only because they put
God would
in this case
it
in the
same
follows that the good which comes
which comes from God. sequences of
this
with existence; and
class
St.
attitude:
man himself makes
from us
is
Augustine traced in
good can enter the
on merit acquired through grace, belongs only
God throughout damned;
justly
eternity; children
who
it
we
good,
superior to that detail the
soul,
original sin, only through a special grace; salvation,
by
this
also be the author of evil will; or if
grant that he produces only will and that it
came from God,
con-
corrupted by
which depends
to those predestined
die without baptism are
the heathen, never having been touched by the
grace of Christ, have never attained virtue.
This dual
conflict,
together with the solution proposed by St.
Augustine, throws light on the setting in which Western thought
was
to evolve: a
Church with
control over salvation.
full
The work
power of
thereafter to exercise full
Pope Gregory the Great was
to be the final consolidation of the spiritual
The
conflicts of the early
cal politics ^
Ad
^
Augustine
power of the Church.
Middle Ages have
to
(in the highest sense of the term)
Demetrium,
Ad
cited by Harnack, Lehrbuch, Marcellinum ii. i.
III,
i6i.
do with
ecclesiasti-
rather than with
THE EARLY MIDDLE AGES
5
dogma
in the Eastern sense, that
the metaphysical structure of
is,
when brought
the divinity. St. Augustine's thought, so rigid
human
bear on the reUgious U£e of the
dogma
to
in the strict sense.
For
soul,
is
to
vague with respect
instance, in the controversy over
the origin of the soul (whose solution seems, moreover, to constitute
an indispensable complement
hesitates
holds that tionism,
to his doctrine of grace),
he
without drawing a conclusion between traducianism, which
human
souls are propagated by generation,
which holds
that each soul
who
fiercely attacks those
believe that
whole nature
quality or his
as if
crea-
"man can
discuss his
own
no part of himself escaped him."
moment when
Furthermore, from the
power with Gregory the Great
and
created ex nihilo; and he
is
*
they seized undisputed
until the twelfth century, the popes
gave no encouragement to theological speculation. Politicians and
were more concerned with establishing
jurists before all else, they
and insuring the
drawn from
rights
souls than with giving direction to
The
II
It
was
Fifth still
an
spiritual
power over
movement.
and Sixth Centuries: Boethius
possible for the philosophical tradition to lend valuable
support to the verities of
faith.
Such was the conviction
nus Mamertus, a Provencal monk,
drew together
468)
their
intellectual
who
in
De
statu
of Claudia-
animae
(ca.
the views of the philosophical authorities on
the spirituality of the soul.
He
cited St. Paul to prove that philos-
ophers were not so ignorant of truth as their contemporaries ac-
cused them of being, and he took his colleagues to task for their intellectual indolence.
He
complained that Plato was treated with
contempt even though "many centuries before the Incarnation," long before
one
God had
God and
men
revealed the truth to men, Plato "discussed the
the three persons in him."
of the late
Middle Ages came
to
^
know
Through Claudianus, the views
on the
corporality of the soul expressed in the Phaedrus, the Timaeus, *
De
anitna et ejus origine
^Migne, Patrologia Latina,
iv. 2.
LIII, 746d.
in-
and
6
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE work
the Phaedo) his
also
table type of erudition,
was the
last
provided them with a model of a lamen-
which consisted of disconnected
and
extracts
descendant of the doxographies in which the age of
summed up its philosophical past as it was drawing to a close; in his work we find alongside the Greek philosophers (Pythagoreans and Platonists) the Roman philosophers (Sextius and
antiquity
Varro), then the barbarians (Zoroaster, the Brahmans, Anacharsis), and, of course, the Stoic Chrysippus, whimsically cited to prove the spirituality of the soul.
In the
work
of Anicius Manlius Severinus Boethius, "the last of
the Romans," born
in 480,
named
consul in 510, appointed to high
by Theodoric, and accused of magic practices and executed
office
Middle Ages had a
in 524, the late
comprehensive but more
less
substantial account of ancient philosophy. Boethius
had undertaken
the staggering task of translating into Latin the works of Plato Aristotle
and those
ceeded, his project, tury,
of several of their commentators.
which was not revived
would probably have changed
Had
and
he suc-
until the eighteenth cen-
radically the course of medieval
philosophy. Actually, however, his accomplishment was limited to the translation of gories, followed
some
of Aristotle's writings
on
logic: the Cate-
by a commentary inspired by Porphyry's;
pretatione, followed by
De
inter-
two commentaries; Porphyry's Isagoge,
lowed by a commentary inspired by Ammonius.
He
fol-
prepared hand-
books on categorical and hypothetical syllogisms and on topical differences, but
he translated none of Aristotle's other works on
logic.
Thus
on
a portion of Aristotle's writings
cogent representative of antiquity! This fact
logic stood as the sole is
and
categories of substance, quality, quantity, to things themselves, as Boethius indicated
as signifiers of things
is
first
of
corporeal thing.
all
It
a
name
follows
is
a
do not
refer
basis of Porphyry's
classes. Aristotle deals
and with things
words. For him, therefore, language
name
so forth,
on the
work, but neither are they simple grammatical with words
important. Aristotle's
human
as signified
institution
by
and any
that serves to designate a particular that
categories
and,
after
them, the
THE EARLY MIDDLE AGES
7
whole of logic are naturally adapted
and made
to corporeal things
for them.
This
the crux of the problem posed at the beginning of the
is
Isagoge: "As for genera and species (designated by words that no
longer signify corporeal, concrete things), have they an existence or are they only in our thoughts? If they exist, are they bodies or in-
corporeal things? If they are incorporeal things, are they separate
or do they exist only in sensible things?" Porphyry merely raised the
commenting on them indicated but did not
questions; Boethius in
sanction the solution proposed by Aristotle. is
patently
drawn from
The proposed
solution
the criticism of Plato's ideas: a genus exists
simultaneously in several individuals and obviously cannot exist in itself;
numerical unity of a being in
itself
is
incompatible with
dispersion of genus in species or of species in individuals.^
Boethius
also
completed some theological works which were
widely read and annotated until the twelfth century. They are closely linked to his dialectical writings; for instance, his
Trinitate
De
sancta
based on the question, "Are the rules of dialectic ap-
is
plicable to propositions enunciated
cautions are to be taken and
what
by the theologian?
What
pre-
particular rules are to be followed
in using discourse for subjects for
which discourse was not
de-
signed?" Boethius was also influential by virtue of his celebrated work,
The
Consolation of Philosophy, which he wrote in prison following
his disgrace. Its literary
Roman
There
form
diatribe
(a
is
hardly a trace of Christianity in the work."^
mixture of verse and prose)
and
its
substance
Platonic theodicy. His aim a victim: Is the course of
is
is
is
drawn from
modeled on the the Stoic and
to explain the injustice of
human
events, so disordered
which he
is
when com-
pared with the perfect order of nature, in the hands of blind fortune?
The
old theme appears in Plato's Gorgias and
Laws and
in Plotinus'
Enneads. His doubting and despair are dispelled by two types of ••
Ibid.,
LXIV, 82b-86a.
{Revue Critique, 1928, p. 377) finds almost no trace of a distinction between purgatory and hell (Patrologia Latina, LXIII, 806). '^Gilson
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
8
come
remedies. First
the "milder cures": Fortune, in a diatribe
shows Boethius that he has no reason
similar to that o£ Teles,
complain, that true happiness accommodates
bad luck has
shows that
Philosophy
resides solely in is
true
God, who
is
all
events, that even
Then come "more which
happiness,
the
Good and
violent cures":
is
independence,
perfect unity.
God, who
the author of nature, can direct beings only toward the good; and
evil, since it is
advantages.
its
to
to
cannot be produced by God,
nothing. All that remains
is
the affirmation of Providence to the fact that, as experience
fit
shows, the wicked prosper. Philosophy replies, through the Gorgias
and the Republic, wicked
men
that their prosperity
are actually unhappy.
The
depends on Providence, whose will natural forces.
The
quite different
from apparent
result
is
is
only apparent, for
is
fate of
all
each being in reality
executed in detail through
the realization of true justice,
And
which
the objection
is
is
raised
that such a view of destiny assumes the negation of freedom,
which
seems
to
justice.
if
be antithetical to divine prescience, Boethius at
first
answers
with Cicero that prescience does not prove the necessity of events,
and then
that
edge of God,
own
it is
wrong
who
for us to base
our concept of the foreknowl-
Hves and perceives in an eternal present, on our
type of reasoning.
A moving book in spite of its factitious one of the few testaments
to a
moral
character,
life
other than the spiritual powers of the day.
not be classed as unique
is
that the
works
it
long remained
inspired by something
The
only reason
it
can-
of Lucan, Vergil,
and
Cicero were also studied during the late Middle Ages. If to these
works we add
his treatise
De institutions arithmetica, De institutio musica, we
based on Nicomachus of Gerasa, and his see
the role that Boethius played in the
Western world
in the
transmission of Hellenic culture to the Middle Ages.
After Boethius, for
going
who was
to the sources
not original but at least deserves credit
and dealing with questions
in depth,
we
humble compilers who devoted their attention to preparing extracts and summaries of ancient works for the instruction find only
of clerics.
One
of their models
was Martianus Capella the African,
THE EARLY MIDDLE AGES
9
who, toward the end of the
Wedding
century, under the
fifth
Mercury and Philology, had written
of
The
title
manual
a
which
in
each book from the third through the ninth was devoted to one of the seven liberal
arts.
knowledge
of his
The to
author was himself a compiler
Varro.
The
who owed most
fourth book (the Dialectic), which
men
begins with a eulogy of the famous Latin scholar, acquainted of the
Middle Ages with the
property,
and
terms
five
—genus,
tions, propositions,
and
The
syllogisms.
sixth
details
book
some
in the
task of assembling
which he had
juxta-
positive theorems.
Cassiodorus (477-575), a friend of Boethius life
mainly
consists
from Euclid's Elements. The seventh book
poses a symbolic arithmetic and
of his long
and with opposi-
from Pliny the Elder,
of a long description of the earth, borrowed
and a few
species, difference,
accident; with the ten categories;
who
spent a part
monastery of Vivarium, took upon himself the
and transmitting the fragmentary knowledge
He
access.
to
wrote an encyclopedia of theology called
the Institutiones divinae and explained the liberal arts in Saccular es lectiones. In
knowledge put
the
first
of the
of the liberal arts
to the service of truth.
two works, however, he is
states
that
rooted in the Bible and must be
He cites
as basic the
grammar
of Donatus,
and QuintiUan,
the rhetoric of Cicero annotated by Marius Victor
a dialectic that does not go beyond that of Martianus Capella, and
summaries of Boethius' arithmetic and Euclid's elements. His
treatise
De anima
was based on
St.
Augustine and Claudianus
Mamertus. The author was aware of the duality of inspiration that sets
soul.
philosophy against religion in the matter of the nature of the
The
"masters of secular letters" define the soul as "a simple
substance, a natural form, different
from bodily matter, possessing
the use of the organs and the potency of of veracious doctors"
it
stance, the cause of life
mortal,
and capable
is
life."
But "on the authority
"created by God, spiritual, a true sub-
on the part of the body,
of turning to
good or
rational
evil."
separate proofs of immortality offered by secular
and im-
He was
able to
men of much
(mainly the proofs found in the Phaedo) from the
proof offered by the "veracious authorities" (that the soul
is
letters
easier
created
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
10
image
in the
God)
of
.
among men, he mentioned
philosophers
error
faith
conditions the question of the relation between reason
was not easy
An
to resolve.
not a
set of speculative verities that
ment
or conflict. It is first
constitutions or rules of that
human
follow
Reason and Faith
Under such and
"who
of evil
^
rather than the law of the creator."
III
knowledge
Finally, in discussing the
two kinds
law are imposed:
It
a spiritual city, one
This
city
—
as the starting point of philos-
grammar,
the arts of speaking
all
rhetoric,
and
dialectic
and discourse; and the
quadrivium, which includes the four subjects posited by Plato the starting point of philosophy
and music. Here liberal arts are
to other clerics
as
—arithmetic,
justified in
doing so only
advance knowledge of divine things.
drivium
Such
is
and Seneca, the
who
teaches
them
to the degree that they
trivium finds
its justifica-
and explaining Scripture and the
tion in the necessity of reading
writings of the
The
as
geometry, astronomy,
in the philosophy of Philo
not ends in themselves; the cleric is
im-
totality of propaedeutics, or the liberal arts that
embraces the trivium
which includes
is
to establish definitively.
and Seneca posited
like Philo
ophy.
it
political
knowledge: secular and divine. Secular knowl-
of
edge embraces the
men
is
can serve as a basis for agree-
imposed in the same way that
Augustinianism intended
plies
Church
institution like the
Church Fathers and
of teaching
dogma. The qua-
indispensable in liturgy and ecclesiastical computation.
restricted applications
do not focus attention on the need for
enlarging upon acquired knowledge and promoting these fields of
own
learning for their
sake; emphasis
is
placed instead on providing,
through encyclopedias that vary in scope, an inventory of the heritage of the past.
The
result
is
that
all
such knowledge
is
and lacking in autonomy, for all that is retained which has been inherited and can be of service to the Church.
rational
It is
purely is
that
not surprising, therefore, that before the time of Charlemagne
®Migne, LXX, 1279,
especially chaps,
i,
ii,
and
x.
THE EARLY MIDDLE AGES
II
encyclopedias were written in the regions of Europe where traces of the intellectual Hfe
still
subsisted,
namely
recalled in ancient books":
as
on the trivium and the quadrivium,
three books dialectic
some
in Ireland.
Bishop of Seville (570-636), wrote his Etymologies dealing
Isidore,
with "the origin of certain things
on
and
in Spain
which chapters
in
taken from Apuleius and Martianus Capella contain
of the elements of logic as well as the divisions of philosophy;
then seventeen books on everything that might interest a
cleric in
matters of the calendar, history, natural history, and geography.
Later the Venerable Bede (672-735) of the monastery of Jarrow
wrote a
De
natura rerum of the same quality. In
it
he copied Isidore,
but more often he relied on Pliny the Elder.
Knowledge ferent.
their
of divine things,
Authority
which
on
rests
arguments on authority, and the Arians
support their view.
St.
Vincent of Lerins
torium, written in 354, to resolve the
based on authority.
authority,
dif-
is
not something simple; even the heretics based
is
He
cited Scripture to
tried in his
difficulties raised
Commoni-
by arguments
laid bare the thought of the Middle Ages
as
he formulated standards for identifying the true tradition in matters of faith: one should
and look with
show preference
distrust
for the opinion of the majority
on private opinions;
if
heresy threatens to
spread, however, one should cling to the opinions of the ancients; if
these opinions are
found
to contain errors,
decisions of an ecumenical council or,
if
one should follow the
no council has been held,
question and compare orthodox teachers and hold to the opinions
common
to
organic;
it
all.
Tradition does indeed grow, but
never proceeds through
rather through development
addition
or
its
growth
innovation but
and elucidation. Thus from the
ginning of the Middle Ages standards were
set
up
is
be-
to allow spiritual
unity to be preserved without any intervention of philosophical
thought.
In contrast, medieval thought concerning divine things was influenced by St. Augustine and the Neo-Platonic tradition.
God
intelligence in the highest sense, the source of the intelligible;
knowledge or contemplation of God
is
is
and
the highest limit of intel-
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
12
knowledge. Like Plotinus,
lectual
the soul has been put in order,
communes with which
itself,
then
it
will dare to see
and the father
verities flow
all
Augustine thought that "when
St.
made harmonious and of
all
beautiful,
and
God, the source from truth."
Beneath
this
vision, reserved for the few, "the intelligent soul united naturally
with
intelligibles perceives truths in a certain incorporeal light identi-
cal in
nature with
The two themes
itself."
^
are unrelated
:
on the one hand, a
discussed by councils and synods as
if
the other hand, a free spirituality in
by
faith but
is
which knowledge
directed toward complete
Middle Ages
great paradox of the
set of
is
is
not limited
knowledge of God. The
the affirmation of their
darity: to understand the truth about
God
is
The
soli-
understand the
to
truths of faith; reason, viewed as enlightened intelligence,
summate
formulas
they were rules of law; and on
must con-
faith.
spirit of the
age
is
revealed particularly in works on the
instruction of clerics, such as the
De
clericorum institutione, by
Hrabanus Maurus (776-856), Abbot of the monastery The third book in the De clericorum institutione
in 822.
books in
pilation of the last three
Doctrine.
It relates all
wisdom,
St.
of the truths of religion revealed in Scripture.
perfection
chapter of the third book,
"is
the study of the
a
com-
Christian
knowledge
"The foundation and
Hrabanus Maurus wrote
of wisdom,"
On
Augustine's
directly or indirectly, to
Fulda
of is
Holy
in
the
second
Scripture."
And
the literary production of the period consists mainly of countless
commentaries of the Old Testament (especially of the work of the six days), the Gospels,
and the Episdes. For the most part these
commentaries merely repeat and amplify the commentaries of the great scholars of the preceding century, St. Hilary
The
rules for writing
and
St.
Augustine.
commentaries were drawn, through the
intermediary of the Greek and Latin Fathers, from Philo's allegorical all
commentaries.
The commentator
knowledge, whether
scientific or philosophical.
requires the cleric to have ®Cf. Boyer,
De
I'ldee
has a right to
knowledge
make
use of
Hrabanus Maurus
of pura Veritas historiarum
de Verite chez saint Augustin
(Paris,
1880), pp. 190, 199.
THE EARLY MIDDLE AGES
13
and
of
modi tropicorum locutionum
distinguish
must be interpreted
a lengthy dictionary of of
other words, to be able to
between Scripture that must be taken hterally and
Scripture that
names
— in
He
also provides
the allegorical interpretations of the
all
assembling
thus
people,
biblical
allegorically.
materials
com-
for
mentaries.
But the commentators go
further. All disciplines
must serve
their
end, even the doctrinae gentilium which include the "liberal arts"
and philosophy. From Boethius
to
Hrabanus Maurus we
detect in
doctrinal writings an intellectual tradition wholly alien to Christianity
and the Church. But our concern
enumeration of
is
not so
much
the
the remnants of ancient culture preserved in the
all
old encyclopedias as the assessment of the attitude of Christian
commentators toward the mass of knowledge transmitted
is,
them
to
without the key that would enable them to gain access to
it,
without the intellectual methods that had made possible
its
that dis-
covery.
Their attitude was somewhat ambiguous. There was (doubtlessly derived the heathen to the
from
Augustine)
same source of truth
truth emanates:
"The
of the century
must be
for these truths
St.
truths
found
as that
in the
a
tendency
to relate all doctrines of
from which Christian
books of the learned
men
Truth and Wisdom,
attributed solely to
were not estabUshed from the outset by those
whose books they
are
read;
instead,
in
they have emanated from
the eternal being and been discovered to the degree that Truth
and Wisdom have permitted learned men
to discover
everything must be related to a single term, whether
found
to
it
be useful in the books of the heathen or what
them; thus be what is
is
salutary
in Scripture" (chap. ii).
The method logical
method
discover
of science did not differ essentially of the
what God had
commentator was
commentator. The
from the
object of science
philo-
was
to
instituted in nature, just as the object of the
to discover
what God had
instituted in Scripture.
This entailed the separation of the bad sciences and the good sciences: the
bad sciences had
to
do with "the
institutions of
men"
14
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
(chap, xvi), that
and the good
with the worship of idols and the magical
is,
were
sciences
in turn divided into
relating to the corporal senses
—history,
two
classes: those
we know
through which
knowledge of the present through the
the past,
arts;
senses,
and con-
jectures concerning the future (for example, astronomy), based
experience {experimentum)
But the notion of
— and the seven liberal
arts.
unique source of truth tending
a
on
bring
to
about fusion and unity was counteracted by a wholly different principle.
According
nated
all else,
commentary
to this principle,
and inventories of the profane
of Scripture domi-
sciences should serve
only to provide materials for illuminating the spiritual meaning of
Grammar,
Scripture.
for example, contains in
view one element indispensable
Hrabanus Maurus'
understanding of the Psalter;
to the
dialectic will teach the rules
and
show what can be deduced
correctly
interrelations of truths that will
from the
truths taught by
and the science of numbers
Scripture; arithmetic
hidden meaning of Scripture, inaccessible
to
will reveal the
the ignorant;
geo-
metrical porportions utilized in the construction of tabernacles and
temples help us to penetrate the spiritual meaning of Scripture; and
astronomy
indispensable in reckoning
is
Knowledge
A
time.-"^^
same end
of the universe serves the
comprehensive image
is
as the liberal arts.
the prime requisite.
Bede
in the
De
natura rerum described the world according to the order of the elements: the sky with
its
planets
and
stars; the air
with
its
meteors,
comets, wind, thunder, lightning, rainbow; the waters, the ocean
with
its
tides, the
with
its
inner
Red
life,
its
Sea,
and the
rising of the Nile; the earth
De
temporibus gives a complete
volcanoes.
catalogue of the six ages of history, the
establishment of the these
vast,
ceptions,
Roman
all-inclusive
we
last of
which began with the
Empire. The information contained in
catalogues,
which, with but few ex-
in
find no trace of direct, personal experience,
which everything
is
in particular), appears in encyclopedias
Hrabanus Maurus, who derived "Migne, CVII, 395-98;
and
in
based on tradition (and on Pliny the Elder
cf.
Augustine
his
De
Hke the
De
universo by
knowledge mainly from
ordine
ii.
13.
Isidore
THE EARLY MIDDLE AGES
15
The work owes
of Seville.
unity) to
its
unity (to the extent that
whole universe in
vast allegorical interpretation of the
its
which every
detail has a spiritual
possesses
it
meaning. The inspiration of the
Holy Scripture permeates every page.
We
what
then,
see,
materials
culture:
salvation of
man.
it
philosophers,
after St.
circles,
warm
losophers were accorded a especially
the
things that are true and in essays,
we must
it
to
Augustine, the ancient phi-
arts,
are called
Hrabanus Maurus,
says
Platonists,"
who
"are found to have said
harmony with our
faith in their treatises
not be afraid but must wrest from them these
from wrongful
things, as
and putting
it
reception. "If those
following his discussion of the liberal
and
placed not on under-
is
from within but on cataloguing
In enlightened
use.
of effecting the
find not the slightest trace of the spirit that
animated the Hellenic age. The emphasis standing
work
the great religious
for
We
absorbed from the Hellenic
Christianity
possessors,
and make use of them" (chap,
xxvi).
we
If
try to picture to ourselves the
means
that a
man
of the
eighth century had of picturing to himself his philosophical heritage,
we
had three sources
find that he
a series of
from
of information.
The
first
was
works which, though authentic, were decadent, detached
their origin, disparate,
and linked together by a common Neo-
Platonic spirituality. Such were Chalcidius'
Commentary on
the
Timaeus, the translation of the beginning of the same dialogue by Cicero, and Macrobius' Commentary on the
which passed from Plotinus and Porphyry
Dream
to St.
of Scipio,
Augustine.
The
second source was the great number of doxographies that provided
many
historical
falsified
details,
which were increasingly is
offered by
Maurus,^^ were used by the Fathers as background Finally
and
with time, about schools that had disappeared. These
doxographies, a good example of which cation
distorted
of
pagan philosophical
the
come
to their identifi-
and Christian
heresies.
Boethius' technical treatises on logic, based on Aris-
tode.
" De universo
sects
Hrabanus
xv.
i
(Migne, CXI).
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
l6
The
catalogue of their philosophical heritage, incomplete and
distorted, explains the confidence as well as the distrust of
Maurus
and illuminated by rays of truth in the hands of
tool
dangerous when
is
Hrabanus
and others like him. Philosophy, indispensable as a logical
men
like Plato,
brings us to the brink of heresy.
it
Pedagogical concern dominates the work of Alcuin (735-804),
who was called from England by Charlemagne in 781 and whose name symbolizes the intellectual renaissance projected by the king of the Franks. Alcuin reformed the clergy of the Prankish
which had sunk
to its intellectual nadir,^^
Empire
and he estabHshed the
Palatine school for the purpose of promoting secular education.
His handbooks on education, grammar, his treatise
rhetoric,
on orthography added nothing
and
dialectic,
and
to earlier compilations.
Alcuin's correspondence shows that he wielded great authority in his
time and that he upheld the
utility
De
respect to theology. In his treatise trinitatis
he cited
St.
Augustine
to
of profane studies with
fide sanctae et individuae
prove that "rules of dialectic are
necessary and that the most profound questions concerning the
Holy Trinity can be elucidated only by
virtue of the subtlety of
the categories."
]ohn Scotus Erigena
IV
The work
of
John Scotus Erigena
is
the best introduction to the
philosophical preoccupations of the theologians of the period. Eri-
gena was the product of the Church of Ireland, which on several occasions
had manifested
its
independence of Rome. Bede in his
Ecclesiastical History quotes the letter in
him
which Pope John
criticizes
for being remiss not only in matters of discipline but also in
matters of doctrine; he was falling back into the Pelagian heresy.
The
were
classic poets
the ninth century,
" Cf.
the precept in
^Migne, XCV,
113.
still
read in Ireland, and Greek was
who was born
studied.^^ Erigena,
was one
De
still
in Ireland at the beginning of
of the "Scots" brought to the continent
spiritu: Disce ut doceas.
THE EARLY MIDDLE AGES
17
He
to teach.
840.
He
was welcomed
works of Dionysius the Areopagite
translated into Latin the
and those of
his
Charles the Bald around
to the court of
commentator, Maximus the Confessor. These works,
previously sent to France by the pope during the reign of Pippin,
were then handed over once again in 827
Louis the Pious by the
to
ambassadors of Emperor Michael IL Erigena's translation
is
made during
Middle Ages,
the
not
word. Like most of the
really a translation in the strict sense of the
translations
is
its
word-for-word
fidelity
exasperating and suggests that the author, like a mediocre school-
meaning
boy, tried to decipher the translated each until the
word
of the sentence only after he
was not translated again
separately. Dionysius
end of the twelfth century.
The works
of Dionysius
were one of the important sources of
the Neo-Platonic conception of things found in Erigena.
were not the
On
sole source
Predestination,
references to the
He
clearly.
shown by
is
which was written
works of Dionysius,
the fact that in his treatise
and which contains no
in 851 his
Neo-Platonism shows up
De
divisione naturae, in addition to
Dionysius and Maximus, he relied mainly on
Gregory of Nyssa,
less
and Epiphanius, and very
Origen, and
Jerome.
St.
St.
He
logic
on
rarely
St.
Ambrose,
often turned for support not only to the
Fathers but also to philosophers or the learned
on
Augustine, then on
frequently on Basil of Caesarea, Gregory
of Nazianzen,
the treatises
That they
refers in sufficient detail to his authorities to enable us
to identify his sources: in the
and
had
men
of the world:
by Boethius, which acquainted him with Cicero
Aristotle, Plato's
Timaeus, sometimes Pythagoras, more often
Pliny the Elder, and also the poets
Ovid and
Vergil.
He
Erigena, unlike his predecessors, was not simply a compiler.
had
a
mind
sufficiently strong
and independent
to enable
him
use his sources without being enslaved by them. His system
to
was
not a mixture, in different proportions, of Dionysius and Augustine; it
was
was
to
a carefully considered reply to the
dominate thinking
all
awesome question
during the
that
Middle Ages. The
Christian image of the universe and the Neo-Platonic image share a
common rhythm:
both are theocentric images that describe the
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
l8
way
dual motion of things, the their first principle
which things move outward from
in
and then return
to the principle. In the Christian
image the succession of these moments
which has
as its starting point a free initiative: creation
demption and a future successive
a series of events, each of
is
moments
life
of
bliss.
from a
are derived
sents a
change in that the same
as
it
first
fall, re-
natural, eternal necessity:
outward motion or movement away from the of absolute unity (the
and
In the Neo-Platonic image,
reality that
principle)
is
first
was
principle repre-
initially in a state
divided
more and more
proceeds through the lower levels of being, and the return
represents a reversal of the process of division,
which now gives way
to unity.
But the opposition between the two images of the universe by no means
is
as clear-cut as suggested here. Hellenic Christianity
was indisputably hypnotized by Neo-Platonism and tended (without ever succeeding completely) to interpret the sequence of events
recounted by the Christian myth as a sequence of sitated
by the nature of things. After the
dominated by the image of tween the emergence of
had of
a life of the universe alternating be-
God and
absorption in God, a pattern that
necessity profoundly influenced the Christian
tion, the fall,
This
Stoics, the
moments necesGreek mind was
work De
crea-
and redemption.
precisely the pattern rediscovered
is
image of
divisione naturae
is
by Erigena, and
his great
a comprehensive interpretation of
Christian theocentrism on the basis of Platonic theocentrism.
His
Neo-Platonism
Predestination.
appears
The monk
clearly
in
his
earlier
work On
Gottschalk posited the existence of dual
predestination, that of the elect
and
that of the
damned;
just as
divine predestination caused the elect to achieve justification eternal
demned
life,
so the other type of predestination forced the
to fall into
punishment.^* that orthodoxy
certain
men
From
a state of godlessness his
useless
Hrabanus Maurus, and
"/^/^., CXXII, 359c-36od.
to
suffer eternal
argument were deduced the conclusions
and good works were
to sin.
and
and con-
and later
that
God
forced
Hincmar, Arch-
THE EARLY MIDDLE AGES
19
bishop of Rheims, saw that the Church was in danger.
with having Gottschalk (849),
Hincmar is
with
stating,
actually refutes Gottschalk by
speculating on the divine essence: is
in
the
same cause cannot produce two opposite produce in him
found is
sin.
which
sin,
in St.
—
is
which
nothingness.
Good, and
is
evil
God
to
God—ac-
if
obvious that Erigena has
is
not a positive
interpreter to
God
:
God
reality.
rhythm
of Neo-Platonic
to his creature,
then the return
God; or moving through nature from God
as
obvious that his idea of rhythm
is
as end.-^^ It
drawn mainly from Maximus
show
is
the Confessor. Erigina quotes Diony-
that man's state after the fall will be
characterized by extreme division and digression ciple
and
a reality; he cannot be the
It is
divisione naturae follows the
from the creature
sius*
effects;
Furthermore God, being the supreme essence,
philosophy: procession from
principle to
dual pre-
Augustine two basic principles of Neo-Platonism
identical to the
The De
place,
produces justification in man, he cannot
the cause solely of good,
cause of
first
contrary to the unity of the divine essence, for the
cording to Gottschalk
is
Synod of Quierzy
the
Augustine, that the true phi-
St.
and
the true religion^^
destination
content
invited Erigena to write against him.
Erigena begins by losophy
condemned by
Not
from the
(God), while redemption will be followed by the
first
final
prin-
union of
beings with each other and with God. Furthermore, he states explicitly that the interpretation of
total reabsorption in
God
redemption as the beginning of
"has received scant attention" and that
only scattered references appear in the writings of the Fathers.
This rhythm simply denotes the division of nature according to all logical differences, as if reality
division of a genus into
and
is
not created, or
nature that
is
created
its
God and
were nothing but the
logical
comes nature that
creates
species. First
as the principle of things;
creates, or the
Word
that
is
then comes
engendered
by the principle and that produces the sensible world; then comes nature that "^
Ibid., 358,
" Cf.
is
created
and does not
according to Augustine
De
create, or the sensible
vera religione, CXXII, v.
the general plan, Migne, CXXII, 528c-d.
world;
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
20
comes nature that
last
supreme end tion
in
whom
terminated.
is
essential unity.
neither created nor creative, or
is
its
According
God is end. The
origin,
and the
Orphic formula, which Erigena
to the old
at the first
and
as the creator,^"
is
God
book) although unaware
middle term,
principle, the
God
with as the
the
as
principle,
is
end; the second with the
identical to the third, the created world;
and
the second
finally
first
same time the division,
identical to the fourth, with
Word
as the
But beneath these differences we detect an
quotes (in the eleventh chapter of the of
God
the motion of things in search of perfec-
third,
which together
constitute
shown through redemption
totality of created beings, are
the
to
be
identical to the fourth. It
ferences
By
presence in his thinking of these dif-
the simultaneous
is
and of
this identity that
seeking always to identify the
in the whole, he
imbues
his
permeates the work of Erigena.
whole in the parts and the
work with
the
same
parts
sort of tension that
we find in thinkers of his sort from Plotinus to Hegel and Bradley. What he is actually describing is the God of Plotinus, the God who seemingly moves from principle to end through the whole cycle of beings, but in
whom
there
find repose.
He
is
said to
in reality
is
tween motion and imm_utability, the
God who
move only because he (Book I). The
the motion of created beings
hypostases
no
is
identified with the Trinity, in
positive determination, while the
in all their simplicity
and
unity,
Erigena, with the help of beings
—the
St.
is
move
the principle of
Plotinian triad of
which the Father has
and the
Spirit distributes
them
of the Trinity
Augustine and Dionysius, finds
—in
turn symbolize the
manifestations, on the one hand, other, suggesting the
and the simple. On
ac-
which
movement
in
of procession or
evolution from the simple to the multiple, from hidden essence to
^'
to
triad essentia virtus operatic, the triad intellecttis ratio
sensus interior
on the
be-
Son contains the primary causes
The images
cording to genera and species.
no opposition does not
Among
the place of the word,
and from the idea
to its expression,
fundamental identity of the multiple
primary causes, cf.
its
De
as Plotinus states in dis-
divisione naturae
ii.
2
(Migne, CXXII, 526).
THE EARLY MIDDLE AGES
21
cussing his intelligibles, there
no inequaUty, no true diversity:
is
they are separated and isolated by inteUigence. That
is
and the
Spirit that contain
becomes a succession or progression,
in the eternal
their eternal unity
is
And
it is
marks the beginning that he
is
and
their properties.
God
and
of Genesis by Philo, he
the
enigma
is
at the
is
God
that
had
of the angels
and of things
notions perfect
vehicle for the return of
words, it
same time the being shaped from image of God. The solution of
of
are
them;
all
him
man
all
is
therefore the
is
in
him. But
man
from Paradise;
trans-
in other
and made him dependent on
way from it
the integrity of his essence.
will not only re-establish the
but will also be marked by the annihilation
and the
spiritualization of restrictions that
all
things.
must be imposed on
compare the system of Erigena and Neo-Platonism.
begin with, in the second part of his doctrine
concerns the nature of
man and
lowed the Fathers with scrupulous his state before
his
of his creator,
things to God, and because the return
This discussion indicates the to
He
inferior to himself.
to his animality
of the material world
man, before
primitive
all
at least as ideas
knowledge of himself and
the necessity of redemption:
any attempt
in him,
his fall resulted in his expulsion
tied
primitive state of
To
above animals with
an old interpretation
in the
but did not detract in any
Hence
is
to
through him, every creature
and it
but he
sought to create a microcosm in which
transgression,
gressed,
man
of
According
might be reunited; they his
effected
begins
an animal with respect to his senses,
intellect.
and through
is
is
and the being created
his creatures
The enigma
of the return, intervenes.
his nutritive life,
respect to his reason
from
here and only here that man, whose creation
a dual being: he
his passions,
it
simultaneous just as
After this extreme division the return of things to
(Book IV).
cause;
gradually evolved an arithmetic that progres-
numbers and
sively reveals all the
its
What was
represents but a further step in the division.
earth
the
world created and unfolded in time can no longer be
sensible
separated from the Son
is
why
and
the return to fidelity: the
after his transgression,
—the
part that
God—Erigena
fol-
dual nature of man,
man
as a
microcosm,
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
22 the
De
Ambrose's
De
of
interpretation
opificio
works.
And
—
of
all
of Nyssa's
turn from Philo's
in
De
imagine, and other
through these writers he managed
myth
things, a
myth
came from
notions
these
borrowed largely
paradiso,
mtindi, Gregory
tradition of the old
God and
Paradise
to reconstruct the
of Anthropos, the intermediary fully
between
developed in the writings of Philo
and completely absent from the works of Plotinus. Through them he also assimilated the anti-Hellenic idea (which he recognized such) of the end of the world and substituted order of Plotinus. There
nature to
is
God through man
If it is
we now
to recall the Plotinian retroversion in
first
God, being and
its
and unknown,
is
is
Word
visible
and unknown,
and
shall see that
will, are identical
primarily a theophany.
The
Of
is
manifested in us
course
terms; but
Father, invisible
Word; and
born in the same sense that intelligence,
the
at first in-
when we come
into con-
with sensible things; and the creation of the other things
simply an opportunity or a means for the fest.
we
emanation in which the
manifested through the divine
divine
is
principle to re-
influences through natural necessity.
willing, nature
the act of creation
its
as being.
part of the work,
not, in a strict sense, a true system of
principle radiates
tact
eternally to
and thus be constituted
return to the
as
for the eternal
nothing in the salvation or return of
which the emanative being returns ceive the overflow
it
Theophany and reabsorption
Word
to be
is
made mani-
in the first principle are differ-
ent from procession and retroversion in that the latter imply that reality
has a history and involves initiatives,
designate an eternal, unchangeable order.
while the former
Bibliography
Texts (und Theologie) des
Beitrdge zur Geschichte der Philosophic vols.
39
Miinster in Westfalen, 1891
Mittelalters.
.
Corpus scriptorum ecclesiasticorum Latinorum. 77 vols. Vienna, 1855 Les philosophes Beiges. Louvain, 1901-42. Continued as Philosophes medie.
vaux. Louvain, 1948.
Migne,
J.
P. Patrologiae cursus completus.
"Series Latina." 221
vols.
Paris,
1844-64.
Useful Translations and Anthologies Fairweather, E. R.
A
Scholastic Miscellany:
Anselm
to
Oc^ham. (The Library
of Christian Classics, Vol. X). Philadelphia, 1956.
Fathers of the Church:
York, 1947
McKeon,
A New
Translation. Edited by R.
J.
Deferrari.
New
.
R. Selections from Medieval Philosophers. 2 vols.
New
York, 1929.
(Paperback reprint). Pegis, A. C.
The Wisdom
Histories
and Studies
of Catholicism.
of
J.
a la fin
Histoire de la pensee. Vol.
du XVI'
York, 1949.
Medieval Philosophy
Burch, C. B. Early Medieval Philosophy. Chevalier,
New
siecle. Paris, 1956.
New
II:
York, 1951.
La pensee
chretienne, des origines
A History of Philosophy. Vol. II: Augustine to Scotus. Vol. Ock^ham to Suarez. Westminster, Md., 1950, 1953. Medieval Philosophy. London, 1952. Curtis, S. J. A Short History of Western Philosophy in the Middle Ages. Westminster, Md., 1950. De Wulf, M. History of Medieval Philosophy. Translated by E, C. Messenger. 2 vols. New York, 1935. Gilson, E. History of Christian Philosophy in the Middle Ages. New York, Copleston, F. Ill: .
1955.
23
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
24
La philosophic au moyen age. i vols. Paris, 1944. The Spirit of Medieval Philosophy. Translated by A. H. Downes.
Gilson, E. .
New
York, 1936.
and Bohner,
Die Geschichte der christlichen Philosophic von
P.
ihren Anjcingen bis Nil^olaus von Cues. Paderborn, 1937. Grabmann, M. Die Geschichte der scholastischen Mcthodc. 2 vols. Freiburg
im Breisgau, .
1909, 1911.
Die Philosophic dcs
und
Scholasti\
Haureau,
Mittelaltcrs. Berlin, 1921.
Geisteslebcn.
Mittclalterliches
.
Mysti}{. 3 vols.
B. Histoire
de
la
Abhandlungen
Munich, 1926, 1936,
zur
Geschichte
de
1956.
philosophic scolastique. 3 vols. Paris, 1872 and
1880. Leff, G. Mediaeval Thought: St. Augustine to Oc\ham. London, 1958. Maurer, A. A. Medieval Philosophy. New York, 1962. Picper, J. Scholasticism, Personalities and Problems oj Medieval Philosophy.
Translated by R. and C. Winston.
Ueberweg,
New
York, i960.
B. Geyer. Vol. II:
Die
patristische
und
Philosophy in the Middle Ages:
P.
E. C. Hall.
Weinberg,
J.
New York, A Short
R.
ed. Revised
by
scholastische Philosophic. Berlin,
1928. Vol. Ill: Philosophic dcs Mittelaltcrs. Edited
Vignaux,
nth
Grundiss der Geschichte der Philosophic,
F.
An
by
P. Wilpert.
1965.
Introduction. Translated by
1959.
History oj Medieval Philosophy. Princeton, N.J.,
1964.
Bibliographies
The
histories of
general
philosophy by
De Wulf,
and Ueberweg have good
Gilson,
critical bibliographies.
Bibliography of Philosophy. Paris, 1937 N. S. 1954 Bochenski, I. M. (ed.). Bibliographische Einfiihrungun in das Studium der .
.
Philosophic. Bern, 1948-53. Bulletin Thomiste.
Farrar,
Le Saulchoir, France, 1924
C, and Evans, A. Bibliography
Sources.
New
.
of English Translations
from Medieval
York, 1946.
Glorieux, P. Repertoire dcs maitres en theologie de Paris au XII I"
siecle.
2
vols. Paris, 1933, 1934.
McGuire, M. Introduction to Medieval Latin: A Syllabus and Bibliographical Guide. Washington, D.C., 1964. Progress of Medieval and Renaissance Studies in the United States and Canada. Edited by S. Harrison Thomson. Bulletin 22. Boulder, Colo., 1952.
Recherche de theologie ancienne et medievale. Separate theologie ancienne et medievale. Louvain, 1929 .
fascicle, Bulletin
de
THE EARLY MIDDLE AGES Journals Franzis\anische Studien. Paderborn, 19 14
.
Gregorianum. Rome.
Revue des
sciences philosophiques et theologiques. Paris, 1907-
Revista di filosofia Neo-Scolastica. Milan, 1909 Scholasti\. Freiburg
im
Breisgau, 1926
The Modern Schoolman. St. Louis, Mo. The New Scholasticism. Washington, D.C. The Thomist. Washington, D.C, 1937
.
.
.
I
Studies Harnack, A. Lehrbtich der Dogmengeschichte. 3 vols. Freiburg, 1894-97. J. Precis de I'histoire des dogmes. 6th ed. Vol. II. Paris, 192 1. 4th
Tixeront,
ed. Vol.
III.
Paris, 1919.
II
Texts Boethius. Opera. Migne, LXIII, .
The Consolation
LXIV.
of Philosophy. Translated by
H. Stewart and
E.
Rand. New York, 19 18. Claudianus Mamertus. Opera. Migne, LIU. Cassiodorus. Opera. Migne, LXIX, LXX. Martianus Capella. Opera. Edited by A. Dick. Leipzig, 1925.
Studies Barrett,
H. Boethius: Some Aspects of His Times and Wor\. Cambridge,
1940.
Courcelle, P. Les lettres grecques en Occident de
Macrobe a Cassiodore.
Paris,
1948.
K. The Propositional Logic of Grabmann, M. Die Geschichte der
Diirr,
1900, 1910. See
I,
148
Boethius.
Amsterdam,
1951.
scholastischen Methode, 2 vols. Freiburg,
ff.
H. The Tradition of Boethius. New York, 1935. Stewart, H. Boethius. London, 1891. Vann, G. The Wisdom of Boethius. Aquinas Paper No. Patch,
20.
Oxford, 1952.
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
26
III
Texts Alcuin. Opera. Migne, C, CI. .
W.
Rhetorica, in
Hornell,
The Rhetoric
of Alcuin
and Charlemagne.
Latin and English translation. Princeton, N.J., 1941. Bede the Venerable. De natura rerum. Migne, XC. .
.
Historia ecclesiastica. Migne,
De
temporibus. Migne,
Hrabanus Maurus. De
De
.
XCV.
XC.
institutione clericorum.
Migne, CVII.
universo. Migne, CXI.
Isidore of Seville.
Etymologiarum
libri
XX. Migne, LXXXII.
Vincent of Lerins. Commonitorium. Migne, L.
Studies Duckett, E. Alcuin: Friend of Charlemagne. New York, 1951. Gillett, H. Saint Bede the Venerable. London, 1935. Gilson, E. Les idees et les lettres. Paris, 1932. Pp. 171-96 on Alcuin.
Turnau, D. Rabanus Maurus, praeceptor Germaniae. Munich, 1900. New York, 1892.
West, A. Alcuin and the Rise of the Christian Schools.
IV Texts John Scotus Erigena. .
De
De
translated in
CXXII, pp. 355-439. CXXII, 442-1022. Book IV, chaps.
praedestinatione. Migne,
divisione naturae. Migne,
McKeon,
Selections,
I,
7-9,
106-41.
Studies Bett,
H. Johannes Scotus Eriugena. Cambridge,
Webb,
C. "Scotus Erigena:
De
1925. divisione naturae," Proceedings of the Aristo-
telian Society, II (1892-94), 121-37.
THE TENTH AND ELEVENTH CENTURIES NOT UNTIL the end of the eleventh century was there a real revival of intellectual activity in the
Western world.
This does not mean, however, that the intermediate period was void or unimportant. Everywhere in monasteries and cathedral cloisters schools
were being founded. These centers were widely
separated but united by a
common
culture.
From
the ninth century
on, there were cathedral schools in Auxerre, Rheims, studies
and
Paris,
and
were pursued in Aurillac, Saint-Gallen, and Chartres. Ma-
terial difficulties
were always present:
the East, papyrus necessarily
after the
and parchment became
remained impoverished;
in
at
rare
that libraries
one of the
860
the library of Saint-Gallen, contained four intellectual revival
so
Arabs conquered richest,
hundred volumes. The
the end of the eleventh century coincided
with the creation of religious orders actively engaged in copying manuscripts, and during the twelfth century the library of
St.
Vincent of Laon contained eleven thousand volumes."^
We
know
with respect
the approximate holdings of the late to philosophical
Middle Ages
works: in the ninth century Saint-
Gallen, for example, possessed Apuleius' works on logic, works by
Cassiodorus, Isidore, Bede, and Alcuin, and Aratus' these
to ^
holdings
were
added
Boethius'
Phenomena)
Consolation,
L. Maitre, Les ecoles episcopales et monastiques de I'Occident depuis
jtisqu'a Philippe
Auguste
27
(Paris, 1866), especially pp.
278
fJ.
Lucan's
Charlemagne
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
28
and The Dream of Scipio (perhaps with Macrobius' commentary) in the tenth century, and Boethius' treatises on logic
Pharsalia,
The
in the eleventh. tellectual
horizon
which were very
We
have
glosses
at a
listing reveals
time when
the
culture
narrow
limits of the in-
was based
solely
on books,
rare.
practically
nothing from the period other than marginal
and commentaries
(most of them unpublished)
the
of
writings of Boethius or Martianus Capella. Education, apart from the Christian doctrine,
gus),
was given over almost exclusively
Eric of Auxerre (died in 876),
lectic.
who
Remi
of
to
dia-
Auxerre (or Remi-
taught in Chartres around 862, Bovo of Saxony, living at
the beginning of the tenth century, Gerbert of Aurillac,
came pope under the name
who opened
pupil Fulbert,
of Silvester II
be-
(999-1003), and his
a school in Chartres in 990, are the
principal authors of commentaries.
century had preserved a
who
A
document from
listing, in the
the eleventh
order in which they were
presented, of the subjects taught in dialectic at Chartres.^ Students
took up in succession: Porphyry's Isagoge, Aristotle's Categories,
Augustine's
Categories
Definitions, Cicero's
(with
a
preface
anonymous compositions
rhetoric, Boethius' Divisions, Gerbert's treatise
rationali,
and
Boethius'
Topics, Aristotle's and Apuleius' Peri Her-
meneias, Boethius' Topical Differences,
on
by Alcuin),
St.
finally Boethius'
De
ratione uti et
Categorical Syllogisms and
Hypo-
thetical Syllogisms.
The
art of discussion
was obviously perfected by such
a system of
education, which endured for years. Every art other than dialectic
would seem Geometry
to
have been neglected. The only exception
is
Gerbert's
983), which seems because of the methods of measurement employed in it to betray the influence of the Arab (ca.
mathematicians.^ But dialectic reigned supreme and inculcated in the
minds of men
tinctions
and
a predilection for discussion, for the endless dis-
divisions
that
dominated the whole of medieval
philosophy. * '
bei
Quoted by A. Clerval, Les ecoles de Chartres an Moyen age (Paris, 1895), p. 117. Wiirschmidt, "Geodatische Messinstrumente und Messmethoden bei Gerbert und den Arabern," Archiv der Mathematik, und Physil{ (1912), p. 315.
THE TENTH AND ELE\ENTH CENTURIES
29
The Controversy
I
What
of
Berengar of Tours
matters in the history of philosophy
is
as the art of discussion as the use to
which
it
to arrive at a conception of reality.
To
not so
much
dialectic
put in an attempt
is
be specific,
we
recall that
Boethius' collection posed several metaphysical problems, the
which
of
comes
celebrated text; next (just as in the case of St. Augustine)
no
the problem,
Middle Ages, of the
celebrated during the
less
The
limit of the application of categories.
ten categories or genera
and
of being apply only to the sensible world,
works only with the incapable in the problem
to
is
some
determine
we
how
it is
since
it
species,
is
dialectic,
embrace genera and
categories that
turn of attaining to a superior
its
reality. Finally,
to light
first
the problem of the reality of universals in Porphyry's
is
But then
reality.
possible to refer to a superior
note that in his commentaries Boethius brought
of Aristotle's technical notions of philosophy, for ex-
ample, the notions of form and matter and of act and potency.
Much more
We
is
involved here than the simple art of discussion.
notice this in Fredegisus' Epistola de nihilo et tenebris,
according to Prantl, the historian of logic,
The
less."
Gerbert's
little treatise
De
it is
nothing
"Since reasonable
said of this difference;
sumed by
is
and
this difference."
rule of logic
which holds
to
is
imply that
rationali et rationalibus uti
art-
is
it
is.
more
in-
Porphyry says in the Isagoge
structive than such artless realism. :
and
rather "stupid
author, a pupil of Alcuin, maintains that nothingness
{nihil) exists, for to say that
(vii)
is
which
the specific difference, using reason it is
is
also said of all species of beings sub-
One might
confront Porphyry with the
that the predicate
must have an exten-
sion superior or at least equal to that of the subject.
violated since the term reasonable
is
a potency
Here
whose
the rule
act
is
is
using
reason, with the result that the subject has an extension superior to its
predicate.
Gerbert replies by
making
a
distinction
between
predicates that are a part of the essence of the subject, as reasonable is
a part of the essence of
man, and
accidental predicates, such as
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
30
using reason
when
only to predicates of the
The
rule of logic applies
type.
first
sharp distinction between essential and accidental attributes
makes
problem of universals. For
possible a clear statement of the
universals,
whose
reality
was the subject of speculation, are nothing
but the genera and species
which
The
said of reasonable.
it is
—for
example, "animal" and "man"
are essential attributes of an individual like Socrates.
point Boethius' commentators, such as Pseudo-Hrabanus
(whose Super Porphyrium the eleventh
generally assigned to the
is
On
Maurus
first
that appeared
century), followed the hints
this
half of in
the
writings of their master and that had their source in Aristotle.
They
repeated what had been said by Boethius and also by Simpli-
cius: that the Categories, the study of attributes,
cannot refer to
things (since res non praedicatur) but only to words as signifiers of things.
Hence
the problem of universals predicates
imbued with
the solution,
essential
to
genus and species
:
We
is
sometimes
reality
exist
only by virtue of
"Individuals,
individual.
the
genus are one and the same not, as
the spirit of Aristode, of
(eadem
res),
species,
and
and universals are
something different from individuals."
stated,
hear an echo of Aristotelian thought, through the intermediary
of Boethius, in the statement that genus to the individual as
The
matter
is
to
and
species
is
form.
middle of the eleventh century, (died
changed into the
also involved dialectic. Paschasius
had taught
860)
ca.
"through the power of the is
to species
controversy over the Eucharist, which took place in the
Radbertus
wine
is
of transubstantiation implied,
and blood of
first,
in
consecration
the
substance of the bread and
Spirit, the
flesh
that
Christ."
an omnipotent
His theory
God whose
will
is
restricted
by no law of nature and, second, radical independence
of
what the
eyes perceive through the senses
faith, since "in the visible species the
more than
that
which
sight
and
and the mind through mind apprehends something
taste
can perceive." Berengar of
Tours had no intention of denying that the Eucharist was a
ment
in the sense in
which the word
is
used by
St.
sacra-
Augustine: a
sacred sign that takes us beyond the sensible appearance to an in-
THE TENTH AND ELEVENTH CENTURIES
31
telligible reality.
We
or an apostate.
ist
must guard against making of him
Imbued with
a rational-
the dialectical teaching of Fulbert
of Chartres, however, he could not conceive of transubstantiation,
which requires us simultaneously wine are on the
altar after the consecration, since
cannot be allowed to stand in
entirety
its
down."* The question implied
struck
and deny that bread and
to affirm
is
right to contradict ourselves in formulating
Many
the
On
same ambiguity.
that neither dialectic nor philosophy
On
establishment of a dogma.
no
real contradiction
The
stantiation.
Adelmann
of Liege,
philosophy:
of
have the
dogmas?
is
had anything
to
do with the
a
good example of the in
its
first line
entirety because of
pagans
and
its
of argument.
biting criticism
but also about the world and what
who
itself
believe in the
same manner recede from
as sailors
God
Timaeus, in the
see shores
the
more reason why,
stars are motionless, that
is
not
Chalcidius'
*
^
human
the
that
snow
is
black." All
from grace
—
senses nor is
appre-
faith.
wrote toward the end of the controversy,
also took the authoritarian viewpoint:
solved "not by
which
commentary on
dogma, neither our
in matters of
who
trees
dismisses the opinion of those
warm and
a virtue that issues
Alger of Liege,
in the
with their towers and
our intelligence can enable us to apprehend that which
hended only by
more
is
dismisses Heraclitus' old notion,
knew through same way that he
believe that "the sun
What
motion of the sky are deceived
the eleventh century
who
it.
the
with a rapid rotary motion, and that
who
them?"^ He
in
is
have
philosophers
noble
absurd than stating that the sky and the those
that
written by his schoolfellow from Chartres,
"Certain
the earth turns on
told
hand he was assured
rightly been scorned for their false opinions, not only about creator,
were
hand he was
the one
the other
is
was entailed by the affirmation of transub-
letter
might well be quoted
It
Do we
this:
parts
its
different refutations appealed to Berengar, but they
marked by
all
"an affirmation
one of
if
reason,
which
Exposition by Lanfranc (Migne, CL, 41 6d). In Heurtevent, Durand de Troarn, p, 290.
the question is
must be
re-
completely inadequate,
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
32
but by the testimony of Christ himself with regard to his saints."
He
explained the relation between reason and faith by the follow-
ing comparison: our intellect with regard to
God
our senses
like
is
comparison with intelligence or one sense in comparison with
in
another, that,
unable to understand but forced to believe what
is
the fundamental discontinuity of the mind.
And
manner
yet the
same Alger,
It
at the
was no contradiction
the reference
on the altar:
is
end of
show
his treatise, tried to
in transubstantiation.
not the same
and when we
altar
"With
it
more
radical
there
would hardly be
possible to state in a
does not understand.
when we
state that the
respect to their appearance
ments are bread and wine; with respect
He
state thaat
explained that
bread
body of Christ
and
that
is
present
is
on the
their form, the ele-
to the substance into
which
they have been changed, the bread and wine are truly and distinctly the
body of Christ."
Finally, criticizing
same way Lanfranc, Abbot
the
in
^
of
Le
Bee,
while
Berengar "for abandoning the sacred authorities and
sorting solely to dialectic,"
and while asserting
fer to settle the debate solely
on the
that he
basis of authority
would
re-
pre-
and "that
in
treating of divine things, he desires neither to propose dialectical
questions nor to answer such questions," nevertheless pointed up his
shortcomings with respect to "the rules of discussion."
And
al-
though Lanfranc censured him for "putting nature before divine power, as
everything,"
dogma
in
settled
^
he
could not change the nature of anything and
still
was unable
to grant that there
that contradicted dialectic.
was anything
Thus, while the question was
by convoking synods that upheld faith (the synods of
and Verceil
Rome
God
if
in
in
1050,
1050 and
tempt was made
to
which condemned Berangar, the synods of
1079,
which forced him
make dogma conform
reason. ^
Migne,
^
Ibid.,
CLXXX,
CL, 419c.
Rome
74oc-d and
7530!.
to recant), every at-
to the rules of
common
THE TENTH AND ELEVENTH CENTURIES
33
Criticism of Philosophy Until the
II
End With
of the Eleventh Century
and the movement toward
the reform of the monastic orders
asceticism that characterized the last part of the eleventh century
(intense
faith
culminated in the crusade of
on the
the need for placing stricter limitations discipHnes. Peter
who
in 1057,
Damian
people
1095),
named Cardinal
(1007-1072),
the solitude of a hermitage,
is
who
one of the reformers
must not arrogantly usurp
proclaimed
his
condemnation? The famous
sibility of
a rule of logic eliminated the
freedom of God, the very foundation of ciously observed that rules
do not have reference
were invented
to the essence
of discussion."
^
it
lies
be-
(first
and the impos-
omnipotence and complete faith.
Peter
Damian
judi-
for use in syllogisms, "they reality
but to the
This meant a return, brought about by a
definitions to be indemonstrable.
method
fate
and matter of
sure instinct, to the doctrine of Aristotle,
and
What
contingent futures by means of the principle of contradic-
Thus
method
stated
argument
dialectical
framed by the Megarians) that demonstrated tion.
He
the role of a master but
be like the servant of a mistress {ancilla dominae)^
hind
of Ostia
sought to shun honor and fame by withdrawing to
the complete inadequacy of dialectic in matters of faith. "that dialectic
felt
role of the profane
who had
So long
of thinking than the syllogistic one,
to the status of a simple
as there
was
it
organon and not
declared premises
was no other
fitting to
to try to
reduce
make
it
the
instrument for investigating reaUty.
But
in addition to dialectic,
tive ease to its role of
bius'
Commentary on
which could be relegated with
rela-
organon, profane books, particularly Macrothe
Dream
of Scipio, spread doctrines about
God and
the world that were diametrically opposed to the Christian
doctrine.
Through them
tions
access
on the transmigration
was given
of souls
and
^ De divina ommpotentia v (Migne, CXLV, 604); and Roman Age (Chicago, 1965), pp. 3-8.
to Pythagoras' specula-
Plato's cf.
concept of the
E. Brehier,
The
Hellenistic
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
34
fabrication of the
tween
Platonists
world
and
mortality of the soul
soul, to say
impHed
nothing of the discussion be-
which suggested
Aristotelians
divinity. In
its
that the im-
them
was
it
stated
were on the earth inhabited but inaccessible regions,
that there
necessitating the conclusion that Jesus
them was something more than
had not saved
all
men. In
a conception of the
dialectic:
world in which salvation through Christ had no place. Manegold
Lautenbach (who died in 1103 in an Alsatian monastery) turned
of
on
adversaries,
his
declaring that readers too
attentive
to
such
dangerous philosophers were under diabolical inspiration.^
Nothing
is
easier in theory
than to separate theology and phi-
losophy, but in practice nothing
words such
is
more
difficult.
Theology used
and was forced to consult Aristotle's CateManegold himself, conceding the kinship
as substantia
gories for definitions.
between certain philosophical doctrines and
accepted the
faith,
Plotinian division that he found in Macrobius of political, purifying,
and purified
virtues.
On
was characterized by the
the whole, then, the eleventh century
inability
dispense with
of thinkers to
profane philosophy or to determine the Hmitations of
applicabil-
its
ity.
St,
Ill
That
Anselm is
why
the reasoning of St.
of great interest.
is
Anselm
of Aosta (1033-1109)
Taking up the Augustinian
tradition
every effort in his teaching at the monastery of
Le
Bee,
he made
where he
succeeded Lanfranc, to establish a more stable equilibrium between reason and faith.
The
reasoning of
St.
Anselm,
who
in 1093 be-
came Archbishop
of Canterbury, is easy to follow: Scripture and Church impose dogmas on our faith, such as those of the existence of God and the Incarnation; man accepts them solely on the
the
basis of authority,
standing. But reflect •*
when
and reason contributes nothing faith exists,
on dogmas and
man
CLV, 147-76).
his
under-
has in addition a tendency to
to seek to understand them.
Contra Wolfelmum (Migne,
to
As
Isaiah puts
it
THE TENTH AND ELEVENTH CENTURIES
35
(7:9), "If
you
will not believe,
you
will not understand." Further-
more, faith seeks to understand {fides quaerens intellectum) and
dogmas
the illumination of this
way
is
that one can acquire by reasoning in
an intermediary between pure
like
faith
and the
direct
vision the elect will have of the divine reality. St. Anselm's attitude is
in turn
mal
an intermediary between fideism that rules out any nor-
and mysticism
exercise of reason
vision into this It is clear
through
that St.
Anselm, through the strength of
on the works of
his meditation
elements of Plato's
which
leads
St.
faith to
to the beatific vision
from
set of
become
faith, that
man
elect
only by the grace of
dogmas on which depends man's become the
tellectual intuition has
Man
by the grace of God.
closely related to
is
and from
a theogonic virtue that reaches
and a
understanding
belief to discursive reflection
the latter to intellectual intuition; but belief has is,
and
his genius
Augustine, rediscovered
The path from
dialectic.
and from understanding dialectic,
that introduces the beatific
life.
is
salvation,
beatific vision
God
and
in-
accorded to the
incapable of taking the initiative
from the
and of attaining the end: the
intellectus receives
from
understand. Except for this datum,
faith, that
which
requires nothing
it is
more than
to
the dialectical subtlety that
outside, it
Anselm took
pains to have his pupils acquire through exercises such as those in the
De
grammatico; separated from
line of reasoning
which seems
We
to
however, the most subtle
to certainty,
but merely
states "that
me."
should note that
cal consideration
logical
cannot attain
faith,
arguments
St.
which to
Anselm's work
is
dominated by a
befitted a prince of the
Church. By using
prove the necessity of the Incarnation, for ex-
ample, he was trying to refute the objections of the infidels that the Christian faith contradicted reason. culiar character of his works, at the
:
common arguments and
said
pe-
clearly
nothing that he said must be
grounded on the authority of Scripture; he must write cussion in
who
That explains the
which he himself pointed out
beginning of the Monologium
ing only
practi-
clearly, us-
restricting himself to simple dis-
which everything was based on "the
necessity of reason
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
36
and the
This meant freeing himself completely
clarity of truth."
from the
conventions of his age and from slavish de-
literary
And
pendence on scriptural commentary.
though we must approach caution,
St.
Anselm
here
we
even
see that
with some degree of
his "rationalism"
took pains to determine what
nevertheless
reason could accomplish independently.
His
effort
was of course
The Monologitim and
restricted to purely theological matters.
the Proslogium, written in that order be-
God
tween 1070 and 1078, dealt successively with the nature of
and the existence of God. The
De
subject the radical unity of
truths in
all
show
was
and conversion of
infidels;
had
it
his
very
He
attempted to
a place in the salvation
he did not show the slightest concern
independent development of reason for
for the
Yet
helpful, that
as its
God. The Cur deus homo,
completed in 1098, explained the Incarnation. that reason
work, had
veritate, a later
own
its
method (and completely apart from
sake.
the
end he
sought to attain) implied conclusions on the nature of reason which
were of universal import and which were independent of his subject.
To
method
begin with, he rediscovered in the
Monologium
the Platonic
that posits for each category of similar things perceived by
the senses
and reason the existence of
a
model
The whole work might
ticipate as equals.
which they
in
bear as
its
par-
epigraph the
fundamental theorem of Proclus' Elements of Theology: "A term equally present to if it is
terms in a
all
not in one of them or in
In the same
way
by virtue of a
St.
all
Anselm saw
common
series
of
them but
that
a
to
prior to
good things
essence, the good,
good and then supremely good. Thus
shown by experience
can explain them
which
only
of them."
are as they are
is
independently
for each category of qualities
be of higher or lesser degree, he estabUshed
supreme greatness through which things are
being through which they there are just things.
all
all
He
are,
a
supreme
great,
justice
an absolute
through which
demonstrated that these terms
all
desig-
nate the same reality since there can be but one supreme nature.
Thus
dialectic leads
fect reality,
from imperfect multiplicity
from the per aliud
to the
per
se.
to a unique, per-
Moreover, the unique
THE TENTH AND ELEVENTH CENTURIES
37 being,
if
exists, exists of itself
it
would be
inferior to
(ex se)
for
;
if
it
had
cause. Finally, the universe
its
and was created or produced by
it
a cause
it
comes from
it
from nothing, but
in a rational
manner which would have been impossible had there the mind of the creator "something resembling a model to be
done
standard."
putting
or, It
Word,
things are in the it is
Word
the
is
a better
it
God,
of
of the thing
a resemblance, or a
him:
identical to
all
created
just as design exists in art not only
produced but before
It is
way, a form,
not been in
and
existence
its
when
after its disappearance.
Monologium two
easy to untangle in the arguments of the
elements that never quite interpenetrate: on the one hand, the Platonic dialectic, which
a general
is
ing from the sensible to the
from per aliud this
method
per se
is
per
to
diversity to unity,
and on the other hand,
a transformation of
world
God
as
no if
which being
the Creator ex nihilo of Genesis
Word. Alselm's confusion
the
plained by the Timaeus, with those
consisting in proceed-
from
into a religious metaphysics, as a result of
defined as
intelligible
se,
method
intelligible,
who from
Philo to
justification for
St.
its
demiurge and
is
and the
surely ex-
model, and by
its
Augustine perpetuated
it,
but there
all is
it.
The Monologium had determined what reason knows of God, he exists. The Proslogium (chaps, ii, iii) demonstrated his exist-
ence by means of a unique argument that has immortaUzed the
name
of St.
Anselm:
"We
believe that
you are something greater
than which no other being can be conceived to exist {quo nihil
majus
cogitari possit). Is
possible that such a nature does not
it
exist because a fool has said in his heart: 'There
the very least this fool,
on hearing
me
he hears; and that which he understands does not understand that this thing its
existence.
.
.
.
And
no God'? But
at
say 'something greater than
which no other being can be conceived to
being implies
is
exist,'
is
exists.
in his
The
understands what
mind, even
if
he
very idea of such a
surely the Being that
is
some-
thing greater than which no other being can be conceived to exist
cannot be solely in the mind; indeed, even
one can imagine a being
like
him who
if
he
is
only in the mind,
exists also in reality
and who
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
38
therefore greater than he.
is
who
mind, the being
is
follows that
It
he were only in the
if
something greater than which no other be-
ing can be conceived to exist would be such that something greater could be conceived to exist."
His proof
starts
not from the contemplation of Providence as
re-
vealed through nature, but from meditation on God, for which St.
"No
Augustine had provided the model.^^
he had
soul,"
said,
"has ever been able or will ever be able to conceive of anything better
than you
.
.
.
and
if
you were not incorruptible,
through thought to something better than thought
is
the
same one can surely :
my
could attain
I
God." The trend of
attribute to
God
that
cannot deny him without diminishing his perfection. things that are of that
was the
God
are in every
way
perfect," Plato
starting point of all rational speculation
had
which one
"God and said.^^
And
on God. But in
no instance had the notion been advanced of making existence an attribute that could not be denied
him by
virtue of his greatness
and
the immensity of his perfection. Philosophers implicitly acknowl-
edged the existence of clinch their
God
because this alone could in some
tion of the heavens without Aristotle's rationality of things verse.
that
way
image of the universe: there would be no eternal moprime mover, no perfect
without a Stoic logos that permeates the uni-
God is implied by the drama man and is, as in every other Anselm, who did not conceive
In Christianity the existence of
is
to
end with the salvation of
instance, a revealed truth.
But
St.
God in his relation to a cosmic order to which he is indispensable, and who did not wish by supposition to make use of revelation, had
of
but one aim: to prove God's existence by the same method of meditation that allowed
him
to conceive
God. His
is
not, as has
been aptly observed,^^ an ontological proof that goes from essence God's essence
to existence, for
proof has as tion of
God
its
as
is
unknown
to us.
starting point, not the essence of it
exists in
our understanding and as
"According to Draeseke, Revue de philosophic (1909), ^Republic 381b. Koyre, ed. and trans., Proslogium (Paris, 1930), p. 201,
p. 639.
n. i.
Therefore his
God it
but the nois
revealed
THE TENTH AND ELEVENTH CENTURIES
39
only through sedulous meditation.
how remote
ter
ence of
its
from
it is
It is this
notion which, no mat-
real essence, allows us to infer the exist-
object.
All these proceedings imply the affirmation of the possibility of a type of meditation that consists in sharpening our awareness of
God
the notion of
that
is
meant
at the
The
name
was
in truth attacking St. Anselm's
reality that
benefit of the in-
Anselm's proof in
St.
based wholly on apprehension. Gaunilon
is
whole theological method "The :
God—that I do not know. Nor me even to guess what
is
is
similar that will enable
you yourself else."
of
state that
is
it
that
we are unable him. The implied
firm or deny anything about
and
is
in theology
is
veritate.
starts
new
offered a
Here,
instance the
by Anselm
that takes us
legitimately to af-
conclusion
tions), of the senses,
shows
is,
and of
how
essences.
all
these truths
certain standard or rectitude.
which it is
ion; an act of will
same way
in the
The mere enumeration
the problem of truth
character of
the
elect.
method
De
He
right intention), of actions (right ac-
relates also to will, to the senses,
what
revelation,
depicts in a particular
The common
signifies
that
multiplicity to unity.
judgment but
signify that
is
multiplicity of truths: the truths of enunciations, of
opinions, of the will (that
these truths
from
nothing
to intellectus as the
application of his
Monologium, he
as in the
movement
from the
to
esse in intellectu
intermediary between faith and the vision of the
Anselm
like. Besides,
no method other than authority and
this negates the role assigned
St.
there anything
which can be likened
notion of God,
:
there
it
Gaunilon challenged Anselm's premise, the
God having no
It
argument by which
line of
Gaunilon, Prior of Marmoutiers, countered the
was indeed
this
end of the eleventh century.
on God without
that one could meditate
struction given by the Church.
of the fool
and
in our understanding,
make
a daring affirmation to
is,
A
is
and
is
true
actions
when
and the
its
aim
is
what
it
is
intended to
when
true
intended to signify; the same is
to the essences.
their conformity to a
verbal statement
and the statement
of
not restricted to
is
is
it
actually
true of an opin-
should be; and in
senses, taken in themselves, are al-
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
40
what
true because a sense always does
ways
should do;
it
finally,
the essences are true in the sense that things always have the es-
God
sence which
they should be. a
has willed that they should have and are what
The
notion of truth refers in every instance, then, to
supreme standard that
not because
it
exists eternally, to a truth that
must be something, but because
other truths are reduced.
it is,
would be impossible
It
and
is
to
rectitude,
which
all
to provide a clearer
statement of theocentric rationalism, which originated with Stoicism
and Neo-Platonism and truths,
not the
is
immanent method
eminent and unique
and
faith
intellect
it
formed
on the one hand
:
intelligible
Both views bend
is
a
human
is
the Christian
God
of
and transcendent world reason toward a region it
must be
trans-
deep-rooted divergence between the two theo-
hand
drama
the divine
discontinuous universe, whose events
of Christianity with
—creation,
sin,
and redemp-
—are due to unforseeable initiatives on the part of a free being;
on the other hand
whose order
is
a continuous universe
eternal
and
plainly in the Incarnation,
are separated in Platonism
invariable.
homo, to the
and
— the
divine and the
new
human — and
law. In the
that in-
Cur Dens
Anselm applies his method of fides quaerens intellectutn dogma of the Incarnation and tries to show the necessary character of the death of Christ.
If
nothing were
concerning the death of Jesus, reason would show that
cannot be happy unless a only
Their divergence shows up
St.
rational
known
without a history, and one
which binds together two natures
troduces into the universe a radically
To
the
into a vision.
centrisms: on the one
tion
them but
obvious in this
Anselm's work, that the contrast be-
cannot be exercised normally and where
But there its
is
particular
mainly the contrast between two ways
and on the other the
of Neo-Platonism.
where
St.
is
of presenting theocentrism
salvation
that discovers
reality that they represent. It
whole of
treatise, as in the
tween
which reason, transcending
in
God
God-man
men
appears and dies for them, for
can atone for a sin that has offended the divine majesty.
be sure,
Anselm does not reduce
Christian truth to a necessary
phase of an eternal order; but once sin has been posited, he
in-
THE TENTH AND ELEVENTH CENTURIES
41
troduces a rational necessity that directs
him toward
the Platonic
vision of things.
IV
Roscelin {Roscellinus Compendiensis) Despite
seemed
its
from
difference
Christianity, Platonism
must have
Anselm, when he saw the consequences of the doctrine
to
dogma
of Roscelin of Compiegne, to be linked by necessity to the of the Trinity. Roscelin's views, label of
known
Roscelin's views are
who
contradicted
recalled, held
whole of the
words
which
are
summed up under
the
nominalism, seem to be grounded on the logic of Boethius. only through a few extracts from those
him (Anselm and Abelard).
will be
it
with Simplicius that Aristotle's Categories and the dialectic
engendered referred not
it
and
as signifiers of things,
Roscelin said the same thing:
between genus and
and
to things but to
was but the
that the Isagoge
terms through which they are expressed.
classification of the five
distinctions
Boethius,
all
the distinctions
species, substance
human
relate to
and
made by
quality, are
discourse.
dialectic
merely verbal
But he added that the
only distinction grounded on reality was that of individual substances.
That
is
what Anselm
exactly
he summarizes in three
says in the passage in
articles the doctrine of the dialectician
universal substances are but verbal expressions (flatus vocis) is
nothing other than a colored body; man's wisdom
his soul." ^^ Roscelin
meant
are able to separate
man from
body, and
speaking
dom
wisdom from
is
that
it
indivisible.
walls,
and
from
Socrates, whiteness
That which, according
man
of
body into corporeal
To
say that
a roof
" Migne, CLVIII,
is
265a.
it
to Abelard,
and conventional
vision of things according to terms
is
to consider
;
"The color
only through speech that
is
the soul, but that the
celin completely arbitrary
:
nothing but
is
parts.
Any
one of
its
are
and wis-
seems to Ros-
not simply the di-
and categories but the very
in reality
we
a white
whom we
in reality Socrates, the whiteness a white body,
a wise soul.
vision of a
is
which
di-
body, such as a house,
made up parts,
is
of foundations,
such as the roof, as
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
42
being
at the
same time
a part of a
whole and a
distinct thing in a
hst of three things.^*
Roscelin seems then to have had the feeUng
meaning
nominaUsm)
of
that
and not
was ordered
that he
this
made by
distinctions
all
lectician existed only in speech
(and
in things.
is
the
the dia-
Yet we know
Council of Soissons (1092) to retract
at the
seems that he had drawn
his opinion
concerning the Trinity.
his inference
from the opinion of Boethius, who used the word "per-
It
son" to designate a rational substance;
God
many
as
it
follows that there are in
substances as persons (tritheism)
three persons are separated just as three angels there
power.
ism?
unity between
is
What
St.
relation
Anselm
them
is
when he
clearly
it
realities;
would
be,
the
and
if
merely a unity of will and of
there between this opinion
is
explains
"whose minds are
it
and the
the Father
;
Son, the begetter and the begotten, are two distinct
and nominal-
speaks of dialecticians
by corporeal images that they can-
so obsessed
we cannot understand how several persons are specifically one single man, how can we understand how several persons are one single God.^ If we are unable to distinguish between a horse and its color, how can we make a distinction between God and his multiple relations? If we are unable to distinguish the individual man from the person, how can we understand that the man assumed by Christ is not a person?" Acnot extricate themselves.
cording to this decisive errors.
for
text,
tritheism
was but one of
His nominalism was a principle subversive of
Roscelin's
all
he made distinctions where none should be made and
make and
If
necessary distinctions.
He
saw
distinct substances; in return
by Anselm), he did not tributes of
God
try to
theology, failed to
in the Trinity three individual
(this is the
make
second point raised
a distinction
between the
at-
(goodness, power, and so forth) and his substance,
nor was he able to
make
a distinction (this
is
the third point) be-
tween the divine person incarnate in Jesus, and his humanity. There was in this cleric from Compiegne a need to see clearly, a need not " Cousin,
satisfied
by the residue of thought from Aristotelianism
Ouvrages inedites d'Abelard,
p. 471.
43
THE TENTH AND ELEVENTH CENTURIES
and Platonism.
It
has been aptly observed that
thing "other than an academic question; the theologian
themselves."
is
if
we have
here some-
universals are reaUties,
dealing not just with formulas but with things
^^
"Seeberg, quoted by Grabmann, Geschichte der scholastischen Methode,
p.
311.
Bibliography
I
Texts
De
Berengar of Tours.
sacra coena adversus Lanjrancuin. Edited by A.
and
On
the
F. Vischer. Berengarii Turonensis opera.
dispute,
the writings of
cf.
Adelmann
Liege
of
Hugh
of Langres
(Migne, CXLIII,
Troarn, pp. 287-303; Lanfranc Troarn (Migne, CXLIX, 1375).
Berlin,
1289)
;
1834.
P.
100.
(Migne, CXLII, 1325) Heurtevent, Durand de
(Migne, CL, 410-12); and Durand of
Fredegisus. Epistola de nihilo et tenebris. Migne,
CV.
Gerbert. Opera. Edited by A, Olleris. Clermont-Ferrand, 1867. rationali et ratione uti. Migne, CXXXIX, 159-68. Opera mathematica. Edited by N. Bubnov. Berlin, 1899. Paschasius Radbertus. De corpore et sanguine domini. Migne, CXX, 1263.
De
.
1350-
Pseudo-Hrabanus Maurus. Super Porphyrium. In V. Cousin, Ouvrages inedites d'Abelard. Paris, 1836. Pp. xvi, Ixxvi.
Studies Ebersolt. Essai sur
Berengar de Tours
et la controverse
sacramentaire au X/*
siccle. Paris, 1903.
Endres,
J.
und
"Fredegisus
Candidus,
Beitrag
ein
zur
Geschichte
der
Philosophie des Mittelalters," Philosophisches ]ahrbuch (1906), pp. 439-46. Heurtevent, R. Durand de Troarn et les origines de I'heresie herangarienne. Paris, 1912.
McDonald, A.
J.
Berengar and the Reform of Sacramental Doctrine. London,
1930.
Pica vet, F. Gerbert:
Un
pape philosophe d'apres
I'histoire et d'apres la legende.
Paris, 1897.
Thomas Aquinas. Sum ma 44
theologiae,
III,
75,
i.
A
reply to Berengar.
THE TENTH AND ELEVENTH CENTURIES
45
IV
II to
Texts Anselm. Opera. Migne, CLVIII, CLIX.
The Proslogium, Monologium, Cur Deus homo. Translated by A. N.
.
Deane. Chicago, 1910. Dialogue on Truth. Translated by R. Peter Damian. Opera. Migne, CXLIV, CXLV. Letter to
Roscelin.
McKeon
in Selections,
Abelard. Migne, CLXVIII. Translated
into
I,
150-84.
French in
Picavet (see below).
Studies Anselms Beweis der Existenz Gottes Munich, 1931. Peter Damian: His Teaching on the Spiritual Life. Washington,
Barth, K. Fides querens intellectum.
Zusammenhang
in
Blum, O.
St.
seines theologischen Progratnms.
D.C., 1947. Clayton, J. St. Anselm:
Endres,
J.
A Critical Biography. Milwaukee, 1933. "Die Dialektiker und ihre Gegner in XI Jahrhunderte," Philo-
sophisches Jahrbuch (1906). .
Petrus
Damiani
und
die
wcltliche
Wissenschaft.
Beitriige
zur
Geschichte der Philosophic des Mittelalters. Vol. VIII. Miinster in Westfalen, 1910.
Gilson, E. "Sens et nature de I'argument de saint Anselme," Archives d'his-
du moyen age, IX (1934), 5-51. Damien et la culture profane. Louvain, 1956. Mclntyre. St. Anselm and His Critics. 1954. Phelan, G. The Wisdom of Saint Anselm. Latrobe, Pa., i960. toire doctrinale et litteraire
Gonsette,
J.
Pierre
Picavet, F. Roscelin, philosophe et theologien
d'apres la legende et d'apres
2d ed. Paris, 191 1. Spedalieri, F. "Anselmus an Gaunilo? sen de recta argumenti interpretatione," Gregorianum, XXVIII (1947), 55-77. I'histoire.
sancti doctoris
THE TWELFTH CENTURY THE TWELFTH CENTURY was
3.
cciitury o£ ficry
and
varied intellectual activity, a century of tumult and confusion: on
one hand there was a need for systematization and unity that gave birth to the encyclopedic tences;
on the other hand,
works of theology
certain circles into a return to ancient est in the sciences of the
called
books of Sen-
a great intellectual curiosity, translated in
humanism and
a
new
inter-
quadrivium. Furthermore, antiquity was
gradually unveiled by translations of hitherto
unknown
authors
and the resources of Hbraries were gradually expanded.
Four main a different
intellectual
tendencies are discernible, each against
background: theologians in
their Sentences
brought
to-
gether and unified the elements of the Christian tradition; Platonists
— true
humanists
—were
linked to the school of Chartres; mys-
were associated with the
tics
and
naturalists constituted a
disturb the spiritual power.
ent thinkers
who
cloister of St. Victor; finally, pantheists
group whose
activities
But there were,
were certain
cannot be placed in any category,
Abelard, whose complex and perceptive
to
in addition, independ-
mind
among them
reflected
all
the
passions of his epoch.
I
The The
Sententiaries
twelfth century was the period of the great theological en-
cyclopedias that were intended "to unite in a single body," as Yves
46
THE TWELFTH CENTURY
47
of Chartres expressed
all this.
life,
and morals. Philosophical preoccupation had no
discipline, faith,
part in
everything relating to the Christian
it,
But there was
a practical necessity in bringing to-
gether a vast array of scattered data. All of these data, often seemingly
had
contradictory,
Christianity
was
to
be unified
to
be preserved.
if
the
The works
spiritual
unity of
of the sententiaries
were prompted by a need not unlike that met by our codes: they
were by nature
juridical rather than philosophical.
Consequently
they were based on philology and on textual criticism. Bernold of
Constance indicated each point on which the authorities seemed
to
contradict each other and, as Vincent of Lerins had done before
him, gave rules for reconciling their views or for choosing between them.
The seventeen-volume Decretum
1116)
is
cepts.
From
universale,
we
of Yves of Chartres (died in
a survey {speculum) of doctrines of faith
the
and
ethical pre-
same period comes Radulphus Ardens' Speculum
something resembUng
a history of Christianity, in
find, alongside specifically Christian teachings, all that
which
remained
of ancient humanistic ethics. Before discussing salvation through
Christ (1.2), he explains the basic moral concepts of good and of virtue (i.i); before explaining faith 1.8),
he develops
human
tion
if
—the
virtues,
he speaks of cardinal
sciences
tries
naively to integrate with faith. For ex-
— according to the ancient system of
he finds that
theoretics, ethics,
(transmitted
and
logic, to
by
which
Isidore is
against the defects that issue
and weakness of the
from
or
Bede)
classifica-
comprise
added mechanics, he hastens
to note piously that the four sciences are four
error,
and
each instance he juxtaposes Christian truths and a hu-
manistic ethic that he
ample,
(1.7
thinking concerning virtue and vice (1.6);
and before deaHng with theological virtues. In
and the sacraments
remedies to be used
original sin: ignorance, injustice,
flesh.
This codification of Christianity occasioned a
series of
works that
continued throughout the twelfth century: the Questions or the
Anselm of Laon (died in 11 17), the Sentences Champeaux (1070-1121), Robert Pulleyn (died Robert of Melun (died in 1167), and especially those
Sentences of
of
WilHam
in
1
150),
of
of
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
48
Lombard,
Peter
the Master of Sentences
(died' in
1164),
which
soon after his death were being used for instruction by Peter
Comestor (died These
in
collections
and Peter of
1176)
were
Poitiers
(died in
1205).
to serve as the basis for all theological in-
struction during the following century.
The
Sic et
non
of Abelard,
who was one
of
Lombard's
teachers,
belongs to the same literary genre, since on each point of the Christian faith he cites the opinions of the Fathers, classifying
them
according to whether they say "yes" or "no." Abelard surely did not intend to draw any skeptical conclusion, but simply "to provoke readers to further pursuit of truth in the process."
He
-^
and
sharpen their perception
to
begins, moreover, by giving rules for reconcil-
ing the opinions of the Fathers.
These works naturally presuppose
a rational basis
The
subject matter
any codification solely
is
impossible.
without which
determined
is
by authority, but logical discussion must establish the
sig-
nificance
and value of an authority. In each
make up
the divisions or chapters in his book, Peter
Lombard com-
pares one text with another, the pro and the contra,
and chooses on
the basis of discussion rather than of citations. This
is
the so-called scholastic method, a dialectical
not one that discovers a
is
method
is
or
is
of Abelard
opinions.
method
The
possible in a
is
mind
scholastic
domain
in
the distribution of materials in the
and Lombard. The substructure of
the recital of the Christian drama,
God and
and
its
their
Here we have
work
is
elements are studied in
the Trinity, Creation, the Angels,
original sin, the Incarnation
eschatology.
subtle
considered as already given.
Another important point
this order:
method designed not
truth but one that grasps corre-
between
the only intellectual
which truth
work
new
contradictions
the origin of
and evaluation: the
for discovery but for examination
spondences
of the paragraphs that
man and
and Redemption, the sacraments, and
a concept of the universe that gradually
gained ascendancy, became dominant, and continued
to appeal to
many
drawn
'
philosophers long after the Middle Ages had
Migne, CLXXVIII, 1349a.
to a
THE TWELFTH CENTURY
49
close. First, the
hierarchy of reaUties
then the drama
itself
God
—original
The
of the elect.
sin,
—God,
the angels,
and man;
redemption, and the return to
dual theme includes
many
variations, but
they are bounded on the one side by a Platonism of which Erigena is
representative
God
turn to of
men
free
and which makes the descent of
man and
his re-
an eternal necessity, and on the other by the orthodoxy
like
Lombard and
and contingent
Thomas, who
St.
initiative at the
posit a
completely
beginning of each act in the
divine drama.
II
The School
of Chartres
Twelfth Century: Bernard of Chartres in the
Offsetting the
work
of the sententiaries
was the development
philosophical theology in the school of Chartres.
moving than
the efforts
made by
Nothing
is
of a
more
the adherents of the school to ex-
tend the intellectual horizon of their era beyond Boethius, Isidore,
and the Fathers.
Among
the initiators were Constantine the African
and Adelard of Bath, who provide valuable testimony concerning the beginnings of the establishment of relations between East
and
West. At the end of the eleventh century, Constantine, born in Carthage, traveled throughout the East.
He
translated, besides the
medieval books of the Arabs and the Jews, Hippocrate's Aphorisms with Galen's commentary, and two of Galen's lations
gave access
to
treatises.
His
trans-
Democritus' theory of corpuscular physics.
Adelard of Bath traveled through Greece and through the Arab lands at the beginning of the twelfth century and brought back
many
translations of mathematical works.
Elements from Arabic and introduced
He
to the
translated Euclid's
West, in addition
to
astronomical works, Alchwarismi's arithmetic. This represented an extraordinary addition to the quadrivium. Adelard was a mathe-
matician
who
also exhibited a predilection for Platonism,
Platonism came not from
St.
and
his
Augustine but directly from the Ti-
maeus, Chalcidius, and Macrobius.
He
wrote his short
treatise
De
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
50
eodem
et diver so to justify
philosophy; in
Philosophy and the
it,
seven arts engage in a debate, following the pattern
and Martianus Capella, with
Philocalia.
The
set
theory of knowledge
myth
outlined in the treatise presupposes the whole Platonic
psyche: intelligence in
state of purity
its
lost;
"then
it
searches for
memory, has recourse the Timaeus, 44a),
what
which allows us
of the imagination; but Plato
knowledge
is
knowledge
is
actually
It
:
sensible, is
starts
without the help
forms of things,
from
body.
as they
They
are
principles, Aristotle
composite things.
the basis of his solution to the problem of universals:
the distinction between genus, species, the distinction between animal,
—for instance, —has no meaning
and individual
man, and Socrates
other than in sensible things; the words designate the
viewed from a different angle.
"When we
they are not implied by the
name
of genus with respect to species. these
universals,
which
same essence
consider species,
not eliminate individual forms but simply ignore
fusing
and very
are probably
also right in stating that perfect
of the archetypal
simply taking opposite courses Plato
Such
its
(cf.
follows that Aristotle
know
exist in the divine intellect before they enter the
from
partially
is
to ignore "very small
knowledge (the minima
we cannot
right in saying that
things and their
tumult of the senses"
atoms, whose existence Adelard granted). is
of the
has lost and, betrayed by
it
to opinion"; "the
big things," prevents rational
knows
body" such knowledge
causes; "in the prison of the
by Boethius
of the species."
we do
them because
The same
is
true
But one must guard against conare
designated
by speech, with
archetypal forms as they exist in the divine intelligence; universals,
according to Aristotle, are
still
only sensible things themselves,
al-
though considered with more penetration. Archetypal forms are neither genera nor species,
which
are conceivable only in relation to
individuals, but "they are conceivable things, in the divine
mind."
knowledge com.parable
man ideas.
And
and
exist apart
sensible
here we are not deaUng with
to the beatific vision
knowledge, for the aim of
from
dialectic
is
but with ordinary huthe contemplation of
51
THE TWELFTH CENTURY who
Bernard of Chartres,
taught in Chartres from 1114 to 1124,
seems to have had the conviction, wholly characteristic of his group, that the
aim of scholarship was not expand
the past but to
we
giants;
it.
"We
to consolidate the
are as dwarfs
knowledge of
on the shoulders of
can see farther and farther into the distance than could
the ancients, not by virtue of the keenness of our sight or the size of
our bodies but because
we
are supported
giants."^ John of Salisbury called
him
and elevated by them
by
as
"the most perfect Platonist
of our time"^ and said that according to Bernard, universals are identical to Platonic ideas.
Was
Bernard
the author of the
also
short outline of Platonism that follows in the Metalogicus} In
John stresses the contrast between the immutability of ideas
and
it
the
mutability of sensible things, drawing his inspiration from Seneca (Eps. 58,
and
19,
One
49d-e).
whom
22),
he quotes, and the Timaeus (Ep.
thing seems certain in any case, and that
nard's brother, Thierry, wrote a
is
commentary on Genesis
that Berin
which
he explained the world through the concurrence of four causes
:
God
the Father as the efficient cause, the four elements as the material cause, the
Son
There
cause.
as the
is
formal cause, and the Holy Spirit as the
final
obviously in this passage an attempt to apply the
cosmogony of the
Aristotelian theory of the four causes to the
Timaeus, and the Christian formulas scarcely hide the four Platonic notions of the demiurge, matter, the order of the world, and the
good
(besides, later
on Thierry
explicitly identifies the
Holy
Spirit
with the world soul of the Timaeus). This interpretation of the
Timaeus
is
found in the
letters of
Seneca
(65. 8-10),
each of Plato's principles of the world with one causes.
The same
interpretation
is
also
who compares
of Aristotle's four
found in the preface
to the
Theology, a ninth-century Arabic work falsely attributed to Aristotle (see
below chap,
The Timaeus nardus
iv, sec. ii).
also served as the source of inspiration for Ber-
Silvestris in his
De mundi
universitate sive
microcosmus about the middle of the century. *
John of Salisbury Metalogicus
^Ibid.
iv.
^s.
iii.
4.
A
megacosmus
et
pupil of Bernard
52
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
William of Conches (died in 1145) wrote a Commentary on the Timaeus and a Philosophia imbued with Platonism. of Chartres,
It
is
worth noting
him
Plato but assigned
contrary to Abelard
that,
a subordinate role
and
who
also followed
tried to use
him
to
support the Christian apologetic, the Platonists of Chartres explained Platonism as an independent philosophy, without trying to reconcile
it
dogma
with
of humanistic imagination
but not without introducing an element
and
a concern for style that gives all the
productions of the school a very special savor. Bernardus
work on cosmogony
good example. In
a
is
play" written before the term was invented plains to
Nous
(that
reigns in matter; first
—a
Nature
com-
Providence) about the confusion that
to
gives in
to create
"mystery
tearfully
and separates the elements
book of Ovid's Metamorphoses)'^ then Nous turns
and promises tion;
is,
Nous
work
his
—Nature
Silvestris'
man
in order to bring the
will in turn shape the
body of
work
man from
(as in the to
Nature
to perfec-
the four ele-
ments (an adaptation of the account in the Timaeus). This seems to be the Christian Trinity dressed in Platonic
identical to the
is
Good (Tagathon),
is
illusory for
Son
garments the Father :
to
Nous, the
Spirit to
which emanates from Nous. But the
the world soul or Entelechia,
comparison
the
we
are dealing not with co-equals but
with a hierarchy of terms, since the world soul connotes an inferior hypostasis, nature,
carnate era,
Word, but
and
and is
since
an
Nous
intelligible
bears
no resemblance
world that contains
to the in-
species,
ments and the world ... the whole
series of fates (fatalis series is
the Stoic term), the order of the centuries, the tears of the poor,
the fortunes of kings."
Alan
III
gen-
individuals, "everything engendered by matter, the ele-
of Lille
and
^
(Alanus de Insulis)
Nature, the unity of nature, and natural laws probably constitute the essentials of the Platonism of Chartres. ers of the last part of the century
the "Universal Doctor," *
who
One
was Alan
of the best think-
of Lille (11 15-1203),
taught in Paris and in Montpellier.
Cousin, Ouvrages inedites d' Abelard, p. 628.
THE TWELFTH CENTURY
53
Though he did not depend directly on the school much of its spirit. He represented nature
tained
of Chartres, he reas a
young
virgin
wearing a crown embellished by stones that symboHzed the planets
and dressed
of every type.
image
cient
mantle on which were embroidered living beings
in a
Thus
the twelfth-century cleric rediscovered the an-
borrowed from the
that Pherecydes of Syros probably
b.c. And to his representation of man as a microcosm, shaped from the same elements as nature. He was in all probability acquainted also with Nemesius' treatise On the Nature of Man, translated by Al-
Babylonians in the sixth century
nature was Hnked that of
fanus in 1058, but he gave reason in sensibility
man with
first
variations
its
spheres of the planets; the soul the head, corresponds to
and the
gels
man and life, all
An
of
like
is
whose
Thus
parts are
the
the motion
like a divine city
is
God and
and the kidneys
air,
the earth.
orthodox
place to the images of the Timaeus:
motion of the sphere of fixed
like the
is
to
of the oblique
where reason,
in the lower part of the
dominant image
Alan could not
and he subordinated nature
and in
heaven, ardor in the heart to an-
bound together by
cleric like
stars,
is
body
to
that of a universal
secret affinities.^
deify nature, of course,
God. But the manner
in
which he
God to nature was borrowed from Proknew through the Boo^ of Causes, trans-
interpreted the relation of clus'
Theology, which he
lated
from Arabic around the middle
where by him under the
Supreme Goodness.^
God
is
simple and mine
theories that posit
title
When
and quoted
else-
Aphorisms on the Essence
of
"The operation
of
he has nature multiple,"
is
between
of
of the century
say,
we must
recall the Platonic
the diverse levels of reaUty only the dif-
ference between an enveloped unity and a developed unity.
William of Conches
IV
It
was the very concept of philosophy
the atmosphere of Chartres. '^
*
De
pianette naturae
Contra haereses
i.
Abundant proof
(Migne, CCX, 431-82).
25.
that tended to
of this is
change in
provided in
54 the
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
work
William of Conches (1080-1145),
of
of Chartres. What made between the
mar,
him
set
apart
was
a pupil of
Bernard
the radical distinction that he
trivium and the quadrivium: the former (gram-
was merely
dialectic, rhetoric)
a study preliminary to philoso-
phy, whereas the latter (mathematics and astronomy) was the part of philosophy, of trast
which the second part was theology. The con-
between the seven
between
a contrast scientific
first
arts
and theology tended
to
be replaced by
(eloquentia or the trivium) and the
belles-lettres
and philosophical study of nature/
And
this
was indeed
the situation depicted by William, who stated in his preface that many teachers would like to restrict instruction to eloquence. A new image of nature was taking shape. William tried to in-
troduce the corpuscular physics of Constantine the African. "Constantine, discussing as a physicist the natures of bodies, applies the
word
elements, in the sense of
principles, to the simplest
first
and
smallest parts of these bodies; philosophers, discussing the creation of the world
and not the natures of
four visible elements." But the
was good
for "those
who,
particular bodies, refer to the
common image
like peasants,
of the four elements
ignore the existence of
everything that cannot be apprehended by the senses." intelligence
was timidly reclaiming
Here, then,
role not only in the acquisi-
its
knowledge of divine things but
tion of
^
also in the determination of
the substance of sensible reality: invisible atoms were contrasted
with
visible elements, a
simple alloy with transmutation. William en-
countered considerable resistance, particularly within the
circle at
Chartres.
The
history of the controversy
is
easily reconstructed
ing WilUam's Philosophia (pp. 49-55)
commentary on Poitiers
the
Timaeus with the
(Gilbertus Porretanus,
by compar-
and the fragment of
his
ideas advocated by Gilbert of
1076-1154), also a pupil
of
Ber-
nard of Chartres and for a long time Chancellor of Chartres. William referred to those who, to refute him, drew support from a
famous passage
Timaeus (43a) which, because
mundi iv. 40 (Migne, CLXXII). Migne, CLXXII, 50a and 49c-d.
''Philosophia *
in the
of the fluidity
I
THE TWELFTH CENTURY
55
were
of the sensible world, denied that the elements
we can
stances. Gilbert,
Timaeus which
making
in
sub-
stable
be sure, thought that he was faithful to the
between the four sensible elements,
a distinction
in conjunction with a certain matter (called by Plato neces-
nurse, mother) produce diverse bodies,
sity, illusion,
and the Ideas
formed of
of the four elements, pure substances that are
He
matter and exist as models {exemplaria) in God.
intelligible
therefore re-
fused to see anything but flux in the intelligible world, and found only in the divine
stability is
reality.^ Physics,
concerned only with forms attached
to
ment, and must therefore refer always Against
this,
WiUiam seems
For example,
physics.
after
to
he observed elsewhere,
matter and their arrangeto
the inteUigible world.
have envisioned an independent
showing that the firmament could not be
made of frozen water, he added: "But I know that others will say, 'We do not know what it is but we know that God is capable of creating it.' Nonsense! What ill-chosen words! Can God make a thing without seeing what as
it
showing
or
is
its
it is
utility
having a reason for
like or
.''"
Thus WilUam
it
to be
did not hesitate to
seek a "natural" explanation of the origin of beings and, with respect to the origin of animals, to return to the speculations of cretius
:
the formation of Hving beings
eration of nature {natura operans)}^ his conception detracted
was
the opposite
must be
To
the
who
countered that
from the divine power, he answered that
true, that
he was exalting
power "which has given such a nature fore,
those
it
since
it
was
this divine
to things and which there-
through the intermediary of the operation of nature, has created
human
body." Such criticisms, he said, come from
men who
ignorant of the forces of nature," whereas "I maintain that
must search trust
in
for reason in all things, but
Holy
the
Spirit
and
in
if
faith."
Lucretius and the Timaeus, he was quick to
such matters naturalism •
Lu-
attributed to the op-
/^/^.,
we
is
a
fails
rather
53-56.
vague blend of
us,
we
put our
perhaps
by
acknowledge that in
can attain only to that which
LXIV, 1265.
" Ibid., CLXXII,
it
Inspired
"are
Platonic
is
probable. His
and Epicurean
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
56
WilHam
themes (and even of Stoic themes, for
defined the world
which
soul as the vigorem naturalem, "the natural force
things by God and through which some things have
and sensation, and
life
The Mysticism
V
still
others have
life,
sensation,
infused in
is
others have
life,
and reason").
of the Victorines
In addition to the sober sententiaries
who
codified Christianity,
and those from Chartres who revived Platonism, the twelfth century gave birth to an important mystical radical tives
reform of the monastic orders.
were
St.
on
movement
linked to a
most important representa-
Bernard (Bernard of Clairvaux, 1091-1153) and
of St. Victor (1096-1141). ligiosus,
Its
The monastic
a life of renunciation; the pursuit of perfection
is
adherence
The
obedience.
common
the
to
code
Hugh
ideal, that of the status re-
of
poverty,
based
is
chastity,
and
shows a continual
history of the monastic orders
alternation between neglect of basic rules, leading to contamination
by the world outside the standard. the
The
Abbey
cloisters,
and reforms
that re-establish the
eleventh century was dominated by the reform of
of Cluny, but the monastic spirit then suffered a re-
lapse until the twelfth century,
when
it
was revived by the Cistercian
reform and the founding of the Carthusian order by of Cologne.
The
the artisan,
and the
Cistercian
ascetic";
sisted only in spiritual
Christianity to
monk was
St.
Bruno
a "composite of the peasant,
the spiritual
life,
in his view, con-
meditation on the fundamental truths of
which he gradually subjected
his intelligence
and
his will.
Such meditation,
in
which cultivation of the imaginative faculty
practically replaced critical reflection,
gave birth to the monastic
mysticism of the twelfth century. Typical
is
Deo by
Cistercian
St.
Bernard,
the
celebrated
the treatise
De
diligendo
and Abbot of
Clairvaux. St. Bernard also preached the second crusade (1146) and
was counselor and
to
of the
whom
to
Pope Eugene
he addressed a
Church and
III,
treatise,
whom he had once instructed De consideratione, on the evils
the duties of the sovereign pontiff. In the think-
THE TWELFTH CENTURY
57
ing o£ this dedicated and enthusiastic of philosophy
is
knowledge of Jesus
man
"the
sum and
substance it
another
men
to love
crucified" or, putting
way, knowledge of God's love for men, which leads
God. This love explains the whole Christian drama. Through love
God
ordained salvation for
(defined by the Stoic the
after
fall;
fall,
word
God
means
sacrifice of Jesus a
all
for
men; but he gave them assent, consensus) which
a free will
led to their
provided through the Incarnation and
and
of satisfying both his justice
his
mercy;
the Christian since that time has been able to save himself by fol-
lowing Christ; the Christian the world, sure
life is
is
and God) and leads through contemplation, which
and not
that
meditation on ourselves, is
"a
a dubious conception of truth," to ecstasy: separated
from the physical senses and no longer aware of is
way
the description of the
from thought or inquiry (which
starts
caught up {rapitur) and delivered to God;
become quite
from
different
itself
itself,
the soul
finally, after
and quite similar
to
it
God,
has it
is
deified.
We should note life.
the traditional elements in his portrait of the inner
They have reappeared from century
Philo, Plotinus,
and
mysticism
instance
speculative. It
is
a
to century since the time of
St.
Augustine. But one fact stands out: in this
is
religious
way
of
life
and
sensible
for the soul
and
and
in
is
no way
not, as in Plotinus, the
basis for a philosophical conception of the universe. It
is
the tradition
of Augustine's inner meditation, not the tradition of Neo-Platonist
metaphysics. in those Paris.
who
We
find the
succeeded
same tendency
him
as
They were no longer
masters of theology
who
head of the
in
to a traditional
devoted
Much
ing from
grammar
of St. Victor
cloister of St.
and
Victor in
Bernard, but
their attention to the instruc-
from the school of Chartres, they
conception of education, and the six books
in the style of Isidore,
theology.
cal
all
Hugh's Didascalicon (with the Epitome
handbooks
Hugh
great politicians like
tion of clerics. Quite different also
adhered
in
in
philosophiam) were
comprising the
liberal arts
and
importance was attached to complete studies, rangto
mechanics and embracing ethics and theoreti-
philosophy (mathematics, physics, and theology), and protests
58
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
were lodged against those collective
who
sought "to mangle and lacerate the
body and who through perversity of judgment choose
which
arbitrarily that
^^
pleases them."
In the twelfth century the
tradition of universalism, very important in the history of philos-
ophy, was being threatened.
We
soon see
shall
who was
responsible
for this.
Mystical contemplation, the stages of whose attainment are de-
numerous Victorine works,
scribed in detail in
thorough intellectual instruction. the Christian
handbook of
difficulty:
buttressed by
is
fullness of the inner life of
described in works such as the
is
et ejus speciebus, a
in
The
De
contemplatione
spiritual exercises of increasing
meditation on morals and the divine orders, the soliloquy
which "the inner man" scrutinizes the
cumspection
which
(circumspectio),
is
secrets of his heart, cir-
the
defense
the
against
seduction of sensible things, and ascension. There are three degrees
which
in ascension: ascensio in actu, in distributing alms,
ings {in affectu),
and
which
consists in confessing our sins,
in scorning wealth; ascension in our feelconsists in perfect humility,
charity, purity of contemplation; finally,
and
consummate
at the highest level,
ascension in intelligence (in intellectu), which consists in created beings turn, its
is
knowing
and eventually the Creator. Knowledge of God,
attained through five modes, each of
predecessor: through created beings
to the idea of the Creator;
them more
in
perfect than
whose contemplation
leads
through the nature of the soul which
image of the divine essence that permeates the body
as
is
an
God
permeates the universe; through Scripture that reveals to us the attributes of
God; through
ascend to him; sessed by very
and
few
sweetness, calmly
a flash of insight that enables us to
through the vision which
finally
at present
and
in which, enraptured
is
"pos-
by divine
and peacefully one contemplates only God." The
mysticism of the Victorines tion at the highest level
is
is
meticulously orthodox; contempla-
but a sublimation of the fundamental
Christian virtues of faith and charity.
Hugh's work was continued by Richard of B.
St.
Victor,
Haureau, Les ceuvres de Hugites de Saint-Victor, pp. 169-70.
whose
THE TWELFTH CENTURY
59
mysticism was even more thoroughly imbued with rationaUsm and
Like
intellectuaHsm.
Anselm, he sought
St.
De
reasons" for divine dogmas, and his
"necessary
find
to
gratia contemplationis
played an important role in the intellectual preparation for a state of ecstasy.
Peter Abelard
VI
Members seem
to
have been quite different and even hostile to one another,
but they were nevertheless fired by the same
we
and Victorines
of the school of Chartres, sententiaries,
In
spirit.
find a feeling of liberation, an exuberance over a
civilization,
their
an
intellectual drive held in
The
resources.
to free itself
twelfth century
of
all
them
dawning
check by the inadequacy of
was the
century truly
first
from encyclopedias and commentaries. Literary forms
became more supple and more personal. Peter Abelard (1079-1142)
epoch. For at
Melun,
Mont
many
years
at Corbeil,
Ste Genevieve.
is
the most typical representative of his
and with growing success he taught
dialectic:
then in Paris at the cathedral school and on
The
Introductions for Novices, the Glosses
and the Short Glosses on Porphyry, and the Dialectic (1121) were the result of this teaching. But about
himself to theology under the guidance of
11 12
he began
Anselm
His teaching career ended catastrophically in
of St. Denis.
He
sur-Seine, then
from 1136
came the
Dame, he sought
nevertheless
resumed
to 1140 at
Le
11 18 as a result
by her uncle,
seclusion in the
his teaching, first at
Paraclet.
his
wholly theo-
is
of his love for his pupil, Heloise. Cruelly mutilated
Fulbert, a canon of Notre
apply
and
of Laon,
instruction at the cathedral school in Paris in 11 13 logical.
to
From
this
Abbey
Nogentperiod of
non (1121), the Theologia Christiana, the Introductio ad theologiam (ca. 1136), and the Ethica.
his life
From
the
inspiration for the Sic et
same period came
also his
History of
My
Misfortunes
(Historia calamitatum), which bears a closer resemblance to Rousseau's Confessions than to St. Augustine's,
respondence with Heloise.
and
his celebrated cor-
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
6o
Abelard's teaching was of the type which during the Middle
Ages invited censure by theologians. Condemned by two
were viewed
De
1121 for the
at Soissons in
in 1141 for the Introductio as
a
summary
and
unitate et trinitate,
ad theologiam, of
all
councils, at
Sens
his theological opinions
the great heresies: Arianism,
Pelagianism, Nestorianism. According to a letter written by the
Archbishop of Rheims
to
Cardinal Guido of Castello (1141)/^ he
denied the equality of the divine persons, the efficacy of grace, and the divinity of Christ;
and
all
the vast intellectual pride for great adversary, St. Bernard
genius
his denials
the pride that
:^^
{humanum ingenium)
sprang from one source
which he had been censured by
his
makes "the human
arrogate everything to
itself,
reserv-
ing nothing to faith," or from the fact that he refused to attach
"any merit
to faith, thinking that
God through
reason."
Thus he was accused Christian
life
of mystery rested
he can understand the fullness of
of trying to change the
by substituting a
and made tradition
on man's confidence
sacraments useless.
The
dogma
that
whole pattern of
eUminated every element
useless,
and a moral philosophy that
in himself
and rendered grace and the
truth
is
that Abelard did not subscribe to
such rationalism. "I do not wish to be so philosophical that Paul," he wrote, "or so Aristotelian
that
I
am
I resist
separated from
how presumptuous it is to discuss rationally that which transcends man and not to stop until all words have been clarified through the senses or through human reason." Christ."
Or
again: "See
-^^
What, tirely
on
then,
was Abelard's conception of reason ?
dialectic, to
It
was based en-
which he devoted himself with passion
to the
almost complete exclusion of the sciences of the quadrivium.
was the founder of to this art.
a school of dialecticians
who
He
restricted philosophy
Moreover, his Dialectic (1121) was based exclusively on
translations of the
works of Boethius and showed no
trace of the
'=Ep. 192 (Migne, CLXXXII). "Letter written in 1140 (Migne, p. 331). "Ep. 17 to Heloise (Migne, CLXXXII, 3750-3783): Introductio ad theologiam 1223d.
THE TWELFTH CENTURY
6l
great
logical
treatises
Aristotle
of
—the
Prior and
the
Posterior
—which
and the Topics
Analytics, the Sophistical Refutations,
were
him commentary
not translated into Latin until 1125. Dialectic remained for
what
was
it
for Boethius
when he was preparing
his
of the Categories: a science dealing not with things themselves but
with words as dialectic has
wish
way
a
we must
the Ethica in
demons on
It
direct
to discover the
universe,
of things.
signifiers
no bearing on our in
which
is
important to note that
knowledge of things;
man
like
we
if
Abelard envisions the
consult, not his dialectic, but a certain passage in
which
this "rationalist"
us by virtue of their
speaks of the influence of the
knowledge of natural
forces:
"For
and stones many
there are in herbs, in seeds, in the natures of trees
forces capable of agitating or assuaging our souls."
^^
forget the contrast between this vivid, passionate
We
must not
knowledge of
nature and the dry dialectical classification whose nets could hardly be expected to catch things.
Yet
cannot be totally disinterested in knowledge of
dialectic
things. Abelard's
program
of dialectical instruction seems at
be quite simple: he studied the non-complex terms
to
and the
predicables
the
categories), then the
proposition
categorical
first
(the five
complex terms, that
proposition and syllogism, and finally definitions and division. simplicity
is
propositions
illusory,
he
is,
and syllogism and the hypothetical Its
however, for in connection with hypothetical
introduces
everything
that
knows through
he
Boethius of Aristotle's Topics, as well as questions on physics and metaphysics, such as the question of matter and form and of the theory of causes.
The
equivocal character of dialectic, which
Aristotle's
method,
is
appeared
at the heart of the celebrated quarrel
words signify
things,
what things
are
over universals:
signified
'°
in
If
by words that
designate the genera and species of individual substances? call that
first
attempt to convert a method of discussion into a universal
We
re-
genera and species ("animal" or "man") are attributes of
opera, ed. Cousin,
II,
608.
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
62
an
but
("Socrates"),
subject
individual
unlike
that
accidents
("white," "wise"), they are contained in the essence of the subject, that
they are such that without
is,
be what
We
them
the subject
would
cease to
it is.
Porphyry and
also recall that
these genera
and
later
Boethius asked whether nature of
species, these universals, existed in the
We
things or were the simple product of a vain imagination.
have
WiUiam
already considered RosceUn's opinion on this point.
of
Champeaux, Bishop of Chalons (1070-1121), had a different opinion. thought that the attribute "man," posited by Socrates, Plato, and
He
was
others,
same
essentially the
and that
reality,
it
was wholly
in
each of these individuals at the same time; he added that these individuals did not differ at
through
their
accidents.
ancient opinion. it
are
added
and the
whom
through
specific difFerences
tells
we
its
his
told, its
was
identity
a
very
when
to
("rational," "lacking in reason"),
identity
when
added
accidents are
us that he discussed the thesis of
and even forced him
he studied)
men, but
their essence, as
are
The genus ("animal") retains
species retains
Abelard
all
Besides,
to
to
it.
William (under
change
his
views.
William then conceded that universals, in different individuals, were the same reaUty "not
essentially but
through the absence of
difference {non essentialiter sed indi-^erenter)'' tive side of the
tween
man
further
as
same
thesis
—the
That
is
the nega-
impossibility of differentiating be-
such in Plato and in Socrates. William went even
and ended by admitting that between the humanity of
Socrates
and the humanity of Plato there was neither
essential
identity nor absence of distinction, but simply simiUtude.^^ It
should be noted that this dispute was not on the same plane
as the conflict which, sixteen centuries earlier, had separated Aristotle from Plato on the subject of the existence of Ideas. It is easy to
reconcile theological Platonism,
which assumes that Ideas are divine
thoughts and models of things, with nominalism, which assumes that universals— as
we name them and conceive of them—do not The origin of nominalism is sometimes
designate any true reality.
" Quoted
in
G. Lefevre, Les variations de Guillaume de Champeaux.
THE TWELFTH CENTURY
6^
attributed to the Platonist Erigena because he thought that dialectic
had
to
Abelard,
who
(dictio) /^
do only with words
who
was a Platonic
in matters of theology
believed "with Macrobius
and Plato
realist
and
that divine intelligence
contains the original species of things, called Ideas before they are
manifested in bodies,"
^^
still
did not accept William's interpreta-
tion of the realism of universals.
He
raised the old objection of
Boethius: ''Res de re non praedicatur."
A
universal
an attribute;
is
therefore "no reality can be attributed to several things, but only a
name." Thus, whereas William considered genus and species in
isolation, as
members
of a classification beginning with the highest
genus and ending with the lowest
and refused
Abelard followed Boethius
to overlook the fact that the universal
else a predicate that is
species,
before
is
impUes several individual subjects
all
of which
it
the predicate. This explains the theory of universals attributed to
him by
his pupil
John of Salisbury:
universals as discourses
(sermones)
"He and
sees subjects of speech in
reinterprets
accordingly
everything that has been written on universals"; in other words, he holds that the universal cannot exist apart from the subjects of
which
it
is
the attribute (sermo praedicabilis)
.
His theory cannot
even be called conceptualism.^^
There
is,
it
seems, a close link between his theory of universals
and the Aristotelian theory of abstraction which Abelard borrowed from the passages totle's treatise first
On
in Boethius inspired by the third
the Soul and of which he seems to have been the
to grasp the significance.
which the imagination,
after
He
describes the process through
sensation
reaUty," fixes the reality in the mind, tellect
apprehends no longer the
"attains
superficially
to
and through which the
in-
reality
itself
property of the reality. This nature or form,
if
from matter,
is
through abstraction
as separated
separate reaUty "There :
is
no
"Prantl, Geschichte der Logi\, ^®
Opera, ed. Cousin,
" John
book of Aris-
II,
II,
24.
of Salisbury Metalogicus.
intellect 28.
but the nature or it
is
never
apprehended
known
without imagination."
as a
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
64
After Abelard, universals were never discussed apart from the conditions of the formation of general ideas.
Thus
the whole cen-
toward a kind of "moderate
tury seems to have been inclined
realism" that granted that general words had a real
meaning but
not that they designated real things to the same degree as sensible things.
De
Such was the
intellectibus?^
attitude of the author of the
The
treatise
treatise
preceded by a remarkable analysis
is
knowledge: an
of intellectual
anonymous
intellectual perception
(intellectus)
when when
of a composite thing, such as three stones, can be simple
perceived by a single intuition (uno intuitu) or composite
known through more but
intellect,
that
its
It is
clear that simplicity
that unites
things
is
always one, provided
and through
a single mental
and unity can
exist in the in-
act "be effected continuously
impulse." tellect
than one impression {pluribus obtutibus);
whether simple or composite,
conjungens), whereas they
{intellectus
are not in things themselves. Similarly in abstraction: intellect, as it
separates
form from matter, divides and separates things
in reality neither divided
that intellect
is
terms such as "man."
and such
Thus we
in
nor separated. In neither case does vain.
The
fact that
no way impUes that
peculiar object of the intellect.
man, and animal
a different viewpoint: species
when
sidered.^^
is it
man
so is
conceive of
I
when
reason
There
is
meaning
As
him
genus when is
same life
and
trace of
follow
and such.
term and an
in-
which
the
is
anonymous fragment, from
thing, but considered
added, individual
no longer a
it
use universal
as such
of the term,
stated in an
are the
I
in reality always such
are dealing not simply with a general
dividual reality but with the
Socrates,
Nor
and
useless
that are
sensibility are considered,
when
accidents are con-
nominalism or of realism
any of these doctrines. Platonic reaUsm, though frequently ad-
in
vocated, applies to a versals,
problem wholly different from that of uni-
and we would search
in vain for a doctrine to give rigid
support to the reality of genera and species within things. Gauthier ^
In Opera, ed. Cousin,
^
Cf.
the
II,
733-55.
anonymous fragments
Mittelahers, IV, Heft
i,
105, 108.
in
Beitriige
zur Geschichte der Philosophic des
THE TWELFTH CENTURY
65
whom
of Martagne, the writer typical
realist,
dividuals.^^
the
dogma
John of Sahsbury presented
as a
argued that universals must be united with
And
Peter
Lombard,
in contrast to St.
Anselm, freed
of the Trinity of every supposition of realism by
making
God
a radical distinction between the unity of the three persons in
and the unity of
species in the
genus or the unity of the individuals
in the species.^^
The
from
and Boethius and that can be summarized
Aristotle
was therefore open
field
in-
to a doctrine that
came two
in
statements: there are in things universal forms that are like images of divine Ideas; these forms have
apprehended separately through
The same
theological
problem
as
no independent existence but are
intellectual abstraction.
posed by Abelard derives from the
intellectual setting as the
problem of
universals. Dialectical
teaching eventually created a certain mentaUty
way, imposed a certain method for classifying stance one
which of
must ask
to
which of Porphyry's
or, to
put
it
another each in-
reality: in
five predicables or to
Aristotle's ten categories a particular thing belongs.
The
question must be asked of each thing, even of the divine reality to
which the most orthodox theologians applied the words "substance," "essence," "quality," "relation," "identity,"
the question
which poses
itself after
and
Boethius,
"difference."
whose
De
That
is
Trinitate
deals exclusively with the application of the terms of dialectic to the
divine reality.
The
We recall Erigena's solution to the problem.
question
is
one that engrossed twelfth-century thinkers, and
Abelard's Christian Theology contains not only his this point
We
own
teaching on
but also an outline of the teaching of his contemporaries.
have noted that
St.
Bernard and
his party accused
Abelard of
exaggerating the role of dialectic in acquiring knowledge of divine things. It is
would be
ridiculous to
assume that
all
directed specifically against the dialecticians
the mistake for
which others have
criticized
of Abelard's
whom
him. "In
work
he accuses of this tract
we
find not an exposition of truth but a defense of truth, especially
^ Metalogicus ii. 1 8. ^Dehove Temperati
realismi antecessores, p. 122.
66
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
against the pseudo-philosophers that attack us with philosophical
arguments."
Abelard then has a middle position between the
^^
who
radical theologians
considered dialectical distinctions as being
true of sensible things alone, refusing to apply
and the rabid
dialecticians
who
them
to divine reality,
sought to apply dialectical distinc-
tions as such to the Trinity.
From
were derived the "heresies" described
the second position
by Abelard the heresy of Alberic of Rheims who, starting from the :
idea that the Father
and the Son are one God, concluded
begot himself; the heresy of Gilbert the Universal identify in
essences
God, besides
—paternity,
his divinity
God
and the three persons, the three
and procession
filiation,
who
that
sought to
three persons; the heresy of Ulger, a teacher
—that
differentiate the
from Angers, who made
a distinction between the attributes of God, such as justice and
mercy, and between the properties of the persons; the heresy of Joscelin of Vierzy
happen
who
manner
in a
taught that
God
can err since certain things
other than that which he ordained; and the
heresy for which Abelard censured the school of Chartres, the belief that
God was
It is
not prior to the world.^^
easy to discern the application of dialectical rules in
all
of
these "heresies": Alberic applies the notion of substance; Gilbert applies the principle that each being has a distinct essence; sees in the Categories
Ulger
no means of separating the persons (Father,
Son) from the other attributes of God; Joscelin of Vierzy applies to the sacred texts the notion of the modality of propositions; the
school of Chartres applies the principle that cause cannot exist
without
effect.
Abelard's solution seems at
God
or
what
say that he
is
is
said of
Opera,
"His
life
ed.
and
fits
into
no category.
He
We
holds that
cannot even
substance since substance, according to Aristotle,
subject of accidents 24
him
be a radical one.
first to
Cousin, his
and of II,
prattle
519.
have
contraries. Cf.
made
his
No name
attack
the
befits
is
the
him. "God
on Roscelin (Theologia 1215c): of impudent professors con-
dialectic
temptible to almost
^
Les
Introductio
tcoles,
all religious men." ad theologiam, ed. Cousin,
pp. 198
ff.
pp.
84-85;
commentary by Robert,
THE TWELFTH CENTURY
67
But running
violates the rules of the philosophers."
brutal application of dialectic
is
Augustine, the path of similitude.
Father
is
Son
to the
as
same wax with
the
wax
is
respect to
parallel to the
and
the path indicated by Plato
We
can say, for instance, that the
image formed from
to the its
St.
essence
it
is
yet the
(essentialiter),
image comes from the wax, and both the image and the
it:
wax have
an exclusive property. It is
same kind
the
Timaeus and
it
is
image that Abelard seeks and finds in the
in the writings of Macrobius.
and he
doctrine literally, exegesis:
of
"The language which
the Timaeus,
of
enigma
is
to allegorical
it
as familiar to philosophers as
And
p. 46).
his exegesis of
like the interpretation of the school of Chartres
identifies the Christian Trinity
and the world
does not take Plato's
reserves the right to subject
{Opera, ed. Cousin,
to prophets"
He
soul,
is
wholly
with the triad of God, Intelligence,
with the result that
allegorical,
eliminates whatever might be heterodox in Plato's work.
pains especially to identify the world soul, the
He
it
takes
creature of the
first
demiurge and the creature through which the demiurge made the world a living being, with the Holy
Spirit. If Plato ascribes to the
world soul a beginning in time but makes the Holy the reason
that he
is
is
the world, to a temporal to the
and progressive operation.
efFects
is
that the
and
in
as a rational
Holy
its gifts
Spirit,
to the
simple in
human
itself,
Plato ascribes
Holy
Spirit confers spiritual life
His intention
is
clear: to
is
teristic
his
that he
way
a
on our body, the world
on our
souls.
eHminate from Plato
all
the naturalism
Abelard was well
procedure was "violent," and he wrote these charac-
Hues: "I
and
is
not in any
that later appealed so strongly to the Renaissance.
aware that
its
views the world
being animated by the world soul, the reason
living being; but just as our soul confers life
soul or
divisible, the
multiple in
is
soul. If Plato
using figurative language, for the world
preter
If
world soul two essences, the indivisible and the
reason
is
Spirit eternal,
referring to the operation of the Spirit in
am
accused of being a violent, troublesome inter-
of resorting to false explanations to
make
the philosophers support our faith and to attribute to
the texts of
them
ideas that
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
68
my
they never had. Let
Holy
accusers recall the prophecy that the
Ghost proffered through the mouth of Caiphas, attributing a
meaning other than
that of the
who pronounced
one
it"
to
it
{Opera,
ed. Cousin, p. 53).
Now we dialectical
understand Abelard's theology:
method, which seeks
to establish
it
neither Anselm's
is
through reason what
is
believed through faith, nor the philosophy of the school at Chartres,
which
degree independent of dogma;
to a certain
is
effort to find in philosophical notions
that he can at least conceive of
VII
rather an
an image of divine
reality so
through analogy.
Polemics Against Philosophy
The
tendencies exhibited by Abelard and by William of Conches
were disturbing in
on
it
it is
circles
preoccupied with monastic reform based
a very simple faith. St.
opposed
violently in the
Aenigma
to
Bernard and those around him were
such tendencies. Their viewpoint
by William of
fidei
St.
William was concerned mainly with the
is
represented
Thierry (died in 1153).
common
faith that
"must
be that of everyone in the Church of God, from the youngest to the oldest." ^^
He
style of the
recalls the
Holy
simpHcity of the Gospel and the peculiar
Spirit; here
we
find
no allusions
to the
complex
questions concerning the Trinity that theologians were obliged to
ask to defend themselves against heresies.
"The predicaments
substance, accident, relation, genus, species,
and the
nature of faith;
to the
are
unworthy
This
is
of divine things" (pp. 409a
the crux of
directed against
must
realities,
Against
this,
all
Timaeus was
that
which
a
like, are alien
of reason, they
and 418b).
the criticisms that
William of Conches.^^
recall that the
divine
common, vulgar instruments
of
William of
To
St.
Thierry
understand them
cosmogony
we
describing, in the
related to the creation of the world.
revealed Trinitary theology aimed to attain to
God
through other means than his relation to the world. William of ^ Migne, CLXXX, 407c. ^ Ibid., CLXXX, 333-40.
THE TWELFTH CENTURY
6g
Conches, drawing his inspiration from Plato (and also from
St.
Augustine), identified the Father with the power through which
God
created the world, the
he created istered
Son
Hence
it.
(as in
Son with wisdom according
the Spirit with the will through
it,
"the Father
is
what he
not with respect to the
is,
orthodox theology) but with respect
through his nature but through his
mode
to his creature, not
God and
The
of being" (p. 338d).
Trinity no longer describes the intimacy of the divine rather relations between
which
to
which he admin-
his creature
but
life,
—for instance, charity
or mercy.
The
goodness, he
is
true only of
analogy
is
Trinity
the
identifying
is
directed at Abelard
criticism
Thierry
God
it
considered in his relation to his creature. His it
is
found in
Bede and Peter Lombard; but
in
destroys the
censures
by
considered in himself that which
nevertheless a classic one;
and subsequently because
the same:
essentially
with the triad of power, wisdom, and
attributing to
God
is
him
meaning also
for
of the mystery.
attributing
St.
Augustine
it is
dangerous
William of
creation
to
St.
"God's
benevolence to his creatures," as the Timaeus does, and for saying that the
Holy
Spirit
is
a soul that permeates everything.
theologian
who knows
better than
God," he
being
moved by
applicable to the
the flesh better than the spirit
says. "It
affection
is
"Here and
is
a
man
plainer than day that these terms
and reaching out
to
—are
something
not
immutable God."
Gilbert of Poitiers {Gilbert de la Porree)
VIII
But even William of
St.
Thierry
doctrine of faith cannot repress
and
is
forced to admit that "the
reject completely the
supplied by men, but must simply adapt principles."
Here he
is
referring to the
them one by one
names to
its
program followed by Boethius
De Trinitate and later by Gilbert of Poitiers in his commentary De Trinitate, According to Gilbert, all heresies have their source
in his
on
in the application to "theological things" of certain principles that
pertain only to "natural things." Despite
all his
precautions on this
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
70
point he less
we
But
it is
well aware of the impossibility of speaking of
is
him
transfer to
"un-
borrowed from natural things."
categories
necessary to guard against distortion: a perilous task which
was not
Gilbert himself
Bernard,
God
able to perform to the satisfaction of St.
who had him condemned by
the councils of Paris (1147)
and of Tours (1148). a
Gilbert,
student of the
school
adhered to
Chartres,
of
its
Platonism. Moreover, he ranked with the best students of Aristotelian logic in his era:
the
title
classic
De
knew
the Analytics, translated in 11 25; under
sex principiis he wrote an essay that will remain a
on the
habitus,
he
six
last
categories
He
and posture.
—action,
stressed particularly the notion of
or of essence, basing his discussion on a passage as
we have
already seen, was utilized at Chartres.^^ Seneca
(elSo?), between the that
form
from Seneca which,
makes
a
between the Platonic Idea and the Aristotelian form
distinction
form
where, when,
passion,
is
model
that exists apart
inherent in the work. This
And what
that Gilbert makes.^^
is
is
from
a
work and
the
precisely the distinction
referred to as his realism con-
in his stating, not that the forms subsist in themselves, but
sists
that the individual substances that
do
subsist independently possess
being or essence by virtue only of the forms inherent in them.
man
A
has being or essence only because he has within himself the
form humanity, which
in turn
is
composed of the forms
make
rationality
and
corporeality. In contrast, the forms that
sist
(the subsistentiae of subsistentes) cannot subsist by themselves,
that
is,
they cannot be subjects.
But Gilbert found
mon
to naturalia
in his
and
examination of form a principle com-
to theologica.
said, is the principle that
Common
God
himself,
persons, a form, the divinity or deity through
given form.
It
was
this
both orders, he
prior to
whom
ff.
the three
the persons are
Epistulae morales 58, 21.
Migne, LXIV, 1268
It is
very distinction that Bernard attacked. Here
"^Cf. John of Salisbury Metalogicus '^
to
"being always comes from form."^^
therefore necessary to posit in
^
substances sub-
ii.
17 (Migne,
CLXXXIX,
875d).
THE TWELFTH CENTURY
71
we have
a
good indication of
problem that wore away the century: of
"To what degree
knowledge
is
the difficulties raised by the critical
all
intellectual strength
of the twelfth
the divine reality subject to the rules
that apply to natural things?"
Abelard's Ethic
IX
The
criticism that
was directed against Abelard's doctrine of
the
Trinity and which culminated in his condemnation at Soissons (1121)
probably hides the more serious criticism that led to his
second condemnation at Sens in 1141. In the twelfth century, the previous centuries,
it
was impossible
dogma from
debate relating to
a
whole
to
separate speculative
set of ideas,
than theoretical, concerning the Christian
as in
life.
more
practical
Just as St. Bernard
the theologian took issue with Abelard the theologian, and for the
same
reasons, the monastic reformers, seeking to return to a strict
code,
were confronted by opponents who proclaimed that marriage
between monks and nuns was carnation.
licit,
or even that salvation
What might
be called theological naturalism was offset
by a liberating movement that the futility of the monastic
finally resulted in a declaration of
life,
the sacraments, and faith.
were the circumstances under which Abelard wrote or Scito te ipsum.
Here indeed,
telHgence reserves everything for
To
be sure, the Ethica
a Christian.
The
is
as St. itself
a dialogue
Bernard
his
Such
Ethica
"human
said,
and nothing
in-
for faith."
^^
between a philosopher and
philosopher himself adheres to Christianity, and
Abelard, represented by the Christian, criticizes sistency in
was pos-
Incarnation and in the absence of belief in the In-
sible prior to the
viewing
as
him
he has yet found convincing.
Still,
Abelard
—who
scandalous the priests' remission of penitence for tested the bishops'
for his incon-
unsound the doctrine of the Apostles which
power
to forgive sin
denounced
money and
—nevertheless
as
con-
defends an
individualistic ethic totally independent of Christian discipline:
an
upright will guided solely by man's conscience and his concept of
^ /^;V/., CLXXXII,
331.
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
72
the good. His ethic leads to the concept of purely personal sin
and
the impossibiUty of original sin or of the reversibility of transgresof moral transgression,
to the radical separation
sions;
wholly internal and which
is
assent to that
which
is
which
thought
to
is
be
bad, and legal transgression; to the impossibility on the part of
any other
man
transgression;
of
and
knowing an
tingent on the reversibility in
all,
his
was
intention,
upon us
once again the Greek and
new
human
faith" ^^ that
in the rescript that he prepared
on the
discuss publicly the Christian faith."
the Ethica
is
a dialogue
is
the
to
Pope Innocent
II,
subject, recalled the letter
who
in
told
Pope John
any position
try to
But we must remember that
between a philosopher and a Christian,
that the philosopher clings tenaciously to Christianity, that Abelard
foreground
Such was "the new
at Sens.
no military man, no person
cleric,
to the
was judged dangerous
Marcian the emperor,
(in reahty a forgery) of
"Let no
brought
morality.
Church and condemned
tradition of the
constitutes a
of the merits of Christ.^^ All
a penetrating intuition that
Gospel and the
which alone
finally to the idea of a personal salvation not con-
represented by the Christian
who
and
finally
criticizes
the
philosopher for being inconsistent in viewing the doctrine of the Apostles as unsound and in declaring at the same time that he finds it
convincing.
The Theology
X
of
Alan
of Lille
Such condemnations did not stop the
irresistible
movement
that
impelled theologians to try to find in the Christian faith a rational structure that
search
was
would
constitute a coherent whole.
a practical necessity
which Abelard used logical tics
their
which must not be overlooked and
advantage several times: the method of
argumentation was the only possible method against here-
who would
not acknowledge the truth. That
of Lille says in his ^~
to
Underlying
opera, ed. Cousin,
De
II,
^Letter (1140) from
also
what Alan
arte seu articulis catholicae fidei, written to-
637-38. Bernard
St.
is
to
Innocent
II
(Migne, CLXXXII, 354).
THE TWELFTH CENTURY
73
ward
end of the century. In
the
book he used
his
(as Proclus
had
once done in his Elements of Theology, with which Alan was acquainted) tiones),
form
the
and
of EucHd, his axioms, his postulates
his theorems.
Yet Alan did not pretend, any more than Abelard, probability through logical argumentation; faith
was "based on
Thus
science."
{peti-
was
there
tingent character
reasons
certain
events that depend on a mysterious decision
The
facts.
between the con-
most of which announce
truths,
made by an incompremethod
hensible God, and the rational character of the
posed to prove these
not sufficient for
in his thinking a contrast
Christian
of
go beyond
he held that
instead,
are
that
to
that
God
fathomless power of
is
sup-
always
limits the reason that could be given for the truths of faith; for
example,
"God
manner"
(iii.
could have ransomed
15)
there
;
some other person,
to
Like Gilbert of
show
the extent to
theologica.
tribution logical
He
become
Poitiers,
mankind
incarnate.
whose
God,
to
for
attributes
God
species,
fit
God, who
and the
is
common
rules of at-
cannot be considered
as a
can be classed according to the
and the
categories of substance, quantity, quaUty, possible to
to
rules of naturalia can be transferred to
a dual principle. First, the
do not apply
in wholly different
necessity for the Son, rather than
he tried in his Theologicae regulae
which the
had
subject
was no
like.
a singular term, into a
diversity of his
attributes
It
im-
is
genus and a
never designates any-
thing other than a unique essence. Second, rules relating to causes
apply both to natural things and to the divine reahty. true of a subject,
is
we always have
whether the subject
the predicate pertains to different
there
is
from the
from the
it
itself.
makes him
attribute "just"
is
predicate
or a created being,
a cause through
which
and that the cause of the attribution
attribute
a cause that
God
is
the right to say that there
If a
If
it
just,
is
and
true that this cause
God is
is
is
just,
different
which designates our interpretation of
its
effects.
In the second principle St.
Anselm's Monologium
we :
see a
new
application of the ideas in
reveaUng the nature of
God by
referring
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
74
as
Dionysius the Areopagite
part of the twelfth century
and the beginning of the
variety of his
to the
phrased
attributes
or,
of his names.
it,
Twelfth-Century Heresies
XI
The
last
marked by
thirteenth,
and
the pontificate of Innocent III
his struggle against the
Empire and by
(1198-1216)
the conflict of the
English barons against the kings of the Angevine dynasty,
most troubled and tumultuous of
of the
all
eras. It
came
is
to
one an
end with the Lateran Council (1215), which confirmed the doctrines of papal authority
and
at the
same time
instituted courts of
inquisition and authorized the creation of the mendicant orders.
The Magna
Charta, which laid the foundation for the security of
English political and personal year.
One
liberty,
year earlier (1214) the
was signed during the same
power of the Capetians had been
estabUshed at Bouvines.
To
understand the importance of these events, which were to
have a momentous impact on the history of
ideas,
we must
picture
to ourselves the conflicting trends of the closing years of the twelfth
century:
on the one hand, a vast
social
upheaval against the
Church, manifested in popular heresies and heterodox doctrines,
and on the
other, a humanistic
the best representative
is
and doctrinaire
Thomas
which
who studied under who was the counselor
John of Salisbury,
Abelard and the dialecticians of France and of
trend, of
a Becket, Archbishop of Canterbury.
In the numerous heresies of the era, and in the associations of the
Beguines, the Capuciati, the Humiliati, and the CathoHc Poor, as well as to
among
Cathari and Albigenses or Waldenses,
it
is
difficult
determine where questions of discipline end and questions of
doctrine Brescia,
saved
if
begin.
Toward
the
middle of the century, Arnold of
a pupil of Abelard, preached that clerics
they possessed land.
pope from
Rome
in 1141.)
could not be
(He was powerful enough to drive the The substantial basis of these heresies
seems always to be the same: the preaching of an ideal of a holy.
THE TWELFTH CENTURY
75
through a return
religious life attainable
and
total liberation
to evangelical simplicity
from the Church and the sacraments. Illuminati
proclaimed that they were sons of God.
Men
like Peter of
Bruys
denied the validity of baptism and the presence of Christ during the Eucharist
and sought
churches and to eliminate ex-
to destroy
About
ternal forms of worship.
founder of the Waldenses, "usurping the evangelical poverty.
Alan of
gious authority and even
Waldo
1170, Peter
of Peter," preached
office
Lille tells us that
human
all
of Lyons, the
he denied
all
reli-
authority, the validity of the
sacrament of the Holy Orders, the institution of absolution, and indulgences.
The same Alan tics
whom
of Lille speaks in his Contra haereticos of here-
he does not name but
who
are easily identified as the
famous Cathari or Albigenses who were dominant France. Here
we
see
of the holy, religious is
in the south of
how
doctrinal opinions are related to the ideal
life.
The yearning
for pure, undefiled holiness
always accompanied by the belief that the soul
force imprisoned by opposing evil forces.
formed among the Albigenses
But
is
a fallen heavenly
this belief
into a precise doctrine in
was
trans-
which we
recognize, not Manicheism, as has sometimes been said, but rather the doctrine of the Gnostics: the world principle, a
demiurge which
Mosaic law; the soul
is
was created by an
of heavenly origin; a fallen angel,
is
evil
same time the author of the
at the
ing punished here on earth; this soul
is
it is
be-
not to be confused with
the soul conceived as a simple vital principle which, like the soul of
an animal, perishes with the body. Christ,
was
in
no way human;
institute
his
presumed
aim of the Christian
which the evil, is
body was but an
to save souls,
illusion. Christ
any of the sacraments and yet the Church owes
to the fact that they are sole
who came
soul,
life
is
to
did not
its
power
be necessary for salvation.
The
to attain to a state of purity in
wholly delivered from sin and incapable of doing
no longer the prisoner
of evil.
The
pure, or the Cathari, are
who have reached such a state. The religious independence demanded by
those
matched by the
political
the Albigenses
was
independence which the rulers of southern
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
76
France, the counts of Toulouse, wished to acquire for themselves.
The
crusade ordered by Innocent
III
and characterized by unspeak-
able cruelties (1207-1214) brought an
power of
the
Among
both the heresy and
to
the counts.
the doctrines
of Joachim of Fiore,
Fiore in Calabria (14:16):
end
"And
I
(i
condemned
Abbot
Lateran Council was that
at the
of the monastery of St. Giovanni at
145-1202). Jesus said in the Gospel of St. John
will [iray the Father,
and he
shall give
you another
Comforter (Paraclete), that he may abide with you for ever."
To
Joachim, the Paraclete was the Holy Spirit, and this verse indicated the three periods in the history of salvation: Mosaic law, the
period of the Father, was the past, and prefigured the Christian
Church; the Church was the present, and prefigured the reign of the Spirit;
was the future announced by Joachim
the Spirit
Church
apocalyptic visions in which he represented the
formed and spiritualized 1260.
in
new
was supposed
era that
to
begin
This was the birth of the idea of an eternal Gospel that
would give the Christ.
in a
in
as trans-
The
idea
definitive
was
spiritual
to persist in
meaning
Franciscan
of
the
Gospel of
circles until the four-
teenth century.'^**
Between the
ideas of
the Albigenses there birth a
new
the contrast
had role
a kinship
spiritual order, different
was
of Christianity,
of the
Church and held
desire to bring to
saw
in the eternal
Gospel
something long anticipated; they
a sense of historical continuity.
realized then
— the
from the existing order. But
great: the Joachimites
consummation
the
Joachim and those of the Waldenses or of
was surely
The
Cathari simply denied the
that the
new
spiritual
order was
and there by the pure or the perfect who had been
initiated to their divine origin.
Thus
they stood for progress on the
one hand, violent revolution on the other.^^
The ology
doctrine of at Paris,
leads to the
as
Amaury
of
Bene (died
1207), Professor of
The-
though quite different from that of the Albigenses,
same
practical attitude.
Cf. Gilson, Saint Bonaventtae, pp. 22 fT. Cf. Delacroix, Le mysticisme spectilatif en
The
Albigenses rediscovered
Allemagnc,
p. 44.
THE TWELFTH CENTURY
77 the
drama
of salvation as
had been described by the Gnostics:
it
the deUverance of the soul, the divine essence imprisoned by
Xo
such drama
each
man
disciples
is
found
work
in the
of
He
Amaun".
evil.
taught that
a part of Christ; according to the commentaries of his
is
he meant that the only reaUty that might
identical to itself
was God, and
God
but the knowledge that
exist eternally
that salvation consisted in nothing
was
things. In his teaching there
is all
nothing that resembled faith and hope, which are the expectation of something better: no evidence of fear of Hell or hopes of Paradise;
no evidence of the beUef that God
in Christ or in the Host, since creatures.
he
is
everv-^vhere
is
way
present in a special
and incarnate
in all
But there was complete assurance, based on personal
was
revelation, of the birth of the definitive reign of the Spirit that to replace the
Church.
Here we recognize Stoics,
Amaury by way
We in
began with the
a pattern of thought that
continued through Plotinus and Dionysius, and reached of Erigena.
see also that the theoretical doctrine of the unity of all being
God was
opposition
strong enough at this time to be translated into overt
whole
the
to
spiritual
Church recognized the danger, and the doctrine of was condemned
at the
Synod of
Paris in 1210
Council in 12 15. At the same time Erigena's
was condemned,
for in
it
Church. The
system of the
the Amauricians
and
De
at the
Lateran
divisione naturae
was seen the source of the
doctrine.
Dur-
ing the same period the doctrine persisted in the writing of David of Dinant, also
book,
De
we know
condemned
tomis hoc his ideas
division to
est
in 12 10.
de divisionibus which ,
refers
is
for separate substances.
if
St.
Erigena, but
Thomas. The
indivisible principle
its
{Nous
vel
mentem)
and
—mat-
for souls,
God
But the triad of matter, inteUigence, and
designates but one substance. to
recalls
that of reaHties into bodies, souls,
ter {hyle) for bodies, Intelligence
David seems
only the tide of his
through Albert the Great and
which he
separate substances; each reaUty has
God
We know
To
estabHsh this conclusion
have employed the principle of the Bool{ of Causes:
we saw them
as distinct
terms
we would have
to posit
beyond
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
78
them
a simple
have in
and
common
indivisible principle that contains
whatever they
known
to
this brings
us
(Avicebron, whose Fons vitae was
David, followed an analogous line of reasoning) back, then, to a unique reality.
We
;
recognize in his triad, not the
Neo-Platonic triad of Macrobius (One, intelligence, and soul), but
drawn from
a triad
the
Timaeus (demiurge,
intelligence or being,
and matter).
]ohn of Salisbury
XII
One
most striking
of the
tiers,
and by William
was John of
figures of the period
who was
bury (1110-1180),
Salis-
taught by Abelard, by Gilbert of Poi-
He was
of Conches.
the friend of
Thomas
Becket and died while serving as Bishop of Chartres.
guished writer, well versed in the
classics,
A
he was familiar not only
with poets like Ovid and Vergil, but also with Seneca and pecially Cicero,
from
moral philosophy the Metalogicus
whom
as well as
and the
he borrowed his knowledge of Stoic
Policraticus, vividly reflect all the preoccuofficial
of the period.
gives us a catalogue of
all
the questions raised
A
belief
was now threatened: the
belief
around 1160 by the diffusion of instruction in that
had prevailed
that dialectic
for a long time
was but one of the seven Hberal
were destined
to serve as
es-
academic doubt. His two great works,
pations of a great ecclesiastical
The Metalogicus
a
distin-
arts
dialectic.
which,
an introduction to theology.
collectively,
Many
twelfth-
century theologians feared that their neat hierarchy was on the
verge of collapse. Dialectic resisted subordination and started to in-
vade theology. Such sin, its
men
as St.
Bernard viewed
it
"a shameful curiosity that consists in acquiring
own
sake, a
primarily as a
knowledge
for
shameful vanity that consists in knowing for the
sake of being known." Such criticisms were heard constandy until the end of the twelfth century
of Sentences satisfied
and they applied even to the authors and compendiums, who were censured for not being
with the Fathers. In his Contra quatuor labyrinthos Fran-
THE TWELFTH CENTURY
79 ciae,
Gauthier, Prior of
and Peter of
St. Victor,
Lombard
took issue with Peter
with Abelard and Gilbert of
Poitiers as well as
Poitiers.
But orthodox theologians were frightened by something more than a mere dialectical invasion that profaned the sacred science
and made dogmas the object of public
debates.
finally
becomes an end in
of the arts, resulted in an almost
art of discussion.
described the "pure philosophers" logic
Prohibition of the teaching
itself.
upon masters
of theology, enforced
monstrous development of the
from
also wit-
the purely formal cultivation of the art of discussion
dialectic:
which
They were
emergence of extremism in
nessing, not without apprehension, the
who
scorned everything apart
and were ignorant of grammar,
"They devote
their lives to
it,
and
John of Salisbury
physics,
and
ethics.
in their old age they are puerile
doubters; they discuss each syllable and even each letter of words
and passages; they and the mass of book can
and they
are always groping, always searching,
never attain wisdom.
.
.
.
They compile
conflicting opinions
scarcely recognize his
own."
is
the opinions of everyone,
such that the author of a
^^
This pointed up the danger of cultivating subtlety for sake and of reviving along the banks of the Seine Petit-Pont did
Greek
—the
schools.
pursuit of sophistry that
Adam
had very few auditors
—as
its
own
Adam du
had ruined
certain
candidly acknowledged that he would have if
he had taught
dialectic using simple, easily
understood formulas.^^ People preferred collections of sophisms such as this one that typifies the
hundred dred
is
than two in relation to three."
John of Salisbury was no enemy of
who
those
Megarian school: "One
than two, for one hundred in relation to two hun-
is less
less
spirit of the
declared
it
useless,
logic,
and he took
such as the enigmatic
calls Cornificius,
who
But John made
logic a simple intellectual tool:
"wallowing in
its
own
mire and muddling
its
i. 6 and 7. Cf Grabmann, Geschichte der scholastischen Methode, Cf. Robert, Les tcoles, p. 69, note. .
^
with
he
boasted of his method to short-cut education.^^
Adam's
own
^ Metalogicus '^
issue
man whom
II,
112.
dialectic,
secrets, is con-
8o
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
cerned with subjects that are useful neither in the family, nor in war, nor in law, nor in the
Church
nor in the Court, nor in the
cloister,
—nowhere except in
school" (viii). Logic was designed not
On
to hide ignorance but to advance knowledge.
was guided mainly by five treatises of the its
it
was then new
clearly that
treatise. To much more
and
to readers,
clearer than that of the Analytics.
With
a sure sense of history,
and independent
the foundations of logic, presented in the
With
all,
in
which
respect to the other
Topics, and the
are designed only to lay the foundation for the
in the Posterior Analytics
man
is
The
and
demonstration taught
art of
nature of things
useless, for the
can never
possibility, impossibility,
know
only in mathematics"
necessity.
(xiii,
"That
is
why
arguments
appHcable
in
the
most
Scholars were well aware that in this that
the
method
ception.
He knew
that
God
its
an epoch: not
of
full
or an angel"
devis-
circumstances.
diverse
way
to dis-
method of
they would reach only
which was probable: "the apprehension of truth
only to the perfection of
so
end).
see clearly outlined the ideal of
cover the nature of things but to find a general
ing
is
the modality of propositions,
demonstration almost always vacillates in physics and has
Here we
are
Organon, the Categories and the Peri Hermeneias
Analytics are merely appendices.
mysterious that
and he
the third book,
in
listed
given the rules for discussion and debate. treatises in the
book
first
Porphyry and Boethius, he addded the
clearly than in
ended with the eighth book, the most useful of
efficacy
the
was much
style
its
constituted a complete
it
and physical questions
ethical
among
Aristotle's Topics, his favorite
Organon, which was then becoming known in
throughout the West. The Topics was of considerable
entirety
importance;
John saw
point John
this
(ii.
lo).
itself
pertains
John was no ex-
beyond reason, which he defined
in the
man-
ner of the Stoics as stability of judgment, there was intelligence (intellectus) that attained to the divine causes of natural reasons,
and wisdom
that
distinctly apart
struggle with
was
as the savor of divine things.
from the sphere
human
tools.
in
But he
which purely human
sets it
interests
THE TWELFTH CENTURY
01
humanism subordinated to theology, characterizes the Policraticus, in which human, moral, and political wisdom is subordinated to a theocracy. With respect to its ethical content, the work is permeated by Stoicism. The rebirth of the doctrine of
The same
spirit,
Stoicism during this period coincided with the spread of naturalism,
whose many manifestations we have noted. The
Stoic
arguments
were known and disputed.^^ John speaks of a Neo-
relating to fate
Stoic {novus stoicus)
from
Pouille,
an Italian named Louis
who had
commentary on Vergil and who, taking up again Dio-
written a
dorus' ancient discussion of contingent futures, concluded that
was impossible perform
is
to
know "whether an
man
action that a
nevertheless a possible action"
(ii.
it
will not
23). Elsewhere
John
proves according to the old Stoic doctrine that "the providence of
God
does not suppress the nature of things and that the order of
things {series rerum, the Stoic definition of fate)
The whole
providence."
imbued with
is
the servant of the law
(Chrysippus' formulation) things. ture;
The
is
cites as a
mistress of
model
legibus. In
in
politics, is
we
it
find
human
divine and
all
in this context the description of the
for the conduct of the prince in a letter cites in his fifth
fested in his
on
and of equity, and that law
He
republic of the bees given in the Georgics (v. 21).
which he
does not alter is
he adds, must be constructed in the image of na-
state,
and he
De
the Stoic ideas of Cicero's
that the prince
which
of the fourth book,
book.
finds precepts
from Plutarch
The same
to Trajan,
Stoic tendency
is
mani-
moral philosophy, particularly in the eighth book,
which he deals with the passions and follows Cicero's Tusculan
Disputations. His Stoicism, like Cicero's,
is
restrained by academic
doubt.
Naturalism imbued with Stoic rationalism If
"the prince
is
because
is
"it is
the minister of priests
an established
authority of divine law,
^
In the fourth chapter
necessity of the Stoics.
is
fits
power
into a theocracy that subjects temporal
and
power.
inferior to them," this
fact that the prince,
subject to the
remarkably well
to spiritual
law of
by virtue of the
justice" (iv. 3, 4).
(546a) he quotes Epicurus' x^P^^ bo^a against the
fatal
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
82
The
divine law that "the
priest, then, is the first interpreter of the
prince
must always have before
his
eyes"
(iv.
hand with statements Hke these:
"The
state
is
God; hence as
his privileges,
which make
an image of the divinity"
realized in the spiritual
power
of Salisbury the Stoic ethic particularly
among
the
"The prince (vi. 25).
and administered
Just as the Stoic
Chartres
in the (vii.
him
law was
established by Christ, so after
at
in
therefore chosen by
his subjects consider
was realized
monks
is
RationaHsm,
an animate body, by
the grace of God, governed by sovereign equity
by the rule of reason" (v. 6).
6).
power go hand
naturalism, and the predominance of spiritual
John
monastic orders,
23).
Bibliography
Texts Anselm of Laon. Extraits inedits des Sentences. Bernold of Constance. Opera. Migne, CXLVIII, p. 1061. Peter Abelard. Sic et non. Migne, CLXXVIII. CXCVIII, pp. 1 049-1 844. Lombard. Opera. Migne, CXCI, CXCIL The Four Boo\s of Sentences. Book I, Dist. IIL Translated by R.
Peter Comestor. Opera. Migne, Peter
.
McKeon,
Selections,
I,
189-201.
Peter of Poitiers. Sententiae. Migne,
CCXI,
Robert of Melun. Extract from
the
783.
Sentences.
Migne,
CLXXXVI,
1015,
1053-
Robert Pulleyn. Sentences. Migne, CLXXXVI, 639. William of Champeaux. Sentences. Published by G. Lefevre in Les variations de G. de Champeaux et la question des universaux. Lille, 1898. Yves of Chartres. Decretum. Migne, CLXL
Studies J. Die Philosophic des Petrus Lombardus und ihre Stellung im XII Jahrhunderte. Beitrdge, Vol. IIL Miinster in Westfalen, 1901. Haskins, C. The Renaissance of the Twelfth Century. Cambridge, 1927. Moore, P. The Worlds of Peter of Poitiers. South Bend, Ind., 1936. Nash, P. "The Meaning of Est in the Sentences (1152-1160) of Robert of Melun," Mediaeval Studies, XIV (1952), 129-42.
Epensberger,
Nitze,
W. 'The
So-called Twelfth Century Renaissance,"
Speculum, XXIII
(1948), 464-71. Sanford, E. "The Twelfth Century Renaissance or Proto-Renaissance?" Spe-
culum, Tremblet,
XXVI
(1951), 635-41.
P., et al.
La Renaissance du
83
XW
siecle. Paris, 1933.
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
84
II
IV
to
Texts Adelard of Bath.
De eodem
et diverso.
Edited by Hans Willner. Beitrdge,
Vol. IV. Miinster in Westfalen, 1903. Pp. 3-34.
Alan of Lille. Opera. Migne, CCX. Bernard of Chartres. No known texts extant. Most of our knowledge of Bernard comes from the works of John of Salisbury. (See section XII, below.)
Bernardus
and
Silvestris.
De mundi
universitate libri duo. Edited by C. S. Barach
Wrobel. Innsbruck, 1876. Gilbert of Poitiers. Opera. Migne, LXIV, i^^^y-i^ii. J.
Thierry of Chartres.
De septem
diebiis.
In
Clarenbaldus von Arras zu Boethius
W. De
Jansen,
Der Kommentar des
Trinitate.
Breslau,
1926.
Pp.
106-12.
William of Conches. Extracts from the commentary on- the Timaeus. In J. M. Parent, La doctrine de la creation dans I'ecole de Chartres. Paris, 1938. .
Philosophia mundi.
the
name
XI T
siecle. Paris, 1951.
Under
of
Honorius Augustodunensis,
Migne, CLXXII.
Studies
De
Lage, R. Alain de Lille: Poete du
H. Die Philosophic des Wilhelm von Conches. Koblenz, 1929. Gilson, E. "La cosmogonie de Bernardus Silvestris," Archives d'histoire doc-
Flatten,
trinale et litter aire .
du moyen
age, III (1928), 5-24.
"Le platonisme de Bernard de Chartres," Revue Neo-Scolastique de
philosophic,
XXV
(1923), 5-19.
Haring, N. "The Case of Gilbert de la Porree, Bishop of Poitiers (1142-54)," Mediaeval Studies, XWl (1951), 1-40. Haskins, C. "Adelard of Bath," The English Review (191 1).
"Un representant du platonisme au XII* siecle: Maitre Thierry de Chartres," Memoires de la Societe archeologique d'Eure-et-Loir,
Jeauneau, E.
XX
(1954), 3-12. Parent, J. La doctrine de la creation dans I'ecole de Chartres. Paris, 1938. .
"Un nouveau temoin de
Aus der
la
theologie dionysienne au XII*
Geisteswelt des Mittelalters. Festgabe in Westfalen, 1935. Poole, R.
"The Masters
Salisbury's
M. Grabmann.
siecle,"
Miinster
of the Schools at Paris and Chartres in John of Time," English Historical Review, XXXV (1920), 321-42.
THE TWELFTH CENTURY
85
V Texts Bernard of Clairvaux. Opera. Migne, CLXXVII. Wor\s. Translated by a priest of Mount Melleray. 6 .
vols.
Dublin,
1920-25. .
On
the
Love of God. Translated by A. Pegis
in
The Wisdom
of
Catholicism. Pp. 230-68.
Hugh
of .
St.
The
New
Victor. Opera. Migne,
Didascaliccn of
CLXXV-CLXXVII.
Hugh
of St. Victor. Translated by
}.
Taylor.
York, 1961.
Studies The Teaching of SS. Augustine, Gregory and Bernard on Contemplation and the Contemplative Life. London, 1951. Castren, O. Bernhard von Clairvaux. Zur Typologie des mittelalterlichen Menschen. Lund, 1938. Gilson, E. The Mystical Theology of St. Bernard. Translated by A. Downes. London, 1940. Haureau, B. Les ceuvres de Hugues de Saint-Victor: Essai critique. Paris, Butler, C. Western Mysticism.
1886.
Hunt, R. "The Introductions mediaevalia Kleinz,
J.
The Theory
D.C., 1944. Weisweiler, H.
XX
and
Williams,
to the 'Artes' in the
("Miscellanea Martin"). Bruggis of
Knowledge
of
Hugh
Twelfth Century," Studia (n.d.),
of St.
"Die Arbeitsmethode Hugos von
XXIV
W. The
St.
pp.
Victor.
85-112.
Washington, Scholasti\,
Victor,"
(1949), 59-87 and 232-67.
Mysticism of
St.
Bernard of Clairvaux. London, 193 1.
VI, VII
Texts Peter Abelard. Theological works. Migne, .
.
.
Opera. Edited by V. Cousin. 2
Ouvrages inedits
CLXXVIII.
vols. Paris, 1849, 1859.
d' Abelard. Edited
by V. Cousin. Paris, 1836.
Peter Abaelards philosophische Schriften. Beitrdge,
XXXI,
1-4.
Miinster, 1919-33. .
Abailard's Ethics. Translated by
.
Glosses on Porphyry
Selections,
I,
208-58.
J.
R.
McCallum. Oxford,
(Introduction). Translated by R.
1935.
McKeon
in
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
86
William of Saint Thierry. Disputatio adversus Abaelardum. Migne, CLXXXII, 531-32. .
.
Aenigma
De
Davy. 2
Fidei.
CLXXX, 397-440. Text, French translation, and notes by M.-M.
Migne,
vie solitaire.
la
vols. Paris, 1914.
Studies
Adam, A. Guillaume de
Saint-Thierry: Sa vie et ses
oeuvres.
Bourg-en-
Bresse, 1923.
Gilson, E. Heloise
and Abelard. Translated by
L. Shook. Chicago,
Kaiser, E. Pierre Abelard critique. Fribourg, Switzerland,
Un
Lasserre, P.
conflit religieux
au XII^
siecle:
1951.
1901.
Abelard contre
S.
Bernard.
Paris, 1930.
Lefevre, G. Les variations de Guillaume de
Champeaux
et la question
des
universaux. Lille, 1898.
"Le probleme de
Lottin, O.
la
d'Aquin," Revue thomiste,
McCallum, J.
VIII
See
X
XXXIX
Abailard's Christian
Thomas
(1934), 477-515.
Theology. Oxford, 1948.
Peter Abailard. Cambridge, 1932.
Sikes,
IX
J.
moralite intrinseque, d'Abelard a saint
II, III,
and IV
See VI and VII
See
II, III,
and IV
XI Texts Alan of
Lille.
Contra haereticos. Migne,
CCX,
305-430.
Studies Alphandery, P. hes Idees morales chez
Xlir
siecle.
les
heterodoxes latins au debut du
£cole des Hautes £tudes, "Sciences religieuses," Vol. XVI.
Paris, 1903.
Arnou, R. "Quelques idees neoplatoniciennes de David de Dinant," Philosophia perennis, I, 115-27. Regensburg, 1930. Broekx, E. Le Catharisme. Louvain, 19 16. Capelle, C. Autour du decret de 1210: Amaury de Bene, etude sur son pantheisme formel. Paris, 1932.
I
THE TWELFTH CENTURY
87
manichSen du XIW Steele: Le "Liber de duobis fragment de rituel cathare. Rome, 1939. Fournier, P. ^tude sur Joachim de Flore. Paris, 1909. Runciman, S. The Mediaeval Manichee. Cambridge, 1947. Thery, G. Autour du decret de 1210: David de Dinant, etude sur son pantheisme materialiste. Paris, 1925. Dondaine, A.
Un
traite
principiis" suivi d'un
XII Texts John of Salisbury. Opera. Migne, CXCIX. Metalogicon. Translated by D. McGarry. Berkeley, 1962. Policraticus. Parts translated by J. Dickinson under the .
.
title
of
Statesman's BooJ^ of John of Salisbury. New York, 1927. Policraticus. Parts translated by J. Pike under the title of Frivolities
The ".
and Footprints of Philosophers. (He does not translate the same books as Dickinson.) Minneapolis, 1938. Daniels, H. Die Wissenschaftslehre des Johannes von Salisbury. Kalderof Courtiers
kirchen, 1932.
Denis, L.
"La question des universaux d'apres Jean de Salisbury," Revue
des sciences philosophiques et theologiques, Haskins, C.
Webb,
The Renaissance
of the Twelfth
C. John of Salisbury. London, 1932.
XVI (1927), 425-34. Century. Cambridge, 1927.
PHILOSOPHY IN THE EAST THE DESTINY o£ the wcstem world during the Middle
Ages was determined
stretching
from India
to
in part by the
Arab conquest, which,
Spain and as far as southern Italy and the
put a screen between Europe and Asia. In 635 the Arabs began to move with lightning speed across the globe;
Greek
islands,
within one century they completed their domination, but were stopped at Poitiers in 732 and in Chinese Turkestan in 751.
finally
They brought with them
a
language and a religion that subse-
quently gained ascendancy over vast trol of Syria,
culture
had been preserved and where,
phers were
They
territories.
seized con-
Egypt, and Persia, countries where the old Hellenistic
still
in the sixth century, philoso-
engaged in writing commentaries on Plato and
we
Aristotle. In this chapter
shall try to assess the
impact of such
events on the course of the history of ideas.
From
the historians
we
learn that only a handful of Arabs were
scattered throughout the vast territories they occupied militarily,
and
that they preserved the administrative
of the conquered nations.
ment
of the Persian
and
social organization
For example, following the dismember-
Empire
that resulted in
its
division into in-
dependent dominions, the Caliphs of Baghdad enlisted in their vice the
whole
Persian rulers.^
financial
An
and
ser-
political organization of the ancient
anologous phenomenon seems to characterize
the intellectual sphere: converted to Islam
and writing
^Cf, Halphen, Les barbares (Paris: Alcan, 1926), Vol.
I,
chaps, x and
in Arabic, xi.
09 the
PHILOSOPHY IN THE EAST
Arab philosophers, most
origin,
found
their
them
of
Aryan
of
rather than Semitic
themes for meditation either in the Greek works
which the Nestorian Christians who populated Asia Minor and Persia translated into Syriac in the
and Arabic
Mazdaist tradition which was
after the sixth century, or
still
alive in Persia
and which
had assimilated elements of Indian philosophy (the mysticism of the Sufi).
The Moslem Theologians
I
The Koran For
theologies. able, the
is
not the direct source of inspiration for
though
several reasons,
its
Koran did not engender anything
theology that dominated Europe. controversies were based trine of the troversies,
To
influence
Moslem
was consider-
similar to the dogmatic
begin with, most theological
on questions
tacitly set aside
by the doc-
Koran. The Trinitarian and the Christological con-
like the
controversy over grace, are meaningless in a
doctrine that assumes the radical unity of
God and
has no place
God and his prophet Mohammed, who consummated the work of the two prophets Abraham and Jesus, are the sum and substance of the religion of Islam sparse and for anything like the sacrament.
:
clear as a desert landscape
and shorn of any
trace of the Hellenic
penchant for complicated speculations on the nature of divine reality.
Furthermore, there
function
is
to interpret
is
in Islam
no
spiritual authority
dogma. The Koran
is
not weighted
whose
down
by an accretion of binding pronouncements. Islam recognizes the prophets as
men
inspired by
God
but holds that not one of them
can add to the teaching of the Koran.
The cal,
sacred book,
much more
contains but one
hammed borrowed from solutely simple
The dogma
practical
and
juridical than theoreti-
dogma, which goes back
to
an idea that Mo-
Jewish monotheism: that of one God, ab-
by nature, whose will
is
omnipotent and inscrutable.
implies a representation of the universe diametrically
opposed to the Neo-Platonic representation generally accepted in the countries conquered by the Arabs.
The
Islamic concept of
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
90
divine arbitrariness stands in sharp contrast to the concept of a rational order of
development which the Greek philosophers
The
troduced into the world.
theme
the only
ology, that
who
lites,
in-
between the two concepts
contrast
is
what may properly be called Moslem theMutakallimoun and the Mutazi-
treated in
the theology of the
is,
took pains to erect against their adversaries a coherent
image of the universe according
Koran.
to the
All reflection was concentrated around two purely theological questions:
God and
negation of multiplicity in
power other than
that of
On
God.
how God, if he is one, can be said forth. Some of them went so far as
the
as
eternal quality along with
posited
them
God
God had any
of
deny that or
just,
deny outright that he
manners of being under in
any way en-
and "whoever
qualities, is
so
to
which divine essence appeared, but without being hanced by them; they were not
and
be good, wise,
modes
all
Moslems asked
point,
first
to
these properties; others, though they did not
had them, considered them
negation of
two Gods."
positing
an
posits
others
Still
as eternal qualities that subsist through the essence of
God.
On
the second point, theologians were
The
determinism.
eighth century.
God, who
dains good.
It
founder of the
impious
man
same time a
is
and
The
denial of free will
had
as its
emergence of the Mutazilites (seceders) in the
Under
the influence of Wazil, the son of Ata, the
Mutazilites conceded that ness of
of both free will
concept limits the power of God, and the
first
second entails natural necessity. counter-eflFect the
wary
in the
sect,
man
has freedom to safeguard the good-
incapable of decreeing a bad act since he or-
is
same
conciliatory spirit that Wazil, the
posited between the righteous believer
the intermediate state of the sinner believer.
His idea
recalls the
who
and the
is
at the
moderate solution that
the middle Stoics offered to the problem of moral progress.
As
for natural determinism,
indissolubly eternal
the
Hnked by
world with a
manner
the
we must
Greek
bear in
tradition
cyclical evolution
and
to to a
mind
the
that
it
is
image of an
god who
acts in
of a natural force. Against this, the thesis of creation
PHILOSOPHY IN THE EAST
91
indeterminism in the production of things not only
entails a radical
the initial
at
Hence 935) to
moment
the continuity of substance
:
God was
assume that
others; bodies, then, are
The same
void. is
but also throughout the course of time.
the atomistic theory advocated by the school of Askari (876is
impossible, for one
would have
not free to create one part without the
made
of discontinuous atoms floating in the
holds true with respect to continuity in time, which
form.ed by a series of indivisible instants, and in movement,
which sity
consists of separate
and individual
There
leaps.
in the inherence of the atom's properties, for all
identical,
and
their properties
cidents. Finally, there
substance at a given
is
no
—color
and
life
—are
no neces-
is
atoms are
superadded
ac-
necessity for the accidents that exist in
moment
to exist there the
following
moment;
they are at each instant the effect of a direct creation of God, and there
no natural law that requires the existence or non-existence
is
of anything whatsoever. In this atomistic theory,
glory of Allah,
we would
which
is
for the
search in vain for something that recalls
the rationalism of Epicurus.
II
The
Influence of Aristotle
and
of
NeO'Platonism
The Greek spread
influence,
initially
running counter
Moslem
through translations from Greek
by the Nestorian Christians who,
first at
489), then in the cloisters of Syria, tury, in the
to
and
to
theology,
Syriac
finally, in the
seventh cen-
convent of Kinnesrin on the Euphrates, translated not
only Aristotle's Organon but also the pseudo-Aristotelian
On
made
the school of Edessa (431-
treatise.
the World, and the works of Galen. After the founding of
Baghdad
in the ninth century,
Arabic, either from Syriac or
many works were
from Greek, and
translated into
in 832 the Caliph
himself founded what amounted to a translation bureau in his capital.
Toward
the
end of the ninth century, an Arab had
access to
almost the whole of Aristotle's work (except the Politics) and to the
commentaries of Alexander, Porphyry, Themistius, Ammonius,
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
92
and John Philoponus;
translations
Plato's dialogues, such as the
were
also available of
The Greek doxography was
through
accessible
Empedocles and
to Pythagoras.
tributed to
was dominated by two
Enneads were
The
of Aristotle's Theology.
which was
To
tases.
Ptolemy's Almagest.
a
summary God,
the triad of
falsely at-
treatises
him. Around 840, extracts from seven
Plotinus' last three
preface
of
attribu-
did the Arab philosophers use these materials? Their inter-
pretation of Aristotle
title
of
Furthermore, medicine was
known through Galen and astronomy through
How
translations
mention works
Plutarch's Lives of the Philosophers, not to ted to
some
Timaeus, the Republic, and the Sophist.
from
treatises
translated into Arabic under the translation
was preceded by a
of the Neo-Platonic theory of hypos-
Intelligence,
and Soul
which each
(in
term derives from the preceding term), was added a fourth term, Nature, which derives from Soul.
made
or material.
The
treatise of the fifth
extracts included, in
Ennead, which
whole doctrine of Plotinus. The second Aristotle
Proclus'
each of the four terms was
correspond to one of Aristotle's four causes
to
efficient,
ond
And
is
final,
formal,
an abridgment of the
treatise falsely attributed to
was the BooJ{ of Causes, which contained
from
extracts
Elements of Theology.
Under
these influences
lowed the Greeks, was
Arab philosophy,
to the extent that
with the two
treatises
mentioned above, the
fifth
the third
we
on the moving Intelligence of the heavens,
book of
his
On
find,
than the
spirit of
A
some ways anything
Aristode from the
spirit of
Neo-Platonism
and a
more is
in-
posi-
sharp contrast to a mythology of spiritual
forces that seems to suffuse the universe
only through intuition.
Aristotle's as well as
that differs
rational empiricism, a logical technique,
tive orientation stand in
along
the Soul, which deals with the nature
of intellectual knowledge. In
conceivable.
fol-
book of the Meta-
and the eighth book of the Physics, which contain
speculations
it
essentially a Neo-Platonic interpretation of
the whole of Aristotle's work. In the foreground
physics
—
entirety, the sec-
its
and
that
is
apprehended
PHILOSOPHY
93
THE EAST
IN
Alkindi
III
The prime
Arab philosophers was
characteristic of the
with which they were able
back and forth between Aris-
to pass
and Neo-Platonism. The
totelianism Peripatetics,
the ease
first
Arab
of the well-known
Alkindi (died in 872), was a mathematician deeply
who
concerned with positive knowledge: "Anyone
wishes to under-
stand logical demonstrations," he said, "ought to devote to the study of geometrical
especially the easier ones since they serve
Demonstration was correct standard
and then
time rules,
obvious examples."
as
him an instrument
to
much
demonstrations and learn their
that required "first a
correct application."
^ It
therefore presup-
posed prior, indemonstrable knowledge. There are three kinds of such knowledge: the
whose
first,
knowledge of the existence of the object
attributes {an sit) are to be demonstrated,
is
given directly by
the senses; the second, knowledge of self-evident universal axioms,
common knowledge and the third,
knowledge of the quiddity or
ables us to demonstrate attributes
We tion
definition of an object, en-
by means of axioms.
recall all the difficulties raised
by Aristotle's theory of defini-
and of quiddity. Alkindi grappled with the same
the quiddity of a being
is
requires neither meditation nor reflection;
is
known
difficulties:
neither through the senses that
ascertain only existence, nor through induction that ascertains only properties.
To
separate the quiddity
from
sensible data
have recourse to a special operation which treatise
De
is
intellectu et intellecto. In conformity
one must
described in the
with the funda-
mental theorem of Aristotle's metaphysics, a being cannot pass
from potency there
must
to act unless
exist
"an
under the influence of an active being;
intellect that is forever active"
always of quiddities. This explains that
is
in the soul (that
is,
why
the "potential intellect"
the capacity of conceiving of quiddities)
can become "intellect that passes from potency to "acquired ^
{adeptus)
Trans. Nagy, p, 46.
and conceives
intellect"
capable
of
and
finally
demonstration.
Thus
act,"
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
94
knowledge of quiddities
is
acquired only in a soul capable of receiv-
ing such knowledge and by virtue of a primary intelligence which
always active and which, being the universal form of things
is
(God) and giving
to things their quiddities or forms, also
endows
these forms with potential intelligence.
Alfarabi
IV
Alkindi's views on the operation of the intellect implied the rudi-
ments of a vast theology. Such a theology was developed by Alfarabi (born at the end of the ninth century). In
and
tration of the influence of Aristotle totle
omy:
he borrowed his a
see the interpene-
that of Plato.
From
Aris-
by Arabic astron-
astral theology, simplified
supreme God above the worlds; heavens composed of eight
and interlinking
concentric cular
we
it
spheres, each with
—the sphere of the fixed bodies
motion governed by an
intellect
and the seven spheres of the seven sublunary sphere.
From
characteristic cir-
its
and beneath
planets;
Plotinus (through the
these, the
work on theology
falsely ascribed to Aristotle)
he borrowed the general image of the
production of living beings
progression as
from the One
and the Changing. The
who by knowing The second
first.
recall
How how
own
knows
things:
in Plotinus the
first
farabi:
from the
essentially the
is
One gave
being that itself it is
is
an
knowledge
it
One
Such
same
It is
is
from absolute unity
its
.^^
We
birth to Intelligence: some-
One
and, turning back to-
One and
the description given by Al-
it is
derived,
it is
composite; for by
therefore necessary to separate knowl-
has of the Principle as the ground of
of
as the
can come only a unique and eternal
intellect; since
only possible.
edge that
itself.
eternal
God,
in their absolute
the One, becomes intelligence by contemplating the
becoming conscious of
Temporal
essence; then in their infinite multiplic-
type of knowledge
thing indeterminate emanates from the
ward
to the
the supreme principle,
is
all
multiplicity to be derived
is
by a law of evolution
if
from the Eternal
starting point
his essence
unity, identical to his ity.
:
to the Multiple,
existence as possible
— that —of is
its
its
existence,
matter (since
PHILOSOPHY
95
matter
THE EAST
merely potential being), and knowledge that
is
which
self,
IN
is
its
form
From
or essence.
it
has of
it-
the three kinds of knowl-
edge are born three beings: from knowledge of the Principle born a second
be to the
intellect that will
from the matter of the
Principle;
sphere (this topical matter
first
from the form
motion)
;
the
sphere.
first
intellect
first
born the matter of the
is
is
born the moving soul of
the procession of intellects
spheres with their souls; each intellect produces in
moving
ordinate intellect, a sphere, and a
moon, dominated by the
of the spheres, the
is
the
first is to
the simple possibility of circular
is
of the intellect
Thus begins
as the
its
and
down
soul, last of
celestial
turn a subto the last
the intellects, the
"active intellect."
Each
intellect
as the
is
law of motion of the sphere:
order of the good that emanates from as
it
acquires
ries its
its
knowledge."
it,
and
it
"It
produces
it
whatever order there
creates
the
order
this
conceives the motion that car-
It also
sphere from one point to the next, and this image
creative:
knows
is
is
in turn
in the transmutation of
elements in the sublunary region. Intellects,
and particularly the
forms of sensible things; but these
divisibly all the quiddities or
quiddities separate
each being
is
human
from each other
soul.
is
the starting point of intellectual
Knowledge
verse of a divisive impulse: best
it
in the sublunary region
where
The
merely a being separated from other beings.
state of separation
the
or active intellect, contain in-
last
is
a unifying impulse
"The
knowledge and
is
in
the re-
active intellect seeks to reunite as
can that which has been divided and creates the acquired in-
tellect of
which human nature
identified in the
human
points in the passage
is
a part."
The
different intellects
soul by Alfarabi are merely the principal
from division
the potential intellect, which
to unity.
At
the lowest point
the capacity to abstract forms
is
is
from
matter and to reunite and classify these forms; above the potential intellect
is
the active intellect,
this capacity.
The
which
and accompanied by individual
and disentangled
is
the effective realization of
intelligible reality, fused at first
as
it
passes
peculiarities,
from sense
is
to the
with
its
image
gradually purified
common
sense
and
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
96
from the common sense tive intellect
to the imagination,
matter for
intellect receives
where the potential
Above each
abstractive activity.
its
ac-
the acquired intellect which through an intuitive
is
look apprehends the unifying principle underlying separate forms.
At
the
summit
all
other intellects and which has unleashed
is
moon, which
the active intellect of the
all
is
prior to
their activity
by
causing the potential intellect to become active. His theory of intellects is
by the
from the theory of Alkindi who, suffused
quite different
spirit of Proclus, structured the intellects into a hierarchy,
with the result that each of them, beginning with the active lect, is as
form
to
matter with respect to
But we must not assume that Alfarabi's theory of
knowledge excludes the
other
modes
of linking the
whole
reality.
As
and the being
series
without a
veil of
can hide; he
is
tween him and
V
soul to
emanations
that can be possessed directly by the
soul that eschews the sensible world. "Being is
intellectual
human
in Plotinus, God may be the first term in a among which human intelligence finds its prerank and place; or he may be the absolute being beyond the
supreme
series of cise
all
intel-
successor.
its
any kind; there
is
beyond everything, he
no accident under which he
neither near nor far; there
is
no intermediary
be-
us."
Avicenna Avicenna (980-1036) added nothing
of Alfarabi. Like Alfarabi he starts ligence;
knows
because he
knows
essential to the metaphysics
from
his essence,
the fundamental causes
a
God who
he knows
is
all
and the pure quiddities of
pure
intel-
things; all
he
things,
even individual things. In the same way Avicenna describes the
emanation of
intellects
and of
efficient souls that
cause the spheres
to turn uniformly, imitating as closely as possible the immutability
of the intellects
from which they
derive.
Like Alfarabi, he attributes knowledge
to the influence that the
agent intellect or the intellect of the sublunary sphere exercises on receptive
intellects.
The
agent intellect gives to sensible things
PHILOSOPHY
97
forms or quiddities
their
receiving them,
cenna
and
types
several
identifies
to the
degree that matter
produces knowledge in
it
principles or axioms,
THE EAST
IN
abstract ideas,
knowledge
as
susceptible of
But Avi-
knowledge: knowledge of
of
knowledge of
through revelation, such
is
intellects.
first
and knowledge
To
of the future.
the
first
made
type corresponds "the intellect that has been prepared or
ready," so called because here potency borders on act; to the second
corresponds the active intellect that actually perceives the intelligible
forms perceived potentially by the material or possible
and
emanated or infused
to the third corresponds the
intellect;
intellect that
"comes from without."
Avicenna describes intellects.
from the
in detail the
mechanism
of the second of the
Slowly one succeeds in separating the abstract notion sensible thing.
form of an
receives only the
the soul but
appendages
its
The
operation begins with sensation, which object ("it
form"), before
is
not the stone that
has been divested of
it
it its
fall
than that of substance: quantity, position, and so forth. brain,
formative" operation, situated in the
image from the temporal or
Then
it
this
to its
still
not divested of individual character-
way
make
pos-
"opinion" that allows the lamb, without reflection, to
tinguish the wolf
tellect,
image but begins
tends toward the universal. For instance, images
sible the
of the
with other similar images, produces a kind of
rude notion which, though istics,
The "imagincavity
the "cognitive, imaginative, or collective" opera-
by associating
tion,
left
spatial conditions of
the individuality of the
retains
still
separate the existence.
in
is
material
—the characteristics that are due to matter and give under categories other —and the accidents that
individuality
ative or
its
from other animals.
that the rational soul,
It is in
dis-
images prepared in
under the influence of the agent
discovers the abstract forms that
make
in-
possible logical, re-
flective operations.
But Avicenna edge in man:
which
is
is
aware of the narrow
"man cannot know
inseparable
example, he does not
limits of intellectual
knowl-
the essence of things but only that
from them or
know what
a
the properties of them."
body
is,
For
but he knows that
it
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
98
has three dimensions. Essences are merely inferred from properties.^
Yet the soul can reach a more perfect
encumbered by
body,
its
of the agent intellect
state
which
to the influence
floods the imaginative faculty, produc-
ing prophetic dreams; and after death perfect
in the state of sleep, un-
:
becomes more receptive
it
will attain to even
it
more
knowledge.
Alhazen (965-1038), one of Avicenna's contemporaries, exerted a strong influence on twelfth-century Latin writers through his Perspective and his study of optics.
which
visual perception
a classic
still
is
He
prepared an analysis of
and which we
shall find
again in Witelo.
Algazel (Al Gazzali)
VI
The work
of Algazel (1058-1111),
who
in Jerusalem, betrays the unrest caused
taught in Damascus and
by the diffusion of Peri-
pateticism in Islam. His Tahafut al-Falasifah ("Destruction of the
Philosophers")
He
refutation.
is
devoted to an exposition of Peripateticism and
points out that the thesis of the eternity of the world
destroys the concept of the indifference of will that one tribute to
its
God, by imposing upon him
which
neither even nor
odd and
an
infinite regres-
impossible since the infinite
is
is
at-
eternally the choice of a
definite order; the infinity of past time implies
sion of causes,
must
therefore contradictory.
ophers been able to demonstrate the unity of
God
number
Nor have
is
philos-
or the spirituality
of the soul or the necessity of the causal link.
But
it
is
difficult to define
Algazel's
Averroes, "he belongs to no sect; he
lowers of Ashari, a Sufi philosophers," self against
and he
among
tried
is
own
views. According to
among the philosopher among
an Asharite
the Sufis, a
*
51-
the
through his Destruction "to protect him-
the wrath of theologians,
who have
always been the
enemies of philosophers."^ Whether or not he was a Skeptic, ^
fol-
Liber aphorismorum de anima, trans. Andre de Bellune, pp. 101-21. Quoted by Worms, in Baucmker, Beitrage zur Philosophic des Mittelalters ,
we III,
PHILOSOPHY IN THE EAST
99
works something resembUng the Skeptics'
find in his
knowledge, which corresponds
critique of
seems to have been
to a current that
during the twelfth century: the uncer-
rather general in Islam
tainty of the senses that contradict each other
and
are contradicted
by reason, the uncertainty of reason whose principles,
just
as
they judge the senses, can be judged according to principles that
remain unknown the
to us.
Here we have
Greek Skeptics, which
Arab
argument
the old line of
found
also
of
in the writings of other
thinkers.^
The Arabs
VII
is
The
in Spain:
philosophers
still
to
Averroes be discussed were products of Spain,
where Moslem culture flourished
in the twelfth century.
Avempace
(Ibn Bad] a, died in 1138) of Saragossa tried in his Rule of the Solitary to describe the different degrees through
apart
from any
tive intellect
social influence,
which a
man,
could identify himself with the ac-
and become a member of a perfect
and medicine
solitary
state
where
justice
—appropriate to our imperfect states which have to — are unknown. Beyond the ideas abstracted
struggle against evils
from matter, described by philosophers, the attain to intelligible forms,
which
are
solitary
man must
separated from matter of
themselves, rather than by intelligence, and which finally reduce
themselves to unity.
Abubacer (Ibn Tufail, 1100-1185) of Cadiz imagined in
his philo-
Hayy ibn Ya\zan ("The History of Hayy ben Yaqdhan"), what Avempace's solitary man would be if he were born on an uninhabited island. Starting from sensible knowledge sophical novel, Risalat
he would
rise to the
forms abstracted from bodies, thence
to their
general causes, the eternal heavens and their movers, and finally to
God, completely separated from the
senses.
Averroes (Ibn Rochd, 1126-1198) of Cordova devoted himself pecially to the task of
the face of ^
Cf. Carra
its
es-
determining the true meaning of Aristotle in
deformation by his interpreters.
de Vaux, Gazdi, pp. 115 and 45.
Two
points deserve
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
100
special attention: his theory of the production of substantial
and
The
his theory of the possible intellect.
we
Avicenna:
see the substantial
ture as something absolutely
Avicenna holds that
this
first is
directed against
form appear spontaneously
new and
forms in na-
not contained in matter, but
would not be
true of
generations; that
all
nature produces spontaneously only combinations resulting from the reciprocal action of the four heat, wetness and dryness)
;
primary or active qualities (cold and
form which through
that the substantial
a certain combination produces a certain being
jorrnarum, which
is
comes from
an intelligence outside and superior
a dator
to nature.
Averroes censures Avicenna for making a natural being not one being but an amalgam of two beings produced by two distinct agents.
He
holds that a
new
form
substantial
matter by another form that already exists in generation:
have
to
man
as to prepare
introduced into
(so-called univocal
we do
not
formarum outside matter. The form is capable from the outset,
to a dator
body that possesses a substantial its
is
engenders man), with the result that
have recourse
by virtue of
it
way
active qualities, of transforming matter in such a
it
to receive
form, and then of engendering form in
the matter transformed in this way.
His theory of
intellect is directed
against the interpretation of
Alexander of Aphrodisias. In the active
intellect,
identical to the intelligible reality that
contemplates. Since the
intelligible reality
is
subject that contemplates intelligibles
How
can we,
ander, by
who
making
of the material intellect
we can
conceive of intelligible beings.
we
But
if
the
is
as a result It
(which
is
ourselves) a
unable to explain
how
follows that the material
capable of reflection, must be uncreated, incorrupt-
ible, identical for all
can
also eternal.
eternal, this question arises:
is
and corruptible being, it is
is
is
are corruptible, contemplate intelligibles? Alex-
created
intellect, if
it
eternal, intelligence
intelligence
men. But then the
difficulty
is
reversed:
How
explain the intellectual activity of each individual, which be-
gins at a certain
moment
in
time?
suppose that the intellectual act
is
The
not a
only possible solution
new
intellection,
an
is
to
act that
L
PHILOSOPHY IN THE EAST
lOI
moment
joins us at this
and disappears with us which
intellect,
What
to the agent intellect. is
originates in us
the simple disposition called the passive
consists in the fact that the state of
our images
lows us to receive the eternal emanation of the agent
We
see
shall
among there
is
no
represent truths,
later
the Latins. conflict
two
the
development of Averroes' philosophy
Here we need only note
that according to
between philosophy and
religion,
him
which simply
steps in the process of thinking: religion veils the
which the philosopher
discovers, in order to bring
within reach of the uninitiated. that the philosopher worships
VIII
al-
intellect.
them
by understanding these truths
It is
God.
Jewish Philosophy through the Twelfth Century
Jewish philosophy developed in the Arab world during the
cendancy of Islam. The Cabala designated not so
much
as-
a particular
doctrine as the Jewish form of Neo-Platonic mysticism. In contrast to the
Talmud,
a juridical
represented a state of
and
commentary on the Law,
literal
mind analogous
it
to that of Philo of Alex-
andria: a mystical interpretation of letters and numbers, which are the signs through)
which Wisdom
ous correspondence between
transmitted to
is
letters
method
meaning and
that reveals in each
a sublime mystery; a
that multiplies the intermediaries
part of
all this
a mysteri-
and the composition of the
world, the divisions of the year, the structure of allegorical
men;
word
man;
of the
the use of the
Law
a higher
mythology of powers and angels
between
God and
his creation.
No
seems very novel.
Whether he spoke
of metaphysics or of the theory of knowledge,
Jew (845-940), reasoned in the main as a Neo-Platonist bent on discovering a hierarchy in which the inferior Isaac IsraeH, an Egyptian
proceeds from the superior and tional soul, tellect,
animal
is
as its
But
intelligence, ra-
soul, vegetative soul; in intelligence, active in-
passive intellect, imagination,
classifications.
shadow:
his compilations
and
sensation,
we
recognize
were useful and not without
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
102
importance, for thirteenth-century Latins found in his
historical
Boo^
famous
of Definitions the
definition of truth: adaequatio rei
et intellectus.
Saadia ben Joseph or Saadiagaon (882-942), an Egyptian Jew
who
and Convictions,
hved in Babylonia, tried in his Book^ of Beliefs
how reason and revelation compleThe command to serve God and the problasphemy and doing harm to others are examples
written in 932, to determine
ment each other hibition against
of rational
in law.
commandments. There
which deal with things
are others
that are in themselves indififerent
and which become law by the
will of
God. The second type of commandment, which must be
vealed,
is
it is
indispensable to the execution of the
first,
which, because
too general, leaves undefined the circumstances of
tion.
How
is it
re-
its
applica-
possible to prohibit theft, for example, in the absence
of a definition of property
}
Jewish philosophy developed in Spain and in Morocco. Avice-
bron of Malaga (Solomon ibn-Gabirol, 1020-1070) wrote a work of great historical importance, the
Fons
vitae,
which was
to
become
one of the main sources of Neo-Platonism during the thirteenth century.
Among
of realities:
other things,
first,
God
it
included a hierarchical classification
exalted above everything, then Will, then
Form, inseparable from the Matter that vitae
had
of the
from
as its objective the
work
is
it
determines.
study of form and matter.
stated in these
a source are concentrated
words: "All things that emanate
when
they are near the source and
dispersed
when
they are far from
universal
form
that contains, united
it."
At in
the highest level itself,
all
lowest level are the sensible things that also contain
which contains
each other and yet distinct from each other. stated by
Avicebron
is
that there are
that each level of reality
is
is
the
forms; at the all
separated from each other and dispersed; between the are realities such as intelligence,
The Fons The thesis
forms, but
two
levels
all
forms, united to
A
second principle
no forms without matter and
matched by
a matter that corresponds in
perfection to the height of the level, for perfection of matter con-
PHILOSOPHY IN THE EAST
103 in
sists
ability to
its
become one with form
Hence
in total union.
the
order in the Fons vitae: beginning with the lowest level, that of corporeal substances, Avicebron studies successively the corporeal
matter that supports sensible qualities, the spiritual matter that supports the substantial spiritual substances
and
form of the body, the matter of intermediary
The
and simple substances
(souls)
finally the universal
knowledge
place of intellectual
Forms
obvious.
are
(intelligences),
matter that supports the universal form.
mixed together
in Avicebron's hierarchy
in intelligence
and united
to
is it,
not through the accidental union that joins them to the body, but
through an essentially
spiritual union.
This
is
an
essential trait of
Neo-Platonism, which does not simply add knowledge over and
above tier
reality
upon
To
tier
but views
it
one of the
as
from the Many
to the
levels of reality
which
rise
One.
eleventh-century Spain also belongs a
movement
character-
ized by mystical piety and brought to light by a recently translated
work
of Ibn Pakuda, called Introduction to Duties of the Heart.
Moses Maimxonides (Moses ben Maimon), a rabbi who was born in
Cordova (1135) and died
in Cairo (1204),
wrote his Guide of the
Perplexed mainly for the purpose of explaining the Law.
up philosophical
subjects
form and of matter
illuminate Scripture. Philosophical speculation
Thomas
a position least
it
said later), but
it
—only in order
to
autonomous
(as
is
confirms the truths of the Law. Such
makes Maimonides' thought somewhat ambiguous,
makes
takes
— the question of separated intelligences, of
the motions of the spheres, of
St.
He
or at
the diflFerent aspects of his thought hard to har-
monize. Take the question of demonstrating philosophically the existence of the unity of
God (Book
II).
Maimonides borrows from
the Peripatetics a demonstration based on the eternity of the universe,
which they grant,
of the celestial spheres, infers
an
infinite
for
it is
through consideration of the motion
which has neither beginning nor end, that he
moving cause which
is
God. Yet he does not view
the eternity of the world as anything but a hypothesis of possible
demonstration. His system of the world, like that of every other
104
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
Arab philosopher, spheres.
basically
is
system
Aristotle's
But here too he remains quite skeptical about the exactness
of his representation,
which he does not consider demonstrable.
Maimonides' main concern was apparently the "Prophecy
social role of the prophet.^
and
intellectual
God
an emanation from
is
which spreads, through the intermediary of the first
concentric
of
active
intellect,
over the rational faculty and then over the imaginative faculty.
makes
Spread over the rational faculty only,
it
spread over reason and imagination,
makes
pensable for drawing
men
to
conflicts
speculative sages;
true prophets, indis-
together into a perfect society and regu-
lating the actions of individuals susceptibility
it
whose
diversity and, consequently,
anything seen
surpasses
among
other
species."
Byzantine Philosophy
IX
In the Middle Ages, the city of Constantinople had sources needed for the continuation tradition.
and
it
But
was
it
a city of jurists, of businessmen
lacked the inclination to do
philosophy
so.
the re-
and theologians,
The number
the University of Constantinople
at
all
Greek philosophical
of the
of chairs of
was minimal
in
comparison with the chairs of sophistry and of jurisprudence.'^ Thus for the
most part we find only scholars and commentators
the only vital question Aristotle. Photius
preserved the
many
is
that of the conflict
(820-897), ^^^ scholar in extracts
Greek philosophers, showed
whose Bibltotheca
that
are
a predilection for Aristotle. Psellus
To him
Plato was the
true theologian: "Aristode generally treated theological
manner
whom
from and abridgments of the works of
(1018-1098) took the role of Plato's defender. a
for
between Plato and
was too human."
Psellus' vast
work was
dogmas
in
the starting
point of the stream of Platonic philosophy that traveled through
Pletho and Bessarion to Renaissance Italy and to the rest of the ^
Guide des egares, trans. Munk, Codex Theodosianiis xiv. 9, 3;
of juridical sciences,
p.
281.
five chairs of rhetoric,
and only one of philosophy.
twenty of grammar, two
105
PHILOSOPHY
THE EAST
IN
West. Thus a clear definition o£ his Platonism
important to the
His main source o£ inspiration was Proclus, "a
history of ideas.
superior
is
man who
penetrated to the heart of everything in phi-
losophy." Elsewhere he states: "I went to Piotinus, to Porphyry,
my
and
to lamblichus before
He
has provided
The
doctrine of Proclus was sure to appeal most strongly to a
me
I
found
haven
in the great Proclus.
with knowledge and with sound ideas."
trained in law. But restoring the pagan philosophy of Plato
mind
was no
even for Psellus. Following the example of John of
easy task
Damascus, who denounced "the satanic the
^
monks
of
Mount Olympus
errors of the
praised by Psellus as a "Hellenic Satan." to criticism
pagan
sages,"
Hellenic philosopher
treated the
As
Psellus said in reply
by his friend Xiphilinus, however, he was merely con-
tinuing the tradition of the Cappadocian Fathers and using Plato in the defense of the Christian
of justice
dogmas: "Are not
and the immortality of the soul the
Plato's doctrines
of similar
basis
own?"^ At the University of Byzantium, restored by Constantine IX (Monomachus), Psellus took pains to re-establish doctrines of our
the tradition of Neo-Platonic instruction
enumerated
in
the
on the
basis of the studies
book of the Republic. For courses
sixth
in
mathematics the textbooks were the works of Nicomachus of Gerasa,
EucHd, and Diophantus; for astronomy, Ptolemy and Proclus; and for music, Aristoxenus.
Added
to these
was philosophy, beginning
with Aristotle's logic and ending with the commentaries of Proclus. Finally
poems
came of
the allegorical explanation of inspired texts, such as the
Orpheus and the Chaldean
oracles. Psellus could not lay
claim to originality with respect to any part of the program of instruction:
"My
sole merit,"
he
says, "consists in
the fact that
I
have gathered together certain philosophical doctrines drawn from a fountain that
had ceased
rationalism that led tions of his era *
and
him
to flow." ^^
to attack
(as
The
and
demons,
a stubborn
for
supersti-
which he
3,
Opera, ed. N. Sathas, in Bibliotheca medii aevi (Paris, ^° Zervos, Michel Psellos, p. 40.
^
was
had Piotinus) the
particularly the belief in
Cf. Zervos, Michel Psellos, p. 193, nn. 2
result
1874-76), pp. 444
ff.
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
I06
Michael Cerularius: Psellus intended
the patriarch
criticized
remain a speculative metaphysician and not
to
deviate
toward
his pupils
Michael
to
theurgy.
The
him was continued by
tradition revived by
and Johannes
of Ephesus
Italus
who
tirelessly transcribed the
Neo-
Platonic commentaries on Aristotle and Plato. Eustratius, the pupil
was
of Johannes and Bishop of Nicaea,
criticized for teaching the
same Plotinian doctrine of hypostases that Abelard taught
a short
time later in Paris. Proclus' Neo-Platonism, though attacked by
(we have,
theologians of
for example, a refutation of Proclus'
Theology by Nicolas of
sisted in the twelfth
Blemmydes,
Elements
in the twelfth century), ^^ per-
century with Michael Italicos and Nicephorus
in the thirteenth
Acropolites, Joseph,
and
Modon
and fourteenth centuries with George
Theodore Metochites, and Nicephorus Gregoras, Demetrios Kydonis and Pletho
in the fifteenth century with
who
(Georgias Gemistus), the court of the Medici
introduced Platonism to Florence at
and who often defended Plato against the
Peripatetics.
He
seems seriously
to
have considered Platonism
tion for a universal religion.
George of Trebizond,
from
all
"When we were
heard him say that in a few years
"I
over the world, by
common
would embrace one and the same whether
it
would be the
Mohammed,
consent and in the same
religion.
.
.
.
And when
asked
religion of Jesus Christ or the religion of
from paganism.'
movement inaugurated by
" ^^
Such was the outcome of the
Psellus.
In contrast to Pletho, Theodorus
Gaza was
the fifteenth-century
representative of the old tradition of reconciling Plato
and Aris-
Byzantium, scholars continued throughout the period
write commentaries on Aristode.
"Ed. Voemel, Trans.
I
men spirit
he replied: 'Neither of these, but a third religion that
will not difFer
tode.^^ In
founda-
as the
in Florence," wrote
Among
Psellus'
own
to
disciples,
Frankfurt, 1825.
Boivin,
Memoires de I'academie des
inscriptions,
II,
171 7;
cited
by
Zervos, Michel Psellos, p. 239.
"
Cf.
Theodorus Gaza De
jato. ed.
Taylor (Toronto, 1925).
I
107
PHILOSOPHY IN THE EAST
Michael of Ephesus wrote a commentary on part of the Organon
and on the tenth book
De
on the
Nicomachean Ethics; Johannes
in the
Italus
on the Nicomachean Ethics
interpretatione; Eustratius
and the Posterior Analytics. In the fourteenth century, Nicephorus Blemmydes,
George
Pediasimus,
and Leo Magentinus paraphrased or
Aristotle's treatises
Pachymeres
on
we
Finally,
should at
Sophonias,
John
summarized
and psychology and copied the com-
logic
mentaries of Simplicius and
(1242-1301),
Ammonius.
least
mention, alongside the
official
philoso-
phers and professors, the persistence in monasteries of a trend
toward mysticism. According of
Mount
to
Climacus, Abbot of the monastery
Sinai at the beginning of the seventh century, one of
earliest manifestations
work known
in the
was
in St. John's
Ladder
to Paradise, a
West through Gerson. It shows more popular than those
the influence
of a philosophical thought Aristotle,
and
matter of
fact, St.
in
it
we
John mentions
and the twenty-ninth is
"one who
has
find an echo of Stoicism
is
made
sations."
(whose
-^^
St.
lives are
(
dcKck^eia)-
his flesh incorruptible,
John saw
and
and Cynicism. As
who
The who
impassive
a
man
has raised his
has subordinated to
in the Patriarchs of the
it all
his sen-
Egyptian desert
recounted in the Laiisiac History) illustrious ex-
amples of such impassivity. His work
is
therefore a link in the chain
that connects Christian mysticism to Pyrrho
The
of Plato
thirty successive steps in his ladder,
impassivity
thought beyond creation, and
its
famous
and
to
Diogenes.
trend toward speculative mysticism, going back to Dionysius
also continued in the Greek monasteries. The anonymous author of an eighth-century commentary on the books of Solomon was inspired by the Neo-Platonism of Maximus, a pupil
the Areopagite,
The trend is also manifested in the writings of Symeon (1025-1092), who held that mystical intuition was incompatible with mundane living and possible only among monks. Gregory
of Dionysius.
Palamas and
his pupil
Nicholas Cabasilas, successive archbishops of
Thessalonica, defended the Hesychasts "Migne,
Patrologia graeca,
who
LXXXVIII, 1148b, 1149a.
held that there existed
I08 apart
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE from the Trinity an uncreated
light that
emanated from the
Trinity and put the mystic in communication with God.
Here we
have the supreme manifestation of Neo-Platonic emanationism in Christianity.
Bibliography
I, II
Studies Abd-el-Djalil.
Le Coran
et la
pensee musulmane.
En
Terre d'Islam, 1939.
Carra de Vaux. Les Penseurs de I' Islam. 5 vols. Paris, 1921-26. De Boer, T. The History of Philosophy in Islam. Translated by E. Jones.
London,
1933.
vols, completed through 1927 (A to K and the and Leyden, 1907 Democratie," Revue thomiste (May and September,
Encyclopedic de I'lslam. 4 first
part of S). Paris
Gardet, L.
"Islam
et
.
1946). .
"Rencontre entre
tristique,"
la
premiere theologie musulmane
Revue thomiste (1947),
Kraus, P. "Plotin chez
les
et
la
pensee pa-
p. 45.
Arabes," Bulletin de I'lnstitut d'tgypte, XXIII
(1940-41), 263-95.
Macdonald, D. Development of Muslim Theology, Jurisprudence, and Constitutional Theory. New York, 1903. Nicholson, R. The Mystics of Islam. London, 1914. O'Leary, D. Arabic Thought and Its Place in History. London, 1922. Quadri, G. La philosophic arabe dans I'Europe medievale des origines a Averroes. Paris, 1947. Sauter, G. "Die peripatetische Philosophie bei den Syrern
Archiv
Sweetman, Ill,
fiir J.
die
Geschichte der Philosophie,
XVII
und den Arabern," (1904).
Islam and Christian Theology. 2 vols. London, 1945 and 1947.
IV
Texts German by F. Abhandlungen, aus dem arabischen
Alfarabi. Translated into
.
Alkindi.
Translated by F. Dieterici.
De
intellectu,
De somno
Der et
Dieterici.
Ubersetzt.
Alfr.rabi's
Leiden,
philosophische 1892.
Musterstaat. Leiden, 1900.
visione,
De quinque
essentiis,
introductorius in artem logicae demonstrationis. Edited by A.
109
Liber
Nagy
in
no THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE medieval translations in Die philosophischen Abhandlungen des Ishaq al-Kindi zum ersten Male herausgegeben. Miinster
their
Ja'qub ben
in Westfalen, 1897.
Studies
De
Boer, T. "Zu Kindi
und
seiner Schule,"
Archiv fur die Geschichte der
Philosophie.XWl (1900), 153-78. Fackenheim, E. The Possibility of the Universe in al-Farabi, Ibn Sina, and Maimonides. American Academy for Jewish Research. New York, 1947. Hammond, R. The Philosophy of Aljarabi and Its Influence on Mediaeval
Thought.
New
York, 1944.
Ibn Madcour. La place d'Al Farabi dans I'ecole philosophique musulmane. Paris, 1934.
Maker, H. "Al-Kindi,
The
Philosopher of the Arabs,'
"
Hebrew
College An-
nual. 1904. Pp. 55-71.
V
VII
to
Texts Algazel.
Algazel's
Metaphysics:
A
Mediaeval
Translation.
by
Edited
J.
Muckle. Toronto, 1933.
La
.
destruction des philosophes. French translation by Carra de Vaux.
Louvain, 1903. Alhazen. Perspectiva. Text and
German translation by Baarman under the "Ueber das Licht," Zeitschrift der deutschen tnorgenldndischen Gesellschaft,XXXVl (1882). Averroes. Averroes Latinus. Edited by H. Shields, et al. A new edition, not title
yet complete; presently 4 vols.
Cambridge, Mass., 1949, 1953, 1956,
1958.
Avicenna. Opera Philosophica. Louvain, 1961. Avicenna on Theology. Translated by A. Arberry. London, 195 1. Kitab-al-Najat. Book II, chap. vi. Translated with notes by F. Rah.
.
man
as
Avicenna s Psychology. Oxford, 1952.
Studies Afhan,
S.
Avicenna, His Life and Wor\. London, 1957. Die Psychologic Alhazens auj Grund von
H.
Bauer,
dargestellt. Miinster in Westfalen, 191
Alhazens
Optil^
W.
Trask.
1.
Carra dc Vaux. Avicenna. Paris, 1900. .
Gazali. Paris, 1903.
Corbin, H. Avicenna and the Visionary Recital. Translated by
New York,
Gardet, L.
i960.
La Pensee
religieuse
d'Avicenne (Ibn Sina). Paris, 1951.
PHILOSOPHY IN THE EAST
Ill
Gauthier, L.
The Philosophy and Theology
Jamil-ur-Rehman. Baroda, 192 1. Gilson, E. "L'etude des philosophies arabe
de
et
son role dans I'interpretation
scolastique," Proceedings of the Sixth
la
M.
of Averroes. Translated by
International Congress of
New
York, 1927. Pp. 592-96. Goichon, M. La distinction de I'essence et de I'existence chez Ihn Sina. Philosophy. Paris, 1937.
Smith,
"Avicenna and the Possibles,"
G.
The
New
Scholasticism,
XVII
(1943), 340-57.
Wensinck, A. La Pensee de Ghazzali. Paris, 1940. Wickens, G.(ed.). Avicenna, Scientist and Philosopher: A Millenary Symposium. London, 1952. Zedler, B. "Averroes on the Possible Intellect," Proceedings of the American
Catholic
Philosophical
Association,
XXV
(1951),
164-78.
VIII
Texts Avicebron (Gabirol). Pons
Latin translation by Jean d'Espagne and
vitae.
Gondissalvi. Edited by C. Bauemeker. Beitrdge, Vol.
I.
Miinster in West-
falen, 1892-95.
Ibn
Pakuda.
Introduction
au
devoirs
des
coeurs.
French
by
translation
Churaqui. Paris, 1950. Isaac Israeli. Opera omnia Ysaac Lugduni, 1515. Moses Maimonides. Guide of the Perplexed. Translated by .
.
.
S. Pines.
Chicago,
1963.
Studies Efros,
"Saadia's
I.
Theory of Knowledge," The Jewish Quarterly Review,
XXXIII (1942-43), 133-70. Finkelstein, L. (ed.). Rab Saadia Gaon:
Studies in His Honor.
New
York,
1944-
Gilson, E.
"Maimonide
et
la
philosophie de I'Exode," Mediaeval Studies,
XIII (1951), 223-25. Husik, J. A History of Mediaeval Jewish Philosophy.
New York, 1916. on Maimonides. New York, 1941. Roth, L. Spinoza, Descartes, and Maimonides. Oxford, 1924. McKeon,
R., et al. Essays
Strauss, L. Philosophie
und
Gesetz, Beitrdge
zub Verstdndnis Maimunis und
seiner Vorldufer. Berlin, 1935.
Wolfson, H. "Maimonides and Halevi," The Jewish Quarterly Review,
3,
2
(1912), 297-337. .
"Maimonides on Internal Senses," The Jewish Quarterly Review,
XXV
(1935), 441-67.
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
112
Vajda, G. Introduction a "La philosophie .
la et
pensee juive du moyen age. Paris, 1947. la theologie de Joseph Ibn Caddiq," Archives
d'histoire doctrinale et litteraire
du moyen
age,
XVII (1949),
106-10.
IX Texts Works
and theologians are included volumes indicated: Gregory Palamas, CL; CXLIX; Nicephorus Gregoras, CXLIX; Nicholas Cabasilas, CL; Photius, CL-CLV; Psellos, CXXII; Symeon, CXX. Demetrios Kydonis. Sur la crainte de la mort. Leipzig, 1901. George Acropolites, Opera. Edited by A. Heisenberg. Leipzig, 1903. John Pediasimus. In Aristoteles analytica scolia selecta. Edited by De Falco. of the following Byzantine philosophers
Migne, Series Graeca, Nicephorus Blemmydes, in
in the
Naples, 1926.
Michael
Italicos.
Correspondence
in
Cramer anecdota graeca oxonensia,
III,
158-203. 1836.
Michael of Ephesus, Eustratius, and Sophonias. Commentaries on Aristotle, in
Berlin
the
Academy
Edition
of
his
works.
Vols.
XX, XXI, and
XXIII. Pletho.
Traite des Lois. Translated
by A.
Pellissier.
Theodore Metochites. Miscellanea philosophica ler.
et
Paris,
historica.
1958.
Edited by Miil-
Leipzig, 1821.
Studies Anastos,
M.
"Pletho's Calendar
and Liturgy," Dumbarton Oal^s Papers, IV
(1948), 183-305. Beck, H. Kirche und theologische Uteratur in byzantinischen Reich. Brehier, L.
La
1959.
civilisation Byzantine. Paris, 1950.
Macrobe a Cassiodore. 1948. M. Nicephore Blemmides comme pedagogue et comme in-
Courcelle, P. Les Lettres grecques en Occident de
Karapiperis,
stituteur. Jerusalem, 1921.
MeyendorfT, Jean. Introduction a I'etude de Gregoire Palamis. Paris, 1959. Russack, H. Un maitre de la spiritualite Byzantine: Nicholas Cabasilas. Paris, 1958. Salaville, S. "Philosophie et theologie,
ou episodes scolastiques
a
Byzance de
1059 a 1 1 17," Echos d'Orient (Paris), XXIX (1930), 132-56. Stephanou, E. ]ean Italos: Philosophe et humaniste. Rome, 1949. Tatakis, B.
La philosophie byzantine.
Vaccari, A.
Un commentaire
Paris, 1949.
byzantin des livres de Salomon. Congress on
Byzantine History. Algeria, 1939. Pp. 105 Un philosophe neoplatonicien du
Zervos, C.
1919. (Editions of Psellos are listed
on
ff.
XV
p. 35.)
siecle:
Michel
Psellos. Paris,
THE THIRTEENTH CENTURY WE
RECALL Augustc Comtc's
encomium
teenth century: the organic age par excellence in
was reaUzed.^
unity, true catholicity, in the
dreams of
all
such a distinct and important pecially favorable as
it
Paris,
and morals.
no other epoch during which
is
:
spiritual
who believe that society can never know common faith to direct thought and action
to serve as the basis for philosophy, art,
Surely there
which
the century that figures
those
peace in the absence of a
and
It is
to the thir-
role.
spiritual life
Circumstances then were
the rebirth of powerful commercial
cities
had es-
favored,
always has, the active exchange of ideas; the University of
which played such an important
of the thirteenth century,
would have been inconceivable without
the Paris of Philip Augustus
the most powerful in
nation; nor
—capital of a realm that was becoming
Europe and
was there any all
countries
Hales, ItaUans such as
Germans such
as
St.
attracting foreigners
from every
trace of national exclusivism in the in-
struction, given in the liturgical
by masters from
role in the intellectual life
language of Christianity and given
—Englishmen
such as Alexander of
Bonaventure and
Albert the Great.
It
St.
Thomas Aquinas,
was the university
of the
whole of western Christianity, and the Pontiff of Christianity, the Vicar of Christ, tried by organizing it
the very center of Christian hfe.
it
and giving
The same
it
statutes to
pope. Innocent
make
III, cre-
ated the Inquisition, confirmed the mendicant orders (Franciscans ^
Systeme de politique positive, ed. Cres (191 2),
113
III,
488.
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
114
and Dominicans), and gave three acts inspired by the
statutes to the University of Paris:
same
spirit,
by the desire
heresies; in the
any temporal
of expurging
men who,
mendicant orders he found
interests or
to strengthen
means
Christian unity. In the Inquisition he found a
freed
from
attachment to their native countries, put
themselves into the exclusive service of Christian thought; and in the University, which under the law,
and
flourishing,
scattered schools that
he found a means of systematizing
all
the
epoch through the teaching of theology.
intellectual Hfe of the
Only the pope had control over he merely asked Philip Augustus
aim was
of faculty of arts, faculty of
drew together
faculty of theology,
were already
names
instruction at the university;
temporal privileges. His
to grant
way
to organize instruction in such a
as to protect theology
against the danger posed by the excessive development of dialectic. Dialectic
must remain an organon, and the "modern doctors of the
liberal arts"
This
is
must be prevented from taking up
what was
Gregory IX in 1228: "Theological wisdom
on each faculty path so that
it
mind on
as the
will not err."
the flesh,
And
.
theological subjects.
1219 and repeated by
said by Innocent III in .
and
.
must
direct
exert
it
its
power
into the right
theology must be explained solely
"according to the traditions tested by the saints," and not through the use of "carnal arms."
phy."
An
order issued in 1231 states that "Mas-
Theology must not make an ostentatious display of philoso-
ters of
Under such
art of discussing
conditions philosophy
is,
and drawing conclusions,
in fact, reduced to the
starting
from premises
Hence the literary form of writings derived from the method used by Abelard in his
established by divine authority.
of the period,
Sic et non, then by the sententiaries of the twelfth century. State-
ments of authority or reasons deduced from authority are advanced for each topic; after the pros
tion
is
given. In this
way
and cons have been
indicated, the solu-
the theologian ignores or avoids any
comprehensive exposition, any synthetic view which, by systematically linking his affirmations,
pear too rational.
A
would make
certain order
is
the Christian doctrine ap-
of course inherent in the ex-
I
I
I
THE THIRTEENTH CENTURY
115
God, the
position of the truths of the Christian doctrine:
the
redemption, and salvation. That
fall,
creation,
the traditional order, the
is
Lombard followed, the order that Thomas Aquinas' Summae. But we must note that it
underlies St.
order that Peter
is
an order of
revealed truths in which each truth depends logically on the one fall,
redemption, are free acts that can be
their effects
but not deduced from necessary prin-
that precedes: creation,
known through ciples. it
Each
article of faith
and each of the affirmations implied by
must therefore be studied
separately.
Reason
is
examining consequences, but not in going back
making
always useful in
to principles or in
syntheses.
But within
its
fixed, rigid frame,
did thirteenth-century thought
have the catholicity that the popes dreamed of imposing on at
all,
it ?
Not
and notwithstanding the wishes of the popes, the thirteenth
century offers the spectacle of sharp conflicts that to speak of a single scholastic philosophy conflicts,
which did not abate
until the
make
even in
impossible
it
The
this period.
Middle Ages had come
an end, stemmed from the attempt to reduce
all
to
higher intellectual
training to theology and to the discipHnes that contribute to theology.
A
need was
knew where ficult it
it
felt for
Then
it
rational!
to maintain the unity of a doctrine that
em-
be a part of theology ?
as divergent as the authoritarian
should philosophy be expelled from theology?
would become independent. In
unity that
men were
philosophy, but no one dif-
it
two methods
Or
human
How
belonged. Should
would be then
ploys simultaneously
and the
a purely
either case, the spiritual
seeking to establish would be broken.
It
would
be broken because they thought, for reasons that were essentially political
and
autonomy
when
of
religious, that
human
it
was not necessary
to
reckon with the
reason. Spiritual unity can be restored only
the attempt to subordinate
all
studies to theology
is
aban-
doned.
The
history of philosophy in the thirteenth century
of such conflicts. It contains intellectual
freedom, the
no
fiery
is
the history
trace of the anticipated rebirth, the
thought that
we found
in the twelfth
Il6
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
century.
the history o£ a quest for unity at any price
It is
at the price of logic and coherence
were
I
social
The
and
intellectual.
Workj
Diffusion of Aristotle's
stemming from attempts
Conflicts
theology were accentuated
came
than
political rather
when
West
in the
to subordinate philosophy to
the complete works of Aristotle be-
accessible to scholars through translations into Latin
Arabic or Greek. These translations opened a virgin
and
—even
a unity desired for reasons that
:
them with
for the first time provided
from
field to scholars
knowledge of
direct
pagan thought uncontaminated by Christian thought. After the middle of the twelfth century a college of translators
working under the
direction of
Ramon, Bishop
Toledo (1126-
of
1151), began translating from Arabic the Posterior Analytics, with the commentary by Themistius, the Topics, and On Sophistical
Refutations. Gerard of
Cremona
teorology, the Physics,
and the
(died in 11 87) translated the treatises
On
Me-
Heavens and On
the
Generation and Corruption, not to mention the apocryphal works, the Theology
and the
treatises
Properties of the Elements.
On
Causes and
Then knowledge
On
the Causes of the
Greek spread.
of
We
find in the twelfth-century manuscripts a translation of the Meta-
M and N which had
physics (except for books lated in 1270),
and even
a
commentary on
still
not been trans-
the work.
And William
the Clerk, in his chronicle of the year 1210, says that the Metaphysics, "recently brought back
from Greek
WiUiam
of
to Latin,"
from Constantinople and
was being read
Moerbeke (1215-1286),
in Paris.
Henry
a friend of St.
translated
of Brabant,
Thomas Aquinas,
Robert Grosseteste, and Bartholomew of Messina were thirteenthcentury Hellenists Aristotle,
who
translated
and notably the
Politics,
all
or a part of the
works
of
which had been ignored by the
Arab philosophers. Translations were also made of the works of Arab and even Greek commentators and of the Jewish philosophers. Alkindi, Alfarabi, Avicenna, and Avicebron were known, and by the middle of
THE THIRTEENTH CENTURY
117
the thirteenth century
all
the commentaries of Averroes except the
one on the Organon could be found in
The
Paris.
starthng impression of such discoveries on minds avid for
bookish instruction but unprepared for their task
is
not hard to
imagine. Readers were poorly prepared to understand and evaluate Aristotle because they lacked the historical perspective necessary to
assign
him
his place; because they
had
access to
common
translations which, in accordance with the era,
were
slavishly literal
him only through practice of the
and often incomprehensible; and
finally
because they did not have, to combat the magic spell of his philosophy, any opposing doctrine from which they could or
draw
support,
—most important—any method to rival the solid Aristotelian con-
struction.
The
only works of Plato that had been translated in the
thirteenth century
were the Phaedo and the Meno; in the second
half of the century Sextus Empiricus' Outlines of
came known; but none Peripateticism,
Pyrrhonism be-
of this could counterbalance Peripateticism.
which drew strength from the weakness of other
doctrines, fell far short of
meeting the demands of the theologians.
Philosophy, always the servant of theology, was supposed to be utilized as a preliminary to provide a
method
of things. But of physics
and auxiliary
of discussion
discipline. It
and not
what the theologians found
was supposed
a statement of the nature in Aristotle
was a system
and theology that suggested an image of the universe
completely incompatible with the one implied by the Christian doctrine and even by the Christian a
god who
stars
is
life:
an eternal, uncreated world;
simply the prime mover of the heaven of the fixed
and whose providence and even knowledge do not extend
things in the sublunary world; a soul which
form
to
of
an
organized body and which must be born and disappear with
it,
which consequently has no supernatural fore cancels the importance of the
redemption, eternal implicitly denied
it.
life:
Aristotle
the simple
destiny,
and which
it
there-
of salvation. Creation,
knew nothing
of
all
this
Here was something more than an
Platonism which, though it
drama
is
fall,
and
eclectic
probably posed a certain danger since
led to the erroneous solutions of Erigena
and Abelard, could
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
Il8
dogma, thanks
nevertheless be reconciled with
and
Dionysius the Areopagite, and which
to
to
St.
Augustine
in addition
showed
concern over the divine reality and the supernatural Ufe of the soul. Aristotelianism refused to take
importance
We totle's
to
must
up such problems or
to attach
them.
body of doctrine represented by Aris-
also note that the
physics, diametrically
opposed
to
Christian theology, con-
trasted just as sharply with the only experimental science
name during
the
any
the Middle
Ages
worthy of
—astronomy. The accurate knowl-
edge available of the variation of the distances of planets with respect to the earth during the course of
should have
made
one of
their revolutions
impossible the formulation of a theory of the
heavens that assigned each planet to a sphere that had the earth as its
center
—a
theory that
fell
back on the doctrine of Ptolemy (the
Almagest had been translated by Gerard of Cremona Pythagorean doctrine of the motion of the earth, high Middle Ages.
The
fact that
it
did not at this
stop the progress of Aristotelianism, but
portant reasons for
its
it
in 1175) or the
known since moment did
the
not
was one of the most im-
decline later on, once the correct theory
had
triumphed.
What
mattered
at this
moment was
that Aristotelianism, far
from
serving the academic poHtics of the popes, threatened to stand as an
insurmountable obstacle. Albert the Great himself denounced the influence of Aristotle's physics
on the heterodox ideas of David
of
Dinant. Similarly, in 1211 the Council of Paris prohibited the teaching of Aristotle's physics, and the statutes brought to the University of Paris in 12 15 by Robert of Cour^on, the papal legate, provided that Aristotle's
works on
logic
and
ethics
hibited the reading of the Metaphysics
The
interdiction
infatuation,
was probably
might be taught but pro-
and the Natural Philosophy.
ineffectual in the face of the public's
and Gregory IX stipulated
that all editions of Aristotle's
works should be expurgated of any statement contrary is
nevertheless true that the Physics
to
dogma.
and the Metaphysics were
It
in-
cluded in the curriculum of the faculty of arts in 1255, that from this
moment on
the authorities
condemned, not
Aristotle, but those
I
THE THIRTEENTH CENTURY
119
who drew from
books doctrines contrary
his
Aristotle gradually
became an indisputable
to
orthodoxy, and that
We
authority.
turn
now
to the history of the Christianization of Aristotle.
Dominicus Gundissalinus
II
The philosophy was
Platonists
of Aristotle
first
and of the Arab or Jewish Neo-
given currency by compilers like Dominicus
Gundissalinus (died in 1151), Archdeacon of Segovia, tion to his translations wrote
sophiae, tears
down
replaces
works such
it
De
as the
modeled on Alfarabi and on Isaac
who
in addi-
divisione philo-
Israeli's Definitions,
the traditional order of the trivium and quadrivium
He and
with the Aristotelian encyclopedia physics, which studies :
mobile and material beings; mathematics, which studies the same beings abstracted from their matter and motion;
which
studies
immobile beings such
as
God and
provides a basis for the study of philosophy.
studying
for
Physics,
and
On
for metaphysics, the
On
the angels. Logic
gives Alfarabi's plan
on physics and metaphysics:
writings
Aristotle's
the Heavens,
He
and theology,
Animals, and,
works that study
finally.
On
the Soul;
in succession essence
and
accident, the principles of demonstration, incorporeal essences, their
hierarchical arrangement,
completely
new
and divine
in the West,
and
action.
it is
The
theology as the study of the immovable mover physics, the study of
the soul as the
universe
is
plan
something
is
important to note that in is
it
closely linked to
movable bodies, which embraces the study of
form of the organic body. The new image of the
antithetical to the Platonic
and Augustinian image that
considered the peculiar and wholly supernatural
life
of
God and
the soul.
The same in
inspiration characterizes the
which Dominicus
criticizes
proof of the immortality of the
and would
and
De
immortalitate animae,
explicitly rejects
human
soul because
also apply to the souls of brutes.
He
the Platonic
it is
too general
accepts only proof
grounded on Aristotelian premises that contain not general principles
but characteristics peculiar to the subject under study. But
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
120 his
main proof
we know,
as
is,
from the body, which ity,
the independence of the intellect
an impersonal immortal-
entails the concept of
something quite different from the continuation of the individ-
ual destiny of the soul.
William of Auvergne
Ill
William of Auvergne, who taught theology produced
typifies the uneasiness
introduction of these
One
new
between the
created by the
first
Paris
1228,
Augustinian by the
principle
make
to
We
a dis-
and the beings derived from or
principle, without getting outside the
when we
in
ideas.
first
of Aristotle's philosophy.
undertaking
in
Arab philosophers had been
of the aims of the
tinction
in a traditional
framework
was indeed
see that theirs
a difficult
the nature of his metaphysics: his
recall
on moving bodies and movers led him to unmoved movers, moving intelligences of
mul-
speculations
posit a
tiplicity of
the heavens,
and
whose dependence on
souls of animals,
not clearly seen.
monotheism of recall
how
intrinsic
It
all
was hard
to reconcile
the religions that
a
unique principle was
his
teaching with the
had issued from Judaism.
We
Alfarabi, then Avicenna, resolved the issue: through an
characteristic,
necessity,
the supreme principle
guished from the movers derived from in itself all that
it is; it is
The
it.
distin-
is
necessary being has
simple and unique. Derived movers, how-
ever, are potential beings, possible in themselves, that exist only
under the influence of the necessary being
who makes them
pass to
act.
Aristotle could
were added
become a monotheist only
to his doctrine.
liam of Auvergne, ing
and
it
who
to Boethius. It
"God
existence:
(esse). In other
when we
say
words,
'He
on the contrary,
is'
fitted
is is
The
if some such distinction was introduced by Wil-
into the scholastic tradition
by link-
the celebrated distinction between essence
the being (ens)
God and
are one
results
it
distinction
whose essence
the being that
we
it
is
to be
attribute to
him
and the same thing." Created being,
from the union of two things that which :
is
THE THIRTEENTH CENTURY
121
{quod
est), or its essence,
and
that through
from the essence
necessity distinct
which
it is
{quo
est), of
by
since the latter cannot exist
itself.
But the distinction between essence and existence which was
method
predicated on the
of Avicenna,
and which helped
monotheism, introduced a new danger. For
lish
supreme principle
must
is
to
make
actual, they
becoming
actual. Po-
then something independent of the supreme being. Only
tentiality is
in this
the role of the
become
potential beings
exist as potential beings prior to their
if
to estab-
way could Avicenna
explain multiplicity in created beings.
WiUiam held that potentiality was not from God but only the power that God has to
In contrast to Avicenna,
something
distinct
give being to things.^
To
this faint difference in interpretation is
the Peripatetics,
who
linked his criticism of
advocated the theory of the eternity of the
world, basing their argument on the principle
we have
so often en-
countered: an immutable essence cannot begin to produce at a certain
moment. William answered
that there could then be
change in the world that was not reduced that
is,
new.
no
We
on the plicity
true change since change
is
to
what preceded
the production of something
see that the Peripatetics, basing the eternity of the
simplicity of the
first
no it
world
principle, could not explain multi-
and change other than through an independent matter, and
the negation of this matter entailed either a denial of the existence of change or the attribution to
quite different
The same of
from
Aristotle's
spirit is at the
knowledge
God pure
of a creative
power
—something
act.
heart of his criticism of the
Arab
theories
that introduced into the soul itself the opposition of
matter and form by showing that the potential intellect becomes actual
under the influence of an
intellect that
is
always active. William
not only refused to accept the separate agent intellect that Avicenna
(and according
to
him, Aristotle) placed in the sphere of the moon,
but also refuted an anonymous theory of the Christian Peripatetics.
According ^
Cf.
to their theory,
Roland -Gosselin,
both the agent
in his edition of St.
intellect
Thomas' De ente
and the material
et essentia, p.
164.
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
122
agent intellect makes the
intellect are a faculty of the soul itself; the
intelligible signs that exist potentially in the material intellect be-
come
actual.
edge which
To is
the soul the Christian Peripatetics attributed knowl-
always actual and which, Uke Platonic reminiscence,
would make any but one
there evolve, as
which he
and images, the
pregnant. There
is
to the soul
From
called the material intellect.
from the seeds of mature beings, and under the
fluence of sensations it
William attributed
instruction useless.
intellect,
is
intelligible
it
in-
forms with which
an appreciable discrepancy between
this
theory and the theory that reduces intelligence to an abstractive faculty.
According
knowledge of
William, abstraction
to
forms;
intelligible
and from the weakness of our knowledge
tellectual
is
the
opinions, of one's doubts,
it
results
is
from our imperfection
spiritual sight.
knowledge of
one's
and therefore of
not inherent in the
The exemplar self,
that
is,
of in-
of one's
a particular being.
Dominicans and Franciscans
IV
More
positive attitudes than those of
gendered
WiUiam
of
Auvergne
en-
and Ox-
conflicts that disturbed the universities of Paris
ford throughout the second half of the thirteenth century.
Toward
end of the century (1284), just as these disturbances were abating, the Franciscan John Peckham, Archbishop of Canterbury, the
wrote the
Roman
Curia: "Let the Holy Church deign to consider
that the doctrines of the
two orders (the Franciscan and the Domini-
can) are almost diametrically opposed to each other on every ques-
open
tion
to discussion; the doctrine of
one of the orders, neglect-
ing and to a certain degree scorning the teaching of the Fathers,
is
based almost exclusively on the teachings of the philosophers."^
And
he was more
Lincoln: in
specific in a letter written in 1285 to the
"You know
any way so long
but
we condemn
cal truth
that
we do
not
condemn
Bishop of
philosophical studies
as they are appropriate to theological
dogmas;
the profane innovations that contradict philosophi-
and the writings of the Fathers— those
•Quoted by Gilson, ttudes de philosophic medievale,
p. 120.
that struck at the
THIRTEENTH CENTURY
"T^^
123
very roots of theology right rejection
some twenty
and derision
years ago
and resulted
of the doctrine of the Fathers.
has a firmer, sounder basis: the doctrine of the sons of
—that and
kind whose works ... are based on both the Fathers
and the philosophers to
it
—or
new
the
doctrine which
which devotes
in almost every way,
and denying everything
stroying
Which Francis
of Brother Alexander of Hales, of Brother Bonaventure
is,
their
posed
St.
in out-
its
directly op-
is
energies to de-
Augustine teaches con-
that St.
cerning the eternal rules of the immutable light, the powers of the soul, the
seminal reasons inherent in matter?"
Here two viewpoints
clash
:
that of the Franciscan, nurtured by St.
Augustine and represented by Bonaventure, and that of the Dominican, descended
and
St.
from
Aristotle
and represented by Albert the Great
Thomas Aquinas. The
which there was no theology and
tried,
Franciscan embraced a doctrine in
between philosophy and
clearcut distinction
following the Neo-Platonic model, to attain to
the divine reality, or at least to an
image of the divine
reality.
The
Dominican, on the other hand, made a sharp distinction between revealed theology and philosophy,
which
and independent from theology
since
is
completely autonomous starts
it
from
sensible ex-
perience and employs a purely rational method. It
is
not enough, however, summarily to contrast Franciscan
Augustinianism with Dominican Peripateticism. In the St.
Bonaventure does not hesitate
to
first place,
follow Aristotle on
many
points. In the second place, in the very midst of their order, Albert
Thomas found many adversaries. It was a Dominican, Robert Kilwardby, who as Archbishop of Canterbury had Thomistic propositions condemned in 1277. In the third place, St. Thomas and
St.
was no
less
opposed than
St.
Bonaventure
to a certain
manner
of
interpreting Peripateticism that led to conclusions directly opposed to the Christian faith,
namely the interpretation of Siger of Brabant
and the movement referred
to as
Latin Averroism. Finally, the two
orders were in agreement on one practical point: the popes were
planning to intrust
to these orders, rather
theological instruction
at
than to the secular clergy,
the University of Paris. Beginning in
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
124
1229, a chair
was reserved
two mendicant
for each of the
orders,
with the result that they became engaged in a violent polemic with the secular clergy.
temponim monks'
Dei V
It is reflected
right to teach,
in the
De
which WilHam of
(1255), in
and
Thomas'
in St.
periculis
novissimorum
Amour
St.
reply,
contests the
Contra impugnantes
cult imj.
Bo?iaventure
St,
Bonaventure was opposed
St.
both orders: "The
to the spirit of
Preachers (the Dominicans) indulge mainly in speculation, which accounts for their name, and then in unctuousness; the Minors (the
Franciscans) indulge St.
first
and then
in unctuousness
in speculation."
Francis of Assisi, the founder of the Minors, had given a
impetus
to spiritual life rather
recommended study before teaching." the spiritualists,
"*
than
to the brothers
to
Church
doctrine,
new
and he
only on condition that they "act
There was among the Franciscans one group,
who
looked with contempt on any doctrinal instruc-
were partisans of Joachim of Fiore, whose thoughts on
tion; they
the eternal Gospel were related to heresies involving the rule of the Spirit.
His views were accepted by the general of the order, John
of Parma,
who had
demned by than
St.
to resign his position in 1257
a tribunal presided over by the
new
and who was con-
general,
none other
Bonaventure.
Now we
have a better understanding of the problem faced by
doctrinaire Franciscans
and theologians:
to reconcile doctrinal
and
rational instruction with the Franciscan concept of free spirituality,
or rather to
make
the doctrine an inseparable element in the
illumination that constitutes the spiritual trinaire Franciscans before the
Hales
(1
170-1245),
Summa, modeled on
*
St.
of
There had been doc-
time of Bonaventure: Alexander of
Master of Theology in Paris, the
who
in
his
Lombard's Sentences, revealed his knowl-
edge of Aristotle but remained faithful
and John
life.
inward
to the
Augustinian tradition;
La Rochelle (Johannes de Rupello,
1200-1245). Both
Bonaventure In hexameron 22. 21; quoted by Gilson, Saint Bonaventure,
p. 3.
THIRTEENTH CENTURY
T^^^
125
them knew and
of
sphere of natural
accepted, for the limited
knowledge, the Aristotelian doctrine of knowledge:
it
through
is
the influence of an agent intellect that the potential intellect can abstract intelligible
we
forms from sensory images; but when
are
dealing with objects that transcend man's aptitude, knowledge be-
comes illuminative and has Giovanni ture, the
di
as its
and became general of is
who
as
Bonaven-
taught in Paris from 1248 to 1255
his order at the age of thirty-six, this spirit.
The
the most
is
teaching of St. Bona-
God,
essentially the journey of the soul to
a
works {Itinerarium mentis
he ascribed to one of his last
He
himself.
Fidanza of Tuscany (1221-1274), known
"Seraphic Doctor"
remarkable representative of venture
God
agent
title
in
which
Deum).
wrote during a period in which the Dominicans were producing
many
purely philosophical works, but
such a work in the
list
of his
own
we would
search in vain for
writings: a vast
Peter Lombard's Sentences and a great
number
commentary on
of shorter
works on
purely theological or mystical subjects. But in his journey he finds reason and philosophy, and he assimilates whatever they have to contribute to the higher spiritual
Assigned
to
its
life.
God,
place in the search that leads us to
philo-
turned
sophical reason has significance only to the degree that
it is
toward God.
lower stage
indicates a transitional step
It
between
where we have but scant knowledge of God and where we have greater knowledge of him. through which
we
contemplation.
"We
pass in going start
It is
from the
from
higher stage
one of the moments
state of
of
stability
a a
simple belief to
faith
and progress
through the serenity of reason before reaching the sweetness of contemplation."
^ St.
Bonaventure adheres
Neo-Platonic philosophy: reason
and an rectly;
of
is
intellectual intuition that it is
not
autonomous
self-sufficient
sciences.
closely to the tradition of
an intermediary between belief
apprehends the
and provides no
Reason no
less
than
first
principle di-
rules for the creation
faith,
on one hand, and
contemplation on the other, issue from sanctifying grace, which manifested
first
is
through the virtue of faith {credere)^ then through
^Quoted by Gilson,
p. 115.
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
126
the gift of understanding that
and
Here we have
.
believed {intelligere credita),
is
through the beatitude of contemplation {videre
finally
lecta)
which
Plato's
The
outlined at the end of the sixth book in the Republic.
tone superimposed on It
changes none of
it
intel-
scheme of the degrees of knowledge
as
pious
basic elements.
its
follows that philosophy, according to Bonaventure, should not
be the fruit of curiosity that seeks to arrive at the essence of reaUty,
but of a religious inclination that leads us toward God. "Creatures
can be considered equally well either as things or as signs,"
Bonaventure considers them
shadows of the nature of God. The
most technical questions that he disputes with
solutions to the
Thomas
In everything he searches
signs.
as
for expressions, images, vestiges,
and
^
sider nature, along with the Bible, as a
book whose divine meaning
must be deciphered. The three unique themes God, the Creation, the return of the soul
and illumination
—or
God
and God
as the
St.
symbolism that makes him con-
are provided by the vast
to
God
of philosophy are
through knowledge
exemplary cause,
The
God
as the ef-
God
is
an
obvious fact: obvious to the soul which through knowledge of
it-
ficient cause,
self
recognizes
as the final cause.
image of God, and which through knowl-
the
itself as
existence of
edge of imperfect, composite, mutable things apprehends the perfect, simple,
immutable being that causes them
emplary cause
blance. as the
and
Word
the
world of Ideas
or the Son.
It is
is
and
his first resem-
not a creature but
therefore one
appears multiple only to the degree that
it
and
God
then because
it is
world. Here
we
first
because
it is
indivisible,
not inferior to
not an intermediary between
find nothing that resembles a
creation of the world.
Nor is we
the world of Plato: here Quoted by Gilson,
p. 209.
it
himself
and
it
gives birth to a finite
multiplicity of sense objects. Bonaventure's intelligible
the world of Plotinus,
*
as the ex-
asserts the existence of Platonic ideas in
finds his true, complete expression
Thus
God
the object of the study of metaphysics. Bonaventure
is
contradicts Aristotle
which God
to exist.
God and first,
fill
is
not
source,
and
the sensible
wholly spiritual
in this sense related in
find nothing to
world
its
any way
to
the infinite gulf
"^"^
127
THIRTEENTH CENTURY from
creature
that separates
impede the return o£ the soul
That
why God
is
from God
ent
unity of the
God.
as the efficient or creative cause
as the
Word,
worlds, the will of
creator and, conversely, nothing to
to
exemplary cause.
model
the
God
From
for an infinite
must be
differ-
within the infinite
number
of possible
chooses one world, and the reasons for his
choice are wholly inscrutable. Bonaventure, in effect, refuses to
concede that the principle of the best possible world can force such a notion
to create the best one:
which world
Through
is
senseless, for
God
no matter
chosen, one can always conceive of a better one.
is
which became more prominent
his "voluntarism,"
in the
Franciscan schools, Bonaventure was even more explicitly opposed
any attempt
to
to establish a continuity
between
God and
created
beings.
Consequently,
all
must evidence both God's im-
created beings
mediate activity and their separation from him or at least contrasting, requirements.
hension of the divine irradiation in
all
The
—two
first
contradictory,
entails
the appre-
created things, the second the
proclamation of their deficiency: deficiency, for the multiplicity of created beings
fusion
of
deficiency, since
of
incapable of receiving the communication and
is
divine
it is
than
other
perfection
necessary for
form and matter, the matter
all
ef-
through multiplication;
created beings to be
composed
stressing the passive side of their
being. Bonaventure did not hesitate to state, along with the other
Franciscans and against creation
and
also
and
St.
Thomas,
that angels themselves,
human
souls,
which
union of form and matter.
that
no pure form existed in
which
are separate intelligences,
are spiritual beings, result
We
need only
know
from the
that a being
is
mutable, active and passive, individual and capable of belonging to a species or genus, in order to say that tential
souls
it
contains matter
—that
being or the possibility of being different. This
and even of angels; contrary
to the belief of St.
is
is,
po-
true of
Thomas, they
are truly individuals. Bonaventure's awareness of the deficiency of
created beings St.
Thomas,
is
also responsible for his acceptance, in opposition to
of the thesis of the plurality of forms. In Aristotle's
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
128
thinking, the
come what the a
form of a
it is;
a being
man
a
is
is
man
that
it
actually to be-
by virtue of the presence in him of
form humanity; each substance, being one, must therefore have
unique substantial form, and
form
this
solutely the nature of the substance.
mating the being added
to
would be
it
and complete; stance,
it is
prepare
in such a to
in reality,
however,
ab-
as
completing and consum-
that nothing substantial can be
make
if
it
form gives perfection
to a sub-
something definite but in order
another degree of perfection which
to receive
be incapable of giving to
body
and determines
concede that created beings can be perfect
not in order to
it
way
defines
Bonaventure does not accept
form
Aristotle's conclusion: to consider
to
which causes
itself.
it
would
For example, sunlight added
to a
that has already reached a certain state of perfection stimulates
activity in
it,
making
a
it
new
substantial form.
The same
spirit is
manifested in his reply to the question of the production of form.
We
one of
recall
become an
Aristotle's
famous theorems: a potential being can
actual being only under the influence of a being that
already actual. His theorem implies that the ated in potential being
is
form
that
is
is
to be cre-
not something already present but some-
thing that evolves under the influence of an actual being (eduction of forms). But such a theory
which limits
it
if
would give
to actual
being an
cannot possess and which will be reduced to
one admits with
der the influence of actual being. link between
the Franciscan thinker
and
all
St.
these theses
and developed un-
—on
several of
Thomas hold opposing
then obvious: multiplicity, hylomorphic composition of plurality of forms,
and seminal reasons are
an autonomous physical world that has in planation.
The
proper
Augustine that potential being con-
St.
tains the seminal reasons that will be manifested
The common
its
efficacy
theses are in perfect
all
which
views all
—
is
things,
methods of negating
itself its
harmony with
principle of ex-
the second re-
quirement, according to which created beings must reveal traces of divine irradiation: through simple analogy, such as the equality of
two
ratios,
resemblance of
and not through true resemblance such
God and
Ideas.
The exemplar
as
the
of this simple analogy
THE THIRTEENTH CENTURY
129 is
image of the Trinity
the
tions
between the three
that St.
different degrees in this analogy, vestiges of divine
which
found
is
attributes
human
soul.
in the rela-
But there are
and these range from shadows or
visible
human
in the
Augustine identified
faculties of the
soul
nature to the true image
in
and which perceives
directly
its
resemblance to God. Through the influence of supernatural grace,
image
the analogical
which
likeness,
will be transformed in the elect into a true
the deification of the soul.
much
not so
It is
is
in itself as in relation to this final state that
Bonaventure analyzes
made
contributions
He
losophers.
and the
in this sphere by Aristotle
and the Arab phi-
accepts the distinction between the agent intellect
possible intellect, but
Thomas, he
knowledge and evaluates the
intellectual
first
Alexander of Hales and
like
makes each of them
a faculty of the soul
fuses to accept the agent intellect as a reality distinct
and
from the
St.
relast
of the celestial intelligences. In his thinking, the negation of the separate agent intellect
is
rules out the positing of soul.
and pure
is
God and
intellect
the
and the
not the same as the relation between pure ac-
passivity; the agent intellect
sible intellect to carry
extracts intelligible
it
any intermediary between
Furthermore, the relation between the agent
possible intellect tivity
another consequence of the principle that
merely helps the pos-
out the operation of abstraction through which
forms from the images of the imagination;
but the possible intellect actually performs the operation and provides the agent intellect with Finally, abstraction tellectual
from
knowledge.
the
species
sensible things
Aristotle's
edge of the sensible world;
is
that
it
contemplates.^
not the only type of in-
empiricism applies only
when we
to
knowl-
are dealing with principles,
with moral virtues, and with God, our method of acquiring knowl-
edge
is
wholly different.
knowledge
Many
sensible species are
the "natural light" within us allows us to acquire
and without recourse
them '
is
needed
to provide
of principles, such as the principle of contradiction, but
due
to
Gilson, p. 354.
no
to reason.
As
for
moral
them immediately
virtues,
knowledge of
sensible species but to our inwardly felt inclina-
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
130
toward the good and
tion
incHnation
is
we
reflection, since
name
are
of self-knowledge
sumes
to the
immediate knowledge that our
we know God through
right. Finally,
made
simple
and knowledge of God,
St.
Bonaventure
knowledge that does not pass through the
direct
self-
under the
in his image. In a word,
as-
circuit of
sensible things.
Any
attempt to justify such knowledge and to ascertain
Bonaventure
mind
attains to being
attain to being
and reasons
we
that
from the old Platonic principle (revived by
starts
according to which there
Avicenna)
is
—that
apply to
knowledge and
St.
But
which do not
realities
is
certain
we do
positively
Thus
not possess.
defined not in
knowledge
itself,
that
to
or to see the eternal ideas like a
is
and
framework
neatly into
fit
the
and
it
entirely; but
it
by virtue of the presence and influence in us of these
nal reasons which
full
God
God. The idea of being
which therefore cannot be known exist only
of
knowledge only where
is
to a stable, identical reality.
is,
not precisely to see
that are in
try to
basis
its
everything to divine illumination. Here
results in the reduction of
can
eter-
most humble form
but as a blurred image of the
God
possesses in his
own
right.
Bonaventure's philosophy therefore represents a trend of great
historical importance.
His thinking
is
dominated by what he con-
fundamental truth: the soul has a supernatural destiny
siders the
made known through the revelation of Christ. In searching for other truths, we cannot proceed as though we were ignorant of the fundamental truth and as though we had an independent method for determining truth
the
first
truth.
and falsehood. All truths
Nature and the soul reach an understanding only
when turned toward God: attributes,
are subordinate to
then nature stands as evidence of divine
and the soul unites us
to
God
through
its
essential func-
tion of love.
But
it
is
obvious that his guiding principle, though
it
was
ac-
cepted by Christian thinkers, had not the slightest influence on the history of Christian orthodoxy.
Here we recognize
the old
Neo-
Platonic principle, evolved in the absence of any Christian influence, that a being
is
fully
what
it is
only because
it
turns back toward
its
THE THIRTEENTH CENTURY
131
own
principle
in Paris
and
Matthew
successors,
and
receives
effluviums.
its
One
of Bonaventure's
of Aquasparta (i 235-1302), Master of
later general of the
order (1287), was to
show
Theology still
more
work the opposition of this doctrine to the AristotelianThomas. In his Quaestiones de cognitione he discusses
clearly in his
ism of
St.
who deny that divine illumination is indisknowledge and who attribute all knowledge to the
"certain philosophers"
pensable to
natural faculty of the agent intellect, repudiating in this
way
the
authority of the "Principal Doctor," St. Augustine. Conversely, he asserts that "all that
is
knowledge depends on truth."
We
find the
John Peckham
certainty through intellectual
eternal reasons
same fidehty
to
movement
at
The
Oxford.
and the
light of the first
Platonism in the Franciscan
(i 240-1 292), a pupil of
Master of Theology gustinian
known with
Bonaventure in Paris and a
strength of this Platonic-Au-
enables us to understand the conditions under
which the Aristotelian counter-movement took shape under the leadership of Albert the Great
and
St.
Thomas.
Albert the Great
VI
The
first
of the great Christian Peripatetics
was the Dominican
Albert the Great (i 206-1 280), called the "Universal Doctor." Master
from 1245
of Theology, he taught in Paris
from 1258
to 1260
and from 1270
1256 he wrote paraphrases of
even interpolated his
own
all
ideas
until his
the
to 1248,
and in Cologne
death. Between 1240 and
known works
of Aristotle
Aristotle's general plan but
which he had neglected (such
De De
to
mineralibus). causis
He
and
on questions which were a part of as the
even added a commentary on the apocryphal
(which he knew
be spurious and which he thought
David the Jew had extracted from the writings of Aristotle and Avicenna). He is also the author of treatises on dogmatic theology, such as his commentary on the Sentences and his aturis,
and
of mystical works, such as his
Dionysius or the
De
Summa
de
cre-
commentary on Pseudo-
adhaerendo Deo. Finally, he played an active
role as the defender of the
Dominicans against the
attacks of Wil-
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
132
Ham
Amour
of St.
crusade in
The
Germany
diversity
(1263).
and scope of
undertaking
his
drawing up an inventory of
of
pope and preacher of the
in 1256, as legate of the
encyclopedia and of contributing to
cealed
from him most of the time the lack
philosophy. Albert seems to have sensed
have made statements such
to
have explained
...
tics
as faithfully as I
books on
wills, in
and how
his
times he
is
—conown
and on such occasions
my philosophical my own opinions, but I
could the opinions of the Peripate-
my
own,
I
put
shall
it,
if
God
so
theology rather than in philosophical treatises."
not hard, therefore, to show
It is
treasures
as these: "In all of
have an opinion of
if I
these
of coherence in his
this,
have refrained from expressing
I
pleasurable task
the treasures contained in Aris-
all
totle's
books
—the
how
Augustinianism contradicts
^
Albert contradicts himself his Peripateticism.
content to juxtapose. For instance, in his
Some-
Summa
of
Theology,^ he warns that there are two concepts of the soul, the Aristotlelian concept of the soul as the
form
an organic body
of
and the theological concept based on the writings of on the one hand and voluntary ranged
tier
from
soul
tween
a description of the
life,
upon
tier
sensible
Aristotle's sensation,
is
thinks,
harmful.
faculties ar-
and showing the progressive elevation of the
knowledge
soul to the earth by
Augustine:
of the intellectual
and on the other the description of
to the things sensed,
what
mechanism
St.
an
to
God. There
act
common
and Augustine's
making
Nor
is
it
no
is
similarity be-
one sensing and
to the
sensuality,
which binds the
what
helpful and shun
seek after
is
there a parallel, in spite of
what Albert
between the Augustinian distinction of higher reason that
guides us and lower reason that makes us conscious of moral law,
and the Peripatetic tellect.
Finally, there
distinction of agent intellect is
a radical difference,
and possible
edges, between Aristotle's will (Trpoat'pecrt? or electio)
the
in-
which Albert acknowlwhich follows
judgment of the understanding, and the exclusively theological
notion of free will, "the faculty of reason and of will through which ®
Quoted by Schneider, Die Psychologic des Alberts, pp. 295
*Tr. 12 qu. 73.
ff.
THE THIRTEENTH CENTURY
133
we
choose good in the presence of grace and evil in
absence."
its
Aristotle offers nothing to correspond to synderesis, "the spark of
consciousness which, according to
Jerome, was not extinguished in
St.
Adam's
soul even though he was driven from Paradise," the faculty knowing the supreme moral rules "not mentioned by the
of
philosophers because they divide the faculties of the soul according to their general objects,
distinction
whereas theologians are able
human
between divine law and
who
the "saints,"
sensible world,
law."
consider the soul apart from
Thus its
make
to
a
the views of
relation to the
complement the views of the philosopher, who knows
the soul only in relation to the body. in
Still,
doctrine evidenced
other respects Albert's
propensities that were strikingly
current of Augustinianism.
The
new
level to
Anselm,
dominant
which philosophical reason-
ing could attain had dropped considerably. as in the case of St.
intellectual
in relation to the
The aim was no
longer,
to find rational explanations for re-
vealed dogmas, the Incarnation, or the Trinity. These were and re-
mained
the order of
we
pure and simple. Philosophical reasoning
articles of faith
can proceed only from
effects to causes,
knowledge
can attain to
God
is last
and
that
which
is
first
in
in the order of being. In other words,
only through the sensible world, through a
cosmological proof proceeding from effect to cause, and not through
an ontological proof. By contemplating the world we can probably infer the existence of tional certainty totle's
God, but we cannot even know with
ra-
whether the world had a beginning in time. Aris-
arguments favoring the eternity of the world are for the most
part ofTset by opposing arguments,
and only
revelation can decide
the issue.
Albert tended generally to separate the terms that Augustinian Platonists sought to unify
and build
into a hierarchy.
For
instance,
thirteenth-century Augustinians, under the direct or indirect influ-
ence of Avicebron, had attributed to as corporeal, a as bodies are
and
all
creatures, spiritual as well
hylomorphic composition: angels and souls
composed
in accordance
of matter
and form. Contrary
as well
to this
with Aristotle's theory of the moving
view
intelli-
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
134
gence which
is
and the soul which
a pure act
is
a form, Albert re-
fused to posit matter as a component of spiritual beings. His refusal
had the
effect of
transforming his vision of the universe. Since form
form of man)
(for example, the
the principle of individuation
source in the matter that
is
by
is
itself a universal,
and
since
in the accidents that have their
is
added
to form,
follows that the na-
it
man—composed of a soul and a body —no common with the nature of an angel. The an-
ture of an individual
longer has gels,
much
in
themselves as species, not as individuals.
same name
the
among
being pure forms, must for that very reason differ
the body, the
is
the
same
human
in angels
and
None of the faculties with in human souls. Bound to
soul attains to rationality only through an
operation of abstraction on sensible images, whereas the angel, with-
out
has impeccable intuitive knowledge.
toil,
intuitive in the case of the angel,
borrows from sensible images
is
all
in
man
The
agent
intellect,
a faint ray of light that
the distinctions of genera
and
species.^^
Thus wherever we
look, universal continuity seems to be
by deep cracks. Albert even refused
to
accept
all
marred
the elements
which, in the Arab Peripatetics' theory of intellectual knowledge,
would have brought man and God which Averroes posited
tellect,
closer together.
as the
tenth sphere, actually containing in
moving
itself all
common to all men, is replaced part of the human soul. There are
The
agent in-
intelligence in the
the intelligibles
consequently
by an agent
that
accordingly as
a
is
and
intellect
many
agent intellects as there are souls. Moreover, the agent intellect
is
devoid of forms and has no function other than that of abstracting
forms from sensible images that come from without.
If a
separate or
angelic intelligence influences us, the result of such an influence a revelation, It is
is
quite distinct
is
from natural knowledge.^^
understandable that under such conditions the study of na-
ture for ^^
which
its
Summa
own
sake interested Albert and that in his thinking the
de creaturis
tract vi (ed. 1651,
" Summa de homine qu. 53
art. 3.
XIX, 77-182).
THE THIRTEENTH CENTURY
135
sciences,
by virtue of the principle that "experiment alone provides
certainty in matters relating to zoology, botany, or mineralogy,"
were beginning
to
become something more than
fantastic bestiaries
or traditional systems of symbols.
We
know
of the
Cologne, but
Arab
the mystical
VII
St.
The
it
movement
that
was
was
popularized
much more
Stras-
doc-
critical
master and that he initiated
his
Thomas Aquinas was elaborated and system-
doctrine formulated by Albert
Thomas Aquinas
(1225-1274), the
at the castle of Roccasecca, of the
the Great in Paris to 1259
Albert's
to culminate in Meister Eckart.
Aquino, he became a Dominican in
From
and Ulrich of
seems that Ulrich was
Peripatetics than
atized by St.
Born
of Strasbourg
German Dominicans who
bourg, the trines in
Hugh
about
little
from 1245
1243.
"AngeHc Doctor."
family of the counts of
He
studied with Albert
then in Cologne.
to 1248,
From
1252
he was again in Paris, where he became Master in 1257.
1259 to 1268 he lived in Italy and
became acquainted with
William of Moerbeke, the Dominican Hellenist who provided him with translations of Aristotle
From self
made
directly
from the Greek
text.
1268 to 1272 he taught in Paris, where he had to defend him-
against the enemies of the regular clergy,
against Siger of
Brabant and the Averroists in the Faculty of Arts, and against the
who
Augustinians
tried to
have him condemned.
Naples in 1272 and died two years
He
left Paris for
while on his way to the
later
Council of Lyons.
During
his
second stay in Paris
treatises in addition to his
Lombard:
the
De
ente et essentia, the
impugnantes Dei cultum St.
Amour's
attacks
his stay in Italy
(1252-1259)
Commentary on
et religionem
De
he wrote three
the Sentences of Peter
veritate,
and the Contra
(at the time of
William of
on the orders). His commentaries date from
and
his association
with William of Moerbeke
(1259-1268): commentaries on Aristotle
— the
De
interpretatione,
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
136
the Posterior Analytics, the Physics, the Metaphysics (twelve books),
On
the Ethics,
the Soul, the Meteorology, the
generatione the Politics (i-iv) ,
(which he recognized
as
De
De
caelo (i-iii), the
commentary on
a
;
the
Boo\
of Causes
being identical to Proclus' Elements of
Theology, translated by William of Moerbeke)
;
and commentaries
on Boethius' theological works and the Areopagite's Divine Names.
Summa
In the same period he wrote the
and began the
1260)
Summa
theologica,
1265 to 1273 but never finished.
wrote polemical works the :
De
contra gentiles (1259-
which he worked on from
During
his last stay in Paris,
he
unitate intellectus contra Averroistas,
against Siger of Brabant; the
De
perfectione vitae spiritualis
and
the Contra retrahentes a religiosa ingressu, against the enemies of
and the
the mendicant orders;
De
aeternitate
mundi
contra mur-
murantes, against the enemies of Peritateticism. During different periods he edited his oral arguments on subjects proposed to
on
specific
him
occasions: the Quaestiones disputatae and the Quaes-
tiones quodlibetales.
In spite of the flawless and perhaps unmatched lucidity of his style,
own
the literary practices of St. that
exists
is
it
difficult to
and what
it
is.
In
Thomas
are so remote
determine whether
him we
no
find
a
from our
Thomistic system
trace of the
emotion and
mettle that gave birth in the eleventh and twelfth centuries to the synthetical
works
which there
in
is
philosophical thought. For instance, his
an uninterrupted flow of
Summa
ing but a series of questions separated into
theologica
articles.
is
Each
notharticle
presents the arguments against the thesis, the arguments for
it,
Only by way
of
and then the
rebuttal to the opposing arguments.
exception (for instance,
do we find
which
a
stress
theologica la pars, qu. 85, Art. 1-3)
pause or a comprehensive survey in the discussions in
his sole
aim
is
to defeat his adversary. Dialectic,
as the art of discussion,
more
Summa
had become an omnipotent sovereign, and
was placed on learning
their invention.
understood
to refute
arguments than on
VIII
THIRTEENTH CENTURY
"^^^
137
Thomas: Reason and Faith
St,
— no objection was raised against choppy, piecemeal expositions —the reason was that philosoIf
such conditions were prevalent
phers and theologians
felt that their
if
task
was not
one had already been made, and not
thesis, since
since truth
had already been found.
sumed two
great syntheses
make
a syn-
to discover truth,
Thomas' undertaking
St.
as-
which he accepted without change
own work:
the basis for his
to
as
the organization of religious truths
accomplished by the twelfth-century sententiaries, and the philo-
Summae,
sophical synthesis of Aristotle. In part of his works, in his
we
find the
rhythm
of
rhythm
contra gentiles
first
God
which has
philosophy:
for
its
instance,
source in the
Summa
the
God, then the hierarchy of created
discusses
from him, then the destiny
ings that proceed
turn to
of the Sentences,
Neo-Platonic
in the eternal
life.
of
man and
be-
his re-
In another part of his works, he
analyzes and annotates the works of Aristotle.
Furthermore, the relation that he
sees
between the two syntheses,
and the philosophical
the theological synthesis of revealed truths
synthesis of truths accessible to reason, brings quility
him
and contentment and makes him much
passionate for inquiry
Whereas they defined
manner
that
than
men
like
St.
to faith
zealous and
Anselm and Abelard.
the relation between reason
and
faith in a
might be termed dynamic, subjecting the truths of
faith to reason, as truths to be progressively
nated, St.
a sense of tranless
Thomas
defines
and which
it
statically: there are truths
definitely transcend
there are philosophical truths telligence, but there
is
and endlessly
which
human
which belong
intelligence,
are accessible to
human
no way of progressing from one order
other. If reason plays a part in matters of faith,
it is
ing consequences from truths belonging to faith
illumi-
we
in-
to the
merely by draw-
when
the latter
are posited as premises, never by demonstrating such truths.
example,
and
For
can demonstrate the necessity of divine grace by show-
ing that without
it
the supernatural destiny of
man would
be im-
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
138
must
possible, but the existence of supernatural destiny
vealed to us by It
is
purely
from
important to note that
intellect
mode
of
life
knowledge
human
its
stance cause."
is,
^^
in general, based
on
Aristotle
source in the sense organs; that
fall
it
"The
:
God
is
why
any-
under the senses cannot be apprehended
intelligence unless
sible things
does not borrow his
natural virtue, for our knowledge in our pres-
its
has
thing that does not
by
Thomas
St.
incapable of apprehending the substance of
is
himself through ent
re-
concept from the theological tradition but evolves
static
his doctrine of
human
be
first
faith.
it
inferred
is
from
the senses. Sen-
cannot enable our intelligence to see what divine sub-
for they are
Thus
efifects
Aristotle's
and do not equal the power of the
empiricism
sible things are
no longer,
hoisted
is
as
would probe
against the indiscretion of reason that
bulwark
a
mysteries. Sen-
Bonaventure, signs to be
as in the case of
interpreted in order to reveal the divine presence, but simple
through which
we
are able laboriously to deduce a cause
do not apprehend in
itself
but only in
its
relations to
efiFects
which we
its effects.
Finally, the very nature of his conception of the relations
between
reason and faith eliminated one of the most powerful forces acting
upon philosophical thought during contradictions between reason
tempt
to reconcile the two,
sophical discussion. St.
and
the preceding centuries:
which gave
faith,
rise to
and which therefore generated
Thomas
starts
truth cannot contradict another;
it
from
is
philo-
follows that no truth of faith
human
weak, since the intelligence of the greatest philosopher
just as inferior to the intelligence of ant's intelligence
tellectual truth
sure that the
is
inferior to his
seems
more penetrating
an angel
own,
it
intellectual truth
discussion will reveal
is
as the simplest peas-
when an infaith, we can be
follows that
to us to contradict a truth of
presumed
at-
the principle that one
could weaken a truth of reason, or vice versa. But since reason
the
an
is
but a fallacy and that a
its falsity.
Philosophy there-
fore remains the servant of faith, not because faith appeals to reason for clarification, not because the affirmations of faith are interwoven ^^
Sum ma
contra gentiles
i.
3.
THE THIRTEENTH CENTURY
139
arguments (for philosophy
in the fabric of rational
knowledge inates
is
trary to faith.
Such
tablish a reciprocal
tion
incapable of proving
it
No
reason,
and the same
power.
From
to es-
interpenetration or even fric-
possible in the purely external relation
is
any attempt
a hierarchy rules out a priori
arrangement.
would be con-
that
all
of
dom-
completely autonomous), but because theology
by declaring
it
mode
as a
will hold true for temporal
between
faith
power and
and
spiritual
above and from without, the spiritual power will
determine the conditions of the temporal power and the scope of
its
functions.
IX
Si.
We
Thomas: The Theory
of
Knowledge
must nevertheless understand
between the Thomistic
that
theory of the relation between reason and faith and the Thomistic theory of reality there
is,
perhaps not an opposition, but at
contrast that explains the development of the philosophy.
the
mode
of
knowing through reason and
through revelation there never cause us to
rise or
total
is
even aspire to
in being itself in reaUty there Platonists taught
there
is
and
as St.
rise to
through reason and the
Thomas
From
the
of
and the
aspects of reaUty provided revelation, or that
of the angels or of the beatific vi-
moment when knowledge, no
common
other words,
to
some
will
believed, with the result that
matter
how humble,
attains directly to being itself, to simple being, there
element
knowing first
the second. Inversely,
known through
reality
knowledge
mode
complete continuity, as the Neo-
no cleavage or gap between the
attained through the sion.
is
the
discontinuity,
least a
Between
must be an
both intellectual truths and truths of faith; in
truths (such as the existence of
God) must be
rationally demonstrable as well as revealed.
These
contrast between Aristotelian
conceives of
God
therefore relies
mon
We
recall the
and Neo-Platonic theology.
Aristotle
abstract considerations have a historical basis.
solely as the
on
prime mover of the sensible world; he
rational demonstration
principles of his physics
and the use of the com-
and metaphysics
in formulating his
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
140
He
concept of God.
God by
demonstrates the existence of
apply-
ing the guiding principle of his general concept of the world: the
Knowledge
priority of act over potency.
or pure act
God
of
knowledge
therefore just as rational as any physical
is
whatsoever. Neo-Platonic theology does not It
prime mover
as the
assumes a position in an
apprehend through
intelligible reality
and
special intuition,
it
from the
start
which
sensible.
pretends to
it
names
uses different
to
designate intuition, depending on the height attained in the divine
Thus
reality.
Aristotle conceived of
and
tional explanation of the universe,
accomplished by a mind that
God
as the capstone in his ra-
that
is
the
most
that can be
forced to start from sensible data.
is
It
can go no farther.
But the mind can go
that far because
knowledge,
The Thomistic
ready said, attains to being.
modes
possible
all
of
universal, embrac-
it is
knowledge and indicating the conditions from the other
of any type of knowledge; limits
and conditions peculiar
point
is
to
it is critical,
defining the
human knowledge. The
inspired by an Aristotelian formula
fully elaborated:
some way
asmuch which
is
"The
sensible things,
an
as perception,
soul
which act
is
in
it
some way
all
with
causis) is
in
to the perceiver
and
to that
the accidents that account for their in-
all
very thing that
it
apprehends: there
edge and the thing known.
knowledge or the
And
subject. It therefore
One must
is
is
beatific vision,
not, as
say only
is
no difference between knowl-
knowledge
known
is
a certain pres-
object in the
knowing
often erroneously stated, an assimila-
(and here we are adopting the second
viewpoint) that by virtue of the principle that "the
knowing
identical to the
is
whether we are dealing with sen-
ence, impossible to analyze, of the
in the
De
things." It
perceived, leaves in the soul the forms of things, without
their matter, but
tion.
view-
perceives through the senses in-
common
dividuality. Furthermore, the intelligence in act
sible
first
which Plotinus and
Proclus (in the Elements of Theology, identical to the
had
al-
theory of knowledge can
be studied from two points of view: from one
ing
we have
as
subject according to the
mode
known
of the
object
knowing
is
sub-
THE THIRTEENTH CENTURY
141
through which the subject,
is
known
assimilation, that
object
and the object
intellectual
"species" that
is
made
is
a preliminary condition o£
the subject thing,
when
can be instances
ject," there
the operation
is,
knowing
similar to the
knowledge. For example, when
and
are as different as the soul
a sensible
knowledge can come about only through
a
both a distinctive form in the intellect and an image
or hkeness of the thing apprehended. species" that the intellect, in
It is
through the "impressed
apprehending a thing, begins the opera-
But no
tion that ends with the definition or "expressed species."
such operation applies to the beatific vision or to the knowledge that
God
has of his
own
essence,
and therefore
knowledge. Knowledge in a general sense
does not define
it
is
all
a direct presence of
being.^^
X
Thomas: Proofs
St.
follows from the hmitations of
It
God
for the Existence of
human knowledge
that the re-
gions of being to which the soul can attain do not extend beyond the
bounds
by Aristotle
set
theology in which tion that
God
—that
God
one can have
is
envisioned as the prime mover.
direct, positive
notion that one can attain to
God
Anselm)
is.
exists.
that since the
They
name
of
God
to posit
first
view hold
having
(like St.
it
God him
follows that is
God
identical to his
as existing.
Those
support the second view, distrusting the strength of reason and
seeing that neither the quiddity of ^^
con-
the being greater than
to exist,
being of is
without
first
God means
also say that since the
essence, to posit the essence of
who
God
Those who support the
which no other being can be conceived
The two
principle: the false principle
that one cannot speak of the existence of
learned what he
a
no-
as false as the
is
only through faith.
on the same
The
evidence of the existence of
without passing through the sensible world
trasting notions are based
bounded by
the physical world
is,
On
this
philosophic,
special point, cf. I,
i.
God
nor even the meaning of
Tonquedec, "Notes d'Exegese thomiste," Archives de
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
142
name
the
God
of
his existence
is
attainable, conclude that
is
Those who support the second view
what they deny our reason
is
:
tion
any demonstration of
impossible.
and greatness
God
of
too
weak
are right with respect to to
apprehend in the perfec-
the reason for his existence.
But when
they conclude that his existence cannot be demonstrated, they are
ignoring the fact that there are two kinds of demonstrations: the
demonstration quid that takes quiddity as a means and goes from essence to
properties, or
its
tion quia that proceeds
with respect
quid
as
from cause
from
to its effect.^^ St.
being inaccessible to
existence of
God
to effect;
effect to cause
Thomas
man
and the demonstra-
and can define cause
considers the demonstration
not only in matters relating to the
but in any instance.
We
recall that
one of the
dif-
theory was the impossibility of discovering a
ficulties in Aristotle's
Nobody is Thomas of this flaw in Peripateticism, and human reason: "Even in sensible things, esunknown to us; that is why they are desig-
rational procedure for attaining to the quiddity of beings.
more conscious than he makes
it
St.
a flaw in
sential differences are
nated by accidental differences that have their source in essential
same way
ferences, in the
for example, "biped"
The
that the cause
signified
by
its
dif-
effect;
posited as the difference of "man."
is
from
type of demonstration that goes
accident to essence
is
effect to cause or
from
and allows us to posit the existence of a thing
without having previous knowledge of the thing and without knowing anything about
brought us in all
its
to
other than that
it
—such
it
is
investigations.
the existence of
God
the
And
it
produces the
normal domain of the the five
effect that
has
human mind
"ways" that lead us
to posit
imply no special mode of knowledge but
merely apply to the question the most commonplace processes of reasoning.
The
first is
borrowed from the eighth book in
is moved is moved by something else; this mover moved or unmoved; if it is unmoved we have what
"Everything that in turn ^*
is
Summa
either
Aristotle's Physics:
contra gentiles
i.
12.
THE THIRTEENTH CENTURY
143
we were call
unmoved prime mover, and that is what we moved it is moved by something else, and we must infinity (which is impossible) or come to an un-
seeking, an
God;
if it is
then proceed
to
moved mover." The second is borrowed from
the Metaphysics: "In
series of efficient causes the first
term
term and the middle term
is
the cause of the last term, whether
is
there are several middle terms or only one;
nated, that of
the if
there
the
term
first
is
which is
the cause
it is
is
also eliminated; therefore if
a regression to infinity in efficient causes,
posit a
The
primary
third starts
we
rupted
from the experience
will be
are the
we
that
we have
of the genera-
fact that they
become
cor-
conclude that they are merely possible beings, that
being already existing. But follows that nothing
We
which
God."
is
was a time when they were brought
that there
it
no cause
this is patently false,
cause which
efficient
and corruption of beings. From the
tion
elimi-
is
eliminated, the middle term cannot be a cause. But
middle terms, will be eliminated. Since
must
the cause
if
cause, with the result that all other causes,
first
ordered
all
the cause of the middle
must therefore
if all
would
to existence
is,
by a
beings were merely possible beings,
actually be,
and
this
is
posit a being necessary in itself,
patently false.
which we
call
God.
The
We
fourth
parison
is
them
is
more
false
possible only because
an absolute being which
The is
borrowed from the second book of the Metaphysics.
can compare two statements with respect to their truth and see
that one of
to
is
fifth is
and the other
we can
less false.
refer to
God.
is
borrowed from John of Damascus and Averroes and
based on the second book of the Physics: "It
trasting
and incongruous things
single order other than to every
and
to
this
is
is
to be joined
impossible for con-
harmoniously in a
through the agency of a being that attributes
each thing
Alternately, in the world
and
The com-
an absolute truth or
its
we
tendency toward a determined end.
see diverse things
form
a single order,
not the exception but the rule. Consequently there must
MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
"T^^
144
be a being through whose providence the world this
being
In
any
all
is
of his proofs there
religious sentiment,
an obvious attempt not
is
any
flight of the soul to
Thomas
natural destiny and God. St.
As
notions of Aristotelian physics. that the value of his proofs
Summa
icism in his
date these proofs.
false
The
.
.
.
;
first is
the second
moved, namely, the
mate
—a
belief
a result critics soon suggested
is
closely
the value of
to
probably referring to such
is
contra gentiles:
of the eternity of the world,
with his super-
introduces only the technical
was linked
Thomas
to introduce
God, anything hav-
man
ing to do with the peculiar relations between
Aristotle's physics. St.
governed, and
is
^^
called God."
"Two
from the supposition
that they proceed
which
presumed by Catholics
is
that in the demonstrations the
body, moves
celestial
denied by
many
world and everything implied by
it
and
itself
people."
crit-
reasons seem to invali-
The
^^
is
first
to be
thing
therefore ani-
eternity
(a world that has
of the
no history
and consequently no redemption or consummation), and animation of the heavens with
all
the dangers inherent in astrology
—
is
it
only at the price of these errors that reason could succeed in establishing the existence of
XI
St.
A
Thomas:
The above
criticism,
God? Christian Interpretation of Aristotle
whether
stand the peculiar situation of temporaries, to
show
justified or not, St.
Thomas
may
help us under-
in the eyes of his con-
and the problems that confronted him. His
that there
was
in Peripateticism a philosophy that
autonomous and independent of dogma and
was
task
was
truly
that could nevertheless
be reconciled with dogma.
But the AristoteUan universe presented features that do not seem to be easily reconciled
God who
is
with Christian
tion in matter that exists apart
Summa ^^
beliefs:
on the one hand, a
only the prime mover of the heavens,
first
produces mo-
from him; and on the
i. 13 and Summa theologica and the second, see i. 13.
contra gentiles
Concerning the
who
i
qu. 2
art. 3.
other,
an
THIRTEENTH CENTURY
"^^^
145
omnipotent God, the creator o£ a world that began in time and
must come
to
The same
an end. contrast
is
found in the notion of
separate intelligences, or souls. According to the
spiritual creatures,
Arab commentators,
Aristotle's separate intelligences are the efficient causes of the ce-
spheres and have the
lestial
him
same nature and even the same func-
supreme God, with the
tion as the
incomprehensible; against
is
dependence on
result that their
this, in
the Christian universe the
angels are creatures capable of falling. Souls, too, offer striking differences. Aristotle holds that the soul is
the
form of an organic body and the principle
biological functions;
the body,
which
it
is its
From
and
body,
it
it
its
itself; its
its
relation to
matter. In the Christian drama, the soul
individual being complete in transitory,
that determines
has individuaUty only through
an
is
connection with the body
is
has a supernatural destiny.
the Aristotelian conception of the soul as the
form of a
seems to follow that the soul perishes with the body. Fur-
thermore,
seems that
it
sensible objects tellectual
if
and corporeal organs (such that there
knowledge
in it),
it
and belongs
impersonal intelligence
is
jointly to all
contrast
is
produced
in-
is
beneath the im-
men. The
eternity of this
something quite different from personal
immortality and nullifies the image of
The same
is
through an inteUigence that no
is
longer has any connection with the body, which passible soul
knowledge of
the soul has independent
found
also
its
supernatural destiny.
in the sphere of
moral philosophy.
Merit, according to Aristotle, depends on virtues that are voluntary acquisitions,
that
utilize
natural
endowments, and
that
are
in-
creased by man's civic activities and by political or social relations
with other to strip
citizens.
man
Against
this,
bare and to isolate
the ideal of the Christian mystic
him
is
may
be exposed
Thomas'
adversaries
that his soul
to the influx of divine grace.
Emboldened by
these obvious contrasts, St.
called attention to these divergent doctrines. St. consists
one
wholly in converting
basic, definitive pattern of
all
Thomas'
strategy
these divergences of doctrine into
divergence acceptable to
all
the faith-
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
146
"Human
philosophy considers crea-
and such, with the
result that the divisions of
divergence of method.
ful: a
tures as being such
The
philosophy correspond to different types of things. faith,
however, does not consider them
for example,
considers
it
fire,
represents divine elevation
ward God
himself.
The
and
not as
Christian
being such and such;
as
but as something that
fire,
some manner,
directs itself, in
philosopher considers what
is
suitable to
creatures according to their proper natures: for example, by
nature
fire
able to
them
tends to
move upward;
what
Christians consider
God:
in so far as they are related to
to-
its
is suit-
for instance, that
they are created by him, that they are amenable to him, and so forth."
^'
Now
how
Thomas applies his strategy to the fiwc problems mentioned earlier. First, God the prime mover and God let
us see
St.
the creator. Aristotelian physics as such generally posits only de-
terminate causes that produce determinate
That
effects.
why
is
recognizes only agents capable by their action of drawing from
it
matter outside and prior to this action the being contained there in potency; such agents simply is,
passage from ill-defined potential being to clearly defined actual
being; and their action in
produce a change or motion, that
But
time.
all
is
not instantaneous but must be unfolded
demonstrations, according to
point to the conclusion that there
whom
agent of
all
same manner the
things, effects
is
St.
Thomas, must
a universal cause
no matter what they may
—and
—that
is,
be, are in the
consequently a cause of being, a
cause that produces ex nihilo and acts instantaneously. This
point of capital importance, but one that supposes a tation of Aristotle's philosophy: the first "way," as
the Physics,
actually a solution to the
is
motion of the
celestial spheres; the
new
problem of the
is,
is
a cause that
is
a
interpre-
one finds
unmoved mover
determinate cause as defined above, that circular
an
it
in
circular
therefore a
makes the
motion contained in the matter of the heavens pass from
potency to
act.
But there
is
no longer any reference
spheres in the Thomistic demonstration, and St.
" Summa
contra gentiles
ii.
4.
to celestial
Thomas
presents
147
THIRTEENTH CENTURY
"^^^
his proof in such a
way
that the
essendi, or creative cause.
The heavens moved by
(Summa contra
he points out
prime mover appears
gentiles
mover
is
the cause of being. St.
causa
the prime mover,
6), are the cause of genera-
ii.
tion for things in the sublunary region,
as the
which proves
Thomas can
prime
that the
therefore respond to
consummate calm. They
the objections of his adversaries with
say
that his proof implies the eternity of the world, since the prime
mover
is
and must therefore produce
forever in act
motion of the heavens, but he sweeps
away
eternally the
their objection
by observ-
ing that the eternity of the world does not imply the independence of the world or the negation of
its
We
creation.
need only assume,
Avicenna has already done, that God created the world from
as
eternity; then,
remains an St.
whether
effect
Thomas
and
it
is
began in time, the world
eternal or
a creature of
the reasons given by
world are not convincing; that
God. Furthermore, according
to
Aristotle for the eternity of the
God
mover
the prime
is
of the
world pertains to his relation to his creation and, consequently, not necessarily to his being. Here reason
is
incapable of reaching a
vaHd conclusion and we must have recourse to us
to faith,
which
with certainty that the world was created in time. In discussing
the second way, he understands
the
simple sense of a prime mover as
is
efficient
being."
The
how
That
is
third
way
the second
way
generally true in the case of
on
involves speculation
pletely alien to the spirit of Aristotle
we
shall see, that there
that the origin of the
and essence
is
recommends
necessity
termining
its
nothing
if
problem of the
quiddity, but this is
is
effects to
allows
distinction
To
and
possibility,
—something
a universal
we determine whether
that does not exist
in
—and
is
not to be found in Aristotle.
that
its
leads to a creative cause.
on essence and the being introduced by essence conclude, as
not in the
cause,
Aristotle, but in the sense of a cause that "transmits
is
reveals
com-
Thomas to cause. The fact St.
between being
be sure, Aristotle
a being exists before de-
because the quiddity of a being
nothing: the quiddity of the goat-stag
exist. Thus the manner Thomas, posed the ques-
such a fanciful animal does not
which the Arabs, and subsequently
St.
is
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
148
between essence and being,
tion of the relation
far
from being
a
continuation or an extension of hints provided by Aristotle, was
Here
just the reverse.
the object
thing exists before determining
not to determine whether a
is
quiddity, but on the contrary, to
its
find out whether quiddity can have a determinate
any question concerning existence
Thomas* terminology) whether essence appearances,
of a thing
that to
it is
necessary;
it is
comes
to
merely possible and in the case of the is
is
to say that
to accord to
it
a privilege that belongs only
is
them from something
it
unique being whose essence
power
matter, then,
and
is
of
which essence
exists of itself,
Thomas contradicts him when he
Here
St.
faithful to
of reason between essence
is
there
is,
is
the
form of which
fourth
and produces
way
But being
rather the realiza-
At
the crux of the
chasm between essence useless.
said that there
was only
was
a distinction
and existence: one can always conceive it
as existing,
but an essence that
something wholly imaginary. But by
whose essence
is
to be, St.
placing at the base of things the most universal form
participations
The
itself is
being only
the spirit of Aristotle. Averroes
positing as the sole necessity the being
Thomas
its
which would render God
of essence without conceiving of
could not actually exist
it is
possible;
essence
to exist.
is
consists.
the affirmation of a gaping
existence, the negation of
more
else;
conceivable in the absence of
not superadded to essence as an accident;
tion of the
to
essence
its
God. All other natures have the property of being merely
their being
from
and technical
a theological preoccupation: to say that the being
is
identical to
is
different
really
is
being. But underlying this question, quite abstract all
meaning before
raised, to find out (to use St.
is
all
and
effects.
way
leads to the
its
effect
the things that possess being are only
same
result.
according to what
leads us to a being which, since
universal cause of the being of
all
induces us to posit a cause that
it is
Normally each thing it is
in act, but the fourth
being in
act,
must be the
other things. Finally, the fifth
is
different
acts
from
way
particular natural
causes. St.
Thomas
followed a circuitous road in substituting for Aris-
THE THIRTEENTH CENTURY
149
prime mover a transcendent being,
totle's
satisfied the
Though angels
demands
the issue seems trifling to a
was one
of the
To
AristoteUanism.
end
modern
reader, the theory of
mover given by
naturally
many moving
animated by
the relation that
a distinct
might
and
exist
among
terpreted as a monotheistic system in
on one,
unmoved
of
was presumed
characteristic motion.
Furthermore,
the various intellects
explored by Aristotle, and his system
is
was not
equally viable whether in-
which
or as a polytheistic system in
re-
were spheres
there
as
in his astronomical system, since each of the spheres to be
we must
Aristotle at the
multiplicity
a
to
intelligences
Thomistic
for
grasp the significance of the issue
of the Physics led
movers, to as
the creator, but he
most serious stumbHng-blocks
the proof of the prime
call that
God
of a faith that required reason to find proof.
intelligences
all
which they
all
depend
act together
but independently of each other. In any event, in Aristotle's system the separate intelligences
—which Dionysius
the Areopagite, follow-
ing an already ancient tradition, compared to the angels of the celestial
We
hierarchy
recall
bron but
—were the equals of God himself.
how the Franciscan school, following not only AviceHugh of St. Victor, had resolved the question: these
also
composed of matter
separate substances are not pure forms, but are
and form. Wherever there
is
indetermination, wherever there
Thus matter
common
is
prop-
plurality or finity, there
is
erty of every substance,
and whether particular substances become
spirits or
is
a
bodies depends on their determining forms; the multi-
plicity of intelligences is
matter.
proves that they have a
common
base which
determined by diverse forms.
But
St.
Thomas
denies outright the hylomorphic composition of
spiritual substances.
One
of his arguments strikes at the heart of
Avicebron's concept of matter and
its
relation to form.
According
to
Avicebron, generation consists in the addition of form to matter,
as
an accident
no true unity is
to a substance.
Hence
in the composite being
there
is
no true generation and
produced in such a way; there
but a simple increment or addition. But Aristotle's concept of
matter as being in potency (marble)
that
becomes actual being
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
150
(statue) as a result of diverse motions or alterations enables us to
understand that hylomorphic composition pertains only to bodies,
and
knowledge
his description of the characteristics of intellectual
proves that, unlike bodies, intellects are pure, immaterial forms; furthermore, in the act of understanding, die intellect to the
When
received in matter a
becomes related it
form
to accidents;
and
intelligence
stance, that
known by
comprehended
how
which
It is
is
are the dif-
that a being can
mode
identical only in
it
{quod
is
merits the
we must make
this distinction
name
We
have
of composition
that of essence
and
God. But in every
between essence or sub-
a distinction
what the thing
another way, art.
The answer
in every creature a
is
we must make
is,
virtue of the
in proportion as the
from that of form and matter:
or that through
its
As an
simple and indivisible, uni-
not equal the simplicity of God.
two terms which are
created thing
it
is
better
is
be avoided.?
still
already seen that there quite different
it
mobile.
be a pure form and
and
form
it
contrary, better
its
is less
ficulties of his thesis to
put
individualized as
separate intelligences are pure forms,
if
being,
it is
excludes the presence of a contrary
it
free of accidents;
presence of
But
divides;
introduced into matter as a result of a motion.
is
object of the intellect, however, versal,
identical
is
comprehends, with die result that the
it
not received in the intelligence as form in matter.^^
intelligible is
form;
that
intelligible
est),
and
of being
very being,
its
(quo
a distinction between
est) its
;
or to
potency
which, introduced into Aristote-
lianism, serves here, as in the case of Albert the Great, to separate
from God. This
the angels
distinction
is
but the abstract statement
of
what
its
essence does not have independently the
which
to
is
it
is
repeat the
be proven, for to say that an angel
is
distinct
same
from
thing.
Still,
is
a creature, or that
power
to be, or that that
which
is,
is
simply to
what we have described
is
not truly
that through
it
an individual being since individuality pertains only
engaged in matter; the angels, pure forms, ^®
Summa
contra gentiles
ii.
50.
diiiFer
among
to
a form
themselves
THE THIRTEENTH CENTURY
151
as species
and not
as individuals,
which was the conclusion reached
by Aristotle.^^
The posits
third difficulty
pecuHar relation that AristoteUanism soul," says
"must be explained in such a way
as to safe-
guard both
personal immortality and
its
its
function as a substantial
20
Here, indeed, totle,
in the
between soul and body. "The individuality of the
a recent interpreter,
form."
is
the soul
is
For
the problem.
the
is
Thomas, who follows
St.
form of the organic body;
Aris-
and body are
soul
not two independent substances, but from their union a unique being,
man,
formed.
is
soul cannot apprehend itself
through
itself.
It
a natural union without which the
is
know
for in effect the soul cannot
itself,
Augustine's statement to the effect that
St.
"the soul has independently notions of incorporeal things"
means
own
actions
that the soul perceives that
{Contra gentiles
Thus
iii.
because
it is
it
perceives
its
46)
the problem of the individuality of
man
is
resolved in ac-
cordance with the general rule that appHes to the individuation of beings composed of form and of matter. itself is specific
identical
form
individuals is
joined.
tion
and is
that, for a
we must
What
therefore the matter to
is
how
understand
matter
nevertheless bear in
is
mind
What
signata), that
dimensions.
is
which form
is,
is
is
signed matter {materia
individuaHzes
form
its
determinate
and
produces
numerical diversity within a given species, not only because to
form an exclusive position with '^^
Metaphysics A.
8.
^ Roland -Gosselin,
respect to any other
1074a, 36. in his edition of
De
as a
defined as a being com-
matter considered with respect to matter
Man,
not for that reason an individual
accounts for individuality
Signed
separates
that the fact of being joined
matter since he
posed of soul and body, but he being.
in
the principle of individua-
to matter in general does not account for individuality. species, already includes
form
that
given species of beings, a specifically
in each individual of the species.
from each other
To
We know
ente, p. 117.
form
it
gives
in time
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
152
and
space, but also because,
form only It
debility,
its
is
it
can receive
and imperfect manner.
in a deficient
follows that for a form engaged in matter to
dividual being tion.
by reason of
become an
diminu-
in every sense a limitation, a debilitation, a
The human
soul, as the
form of the body,
is
in-
subjected to just
such conditions and acquires individuality only by virtue of the
body whose form ence.
and with which
it is
would seem
It
that
we must
has a perfect correspond-
it
conclude from
dividuality ought to follow the destiny of the
with
it.
soul,"
But such
he
is
says, "is a
not the teaching of
form which by
pend on matter. Consequently,
St.
Thomas: "The human
virtue of
its
being does not de-
souls are multiplied as bodies are
multiplied, but the multiplication of bodies
multiplication of souls; and that
is
why
it
is is
not the cause of the
not necessary, once
bodies are destroyed, for the plurality of souls to
{Contra gentiles
Here we duced, as
if
ii.
that in-
this
body and disappear
come
an end"
to
81).
which the Christian
see the extent to
from the
faith
is
intro-
outside, to limit Aristotelian biologism.
But
we need to examine more closely the procedure through which St. Thomas manages to insert into Peripateticism the doctrine of the permanent individuality of the
He
soul.
has but one philosophical
reason for accepting the permanence of the individuality of the
human
soul outside
its
body, and that
soul, in addition to the operations
of an intelligence that
or assistance of matter:
ii.
But the solution
human
it,
like other material
forms"
68) raises
another serious
intelligence to the rest of the
with the
the existence in the
knows its objects without the intermediacy "The intelligent soul is therefore not totally
attached to matter or immersed in
{Contra gentiles
is
required by the corporeal organs,
human
series of interpretations
difficulty: the relation of
soul.
that the
We
are already famiUar
Greek and Arab com-
mentators had formulated on the basis of Aristotle's handling of point.
They were almost unanimous
this
in seeing in the independence
of the intellectual operation, with respect to the organs of the body,
proof that the intellect was not included in the definition of the
THIRTEENTH CENTURY
T^^^
153
form of the body;
soul as the
engaged forms.
in thinking
when
actively
— to universal or specific
all
men,
it is
not a part of the soul.
problem hinges the destiny of Thomistic Aristotelianism
this
with Arabic Peripateticism. Albert the Great had
rivalry
its
object
independent of matter and therefore not susceptible of
individuation. Identical in
in
its
follows that the intellect can be nothing other than a uni-
It
versal form,
On
in contrast, the intellect
identical to
is
already seen
nically different
and the
full significance,
its
forms
fact
is
that
under tech-
continued to preoccupy Western man.
it
All of the Peripatetics, whether Christian or Arab, have a com-
mon
starting point
operation.
It
—their
manner
of interpreting the intellectual
an abstractive operation through which
is
specific
forms, apprehended potentially in sensible data and in the images
more
images or phantasms.
St.
from the
these data, are extracted
Thomas
reduces to two the
number
of
necessary for the operation: the agent intellect and the
intellects
The
possible intellect.
phantasms; the
agent intellect extracts the specific forms of
intellect
becoming anything
of
from
or less elaborated
which
like a
is
blank tablet and susceptible
receives the extracted forms.
The two
in-
never function, therefore, except in connection v/ith other
tellects
operations that in turn require corporeal organs; by themselves they yield
no knowledge.
Once ficulty
Or
is
the intellectual operations have been
is
in
knowing
their subject.
Are
only one of them, the agent
The
first
view
is
St.
patently illogical, for the relation
of the agent intellect first
Thomas'
real adversary
many
gentiles
76).
St.
ii.
dif-
intellects "separate".'^
while the pos-
intellects
belong to
Thomas. But Avicenna's
to the
thesis
and proportion between the
and the potency
must belong
that the
pioned by
Or do both
the
that of Averroes, the second that of
Avicenna, and the third that of is
two
intellect, separate
sible intellect is part of the soul?
the soul?
the
described,
of the possible intellect
same
is
act
such
subject as the second. St.
then was Averroes, whose view was cham-
of the professors at the University of Paris (Contra
Thomas had
only to demonstrate that an intellectual substance
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
154
could be the form of a body. Finding no support in Aristotle for his demonstration, he could do no more than
which move
souls of the celestial spheres,
the desire that they have for the good.^^
an example the
cite as
their spheres because of
He
therefore stated rather
than demonstrated that "an intellectual substance can be a formal principle of being for matter" {Contra gentiles
But even
if
his point
demonstrated,
is
ii.
58).
it is still
that the inclusion of intelligence with the other
necessary to prove
powers of the soul
does not in turn compromise the unity and indivisibility of the
power not
soul. Is the intellectual
and
nutritive
different in this respect
from
sensitive
power, each of which seems to constitute
Here
the technical problem of the plurality of
a separate soul?
forms comes into the picture. The Augustinians, in agreement with
Avicebron on
this point,
held that in material composites, matter
determined by several forms. As
more
we
perfect beings
the body
element
is
we
rise
from
perfect beings to
find successive additions of higher forms:
determined by the simple form of corporeality; to an
added the form of the element;
is
less
is
to a
mixture of
ele-
ments, the form of the mixture; to a plant, the nutritive soul; to
an animal, the sensitive
soul,
and
so forth.
The higher form
is
simply added to the lower form: "The lower forms are contained in the higher forms until
which combines criticized
all
all
are reduced to the primary universal form,
forms."
^^
Their
thesis,
which had already been
by Avicenna, seemed unacceptable to
plurality of
forms in a being
is
St.
Thomas. The
incompatible with
its
unity.
A
pluraHty of forms cannot create a true substance; for a composite
being endowed with a single form, such as a body, substance,
and
a
new form
is
already a
can be added to an already existing sub-
stance only as an accidental attribute. It is
easy to see in this discussion a conflict between the
a universe consisting of a hierarchy of forms, each of receive
its
complement
in the whole)
^ Sumtna
(for unity
is
contra gentiles
ii.
76.
vitae 143. 13 (ed.
them eager
to
never in the individual but only
and the Peripatetic image of
* Avicebron Pons
image of
Bauemker).
a universe consisting of
THE THIRTEENTH CENTURY
155
individual beings each having in
To
the second view
its
operations.
linked the thesis of unity of form in each
is
individual being. But
the principle of
itself
also
it is
by virtue of
this thesis that St.
Thomas human
avoids the danger that threatened the unity of the individual being. For intelligence it
also the single
is
emanate
not only the form of the organized body;
is
and unique form of the body, and from
Hence
are executed by the organs of the body.
human body from
the
wholly an intelligent soul that draws
is
relation to the
its
body and
it
whose operations
the sensitive or vegetative faculties
all
its
form of the individuality
independence from the im-
its
material character of the operations through which knowledge
is
acquired.
But there
still
is
one strong argument against
tion of intelligence: since intelligence
and
since
object
its
is
a
universal form,
multipHed in diverse individuals. theological master stroke:
St.
God
this
impHes a contradiction. But even
cannot create several
intellects of the
that such multiplication
acteristic that
loud, if
it
instance, a
and
yet
it
it
its
are
its
object,
cannot be truly a
is
adduced
same
to
show
species because
grant that
would not
would imply
prevents a thing from not having in
For
we
if
the nature of intellect to be multiplied,
low
intelligence
Thomas' answer
"Clumsy arguments
that
this individualiza-
in act identical to
is
it is
not of
necessarily fol-
contradiction.
Nothing
nature the cause of a char-
nevertheless possesses by virtue of another cause.
low tone does not have the
characteristic of being
can be loud and not imply a contradiction. Similarly,
everyone's intellect were unique because
natural cause of multiplication,
it
it
does not contain a
could nevertheless accommodate
multipHcation without contradiction, by virtue of a supernatural cause. Let this be said not so
much
for our present purposes as to
prevent such a line of reasoning from being extended to other subjects, for
dead text
it
could be used to prove that
to rise or the
we
bend
see that St.
—that
^ De
bUnd
is,
God
cannot cause the
to recover their sight." ^^ In this revealing
Thomas
does not hesitate to enjoin reason to
to support faith or to
remain
unitate intellectus contra Averroistas, chap.
vii.
silent.
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
156
There there
God
as the cause of the world,
and
a revealed theology that transcends reason; similarly, to
is
human
direct
world that allows us
a rational physics of the sensible
is
ascend through reasoning to
to
conduct there
a natural ethic based
is
on the spon-
taneous orientation of the will toward happiness and the good, and there
is
a supernatural destiny
with respect to which our only guide
sanctifying grace, something that goes
is
beyond
will illuminated by
reason. St.
Thomas' fundamental
from
good
that
is
is its
end, which
is
means
the
From
Aristotle.
that our will
ideas
on natural morality
are
Nicomachean Ethics comes
the
directed naturally
borrowed
the notion
and spontaneously toward the
end, that our free will consists not in choosing our
not free, but in choosing through rational deliberation
that lead us to our end.
There must accordingly be
a
natural light to provide us with the premises of our practical de-
This natural light
liberations.
Thomas
interprets
state) that
as
a
is
manifested in synderesis, which
natural and immutable
divided into particular precepts.
is
From
habitus
synderesis comes
rectitude of will. Virtues are acquired practices deriving fact that
we
are capable
St.
(stable
from the
through free will of choosing the best
means. His view assumes that morality and legality are based on divine reason, to which the divine will
subject: "Eternal
is
but the reason of divine wisdom; the divine is
subject to this reason
and consequently
will, since
it is
law
is
rational,
to the eternal law."
The
immutability of law based on reason, contested later by the Ockhamists, nevertheless remains the foundation of one whole group of
modern
theories of law.
And
it is
from
St.
Thomas
that Grotius
received the concept in the seventeenth century, through the in-
termediacy of the Scholastic, Vasquez (died in 1506).^*
But natural to the charity to
light provides
no means of
and beatitude of the
knowledge of God, which
alone ^*
is
capable of satisfying
Gurvitch,
(1927), p. 369.
"La Philosophic du
all
is
elect.
The
elect
impossible in this
human
droit
access to the higher virtues,
owe life,
their bliss
and which
desires.
de H. Grotius," Revue de Metaphysiqtie
THE THIRTEENTH CENTURY
157
The
great political treatise
Thomas, has been
to St.
wrote the
regiwine principtim, once attributed
Ptolemy of Lucca
identified as spurious.
treatise (or at least the first part of it)
an exemplary manner the application to
illustrates in
of the Thomistic spirit as
Thomas:
De
1301. It
political
matters
revealed in the philosophy of
is
it
power pursuing the
civil
around
civic
St.
good with the same freedom
that reason exhibits in pursuing truth in speculative matters; but at
same time absolute
the
any way
in
God
certainty that,
if civil
power runs counter
aims of spiritual power that has received from
to the
the mission of guiding
man
to salvation, civil
power
is
in error
and must be
corrected. This accounts for the wholly rational, al-
most
character of Thomistic policies in temporal matters:
realistic
"The kingdom
The
kingdom.'* of
all;
and
if
he
declare his
to
is
power
sacrifices the
the latter are freed
it
made
not
is
king's
for the king, but the king for the
good of
On
power nonexistent.
"For divine law
his subjects for his
from any obligation
understood that the rational
state
identifies the true
Church."
to the ministry of the
right to
only for the pursuit of the good
exists
^^
to
good,
the right
the odier hand, however,
must be
good, and
That
own
him and have
is
why
its
a
Christian
state.
teaching belongs
the
Church has the
excommunicate and depose kings. This type of modified
theocracy,
which
leaves to the temporal
power freedom correspond-
ing to the freedom that theology leaves to rational philosophy, con-
with the
trasts
De
regimine Chfistiano, written during the same
period (1301-1302) by John of Viterbo, an Augustinian hermit
who
advocated a more rigid theocracy in the face of the growing pretensions of national kingdoms.
XII
Latin Ai/erroism: Siger of Brabant
There
is
no doubt but that the introduction of Peripateticism
into the University of Paris resulted in the destruction of the unity of
medieval culture century.
^ De
The
as
it
had been envisioned up
until the twelfth
study of the seven liberal arts was supposed to provide
regimine principum
i.
13.
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
158
the basic
grounded
knowledge needed by commentators, and theology was in the commentaries on Scripture written by the Fathers.
Moreover, encroachment was prohibited, and the faculty of to exclude all theological matters
arts had from the curriculum. But where
could the philosophy of Aristotle find a place in the system ? In the faculty of arts, since there
was no
an authority on theology.
As
possibility of his
a matter of fact, toward the middle of
the century the curriculum included the study of
encyclopedia, beginning with the
many
all
the AristoteUan
Organon and continuing through
the Ethics, the Physics, the Metaphysics, in the introduction of
being considered
and
so on.^^
This resulted
questions external to the seven arts and
relating to theology.
The situation was perilous, for in the faculty of arts scholars were to comment solely on the philosophy of Aristotle and were not to concern themselves in any way with possible disagreement between his doctrines
and
faith.
"Here," said Siger of Brabant, explaining his
interpretation of Aristotle's writings
the interpretation of Albert
and
on the
St.
intellect (in contrast to
Thomas), "we
identify the intention of the philosophers,
mainly
are trying to
Aristotle. It
may
well be that the philosopher held an opinion that does not conform to truth
and
that revelation provides us with information about
the soul which cannot be inferred by natural reason; but here are in no
natural
way concerned with from
things
the
divine miracles for
viewpoint
of
the
we
we
are discussing
physician.'
The
Thomistic synthesis did, of course, provide a principle of agree-
ment: what reason teaches us cannot be contrary reveals to us,
and
there
if
is
an apparent contradiction,
to
what
faith
it
results
from
the fact that reason has been misguided.
The Masters proof.
of Arts submitted the principle to an experimental
Reason was interrogated independently of
mining whether
its
a simple matter of collecting the facts. **
II,
and
deter-
There was no doubt about
Chartulary of the University, quoted by Gilson, ttudes, p. 56.
^ Ed. Mandonnct,
faith,
conclusions were in agreement with faith was
153-54.
~HI THIRTEENTH CENTURY
159
the answer in the
of Alts
who
mind
of Sigcr of Brabant, the cdcbiatcd Master
taught the AYcnoist interpretation of Aristotk at the
University of Paris from 1266 to 1277 and wiio was the initiator of
movement known
the
as Latin Averroism: Aristotle's theses con-
::izizt revealed doctrines. It
mm
a simple statement of
there
is
would seem fact,
that his conclusion
and noi^ierc does he
is
to
infer that
a "double truth," one truth for philosophers and one truth
for theologians. Others
may have
reached such a conclusion, but he
does not hesitate to state that "faith ^leaks the truth, even though
some philosophers have held a di^rent opinion." The identity of intellect in aU men, the necessity of
events, the
eiemity of the world, the destruction of the soul with the body, the
n^ation of knowledge of sqparate substances in God, the negation of divine providence in the sublunary
—such
r^ion
are the
main
items cm which Siger's Averroism and the Christian faith differ, and which Giles of Lessines collected from the teaching of Sigcr in 1270 for submission to Albert the Great.^
Here we find almost
all
Aristode and which St.
De amma ings >:.
of the theses wtdch Averroes attributed to
Thomas
denied.
A
treatise
such as Siger's
inuUectiva also contains a discussion dt Aristode's writ-
on the
intellect
Thomas (who
and the
interpretations of Albert the Great
are identified by name). It
is
and
not true^ according
Aristode, that the v^ctadve and sensitive Acuities belong to the same subject as the intellectual Acuity. Intelligence must be joined to the body during its operation since it can apprehend only whatever is
in the images that involve the corporeal organ of the imagination;
but intelligence alone understands, and understands, soul
we
are not speaking of
when we
man
say that a
man
as a being composed of
and body but only of his intellect.
In ^ite of the precautions taken by Siger, his teaching was judged dangerous by the Paris,
ecclesiastical authority.
In 1270 the Bishop of
£tienne Tempier, condenmed thirteen propositions in Aver-
*G£. *Xa Arm^ti^ dc ooosahaliQa** v^ "Ta reponsc d'AIbcrt,'" fAvcrwdum Utim am XW* aide, II, 29.
SigfT if Br^bmmt et
in P.
Mandooneta
l60 roist
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
teaching concerning the knowledge of God, the eternity of the
human
world, the identity of
invitation of
intellects, fatality
had submitted
tions that Giles of Lessines
— the
to Albert.
very proposi-
In 1277, at the
Pope John XXI, the Bishop of Paris conducted an
new condemnation
inquiry that resulted in a
The condemnation
starts
by attributing
of 219 propositions.
to the Averroists the double-
truth theory: "they say that things are true according to philosophy
but not according to the Catholic truths
and
damned
as
if
faith, as if there
there were in the
truth contrary to the truth of the
a
Siger, obliged to leave the University,
quisitor of France.
He
were two opposite
words of the heathen who are
Holy
Scripture."
was summoned before the
^^
In-
appealed to the Holy See, but was sentenced
to be interned for life.
He
died tragically in 1282, stabbed by the
who served as his secretary. The Averroist movement, which was
cleric
led not only by Siger but
also by Boetius of Sweden and Bernier of Nivelles, who were condemned along with him, continued in spite of such harsh measures.
John of Jandun, Master of Arts in Paris about 1325 (died in 1328), was excommunicated in 1327 by Pope John XXII. He nevertheless
was adhering
protested that he, too,
must be
divine authority
reason of
human
relied
invention."
faith contrary to reason
^^
on
He
to the faith: "It is certain that to a greater
sought
degree than any
support opinions of
to
"by granting as possible with
our reasoning leads us to declare impossible."
He
God
that
therefore
logically to a type of fideism. "I assert the truth of all these
he
said,
was
led
dogmas,"
speaking of dogmas which contradicted Aristotle, "but
do not know
how
to
demonstrate them; those
have an advantage, but through
which
faith."
We
I
possess
portant role during the Renaissance. "^Ibid.M, 175.
^Quoted by
them and
shall see later that
Gilson, ttudes, p. 71.
I
who do know how confess
them
solely
Averroism played an im-
THE THIRTEENTH CENTURY
l6l
Thomism
Polemics Relating to
XIII
The condemnation midst of a
Tempier
directed by
in
1277
came
own
but also by Peripateticism in general. Judged from his point, St.
Thomas was
De
is
but a lengthy reply
his
exactly
to
Viewed from the
philosophy was Peripatetic, and
it
was
Averroism,
outside, difficult
howto
see
where the danger posed by Aristotelianism, which had been
Thus some
introduced into the University of Paris, would stop. the 219
His
was probably
imitate intellectus contra Averroistas
written in 1270 to refute Siger. ever,
view-
surely the adversary of the Averroists.
vast theory of the intellect
and the
the
in
brought about not only by Averroism
state of uneasiness
condemned
the innovations of
the impossibility
of
propositions relate not to Siger himself but to
Thomism. Those
of the
through matter alone
(42, 43),
that
of
plurality
seemed suspect include:
worlds
and the
(27),
individuation
necessity for the will to
Thomas found some contradictions in his own order: the Dominicans who had preceded him at the University of Paris, Roland of Cremona and Hugh of St. Cher, were Augustinians. One of his most ardent
pursue that which
adversaries of
is
judged good by the
was the Dominican Robert Kilwardby who,
Theology
at
Oxford from 1248
terbury in 1272, taught
He
intellect (163). St.
St.
to 1261
as
Master
and Archbishop of Can-
Bonaventure's ideas on matter and form.
held that matter contained the seminal reasons that explain the
production of things; and, contrary to the thesis of the unity of form, he taught that the soul was not simple but composed of vegetative, sensitive,
and
intellectual parts. It
is
not surprising that
he had the theory of the unity of form condemned 1277.
The some
to the see of
condemned in
which he
Canterbury, the the
at
Oxford
in
condemned by his successor Franciscan John Peckham. The latter
theory was repeatedly
new
philosophy in
its
entirety in a letter of 1285
criticized "the profane innovations in vocabulary intro-
duced during the
last
twenty years into the very heart of theology,
going against the true philosophy and offending the
saints."
And
he
l62
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
called attention especially to the trine "of eternal rules
abandoning of the Augustinian doc-
and immutable
powers of the
light, of the
and of
soul, of seminal reasons inserted into matter,
The passage evidently refers Thomism: agent intellect, unity of
number
a
of
corresponding
other doctrines."
to the
theses in
forms, theory of the
eduction of forms.
Henry
XIV
From
of
Ghent
these dry formulations
emerge two opposing views of the
universe. In the Augustinian universe reason tion, is
already an illumina-
being already possesses form and aspires to
new
forms, matter
pregnant with determinations that will engender form; in the
knowledge
Peripatetic universe all intellectual
individual being
A
is
is
complete in
abstraction,
is
the
matter passively awaits form.
itself,
leading exponent of anti-Thomistic Augustinianism in Paris was
the secular master
Henry
Theology in Paris
in 1277,
patetic principle
which
of Ghent, the doctor solemnis. Master of
he died in 1293. Contrary
form
states that
to the Peri-
gives being to matter, he
held that matter exists independently and subsists in actuality. subsistence
the
form
is,
that
of course, imperfect
complements
it
and
leaves
and makes
it
complete. In his view,
contrary to the Thomistic principle, essence
from being. According
to St.
Thomas
Its
capable of receiving
it
is
not really distinct
each essence awaits
its
actuali-
zation from universal being and, as pure potentiality, has no in-
dependent right
to
it.
Henry held
that essence has
its
own
being
independently and that to diverse essences correspond an equal
number
of diverse beings
—a principle which allows
to
each essence
something of the power of God. His theory of individuation was equally anti-Thomistic: individuation negation.
The
due not
to matter but to
individual being, the lower term in the division, be-
comes incapable of dividing in identifying
is
itself
its
turn;
it
is
equally incapable of
with the other individual beings and of com-
municating with them. The theory of essences and individual beings led him,
it
would seem,
to
posit the objects of our
intelligence
THE THIRTEENTH CENTURY
163
God
in
man,
himself, at least at their highest level.
from natural
starting
God
eternal light that
from whomever he
gives to
No
wills."
"that
whomever he
wills
and withholds
other theory reveals
more
clearly
and Thomism, which outlines sharply
the contrast between his view the limits of reason
Thus he thought
things, cannot attain to the rules of
and could be epitomized
in these
words: con-
knowledge. The essence of
tinuity in being but discontinuity in
Augustinianism, which views reason as a continuation of illumination, is this: continuity in
edge.
From
being and therefore continuing in knowl-
two opposing views
the
conceptions of the spiritual
God
or love. Will, which
loving, therefore has an
meritorious in
XV
issue
two
To Henry
strikingly different
of Ghent, the
not knowledge of God, as in the case of
this life is
union with
as St.
life.
Thomas
own
its
holds,
end superior right.
is
to
St.
end of
Thomas, but
the faculty of desiring or that of intelligence
and
Consequently intelligence does not,
impose on will the end that
it
pursues.
Giles of Lessines
Thomism, following ardent
its
defenders.
the
condemnation of
Countless
1277,
refutations
was not without
were prompted
by
La Mare's Correctoriutn fratris number of dissertations designed to show Thomism. The Dominican Giles of Lessines
the appearance in 1278 of William of
Thomae,
in particular a
the inner coherence of
(died in 1304) published such a treatise, the (1278), in sible
which he presented the same argument from every pos-
from the surface or the surface from the body)
are really multiple
which they
and
are parts
different as forms, yet in the
and
in
which they have
their physical
derive, as secondary acts derive
Furthermore, Ed.
De Wulf,
we
p. 57.
unique subject
which they have individual
constitute but one being, that has
''
unitate formae
viewpoint: "Although the forms abstracted by judgment (for
instance, the line
of
De
its
roles they
source in the form through
being and from which their functions
from the primary
act."
^^
find secular clerics Hke Godfrey of Fontaines
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
164
(died in 1308),
Henry
who sometimes
of Ghent,
and defends
takes a stand against his teacher,
certain points in the Thomistic doc-
being does not differ
Thomas from essence. God
of a thing just as he
is
trine.
Godfrey grants that
created both
thing
is
existence.^^
the cause of
essence and
created both
patently
is
its
St.
its
that
false
Godfrey
its
wrong
is
the cause of the essence
is
its
in
also contradicts
existence are in act; but
potency with respect to
it
its
the Thomistic theory of in-
dividuation which, according to him, would
is
is
existence are in potency; after the
posit anything but accidental diflferences
"which
in holding that
existence; before a thing
its
essence and
essence
is
make
it
impossible to
between individual beings,
an obvious disadvantage." But he defends, against the
knowledge by
doctrine of illuminism, the theory of intellectual
abstraction and, against the doctrine of voluntarism, the Thomistic thesis
according to which will
is
subject to the understanding.
Finally, at the beginning of the fourteenth century
vaded some of the
member
a
of
the
Rome
per-
(died in 1316),
of the Augustinian hermits order, defended the thesis
unity
Cistercians,
influential orders. Giles of
Thomism
of
forms.
Humbert introduced Thomism
and Gerard of Bologna introduced
it
to
the
to the Carmelites.
Thomas Aquinas was canonized by Pope John XXII in 1323, and we recall that Dante (1265-1316) reserved a place for him in the Divine Comedy: in the fourth heaven Dante meets the masters of philosophy and theology, of
Thomas
has on his
left
whom
the greatest
is
St.
Thomas.
St.
Siger of Brabant, and the poet has the saint
The passage has caused his commentators considerable difficulty and may indicate that in the minds of his friends and enemies alike, St. Thomas has essentially the same aim as
eulogize the Averroist.
Siger: to bring together Aristotle
ancient theological tradition.
^
Ed.
De Wulf and
Pelzer, pp. 305-6.
and
Christ, notwithstanding the
THE THIRTEENTH CENTURY
165
The Oxonian Masters
XVI
Augustinianism and Peripateticism are not the only philosophical
The
currents of the thirteenth century.
now
turn our attention,
than the movements
is
harder
To
to define.
we have been
which we
third current, to
studying,
a greater degree
is
it
in
some ways
a
continuation of twelfth-century thought and a clear anticipation of
modern philosophy. The
Chartres that freely assimilated
spirit of
the positive sciences, mathematics
nature considered as a whole
an attachment
tion in
same time
and the experimental
to
—an
intuition that
Platonism
positive, naturalistic,
—
First
ander caelo
this
found
spirit
its
which
and haunted by the
versal intuition appears once again in a this brief
sciences,
and the pursuit of the metaphysical intuition of
classical erudition,
satisfac-
is
the
at
desire for uni-
group of thinkers
to
whom
History cannot give the space that they deserve.
come
the Oxonians. Their spirit appears vaguely in Alex-
Neckham and the
(died in 1217),
De anima
who was
of Aristotle;
contemporary, Alfred of Sereshel,
it
who
familiar with the
De
appears more clearly in his learned Arabic
when
travel-
ing in Spain. Alfred translated from Arabic to Latin pseudoAristotle's
De
supplement
vegetabilibus
to the
and the Liber de
congelatis,
Meteorology, he wrote the
De motu
which
is
a
and
cordis)
he was acquainted with Hippocrates' Aphorisms and with Galen's
Medical Art. Michael the Scot (died about 1235) translated from Arabic Al Bitrogi's (the astronomer
and
Aristotle's
Frederick
and the alchemist who appear
in Dante's Inferno),
II.
finally
of the University of
death in 1253.
cluded mainly his optics
sphaera, works by Averroes and Avicenna
History of Animals, which he dedicated to Emperor
Oxonianism his
De
{On Light
the Mirror,
On
flowered in Robert Grosseteste, Chancellor
Oxford and Bishop of Lincoln from 1235
The twenty-nine
treatises
Color,
On
by Baur
in-
the treatises
on
edited
scientific writings, particularly
or the Delineation of Forms,
On
until
the
Rainbow and
Corporeal Motion and Light), but they
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
l66
on
also included treatises
acoustics,
well as metaphysical writings on ligences,
and on
God. In
short, his
on the study of
astronomy, and meteorology, as
man
and the order of
creations
microcosm, on
as a
their
intel-
emanation from
a conception of the physical universe predicated
is
light,
a metaphysical conception of the universe
predicated on the idea of the emanation of forms from unity; is
it
the radical fusion of a system of physics describing the laws of
diffusion of light
and
a system of metaphysics describing the
emana-
tion of beings.
Here
light in
in the Stoic
and
cosmogony. Through
a role analogous to that of fire
expansion,
its
condensation,
immediately
in the universe. It has the property of being
present in
all
places: "It
indeed propagated in every direction,
is
with the result that from one luminous point
gendered a sphere of light feres."
its
"primary corporeal form" explains every
rarefaction, this
its
body
some ways plays
To
is
immediately en-
as large as desired, unless a
explain the cosmos
and
its
shadow
inter-
spheres, Grosseteste required
only the spherical propagation and infinite swiftness of light, whose
expansion
is
checked by darkness: "Everything
by virtue of the multiplication of light
But we must discover what vestigations.
For
in
lies
at
:
and
the heart of his bold in-
metaphysics of light
his
is
and
the
is
inseparable
figures that are to
the propagation of light;
one, born of the
itself."
mathematical physics of nature optics of the lines, angles,
is
and multiple things are multiple only
perfection of a unique light,
some degree
this outline of
germ
of a
from the study realized in
mathematical physics
culminates in the affirmation of the existence of a precise order in nature, an order of
"Any
which the mind can have
operation in nature
is
(finitissimo)y orderly, concise,
From
a precise conception.
accomplished in the most definite
and perfect manner
possible."
the school of Robert Grosseteste comes a
^^
Sumtna
philo-
sophiae that includes nineteen treatises on subjects ranging from the history of philosophy to mineralogy. In spite of
—among the ^ Dc
earliest
its
fantastic features
philosophers the author places not only Isidore,
luce, ed. Baur, p. 75.
I
THE THIRTEENTH CENTURY
167
Berossus, Josephus, and St. Augustine, but also
Mercury
manner
—the Summa evidences
in
which the Arab
having him
Ptolemy
cite
Emperor Hadrian
related to salvation.
He
in the
De
caelo
The
handled
298).
The
to
author also
all
motion would be
is
their
"The its
self"
it
{Summa
philosophiae,
what would
He
also
p.
set the in-
their
images
upholds the Augustinian
intellect's
acquires an understanding of
He
declared in-
images {idola) rather than essences
species but rather has intuitive
(p. 436).
Thomism.
joined to the intellect, in the ab-
on the question of the
soul as
own
Thomas
what we would apprehend would be
rather than forms themselves." tradition
to
us that
the Augustinians, to acknowledge
knowledge
intellectual
essence of a thing
themselves, and
tells
metaphysical issues he contradicts
sence of any intermediary, for "otherwise tellect in
up the
Aristotle's texts,
and address himself
the existence of the intelligible species that St.
dispensable
and
erred in their treatment of natural things not
On
along with almost
refuses,
Atlas,
a critical spirit by pointing
translators freely
in the Meteorology.
may have
theologians
Abraham,
knowledge of itself
itself:
does not receive
knowledge {contuert) of
it-
clings not only to the notion of the intuitive
character of the intellectual
knowledge of essences
of things or of
ourselves, but also to the idea that the intellectual soul
is
an
in-
dividual being, unrelated to the body.
Roger Bacon
XVII
The most remarkable the
of the
Oxonian
scholars
was Roger Bacon,
doctor mirabilis, whose impetuous, ardent, and indomitable
spirit
was
more
critical
reflected in his life as well as in his writings.
No
one was
than he of the ignorance and stupidity of the "Parisian
philosophers," and particularly of their negligence in the matter of
studying languages, mathematics, and the natural sciences. Born
between 1210 and Oxford, for
1214,
whom
he was
first
a pupil of
Robert Grosseteste
he always evidenced profound admiration.
at
He
Hved in Paris between 1244 and 1252. After entering the Franciscan order and returning to Oxford he wrote his Opus majus (1266-
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
l68 1268).
Divided into seven
human
work
parts, the
discusses the causes of
ignorance; the relation of philosophy and theology to the
science of languages; the utility of mathematics in physics, astron-
omy, the reform of the calendar, and geography; mental
and moral philosophy. Begun
science,
at
optics,
experi-
the request of
Pope Clement IV, the Opus majus was accompanied by two other works which contained preUminary
Opus minus and
studies: the
the Opus tertium. In 1278 Roger Bacon wrote the Speculum
stronomiae (wrongly attributed judicial astrology. In
it
he called in question the condemnation of
hundred and
astrology pronounced in the one tion in the
list
condemned
in 1277 by
seventy-first proposi-
Bishop Tempier: "Through
signs one can recognize the intentions of
men and
intentions." This text probably sealed his
doom:
Franciscans,
who
since 1277
can order, condemned
The truth is of Thomism, a the limits
had been following
harmony between
resulted in complete
him
work
careful partitioning that prescribed for each thinker
beyond which he must not venture. Bacon was the of
manner
fist"
{velut in
palmam) what divine pugnum). He recalled which had
pre-
Middle Ages and which had been borrowed
Augustine and Bede: the hberal
terpreting Scripture,
writings constitute but
all
of conceiving spiritual unity
vailed throughout the
fore-
wisdom. Philosophy and canon law merely
concentrates "in the
the ancient
St.
and the Domini-
struck at the very roots
"spread over the palm of the hand" {velut in
from
a policy that finally
to prison in 1278.
that Bacon's massive
common body
wisdom
changes in their
the general of the
his order
most champion of the unity of wisdom; one
as-
Albert the Great), a defense of
to
pagan philosophy
arts
were
to be
used in
in-
in refuting the errors of the
heathen; the result was that "philosophy considered independently"
and apart from the general plan "has no as interpreted
by the Arabs,
is
called
unity; he grants that intellectual
utility." Aristotle himself,
upon
to
guarantee spiritual
is
impossible without
knowledge
the help of an agent intellect that contains
words, the agent intellect thing, then such
knows
knowledge
all
forms; in other
everything, but "if
befits
it
knows
every-
not a soul, not an angel, but
THE THIRTEENTH CENTURY
169
God
And
alone."
if
Bacon did not go
least stated that
the essences in
God, he
intellect that
Word,
Thus
at
under the
intellectually only
immediate influence of an agent the author of our salvation.
with certain
so far as to say,
we see immediately we acquire knowledge
Franciscans, that
identical to the
is
Christian philosophers, far
from Hmiting and contracting the domain of
their investigations,
"ought
the writings of the
bring together in their treatises
to
all
much
philosophers on the subject of divine truths, and even to go
becoming theologians."
without
unity
is
proven, obviously, by recourse to the divine origin of wisdom.
Its
but
farther,
divine origin
is
Spiritual
demonstrated, according to Bacon, by the
also
fanciful history of philosophy
which he borrows from the Church
Fathers: philosophy, revealed to the patriarchs, was transmitted
through different intermediaries
through them,
to the Christians.
tion of divine
wisdom
And
—Scripture
pagan philosophers and,
the
to
Scripture
which
"in
also the
is
is
summa-
found every
crea-
ture or the
image of every
creature, in
singularity,
from the height
of the heavens to the ends of the earth,
with the result that just he saw
lit
to
as
God made
its
universal type or in
and
his creatures
put his creatures in the scriptures, whether
its
Scripture,
we
under-
stand this hterally or in the spiritual sense."
His conception of wisdom
leads,
moderate theocracy: "for by the
God it
is
kind."
"no other science
The Baconian
clerics,
city
is
the most im-
to
wisdom
organized and the Church of the faithful
rules the world,
mit
practically,
light of
is
the
laid out." Since
needed for the use of man-
resembles the Platonic city: at the sum-
underneath scholars, underneath them
finally artisans; ecclesiastical
superior to
civil
wise men,
who
law grounded
law; popes and princes because they possess
ones to possess power;
Church of
finally, religious
solely
who
soldiers,
and
on Scripture and
choose as counselors
wisdom should be
the only
unity of the world achieved
through an apostolate founded on wisdom.
There
is
a strange contrast between these features of Baconian
thought and the points in his doctrine that are generally given
primary attention and are of primary
historical significance.
Roger
lyO
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
Bacon extolled the experimental method
"We
one:
possible
states.
.
onstration unless truth .
.
.
is,
and
that
is
this
method
why
separable
or almost
all
all
of the secrets,
ignored by most of those
and the
greatest
An
who
devote them-
advocate of the experimental method, he
same time the idea of mathematical physics
at the
from
it:
The
conclusions are verified by experience.
its
selves to learning."
teste, to
does not give us the reason for what
however, that no one today shows concern over
secrets, of science are
had
if it
Reason, in turn, cannot separate sophistry from dem-
.
.
says,
and reason; but authority does not con-
knowledge
tribute to our it
the only
science as
have three methods of knowing," he
experience,
"authority,
in
that
is
in-
physics linked, as in the case of Robert Grosse-
Ptolemaic optics as interpreted by the Arab mathematician
Alhazen, to the geometric structure of optics in cases of
reflection,
and the theory of the rainbow. The mathematical
refraction,
struc-
ture of the point of combustion behind a convex lens lighted by the
sun seemed the
Bacon
to
to
provide "the proper and necessary cause of
phenemenon." At the same time that he was working with
mathematics. Bacon also took up technical problems, ranging from the engineering techniques that caused
machines and flying machines, and
him
to
imagine automotive such as the
social techniques
problem of organizing work and providing for public welfare. This experimental, mathematical, and technical
spirit
had indeed
been present in the case of engineers, architects, and artisans throughout the Middle Ages, but, carried into speculative matters,
make Bacon
to
must not
the true ancestor of
modern philosophy.
lose sight of his enlightened theocracy;
Clement IV
as the
pope destined by the
whose union
would be
method
as
we
no
find
constitutes
inexplicable it is
if
the
we
two
world
features
physiognomy of Bacon. The union
we were
method
Still,
stars to convert the
dealing with the experimental
understood today. But such
precise
seems
he looked upon
Catholicism. Illuminism and positivism are the
to
it
is
not the case; in
him
either for designing experiments or de-
ducing laws from them.
The word experimentum was
closely linked, for a thirteenth-cen-
THE THIRTEENTH CENTURY
lyi
tury
man,
Bacon
it
no longer suggests
man who
essentially the
is
unknown
forces life
to ideas that
to other
men;
to us.
An
expert to
can release and utilize occult
the alchemist creates the eUxir of
and the philosopher's stone; the astrologer knows the powers of
the stars; the magician
knows
the formulas that control the wills of
men. The image of the universe provided by experiment from
diiiferent
is
quite
that provided by the physics of the philosopher: the
deduces natural phenomena from the properties of the four
latter
experiment involves the acquisition of knowledge of
elements;
hidden forces which are irreducible
to the forces of the elements,
such as those brought to light by Peter of Maricourt in connection
with his studies of the magnet. science he
is
thinking of a
When
secret, traditional science that consists in
the investigation of occult forces of these forces confers is
Bacon speaks of experimental
on the
and of the power
expert.
essentially the universe described
The
that
knowledge
universe of the experts
by Plotinus: a
set of interpene-
which have ema-
trating forces, enchantment,
magic words,
forces
nated from the
which people
are unwittingly subject.
Bacon
stars
and
to
finds in perspective the typical illustration
the diffusion of each such force, starting
from
and example of point of origin;
its
perspective, studied intensively during his time, provides in the dif-
fusion of Hght an example of the "multiplication of species." This multiplication
mingled
like the general
is
law of the forces that are
inter-
in space.
from
Starting
there.
Bacon attaches much
less
importance to
control of facts than to the discovery of secrets or of astonishing facts
that the experts transmit to each other
generation. to
is
him
He
the
from generation
to
welcomes with unbelievable credulity {credulitas
first
of the expert's virtues) Pliny the Elder's tales
about the diamond that was attacked by the blood of a he-goat
(PUny 32.
20. i; 37.
13),
15), the use of castor beans in
and many other fabricated
periences of peasants
facts
medicine (Pliny
borrowed from the
ex-
and old women.
Corresponding
to the experience of nature as defined here are in-
ward experiences
relating to spiritual things: the illuminations re-
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
172
ceived by the patriarchs and the prophets. Such experiences, at their
highest degree, are also shrouded in mystery: beyond virtues, be-
yond the ecstasy
Holy Ghost and divine
gifts of the
and
their various forms, each of
peace, are "states of
which
in
key
to
its
own way
re-
He who
has the
such spiritual secrets also possesses thereby the key to
human
veals experiences impossible to convey in words."
sciences.
Bacon's doctrine, with
all
its
shortcomings and even because of
them, admirably points up the impatience with which certain of the thirteenth century
endured the limitations which the "phi-
losophy of the Parisians" sought to impose on
Their contention was that true
is
the universe.
outside such limitations,
wisdom know what
men
en-
to do.
Witelo and the Perspectivists
XVIII
A
reality
man and
powers where only a few rare
in an abyss of miraculous
lightened by a superior
men
kindred
characterizes
spirit
Poland between 1220 and
same time Hellenist.
as St. It
was
1230.
Thomas, at
works of Witelo, born
the
He
and was,
resided in Italy
a friend of
in
at the
William of Moerbeke, the
the request of the latter that he wrote the
Perspectiva, a compilation of the of Perga, of the Optics of
works of Euclid and Apollonius
Ptolemy (which had been translated into
Latin in the twelfth century), and especially of the Optics of Alhazen,
the
Arab
scholar.
He
translated
remarkable
Alhazen's
modern
studies of acquired visual perceptions, the basis of all ories of the
psychology of perception.
intelligentiis, in
He
also
wrote a
treatise,
the-
De
which, following the Book^ of Causes, he studied
the three Neo-Platonic hypostases: the First Cause or the One, Intelligence,
and Soul.
Like Robert Grosseteste he linked perspective metaphysics.
The symbolism
of light
to
marking the
Neo-Platonic actions of the
One was probably based on St. Augustine and the Epistle to the Romans, but he developed his symbolism through studies in per-
THE THIRTEENTH CENTURY
173
Light
spective.
a simple
is
body and
of multiplying itself: "the simplest
for this very reason capable
is
body
characterized by the
is
greatest extension; water by a greater extension than earth, air by a
and
greater extension than water, air."
Light, the most
tension;
it
fire
by a greater extension than
subtle of bodies, therefore has the greatest ex-
room for bodies; it allows models to be reflected in this way is the principle of knowledge. Neo-Platonic
has
matter and in
metaphysics has one times and which
trait
which we have already noticed
apart
sets it
from Thomism. That
is
several
the preponder-
ance of love over knowledge: "In the same being love naturally precedes knowledge edge, not because
edge makes
.
.
.
and love
knowledge
is
is its
consummated through knowl-
complement but because knowl-
multiply and live independently.
it
.
.
.
Knowledge
is
not the perfection of love; but rather, quite the contrary, knowledge is
conditioned by enjoyment and love." Finally,
we
find the
pecially optics,
in 1297,
of the
link
between experimental
and Neo-Platonic metaphysics
who was born
berg,
same
and died
became Master
ca. 1250,
after 1310.
The
in Dietrich of Vri-
of
Theology
in Paris
author of a mathematical theory
rainbow which explains the phenomenon by
fraction followed by reflection
studies, es-
a
on raindrops, he adhered
double to
re-
an Au-
gustinian and Neo-Platonic philosophy quite different from the official
doctrine of his order, the Dominicans.
trine of the three hypostases in Proclus'
He
adhered
to the doc-
Elements of Theology and
he accepted the image of the production of things through emanation
and
their
conversion, though he reconciled
theory of Creation. Against
this,
notion of the agent intellect and identified of the
mind {abditum
memoriae
nostrae),
and immutable
it
the
and the image of God
in
and
with the hidden part
memory
(profunditas
which the
eternal laws
mentis), the depths of
truths are immediately
contrast to abstraction,
them with
he borrowed from Aristotle the
effortlessly present
which involves only the
(in
faculty of cognition).
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
174
Ramon
XIX
The
Lull
and
vast
neglected
still
dominant preoccupations
work
of
Ramon
Lull reveals the
of the last years of the thirteenth century.
His books, written in Catalan but translated for the most part into
were
designed to serve a practical aim:
to
establish
Catholicism, which he considered identical to reason,
all
over the
Latin,
all
world. His actions and an unrelenting flood of propaganda were
motivated by
and children
this
aim. Born in Majorca in 1235, he
in 1265 to devote all
years he studied the language
left his
wife
his time to his mission. For nine
and science
of the
Arabs in Majorca.
In about 1288 he proposed to the popes a plan for a crusade and for missions in the land of the infidels. In 1298, and later in 1310 and 131
1,
(still
he was in Paris, where he wrote a great number of
treatises
in manuscript) against the Averroists. In 1311 he attended the
council of
Vienna and proposed the adoption of
ing Arabic and
Hebrew
in
der to prepare missionaries. vert the infidels
A man whose
Rome and in several He himself departed
and died there
passionately
activity
his plan for teach-
universities in or-
Tunis
for
to con-
in 1315.
committed
and
to a practical task,
was motivated by
vision,
a
Ramon
a mystic
Lull wrote
Dialogues and Canticles of the Lover and the Beloved and a famous
work on what he termed general design of his oretical. fidels
Like
and
all
life,
those
his
who
heretics, Lull
Ars magna, the
Ars major
means
practical rather than the-
Middle Ages
tried in the
To
this
art of reasoning.
end he wrote
He
appealing and so easy that even the the
is
to
combat
his
make
Ars generalis
work so common people would have tried to
the
of defending the faith: a universal religion based
equally universal
in-
intended "to prove the articles of faith
through necessary reasons." or
"the great art." In keeping with the
method
of thinking.
Such was
Lull's
on an
idea of
Catholicism.
Exactly what
is
his "great art"?
could not resolve two problems:
We
first,
recall that Aristotle's logic
the discovery of the neces-
"^^^
175
THIRTEENTH CENTURY
sary premises or principles that could give to the conclusion of the
syllogism a demonstrative or scientific character; second, given the
extreme terms, the discovery of the middle term that could unite them. These are the two problems that Lull boasts of resolving in
Ars magna. His
is
rather an art of invention. This treatises:
De
an
not, strictly speaking, is
shown by
art of
the
venatione medii inter subjectum
compendiosa inveniendi veritatem, seu
titles
some
of
of his
praedicatum; Ars
et
magna
ars
reasoning but
major; ars
et
inveniendi particularia in universalibus; quaestiones per artem de-
monstrativam seu inventivam
"Each science has
own
its
solubiles:
principles,
For
the principles of other sciences.
Ars inventiva veritatum.
and they
are different
from
judgment requires a
instance,
general science with general principles in which are implied and
contained the principles of particular sciences, just as the particular is
implied by and contained in the universal." These are the open-
magna
ing words in the Ars
method that
that Aristotle
makes
had indicated
to discover the
possible the resolution of a question, that
whether a predicate given subject
all
is
we
recall
the
middle terms
is,
to
determine
true of a given subject: by identifying for a
and
possible predicates
possible subjects,
We
generalis et idtima.
for a given predicate all
of necessity discover every possible
middle
term between the subject and the predicate. Lull's Ars magna generahzation of Aristotle's procedure.
He
thinks
first
is
a
of discover-
ing every possible predicate of a given subject by enumerating the
following attributes: bonitas, magnitudo, aeternitas; potestas,
sa-
pentia, voluntas; virtus, Veritas, gloria; differentia, concordia, contrarietas; tas.
The
relations.
principium,
medium
Any
questions: whether it is,
where
The
how it is,
last nine,
big
it it is
is,
combination of them, and the com-
to a
bination follows certain rules.
how
majoritas, aequalitas, minori-
predicate, according to him, can be related either to
one of these attributes or
is,
finis;
nine words designate divine attributes, the
first
With
what
it
is,
respect to a subject, he asks ten
what
{quantum), what
with what
it
is
it is
why it is, {quale), when it
made
like
of,
it is.
foregoing remarks are enough to show that Lull's Ars
magna
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
176
could not break through the circle of Aristotle's logic. His presumed art of invention
merely an
is
tain concepts, not
an
art of classifying
and combining
them. At times
art of discovering
it
cer-
seems that
he confuses order with invention. For instance, he advises the "ar-
who
tist"
deals with physics "successively to apply the ten rules to
which he
the concept about
is
doubtful" (that of nature), in other
And
words, to ask the ten questions enumerated above. (fol.
78 b.)
:
rules is
and
on the color of
"Just as a glass takes
unknown term
background, so an
species of rules to
it is
exposed {discurritur) y His
obviously a purely formal explanation;
what we ought
and
to ask of a thing
different angles, but
it
red or green
colored or illuminated by the
is
which
its
he adds
it
to
enables us to determine
examine the thing from
will never enable us to discover the answers.
Such are the main currents of thirteenth-century thought. Against the
background of
universal unity. It
dream is
their diversity
of a
one
period
trait
we have been
have been inaugurated by Innocent
III,
stands out: the
and of
organization
hierarchical
fitting that the
common
spiritual
studying should
who, more than any other
pope, defended the primacy of the spiritual power, and that the regular clergy, directly dependent on the pope, should have exercised
an important
The
role in the universities.
systems
examined derived from the same force that gave
we have
birth to the cru-
sades: the urge to spread Catholicism everywhere. This spiritual
unity was projected
upon metaphysical
reality,
and everyone, with-
out exception, believed that Neo-Platonic metaphysics (easily reconciled with the idea of the Creation), with archy,
was an exact representation
was constructed pletely
in
which temporal power was
by the spiritual power or subordinated
the terrestrial city were in the sense that an office
by a higher power
The
its
is
autonomous
whose
unity and
of this reality.
limits
in the
A
its
either absorbed to
it.
hier-
political ideal
If
com-
reason and
minds of some,
it
was
have been precisely delineated
autonomous.
thrust toward unity
was
decisively checked. In the fourteenth
century, even as the throes of the
Hundred
Years'
War
were giving
shape to the nationalism that was to destroy forever the dream of
177
THE THIRTEENTH CENTURY
political
and Christian
shattered.
unity, the
For the truth
is
image of the universe was being
that the very elements that the thirteenth-
century thinkers had accepted for their edifice surreptitiously contributed to
method,
seemed
tem
its
collapse. Platonism, Aristotelianism, the experimental
mathematics, at the
time
to
ancient
of Christian thought
pletely
traditions
—
all
these
forces
have had a part in the construction of a
were found in the
independent of the Christian
light of
that sys-
day to be com-
belief in a supernatural destiny.
Bibliography
I
to III
Texts Dominicus
Gundissalinus.
De
divisione
philosophiae.
by
Edited
Baur.
Beitrdge, Vol. IV. Miinster in Westfalen, 1903.
De immortalite animae. Edited by Bulow. Ibid., Vol. De unitate. Edited by Correna. Ibid., Vol. I, 1891. De anima. Edited by Loewenthal. Berlin, 1890.
.
.
.
William of Auvergne. Opera omnia. 2
II.
1897.
vols. Paris, 1674.
Studies Callus, D, "Introduction of Aristotelian Learning to Oxford," Proceedings of
the British Academy, XXIX (1943). Chroust, A. "The Definitions of Philosophy in the 'De divisione philosophiae'
Dominicus Gundissalinus," The
of
New
Scholasticism,
XXV
(1951), 253-
81.
Denifle, H.,
and Chatelain, A. Chartularium
4 vols. Paris, 1889-97. Gilson, E. "La notion d'existence chez d'histoire doctrinale et litteraire .
"La Servante de
la
universitatis parisiensis. Vol.
I.
Guillaume d'Auvergne," Archives
du moyen
age,
XV
(1946), 55-91.
theologie," Etudes de philosophie medievale (Stras-
bourg, 192 1), pp. 30-50.
McKeon, R.
"Aristotelianism
in
Western Christianity"
in
Environmental
Factors in Christian History. Chicago, 1939. Pp. 206-31. Rashdall, H. The Universities of Europe in the Middle Ages. 3 vols. Oxford, 1936.
Van
Steenberghen, F. Aristotle in the
West; The Origins of Latin Aris-
totelianism. Translated by L. Johnston. Louvain, 1955. .
The
Philosophical
1955-
178
Movement
in the Thirteenth Century.
New
York,
THE THIRTEENTH CENTURY
179
IV
VI
to
Texts Albert the Great. Opera omnia. Edited by A. Borgnet. 38 vols. Paris, 1890-99. .
On
and the
the Intellect
Selections,
I,
Intelligible.
Book
I.
Translated by R. McKeon.
326-75.
Alexander of Hales. Summa theologica. 4 vols. Quaracchi, 1924-48. St. Bonaventure. Opera omnia. 10 vols. Quaracchi, 1882-1902. .
Commentary on
the Sentences,
I,
3,
i.
Translated by R. McKeon.
Selectio ns,\\, 118-48.
De
.
reductione
Therese Healy. .
artium
ad theologiam. Translated by
Bonaventure, N.Y., 1939. The Mind's Road to God. Translated by G. Boas.
Sr.
Emma
St.
New
York, 1953.
Studies Boehner, Ph. "The System of Metaphysics of Alexander of Hales," Franciscan Studies, II (1951), 157-201.
Bourke, V. "The Provenance of the
De
apprehensione Attributed to Albertus
Magnus," Speculum, XVIII (1943), 91-98. Gilson, E.
"L'Ame
raisonnable chez Albert
doctrinale et litteraire .
du moyen
age,
le
Grand," Archives d'histoire
XIV
(1943-45), 5-72. "La philosophie franciscaine," in Saint Francois d'Assise. Paris, 1927.
Pp. 148-75. -.
The Philosophy
F. Sheed.
London,
of St. Bonaventure. Translated by
I.
Trethowan and
1938.
Grabmann, M. "Albertus Magnus Theologe Philosoph und Naturforsher," Philosophisches Jahrbuch der Gorresgesellschaft,
LXI
(1951), 473-80.
Kennedy, L. "The Nature of the Human Intellect According to St. Albert the Great," Modern Schoolman, XXXVII (i960), 121-37. Klubertanz, G. "Esse and Existere in the Philosophy of St. Bonaventure," Mediaeval Studies, YUl (1946), 169-88. O'Donnell, C. The Psychology of St. Bonaventure and St. Thomas Aquinas. Washington, D.C., 1937. Pegis, A. "St. Bonaventure and the Problem of the Soul as Substance." Chap, ii in St. Thomas and the Problem of the Soul in the Thirteenth Century. Toronto, 1934.
VII
to
XI
Texts St.
Thomas Aquinas. Opera omnia. Parma 73. Reprinted:
New
York, 1948.
edition.
25 vols. Parma,
1852-
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
l8o St.
Thomas Aquinas. Summa Translated
disputatae.
theologica.
by
Summa
EngHsh
the
contra Gentiles. Quaestiones
Dominican
Fathers.
London
(B.O.W.) Basic Writings. Edited by A. Pegis. 2 vols.
.
New
York, 1948.
Sources
De Wulf, M.
i,tudes historiques sur I'esthetique de S.
Thomas d'Aquin. Lou-
vain, 1896.
Finance,
de. Etre et agir
J.
dans
la
philosophic de
S.
Thomas. BibHotheque
des Archives de philosophie. Paris, 1945. Forest, A. La structure metaphysique du concret scion S. Paris,
Thomas d'Aquin.
93 1.
1
Garrigou-Lagrange, R. God: His Existence and His Nature. 2 lated by B. Rose.
Gilson, E.
The
vols.
Trans-
London, 1934-36.
Christian Philosophy of St.
Thomas Aquinas.
Translated by
New
L. K. Shook.
York, 1956. S. Thomas d'Aquin. ("Les moralistes chretiens.") Paris, 1941. Grabmann, M. Der gottliche Grund menschlicher ahrheitsdrXenntnis nach .
W
Augustinus und Thomas von Aquin. Cologne, 1924. Das Seelenleben des heilingen Thomas von Aquin. Munich, 1924. Lottin, O. he droit naturel chez S. Thomas et ses predecesseurs. Bruges, .
1926.
Psychologic et morale aux XII^ et XII I^
.
siccles.
Vol. L Problem es de
Lou vain, 1942. Maritain, J. St. Thomas Aquinas. London, 1946. Peghaire, J. Intellectus et ratio scion S. Thomas d'Aquin. Paris, 1936. Roland-Gosselin, B. La doctrine politique de S. Thomas d'Aquin. Paris, Psychologic.
Sertillanges,
Foundations of
A.
Thomistic Philosophy.
Anstruther. London, 193 1. }. de. Les principes de la philsophie thomiste.
Tonquedec,
Translated
La
1928.
by G.
critique de la
connaissance. Paris, 1929.
XII to
XV
Texts Giles of Lessines.
Le traite "De unitate formae" de M. De Wulf. Lou vain, 1901.
Gilles
de Lessines: Texte
inedit et etude.
Henry
of Ghent. .
Summa
theologica. 3 vols. Ferrara, 1646.
Quodlibeta. 2 vols. Venice, 1608.
of Brabant. Die Impossibilia des Siger von Brabant. Edited by C. Baeumker. Beitrdge, Vols. II, VI. Miinster, 1898. L'Opuscule de Siger de Brabant "De Aeternitate Mundi." Edited by W. Dwyer. Louvain, 1937.
Siger
.
THE THIRTEENTH CENTURY
101
Studies D. The Condemnation of
Callus,
Thomas
St.
Oxford. Westminster, Md.,
at
1946.
Hocedez, E. "Gilles de
Rome
et
Henri de Gand" Gregorianum (1927).
Kendzierski, L. "Eternal Matter and Former in Siger of Brabant,"
The Modern
Schoolman, XXXll (1955), 223-41. Mandcnnet, P. Siger de Brabant et I'averroisme latin au Xlll^ siecle. 2 vols. "Les philosophes beiges," Vols. VI, VII.) Louvain, 1908-11. Maurer, A. "Esse and Essentia in the Metaphysics of Siger of Brabant," Mediaeval Studies, VIII (1946), 68-85. "Another Redaction of the Metaphysics of Siger of Brabant?" Mediaeval Studies, XI (1949), 224-32. Paulus, J. Henri de Gand. Essai sur les tendances de sa metaphysique. Paris, .
1938.
Van Steenberghen.
"Siger
of
Brabant,"
The Modern Schoolman, XXIX
(1951), 11-27.
XVI
to
XIX
Texts
De naturis rerum. Edited by T. Wright. London, 1863. De motu cordis. Text in C. Baeumker, Des Alfred von {Alfredus Anglicus) Schrift De motu cordis. Beitrdge, Vol.
Alexander Neckham. Alfred of Sareshel. Sarcshel
XXIII. Miinster in Westfalen, 1923. Dietrich of Vriberg.
Meister
De
Dietrich,
intellectu et intelligibili.
sein
Leben,
seine
De
habitus. In E. Krebs,
Wissenschaft.
Beitrdge,
Vol.
V.
Miinster in Westfalen, 1906. .
De
Thierry
esse et essentia. In E. Krebs,
de
Fribourg,"
"Le
traite
'De esse
et
essentia'
de
Revue Neo-Scolastique de philosophic, XVIII
(1910,511-36. Lull. Opera omnia. Edited by I. Salzimger. 8 vols. Mainz, 1721-42. Robert Grosseteste. Shorter philosophical treatises in L. Baur, Die philosophische Werl^e des Robert Grosseteste. Beitrdge, Vol. IX. Miinster in
Ramon
Westfalen, 1912.
(The
last
part contains the
Summa
philosophica, er-
roneously attributed to Robert.) .
On
Truth.
On
the Truth of Propositions.
Translated by R. McKeon. Selections,
I,
On
the
Knowledge
of
God.
263-87.
On Ught or the Beginning of Forms. Translated by C. Riedl. Milwaukee, 1942. Roger Bacon. Opus Maius. Edited by J. Bridges. 2 vols. Oxford, 1 897-1900. Opus Maius. Translated by R. Burke. 2 vols. Philadelphia, 1928. .
1
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
82
De
Witelo. Vol.
III.
Extracts from the Perspectiva in C. Baeumker, und Naturjorscher des XIII ]ahrhunderts. Beitrdge,
intelligentiis.
Witelo, ein Philosoph
Miinster in Westfalen, 1908.
Studies Callus, D. (ed.). Robert Grosseteste: Scholar
and Bishop. Oxford,
1955.
Carton, R. L'experience physique chez Roger Bacon, contribution a I'etude de la methode et de la science experimentale au XIII^ siecle. Paris, 1924. Crombie, A. Robert Grosseteste and the 0rigi?js of Experitnentd Science, iioo-iyoo. Oxford, 1953. Crowley, T. Roger Bacon: the Problem of the Soul in His Philosophical
Commentaries. Louvain, 1950. S. Roger Bacon and His Search for a Universal Science. Oxford, 1952. Gauthier, L. "Un psychologue de la fin du XIIP siecle: Thierry de FriEaston,
bourg," Revue Augustinienne
,
XV
(1909), 657-73;
XVI
(1910),
178-
206, 541-66.
Hunt, R. "Alexander Neckham." Unpublished thesis. Cf. F. Ueberweg, Grundiss der Geschichte der Philosophic, p. 731. Lacombe, G. "Alfredus Anglicus in Metheora," Aus der Geisteswelt des
M. Grabmann. Miinster in Westfalen, 1935. Roger Bacon. Essays contributed by various writers. Ox-
Mittelalters, Festgabe Little,
A.
(ed.).
ford, 1914.
Lynch,
L.
"The Doctrine
of
Divine
Grosseteste," Mediaeval Studies, III Peers, E. Fool of
Love: The Life of
Ideas
and
Illumination
in
Robert
(1941), 161-73.
Ramon
Lull.
London,
1946.
Sharp, D. Franciscan Philosophy at Oxford in the Thirteenth Century. Oxford, 1930.
*
THE FOURTEENTH CENTURY I
Duns The
Scot us
symptom
first
of collapse
is
found in the trend inaugurated
by Duns Scotus, the "Subtle Doctor." His career was very
Born
England before
in
1270,
he was educated
at
brief.
Oxford, where he
acquired the traditional taste for mathematics, which was supposed to
provide a model of certainty.
he taught in Aristotle
and
De rerum
Paris.
his
From
1305 until his death in 1308
In England he wrote his commentaries on
Questions on the Sentences of Peter
Lombard
(the
principio, attributed to this period, has been proven in-
authentic); and in Paris, the Reportata parisiensia and the Colla-
De
tiones. In the
ority of the
Duns
perfectione statuum he shows the religious superi-
mendicant monks over the regulars.
Scotus has no place in any of the currents that
lowed. Those
who would make him an Augustinian
we have
fol-
are unable to
account for his sharp criticism of the school's most precious theories those of intellectual
knowledge
as illumination, of
:
seminal reasons
contained in matter, and of innate knowledge contained in the soul.
But he
is
even
less
a Thomist, for his
most celebrated doctrines
actual existence of matter, individuation through
the priority of the will those of St.
One tion
is
form
—the
{haecceity),
—are deliberately and consciously opposed
to
Thomas.
of the essential traits that isolates
the outright affirmation of
183
him and
what might be
gives
him
distinc-
called the histori-
1
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
84
cal character of the Christian vision of the universe. Creation, in-
carnation, the attribution of the merits of Christ acts
on the part of God,
—these
in the fullest sense of the
are free
word; that
is,
they are acts which might not have occurred and which are depend-
who
ent on the initiative of God, will. St.
the motives of that jects
God
why he
is
has no reason other than his
Anselm's credo ut intelligam and the attempt are diametrically opposed to this
lengthened in a singular
of faith, the credibilia,
way
"which are
the the
all
to
new list
own
examine
spirit.
And
of pure ob-
more
certain
to
Catholics because they are not based on our blind and often vacillating
judgment but find firm support
Omnipotence, incommensurability, truth, justice, providence
— almost
in the
most
solid of verities."
infinity, life, will, all
omnipresence,
the divine attributes that St.
Thomas deduced from the notion of God as the cause of the world — are to Duns Scotus objects of faith. He nevertheless acknowledges a rational proof of the existence of
mundi
that forces us to pass
from the changing being of our
perience to necessary being that has
proof could not have as it
God, the proof a contingentia its
own
has, the notion of "the being greater than
can be conceived to exist"; for idea,
but one
beings,
we have
and the
first
Anselm
starting point, as St.
its
this
notion
insists that
which no other being
is
not a simple, innate
fashioned for ourselves on the basis of
step
to
is
show
These views could be summarized
that in
ex-
reason for being. This
it is
finite
not contradictory.
one statement: Duns Scotus
exhibits hardly a trace of Neo-Platonism.
The
concept of the con-
tinuity of all things, of a hierarchy of grades of living beings, has
almost disappeared.
If
Augustinianism affirmed continuity in being
and therefore continuity
in
knowledge, and
Thomism
continuity in
being but discontinuity in knowledge, the doctrine of Scotus might be formulated: discontinuity in being and discontinuity in knowledge."^
As
a matter of fact.
Duns
Scotus used every concept that had
gained ascendancy during the thirteenth century: possible
and agent ^
The
intellect,
matter and form, universal and individual, will
affirmation of the continuity of forms
the authenticity of
which
intellect
is
dubious.
is
found only
in
De rerum
principio,
THE FOURTEENTH CENTURY
185
and understanding. But whereas
in the case of earHer thinkers these
concepts evoked each other, were associated with each other, fitted
and formed
into a hierarchy,
aim
a coherent pattern, the
of
Duns
Scotus seems to have been to exhibit independent terms, each of
which has added
and
sufficient reality:
Scotus seems to abandon the principle of universal analogy
which was the moving and even
force behind continuity for Bonaventure
Thomas. By declaring
for St.
that the being has a univ-
and not an equivocal sense with respect
ocal tures
(that
whole
is,
that
signifies
it
the
to
God and
is
same
and
title
from one
in a derived sense, to another
in the
same way
which consequently provides no means
—God
God
being in a nobler sense. For the creature and
lated by the
his crea-
same thing), he removes the
basis of the analogical relation that allows passage
term (the creature), being
who
terms which can, of course, be
each other but which do not require each other.
to
Duns
full
are re-
notion of being,
to the
them by com-
of separating
paring them.
The discontinuity is manifested first in the theory of matter. Here Duns Scotus contradicts both Augustinianism and Thomism: the former because he denies the existence of seminal reasons in matter,
and the
because he denies the Peripatetic principle that there
latter
no potency which can make matter
is
exist
without form. In short,
he denies what the two theories, which contrast so sharply in other
common:
ways, have in
(in Augustinianism) that
makes
ter to exist
it
the link between matter
causes matter to contain an inner principle
form and which
aspire to
(in
Thomism)
only relative to the form that makes
Scotus (like
Henry
tinct idea, has
objection that
its if
of
Ghent) thinks
own
this
and form which
is
actuality.
He
it
an actuaUty.^ Duns
that matter, since is
causes mat-
it
has a dis-
not stopped by Aristotle's
true a composite being
made
of
form and
matter consists of two actual beings that are added to each other,
and
that the composite being
Duns tion in a ^
no longer has unity.
Scotus' theory of haecceity solves the
manner
problem of individua-
that obviously runs counter to both
In II Sententiarum, disL, xii, ed.
Wadding, VI, 664-99.
Thomism and
1
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
86
We
Augustinianism.
that
recall
the
extended their
Peripatetics
lowest classification of genera and species to the lowest or most
and
specialized species,
individual beings in which specific
telligible to the
tributed;
that they refused to attribute anything in-
form was
dis-
they attributed purely numerical division to matter, to
the addition of accidents to specific form.
We
also recall that the
Augustinians, contemplating the supernatural destiny of the individual soul, conferred on intelligible to itself
it
name
it
independent self-knowledge, making
even though singular, and repudiated in the
of faith the theory of individuation through matter. Traces of
Augustinianism are undoubtedly found in the thinking of the
Duns
Franciscan
Scotus to acknowledge the Thomistic thesis, to be:
form
lieve that nature or specific
same
the
and
species,
would be
to believe that
is
the
same
in every individual in
Averroes"
to revert to "the accursed
human
^
nature, intrinsically undivided, can be
divided only quantitatively, as homogeneous water might be distributed in different vessels.
But Duns Scotus had a much more
general aim: to give to every individual being as such an intelligibility
analogous to that which the Peripatetics give to species, that
a determination through positive
and
essential characteristics
not through negative and accidental ones. "Socraticity"
is
positive even before the existence of Socrates in matter,
of changes in quantity
sists in spite
Socrates. It
is
Since this entity in the matter to to the
body
is
it
per-
affecting the real
included neither in specific form (equinity) nor
which
linked (the corporeal structure
it is
of every horse, for instance),
side form, outside matter,
is
common
look for
it
out-
in
must look
mind
for haecceity in
that passing
from
an ultimate
species to in-
not the same as passing from genus to species:^
from genus
'Vol. VI, p. 405. *Vol. VI, p. 413
we must
and consequently outside the composite
We
But we must bear
dividual beings in passing
and
Scotus to posit a determinate entity, haecceity.
being formed by them. reality.
and
something
the unity of the individual being, universally accepted,
Duns
that forces
and accidents
is,
to species, the
genus
is
to the difference as a
THE FOURTEENTH CENTURY
187
potential being
to the
is
form
that determines
genus and difference are fused in
it,
most specialized
species
dividuaUty for
perfection. It follows that in one
its
quite definite:
is
and
that
unique reaHty. Against
a
it
why
is
this,
the
does not require in-
and the same
in-
dividual being (a horse) "the singular entity (the haecceity of the
horse) and the specific entity are formally distinct realities." This
means
that individuality
simply added to the species without
is
there being any intelligible
bond
importance of
obvious in
this trait is
Thomas' conception of Platonic tradition,
we
things, not as ours, in
St.
Duns
Scotus' criticism of St.
Neo-
angelic knowledge. Following in the
Thomas
The
of continuity between the two.
held that the angels
know
singular
do, but because they possess an intellect superior to
which knowledge of singulars
Duns
universals. In the thinking of
contained in knowledge of
is
Scotus such continuity
for-
is
ever impossible.
Duns
makes matter an
Scotus
actual reality even without form,
and he makes the individual being species.
way he
In the same
activity that
to a certain
is
form from the
sensible
image wherever
it
is
to sepa-
may
potentially; but the distinctive role of the possible intellect act of understanding,
and
it
the total cause of this act.
is
product of abstraction,
telligible species, a
an
degree autonomous with respect to the
agent intellect: the distinctive role of the agent intellect rate the specific
from
a positive reaUty distinct
attributes to the possible intellect
is
exist
is
The
the in-
necessary not for pro-
ducing the act of understanding, which derives solely from the possible intellect,
but for relating the act to
also believes that the distinction
between
this or that object.^
acts is
made
by that between objects even though the distinction solely
from the
intellectual powers.
and Augustinian illuminism of
Henry
and of
of
Ghent
is
principles
contrast
He
obvious only itself
between
derives
his theory
counters the thesis
that sensible objects cannot illuminate the soul
that divine enlightenment
first
The
also obvious.
He
which
is
necessary by citing the certainty
are clearly
apprehended
as
soon
as their
terms are apprehended, the certainty of experience, and the inner "Vol.
Ill,
pp. 362, 365.
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
100
autonomous
data
the
of
certainty
consciousness
of
—
and
spirit
in direct contrast to
the primacy of the will over understanding.
behind the good
known
mands understanding" by ject;
it
direct,
Thomism, he
asserts
certainty.
In the same
trails
examples of
all
No
matter
how
far
it
by understanding, the will "com-
directing
follows that "understanding,
it
to consider this or that ob-
the cause of volition,
if it is
is
a
The aim of Duns Scotus is not to ofThomism the Augustinian view that makes
cause dominated by the will." fer as a substitute for
love rather than will
knowledge the
from understanding
just as
final
end of
things, but to free
he freed matter from form, the
individual being from the species, the intellect from divine illumination.
For these considerations
that the will
is
all
point mainly to the conclusion
wholly free: "Nothing other than the will
is
the
total cause of volition in the will."
Duns
Scotus carries his psychological views over into theology.
There can be no subjugation of God's his understanding.
God
To
are not in any
way
writings of Scotus do
we
creations of his will,
good conceived by
and nowhere
find a theory of the primacy of will
the creation of eternal verities. sible
will to a
be sure, the possibles rationally conceived by
The
what
will cannot will
is
in the
and of impos-
But the possibles conceived by God's
and contradictory.
reason impose no restrictions on his creative will: "There
is
no
cause for the divine will to have willed this or that, other than the fact that the divine will
pend on the "no rule
The
is
is
Thus
the divine will."
rule of goodness; instead, the will
is
will does not de-
the
first rule,
and
right unless accepted by the divine will."
thesis of the relation
between the good and the divine will
strongly influenced the moral philosophy of precepts that cause us to
know
the
Duns
Scotus.
good depend on
The moral
a divine law;
but the good derives solely from the fact that these precepts have
been willed by God; and since his will that
God might have
Decalogue.
given
is
arbitrary,
commandments
it is
conceivable
other than those in the
\
THE FOURTEENTH CENTURY The
and
arbitrariness
Duns
radical discontinuity that
Scotus in-
troduced into even the divine reaUty dominated his conception of poHtics.
A
fusion of social atomism and unbridled authoritarianism,
conception was the reflection in society of the vision of the uni-
this
verse that
wt have been examining: men were
at first equal,
but
they willingly sacrificed their independence to an authority established by
them
which they subjected
in order to limit the dangers to
each other on account of their egoism; since that time the authority that they set
up has become omnipotent and
and revoking properties
tablishing, distributing,
are
no laws other than the
are
no duties other than duties
monarchy to
at the
that
to
fit;
there
him; there
God, and among such duties
beginning of the thirteenth century by a Capetian
had arrogated
The voluntarism work
to itself the absolute
Born before
God
Duns
of
Scotus found
its
of a fourteenth-century Oxonian,
power accorded
fullest expression in
Thomas Bradwardine.
he died Archbishop of Canterbury in 1349.
1290,
mathematician
who found
the
appealing, he wished only to demonstrate that the concept of
remembered mainly
as the anti-Pelagian
who
thinking there will."
is
"no reason or necessary law in
Furthermore, "divine will
of every motion," is
and the
necessitated by
It is
since, instead of joining
thrall's ®
dependence on
Cf. B, Landry,
Duns
God
prior to his
the efficient cause of every thing,
freest act that
can be accomplished by
will
was widely accepted during the
a dry theory, far
God
to
man
removed from mysticism
through meditation and
makes man's dependence on God something
it
causality. In his
God.
His theory of the enthralled fourteenth century.
is
is
almost went so far as
deny outright any causality other than divine
man
A
Anselmian proof of the existence of
the most perfect being does not imply a contradiction; but he
to
is
(who were being persecuted and
by the Franciscan's theory).^
it
the
he sees
as
positive laws instituted by
the forcible conversion of Jews
banished
absolute, the chief es-
his lord:
Scot, pp. 233-45.
"Man
is
external,
the thrall of
love,
like
a
God, but by
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
190 his
own
free will
and not by
saw
The
theory was represented
who
condemned in 1347. Among the condemned which said that "God wills that a man should
forty of his theses
theses
were those
and be
sin
constraint."
by the Cistercian John of Mirecourt,
at the University of Paris
a sinner, that
he
is
the cause of sin as sin, of the evil of
guilt as evil of guilt, the author of sin as sin."
His theological de-
terminism, through the Englishman John WycliiTe, influenced Luther.
Thus
the doctrine of
Duns
Scotus,
which
attracted
many com-
mentators and was even taught in the leading universities of Europe,
was
II
new spirit.
a fountainhead of the
The
Universities in the Fourteenth
and Fifteenth Centuries The
social
importance of the universities during the fourteenth
century and the
first
part of the fifteenth century can hardly be ex-
By pragmatic
aggerated.
by Louis XII in
sanction, reconfirmed by a decree issued
1499, privileges
were granted
the universities in the conferring of benefices.
appointment
to
The
years of unipre-
to the office of curate in a city parish.
But
the freedom that existed within the university
elsewhere.
Long
and canon law) were a
versity study (three years in theology
requisite to
to the graduates of
university
was "the
oracle of the
had no counterpart
mind and
European thought, the most redoubtable power
fronted the legal powers.
No
body
freer,
is
the guide
that ever con-
no organization more
democratic. Meetings of societies, faculties or nations, and general
meetings; the right to legislate on ing, justice; in
tation
elected
.
.
.
and
some
all
—administration, teach-
matters
of them, students are even accorded represen-
and professors are recruited by for a specified time (rector
or six months, or for one year at most)
;
professors; authorities are
and proctor for against the
three, four,
meddUng
of the
central authority or local powers, the solid armature of uncontested privileges; fiscal exemption, the right to be
and, to enforce these guarantees, the
power
judged by one's peers to
suspend instruction
THE FOURTEENTH CENTURY
191 .
such
.
.
The
middle of the
universities continued to flourish until the
fifteenth century,
when
and influence even speculation
came
and consecrated by popes and
the charter recognized
is
"^
kings."
weakened
their
power
as they reinforced the central authority,
when
diverse circumstances
was abandoned, and when preparation
Then
their sole concern.
for degrees be-
the universities ceased for a long
time to be the centers of activity they had once been, and the ual
life
But
spirit-
continued under different conditions.
and
in the fourteenth
fifteenth centuries
the spirit of in-
dependence was manifested in bold, new speculations
much more
closely related to the tradition of the twelfth century than to that of
the thirteenth.
The whole
era
was dominated by the
the antiqui and the moderni.
The
conflict
ancients were in
between
reality the in-
novators of the thirteenth century, deeply immersed in discussions
motivated by the concepts of Aristotle and his Arab commentators:
form and matter, the principle of individuation, agent possible intellect, intelligible telligences of the heavens.
and
sensible species, the
The moderns were
intellect
moving
those who, far
providing contradictory or supporting evidence on the jected
them
as senseless
and turned back
vision of the universe that
we saw
to the free
tempt
issues,
and the
William of Conches. There was no longer an St.
Anselm, or
Bonaventure, or
the Hmits of reason, as in the case of St. speculation unfolded freely
re-
outlined in the eleventh and
to rationalize faith, as in the case of St.
luminate reason, as in the case of
in-
from
and uncluttered
twelfth centuries: the nominalism of Roscelin and Abelard atomistic theory of
and
to
atil-
to prescribe
Thomas. Philosophical
and independently.
In the midst of such agitations no part of the old system of Christianity could survive. lated
The power
of the
emperor was annihi-
by the splintering of the empire into more than three hundred
principalities that
eroded the central power. "As the princes devour
the empire, so the people will devour the princes," predicted Nicho'
Imbart de
la
Tour, Les origines de la reforme,
I,
347, 527
fl.
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
192
Cusa
las of
thereby, that
in 1433.^
and
it
resulted
was
in
The power
of the popes
was not enhanced
seriously impaired by the great schism (1348)
the
Council of Constance
and the
(1414-1418)
Council of Basel (1433), both of which simply intensified the conflict
who believed in the (whom they considered an and the Ultramontanists, who be-
between the advocates of Conciliarism,
supremacy of the council over the pope administrator of the Church), lieved that the pope
had unlimited power. As the
traditional
powers
declined, national royalties gained incomparable strength.
The
masters of the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries took an ac-
tive part in the diverse conflicts that terests
and focused attention on
them were
The
so
many
and were
active politically
involved so
many
practical in-
judicial concepts.
Most
of
jurists as well as philosophers.
great initiator of nominalism, William of
Ockham, was
also
one of the opponents of John XXII. Excommunicated in 1328, he
was received
at the court of
Emperor Louis
of Bavaria,
found John of Jandun, another enemy of the pope. In
his
where he Defensor
pads, John of Jandun had maintained that "the universaUty of the citizens
1327).
was the only human
legislator" (he
William remained there
for
wrote pamphlets against the pope,
was excommunicated
more than twenty
among them
errorum papae Johannis XXII and a vast
the
political
years
in
and
Compendium
work, the Dia-
logus inter magistrtim et discipulum de imperatorum et pontificum potestate.
Another nominalist, Durand of Saint Pour^ain, was the
author of the treatise
De
great schism caused
Henry
jurisdictione ecclesiastica et
of
de legihus. The
Hainbuch, the mathematician and
astronomer, to write after 1378 numerous works on the require-
ments for peace in the Church; but he nomics and
politics.
defended Conciliarism hand, went over after
becoming
at
Basel. Nicholas
to the pope's side at the
wrote works on eco-
of Cusa,
on the other
Council of Constance and,
a cardinal, took a leading role in all of the eccle-
siastical affairs of his ^
also
In the fifteenth century Cardinal Peter of Ailly
time: the internal reform of the clergy in Ger-
Quoted by Vansteenberghe, Le Cardinal Nicolas de Cues
(Paris,
1920), p. 47.
THE FOURTEENTH CENTURY
193
many, the refutation of against the
Turks
The Beginnings
Ill
A
the Hussites,
and preparations
for a crusade
in 1454.
Nominalism
of
study of the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries brings us face
to face
with a generation of
who had
men whose minds were
cold and sober,
the religious enthusiasm that animated the genera-
lost
and who had acquired, through the
tions of the great crusades,
complicated diplomacy necessitated by the most this era, the clear
and
For under the blows of the nominalists, the metaphysical
trine.
structure erected during the thirteenth century collapsed.
inaUsm of special
this
universals. It
metaphysical
Platonists thought they
was
a
new
which
spirit
treated as
realities that the Peripatetics
had discovered, which
and relegated the affirmations of
and the
stressed experience
domain
religion to the
of pure
where any communication with reason was impossible.
The
of the nominalists
first
was the Dominican Durand of Saint
who
Pour^ain (in the Auvergne), Bishop of Meaux,
He
The nom-
period was not simply a particular solution to the
problem of
fictitious all the
faith
during
trivial issue
positive outlook that characterized their doc-
died in 1334.
refused to accept the authority of any doctor "no matter
celebrated or solemn he
may
be."
sensible
and
sary but
which no one has ever
tellect
intelligible species
whose is
which
he viewed St.
The
Thomas deemed
seen. Also fictitious
agent intellect
is
fundamental
sensible images,
must be apprehended through
But everything
is
more than
reversed
a certain
if
manner
out paying attention to
its
is
reaUty, since
neces-
the agent in-
is
indeed necessary
taken for the specific form which
reality of things; the
how
as fictitious the
abstractive operation, rightly understood, in
implies existence. universal
And
no way
when
the
the fundamental it
not given in
is
a higher operation.
the universal springs
from nothing
of considering the sensible
image with-
individual properties; the universal do:s
not exist prior to such consideration, and
it
differs
from the
individ-
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
194
from the determinate. Conse-
ual being as the indeterminate differs
quently the problem of individuation
fictitious;
is
the species exists prior to the individual being, since dividualizes
Theology
is
way
In the same of
and the truth
it;
which
ual being,
the
first
it
assumes that
it
asks w^hat in-
that nothing exists but the individ-
is
object of our knowledge.
the Franciscan Peter Auriol,
and died
at Paris in 131 8
who became Master
Avignon
at
in 1322 at the
court of Pope John XXII, his protector, shows a definite preference for
nominalism in
universals goes
deed,
"it is
his
the Sentences.
no deeper than knowledge
nobler to
monstratum) than This formula
Commentary on
is
to
of
of individual realities; in-
know an individual, designated reaUty {deknow it in an abstract, universal manner." ^
illuminated by Peter Auriol's attempted analysis of
knowledge: things produce in the differ in strength
and
{esse intentionale) ,
3.
"impressions" that
intellect
may
precision; consequently they produce in the
an "appearance" which Peter also
intellect
Knowledge
calls
an intentional being
(forma specularis), a concept or a
reflection
conception, or an objective appearance
—
all
synonyms designating,
not the Thomistic species or intermediary through which the soul
knows
a thing, but the true object of
note that his semblance reaUty distinct
is
from what
in it
knowledge.
represents;
it
the thing
is
ent" in the mind, but only to the extent that the mind.
ception"
when
He
is
adds that there
is
knowledge
wholly imperfect and
is
therefore
means from confusion
of
should also
and
itself,
a
"pres-
actually visible to
genus when the "con-
knowledge
distinct.
from the universal to clarity
it is
indistinct,
becomes more perfect and more
it
knowledge
We
no way an image of the thing with
The
of species
progression of
to the singular,
which
distinction.
William of Ochjiam
IV
The
Uam
greatest of the nominalists
of
Ockham, who deduced
was born between 1280 and 'Vol.
I,
p.
8i6b
all
was the English Franciscan Wilthe consequences of the theory.
1290, studied at
He
Oxford, and died in
195
THE FOURTEENTH CENTURY
1349 or 1350. In the fourteenth
and
{venerabilis inceptor)
the venerable initiator
he was called
fifteenth centuries
of nominalism, the
monarch or standard-bearer {antesignanus) of the nominaUsts, and his
were
associates
nominaHsts
indifferently
called
{nominates),
terminists, or conceptists.
WilHam's arguments against the existence of universals were not new. They were used in the eleventh and twelfth centuries and go back through Boethius to Aristode's discussion of Plato's ideas: since the universal
is
supposed
individual being, which plain singulars
is
is
independently
to exist
it
must be an
contradictory; to posit universals to ex-
not to explain but to double beings (application of
economy previously employed by Peter by WiUiam in this way: nunquam ponenda est
the celebrated principle of
Auriol and stated
pluralitas sine necessitate)',
finally,
to
put universals in singular
mind would extricate them through make them individual beings.
things from which the tion
is
also to
But neither does William,
and
to all the ancient
versals in
sio
animae) or
word
words
to
on
this point to
Boethius
commentators of the Categories, place uni-
words themselves.
the significations of a
faithful
still
abstrac-
He
attributes
them
instead either to
(intentio animae, conceptus animae, pas-
as signifiers of something. In the second
sense they are conventional since
words are a human
institution; but
in the first sense they are natural universals {universalia naturalia).
By designating
universals as signs or significations,
William
(as
Abelard had done before him) transposed the question of the nature of universals into that of their use in knowledge.
and
this
accounts in full for their existence
—in
They
are used
propositions to re-
place the very things that they designate (supponere pro bus). Far
from being a
fiction or a chimera, they are
ipsis re-
images which
can represent equally any of the singular things contained in their extension,
and which can replace them
signified.
One must
universal
is
never lose sight of their reference to things; the
never anything more than a predicate that can refer to
several things;
praedicatur.
as the sign replaces the thing
it is
not a thing, by virtue of the axiom: res de re non
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
196
Ockham
knowledge
teaches that primary
is
things, "the apprehensive act" which, as in
cludes a
judgment of
existence.
Such
intuition
are in
knowledge of
no way dependent on the
and of other things
joy, or sadness,
Thus
rectly." ^^
persists in the trast
the contrast
thinking of
and
case "our intellect
certain intelligibles that
such as intellection, volition,
that
man
can experience
between the sensible and the
this nominalist,
realities
the contrast between
but no longer
di-
intelligible is it
a con-
the internal.
on which they are based or modeled;
two types
of experience, the external
would have
to relate.
know whether
whether the the soul
Thus
the soul
act of
the
is
which the data of experience
neither reason nor experience enables us is
an incorruptible and immaterial form,
comprehending implies such
form of the body.^^
and reason
sensibility
and
follows that the contrast provides us with no basis
It
for positing a metaphysical reality to
to
either external
between the concrete and the abstract or between sense data
and the metaphysical it is
senses,
is
which
attains to sensible things, or internal, in
acquires particular, intuitive
intuition of singular
Stoicism, always in-
a form, or
whether
Instead, the contrast
between
Ockham, following the practice of Thomas, to separate intellect and add to them a third form, the forma cor-
inclines
Aristotle but in opposition to St.
the sensible soul
and
to
we provided with knowledge of God and his attributes. Since we do not know him intuitively, we persist in formulating our own idea of God. But such an idea, built on features
poreitatis.
Nor
are
borrowed from things within the range of our experience, enable us to penetrate to his existence as
The same effects
is
St.
true of any attempt to go back,
will not
Anselm wished to do. like St. Thomas, from
The principle of the demonstration "Everymoved is moved by something else" is neither self-
to the cause.
thing that
is
evident nor demonstrated (we shall see the attacks to which subjected by the Ockhamists) the series of causes one the
first
cause
—
is
the other
must eventually come
to a
it
was
in tracing
stopping point,
probable but cannot be conclusively proven. Here
^^
In sentential Prolegomena, qu.
'^
Quodlibit
I.
;
principle— that
qu. 10.
i.
197
"^^^
FOURTEENTH CENTURY
we have one more and the
infinity,
Such
a faith,
reason to conclude that the unity of God, his
trinity of
persons are pure articles of faith.
wholly external and impervious
well as obligatory: the acts of volition
no other reason. "God
The
is
to
are arbitrary as
Decalogue are pure
of the
whom we owe
obedience for
not obliged to perform any act;
do that which he
fore right for us to
V
commandments
on the part of God,
to reason, favors the
God
view that the moral precepts that come from
it is
there-
wills."
Parisian Nominalists of the Fourteenth Century:
Criticis7n of Peripateticism
The
teaching of the theories of William of
Ockham was
ited in the faculty of arts of the University of Paris in 1339
More than
a century later, in 1473,
hibited the teaching of
prohib-
and
1340.
an edict of Louis XI again pro-
Ockhamism, and
the masters
had
to take
an
oath to teach realism. Between the two dates, while the Oxford science languished, there arose at the University of Paris a nominalistic
movement which was
very important in the history of science
and philosophy, and which
P.
Duhem
is
the
first to
have studied
and evaluated properly. Pope Clement VI watched uneasily as the
Masters of Arts turned
the following year he of Mirecourt
to "sophistical doctrines." ^^
condemned
the theses of the Cistercian
who, inspired by Duns Scotus, declared
Ockham,
the only real cause, and, with
in 1346
During
that
John
God was
that hate for others
was
demeritorious only because prohibited by God.
In 1346 he condemned the theses of another master, Nicholas of Autrecourt, a Master of Arts.
The
next year Nicholas had to abjure
his theses publicly at a convocation of the university.
physics in
which
which the only causality
is
all
change
efficient
denied
—
is
cause
reduced is
to local
God and
in
A
corpuscular
motion, a world in
which any natural
such was the simple image of the universe that
Nicholas wanted to substitute for Aristotelian physics and metaphysics which, in his opinion, contained not a single demonstration ^"
Chartularium Universitatis parisiensis
II.
i,
p.
588.
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
198
and should be abandoned
and
in favor of the study of Aristotle's Ethics
Politics.
He
advanced
his theses
by attacking the two great notions
at the
heart of physics and metaphysics, namely causality and substance.
His method of
criticism,
which has been compared
to that of
Hume
but which was closer to that used by Sextus Empiricus in his tropes
on
causes,
known through WilHam
of Moerbeke's translation of the
Outlines of Pyrrhonism, consisted essentially in applying as the criterion of truth the principle of contradiction as
Then he could easily show known to exist, it cannot be
metaphysics.
thing
is
(through evidence that can be reduced
that
it
"from the
is
is
will be burned.
it
placed near oakum,
one
inferred through evidence
to the first principle or to the
certainty of the first principle) that another thing exists." fact that a flame
stated in
fact that
I
From
the
cannot infer positively that
can only conclude with probability that since
I
my hand grew warm whenever I placed it near a flame, oakum will grow warm under the same conditions. Such criticism destroyed Peripatetic physics, which related the bond of causality to the bond of identity (any causality being in principle the production of like
by
like),
and
in this
of the world, trast,
way
insured the unity of becoming, the unity
and consequently the unity of monotheism;
in con-
Nicholas' viewed becoming as a succession of disconnected
mo-
ments.
The same
criticism applies to the notion of substance.
The
sub-
stance posited by Aristotle as the basis for the Ukenesses provided by the senses it)
is
known
neither intuitively (since everyone
and substance another, and sions
am of
would know
nor through discursive reasoning, since likenesses are one thing it
is
not permissible to
from one thing and apply them
absolutely certain only of the objects (objectis) of
my
acts."
Among
the impossibilia
proposition: "Everything that appears to us
we
my
senses
which Siger of Brabant
fered to demonstrate through a play on logic
dream, with the result that
draw conclu-
to another. It follows that "I
is
and of-
was the following but semblance and
are not certain of the existence of
THE FOURTEENTH CENTURY
199
And
^^
anything."
Siger stressed the following argument: likenesses
are provided not by our senses but by another faculty that alone can
judge whether they are true likenesses. Nicholas simply carried the
argument
to its logical conclusion
by showing that the principle of
contradiction cannot enable us to go beyond appearances to reality.
way he
In the same
attacked the notion of the faculties of the soul,
asserting that there
from the
Parisian Nominalists
The world
of Aristotle
was the very thing that
moved
is
is
contains in actu that
moving body. This
we have
is
is
eternally.
dynamics: "Every-
The
else."
at the initial
principle
moment, but
produced by a mover that
is
in the process of being realized in the
two of the most singular
the source of
yet
his
moved by something
moment, motion
Dynamics
apart. Still to be attacked
namely
the-
examined: the theory of the motion of pro-
which can continue only by
stantly being
which
had been torn
which is
Aristotle's
mean: not only
to
also at each successive
ories that
and
basis of his system,
must be interpreted
jectiles
basis for inferring the existence of will
act of volition.
The
VI
no
is
virtue of a thrust that
is
con-
renewed; and the theory of the motion of the heavens
possible only by virtue of
The
theory of
moving
moving
intelligences that exist
intelligences in the heavens
had been
linked by the Arabs and by thirteenth-century philosophers to a theological conception of the universe to
which
it
contributed in-
dispensable support: the angeUcal hierarchy of Dionysius the Areopagite
was
realized in the separate intelligences
whose nature stim-
ulated endless speculation. Furthermore, Aristotle's ciple also served to support
of his
first
We ciple.
way
see, It
Thomism
since
it
dynamic
prin-
was the major premise
proof of the existence of God. then,
what strong
interests
were linked
to
the prin-
was attacked by the Parisian nominaUsts who ground for the development of modern
cleared the
^^Mandonnet, Siger de Brabant,
II,
77.
in
this
physics,
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
200
founded mechanics, substituted
for the
telHgences a celestial mechanics
whose
mythology of moving principles
to
same time broke the bond
those of terrestrial mechanics, and at the of continuity that the old
in-
were identical
dynamics established between the physical
theory of things and the metaphysical structure of the universe.
John Buridan was born
Bethune around 1300; he served
at
as
Rector of the University of Paris {ca. 1348) and died not long after
He
1358.
introduced the notion of impetus, which must be under-
The
stood as the antithesis of Aristotle's dynamic principle.
borrowed from the motion of Aristotle's physics:
if
a stone
is
thrown
idea
is
which was the crux of
projectiles,
into the
air,
mover im-
the
moved object a certain power that makes it capable of continuing the move by itself in the same direction; the force of the
parts to the
impetus
would and
proportional to the speed of the stone; and the motion
is
last indefinitely if
its
weight. But
if
not weakened by the resistance of the air
we
posited circumstances under
weakening would not occur, to the lessly.
motion would not
its
conceivably true of the heavens:
God
which such
cease.
Such
is
very beginning imparted
at the
heavens a uniform and regular motion that continues end-
This
thesis nullifies
moving
intelligences
and even any
special
concurrence on the part of God, likens the motions of the heavens to
the
motion of
projectiles,
and together with the principle of
inertia, establishes the unity of
mechanics.
It
also relegates to the
past not only the theory of natural places but also the finitude of
the w^orld
and geocentrism. But the new principle did not
the full measure of
applying
it
incorrectly
form motion rectilinear
its
disclose
fruits at the outset,
and Buridan himself was
when he assumed
that the circular
of a sphere
and uni-
could continue independently, just as
motion could, by virtue of an
The same mistake was made by
initial
impetus.
Albert of Saxony, Rector of the
University of Paris (1353) and Bishop of Halberstadt from 1366 until
his death in 1390.
that posed the
ferent
But
at the
problem of
same time he enunciated
celestial
mechanics in
way: "The earth moves and the heavens are
since there
was no longer any physical reason
a hypothesis
a completely at rest."
dif-
For
for the immobility of
201
THE FOURTEENTH CENTURY
the earth, as there to
had been
determine whether the
Here we
in the case o£ Aristotle,
new
it
remained only
hypothesis "will save phenomena."
find a resurgence of the old Pythagorean vision of the im-
mobihty of the heavens (never wholly absent during the Middle
Ages
since
some
Erigena and Albert the Great referred of
saw
of Plato's interpreters
Meyronnes indicated
old image had the support of
pable of bringing out
to
a preference for
new
it,
and the
Scotist Francis
around 1320; but now the
it
notions of general mechanics ca-
full significance.
its
Timaeus).
in the
it
Furthermore, and in the
same
spirit,
apart
from any hypothesis concerning natural
fined,
though not yet accurately, the relation between speed, time,
Albert of Saxony investigated the problem of gravity
and the space traversed by Nicole Oresme, as
who
and he de-
places;
falling bodies.
studied theology in Paris in 1348 and served
Bishop of Lisieux from 1378 until his death in 1382, was one of
the disseminators of the
new
mechanics. In his
celestial
Commentary
on the Bookj of the Sky and the World (written in the vernacular like a
number
of his other works), he
ment nor reason proves "several persuasive
showed
that neither experi-
the motion of the heavens, and he cited
arguments
to
show
motion while the heavens do not."
that the earth has a diurnal
He
did not forget to
draw
the
conclusion that "such considerations can be used to advantage in
defense of our Faith."
The same man
the use of geometrical co-ordinates,
discovered, before Descartes,
and before
Galileo, the exact
formula for the distance covered by a body falling with uniformly accelerated motion.
His ideas were propagated by Marsilius of Ing-
hen (died
and by Henry of Hainbuch, who served
in 1396)
tor of the University of
Vienna
in 1393 (died in 1397),
works on astronomy and physics are
still
V
later,
in
during the
last years
of his
life,
Rec-
unpublished.
Ockhamism was continued by Cardinal Peter 1420), who became Chancellor of the University and
as
and whose
of Ailly
(1350-
of Paris in 1389,
served as legate for Martin
Avignon. Like Nicholas of Autrecourt, he was convinced that
the existence of the external world could not be proved since "if
every sensible external thing were destroyed,
God
could
still
pre-
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
202
same sensations
serve the
in our souls."
Nor
is
the existence of
demonstrable; the existence of both the external world and
remains merely probable. Like the divine will
no way
in
is
WiUiam
of
Ockham, he
God
a "will that
stated that
subject to the rationality of the good,
but that the natural order and the moral order willed by
from
God
not directed by any reason to will as
is
God God
it
derive does."
not just because he loves justice but, inversely, a thing
is
just because
God
loves
it,
that
is,
because
it
is
pleases him.
Oc\hamism, Scotism, and Thomism
VII
The
history
of
the
of
universities
the
fourteenth
century
is
mainly the history of the struggle between the ancients and the moderns. Ockhamism spread, particularly in Germany, where
was popularized by
who
Biel,
1495.
who
in the
theology, in
Biel's pupils, Gabrielists
good
The
as
to
which God seems more Hke
and
God who
a capricious
nominaHst arbitrary
submits his will to the law of order and
conceived by his understanding.
ancients were,
especially
such as Staupitz and Nathin,
Augustinian convent introduced Luther
Jehovah than a the
it
but not very original advocate, Gabriel
taught at the University of Tubingen in 1484 and died in
was
It
a faithful
of course,
represented in the universities,
by commentators: Johannes Capreolus (1380-1444)
in
in Florence;
and
Dionysius the Carthusian (1402-1471) in Cologne, which was
still
Paris
and Toulouse;
a purely
Thomist
century,
from 1505
Summa theologica, the Summa contra first
St.
Antoninus (1389-1459)
university. to 1522,
At
the beginning of the sixteenth
Cajetan wrote a commentary on the
and Francis gentiles in
Silvester of Ferrara
A
Franciscan Scotist of the
John
of Ripa, exercised a strong
1516.
half of the fourteenth century,
wrote one on
influence at the University of Paris until the
end of the century. In
Paris one of his disciples, Louis of Padua, witnessed the
condemna-
on change and contingence
in the will
tion in 1362 of propositions
of
God which
he had extracted from his master's teaching.
It
was
203
FOURTEENTH CENTURY
"^^^
mainly on account of him,
nominaUsm did not
seems, that
it
in-
vade every center of instruction.
VIII
German Mysticism
in the Fourteenth Century:
Ec\hart
The counterpart of the nominalist movement was the mystical movement that developed during the same era, especially in Germany. Toward the end of the fourteenth century, Gerson defined mystical theology as "clear and savory knowledge of things that basis of the Gospel." ^^ Mystical theology
on the
are believed
"must
human investiknown through a
be acquired through penitence rather than through gation,"
and
it
would seem
"God
that
is
better
feeling of penitence than through rational study."
French mystic who was
We
see in this
a friend of Peter of Ailly the influence of
whom
mysticism was mainly a method of medi-
tation linked to spiritual
advancement. Scholastic theology proves
and demonstrates, and
leads to a system of well-ordered ideas;
the Victorines, for
it
mystical theology sees and savors, and
it
leads to an ineffable union
with God.
Mysticism was profoundly separated from the philosophy of the
by the setting and the conditions under which
universities
oped in Germany,
was inseparable from the
It
spiritual
meditation
from sermons than to the
lower
cloistered
associated
and from
the twelfth century, ^*
St.
and
Contra vanam curiositatem links
Bonaventure and p.
with
life,
all
it
it
devel-
assumed.
the training in
monastic
the
a general
organization,
,
ed.
particularly in a belief in the
many Dulin
that extended to the
instances of millenarianism in
(1706),
it
led to the
I,
106.
Of
Bernard than
among
to the
the
sudden ap-
course,
the Chancellor of the University of Paris
to St.
469).
mood
in the fourteenth
of the specific traits that are found
Gerson [1940],
with
and was manifested
millennium. There had been
mysticism, which
forms that
literary
in the vernacular that appealed to sentiment rather
intellect,
classes
by the
as well as
more
Gersonian closely
to
Areopagite and Erigena, has none
German
mystics
(cf.
A. Combes, Jean
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
204
pearance of a great number of prophets and prophetesses
nounced
was coming
that the cycle
was about
to
who
an-
an end and that the antichrist
Mysticism/^ even when doctrinal, retained
to appear.
many cf the features that linked German mystics of the fourteenth
to
it
common
the
people: the
century favored the vulgar lan-
guage; they explained through affirmation, through visions, but they never discussed or tried to provide proofs; according to Eckthe
hart,
most speculative of them
help the soul break
convinced of
He
away from
was saying the same thing with his
close affinities
indebted
was
1260,
own
to his predecessor.
—except
of the
as
to
become
whose doctrine had
as Plotinus,
even though Eckhart was not directly
The Dominican John
Eckhart, born in
1
—he
lived in Ger-
Vicar General of his order after 1307
good reputation
Dominican convents
years of his
who
a
to
of the divine nature/^
for a stay in Paris in 131
many, where he served
and acquired
aim was always
their
University of Paris in 1300, but from 1304 until his
at the
death in 1327
all,
body and seek God,
and of the purity
nobility
its
the
as a teacher, preacher,
of his order in
and reformer
Bohemia. The
last
two
were darkened by the attacks of the Franciscans,
life
caused twenty-eight of his theses to be condemned in
Rome
in 1329. It
would be
in his to
man
a
such a point that he
philosophy, tian
if
we
life. First,
this
Dominican, who was
rightly credited with originating first
examine
and monastic
German
his conception of the Chris-
whole system of
a
good works,
man away from
how
of action, carried metaphysical speculation is
did not
comes
evangelical precepts love, humility,
turn
understand
difficult to
own way
spiritual interpretation of
rules derived
from them poverty, :
prayers. All these rules, intended to
himself and the world and to bring
him
nearer to God, are given a purely spiritual interpretation by Eckhart: poverty
is
the state of a
"Pastor, Histoire des Papes,
de Cues,
"Ed.
man who knows
166, cited by Vansteenberghe,
I,
p. 33. Pfeiffer, p. 191;
compare
nothing,
Plotius
Enneads
iv. 3. i.
who wants
Le Cardinal Nicolas
205
THE FOURTEENTH CENTURY
nothing, and
who
and from
creatures, the
all
has nothing. Completely severed from himself
man who
will to accomplish the will of
God
he allows
passivity;
is
God; he
truly poor lacks even the is
in a state of complete
accomplish his work in him; he
to
is
ready to suffer the torments of Hell or to partake of the joys of
The union
beatitude.
end only
in
cism, love tion,
is
of love
complete as possible and has
as
its
In keeping with an enduring feature of mysti-
itself.
no longer
a
permanent deficiency
God
but a plenitude identical to
amorous soul therefore
is
as in Plato's descrip-
The
himself.
action of the
characterized by no deficiency and
Love and
subservient to no end. far
is
all
from being acquisitions of the
from
the virtues that issue soul, are therefore
the profound unity in
which
are indissolubly fused
that thereafter are accomplished effortlessly
and unconsciously, and
love,
Eckhart
(as
expresses the Plotinian view) the very being of the soul.
is
They
are
the virtues
all
and even involuntarily
no gradation; good works,
that exhibit
almsgiving, and fasting are worthless unless the will that motivates
them
is
taken into consideration.
ternal success
and superior
spatial circumstance,
the internal
brooks no obstruction and
work which alone draws
any ex-
will, indifferent to
any temporal or
for this very reason to
something external and limited is
The
us to God.
to a definite,
is
the true work,
Nor
is
true prayer
momentary end;
it
constant submission to the will of God.
Here we
see the resurgence in full force of a
standing the inner
life
been formulated with such
end of the
ment
means
of under-
which, since the time of Plotinus, had never clarity
and completeness: love
as the
spiritual life, the fusing of all virtues into one, the attain-
of complete freedom by placing the soul once again at
proper depth, that restricted
is,
beyond the
and circumscribed. That
states is
in
which
its
activity
its
is
indeed the Plotinian tradition
that has often appeared as the counterpart to another tradition: the tradition according to
and return
to self,
is
which
virtue, instead of
being withdrawal
a voluntary acquisition involving multiple
repeated exposure to external, social conditions. But
it
is
and
worth
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
206
noting that Eckhart's doctrine, like Plotinism, does not lead to the
kind of abstention from overt tury
was
activity that in the seventeenth cen-
The lower
called quietism.
activities of the
soul
—those
that lead to action, will, reason, understanding, external perception
—are not eliminated by
on
the soul's withdrawal into itself but are
The problem that tormented resolved: when one possesses the right
the contrary ordered and directed. the Stoics so
much
here
is
principle, right actions independently follow.
The rhythm
of this mystical conception of the spiritual
life
pre-
dominates in Eckhart's theology and metaphysics. Fourteenth-century thinkers
had long been familiar with
this
rhythm: original
unity of beings, division, return to unity. Since the time of the
somewhat by
Stoics this pattern, modified
had been the substructure of every
Whether passage from one
many was
to
diverse considerations,
single vision of the universe.
envisioned as an emanation
or a creation, the general conception of things
had always been
dominated by the idea that the consummation of things was a
re-
turn to unity with God, a veritable deification.
Eckhart advanced the view that the return impossible,
even
senseless,
from God were thought same sense
to unity
individual
finite
if
would be
creatures
remote
be endowed with true reality in the
to
as the divine reality.
His whole system of metaphysics
summed up in this negation: "Individuality is a mere {unum purum nihil) eliminate this nothing and creatures are one." What he means is that unification with God,
therefore
is
accident, nothing all
which
is
the
;
consummation of
us the reaUty of things. speculative mysticism
It is
and
destiny, simultaneously discloses to
in this sense that his mysticism
that his doctrine of destiny
is
at the
is
a
same
time a doctrine of being.
The
unity of
God
is
not destroyed
if
we
conceive of things in the
fullness of their diversity as the manifestation or revelation
deeper unity.
If a
the thought that
word it
expresses an inner thought,
expresses;
and
it
is
enough
it
of a
unites with
for the
many
to
appear to us as such in order for us to deny their diversity and their
independent being and to
relate
them
to
God from whom
they
207 issued. I
know
"^^^
FOURTEENTH CENTURY
Thus
as
soon as
in the Trinity. priate:
is
method
his
Many
which the Father
is
unity,
first
And
expressed?
Word is
not the Spirit the bond of
after those in
William of Moerbecke's
Elements of Theology), however, above the {Gottheit)
divinity
posits
as
non-participated
a
The
the three persons constitute the "natured nature."
corresponds
Proclus'
to
known and
unity in which the
participated
knower
the
expresses the thought of the Father;
The
on the
his analogy
an "unnatured nature" that remains intact while underneath
Father,
side
as revealed
or Intelligence through
Son and the Father? Basing
translation of Proclus'
Trinity he
God
Augustinian views of the Trinity are appro-
(which he modeled
triads
to the diversity of
not the Son the Verbum, the
love that unites the
God
from God.
that they issue
Eckhart applies
conceive of things as revelations of
I
and the
first,
the
unity,
the
absolute
are identified; the
Son
them.
Spirit unites
creation of the world, or the procession of created things out-
God,
essentially
is
no
diflFerent
from the generation
by the Father, for the created world
God. Each thing has the Creation
is
God
And
that
causality other than
is
is
through which
why,
Son
nothing but an expression of
eternal being, included in the
its
a non-temporal act
himself in his Son.
no divine
in
of the
God
Word
expressed
since Eckhart acknowledges
immanent
causaUty,
it is
not permis-
sible to conceive of the individual existence of each creature in a
determinate time and space as the result of a positive act of God.
moment God
created heaven
earth, for the finite existence of things apart
from God, the
wrong
It is
and
to say that at a certain
diversity that separates them, can only be
and
all
The
evil,
and a defect associated with
But of
as
nothingness
privation. Eckhart obviously clings tenaciously to the Plotinian
and Augustinian theory of tion
viewed
it is
nothing
less
which makes
evil a
simple priva-
diversity.
than the knowledge of the primitive unity
creatures that brings the world back to the point of
soul has
no other function than
this
knowledge.
its
origin.
We
would
expect Eckhart willingly to accept the Aristotelian statement that "the soul
is
in
some way
all
things" and that in the active intellect
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
208
the object
identical to the subject.
is
We
would
him
also expect
to
accept the Neo-Platonic thesis that each hypostasis, soul as well as intellect,
includes
all
things in
of his theory of the soul,
times
is) as
own way. That
its
The depth
(Fun^e) or
the "spark of the soul"
where every creature rediscovers
its
of the soul,
synderesis,
some-
it
what he the place
is
unity. Consequently,
knowledge
in the highest sense (suprarational is
(as
the starting point of his doctrine, but instead, as in the
case of Plotinus, as the outcome. calls
the true basis
is
which cannot be considered
knowledge
of this unity or faith)
not the representation of things that would be and would remain
external to
it;
such knowledge
rather a transmutation of things
is
themselves in their return to God. spiritual
aspect
Stoics already
the
of
saw
We
might say
conflagration
universal
a purification rather
that
which
in
Adam
whom
is
consummated
to attain: the perfect
all
union of
of the historical, judicial,
doctrine remains.
The
occurred even in
the
than as a paragon, as the
which
that
God and
certain
human
the
From
whom
Eckhart's thought the
cultivation of the inner
Hardly a
incarnation of Christ, which
much
as
in
soul endeavors
his creature.
Adam's
sin,
primarily on the basis of atoning for original
century drew not so
less
man
trace
and sacramental aspect of the Christian
absence of
the guide for souls through
the
than a material conflagration.
In Eckhart's Christianity, Christ, incarnate in Jesus, acts the redeemer of the sin of
is
it
is
sin.
would have
not explained Christ
rather
is
the universe returns to God.
German
mystics of the fourteenth
a metaphysical theory as a guide to the
life.
John Tauler
(i 300-1 361)
Suso (1300-1365) were primarily preachers.
and Henry
The Flemish
mystic
John Ruysbroeck (1293-1381), Prior of the convent of Griinthal near Brussels, through his predilection for the allegorical interpre-
mind Philo's piety more often than "The soul must understand God through God," he says in The Adornment of the Spiritual Nuptials, "but those who wish to know what God is and to study him should understand that this is prohibited. They would become intation of Scripture, brings to
Plotinus' talent for speculation.
sane. All created light
must
fail
here; the quiddity of
God
tran-
209 scends
THE FOURTEENTH CENTURY all
must
creatures; one
them
try to penetrate
.
.
.
that
true sobriety."
^"
His interesting statement reveals the profound age which characterized the
Gone is
the universe in
is
last
intellectual cleav-
part of the fourteenth century.
God and
reason
choices: nominalism, in
which
which the world
perfected by faith. These are
reason
and not
believe the articles of faith is
two
leads to
under the guidance of experience begins
to
become
ac-
quainted with the natural laws of things, and in which faith cannot be superadded to reason unless by an arbitrary decree or yield
knowledge
of
God
other than that of his absolute, unaccountable
power; and mysticism, which goes
directly to
God
without passing
through nature and subsequently rediscovers nature only thing permeated by serious, perhaps,
between two
is
God and
intellectual settings: the universities,^^
of science
where the
some way reabsorbed
was coming
into existence
was much more
^"
social
a true
masses and included not only the speculations of
movements
that
were
than intellectual.
Trans. Hello,
p. 6i.
But not because there were no mystics in the universities (as A. Combes notes ]ean Gerson, p. 469); Gerson was Chancellor of the University of Paris from
^^
in
where
and where the
closely linked to the spiri-
the profound mystics but also vast popular
more
him. More
were being elaborated, and the monasteries,
spiritual life
tual life of the
in
the fact that this cleavage reflected the contrast
intellectual aristocracy
methods
in
some-
as
1395 to 1429.
Bibliography
I
Texts
Duns
Scotus.
Opera omnia. Edited by L. Wadding. 26
vols. Paris
(Vives),
1891-95. .
De primo
principio. Translated by E. Roche. St. Bonaventure, N.Y.,
1949. .
Philosophical Writings. Selections translated by A. Wolter. London,
1962.
—
.
The Oxford Commentary on
Sentences.
I,
III,
4.
the
Translated by R.
Thomas Bradwardine. De
Four Boo\s
McKeon
of the Master of the
in Selections,
II, 313-50. causa Dei adversus Pelagium et de virtute cau-
sarum ad suos Mertonenses Libri
tres.
London,
161 8.
Studies Gilson, E. "Avicenne et le point de depart de doctrinale et litteraire
du moyen
age,
II
Jean Duns Scot. Paris, 1952. Grajewski, M. The Formal Distinction of
Duns
Scot," Archives d'histoire
(1927).
.
1944.
Duns
Scotus.
Washington, D.C.,
—
M. Die Kategorien und Bedeutungslehre des Duns Scotus. Tubingen, 1916. Laun, J. "Recherches sur Thomas de Bradwardin precurseur de Wiclif," Revue d'Histoire et de philosophic religieuse (Strasbourg), IX (1929), 217Heidegger,
33-
The Medieval Science of Weight. Madison, Wise, 1952. Pp. 285Thomas Bradwardine. Shircel, C. L. The Univocity of the Concept of Being in the Philosophy of Duns Scotus. Washington, D.C., 1942. Wolter, A. The Transcendentals and Their Function in the Metaphysics of Duns Scotus. St. Bonaventure, N.Y., 1946. Moody,
E.
91 on
210
THE FOURTEENTH CENTURY
211
IV Texts William of Ockham. Super quatuor tiones
earumdemque
libros sententiarutn subtilissimae quaes-
decisiones. Lyons, 1495.
.
Quodlibeta septem. Paris, 1487. Strasbourg, 149 1.
.
Breviloquiutn de potestate papae. 1937. Critical
.
edition of
Ockham's
works in 25 vols, is in Bonaventure, N.Y. (Vol. I,
non-political
preparation by the Franciscan Institute,
St.
1956).
Selected Quodibetal Questions. Translated by R.
.
McKeon,
Selections,
360-421.
II,
Oc\ham:
Philosophical Writings. Translated by Ph. Boehner.
New
York, 1957.
Studies Boehner, P. Collected Articles on Oc\ham.
"Ockham's Conception
Maurer, A. Studies,
St.
the
Bonaventure, N.Y., 1958. Unity of Science," Mediaeval
(1958), 98-112.
The Logic of William of Oc\ham. New York, 1935. A. "Some Recent Interpretations of Ockham," Speculum, XXIII
Moody, Pegis,
XX
of
E.
(1948),
458-63.
"Les 51 articles de Guillaume Occam censures en Avignon, en Revue d'histoire ecclesiastique, XVIII (1922), 240-70. Shapiro, H. Motion, Time, and Place According to William Oc\ham. St.
Pelzer, A.
1326,"
Bonaventure, N.Y., 1957. Vignaux, P. "Nominalisme," Dictionnaire de theologie catholique, XI (1931), 733-84-
Webering, D. Theory of Demonstration According
to
William Oc\ham.
St.
Bonaventure, N.Y., 1953. II, III,
V, VI
Texts Albert of Saxony. Quaestiones super octo physicorum libros. Padua, 1493. Venice, 1504 and 1516. .
Durand
of
(third
Pourgain.
Saint
and
last
In
et
Sententias
redaction of his
Paris, 1508. Fifteen editions .
mundo. Pavia, 1481. Venice, 1520. commentariorum libri quatuor commentary on Lombard's Sentences).
Quaestiones in libros de caelo
were published during the sixteenth century.
Quaestio de natura cogitationis. Edited by Koch. Miinster in West-
falen, 1929.
2d
edition, 1935.
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
212
John Buridan. Quaestiones super octo physicorum
1509 and
Paris,
libros.
1516.
John of Jandun. Quaestiones i?i XII libros metaphy sicorum Venice, 1586. John of Mirecourt, Condemned propositions are in Denifle, Cartularium .
universitatis parisiensis. Paris, 1891. Pp. 610-14.
Nicholas of Autrecourt. Exigit ordo executionis. "Nicholas of Autrecourt," Mediaeval Studies,
Nicholas Oresme. "Maistre Nicole Oresme,
le
Edited
Text and Commentary," Mediaeval Studies,
O'Donnell.
J.
(1941),
III
V
(1942), 159-297; (1943). 167-333. De difformitate qualitatu7n (unpublished,
cf.
.
Leonard de
by
(1939), 179-280. Livre du Ciel et I
P.
du Monde, IV
185-280;
Duhem, Etudes
sur
Vinci, 3d series, Paris, 19 13, p. 373).
Commentariorum in I Sententiarum. Rome, 1596. Commentariorum in II Sententiarum. Rome, 1605. Peter Auroli Scriptum super primum Sententiarum. Edited by
Peter Auriol. .
.
E.
Buytaert. St. Bonaventure, N.Y., 1953.
Peter of Ailly. Quaestiones super
primum, tertium
et
quartum Sententiarum.
Venice, 1478, 1490, 1500.
Studies Borchert, E.
Der
scholasti\
Einftuss des
nach
dem
Nominalismus auf die Christologie der Spdt"De communicatione idiomatum" des
Tra\tat
Nicolaus Oresme. Miinster in Westfalen, 1940. Der Konceptualismus in der Universalienlehre des Petrus Aure-
Dreiling, E. oli.
Munster in Westfalen, 1913. Etudes sur Leonard de Vinci. 2d series. Paris, 1909. Pp. 379-
Beitrlige, Vol. XI.
Duhem,
P.
441.
3d
series. Paris, 1913.
Pp. 1-492.
Gilson, E. "La doctrine de la double verite," Etudes de philosophic medievale. Strasbourg, 192 1. Pp.
Koch, J. Durandus von Aquin zu Grundlegung. Michalski, C. "Le siecle,"
de
S.
51-75 on John of Jandun.
Porciano, O.P., Forschungen
Beginn des
14.
(Beitrdge, 26,
zum
Streit
um Thomas
Jahrhunderts; I Teil, Uterargeschichtliche
I.)
Munster
in Westfalen,
1927.
criticisme et le scepticisme dans la philosophie
Bulletin
de I'academie polonaise
(1925), pp.
41-122.
du XIV® Cracow,
1926.
O'Donnell. "The Philosophy of Nicholas of Autrecourt and His Appraisal of Aristotle," Mediaeval Studies, IV (1942), 97-125.
"Un 'programme de vie' de "Le 'De exercitato proficiencium' de Pierre
Vansteenberghe, E.
welt des Mittelalters,
du moyen age" and Aus der GeistesFestgabe M. Grabmann. Munster in Westfalen, la
fin
d'Ailly,"
1935. Pp. 1231-1246.
Weinberg,
Nicholas of Autrecourt: J. Thought. Princeton, 1948.
A
Study
in
Fourteenth
Century
THE FOURTEENTH CENTURY
213
VII Texts Commentary on
Cajetan,
the
the Leonine edition of
Gabriel
Biel.
Epitome
St.
et
Summa
theologica of
St.
Thomas. Printed
in
Thomas.
collectorium
Occamo super quatuor
ex
libros
sententiarum. Tubingen, 1512.
Johannes
Capreolis.
Defensiones.
Thomas de Aquino, Book
Libri
IV Defensionum
IV. 7 vols. Tours,
1
theologiae
divi
889-1908.
Studies Carre,
M,
Feckes,
and Nominalists. New York, 1945. Die Rechtjertigungslehre des Gabriel Biel und ihre Stellung
Realists
C.
innerhalb der nominalistische Schule. Miinster in Westfalen, 1925. Gilson, E. "Cajetan et I'existence," Tydschrijt voor Philosophie,
XV
(1953),
267-86.
Grabmann, M. "Johannes Capreolus,
Thomas (Fribourg Penido,
T.
"Cajetan
O.P., der Princeps
[Switzerland]),
et
notre
Thomistarum," Divus
XXII (1944), 85-109,
connaissance
analogique de
145-70.
Dieu,"
Thomiste,XVll (1934-35), 149-92. Schwamm, H. Magistri fohannis de Ripa O.F.M. doctrina de divina.
Rome,
Revue
praescientia
1930.
VIII Texts Henry
Boo\ of Eternal Clark. London, 1953.
Suso. Little
lated
by
J.
Wisdom:
John Gerson. Opera oinnia. Edited by M.
Little
Ellies
du
Boo{
of Truth. Trans-
Pin. 5 vols.
Antwerp,
1706.
John Ruysbroeck. The Adornment of the Spiritual Marriage. The Sparkling Stone. The Boo\ of Supreme Truth. Translated by C. Wynschenk. New York, 1916. John Tauler. Opera omnia. Paris, 1623. Meister Eckhart. Sermons and tractates in Meister Echhart. Translated by C. deB. Evans. 2 vols. London, 1931.
Tal\s of Instruction The Boo\ of Divine Comfort, The Aristocrat, Disinterest and Sermons, in Meister Eckhard. Translated by R. Blakney. New York, 194 1. .
About
,
"^^^
214
MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
Studies Master Ec\hart and the Rhineland Mystics. TransJ. by Hilda Graef. New York, 1957. Meister Ec\hart: An Introduction to the Study of His Worlds. Lon-
Ancelot-Hustache, lated
Clark,
J.
don, 1957. The Great .
German
Mystics: Ec^hart, Tauler,
and Suso. Oxford,
Combes, A, John Gerson: Commentateur dionysien. Paris, 1940. Jean de Montreuil et le Chancelier Gerson. Paris, 1942. Connolly, J. John Gerson: Reformer and Mystic. Louvain, 1928. De Hornstein, X. Les grands mystiques allemands du XI V^ siecle:
1949.
.
EcJ{hart,
Tauler, Suso. Lucerne, 1929. Delacroix,
H. Le mysticisme
speculatif en
Allemagne au XI V^
siecle.
Paris,
1900.
Lavand,
B. L'osuvre
mystique de Henri Suso. 4
vols.
Fribourg, Switzerland,
1946-47.
Muller-Thym. The Establishment of the University of Being in the Doctrine of Meister EcJ{^hart of Hochheim. New York, 1939. Wauthier D'Aygalliers, A. Rusybroec\ the Admirable. Translated by F. Rothwell. London, 1925.
THE RENAISSANCE DURING THE FIFTEENTH CENTURY there was a sharp contrast between the universities
laymen and and popes:
clerics
mingled
and the humanistic
circles
where
under the protection of princes
freely
for instance, at the Platonic
Academy in Lorenzo the Academy in Venice. In
Magnificent's Florence and at the Aldine these
new
settings
the desire for
no
practical consideration took precedence over
knowledge
pletely liberated,
for
its
own
sake.
were no longer forced,
meet the need of providing training
Human
minds, com-
as in the universities, to
for clerics.
The
following cen-
tury witnessed the founding of the College of France which, unlike the University of Paris,
edge rather than the
had
as
its
aim
classification of
the
advancement of knowl-
accumulated and traditional
materials.
The new freedom produced
a multipHcation of doctrines
and
thoughts which had been incubating throughout the Middle Ages but which had previously been repressed. This confused mixture
might be
called naturalism, for generally
universe nor
sought
human
it
subjected neither the
conduct to a transcendental
to identify their
most viable and
it
immanent
fruitful ideas, the
turned away from
all
that
rule,
but simply
laws. It contained, alongside the
worst monstrosities; above
all,
had been previously accomplished.
"Laurentius Valla finds fault with Aristotle's physics," wrote Poggio,
"He
who was finds
as
much
Boethius'
215
a
humanist and Epicurean
Latin barbaric,
destroys
as
was
religion,
his friend.
professes
2l6
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
heretical ideas, scorns the Bible.
the Christian religion
is
superior to any proof!"
Roman
.
.
.
And
has he not taught that
based not on proofs but on belief which
But Poggio was
"^
in
is
the service of the
Curia, and as for Laurentius Valla, the Cardinal of Cusa
recommended him
to the
pope in 1450 and wanted him
to enter its
service.
This intense desire for a new,
voked or
at least
dangerous
difiFerent,
life
was pro-
accentuated by an enormous expansion in the
and
possible range of experience
in technology.^ In
whole pattern of the material and
one century the
Europe had
intellectual life of
changed. Temporal expansion of the range of experience occurred
when humanists (who
took up the study of oriental languages in
Greek and Latin
the sixteenth century) read the tant than the discovery of
new
texts
texts.
was the manner
Less impor-
in
which the
De offlciis was the same text for both Ambrose and Erasmus, but St. Ambrose was seeking rules for his clerics whereas Erasmus found in it a moral philosophy, autonomous and independent of Christianity; and the emphasis was no old were read: Cicero's
St.
longer on utilizing the ancient texts to explain Scripture, but on
understanding the
texts themselves. Spatial
of experience occurred
when
explorers
the oLKovfiiya set by Christianity
expansion of the range
went beyond the confines of
(following the Greeks) as the
boundaries of the habitable earth, and discovered not only
new
lands that caused people to look beyond the Mediterranean, but also
new human
types,
whose
religion
Technological expansion was pass,
possible not only by the
at the
which
same time
are to be credited to Italian artists
artisans.
The men
although bound by tradition, sensed that stirring
^Quoted by H. Busson, Les Sources ^
In
Un
nouveati
the Renaissance:
"Man cannot endure
has plunged him."
et le
moyen age (1927), N.
who
of the fifteenth century, life
that
had long been
once again and that the destiny
was mankind was recommencing. "Everywhere," wrote
in a state of suspension
of
com-
gunpowder, and printing, but also by industrial or mechanical
inventions, several of
were
made
and customs were unfamiliar.
the Cardinal
developpement du rationalisme,
Berdiaefif
is
p.
55.
struck by the individualism of
the isolation into which the humanistic age
THE RENAISSANCE
217
Cusa around
of
"we
1433,
see the
minds
men most
of
devoted to
the study of the liberal and mechanical arts turn back to antiquity,
and with extreme about
to
Men more
^
were naturally inclined
ments the
were
avidity, as if the full cycle of a revolution
be completed."
to contrast
traditional conceptions of
new
with the
man and
develop-
based on a
life
much
number of Middle Ages
limited range of experience. In spite of a vast
divergences and diversities there was throughout the
but one image, or rather one single frame into which could be fitted
every possible image of the universe: the frame that
called theocentrism.
From God
God
as the principle to
and consummation, following the passage through this
formula could be made
as well as the
fit
the
finite
most orthodox of the
end
beings
Summae
most heterodox of the mystics, for the order of na-
and the order of human conduct take
ture sity
to
we have
as the
their place as
by neces-
if
between the principle and the end.
Such
a synthesis
was
possible only so long as
in the universe in relation to
its
creatures or manifestations of
gaged
in
moving toward
or
origin or
God,
all
its
men saw
end,
finite
everything beings as
all finite
spirits
away from God. But
as
being en-
the concept of
theocentrism was gradually abandoned: as early as the twelfth century humanistic naturalism emerged and focused attention on the study of the structure
century
the
and
forces of society; in the fourteenth
Ockhamists, deliberately neglecting everything that
related to the origin or
end of things and even demonstrating the
fallacy of believing that
something of the divine plan could be ap-
prehended in the contrast between the immutable heaven and the sublunary region, studied nature in and for
two
centuries,
itself. It
was the next
however, that offered every reason for abandoning
the concept of theocentrism. Strange mysterious depths in history
and
in nature, hardly suspected previously,
philology on the one yielded
with ^
its
new
data on
historical
now began
to appear:
hand and experimental physics on
man and
moments
the universe.
—creation,
sin,
The
redemption
Quoted by Vansteenberghe, Le Cardinal Nicolas de Cues,
the other
Christian
p. 17.
—
drama
could no
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
2l8
longer circumscribe a nature whose laws were completely indifferent to
of
it,
it,
humanity one segment of which was
a
an era in which Christians themselves threw
power and won acceptance
spiritual
Such
opposed
The most important was and
at the
conception of
number
infinite
that practical
of repercussions.
men, men of
action, artists
kind were brought
artisans, technicians of every
ground
or even de-
life
to the idea of Christian unity.
change entailed an
a vital
ignorant
in their politics of goals totally
aHen to the supernatural ends of the Christian liberately
totally
off the shackles of
to the fore-
The new
expense of meditative and speculative men.
man and
rather than conceived,
nature was a conception that was realized
and the names of true philosophers, from
Nicholas of Cusa to Campanella, are overshadowed by those of great captains to the
and
word, was
all
Leonardo da Vinci, all
Technique, no matter what sense
artists.
and
vellian poUtics
was hardly a philosopher who was not
was
to restore the
thinkers, but before this they
—and
methods
that
were practitioners
would allow them
forms and thoughts of the ancients. this
is
perhaps
great
the
paradox of the era
philosophers of the Renaissance, from Nicholas of Cusa to panella, took pains to organize their thought
design of the universe.
many
The all
the
from leading them
more
God
as the principle
contrast between this ancient
we to
observe
new
it
ideas,
that the great task of philosophy
to organize everything in the material
the spirit in terms of
—the
Cam-
around the ancient
return to Platonism, as
of these philosophers, far
simply convinced them
was
at the
a technique intended for the ItaHan princes.
of philology, concerned with the
in
was
physicist
a doctor or at least an astrologer and an occultist. Machia-
The humanists were
Yet
attributed
technician
painter, engineer, mathematician,
in one: but there
same time
The consummate
that mattered.
is
world and in the world of
and God
as the end.
The
scheme and the new philosophy of
nature that they integrated into their system accounts for the extreme difficulty of their doctrine.
THE RENAISSANCE
219
The Diverse Currents
I
Thought
of
In spite of the general confusion that marks the Renaissance, the
foregoing considerations allow us to separate several fairly distinct philosophical currents, the
of
first
which
early centuries of Christianity,
the Platonic current.
is
Platonism had been warmly received by the
new
religion since the
and fifteenth-century Platonic hu-
manists such as Marsilio Ficino
entertained a sincere hope of
still
finding in Platonism a philosophical synthesis favorable to Christianity,
thus unwittingly continuing the tradition of Chartres and
The second
of Abelard.
current
is
that of the Averroists of the
University of Padua: they followed a tradition uninterrupted from the time of Siger of Brabant
and transmitted
Padua
to
on an Aristotelian interpretation opposed
rests
tian Peripatetics;
it
The
to that of the Chris-
reveals a naturalistic Aristotle, an Aristotle
rigorous determinism;
it is
Paduan
science since the
not to be linked to the
dawn
discovered
how
who
to
of
a
modern
reactionaries upheld the spirit of Aristotle's
third current
is
that of the true scholars
neither Plato nor Aristotle but Archimedes, the
is
tradition
and the immortality of the soul but proclaims
denies Providence
physics.
at the be-
The
ginning of the fourteenth century by Peter of Abano.
join
mathematics
to
whose model
man who
experience;
first
completely
ignored during the Middle Ages, Archimedes brings us suddenly to a state of science
could teach. third
and
A
its
fourth current, which
leads to
like the scholar
much more advanced no
who
than anything that tradition is
no
fixed, definite formula,
less
is
original than the
that of moralists
studies nature independently of
end, set out to describe the natural
man
origin
and
without taking into
account his supernatural destiny. Their description of is
its
who,
actually rooted deep in the ancient systems of
human
nature
moral philosophy,
especially the Stoic. It
seems that
Ockhamism enunciated
the supposition implicit in
the doctrines of each current (with the exception of the
first)
after
the fourteenth century: nothing in nature can bring us to the objects
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
220
of faith; faith
is
a sealed domain, one circumscribed
and
inaccessible
except by virtue of a gracious gift of God. But was that not also the
fundamental idea of the Reformation? Neither our intelligence nor our will can help us through natural means to lay the slightest basis
for
faith.
The Reformation was
scholastic theology
cause
and humanism;
denied with
it
Ockham
God; and
it
opposed
equally
to
both
denied scholastic theology be-
that our rational faculties can lead us
humanism
from nature
to
than for
dangers since natural forces can impart no religious
its
it
repudiated
less for its errors
meaning.
But the Reformation was tric
theses associated with
it.
humanism
as hostile as
conception of the universe and to
Both chose
all
to ignore the synthesis of the
natural and the divine, of the sensible world and
with
the consequences that
all
to the theocen-
the moral and political
its
principle, along
had been imagined during the
thir-
teenth century.
Thus
there
were two ways, each contrasting with the
other, of
trying to rediscover the intellectual unity destroyed by the apparently definitive cleavage
between knowledge of nature and divine
by taking pains to organize an autonomous moral nature as
its
standard, or by denying
man
reality:
that has
life
the possibiUty of justifying
himself other than through grace.
II
Platonism: Nicholas of Cusa (Nicolaus Cusanus)
The
intestine struggle
of the universe
between the ancient theocentric scheme
and the humanistic method stands out
clearly in
the greatest of the fifteenth-century thinkers. Cardinal Nicholas of
Cusa (1401-1464).
We
hamism, transmitted
to
find in his
him by
work
a strange blend of
his teachers in Heidelberg,
Ock-
and of
Neo-Platonism, thoroughly assimilated through the reading not only of Dionysius the Areopagite but especially of the great works of Proclus: the
Elements of Theology, the Commentary on the
Parmenides, and Platonic Theology. In spite of his extremely imperfect
knowledge of the Greek language,
his direct
and sustained
THE RENAISSANCE
221
was of
contact with the roots of Platonism
capital importance.
The
Neo-Platonism of the Arabs and even of Dionysius the Areopagite
was
totally diiiFerent; totally different also
The
Plotinus and of Proclus.
lower
to the
was concerned mainly with
first
from
describing the hierarchy of beings,
was the Neo-Platonism of the angels or intelligences
in order to determine in
spirits,
physical position of each being.
The
some way
the meta-
much closer to Plato, show how each degree
second,
notwithstanding their differences, sought to
in the scale of the hierarchy of living beings contains the fullness of reality
but reveals
things, as
do
from
it
hypostasis contains
it
in
One
a different angle: the
and the
Intelligence, Soul, its
own
contains
way. In the
indistinct; in Intelligence they interpenetrate,
One
things are
all
thanks to an intuitive
vision that sees all things in each thing; in Soul they are
bound by anything but
the bonds
all
sensible world, but each
no longer world
of discursive reason; in the
they remain external to each other, with the result that their difference can be expressed in terms of of being.
The
knowledge rather than
in terms
Neo-Platonist conceived the passage from one hy-
postasis to the next highest, less as the passage
from one
reality to
the next than as the ever deepening, ever unifying vision of one
the
and
same universe.
The Neo-Platonic
idea, expressed in
myriad ways
in the
De
docta
ignorantia (1440) and in the other works of the cardinal, was the
He
very heart of his thought.
him
allow
to reach a
was searching
method
for a
that
would
higher plane for viewing the universe than
that of reason or the senses: to see
all
things intellectualiter rather
than rationaliter was his aim.
Take good
his conception of
mathematics.
results in this sphere, his
because of
its
meant
Aristotle: for
to
Though
thought
is
it
what mathematics
the geometrical characteristics of a
natural being, such as the stature of tion of the sky,
produce
nevertheless of interest
orientation. First let us recall briefly
him
failed to
man
depended on the essence
or the physical configura-
of this being; consequently
geometry, the study of such configurations, could be nothing more than a science of abstract
realities that
do not have
their causes within
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
222
them. Mathematical reasoning linked the properties of forms, ically
stat-
given by definition, to each other. Geometry had long occupied
the inferior position that to accord to
many
Renaissance thinkers were disposed
Fracastoro, for example, noted that mathematics,
it.
with objects that are too humble and too lowly,
though
certain, deals
and
thought was echoed in the Discourse on Method. Nicholas of
his
Cusa would have liked
mathe-
to see instituted, alongside visual
matics as represented by the surveyor's art and rational mathematics as represented
by EucHd, an "intellectual mathematics."
he picturesquely labeled the (1450), which call
of
art
It is
what
"geometric transmutations"
deals with problems that
modern mathematicians
problems of limit the coincidence of forms that the geometrician :
we see intuitively that an chord when the arc is minimum.
considers distinct. For example, circle coincides
The
with the
coincidence of the arc and the chord
is
arc of a
but one application
of the general principle of the coincidence of opposites that accounts for intellectual
knowledge of things; the principle of contradiction,
on the other hand, accounts
for rational
knowledge. Intelligence
the unity behind contraries that reason contrasts tually exclusive.
toward the
is,
Thus knowledge
intellectual as
the mental state of the
edge,
knows how
far
shorten the distance. here,
is
The
from
a limit; "learned ignorance"
is
not satisfied with rational knowl-
intellectual
knowledge and
tries to
coincidence of opposites, as interpreted
but one aspect of the
Platonists is
is
tends toward the irrational, that
toward
man who,
he
sees
and declares mu-
state of unity of all things in
which the
saw the explanation of being and of knowledge; but
it
an aspect that can introduce a multiplicity of problems
—as many
Thus
the curve
concrete problems as there are pairs of opposites.
coincides with the straight line, a state of rest with motion; "motion
merely
is
all
seriate rest (quies seriatim ordinata)
the great contrasts
.^"^
Condemned
on which Aristotelian physics was based.
We need not dwell on the metaphysics of Nicholas simply projects these diverse
To what *
De
are
states of unities
of Cusa,
on the plane of
which reality.
the Platonists called state of unity he applies the term
docta ignorantia
ii.
3.
RENAISSANCE
T^^^
223
complicatio, and to
what they
the term explicatio.
"God
and the world
things in the state of explicatio. Both
is all
is
God
the absolute
is
things" in the state of complicatio,
all
maximum
the universe constitute a
but
called state of dispersion he appHes
maximum,
containing
all
the possest in
God and
possible being,
which
all
power
{posse) has already attained to being {est). Here, however, maxi-
mum that
does not signify the greatest of beings, which would imply
being compared with
it is
makes
ceive of the excess that
say that
The
opposition. in
which
act.
Or
verse
universe
again:
that
maximum
the
that
is,
it
is
we must
apart from any
"contraction" or reduction
composite and discrete, passes from potency to
reality,
is its
is
Furthermore, to con-
disproportionate to things,
it
minimum,
also the
is
it
finite beings.
"God
the absolute quiddity of the world; the uni-
is
contracted quiddity." In this
maximum
contraction, or the
shows the explicatio in the process of becoming
universe, Nicholas
rather than as completed. Like Plotinus, in fact, in his physics he
show
tries to
that everything
instance, the four elements
they are mixed, and
still
is
do not
fire itself
contained in everything: for
exist in a
pure
state, as in
Aristode;
contains a blend of the three other ele-
ments.
Knowledge, through which unity,
of
is
knowledge there
which is
in
is
some way is
is
a basic confusion,
in
it
it.
all
reduced in the soul
to
noted by several historians,
things in the state of complication
produces
little
by
little
Since the explicatio
is
plicity, it is in principle inferior to
ever,
is
highly instructive. Like Aristotle, he assumes that the soul
knowledge ever
diversity
the reverse of the notion of explicatio. In Nicholas' theory
is
and
that the
the "explication" of what-
a state of expansion and multithe complicatio. Inversely,
knowledge, or the actuation of the powers of the
soul,
howis
an
It would seem that Nicholas of Cusa was vaguely aware that knowledge depends on two opposite motions, analysis and
enrichment.
synthesis, but that
How ways
to
is
dogma
he
calls
them both
explicatio.
affected by his Platonism?
be torn between the
truths of faith above
human
Ockhamist
His mind seems
principle
al-
that sets the
apprehension and the Platonic theses
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
224
that describe the divine reaUty
the universe
itself.
^
means
that
Cusa does not assume,
It is
forever impossible "to understand
participate variously in one infinite form,"^
emanative metaphysics
modern
is
much
so
since in the case
one and the
to create are
God
is
every-
like Plotinus, that
a necessary principle that forces the multiple to
is
the one.
proach
statement: "Since
creation identifiable here as a free, positive act of the
Is
divine will? Nicholas of there
and
thing, the act of creation simply
thing."
this
was created by the highest being, and
o£ the highest being to be, to do,
same
Take
how
and the hope of any
abandoned. Here again
is
in that he tries to extract
emerge from
diverse creatures
we
see that his ap-
from Neo-Platonism not
a metaphysics to provide a general explanation of the uni-
method and
verse as a
a spirit to enable
him
to attack concrete
and
limited problems.*^
Platonism
Ill
At many
Cusa surpassed by
far the
now going
examine.
The
his duties, could devote only a litde
time
points Nicholas of
thinkers
whose Platonism we
cardinal,
overwhelmed by
and
to philosophical meditation,
are
his ideas
went beyond the mere discovery of
were often vague; but he
method
a
to
in Platonism.
of contrast the objective of Platonists after Marsilio Ficino to focus attention
on the
By way
had been
religious or poetic content of the master's
They searched not only
doctrines.
other
for points of
agreement between
Platonism and Christianity to prove, contrary to the Paduan Averroists, that
philosophy was Christian, but also for the unifying force
of a religion
common
to all
mankind one which appears somewhat
obscurely in the traditions of
:
all
nations and of which Christianity
probably but a momentary aspect. This notion brought the °
Ibid.
ii.
24.
'
Ibid.
ii.
25.
is
human-
^Nicholas had a French disciple in the person of Charles de Bouelles (Bovillus), professor of theology at Saint-Quentin and author of De nihilo (1510); discussed by M. de Gandillac in Revue d'Histoire de la philosophie (1943), p. 43.
THE RENAISSANCE
225 istic
Reformation and
Platonists into conflicts with the
tually,
The
also,
even-
with the Counter Reformation. significance
the
of
between Aristotelianism and
conflict
Platonism initiated by Pletho's pamphlet against Aristotle (Florence, 1440)
is
obvious. Like Cardinal Bessarion and his supporters, he
intended to use Plato as a defense against fatalism and the negation of the immortality of the soul.
and wrote
translated Plotinus (1492)
of Marsilio Ficino,
who
commentary on Plato
(the
The works a
Theologia platonica de immortalitate animorum) preted in the same light. a necessary less to
complement
He saw
Christians."
well as souls
translator
^
will
gladly
few changes,
a
God
Ficino found in Plato
endowed with
He
mortality.
What was needed was
With
which, perhaps, will persuade them.
would be
which was power-
to religious preaching,
which philosophers
religion
,
his philosophical investigations as
destroy the impiety of Averroes.
philosophical
are to be inter-
hear
the Creator as
was not an original thinker, but he was
the sixteenth century)
and
Platonists
a personal existence, freedom,
and commentator, whose books (published
"a
and ima skilled
in Paris
during
remained the source of information con-
cerning Plato and Plotinus throughout the Renaissance.
We Pico
more
find a kindred attitude but a della
Mirandola
(1463-1494),
up once again the common
who
fertile
in
his
imagination in
Heptaplus took
practice of interpreting the
Mosaic writ-
ings allegorically. In his Heptaplus he rediscovered the complicated
and dazzling metaphysics of the Cabala and the Zohar. His work contained nothing that had not been familiar since Philo of Alexandria, but
it
was notable
in that
it
once again linked allegory and
the idea of a universal religion.
The whole phantasmagoria
the
of
Cabala reappeared in the
sixteenth century in the metaphysical constructions of the
German
mystics. In their world, as in the world of Plotinus, everything
symbol, everything ing degrees of ^
is
affinity
in everything,
which,
Thcologiae platonicae procemium,
and science
when known, p. iv;
is
a
consists in identify-
also enable us to
quoted by Bus^on, Sources,
p. 174.
under-
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
226
how
Stand
things act on each other. Such
Paracelsus (1493-1541),
of
all
presumed correspondences of
of
is
the
whose works
aim of the physician
are but the discovery
type between the things of
this
nature.
We
need not dwell on these oddities but should note
German-speaking
sion in the
countries.
their dilTu-
Notwithstanding the protes-
Lutheran orthodoxy, Paracelsus and Meister Eckhart, both
tations of
writing in German, became the leaders of these mystical societies in
which were incubated the ideas
finally translated into the
popular
works of Valentin Weigel (1533-1588) and later of Jacob Boehme (1575-1624), initiates who went beyond the letter of Scripture, attaining to the mysteries of the divine
outcome of
At
the
this
life.
Later
we
liefs.
it
is
we
this chapter
how
shall see
Platonic spiritualism
Christianity
let
and unsystematically,
linked, diffusely
Plato's
examine the
movement.
end of
produced veritable philosophical systems. Here
how
shall
was becoming
us note briefly
Christian be-
to
of
tenet
favorite
a
the
humanists. Erasmus, in his book In Praise of Folly (published in Paris in 151
1
and eminently
that both Christianity
successful),
was quite happy
and Platonism agreed
that the
to record
human
soul
is
chained to the body and prevented by matter from contemplating truth,
and
shadows
that the sages
for realities" are in
wholly incHned xlvi).
"who
to
deplore the folly of those
Amaury Bouchard,
wrote a
mistake
agreement with the pious "who are
the contemplation of invisible things"
This eclecticism developed in France
century:
who
all
(chap,
during the sixteenth
"clerk-counselor in the king's hostel,"
treatise {ca. 1530) ''De rexcellence et
immortalite de I'dme,
drawn not only from Plato's Timaeus but also from a number of other Greek and Latin philosophers, from members of both the Pythagorean and the Platonic famiUes." In other words, the quotations attributed to Pythagoras, Linus,
and Orpheus were borrowed
from
The
Ficino's
I'eternite, a
Theologia Platonica^
poem
in eight cantos written
Encyclie des secrets de
around 1570 by Fevre de
la Boderie, is typical of the apologies of Christianity °
Busson,
ibid.,
pp. 174-75
addressed "to
THE RENAISSANCE
227
libertines
and
to
who have gone
those
and linked
astray"
to
Platonism: the immortal soul (the Phaedrus), the soul separated
from the body and
proof of the existence of attains to Eternity. In the
Et puisqu'elle
God
words
by virtue of the fact that the soul of the poet:
attaint bien jusqu a V'&ternite,
II te
faut confesser
Car
s'il
Ne
une Divinite:
n'en estoit point, ton
dme
tant isnelle
pourroit concevoir une Essence eternelle.
Here we have
and
.
.
later.^^
particular aspect of the influence of Plato compels attention,
this is the diffusion
Platonic love
(e'/ow?)
which according
whether
is
it
throughout
on love found
of the ideas
tas)f
.
the elements of a Christian Platonism, the very ele-
ments that Descartes utiUzed seventy years
One
Phaedo), and
in possession of innate ideas (the
is
in the
literary
quite different
to the
Gospel
is
the love of self or by the Victorines
from the love of God
{cari-
The
latter,
the
supreme
virtue.
is
and the Franciscans
from any attachment
an end.^^ Platonic
and Poverty,
circles
considered by the Thomists as basically identical to
disinterested love free either case
and philosophical
Phaedrus and in the Symposium
as pure,
to natural impulses,
is
in
love, the offspring of Resourcefulness
always a deficiency, a desire forever unsatisfied and
deprived of the beauty that
it
seeks, a perpetual state of uneasiness.
This doctrine expressed in the Symposium appears in books that
were prevalent toward the middle of the sixteenth century. In
The
Courtier (1528), Baldassare CastigHone described
all
the stages
through which love ascends from lower to higher beauties. But
was
especially
Leon Hebreo who,
in his
Dialog hi di
Am ore
maintained that love and desire often coincide, that love
is
it
(1535),
already
expressed in the sublunary world by the desire for procreation, even
though ^^
but an enfeebled image of the love that reigns in the
ibid., pp. 600-601. Rousselot, in Beitrdge zur Geschichte der Philosophic des Mittelalters, Vol.
Busson,
"Cf. VI.
it is
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
228
world of
intelligences.^^ In his Solitaire
who
Tyard,
amorous
the theory of parallel
between the
to enjoy divine
folly outlined in the
and eternal beauty," and prophetic and poetic
Odes
its
(I,
asserted that "poetry
sources of man."
but
Phaedrus and drew a
folly of love, or "the fervent desire of the soul
spiration. Finally, in his
Tyard and
premier (1552), Pontus de into French, introduced
Leon Hebreo's work
translated
Thus
starting point
and
love its
in-
x) Ronsard followed Pontus de
comes from God, not from the
re-
no longer the end of a higher Hfe
is
driving force.^^
The Paduans: Pomponazzi
IV
The
University of Padua, dependent after 1405 on the Most Serene
RepubHc
of Venice
which named and discharged masters without
the intervention of the Church, remained a stronghold of intellectual
freedom during the
and
itself
power annulled by
came
fifteenth
later the Jesuits
and sixteenth
who founded
centuries.
The
a college there
Inquisition
saw
their
the Venetian senate: there the secular state be-
the protector of philosophers.^^
The most famous of the Paduan masters was Pomponazzi (14621525), who raised the following question: assuming that we possess no divine revelation, what idea are we to formulate concerning man and
his place in the universe?
in Aristotle
and
his
He
found an answer
commentators. In his
De
to his question
immortalitate animae
(1516) he not only demonstrates that the intellectual soul, inseparable
from the
sensitive soul (since
it
cannot think without images), must
be mortal like the body, but he also draws practical conclusions from his
demonstration (chaps, xiii-xvi)
and must take
must find
as his
man
:
end humanity
in the love of virtue
motive for action; he must
has no supernatural end
itself
and
his daily tasks;
and the ignominy of
know
that
it is
he
evil a sufficient
"the legislator who,
know-
^ Cf H. Pflaum, Die Idee der Liebe Leone Ebreo (1926), which nevertheless shows in detail (pp. 1 12-13) the influence of St. Bonaventure. " Busson, Sources, pp. 399-400. " Cf. R. Charbonnel, La pensee itcdienne au siecle, pp. 258-59. .
XW
THE RENAISSANCE
229
common
ing man's penchant for evil and considering the
decided that the soul
good, has
immortal, not through his concern for
is
men
but through his propriety and his desire to lead
truth,
to
virtue."
Here
something not found in Siger of Brabant: a positive con-
is
human
ception of
life
in the
De fato,
The brunt
we
we
free will,
we
the end of the book
fit
is
leveled against attempts to
is
and providence:
will, fate,
and destroy
posit fate
free will;
if
we
"If
posit
destroy providence and fate." In his affirmation of the
identity of providence
(which
Stoic
Stoic inspiration
de praedestinatione, written in 1520.
libero arbitrio et
of Pomponazzi's attack
posit providence,
same
find the
bring about the reconciliation of free
we
The
not linked to supernatural destiny.
overtones are unmistakable, and
and
we
fate
we
recognize the Stoic
:
all evils
at
into the plan of the universe, evil
is
are justified because they
inseparable
the cycle of fortune metes out diverse fates to
determinism in which
and
find once again the complete Stoic theodicy
also that of Plotinus)
tion of fate that bears
spirit,
no resemblance
facts
determine
from good, and
men. His
a concep-
is
to the theory of scientific
facts;
it is still
the Stoic con-
ception of the universe in which parts are defined by their relation to the
whole.
Pomponazzi elaborated
the consequences of his naturalistic con-
ception of the universe in his
rum
De
naturalium effectuum admirando-
causis seu de incantationibus liber, published in
theory of miracles that he expounds certainly Stoic
and Plotinian doctrine of the universe than
scientific
determinism.
He
by citing the postulate of
is
not wiUing simply
scientific
1556.
owes more
The
to the
to a true sense of
to counter miracles
determinism.
He
acknowledges
(as Plotinus does) that miraculous facts are exceptional facts per-
taining to the establishment of religions, for example, and "do not
conform
to the
common
course of nature."
Though
they are
still
natural facts, they are to be explained by going beyond the depth ordinarily attained in the study of nature: one
the occult powers of herbs, stones,
and minerals,
must learn about as
PHny
the Elder
described them; one must identify the sympathy that binds
man
the
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
230
microcosm distant
influences ;^^
The
cures.
is
treatise as a
astrology
know
one must
finally,
imagination, which
stituting
world and subjects him
to the diverse parts of the
capable through
demonology:
it
power of
to
the
suggestion of producing
whole was written
for
the
for the purpose of sub-
represented
great step
a
forward, though the advancement was social rather than speculative since
it
eliminated any pretext for witchcraft
Even while proclaiming himself was disseminating of
dogma.
Still, it
a concept of
trials.
a faithful believer,
man and
Pomponazzi
the universe independent
should be noted that his view was alien
perience and to the positive sciences, and that
it
to ex-
was based on very
ancient conceptions of the universe. Indeed, the Aristotelians of
Padua were
far
removed from the current
to Kepler, Galileo,
absurd theory of the motion of
more
from Buridan
and Descartes: throughout the sixteenth century
ItaHan Peripateticism countered the
It is
that runs
new dynamic with
Aristotle's
projectiles.^^
obvious that Pomponazzi's conception of the universe
to Stoicism
and Plotinus than
sions that took place
between those
who
to Aristotle.
The famous
owed
discus-
between Alexandrians and Averroists, that
is,
pretended to follow Alexander of Aphrodisias
and those who pretended
to follow
Averroes in the interpretation of
the Aristotelian theory of intelligence, did not penetrate to the heart of the matter. soul
The Alexandrians
(like
was mortal because the possible
intellect acts
Pomponazzi) held
intellect
on which the agent
was nothing but an arrangement of man's organs favor-
ing such action; the Averroists held that the possible the agent intellect,
upon
the
human
was
eternal but also impersonal
soul, to the extent that
it
knowledge, an impersonal immortality. Averroists
was Nifo, who took
immortalitate (151 8), and
issue
whom
Leo
Compare
Plotinus Enneads
iv. 4.
of the
most famous
with Pomponazzi in his
X
encouraged in
.
Steele, p.
De
his struggle
more dangerous than
36-42.
" Cf Duhem, Bulletin italien (1909). " Charbonnel, La pensee italienne au XVV
intellect, like
and conferred
participated in intellectual
One
against Alexandrianism,-^^ considered even ^'
that the
229.
231
THE RENAISSANCE
Averroism.
We
should note that what was presumed to be the
doctrine of Alexander of Aphrodisias actually reproduced the teach-
ing of Aristocles, one of Alexander's masters,
who was
steeped in
more
in the in-
the Stoic doctrine: thus Stoicism reappeared once
But we should
terpretation of Aristotle.
made beyond
implied that no progress had been
mechanism
the
also note that the debate
a conception of
of intellectual knowledge, long since
abandoned by
the Ockhamists.
The Development
V
of
Averroism
Geronimo Cardano (1501-1576), who studied in Pavia, then in Padua until 1525, and who achieved fame as a physician, was representative of
Paduan naturalism:
and Plotinian conception of
a Stoic
the world (Plotinus' theory of the world, isolated hypostases,
and
is
astrology.
that "he
This incorrigible Bohemian, of
was a great
man
propria) that he was envious,
whom
his theory of
among
^^
Leibnitz said
and without them
in spite of all his faults
would have been incomparable," vindictive,
from
very close to Stoicism) quite favorable to occultism
stated in his confessions
{De
vita
other things "a disparager of religion,
melancholic,
hypocritical,
magician." His history of religions
is
and
the grandeur and the decadence of religions in diverse climates, he relates
them
and
perfidious,
a
indeed singular; in view of
to
their distribution
the influence of the con-
junctions of the stars and matches their history with the great cosmic periods; he draws
up
the horoscope of Christ, born under the con-
junction of Jupiter and the Sun, and relates the Judaic law to Saturn.^^ In his world,
by heat and embracing are living even
which all
is
animated by
a
unique soul activated
individual souls and in which
though they may
influences are propagated at will by those
who know how
control over them. His conception of the soul, ^*
Theodicee,
^*
Cf. Bayle, Dictionnaire, art. Cardan,
sec.
all
appear to be insensible,
251.
Remarque
P.
beings
magical to
win
sometimes called a
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
232
universal
spirit, inclines
Cardano
Averroism and
to accept
to reject
immortality.
The Paduan movement (1550-1631).
Roman
A
in Italy
came
professor in Padua, he
was brought
The
court in 161 1 and again in 1613.
he was accused of having upheld in
an end with Cremonini
to
his
De
to trial before a
doctrinal points that
caelo are characteristic
Paduan AristoteUanism the eternity and necessity of the heavens, which led him to deny creation; the close link between the soul of
:
and the body, which made him deny immortality; and the action of
God
which was not
as a simple final cause,
divine
personality
in keeping with the
and divine providence. What impressed
his
contemporaries most was the fact that his propositions endangered Christian beliefs.
It
should also be noted that with the appearance of
Copernicus, Kepler, and Galileo, Aristotle's concept of the eternal
motion and
finality of the
heavenly bodies became nothing but an
outmoded encumbrance. The were concerned with
therefore necessary to
It is
between
trite
Platonists, in contrast to the
make
a distinction in
obsolete formulations of
ligious criticism
Paduans,
scientific progress.
Paduan thought
dogma and moral and
whose influence was profound,
re-
especially in France.
Because not translated into any rigid philosophical doctrine, such un-
hampered thought and countless
criticism infiltrated literature
ways and became the hallmark of
were many
intellectual ties
and poetry
so-called libertines.
between France and
Italy
around
in
There 1540.^^
Calvin was well acquainted with the Italians and distrusted them.
They
are the ones, he wrote in 1539,
who
said "that religion
was
invented in ancient times by a few astute, subtle minds for the
From
purpose of restraining the ignorant populace."
^^
1567 Vicomercato, at the request of Francis
taught Averroism
the College of France.
at
Fernel
who
in the
De
portrait of a confirmed
^ ^
Busson, Sources,
first
1542 to
In France he had students hke Jean
abditis
rerum causis (1548) sketched the
Alexandrian
part of
I,
Book
Institution chretienne , ed. Lefranc,
I, I,
whom
he
chaps, iv and v. 5.
calls
Brutus.
THE RENAISSANCE
233
The
VI
"A even
Movement: Leonardo da Vinci
Scientific
lie
is
if it
so vile,"
wrote Leonardo da Vinci (1452-1519), "that
spoke well of divine things,
charm; truth
is
meanest things that
and
significant
it
of such excellence that it
praises.
inferior
would
Truth, even
things,
is
if it
from
detract
lends
it
their
nobiUty to the
its
has to do with in-
superior to uncertain
infinitely
opinions concerning the most sublime and exalted problems.
But you who
live
on dreams, you find your pleasure
.
.
.
in the sophisms
concerning revealed, uncertain things rather than in certain, natural conclusions that do not rise to such heights." His opinion was
Pomponazzi had
diametrically opposed to that of the Paduans; stated that the nobility of a science derived
all
the implications of this. In the centuries
we have been the
means
is
whose
God
studying, the good was identified with
of attaining to "truth," then,
through the Word, or reason; but truth
means
nobility of
itself
was always beyond the
If,
on the contrary, truth
defined through certain, natural conclusions,
it
for this very
is
human mind;
be defined without reference to a transcendent, external also true,
as a systematic is
due
is
in
and
for the
and
total vision of the universe
same
reason, that truth
to revelation, to reason, or to
some way dismembered
himself;
either divine revelation
human mind.
at the disposal of the
history
was
reason proportionate to the resources of the
it is
its
than from the certainty of demonstration. Let us
object rather
examine
from the
is
it
can
reality.
But
not revealed
(whether the vision
both revelation and reason), but
into a multitude of propositions linked
not by the unique truth that they express but by the method through
which
As
their certainty has
been acquired.
a scholar, Leonardo, though he did not accept the results of
the dynamics of the Ockhamists, was nevertheless of those the
who
syllogism
propagated
its
spirit.
among
the ranks
Criticizing the spider
and looking upon alchemists and
webs of
astrologers
as
"charlatans or fools," he allied himself with those who, like Tartaglia
and
Galileo, placed above
all
else the
works of Archimedes and
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
234
took up the questions of dynamics at the point where he
As
left
Leonardo was
a typical Italian of the Renaissance, however,
dynamist: in motion he sought the spiritual mover; in the
body he sought the action of a soul that has realized
human form; and
idea of the ful
nature." sire,
.
.
.
Still,
and
this
there
is
same
its
desire
is
new
spring,
always the
new
the inseparable quintessence of
obviously a vast difference between this de-
the ancient Aristotelian
It
body
an effusive production of forms that are forever changing, and
is static
VII
in the
a
human
in the spirit, desire "which, with joy-
impatience, always awaits the
summer
them.
form
on things an order
that imposes
that
and, to the degree that matter permits, eternal.
Pyrrhonism: Montaigne would be impossible
to
overemphasize the importance of the
who looked with scorn on all systems, who spoke as men to other men and not as masters to their disciples, and who in the study of the human mind provided us with an example of sincerity like that provided by such men as Leonardo in the study of nature. thinkers
There were of course outspoken venture des Periers,
who
in his
Cymbalum mundi
the style of Lucian, ridiculed the Gospel
We
also
find
freethinkers like Bona-
critics,
and
its
(1537), written in
miracles.
throughout the sixteenth century a current of
Pyrrhonism and Skepticism which did not run counter
which was often even against philosophy tainty
and Vanity
in
agreement with
and the
it,
of the Sciences
dialectic: the sciences
(and by
as the arts of divination,
and
and the Arts
this
late
On
(1527),
the Uncer-
Agrippa von
Middle Ages against
he meant mathematics
as well
horsemanship, and the like) are uncertain
useless since religion alone
Omer
but which was directed
sciences. In his treatise
Nettesheim recalled the old diatribes of the
to religion,
shows us the road
to happiness.
Talon, the author of the Academia (1548), stated that Aristotle
was "the father of
atheists
and
fanatics," ^^
and
that by attacking
him, he was attacking "the philosophy of the pagans and the ^Quoted by
Busson, Sources, p. 287.
THE RENAISSANCE
235
heathen."
Thus Pyrrhonism,
ridiculed by Rabelais
(who borrowed
no way
anti-Christian.^^
the formulations of Sextus Empiricus),
Omer Talon
viewed
it
not as a criticism of faith but as true philos-
ophy "which has complete freedom
ment
that
it
is
brings to bear on things and
opinion or to an author."
On
and judg-
in the appreciation
not chained to an
is
book follows Cicero's
basic points his
Academica. Rabelais and Montaigne surpassed by far the authors of such incidental writings.
They were
the creators of matchless literary
forms in which thought, liberated from the trated to things
dialectical
mold, pene-
and men. Though these moralists had hardly any
contact with the scientific
movement
of their time, they developed
which was not
a scrupulous intellectual integrity
easily
compromised.
Rabelais' lucid raillery spared neither the debaters in the universities,
nor the workers of miracles, nor the authors of
false decretals.
pudiating any theoretical construction, Montaigne
man
himself and others the true nature of man, to view
in his in-
and moral nakedness, apart from the deceptive ap-
tellectual
pearances imparted to
through
him by
pretentious doctrines that define
his relation to the universe
and
to
In a passage from the Apology for
Montaigne drew up the balance sheet
"The heavens and
(1580)
for science in his century:
the stars have been in motion for three thousand
when someone earth that moved
took
dred years ago,
was the
.
upon himself
and
.
.
it
in our
has established the doctrine so firmly that all
astrological consequences.
.
.
.
own
latter possess,
what
human
reason.
named ^ Tiers
Paracelsus livre
is
time Copernicus
won .
.
acceptance, .
What
cre-
particular privilege causes the
course of our invention to end with them? that medicine has been in the
hun-
maintain that
Before the principles of matter,
other principles found favor with
do the
to
regularly applied to
it is
form, and privation introduced by Aristotle had dentials
him
God.
Raymond Sebond
years; everybody believed this to be true until about eighteen
it
Re-
strove to find in
world?
It is
.
.
.
How
said that a
long
is
it
newcomer
changing and reversing the whole order of
de Pantagniel (1546), chap. xxix.
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
236
the ancient rules.
thought
is
.
.
.
And
have been told that in geometry (which
I
have gained the highest point of certainty
to
sciences)
the truth of experience.
For example, Jaques
house that he had found two
had nevertheless even
who
the
cast
Peletier told
me
at
my
moving toward each other but
lines
verified that they could never touch each other
extended to
if
among
there are inevitable demonstrations that are subverting
A
...
infinity.
thousand years ago, anyone
doubt on the science of cosmography and universally
ac-
cepted opinions would have been guilty of Pyrrhonism; to believe
was
in antipodes
heresy. In our
solid earth has just
dicates
more
century an infinite expanse of
men
clearly that reflective
were deeply conscious of the universe.
own
been discovered" (Essais
ii.
No
passage in-
of the late sixteenth century
medieval vision of the
fragility of the
The abandonment
12).
of geocentrism
and
criticism of the
principles established by Aristotle, innovations in medicine, the dis-
covery of asymptotes, the discovery of America
—
all
were
facts that
showed, contrary to what had been beHeved, that reason could not attain
fixed
to
founded a
and immutable principles on which might be
definitive
science:
mathematics, astronomy, medicine,
philosophy, everything was at that
Was
a definitive science?
was
:
moment undergoing
change.
the old, ineffectual science to be replaced by another science,
"Who
Montaigne was by no means convinced
may
"but that a third opinion, a thousand years from now, turn the
that
it
knows," he said in speaking of Ptolemy and Copernicus,
first
two?"
And
in spite of
geographers of our day" are wrong "in assuring us that thing has been discovered and seen." state; it is the
continuous state of the
was not indifference and
inertia
over-
Columbus' discovery, "the
Change
is
now
every-
not a provisional
human mind. But Pyrrhonism
either:
dogmatism was
inert;
skepticism was an investigation, an unlimited inquiry conducted by
an almost insatiable mind. Montaigne was
not, like
Omer
Talon,
an academician; he did not share in the "ordinary, bland opinion .
.
.
introduced by docile people
.
.
.
that our self-sufficiency can
lead us to the cognizance of other things, limitations
beyond which
it is
and that
foolhardy to put
it
it
has certain
to use."
His skep-
THE RENAISSANCE
237
ticism could not
accommodate the imposition
on the human mind: it .
and
curious
is .
avid.
.
.
and take shape gradually
to ascribe
our mind, for
to
not rigidly cast but evolve
arts are
as they are repeatedly
do not cease probing and searching
I
of fixed boundaries
bounds
Having proven through experience
.
and the
that the sciences
.
hard
"it is
for
wielded and polished,
my
whatever
cannot discover; and by re-examining and shaping the I
provide
more
my
my
to
The
only
my
it is
fixed principles.
unburden on ing, his
me
all
that
and the
fact
causes
first
and
said
principles, let
the rest of his science;
if
is
(iii.
is
who
started
man
not boldly miss-
is
not directed
"proceed
to-
presumed pace
at a
8)
that Montaigne's universe, as
lack
"If a
:
him
the foundation
criticism
self-sufficiency of those
and varied
diverse
my
which supposedly
the positive results of the sciences but toward their
The as
was
Concerning such a science he
too imperiously magistral"
still
it
for a third person,
despair, nor should
words are barren." Montaigne's
principles
matter,
own."
science that he repudiated
admits his ignorance of
new
deriving from
same thing
make me
ought not
of strength, for
ward
facility for
pleasure; so long as he does the
difficulty
from
some
successor with
strength
if
the traditional
we
can
is
just
image of the world
be-
call
that,
it
queathed by antiquity was unified and monotonous: nothing
re-
mains of the universal analogy that dominated the ancient conception of things.
"The world
"No
so universal in this
quality
variety.
.
.
is
is
but variety and dissemblance"
image of things
.Resemblance does not
difference creates otherness"
(iii.
among
"nations
13).
who have
But
this diversity
must not be
shows that there are
common
in the
new
never heard of us," customs and
beliefs strikingly similar to those of the Christian nations
there then a
2).
and
create oneness to the degree that
stated too categorically: experience Indies,
(ii.
as diversity
dealing with beliefs which, no matter
how we
12). Is
(ii.
natural source? Certainly not! For here
we
are
approach them, "do
not seem to belong to our natural discourse." Such resemblances are
more astounding than worker of miracles."
reassuring:
"The human mind
is
a
great
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
238
No
which the
ture
Human
unique, permanent nature at the heart of things.
recommended
Stoics
we
that
follow
is
na-
nothing that
can be known; of course
"it is
some natural
seen in other creatures; but they are no
laws, as
is
longer to be found in us, for everything, dominating,
reasonable to believe that there are
human
reason boldly interferes in
commanding, muddling, and confounding
the appearance of things in keeping with
its
vanity and inconstancy"
(ii.I2).
Under such
conditions, the doctrinal learning of
draws
scholars by profession ture but
mental
men ...
of
true usage the noblest
its
from knowledge
rigidity not it
mean
price"
to penetrate into a region that
kind; little
draws
its
value not from
how
to
draw from
itself
this
is
from
probably
does not cause
divine and superior to
is
its
And
8).
(iii.
from
object but
the boasting of a surgeon
is
he knows
less
his
it
worth
it
and most powerful acquisition
Montaigne's authentic discovery: science by
man
of na-
and very precious usage, which
a thing of very noble
not to be possessed at a
are
"to establish their funda-
and worth." This does not prevent
self-sufficiency
being "in
is
its
from those who seek through
men who
who
its
man-
usage; of
recounts his cures "un-
his treatment
something
to
shape
judgment." The worth of science derives from the worth of the
man who
it to use. That is why Montaigne man— not evasive universal nature or man saved by the grace of God, but man as he finds him, "bereft of outside help, armed solely with his own arms and stripped of divine
dominates
it
and puts
has for his perpetual subject,
cognizance and grace" Essais,
(ii.
12).
Hence
the
undertaking of the
whose methodical character becomes more
definite as
he
writes: "I dare not only to speak of myself, but to speak only of
myself"
(iii.
8). "It is a
thorny undertaking, more so than
would
it
seem, to follow such a vagabond course as that of our mind, to penetrate the dark depths of
hend
so
many
several years self,
I
fleeting
its
inner recesses, to choose and appre-
motions created by
have been directing
my
its
agitations.
.
.
.
For
thoughts only toward my-
examining and studying only myself; and
if
I
study some-
"^^^
239 thing,
it is
RENAISSANCE
for the purpose of applying
aptly, in myself.
.
.
description of one's
neither to
and
ciples self
fall
.
No
self,
it
more
description compares in difficulty to the
or surely in utility"
self
The
6).
(ii.
back upon what are presumed
harden one's
to
put
to myself, or to
it
to
object
is
be rational prin-
against experience, nor to
one's
let
be borne along willy-nilly by universal change. Here, too, one
must "choose and apprehend," and
Unked
to a divine
world but
involves not an intellect
this
sincere, attentive,
and prolonged
self-
examination.
The same
active skepticism
was put forward
the doctor Francisco Sanchez in his
way
Quod
brilliantly
by
nihil scitur (1581).
By
less
of contrast, however, this breviary of skepticism in
draws together the arguments against the existence of
which he
a perfect
and
complete science (things are so interlinked that complete knowledge of one of
them would imply complete knowledge
is
inaccessible to us) contains positive advice
is
accessible to
which tact
VIII
is
man: "One must not turn
to forsake nature,
The
and
Political
to
men and
but one must above
with things through experience."
Moralists
to
of the whole that
on how
know
Plutarch, were
life
The
brought ancient
read most assiduously, Cicero, Seneca, and even
imbued with popular Stoicism
philosophical doctrine.
Still,
a nucleus of Stoic ideas,
we
the Stoicism of St.
of the type concerned
the exposition of a rational
can hardly speak of a rebirth since
though somewhat neglected, had never
appeared during the whole medieval period.
We
Ambrose, which preserved
a Ufe of virtuous
^ Quoted by G. Sortais, La ^ De officiis i. 135; 85. i.
con-
Thinners
more with moral guidance than with
end
make
^^
conditions of development of the intellectual
who were
that
their writings,
all else
about a rebirth of Stoicism in the sixteenth century. authors
all
need only
as the
harmony between nature and philosophie moderne, p. 40.
dis-
recall
appropriate
self,^^
and the
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
240
extent to
which handbooks of moral guidance such
Alcuin,^^ Hildebert of Lavardin,^^ and
and Cicero
many
in their definitions of virtues
as
those of
others followed Seneca
and
vices
and
in their
conception of honesty. Roger Bacon's moral philosophy was inspired
from
start to finish
by Seneca. The moral philosophy of the Stoics
could be put in juxtaposition with the truly Christian Christianity could never absorb or supplant
it;
but
life,
the Stoics of the
Renaissance were conscious of the independence of their ethic even
though they were not
hostile to Christianity;
indeed, their Neo-
Stoicism represented a concerted attempt to reconcile the Stoic doc-
with the Christian
trine
the part of
men
life.
Not without
like Calvin,
who
protestations, however,
on
ardently defended the Christian
doctrine against the reproach of Stoicism; he viewed with horror the confusion "maUciously" created by his enemies between pre-
destination in nature
there
and
Stoic "fate," the latter being "a necessity contained
by virtue of a perpetual conjunction of
a vast difference between the Christian
is
and the
Stoic sage
who
who
seems "to be indifferent
things"; and
all
carries the Cross
to everything
and
msensitive to pam. It
was nonetheless
century especially,
true that in the second half of the sixteenth
many men showed
a predilection for the ethical
works of Cicero and Marcus Aurelius, and an even larger number for the
works of Seneca and Epictetus;
lated into French, studied, annotated,
all
of their
works were
trans-
and imitated. These works,
proceeding through metaphors and precepts which are impressed on the
mind through
strations,
a kind of immediate necessity, without
and which
satisfy a
demon-
need for comfort or consolation, met
with unprecedented success. They train the
mind
to discriminate
between the supernatural end of our actions that can be
known
only
through revelation and the effective guidance of our conduct. "M. T. Cicero and the other pagan Philosophers
^ Migne, ""
M/^.,
Pairologia Latina, CI, 613
CLXXI,
ff.
1007.
^Institution chretienne ,
I, viii,
xvi;
III, viii, ix.
may have
erred by mis-
THE RENAISSANCE
241
interpreting the end of
good works, but Christians can
from them and acquire from them But
was the complete
it
from Louvain, took pains
and Physiologia Stoicorum)
[1603]
classified all that eca,
was
works (Manuductio ad
excellent short
learn
Stoic doctrine, including metaphysics, that
Justus Lipsius, the scholar
The
profitable doctrines."
still
^^
known
could be
to disseminate.
Slot cam philosophiam
which he drew together and
in
in his time (mainly
through Sen-
about the Stoics), were preceded by a preface in which the author
warn
careful to
us "that no one should follow the Stoics in
seeking the ultimate good or happiness in nature unless nature
God
understood as
We
himself."
Seneca's inspiration that he
was
is
but the will of
himself his In the
own
life
God
able to
mind:
that could shock the Christian fate
can say that
it
was thanks
deny everything
is
to
in Stoicism
for instance, Seneca says that
himself and that
God
is
free "since he
is
necessity."
and works of Guillaume
Du
Vair (1556-1621)
significance of Neo-Stoicism.
fully the practical
family of magistrates, he was at
first
we
see
Coming from
under strong suspicion
a
at the
League, but with the arrival of Henry IV he became clerk-counselor
and
of the parlement of Paris, of Aix.
His Stoicism, contrary
true during this period,
draws from
He
later first president of the
to
what seems
was not
to
parlement
have been frequently
that of a submissive
man who
his readings only the strength to accept the inevitable.
was ready
for action
(and
this is the soul of Stoicism, the Stoi-
cism of Epictetus). At the risk of his Hfe he supported the cause of the legitimate king in his Traite de la Constance et Consolation es
Calamitez publique, written in 1590 during the siege of Paris by
Henry
of Navarre.
The
his country," to cure ity,
the
treatise
France of
was inspired by all
his desire to "serve
her ills— the luxury of the nobil-
simony of the Church, the perversion of
justice.
Neo-Stoicism born of the desire for moral guidance was quite ferent (and here ^Preface
to
we
find
what might be
of chap,
iii
dif-
paradox of history)
Les Offices de M. T. Ciceron. trans. Belleforest (1583); quoted by siecle, p. 131 (on translations, cf.
Mile Zanta, La Renaissance du sto'icisme an XVl^ all
called a
of the second part).
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
242
from the
minds
Stoic naturalism that nourished the
such as the Paduans or the Platonists of the
of freethinkers
Renaissance.
late
The
sentiment of spirituality that permeates the thinking of the Stoics
whom we
have been discussing
ception of the universe;
from being linked
far
it
to
is
not linked to any particular con-
concerns only the conscience of
blends with the Platonic spirituality whose role dicated. It
interesting to note that
is
man
Du
we have
already in-
Vair's Constance ends with
the words spoken on his deathbed by de
Thou, president
parlement of Paris, concerning self-knowledge: "Discourse sary for
knowing
things
whose forms
immersed
are
avoid learning anything about
naked and take up
it.
.
.
.
And
all
it.
the
For
is
back completely into one's
By
self-consciousness."^^
to raise self,
it is, it
of the neces-
manner
.
.
must enter the
.
to
is
in-
room; anything accessory thwarts
for this reason the true
of the nature of the soul
as
is
in matter
but to try to understand the nature of our soul in this
tellect
and,
any pantheistic vision of the world, readily
means it
of acquiring
knowledge
above the body and draw
it
so that self-reflection will lead to
asserting
the
independence of the
self,
such Stoicism borders on spiritualism, which asserts the autonomy
mind with
of the
Stoicism
among
is
respect to the
who were
Du
pressed so perfectly in
that
ills
not Stoics in the
is
itself.
right
strict
.
.
.
sense, to
with defective judgment which
we
it
is
find ex-
Vair ("for our will has the power to ad-
our opinion in such a manner that
which
has of
This idea from Epictetus, which
to us to reform.
just
it
responsible for the preservation of the tendency, even
the moraUsts
identify the source of our
up
knowledge
it
will give
its
assent only to
adhere to things that are manifestly true,
forbear and delay in the case of doubtful things, and reject whatever is
false"),
is
also at the heart of Pierre Charron's Sagesse (1603), not-
withstanding the strength of Montaigne's influence on the book.^^
Charron
If
"lofty
who
refrains
to
the
word "wisdom"
the
and bombastic meaning of the theologians and philosophers
take pleasure in describing and depicting things that have not
^Ed. Flach,p. 221. La Philosophic morale
^^
from attributing
des Stoiques, quoted by Zanta, p. 293.
"T^^
243
RENAISSANCE
yet been seen
fection that
and elevating them
human
nature
is
to
such a high degree of per-
incapable of reaching
than through the imagination" (Preface),
he requires
and
as the conditions of
freedom with respect
We
it is
nonetheless true that
"liberation
from the
world and the passions," and "complete
vices of the
Epictetus.
wisdom
them other
to
judgment
errors
intellectual
as well as will." ^^ All this
pure
is
should add that his concept of freedom entails the
precept "to obey and observe the laws, customs, and ceremonies of the land." It
follows that the moralist
stead of trying to find
According foibles ist is
is
to
inclined to study
is
some transcendent
man
as
he
is
in-
principle for his conduct.
Charron, self-knowledge or knowledge of
human
an important element of wisdom, and the task of the moral-
and
therefore to depict passions
their causes.
Contemporaneously with humanistic moral philosophy there arose a reaUstic politics
which refused
which
rejected everything concerning the divine
and contracts between princes and
right of princes
to see in society
their subjects,
anything more than the play of
human forces and the collision of passions. The prime example of the new politics is The Prince, the famous work by Niccolo Machiavelli ( 1 469-1 527), who gives us the fruits of the experience he acquired as a diplomatic agent of the Florentine Republic. Here are the aphorisms that justify the solidated his authority:
means through which the prince con-
"The common people take delight in evil; a ^^ Whether he is a prince is worthless."
multitude without a leader
by the will of the people
who wish
to use
authority.
The
institutions,
prince
and
is
against the powerful, yield to his
not a legislator but a warrior: "war,
discipline
its
him
must make everyone
or by the grace of the powerful, he
are
the only object to
its
which the
prince ought to give his thoughts and his application and which he
ought
who
to
make
his profession; for
war
is
the true profession of one
governs."^* Consequently a prince ought not to worry over
^ Book II, chaps, and ^ Histoire, II, 34; Discours, i
ii.
I,
44.
^Prince, chap, xiv, trans, in F. Franzoni, La Pensee de N. Machiavel,
p. 173.
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
244
when he
the charge of cruelty jects.
True clemency
exacting obedience from his sub-
is
few examples of harshness
consists in setting a
rather than in allowing the initiation of disturbances that will over-
Nor
turn the whole social order.
word
if
such fideUty
know how
circumstances: a prince "must act like a beast or like a
with laws, but
this
way
ten act "like a beast"
Here everything depends on
hurtful.
is
man"; he
of fighting
—that
is,
the prince obliged to keep his
is
acts like a
not
is
and a century
sufficient,
men
of-
of the Renaissance found
later Francis
must thank Machiavelli and
writers like
without dissimulation what
men
they ought to do."
and he must
he must use violence.
Lessons in realism are indeed what in Machiavelli,
the
moment to man when he fights
at the right
"We
Bacon could write:
him who
say openly
are accustomed to do, not
and
what
^^
the problem of the prince that Machiavelli poses at the be-
It is
ginning of the sixteenth century in
Italy;
it is
the problem of the
tyrant that fitienne de la Boetie (1530-1563) poses in his Discours
de
la servitude volontaire,
which he wrote, according
to his friend
Montaigne, "not yet having attained the age of eighteen, in honor of liberty
and against
How
tyrants."
can an infinite number of
persons allow themselves to be tyranized by one velli's
problem, considered
this
common
prince but from the viewpoint of the
could do nothing
if
will to be enslaved: "It
is
right,"
it is
so tiny
who
the people serfs
people.
The
tyrant
cut their throats; who,
to their misfortune, or rather
people cease in this
way
to use their "natural
because "the seeds of good that nature plants in us are
and
endure the
delicate that they cannot
caused by improper nourishment;
it
is
slightest
De dignitate et augmentis scientiarum Book ^Ed. Paul Bonnefon (1922), p. 56. '^
,
Ibid., p. 69.
wound
harder for them to subsist
than to degenerate, to decrease, and to come to nothing."
''
Machia-
or freemen, forsake their freedom
and take on the yoke; who consent it."^^ If the
It is
he did not find on the part of the people the
having the choice of being pursue
man ?
time not from the viewpoint of the
VII, chap,
ii,
sec. lo.
^^
Thus
RENAISSANCE
'T^^
245
La
the thought of
Boetie manifests a concern for the right of the
people and a juridical idealism that
set
him completely
apart
from
Machiavelli.
IX
An
Adversary of Aristotle: Peter
On
reading the elegant works of Peter
modern reader may
The
fact
is
that he
and by the
of the
wished
to
instruction
remedy the
a
man who was
offered
situation,
a speculative phi-
in
disturbed by the
the Parisian
schools,
who
and who encountered routine
re-
His tribulations are well known: born of a
sistance at every turn.
very poor family in Picardy, he 1536 by defending the
thesis
won
his degree of
Master of Arts in
"Everything that Aristotle taught
is
icommenticid) r In 1543 he published the Aristotelicae animad-
versiones\ the Peripatetics
was put before
the case
had him brought before
the king; Francis
I,
and
letters
lishing.
The
sions he
kingdom through
Ramus from
fault with Aristotle,
his ignorance,
suring strongly
was
his "con-
many
lifted
he obviously manifested and
and he even showed bad
faith
things that are good and true."^^
by Henry
II in 155 1,
and
for ten years
by cen-
The interRamus had
a brilliant career at the College of France, without departing
the old
framework of grammar,
dealt with
Converted
all
teaching or pub-
decree states that "because in his book on Animadver-
found
made known diction
sciences," prohibited
the parlement;
on account of
cern" for "the growth and enrichment of his
good
(1515-1572)
tragic events that they
was not primarily
losopher but rather a professional sterility
Ramus
well be astounded by his fame in his time, by
the tempests raised by his books, initiated.
false
Ramus
Ramee)
{Pierre de la
to
from
and quadrivium,
for his lessons
rhetoric, dialectic, arithmetic,
and geometry.
the trivium
Calvinism in 1562, he
left
Paris during the civil wars;
he found a hearty welcome in Germany and Switzerland, where he taught from 1568 to 1570. assassinated
two days
He
after the
returned to Paris in 1570 and was
massacre of
^ Decree quoted by Waddington, Ramus,
p. 50.
St.
Bartholomew, on
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
246
August
A
Charpentier, his colleague and implacable enemy,
26, 1572.
was accused of
murder.
his
teacher before
and
a simplicity
all else,
clarity
he tried
to
bring to every subject taught
no longer prevalent.
He
was, as Bacon said
not without irony, the "father of summations." His Animadversiones (1543)
was supplemented by
his brief Dialectique (1555)
and by
Advertissements sur la reformation de VUniversite de Paris au (1562), in
The
which he protested against the complexity
heart of his criticism of Aristotle
lines
"He wanted
:
to
make two
the other for opinion"; he
is
his
Roy
of instruction.
probably stated in these
systems of logic, one for science and
wanted
to separate live discussion, that
practiced naturally by "poets, orators, philosophers and, in a word,
by
excellent
all
men," from a
certain chaotic accumulation of useless
To sum up
rules that clutter the mind.^^ logic or dialectic
is
a practical art based
from doctrine and think
start
how
to reel off the rules in
Ramus: Some people
the thought of
on nature.
that they are learning logic "to school." ^^
from nature and keep company
One ought
know
instead to start
for a long time with poets, orators,
and philosophers. It
has been judiciously observed that Ramus* dialectic was
eled
on the
into
two
which
disposition or arrangement,
These are the topics, fects,
two
first
He
divides dialectic
consists in finding
arguments; and
and Quintilian.*^
rhetoric of Cicero
parts: invention,
which
consists in putting
classes of
order once they have been found. For the discovery of arguments.
Method
resolution of problems such as this one
grammar on we put them ** *^
in order.
arguments
—causes,
ef-
so forth. Disposition concerns both the formulation of ar-
guments and the method of grouping them
^ La
them
parts of rhetoric. Invention goes back to the
which indicate the general
and
mod-
a square of paper in order?
Dialectique, p.
Ramus
in the clearest possible
Ramus
order
is
distinct
from
or order applies only to the :
Having put each
precept of
and jumbled the squares, how can
has only to remark: "First, there will
8.
La Dialectique (1576 edition), p. 65. G. Sortais, La phlosophie moderne, p.
24, n. 3,
and
p. 39.
THE RENAISSANCE
247
be no need for invention, for everything has already been discovered."
He
therefore has not the sUghtest presentiment of the intimate
bond between order and invention
that Descartes discovered not in
and poets but in mathematics.
orators
In some contemporaneous
treatises
we
find a clearer presentiment
of method. In 1558 Acontio published a
method
examining the truth of a thing
and
which
it
parts:
method
method
(citra veritatis
has been acquired."
it
examen),
Thus
*^
his definition contains
is
general ideas but also "innate notions which,
is
two
from the most familiar
and the most familiar
pel everyone to grant assent
pursue knowledge
to
and method of exposition. The
investigation
of investigation consists in going
the least familiar
that defined
possible, in addition to
proper fashion the method through
to teach in a
of
De methodo
procedure that makes
as "a correct
to
Acontio not only
to
when advanced, com-
—for instance, the notion that the whole
greater than the part." But the
method remains nothing more
than an accessory that will not eliminate the need for examination of the thesis to
which
it
leads.
Ramism had
Despite such real weaknesses, the middle
Ramus
seventeenth
the
of
clearly recognized
and
century,
and write
ample of good to
the fruit of
vulgar language, ciples
I
—things that
many
We
desire,
scholars, to deliver
make known
disputes."
and that led him
in the vulgar language:
Greek and Latin schools and
especially
my
my
"When
I
Germany.
to forsake the
return from the
by way of imitating the exlesson to
my
country
study through the
was unable
.
medium
perceive several things repugnant I
in
called attention to the exigency of
clarity that characterized his era
schools
a strong appeal until
.
.
and
of the
to these prin-
to perceive in school because of so
^^
should add that Ramus, the enemy of AristoteHanism, met
along the
way
all
the pupils of the Paduans.
He
attacked Aristotle
not only as a logician but also as a freethinker and as the author of a theology that denies providence
and creation
La philosophic moderne de Bacon et Ramus,
*^
Quoted by G.
*'
Preface to the Dialectique, quoted by Waddington,
Sortais,
as well as the Leibniz, p. 46. p. 405.
author
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
248
He
of a moral philosophy independent of religion. his
the
opponents
Paduan
him with
ethic, the
as
Ramus
(Pro
P. Rami, 1551)
con-
novum Academiam
the indispensable character of an independent
one which "taught the pagans their domestic, public, and
and which teaches us
civil duties,
no price
sions"; "at
God
ence to
had
the libertines of his time. Galland, the friend of
all
Peripatetic Vicomercato, in his reply to
schola parisiensi contra
fronted
therefore
will
I
our desires and our pas-
to control
allow anyone to advocate piety and obedi-
while remaining silent about civic virtues."
^^
Platonism: Postel and Bodin
X
The
had
Platonic spirit
a pressing need for unity, a
need not
evidenced elsewhere. This search for unity characterized the great systems that brought to a close the period of the Renaissance.
came Guillaume
First
Postel's attempt, practical as well as theoreti-
nature, to utilize his
cal in
knowledge
1542). Postel thought that such unity rational character of religious truths
broke the unity of Christianity, no icism,
:
of oriental languages to
{De
realize the religious unity of the globe
was
orbis terrae concordia,
possible
by virtue of the
hostile to Protestantism,
less
than to authoritarian Cathol-
which estabUshed the Council of Trent, he saw
in a return to the forgotten origin of all religions,
His main concern was
to
refute the
which
salvation only
which
is
reason.
Paduans by demonstrating
creation ex nihilo
and personal immortality, and he confronted them
with Plato: "For
to refute Plato's Ideas, the
stances,
and everything implied by innate wisdom, they have gone
so far as to act." ^^
a
man
notion of separate sub-
We
deny
God
must add
by representing him
being constrained
that Postel's rational religion
of the Renaissance, that of a scholar
and Pico
as
della Mirandola, tried to relate
who, it
to
remained that of
like Marsilio Ficino
to a tradition
whose
echoes he found not only in Plato but also in the revelation of the sibyls, in the
Jewish Cabala, and
**
Quoted by Busson, Sources,
*^
Ibid., p. 297.
p. 225.
among
the Etruscans to
whom
he
RENAISSANCE
"^^^
249
devoted one book: a tradition that derives from Reason, here conceived no longer as a simple faculty of ratiocination but as the
Word,
the Logos, the world soul that animates
all
beings and in-
spires the prophets.
The
Jean Bodin was the author of a Republique (1577),
jurist
which he opposed Plato
in
to
MachiaveUi and stated that the
authority of the state remains subject to natural law (for instance,
cannot aboHsh private property), and that the
human
than that of the highest parative
method
in
good.
state
He
it
has no end other
introduced the com-
law with the intention of deducing from the
comparison a universal law. The fundamental idea of
his
plomeres, a colloquy between seven learned
Catholic,
men —a
Heptaa
Lutheran, a Calvinist, a Jew, a renegade Moslem, a Theist, and a Skeptic
—was
religions a
which
was
"is
still
the
same
common
as that of Postel: to select
core that can
simply the pure
more
all
existing religion
quest for God." But his religion
spirit's
simplified than Postel's, for
thing except the affirmation of one the exercise of moral virtues; attitude that caused
him
and
from
become the universal it
God and
in practice
contained hardly any-
of his worship through
he arrived
at a tolerant
to recognize all religions "in order not to
be accused of being an atheist or a dissident capable of disturbing the tranquiUty of the RepubHc."
^^
Italian Platonism: Telesio
XI
Social preoccupations
dominated the thought of Postel and of
Bodin. Quite different were the Italian thinkers to be discussed now: those
who beUeved
in universal animism. Like the Paduans, they
subscribed to the theory of a living universe; they differed from the
Paduans
in that,
first,
they were hostile to Aristotle and, second,
they offered their doctrine as a comprehensive view of reality, some-
thing wholly self-sufficient and not simply an adjunct to faith.
In the forefront was Telesio (1509-1588) who, according
Bacon, was the 'Ubid.,^. 168.
first
of the
to
Francis
moderns {novorum hominum primum).
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
250
He its
known through
revived Stoic animism, which he could have
He
Diogenes Laertius, Seneca, and Cicero.
two
principles:
heat
and
an active force and completely inert and passive
moving
matter. But the
force
or
force
contractile
divided into expansive force or
is
Expansion and contraction,
cold.
through their diverse degrees, explain of living beings. living being,
The
which
dynamism with
accepted
is
active force
a part of
is
the qualitative differences
a body, and the soul of the
also a body, a breath or
it, is
spread throughout the cerebral
all
cavities
pneuma,
and nerves. This conception
of the soul, popularized in the prevalent theory of animal spirits,
implies a thesis similar to that of the Stoics concerning the nature of
knowledge: sensation
is
wherein an object modifies the
a contact
breath or spirit which reacts defensively in accordance with nature;
its
De finibus)
own
(here Telesio follows the third
act of self-preservation
book of Cicero's
its
accounts for the development of ethics,
thanks to man's awareness of the interdependence of his welfare and that of others; is
officiis)
and the principal
(as in Cicero's
social virtue
mankind, whereas the inner virtue
is
the sublimity that
goodness in virtue. Intellectual knowledge
finds
De
(memory and
thought) consists in turn of preserving sensations and using them as a substitute for the senses
when
the latter are missing. Further-
more, sensation and consciousness are found not only
and animals but constitutes the
also in all
among men
Hving beings whose harmonious whole
animate universe.
Telesio also firmly supported the thesis of an immaterial soul
which
is
added
to the other soul
natural destiny, but
it is
and which has
to
do with our super-
difficult to interpret this
addition as any-
thing but a prudent measure in view of the powers of the Church
XII
Italian Platonism:
Giordano Bruno
Giordano Bruno (1548-1600) often named among
his
Italian
masters Francesco Patrizzi (1529-1597), professor at Ferrara and
Padua,
who had an
important role in disseminating
this esoteric
type of Platonism that blends together the ideas in the dialogues.
THE RENAISSANCE
251
Hermetic books, and the Chaldean
the mysticism of the
The same
oracles.
syncretism appears in the works of Bruno.
"Only an ambitious and presumptuous man," wrote Bruno, to
persuade others that there
of nature.
.
.
.
is
Even though we must always
most contemplative and
firmest, the
mode
of meditation,
yields
good
fruits
we have no
elect the surest
path and the
many good
things even though he does not
by reading Anaxagoras,
same
who
go beyond the
sets
many
soul.
No
We
above the soul an
intellect that Socrates, Plato, Trismegistus,
God."
tree.
things even though they
and
loftiest
mode
right to censure another
above the qualities of matter. Heraclitus says
rise
call
distinct
even though they are not from the same
Epicureans have said
"tries
but one path that leads to knowledge
that
The
do not
excellent
can profit
—the
intellect
and our theologians
^^
passage could better express Bruno's electicism and his dream
of an
He had
all-encompassing philosophy.
Aristotle
—the
man
"injurious
parage the opinions of
all
only one
enemy
and ambitious, who wished
other philosophers and their
to dis-
manner
of
philosophizing."
Such richness or rather such profusion of thoughts who,
like Leibnitz at a later date,
wished
to lose
in a philosopher
no part of the
speculations of his predecessors, has always been disconcerting to
those
who
contains
World
a
hierarchy of Plotinian
Soul,
infinity of tus'
try to explain systematically the doctrine of
hypostases
—God,
It
and Matter; the heliocentrism of Copernicus and the
worlds linked to
it;
Parmenides' Identity; and Democri-
atomistic theory, along with corpuscular physics.
Bruno's principal theses, not ordinarily found together. seen
Bruno.
Intelligence,
Plotinism closely Unked to geocentrism, which
These are
We alone
have can
provide a sensible image of unity; but Plotinus condemns any theory of atomism that
would
the continuity of
Do we
life.
substitute mechanical composition for
find in
systems? This seems impossible "Delia Causa
(ed. Gentile)
i.
170.
Bruno
when we
a series of successive
consider the works that
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
252
he wrote over a period of ten years 34 and 44.
Or do we
(i 582-1 592),
between the age of
prefer to see a tissue of contradictions in the
works written throughout
a troubled Hfetime by a
doned the Dominican convent in
man who
aban-
1576, aroused the suspicions of
Lutherans and Calvinists aHke, and languished for eight years in
from which he was released
the prisons of the Inquisition,
only to be burned at the stake ?
many
and even
inconsistencies
we
true that
It is
such
absurdities,
in 1600
find in his works as
singular
his
mathematical atomism which, composed of rows of points, seems to date from a period prior to Plato, before the discovery of irrationals.
But he nevertheless managed solidarities: indeed,
we
to extricate
Platonism from damaging
recall that in the
beginning Platonism, un-
was not linked
like the system of Aristotle,
centrism; that Erigena and Nicholas of Cusa,
whom
Bruno
in
any way
two great
to geo-
Platonists
particularly esteemed, favored the heliocentrism of the
Pythagoreans; that in the Timaeus Plato himself, after speaking of the world as of a living being
and of
which the world
of atoms according to
regular solids inscribable in spheres.
(and not
to that of
the
to Plato atoms, lines,
and
who
suggested to
is
soul, outlines a doctrine
composed of
It is to Plato's
Democritus) that Bruno
"To Pythagoras
text:
its
him
first
principles are
surfaces." ^^ It
is
corpuscles,
doctrine of atoms
refers in the following
monads and numbers;
Plato,
the idea of giving to
all
and not Epicurus, atoms a spherical
shape.
Thus Bruno,
a true exponent of intuition, broke
secular associations of ideas.
the contemplatio ordinis, things, but this
is
Vulgar
Platonists did not
knowledge
away from go beyond
of the hierarchical order of
merely the fourth degree in a scale that includes
nine degrees, the
last
two of which
one's self into the thing
are "the transformation
of
and the transformation of the thing into
one's self."^^ Furthermore,
Bruno
sees the perfect interpenetration
of every degree of knowledge: "It can be demonstrated," he writes,
"that
if
intelligence participates in sense,
^ De minimo ^ Sigillus
i.
lo.
sigillorum
i.
34.
then sense will be in-
THE RENAISSANCE
253
This significant text contains no trace of the op-
telligence itself."
and the
position between the senses
among
the vulgar Platonists, and
which
intellect
of thought: a continuous sUding (whether he
and
intellect or
most hallowed
is
clearly reveals Bruno's pattern
it
with the sensible and the
dealing with sense
is
intelligible)
from par-
ticipation to identity.
This fact explains the principal
He
—
reduces
all
one: the
to
hypostases
life
animal," which
is
—God,
same time one and
he cannot postulate matter that
and
Soul, Matter
and venerable
multiple.^^ In particular,
nothing more than non-being
is
that does not already contain every seminal reason.
from Plotinus
differs
divine reality
is
than
less
exactly
and
stance
him
unities of
numbers
existence.
God
is
Here he
generally supposed, for a truly the term intelligible
only modes of a unique sub-
numbers
are to the substance as
compound owe their
they
is
what Plotinus meant by
matter. All individuals are to
the
World
Intelligence,
of the universe, "the holy, sacred, at the
world.
traits of his vision of the
to unity, or rather as
which
to the primitive unity to
the
monad
of beings, the substance of substances, or as
of monads, the entity it
expressed in
is
De
immenso: .
.
.
Rerum
fades
Intimius cunctis
dum
quam
tantum fluctuat sint sibi
extra,
quaeque, vigens
est
Entis principium, cunctarum fons spicierum,
Mens, Deus, Ens, Unum, Verum, Fatum, Oratio, Ordo?^
"Whereas the surface of things continues essential to all things
Mind all
all
Word, Order." In
realities of different
infused into
he
is
more
than they are to themselves, the living principle
of being, the source of Fate,
to fluctuate,
forms. Mind, God, Being, One, Truth,
certain expositions
degrees: all
Mind
Mind
broken up into
superior to everything, or
things, or Nature;
and Mind that
things, or Reason.^^ In other expositions a
^ De immenso, quoted by Charbonnel, La ^^ De immenso viii. 10. i. ^^ De minima (beginning).
is
unique
Pensee italienne, p. 455,
traverses
reality n. 2.
God; is
the
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
254
focal point
and such
differences are of slight importance; they are
of value only to those
who
ports transcendence of
immanence, which makes sense only when
seek to determine whether
we accept God and nature as static and when we accept Bruno's dynamism with
contiguous stress
its
Bruno sup-
realities,
on the
not
active,
animating principle.
That
is
the explanation of the thesis of the infinity of the universe,
for divine infinity can be expressed only in a universe that
That
infinite.
is
adology)
.
The
also
the explanation, in spite of the apparent paradox,
of his atomistic theory (which could fact
is
prime
simplicity the
is
more
aptly be called
that Bruno, like Leibnitz at a later date,
monmakes
Compositum porro
characteristic of substance:
nullum substantia vera est^^ he accepts atoms, but they are not the
for this reason that
It is
"impious elements" of Democritus.^* Bruno's physics
way
mechanistic: surrounding atoms
region in which the world moves and
is
is
not in any
the ether, "an
lives," ^^ a
immense
medium which
fills
the space, body, and soul of the world and in which atoms are constituted
and combined; and
the nucleus around result
is
that
in each individual
which atoms
Bruno preserves both
collect
and
is
a soul that
fall
is
into place.
Hke
The
the Plotinian conception of the
individual as the image of the whole and a microcosm, and the
Democritean conception of the
indivisible element as a constituent
unit.
Through
his system
Bruno hoped,
ism, to achieve true religious unity,
as Ficino
did through Platon-
which he contrasted with the
unity of the Reformers, misanthropic minds that
sow discord
every-
where; with the unity of fanatical, pessimistic Catholicism that the
enemy
bloodthirsty
of nature; with the unity of
Judaism and
its
is
jealous,
God;^^ with the unity that he associates with the
"Egyptian religion," that
with the religious Platonism of Hermes
is,
Trismegistus. His religion
is
^ De minimo 3. 29. " De immenso v. 8. 36. ^ De minimo 2. 10. ^ Cf. the texts in Charbonnel, La
a gnosis;
it is
knowledge on the part
i.
i.
Pensee italienne, pp. 488-90.
THE RENAISSANCE
255 of
man
that
"God
than he can be
The thought Bruno
of
near him, with him, and more essential to
is
to himself."
of Lucilio
in precision
Vanini (1585-1619)
and
He
in breadth.
falls far
fled
short of that
from one place
another seeking refuge from his persecutors and finally to the Inquisition,
He
which had him burned
remembered mainly
is
him
^^
as a heretic at
as the disseminator
fell
to
victim
Toulouse.
and popularizer of
the theses of the Paduans.
Italian Platonism:
XIII
The
Campanella
animistic current culminated in the system of
Campanella,
who was
unquestionably a
spite of the period in
portant work,
De
published in 1620,
which he
is
which
parts of his parts are
clarity to obscurity
preservation
of
it is
ever
is
whole."
the
In
it
scholars
The
first
have
all
argument
is
Stoics
attributed only
to
the
main arguments
are sentient
it
and that
animals
is
parts are
imply sensa-
that of Chrysippus in Cicero's
De
and what-
all its
instincts or impulses that
deorum\ the second uses the theory of beings, following the
have identified
of the
a sentient being are of Stoic origin
a fortiori in the whole;
is
sentient because they tion.
is
Two
sentient because certain parts of
in the parts
demonstrated that the
but sufficient for his preservation and for the
demonstrate that the world
that
it is
knowing God, and that all his imbued with sense ranging from
panpsychism of Bruno and of Telesio. to
His most im-
described in the subtitle as "an admirable con-
the statue of the living,
and the
parts
of the Renaissance in
lived (1568-1639).
sensu rerum et magia, completed in 1604 and is
tribution to occult philosophy in
world
man
Tommaso
finibus, but
extended here to
De
natura
what the all
living
example of Plotinus. Campanella no longer
recognizes the hierarchy of animals, plants, and inanimate beings postulated by Aristotle and the Stoics. Like Plato and Plotinus he sees only
degrees: the nutritive faculty presupposes the sentient
faculty; intellect *'^
is
identical to sense; animals think
Quoted by Blanchet, Campanella,
p. 452.
and are en-
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
256
dowed with something cursus universalis)
.
To
that resembles
this
magic, conceived as Plotinus conceived a positive art of stars or
which
employing the occult
from the simple tension
is
discursive reasoning
conception of the world it
Ennead:
as
emanate from the
The
of the will.^^
{dis-
linked natural
in the fourth
forces that
typical of the action of nature,
is
action of magic,
diametrically opposed to
is
mechanism, which was then on the verge of triumph.
On
the naturalism of the Renaissance
erected a metaphysic
is
that develops the principle of the Plotinian system:
sympathy
in the sensible
world
the intelligible world. Sensible object
and
subject;
it
is
knowledge
more about
reveals to us nothing
the object
identified with
is
perceived. Typical of intellectual knowledge, however,
edge that the soul acquires independently of is
in fact inseparable
knowledge of cause itself
it is;
it is
itself;
all
just such self-consciousness.
is
knowl-
is
By acquiring itself
moment when
other things at the
changed into them. Yet the change
what
knowledge
knowledge of
things, "the soul acquires
what
it is
from
is
but a contact between
is
than the aspect through which the perceiver is
whatever
intimate union and identity in
it
be-
feels
not knowledge but the
cause or occasion of knowledge." According to the same principle, the
common
properties
and
similarities that
bind things together
provide the soul with an opportunity to contemplate Ideas; the assimilation of the
known
object to the
reahzed in our general concepts,
The
soul
all
—Power,
subject, imperfectly
perfectly reaUzed in the Idea.
and nature lead Campanella
"primaHties"
and of
is
knowing to a
Wisdom, and Love
God who
—the
contains in his
model
of our soul
things: a universal analogy that allows this sensuaHst to
ascend from the sensible to the
intelligible.^^
In 1599 Campanella took part in a conspiracy in Calabria where,
according to the records of the
trial instituted
parently represented himself as a
against him, he ap-
new Messiah and
tried to set
a theocratic republic similar to the one described later in
^ Cf. Blanchet, ^ Gilson, "Le
Campanella,
Citta
p. 217.
raisonnement par analogic chez T.
philosophic medievale, p. 125.
La
up
Campanella,"
in
Etudes de
THE RENAISSANCE
257
that of the regeneration of
The dominant mankind on the
He was
deeply concerned
del Sole, completed in 1602
idea of his Utopia
is
and published
more productive organization.
basis of a
with economic
in 1623.
"There are seventy thousand souls
realities:
in
Naples," he wrote, "and hardly ten or fifteen thousand workers are
numbered among them. Thus die for the sake of an
the workers exhaust themselves
employment
and
that exceeds their strength. In
the city of the Sun, the tasks are equally distributed, with the result that
no one works
economic
on
result
for
more than four hours each
was not the
to the discovery of the
God
them
drives
of a regenerated
there for
essential point:
day."
"A few men
Still,
the
are spurred
new world by the desire for riches, but a much more exalted purpose." This idea
humanity
that
would
attain
its
unity through a
natural religion basically identical to Christianity, was the funda-
mental idea of those
who brought
about the revival of Platonism
during the Renaissance.
XIV
Spanish Mysticism
Just as
the experimental
method
Leonardo abandoned the
of
metaphysical construction of the universe and saw in things mo-
mentary and changing equilibriums of tion of an ideal plan, so the
forces rather than the realiza-
contemporaneous mysticism of the
Spaniards abandoned speculation on the structure of the divine reaUty.
The
"God," said
sixteenth-century mystics practiced intellectual humihty: St.
John of the Cross (died
to give full credence (to
in 1591), "does not
wish us
our intimate and personal revelations) so
human channel of man's Church was total. The same St. John
long as they have not passed through the
mouth."
^^
Submission
to the
was
of the Cross rejected the idea that there that could lead the spirit
from the
sensible
procedure
a rational
world
to
God "Nothing :
created or conceived can provide the intellect with an appropriate
means **
of uniting with
God. Everything
Miguel de Unamuno, L'Essence de I'Espagne,
p.
that can be accomplished 215.
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
258
by the him."
intellect
^^
an obstacle rather than a means of approaching
is
Thus what
the mystic seeks through union with
God
not
is
the revelation of the essence of things or an answer to a question,
but above
all else
an inner freedom that
liberates
him from any
an immediate knowledge not dependent on meditation
restraints,
or on a process of reasoning. According to the testimony of
St.
Theresa (1515-1582), the divine inner words which the mystic cannot
fail to
hear,
which transform the
soul,
and which have such
a force that nothing can efface them, are nevertheless produced in the soul at
them and
moments when
are not
the mystic
prompted by
is
incapable of understanding
a desire to hear them.^^
The Spanish
mystic seeks the inner perfection of his soul and not, Uke Erigena or Eckhart, the revelation of the principles of the universe.
nature of the relation between the religious intellectual
life
'^
Cf.
J.
The
history of
thought, which had gone on for centuries, changed
under the influence of such mysticism.
^
and the
Baruzi, Saini-Jean de la Croix, pp. 412-13.
Vie de sainte Therese (trans. Bouix), chap, xxv, p. 323.
Bibliography
I
and
II
Texts E., Kristeller, P., and Randall, J., Jr. (eds.). The Renaissance Philosophy of Man. Chicago, 1948. Santillana, G. (ed.). The Age of Adventure: The Renaissance Philoso-
Cassirer,
De
phers. Boston, 1957.
Studies
Humanism. Translated by A. V. Littledall. WestminMd., 1958. Burckhardt, J. The Civilization of the Renaissance in Italy. Translated by S. G. Middlemore. New York, 1935. New edition, 1944. Bush, D. The Renaissance and English Humanism. Toronto, 1939.
Bouyer, L. Christian ster,
Collins,
J.
A
History of Modern European Philosophy. Milwaukee, 1954. Pp.
13-50.
De
Lagarde. Le naissance de
l' esprit
Idique au declin
du moyen
age. 6 vols.
Paris, 1948.
W. The
Ferguson,
Renaissance in Historical Thought: Five Centuries of
Interpretation. Boston, 1948.
N. Renaissance Concepts
Gilbert,
of
"Humanisme medievale
Gilson, E.
Method.
New
York, i960.
et Renaissance," in
Les idees
et les lettres.
Paris, 1932.
Haydn, H. The Counter-Renaissance. New York, 1950. Howell, W. Logic and Rhetoric in England, i^oo-iyoo. Princeton, 1956. Kristeller, P. Renaissance Thought: The Classic, Scholastic and Humanist Strains. .
Lucas, H. Riedl,
New
York, 1955.
Thought and Letters. Rome, 1956. The Renaissance and the Reformation. New York, 1934.
Studies in Renaissance
A
J.
Catalogue of Renaissance Philosophers (1^^0-16^0). Milwaukee,
1940. Sellery,
G. The Renaissance:
259
Its
Nature and Origins. Madison, Wise, 1950.
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
26o
III
Texts Erasmus. Opera omnia. Lugduni Batavorum, 1703-1706. The Praise of Folly. Translated by H. H. Hudson. Princeton, 194 1. Leon Hebreo. Critical edition of Dialoghi di Amore. Edited by C. Gebhardt. .
Heidelberg, 1929. The Philosophy of Love. Translated by C. Roth. Soncino Jewish Publication Society. 1937. .
Marsilio Ficino. Opera omnia. Paris, 1641. .
Five Questions concerning the Mind. Translated by
E. Cassirer, et
al.,
The Renaissance Philosophy
J.
Burroughs, in
Man. Pp. 193-214. Edited by E. Hoffman and R. of
Opera omnia. 7 vols. Klibansky. Leipzig, 1932-53. On Learned Ignorance. Translated by G. Heron. London, 1954. The Vision of God. Translated by E. Salter. New York, i960.
Nicholas of Cusa.
.
.
Paracelsus. Selected Writings. Translated by
N. Gutterman.
New
York, 1951.
Pico della Mirandola, Opera. Bologna, 1496. Oration on the Dignity of Man. Translated by E. Forbes, in E. Cas.
sirer, et al.,
The Renaissance Philosophy
of
Man,
pp. 223-54.
Studies Bett,
H. Nicholas of Cusa. London,
Cassirer,
1932.
"Giovanni Pico Della Mirandola," fournal of the History of
E.
Ideas, III (1942), 123-44, 319-46.
Dulles,
A. Princeps concordiae: Pico della Mirandola and the Scholastic
Tradition. Cambridge, 1941.
Huizinga,
J.
Erasmus
Kristeller, P. .
"The
of Rotterdam.
The Philosophy Scholastic
New
York, 1952.
of Marsilio Ficino.
New
York, 1943.
Background of Marsilio Ficino," Traditio,
257-318.
II
(1944),
H. Magic into Science: The Story of Paracelsus. New York, 195 1. M. Erasmus and the Northern Renaissance. London, 1949. Robb, N. Neoplatonism of the Italian Renaissance. London, 1935. Sigmund, P. Nicholas of Cusa and Medieval Political Thought. New Haven Pachter,
Phillips,
and Oxford,
1963.
Vansteenberghe, E. Le Cardinal Nicolas de Cues. 1920.
THE RENAISSANCE
26l
IV
VI
to
Texts Leonardo da Vinci. The Notebooks of Leonardo da Vinci. Arranged and translated by E. MacCurdy. 2 vols. New York, 1938. Philosophical Diary. Selections, translated by Wade Baskin. New .
York, 1959. Petrarch. Opera. Venice, 1503. On His Own Ignorance and That of Many Others, and other selections, in E. Cassirer, et al., The Renaissance Philosophy of Man, pp. 34.
146.
Pomponazzi. Opera.
On
.
by
J.
Man,
Basel, 1567.
the Immortality of the Soul. Translated by
Randall,
Jr.,
in E. Cassirer, et
al..
W. Hay,
II.
Revised
The Renaissance Philosophy
of
pp. 280-384.
Studies Douglas, A. The Philosophy and Psychology of Pietro Pomponazzi. York, 1910.
Duhem,
Etudes sur Leonard de Vinci. Paris, 1906-13. "Augustine and the Early Renaissance," Review of Religion,
P.
Kristeller,
P.
VIII (1944), 339-58. On Petrarch. "Ficino and Pomponazzi on the Place of .
Man
in
the Universe,"
Journal of the History of Ideas, V (1944), 220-26. Mabilleau, L. Cesare Cremonini: La philosophic de la renaissance en Paris,
1
MacCurdy, Randall,
New
Italic.
88 1. E.
J.,
The Mind of Leonardo da Vinci. New York, "The Development of Scientific Method
Jr.
1928. in
the School of
Padua," Journal of the History of Ideas, I (1940), 177-206. Seailles, G. Leonard de Vinci. 4th ed. Paris, 191 2. Whitfield, J. Petrarch and the Renascence. Oxford, 1943. .
Machiavelli. Oxford, 1947.
Ufe of Petrarch. Chicago, 1961. Vidari. "G. Cardano," Rivista italiana di filosofia, VIII (1893). Wilkins, E.
VII
to
X
Texts Guillaume du Vair. The Moral Philosophic of the Stoic\s, written in French by Guillaume Du Vair. Translated by Thomas James. Edited by R. Kirk. New Brunswick, N. J., 1951.
THE MIDDLE AGES AND THE RENAISSANCE
262
Justus Lipsius.
Two
Bootes of Constancie, written
in Latin
by Justus Lipsius.
Translated by Sir John Stradling. Edited by R. Kirk and C. Hall.
Brunswick, N. Machiavelli,
J.,
New
1939.
N. Tutte
le
opere.
Edited by G. Mazzoni and M. Casella,
Florence, 1929. .
The Prince and Other Wor\s. Translated by A.
Gilbert.
New
York,
1941. -.
The
Discourses. Translated by L. Walker. 2 vols.
London,
1950.
Montaigne. The Complete Wor\s of Montaigne. Translated by D. Frame. Stanford, 1957. Pierre Charron.
Of Wisdom. Translated by G. Stanhope.
3 vols.
London,
1729.
Studies Frame, D. Montaigne's Discovery of Man. New York, 1955. Gilbert, A. Machiavelli' s Prince and Its Forerunners. Durham, N. C., 1938. Hale, J. Machiavelli and Renaissance Italy. New York and London, 1961. Mauzey, J. Montaigne's Philosophy of Human Nature. Annandale-on-Hudson, N. Y., 1933. Mesnard, P. L'essor de la philosophic politique au XVI^ siecle. Paris, 1951. Ong, W. Ramus, Method, and the Decay of Dialogue. Cambridge, 1958. Popkin, R. The History of Scepticism from Erasmus to Descartes. Assen, i960. Ridolfi,
Sabrie,
The J.
Saunders,
Life of Niccolb Machiavelli. Chicago, 1963.
De I'humanisme J.
au rationalisme: Pierre Charron. Paris, 1913. The Philosophy of Renaissance Stoicism. New
L. fustus Lipsius:
York, 1955. Strowski, F. Montaigne. Paris, 1931. Whitfield,
Zanta, L.
XI
J.
Machiavelli. Oxford, 1947.
La Renaissance du
stoicisme au
XVI^
siecle. Paris, 1914.
XV
to
Texts Campanella. Opera. Vols. Giordano Bruno. Opere .
I, II,
and IV.
Paris, 1637.
Edited by G. Gentile. 3 vols. Bari, 1907-9. Opera latina conscripta. Edited by F. Fiorentino, et al. 3 vols. Naples, italiane.
1879-91.
On the Infinite Universe and Worlds. Translated by D. Singer in Giordano Bruno: His Life and Thought. New York, 1950. -. Concerning the Cause, Principle and One. Translated by A. Greenberg in The Infinite in Giordano Bruno. New York, 1940. Guillaume Postel. De orbis concordia. Book IV. Basel, 1544. Jean Bodin. Les six livres de la Republique. Lyons, 1579. .
THE RENAISSANCE
263
Jean Bodin.
The Six Boo\
of a
translation of 1606, edited
Commonweale. Facsimile
reprint of the English
by Kenneth Douglas McRae.
New Haven
and
Oxford, 1962. St.
John of the Cross. The Complete Worhj of by E. Peers. London, 1934.
St.
John of the Cross. Edited
Studies Baruzi,
Saint Jean de la Croix et le probleme de I'experience mystique.
J.
Paris, 1924.
New
edition, 1931.
Blanchet, L. Campanella. Paris, 1920.
Bruno de
Jesus-Marie. Saint Jean de la Croix. Paris, 1929.
Tommaso Campanella:
DiNapoli, G.
Filosofo della restaurazione cattolica.
Padua, 1947. Fiorentino, F. Telesio, studii storici suU'idea della natura nel risorgimento italiano. Naples, 1872-74.
"Communication sur Jean Bodin," Academie des
Lefranc, A.
(Session of January
Mercati, A.
Mesnard,
//
J.
de
Inscriptions
1928).
sommario del processo
P. L'essor
Moreau-Reibel,
6,
di Giordano Bruno. Vatican City, 1942.
la philosophic politique
Jean Bodin et
le
droit public
au
XVl^
siecle.
compare dans
Paris,
1936.
ses rapports
avec la philosophic de Vhistoire. Paris, 1933. E. Les aspects de Dieu dans la philosophic de G. Bruno. Paris, 1926.
Namer, Nelson,
J.
Renaissance Theory of Love:
The Context
New
of
Giordano Bruno's
York, 1958. Peers, E. Spanish Mysticism: A Preliminary Survey. London, 1926. Studies of the Spanish Mystics. New York and Toronto, 1927. "Eroici Furiori."
.
Troilo, E.
La
filosofia di
Yates, F. Giordano
Giordano Bruno. Turin, 1907.
Bruno and the Hermetic Tradition. Chicago,
1964.
INDEX Abelard, 41, 46, 48, 52, 59-68, 71-74, 78-79, 106, 114, 117, 137, 191, 219
Abraham,
Amaury
89, 167
Abubacer, 99 Acontio, 247 Acropolites, George, 106
Adam,
133, 208
Adam du
Petit-Pont, 79
Adelard of Bath,
Adelmann
Alkindi, 93-94, 96, 116 Allah, 91
49,
50
of Liege, 31
of Bene, 76-77
Ammonius,
6, 91,
107
Anacharsis, 6
Anaxagoras, 251 Anselm of Laon, 47, 59 Apollonius, 172
Apuleius,
II,
27-28
Aratus, 27
Alan of Lille, 52-53, 72-73, 75 Alberic of Rheims, 66
Archimedes, 219, 233 Arianism and Arians,
Albert the Great, 77, 113, 118, 123, 131-35, 150, 153, 158-60, 168, 201
Aristocles, 231
11,
60
Aristotelianism and Aristotelians, 28,
Albert of Saxony, 20Q-201
42, 48, 51, 60, 63, 70, 119, 125, 131-
Albigenses, 74-76
32,
Al
158,
161,
230,
232, 234,
Bitrogi, 165
Alchvvarismi, 49 Alcuin, 16, 27-29, 240
Alexander, 91 Alexander of Aphrodisias, 100, 230-
139-40,
Aristotle,
144-46,
177,
6-7,
149,
152-53,
207, 222, 225,
197,
247
15,
17,
28-30, 33-34,
38, 41, 50, 61-62, 65-66, 80, 91-94, 121,
126-29,
137-39,
141-42,
144-45,
156,
158-60,
164-65,
104,
106-7,
131,
133,
1
16-17,
Alexander of Hales, 113, 123-24, 129 Alexander Neckham, 165
147-49,
Alexandrians, 230 Alfanus, 53
202, 215, 219, 223,
151,
167, 174-76, 183, 191, 195-96, 198-
225, 228,
230,
232, 234-35, 245-47, 251-52, 255
Alfarabi, 94-96, 116, 119-20
Aristoxenus, 105
Alfred of Sereshel, 165 Algazel, 98
Arius, 2-3
Alger of Liege, 31-32 Alhazen, 98, 170, 172
Ashari, 98
265
Arnold of Ata, 90
Brescia, 74
INDEX
266
Bouchard, Amaury, 226
Athanasius, 3
and
Augustinianism
161,
154,
10, 34,
Augustinians,
165,
167,
183-88,
Bouix, 258 n.
Bovo
of Saxony, 28
Boyer, 12 n.
202, 207
Avempace, 99
Bradley, 20
Averroes, 98-101, 117, 134, 143, 148,
Bradwardine, Thomas, 189 Brahmans, 6
153, 165, 225
and
Averroism 164,
Averroists,
159-61,
219, 224, 230-33
174,
Avicebron, 78, 102-3, 116, 133, 149,
130-31,
Bruno, Giordano, 250-55 Buridan, 199, 230 Busson,
154 n.
154,
Avicenna,
Brehier, E., 33 n.
96-98, 147,
100,
i53-54>
116,
120-21,
165
216
H.,
Bacon, Francis, 244, 246, 249 Bacon, Roger, 167-72, 240
Caiphas, 68
Bartholomew
Calvin, 232, 240
Baruzi,
J.,
154 n.
256
n.
226
n.,
248 n.
n.
Capreolus, Johannes, 202
Bayle, 231 n.
Becket,
n.,
Calvinism and Calvinists, 245, 249, 252 Campanella, Tommaso, 218, 255-57,
258 n. n.,
n.,
Cajetan, 202
of Messina, 116
Basil of Caesarea, 17
Bauemker, 98 Baur, 165, 166
225
n.,
227 n., 228 n., 232 n., 234 Byzantine philosophy, 104-8
Thomas
a,
Cardano, Geronimo, 231, 232
78
Bede (Venerable),
11, 14, 16, 27, 47,
Carra de Vaux, Cassiodorus,
69, 168
9,
B.,
99
n.
27
Belleforest, 241 n.
Castiglione, Baldassare, 227
BerdiaefT, N., 216 n.
Cathari, 74, 76 Chalcidius, 15, 31, 49
Berengar of Tours, 29-32 Bernard of Chartres, 49, 51, 55 Bernardus Silvestris, 51-52
Charbonnel, 254
R.,
228
n.,
230
n.,
253
n.,
n.
Bernier of Nivelles, 160
Charlemagne,
Bernold of Constance, 47
Charles de Bouelles (Bouillus), 224 n.
Berossus, 167
Charles the Bald, 17 Charpentier, 246
Bessarion (Cardinal), 104, 225 Biel, Gabriel,
Christianity 13,
Jacob, 226
49-50, 60-63, 65, 69, 80,
136, 195, 215 Boethius of Sweden, 160
Boivin, 106 n.
Bonaventure, see St. Bonaventure Bonnefon, Paul, 244 n.
15,
and
Christians, 2, 3, 7,
17-18,
33,
38,
48, 51-52, 56-58, 60,
Boethius, 5-10, 13, 15, 17, 27-30, 4142,
10, 16
Charron, Pierre, 242-43
202
Blonchet, 255 n., 256 n. Bodin, John, 249
Boehme,
i,
120,
76, 105, 107-8,
1
d-],
40-41,
46,
71-73, 75-
13-14, 116-17, 121-
23, 131, 145-46, 152, 169, 184, 208,
216-19,
224-26, 232,
257 Chrysippus,
6, 81,
240-41,
248,
255
Cicero, 8-9, 15, 17, 28, 78, 81, 240
Claudianus Mamertus,
5,
9
INDEX
267
Durand
Clement IV, 168, 170 Clement VI, 197
Du
of Saint Pourgain, 192-93
Vair, Guillaume, 241-42
Clerval, A., 28 n.
Eckhart, see Meister Eckhart
Climacus, 107
Columbus, 236 Combes, A., 203 n., 209 Comte, Auguste, 113
Empedocles, 92 Epictetus, 240-43
n.
and
Epicureanism
Conciliarism, 192
Epicureans,
55,
215, 251
Constantine IX, 105 Constantine the African, 49, 54 Copernicus, 232, 235-36, 251 Cousin, v., 52 n., 61 n., 63 n., 64 66 n., 67-68, 72 n.
Epicurus, 81
252
n., 91,
Epiphanius, 17 Erasmus, 216 n.
Cremonini, 232
Eric of Auxerre, 28
Erigena, John Scotus, 16-22, 49, 63, 65, ^-j, 117, 201, 203 n., 252, 258
Cres, 113 n.
Euclid,
Cynicism, 107 Cyril of Alexandria, 3
Eugene
56 Eustratius, 106-7
Dante, 164 David of Dinant, 77-78, 118, 135 David the Jew, 131
Fernel, Jean, 232
Dehove, 65
Fracastoro, 222
9, 49, 73, 105, 172,
222
III,
Ficino, Marsilio, 219, 224-25, 248, 254
Flach, 242 n.
n.
Francis
Delacroix, 76 n.
Demetrios Kydonis, 106
I, 232, 245 Francis of Meyronnes, 201
Democritus, 49, 251-52, 254
Franciscans, 122-24, 189, 193-94, 202,
Descartes, 201, 227, 230, 247
227 Franzoni,
Des
Periers, Bonaventure,
234
F.,
243 n.
Fredegisus, 29
Dietrich of Vriberg, 173
Diodorus, 81
Frederick
Diogenes, 107
Fulbert of Chartres, 28, 31, 59
Diogenes Laetius, 250 Dionysius the Areopagite, 74,
77,
107,
118,
136,
17,
19-20,
149,
199,
II,
165
Galen, 49, 91-92, 165 Galileo, 201, 230, 232-33 Galland, 248
203 n., 220 Dionysius the Carthusian, 202
Gandillac,
Diophantus, 105 Dominicans, 122-24,
Gaunilon, 39 Gauthier (Prior of
193,
i35j
^^i,
204
Dominicus Gundissalinus, 119 Donatism and Donatists, 3, 9 Donatus, 9 Draeseke, 38
Duhem,
n.
P., 197,
230 n.
173,
M.
de, 224 n.
St.
Victor), 79
Gauthier of Martagne, 64 Gemistus, Georgias, see Pletho Gentile, 251 n.
George of Trebizond, 106 Gerard of Bologna, 164 Gerard of Cremona, 1 16-18
Dulin, 203 n.
Gerbert of Aurillac, 28-29
Duns
German
Scotus, 183-90, 197
mysticism, 203-9
INDEX
268
Gerson, 107, 203, 203
Hrabanus Maurus, 12-15,
209 n.
n.,
Gilbert of Poitiers (Gilbert de
la
Por-
54-55, 69-70, 73, 78-79
ree),
Gilbert the Universal, 66
Rome, 164
Gilson,
fi.,
125
n.,
122
St.
of St. Victor, 56-58, 149
n.,
12411.,
198
Hussites, 193
12911., 15811., 160 n.,
256 n. Giovanni di Fidanza, 125 Gnosticism and Gnostics, 75, 77 Godfrey of Fontaines, 163-64
lamblichus, 105
Gottschalk, 18-19
Imbart de
Grabmann, 43 Gregory Gregory Gregory Gregory
18
Cher, 161
of Strasbourg, 135
Hume,
711., 7611.,
126
n.,
of
Humbert, 164
Giles of Lessines, 159-60, 163
Giles of
Hugh Hugh Hugh
Ibn Pakuda, 103 Ibn Rochd, see Averroes
Ibn Tufail, see Abubacer la
Tour,
P., 191 n.
Innocent
II,
IX, 114, 118
Innocent
III, 74, 76, 1
of Nazianzen, 17
Isaiah, 34
of Nyssa, 17, 22
Isidore of Seville, 11, 27, 47, 49, 57,
n.,
79 n.
the Great, 4-5
72, 72 n.
13-14, 176
166
Grosseteste, Robert, 116, 165-67, 170,
172
Israeli, Isaac, loi,
119
Italian Platonism,
249-57
Grotius, H., 156, 156 n.
Guido
of Castello, 60
Jesuits,
Gurvitch, 156 n.
Jesus
228
Christ,
30,
2,
32,
40,
42,
57, 60, 72, 75-77, 82, 89, 106,
Hadrian, 167 Halphen, 88 n.
184, 208, 231 Jewish philosophy, 101-3
Harnack, 2 n., 4 n. Haureau, B., 58 n. Hebreo, Leon, 227-28
Joachim of Fiore, 76, 124 Johannes de Rupello, 124 Johannes Italus, 106-7 John (Pope), 16, 72
Hegel, 20
John XXI, 160 John XXII, 160,
Hello, 209 n. Heloi'se, 59, 60 n.
Henry Henry Henry Henry Henry
245 of Brabant, 116 II,
of Ghent, 162-64, 185, 187 of
Hainbuch,
192, 201
Heraclitus, 31, 251
Orthodoxy and
Hermes
164, 192, 194
John Philoponus, 92 John of Damascus, 105, 143 John of Jandun, 160, 192 John of La Rochelle, see Johannes de Rupello
of Navarre, 241
Heresies, see
47, 164,
heresies
Trismegistus, 251, 254 Hesychasts, 107
John John John John
of Mirecourt, 190, 197 of
Parma, 124
of Ripa, 202 of Salisbury, 51, 51 n., 63, 6^
Heurtevent, 31 n. Hildebert of Lavardin, 240 Hincmar, 18-19
Josqelin of Vierzy, 66
Hippocrates, 49, 165
Joseph, 106
65, 70 n., 74,
n.,
78-82
John of Viterbo, 157
i
269
INDEX Marius Victor, 9
Josephus, 167
Marsilius of Inghen, 201
Martianus Capella, 8-9, Martin V, 201
Kepler, 230, 232
Kilwardby, Robert, 123, 161 Koyre, 38 n.
B.,
50
Mary, 3
Matthew of Aquasparta, Maximus, 17, 107
La Boderie, Fevre de, 226 La Boetie, Etienne de, 244 Landry,
11, 28,
131
Megarians, 33, 79 Meister Eckhart, 135, 203-9, ^^6, 258 Metochites, Theodore, 106
189 n.
Lanfranc, 31 n., 32, 34 Latin Averroism, 157-60
Michael
17
II,
Laurentius Valla, 215-16
Michael Cerularius, 106
Lefevre, G., 62 n.
Michael
Lefranc, 232 n.
Michael of Ephesus, 106-7
106
Italicos,
Leibnitz, 231, 254
Michael the Scot, 165
Leo X, 230 Leo Magentinus, 107 Leonardo da Vinci,
Migne, 5 19 218, 233-34, 257
Linus, 226
n.,
10
n.,
20
n.,
n.,
n.,
54 n., 60 240 n.
n.,
41 n., 48 n., 53
70
n.,
72
14 n., 15 n., 16
31 n., 32 n., 33
n,,
n.,
107
34 68
n., n., n.,
n.,
Lipsius, Justus, 241
Mohammed,
Lombard, see Peter Lombard Lorenzo the Magnificent, 215
Montaigne, 234-39, 242 Moralists and political thinkers, 239-
Louis XI, 197 Louis XII, 190
Moslem
theologies, 89-91
Louis of Bavaria, 192 Louis of Padua, 202
Museum
of Alexandria,
Louis the Pious, 17 Lucan, 8, 27, 234
Mutazilites, 90
89, 106
45 i
Mutakallimoun, 90 Mysticism of the Victorines, 56-59
Lucian, 234 Lucretius, 55 Lull, Ramon, 174-75
Nagy, 93
Luther, 190, 202
Nemesius, 53 Neo-Platonism and Neo-Platonists,
n.
Nathin, 202
Lutherans, 252
2,
II, 17-19, 21, 40, 57, 78, 89, 91-93,
Machiavelli, Niccolo, 218, 243-45, 249
101-3,
Macrobius,
139-40, 172-73, 176, 184, 187, 208,
15, 28, 33-34, 49, 63, 6j,
123,
125,
130,
137,
220-32, 248-57
78
Maimonides
105-8,
(Moses
ben
Maimon),
Nestorianism, 60
103-4 Maitre, L., 27 n.
Mandonnet, P., 158 n., 159 n., 199 Manegold of Lautenbach, 34 Manicheism, 75
Neo-Stoicism, 240-41 Nestorius, 3
n.
Nettesheim, Agrippa von, 234
Marcian, 72
Nicephorus Blemmydes, 106 Nicephorus Gregoras, 106 Nicephorus Pediasimus, 107
Marcus Aurelius, 240
Nicholas of Autrecourt, 197, 199, 201
270
INDEX
Nicholas Cabasilas, 107 Nicholas of Cusa, 192, 216-18, 22024,
Peter of Poitiers, 48, 79
252
Modon, 106 Nicomachus of Gerasa, 8, Nicolas of
204 n. Pflaum, H., 228 n. Pfeiffer,
105
Pherecydes of Syros, 53 Philip Augustus, 1 13-14 Philo of Alexandria, 10,
Nifo, 230
Nominalism, 193-203
Ockham, see William of Ockham Ockhamism and Ockhamists, 194-99,
201-2,
217,
219-20,
156,
223,
Photius, 104
Pico della Mirandola, 225, 248 Plato, 5-7, 10, 16-17, 33, 35, 50, 62-
Talon, 234-36
63, 67, 69, 92, 104-7, ii7» 126, 195,
Origen, 17 Orpheus, 228
201, 219, 225-27, 251-52, 255
Platonism and Platonists,
Orthodoxy and 17, 52,
heresies, 2-5,
74-78
169,
165,
Pachymeres, George, 107
177,
Pliny the Elder,
Paracelsus, 226, 236
Plotinians
204
17,
14,
171,
i,
34, 206,
n.,
231,
126,
105,
140,
171,
204,
205, 208, 223-25, 229, 230 n.,
251,
253,
255-56
Plutarch, 81, 92, 239
122, 131, 161
Poggio, 215-16
60
Political
thinkers, see Moralists
and
political thinkers
Pelagius, 3, 4 Peletier, Jacques, 236
Pomponazzi, 228-31, 233
Peripatetics,
161, 165, 186, 193, 197-99,
152-
245
Porphyry,
(y-']^
15,
28-29, 62, 65, 80,
91, 105
Guillaume, 248-49
Perspectivists, 172-73
Postel,
Peter Auriol, 194-95 Peter Comestor, 48
Prantl, 29, 63 n.
Proclus, 36, 53, 73, 92, 96, 105-6, 173, 207, 220-21
Peter
124-25,
11,
and Plotinism,
96,
94,
Pediasimus, John, 107
115,
9,
Plotinus, 7, 12, 15, 20, 22, 57, 77, 92,
Patrizzi, Francesco, 250
Damian, 33 Peter Lombard, 48-49,
242,
229, 231, 251, 254, 256
Parmenides, 251 Paschasius Radbertus, 30 Pastor, 204 n.
and
218-32,
229
Parisian Nominalists, 199-202
3, 16,
193,
225
255 Palamas, Gregory, 107
54,
15,
248-57 Pletho (Georgias Gemistus), 104, 106,
Paduans, 228-31, 233, 242, 247, 249,
Peripateticism
6,
70, 105, 119, 126, 130-31, 133, 139,
78
Peckham, John,
i,
36-37, 40-41, 46, 49-52, 55-56, 64,
Oxonian masters, 165-67
Pelagianism,
21-22,
Pippin, 17
Oresme, Nicole, 201
Ovid,
12,
loi, 208, 225
57,
37,
23i» 233
Omer
Peter of Bruys, 75 Peter of Maricourt, 171
65,
183
69,
79,
Psellus, 104-6
Pseudo-Dionysius, 131
Peter of Abano, 219
Pseudo-Hrabanus Maurus, 30
Peter of Ailly, 192, 201, 203
Ptolemy, 92, 105, 118, 167, 236
INDEX
271
Ptolemy of Luca, 157
St.
Pyrrho, 107
St.
Bruno of Cologne, 56 Francis of Assisi, 124
Pyrrhonism, 234-39 Pythagoras,
17, 33, 92, 226,
252
Pythagoreanism and Pythagoreans,
i,
118, 20 r, 226, 252
6,
St.
Hillary, 12
St.
Jerome,
St.
John, 107
St.
Quintilian, 9, 246
133
17,
John of the Cross, 257 5, 60
St.
Paul,
St.
Theresa, 258
St.
Thomas Aquinas,
49, 77, 103, 113,
Rabelais, 235
115-16, 121
Radulphus Ardens, 47
131,
Ramism, 247 Ramon, 116 Ramus, Peter
183-84, 187, 191, 193, 196 St.
Ramee),
(Pierre de la
245-48
123-24, 126-27, 129,
135-59, 161, 163-64, 167, 172,
Vincent of Lerins,
11,
47
Sanchez, Francisco, 239 Sathas, N., 105 n.
Reason and
Remi
n.,
10-16
faith,
Schneider, 132 n.
of Auxerre, 28
Richard of
St.
School of Chartres, 49-52 Scotism and Scotists, 201-2
Victor, 58
Robert, 66
n., 79 n. Robert Pulleyn, 47 Robert of Cour^on, 118
Seeberg, 43 n. Seneca, 10, 51, 70, 78, 239-41, 250
Robert of Melun, 47
Sextius, 6
Roland-Gosselin, 121 Roscelin sis),
Sententiaries, 46-49
n.,
(Roscellinus
41-43, 62, 66
n.,
151 n.
Sextus Empiricus, 117, 198, 235
Compendien-
Siger of Brabant, 123, 135-36, 157-61,
198-99, 219, 229
191
Rousseau, 59 Rousselot, 227 n.
Simplicius, 30, 41, 107
Ruysbroeck, Henry John, 208
Skepticism and Skeptics, 98-99, 234-
Saadiagaon (Saadia ben Joseph), 102
Socrates, 30, 41, 50, 62, 64, 186, 251
Silvester
II,
28
39
Solomon, 107
Sabellius, 2 St. St.
Ambrose, 17, 22, 216, 239 Anselm, 34-42, 59, 65, 68,
137, St.
73, 133,
14
n.,
15-17,
3-5,
40.,
19-20,
19
9,
11-13,
n.,
28-30,
Stoicism and Stoics,
35> 37-39, 49» 57, 59, 69, 118, 123,
St.
Bartholomew, 245 Bernard (Bernard of Clairvaux),
56-57,
60,
65,
68,
71,
72
18, 38, 40,
52, 56-57, 77, 80-82, 81 n., 107, 166,
n.,
78,
Sufi, 89,
98
Suso, Henry, 208 Sylvester, Francis, 202
203 n.
Symeon, 107
Bonaventure, 113, 123-31, 124 n., 138, 161, 185, 191, 203 n., 228 n.
Tartaglia, 233
St.
4, 7,
n.
206, 219, 229-31, 238-41, 250, 255
128-29, 131-32, 151, 167-68 St.
ibn-Gabirol, see Avicebron
Sophonias, 107 Sortais, G., 239 n., 246 n., 247 Spanish mysticism, 257-58 Staupitz, 202
196
141, 184,
Antoninus, 202 Augustine,
St.
Solomon
INDEX
272
Voemel, 106
Tauler, John, 208
n.
Taylor, 106 n. Teles, 8
Wadding, 185 n. Waddington, 245
Telesio, 249, 255
Tempier,
fitienne, 159, 161, 168
Themistius, 91, 116
Therapeutae,
Peter, 75 Wazil, 90 Weigel, Valentin, 226
106, 106 n.
i
Thierry, 51
Thomas Aquinas,
see
St.
Thomas
Aquinas
Thomism and
Thomists, 161-64, 167-
Thou, 242 Tonquedec, 141
78,
William
116,
135-36,
of
Ockham,
192,
194-99,
202, 220
William of St. Amour, 124, 131 William of St. Thierry, 68-69 William the Clerk, 116
^
Ulrich of Strasbourg, 135 Ultramontanists, 192
Unamuno, Miguel
Witelo, 98, 172
de, 257 n.
Worms,
Universities, 190-94
E
98 n.
Wulf, M. de, 163 n., 164 Wiirschmidt, 28 n.
Vanini, Lucilio, 255
Vansteenberghe,
William of La Mare, 163 William of Moerbecke, 172, 198, 207
Trajan, 81
n.
Wyclifle, John, 190
192
217 n. Varro,
William of Auvergne, 120-22 William of Champeaux, 47, 62-63 William of Conches, 52-56, 63, 68, 191
68, 173, 183-85, 188, 199, 201
Ulger,
247 n.
Waldo,
Theodoric, 6
Theodorus Gaza,
n.,
Waldenses, 74-76
9 Vasquez, 156 6,
n.,
204
n.
Xiphilinus, 105
Yves of Chartres, 47-48
I
Vergil, 8, 17, 78, 81
Vicomercato, 232, 248
Zanta, 241
n.,
Victorines, 56-59, 203, 227
Zervos, 105
Vincent of Lerins, 47
Zoroaster, 6
242 n.
n.,
106 n.
PHOENIX BOOKS in
P
I
Philosophy
Herman Randall, Jr.: The Renaissance Philoso-
Ernst Cassirer, Paul Oskar Kristelkr, and John
phy of Man
P 5 P 8 P9 P i6
Jacques Maritain:
T.V.
Man
and the State
Smith: editor: Philosophers Speak for Themselves:
T. V. Smith: editor: Philosophers Speak for Themselves:
Karl Lowith: Meaning in History:
The Theological
From From
Thales to Plato Aristotle to Plotinus
Implications of the Philosophy
of
History
P
17
T. V. Smith and Marjorie Grene, editors:
P
18
T. V. Smith and Marjorie Grene, editors:
P P P P P
30
Rudolph Carnap: Meaning and Necessity:
34
Marjorie Grene: Introduction to Existentialism
Philosophers Speak for Themselves:
From
Descartes to Locke
Philosophers Speak for Themselves: Berkeley,
A
in Semantics
Richard Weaver: Ideas
Yves R. Simon: Philosophy of Democratic
81
Hans Reichenhach: Experience and Prediaion: Structure of Knowledge
Government
An
Manley Thompson: The Pragmatic Philosophy of C. Leo
Strauss:
The
Political
Lewis White Beck: Michael Polanyi:
and Modal Logic
Have Consequences
44 67
P no P 112 P 114 P 128 P 142 P 143 P 155 P 167 P 184 P 195 P 198 P 199 P 201 P 225 P 239
Hume, and Kant
Study
Philosophy of Hobbes:
A Commentary
Its
Analysis of the Foundations and the S. Peirce
Basis
and
Its
Genesis
on Kant's Critique of Practical Reason
The Study of Man
Charles Hartshorne and William L. Reese, ediiors: Philosophers Speak
Karl Jaspers:
The Future of Mankind
Michael Polanyi: Science, Faith and Society
Muhsin Mahdi: Ibn Khaldun's Philosophy of History Paul Shorey:
Leo
Strauss:
What
Plato Said
Natural Right and History
Emile Brehier: Emile Brehier:
The The
Hellenic
Age
Hellenistic
David Grene: Greek
Political
and
Roman Age
Thought
N. A. Nikam and Richard McKeon, editors: The Edicts of Asoka Robert B. Heywood, editor:
The Works of the Mind
of God
PHOENIX BOOKS in Religion
P 19
Paul
P 92 P 95 P 131 P 137 P 141 P 142 P 154 P 162 P 164 P 193 P 215 P 220
Joachim
Tillich:
The
W^dc/i;
Protestant Era
Sociology of Religion
Archibald G. Baker, editor:
A
Short History of Christianity
The Prayers of Kierkegaard Dallin H. Oaks, editor: The Wall between Church and Solomon Goldman: The Ten Commandments
Perry D. LeFevre, editor:
State
Charles Hartshorne and William L. Reese, editors: Philosophers Speak of
Paul
Tillich: Biblical
Thomas Ernest
F.
O'Dea: The
Cadman
God
Religion and the Search for Ultimate Reality
Mormons
The Study of the Bible, Revised Edition and Freedom in the Modem World Desert Saints: The Mormon Frontier in Utah Colwell:
Herbert J. Muller: Religion
Nels Anderson:
Edgar J. Goodspeed:
A
History of Early Christian Literature. Revised by Robert
M. Grant
4
PHOENIX BOOKS in History
P
2
P
II
John A. Wilson: The Culture of Ancient Egypt
P
13
Ernest Staples Osgood:
P 16
Edward Chiera: They Wrote on Clay
The Day of the Cattleman
The
Karl Lowith: Meaning in History:
Theological Implications of the Philosophy of
History
P 22
Euclides da
P 27 P 28
Daniel ]. Boorstin:
P 29 P 36
David M.
Cunha: Rebellion in the Backlands
Potter:
The Genius of American
The King and His England
Eleanor Shipley Duckett: Alfred the Great:
A. T. Olmstead: History of the Persian Empire
P 40 P 61
Giorgio de Santillana:
P 66
Alan Simpson: Puritanism in Old and
P 69
Gustave E. von Grunebaum: Medieval Islam
P 70 P 80
Oscar Jdszi: Dissolution of the Habsburg
P
125
Warren
S. Tryon:
Life in America, 1790-1870
P 150
Kenneth Stampp:
P
Eric L. McKitrick:
McDonald:
Donald Culross
P 156-157
Marc
New
England
Monarchy
When Egypt
George Steindorff and Keith C. Seek: Forrest
P 161
The Crime of Galileo
My Native Land:
The Colonial Craftsman
Carl Bridenhaugh:
P 144 P 147 153
Politics
People of Plenty: Economic Abundance and the American Character
We the People: The Economic
Peattie:
Ruled the East Origins of the Constitution
Venice: Immortal Village
And the War Came: The North and the Andrew Johnson and Reconstruction
Bloch: Feudal Society, Vols I and II
Richard C.
Wade: The Urban Frontier: Pioneer Life
Lexington, Louisville, and
St.
163
Ernest
P
165
Almont Lindsey: The Pullman Strike
K. Bramsted: Aristocracy and the Middle-Classes
P 166
William H. McNeill: Past and Future
P 167 P 168
Muhsin Mahdi: Ibn Khaldun's Philosophy of History
P 179
Leon F. Litwack: North of Slavery
P
Karl Lehmann:
Henry Bamford Parkes: Marxism:
in
Germany
An Autopsy
Thomas Jefferson
P 186
Frederick B. Artz:
P
Herbert ]. Midler: Religion and
193
in Early Pittsburgh, Cincinnati,
Louis
P
181
Secession Crisis, 1860-61
From
the Renaissance to Romanticism
Freedom
P 194
M. M. Knappen: Tudor Puritanism
P 202
Reginald C. McGrane:
P 210
Avery Craven: The
P 222
Milton Mayer:
in the
Modem World
The Panic of 1837
Coming of the
Civil
War
They Thought They Were
Free:
The Germans 1933-45
PHOENIX BOOKS and Law
in Political Science
A. Hayek: The Road to Serfdom
P 4
F.
P
Jacques Maritain:
5
Man
and the State
The Genius of American
P 27
Daniel ]. Boorstin:
P 67
Yves R. Simon: Philosophy of Democratic
P 84
Edward H.
P 97
Gertrude Himmelfarb:
P III
Milton Friedman: Capitalism and
P 112
Leo
P
Carl Brent Swisher:
113
P 115
An
Levi:
Strauss:
The
Robert A. Dahl:
Introduction to Legal Reasoning
Lord Acton:
Political
A
Preface to Democratic
The
Sebastian de Grazia:
P
Bertrand de Jouvenel: Sovereignty:
135
Politics
Its
Basis
Political
and
Its
in the
Genesis
United
States
Theory
Community:
A
Study of Anomie
A. Hayek, editor: Capitalism, and the Historians
An
Walter J. Blum and Harry Kalven,Jr.:
Carl Joachim Friedrich:
Inquiry into the Political
The Uneasy Case
The Philosophy of Law
P 137
Dallin H. Oaks, editor:
P
Karl Jaspers:
143
Conscience and
in
Philosophy of Hobbes:
F.
P
Study
The Growth of Constitutional Power
P 116
121
A
Freedom
P 120 P 130
PoUtics
Government
Good
for Progressive Taxation
in Historical Perspective
The Wall between Church and
State
The Future of Mankind
We the People
P 144
Forrest
McDonald:
P 152
Allison
Dunham and
P 160
Robert Endicott Osgood: Ideals and Self-Interest in America's Foreign Relations
Philip B. Kurland, editors:
An
Mr.
P 168
Henry Bamford Parkes: Marxism:
P 174
Morris Janowitz:
P
Ernst Freund: Standards of American Legislation
182
The
A
Autopsy
Military in the Political
Development of New Nations
Study of War
P 185
Quincy Wright:
P 189
Hans Morgenthau:
P 190
Karl Loewenstein: Political
Scientific
Man
vs.
Power
Power and
Politics
the Governmental Process
P 196
Walter F. Murphy: Congress and the Court
P 197
Lloyd A.
P 203
Philip B. Kurland, editor:
P 207
Arthur A. Cohen:
P 223
James Q. Wilson: The Amateur Democrat
Fallers:
Justice
Bantu Bureaucracy
The Supreme Court and
the Constitution
The Communism of Mao Tse-tung