250 111 6MB
English Pages 448 Year 2008
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Carnegie Mellon Symposia on Cognition David Klahr, Series Editor Anderson • Cognitive Skills and hei r Acquisition Carroll/Payne • Cognition and Social Behavior Carver/Klahr • Cognition and Instruction: Twenty-Five Years of Progress Clark/Fiske • Afect and Cognition Cohen/Schooler • Scientiic Approaches to Consciousness Cole • Percetpion and Production of Fluent Speech Farah/Ratclif • he Neuropsychology of High-Level Vision: Collected Tutorial E ssays Gershkof-Stowe/Rakison • Building Object Categories in Developmental Time Granrud • Visual Perception and Cognition in Infancy Gregg • Knowledge and Cognition Just/Carpenter • Cognitive Processes in Comprehension Kimshi/Behrmann/Olson • Perceptual Organization in Vision: Behavioral and Neural Perspetives Klahr • Cognition and Instruction Klahr/Kotovsky • Complex Information Processing: he Impact of Herbert A. Simon Lau/Sears • Political Cognition Lovett/Shah • hinking With Data MacWhinney • he Emergence of Language MacWhinney • Mechanisms of Language Acquisition McClellan/Siegler • Mechanisms of Cognitiive Development: Behavioral and Neural Perspectives Reder • Implicit Memory and Metacognition Siegler • Children’s hinking: What Develops? Sophian • Origins of Cognitive Skills Steier/Mitchell • Mind Matters: A Tribute to Allen Newell VanLehn • Architectures for Intelligence
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action Edited by
Roberta L. Klatzky Brian MacWhinney Marlene Behrmann
Psychology Press Taylor & Francis Group 270 Madison Avenue New York, NY 10016
Psychology Press Taylor & Francis Group 27 Church Road Hove, East Sussex BN3 2FA
© 2008 by Taylor & Francis Group, LLC Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 International Standard Book Number-13: 978-0-8058-6288-1 (0) Except as permitted under U.S. Copyright Law, no part of this book may be reprinted, reproduced, transmitted, or utilized in any form by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying, microfilming, and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without written permission from the publishers. Trademark Notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to infringe. Visit the Taylor & Francis Web site at http://www.taylorandfrancis.com and the Psychology Press Web site at http://www.psypress.com
Contents
About the Editors
vii
Contributors
ix
Editors’ Preface Roberta L. Klatzky, Marlene Behrmann, and Brian MacWhinney
xi
1
Measuring Spatial Perception with Spatial Updating and Action Jack M. Loomis and John W. Philbeck
2
Bodily and Motor Contributions to Action Perception Günther Knoblich
3
The Social Dance: On-Line Body Perception in the Context of Others Catherine L. Reed and Daniel N. McIntosh
4
Embodied Motion Perception: Psychophysical Studies of the Factors Defining Visual Sensitivity to Self- and Other-Generated Actions Maggie Shiffrar
1 45
79
113
5
The Embodied Actor in Multiple Frames of Reference Roberta L. Klatzky and Bing Wu
145
6
An Action-Specific Approach to Spatial Perception Dennis R. Proffitt
179
7
The Affordance Competition Hypothesis: A Framework for Embodied Behavior Paul Cisek
8
fMRI Investigations of Reaching and Ego Space in Human Superior Parieto-Occipital Cortex Jody C. Culham, Jason Gallivan, Cristiana Cavina-Pratesi, and Derek J. Quinlan
203
247
v
vi 9
10
11
Contents The Growing Body in Action: What Infant Locomotion Tells Us About Perceptually Guided Action Karen E. Adolph
275
Motor Knowledge and Action Understanding: A Developmental Perspective Bennett I. Bertenthal and Matthew R. Longo
323
How Mental Models Encode Embodied Linguistic Perspectives Brian MacWhinney
369
Author Index
411
Subject Index
419
About the Editors
Marlene Behrmann, PhD, i s a p rofessor i n t he Depa rtment o f Psychology, C arnegie M ellon U niversity, a nd ha s a ppointments in t he C enter f or t he Neural Ba sis o f C ognition (Carnegie Mellon University a nd U niversity o f P ittsburgh) a nd i n t he Depa rtments of N euroscience a nd C ommunication Di sorders a t t he U niversity of P ittsburgh. Her research focuses on t he ps ychological a nd neural mechanisms that underlie the ability to recognize visual scenes and objects, represent them internally in visual imagery, and interact with them through eye movements, reaching and grasping, and navigation. One major research approach involves the study of individuals wh o ha ve su stained b rain d amage t hat s electively a fects their v isual p rocesses, i ncluding i ndividuals w ith l esions t o t he parietal cortex and to the temporal cortex. hi s neuropsychological approach is combined with several other methodologies, including behavioral st udies w ith n ormal sub jects, s imulating n eural b reakdown u sing neural network models, a nd ex amining t he biological substrate using functional and structural neuroimaging to elucidate the neural mechanisms supporting visual cognition. Roberta L. Klatzky, PhD, is a professor of psychology at Carnegie Mellon University, where she is also on the faculty of the Center for the Neural Basis of Cognition a nd t he Human–Computer Interaction Institute. She received a BS in mathematics from the University of Michigan and a PhD in experimental psychology from Stanford University. Before coming to Carnegie Mellon, she was a member of the faculty at the University of California, Santa Barbara. Klatzky’s research interests are in human perception and cognition, with special emphasis on spatial cognition and haptic perception. She ha s done ex tensive research on human haptic a nd v isual object recognition, navigation under visual and nonvisual guidance, and perceptually guided action. Her work has application to navigavii
viii
About the Editors
tion aids for the blind, haptic interfaces, exploratory robotics, teleoperation, and virtual environments. Professor Klatzky is the author of over 200 articles and chapters, and she has authored or edited six books. Brian MacWhinney, PhD, is a professor of psychology at Carnegie Mellon University. He is also on the faculty of Modern Languages and the Language Technologies Institute. His work has examined a variety of issues in irst and second language learning and processing. Recently, he has been exploring the role of embodiment in mental imagery as a support for language processing. He proposes that this embodied mental imagery is organized through a system of perspective taking that operates on the levels of direct perception, space/time/ aspect, action plans, and social schemas. Grammatical structures, such as pronominalization and relativization, provide methods for signaling perspective switches on each of these levels. He is interested in relating t his h igher l evel ps ycholinguistic ac count t o ba sic n eural a nd perceptual mechanisms for t he construction a nd projection of t he body image.
Contributors
Karen E. Adolph, PhD Department of Psychology New York University New York, New York (USA) Bennett I. Bertenthal, PhD Department of Psychology University of Indiana Bloomington, Indiana (USA) Cristiana Cavina-Pratesi, PhD Department of Psychology University of Durham Durham, Great Britain (UK) Paul Cisek, PhD Department of Physiology University of Montreal Montreal, Quebec (Canada) Jody C. Culham, PhD Department of Psychology and Ne uroscience Program University of Western Ontario London, Ontario (Canada) Jason Gallivan, PhD Neuroscience Program University of Western Ontario London, Ontario (Canada)
Günther Knoblich, PhD Rutgers University Newark, New Jersey (USA) and Center for Interdisciplinary Research University of Bielefeld Bielefeld, Eastern Westphalia (Germany) Matthew R. Longo, PhD Institute of Cognitive Neuroscience University College London London, Great Britain (UK) Jack M. Loomis, PhD Department of Psychology University of California, Santa Barbara Santa Barbara, California (USA) Daniel N. McIntosh, PhD Department of Psychology University of Denver Denver, Colorado (USA) John W. Philbeck, PhD Department of Psychology George Washington University Washington, D.C. (USA)
ix
x
Contributors
Dennis R. Proitt, PhD Department of Psychology University of Virginia Charlottesville, Virginia (USA)
Maggie Shifrar, PhD Department of Psychology Rutgers University Newark, New Jersey (USA)
Derek J. Quinlan, PhD Neuroscience Program University of Western Ontario London, Ontario (Canada)
Bing Wu, PhD Robotics Institute Carnegie Mellon University Pittsburgh, Pennsylvania (USA)
Catherine L. Reed, PhD Department of Psychology University of Denver Denver, Colorado (USA)
Editors’ Preface
his volume is a collection of papers presented at the 34th Carnegie Symposium on Cognition, held at Carnegie Mellon University in Pittsburgh in June 2006. he s ymposium w as motivated by t he increasing visibility of a research approach that has come to be called embodiment. But what, exactly, is embodiment? For an insight into this question, consider a s eemingly elementary ac tion: breathing. W hen we breathe, we engage in a series of inhalations that are largely involuntary. hese inhalations are physiologically equivalent to the inhalations we produce voluntarily when we want to snif a lower. Even so, are the efects of the involuntary inhalations the same as the efects of the voluntary snifs? Brain imaging shows that there are clear diferences in activation, depending on the intention of the snifer (Zelano et al., 2005). If it is true that even something as basic as breathing is co ntextualized, w e sh ould n ot be su rprised t o ind t hat p erception a nd cog nition a re per meated by t he context of t he s elf i n t he world, where t hat context i s s ensory, spatial, temporal, soc ial, a nd goal directed. hat is embodiment. Our deinition o f em bodiment t akes co ntextual i nluence a s i ts cornerstone. It is based on the assumption that the way people perceive and act in the world around them is inluenced by their ongoing representations of th emselves in th at world. he overarching goal of the 34th symposium was to further our understanding of embodiment f rom m ultiple perspec tives—mechanistic (including co mputational), ne urophysiological, a nd d evelopmental. W e i ntended to identify i mportant p henomena t hat r elect em bodiment, adv ance theoretical u nderstanding ac ross a b road r ange o f r elated ields, and provide a foundation for future eforts in this emerging area of research.
xi
xii
Editors’ Preface
he f ormulation o f em bodiment u nderlying t he sha ping o f t he symposium w as p urposefully g eneral, i n o rder t o ac commodate the variety of approaches we saw as relevant. One particularly clear position has been ar ticulated by Clark (1999). Clark seized on J. J. Gibson’s concept of a fordance as t he central construct of embodiment. Gibson proposed that the environment ofers or “afords” to the perceiver/actor d irect c ues about what ac tions a re pos sible. A s the organism acts on the environment, its own state changes, as do the afordances ofered by the world, creating an ongoing dynamic chain. W hen a n o rganism i s a ble to c reate a n i nternal si mulation of t hese dy namic e vents, presumably by i nvoking its i ntrinsic perceptual–motor mechanisms, something new happens: A mode of processing emerges that facilitates perception and cognition. It is the embodied mode. he idea that an embodied processing mode exists has won increasing acceptance, but its scope remains a po int of contention. As formulated by Clark (1999), an extreme view of embodied cognitive science is that all thinking is embedded in body-based dynamic simulations; there is no i xed modular structure for the mind, nor do t heorists n eed t o post ulate abst racted r epresentations. W ilson (2002, p. 626) described as radical the view that, “he information low between mind and world is so dens e and continuous t hat, for scientists studying the nature of cognitive activity, the mind alone is not a meaningful unit of analysis.” We are not such extremists, but we ind the range of phenomena that potentially relect the embodied context to be rich indeed. Consider some e veryday obs ervations t hat m ight i nvoke s imulation of the body: A person turns to a friend while walking but maintains her course unerringly. An infant who is just mastering the act of walking ac commodates i mmediately to wearing a h eavy coat. A ten nis player inds her game improved ater watching a professional match. A newborn imitates a face he sees. Grandparents and grandchildren watching a p uppet show respond to t he dolls’ gestures and expressions as if they were people. Few formalisms have been put forward to describe how the context of the perceiver/actor functions at a mechanistic level and what neural structures support those functions. At this point, we have more phenomena than we have mechanisms. Behavioral research has revealed a n umber of tantalizing outcomes t hat point to a r ole for the representation of the body in basic human function. Embodi-
Editors’ Preface
xiii
ment has been theorized to play a r ole in eye movements, reaching and g rasping, locomotion a nd navigation, i nfant i mitation, spatial and soc ial perspec tive t aking, p roblem so lving, a nd dy sfunctions as d iverse a s phantom l imb pa in a nd autism. Neuroscientists have identiied multiple sensorimotor maps of the body within the cortex, speciic brain areas devoted to t he representation of space and place, and cells that acknowledge the relation between one’s own and another’s movements. Developmental researchers have studied neonatal behaviors i ndicating a r epresentation of s elf a nd have t raced the course of spatially oriented action across the early years. Computational m odelers ha ve po inted t o s ensory-based f eed-forward mechanisms in motor control. In organizing the symposium, we felt that what was needed was a shared efort to merge these perspectives to further our understanding of the forms and functional roles of the embodied representation. As a po tentially u seful st arting po int, w e su ggest t hree em bodied perspectives t hat m ight form a co ntext for perceiving, ac ting, a nd thinking: 1. 2.
3.
he body image is the ongoing internal record of the relative disposition of body parts across time. he bod y sche ma i s t he s et o f p otential b ody i mages, w here t he potential pertains either to the capability of all members of a species or speciically to one’s own self. (We acknowledge that these terms have a variety of deinitions in the literature—see Paillard, 1999, following Head & Holmes, 1911.) he spatial image is a representation of the current disposition of the body within surrounding space at a given point in time.
How might the body image, body schema, and spatial image play a role in perception and action? Directly opposing the extreme view of embodiment, what we will call the nonembodied approach would postulate t hat body -based r epresentations a re m erely el ements o f information p rocessing t hat p rovide n ecessary d ata f or co mputations. F or ex ample, co rollary-discharge t heory de scribes a n a lgorithm that enables the organism to keep a stable spatial image during an eye movement, whereby the updating of eye-position coordinates cancels the low of visible elements in retinal coordinates. Both coordinate systems exist and provide necessary data, but this mechanism imputes no special status to them. As another example, updating of the spatial image while walking without vision might be performed
xiv
Editors’ Preface
by sensing proprioceptive signals, deriving estimates of translational and rotational velocity, and feeding those to an internal process that integrates the signals over time. In this example, as in the irst, the aferent s ignals a nd t he der ived e stimate a re m erely d ata; t he fac t that they represent the body has no special mechanistic implications. his model requires neural mechanisms related to the self solely to support a coherent body experience. A second model, which we call the mapping model, proposes that the body image and schema function as integrated representations of relatively complex sensorimotor patterns. However, this model further stipulates that body representations play no fundamental role beyond s erving a s complex elements for purposes of i nput matching and output generation. On the input side, sensorimotor patterns would r esonate t o per ceptual i nputs, h ence enab ling r ecognition (conscious or unconscious) of one’s own or another’s action. On the output s ide, t he body i mage s erves a s a t oken for motor s ynergies that execute complex ac tions. Activation of t he body i mage would initiate execution of the corresponding motor program, but beyond this “ button-pressing” f unction, embodiment would play no direct role i n motor control. he mapping model requires neural mechanisms to represent complex patterns i n perception a nd ac tion, but does not propose that they are simulated to provide context. A third approach, which we call the embodied model, assumes that body representations are a unique form of data that are mechanistically involved in a broad set of information-processing capabilities, by virtue of perceptual–motor simulation and the context it provides. he visual input from another’s actions might be i nterpreted by activating the body image, analogously to the analysis-by-synthesis theory of speech perception, which postulates that listeners create or synthesize an ongoing predictive model of the speech that they are hearing. he body s chema might a llow per formers to compare t he observed behavior of another to their own habitual actions, enabling them to improve by watching an expert. he spatial image would be used to plan pathways through the immediate environment. his f raming of t he em bodied m odel g ives r ise t o f undamental issues, including: How are t he body i mage, body s chema, and spatial i mage i mplemented, f unctionally a nd n europhysiologically? (Some i mplementation i s r equired, wh ether one a ssumes t he n onembodied model, where t hese representations merely support subjective impressions, or the mapping or embodied model, where they
Editors’ Preface
xv
function directly in information processing.) How do these entities function in thinking, as well as perceiving and acting? How and for what purposes a re d iverse body pa rts i ntegrated i nto a r epresentation of the self, and how is this representation updated as the person/ environment linkage changes through external forces or the person’s own ac tions? W hat k inds o f n eural st ructures su pport s imulated movements o f t he body t hat m ight be u sed f or l earning a nd p removement planning? What are the developmental origins and timecourse of the body image, spatial image, and body schema? Authors of this volume bring to bear on these and related questions a broad range of theory and empirical indings. Biological foundations and models are dealt with by Culham and Cisek; the spatial image is the focus of chapters by Klatzky, Loomis, and Proitt; Reed and Shifrar consider t he body i mage a nd body s chema; K noblich, Adolph, a nd Bertenthal provide t he de velopmental v iewpoint; a nd MacWhinney brings a linguistic perspective. he symposium leading to this book was charged with excitement about the speciic research presented and the overall perspective of embodiment, and it is our hope that its publication will enable readers to share in that excitement. We gratefully acknowledge the symposium support provided by the National Science Foundation under Grant No. 0544568. Roberta Klatzky Marlene Behrmann Brian MacWhinney References Clark, A. (1999). An embodied cognitive science? Trends i n C ognitive S ciences, 3, 345–351. Head, H., & Holmes, G. (1911). Sensory disturbances from cerebral lesions. Brain, 34, 102–254. Paillard, J. ( 1999). B ody s chema a nd b ody i mage—A double d issociation in d eaferented pa tients. I n G . N. G antchev, S . M ori, & J. Ma ssion (Eds.), Motor control, today and tomorrow (pp. 197–214). Soia, Bulgaria: Academic. Wilson, M. (2002). Six views of embodied cognition. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 9, 625–636. Zelano, C., Bensai, M., Porter, J., Mainland, J., Johnson, B., Bremner, E. et al. (2005). Attentional modulation in human primary olfactory cortex. Nature Neuroscience, 8, 114–120.
1 Measuring Spatial Perception with Spatial Updating and Action
Jack M. Loomis and John W. Philbeck
Measurement of perceived egocentric distance, whether of visual or auditory t argets, i s a t opic of f undamental i mportance t hat i s st ill being actively pursued and debated. Beyond its intrinsic interest to psychologists a nd philosophers a like, it is i mportant to t he u nderstanding of many other topics which involve distance perception. For example, many complex behaviors like driving, piloting of aircrat, sport activities, and dance oten involve distance perception. Consequently, understanding when and why errors in distance perception occur w ill i lluminate t he reasons for er ror a nd d isluency i n t hese behaviors. Also, the understanding of distance perception is important in the current debate about the “two visual systems,” one ostensibly concerned with the conscious perception of 3-D space and the other with on-line control of action. Similarly, determining whether nonsensory fac tors, such a s i ntention t o ac t a nd en ergetic st ate o f the obs erver, i nluence per ceived d istance, a s ha s be en cla imed (e.g. P roitt, Stefanucci, Ba nton, & Epstei n, 2 003; Witt, Proitt, & Epstein, 2004, 2005) depends critically on the meaning of distance perception a nd how it is to be m easured. Still a nother topic where measurement o f d istance per ception is cr itical is sp atial u pdating (the imaginal updating of a t arget perceived only prior to observer movement) in volving o bserver tr anslation. B eing a ble t o m easure 1
2
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
the accuracy of spatial updating depends upon being able to partial out errors due to misperception of the initial target distance (Böök & Gärling, 1981; Loomis, Klatzky, Philbeck, & Golledge, 1998; Loomis, Lippa, Klatzky, & Golledge, 2002; Philbeck, Loomis, & Beall, 1997). Finally, m easurement o f d istance per ception is i mportant f or t he development of efective visual and auditory displays of 3-D space. Indeed, de veloping v irtual r eality s ystems t hat ex hibit na turally appearing scale has proven an enormous challenge, both for visual virtual reality (Loomis & Knapp, 2003) and for auditory virtual reality (Loomis, Klatzky, & G olledge, 1999), and there has been a spate of recent research articles concerned with understanding the causes for uniform scale compression in many visual virtual environments (e.g., Creem-Regehr, Willemsen, Gooch, & ho mpson, 2005; Knapp, 1999; K napp & L oomis, 2004; Sahm, Creem-Regehr, ho mpson, & Willemsen, 2 005; hompson, W illemsen, G ooch, Cr eem-Regehr, Loomis e t al ., 2 004). Virtual reality s ystems th at successfully c reate a realistic sense of scale will enjoy even greater aesthetic impact and user acceptance and will prove even more useful in the training of skills, such as safe road crossing behavior by blind and sighted children.
Indirectness of Perception Naïve realism is the commonsense view that the world we encounter in everyday life is identical with the physical world that we come to k now about t hrough our s chooling. Following dec ades of i ntellectual inquiry, philosophers of mind and scientists have come to an alternate v iew referred to a s “representative realism”—that contact with t he physical world is indirect a nd t hat what we experience in everyday life is a representation created by our senses and central nervous system (e.g., Brain, 1951; Koch, 2003; Lehar, 2003; Loomis, 1992; R ussell, 1 948; S mythies, 1 994). I ndeed, t his r epresentation, generally referred to as the phenomenal world, is so highly consistent and veridical that we routinely make life-depending decisions without ever suspecting that the perceptual information upon which we are relying is once removed from the physical world. he high degree of functionality of the perceptual process accounts for its being selfconcealing and for the reason that most laypeople and indeed many scientists think of perception as little more than attention to aspects of the environment.
Measuring Spatial Perception with Spatial Updating and Action
3
he r epresentational na ture o f per ceptual ex perience is ea sy t o appreciate w ith co lor v ision bec ause t he ma pping f rom p hysical stimulation to perceptual spac e entails a h uge loss of i nformation, from the many dimensions of spectral lights to the three perceptual dimensions of photopic color vision. In order to appreciate the representational nature of perception more generally it is helpful to keep in mind such perceptual phenomena as diplopia, binocular stereopsis elicited by stereograms, geometric visual illusions, and motion illusions; such phenomena point to a physical world beyond the world of appearance. A lthough experiencing such p henomena momentarily reminds us of the representational nature of perception, we too easily la pse back i nto na ïve r ealism wh en d riving o ur c ars, eng aging in sports ac tivity, a nd i nteracting w ith other pe ople. It i s quite a n intellectual challenge to appreciate that the very three-dimensional world we experience in day-to-day life is an elaborate perceptual representation. Indeed, many people seem to be naïve realists when it comes to visual space perception, for they think of visual space perception largely as one of judging distance. But, visual space perception is so much more than this—it gives rise to our experience of the surrounding v isual w orld, c onsisting o f su rfaces a nd objects ly ing in dep th ( e.g., G ogel, 1 990; H oward & R ogers, 2 002; L oomis, Da Silva, Fujita, & F ukusima, 1992; Marr, 1982; Ooi, Wu, & H e, 2006; Wu, O oi, & H e, 2 004). V irtual r eality ma kes t he r epresentational nature o f v isual spac e per ception ob vious ( Loomis, 1 992), f or t he user experiences being immersed within environments which have no physical existence (other t han being bits in computer memory). Teleoperator s ystems a re u seful f or d rawing t he s ame co nclusion. Consider a visual teleoperator system consisting of a head-mounted binocular d isplay a nd ex ternally mounted v ideo c ameras for d riving t he display. he user of such a tel eoperator system ex periences full presence in the physical environment while being intellectually aware t hat t he v isual st imulation co mes o nly i ndirectly b y w ay o f the display. Because the added deg ree of mediation associated with the display pales in comparison with the degree of mediation associated w ith v isual processing, t he representational nature of perception when using a teleoperator points to the representational nature of ordinary perception. How one conceives of perception determines how one goes about measuring perceived distance. For the researcher who accepts naïve realism, perceiving distance is simply a matter of judging distance in “physical space.” Under t his conception, one can simply ask t he
4
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
observer how far away objects are and then correct for any judgmental biases, such as reporting 1 m as 2 m. In contrast, for researchers who adhere to the representational conception, the measurement of distance perception is a major challenge, inasmuch as one is attempting to measure aspects of an internal representation. Because one starts with behavior of some kind (e.g., verbal report, action) and because there c an be d istortions a ssociated w ith t he readout f rom i nternal representation to behavior, measurement of perception depends on a theory connecting internal representation to behavior, a theory that is best developed using multiple response measures (e.g., Foley, 1977; Philbeck & Loomis, 1997).
Some Methods for Measuring Perceived Distance Verbal report and magnitude estimation are t wo traditional methods f or m easuring per ceived d istance ( Da S ilva, 1 985). F igure 1 .1 gives the results of a number of studies using verbal report for target distances out to 28 m (Andre & R ogers, 2006; Foley, Ribeiro, & Da Silva, 2 004; Kelly, L oomis, & B eall, 2 004; K napp & L oomis, 2 004; Loomis et al., 1998; Philbeck & Loomis, 1997). he data sets are generally well it by linear functions with 0 intercepts, but the slopes are generally less than 1.0. he mean slope is 0.80. Concerns abo ut t he pos sible i ntrusion o f k nowledge a nd bel ief into such judgments (Carlson, 1977; Gogel, 1974) have prompted the search for alternative methods. So-called indirect methods make use of other perceptual judgments thought to be less subject to intrusion by cognitive factors and then derive estimates of perceived distance by way of theory. Several of these methods rely on so-called perceptpercept co uplings. S pace per ception r esearchers ha ve l ong k nown that per ceptual va riables o ten co vary w ith o ne a nother ( Epstein, 1982; Gogel, 1984; Sedgwick, 1986). In some cases these covariations may be t he result of joint determination by common stimulus variables, but in other cases variation in one perceptual variable causes variation in another (Epstein, 1982; Gogel, 1990; Oyama, 1977); such causal covariations are referred to as percept-percept couplings. he best k nown coupling i s t hat be tween perceived s ize a nd perceived egocentric distance and is referred to as size-distance invariance (Gilinsky, 1 951; M cCready, 1 985; S edgwick, 1 986). S ize-distance invariance i s t he r elationship be tween perceived s ize (S’) a nd perceived egocentric distance (D’) for a v isual stimulus of angular size
Measuring Spatial Perception with Spatial Updating and Action
5
α: S ’ = 2D’ t an (α/2). A spec ial c ase o f s ize-distance i nvariance i s Emmert’s Law—varying the perceived distance of a stimulus causes perceived s ize to v ary p roportionally, w ith a ngular s ize h eld co nstant. Another coupling of perceptual variables is that between the perceived distance of a target and its perceived motion (Gogel, 1982, 1993). G ogel dem onstrated t hat t he perceived m otion o f a n object can be altered by mere changes in its perceived distance while keeping all other variables constant. He developed a quantitative theory for this coupling between perceived distance and perceived motion and applied it in explaining the apparent motion of a variety of stationary ob jects, such a s dep th-reversing igures a nd t he i nverted facial mask (Gogel, 1990). he existence of percept-percept couplings is m ethodologically i mportant, for t hese couplings c an be u sed t o measure perceived distance in situations where the researcher wishes observers not to be aware that perceived distance is being measured. Judgments of perceived size and perceived motion have been used to measure perceived distance (e.g., Gogel, Loomis, Newman, & Sha rkey, 1985; Loomis & K napp, 2003) and to demonstrate the efect of an e xperimental manipulation on perceived d istance (e.g., Hutchison & Loomis, 2006a). Another indirect method of measuring perceived distance involves judgments of collinearity and relies on the perception of exocentric direction. A visible pointer is adjusted by the observer to be aligned with t he t arget st imulus (W u, K latzky, Sh elton, & S tetten, 2 005); these authors used the method to measure the perceived distance of targets within arm’s reach under the assumption that the pointer is perceived correctly. Application of the method to the measurement of la rge perceived d istances seems promising, but t he method w ill have to compensate for systematic biases in exocentric direction perception (Cuijpers, Kappers, & Koenderink, 2000; Kelly et al., 2004). Still other indirect methods rely on judgments of perceived exocentric extent and attempt, by way of theory, to construct scales of perceived d istance. he best k nown ex ample is t he work by Gi linsky (1951) a nd, more recently, O oi a nd He (2007). I n t heir ex periments, observers constructed a s et of equal-appearing intervals on the g round ex tending d irectly a way f rom t he o bserver. he more distant i ntervals had t o be made p rogressively la rger i n o rder t o appear of constant size. Assuming that perceived egocentric distance over t he g round plane to a g iven point i s t he concatenation of t he equal appearing intervals up to that point, the derived perceived distance can be associated with the corresponding cumulative physical
6
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Figure 1.1 Summary of verbal reports of distance for visual targets. he data from t he d iferent s tudies h ave b een d isplaced ve rtically for pu rposes of c larity. he dashed line in each case represents correct responding. S ources from top to bottom: Experiment 3 of P hilbeck and Loomis (1997), experimental condition of Experiment 2A of Loomis et al. (1998), calibration condition of Experiment 2A of Loomis et al. (1998), results for gymnasts in Experiment 1 of Loomis et al. (1998), results of f ull ield of v iew condition of K napp & L oomis (2004), mean data from the control conditions in the 3 experiments of Andre and Rogers (2006), results of Kelly, Loomis, and Beall (2004), and egocentric distance judgments of Foley et al. (2004).
distance. he der ived f unction o f per ceived eg ocentric d istance i s compressively nonlinear even within 10 m a nd under full-cue conditions. Because t he derived f unction is noticeably discrepant with other functions to be d iscussed here and because there are process interpretations f or d oubting t hat t he der ived f unction i s i ndeed a measure of perceived distance, we do not discuss it further.
Methods Based on Action and Spatial Updating Given t he i mportance of d istance perception a nd t he lack o f consensus about how to measure it, researchers have occasionally pro-
Measuring Spatial Perception with Spatial Updating and Action
7
posed n ew m easurement p rocedures. H ere, w e f ocus o n r elatively new methods for measuring perceived distance that rely on action, sometimes w ith t he i nvolvement o f spa tial u pdating. he typical procedure begins with the stationary observer viewing or listening to a target stimulus. Ater this period of “preview,” further perceptual i nformation abo ut t he t arget i s r emoved b y oc cluding v ision and hearing, a nd t he observer attempts to demonstrate k nowledge of the target’s location by some form of action (e.g. pointing, walking, or throwing a ball). Visually directed pointing was a term coined by Foley and Held (1972) to refer to blind pointing with the inger to the 3-D location of a v isual target that had been previously viewed. his type of response has been used in other studies to measure the perceived locations of v isual targets w ithin a rm’s reach (e.g., Bingham, Bradley, Bailey, & Vinner, 2001; Foley, 1977; Loomis, Philbeck, & Zahorik, 2002). For more distant targets, ball or bean bag throwing has been used (Eby & Loomis, 1987; He, Wu, Ooi, Yarbrough, & Wu, 2004; Sahm et a l., 2005; Smith & S mith, 1961). A nother form of v isually d irected ac tion, blind walking (sometimes c alled “open loop walking”), has been used to study the perception of distances of “action space” (distances beyond reaching but within the range of most action planning; Cutting & V ishton, 1995); here t he observer typically v iews a t arget on t he g round a nd attempts to w alk to its location without vision. hese various forms of open-loop behavior, along with others to be discussed, are referred to collectively as “perceptually directed action.” Many studies have used blind walking to assess t he accuracy of perceiving the distances of targets viewed on the ground under fullcue co nditions, f or d istances u p t o 2 8 m ( Andre & R ogers, 2 006; Corlett, Byblow, & Taylor, 1990; Corlett & Patla, 1987; Creem-Regehr et al., 2005; Elliott, 1987; Elliott, Jones, & Gray, 1990; Knapp & Loomis, 2004; Loomis et al., 1992; Loomis et al., 1998; Messing & Durgin, 2005; Rieser, Ashmead, Talor, & Youngquist, 1990; Steenhuis & Goodale, 1988; homson, 1983; Wu e t a l., 2 004). Figure 1.2 shows many of the results, with the data sets shited vertically for purposes of clarity. Except for two data sets, perceived distance is proportional to physical distance with no evidence of systematic error (slopes of the best itting l inear f unctions a re generally close to 1, a nd i ntercepts are near zero). In contrast, when t he same task, modiied for audition, is u sed t o st udy d istance per ception o f so und-emitting sources heard out-of-doors, systematic errors are observed over the
8
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Figure 1.2 Summary of blind walking results for vision. he data from the diferent studies have been displaced vertically for purposes of clarity. he dashed line in each case represents correct responding. Sources f rom top to b ottom: E xperiment 3 of P hilbeck and Loomis (1997), Experiment 1 of W u, Ooi, and He (2004), mean data from the control conditions in the 3 experiments of Andre and Rogers (2006), results of E lliott (1987), average of t wo g roups of ob servers f rom E xperiment 1 of Loomis et al. (1998), Experiment 2b of Loomis et al. (1998), Experiment 1 of Loomis et al. (1992), homson (1983), Rieser et al. (1990), Steenhuis and Goodale (1988), and Experiment 2a of Loomis et al. (1998).
same range of d istances (Ashmead, DeFord, & N orthington, 1995; Loomis et al., 1998; Speigle & Loomis, 1993). Figure 1.3 shows representative results; this time, the data sets have not been shited vertically. he be st l inear f unctions have slopes close to 0. 5, i ndicating response co mpression r elative t o t he st imulus r ange, a nd t here i s considerable variability in the intercepts. We should mention, however, that in a recent review of these and other results obtained using other response measures including verbal report, Zahorik, Brungart, and Bronkhorst (2005) it power functions to the data and generally found exponents less than 1.0, the interpretation being that perceived auditory d istance i s a co mpressively n onlinear f unction o f so urce distance. Still, for t he range of d istances i n Figure 1.3, t he conclusion that they are linear functions with roughly constant slope but
Measuring Spatial Perception with Spatial Updating and Action
9
Figure 1.3 Summary of bl ind walking results for aud ition. hese are the actual data and have not been displaced vertically for purposes of clarity. he dashed line represents correct responding. Sources from top to bottom: Ashmead et al. (1995), Speigle and Loomis (1993), Experiment 1 of L oomis et al. (1998), and Experiment 2a of Loomis et al. (1998)
varying intercept is justiied. he source of the variation in intercept is a mystery. With vision, systematic errors do arise. Sinai, Ooi, and He (1998) and He et al. (2004) have found that when the ground surface is interrupted by a g ap, v isual targets resting on t he ground are mislocalized even with full cue viewing. Larger systematic errors occur when visual cues to distance are minimal. Figure 1.4 gives the results of a st udy by Philbeck a nd L oomis (1997) i n wh ich blind w alking responses a nd v erbal r eport w ere ob tained u nder t wo co nditions: reduced cues (luminous targets of constant angular size at eye level in the dark) and full-cues (the same targets placed on the loor with normal room lighting). When cues were minimal, both types of judgment showed large systematic errors, and when cues were abundant, both types of judgment showed small systematic errors. his study also showed that when the verbal responses were plotted against the walking responses in these and two other conditions, the data were
10
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Figure 1.4 Results of a n e xperiment u sing b oth ve rbal re port a nd v isuallydirected blind walking in reduced-cue and full-cue conditions. Adaptation of Figure 5 f rom Philbeck, J. W. & L oomis, J. M . (1997). Comparison of t wo indicators of v isually p erceived e gocentric d istance u nder f ull-cue a nd reduced-cue conditions. Journal of E xperimental Ps ychology: H uman P erception a nd P erformance, 23, 72–85.
well it by a single linear function, suggesting that variations in the two response measures are controlled by the same internal variable, visually perceived distance. A related experiment was concerned with measuring the perceptual er rors i n v isual v irtual r eality (Sahm e t a l., 2 005). Obs ervers performed blind walking and bean bag throwing to targets in both a real environment and a v irtual environment modeled on the real environment. Prior to testing, observers were given feedback only about t heir t hrowing per formance i n t he r eal en vironment. he results are given in Figure 1.5. he fact that the transition from the real to virtual environment produces the same errors in walking and throwing supports the claim that the two actions, one that involves locomotion and the other that does not, are controlled by the same internal variable, visually perceived distance. In addition, the results provide further support for the growing consensus that current virtual reality s ystems produce u nder perception of d istance (Knapp, 1999; hompson et al., 2004).
Triangulation Methods he s imilarity o f t he w alking m easures a nd v erbal r eports abo ve might be taken as evidence of a simple strategy for performing blind
Measuring Spatial Perception with Spatial Updating and Action
11
Figure 1.5 Results of an experiment using both visually-directed blind walking and v isually d irected t hrowing i n re al a nd v irtual e nvironments. Re printing of Figure 3 of S ahm, C. S., Creem-Regehr, S. H., hompson, W. B., & Wi llemsen, P. (2005). hrowing versus walking as indicators of distance perception in similar real and virtual environments. ACM Transactions on Applied Perception, 2, 35–45.
walking—while perceiving the target, estimate its distance in feet or meters, and then, with vision and hearing occluded, walk a distance equal to the estimate. Whereas t he blind walking t ask m ight well be per formed u sing this s imple st rategy, t here a re o ther cl osely r elated t asks t hat c annot. F oremost a re t riangulation t asks t hat r equire t he obs erver t o constantly u pdate t he est imated l ocation o f t he t arget wh ile m oving about i n t he absence of f urther perceptual i nput specifying its location. Figure 1.6 depicts three triangulation tasks that have been used. In “triangulation by pointing,” t he observer v iews (or listens
Figure 1.6
hree triangulation methods (see text for explanation).
12
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
to) a target and, then without further perceptual information about its location, walks along a st raight path to a new location (speciied by auditory or haptic signal) and then points toward the target. he pointing direction is used to triangulate the initially perceived and spatially updated target location. In one variant, the arm orientation was monitored continuously as the observer walked along a straight path (Loomis et a l., 1992) a ter v iewing a t arget on t he g round up to 5.7 m away; the average pointing responses were highly accurate. “Triangulation by walking” (also, “triangulated walking”) is similar to triangulation by pointing except that ater the initial straight path, the observer turns and walks a short distance toward the target. he walking direction ater the turn is used to triangulate the perceived and updated target location. Finally, in the “ indirect walking” version of triangulation, the observer walks to a turn point (speciied by auditory or haptic signal), and then attempts to walk the rest of the way to the updated target location. Figure 1.7 gives the results of a number of experiments using the diferent triangulation methods to measure the perceived distance of targets viewed under full-cue conditions (Fukusima, Loomis, & Da Silva, 1997; Knapp, 1999; Loomis et al., 1998; Philbeck et al., 1997; hompson et al., 2004); as in Figure 1.2, the data sets have been vertically shited for cla rity. A lthough the data are more variable than with blind walking (Figure 1.2), they indicate overall that perceived distance is proportional to target distance with little systematic error.
A Model of Perceptually Directed Action Because blind walking and the triangulation methods just mentioned rely on actions that occur ater the percept has disappeared, it might be argued that these methods cannot be used to measure perception because the action depends upon postperceptual processes (e.g., Proitt et al., 2006). However, we maintain that a valid measurement method is one for which the variations in the indicated values (those resulting f rom t he measurement process) are coupled to variations in the variable being measured and for which a calibration between the two has been established (Hutchison & Loomis, 2006b). As with any measurement device (e.g., a thermometer with an electronic display), the indirectness of the mechanism between the variable being measured and the indicator has no bearing on whether the indicated
Measuring Spatial Perception with Spatial Updating and Action
13
Figure 1.7 Summary of t riangulation re sults for v ision u sing t riangulation by pointing, triangulation by walking, and indirect walking, all obtained under fullcue conditions. he data from the diferent studies have been displaced vertically for purposes of clarity. he dashed line in each case represents correct responding. Sources from top to b ottom: results of i ndirect walking by P hilbeck et al. (1997), results of t riangulation by w alking in real environment (hompson et a l., 2004), outdoor results of Knapp (1999), average of two conditions from Experiment 3 (triangulation by w alking) of Fu kusima et al. (1997), Experiment 3 (direct and indirect walking) of Loomis et al. (1998), average of two conditions from Experiment 4 (triangulation by walking) of Fukusima et al. (1997), and average of two conditions from Experiment 2 (triangulation by pointing) of Fukusima et al. (1997).
values are proper measures of the variable of interest, here perceived distance. In the case of perceptually directed action, what is required is a theory linking the indicated value to perceived distance. Action can be used to measure perception provided that the postperceptual processes introduce no systematic biases or, if they do, that the biases can be co rrected for by w ay of c alibration. O f course, a s w ith a ny measurement device or method, the precision of measurement will ultimately be limited by random noise associated with each of the subsequent processes, even if systematic biases can be eliminated by calibration. Here, we present a model of perceptually directed action that links the perceptual representation to the observed behavior. he model
14
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Figure 1.8 A block diagram of perceptually directed action (see text for explanation).
involves a number of processing stages (Figure 1.8). For similar models, see Böök and Gärling (1981), Loomis et a l. (1992), Medendorp, Van A sselt, a nd Gi elen (1999), a nd R ieser (1989). F irst, t he v isual, auditory, or haptic stimulus gives rise to the percept, which may or may not be coincident with the target location (Figure 1.9). Accompanying t he percept i s a m ore abst ract a nd probably m ore d ifuse “spatial i mage,” wh ich continues to ex ist i n representational spac e even ater the percept ceases. here is evidence that the spatial images from diferent modalities are functionally equivalent, perhaps even amodal in nature (Avraamides, Loomis, Klatzky, & Golledge, 2004; Klatzky, L ippa, L oomis, & G olledge, 2 003; L oomis, L ippa e t a l., 2002). We assume that the spatial image is coincident with the percept, but future research may challenge this assumption; for now, it appears that error in the percept is carried over to the spatial image. When the actor begins moving, sensed changes in position and orientation (path i ntegration) re sult i n s patial up dating of t he s patial image (Böök & G ärling, 1981; L oarer & S avoyant, 1991; L oomis et al., 1992; Loomis, Klatzky, Golledge, & Philbeck, 1999; Rieser, 1989; homson, 1983). At any point in the traverse, as depicted in Figures 1.8 and 1.9, the observer may be asked to make some nonlocomotion response, such as pointing at or throwing to the target or verbally reporting the remaining distance. he response processes clearly are diferent for diferent types of response. An important assumption, to be discussed later, is that the response is computed in precisely the s ame fa shion wh ether ba sed o n t he co ncurrent per cept o f t he target or on the spatial image of the target (whenever the percept is absent). his assumption is depicted in Figure 1.8 by the convergence
Measuring Spatial Perception with Spatial Updating and Action
15
Figure 1.9 From le t to r ight, d epiction of 3 s uccessive mome nts d uring p erceptually directed action. A. he observer perceives a target closer than its physical distance. Accompanying t he perceived target is a more a bstract and spatially dif use spatial image. B. With the stimulus and its percept no longe r present, the observer move s t hrough s pace, up dating t he e gocentric d istance a nd d irection of t he target. I f path integration is accurate (as depicted here), t he spatial image remains stationary with respect to the physical environment. C. Ater moving, the observer can make another response to t he updated spatial image, by c ontinuing to move toward it, by pointing at it, by throwing at it, or by making a verbal report of the distance remaining.
of percepts, initial spatial images, and updated spatial images onto the output transforms for diferent types of responses. Not dep icted i n F igure 1.8 i s a n onperceptual i nput t o t he c reation of a spa tial image. Loomis and his colleagues (Avraamides et al., 2004; Klatzky et al., 2004; Loomis, Lippa et al., 2002) have shown that once a perso n forms a spa tial i mage, whether based on a spa tial percept or based on spatial language, subsequent behaviors (like spatial updating a nd exocentric d irection judgments) appear to be indiferent to the source of the input, suggesting that spatial images based on diferent inputs might be a modal. he implication is that the spatial image produced by vision, hearing, or touch, can, in principal, be modiied by higher-level cognition so as not to be spatially coincident with the percept. Whether this dissociation between percept a nd spa tial i mage e ver oc curs r emains t o be de termined, but the evidence to be reviewed is consistent with the assumption of coincidence.
16
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Accurate pa th i ntegration a nd co nsequent ac curate u pdating m ean t hat t he spa tial i mage r emains i xed w ith r eference t o the physical environment. If path integration is in error, multiple updated targets move with respect to the physical environment, but they move t ogether r igidly. I f only s ensed s peed but not heading during path integration is of by a constant factor, blind walking to a target over very diferent paths will cause the terminal points to coincide even though the convergence point will not coincide with the i nitially per ceived l ocation. C omparisons o f i ndirect w alking responses w ith d irect w alking r esponses t o t he s ame v isual t argets indicate that walking results in accurate path integration and consequent accurate spatial updating (Loomis et al., 1998, Philbeck et al., 1997). Figure 1.10 gives the average terminal locations for direct and indirect walking responses to visual and auditory targets
Figure 1.10 Stimulus layout and results of an experiment on spatial updating of visual and auditory targets by Loomis et al. (1998). he observer stood at the origin and saw or he ard a t arget (X) lo cated either 3 or 1 0 m d istant at a n azimuth of 80°, -30°, 30°, or 80°. Without further perceptual information about the target, the observer attempted to walk to its location either directly or indirectly. In the latter case, the observer was guided forward 5 m to the turn point and then attempted to walk the rest of the way to the target. he small open circles are the centroids of the direct path stopping points for the 7 observers, and the small closed circles are the centroids for t he indirect path stopping points. Reproduction of Fi gure 5.6 f rom Loomis, J. M., Klatzky, R. L., Golledge, R. G., & Philbeck, J. W. (1999). Human navigation by path integration. In R. G. Golledge (Ed.), Wayinding: Cognitive mapping and other spatial processes (pp. 125–151). Baltimore: Johns Hopkins.
Measuring Spatial Perception with Spatial Updating and Action
17
in one of these studies (Loomis et al., 1998). he congruence of the direct and indirect terminal points and their near coincidence with the v isual t argets dem onstrate t he ac curacy o f u pdating. he fact that the terminal points for audition are further from the auditory targets (along the initial target directions) than the vision signiies the poo rer acc uracy o f auditory d istance perception co mpared t o visual distance perception. Whereas actively controlled walking to targets at normal walking speeds produces accurate path integration and u pdating f or sh ort pa ths (e.g., P hilbeck, K latzky, B ehrmann, Loomis, & Goodridge, 2001), walking at unusual speeds or passive transport by w heelchair or ot her c onveyance ge nerally re sults i n degraded updating performance (Israël, Grasso, Georges-François, Tsuzuku, & Ba thos, 1 997; J uurmaa a nd S uonio, 1 975; Ma rlinsky, 1999a, 1999b; Mittelstaedt & Glasauer, 1991; Mittelstaedt & Mittelstaedt, 2001; Sholl, 1989), especially for older adults (Allen, Kirasic, Rashotte, & Haun, 2004). A more recent v ariant of perceptually d irected action prov ides a means of measuring the 3-D perceived location of a v isual stimulus perceived to lie above the ground plane (Ooi, Wu, & He, 2001, 2006). Figure 1.11 depicts t he procedure a nd t ypical pattern of results for luminous v isual targets placed on t he ground in an otherwise dark room. At the let, the observer views the target. Because of insuicient distance cues, the target is perceived to be closer than it is, resulting in the percept being elevated. he observer, wearing a blindfold, then walks out to the perceived and updated target and gestures by placing the hand at its location. Despite errors in distance (which are like those
Figure 1.11 Procedure and typical results for t he experiments of O oi, Wu, and He (2001, 2005). A glowing target was placed on the ground in an otherwise dark room. At t he le t, t he ob server v iews t he t arget. B ecause of i nsuicient distance cues, t he target is perceived to b e closer t han it i s, resulting in t he percept being elevated. he observer, wearing a bl indfold, t hen walks out to t he perceived a nd updated target and crouches to place the hand at its location. he angle α is “angular declination” (or “height in the ield”), which is an important cue to egocentric distance.
18
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
reported by Philbeck and Loomis [1997]; see Figure 1.4), the indicated locations lay in very nearly the same direction as the targets as viewed from the origin. Given the complexity of this “blind-walking–gesturing” r esponse, t his i s a r emarkable r esult. I t i s d iicult to imagine any interpretation of this result other than one of systematic error in perceiving the target’s distance followed by accurate path integration and spatial updating. Similar evidence supporting this interpretation comes from the aforementioned studies involving both direct and indirect walking (Loomis, Klatzky et al., 1998; Loomis, Lippa et al., 2002; Philbeck et al. 1997). When people walked along indirect paths while updating, they traveled to very nearly the same locations as when traveling along direct paths. Importantly, when the terminal points cl early de viated f rom t he t argets i n ter ms o f d istance, i ndicating distance errors, the directions were nonetheless quite accurate (Loomis, Klatzky et al., 1998; Loomis, Lippa et al., 2002; Philbeck et al. 1997). he conclusion is strong that observers were traveling to the perceived and updated target locations. Still further evidence that perceptually directed action can be used t o m easure per ceived l ocation a nd, t hus, per ceived d istance, comes f rom recent work by Ooi et a l. (2006). he y performed two experiments, one involving t he blind-walking—gesturing response to luminous point targets in the dark—and the other involving judgments of the shapes of luminous igures, also viewed in the dark. he indicated locations and judged slants were consistent with the targets in the two tasks being located on an implicit surface, extending from near the observer’s feet and moving outward while curving upward; the a uthors h ypothesize t hat t he i mplicit su rface r elects intrinsic biases of the visual system, like the speciic distance tendency (Gogel & Tietz, 1979). It is signiicant that two such very diferent responses, one involving action and other involving judgments of shape, can be understood in terms of a unitary perceptual process. he lexibility of perceptually directed action is indicated by studies demonstrating on-line modiication of the response. In a h ighly inluential paper, homson (1983) reported an experiment that prevented t he obs erver f rom ex ecuting a p replanned r esponse. On a given trial, the observer viewed a target on the ground some distance ahead. Ater the observer began blind walking toward the target, the experimenter gave a signal to stop and throw a beanbag the remaining d istance. A ccuracy w as h igh e ven t hough obs ervers d id n ot know at wh ich point t hey would be c ued to t hrow, demonstrating a lexible response combining two forms of action. Another exam-
Measuring Spatial Perception with Spatial Updating and Action
19
ple of on-l ine modiication comes f rom one of t he ex periments on direct a nd indirect w alking to t argets (Philbeck e t a l., 1997). Here observers viewed a target, ater which their vision and hearing were occluded. On c ue f rom t he ex perimenter, t he obs ervers w alked t o the target a long one of t hree paths. Because t hey were not cued as to which pat h to take until a ter vision was occluded, the excellent updating performance indicates that observers could not have been preprogramming t he response. Given t hese results, it appears t hat action directed toward a goal is extremely lexible. Presumably, once a goal ha s been established, a ny combination of ac tions, i ncluding walking, sidestepping, crawling, and throwing can be assembled “on the ly” to indicate the location of an initially perceived target. For other evidence of on-line adjustment of perceptually directed action, see the paper by Farrell and ho mson (1999). Despite the involvement of cognitive and locomotor processes in perceptually directed action, the results of a number of experiments demonstrate that this method provides a pure, albeit indirect, measure o f per ceived d istance (and d irection). hey do so by demonstrating t hat cog nitive a nd motor processes contribute l ittle to t he systematic error of task performance. Especially compelling are the results demonstrating t he absence of systematic error in path integration, spatial updating, and response execution through the congruence o f d irect a nd i ndirect w alking pa ths ( Loomis, K latzky e t al., 1998; Loomis, Lippa et al., 2002; Philbeck et al., 1997; see Figure 1.10) and the result of Ooi et al. (2001, 2006) showing that terminal location of a co mplex spatial response is consistent with t he initial target d irection. I n add ition, t he close coupling of ac tion a nd verbal responses in both reduced-cue and full-cue conditions (Philbeck & Loomis, 1997), the close coupling of blind walking and throwing responses in both real and virtual environments (Sahm et al., 2005), and t he close coupling of blind walking/gesturing and shape judgments (Ooi et al., 2006; Wu et al., 2004) is further support that the action-based method provides a m easure of distance perception. A later section showing that spatial updating can be used to correct for biases in verbal report provides still further evidence.
Role of Calibration in Perceptually Directed Action Although w e bel ieve t hat cog nitive a nd m otor p rocesses d o n ot contribute appreciably to systematic errors in perceptually directed
20
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
action, such processes are clearly required to control and execute the response. In light of this, and given the very high accuracy of visually directed action under full-cue conditions, there is good reason to believe that perceptually directed action depends on some adaptation process t hat ke eps t he ac tion s ystem i n c alibration. I ndeed, several forms of adaptation of perceptually directed action have been demonstrated (Durgin, Fox, & Kim, 2003; Durgin, Gigone, & Scott, 2005; Durgin, Pelah, Fox, Lewis, Kane et al., 2005; Ellard & Shaughnessy, 2003; Mohler, Creem-Regehr, & hompson, 2006; Ooi et a l., 2001; Philbeck, O’Leary, & L ew, 2004; R ichardson & W aller, 2005; Rieser, Pick, Ashmead, & Garing, 1995; Witt et al., 2004). Does adaptation call into question the claim that perceptually directed action can be used to measure perception? Because per ception, pa th i ntegration/spatial u pdating, a nd response ex ecution a ll co ntribute t o pe rceptually d irected a ction, adaptation o f a ny o f t hese p rocesses o r o f t he co uplings be tween them c an be ex pected t o a lter t ask per formance. A daptation t hat alters perceived distance will inluence all measures of distance perception ( verbal r eport, s ize-based m easures, a nd a ll ac tion-based measures, i ncluding w alking a nd t hrowing) f or wha tever s ensory modality has been adapted. In the aforementioned study, Ooi et al. (2001) used prism adaptation during a prior period of walking with vision to alter the efective “angular declination,” one of the cues in sensing target distance (represented by α in Figure 1.11). he results showed that perceived distance was indeed altered because walking and t hrowing r esponses were s imilarly a fected, e ven t hough on ly walking was used during adaptation. Adaptation o f t he pa th i ntegration p rocess a lters t he g ain o f sensed self-motion relative to actual physical motion and is expected to have a uniform inluence on walked distance. hat is, if the gain is halved, observers ought to walk twice as far in order to arrive at the updated targets, and this efect should apply to all targets regardless of initial distance and t he path taken. If t he adaptation of walking speed is speciic to walking direction, t hen t he efect of adaptation on path integration will depend upon the walking direction. Rieser et al. (1995) had observers walk on a treadmill while being pulled by a tractor and altered the normal relationship between vision and the proprioceptive cues of walking. Adaptation to this altered relationship produced reliable changes in the walked distance to previewed targets but did not afect throwing to targets, a result that rules out
Measuring Spatial Perception with Spatial Updating and Action
21
perceptual ad aptation. he ma gnitude o f r ecalibration depen ded upon walking direction. A likely interpretation is that sensed selfmotion w as a ltered b y t he ad aptation p rocess. D urgin a nd h is colleagues have additional e vidence of re calibration of s ensed s elfmotion (Durgin, Fox et al., 2003; Durgin, Gigone et al., 2005; Durgin, Pelah et a l., 2005), a lthough their results and interpretation of the c ause of r ecalibration d ifer somewhat from those of Rieser et al. (1995). It might be thought that recalibration involves a comparison of sensed self-motion signaled by idiothetic (proprioceptive and inertial) cues and the overall pattern of optic low, but recent results by hompson, Mohler, and Creem-Regehr (2005) show that the recalibration depends upon the perceived scale of the environment, with optic low held constant. his means that recalibration is determined by the comparison between sensed self-motion signaled by idiothetic cues a nd t he s ensed s elf-motion ba sed on v isual perception of t he environment, which depends upon distance perception. he accuracy of visually directed action under full cues (Figures 1.2 and 1.7) clearly relies on calibration of the gain of walking relative to visual perception. his calibration is likely to be induced by sensing of just the near visible environment (e.g., hompson et al., 2005). An interesting implication is that adaptation of visually sensed selfmotion ought to afect any form of action based on spatial updating regardless of the modality with which the target is perceived; thus, the indicated distance to a target based on perceptually directed action will be altered the same amount by visual recalibration whether the targets are visual, auditory, or haptic, provided that the initially perceived distances are the same for the diferent modalities. An experiment comparing the efects of feedback on blind walking a nd v erbal r eports (Mohler e t a l., 2 006) sh owed e vidence o f a form of recalibration not conined to t he action system. To i nduce recalibration, the authors took advantage of the systematic underperception of distance in virtual reality. Observers gave verbal reports and performed blind walking to targets seen in the virtual environment before and ater getting feedback about their errors. During the feedback phase, observers blind walked to the estimated locations of the targets and were given feedback about their errors. Both walking responses and verbal reports showed considerable improvement with the feedback. Because verbal reports were afected, the recalibration cannot be conined to a change in sensed self-motion. Although the common recalibration is consistent with a modiication of perceived
22
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
distance, the authors conclude that it is more likely a result of a cognitive rule that inluences both types of responses. If true, this might be t he result of a cog nitive a lternation i n t he spatial i mage so t hat it d oes n ot co incide w ith t he per ceived t arget. I f so , t riangulation responses ought to be similarly afected. Still another form of adaptation has been demonstrated by Ellard and Shaughnessy (2003). In their experiment, observers viewed targets at varying distances on diferent trials and blind walked to them. For two of the targets, observers were given false feedback about the accuracy of their responses. Telling observers that they had u ndershot the target resulted in overshooting on subsequent trials. his form of adaptation was speciic to t he targets for which fa lse feedback was given. he result by Ellard and Shaughnessy (2003) raises the possibility of a form of adaptation that might undermine the claim that perceptually directed action measures perception. In particular, this type of adaptation could potentially explain the linearity (proportionality) b etween r esponded di stance an d v isual t arget di stance un der full cues even if perceived distance should in fact be a compressively nonlinear f unction o f t arget d istance, a s cla imed, f or ex ample, b y Gilinsky (1951). It would have to be a type of adaptation that modiies neither perception (which afects all responses, whether actionbased or not) nor path integration (which afects all walked distances by the same scale factor). In addition, because of the aforementioned triangulation re sults, it wou ld h ave t o a fect t he coupling be tween perceived d istance a nd s ensed d isplacements f rom t he o rigin, regardless of path taken, and do so in a way that varies nonlinearly with distance from the origin (so as to compensate for the putative nonlinearity between target and perceived distances). here a re at least t hree l ines of e vidence a gainst t he hypothesis that this type of distance speciic adaptation undermines t he measurement of perceived d istance. he irst is t hat people rarely v iew distant targets and then walk to them without vision. Error feedback following such blind walking would be needed to “calibrate” perceptually d irected a ction b ased on t he put ative non linearity b etween target distance and perceived distance. he second line of evidence is concerned with whether adaptation following v isual feedback about open-loop walking er rors generalizes to other forms of perceptually directed action. Richardson and Waller (2005; E xperiment 2) had obs ervers per form blind walking
Measuring Spatial Perception with Spatial Updating and Action
23
to targets in virtual reality. At the outset, their observers walked to locations only about half of the simulated target distances, along both direct and indirect paths, indicating the underperception of distance in virtual reality found by others using a variety of methods (Knapp, 1999; Sahm et al., 2005; hompson et al., 2004). Observers were then given a period of training involving open-loop walking to the targets along direct paths; ater arriving at the estimated position of the target on each trial, the observer was given explicit feedback about the undershoot error. Ater t raining, obs ervers were once a gain te sted using direct and indirect walking. he t raining el iminated 79% of the undershoot error for direct walking but only 27% of the undershoot error for indirect walking. he large diference in amounts of recalibration argues t hat if people get explicit feedback about t heir blind w alking i n t he real world so a s t o a llow for correct w alking to compensate for putative nonlinearity in perceived distances, this type of recalibration still would not explain the high accuracy with which people perform triangulation tasks. In a f ollow-up st udy, R ichardson a nd Waller (2007) f ound t hat observers wh o w ere a llowed t o w alk a round i n i mmersive v irtual environments w hile c ontinuously i nteracting w ith v isual t argets exhibited a m ore g eneral f orm o f r ecalibration. C ontrasting w ith the results obtained with explicit feedback in their earlier study, the results of this study showed that the implicit feedback accompanying interaction with the environment during the training phase did allow for an equal amount of recalibration when walking open-loop along direct and indirect paths during the testing phase. Prima facie, this result appears to support the hypothesis that recalibration accounts for accurate visually directed action despite nonlinear functions for egocentric distance. However, their result is also consistent with two other hypotheses: recalibration of v isual perception a nd recalibration of sensed self motion. Further experiments not relying on updating (e.g., verbal report and ball throwing) are needed to distinguish between the three alternative hypotheses. he third line of evidence against the hypothesis is made possible by comparing the accurate responses to visual targets with the systematically compressed responses to auditory targets. Figure 1.12 gives t he results of t wo ex periments (Loomis e t a l., 1998) f rom 12 observers wh o made bo th v erbal a nd b lind w alking r esponses t o visual targets and 12 observers who made bo th types of responses to auditory targets; some observers were given targets at 4, 10, and
24
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Figure 1.12 Results of two experiments on visual and auditory distance perception (Experiments 1 a nd 2a from Loomis et al. [1998]). he same observers made verbal and blind walking responses to b oth visual and auditory targets in a l arge open ield. Seven responded to targets at 4, 10, and 16 m, and 5 observers responded to targets at 4, 8, 12, and 16 m. he best itting linear functions are plotted as well. In the right panel, arrows indicate how, for a given visual target distance, the corresponding “equivalent” auditory distance was determined, this being the distance of the auditory target which produced the same walked distance.
16 m, a nd others were given targets at 4, 8, 12, and 16 m. he best itting linear functions (with 0 intercepts) for the combined data sets are plotted as well. If t he ac curate r esponses t o v isual t argets r elect so me so rt o f calibration process acting on the visually-based action process, presumably t he s ame c alibration d oes n ot a pply t o auditorially ba sed action, given t he very large systematic errors. hus, t he t wo action processes must i nvolve d iferent c alibration f unctions. his means that if a visual target distance and an auditory target distance produce t he same value of blind walking, t he corresponding values of visually perceived a nd auditorially perceived d istance must be d ifferent. hus, we would expect that since the process of making a verbal report is common to both modalities, t he verbal reports ought to be diferent for visual and auditory target distances that produce the s ame ac tion response, a ssuming t hat t he v isually-based ac tion responses have been calibrated through experience. To test this idea, we have used the best itting linear functions to the blind walking (motor) responses (Figure 1.12) to ind, for each visual t arget di stance, t he c orresponding a uditory t arget di stance that produced the same walking responses (see arrows in the right panel o f F igure 1 .12). he v isual t arget d istance a nd “ equivalent” auditory target distances were then used to compute the corresponding verbal reports f rom t he best-itting l inear f unctions. he func-
Measuring Spatial Perception with Spatial Updating and Action
25
tion relating the verbal reports for vision and the verbal reports for audition i s very nearly t he identity f unction ( linear f unction w ith slope o f 1.04 a nd i ntercept o f - 0.22 m). his means that the vi sually-based a nd a uditorially-based ac tion p rocesses a re e ssentially identical. At least for these data, there is no evidence of a calibration of blind walking to compensate for a putative compressively nonlinear perceptual function. On the basis of the three lines of evidence, we conclude that perceptually directed action does provide a comparatively pure measure of perception when action is properly calibrated to near surrounding space. Also based on both the perceptually directed action results of Figures 1.2 and 1.7 and the verbal report results of Figure 1.1, we conclude that visual distance perception is a linear function of target distance out to at least 25 m on the ground plane when distance cues are abundant.
Using Spatial Updating to Correct for Bias in Verbal Reports of Egocentric Distance Figures 1 .1, 1 .2, a nd 1 .7 sh ow t hat v isually per ceived eg ocentric distance i s a l inear f unction o f p hysical d istance o ut t o 25 m a nd that v erbal r eports a re g enerally abo ut 8 0% o f t he d istances i ndicated by ac tion. his systematic diference in response va lues does not, by itself, indicate that diferent internal representations of distance control the two types of responses, for Foley (1977) and later Philbeck a nd L oomis (1997) presented a m odel i n wh ich t he s ame internal r epresentation o f d istance, oste nsibly per ceived d istance, acts through diferent output transforms to determine the indicated responses (see right part of Figure 1.8). Philbeck and Loomis (1997) showed that verbal reports and blind walking to targets, while systematically diferent, were related to each other by a ixed mapping when switching from reduced-cue to full-cue viewing (also see the above analysis in connection with Figure 1.12). his is co nsistent with there being just a single internal representation of distance acting through diferent output transforms. However, it is possible, even likely, t hat t he o utput t ransforms f or ac tion a nd v erbal r eport a re sometimes afected diferently by experimental manipulations, such that there is no ixed mapping between the two types of responses. For example, an observer can view a photograph and make reliable judgments of d istance of depicted objects, but a sking obs ervers t o
26
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
perform open-loop walking to the same depicted objects is likely to be met with reluctance followed by very noisy performance. Andre and Rogers (2006) have found that experimental manipulations, including v iewing t argets t hrough ba se up a nd ba se down prisms, can diferentially afect blind walking and verbal report. hey interpret t heir indings i n ter ms of d iferent i nternal representations of distance, but it is possible that the diferential efects are produced at the level of response production and execution. In connection with the hypothesis that action and verbal report involve the same internal representation but diferent output transforms, a spec ial c ase c an be i dentiied i n wh ich verbal reports a re subject t o a s ystematic u nder r eporting b ias ( b) t hat i s a co nstant proportion of perceived egocentric distance (i.e., b Pattern licker
Dechent & Frahm, 2003 (fMRI)
Luminance licker > Pattern licker
Figure 4
N/A -60 N/A -70
2 15
(V6) Table 2 average (V6A)
Figures 5, 6
Pointing preparation Astaiev et al., 2003 (fMRI)
Delayed pointing > Delayed saccade
-7
-79
42
Table Supplementary Material Pcu
Figure 1E
Connolly et al., 2003 (fMRI)
Delay activity for efector and location > Delay activity for efector only
-1
-74
38
Results secti on
Figure 3
Reaching preparation Beurze et al., 2006 (fMRI)
Cue for target location > ixation
-24
-67
31
Table 2
Figure 2
Cue for efector > ixation
-21
-70
37
Table 3
Figure 3
-10
-90
36
Table 2 (POJ)
Figure 3a
Reaching Prado et al., 2005 (fMRI)
Reach to nonfoveated targets > Reach to foveated targets
fMRI Investigations of Reaching and Ego Space
Reference (technique)
Contrast
Talairach coordinates X
Y
Z
Source in reference for Talairach coordinates
257
Source igure in reference for foci in our Figure 8.5
Pellijef et al., 2006 (fMRI)
Reaching to novel position > Reaching to repeated position
-21
-58
42
Table 1 Average (Pcu)
Figure 1
DeJong et al., 2001 (PET)
Reach to variable targets > Reach the same target
-22
-82
29
Table 1 Average (PCu, Cu and POS)
Figure 1
Experiment 1 (fMRI)
Reach-to-touch > Touch AND Reach-tograsp > Grasp
-7
-82
30
Average(upperlower POS)
Figure 1
-11
-72
46
Results section
Figure 10
V6 Retinotopy Pitzalis et al., 2006 (fMRI)
Wide-ield retinotopic map Near preference
Experiment 2 (fMRI)
Passive-viewing within reach > Passiveviewing outside reach
1
-75
29
Figure 2
Experiment 3b (fMRI)
Vergence near the head > Vergence far from the head
-8
-86
28
Figure 3
midway between the two objects. he room remained d ark except for a 2 s period for each trial in which the object was illuminated and the action was executed. Prior to each trial, the experimenter placed a new object on t he platform a nd t he subject received a n auditory cue via headphones to “reach,” “grasp,” or “look” on the upcoming trial. At t he beginning of each trial, a b right LED mounted on t he ceiling of the magnet was illuminated for 2 s, prompting the subjects
258
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
to perform the cued action (and then return the hand to the starting location) or to passively view the object. Ater each trial, the subject rested in darkness for a 12 s intertrial interval. We irst identiied brain areas involved in the grip component by performing a r andom e fects contrast between grasping objects at the reachable location vs. touching objects at the reachable location, consistent w ith previous st udies (Binkofski et a l., 1998; Culham et al., 2003; Frey, Vinton, Norlund, & Graton, 2005). As expected, this contrast produced activation in the anterior intraparietal (AIP) cortex, speciically at the junction of the IPS and the postcentral sulcus (PCS; see Figures 8.2b; Talairach coordinates in Table 8.1). AIP also showed higher activation for grasping vs. reaching at the adjacent location (Figure 8.2c). We then identiied brain areas involved in the transport co mponent b y per forming a co ntrast be tween t ouching objects at the reachable location vs., touching objects in the adjacent location. his contrast produced activation in SPOC (see Figures 8.2d), which also showed higher activation for grasping objects in the reachable vs. adjacent location (Figure 8.2e). he SPOC activation for t he t wo pa ssive v iewing conditions w as identical (Figure 8 .2e), suggesting that stimulus confounds (such as retinal location) could not account for the activation diference attributed to the transport component.
Implications hese results demonstrate that the transport and the grip component of a reach-to-grasp task rely on diferent brain structures. While AIP is activated by the computation of grip aperture regardless of whether a reach is required to acquire the object, SPOC is much more active when a ctions a re ex ecuted t oward a n o bject r equiring a rm ex tension. A f unctional d issociation be tween t he t wo co mponents d oes not imply that they work separately from one another. Indeed the two components t ake place simultaneously a nd behavioral ex periments have shown that they are closely choreographed. In the future, functional connectivity studies would be v aluable for investigating the nature of the crosstalk between SPOC and AIP.
fMRI Investigations of Reaching and Ego Space
259
Experiment 2: A Preference for Objects within Arm’sLength in Superior Parieto-Occipital Cortex Rationale We reasoned that if SPOC is involved in reaching movements, it may show a preferential response to objects within reachable space. Given past research from our lab (Cavina-Pratesi et al., 2007) showing that human A IP a nd S POC a re ac tivated b y t he v isual p resentation o f an object within reachable space even without any overt action, we investigated whether or not such passive viewing responses would be modulated by whether objects were within vs. out of reach.
Methods and Results Within t he s ame s essions a s E xperiment 1 , a nd u sing t he s ame setup a nd t he s ame 10 sub jects, w e r an E xperiment 2 t o ex amine whether the response in transport- and grip-related areas would be modulated by ob ject d istance. Once again, we presented objects i n the adjacent and reachable locations; however, we also included an additional location that was beyond reach (see Figure 8.3a). Subjects maintained i xation on a central point throughout all trials. On some trials, subjects were i nstructed to reach-to-touch or reach-to-grasp objects i n one of t he t wo reachable locations (though ac tions were never performed to the other two locations). On other trials, subjects simply passively viewed an object placed at any of the three locations (adjacent, reachable, and unreachable). We per formed a co njunction a nalysis t o i dentify r egions t hat were more activated during passive viewing for objects within reach than outside of reach ([adjacent > u nreachable] A ND [reachable > unreachable]). As shown in Figure 8.3b, this contrast produced activation in SPOC (Talairach coordinates in Table 8.1). As expected by the co ntrast u sed t o i dentify t he a rea, t here w as h igher ac tivation during for passive viewing of adjacent and reachable locations than unreachable locations; in addition, the area responded more strongly to grasping and reaching (at the reachable location) than to passive viewing (Figure 8.3b). he activation partially overlapped with the transport-related region identiied in Experiment 1.
260
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Figure 8.3 Methods, s tatistical m aps a nd f MRI a ctivation for E xperiment 2 investigating responses to re achable vs. u nreachable objects. a) S chematic representation of t he t hree p ossible lo cations at w hich objects we re pre sented d uring passive viewing trials. he arc highlights the area corresponding to t he moveable range of the arm. he cross represents the location of the i xation point. In addition to these three conditions, two other conditions, not shown, were included: Grasping an object at the reachable location and touching an object at the reachable location. b) Group activation showing the region of SPOC that was activated by a conjunction analysis of ([adjacent > unreachable] AND [reachable > unreachable]). c) Bar graphs display the magnitude of peak activation (%BSC) in all conditions for the region circled in b. A full-color version of the igure is available online at http:// psychology.uwo.ca/culhamlab/PDFs/Culham_etal_CMUchapter8_ColorFigs.pdf
Implications hese results are consistent with earlier suggestions that peripersonal space may have a particular relevance within the dorsal stream. Speciically, they suggest that neurons within SPOC show a preferential response to ob jects w ithin re achable s pace, e ven w hen no e xplicit action is required. he se indings are consistent with the suggestion that an object can automatically evoke afordances, potential actions that can be performed on the particular object (Gibson, 1979). Moreover, they suggest such afordances may have neural correlates within brain areas responsible for particular types of actions. We have additional control experiments underway to ensure that these r esults a re n ot d ue t o pos sible st imulus co nfounds such a s object size or position within the visual ield; however, we think such confounds are unlikely to account for our data. In our experiments,
fMRI Investigations of Reaching and Ego Space
261
the objects had t he same physical size but naturally further objects subtended a smaller retinal image size than closer objects. Although some brain a reas w ithin t he ventral st ream have been found to be modulated b y r etinal i mage s ize ( Hasson, Ha rel, L evy, & Ma lach, 2003; Ma lach, L evy, & Ha sson, 2 002), o ur ac tivation w as f ound within t he d orsal st ream, wh ere o ne w ould ex pect r eal w orld s ize would be more relevant than retinal size. Another possible concern is the diference in retinal position of the objects. he placement of the objects was restricted by the reachable space, which was limited to an arc-shaped zone with the fulcrum at the right elbow. hu s, the retinal location of the objects in the three positions could not be held constant. Ba sed on t he geometry of t he s etup: (1) a ll t hree objects were in the lower visual ield with the near object being more peripheral and the far object appearing closer to the fovea; (2) the adjacent and unreachable objects were in the let visual ield while the reachable object was in the right ield; and (3), the i xation point was midway in depth between the adjacent and reachable objects (as in Expt. 1). We d on’t bel ieve t hat t hese fac tors co ntributed t o o ur indings because: (1) t here were no activation diferences i n SPOC between the adjacent and reachable objects, suggesting that retinal eccentricity isn’t likely to play a role; (2) if visual hemiields were a critical factor, we would predict g reater let hemisphere activation for objects in the reachable location compared to the adjacent and unreachable locations (with t he co nverse pa ttern i n t he r ight h emisphere), b ut no such pa ttern was observed; and (3) given that SPOC lies within the dorsal stream and is sensitive only to low spatial frequencies, it is unlikely to be sensitive to the image blurring that would strongest for the furthest object. Given that the reach-selective SPOC appears to be more activated by objects in reachable space than beyond, a f uture line of research will investigate whether this efect can be m odulated by ex tending peripersonal space by providing the subject with a tool. Growing evidence suggests t hat tools can ex tend t he range of action space a nd this can afect neural and behavioral responses. A seminal study by Iriki and colleagues (1996) demonstrated that when a macaque monkey learns to use a tool, the receptive ields of reach-selective neurons in t he i ntraparietal co rtex ex panded t o en compass t he spac e t hat became reachable with the tool. Human neuropsychological studies have also found that peripersonal space is modiied by availability of a tool. For example, a patient with let neglect in peripersonal space
262
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
showed an extension of that neglect to far space during line bisection tasks when using a stick but not when using a laser pointer, suggesting that the stick was treated as an extension of the body but the laser pointer was not (Berti & F rassinetti, 2000). Although these human neuropsychological st udies su ggest t hat t he human b rain, l ike t he monkey b rain, co ntains n eurons t uned t o ac tion spac e, t he la rge extent of lesions makes it diicult to determine which areas contain such neurons. We expect that SPOC is one such region and that its response to objects during passive viewing should be modulated by the availability of a tool to extend reachable space.
Experiment 3: A Preference for Near Gaze in Superior Parieto-Occipital Cortex Rationale Experiment 3 from our lab (Quinlan & Culham, 2007) also suggests that the human SPOC may be particularly responsive to near space. Speciically, we found that SPOC activation was modulated by gaze distance, with stronger responses when subjects were ixating upon a near point than a far point. his research arose from an earlier experiment that had originally been i ntended t o ex amine t he pos sibility o f a p reference f or n ear space in a h uman area that has been proposed as the human functional eq uivalent o f t he mac aque v entral i ntraparietal (V IP) a rea (Bremmer et a l., 2001; Goltz et a l., 2001; see a lso Sereno & H uang, 2006). Electrophysiological studies have shown that a subset of neurons within macaque VIP respond more strongly to motion in ultranear space (very close to the face) than at further distances (Colby, Duhamel, & Goldberg, 1993), so we investigated whether putative human VIP demonstrated a similar near preference to motion. In an initial experiment, we had presented subjects with patterned objects that loomed toward the face and receded. he objects could be presented at one of three distance ranges: near the face, above the hand, or above the feet. Stimuli were carefully equated for low-level visual properties such as visual angle, velocity and so forth. Although we did n ot obs erve a p reference f or ob jects m oving i n n ear spac e v s. far space within the putative human VIP, we did observe activation in SPOC. In our initial experiments, we had i nstructed subjects to
fMRI Investigations of Reaching and Ego Space
263
follow t he looming-and-receding t argets w ith t heir e yes. hus one factor that may have led to activation in the superior occipital cortex was the distance at which gaze was directed. We conducted an experiment to de termine whether simply having the eyes gaze on a n ear vs. far point could induce activation in the superior parieto-occipital cortex. When the eyes are directed to close targets, a near response is invoked that consists of three components called the near triad. First, when looking at near targets, the eyes rotate inward to maintain i xation on the object with each eye (vergence). Second, the lens of the eye thickens to keep the object in focus (accommodation). hird, t he pupil constricts to i ncrease t he depth-of-ield. A lthough t hese co mponents ha ve so metimes be en studied i n i solation ( Hasebe e t a l., 1 999; R ichter, C ostello, S ponheim, Lee, & P ardo, 2004; R ichter, Lee, & P ardo, 2000), in the real world, they co-occur. herefore, we simply asked the subjects to look at each point, such that vergence, accommodation, and pupil size all provided cues as to the depth of the ixation point.
Methods and Results We gave eight right-handed subjects the simple task of gazing at small (0.7°) st ationary l ights ( LEDs) a t o ne o f t hree d istances a long t he natural line of sight: 15, 26 or 84 cm from the eye (See Figure 8.4a). he LEDs were viewed in an otherwise completely dark scanner and were calibrated to have the same luminance and visual angle. Only one LED was illuminated at a t ime and subjects were instructed to maintain i xation o n wh ichever L ED w as c urrently i lluminated. When one LED was extinguished and another was illuminated, the subject made a s imple vergence shit (w ithout a ny s accadic c omponents) from the irst LED to the second. LEDs were illuminated for 16 s a t a t ime i n ps eudo-random order. Subjects lay supine w ithin the magnet and viewed the LEDs through a mirror tilted at approximately 45°. A su rface coil was used to provide high signal-to-noise within the occipital and parietal cortices. A contrast of near vs. far viewing produced robust activation just posterior to the superior parieto-occipital sulcus in all eight subjects (Figures 8 .4b & 8 .4c; Talairach coordinates i n Table 8 .1). he time courses from this region within SPOC showed that following an initial t ransient response to a cha nge i n gaze d istance, t here was a
264
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Figure 8.4 Methods, s tatistical m aps a nd f MRI a ctivation for E xperiment 3 investigating re sponses to ne ar v s. f ar ve rgence. a ) S chematic re presentation of the e ye p ositions u sed i n t he d istance i xation e xperiment. he e yeballs a nd t he vergence a ngle a re showed f rom above. Subjects i xated one of t hree i lluminated light emitting diodes (LEDs) that were positioned at 15, 26 and 84 cm. Fixation was held for 16 seconds at w hich time the LED was extinguished and a ne w LED was i lluminated. b) A ctivation m ap re sulting f rom a c omparison of ne ar v s. f ar i xations. c) B ar g raph d isplays t he m agnitude of s ustained a ctivation i n SP OC (%BSC) for e ach i xation d istance, ave raged a cross subjects. A f ull-color ve rsion of the igure is available online at http://psychology.uwo.ca/culhamlab/PDFs/Culham_etal_CMUchapter8_ColorFigs.pdf
sustained response that scaled with the distance of the ixation point (highest for the near point, lowest for the far point). At lower thresholds, w e obs erved ac tivation s ites el sewhere i n t he oc cipital l obe, though these were less consistent between subjects and less robust than t he S POC f ocus. E ye t racking o utside t he s canner i ndicated that the activation diferences were not due to diferences in stability of gaze across the three distances.
Implications hese r esults su ggest t hat S POC ac tivation i s m odulated b y g aze distance, wh ich ma y p rovide t he d orsal st ream w ith i nformation about object distance for action. In order to compute real world distance, the visual system needs information about where the eyes are currently d irected ( based on vi sual signals, proprioceptive signals from the eye muscles, and/or eference copy signals generated with the co mmand t o m ove t he e yes) a s w ell a s i nformation abo ut t he location of the target with respect to gaze (based on retinal location and binocular disparity). We propose that the modulation of SPOC
fMRI Investigations of Reaching and Ego Space
265
activity by gaze distance provides the irst key component necessary for computing target locations for action. Both single neurons of the macaque PRR (Cohen & Andersen, 2002) and a reach-related region of the human brain (in the anteromedial IPS) (DeSouza et al., 2000) have responses that can be modulated by directing eye gaze letward vs. rightward. Such eye-position dependent modulation properties, sometimes referred to as gain ields, are thought to play an important role in the conversion of information from retinotopic to egocentric (e.g., head-centered) coordinate frames. Our results suggest that gain ields may also exist in the third dimension, depth, to provide signals which could also be useful for the computation of physical distance, which is particularly important for the accurate control of actions. Indeed, behavioral studies suggest that eye position and vergence play an important role in the accuracy of reaching movements (Bock, 1986; Henriques & Cr awford, 2000; Henriques, Klier, Smith, Lowy, & Cr awford, 1998; Henriques, Medendorp, Gielen, & Crawford, 2003; Neggers & Bekkering, 1999; van Donkelaar & Staub, 2000). Because w e a llowed a ll t hree co mponents o f t he n ear r esponse (vergence, accommodation, and changes in pupil size) to co-occur, we cannot deinitively state whether any one of these three components i s t he d riving f orce i n t he n ear-selective r esponse i n S POC. However, pa st r esearch ha s su ggested v ergence p rovides a m uch stronger cue to distance than the other two components (e.g., Foley, 1980).
General Discussion To s ummarize, w e h ave r eported th ree s tudies th at h ighlight th e importance o f t he h uman S POC i n t ransporting t he a rm d uring reaching m ovements a nd i n en coding per ipersonal spac e. S patial encoding of peripersonal space appears to be ba sed on modulation of activation by both object position (with gaze i xed) a nd by gaze distance (when n o ob ject i s p resent). A lthough t he ex act r elationships between the activation foci in our three experiments are yet to be determined, t hese results taken together suggest t hat t he SPOC region in general may be a key node within the dorsal stream for the computation of object distance, as needed to g uide actions such a s reaching.
266
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Taken t ogether, t he r esults o f t he t hree ex periments su ggest that multiple f actors a fect r esponses w ithin SPOC. G aze d istance alone may su ice to modulate responses i n SPOC (Experiment 3). However, e ven wh en g aze is h eld co nstant, t he S POC r esponse t o objects during passive viewing depends on whether or not they are in reachable space (Experiment 2). Furthermore, the SPOC response depends n ot o nly o n abso lute d istance, b ut o n ac tions per formed toward objects: t he response t o f urther, but st ill reachable o bjects, can be higher than the response to adjacent objects when actions are performed on the objects (Experiment 1). At irst this may seem contrary to the indings of Experiments 2 and 3 of a near preference in SPOC; however, the computations for guidance of the arm to an object are more complex when t he object is f urther f rom t he ha nd and this may recruit SPOC to a greater degree. In add ition, o ur d ata su ggest t hat e ye pos ition ma y be a nother critical component in the relationship between space and hand. hat is, t onic s ignals abo ut c urrent g aze d istance ( perhaps v ergence i n particular) may provide useful signals for enhancing the response to stimuli in near space and for computing the egocentric target location to guide arm movements. Other research has also suggested that SPOC may encode eye position information. First, the region is part of a network for eye movements (Paus et al., 1997). Second, SPOC is modulated by saccadic eye movements, even in the dark (Law, Svarer, Rostrup, & Paulson, 1998), supporting our indings that eye position signals are important in the area, even in the absence of other visual stimulation or task demands. here is growing evidence from past studies, as well as the three new studies presented here, to suggest that SPOC plays an important role in actions such as reaching and pointing; however, it remains to be determined whether SPOC comprises diferent subregions. Preliminary comparisons within subjects suggested some overlap between the transport-selective activation in lower POS in Experiment 1 and the reachable-selective activation in Experiment 2; however, no such intrasubject comparisons were possible between Experiments 1 & 2 compared to E xperiment 3. Figure 8 .5 presents a s chematic of t he activation foci from numerous studies which have reported SPOC activation. Our loose deinition of SPOC includes the superior end of the parieto-occipital sulcus, as well as the regions immediately posterior (in the cuneus) and anterior (in the precuneus) to the sulcus. Several cha racteristics of t he SPOC region c an be n oted i n Figure
fMRI Investigations of Reaching and Ego Space
267
Figure 8.5 Summary of activation foci within superior parieto-occipital cortex in nine past studies and the three present studies. Activation foci are shown on the medial su rface o f o ne r epresentative sub ject’s l et hemisphere. he c ortical s urface was deined at the gray-white matter border and has been partially inlated to reveal regions within the sulci (concavities, in dark gray) and on the gyri (convexities, in light gray). Foci are schematically represented based on their sizes and anatomical locations relative to the parieto-occipital, calcarine, and cingulate sulci, as depicted in igures from t he original studies, as speciied in Table 1. A f ull-color version of t he igure i s av ailable on line at h ttp://psychology.uwo.ca/culhamlab/ PDFs/Culham_etal_CMUchapter8_ColorFigs.pdf
8.5. First, the response properties in the region strongly suggest it belongs w ithin t he dorsal st ream. Using human ma gnetoencephalography (MEG), Ha ri a nd colleagues have reported a f ocus i n t he dorsal pa rieto-occipital su lcus w ith d orsal st ream p roperties: fa st latencies, sensitivity to luminance rather than pattern changes, and motion selectivity (Hari & Salmelin, 1997; Portin et al., 1998; Vanni, Tanskanen, Seppa, Uutela, & Ha ri, 2001). Human f MRI has found somewhat more i nferior fo ci for l uminance ( vs. p attern) c hanges (Dechent & Frahm, 2003) and blinking (Bristow, Frith, & Rees, 2005). Second, SPOC has been commonly activated by the preparation and execution of pointing a nd reaching movements, w ith some studies reporting activation anterior to t he superior POS i n t he precuneus (Astaiev et al., 2003; Connolly et al., 2003; Pellijef et al., 2006; Prado et al., 2005), and some studies also reporting activation in the POS or behind it in the cuneus (Beurze et al., 2007; Connolly et al., 2003; de
268
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Jong et al., 2001). hird, the recent human fMRI work of one group with experience in neurophysiology of reach-related a reas (Galletti et a l., 2 003) ha s l ed t o t he p roposal t hat t he h uman eq uivalent o f V6 lies posterior to the superior POS while the human equivalent of V6A is more anterior, on the parietal side of the superior POS. Putative human V6 contains a s imilar retinotopic map a s mac aque V6 (Pitzalis, Galletti et al., 2006b); whereas, putative human V6A, like macaque V6A, has only weak eccentricity mapping and shows reachrelated responses (Pitzalis, Galletti et al., 2006a). In sum, recent evidence from other labs and from the three experiments summarized here suggest that the human SPOC is a d orsal stream area involved in planning actions to locations in near space based on information such as current gaze angle.
Acknowledgments his research was funded by grants to JCC from the Canadian Institutes o f H ealth Re search ( CIHR), t he N atural S ciences a nd E ngineering Research Council (of Canada), the Canadian Foundation for Innovation and the (Ontario) Premier’s Research Excellence Award. CCP was funded by a CIHR grant to the Group on Action and Perception. We thank Claudio Galletti and Patrizia Fattori for explaining the relationship between the parietal reach region and area MIP. We also thank Marlene Behrmann and John Zettel for comments on an earlier drat.
References Andersen, R. A., & Buneo, C. A. (2002). Intentional maps in posterior parietal cortex. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 25, 189–220. Astaiev, S. V., Shulman, G. L., Stanley, C. M., Snyder, A. Z., Van Essen, D. C., & C orbetta, M. (2003). Functional organization of human intraparietal and frontal cortex for attending, looking, and pointing. Journal of Neuroscience, 23(11), 4689–4699. Berti, A ., & F rassinetti, F. (2000). W hen far becomes near: remapping of space by tool use. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 12(3), 415–420. Beurze, S. M., De Lange, F. P., Toni, I., & Medendorp, W. P. (2007). Integration of t arget and e fector i nformation i n t he h uman b rain d uring reach planning. Journal of Neurophysiology, 97(1), 188–199.
fMRI Investigations of Reaching and Ego Space
269
Binkofski, F., Dohle, C., Posse, S., Stephan, K. M., Heter, H., Seitz, R. J., et al. (1998). Human a nterior i ntraparietal a rea subs erves prehension: A combined lesion and functional MRI activation study. Neurology, 50(5), 1253–1259. Bock, O. (1986). Contribution of retinal versus extraretinal signals towards visual localization in goal-directed movements. Experimental Brain Research, 64(3), 476–482. Bremmer, F., Schlack, A., Shah, N. J., Z airis, O., Kubischik, M., Hofman, K.-P. et al. (2001). Polymodal motion processing in posterior parietal and premotor cortex: A human fMRI study strongly implies equivalencies between humans and monkeys. Neuron, 29(1), 287–296. Bristow, D., Frith, C., & Rees, G. (2005). Two distinct neural efects of blinking on human visual processing. Neuroimage, 27(1), 136–145. Calton, J. L., Dickinson, A. R., & Snyder, L. H. (2002). Non-spatial, motorspeciic activation in posterior parietal cortex. Nature Neuroscience, 5(6), 580–588. Cavina-Pratesi, C., Goodale, M. A., & Cu lham, J. C . (2007). f MRI reveals a d issociation b etween g rasping a nd p erceiving t he si ze o f re al 3D objects. Public Library of Science (PLOS) One, 2(5), e424. Cohen, Y. E ., & A ndersen, R . A . (2002). A c ommon ref erence f rame f or movement plans in the posterior parietal cortex. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 3(7), 553–562. Colby, C . L ., D uhamel, J.-R., & G oldberg, M . E . (1993). Ventral i ntraparietal a rea o f t he mac aque: A natomic lo cation a nd v isual re sponse properties. Journal of Neurophysiology, 6(3), 902–914. Colby, C. L., Gattass, R., Olson, C. R., & Gross, C. G. (1988). Topographical organization of cortical aferents to extrastriate visual area PO in the macaque: A dual tracer study. Journal of Comparative Neurology, 269, 392–413. Colby, C. L., & Goldberg, M. E. (1999). Space and attention in parietal cortex. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 22, 319–349. Connolly, J. D., Andersen, R. A., & Goodale, M. A. (2003). fMRI evidence for a “parietal reach region” in the human brain. Experimental Brain Research, 153(2), 140–145. Connolly, J. D ., G oodale, M . A ., De souza, J. F ., Menon, R . S ., & Vi lis, T. (2000). A c omparison o f fr ontoparietal f MRI a ctivation d uring anti-saccades an d an ti-pointing. Journal of N europhysiology, 8 4(3), 1645–1655. Cooke, D. F., Taylor, C. S., Moore, T., & Gr aziano, M. S. (2003). Complex movements evoked by m icrostimulation of t he ventral i ntraparietal area. Proceedings of th e National Academy of S ciences of th e United States of America, 100(10), 6163–6168. Culham, J. C. (2004). Human brain imaging reveals a parietal area specialized for grasping. In N. Kanwisher & J. Duncan (Eds.), Attention and
270
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
performance: Vol. 10. Func tional b rain im aging of hum an c ognition (pp. 417–438). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Culham, J. C. (2006). Functional neuroimaging: Experimental design and analysis. In R. Cabeza & A. Kingstone (Eds.), Handbook of functional neuroimaging of cognition (2nd ed., pp. 53–82). Cambridge MA: MIT Press. Culham, J. C., Cavina-Pratesi, C., & Singhal, A. (2006). he role of parietal cortex in visuomotor control: What have we learned from neuroimaging? Neuropsychologia, 44(13), 2668–2684. Culham, J. C ., Danckert, S. L ., DeSouza, J. F., Gati, J. S ., Menon, R . S., & Goodale, M . A . ( 2003). Vi sually g uided g rasping p roduces f MRI activation in dorsal but not ventral stream brain areas. Experimental Brain Research, 153(2), 180–189. Culham, J. C., & Kanwisher, N. G. (2001). Neuroimaging of cognitive functions i n h uman pa rietal c ortex. Current O pinion in N eurobiology, 11(2), 157–163. Culham, J. C ., & V alyear, K . F. (2006). Human pa rietal c ortex i n ac tion. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 16(2), 205–212. de Jong, B. M., van der Graaf, F. H., & Paans, A. M. (2001). Brain activation related to t he representations of external space and body scheme in visuomotor control. Neuroimage, 14(5), 1128–1135. Dechent, P., & Frahm, J. (2003). Characterization of the human visual V6 complex by f unctional magnetic resonance imaging. European Journal of Neuroscience, 17(10), 2201–2211. DeSouza, J. F ., D ukelow, S . P., G ati, J. S ., Menon, R . S ., A ndersen, R . A ., & Vi lis, T. (2000). E ye p osition sig nal m odulates a h uman pa rietal pointing region during memory-guided movements. Journal of Neuroscience, 20(15), 5835–5840. DiFranco, D., Muir, D. W., & Dodwell, P. C. (1978). Reaching in very young infants. Perception, 7, 385–392. diPelligrino, G., Ladavas, E., & Farne, A. (1997). Seeing where your hands are. Nature, 388, 730. Eskandar, E. N., & Assad, J. A. (1999). Dissociation of visual, motor and predictive signals in parietal cortex during visual guidance. Nature Neuroscience, 2(1), 88–93. Foley, J. M . (1980). Bi nocular d istance p erception. Psychological Re view, 87(5), 411–434. Frak, V., Paulignan, Y., Jeannerod, M., Michel, F., & Cohen, H. (2006). Prehension movements in a pa tient (AC) w ith posterior parietal cortex damage a nd p osterior c allosal s ection. Brain and C ognition, 60 (1), 43–48. Frey, S. H., Vinton, D., Norlund, R., & Graton, S. T. (2005). Cortical topography of human a nterior i ntraparietal c ortex ac tive during v isually
fMRI Investigations of Reaching and Ego Space
271
guided g rasping. Brain Re search, Cognitive Brain Re search, 23(2–3), 397–405. Gail, A., & A ndersen, R . A. (2006). Neural dy namics in monkey parietal reach re gion re lect context-speciic s ensorimotor t ransformations. Journal of Neuroscience, 26(37), 9376–9384. Galletti, C., Kutz, D. F., Gamberini, M., Breveglieri, R., & Fattori, P. (2003). Role o f t he m edial pa rieto-occipital c ortex i n t he c ontrol o f re aching a nd g rasping m ovements. Experimental Brain Re search, 153(2), 158–170. Gibson, J. J. ( 1979). he ecol ogical appr oach t o v isual pe rception. B oston: Houghton Milin. Goltz, H. C., Dukelow, S. P., De Souza, J. F. X., Culham, J. C., van den Berg, A. V., Goosens, H. H. L. et al. (2001). A putative homologue of monkey area VIP in humans. Paper presented at the Society for Neuroscience, San Diego, CA. Goodale, M. A., & Jakobson, L. S. (1992). Action systems in the posterior parietal cortex. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 15(4), 747. Goodale, M. A., & M ilner, A. D. (1992). Separate visual pathways for perception and action. Trends in Neurosciences, 15(1), 20–25. Graton, S. T., Fagg, A. H., Woods, R. P., & Arbib, M. A. (1996). Functional anatomy of pointing and grasping in humans. Cerebral Cortex, 6(2), 226–237. Grekes, C., & Fink, G. R. (2005). he functional organization of the intraparietal sulcus in humans and monkeys. Journal of Anatomy, 207(1), 3–17. Grekes, C., Ritzl, A., Zilles, K., & Fink, G. R. (2004). Human medial intraparietal c ortex s ubserves v isuomotor c oordinate t ransformation. Neuroimage, 23(4), 1494–1506. Halligan, P. W., & Ma rshall, J. C . (1991). Let neglect for near but not far space in man. Nature, 350(6318), 498–500. Halverson, H. M. (1931). An experimental study of prehension in infants by means of systematic cinema records. Genetic Psychology Monographs, 10, 110–286. Hari, R., & Salmelin, R. (1997). Human cortical oscillations: A neuromagnetic view through the skull. Trends in Neurosciences, 20(1), 44–49. Hasebe, H ., O yamada, H ., K inomura, S ., K awashima, R ., O uchi, Y ., Nobezawa, S . e t a l. (1999). H uman c ortical a reas ac tivated i n rel ation to v ergence e ye m ovements-a P ET s tudy. Neuroimage, 1 0(2), 200–208. Hasson, U., Ha rel, M., L evy, I., & Ma lach, R . (2003). L arge-scale m irrorsymmetry o rganization o f h uman o ccipito-temporal ob ject a reas. Neuron, 37(6), 1027–1041.
272
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Henriques, D. Y., & Cr awford, J. D . (2000). D irection-dependent d istortions o f re tinocentric spac e i n t he v isuomotor t ransformation f or pointing. Experimental Brain Research, 132(2), 179–194. Henriques, D. Y., K lier, E . M., Smith, M. A., Lowy, D., & Cr awford, J. D . (1998). Gaze-centered remapping of remembered v isual space in a n open-loop pointing task. Journal of Neuroscience, 18(4), 1583–1594. Henriques, D. Y., Medendorp, W. P., Gielen, C. C., & Crawford, J. D. (2003). Geometric computations underlying eye-hand coordination: Orientations of t he t wo e yes a nd t he he ad. Experimental Brain Re search, 152(1), 70–78. Iriki, A ., T anaka, M ., & I wamura, Y . ( 1996). C oding o f m odiied body schema during tool use by mac aque postcentral neurones. Neuroreport, 7(14), 2325–2330. Jeannerod, M. (1981). Intersegmental coordination during reaching at natural visual objects. In J. Long & A. Baddeley (Eds.), Attention an d Performance ( Vol. 60, pp. 153–168). Hillsdale NJ: Erlbaum. Jeannerod, M. (1984). he timing of natural prehension movements. Journal of Motor Behavior, 16(3), 235–254. Jeannerod, M . (1986). Mechanisms o f v isuomotor c oordination: A s tudy in n ormal a nd b rain- d amaged sub jects. Neuropsychologia, 2 4(1), 41–78. Jeannerod, M ., De cety, J., & M ichel, F . ( 1994). I mpairment o f g rasping movements following a b ilateral posterior parietal lesion. Neuropsychologia, 32(4), 369–380. Karnath, H. O., & Perenin, M. T. (2005). Cortical control of visually guided reaching: evidence from patients with optic ataxia. Cerebral Cortex, 15(10), 1561–1569. Kawashima, R., Naitoh, E., Matsumura, M., Itoh, H., Ono, S., Satoh, K. et al. (1996). Topographic representation in human intraparietal sulcus of reaching and saccade. Neuroreport, 7, 1253–1256. Kertzman, C., Schwarz, U., Zeiro, T. A., & Hallett, M. (1997). he role of posterior pa rietal c ortex i n v isually g uided re aching movements i n humans. Experimental Brain Research, 114(1), 170–183. Ladavas, E . (2002). Functional and dy namic properties of v isual peripersonal space. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 6(1), 17–22. Ladavas, E., diPellegrino, G., Farne, A., & Zeloni, G. (1998). Neuropsychological evidence of an integrated visuotactile representation of peripersonal spac e i n h umans. Journal of C ognitive N euroscience, 1 0(5), 581–589. Ladavas, E., Farne, A., Zeloni, G., & di Pellegrino, G. (2000). Seeing or not seeing w here yo ur ha nds a re. Experimental Br ain Re search, 1 31(4), 458–467.
fMRI Investigations of Reaching and Ego Space
273
Ladavas, E., Zeloni, G., & Farne, A. (1998). Visual peripersonal space centred on the face in humans. Brain, 121(Pt. 12), 2317–2326. Law, I., Svarer, C ., Rostrup, E ., & Pa ulson, O. B. (1998). Pa rieto-occipital cortex ac tivation during s elf-generated e ye movements i n t he d ark. Brain, 121(Pt. 11), 2189–2200. Malach, R ., L evy, I ., & Ha sson, U. (2002). he topography of h igh-order human object areas. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 6(4), 176–184. Maravita, A., & Iriki, A. (2004). Tools for the body (schema). Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8(2), 79–86. Milner, A. D., & Goodale, M. A. (1995). he visual brain in action. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Neggers, S. F., & B ekkering, H. (1999). Integration of v isual and somatosensory target information in goal-directed eye and arm movements. Experimental Brain Research, 125(1), 97–107. Paus, T., Jech, R., hompson, C. J., C omeau, R., Peters, T., & Evans, A. C. (1997). Transcranial magnetic stimulation during positron emission tomography: A new method for studying connectivity of the human cerebral cortex. Journal of Neuroscience, 17(9), 3178–3184. Pellijef, A ., B onilha, L ., M organ, P. S ., M cKenzie, K ., & J ackson, S . R . (2006). Pa rietal u pdating o f l imb p osture: A n e vent-related f MRI study. Neuropsychologia, 44(13), 2685–2690. Pitzalis, S., Galletti, C., Huang, R. S., Patria, F., Committeri, G., Galati, G. et al. (2006a). Visuotopic properties of the putative human homologue of the macaque V6A. Paper presented at the Organization for Human Brain Mapping, Florence, Italy. Pitzalis, S ., G alletti, C ., H uang, R . S ., Pa tria, F., C ommitteri, G ., G alati, G. et al. (2006b). Wide-ield retinotopy deines human cortical visual area v6. Journal of Neuroscience, 26(30), 7962–7973. Pitzalis, S., Sereno, M., Committeri, G., Galati, G., Fattori, P., & Galletti, C. (2006). A possible human homologue of the macaque V6A. Journal of Vision, 6(6), 536a. Portin, K ., Salenius, S ., Salmelin, R ., & Ha ri, R . (1998). Activation of t he human occipital and parietal cortex by pattern and luminance stimuli: Neuromagnetic measurements. Cerebral Cortex, 8(3), 253–260. Prado, J., C lavagnier, S ., O tzenberger, H ., S cheiber, C ., Ken nedy, H ., & Perenin, M . T. (2005). Two c ortical s ystems f or re aching i n c entral and peripheral vision. Neuron, 48(5), 849–858. Previc, F. H. (1998). he neuropsychology of 3-D space. Psychological Bulletin, 124(2), 123–164. Quinlan, D. J., & Cu lham, J. C. (2007). fMRI reveals a preference for near viewing in the human superior parieto-occipital cortex. Neuroimage, 36(1), 167–187.
274
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Richter, H. O., Costello, P., Sponheim, S. R., Lee, J. T., & Pardo, J. V. (2004). Functional ne uroanatomy of t he h uman ne ar/far re sponse to bl ur cues: Eye-lens accommodation/vergence to p oint t argets v arying i n depth. European Journal of Neuroscience, 20(10), 2722–2732. Richter, H. O., Lee, J. T., & Pardo, J. V. (2000). Neuroanatomical correlates of the near response: Voluntary modulation of accommodation/vergence in the human visual system. European Journal of Neuroscience, 12(1), 311–321. Sereno, M. I., & Huang, R. S. (2006). A human parietal face area contains aligned head-centered visual and tactile maps. Nature Neuroscience, 9(10), 1337–1343. Singhal, A., Kaufman, L., Valyear, K., & Culham, J. C. (2006). fMRI reactivation of the human lateral occipital complex during delayed actions to remembered objects. Visual Cognition, 14(1), 122–125. Smeets, J. B., & Brenner, E. (1999). A new view on grasping. Motor Control, 3(3), 237–271. Snyder, L . H ., B atista, A . P., & A ndersen, R . A . (2000). I ntention-related activity i n t he p osterior pa rietal c ortex: A re view. Vision Re search, 40(10–12), 1433–1441. van Donkelaar, P., & Staub, J. (2000). Eye-hand coordination to visual versus remembered targets. Experimental Brain Research, 133(3), 414–418. Vanni, S., Tanskanen, T., Seppa, M., Uutela, K., & Hari, R. (2001). Coinciding early activation of the human primary visual cortex and anteromedial c uneus. Proceedings of th e N ational A cademy of S ciences, U.S.A., 98(5), 2776–2780. von H ofsten, C . ( 1979). De velopment o f v isually-directed re aching: he approach phase. Journal of Human Movement Studies, 5, 160–178. von Hofsten, C . (1982). Eye-hand coordination in t he newborn. Developmental Psychology, 18, 450–461. Weiss, P. H., Marshall, J. C., Wunderlich, G., Tellmann, L., Halligan, P. W., Freund, H. J., et al. (2000). Neural consequences of acting in near versus far space: A p hysiological ba sis for clinical d issociations. Brain, 123( Pt. 12), 2531–2541.
9 The Growing Body in Action What Infant Locomotion Tells Us About Perceptually Guided Action
Karen E. Adolph
A Changeable Body in a Variable World Twenty years ago, Eleanor Gibson (1987) asked, “What does infant perception tell us about theories of perception?” (p. 515). Her answer was t hat t heories of perception, t ypically built on adults’ behavior in esoteric recognition and discrimination tasks, must take into account the perceptual accomplishments of young infants. Although infants cannot recognize letters, follow researchers’ instructions, or provide researchers with verbal judgments about their percepts, they can generate perceptual i nformation t hrough spontaneous ex ploratory movements a nd u se it for g uiding motor ac tion. I n Gibson’s (1987) words, “Present-day theories of perception are going to have to give an account of how perception gives rise to and guides action” (p. 518). Perhaps, the fact that infants make such diicult subjects in traditional perception pa radigms encouraged researchers to recognize the links between perception and motor action. Infants create visual, t actile, vestibular, a nd muscle-joint i nformation by moving their eyes, heads, and bodies. he consequent perceptual information 275
276
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
can provide the basis for selecting and modifying future movements because it is both exteroceptive, specifying events and objects in the environment, a nd proprioceptive, spec ifying t he c urrent st atus of the body and its participation in ongoing events. Here, I pose Gibson’s question once again, but now in the context of a new literature on the perceptual guidance of motor action. he notion that a central function of perception is to guide motor action is no longer new. But, in t he midst of a n ew generation of t heorizing ba sed on adults’ behavior i n e soteric motor dec ision t asks, my answer will be that perception-action studies with infants tell us that theories of perception-action coupling will have to take learning and development into account. Issues of learning and development are accentuated in research with infants because changes in infants’ bodies and motor skills are especially dramatic, and encounters with novel features of t he environment a re especially pronounced compared with later periods of life. However, learning and development are not limited to infancy. hroughout the life span, bodily propensities change due to gains and losses in weight, muscle stifness, and strength. New motor sk ills a re acquired a nd old ones a re lost. he environment still holds some surprises. At any age, the central problem for understanding perceptually guided action is how observers cope with a changeable body in a variable world.
Embodied and Embedded Action Motor actions are always embodied and embedded (Bernstein, 1996; Clark, 1997). he functional outcome of motor actions is inextricably bound to the biomechanical status of the body (the size, shape, mass, compliance, strength, lexibility, and coordination of the various body parts) and the physical properties of the surrounding environment (the surfaces and media that support the body, the objects toward which movements are directed, and the efects of gravity acting on the various body parts). A few, haphazard, feather-kicks of a 12-week-old f etus c an p ropel i t so mersaulting, n early w eightlessly, through the buoyant amniotic luid, whereas powerful muscle forces, precisely timed to exploit inertia, are required for an expert gymnast to launch a so mersault at the end of a t umbling run. From fetus to skilled a thlete, m otor ac tions a re a lways constrained o r fac ilitated by the body’s current dimensions and propensities in the context of
The Growing Body in Action
277
an i mmediate en vironment w ith pa rticular p hysical su pports a nd hindrances. Depending o n t he c urrent co nstellation o f body a nd en vironmental fac tors, t he s ame f unctional outcome c an require very d ifferent muscle actions and, reciprocally, the same muscle actions can result i n ve ry d iferent f unctional out comes (B ernstein, 1996). For example, for fetuses to bring their hands to their mouths in the irst weeks of gestation, they must lex their arms at the shoulder because their a rm buds a re so sh ort (Moore & P ersaud, 1998). To per form the same hand-to-mouth behavior several weeks later, fetuses must bend their arms at the elbow to take their longer limbs into account (Robinson & K leven, 2005). he same leg kicks that somersault the fetus through the amniotic luid early in gestation fail to extend the legs toward t he end of gestation when t he growing fetus is pressed against t he u terine w all ( de V ries, V isser, & Pr echtl, 1 982). A ter birth, v igorous l eg k icks lex a nd ex tend t he l egs, b ut w ithout t he buoyancy of the amniotic luid, gravity keeps t he infant rooted in place (helen & Fisher, 1983). he cha nging constraints of t he body a nd environment a re not limited to developmental changes (such as the lengthening and differentiation o f t he f etal a rm a nd t he dec rease i n spac e w ithin t he uterus). At a ny point i n t he l ifespan, t he fac ts of embodiment c an vary due to seemingly insigniicant factors in the course of everyday activity (Adolph, 2002; Reed, 1989). Carrying an object can alter the body’s functional dimensions. Variations in clothing and footgear can afect the ability to create resistive forces. Leaning forward, liting an arm, turning the head, or even drawing a deep breath can create moment-to-moment changes in the location of the body’s center of mass and, as a consequence, pose continually changing demands for m aintaining b alance. S imilarly, v ariability an d n ovelty in t he environmental co ntext i s t he r ule, n ot t he ex ception. A ctions a re typically performed in a world that is cluttered with potential obstacles and opportunities. Objects and surfaces have dimensions, material properties, and locations that can change from one encounter to the next (think of cha irs, doors, a nd t he condition of t he sidewalk due to weather a nd debris). Ma ny objects move a nd pa rticipate i n events—people, animals, balls, and cars. As the Greek philosopher, Heraclitus put it, “No man ever steps in the same river twice, for it is not the same river and he is not the same man.”
278
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Affordances he Gibsons’ concept of afordances captures the functional signiicance of embodied a nd embedded ac tion (E. J. Gibson, 1982; E . J. Gibson & Pick, 2000; J. J. Gibson, 1979). Afordances are possibilities for motor action. he probability of performing a n action successfully depends on the it between the behaviorally relevant properties of the body i n relation to the surrounding environment (Adolph & Berger, 2006; Warren, 1984). As such, afordances relect the objective state of afairs. Actions have a certain probability of success, regardless of whether actors perceive, misperceive, or take advantage of the possibilities. hus, the notion of afordances is distinct from claims about h ow a fordances m ight be per ceived o r ex ploited, a nd t he description of an afordance involves only the relationship between the relevant physical features of the body and environment. Because a fordances a re r elational, t he fac ts o f em bodiment must be t aken w ith reference to t he properties of t he environment in which the body i s embedded and vice versa. For example, walking over open ground is possible only when walkers have suicient strength, post ural control, a nd endurance relative to t he length of the path, and the slant, rigidity, and texture of the ground surface. Walking between two obstacles is possible only when walkers’ largest body dimensions are smaller than the size of the opening (Warren & Whang, 1987). In fact, bodily propensities and environmental properties are so intimately connected for supporting motor actions that changes in a single factor on either side of the afordance relationship alter the probability of successful performance. For example, Figure 9.1A shows the afordance function for a t ypical 14-month-old toddler walking down an adjustable sloping ramp. On shallower slopes, from 0° to 20°, the probability of walking successfully is close to 1.0. On slopes between 20° and 32°, tiny changes in the degree of slant cause the probability of success to drop from 1.0 to 0. he afordance threshold, deined here as the slope where the probability of success is 0.50, is approximately 26°. Figure 9.1B shows the afordance function f or a n ad ult w oman w alking t hrough a n ad justable d oorway (Franchak & Adolph, 2007). For wider doorways, larger than 31 cm, the probability of walking successfully is 1.0. With small changes in doorway width, the probability of success drops from 1.0 to 0. he estimated afordance threshold is 30 cm. Reciprocally, changes in body dimensions and propensities—both structural and dynamic aspects of the body—afect the probability
The Growing Body in Action A
B
C
D
279
Figure 9.1 Afordance t hresholds. (A) A fordance f unction for one 1 4-monthold infant walking down slopes. he function is calculated by the ratio of successful a nd f ailed at tempts to w alk. he afordance t hreshold i s t he e stimated s lope where the probability of walking successfully is 0.50. (B) Afordance function and threshold for one woman walking through doorways. (C) Developmental changes in afordance thresholds for one infant walking down slopes. Figure adapted from R. Kail (Ed.), Advances in Child Development & Behavior, by K. E. Adolph, “Learning to keep balance,” 2002, with permission from Elsevier Science. (D) Developmental changes in afordance thresholds for one pregnant woman walking through doorways.
of performing these same actions successfully. he changes may be temporary: For example, afordance thresholds for infants walking down slopes decreased by 4.4°, on average, while loaded with lead weights on their shoulders (Adolph & Avolio, 2000). Similarly, afordance thresholds for navigating between two obstacles would increase while carrying a p izza box or wearing bulky clothing. Or, cha nges may be more permanent as the result of injury, aging, growth, weight gain/loss, increase/decrease in motor proiciency, and so on. Figure 9.1C shows t he cha nge i n a fordance t hresholds for w alking down slopes f or o ne i nfant o ver w eeks o f te sting ( Adolph, 1 997). W ith changes in the infant’s body dimensions and walking skill, he could manage steeper slopes each week than the last. Figure 9.1D shows the change i n a fordance t hresholds for pa ssing t hrough doorways for one woman over the course of her pregnancy (Franchak & Adolph,
280
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
2007). Increase in her body dimensions and decrease in her ability to contort and compress her abdomen caused a corresponding increase in afordance thresholds over weeks of testing.
How Development Changes Affordances for Action he examples of infants walking down slopes and pregnant women walking through doorways illustrate how rapidly and dramatically afordances c an cha nge w ith de velopment. A pa ssable d oorway a t one month becomes impassable a month later. An impossibly steep slope this week becomes navigable a week later. In essence, when possibilities for motor action are plotted against a continuously changing feature of the environment (as in Figures 9.1A-B), developmental changes in body dimensions and skills shit the afordance function back and forth along the x-axis, causing a corresponding shit in the value of the threshold. Developmental changes in the body, its propensities, and the surrounding environment are especially striking in the beginning of life.
Body Growth he rate of fetal body growth, for example, is far more astronomical than the external view of mothers’ bulging abdomens might suggest. At 4 weeks postconception, the average embryo is 4 mm long, about the size of a pe a (Moore & Persaud, 1998). he head comprises one half of t he b ody length. From p ea-sized embryo to term ne wborn, fetuses i ncrease t heir h eight b y a pproximately 8 ,000% a nd t heir weight by 42,500%. By the end of gestation at 38 to 40 weeks, the newborn i s 57 c m long, a nd t he head comprises one fourth of t he body length (Ounsted & M oar, 1986). By co mparison, adults’ head length is one eighth of their total body height (C. E. Palmer, 1944). Rapid and dramatic body growth continues during infancy. Like fetal growth, the rates of change during infancy difer for diferent parts of the body. Gains in infants’ body length are faster than gains in weight and head circumference, so that overall body proportions undergo a general slimming. In essence, infants begin to grow into their large heads. heir top-heavy bodies become increasingly cylindrical and their center of mass moves from the bottom of the ribcage
The Growing Body in Action
281
to below the belly button. Ater 2 years of age, rate of body growth slows until the adolescent growth spurt. Continuous body growth as represented by the smooth curves on a standard growth chart is actually a m isrepresentation. Children’s body growth—from fetus to adolescent—is episodic, not continuous (Johnson, Veldhuis, & Lampl, 1996; Lampl, 1993; Lampl, Ashizawa, Kawabata, & J ohnson, 1998; Lampl & J eanty, 2003; Lampl & J ohnson, 1993; Lampl, Johnson, & Frongillo, 2001). hat is, brief, 24-hr periods of extremely rapid growth are interspersed w ith long periods of stasis during wh ich no g rowth occurs for days or weeks on end. Figure 9.2A shows the smooth growth functions on a standard growth chart for height, and Figure 9.2B shows the actual episodic increases in height for one inf ant. Episodic growth i s c haracteristic of cha nges i n height, weight, head circumference, a nd leg bone growth. F or ex ample, d aily m easurements o f i nfants’ h eight sh ow increases of 0.5 to 1.65 cm punctuated by 2- to 28-day periods of no growth (Lampl, Veldhuis, & J ohnson, 1992). he t iming of g rowth spurts, the amplitude of the changes, and the length of the plateaus when no growth occurs show large intra- and intersubject variability. he long plateaus with no growth are not related to stress or illness. Rather, normal, healthy children grow in its and starts. Even within a 24 -hr per iod, g rowth i s ep isodic. Ch ildren g row m ore a t n ight while lying down than during the day while standing and walking, especially in their weight-bearing extremities (Lampl, 1992; Noonan et al., 2004).
Motor Proficiency and New Perception-Action Systems. During the same time period that infants’ body size and body proportions are changing, so are their abilities to perform various motor skills (for reviews, s ee Adolph & B erger, 2 005, 2 006; B ertenthal & Cliton, 1998). For example, between 5 a nd 8 m onths, most infants begin l earning t o s it ( Bly, 1 994; F rankenburg & Dodd s, 1 967). A t irst, balance is so precarious that they must prop themselves upright in a tripod position by supporting their body weight on their arms between their outstretched legs. heir hamstrings are so loose, that they l ose ba lance i n a 36 0° a rc, i ncluding fa lling n ose-to-knees. Gradually, only one arm must be used for balance. hen, the hands become f reed f rom s upporting f unctions, irst mome ntarily, a nd
282
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Length (cm)
A
Age (years)
Length (cm)
B
Age (mos) Figure 9.2 Growth curves for height. (A) Standard growth curves from birth to 18 years. Data are mathematically smoothed and averaged over children. Dashed line represents boys. Solid line represents girls. Adapted from growth charts developed by t he National C enter for H ealth St atistics i n c ollaboration w ith t he National C enter for C hronic D isease P revention a nd H ealth P romotion ( 2000). (B) M icrogenetic e pisodic g rowth c urve for one e xemplar i nfant. E ach ve rtical line re presents d aily re plicate ob servations. Re printed f rom Science, 2 58, by M . Lampl, J. D. Veldhuis, and M. L. Johnson, “Saltation and Stasis: A Model of Human Growth,” pp. 801–803, 1992, with permission from the American Association for the Advancement of Science.
The Growing Body in Action
283
later for extended periods. Finally, infants can turn their heads, lean in various directions, and hold objects and manipulate them without losing balance. Most infants’ irst success at forward locomotion is crawling (others may initially “log roll,” “bum shule,” or “cruise”). Many crawlers irst ma ster p rone p rogression b y bel ly c rawling, wh ere t heir abdomens rest on the ground during part of each crawling cycle (Adolph, Vereijken, & Den ny, 1998). hey use their arms, legs, and bellies i n v arious, id iosyncratic c ombinations, s ometimes pu shing with o nly o ne l imb i n a g irdle a nd d ragging t he la me a rm o r l eg behind, sometimes pushing with irst the knee then the foot on one leg, a nd so metimes la unching t hemselves f rom k nees o r f eet o nto belly during each cycle. hey may move arms and legs on alternate sides of the body t ogether like a t rot, ipsilateral limbs together like a lumbering bear, lit front then back limbs into the air like a bunny hop, and display irregular patterns of interlimb timing—the possibilities a re i mmense bec ause ba lance is so u nconstrained w ith t he abdomen r esting o n t he loor. Fi gure 9.3A s hows one i nfant’s p attern of interlimb timing over a series of cycles (Adolph et al., 1998). First, he moved his let arm forward. hen, he pushed with both legs and l ited h is abdomen of the loor. Next he moved h is r ight a rm forward. Use of the right leg was especially variable, and for a l ong period the infant maintained the leg alot. Despite tremendous intraand i nter-subject variability i n crawling movements, proiciency at belly c rawling i ncreases w ith e ach w eek o f p ractice, a s i ndicated by i mprovements i n c rawling spe ed ( Figure 9.4A) a nd step l ength (Adolph et al., 1998). Eventually (typically, at about 8 m onths of a ge), i nfants acquire suicient strength and balance control to crawl with their abdomens of the loor. In contrast to the variability endemic in belly crawling, the t iming i n i nterlimb coo rdination o f ha nds-and-knees g aits i s nearly uniform (Adolph et al., 1998; Freedland & Bertenthal, 1994). Within the irst week or two ater achieving hand-and-knees crawling, i nfants m ove t heir a rms a nd l egs i n a n a lternating n ear-trot. Figure 9.3B shows the pattern of interlimb timing in one infant that is typical of hands-and-knees gaits. She moved her right arm and let leg together a nd her let a rm a nd right leg together, w ith t he a rms slightly preceding the legs in each case. Again, proiciency at crawling shows dramatic improvements over the course of a few months (Figure 9.4B), with increases in the amplitude and speed of crawling movements (Adolph et al., 1998).
284
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
A
Limb
Belly Crawler
Time (seconds) B
Limb
Hands/Knees Crawler
Time (seconds) Figure 9.3 Patterns of i nterlimb t iming i n (A) b elly c rawling, a nd ( B) h andsand-knees crawling. Shaded regions represent t ime when t he l imb (or belly) was supporting t he b ody i n s tance. O pen re gions re present t ime w hen t he l imb (or belly) was moving forward in swing.
Typically, coincident with crawling at about 10 months of age (Frankenburg & Dodds, 1967), infants begin to master upright postures. hey pull to a stand against furniture and later cruise—that is, move sideways in an upright position while holding onto furniture for support. Initially, cruisers’ arms do most of the work of supporting body w eight, ma intaining ba lance, a nd ste ering; t he l egs h old only part of the body weight (many infants begin cruising up on their toes) a nd oten become crossed and entangled. As the legs take on more of a supporting function, infants put less weight on their arms
The Growing Body in Action
285
B
A
C
Figure 9.4 Developmental c hanges i n ve locity d uring ( A) b elly c rawling, ( B) hands-and-knees c rawling, a nd ( C) w alking. Cr awling d ata we re a dapted f rom Child Development, 69, by K. E. Adolph, B. Vereijken, and M. Denny, “Learning to crawl,” pp. 1299–1312, 1998, with permission from Blackwell Publishers.
and t he coo rdination be tween a rm a nd l eg m ovements i mproves (Vereijken & Adolph, 1999; Vereijken & Waardenburg, 1996). Walking i s t he m ost h eralded o f i nfants’ m otor sk ills, p robably because it is such an obvious step toward adultlike behavior. On average, infants take their irst toddling steps toward the end of their irst year (Frankenburg & Dodd s, 1967), but like most motor sk ills, t he range in the age of walking onset is extremely wide (9 to 16 months of age). Like crawling, improvements in walking are most rapid and dramatic in the irst few months ater onset, and thereater begin to asymptote a nd r elect m ore sub tle t ypes o f cha nges (Adolph, Vereijken, & Sh rout, 2003; Bril & B reniere, 1992; Bril & L edebt, 1998). Asymptotic performance curves are typical of motor performance, including measures of errors (e.g., missteps), variability (e.g., coeficient of variation), speed, amplitude, and accuracy (Schmidt & Lee, 1999). I nfants’ step l engths i ncrease, t he la teral d istance be tween
286
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
their legs a nd out-toeing decrease, both i ntra- a nd i nterlimb coordination b ecome le ss v ariable a nd more e icient, a nd a s shown i n Figure 9.4C (Adolph, Garciaguirre, & Badaly, 2007a; Garciaguirre, Adolph, & Shrout, 2007), infants walk faster. Note that novice walking infants move twice as fast in their irst weeks of walking as experienced crawlers do in their last weeks of crawling. Once infants can string a s eries of consecutive w alking steps t ogether, t he ability to walk provides them with a more time-eicient mode of travel. he de velopmental cha nges i n s itting, c rawling, c ruising, a nd walking relect more than the acquisition of motor proiciency. he transitions be tween e ach o f t hese post ural m ilestones r elect the acquisition of new perception-action systems (Adolph, 2002, 2005). Whereas changes in motor proiciency shit the afordance function back and forth along the x-axis (as illustrated in Figure 9.1), transitions to new perception-action systems create new afordance functions. Each posture represents a d iferent problem space deined by a unique set of parameters for maintaining balance. Each has a different key pivot around which the body rotates (the hips for sitting, the wrists for crawling, the shoulders for cruising, and the ankles for walking) and a diferent region of permissible postural sway within which the body can rotate before falling. Infants use diferent muscle groups for keeping t he body u pright and for propelling it forward. here a re d iferent v antage po ints f or v iewing t he g round a head, correlations be tween v isual a nd v estibular i nformation, ac cess t o mechanical i nformation f rom t ouching t he g round, a nd so o n. I n Campos and colleagues’ (2000) words, he ma pping b etween v ision a nd p osture t hat r esults f rom crawling experience will need to be remapped as the infant acquires new motor sk ills such a s s tanding a nd w alking…In fact, remapping is likely to occur with the acquisition of every new motor skill in a continuously coevolving perception-action cycle. (p. 174)
Each post ure r equires m oving d iferent body pa rts a nd ba lance i s controlled by diferent sources of visual, vestibular, and mechanical information. Ater the infancy period, it is hard to imagine comparable novelty in perception-action systems, but bicycling, swimming, and swinging arm over arm along monkey bars are likely candidates because these sk ills i nvolve such d iferent c onstraints on maintaining bal-
The Growing Body in Action
287
ance. In bicycling, for example, the key pivot is at the bottom of the front wheel and the region of permissible postural sway depends on the angles of the wheels as well as the body’s position. While swinging on monkey bars, the body rotates around the shoulders, and the arms must support the entire body weight. Rather than representing the acquisition of new perception-action systems, most of the locomotor sk ills acq uired d uring ch ildhood a nd ad ulthood (driving a car, motorcycling, rock climbing, ice skating, skiing, surf boarding, etc.) may relect the growth and adaptation of existing perceptionaction systems for sitting, crawling, cruising, and walking.
Environment Developmental changes in infants’ bodies and skills bring about corresponding changes in the environment. New postures and vantage points and new and improved forms of mobility allow infants to gain access to new places a nd surfaces. Instead of looking at t he legs of the cofee table, they can peer over the top. Instead of looking at an object from across the room, they can go to retrieve it. Rather than waiting for caregivers to transport them, they can go to see things for themselves. Features of the environment that adults take for granted, such as sloping ground and narrow openings between obstacles, are novel for newly mobile infants. Moreover, de velopmental ex pansion i n t he en vironment i s n ot solely depen dent o n de velopmental cha nges i n m obility. A l eaner, more mature looking body and better performance of various locomotor sk ills may i nspire caregivers to provide i nfants w ith g reater access to the environment. Now, parents may put infants on the loor with greater frequency, remove the gate blocking the stairs, and allow infants to travel into an adjoining room on their own.
Summary: Changing Affordances Changes i n i nfants’ bod ies, p ropensities, a nd en vironments oc cur concurrently, but along diferent developmental trajectories. Singly, or in combination, t hese fac tors c an cha nge t he constraints on ac tion. Episodic body growth means that infants begin a new day with a new body size and a n ew set of body p roportions. In particular, less top-
288
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
heavy body p roportions and increased muscle mass relative to body fat introduce new possibilities for keeping balance in stance and locomotion. R apid i mprovements i n motor proiciency mean that afordances for ba lance a nd locomotion cha nge f rom week to week, a nd these changes will be most pronounced in the irst months ater infants acquire a new perception-action system. Moreover, because the acquisition of sitting, crawling, cruising, and walking postures appear staggered over several months, at each point in development, infants are experts in an earlier developing posture and novices in a later developing one. hus, a situation that afords balance in an experienced sitting posture may be impossible in a novice crawling posture. Developmental changes in infants’ environments mean t hat infants are likely to encounter novel features of t he environment t hat a ford or pre clude the use of their newly acquired perception-action systems.
Infants’ Perception of Affordances he critical question for understanding the adaptive control of action, of course, is wh ether a fordances a re perceived—whether ch ildren and adults gear t heir motor decisions to t he actual possibilities for action (for reviews, see Adolph, 1997; Adolph & Berger, 2005, 2006; Adolph, Eppler, & Gibson, 1993). Given the constant lux of developmental changes, t he cha llenge for infants is to detect t he new constraints on action. Infants must continually update their assessment of afordances to take their new bodies, skills, and environments into account. I begin with the problem for perception and then describe three case studies (avoiding a precipice, navigating slopes, and crossing bridges) that highlight the importance of learning and development in the perceptual guidance of locomotion.
The Perceptual Problem Perceiving a fordances, l ike a ny per ceptual p roblem, beg ins w ith a de scription o f wha t t here i s t o be per ceived ( J. J . Gibso n, 1 979). As i llustrated b y t he i ndividual d ata i n F igures 9.1A-B, l ike ma ny psychophysical fu nctions, th e c urves th at c haracterize th e t ransition from possible to impossible actions are typically steep, S-shaped functions with long extended tails. Although afordance thresholds
The Growing Body in Action
289
for walking down slopes and passing through doorways vary widely between i ndividuals, t he f unctions across i ndividuals a re similarly steep. M ore ge nerally, re gardless of t he lo cation of t he a fordance function along the x-axis, most actions are either possible or impossible for a wide range of situations that lie along the tails of the function, and have a shiting probability of success for a narrow range of situations that lie along the inlection of the function. Consider, f or ex ample, t he en tire r ange o f sl opes, f rom 0 ° t o 90°, and the entire range of doorways (or more generally, openings between obstacles), f rom 0 c m to ininitely w ide. Regardless of t he particulars of the current situation, the inlection of the afordance function is likely to occupy only a small section of the range of possibilities. he consistent shape of the afordance function simpliies the p roblem f or per ception: I n m ost c ases, per ceivers m ust d etermine only which tail of the function best describes the current situation (e.g., the slope is perfectly safe or impossibly steep; the doorway is completely passable or absolutely impassable). However, because of the particulars of the current situation (the slope is slippery, the walker is carrying a l oad, walking proiciency has i mproved, e tc.), t he l ocation o f t he i nlection o f t he f unction along t he x-axis—whether t he perso n c an ma nage ste ep sl opes o r only shallow ones, narrow doorways or only wider ones—can vary widely f rom o ne m oment t o t he n ext. I n fac t, a n u nlimited n umber o f v ariables i ncluding fac tors such a s sla nt, f riction, l oad, a nd walking proiciency, create an n-dimensional axis, along which the afordance f unction s lides f rom mome nt to mome nt. he changing location of the afordance function complicates the problem for perception: Obs ervers m ust de termine wh ere a long t he x-axis (or, more generally, n-dimensional axis) the transition from possible to impossible occurs, that is, the region where their threshold currently lies. Figures 9.1C and 9.1D show dramatic developmental changes in the location of the afordance threshold for individual participants. To illustrate further, the range in afordance thresholds for walking down slopes for 14-month-olds (± 1 week of age) is quite large, from 4° t o 2 8° ( Adolph, 1 995; A dolph & A volio, 2 000). he wide range in afordance t hresholds g iven t he na rrow spread i n ch ronological age r elects t he v ariable t iming a nd a mplitude of d evelopmental changes. In addition, in the event that the afordance lies along the inlection o f t he c urve (e.g., t he p robability o f w alking s afely d own t he
290
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
slope or t hrough t he doorway i s be tween 0 a nd 1.0), or perceivers are unsure about the precise location of the transition from possible to impossible, they must weigh the probability of success against the penalties f or u nder- a nd o verestimation er rors. hus, m otor dec isions—like a ny per ceptual j udgment—relect bo th o bservers’ se nsitivity to the perceptual information and a r esponse criterion. For both i nfants a nd adults, some outcomes such a s fa lling downward (down a slope or over the brink of a clif ) constitute a highly aversive penalty, whereas other outcomes such as entrapment (e.g., becoming wedged in an overly narrow doorway) constitute a relatively innocuous penalty (Adolph, 1997; Joh, Adolph, Narayanan, & Dietz, 2007; C. F. Palmer, 1987; Warren & W hang, 1987). Factors such a s motivation and fatigue may also play an important role in setting a response criterion. What kind of data would constitute evidence that infants (or animals of any age) can solve the perceptual problem of detecting afordances? One source of evidence is infants’ motor decisions, that is, whether infants match their attempts to perform a t arget action to the conditional probability of success. Obtaining such data requires test paradigms where the challenges are novel, the probability of success varies from trial to trial, and infants are suiciently motivated to produce a large number of trials while staying on task. If infants’ response c riterion i s t oo l iberal, t hey a re l ikely t o r espond i ndiscriminately, precluding a ssessment of t heir sensitivity to t he a fordances. If their response criterion is too conservative, they are likely to refuse to participate in the experiment. Fortunately, infants love to p ractice t heir n ewly de veloping m otor sk ills, a nd w ith a b it o f incentive (praise from their caregivers and pieces of dry cereal) they happily produce dozens of t rials over a l engthy s ession. W hen t he penalty for error is falling downward, infants’ response criterion is suiciently conservative to assess their perception of afordances for balance and locomotion.
Case Study 1: Avoiding Cliffs and Gaps An obvious test case to study infants’ perception of afordances is a falling of place (E. J. Gibson, 1991). A basic requirement for balance and locomotion is a continuous loor to support the body. A ground surface t hat terminates i n a la rge d rop-of is a clif. A g round su r-
The Growing Body in Action
291
face that is interrupted by a w ide gap is a crevasse. hese should be avoided.
The Visual Cliff Most researchers have studied infants’ perception of afordances at the edge of a drop-of on a “visual clif,” rather than a real one. First devised by Gibson a nd Walk (E. J. Gibson & W alk, 1960; Walk & Gibson, 1961), the apparatus is a large glass table with wooden sides, divided in half by a na rrow board. On t he “deep” side, a pa tterned surface lies on the loor far below the glass, creating the illusion of an abrupt drop-of. On t he “shallow” side, t he patterned surface is placed directly beneath the glass, providing visual information for a continuous ground surface. he glass serves to ensure infants’ safety if they venture onto the deep side and the wooden sides prevent them from falling of the table onto the loor. Human infants a re placed on t he c enterboard a nd c aregivers en courage t hem f rom irst one side a nd t hen t he o ther ( Figure 9.5). O ther a nimals a re p laced o n the centerboard and given several minutes to descend to the side of their choice. Dozens of i nvestigations have y ielded i ntriguing but conlicting indings regarding the role of locomotor experience in avoiding the deep side of the visual clif. Precocial animals such as infant goats and chicks, who walk moments ater birth, avoid the deep side on their irst ex posure ( E. J . Gibso n & W alk, 1960; Walk & Gibso n, 1961). Similarly, some altricial animals such as rats, whose locomotor skills develop slowly, do not require visual experience with locomotion to avoid the apparent drop-of (Walk, Gibson, & Tighe, 1957). However, other a ltricial spec ies such a s k ittens, r abbits, a nd i nfant humans, crawl r ight o ver t he ed ge o f t he de ep s ide wh en t hey irst become mobile. he problem is not lack of depth perception because human infants can see the drop-of months before they begin crawling. A frequently cited study with human infants showed that crawling ex perience p redicts a voidance o f t he a pparent d rop-of, when testing a ge i s controlled: A ter only t wo weeks of c rawling ex perience, 6 5% of i nfants c rawled o ver t he de ep s ide of t he v isual cl if, but a ter six weeks of crawling experience, the percentage dropped to 35% of infants (Bertenthal, Campos, & Ba rrett, 1984). However, other c ross-sectional st udies found t he opposite results, where t he
292
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Figure 9.5 Crawling i nfant o n t he v isual c lif. O n t he d eep sid e, s afety g lass covered a l arge d rop-of. Caregivers beckoned to i nfants f rom t he far side of t he obstacle. A dapted f rom Psychological M onographs: G eneral a nd Ap plied, 7 5(15, Whole No. 519), by R. D. Walk & E. J. Gibson, “A comparative and analytical study of visual depth perception,” 1961, with permission from the American Psychological Association.
duration of crawling experience, controlling for age, was positively related to crossing over the deep side (Richards & Rader, 1981, 1983). Longitudinal d ata a re i nconclusive bec ause i nfants l earn f rom repeated testing that the safety glass provides support for locomotion and they become more likely to cross over (Campos, Hiatt, Ramsay, Henderson, & S vejda, 1 978; Ep pler, S atterwhite, Wendt, & B ruce, 1997; Titzer, 1995). Some evidence suggests t hat locomotor ex perience is posture-speciic: he same crawlers who avoided the drop-of when te sted on t heir ha nds a nd k nees c rossed over t he cl if when tested moments later in an upright posture in a wheeled baby-walker (Rader, Ba usano, & R ichards, 1 980). O ther e vidence su ggests t hat locomotor experience generalizes from an earlier developing perception-action system to a later developing one: 12-month-old walking infants avoided the apparent drop-of ater only two weeks of walking experience appended to their several weeks of crawling experience (Witherington, Campos, Anderson, Lejeune, & Seah, 2005). Albeit the most famous test paradigm, the visual clif is not optimal. Discrepant indings may result from methodological problems
The Growing Body in Action
293
stemming from the design of the apparatus. he safety glass presents mixed messages: he v isual clif looks dangerous, but feels safe. In fact, because human infants quickly learn that the apparatus is perfectly safe, avoidance attenuates and they can only be tested with one trial on the deep side. In addition, the safety glass may lead to underestimation of i nfants’ er rors. Sometimes i nfants lean forward onto the g lass w ith t heir ha nds o r st art onto t he g lass a nd t hen r etreat (e.g., Campos et al., 1978); if the glass were not there, they would have fa llen. M oreover, t he d imensions o f t he v isual cl if are ixed so that researchers cannot test the accuracy of infants’ responses or ask whether infants scale their locomotor decisions to the size of the challenge. he heights of t he sha llow a nd de ep sides l ie fa r on t he tails of t he a fordance fu nction, rather than near the i nlection of the curve. Adjustable Gaps: A New Psychophysical Approach Circumventing t he m ethodological p roblems o n t he v isual cl if required a n ew approach. hus, we devised a n ew “gaps” paradigm (Adolph, 2000). Rather than a glass table with wooden sides, 9.5month-old infants were observed as they approached a deep crevasse between two platforms (Figure 9.6A-B). We removed the safety glass so that visual and haptic information would be in agreement rather than in conlict, and perceptual errors would lead to the real consequence of falling. To ensure infants’ safety, a h ighly trained experimenter followed alongside infants to provide rescue if they began to fall. Fortunately, “spotting” infants did not produce the same problem a s t he s afety g lass: I nfants d id not simply learn to rely on t he experimenter to c atch t hem, a nd avoidance d id not attenuate over trials. he dimensions of the apparatus were adjustable, rather than i xed, so t hat we could a ssess t he ac curacy of i nfants’ motor dec isions. Moving one platform along a c alibrated track varied the gap width from 0 to 90 cm in 2 cm increments. Because the depth of the crevasse between the two platforms was always the same, the penalty for fa lling w as i dentical ac ross a ll r isky g ap s izes. he la rgest g ap width had a pproximately t he s ame d imensions a s t he de ep side of the standard visual clif. Most critical, to determine the role of experience and the speciicity of learning across developmental transitions in perception-action systems, each infant was tested in an earlier developing sitting posture (M sitting ex perience = 1 5 weeks) a nd a la ter de veloping c rawling
294
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
A
B
Figure 9.6 Infants i n ( A) sit ting a nd ( B) c rawling p ostures at t he e dge of a n adjustable gap in the surface of support. Caregivers (not shown) ofered lures from the f ar sid e of t he gap . A n e xperimenter ( shown) fol lowed a longside i nfants to ensure their safety. Reprinted from Psychological Science, by K. E. Adolph, “Speciicity of le arning: Why infants fall over a ve ritable clif,” pp. 290–295, 2000, with permission from Blackwell Publishers.
posture (M crawling experience = 6 w eeks). (Note t hat t he average duration of experience in the less familiar crawling posture was similar to the duration of crawling experience in the more experienced group in Bertenthal and colleagues’ (1984) study with infants on the visual clif.) As shown in Figures 9.6A-B, the task for the infants was
The Growing Body in Action
295
the same in both postures—to lean forward over the gap to retrieve an attractive lure. Caregivers stood at the far side of the landing platform a nd e ncouraged i nfants’ eforts. R ather th an t esting i nfants with only one trial, infants were observed over dozens of trials. We used a modiied psychophysical staircase procedure to estimate each infant’s afordance threshold, and then assessed infants’ motor decisions b y p resenting s afe a nd r isky g aps, r elative t o t he t hreshold increment. Motor dec isions were de termined ba sed on a n attempt rate: he number of successful plus failed attempts to span the gap divided by the sum of successful attempts, failed attempts, and refusals to attempt the action. (he inverse avoidance rate yields the same information.) Adaptive motor decisions would be evidenced by high attempt rates on gaps smaller than the afordance threshold, and low attempt rates on gaps larger than the threshold. Two experiments conirmed the role of experience with balance and l ocomotion i n de tecting a fordances f or c rossing a c revasse (Adolph, 20 00). W hen tested i n t heir ex perienced s itting post ure, infants g auged p recisely h ow fa r f orward t hey co uld l ean w ithout falling into the hole. hey scaled their motor decisions to their body size a nd sitting proiciency so t hat t heir attempt rates matched t he conditional p robability o f suc cess. N one o f t he i nfants a ttempted the la rgest 90-cm gap. Like t he v isual cl if, t he gaps pa radigm was relatively novel: Typically, infants are not encouraged to cross a deep precipice on their own. hus, adaptive motor decisions in the sitting posture attest to transfer of learning from everyday experiences to a novel environmental challenge. However, when facing the crevasse in their less familiar crawling posture, t he s ame i nfants g rossly o verestimated t heir abilities a nd fell into impossibly wide gaps on trial ater trial. Infant showed a higher proportion of errors at each risky gap size in the less experienced crawling posture compared with the more experienced sitting posture. For example, in the crawling posture, 33% of infants in each of the two experiments fell over the brink of the largest 90-cm gap on every t rial, but none of t he infants attempted t he 90-cm gap in the sitting posture. It i s u nlikely t hat t he d iference be tween s itting a nd c rawling relects diferent r esponse c riteria. C onditions w ere b locked a nd counterbalanced, and there were no diferences between infants who experienced repeated rescues by the experimenter when tested irst in the crawling posture and infants who were tested irst i n the sitting posture. It is also unlikely that the diference be tween s itting
296
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
and crawling relected diferences in visual or mechanical access to the gap. In both postures, we conirmed from videotape that infants made v isual contact w ith t he gap at t he start of each t rial; i ndeed, the apparatus and lure were arranged so that the gap was directly in infants’ line of sight. In addition, infants spontaneously explored the gap in both sitting and crawling positions by leaning forward while extending and then retracting their a rm i nto the gap. R ather, the disparity between attempt rates in the sitting and crawling postures indicates that learning does not transfer across developmental transitions in perception-action systems. Apparently, what infants know about ke eping ba lance wh ile s itting d oes n ot h elp t hem t o g auge afordances in the same situation when learning to crawl. he new methodological approach of testing infants with multiple trials at a range of safe and risky increments also revealed something that could not be a ssessed with one trial on each side of the v isual clif—the a daptiveness of i nfants’ motor d ecisions re lative to t heir individual afordance thresholds and over variations in the perceptual information. he proportion of infants (33%) who attempted to span the 90-cm gap width in a crawling posture replicated the results from Bertenthal and colleagues’ (1984) study of infants on the visual clif, where 35% of infants in the six-week-experience group crawled over the deep side. However, trials at sma ller but equally risky gap increments (the depth of the crevasse was always the same), showed that s ix w eeks o f c rawling ex perience w as n ot su icient to ensure even a 33% error rate when faced with a deep crevasse. On sma ller, risky gap increments, attempt rates increased sharply in the crawling posture, indicating that infants’ motor decisions were more adaptive farther out on the tails of the afordance function and less adaptive on r isky gap i ncrements closer to t he t hreshold. he s ame pattern held for t he ex perienced sitting post ure, but t he attempt r atio w as lower at each risky gap width. Similarly, o ther r esearchers ha ve f ound spec iicity o f l earning between sitting and crawling postures when testing infants with barriers in their path. In a longitudinal study, infants reached around a barrier t o r etrieve a t arget ob ject wh ile te sted i n a s itting post ure several w eeks bef ore t hey dem onstrated t he ab ility t o r etrieve t he object while tested in a crawling posture (Lockman, 1984). In a follow-up cross-sectional study, 10- and 12-month-olds were more successful at retrieving objects f rom behind a ba rrier when t hey were sitting than when they had to execute the detour by crawling (Lockman & Adams, 2001).
The Growing Body in Action
297
In a v ariant of t he gaps pa radigm, infants a lso showed posturespeciic l earning ac ross t he de velopmental t ransition be tween t wo upright postures—cruising a nd walking (Adolph, 2005; Leo, Chiu, & Adolph, 2000). Infants were tested at 11 months of age, when they averaged eig ht weeks of ex perience c ruising s ideways a long f urniture, but t hey had n ot yet beg un to walk i ndependently. Using t he psychophysical procedure to estimate afordance thresholds and assess m otor dec isions, i nfants w ere te sted i n t wo co nditions. A “handrail” condition was relevant to infants’ experience maintaining balance with the arms in cruising: here was an adjustable gap (0 to 90 cm) in the handrail they held for support and a continuous loor ben eath t heir f eet ( Figure 9.7A). A “ loor” co ndition w as r elevant f or ma intaining ba lance w ith t he l egs i n w alking: he loor had a n adjustable gap (0–90 cm) a nd t he ha ndrail was continuous (Figure 9.7B). Because the handrail may have blocked infants’ view of the loor near their feet, an experimenter called infants’ attention to the gap in both conditions at the start of each trial to ensure that they saw the size of the obstacle. In the handrail condition, infants correctly gauged how far they could st retch t heir a rms t o c ruise o ver t he g ap i n t he ha ndrail. Attempt rates were scaled to the actual afordance function: Attempt rates w ere h igh o n s afe g aps sma ller t han t heir t hresholds a nd decreased sharply on risky gaps larger than their thresholds. However, i n t he loor condition, t he s ame i nfants showed g rossly i naccurate moto r de cisions. hey a ttempted s afe a nd r isky ga ps a like, despite viewing the gap in the loor at the start of each trial. Every infant showed higher error rates on risky gap increments in the loor condition compared with the handrail condition, and 41% of infants attempted to cruise into the 90-cm gap in the loor. Newly walking 11-month-olds erred in both conditions, as if they did not know how many steps t hey could ma nage be tween g aps i n t he ha ndrail, a nd they did not realize that they need a solid loor to support their bodies. I n su mmary, a lthough c ruising a nd w alking sha re a co mmon upright post ure, practice cruising does not appear to te ach i nfants how to detect afordances for walking.
Case Study 2: Navigating Slopes A series of longitudinal and cross-sectional experiments with infants on slopes provide further evidence that infants must learn to detect
298
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action A
B
Figure 9.7 Cruising i nfants w ith ( A) a n a djustable gap i n t he h andrail u sed for m anual s upport, a nd a c ontinuous loor b eneath t he fe et a nd ( B) a n a djustable gap i n t he loor, a nd a c ontinuous h andrail to hold for s upport. C aregivers (not shown) encouraged infants from the end of the landing platform. An experimenter (shown) followed alongside infants to e nsure their safety. Reprinted from A. Woodward & A. Needham (Eds.), Learning and the infant mind, by K. E. Adolph & A. S. Joh, “Multiple learning mechanisms in the development of action,” in press, with permission from Oxford University Press.
afordances f or ba lance a nd l ocomotion, a nd t hat l earning oc curs in t he context of d ramatic de velopmental cha nge (for r eviews, s ee Adolph, 2002, 2005; Adolph & Berger, 2006; Adolph & Eppler, 2002). Like c lifs a nd g aps, na vigating o ver sl opes i s r elatively n ovel f or infants. On pa rents’ r eports, m ost i nfants ha ve n ever c rawled o r walked over steep slopes or u sed a p layground sl ide on t heir own.
The Growing Body in Action
299
Compared w ith c lifs a nd g aps, sl opes ha ve a co ntinuous v isible and tangible surface between the brink and the edge of the obstacle rather than an abrupt discontinuity. hus, sloping ground provides a u nique test c ase for a ssessing t ransfer of learning f rom e veryday experience to a novel environmental challenge. We devised an adjustable sloping walkway by connecting a middle sloping r amp to t wo lat pl atforms w ith pi ano h inges (Fi gure 9.8). One platform was stationary. Raising and lowering the second platform allowed the degree of slant to be adjusted from 0° to 90° in 2° increments. he psychophysical method was used to determine an afordance t hreshold f or e ach i nfant f or c rawling o r w alking. Safe a nd r isky sl opes w ere p resented r elative t o t he t hreshold t o assess infants’ motor decisions. Caregivers stood at the top or bottom of t he w alkway a nd en couraged t heir i nfants t o come up or down. An experimenter followed alongside infants to ensure their safety. As in the gap studies, the penalty for errors on downhill slopes was falling downward, a co nsequence t hat i nfants ind aversive. Many falls d uring de scent w ere q uite d ramatic—with t he ex perimenter catching infants midair, spread-eagled like Superman, on the slope
Figure 9.8 Infant descending an adjustable slope. Caregivers (not shown) encouraged infants from the end of t he landing platform. An experimenter (shown) followed a longside i nfants to e nsure t heir s afety. Re printed f rom t he Monographs of th e S ociety fo r R esearch in C hild D evelopment, 62 (3, S erial N o. 251), by K . E . Adolph, “Learning in the development of i nfant locomotion,” 1997, with permission from Blackwell Publishers.
300
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
as t hey t umbled downward he adirst or on t heir back s a s i nfants’ feet slid out from under themselves. In contrast, falling while crawling or walking uphill is less aversive. When infants fell, they could lean forward and safely catch themselves with their hands.
Crawling and Walking Down Slopes In a longitudinal study (Adolph, 1997), infants were observed going up a nd d own sl opes e very t hree w eeks, f rom t heir irst w eek o f crawling, u ntil s everal m onths a ter they began walking. Infants’ performance on uphill slopes relected their indiference to the penalty for er rors. Attempt r ates were u niformly h igh on r isky sl opes at each week of crawling and walking. Infants launched themselves at impossibly steep slopes and made h eroic eforts to reach t he top platform, but failed repeatedly over dozens of trials. Infants’ performance on downhill slopes was a very diferent story. hey ad opted m ore co nservative r esponse cr iteria a nd i t wa s possible to track weekly changes in their motor decisions. In their irst week of crawling, i nfants plunged headirst down i mpossibly r isky slopes and required rescue by the experimenter. hey fell down 75% of risky slopes. With each week of locomotor experience, motor decisions gradually zeroed in on infants’ actual ability until attempts to descend closely matched the probability of success. Ater 22 weeks of crawling, attempt rates had decreased to 0.10 on risky slopes. Clearly, infants were not simply learning that the experimenter would catch them bec ause t hey bec ame m ore r eticent t o a ttempt r isky sl opes, rather than more reckless. he steady decrease in errors points to impressive transfer because infants’ afordance thresholds, crawling proiciency on lat ground, and body dimensions changed from week to w eek. A r isky sl ope o ne w eek w as per fectly s afe t he n ext w eek when c rawling sk ill had i mproved. S afe sl opes f or bel ly c rawling were impossibly risky a week or so later when infants began crawling on hands and knees. Despite m onths o f te sting a nd h undreds o f t rials de scending slopes, infants showed no evidence of transfer from crawling to walking. Errors were just as high in infants’ irst week of w alking as in their irst week of crawling, and learning was no faster the second time around. Learning was so posture-speciic that new walkers showed dissociations in their motor decisions between consecutive
The Growing Body in Action
301
trials, tested a lternately in t heir old, fa miliar crawling posture and in t heir u nfamiliar upright posture. When placed prone at t he top of a 36° sl ope, new walkers behaved l ike ex perienced crawlers a nd avoided de scent. Moments later, when placed upright at t he top of the same slope, they walked straight over the brink and fell. When placed prone again, they avoided, and so on. As in crawling, errors were a lways h ighest o n r isky s lopes cl osest t o i nfants’ a fordance thresholds and lowest on slopes farthest out on the tail of the afordance function. Moreover, infants in a control group who were tested only in their irst and tenth weeks of crawling and in their irst week of w alking w ere i ndistinguishable f rom i nfants wh o had ex perienced hundreds of trials on slopes. Apparently, learning transferred from everyday experience on lat ground to detecting afordances of slopes. Slope experience was not required. Cross-sectional d ata re plicated t he indings f rom t he lo ngitudinal obs ervations. E ight- t o 9 -month-old i nfants w ith 6 .5 w eeks of c rawling ex perience, o n a verage, a ttempt t o c rawl d own sl opes far be yond t heir ab ilities ( Adolph e t a l., 1 993). E leven-month-old infants, averaging 13 weeks of c rawling ex perience, ma tched t heir attempts to crawl to the probability of success (Mondschein, Adolph, & Tamis-LeMonda, 2000). Likewise, 12-month-old crawlers showed highly adaptive motor decisions for descending slopes. In contrast, 12-month-olds who had j ust beg un walking, attempted i mpossibly steep slopes on repeated trials. heir attempt rates were 0.73 on 50° slopes (Adolph, Joh, Ishak, Lobo, & Berger, 2005). By 14 months of age, when infants averaged 11 weeks of walking experience, attempts to walk were geared to infants’ actual abilities (Adolph, 1995). By 18 months of a ge, i nfants were h ighly ex perienced w alkers, a nd t heir motor de cisions w ere e ven mo re inely at tuned to t he a fordances for walking down slopes (Adolph et al., 2005). At every age, infants showed more adaptive motor decisions for going down slopes than for going up, indicating that they adopted diferent response criteria for a scent a nd de scent. Moreover, at e very a ge a nd for both uphill and d own, i nfants sh owed l ower a ttempt r atios o n sl opes fa rthest out on the tail of the afordance function and higher attempt ratios on s lopes closest t o t heir a fordance t hreshold. hese data s uggest that perceptual discrimination of afordances is most diicult in the region bordering the transition from possible to impossible actions. Across ages, perceptual learning relects a process of gradually gearing motor decisions to the afordance threshold.
302
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Walking with Weights By the time infants are tested in the laboratory, they may have had several days to adjust to naturally occurring changes in their body dimensions a nd m otor p roiciency. H owever, tem porary cha nges in bodily propensities, such as changes in the location of the center of mass while carrying a t oy, require instant recalibration to a n ew afordance t hreshold. he add ition o f t he t oy a lters i nfants’ f unctional body dimensions. Experimental manipulation of infants’ body dimensions showed that experienced 14-month-old walking infants (averaging 9 w eeks of w alking ex perience) c an u pdate t heir a ssessment o f t heir o wn abilities on the ly (Adolph & Avolio, 2000). Infants wore a tightly itted Velcro vest with removable shoulder packs illed with either lead weights (25% of their body weight) or feather-weight polyil (Figure 9.9). he lead-weight load made infants’ bodies more top-heavy and immaturely p roportioned, a h indrance e specially wh ile w alking down sl opes. W hile c arrying t he l ead-weight l oads, i nfants’ a fordance t hresholds were several deg rees sha llower t han wh ile c arrying the feather-weight loads. he load condition changed randomly
Figure 9.9 Infant we aring itted V elcro ve st w ith re movable s houlder p acks. Lead-weight or feather-weight loads could be itted into the shoulder packs at various percentages of i nfants’ body weight. Reprinted from J. L ockman, J. Re iser, & C. A . Ne lson (E ds.), Action a s a n or ganizer of p erception a nd c ognition d uring learning and development: Symposium on C hild Development (Vol. 33), by K . E. Adolph, “Learning to le arn in the development of a ction,” pp. 91–122, 2005, with permission from Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
The Growing Body in Action
303
from trial to trial, meaning that infants would have to detect the different afordance thresholds for the lead- and feather-weight loads at the start of each trial. Indeed, infants recalibrated their judgments of risky slopes to their new, more precarious balance constraints. hey correctly t reated t he s ame deg rees of slope a s r isky wh ile wearing the lead-weight shoulder-packs but as safe while wearing the featherweight shoulder-packs. In both conditions, attempt rates were lowest for slopes farthest out on the tail of the afordance function and highest for slopes closest to the threshold. Recalibration t o t he w eights a ttests t o i mpressive t ransfer o f learning on several counts. he slopes were relatively novel—few of the infants had walked over steep slopes prior to participation. Carrying a l oad attached to the body w as novel—infants did not carry backpacks or purses. And, the loads decreased infants’ walking proiciency and required adjustments in gait patterns just to stay upright and move forward. In fact, walking with smaller loads (15% of body weight) over lat ground causes 14-month-olds to take smaller, slower steps, keep both feet on the ground for longer periods of time, and hold one foot in the air for shorter periods of time (Garciaguirre et al., 2007).
Case Study 3: Spanning Bridges One of the consequences of developmental changes in infants’ motor skills is that aspects of the environment can take on new functional signiicance. A handrail, for example, is a necessary support for balance and locomotion for cruising infants. Without the handrail (or edge of a piece of furniture), cruisers cannot move in an upright position. D uring t he c ruising per iod of de velopment, t he ha ndrail ha s the same functional status as the loor. Ater infants begin walking, however, a ha ndrail is unnecessary under normal conditions. Children and adults typically use handrails only to augment their natural abilities when they are tired or when the conditions are treacherous. he handrail becomes supplemental and functions as a tool.
Using a Handrail At 1 6 m onths o f a ge, m ost i nfants a re r elatively ex perienced ( 18 weeks, on average) and proicient walkers. On lat ground, they walk
304
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
unsupported, w ithout h olding a ha ndrail o r a c aregiver’s ha nd t o augment t heir ba lance. Only a f ew infants have experience using a handrail to climb and descend stairs (Berger, heuring, & A dolph, 2007). hus, a novel situation was devised where the use of a ha ndrail would be w arranted (Berger & A dolph, 2003). Wooden bridges of v arious w idths (12 c m t o 7 2 c m) spa nned a 7 6-cm-deep p recipice over a 74-cm-long gap. he bottom of the precipice was always clearly vi sible o n e ither s ide o f th e b ridge an d th e l ength o f th e bridge required infants to take several steps at a minimum in order to cross. On some trials, a wooden handrail was available for infants to hold on to, a nd on other t rials, t he ha ndrail was absent (Figure 9.10). Without the handrail, the narrowest bridges were impossible: Bridges w ere na rrower t han t he i nfants’ w idest d imensions a nd their dynamic base of support (infants walk with their legs splayed apart and their bodies oscillate from side to side). Walking sideways was not a n option because infants cannot keep ba lance while edging along sideways unsupported. Parents stood at the far side of the precipice ofering toys as a lure. An experimenter followed alongside infants to ensure their safety. As expected, infants perceived diferent possibilities for walking based on bridge width. More important, infants’ perception of afor-
Figure 9.10 Infant crossing an adjustable bridge. Caregivers (not shown) encouraged infants from the end of t he landing platform. An experimenter (shown) followed a longside i nfants to e nsure t heir s afety. Re printed f rom Developmental Psychology, 39(3), by S. E. Berger & K. E. Adolph, “Infants use handrails as tools in a locomotor task,” pp. 594–605, 2003, with permission from the American Psychological Association.
The Growing Body in Action
305
dances was also related to the presence of the handrail. Infants ran straight over the widest bridges, ignoring the handrail when it was available. However, on narrow 12- to 24 cm bridges, infants attempted to walk when the handrail was available and avoided walking when the handrail was removed. To use the handrails, infants turned their bodies sideways, and modiied t heir walking gait by inching a long with their trailing leg following in the footstep of their leading leg. Falling w as r are i n bo th ha ndrail co nditions: On ly 6 % o f i nfants’ attempts en ded i n a fa ll. A pparently, i nfants r ecognized t hat t he handrail ofered add itional pos sibilities f or u pright l ocomotion b y augmenting their balance on narrow bridges.
Wobbly and Wooden Handrails A follow-up study showed that experienced walking infants take the material substance of the handrail into account (Berger, Adolph, & Lobo, 2005). A pair of wobbly handrails was constructed from rubber a nd foam. W hen i nfants pressed t heir weight onto t he wobbly handrails, t he ha ndrails def ormed a nd s agged d ownward ( Figure 9.11). Parents standing on the far side of the landing platform encouraged their 16-month-old walking infants to cross 10- to 40-cm-wide
Figure 9.11 Infant testing a wobbly h andrail used for s upport. Caregivers (not shown) encouraged infants from the end of the landing platform. An experimenter (shown) fol lowed a longside i nfants to e nsure t heir s afety. Re printed f rom Child Development, 76, by S. E. Berger, K. E. Adolph, and S. A. Lobo, “Out of the toolbox: Toddlers d iferentiate wobbly a nd wooden handrails,” pp. 1294–1307, 2005, w ith permission from Blackwell Publishers.
306
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
bridges. A handrail was available on every trial. On some trials, the handrail was built of sturdy wood as in the earlier experiment, and on other trials, t he ha ndrail was wobbly rubber or foam. A ll t hree handrails looked solid. hus, to make the distinction between sturdy and wobbly handrails, infants needed to test the handrail before stepping out onto the bridge to determine whether it would give beneath their weight. On the widest bridges, infants walked straight across regardless of handrail type. But, on the 10- to 20-cm bridges, infants were more likely to walk when the handrail was built of sturdy wood than when it was wobbly. hus, infants d id not perceive t he ha ndrail as a support for augmenting ba lance merely bec ause it w as a su rface stretching from here to there. Rather the rigidity of the surface was an important source of information for afordances. Infants generated haptic information about the material substance of the handrail by pushing, tapping, squeezing, rubbing, and mouthing the surface before leaving the starting platform.
Learning in Development What do these case studies of infant locomotion tell us about perceptually guided action? As in research on afordances with adult participants (Kinsella-Shaw, Shaw, & Turvey, 1992; Mark, Jiang, King, & Paasche, 1999; Warren, 1984; Warren & Whang, 1987), the data from research with infants indicate that experienced observers can readily a nd ac curately de tect pos sibilities f or m otor ac tion. P erceiving whether it is possible to walk through an aperture, step over a gap, climb up a stair, walk over a slope, and so on requires that perceptual i nformation about t he environment (aperture w idth, gap size, stair height, slant) be related to perceptual information about the self (current body d imensions, level of balance control, and so on), and some so urces o f i nformation ma y s imultaneously spec ify r elevant aspects of both environment and self (e.g., optic low). Exploratory movements close the perception-action loop by providing information about what to do next based on information for afordances in the current moment (Joh et al., in press; Mark, Baillet, Craver, Douglas, & Fox, 1990). Visual information about upcoming obstacles can elicit m ore f ocused i nformation g athering abo ut pos sibilities f or locomotion through touch, postural sway, and testing various strategies (Adolph, Eppler, Marin, Weise, & Clearield, 2000).
The Growing Body in Action
307
Studies with infants tell us something new. he evidence indicates that the ability to detect afordances requires learning (e.g., Adolph, 2005; Ca mpos et a l., 2 000; E . J . Gibso n & P ick, 2 000). E xploiting the f ull r ange of pos sibilities for ac tion, a nd perhaps more i mportant, c urtailing i mpossible ac tions i n r isky s ituations, d oes n ot come automatically with the acquisition of balance and locomotion. Afordances (or lack o f t hem) t hat seem blatantly obvious to u s a s adults (“Don’t fall over the clif !”) are not obvious to newly mobile infants. Instead, perceptually guided action improves as infants gain experience with their newly acquired perception-action systems. Of course, i nfants beco me o lder a s t hey acq uire m ore ex perience, so that a ge-related a nd ex perience-related cha nges a re normally confounded. H owever, t he i ndependent e fects o f ag e a nd ex perience can be a ssessed st atistically a nd ex perimentally ( in l ongitudinal studies with experience held constant, and in cross-sectional studies with age held constant), and experience is the stronger predictor (for reviews, see Adolph, 1997; Adolph & Berger, 2006). A r elated iss ue co ncerns t he speci icity o f l earning. O ptimally, detecting afordances should be ma ximally lexible so t hat learning transfers to novel variations in both the body and environment. Flexibility is critical at every stage of life because local conditions are continually in lux. However, the infancy period provides an especially useful window into learning and transfer, given the rapid, large-scale developmental c hanges in inf ants’ b ody dim ensions, m otor p roiciency, and environments. Moreover, the acquisition of new postural control systems over t he irst t wo years of life a llows researchers to ask abo ut de velopmental co nstraints o n l earning, t hat i s, wh ether learning transfers from one perception-action system to another. he evidence points to broad transfer of learning within perception-action s ystems a nd na rrow spec iicity of learning between perception-action s ystems. E xperienced i nfants de tected n ovel afordances for sitting, crawling, cruising, and walking. hei r motor decisions r elected t he cha nging r elationship be tween body a nd environment. hey ad apted to v ariations i n en vironmental c onstraints (gap width, slope, bridge width, and so on), and to naturally occurring and experimentally induced changes in their body dimensions and skills (e.g., lead-weight shoulder packs). In contrast, novice infants showed poorly adapted motor decisions. he y attempted impossibly steep slopes and wide gaps and deep clifs, and appeared to ig nore i nformation abo ut t he l imits o f t heir p hysical ab ilities. Novices showed no evidence that learning transfers from an earlier
308
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
developing perception-action system to a later developing one. Over weeks of experience, infants’ motor decisions gradually honed in on the current constraints on action so t hat infants’ attempts matched the actual afordances for action. Experience w ith pa rticular t ypes of challenges (such as practice descending slopes) was not required. What infants needed was 10 to 20 weeks of everyday experience with balance and locomotion.
Learning Sets A candidate learning mechanism that could support lexible transfer within perception-action systems and speciicity across perception-action s ystems i s a l earning s et (Adolph, 2 002, 2 005; A dolph & E ppler, 2 002). he ter m w as irst coined by Ha rlow (1949, 1959; Harlow & Kuenne, 1949) to refer to a s et of exploratory procedures and st rategies t hat p rovide t he m eans f or g enerating so lutions t o novel problems of a pa rticular t ype. Acquiring t he ability to solve novel problems—or “ learning to learn,” a s Ha rlow put it—is more efective for a b roader r ange of situations t han learning pa rticular solutions for familiar problems (Stevenson, 1972). In fact, in a world of continually varying and novel afordances, learning simple facts, cue-consequence a ssociations, a nd s timulus ge neralizations wou ld be ma ladaptive. Yesterday’s fac ts a nd consequences may no longer hold. Features of the environment may be truly novel. With a learning set, the scope of transfer is limited only by the boundaries of the particular problem space. Learning sets have three important characteristics. First, learning sets support broad transfer of learning to novel problems. For example, in Harlow’s (1949, 1959) model system, adult monkeys learned to solve discrimination problems (e.g., ind which of two objects hides a raisin) or oddity problems (which of three objects hides a r aisin). Object features v aried f rom one t rial block t o t he next. W hen t he monkeys had acquired a learning set, they demonstrated perfect performance with pairs or trios of completely new shapes. hey could igure out i n one t rial wh ich object features were relevant for t hat trial block. For discrimination problems, they used a win-stay/loseshit r ule: I f t he irst object t hey ex plored co vered t he r aisin, t hey tracked that object over the trial block; if not, they tracked the other one. For oddity problems, they used an odd-man-out strategy: he
The Growing Body in Action
309
target ob ject d ifered f rom t he o ther t wo o n m ore features. A lbeit monkeys’ learning sets involved only simple strategies for operating within a tiny problem space, the learning sets represented something far more powerful than stimulus generalization. Monkeys were solving truly novel instances of a pa rticular type of problem. hey had acquired a means for coping with novelty. he second characteristic of learning sets is that transfer is limited t o t he s ize o f t he p roblem spac e. F or ex ample, m onkeys wh o had acquired a learning set for discrimination problems could solve new instances of discrimination problems on the irst presentation of a new pair of objects. However, experts at discrimination problems were no better than novices when challenged with oddity problems. Similarly, experts on oddity problems behaved like novices on discrimination problems. Discrimination and oddity problems each occupied a diferent problem space. he t hird cha racteristic o f l earning s ets i s t hat acq uisition i s extremely sl ow a nd d iicult. I t en tails r ecognition o f t he p roblem space (e.g., the pairs of objects in a discrimination problem), identiication of the relevant parameters for operating within it (object color or shape rather than spatial position), acquisition of the appropriate exploratory procedures for generating the requisite information (visual a nd ha ptic ob ject s earch), a nd abst raction o f g eneral st rategies t o so lve t he p roblem a t ha nd (win-stay/lose-shit strategy to track the food). Harlow’s monkeys required hundreds of trial blocks with d iferent i nstances o f t he pa rticular p roblem t ype p resented over multiple sessions—thousands of trials in total—to acquire a learning set for the small and circumscribed arena of discrimination problems or o ddity proble ms. A t irst, m onkeys s earched ha phazardly or searched under objects in a particular position. hey had to unlearn o verly na rrow st rategies for s earching w ith t he pa rticular pair of objects i n t he c urrent t rial block (e.g., g reen c ylinders h ide raisins), before abstracting general strategies that would enable them to ind the raisin with novel objects in the next trial block. How might the learning set framework be a pplied to perceptual guidance of action? On the learning set account, each new postural control system that arises in the course of motor development operates as a distinct problem space. Compared with the simple discrimination and oddity problems in Harlow’s model system, the problem space for postural control is extremely broad. he range of problems is en ormous. E very m ovement o n e very su rface co nstitutes a d if-
310
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
ferent problem for post ural control. Every cha nge i n i nfants’ body growth and skill level creates diferent biomechanical constraints on balance and locomotion. Whereas Harlow’s monkeys required thousands of trials in a daily regimen to acquire learning sets for simple discrimination and oddity problems, human infants might require hundreds of t housands or m illions of “ trials” ove r m any we eks or months—epochs of experience—to acquire a learning set for coping with balance and locomotion. Flexibility o f l earning a rises a s i nfants beg in t o co nsolidate a learning set. Experience using a newly developed perception-action system provides infants with the necessary repertoire of exploratory procedures a nd st rategies f or so lving p roblems o n-line. I nformation-generating behaviors provide the basis for identifying the critical parameters for the particular problem space and for calibrating the settings of those parameters under changing conditions. Exploratory movements generate the requisite information about the current st atus of t he body r elative to t he environment a nd v ice versa: visual exploration as infants notice the obstacle, swaying movements as t hey ma ke t heir approach, haptic ex ploration a s t hey probe t he obstacle with a l imb, and means-ends exploration as they test various alternatives (Adolph & Eppler, 2002; Adolph et al., 2000; Adolph & Joh, in press). hus, within the boundaries of each problem space, infants can cope with novel and variable changes in afordances for action. Speciicity o f l earning em erges bec ause d iferent perceptionaction s ystems a re deined b y d iferent s ets o f c ritical pa rameters. Sitting, c rawling, c ruising, a nd w alking, f or ex ample, i nvolve d ifferent parameters for maintaining balance: diferent regions of permissible post ural s way, muscle g roups for ba lance a nd propulsion, vantage points for viewing the ground, sources of perceptual information abo ut t he body ’s m ovements, co rrelations be tween v isual and v estibular i nput, a nd so o n. B ecause e ach p roblem spac e ha s unique parameters, learning does not transfer between perceptionaction s ystems. W hat i nfants l earn abo ut ba lance a nd l ocomotion in a c rawling posture, for instance, does not help them to solve the problem o f ba lance a nd l ocomotion i n a n ewly acq uired w alking posture.
The Growing Body in Action
311
Everyday Experience A q uestion t hat ari ses a bout l earning m echanisms t hat r equire particular t ypes of practice is whether t he actual opportunities for learning a re co nsistent w ith t he p urported r egimen: A re l earning sets p lausible? I n t his c ase, i nfants w ould n eed i mmense a mounts of practice with varied instances of each problem type to acquire a learning set for each perception-action system. he available laboratory d ata support such a p roposition. For example, a ter six weeks of everyday experience with balance and locomotion, infants avoid a drop-of on the deep side of the visual clif and a 90-cm-gap; ater 15 w eeks o f ex perience, t hey ma tch t heir m otor dec isions t o t he physical d imensions o f t he d rop-of ( Adolph, 2 000; B ertenthal e t al., 1984). Infants require 10 weeks of locomotor experience before errors dec rease to 5 0% on r isky slopes a nd 2 0 weeks before er rors decrease to 10% (Adolph, 1997). More convincing evidence that everyday experience could support infants’ acquisition of learning sets is provided by naturalistic d ata ob tained f rom d aily ch ecklist d iaries, “ step-counters” i n infants’ shoes, and video recordings of infants crawling and walking in everyday environments (Adolph, 2002; Adolph, Robinson, Young, & Gill-Alvarez, in press; Chan, Biancaniello, Adolph, & Marin, 2000; Chan, L u, Ma rin, & A dolph, 1 999; G arciaguirre & A dolph, 2 006; Robinson, A dolph, & Y oung, 2 004). I n fac t, i f r esearchers co uld design a p ractice r egimen m ost co nducive t o acq uiring a l earning set, i t w ould r esemble i nfants’ e veryday ex periences w ith ba lance and locomotion. Infants’ locomotor experience is immense—on the order of practice r egimens u sed b y O lympic a thletes a nd co ncert p ianists t o achieve expert performance, rather than the experimental training sessions administered to monkeys in Harlow’s original studies. In 15 minutes of f ree play, for ex ample, t he average 14-month-old w alking i nfant t akes 550 steps , t raveling ha lf t he d istance up t he E ifel Tower (Garciaguirre & A dolph, 2 006). I n t he co urse o f a d ay, t he average toddler takes more than 13,000 steps, traveling the length of 39 American football ields. Crawling experience is less intense, but equally remarkable. At t he end of t he d ay, t he average crawler ha s taken more than 3,000 steps (Adolph, 2002). Practice w ith b alance an d l ocomotion i s di stributed o ver tim e, rather than massed, so that infants have time to recover from fatigue,
312
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
renew their motivation to continue, and consolidate what they have learned. Infants must work to keep their bodies in balance during all o f t heir w aking h ours. H owever, t hey a re ac tually o n t he loor engaged in stance or locomotion for only 5 t o 6 h ours per d ay, and most of that time (approximately 80%), they are in stance (Adolph, 2002; G arciaguirre & A dolph, 2 006). hus, l ocomotion oc curs i n short, l ittle bouts of ac tivity, i nterspersed w ith longer rest per iods. Practice i s a lso d istributed ac ross d ays. On so me d ays, i nfants s it, crawl, cruise, or walk, but on other days, they do not (Adolph, Robinson e t a l., 2 007; R obinson e t a l., i n p ress). Di stributed p ractice across days is most noticeable when infants are irst acquiring a new perception-action system. Falling is commonplace. Toddlers fall, on average, 15 times per hour ( Garciaguirre & A dolph, 2 006). M ost fa lls a re n ot s erious enough to make infants cry or to warrant parents’ attention. Surprisingly, infants fall most frequently due to unexpected shits i n their center of mass; they lit t heir a rm or t urn t heir head a nd t ip over. Although i nfants t rip a nd sl ip wh en t he el evation a nd f riction o f the ground surface is variable, most indoor loor coverings are uniform in elevation and provide suicient traction. hus, like Harlow’s monkeys who learned to ignore local contingencies between object features i n a pa rticular t rial block, i nfants may learn to ig nore t he color and visual texture of loor coverings, and focus on changes in elevation and layout that specify varying afordances. Finally, infants’ practice is variable, rather than blocked, so that infants experience balance and locomotion in various physical and social contexts, typically changing ater a few minutes or so. Infants travel through all of the open rooms in their homes, averaging 6 to 12 diferent ground surfaces per day (Adolph, 2002; Chan, Biancaniello et al., 2000; Chan, Lu et al., 1999). Of course, the size of infants’ homes, t heir la yout, t he f urniture a nd loor co verings, a nd so o n, vary t remendously ac ross i nfants a nd g eographic r egions. I nfants reared in Manhattan, for example, are unlikely to have regular access to stairs, and unlikely to crawl and walk over grass, sand, and concrete (Berger et al., 2007). Infants reared in the suburbs have regular exposure to all of those surfaces. In sum, infants’ everyday locomotor ex periences resemble a t ype of practice regimen t hat would be highly conducive to acquiring a l earning set: immense a mounts of variable a nd d istributed p ractice ( Gentile, 2 000; S chmidt & L ee, 1999).
The Growing Body in Action
313
After Infancy? Walking is not the endpoint in locomotor development. Ater infancy, children and adults continue to master new locomotor skills. Unfortunately, developmental research on perceptually guided locomotion is largely limited to infancy, and research with adults has focused on skills acquired during infancy that involve sitting and upright locomotion (e.g., Mark et al., 1990; e.g., Warren, 1984; Warren & Whang, 1987). hus, the developmental story of perceiving afordances ater the infancy period is largely speculative. Most forms of locomotion acquired ater i nfancy a re l ikely t o be o utgrowths o f t he per ception-action s ystems acq uired d uring infancy. Like toddlers’ use of a handrail for crossing bridges, specialized skills such as ice skating, skiing, surf boarding, and dancing on pointe are likely to represent enlargement of the problem space for upright locomotion. L ike st anding a nd walking, t he ke y pivots for maintaining balance are at the ankles and hips. Driving and kayaking may be en largements of t he problem spac e for s itting; t he ke y pivot is at the hips. Rock-climbing may be an outgrowth of crawling because the body is supported over all four limbs. Some specialized skills, however, may constitute new perceptionaction systems, as diferent from the skills acquired during infancy as crawling is from walking. Skills such as brachiating hand-overhand along monkey bars, bicycling, and swimming require special environments (water), opportunities (access to water), devices (bicycles, monkey bars), and social supports (supportive parents and peer models) f or acq uisition a nd per formance. L ike t he post ural m ilestones in infant development, bicycling, swimming, and brachiating involve n ew c ritical pa rameters f or co ntrolling ba lance a nd l ocomotion: new regions of permissible postural sway, key pivots about which the body r otates, sources of perceptual information, vantage points for viewing the support surface, and so on. As w ith inf ants’ p ostural mi lestones, lexibility i s i mperative for per ception-action s ystems acq uired la ter i n l ife. Ch ildren a nd adults m ust ad apt ac tions t o t he cha nging a fordances ofered by variations i n t he environment a nd i n t heir own bod ies a nd sk ills; motor decisions should take penalties for error into account. hus, specialized sk ills ma y r equire acq uisition o f n ew l earning s ets f or each new problem space. Ten- to 12-year-old children, for example, showed evidence of lexible m otor dec isions f or b icycling t hrough
314
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
traic in tersections in an imm ersive, in teractive, v irtual e nvironment (Plumert, Kearney, & Cremer, 2004). While seated on stationary bikes, ch ildren v aried t he l ikelihood of c rossing t he simulated road and adjusted their rate of pedaling in accordance with the time gaps presented by faster and slower moving “cars.” Despite i mportant s imilarities, t he per ception-action s ystems acquired d uring i nfancy a nd t hose acq uired la ter i n l ife ha ve t wo important diferences. First, age-related changes in cognition, motivation, and social skills may afect motor decisions about afordances. Infants, for example, are not embarrassed to fall, but older children and adults may be. Infants may not explicitly consider consequences, but older ch ildren a nd adults do. I nfants c annot u se ex plicit r ules (e.g., “ look bo th w ays bef ore c rossing t he st reet”), b ut o lder ch ildren a nd ad ults c an. M oreover, ch ildren a nd ad ults ha ve y ears o f experience ma king m otor dec isions f or t he per ception-action s ystems ac quired d uring i nfancy. P ossibly, per ception-action s ystems acquired later in life can bootstrap from earlier acquired systems by incorporating heuristic strategies and general information generating behaviors. A second important diference is that infants’ perception-action systems are acquired under intense practice regimens. Infants practice sitting, crawling, and walking, for example, during most of their waking hours. Practice is variable (hundreds of “trials” keeping balance on diferent su pport su rfaces i n d iferent physical a nd social contexts) a nd distributed (short bouts of activity interspersed w ith rest periods), gearing infants for broad transfer of learning. In contrast, bec ause t he spec ialized sk ills acq uired a ter i nfancy r equire special opportunities for performance, children accumulate smaller quantities of experience under more limited practice schedules.
Conclusions I conclude where I began, with how infant locomotion speaks to the larger l iterature o n per ception-action co upling. S tudies o f i nfant locomotion raise several issues that any theory of perceptually guided action should address. First, motor decisions must be geared to afordances. For motor action to be adaptive, it must take the constraints and propensities of the body and the environment into account. Second, the central problem in detecting and exploiting afordances for
The Growing Body in Action
315
action is the means for coping with novelty and variability. Because the body and environment are always changing, behavioral lexibility is paramount. hird, human infants must learn to cope with novelty and variability. Infants develop new motor abilities before they use their abilities adaptively. With suicient experience, infants’ motor decisions a re as accurate as t hose of adults. Fourth, situations t hat call for immense behavioral lexibility require a learning mechanism that supports extremely broad transfer. Learning sets are a likely candidate for such a mechanism. What infants learn when they acquire a learning set are exploratory procedures and strategies for on-line problem solving. As Harlow put it, they are learning to learn. Finally, learning i s a lways n ested i n t he co ntext o f de velopmental cha nge. Changes in infants’ bodies, sk ills, and environments are rapid and dramatic, but changing afordances are not limited to infancy, and learning surely does not cease ater a few months of walking experience. Animals of every age continually learn new ways of detecting possibilities for ac tion at t he same t ime t hat t hose possibilities a re changing.
References Adolph, K . E . (1995). A ps ychophysical a ssessment of to ddlers’ a bility to cope with slopes. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 21, 734–750. Adolph, K . E . (1997). L earning i n t he development of i nfant locomotion. Monographs of th e S ociety fo r Re search in C hild D evelopment, 62(3, Serial No. 251). Adolph, K. E. (2000). Speciicity of learning: Why infants fall over a v eritable clif. Psychological Science, 11, 290–295. Adolph, K. E. (2002). Learning to keep balance. In R. Kail (Ed.), Advances in chil d d evelopment an d be havior (Vol. 3 0, pp. 1–30). A msterdam: Elsevier Science. Adolph, K . E . (2005). L earning to le arn i n t he de velopment of ac tion. I n J. Lockman & J. Rei ser (Eds.), Action as an organizer of learning and development: he 32nd Minnesota Symposium on Child Development (pp. 91–122). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Adolph, K. E., & Avolio, A. M. (2000). Walking infants adapt locomotion to c hanging b ody d imensions. Journal of E xperimental P sychology: Human Perception and Performance, 26, 1148–1166.
316
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Adolph, K . E ., & B erger, S . E . ( 2005). P hysical a nd m otor de velopment. In M. H. Bornstein & M. E. Lamb (Eds.), Developmental science: An advanced textbook (5th ed., pp. 223–281). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Adolph, K. E ., & B erger, S. E . (2006). Motor development. In D. Kuhn & R. S. Siegler (Eds.), Handbook of chil d psychology: Vo l. 2 . Cognition, perception, and language (6th ed., pp. 161–213). New York: Wiley. Adolph, K. E., & Eppler, M. A. (2002). Flexibility and speciicity in infant motor skill acquisition. In J. W. Fagen & H. Hayne (Eds.), Progress in infancy research (Vol. 2, pp. 121–167). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Adolph, K. E ., Eppler, M. A., & Gibs on, E . J. (1993). Development of perception of afordances. In C. K. Rovee-Collier & L . P. Lipsitt (Eds.), Advances in infanc y r esearch (V ol. 8 , pp . 5 1–98). N orwood, N J: Ablex. Adolph, K . E ., Eppler, M. A ., Ma rin, L ., Weise, I. B., & C learield, M. W. (2000). E xploration i n t he s ervice o f p rospective c ontrol. Infant Behavior and Development, 23, 441–460. Adolph, K . E ., & J oh, A . S . (in p ress). M ultiple le arning m echanisms i n the de velopment of ac tion. I n A . Woodward & A . Needham (Eds.), Learning and the infant mind. New York: Oxford University Press. Adolph, K. E., Joh, A. S., Ishak, S., Lobo, S. A., & Berger, S. E. (2005, October). Speciicity of infants’ k nowledge for action. Paper presented at the Cognitive Development Society, San Diego, CA. Adolph, K. E., Robinson, S. R., Young, J. W., & Gi ll-Alvarez, F. (in press). What is the shape of developmental change? Psychological Review. Adolph, K . E ., Vereijken, B ., & Den ny, M . A . (1998). L earning to c rawl. Child Development, 69, 1299–1312. Adolph, K. E., Vereijken, B., & Shrout, P. E. (2003). What changes in infant walking and why. Child Development, 74, 474–497. Berger, S . E ., & A dolph, K . E . (2003). I nfants u se ha ndrails a s to ols i n a locomotor task. Developmental Psychology, 39, 594–605. Berger, S. E., Adolph, K. E., & Lobo, S. A. (2005). Out of the toolbox: Toddlers diferentiate wobbly and wooden handrails. Child Development, 76, 1294–1307. Berger, S. E., heuring, C. F., & Adolph, K. E. (2007). How and when infants learn to climb stairs. Infant Behavior and Development, 30, 36–49. Bernstein, N. (1996). On dexterity and its development. In M. L. Latash & M. T. Turvey (Eds.), Dexterity and its development (pp. 3–244). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Bertenthal, B. I., Campos, J. J., & Barrett, K. C. (1984). Self-produced locomotion: A n or ganizer of e motional, c ognitive, a nd s ocial d evelopment in infancy. In R. N. Emde & R. J. Harmon (Eds.), Continuities and discontinuities in development (pp. 175–210). New York: Plenum Press.
The Growing Body in Action
317
Bertenthal, B. I., & Cliton, R. K. (1998). Perception and action. In D. Kuhn & R. S. Siegler (Eds.), Handbook of child psychology: Vol. 2. Cognition, perception, and language (5th ed., pp. 51–102). New York: Wiley. Bly, L . (1994). Motor s kill a cquisition in th e irst year. S an A ntonio, T X: herapy Skill Builders. Bril, B., & Breniere, Y. (1992). Postural requirements and progression velocity in young walkers. Journal of Motor Behavior, 24, 105–116. Bril, B., & L edebt, A. (1998). Head coordination as a m eans to a ssist sensory integration in learning to walk. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 22, 555–563. Campos, J. J., Anderson, D. I., Barbu-Roth, M. A., Hubbard, E. M., Hertenstein, M. J., & Witherington, D. C. (2000). Travel broadens the mind. Infancy, 1, 149–219. Campos, J. J., H iatt, S ., R amsay, D., Henderson, C ., & S vejda, M . (1978). he emergence of fear on the visual clif. In M. Lewis & L. Rosenblum (Eds.), he development of afect (pp. 149–182). New York: Plenum. Chan, M . Y ., Bi ancaniello, R ., A dolph, K . E ., & Ma rin, L . ( 2000, J uly). Tracking infant s’ l ocomotor e xperience: he te lephone di ary. P oster presented to t he International Conference on Infant Studies, Brighton, England. Chan, M. Y., Lu, Y., Marin, L., & Adolph, K. E. (1999). A baby’s day: Capturing crawling experience. In M. A. Grealy & J. A. homp son (Eds.), Studies in pe rception and a ction (Vol. 5, pp. 245–249). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body, and world together again. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. de Vries, J. I. P., Visser, G. H. A., & Prechtl, H. F. R. (1982). he emergence of fetal behaviour. I. Qualitative aspects. Early Human Development, 7, 301–322. Eppler, M . A ., S atterwhite, T ., W endt, J., & B ruce, K . ( 1997). I nfants’ responses to a v isual c lif a nd o ther g round su rfaces. I n M . A . Schmuckler & J. M. Kennedy (Eds.), Studies in perception and action (Vol. 4, pp. 219–222). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Franchak, J. M ., & A dolph, K . E . (2007, Ma y). Perceiving ch anging a fordances for action: Pregnant women walking through doorways. Paper presented a t t he M eeting o f t he Vi sion S ciences S ociety, S arasota, FL. Frankenburg, W. K ., & Do dds, J. B . (1967). he Denver Developmental Screening Test. Journal of Pediatrics, 71, 181–191. Freedland, R . L ., & B ertenthal, B . I . ( 1994). De velopmental c hanges i n interlimb c oordination: T ransition to ha nds-and-knees c rawling. Psychological Science, 5, 26–32.
318
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Garciaguirre, J. S., & Adolph, K. E. (2006, June). Infants’ everyday locomotor e xperience: A w alking an d fa lling m arathon. Pap er p resented to the International Conference on Infant Studies, Kyoto, Japan. Garciaguirre, J. S ., A dolph, K . E ., & Sh rout, P. E . (2007). B aby c arriage: Infants walking with loads. Child Development, 78, 664–680. Gentile, A. M. (2000). Skill acquisition: Action, movement, and neuromotor processes. In J. Carr & R. Shepard (Eds.), Movement science: Foundations fo r physical th erapy in r ehabilitation (2nd ed., pp. 111–187). New York: Aspen Press. Gibson, E. J. (1982). he concept of afordances in development: he renascence of functionalism. In W. A. Collins (Ed.), he concept of development: he M innesota s ymposia on chil d ps ychology (Vol. 1 5, pp . 55–81). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Gibson, E. J. (1987). Introductory essay: What does infant perception tell us about theories of perception? Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception & Performance, 13, 515–523. Gibson, E . J. ( 1991). An od yssey i n l earning and pe rception. C ambridge, MA: MIT Press. Gibson, E . J., & P ick, A . D. (2000). An ecological approach to perceptual learning and development. New York: Oxford University Press. Gibson, E. J., & Walk, R. D. (1960). he “visual clif.” Scientiic American, 202, 64–71. Gibson, J. J. ( 1979). he ecol ogical appr oach t o v isual pe rception. B oston: Houghton Milin. Harlow, H. F. (1949). he formation of learning sets. Psychological Review, 56, 51–65. Harlow, H . F . ( 1959). L earning s et a nd er ror f actor t heory. I n S . K och (Ed.), Psychology: A s tudy of a sc ience ( pp. 4 92–533). N ew Y ork: McGraw-Hill. Harlow, H. F., & Kuenne, M. (1949). Learning to think. Scientiic American, 181, 3–6. Joh, A . S ., A dolph, K . E ., N arayanan, P. J., & D ietz, V. A . (2007). G auging p ossibilities f or ac tion ba sed o n f riction u nderfoot. Journal of Experimental P sychology: H uman P erception an d P erformance, 3 3, 1145–1157. Johnson, M. L ., Veldhuis, J. D ., & L ampl, M. (1996). Is g rowth saltatory? he usefulness and limitations of frequency distributions in analyzing pulsatile data. Endocrinology, 137, 5197–5204. Kinsella-Shaw, J. M ., Shaw, R ., & Turvey, M. T. (1992). Perceiving “walkon-able” slopes. Ecological Psychology, 4, 223–239. Lampl, M . (1992). Fu rther obs ervations on d iurnal v ariation i n standing height. Annals of Human Biology, 19, 87–90. Lampl, M. (1993). Evidence of saltatory growth in infancy. American Journal of Human Biology, 5, 641–652.
The Growing Body in Action
319
Lampl, M., Ashizawa, K., Kawabata, M., & Johnson, M. L. (1998). An example of variation and pattern in saltation and stasis growth dynamics. Annals of Human Biology, 25, 203–219. Lampl, M ., & J eanty, P. (2003). T iming i s e verything: A re consideration of fetal growth velocity patterns identiies th e i mportance o f i ndividual a nd sex diferences. American Journal of H uman Biology, 15, 667–680. Lampl, M., & J ohnson, M. L. (1993). A c ase study in daily growth during adolescence: A si ngle spurt or changes i n t he dy namics of saltatory growth? Annals of Human Biology, 20, 595–603. Lampl, M., Johnson, M. L ., & F rongillo, E . A. (2001). Mixed d istribution analysis identiies saltation and stasis growth. Annals of Human Biology, 28, 403–411. Lampl, M., Veldhuis, J. D., & Johnson, M. L. (1992). Saltation and stasis: A model of human growth. Science, 258, 801–803. Leo, A. J., C hiu, J., & A dolph, K. E. (2000, July). Temporal and functional relationships of c rawling, c ruising, an d w alking. P oster p resented a t the International Conference on Infant Studies, Brighton, UK. Lockman, J. J. ( 1984). he de velopment of de tour a bility during i nfancy. Child Development, 55, 482–491. Lockman, J. J., & Adams, C. D. (2001). Going around transparent and gridlike barriers: Detour ability as a perception-action skill. Developmental Science, 4, 463–471. Mark, L . S ., Baillet, J. A ., Cr aver, K . D., Douglas, S . D., & F ox, T. (1990). What an actor must do in order to perceive the afordance for sitting. Ecological Psychology, 2, 325–366. Mark, L. S., Jiang, Y., King, S. S., & Paasche, J. (1999). he impact of visual exploration o n j udgments o f w hether a gap i s c rossable. Journal of Experimental P sychology: H uman P erception an d P erformance, 25 , 287–295. Mondschein, E . R ., Adolph, K. E ., & Tamis-LeMonda, C . S. (2000). Gender b ias i n m others’ e xpectations a bout i nfant c rawling. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 77, 304–316. Moore, K. L., & Persaud, T. V. N. (1998). he developing human: Clinically oriented embryology (6th ed.). Philadelphia: W. B. Saunders. Noonan, K. J., Farnum, C. E., Leiferman, E. M., Lampl, M., Markel, M. D., & Wi lsman, N. J. ( 2004). Growing pa ins: A re t hey due to i ncreased growth during recumbency as documented in a lamb model? Journal of Pediatric Orthopedics, 24, 726–731. Ounsted, M ., & M oar, V. A . (1986). P roportionality c hanges i n t he irst year of life: he inluence of weight for gestational age at birth. Acta Paediatrica Scandinavia, 75, 811–818. Palmer, C . E . (1944). St udies of t he center of g ravity i n t he human body. Child Development, 15, 99–163.
320
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Palmer, C. F. (1987, April). Between a rock and a hard place: Babies in tight spaces. Poster presented at the meeting of the Society for Research in Child Development, Baltimore, MD. Plumert, J. M., Kearney, J. K., & Cremer, J. F. (2004). Children’s perception of gap a fordances: Bicycling ac ross t raic-i lled intersections in an immersive virtual environment. Child Development, 75, 1243–1253. Rader, N., B ausano, M ., & R ichards, J. E . ( 1980). O n t he na ture o f t he visual-clif-avoidance r esponse in h uman inf ants. Child De velopment, 51, 61–68. Reed, E. S. (1989). Changing theories of postural development. In M. H. Woollacott & A. Shumway-Cook (Eds.), Development of posture and gait across the lifespan (pp. 3–24). Columbia, SC: University of South Carolina Press. Richards, J. E., & Rader, N. (1981). Crawling-onset age predicts visual clif avoidance in inf ants. Journal of E xperimental P sychology: H uman Perception and Performance, 7, 382–387. Richards, J. E ., & R ader, N. ( 1983). A fective, b ehavioral, a nd a voidance responses on t he v isual clif: Efects of crawling onset age, crawling experience, and testing age. Psychophysiology, 20, 633–642. Robinson, S. R., Adolph, K. E., & Young, J. W. (2004, May). Continuity vs. discontinuity: H ow diferent ti me scal es o f beha vioral mea surement afect th e pat tern of d evelopmental ch ange. P oster p resented a t t he meeting of the International Conference on Infant Studies, Chicago, IL. Robinson, S. R., & Kleven, G. A. (2005). Learning to move before birth. In B. Hopkins & S. Johnson (Eds.), Advances in infancy research: Vol. 2. Prenatal development of postnatal functions (pp. 131–175). Westport, CT: Praeger. Schmidt, R. A., & L ee, T. D. (1999). Motor control and learning: A be havioral emphasis (3rd ed.). Champaign, IL: Human Kinetics. Stevenson, H. W. (1972). Children’s learning. New York: Appleton-CenturyCrots. helen, E ., & F isher, D . M . (1983). he or ganization of s pontaneous le g movements i n ne wborn i nfants. Journal of M otor B ehavior, 1 5, 353–377. Titzer, R . ( 1995, Ma rch). he d evelopmental d ynamics of un derstanding transparency. Pap er p resented a t t he m eeting o f t he S ociety f or Research in Child Development, Indianapolis, IN. Vereijken, B ., & A dolph, K . E . (1999). Transitions i n t he de velopment o f locomotion. In G. J. P. Savelsbergh, H. L. J. van der Ma as, & P. C. L. van Geert (Eds.), Non-linear analyses of developmental processes (pp. 137–149). Amsterdam: Elsevier.
The Growing Body in Action
321
Vereijken, B., & Waardenburg, M. (1996, April). Changing patterns of interlimb coo rdination f rom su pported t o i ndependent w alking. Poster presented at t he meeting of t he I nternational C onference on I nfant Studies, Providence, RI. Walk, R. D., & Gibson, E. J. (1961). A comparative and analytical study of visual depth perception. Psychological Monographs, 75(15, Whole No. 519). Walk, R. D., Gibson, E. J., & Tighe, T. J. (1957). Behavior of light- and darkreared rats on a visual clif. Science, 126, 80–81. Warren, W . H . ( 1984). P erceiving a fordances: Vi sual g uidance of s tair climbing. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 10, 683–703. Warren, W. H., & W hang, S. (1987). Visual guidance of walking through apertures: Body-scaled information for afordances. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 13, 371–383. Witherington, D. C ., C ampos, J. J., A nderson, D. I., L ejeune, L ., & S eah, E. (2005). Avoidance of heig hts on t he v isual clif i n newly walking infants. Infancy, 7, 3.
10 Motor Knowledge and Action Understanding A Developmental Perspective
Bennett I. Bertenthal and Matthew R. Longo
he prediction of where and how people are going to move has obvious relevance for social interaction. As adults, we are extremely adept at predicting at least some of t hese behaviors automatically i n real time. If, for example, we observe someone reaching in the direction of a half-illed glass on a table, we can predict with relative certainty that the reaching action is directed toward the glass. Oten, we can also predict if the actor intends to drink from the glass or intends to remove t he glass depending on t he state of t he actor as well as t he context surrounding the action. How d o w e de tect t he g oals, i ntentions, a nd st ates o f o thers so rapidly w ith l ittle i f a ny a wareness o f t hese i mplicit i nferences? According to a g rowing number of social neuroscientists, there are specialized mechanisms in the brain for understanding actions and responding to them. Evidence from neuroimaging studies and neuropsychological studies of normal and brain damaged patients ofer considerable support for t his cla im (Decety & S ommerville, 2 004; Frith & F rith, 2 006; Gr èzes, F rith, & P assingham, 2 004; Pelphrey, Morris, McCarthy, 2005; Saxe, Xiao, Kovacs, Perrett, & K anwisher, 2004). he a vailability o f spec ialized p rocesses su ggests t hat t he brain may be i ntrinsically prepared for this information and, thus, that action understanding should be evident early in development. 323
324
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Indeed, ev en n eonates s how ev idence o f r esponding t o h uman behaviors, such as speech, gaze, and touch (Lacerda, von Hofsten, & Heimann, 2001; von Hofsten, 2003). It is not entirely clear, however, that these responses are contingent on perceived actions as opposed to movements. In order to avoid unnecessary confusion, it behooves us t o beg in b y d istinguishing be tween m ovements a nd ac tions. Human actions a re comprised of a b road range of limb, head, a nd facial movements, but not all body movements are actions. We reserve this latter description for goal-directed movements. hese are movements that are planned relative to an intrinsic or extrinsic goal prior to their execution. For example, a prototypical goal-directed action might i nvolve ex tending a n a rm to g rasp a ba ll resting on a t able. By contrast, waving an arm and accidentally hitting a ba ll does not represent an action. Recent indings suggest that infants understand the g oal-directed na ture o f ac tions b y t he s econd ha lf o f t he irst year a nd per haps e ven e arlier (e.g., C sibra, G ergely, B iro, K oos, & Brockbank, 1999; Kiraly, Jovanovic, Prinz, Aschersleben, & Gergely, 2003; Luo & Ba illargeon, 2002; Woodward, 1998; 1999; Woodward & Sommerville, 2000).
Two Modes for Understanding Actions What are the mechanisms that underlie action understanding? By action understanding, we mean the capacity to achieve an internal description or representation of a per ceived ac tion a nd to use it to organize a nd p redict a ppropriate f uture beha vior. Rec ent n europhysiologically motivated theories (Jeannerod, 1997, 2001; Rizzolatti, Fogassi, & Gallese, 2001) suggest that there are two mechanisms that might explain how action understanding occurs. he more conventional mechanism involves some form of visual analysis followed by categorization and inference. his type of analysis can be thought of as progressing through stages of processing comparable to those proposed by Marr (1982). hese processes are mediated via the ventral visual pathway of the brain and are independent of the motor system. For ex ample, when we obs erve a ha nd g rasping a g lass, t he v isual system parses this scene into an object (i.e., the glass) and a moving hand that eventually contacts and grasps the glass. his visual input is recognized and associated with other information about the glass and the actor in order to understand the observed action.
Motor Knowledge and Action Understanding
325
Whereas this irst mechanism applies to all visual information, the second mechanism is unique to the processing of actions (and, perhaps, ob ject a fordances) a nd ha s be en r eferred t o a s a direct matching or observation-execution m atching system (Rizzolatti et al., 2001). With this mechanism, visual representations of observed actions are mapped directly onto our motor representation of the same action; an action is understood when its observation leads to simulation (i.e., representing the responses of others by covertly generating similar subthreshold responses in oneself) by the motor system. hus, when we observe a ha nd grasping a g lass, the same neural ci rcuit t hat p lans o r ex ecutes t his g oal-directed a ction becomes active in the observer’s motor areas (Blakemore & Decety, 2001; Iacobo ni, M olnar-Szakacs, G allese, B uccino, Ma zziotta, & Rizzolatti, 2005; Rizzolatti et al., 2001). It is the “motor knowledge” of the observer that is used to understand the observed goaldirected a ction v ia c overt i mitation. For t his re ason, k nowledge of the action will depend in part on the observer’s speciic motor experience with the same action (Calvo-Merino, Glaser, Grèzes, Passingham, & Ha ggard, 2005; Longo, Kosobud, & B ertenthal, in press). In co ntrast t o t he irst v isual m echanism, t he low of information b etween p erception an d a ction b y dir ect m atching e nables more than an appreciation of the surface properties of the perceived actions. Simulation enables an appreciation of the means (i.e., how the body parts are arranged to move) by which the action is executed as well as an appreciation of the goal or the efects of the action. his implies that the observer is able to covertly imitate as well as predict the outcome of an observed action.
Simulation of Actions Although this latter hypothesis for explaining how we understand actions d ates back t o t he i deomotor t heory o f J ames ( 1890) a nd Greenwald (1970), direct evidence supporting this view emerged only r ecently w ith t he d iscovery o f m irror n eurons i n t he v entral premotor c ortex of t he mon key’s br ain. he se neurons discharge when the monkey performs a goal-directed action as well as when the monkey observes a human or conspeciic perform the same or a similar action (Gallese, Fadiga, Fogassi, & Rizzolatti, 1996; Rizzolatti,
326
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Fadiga, G allese, & F ogassi, 1 996). hus, t hese n eurons p rovide a common internal representation for executing and observing goaldirected action. More recently, mirror neurons were also observed in the inferior parietal lobule which shares direct connections with the premotor cortex (Fogassi et al., 2005). his latter inding is important for explaining how visually perceived face and body movements are represented by mirror neurons in the premotor cortex. hese movements a re coded b y t he superior tem poral su lcus, wh ich d oes n ot p roject d irectly t o t he m irror n eurons i n t he v entral p remotor co rtex. I nstead, t he su perior temporal sulcus projects to the inferior parietal lobule which is connected to the ventral premotor cortex (Rizzolatti & Cr aighero, 2004). hus, mirror neurons are innervated by a fronto-parietal circuit in the motor system that also receives visual inputs from the superior temporal su lcus. Human neuroimaging a nd t ranscranial magnetic st imulation st udies have shown ac tivation of a h omologous fronto-parietal circuit during both the observation as well as the imitation of actions (Brass, Zysset, & v on Cramon, 2001; Buccino e t a l., 2 001; Dec ety, Cha minade, Gr èzes, & M eltzof, 2002; Fadiga, Fogassi, Pavesi, & R izzolatti, 1995; Grèzes, Armony, Rowe, & Passingham, 2003; Iacoboni, Woods et al., 1999; Koski, Iacoboni, Dubeau, Woods, & Ma zziotta, 2003; for a r eview, see R izzolatti & Craighero, 2004). his ne urophysiological e vidence i s c omplemented by re cent behavioral evidence showing that the observation of actions facilitates o r p rimes r esponses i nvolving s imilar ac tions. F or ex ample, visuomotor priming is observed when grasping a bar in a horizontal or vertical orientation is preceded by a picture of a hand or the observation of an action congruent with the required response (Castiello, Lusher, Mari, Edwards, & Humphreys, 2002; Edwards, Humphreys, & Castiello, 2003; Vogt, Taylor, & Hopkins, 2003). Similarly, response facilitation is observed when the task involves responding to a t apping or liting inger or an opening or closing hand that is preceded by a congruent (e.g., index inger responds to observation of t apping i ndex inger) a s opposed to i ncongruent st imulus (e.g., index inger responds to observation of tapping middle inger) (Bertenthal, Longo, & Kosobud, 2006; Brass, Bekkering, & Prinz, 2001; Brass, Bekkering, Wohlschlager, & Pr inz, 2000; Heyes, Bird, Johnson, & Haggard, 2005; Longo et al., in press).
Motor Knowledge and Action Understanding
327
Prediction of the Effects of Actions While t he p receding e vidence su ggests t hat ac tion obs ervation i s accompanied by covert imitation of the observed action, additional evidence su ggests t hat ac tion obs ervation a lso leads to t he prediction of t he efects or outcome of t he ac tion. I n a st udy by K andel, Orliaguet, a nd V iviani ( 2000), pa rticipants w ere sh own a po intlight tracing of the irst letter of a t wo-letter sequence handwritten in cursive, and they were able to predict the second letter from the observation of t he pre ceding move ments. Ne uroimaging e vidence revealed t hat a f ronto-parietal c ircuit (associated w ith t he h uman mirror system) was activated when predicting the next letter from a point-light tracing, but this same circuit was not activated when predicting the terminus of a point-light tracing of a spring-driven ball ater it bounced (Chaminade, Meary, Orliaguet, & Decety, 2001). he inding that the fronto-parietal circuit was only activated when predicting the outcome of a human action and not when predicting the outcome of a mechanical event is consistent with other research suggesting that the mirror system is restricted to biological movements (e.g., K ilner, Paulignan, & Bla kemore, 2003; Tai, S cherler, Brooks, Sawamoto, & Castiello, 2004). his last inding implies that the direct matching system is sensitive to the perceived similarity between observed and executed responses, and t hus, observers should show an improved ability to predict t he efects o r o utcome o f a n ac tion ba sed o n t heir o wn a s o pposed t o others’ m ovements bec ause t he ma tch be tween t he obs erved a nd executed actions should be greatest when the same person is responsible for both (e.g., Knoblich, 2002; Knoblich, Elsner, Aschersleben, & Metzinger, 2003). A few recent studies manipulating the “authorship” of the movements ind that predictability is indeed greater when predicting the outcomes of self-produced as opposed to other produced movements (Beardsworth & Buckner, 1981; Flach, Knoblich, & Prinz, 2003; Knoblich & Flach, 2001; Repp & Knoblich, 2004). Why s hould c overt i mitation or si mulation of move ments c ontribute t o p redicting t heir e fects? he a nswer i s r elated t o t he inertial la gs a nd n eural co nduction dela ys t hat acco mpany l imb movements in the human body. As a co nsequence of these delays, it i s i nsuicient for movements to b e g uided by s ensory fe edback, because such m ovements would be per formed in a jer ky and stac-
328
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
cato fashion as opposed to being smooth and luid (Wolpert, Doya, & Kawato, 2003). hus, the execution of most movements requires prospective control or planning. Based on computational studies, it has been proposed that this planning or control involves an internal model, d ubbed forward mo del, wh ich p redicts t he s ensory co nsequences of a motor command (Jordan, 1995; Kawato, Furawaka, & Suzuki, 1987; M iall & W olpert, 1996; Wolpert & Fla nagan, 2 001). Presumably, t he s imulation o f a g oal-directed ac tion i ncludes t he activation of t hese forward models enabling prediction a s well a s covert imitation of the behavior. As motor behaviors are practiced and l earned, t hese f orward m odels beco me be tter spec iied and enable m ore p recise p rediction o f t he en suing m otor c ommands. According t o Wolpert e t a l. (2003), s imilar forward models could be used to predict social behaviors, such as facial expression, gaze direction, or posture.
Perception of the Structure of Human Movements One additional source of evidence suggesting that an observationexecution matching system is functional in human observers derives from their showing greater sensitivity to biological motions that are consistent as opposed to inconsistent with the causal structure of an action. A common technique for studying the perception of human movements i nvolves t he depiction of t hese movements w ith pointlight displays. hese displays are created by ilming a person in the dark with small lights attached to his or her major joints and head. (An ex ample of six s equential f rames f rom a po int-light d isplay i s presented in Figure 10.1.) It is also possible to synthesize these nested pendular motions, which is the technique that we have used in much of our previous research (see Bertenthal, 1993, for a review). Johansson (1973) was the irst to systematically study the perception of these displays. He reported that adult observers perceive the human form and identify diferent actions (e.g., push-ups, jumping jacks, etc.) in displays lasting less than 200 ms, corresponding to about ive frames of a ilm sequence. his inding is very impressive because these displays are devoid of a ll featural information, such a s clothing, sk in, or hair. It thus appears that recognition of actions can result exclusively from the extraction of a unique structure from motion-carried information.
Motor Knowledge and Action Understanding
329
Figure 10.1 Six sequentially sampled frames from a moving point-light display depicting a person walking.
In spite of t hese i mpressive indings, t he recognition of upsidedown biological motion displays as depicting a person or the person’s direction of gait is signiicantly impaired (Bertenthal & Pinto, 1994; Pavlova & Sokolov, 2000; Sumi, 1984; Verfaillie, 1993). If recognition was based only on the perception of structure from motion, then the orientation of the human form should not matter. It thus appears that some additional processes involving the causal structure of human movement contribute to the perception of biological motions. For similar reasons, point-light trajectories obeying the kinematics of human movement are perceived as moving at a uniform speed, even though the variations in speed can exceed 200%. By co ntrast, observers are much more sensitive to speed diferences in point-light trajectories that do not conform to the kinematics of human movements (V iviani, Ba ud-Bovy, & Red oli, 1997; V iviani & M ounoud, 1990; V iviani & S tucchi, 1 992). hese la tter indings t hus su ggest that curvilinear movements are not perceived in terms of the actual changes that occur in velocity, but rather in terms of the biological movements that appear smooth and uniform when executed by one or more articulators of the human body. Although the preceding evidence is consistent with motor knowledge contributing to action understanding, it is diicult to rule out perceptual l earning a s t he p rincipal r eason f or obs ervers sh owing diferential sensitivity to familiar and unfamiliar biological motions. Indeed, this same confound is present when interpreting much of the previously reviewed evidence suggesting that motor knowledge contributes to the prediction of human actions. his confound also adds to the challenge of testing whether motor knowledge contributes to infants’ understanding of others’ actions, which is why it is necessary to consider the contributions of visual attention and experience when studying the functionality of the observation-execution matching system during infancy.
330
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Developmental Evidence for an Observation– Execution Matching System For t hose u nfamiliar w ith t he preceding e vidence f or a n obs ervation–execution ma tching s ystem, i t w ill be u seful t o r ecap h ow a direct matching system contributes to action understanding. he traditional view is that others’ actions are understood via the same perceptual and conceptual processes as are all other visual events. If, however, t he perception of ac tions a lso ac tivates t he motor system (i.e., direct matching), then the speciic motor knowledge associated with the perceived actions will contribute to understanding others’ actions. he speciic m echanism f or t his u nderstanding i s co vert imitation or simulation of the observed action. Although the motor response is not overtly executed, the planning for speciic movements (i.e., means) as well as the efects or perceptual consequences (i.e., the goal) are automatically activated in the motor cortex. hi s activation imparts to the observer embodied knowledge of the perceived action (i.e., motor knowledge) without the need to rely on visual experience or logical inferences based on t he perceived information. he implication is that we can then understand others’ actions, such as liting a c up, playing the piano, or displaying a d isposition, such a s displeasure, based on the internalized motor programs available to us for performing the same actions. In the remainder of this chapter, we will review a series of experiments designed to investigate whether motor knowledge contributes to action understanding by infants. Although it is certainly possible for i nfants t o ach ieve t his u nderstanding f rom v isual ex perience alone, t here ex ists a de velopmental adv antage for d irect matching, because such a m echanism does not necessitate speciic conceptual or symbolic knowledge of actions, which demand the development of h igher-level cog nitive p rocesses. hus, t he f unctioning o f t his system may ofer an explanation for the precocious development of young i nfants’ u nderstanding o f ac tions, a nd soc ial de velopment more generally (Tomasello, 1999). he evidence is divided into three sections. First, we will review a series of experiments showing that infants demonstrate perseverative s earch er rors f ollowing obs ervation o f so meone el se’s ac tions. his evidence will be used to support the claim that an observation execution matching system is functional in infants and that action observation e licits c overt i mitation. S econd, we w ill re view re cent
Motor Knowledge and Action Understanding
331
experiments showing that infants visually orient in response to deictic gestures, and that this response is speciically a function of motor knowledge enabling prediction of t he efect of a n observed action. Finally, we will review evidence showing that infants perceive biological motions depicting fa miliar but not u nfamiliar ac tions, a nd that t he de velopment o f t his per ceptual sk ill i s a t l east co rrelated with the development of their motor skills.
Perseverative Errors in Searching for Hidden Objects he Piagetian A-not-B error, observed in 8- to 12-month-old infants, is among the most consistently replicable indings in developmental psychology. In t his task, i nfants irst search correctly for a n object they see hidden in one location (A) on one or more trials, but then continue to search at the A location ater the object has been hidden in a new location (B). A number of researchers attribute this search error to the formation of a prepotent response. For example, Smith, helen, and colleagues (Smith, helen, Titzer, & McLin, 1999; hel en, Schoner, Scheier, & Smith, 2001) claim that the error arises from the task dynamics of reaching, which causes the motor memory of one reach to persist and inluence subsequent reaches. Diamond (1985) argues that one cause of the error is the inability to inhibit a previously rewarded motor response. Zelazo and colleagues (Marcovitch, & Z elazo, 1 999; Z elazo, Re znick, & S pinazzola, 1 998) ac count f or perseverative r esponses i n y oung ch ildren i n ter ms o f t he r elative dominance of a response-based system “activated by motor experience” o ver a co nscious r epresentational s ystem ( Marcovitch & Zelazo, 1999, p. 1308). In each of these accounts, a history of reaches to the A location is a crucial aspect of the perseverative response. If an observation-execution matching system is functional in young infants, then simply observing someone else reach to the same location repeatedly may be suicient for eliciting this error. his prediction follows from the claim that observing an action will lead to covert imitation of that same action, and thus will be functionally similar t o ex ecuting t he ac tion o neself. We ( Longo & B ertenthal, 2006) tested this prediction by administering the standard A-not-B hiding t ask t o a s ample o f 9 -month-old i nfants. Twenty 9 -monthold infants were tested with the canonical reaching task, and twenty
332
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
were tested in a co ndition in which t hey watched a n experimenter reach, but did not reach themselves. Infants were seated on their mother’s lap in front of a t able covered with black felt and allowed to play with a toy (a rattle or a plastic Big-Bird) for several seconds. Four pretraining trials were administered using procedures similar to those used by Smith et al. (1999). On the irst pretraining trial, the toy was placed on top of a covered well. On the second trial, the toy was placed in the well but with one end st icking out of t he well. On t he t hird t rial, t he toy was placed completely in the well but let uncovered. On the inal trial, the toy was placed completely in the well and covered. he experimental trials used a t wo-well apparatus and consisted of three A trials and one B trial (see Figure 10.2). Infants in the reaching condition were allowed to search on all trials. Infants in the looking condition were only allowed to search on the B trial and observed the ex perimenter recover t he object on t he A t rials. On e ach t rial, the toy was waved and the infant’s name was called to attract his or her attention. he experimenter removed the lid with one hand and placed the toy in the well with the other hand. he location (right or let) of t he A t rials a nd ex perimenter’s a rm (right or let; coded as which arm the experimenter used to hide the toy) were counterbalanced between infants. hus, t he experimenter’s reaches were ipsilateral ha lf o f t he t ime (right-handed r each t o t he l ocation o n t he right or let-handed reach to location on t he let) and contralateral
Figure 10.2 Infant searching for toy in one of the two hiding wells (from Longo & Bertenthal, 2006).
Motor Knowledge and Action Understanding
333
half of the time (right-handed reach to the location on the let or lethanded reach to the location on the right). For A trials in the reaching condition, the apparatus was slid forward to within the baby’s reach following a 3 s delay. If, ater 10 s, the infant had not retrieved the toy from the A location, the experimenter uncovered the well and encouraged the infant to retrieve the toy. For A trials in the looking condition, the experimenter did not slide the apparatus toward the infants and recovered the toy following a three second delay. he ex perimenter u sed t he s ame a rm to retrieve t he toy as was used to hide the toy. On B t rials, in both conditions, the experimenter hid the toy (using the same hand as on the A trials) and then the apparatus was moved to within the infant’s reach following a 3 s delay. he dependent measure was whether the infant searched for the hidden toy at the correct B l ocation or reverted to search at the A location where the toy had been previously found. he results revealed that infants in the Reaching condition were signiicantly more likely to make an error on B trials (15 of 20) than on any of the A trials, the canonical A-not-B error. Infants also made signiicantly more errors on looking B t rials (12 of 20) than infants in the reaching condition made on A trials (see Figure 10.3). hese results dem onstrate t hat o vert r eaching t o t he A l ocation b y t he infant is not necessary to elicit the A-not-B error. During training, 80
Search Error (% Infants)
70 60 50 40 30 20 10 0 A1
A2
A3
Reaching B Looking B
Trial
Figure 10.3 Percentage of i nfants s earching i ncorrectly on irst, second, and third reaching A t rials, searching B t rial, and looking B t rial (from Longo & Bertenthal, 2006).
334
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
infants in the looking condition had reached four times to a central location u sing t he s ingle-well a pparatus, b ut had never r eached t o the A location. Still, they were found to “perseverate” on their very irst reach using t he t wo-well apparatus. he l ikelihood of ma king an error did not difer between the two B conditions. In sum, these data suggest that looking A trials inluenced performance on the B t rials. Nonetheless, in order to establish that these responses a re t ruly perseverative, a s o pposed t o s imply r andom, i t is necessary to demonstrate errors on signiicantly more than 50% of the trials. Binomial tests revealed greater than chance perseveration on reaching, but not on looking B t rials. hus, t hese d ata a re consistent with indings from previous studies showing that infants perseverate ater reaching A trials, but the evidence of perseveration following looking A trials was somewhat equivocal. In t he s econd e xperiment, we s ought to prov ide more d einitive evidence for pers everative s earch i n t he looking condition. Ma rcovitch, Z elazo, a nd S chmuckler ( 2002) f ound t hat t he l ikelihood of a pers everative s earch er ror i ncreased a s t he number of A t rials increased, at least between the range of one to six. If the A-not-B error is indeed a function of similar mechanisms inducing perseverative search in both the reaching and looking conditions, then we would expect search errors in the looking condition to be more robust as the number of A trials increases. hus, in order to increase the likelihood of inding perseveration at greater than chance levels, the following experiment included six looking A trials instead of three. hirty 9-month-old infants were tested following the procedures described for the irst experiment, except that all infants were tested in t he looking condition a nd t here were six i nstead of t hree A t rials. he r esults f rom t his ex periment r evealed t hat 70% (21 of 3 0) of the infants made t he A-not-B error, signiicantly more than half of t he s ample. his inding s uggests t hat ob servation of a re aching ac tion is su icient to elicit perseverative search. As such, t hese indings are consistent with infants covertly imitating the observed action of searching for the toy in the covered well. Can these results be explained by other mechanisms? Some researchers suggest that the crucial factor leading to search errors at the B location is not a history of reaching to the A location, but rather a history of visually attending to or planning to reach to the A l ocation (e.g., Di edrich, H ighlands, S pahr, helen, & S mith, 2001; Munakata, 1997; Rufman & L angman, 2002). In t he current
Motor Knowledge and Action Understanding
335
experiments, g reater a ttention t o o ne l ocation t han t he o ther w ill likely covary with the history of simulated reaching to that location, and t hus i t i s d iicult t o d isambiguate t hese t wo i nterpretations. Although th is attentional c onfound i s oten a p roblem wh en te sting the contribution of motor knowledge to performance, converging analyses assessing infants’ own reaching behavior were helpful in showing t hat a n attentional i nterpretation was not su icient for explaining their search errors. It is well documented in the literature that infants show an ipsilateral bias in their reaching. Bruner (1969), for example, referred to the apparent inability of young infants to reach across the body midline as t he “mysterious midline ba rrier,” a rguing t hat contralateral reaches do not oc cur before 7 m onths of a ge. C ontralateral reaching becomes more frequent with age both on reaching tasks during infancy (van Hof, van der Kamp, & Savelsbergh, 2002) and in “hand, eye, and ear” tasks in later childhood (Bekkering, Wohlschläger, & Gattis, 2000; Schoield, 1976; Wapner & Cirillo, 1968). Nevertheless, a clear preference for ipsilateral reaches is consistently observed in early development. In Experiment 1, infants showed an ipsilateral bias in their reaching. On l ooking B t rials, 9 0% (18 o f 2 0) o f t he i nfants made ipsilateral r eaches, wh ich w as sig niicantly more than would be expected by chance. Similar ipsilateral biases were observed on the three reaching A t rials (81.7%), and the reaching B t rials (73.7%, 14 of 19 one-handed reaches). I ntriguingly, infants’ simulation of t he experimenter’s actions mirrored t heir motor bias, as infants i n t he looking condition were signiicantly more likely to reach to location A than to location B wh en the experimenter had r eached ipsilaterally (8 of 10), rather than contralaterally (4 of 10) (see Figure 10.4). his result suggests that infants’ responses following observation of the ex perimenter’s reaches were not random, at least for ipsilateral reaches. In Experiment 2, an ipsilateral bias in infants’ reaching was again observed, with 85% (23 of 27) of one-handed reaches scored as ipsilateral. Furthermore, this ipsilateral bias was again mirrored by infants’ representation of the experimenter’s reaching. Perseveration was observed more oten than predicted by chance when the experimenter had r eached i psilaterally o n t he A t rials (13 o f 1 5 i nfants made the error), but not when the experimenter had reached contralaterally (8 of 15 made the error). his diference between conditions was signiicant (see Figure 10.4).
336
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
100
Search Error (% Infants)
90
Ipsilateral Contralateral
80 70 60 50 40 30 20 10 0
Exp. 1
Exp. 2
Figure 10.4 Percentage of i nfants s earching i ncorrectly fol lowing ob servation of ipsi- and contralateral reaches by t he experimenter in the looking condition of Experiments 1 and 2 (from Longo & Bertenthal, 2006).
It is very possible that the infants’ ipsilateral bias may have inluenced their likelihood of covertly imitating the experimenter. A number of recent studies suggest that simulation by the mirror system is signiicantly st ronger wh en obs erved ac tions a re w ithin t he m otor repertoire of the observer (e.g., Calvo-Merino et al., 2005; Longo et al., in press). If an observer does not possess the motor skill to precisely and reliably perform an action, then he or she cannot simulate it with the same level of speciicity as a skilled performer. Since infants have diiculty r eaching co ntralaterally, s imulation o f o bserved co ntralateral reaches should be w eaker than that for ipsilateral reaches, or perhaps absent entirely. hus, if an observation-execution matching mechanism is operative, then infants should perseverate more oten following observation of ipsi- rather than contralateral reaches to the A location by the experimenter, as we found. Although the preceding indings a re not meant t o d iscount t he relative contributions of at tention to response perseveration, at t he very least the current evidence appears to challenge the suiciency of an attentional explanation focused on spatial coding of the hidden object. I n pa rticular, it i s not at a ll apparent how such a n ac count would ex plain wh y i nfants sh owed g reater pers everation a ter observing the experimenter reach ipsilaterally than contralaterally.
Motor Knowledge and Action Understanding
337
Other po tential ex planations i nvolving, f or ex ample, ob ject r epresentations (e.g., Munakata, 1998), have similar diiculty accounting for this efect. By contrast, a direct matching interpretation accounts for this efect in terms of infants’ own diiculties with contralateral reaching, which should lead to weaker or absent motor simulation following observed contralateral, compared with ipsilateral reaches, and consequently less perseveration. he inal experiment in this series was designed to probe whether a simulative response to an observed action is initiated only when the ac tion i s per formed b y a h uman a gent o r a lso wh en i t i s per formed by a r obot or some other mechanical a gent. A s previously discussed, research with adults reveals that the execution of an action is oten facilitated when observing t hat same ac tion, a nd i mpaired when observing a d iferent action (Brass et al., 2001; Bertenthal et al., 2006). It appears, however, that this conclusion applies only when observing actions performed by human agents. For example, Kilner et al. (2003) instructed participants to make vertical or horizontal arm movements while observing either a human or a robot making the same or t he opposite a rm movements. he results showed t hat observation of incongruent arm movements interfered signiicantly with the performance by the observer, but this efect was limited to observation of t he human a gent. W hen obs erving t he robot, t here was no evidence of an interference efect on the performance of the observer. In order to test this same question with infants, we modiied t he testing situation so t hat the human experimenter would be h idden behind a c urtain, but would be ab le t o ma nipulate t he covers a nd the toy with two large mechanical claws that were held vertically in front of the curtain. hus, t he i nfant w as only able to obs erve t he mechanical claws, a nd even t he experimenter’s ha nds t hat g ripped the mechanical claws were not visible (see Figure 10.5). A total of 30 infants were tested, and the procedure was similar to that used in the preceding experiment. Ater the training trials, there were six A trials followed by one B trial. From the infants’ perspective, the hiding and inding of the toy was identical to the previous two experiments, except t hat t he ex perimenter w as n ot v isible a nd t wo m echanical claws a ppeared i n h er p lace. Unlike t he r esults f rom t he p revious experiments, t he pers everative er ror w as made b y only 4 0% (12 of 30) of the infants, which was signiicantly less than occurred in the previous two experiments. Moreover, the likelihood of the error was
338
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
essentially the same for ipsilateral and contralateral searches by the claw. hus, the substitution of a mechanical agent for a human agent reduced the frequency of the perseverative error. Our i nterpretation f or t his inding i s t hat inf ants’ t endency t o simulate observed ac tions is less l ikely when t he ac tion is not performed by a human. We realize, however, that the mechanical agent is less fa miliar t han t he human agent, a nd t hus fa miliarity, per s e, may be r esponsible for t hese diferences in t he likelihood of a per severative sea rch e rror. I n f uture r esearch, w e p lan t o m anipulate whether the mechanical claw is observed as an independent agent or as a t ool used by the human agent. If perseverative performance is greater when the mechanical claw is perceived as a tool, the importance o f fa miliarity f or ex plaining pers everative per formance w ill be diminished, because familiarity will remain constant in both the tool and agent conditions. Although support for t his prediction awaits a n empirical te st, a recent study by Hofer, Hauf, and Aschersleben (2005) suggests that infants d istinguish be tween t ools a nd m echanical a gents. I n t his experiment, 9 -month-old i nfants d id n ot i nterpret a n ac tion per formed by a m echanical claw as goal-directed but did interpret the action as goal-directed when the mechanical claw was perceived as a tool. Presumably the tool is interpreted as goal-directed at an earlier age than the mechanical agent because infants perceive it as an
Figure 10.5 Infant observing the toy being hidden by two mechanical claws.
Motor Knowledge and Action Understanding
339
extension of the human arm, and thus are better able to simulate and understand its efects. Until r ecently, t his inding ma y ha ve s eemed a t odd s w ith t he evidence f or m irror n eurons i n t he m onkey’s b rain. W hen t hese neurons w ere irst d iscovered, it w as reported that they d ischarge to goal-directed actions performed by conspeciics or humans, but not to actions performed by tools, such as a pair of pliers (Rizzolatti et al., 2001). Recently, however, Ferrari, Rozzi, and Fogassi (2005) reported identifying a po pulation of neurons in t he monkey’s ventral p remotor c ortex th at s peciically d ischarges to g oal-directed actions executed by tools. Taken together, this evidence suggests that an action performed by a tool perceived as an extension of a human agent will be more likely to induce motor simulation than an action performed by the same tool perceived as a mechanical agent.
Visual Orienting in Response to Deictic Gestures Joint attention to objects and events in the world is a necessary prerequisite for sharing experiences with others and negotiating shared meanings. As Baldwin (1995, p. 132) puts it: “ joint attention simply means the simultaneous engagement of two or more individuals in mental focus on one and the same external thing.” A critical component in establishing joint attention involves following the direction of someone else’s gaze or pointing gesture (Deak, Flom, & Pick, 2000). Both of these behaviors require that the deictic gesture is interpreted not a s t he g oal, i tself, b ut r ather a s t he m eans t o t he g oal. W hen responding to a redirection of gaze or to the appearance of a pointing gesture, the observer does not i xate on the eyes or the hand but rather focuses on the referent of these gestures (Woodward & Guarjardo, 2002). In this case the behavior is communicative and the goal is some distal object or event (“there’s something over there”). hus, it is necessary for the observer to predict the referent or the goal of the action from observing its execution by someone else. Until recently, the empirical evidence suggested that infants were unable t o f ollow t he d irection o f a g aze o r a po int u ntil a pproximately 9 to 12 months of age (e.g., Corkum & Moore, 1998; Leung & Rheingold, 1981; Scaife & Bruner, 1975). If, however, these behaviors are m ediated b y a n obs ervation-execution ma tching s ystem, t hen gaze-following should precede following a pointing gesture because
340
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
control of eye movements and saccadic localization appear at birth or soon thereater (von Hofsten, 2003), whereas the extension of the arm a nd i ndex inger t o f orm a po inting g esture d oes n ot a ppear until approximately 9 months of age (Butterworth, 2003). Indeed, it should be possible to show evidence of gaze-following long before 9 months of age. his prediction has now been validated. Hood, Willen, and Driver (1998) ad apted a m ethod po pularized b y P osner ( 1978, 1 980) f or studying spatial orienting. In a prototypical study, adult subjects are instructed to detect visual targets, which may appear on either side of a ixation point. heir attention can be cued to one side or the other before the target appears (e.g., by a brief but uninformative lash on that side). he consistent inding f rom t his paradigm is t hat target detection i s more r apid on t he c ued s ide, bec ause attention i s oriented in that direction. It is relevant to note that the attentional cueing preceding the orienting response is covert and does not involve an overt eye movement. As such, this attentional cueing is consistent with a simulation of an eye movement that enables prediction before the visual target appears. Hood et al. tested 4-month-old infants to determine if they would shit their visual attention in the direction toward which an adult’s eyes turn . he d irection o f per ceived g aze w as ma nipulated i n a digitized adult face. Ater infants oriented to blinking eyes focused straight ahead, the eyes shited to the right or to the let. A key innovation of this paradigm was that the central face disappeared ater the eyes were averted to avoid diiculties with infants disengaging their i xation of the face. An attentional shit w as measured by the latency and direction of infants’ orienting to peripheral probes presented ater t he face d isappeared. Infants oriented faster and made fewer errors when presented with a probe congruent with the direction of gaze than when presented with an incongruent probe. he se indings suggest that young infants interpret the direction of gaze as a cue to shit attention in a speciied direction. It is signiicant to note t hat t he attentional cue was not i n t he location of t he probe, but simply pointed to t hat location. hus, faster responding to t he spa tially co ngruent c ue r equired t hat i nfants u nderstand a t some level the meaning of the change in gaze direction in order to predict the future location of the probe. More recent research reveals that gaze following was restricted to a face in which infants observed a dynamic shit in gaze direction (Farroni, Johnson, Brockbank, &
Motor Knowledge and Action Understanding
341
Simion, 2000). When the averted gaze was presented statically, there was no evidence of i nfants following t he gaze shit. Intriguingly, a new report by Farroni and colleagues (Farroni, Massaccesi, Pividori, & J ohnson, 2 004) su ggests t hat t hese indings a re re plicable w ith newborn infants. With K atharina R ohling, we sought to extend this paradigm to study whether infants younger than 9 m onths of age would also reorient their attention in response to the direction that another person is pointing with their hand. Interestingly, Amano, Kezuka, and Yamamoto (2004) co nducted a n obs ervational st udy sh owing t hat 4-month-old infants responded diferently to the pointing done by an ex perimenter a nd t heir mothers. I n order to redirect attention, infants more oten needed t he combination of eye gaze a nd pointing while interacting with the experimenter than while interacting with their mothers. W hen i nteracting with their mothers, i nfants were ab le t o f ollow t he po inting g esture a lone wh ile t he m others maintained eye contact. One interpretation for these indings is that infants are more familiar with their mothers’ gestures and thus are more likely to correctly interpret them. A diferent interpretation is that i nfants a re more l ikely to follow t he pointing gesture of t heir mothers because their mother’s face is more familiar and thus it is easier for them to disengage from the face. By adapting the same paradigm used by Hood et al. (1998) to study gaze-following, we were able to eliminate some of the possible confounds present in previous studies of pointing because infants did not have to disengage from a central stimulus of a face. Infants between 4.5- and 6.5-months-old were tested. hey were shown a series of computerized stimuli on a projection screen while sitting o n t heir pa rents’ la ps. E ach t rial co nsisted o f t he f ollowing sequence of events (see Figure 10.6): 1.
he hand appeared on the screen with ingers oriented upward. he ingers waved up and down and were accompanied by a voice saying “look baby, look!” to recruit the baby’s attention. his segment was played until the infant i xated the hand. 2 . Once the inger waving ended, t he ha nd was s een t ransforming into a c anonical pointing gesture that moved a sho rt distance in the direction of the pointing inger. his segment lasted 1000 ms. 3. Ater the hand disappeared, a digitized picture of a toy appeared randomly on the let or right side of the screen. On half of the trials, this probe was congruent with the direction of the point and
342
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
1. Finger waving
2. Finger pointing (1000 ms)
3. Probe appears
Figure 10.6 Stimulus sequence for e ach t rial. 1. Fi ngers wave up a nd down. 2 . Index inger points toward let or right side of screen. 3. Probe appears on let or right side. (his sequence corresponds to an incongruent trial.)
on the other half of the trials it was incongruent with the pointing direction. he probe rema ined v isible for 3 s a nd was accompanied by a voice saying “wow!” Two diferent toys (a clown and an
Ernie puppet) were presented i n a r andomized order (Figure 10.6).
Based on the videotapes of the infants’ behavior, we measured the response t ime to s hit a ttention i n t he d irection o f t he per ipheral probe. he probe that appeared in the direction cued by the pointing inger is referred to as the congruent probe, a nd t he probe t hat appeared in the opposite direction is referred to as the incongruent probe. A total of 20 infants completed an average of 26 trials (S =6.2, range: 10–32). As can be seen in Figure 10.7 (Dynamic condition), infants oriented toward the congruent probe signiicantly faster than they d id t oward t he i ncongruent p robe. hese r esults su ggest t hat infants as young as 4.5 months of age respond to a dynamic pointing gesture by shiting their visual attention to a shared referent. he second experiment tested whether the movement of the pointing inger w as n ecessary t o el icit t he sh it in attention or whether a st atic po inting g esture w ould be su icient. A n ew s ample o f 14 infants between 4.5 to 6.5 months of age was tested with t he same
Motor Knowledge and Action Understanding
343
Figure 10.7 Mean response times for infants to orient toward the congruent and incongruent probes. In the dynamic condition, infants were shown a pointing inger that moved a short distance in the same direction that the i nger was pointing. In the static condition, infants were shown a pointing i nger that didn’t move.
procedure, except that the pointing inger remained stationary when it appeared on t he s creen for 1000 ms . I nfants completed a n average of 22 trials (SD=7.7, range: 10–32). Unlike t he responses to t he dynamic pointing inger, infants showed no diference in responding to the congruent and incongruent probe (see Figure 10.7, Static condition). It thus appears that observation of an action and not just the inal state i s n ecessary f or y oung i nfants t o f ollow a po int, a nalogous to t he indings of i nfants following e ye gaze (Farroni e t a l., 2 000). Two possible interpretations for these results are that the movement associated w ith t he gesture i ncreased t he s alience of t he st imulus, or increased the likelihood of visual tracking in the direction of the moving inger. Either of these two possibilities would bias infants to shit their attention in the direction of the pointing gesture. If the results were exclusively a function of following the principal direction of the moving inger, then we would expect a reversal in the reaction time results when the inger moved backwards rather than forwards. he n ext ex periment te sted t his i nterpretation. A t otal of 25 i nfants between 4.5 and 6.5 months of age were tested in two conditions. In t he forward condition, t he d irection of t he pointing inger and the movement of the inger were compatible, whereas in
344
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Figure 10.8 Mean response times for infants to orient toward the congruent and incongruent probes. In the forward condition the inger moved in the same direction it w as pointing. In the backward condition the inger moved in the opposite direction that it was pointing.
the backward condition, the direction of the pointing inger and the movement of the inger were incompatible. Half of the trials in each condition involved a congruent probe and half of the trials involved an incongruent probe. Infants completed an average of 25 trials (SD=5.68, range: 14–31). In t he f orward co ndition, i nfants sh owed t he s ame adv antage f or responding to the congruent vs. incongruent probe that they showed in the irst experiment (see Figure 10.8). In the backward condition, infants were ex pected to show t he opposite pattern of responses i f they were responding only to the direction of movement and not to the direction of the pointing inger. As can be observed in Figure 10.8, this pattern of results was not obtained—infants responded just as fast to the congruent as to the incongruent probe. he se results thus suggest t hat i nfants as young as 4.5 months of age do not respond to a sha red referent simply by following the direction of movement irrespective of the direction of the point. A third possibility for why infants were able to follow the direction of a dy namic point is that the perceived point is mapped onto infants’ own motor representations for pointing. his hypothesis is supported by at least two sources of evidence. In the case of pointing, the goal of the observed action is to reorient the attention of another
Motor Knowledge and Action Understanding
345
person so t hat a n ob ject beco mes t he sha red f ocus o f a ttention (Woodward & G uajardo, 2 002). Re search w ith ad ults r eveals t hat action s imulation fac ilitates t he ab ility o f obs ervers t o p redict t he efect of an action (e.g., Chaminade et al., 2001; Knoblich, & Flach, 2001; L ouis-Dam, Orliaguet, & C oello, 1999; Orliaguet, K andel, & Boe, 1997). In addition, recent research suggests that slightly older infants, 6 to 12 months of age, also understand the goals or efects of an action (e.g., Gergely, Nádasdy, Csibra, & Biró, 2003; Luo & Ba illargeon, 2006; Woodward, 1998). If visual attention is the principal factor responsible for the preceding results, then it should not matter whether the action is carried out by a h uman or a m echanical a gent a s long a s both a gents are equally salient. If, however, the preceding results are a f unction of ac tion simulation, t hen t he d istinction be tween a h uman a nd a mechanical agent should ma ke a d iference. Recall t hat simulation depends o n t he per ceived s imilarity be tween t he obs erved ac tion and the speciic motor responses available to the observer. In the last experiment, we put this hypothesis to the test by repeating t he p revious ex periment w ith a st ick m oving t o t he l et or t o the right in place of a h uman ha nd. he stick initially appeared to be pointing toward t he i nfant a nd w aved up a nd down i n a ma nner similar to the ingers waving up and down. Ater the infant ixated the stick, it was rotated so that it pointed toward the let or the right side of t he screen, a nd t hen moved a sh ort d istance either i n the direction it was pointing or in the opposite direction. his movement lasted 1000 ms. Similar to the previous experiments, the stick then disappeared and was replaced by a toy probe that appeared on the let or right side of the screen. A new sample of 18 infants between 4.5 and 6.5 months of age was tested. Infants completed an average of 22 trials (SD=5.3, range: 12– 30). In both t he forward a nd back ward conditions, infants did not show a sig niicant response time advantage to either t he congruent direction of pointing or the congruent direction of movement (i.e., forward m ovement: co ngruent co ndition o r back ward m ovement: incongruent condition) (see Figure 10.9). It is possible that this result is attributable t o t he dec reased fa miliarity or s alience of t he st ick, because, on average, response times were higher. However, this factor, by itself, is unlikely suicient to explain the null results, because the critical inding is not the absolute diference in response times, but rather the relative diference in response times. Accordingly, we conclude that infants, like adults, are more likely to predict the efect
346
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Figure 10.9 Stick experiment. Mean response times for infants to orient toward the congruent and incongruent probes. In the forward condition the inger moved in the same direction it was pointing. In the backward condition the inger moved in the opposite direction that it was pointing.
of a n a ction w hen it i s p erformed by a h uman e fector, s uch a s a hand, as opposed to a mechanical efector with little resemblance to the morphology or movements of the human action. In su m, t hese results on following t he d irection of a po int su ggest that infants as young as 4.5 months of age are capable of shiting their attention in response to this action as long as the action is performed by a h uman agent. his inding t hus appears consistent with infants predicting the goal of the deictic gesture, but there is a problem with attributing this prediction to simulating the observed action. A n umber of studies agree that canonical pointing emerges on average at 11 months of age, although some babies as young as 8.5 months of age have been observed to point (Butterworth & M orissette, 1996). If action simulation requires that the observed action is already in the motor repertoire of the observer, then the interpretation of simulation as the basis for predicting the referent cannot be correct. here is, however, another way to interpret the basis for simulation which is more compatible with the current indings. Infants as young as 4.5 months of age are not able to diferentiate t heir ha nd and ingers so that only the index inger is extended in the direction of t he a rm, but it is entirely possible t hat t he ex tension of t he a rm
Motor Knowledge and Action Understanding
347
and hand is sometimes performed for the same purpose as a pointing gesture at an older age. Consistent with this hypothesis, Leung and R heingold ( 1981) d irectly co mpared 1 0.5- t o 1 6.5-month-old infants’ arm extensions with open or closed hands and arm extensions with index inger extended toward objects located at a distance from where they were sitting. he authors report that at the younger ages the majority of responses were reaches rather than pointing gestures to the distal objects. Although reaches are typically associated with an instrumental response, they were interpreted in this context as serving a social communicative function because they accompanied looking at and vocalizing to the mother. he preceding evidence thus suggests that two actions executed by infants can share the same goal even though the means for achieving that goal difer. Interestingly, most of the evidence for an observationexecution matching system is based on shared goals and not shared means to achieve these goals. Consider, for example, the previously discussed n europhysiological indings on mirror neurons. It was shown that these neurons discharge when observing or executing the same goal-directed action regardless of whether or not the speciic movements ma tched ( Rizzolatti e t a l., 1 996). L ikewise, beha vioral research with human adults shows that response priming following observation of an action depends primarily on the observation of the goal and not the speciic means to the goal. For example, Longo et al. (in press) tested human adults in a choice reaction time task involving imitation of an index or middle inger tapping downwards. he results showed equivalent levels of response priming following t he observation of a b iomechanically possible or impossible inger tapping movement. In this example, the movements were diferent, but the goal of tapping downwards was the same in both conditions. If the movements associated with the observation of a goal-directed action need not be identical in order to simulate an observed action, then it may be suicient that the two representations share some similar features. Indeed, this is the basis for the theory of event coding as presented by Hommel, Müsseler, Aschersleben, and Prinz (2001). It is well established that infants are capable of predictive reaching for moving objects by 4.5 months of age (Bertenthal & von Hofsten, 1998; R ose & B ertenthal, 1995). he m otor r epresentation f or predictive reaching may be su icient to make contact with the goal of specifying a distal referent for young infants to index and predict the goal of the point. Clearly, more research is needed to fully evaluate this h ypothesis, b ut t he pos sibility t hat a co mmon code u nderlies
348
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
the observation and execution of a ma nual gesture for specifying a distal referent by 4.5 months of age is certainly consistent with the available evidence.
Perception of Point-Light Displays of Biological Motion he irst step i n u nderstanding h uman ac tions is t o per ceptually organize the constituent movements in a manner consistent with the causal structure of the action. We have relied on moving point-light displays depicting biological motions to study this question, because observers a re t hen f orced t o per ceptually o rganize t he st imuli i n terms of t he movements of t he l imbs w ithout a ny contextual c ues speciied by featural information. In spite of the apparent ambiguity in these displays, adult observers are quite adept at extracting a coherent a nd unique structure f rom t he moving point-lights (Bertenthal & P into, 1994; Cutting, Moore, & M orrison, 1988; Johansson, 1973; Proitt, Bertenthal, & Roberts, 1984). his conclusion is true even when the stimulus displays are masked by a large number of additional point-lights that share the same absolute motion vectors w ith t he point-lights comprising t he biological m otion d isplay. I n one ex periment (Bertenthal & P into, 1994) obs ervers w ere i nstructed t o j udge wh ether t he b iological motion display depicted a person walking to the right or to the let. he t arget w as comprised of 11 point-lights t hat moved i n a ma nner consistent with the spatiotemporal patterning of a person walking, but was masked by an additional 66 moving point-lights that preserved the absolute motions and temporal phase relations of the stimulus display (see Figure 10.10). In spite of the similarity between the point-lights comprising the target and those comprising the distracters, ad ult obs ervers d isplayed v ery h igh r ecognition r ates f or judging t he correct d irection of t he g ait. his ju dgment c ould not be a ttributed t o t he per ception o f i ndividual po int-lights, bec ause recognition performance declined to chance levels when the stimuli were rotated 180°. I f per formance was ba sed on t he movements of individual p oint-lights, th en th e o rientation o f th e d isplay s hould not have mattered. Apparently, obs ervers were de tecting a n orientation speciic spatiotemporal st ructure of t he moving point-lights because it matched their internal representation which was limited by ecological constraints to a person walking upright.
Motor Knowledge and Action Understanding
349
Figure 10.10 Let panel depicts point-light walker display appearing to walk to the right. (Outline of human form is drawn for illustrative purposes only.) Right panel depicts point-light walker display masked by moving point-lights preserving the a bsolute mot ions a nd t emporal ph ase re lations of t he t arget s timulus (from Bertenthal & Pinto, 1994).
his orientation speciicity appears to be the norm with regard to the perception of biological motions (e.g., Pavlova & Sokolov, 2000; Sumi, 1984). One intriguing interpretation for this repeated inding is that motor experience contributes to the perception of biological motions. Of course, this inding is also consistent with visual experience contributing to the perception of biological motions in a pointlight display. Although there is still insuicient evidence to reach any irm conclusions, some recent experiments by Shifrar and colleagues (Jacobs, P into, S hifrar, 2 005; L oula, Pr asad, Ha rber, & Sh ifrar, 2005; S hifrar & P into, 2 002; S tevens, F onlupt, Sh ifrar, & Dec ety, 2000) have suggested that motor experience provides a unique contribution t o t he per ception o f b iological m otions b y ad ults. I n t he remainder of this section, we will explore whether the same conclusion holds for infants’ perception of biological motions. In a s eries o f st udies beg un i n t he 1 980s, m y co lleagues a nd I (Bertenthal, Proitt, & Cutting, 1984; Bertenthal, Proitt, & Kramer, 1987; Bertenthal, Proitt, Kramer, & Spetner, 1987; Bertenthal, Profitt, Spetner, & homas, 1985; Pinto & Bertenthal, 1992) showed that infants are sensitive to the spatial and temporal structure in biologi-
350
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
cal m otion d isplays. F or ex ample, 3 - a nd 5 -month-old i nfants a re able to discriminate a canonical point-light walker display from one in which the spatial arrangement of the point-lights is scrambled or the temporal phase relations of the point lights are perturbed (Bertenthal, Proitt et al., 1987a; Bertenthal, Proit, Spetner et al., 1987b). Similar to adults, infants show an orientation speciic response by 5 months o f a ge ( Bertenthal, 1 993; P into & B ertenthal, 1 993; P into, Shrager, & Bertenthal, 1994). At 3 months of age, infants discriminate a c anonical f rom a per turbed po int-light w alker d isplay wh en t he displays are presented upright or upside down (Pinto et al., 1994). By 5 m onths of age, i nfants only d iscriminate t hese d isplays when they a re p resented u pright ( Pinto e t a l., 1 994). O ur i nterpretation for t his de velopmental sh it i s t hat i nfants a re responding to local conigural diferences at 3 months of age, but they are responding to global conigural diferences at 5 m onths of age (Bertenthal, 1993). In essence, the local conigural diferences can be detected independent of orientation. Converging e vidence f or t his i nterpretation co mes f rom t wo experiments sh owing t hat i nfants d o n ot d iscriminate po int-light walker d isplays r equiring a g lobal per cept u ntil 5 m onths o f a ge. In the irst of these experiments (Pinto, 1997), 3- and 5-month-old infants were tested for discrimination of two point-light walker displays w ith a hab ituation pa radigm. I n t his pa radigm, i nfants a re presented with one of the two stimulus displays for a series of trials until their visual attention to the stimulus declines signiicantly, and then t hey a re p resented w ith a n ovel st imulus d isplay f or t wo t rials. Increased visual attention to the novel display is interpreted as discrimination. Infants were presented with a point-light walker display translating across the screen during the habituation phase of the experiment. Following habituation, infants were shown a t ranslating point-light walker display in which the point-lights corresponding to the upper portion of the body were spatially shited relative to the point-lights corresponding to the lower portion of the body. According to adult observers, this spatial displacement resulted in the perception of two point-light walkers in which one appeared to have its legs occluded and the other appeared to have its torso, arms, and head occluded. If i nfants d id n ot per ceive a po int-light w alker d isplay a s a g lobal percept, then they would be less likely to detect this perturbation because bo th t he spa tially a ligned a nd sh ited d isplays w ould be
Motor Knowledge and Action Understanding
351
perceived as a n umber of subgroupings of point lights. If, however, infants d id per ceive t he hab ituation st imulus d isplay a s a u nitary object, t hen t he spa tially sh ited t ranslating w alker wou ld b e d iscriminated f rom t he p receding t ranslating po int-light w alker. he results revealed that 3-month-old infants did not discriminate these two displays, but 5-month-old infants did. In the second study, Amy Booth, Jeannine Pinto, and I conducted two ex periments testing 3 - a nd 5 -month-old i nfants’ sensitivity to the symmetrical patterning of human gait (Booth, Pinto, & Bertenthal, 2 001). I n t his c ase, s ensitivity t o t he pa tterning o f t he l imbs implies t hat d iscrimination be tween d isplays co uld n ot oc cur o n the basis of the perceived structure of any individual limb. If infants were primarily s ensitive to t his patterning, t hen we predicted t hat they w ould n ot d iscriminate be tween a po int-light d isplay dep icting a perso n walking a nd a perso n r unning bec ause both d isplays share the same symmetrical gait pattern (even though they difer on many additional dimensions). By contrast, infants should discriminate between two displays in which the symmetrical phase relations of the limbs were perturbed. A habituation paradigm was again used to test infants’ discrimination of the point-light displays. In Experiment 1 infants were presented with a po int-light display depicting a perso n running and a second display depicting a person walking (see Figure 10.11). Unlike previous experiments in which the stimulus displays were synthesized with a computational algorithm, the stimulus displays in this study were created with a m otion analysis system that tracked and stored the three-dimensional coordinates of discrete markers on the major joints of a person walking or running on a treadmill. Infants’ discrimination per formance r evealed t hat 3 -month-old i nfants
Figure 10.11 Four frames of the walker (in gray) superimposed over the runner (in bl ack). Point-lights a re c onnected for e ase of c omparison (from B ooth e t a l., 2001).
352
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
(a)
(b)
Figure 10.12 (a) Top panel; Walker vs. Runner. Mean looking times on t he last three habituation trials and on the two test trials as a function of age. he stimuli included a point-light walker and a point-light runner, each of which served as the habituation stimulus for half of the infants. (b) Bottom panel; Walker vs. PhaseShited Runner. Mean looking times on the last three habituation trials and on the two test trials as a function of age. he stimuli included a point-light walker and a phase-shited point-light runner, each of which served as the habituation stimulus for half of the infants (from Booth et al., 2001).
Motor Knowledge and Action Understanding
353
discriminated t he w alker a nd t he r unner, wh ereas 5 -month-old infants did not (see Figure 10.12a). hese results are consistent with the possibility that 3-month-old infants were responsive to the differences i n t he speed a nd joint a ngles of t he t wo d isplays, but t hat 5-month-old i nfants w ere m ore s ensitive t o t he s ymmetrical pa tterning of both d isplays a nd t herefore were less attentive to lowerlevel diferences. In order to conirm this interpretation, a second experiment was conducted to assess whether 3- and 5-month-old infants were sensitive to d iferences i n t he s ymmetrical pa tterning o f g ait. I nfants were tested for discrimination of a canonical point-light walker and a point-light runner in which the point-lights corresponding to the right leg and the let arm were temporally phase shited by 90o. he efect of this manipulation was to create a display in which one pair of di agonally opposite limbs reversed direction at 90 o a nd 2 70o of the gait cycle, whereas the other pair of limbs reversed direction at 0o and 180o of the gait cycle (see Figure 10.13). he results from this experiment revealed that both 3- and 5-month-old infants discriminated t he t wo point-light d isplays (see Figure 10.12b). Presumably, the younger i nfants d iscriminated t hese d isplays for t he same reason that they discriminated the two displays in the irst experiment, although st rictly spe aking w e c annot r ule o ut t he pos sibility t hat they also detected the change in the symmetrical patterning of the displays. By contrast, the older infants had not discriminated the two displays in the irst experiment, and thus their discrimination performance can only be explained in terms of detecting the changes in the gait pattern.
Figure 10.13 Four frames of the walker (in gray) superimposed over the phaseshited runner (in black). Point-lights are connected for ease of comparison (from Booth et al., 2001).
354
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Taken t ogether, t he r esults f rom t hese la st t wo ex periments a re illuminating for a number of reasons. First, they conirm that by 5 months of age, infants respond perceptually to the global structure of a moving point-light display. Second, the results from the second study suggest that infants by 5 months of age are sensitive to a fairly subtle h igher-level property of t he d isplays—symmetrical pa tterning of the gait pattern. One interpretation for these indings is that the visual system becomes more spatially integrative with development and also becomes more sensitive to the temporal properties of moving point-light displays. A second interpretation is that infants’ sensitivity to a point-light walker display as a u nitary object or as a hierarchical nesting of pendular motions w ith dy namic s ymmetry is speciically related to this stimulus depicting a familiar event. We have previously argued that the orientation speciicity of our indings suggests that visual experience is an important factor in the perceptual organization of these displays (Bertenthal, 1993). he third and inal interpretation is that a globally coherent and hierarchically nested moving object with bilateral symmetry corresponds to an internal representation that is relevant not only to the perception of human gait, but to the production of this behavior as well. Previous research reveals that infants capable of stepping on a split treadmill are biased to maintain a 180° phase relation between their two legs even when both sides of the treadmill are moving at diferent speeds (helen, U lrich, & N iles, 1 987). I n a l ongitudinal investigation of t his phenomenon, helen a nd Ulrich (1991) report that infants’ performance shows rapid improvement between 3 a nd 6 months of age (see Figure 10.14). Interestingly, this is the same period of development during which infants show increased perceptual sensitivity to the global coherence of biological motions, especially as deined by bilateral symmetry or 0˚ and 180˚ phase modes. his correspondence in age gives further credence to the suggestion of a shared representation between the perception and production of biological motions. As previously discussed by Bertenthal and Pinto (1993), t he perception a nd production of human movements sha re similar processing constraints relating to the phase relations of the limb movements; thus the development of one skill should facilitate the development of the other skill and vice versa. he evidence for a shared representation is also supported by the results from a neuroimaging study conducted by Grèzes, Fonlupt et al.(2001) showing t hat perception of point-light walker d isplays by
Motor Knowledge and Action Understanding
355
Figure 10.14 Mean number of a lternating steps by t rial and age, pooled across all infants. Trials 1 and 9 are baseline trials (from helen & Ulrich, 1991).
adults activates an area in the occipital-temporal junction as well as an area in the intraparietal sulcus. Whereas the former cortical area is associated with the perception of objects, the latter area is part of the neural circuit involved in the planning and execution of actions. Converging evidence supporting this inding has also been reported by Saygin, Wilson, Hagler, Bates, & Sereno (2004). It is thus possible that the perception of these point-light displays by infants also activates t he m otor s ystem wh ich co nfers v ia s imulation a n a ppreciation o f t he d iferences be tween a c anonical a nd a n u nnatural g ait pattern. One inal source of evidence to support this conjecture comes from an experiment testing infants’ discrimination of a canonical pointlight cat and a phase-shited point-light cat (Bertenthal, 1993). Similar to the indings on discrimination of inverted point-light displays, 3-month-old infants discriminated these two point-light cat displays, but neither 5- nor 8-month-old infants discriminated these displays. Presumably, 3-month-old infants discriminated these displays based on local diferences that were not speciic to the identity of the stimulus. Although it is reasonable to suggest that older infants did not
356
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
discriminate these displays at a global level because they lacked suficient v isual ex perience, co rrelative e vidence i s i nconsistent w ith this hypothesis (Pinto et al., 1996). When infants were divided into two groups based on whether one or more cats or dogs lived in their home, the results revealed absolutely no diference in discrimination performance as a function of whether or not infants had daily visual experience with a cat or dog. hus, it appears that infants’ insensitivity to t he spatiotemporal per turbations i n t hese d isplays may have not be en attributable to t heir l imited v isual ex perience, but r ather to their limited motor knowledge of quadrupedal gait. Interestingly, infants begin crawling on hands-and-knees between 7 and 9 months of age, which suggests that crawling experience as opposed to visual experience may have been a better predictor of their discrimination performance.
Conclusions he indings su mmarized i n t his chapter provide some of t he irst evidence to suggest that an observation-execution matching system is functional during infancy and contributes to action understanding through: (1) online simulation of observed actions; (2) prediction of the efects of observed actions; and (3) perceptual organization of component movements comprising an action. In order to avoid any confusion, we want to emphasize that suggesting a possible contribution o f t he m otor s ystem f or t he per ception a nd u nderstanding of actions is not meant to exclude the very important contributions of m ore t raditional m echanisms ( e.g., v isual a ttention a nd v isual experience) f or u nderstanding ac tions. F urthermore, t he e vidence presented is by no means deinitive, but it is buttressed by recent neurophysiological, neuroimaging, and behavioral indings suggesting a shared representation for t he observation a nd execution of ac tions by primates and human adults (e.g., Bertenthal et al., 2006; Decety & Grèzes, 1999; Rizzolatti et al., 2001; Rizzolatti & Craighero, 2004). he spec ialized c ircuitry a nd a utomatic ac tivation f ollowing observation of an action suggest that the neural mechanisms mediating these functions may be part of the intrinsic organization of the brain. Indeed, this hypothesis is supported by evidence showing neonatal imitation (Meltzof and Moore, 1994). he best known example of imitation in young infants is the evidence for oro-facial gestures
Motor Knowledge and Action Understanding
357
(mouth opening and tongue protrusion) by infants who have never seen their own face (Meltzof & Moore, 1977). Unlike true imitation (cf. Tomasello & Call, 1997), only actions already in the motor repertoire can be facilitated. Still, visual information about the perceived action must somehow be mapped onto the infants’ own motor representations (Meltzof & Moore, 1994). In essence, this is the function of an observation-execution matching system. Corollary evidence on t he prenatal and early postnatal development of these oro-facial gestures is consistent with this conjecture. It is well established that fetuses perform mouth opening and closing and tongue protrusion while in utero (Prechtl, 1986). hus, these gestures are already part of the neonate’s behavioral repertoire at birth. he evidence also suggests that neonates are more likely to match the modeled gesture ater it’s been presented for some period of time (~40 s), rather than immediately (Anisfeld, 1991). his inding is consistent with a motor priming explanation in which activation would be expected to build up gradually as the gesture is modeled, as opposed to an explanation claiming the availability of higher-level processes from birth (cf. Meltzof and Moore, 1994). Finally, the empirical evidence suggests that the likelihood of automatic imitation increases until around 2 months of age, and then declines and virtually disappears by 5 months of age (Fontaine, 1984; Maratos, 1982). It is during this same window of time, approximately 2 and 6 months of age, that neonatal re lexes a re g radually i nhibited (McGraw, 1943), su ggesting that similar cortical inhibitory processes may serve to suppress neonatal imitation. As t he spo ntaneous el icitation o f t hese o vert fac ial g estures becomes gradually inhibited with age, they do not disappear entirely. Instead they become subject to volitional control such that the infant determines when and how they are elicited—imitation is no longer automatic, and the observation of a facial gesture will not lead to its execution by the infant. hus, rather than relecting a precocial social ability of the infant as suggested by Meltzof and Moore (1994), neonatal imitation may relect a striking inability of the infant to inhibit activation of the motor system by direct matching mechanisms. (See Nakagawa, S ukigara, a nd B enga (2003) f or so me p reliminary e vidence supporting this interpretation.) Similar compulsive imitation is observed in adults ater lesions of areas of the frontal lobe involved in inhibitory control (Lhermitte, Pillon, & Serdaru, 1986), and even in healthy adults when attention is diverted (Stengel, 1947).
358
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Although overt imitation of facial gestures ceases with the development of inhibition, covert imitation continues and provides speciic k nowledge about t hese gestures when observed i n others. We suggest that this same developmental process is played out at diferent ages for many other important behaviors (e.g., direction of gaze, visually directed reaching and grasping, vocalizations of sounds). As these behaviors are practiced, the infant develops greater control of their ex ecution a s w ell a s k nowledge o f t heir e fects o r o utcomes. he development of these motor schemas enables infants to covertly simulate and predict the efects of similar actions performed by others. his reliance on the developing control of self-produced actions explains why action understanding continues to develop throughout the lifespan. Finally, t he indings reviewed in t his chapter a re relevant to t he current debate in the literature regarding the development of action understanding. he e arly de velopment o f r epresenting ac tions a s goal-directed ha s be en st udied f rom t wo d iferent t heoretical perspectives: ( 1) ac tion u nderstanding i s r eciprocally co upled t o t he capacity t o produce g oal-directed ac tions ( Hofer, Ha uf, & A schersleben, 2 005; L ongo & B ertenthal, 2 006; S ommerville, Woodward, & Needham, 2005), or (2) recognizing, interpreting, and predicting goal directed actions is an innately based, abstract, and domain-speciic representational system, specialized for identifying intentional agents or for representing and interpreting actions as goal-directed (e.g., Ba ron-Cohen, 1 994; C sibra & G ergely, 1 998; G ergely e t a l., 1995; P remack, 19 90). he irst perspec tive i s co nsonant w ith t he views discussed in this chapter. he seco nd perspec tive s uggests that i nfants a re i nnately s ensitive to abstract be havioral c ues (s uch as self-propulsion, direction of movement or eye gaze) that indicate agency, intentionality, or goal-directedness, irrespective of previous experience with the types of agents or actions that exhibit these cues. Infants are presumed sensitive to unfamiliar actions of humans or unfamiliar agents with no human features from very early in development as long as the actions are consistent with one or more of the proposed abstract cues. Although the indings presented here cannot resolve this controversy, at the very least they cast doubt on the assertion that understanding goal-directed actions is based on an abstract representation that is independent of whether the agents are human or mechanical. In both object search a nd follow t he point st udies, i nfants showed
Motor Knowledge and Action Understanding
359
diferent levels of responding to human and mechanical agents. Moreover, the evidence reviewed on infants’ sensitivities to biological motions suggests that the perceived structure of a point-light display is signiicantly greater when the display depicts a human action as opposed to a fa miliar or u nfamiliar quadrupedal ac tion. A s we and o ur co lleagues co ntinue t o i nvestigate t he e vidence f or co mmon coding of observed and executed actions by infants, we hope to develop a more inely nuanced theory that will reveal what speciic knowledge abo ut ac tions i s i nnate a nd wha t k nowledge de velops with age and experience.
References Anisfeld, M. (1991). Neonatal imitation. Developmental Review, 11, 60–97. Amano, S., Kezuka, E ., & Yamamoto, A. (2004). Infant shiting attention from an adult’s face to an adult’s hand: A precursor of joint attention. Infant Behavior and Development, 27, 64–80. Baldwin, D. A. (1995). Understanding the link between joint attention and language. In C. Moore & P. Dunham (Eds.), Joint attention: Its origins and role in development (pp. 131–158). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Baron-Cohen, S. (1994). How to build a baby that can read minds: Cognitive mechanisms in mindreading. Cahiers de Psychologie Cognitive/ Current Psychology of Cognition, 13, 1–40. Beardsworth, T., & Buckner, T. (1981). he ability to recognize oneself from a video recording of one’s movements without seeing one’s body. Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society, 18, 19–22. Bekkering, H., Wohlschlager, A., & Gattis, M. (2000). Imitation of gestures in children is goal-directed. Quarterly Journal of E xperimental Psychology, 53A, 153–164. Bertenthal, B . I . (1993). Perception of biomechanical motions by i nfants: Intrinsic image and knowledge-based constraints. In C. E. Granrud (Ed.), Carnegie symposium on cognition: Visual perception and cognition (pp. 175–214). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Bertenthal, B. I., Longo, M. R., & K osobud, A. (2006). Imitative response tendencies f ollowing obs ervation o f i ntransitive ac tions. Journal of Experimental P sychology: H uman P erception an d P erformance, 3 2, 210–225. Bertenthal, B. I., & P into, J. (1993). Complimentary processes in t he perception a nd production of human movements. I n L . B . Sm ith & E . hel en (Eds.), A dynamic systems approach to d evelopment: Applications (pp. 209–239). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
360
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Bertenthal, B. I., & Pinto, J. (1994). Global Processing of Biological Motions. Psychological Science, 5, 221–225. Bertenthal, B. I., Proitt, D. R., & Cutting, J. E. (1984). Infant sensitivity to igural coherence in biomechanical motions. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 37, 213–230. Bertenthal, B. I., Proitt, D. R., & Kramer, S. J. (1987). Perception of biomechanical motions by i nfants—Implementation of various processing constraints. Journal of E xperimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 13, 577–585. Bertenthal, B . I ., P roitt, D . R ., K ramer, S . J., & Sp etner, N. B . ( 1987). Infants’ en coding o f k inetic d isplays v arying i n rel ative c oherence. Developmental Psychology, 23, 171–178. Bertenthal, B. I., Proitt, D. R., Spetner, N. B., & homas, M. A. (1985). he development o f i nfant se nsitivity t o b iomechanical m otions. Child Development, 56, 264–298. Bertenthal, B. I., & Von Hofsten, C . (1998). Eye, head a nd t runk control: he foundation for manual development. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 22, 515–520. Blakemore, S . J., & De cety, J. ( 2001). F rom t he p erception o f ac tion to the u nderstanding o f i ntention. Nature Re views N euroscience, 2 , 561–567. Booth, A., Pinto, J., & Bertenthal, B. I. (2002). Perception of the symmetrical patterning of human ga it by i nfants. Developmental Psychology, 38, 554–563. Brass, M., Bekkering, H., & Prinz, W. (2001). Movement observation afects movement e xecution i n a si mple re sponse t ask. Acta Ps ychologica, 106, 3–22. Brass, M., Bekkering, H., Wohlschlager, A., & P rinz, W. (2000). Compatibility b etween obs erved a nd e xecuted inger movements: C omparing s ymbolic, spa tial, a nd i mitative c ues. Brain and C ognition, 4 4, 124–143. Brass, M., Zysset, S., & von Cramon, D. Y. (2001). he inhibition of imitative response tendencies. NeuroImage, 14, 1416–1423. Bruner, J. S. (1969). Eye, hand, and mind. In D. Elkind & J. H. Flavell (Eds.), Studies in cognitive development: Essays in honor of Jean Piaget (pp. 223–235). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Buccino, G., Binkofski, F., Fink, G. R., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., Gallese, V. et al. (2001). Action observation ac tivates premotor a nd pa rietal a reas in a somatotopic manner: An fMRI study. European Journal of Neuroscience, 13, 400–404. Butterworth, G. (2003). Pointing is t he royal road to l anguage for babies. In S. Kita (Ed.), Pointing: Where language, culture, and cognition meet (pp. 61–83). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Motor Knowledge and Action Understanding
361
Butterworth, G., & Morisette, P. (1996). Onset of pointing and the acquisition of language in infancy. Journal of Reproductive and Infant Psychology, 14, 219–231. Calvo-Merino, B., Glaser, D. E., Grezes, J., Passingham, R. E., & Haggard, P. ( 2005). A ction obs ervation a nd ac quired m otor s kills: A n f MRI study with expert dancers. Cerebral Cortex, 15, 1243–1249. Castiello, U ., Lu sher, D ., Ma ri, M ., E dwards, M ., & H umphreys, G . W. (2002). Obs erving a h uman o r a rob otic ha nd g rasping a n ob ject: diferential motor priming efects. In W. Prinz & B. Hommel (Eds.), Common mechanisms in perception and action: Attention and performance (Vol. 12, pp. 315–333). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Chaminade, T., Meary, D., Orliaguet, J.-P., & De cety, J. ( 2001). Is p erceptual anticipation a motor simulation? A PET study. NeuroReport, 12, 3669–3674. Corkum, V., & Moore, C. (1998). he origins of visual attention in infants. Developmental Psychology, 34, 28–38. Csibra, G ., & G ergely, G . ( 1998). he tele ological o rigins o f m entalistic action explanations: A developmental hypothesis. Developmental Science, 1, 255–259. Csibra, G., G ergely, G., Bi ro, S ., Koos, O., & B rockbank, M . (1999). G oal attribution without agency cues: he perception of “pure reason” in infancy. Cognition, 72, 237–267. Cutting, J. E ., Moore, C., & M orrison, R. (1988). Masking the motions of human gait. Perception and Psychophysics, 44, 339–347. Deak, G. O., Flom, R. A., & Pick, A. D. (2000). Efects of gesture and target on 12- and 18-month-olds’ joint visual attention to objects in front of or behind them. Developmental psychology, 36, 511–523. Decety, J., Chaminade, T., Grezes, J., & Meltzof, A. N. (2002). A PET exploration of the neural mechanisms involved in reciprocal imitation. NeuroImage, 15, 265–272. Decety, J., & Grèzes, J. (1999). Neural mechanisms subserving the perception of human actions. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 3, 172–178. Decety, J., & Sommerville, J. A. (2004). Shared representations between self and other: A social cognitive neuroscience view. Trends i n C ognitive Sciences, 7, 527–533. Diamond, A. (1985). he development of the ability to u se recall to g uide action, as indicated by infants’ performance on A-not-B. Child Development, 56, 868–883. Diedrich, F. J., H ighlands, T. M., Spa hr, K . A ., helen, E ., & Sm ith, L . B. (2001). he role of target distinctiveness in infant perseverative reaching. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 78, 263–290. Edwards, M. G., Humphreys, G. W., & Castiello, U. (2003). Motor facilitation following ac tion obs ervation: A b ehavioral s tudy i n prehensile action. Brain and Cognition, 53, 495–502.
362
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Fadiga,L., Fogassi, L., Pavesi, G., & Rizzolatti, G. (1995). Motor facilitation during action observation: A magnetic stimulation study. Journal of Neurophysiology, 73, 2608–2611. Farroni, T., Johnson, M. H., Brockbank, M., & Si mion, F. (2000). Infants’ use of ga ze d irection to c ue attention: he i mportance of perceived motion. Visual Cognition, 7, 705–718. Farroni, T., Massaccesi, S., Pividori, D., & Johnson, M. H. (2004). Gaze following in newborns. Infancy, 5, 39–60. Ferrari, F., Rozzi, S ., & F ogassi, L . (2005). M irror neurons re sponding to observation of actions made with tools in monkeys ventral premotor cortex. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 17, 221–226. Flach, R., Knoblich, G., & P rinz, W. (2003). Of-line aut horship efects in action perception. Brain and Cognition, 53, 503–513. Fogassi, L., Ferrari, P. F., Gesierich, B., Rozzi, S., Chersi, F., & Rizzolatti, G. (2005). Pa rietal lob e: From ac tion o rganization to i ntention u nderstanding. Science, 308, 662–667. Fontaine, R. (1984). Imitative skills between birth and six months. Infant Behavior and Development, 7, 323–333. Frith, C., & Frith, U. (2006). How we predict what other people are going to do. Brain Research, 1079, 36–46. Gallese, V., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., & Rizzolatti, G. (1996). Action recognition in the premotor cortex. Brain, 119, 593–609. Gergely, G ., Nádasdy, Z ., C sibra, G ., & B írό, S . (1995). Taking t he i ntentional stance at 12 months of age. Cognition, 56, 165–193. Greenwald, A . G . (1970). S ensory f eedback m echanisms i n p erformance control: Wit h s pecial re ference to t he id eo-motor me chanism. Psychological Review, 77, 73–99. Grèzes, J., Armony, J. L., Rowe, J., & Passingham, R. E. (2003). Activations related to “mirror” and “canonical” neurones in the human brain: An fMRI study. NeuroImage, 18, 928–937. Grèzes, J., Fonlupt, P., Bertenthal, B. I., Delon-Martin, C., Segebarth, C., & Decety, J. (2001). Does perception of biological motion rely on speciic brain regions? NeuroImage, 13, 775–785. Grèzes, J., Frith, C., & Passingham, R. E. (2004). Inferring false beliefs from the ac tions o f o neself a nd o thers: A n f MRI s tudy. NeuroImage, 21, 744–750. Heyes, C., Bird, G., Johnson, H., & Haggard, P. (2005). Experience modulates automatic imitation. Cognitive Brain Research, 22, 233–240. Hofer, T., Hauf, P., & Aschersleben, G. (2005). Infant’s perception of goaldirected ac tions p erformed by a m echanical c law de vice. Infant Behavior and Development, 28, 466–480. Hommel, B., Musseler, J., Aschersleben, G., & Prinz, W. (2001). he theory of event coding (TEC): A framework for perception and action planning. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24, 849–937.
Motor Knowledge and Action Understanding
363
Hood, B. M., Willen, J. D., & Driver, J. (1998). Adult’s eyes trigger shits of visual attention in human infants. Psychological Science, 9, 131–134. Iacoboni, M., Molnar-Szakacs, I., Gallese, V., Buccino, G., Mazziotta, J. C., & Rizzolatti, G. (2005). Grasping the intentions of others with one’s own mirror neuron system. PLoS Biology, 3, 529–535. Iacoboni, M., Woods, R . P., Brass, M., Bekkering, H., Ma zziotta, J. C ., & Rizzolatti, G. (1999). Cortical mechanisms of human imitation. Science, 286, 2526–2528. Jacobs, A ., P into, J., & Sh ifrar, M . ( 2004). E xperience, c ontext, a nd t he visual perception of human movement. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 30, 822–835. James, W. (1890). he principles of psychology (Vol. 1). New York: Dover. Jeannerod, M . ( 1997). he co gnitive n euroscience o f acti on. C ambridge, MA: Blackwell. Jeannerod, M. (2001). Neural simulation of action: A unifying mechanism for motor cognition. NeuroImage, 14, S103–S109. Johansson, G. (1973). Visual perception of biological motion and a model for its analysis. Perception and Psychophysics, 14, 201–211. Jordan, M . I . (1996). C omputational a spects of motor c ontrol a nd motor learning. In H. Heuer & S. Keele (Eds.), Handbook of perception and action, Vol. 2: Motor skills (pp. 71–120). New York: Academic Press. Kandel, S., Orliaguet, J. P., & Viviani, P. (2000). Perceptual anticipation in handwriting: he role of i mplicit motor c ompetence. Perception and Psychophysics, 62, 706–716. Kawato, M., Furawaka, K., & Suzuki, R. (1987). A hierarchical neural network m odel f or t he c ontrol a nd le arning o f vol untary m ovements. Biological Cybernetics, 56, 1–17. Kilner, J. M ., Pa ulignan, Y ., & Bl akemore, S .-J. ( 2003). A n i nterference efect of ob served biolo gical move ment on a ction. Current Biol ogy, 13, 522–525. Kiraly, I., Jovanovic, B., Prinz, W., Aschersleben, G., & Gergely, G. (2003). he e arly o rigins o f g oal a ttribution i n i nfancy. Consciousness an d Cognition, 12, 752–769. Knoblich, G. (2002). Self-recognition: Body and action. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 6, 447–449. Knoblich, G., Elsner, B., Aschersleben, G., & Metzinger, T. (2003). Grounding the self in action. Consciousness and Cognition, 12, 487–494. Knoblich, G., & Flach, R. (2001). Predicting the efects of actions: Interactions of perception and action. Psychological Science, 12, 467–472. Koski, L ., Iacoboni, M., Dubeau, M.-C., Woods, R . P., & Ma zziotta, J. C . (2003). M odulation o f c ortical ac tivity d uring d iferent imitative behaviors. Journal of Neurophysiology, 89, 460–471.
364
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Lacerda, F., von Hofsten, C., & Heimann, M. (Eds.). (2001). Emerging cognitive abilities in early infancy. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Leung, E. H., & Rheingold, H. L. (1981). Development of pointing as a social gesture. Developmental Psychology, 17, 215–220. Lhermitte, F., Pillon, B., & Serdaru, M. (1986). Human autonomy and the frontal lobes. Part I: Imitation and utilization behavior: A neuropsychological study of 75 patients. Annals of Neurology, 19, 326–334. Longo, M. R., & B ertenthal, B. I. (2006). Common coding of observation and execution of action in 9-month-old infants. Infancy, 10, 43–59. Longo, M . R ., Kosobud, A, & B ertenthal, B. I. (in press). Automatic i mitation of biome chanically i mpossible a ctions: E fects o f p riming movements v s. g oals. Journal of E xperimental P sychology: H uman Perceptions and Performance. Louis-Dam, A ., O rliaguet, J.-P., & C oello, Y. (1999). Perceptual a nticipation in grasping movement: When does it become possible? In M. A. Grealy & J. A. hom son (Eds.), Studies in perception and action V (pp. 135–139). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Loula, F., Prasad, S., Harber, K., & Shif rar, M. (2005). Recognizing people from t heir m ovement. Journal of E xperimental P sychology: H uman Perception and Performance, 31, 210–220. Luo, Y., & Baillargeon, R. (2005). Can a self-propelled box have a goal? Psychological Science, 16, 601–608. Maratos, O. (1982). Trends in the development of imitation in early infancy. In T. G. Bever (Ed.), Regressions in m ental de velopment: Ba sic phenomena and theories (pp. 81–102). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Marcovitch, S., & Z elazo, P. D. (1999). he A-not-B er ror: Results f rom a logistic meta-analysis. Child Development, 70, 1297–1313. Marcovitch, S., Zelazo, P. D., & Schmuckler, M. A. (2002). he efect of the number of A t rials on performance on t he A-not-B task. Infancy, 3, 519–529. Marr, D. (1982). Vision: A computational investigation into the human representation and processing of information. New York: W. H. Freeman. McGraw, M . B . (1943). Neuromuscular m aturation of th e hum an infant . New York: Columbia University Press. Meltzof, A. N., & Moore, M. K. (1977). Imitation of facial and manual gestures by human neonates. Science, 198, 75–78. Meltzof, A. N., & Moore, M. K. (1994). Imitation, memory, and the representation of persons. Infant Behavior and Development, 17, 83–99. Miall, R . C ., & W olpert, D. M . (1996). Forward models for physiological motor control. Neural Networks, 9, 1265–1279. Munakata, Y. (1997). Perseverative reaching in infancy: he roles of hidden toys and motor history in the AB task. Infant Behavior and Development, 20, 405–415.
Motor Knowledge and Action Understanding
365
Munakata, Y. (1998). Infant perseveration and implications for object permanence theories: A PDP model of the AB task. Developmental Science, 1, 161–184. Nakagawa, A., Sukigara, M., & Benga, O. (2003). he temporal relationship between reduction of early imitative responses and the development of attention mechanisms. BMC Neuroscience, 4, http://www.biomedcentral.com/1471-2202/4/33. Orliaguet, J.-P., Kandel, S., & Boe, L. J. (1997). Visual perception of motor anticipation in cursive handwriting: inluence of spatial a nd movement information on the prediction of forthcoming letters. Perception, 26, 905–912. Pavlova, M ., & S okolov, M . ( 2000). O rientation sp eciicity i n biolo gical motion perception. Perception and Psychophysics, 62, 889–899. Pelphrey, K. A., Morris, J. P., & M cCarthy, G. (2005). Neural basis of eye gaze processing deicits in autism. Brain, 128, 1038–1048. Pinto, J. ( 1997). De velopmental c hanges o f i nfants’ p erceptions o f p ointlight d isplays o f h uman ga it. Dissertation A bstracts I nternational: Section B: he Sciences and Engineering, 57(8-B), 5365. Pinto, J., & B ertenthal, B. I. (1992). E fects of phase relations on t he perception of biomechanical motions. Investigative Ophthalmology and Visual Science, 33Suppl., 1139. Pinto, J., & B ertenthal, B. I. (1993). Infants’ perception of u nity i n pointlight displays of human gait. Investigative Ophthalmology and Visual Science, 34 Suppl., 1084. Pinto, J., B ertenthal, B. I., & B ooth, A. (1996). Developmental changes in infants’ re sponses to b iological m otion d isplays. Investigative O phthalmology and Visual Science, 37 Suppl, S63. Pinto, J., Sh rager, J., & B ertenthal, B. I. (1993). Developmental changes in infants’ perceptual processing of biomechanical motions. In Proceedings of th e Annual Conference of th e Cognitive Science Society. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Posner, M . I . ( 1978). Chronometric e xplorations of mind . H illsdale, N J: Erlbaum. Posner, M . I . (1980). O rienting of attention. Quarterly Journal of E xperimental Psychology, 32A, 3–25. Prechtl, H . F. R . (1986). N ew p erspectives i n e arly h uman de velopment. European Journal of Obstetrics, Gynecology and Reproductive Biology, 21, 347–355. Premack, D. (1990). he infant’s theory of self-propelled objects. Cognition, 36, 1–16. Proitt, D. R., Bertenthal, B. I., & Roberts, R. J. (1984). he role of occlusion in reducing multistability in moving point light displays. Perception and Psychophysics, 35, 315–323.
366
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Repp, B ., & K noblich, G . ( 2004). P erceiving ac tion i dentity: H ow p ianists re cognize t heir o wn p erformances. Psychological S cience, 1 5, 604–609. Rizzolatti, G., & Cr aighero, L. (2004). he mirror-neuron system. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 27, 169–192. Rizzolatti, G., Fadiga, L ., Gallese, V., & F ogassi, L . (1996). Premotor cortex a nd t he recognition of motor ac tions. Cognitive Brain Re search, 3, 131–141. Rizzolatti, G., Fogassi, L., & Gallese, V. (2001). Neurophysiological mechanisms underlying the understanding and imitation of action. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 2, 661–670. Rose, J. L., & Bertenthal, B. I. (1995). A longitudinal study of the visual control of posture in infancy. In R. J. Bootsma & Y. Guiard (Eds.), Studies in perception and action (pp. 251–253). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Ruf man, T., & Langman, L. (2002). Infants’ reaching in a multi-well A not B task. Infant Behavior and Development, 25, 237–246. Saxe, R ., X iao, D.-K., K ovacs, G ., Perrett, D. I ., & K anwisher, N. ( 2004). A re gion o f r ight p osterior su perior tem poral su lcus re sponds to observed intentional actions. Neuropsychologia, 42, 1435–1446. Saygin, A. P., Wilson, S. M., Hagler, D. J., Bates, E., & Sereno, M. I. (2004). Point-light biological motion p erception ac tivates human premotor cortex. Journal of Neuroscience, 24, 6181–6188. Scaife, M., & Bruner, J. (1975). he capacity for joint attention in the infant. Nature, 253, 265–266. Schoield, W. N. (1976). Ha nd movements which cross t he body midline: Findings rel ating a ge d iferences to handedness. Perceptual a nd Motor Skills, 42, 643–646. Shif rar, M ., & P into, J. ( 2002). he visual analysis of bodily motion. In W. P rinz & B . H ommel ( Eds.), Common me chanisms in pe rception and action: Attention and performance (Vol. 19, pp. 381–399). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Smith, L. B., helen, E., Titzer, R., & McLin, D. (1999). Knowing in the context of acting: he task dynamics of the A-not-B error. Psychological Review, 106, 235–260. Sommerville, J. A., Woodward, A. L., & Needham, A. (2005). Action experience alters 3-month-old infants’ perception of others’ actions. Cognition, 96, B1–B11. Stengel, E . (1947). A c linical a nd p sychological s tudy of e cho-reactions. Journal of Mental Science, 93, 598–612. Stevens, J. A ., F onlupt, P., Sh if rar, M ., & De cety, J. ( 2000). N ew a spects of motion perception: Selective neural encoding of apparent human movements. NeuroReport, 11, 109–115. Sumi, S. (1984). Upside-down presentation of the Johansson moving lightspot pattern. Perception, 13, 283–286.
Motor Knowledge and Action Understanding
367
Tai, Y. F., Scherler, C., Brooks, D. J., Sawamoto, N., & Castiello, U. (2004). he h uman p remotor c ortex i s ‘ mirror’ o nly f or b iological ac tions. Current Biology, 14, 117–120. helen, E., Schoner, G., Scheier, C., & Smith, L. B. (2001). he dynamics of embodiment: A ield theory of infant perseverative reaching. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24, 1–86. helen, E., & Ulrich, B. (1991). Hidden skills. Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development, 56 (No. 1 Serial No. 223). helen, E., Ulrich, B. D., & Niles, D. (1987). Bilateral coordination in human infants: Ste pping o n a spl it-belt t readmill. Journal of E xperimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 13, 405–410. Tomasello, M. (1999). he cultural origins of human cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Tomasello, M., & C all, J. ( 1997). Primate cog nition. O xford: O xford University Press. van Hof, P., van der Kamp, J., & Savelsbergh, G. (2002). he relation of unimanual and bimanual reaching to crossing the midline. Child Development, 73, 1353–1362. Verfaillie, K. (1993). Orientation-dependent priming efects in the perception of biological motion. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 19, 992–1013. Viviani, P., Baud-Bovy, G., & Re doli, M. (1997). Perceiving a nd tracking kinesthetic s timuli: Fu rther e vidence of motor -perceptual i nteractions. Journal of E xperimental P sychology: H uman P erception an d Performance, 23, 1232–1252. Viviani, P ., & M ounoud, P . ( 1990). P erceptual-motor c ompatibility i n pursuit t racking o f t wo-dimensional m ovements. Journal of M otor Behavior, 22, 407–443. Viviani, P., & Stucchi, N. (1992). Biological movements look uniform: Evidence of motor-perceptual interactions. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 18, 603–623. Vogt, S., Taylor, P., & Hopkins, B. (2003). Visuomotor priming by pictures of hand postures: Perspective matters. Neuropsychologia, 41, 941–951. von Hofsten, C. (2003). On the development of perception and action. In J. Valsiner & K. J. Connolly (Eds.), Handbook of developmental psychology (pp. 114–171). London: Sage. Wapner, S., & Ci rillo, L . (1968). Imitation of a m odel’s ha nd movements: Age c hanges i n t ransposition o f le t-right relations. Child De velopment, 39, 887–894. Wolpert, D. M., Doya, K., & Kawato, M. (2003). A unifying computational framework f or m otor c ontrol a nd s ocial i nteraction. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B, 358, 593–602. Wolpert, D. M., & Fl anagan, J. R . (2001). Motor prediction. Current Biology, 11, R729–732.
368
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Woodward, A . L . (1998). I nfants s electively encode t he goal object of a n actor’s reach. Cognition, 69, 1–34. Woodward, A. L. (1999). Infants’ ability to distinguish between purposeful and nonpurposeful behaviors. Infant Behavior and Development, 22, 145–160. Woodward, A . L ., & Gu ajardo, J. J. ( 2002). I nfants’ u nderstanding of t he point gesture as an object-directed action. Cognitive Development, 17, 1061–1084. Woodward, A. L., & S ommerville, J. A . (2000). Twelve-month-old infants interpret action in context. Psychological Science, 11, 73–77. Zelazo, P. D., Reznick, J. S ., & Spinazzola, J. (1998). Representational lexibility and response control in a multistep multilocation search task. Developmental Psychology, 34, 203–214.
11 How Mental Models Encode Embodied Linguistic Perspectives
Brian MacWhinney
Humans d emonstrate a re markable a bility to t ake ot her p eople’s perspectives. W hen w e w atch m ovies, w e ind o urselves i dentifying with the actors, sensing their joys, hopes, fears, and sorrows. As viewers, we c an be m oved t o ex hilaration a s we w atch our h eroes overcome obstacles; or we can be moved to tears when they sufer losses and defeats. his process of identiication does not always have to be l inked to i ntense emotional i nvolvement. At a soc cer match, we c an follow t he movements of a p layer moving i n to shoot for a goal. We can identify with the player’s position, stance, and maneuvers a gainst t he cha llenges ofered by t he defenders. We c an t rack the actions, as t he player drives toward t he goal a nd k icks t he ba ll into the net. his ability to take the perspective of another person is very general. Just as we follow the movements of dancers, actors, and athletes, we can also follow the thoughts and emotions expressed by others in language. In this paper, we will explore the ways in which language builds upon our basic system for projecting the body image to support a r ich system of perspective tracking and mental model construction.
369
370
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Projection It is useful to think of projection as relying on the interaction of four systems, each of which is fundamental to psychological functioning. hese four systems involve body i mage, localization, empathy, a nd perspective tracking.
Body Image Matching In order to assume t he perspective of another actor, one must irst be ab le t o co nstruct a f ull i mage f or o ne’s o wn body. his image expresses not only t he positions of our organs a nd l imbs, but a lso their movements and conigurations. For most of us, the notion of a body schema is something natural and inescapable. However, there are v arious n eural d isorders a nd i njuries ( Ramachandran, 2 000; Ramachandran & Hubbard, 2001) that can lead to the disruption of the body image. he construction of the body image is based on processing in a w ide variety of sites including the cerebellum (Middleton & S trick, 1998), medial prefrontal cortex (Macrae, Heatherton, & Kelley, 2 004), primary motor cortex (Kakei, Hofman, & St rick, 1999), and insula (Adolphs, 2003). In order to achieve perspective taking, we need a system that can project our body i mage t o o ther a gents. he irst step in this process must involve body part mapping. We have to identify speciic organs or body parts on others that we then map onto parallel parts in our own body i mage. Meltzof (1995) and others have traced the roots of body part matching back to infancy, when the baby can already demonstrate matching by imitating actions such a s tongue protrusion or head motions. We have learned t hat, when a sub ject in an f MRI experiment tracks t he movements of a pa rticular limb or organ, there is corresponding activation of the same neural pathways t he subject would use to produce t hose actions. For example, when w e i magine per forming b icep c urls, t here a re d ischarges t o the biceps (Jeannerod, 1997). When a t rained marksman imagines shooting a gun, the discharges to the muscles mimic those found in real target practice. When we imagine eating, there is an increase in salivation. Neuroimaging studies by Parsons et al. (1995) and Martin, Wiggs, Ungerleider, a nd Ha xby (1996) a nd Cohen et a l. (1996) have shown that, when subjects are asked to engage in mental imag-
How Mental Models Encode Embodied Linguistic Perspectives
371
ery, t hey use m odality-speciic s ensorimotor c ortical s ystems. For example, in the study by Martin et al., the naming of tool words speciically activated t he areas of t he let premotor cortex that control hand movements. Similarly, when we observe pain in a particular inger i n a nother person, t ranscranial ma gnetic st imulation shows activation of the precise motor area that controls the muscle for that same inger (Avenanti, Bueti, G alati, & Ag lioti, 2 005). he general conclusion from this research is that, once we have achieved body part matching, we can perceive t he ac tions of others by projecting them onto the mechanisms we use for creating and perceiving these actions ou rselves. I n e fect, w e r un a cog nitive s imulation ( Bailey, Chang, Feldman, & Narayanan, 1998) and we match the products of this cognitive simulation to our perception of the actions of others. his ability to compute a cognitive simulation is at the heart of both projection and imagery. From recent single-cell work with monkeys, we know that perceptual-motor ma tching i s a v ery g eneral a spect o f t he p rimate brain. Apart from the mirror neurons (Rizzolatti, Fadiga, Gallese, & Fogassi, 1996) that were originally identiied in the monkey counterpart to Broca’s area, there are also perceptual-motor matching systems in other areas of both frontal and parietal cortex. he facility with wh ich we a re able to project perspec tive onto others suggests that the body matching system is probably quite extensive, but the exact extent of this system is not yet known.
Localization In order to assume t he perspective of another actor, one most a lso position that actor correctly in mental space. To do this we rely on the same system that allows us to locate our own bodies in space. his system must be robust against eye movements and turns of the head (Ballard, Hayhoe, Pook, & Rao, 1997); it should allow us to maintain facing and update our position vis-à-vis landmarks and other spatial conigurations (Klatzky & Wu; Proitt, this volume). Once we have succeeded i n projecting our body i mage to t he other, we c an next begin to position this projected image in the distal physical location (Loomis & Philbeck, this volume). One diicult part of this projection i s t he r equirement t hat w e r otate o ur body i mage 180º i f t he other person is facing us.
372
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Empathy In order to assume the emotional and social perspective of another, we must irst be ab le to have access to our own emotions. We c an then project or transfer these feelings to others. Of course, there is no doubt that humans have a well-organized system of emotions that maps into physiological expression through the face, body, and autonomic nervous s ystem. Once we have ach ieved projection of body image and spatial location, we can begin to identify with the emotions of the other person. Studies of patients with lesions (Adolphs & Spezio, 2006) have pointed to a role for the amygdala in the processing of emotional expression. Studies w ith normals using f MRI (Meltzof & Decety, 2003) have shown activation in the amygdala and temporal areas (Pelphrey et al., 2003; Pelphrey, Morris, & McCarthy, 2005; Pelphrey, Viola, & McCarthy, 2004) for the processing of social expressions and actions.
Perspective Tracking To obtain smooth projection, we must be able to constantly update, shit, a nd t rack t he other actor on each of t hese d imensions (body image, spa tial l ocation, em pathy). To d o t his, w e ha ve t o t reat t he other body as obeying the same kinematic principles that govern our own body (Knoblich, this volume). At the same time, we must be able to distinguish the projected or imagined image from our own body image. his means that the tracking system must allow us to treat the projected image as “ictive” or “simulated” and our own body image as real. Ma intaining t his t ype of clear s eparation be tween simulation and reality would seem to require special neuronal adaptations. hese ad aptations i nclude m irror n eurons a s o ne co mponent, b ut they also require additional support from frontal areas for attention and r egulation. his additional support is required to allow us to shit perspective between multiple ex ternal agents. For t his system to function smoothly, we must store a coherent ictive representation of t he other person. In order to switch smoothly between perspectives, it is crucial that the projected agent be easily accessed and constructed as a clearly separate ictive representation. Researchers such a s Do nald (1991) a nd Giv on (2002) ha ve p roposed that, two million years ago, homo erectus relied on a system of
How Mental Models Encode Embodied Linguistic Perspectives
373
gestural and mimetic communication to further social goals. Adaptations that supported this tracking of visual perspectives would have f ormed a n e volutionary subst rate f or t he la ter elabo ration o f perspective tracking in language (MacWhinney, 2005). here is still a close temporal a nd conceptual l inkage between gesture a nd la nguage (McNeill, 1992), suggesting that both systems continue to rely on a core underlying set of abilities to track perspective. Subjective evidence from drama, movies, and literature suggests that identiication is a dynamic and integrated process. his process produces a lowing match between our own motoric and emotional functions and the motoric and emotional functions of others. However, n eurological e vidence r egarding t he dy namic f unctioning o f this system is still missing. We know that there is neuronal support for each of the four projection systems. However, we cannot yet follow perspective tracking in real time. In large part, this gap in our knowledge i s a f unction of t he l imitations of m easurements t aken through methods such as fMRI and ERP.
The Perspective Hypothesis Fortunately, there is evidence of a very diferent type that can help us understand the nature of ongoing projection and perspective taking. his is the evidence that is encoded in the structure of grammatical systems. Close a nalysis shows how g rammar relects the cognitive operations u nderlying perspec tive t racking. I r efer t o t his g eneral view o f m ental p rojection a s t he perspec tive h ypothesis. W e c an decompose the overall perspective hypothesis into six more speciic assumptions or claims: 1. Language functions by p romoting the sharing of mental models between the speaker and the listener. 2. To build up complex mental models, referents a nd ac tions must be connected dynamically through temporal, spatial, and causal linkages. 3. he l inks i n m ental m odels a re s tructured by p erspective tracking. 4. Perspective tracking is supported by speciic neuronal projection systems that keep these cognitive simulations separate from direct perception and action.
374
5.
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
he primary function of grammatical devices is to mark perspective tracking, as it emerges in conversation and narrative. 6. Perspective tracking, as realized in language, facilitates the linking o f m ental s ystems a nd t he c ultural t ransmission o f l inked structures.
For ps ychologists a nd cog nitive l inguists, t he irst t wo a ssumptions a re la rgely u ncontroversial. S ince t he beg inning o f t he C ognitive R evolution, r esearchers h ave a ssumed t hat c omprehension involves the construction of linkages in complex mental models. In regard to these irst two claims, the perspective hypothesis is simply building on traditional, well-supported, assumptions. he traditional form of assumption 3 i s that that discourse linkages i nvolve coreference between nodes i n semantic st ructure. For example, we could have a discourse composed of two simple propositions in a sentence such as: the boy kicked the ball, and the ball rolled into the gutter. In the mental model or semantic memory constructed from this sentence, the ball of the irst clause is linked through coreference to the ball of the second clause. In classic models of sentence interpretation (Budiu & Anderson, 2004; Kintsch & Van Dijk, 1978), the ma in m echanism f or d iscourse l inkage w as co reference. E ven models t hat d ecomposed s emantic s tructure ( Miller & J ohnsonLaird, 1976) still maintained a reliance on coreference as the method for linking propositions in mental models. he perspective hypothesis introduces a fundamental shit in our understanding o f t he co nstruction o f m ental m odels. I n t his n ew view, wh ich i s en coded a s a ssumption 3 , p ropositions a re em bodied representations constructed from a speciic perspective, which is initially the perspective of the sentential subject. We can refer to the combined i nteraction o f perspec tive t aking a nd perspec tive sh iting a s perspec tive t racking. A lthough co reference p lays a s econdary r ole i n l icensing l inkage be tween propositions, mental models use perspec tive t racking a s t heir p rimary i ntegrating m echanism. In the case of our simple example sentence, this means that the perspective of the boy in the irst sentence is sh ited to that of the ball in the second clause and we then track the motion of the ball as it rolls into the gutter. In other words, we construct mental models by taking and shiting perspectives. Within this larger process of perspective tracking, deixis, or verbal pointing, plays a role of bringing new referents to our attention or locating referents in either working memory or long-term memory. However, the structuring of proposi-
How Mental Models Encode Embodied Linguistic Perspectives
375
tions into mental models depends primarily on taking the perspective of the entities discussed in a discourse and tracking this low of perspective between the various discourse participants. Assumption 4 is grounded on the growing evidence from cognitive neuroscience regarding speciic neuronal systems t hat manage the projection of body image, spatial location, and emotion. Without making t his assumption, it would be v ery diicult to imagine how one could believe that language processing relies intimately and continually on neuronal support for perspective tracking. Assumption 5 i s t he c enterpiece o f t he perspec tive h ypothesis. When this assumption is linked to assumption 3, it takes on a particularly st rong f orm. he co mbination o f t hese t wo a ssumptions represents a n ovel pos ition i n cog nitive s cience. Re searchers wh o emphasize the formal determination of linguistic structure (Chomsky, 1975) have repeatedly rejected links between grammatical structure a nd “pragmatic” fac tors such a s perspec tive t aking. A lthough cognitive linguistics provides a role for perspective in the theory of subjectivisation (Stein & Wright, 1995), there is little acceptance of assumption 3. Despite the importance of embodied cognition to cognitive linguistics, there are no current models in this tradition that rely on perspec tive t racking a s t he major force i ntegrating m ental models. Within experimental psychology, recent work has focused on demonstrating the embodied nature of mental models. For example, Stanield and Zwaan (2001) found t hat, when given sentences such as John poun ded th e n ail into th e loor, subjects a re fa ster to na me pictures of nails pointing downward than nails pointing sideways. his indicates that they construct interpretations with a na il pointing downward. Results of this type, summarized in the chapters in Pecher and Zwaan (2005), provide clear and important evidence for the embodied nature of mental models, but they tell us little about perspective t racking. To ex amine t he co urse o f perspec tive t racking experimentally, we will need to use online measures of interpretation, such a s c ross-modal na ming, wh ich w ill a llow u s t o p robe ongoing changes in mental models as they are being constructed. Assumption 6 focuses on the consequences of perspectival mental models for promoting conceptual integration and cultural transmission. Perspectival mental models provide a g eneral rubric for k nitting together all of cognition. Consider a sentence, such as Last night, my sister’s friend reminded me I had dropped my keys under the table behind th e ga rage. H ere, w e s ee h ow a s ingle u tterance integrates
376
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
information about time (last night), social relations (sister’s friend), mental a cts ( remind), spac e ( under, be hind), ob jects ( keys, tabl e, garage), a nd ev ents ( drop). he sentence produces an integrated tracking across the perspectives of the sister, the friend, the speaker, and t he v arious l ocations. A lthough t his i nformation ma y be i nitially activated in diferent regions of the brain, language achieves an integration of this information across all of these domains. he p rimary f ocus o f t his pa per i s o n a ssumption 5 . W e w ill conduct this exploration in three parts. We will begin with a psycholinguistic account of how perspectives are shited t hrough sentence st ructures. Second, we w ill conduct a l inguistic examination of a w ide r ange o f g rammatical co nstructions t o u nderstand h ow they mark perspective tracking. Finally, we will consider the consequences of this analysis for theories of cognition and development in accord with assumption 6.
Perspective Tracking Modern psycholinguistic research has tended to focus on the process of sentence comprehension or interpretation, rather than sentence production. It is much easier to achieve experimental control over comprehension t han over production. B ecause our models of sentence i nterpretation a re m ore de tailed, i t i s e asiest t o ex plain the function of perspective tracking irst for comprehension and to extend this account later to perspective marking in production. On the comprehension side, there are ive important principles that have a direct bearing on perspective tracking. 1.
2.
Incremental In terpretation. he irst p rinciple, w hich ha s b een widely supported in recent research, is the principle of incrementalism. According to this principle, the listener attempts to go from words to mental models as soon as material is unambiguously recognized. In processing terms, incrementalism is equivalent to the notion of c ascading (McClelland, 1979) i n w hich processes feed into each other as soon as t hey reach a p oint where data can be passed. Load R eduction. I n s ome c ases, p rocessing ma y i nvolve pl acing phrases i nto w orking m emory w ithout ye t c ommitting to t heir grammatical role o r w ithout a ttaching t hem to o ther p hrases. However, if the listener can attach material to a f ully interpreted mental model, then this will reduce processing load.
How Mental Models Encode Embodied Linguistic Perspectives
3.
4.
5.
377
Starting Points. his principle of load re duction t hrough attachment ( Gibson, 1 998) i nteracts w ith a t hird p rinciple t hat g overns t he centrality of t he starting point (MacWhinney, 1977) or the A dvantage o f F irst M ention (Gernsbacher, 1 990). W hen w e begin a sentence, we use the irst nominal phrase as the basis for structure building (Gernsbacher, 1990). As we move through the sentence from let to right incrementally, we add to this structure through attachments. When a phrase or word cannot be attached, it i ncreases t he load . S o, w e a re m otivated to a ttach p hrases a s soon as possible to reduce these costs (O’Grady, 2005). Role Slots. he process of phrasal attachment is driven by role slot assignments. In d iferent m odels, t his p rinciple ha s v ery d iferent names, varying from thematic role assignment to theta-binding. he basic idea (MacWhinney, 1987a) is that predicates (verbs, adjectives, prepositions) e xpect to at tach to no minal a rguments that i ll various thematic or case roles, such as agent, object, or recipient. For l anguages t hat rely o n SVO, S OV, or VSO orders, the irst noun is placed tentatively into the role of the perspective. his perspective t hen actively searches for a v erb t hat w ill a llow it to assume a dynamic perspective. For example, in the sentence the runner fell, we begin with the perspective of the runner as the starting p oint. We t hen m ove o n i ncrementally to t he v erb fall. At that point, the linkage of runner to the role slot for a perspective for fell allows us to build a mental model in which the runner engages in the action of falling. Competition and Cu es. Role s lot i lling i s a c ompetitive p rocess ( MacWhinney, 1 987a). I n c omprehension, s everal n ominal phrases o r “ slot i llers” ma y c ompete f or a ssignment to a g iven slot and role. Only one of the i llers can win this competition, and the losers must then compete for other slots. he outcome of the competition is determined by the presence of grammatical, lexical, and semantic cues that favor one or the other competitor. he process of cue summation obeys basic Bayesian principles.
At this point, it would perhaps be useful to think about how these ive principles lay the groundwork for the Perspective Hypothesis. In a sense all of these principles are integrated by the basic need during comprehension to construct a m ental model. he pr inciples of incremental i nterpretation a nd load reduction a re d irect responses to t he fac t t hat t here i s a cost a ssociated w ith ma intaining u nattached verbal chunks in short-term memory. In order to reduce this cost, we adopt the initial hypothesis that the irst nominal is the perspective. Because the construction of mental models is perspectival
378
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
(assumption 3 abo ve), we are able to take this starting point as the foundation for a larger mental model. he status of the starting point as the perspective is further supported if it can compete successfully for the perspective slot on the verb. In some marked constructions and word orders, it may lose out in this competition. But to understand how this happens, we need to look more closely at the dynamics o f perspec tive t racking t hrough g rammatical co nstructions. Some of the forces that work to either maintain or shit this initial perspective include: 1. Shit. If the verb takes multiple thematic roles, then it may shit perspective from the starting point to secondary perspectives. his can o ccur f or t ransitives, pa ssives, c lets, a nd a v ariety o f o ther constructions. In most cases, this shit i s not c omplete, a nd t he perspective of the starting point is at least partially maintained. 2. Modiication. I ndividual ref erents ma y b e f urther m odiied or el aborated by a ttached p hrases a nd c lauses. his occ urs i n relativization, c omplex N P f ormation, app ositives, a nd o ther constructions. 3. Maintenance. P erspective c an b e ma intained ac ross c lauses by devices (or cues) such as anaphoric pronouns, gerunds, resumptives, and conjunctions.
Structure vs. Function Having now listed the general assumptions of the perspective hypothesis, we are in a position to explore the application of this hypothesis to a wide variety of syntactic constructions. However, before beginning t hat ex ploration, w e n eed t o co nsider a co mpeting a pproach that accounts for some, but not all of the phenomena to be discussed. his approach, developed within generative linguistics over the last 50 years (Chomsky, 1957), which attempts to account for syntactic patterns in terms of structural relationships. Of t he various structural r elationships ex plored d uring t his ha lf c entury, per haps t he most prominent is the relation called c-command. We will therefore begin our exploration by comparing two diferent accounts of coreference—one based on the constraints imposed by c-command and another based on t he constraints imposed by perspective tracking. his analysis is not intended to reject a possible role for c-command in linguistic description. Rather, the goal here is illustrate the impact of perspective tracking on grammatical constructions.
How Mental Models Encode Embodied Linguistic Perspectives
379
Coreference We will begin our explorations with a consideration of a few selected aspects of the grammar of coreference. Consider sentences 1 and 2: Coreference b etween he and Bill is possible in (1), but blocked in 2. 1. 2.
*Hei says Billi came early. Billi says hei came early.
he coreferential reading of these sentences is marked by the presence of subscripts on the nominals. Without these subscripts and the coreference they require, the pronoun he in 1 c an refer to someone mentioned outside of the sentence, such as Tom. What is speciically blocked in 1 is coreference between he and Bill as indicated by their subscripts. he perspec tive h ypothesis acco unts f or t he u ngrammaticality of 1 by invoking the principle of referential commitment. When we hear he in 1, we need to take it as the starting point for the construction of a m ental model for the clause. his means that we must make a referential commitment. We cannot wait until later to identify he. In (2), on the other hand, Bill is already available for coreference and so it is easy to link he to Bill. he theory of government and binding (Chomsky, 1982; Grodzinsky & Rei nhart, 1993; Rei nhart, 1981) s eeks to ex plain t his phenomenon (and ma ny o thers) i n ter ms o f st ructural r elations i n a phrase-marker tree. he backbone of this account is a relation known as c-command. Each element in the tree is said to “c-command” its siblings a nd t heir de scendants. Pr inciple C o f t he b inding t heory requires that lexical NPs such as Bill or the man be “free”; that is, not coindexed with a c-commanding element. his principle excludes a coreferential reading for 1 in which Bill is coindexed with the c-commanding pronoun, but not for 2 i n which t he i ntended a ntecedent c-commands the pronoun rather than vice versa. Grammatical subjects are always in a syntactic position that allows them to c-command other elements in the same clause. his means that there is a very close parallel between the patterns expressed in ccommand and the principle of referential commitment from the perspective hypothesis. Because initial nominals serve as the bases for structure building and perspective propagation, it is initially diicult to distinguish the structural account from the functionalist account. However, i f we l ook cl osely, we w ill s ee t hat t here a re a variety of
380
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
phenomena that can be understood better in terms of mental model construction than in terms of c-command. Noncentrality One i nteresting contrast i s t he r elative i ncrease i n ac ceptability of coreference t hat oc curs a s o ne m oves f rom c entral t o per ipheral arguments. C-command blocks coreference in 3 and 4. his prediction of c-command is correct for 3. However, for many speakers, 4 is possible, although c-command disallows it. 3. 4 . 5. 6.
*Hei said Billi was crazy. *John told himi that Billi was crazy. John said to himi that Billi was crazy. John told hisi mother that Billi was crazy.
Although c -command ma kes t he w rong p redictions f or 4 , i t co rrectly allows for coreference in 5 a nd 6, since the pronouns here do not c-command Bill. he perspective hypothesis views this contrast in a very diferent way. As a further corollary of assumption 3 and its corollary of referential commitment, we have the following: Principle o f N oncentrality: I f a n e lement i s not c entral to t he bu ilding of a me ntal mo del, t hen it ne ed not b e re ferentially c ommitted a nd i s therefore op en for b ackward a naphora. he le ss c entrally i nvolved t he element, the more it is open for backward anaphora.
he most central argument is the subject (he in 3), followed by the object (him in 4), the oblique or prepositional object (him in 5), and inally a possessor in a complex NP (his in 6). As these roles become less and less central to the process of structure building, they become more and more open to backward anaphora. Delaying Commitment C-command p rovides n o ac count f or t he g rammaticality o f s entences such as (7–9). his is because pronouns in subordinate clauses are too low in the structure to have NPs in other clauses as siblings. 7. 8. 9.
Ater Lesteri drank the third vodka, hei dropped his cup. Ater hei drank the third vodka, Lesteri dropped his cup. *Hei drank the third vodka, and Lesteri dropped his cup.
How Mental Models Encode Embodied Linguistic Perspectives
381
Although bo th 8 a nd 9 ha ve a p ronoun t hat p recedes t he t arget noun Lester, t he coreferential reading of 8 i s e asier to get t han the coreferential reading of 10. A lthough c-command provides no account for this contrast, it can be explained by reference to the perspective hypothesis. To do this, we can rely on the following corollary derived from assumption 5. Principle of Cue Marking: he default process of perspective tracking can be modiied by grammatical cues that signal delays in referential commitment, clausal backgrounding, or shits in perspective.
In t he c ase of 8 , t he c rucial g rammatical c ue i s t he subordinating conjunction ater, which signals the beginning of a background clause. I n t he co nstruction o f a m ental m odel, back ground ma terial is placed “on hold” for later attachment to foreground material. However, the storage of the backgrounded initial clause of 8 does not incur a la rge p rocessing cost , s ince i ts co mponent p ieces a re f ully structured. Moreover, as long as it remains in the background, the pronoun can be i nvolved in backward coreference. Because there is no cue i n 9 t o protect t he pronoun, it must be co mmitted referentially and backward anaphora is blocked. As a further illustration of the efect of grammatical cues in the delaying of commitment, consider the contrast between 10 and 11. 10 . *Shei jumped inside the car, when Debra i saw a large man lurking in the shadows. 1 1. Shei w as j umping i nside t he c ar, w hen Deb ra i s aw a l arge ma n lurking in the shadows.
Here the presence of progressive aspect in 11 places the information in the main clause “on hold” in the mental model, because this information is being judged as relevant to the interpretation of the subsequent clause. In a s eries of experiments, Harris a nd Bates (2002) show that progressive marking leads to greater acceptance of backward anaphora. hus, the progressive functions like the subordinating conjunction as a cue to delaying of commitment. A similar efect is illustrated by 12 and 13 from Reinhart (1983). 1 2. In Carter’si hometown, hei is still considered a genius. 1 3. In Carter’si hometown, hei is considered a genius.
382
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Here, it is easier to get a coreferential reading for 12 than for 13. his is because still serves as a c ue that forces perspective promotion in the preposed prepositional phrase. he opposite side of this coin involves the way in which indeinite reference blocks forward anaphora (i.e., the establishment of coreference between a f ull nominal and a f ollowing pronoun). It is somewhat easier to achieve forward anaphora in 14 than in 15. 14. While Ruth argued with the mani, hei cooked dinner. 15. *While Ruth argued with a mani, hei cooked dinner.
In the case of 14, once we shit perspec tive f rom Ruth to the man, we now have a deinite person in mind and it makes good sense to continue that perspective with he. In 15, on the other hand, we have no clear commitment to the identity of a man and using this unclear referent as the binder of he seems strange.
Reflexivization he c-command relation is also used to account for patterns of grammaticality in the use of relexive pronouns, such as herself or myself. he most common use of these pronouns is to mark coreference to a “clausemate,” which is oten the subject of the current clause, as in 16 and 17. 1 6. *Mary i pinched heri. 17 . Mary i pinched herself i.
he perspective of t he relexive is a r ather remarkable one, since it forces the actor to look back on herself as both the cause of the action and the recipient of the action at the same time. When bo th r eferents a re c entral a rguments, r elexivization is mandatory. S entences l ike 1 6 a re i mpossible i f t he t wo n ominals are coreferential. However, i f one of t he nominals is central to t he process of s entence building, a nd i f t he other material i n t he s entence serves to shit perspective away from the starting point, then a clausemate coreferent can use a nonrelexive pronoun. Sentences 18 and 19 illustrate this.
How Mental Models Encode Embodied Linguistic Perspectives
383
18 . Phili hid the book behind himi/himself i. 19 . Phili ignored the oil on himi/himself i*.
In 18, n onrelexive co reference a nd r elexive c oreference a re b oth possible. In 19 only anaphoric coreference is possible. his is because the act of hiding tends to maintain the causal perspective of “Phil” more than the act of ignoring. When Phil hides the book, it is still very much in his mind and so its position vis-à-vis his body still triggers self-reference. However, when Phil ignores the oil, it is no longer in his mind. At this point, the observation of the oil is dependent on an outside viewer and no longer subject to relexivity. Nouns such as story or picture can also trigger perspective shiting within clauses. In 20 and 21, relexives are required if there is coreference, because there is no intervening material that shits perspective away from either John or Mary. In 22, however, the nonrelexive is possible, since the story sets up a new perspective from which John is viewed as an actor in the story and not a l istener to the story. In 23, the action of telling involves Max so deeply in the story itself that the full perspective shit is impossible and the non-relexive cannot be used. 20. 21. 22 . 23 .
John talked to Mary i about *heri/herself i. John talked to Mary i about *himi/himself i. Johni heard a story about himi/himself i. Max i told a story about *himi/himself i.
he p resence o f i ntervening perspec tives fac ilitates t he u se o f short distance pronouns that would otherwise be blocked by relexives. Consider these examples: 24 . Johni saw a snake near himi/himself i. 25 . Jessiei stole a photo of heri/herself i out of the archives.
he material that detracts from the relexive perspective may also follow t he p ronoun, a s i n t hese ex amples f rom Tenny a nd S peas (2002). 26. Johni signaled behind himi/himself i to the pedestrians. 27 . Billi pointed next to himi/himself i at the mildew on the roses. 2 8. Luciei talked about the operation on heri/herself i that Dr. Edward performed.
384
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
In these sentences, use of the nonrelexive prepares the listener for a shit of perspective following the pronoun. Without that additional material, the nonrelexive would be strange. Finally, perspective shit can also be induced by evaluative adjectives such as beloved or silly, as in these examples from Tenny and Speas (2002): 29 . Jessiei stole a photo of *heri/herself i out of the archives. 30 . Jessiei stole a silly photo of heri/herself i out of the archives.
In all of these cases, creation of an additional perspective can serve to shit attention away from the core relexive relation, licensing use of a nonrelexive pronoun.
Ambiguity Syntactic a mbiguities a nd g arden pa ths a re t ypically de scribed i n terms of the construction of alternative structural trees. However, we can also view ambiguities as arising from the competition (MacDonald, Pearlmutter, & Seidenberg, 1994; MacWhinney, 1987b) between alternative perspectives. Moreover, if we look closely at the processing of t hese a mbiguities, t here is evidence for perspec tive t racking efects that go beyond simple structural competition. Consider the examples in sentences 31 to 34. 31. 32. 33. 34.
Visiting relatives can be a nuisance. Crying babies can be a nuisance. Teasing babies is unfair. If they arrive in the middle of a workday, visiting relatives can be a nuisance.
Looking at each of these ambiguities in terms of the principle of incremental interpretation, we can see how alternative perspectives organize alternative interpretations. In each case, there is a competition be tween t he overtly ex pressed noun following t he pa rticiple and a n u nexpressed subject. I n each c ase, t he pa rticiple is looking to ill the subject/perspective role. In example 31, it is plausible that relatives could be visiting. With relatives illing t he role of t he perspective, the interpretation is that “if relatives visit you, they can be a nuisance.” At the same time, we are also able to imagine that some unspeciied person serves as the omitted perspective of visit. In this
How Mental Models Encode Embodied Linguistic Perspectives
385
case, the relatives ill the role of the object, yielding the interpretation that “it can be a nuisance to pay a visit to one’s relatives.” In example 32, on t he other ha nd, t he verb is intransitive. If we were to associate the perspective with an unexpressed subject, then we wou ld have no role for babies. So, here, only one interpretation is possible, and it involves the babies as the initial perspective. hat initial perspec tive is e ventually sh ited at t he word nuisance, since we ha ve t o t ake t he perspec tive o f t he perso n bei ng a nnoyed t o understand how the babies become a nuisance. In 33, the babies are unlikely to be d oing t he teasing a nd t hey serve as good objects, so the unexpressed subject wins the role of perspective. In 35, the foregrounding of they in the irst clause prepares the way for perspective continuation t o t he seco nd cla use wh ich p romotes relatives as t he subject of v isiting. A lthough, we c an st ill ind a n a mbiguity i n 34, we are less likely to notice it than in 31. As we trace through these various competitions, we see that the demands for incremental construction of a perspectival mental model work to shape the extent to which we can maintain alternative ambiguous perspectives. Perspectival a mbiguity c an a lso a rise f rom t he co mpetition between alternative phrasal attachments. In example 35, the initial perspective resides with Brendan. Although the verb ly would prefer to have a preverbal noun serve as its perspective, the implausibility of seeing a c anyon ly t hrough t he a ir tends to force us away f rom this syntactically preferred option. 35. 36. 3 7. 38 .
Brendan saw the Grand Canyon lying to New York. Brendan saw the dogs running to the beach. he women discussed the dogs on the beach. he women discussed the dogs chasing the cats.
However, t he sh it t o t he perspec tive o f the d ogs is easier in 36, although a gain w e c an ma intain t he perspec tive o f Brendan if we wish. In cases of prepositional phrase attachment competitions, such as 37, we can maintain the perspective of the starting point or shit to the direct object. If we identify with the women, then we have to use the beach as the location of their discussion. If we shit perspective to the dogs then we can imagine the women looking out their kitchen window and talking about the dogs as they run around on the beach. In 38, on the other hand, we have a harder time imagining that the women, instead of the dogs, are chasing the cats. Sentences such a s
386
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
37 a nd 38 ha ve motivated a v ariety of formal accounts of sentence processing within the framework of the Garden Path account (Frazier, 1987). For these sentences, the perspective hypothesis provides an acco unt t hat f ocuses o n co nceptual co mpetitions, r ather t han recovery from nonconceptual parsing decisions. It is possible to shit perspective abruptly between clauses by treating the verb of the irst clause as intransitive and the following noun as a n ew subject. A sh it of this type is most likely to occur with a verb like jog that is biased toward an intransitive reading, although it can also function as a transitive. Examples 39 to 41 illustrate this efect: 39. Although John frequently jogs, a mile is a long distance for him. 40. Although John frequently jogs a m ile, the marathon is too much for him. 41. Although John f requently smokes, a m ile i s a sho rt d istance for him.
Detailed s elf-paced r eading a nd e ye-movement st udies o f s entences like 39, with the comma removed, show that subjects oten slow down just ater reading a mile. his slow-down has been taken as evidence for the garden-path theory of sentence processing (Mitchell, 1994). However, it can also be interpreted as relecting what happens during the time spent in shiting t o a n ew perspec tive wh en the cues preparing the processor for the shit are weak. Examples of this type show that perspectival shit ing is an integral part of online, incremental sentence processing (Marslen-Wilson & Tyler, 1980). his description of the processing of these ambiguities has relied on the six assumptions stated earlier. In particular, these perspective shits are triggered by alternative activations of role i llers and phrasal attachments, a s s peciied i n g reater de tail i n de scriptive ac counts such as MacWhinney (1987a) or O’Grady (2005) or in computationally explicit models such a s Kempen a nd Hoenkamp (1987) or Hausser (1999). hese competitions play out as we add incrementally to the ongoing perspectival mental models we are creating. Syntactic processes play out t heir r ole t hrough t he competitive operation of role i lling and attachment, but the actual shit of perspective occurs within t he m ental m odel t hat i s bei ng co nstructed i n a s imulated perspectival space.
How Mental Models Encode Embodied Linguistic Perspectives
387
Scope Ambiguities i n q uantiier s cope p rovide a v ery d iferent w ay o f understanding the operation of perspective tracking. To understand what is at issue here, consider this example: 42. Every boy climbed a tree.
For s entences t hat beg in w ith q uantiied n ominals l ike every boy, the construction of a n i nitial perspec tive is more complex t han i n the case of sentences that begin with a s imple nominal like my dog or Bill. For simple nominals, we only have to create a single uniied imagined agent i n perspec tival space. For quantiied nominals, we have to create a perspective that allows for multiple agents. Moreover, right from the beginning, we have to take into account the nature of the quantiier. We can t hink of quantiied perspectives in terms of Venn diagrams (Johnson-Laird, 1983). For the phrase every boy, we set up a Venn diagram that includes several nodes characterized as boys. We do not need to actually count these nodes in our imagination. Instead, we use an automated procedure for perspective activation that sets up enough imagined nodes to satisfy us that there are several boys. We then link every to climb by duplicating the acts of climbing across the multiple perspectives. We do not have to actually make each boy engage in climbing in our mind. Instead, we can rely on an automated procedure that makes one boy climb and then assumes that the others will “do the same.” he ambiguity in sentence 42 arises when we come to a tree. At this point, we have the option of imagining climbing either a single tree or multiple trees (O’Grady, 2006). We can think of this ambiguity as involving a single uniied multiple perspective with many boys and one tree versus a d ivided multiple perspective with many boys and many trees. If we imagine that the initial perspective constitutes a uniied group, we are relatively less likely to imagine multiple trees. In fact, the nature of the verb determines the extent to which we keep a uniied or divided multiple perspective. Consider t hese examples from O’Grady (2006): 43. Everyone gathered at a restaurant. 44. Everyone surrounded a dog.
388
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Here, the activity of gathering or surrounding requires the individuals i n t he i nitial multiple perspec tive t o ac t i n concert. W hen they ac t t his w ay, t he co mponents o f t he m ultiple perspec tive a re more likely to focus on a single object, rather than multiple objects. hus, t he sh it to a u niied s ingle r epresentation f or t he ob ject i s determined by the embodied representation of the subject’s perspective as it combines with the activity of the verb. Scope ambiguities also display interesting interactions with grammatical constructions t hat sh it t he order of s entence elements. I n example 45, we can imagine either that the students are all reading the same books or that each student is reading a diferent set of three books. his contrast is much like the contrast in 42 between a multiple perspective that remains uniied when processing the object and a multiple perspective that divides when processing the object. 45. Two students read three books. 4 6. hree books are read by two students.
In 46, on the other hand, it is diicult to imagine more than one set of three books. As a result, 46 does not permit the ambiguity that we ind i n 45. his efect i llustrates t he operation of a ssumption 3 regarding the conceptual centrality of the starting point. According to assumption 3, starting points constitute the foundation stone for the construction of the rest of the ediice of the sentence. Because the remaining ediice rests on this foundation stone, we need to make as full a commitment as we possibly can to the referential clarity of the starting point. We can express this particular corollary of assumption 3 in these terms: Principle of R eferential C ommitment: N ominals t hat a re b eing u sed a s starting points should be linked to unambiguous referents in mental models. I f f ull d einite c oreference c annot b e a chieved, t hen nom inal starting points are assumed to be uniquely identiiable new referents.
In t he c ase o f 4 6, t his m eans t hat, o nce three book s a re post ulated in mental space they cannot be multiplied into two sets of three books as in 45. his same principle is involved in the construction of interpretations for sentences like 47 to 50: 4 7. he devoted environmentalist tracked every mountain goat. 48. A devoted environmentalist tracked every mountain goat.
How Mental Models Encode Embodied Linguistic Perspectives
389
4 9. he boy ate every peanut. 50. A boy ate every peanut.
he contrast in these sentences is between starting points that are fully referential, as in 47 and 49, and those that are indeinite, as in 48 and 50. When the starting point is fully referential, it cannot later be divided by backwards multiplication of perspectives. As a result, 47 and 49 a re not ambiguous. However, in 48 we can imagine each mountain goat being tracked by a diferent environmentalist. To do this, we return to the perspective of the starting point and multiply that perspec tive. his multiplication of perspectives is possible for 48, bec ause i ndeinite perspec tives a re not a s f ully committed referentially a s de inite perspec tives. I n 50, we c an i magine a s imilar ambiguity, although the idea of many boys each eating only one peanut is perhaps a bit silly. Perspective t racking t heory a lso ex plains wh y 5 1 a nd 5 2 a re acceptable, whereas 53 is questionable. In 51 the perspective of every farmer is distributed so that each of the farmers ends up owning a well-fed donkey. In this perspective, there are many donkeys being fed. his means t hat we can continue in (52) by asking whether or not all of these donkeys will grow. Sentence (53), on the other hand, forces us to break this distributive scoping and to think suddenly in terms of a single donkey, which violates the mental model set up in the main clause. 51. Every farmer who owns a donkey feeds it. 52. Every farmer who owns a donkey feeds it, but will they grow? 53. Every farmer who owns a donkey feeds it, but will it grow?
Relativization Restrictive r elative cla uses p rovide f urther e vidence o f t he i mpact of perspective shit ing on sentence processing diiculty. Processing these st ructures c an r equire u s t o co mpute m ultiple sh its o f per spective. Consider these four types of restrictive relative clauses: 5 5 5 5
4. 5. 6. 7.
SS: OS: OO: SO:
he dog that chased the cat kicked the horse. he dog chased the cat that kicked the horse. he dog chased the cat the horse kicked. he dog the cat chased kicked the horse.
0 switches 1- switch 1+ switch 2 switches
390
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
In the SS type, the perspective of the main clause is also the perspective of the relative clause. his means that there are no true perspective switches in the SS relative type. In the OS type, perspective lows f rom t he ma in clause subject (dog) to t he ma in clause object (cat) in accord with the general principle of partial shit of perspective to the object. At the word that perspective then lows further to the cat as the subject of the relative clause. his perspective shit is made less abrupt by the fact that cat had already received secondary focus b efore t he s hit w as made . I n t he OO t ype, perspec tive a lso switches once. However, in this case, it switches more abruptly to the subject of the relative clause. In the SO relative clause type, there is a double perspective shit. P erspective begins with the main clause subject (dog). When the next noun (cat) is encountered, perspective shits once. However, at the second verb (kicked), perspective has to shit back t o the initial perspective (dog) to complete the construction of the interpretation. Sentences w ith m ultiple ce nter e mbeddings h ave e ven m ore switches. Consider an example like (58) which has four diicult perspective switches (dog -> cat -> boy -> cat -> dog). 58 . he dog the cat the boy liked chased snarled. 59. M y m other’s b rother’s w ife’s si ster’s do ctor’s f riend had a he art attack.
Sentences that have as much perspective shit ing as 58, without additional lexical or pragmatic support, are incomprehensible, at least at irst hearing. But note that the mere stacking of nouns by itself is not enough to t rigger perspec tive sh it overload. C onsider example 59. In that example, we do not really succeed in taking each perspective and s witching to t he next. I nstead, we just a llow ourselves to sk ip over e ach perspec tive a nd la nd o n t he la st o ne m entioned. I n t he end, we just know that someone’s friend had a heart attack and fail to track the relation of that friend to the mother’s brother. In the terms of a p rocessing model, we can say t hat we continue to push words onto a stack and end up losing track, in terms of our mental model, of the items that were pushed down to the bottom of the stack. In the case of 59, we still end up with an interpretable sentence. In the case of 58, the result makes little sense. Researchers have oten t ried to account for these processing dificulties in structural terms. However, fMRI work (Booth et al., 2001;
How Mental Models Encode Embodied Linguistic Perspectives
391
Just, Carpenter, Keller, Eddy, & hulborn, 1996) has contrasted the processing of object relative sentences like 57 with the processing of subject r elatives l ike 5 4. hese st udies ha ve sh own t hat 57 p roduces g reater ac tivation i n a w ide variety of let-hemisphere areas. Models such as that proposed by Grodzinsky and Amunts (2006) have attempted to link structural complexity to processing in Broca’s area. But the f MRI results show that complexity leads to activation across a far wider area. his wider proile of activation is consistent with t he i dea t hat t he c omplexity in volved i s n ot s tructural, b ut rather involves the fuller construction of switched perspectives in a full mental model. Perhaps n o s entence ha s igured m ore h eavily i n d iscussions o f sentence processing than example 60. 6 0. he horse raced past the barn fell.
he co mpetition m odel ac count o f p rocessing i n r educed r elative sentences of this t ype emphasizes the dual morphological f unction of verbal sui x -ed. his sui x can mark either the past tense or the past pa rticiple. W hen -ed ma rks t he pa st tense, t he verb raced is a simple intransitive with horse as its subject or perspective. However, when -ed marks the participle, then the verb raced allows for a nonexpressed subject and takes the horse as the object, much as in the shit of sentence 32 above with the visiting relatives. Because the resting activation of the past tense interpretation of the sui x is higher than that of the participle, listeners may not pick up the participle interpretation until they realize that the sentence will not parse with the pa st tens e i nterpretation. I n t his c ase, w e s ense a g arden pa th because we only ac tivate t he weak perspective coniguration when the strong coniguration fails. However, similar conigurations will behave very diferently. For example, in 61, we sense no garden path because there is no noun following kept that would allow the transitive r eading a nd w e t herefore ha ve t o r ely o n t he r educed r elative reading. In 62, there is no ambiguity, because the irregular participle cannot be confused with the past tense. 6 1. he bird kept in the cage sang. 6 2. he car driven past the barn honked.
392
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Clitic Assimilation As a further, detailed example of the impact of perspective taking on grammar, let us consider the process of clitic assimilation. In English, the ininitive to oten fuses with a preceding modal verb to produce contractions such as wanna from want to in cases such as 64. However, this assimilation is blocked in environments like the one in 65, making 66 unacceptable. 63. 64. 65. 66.
Who do you want to see? Who do you wanna see? Who do you want to go? *Who do you wanna go?
he perspective hypothesis views the reduced ininitive in 64 as a cue that marks perspective maintenance. In 65, this reduction is impossible, because there is a forced processing shit from who to you and then b ack t o who(m). I ninitive r eduction a lso ma rks perspec tive maintenance in examples 67 to 69. 67. I get ta go. (Privilege) 68. I got ta go. (Privilege, past tense) 69. I gotta go. (Obligation)
In 67 and 68 , t he privilege of going is due presumably to the intercession o f a n o utside pa rty. he perspec tive o f t his o utside pa rty interrupts perspec tive ma intenance. I n 6 9, o n t he o ther ha nd, t he obligation is i nternal to t he speaker a nd perspec tive is ma intained across the reduced ininitive.
Implicit Causality Much of our a nalysis here ha s focused on perspec tive ma rking by highly grammaticalized forms like pronouns, participles, gerundives, relativizers, a nd i ninitives. However, perspec tive ma rking ex tends far beyond g rammatical forms, appearing w idely i nside adjectives, verbs, nouns, and prepositions. Individual lexical items can characterize complex social roles and mental acts. Items like libel, Internet, or solidarity, encode social scenarios organized about t he perspective of social actors. Let us take the noun libel as an example. When
How Mental Models Encode Embodied Linguistic Perspectives
393
we spe ak o f so me co mmunication a s bei ng “ libelous,” w e a re t aking t he perspec tive o f a n “ accused” perso n wh o decla res t o so me general audience t hat t he (purported) l ibeler ha s a sserted t hat t he accused has engaged in some illegal or immoral activity. Moreover, the accused wishes to convince the general audience that the libeler’s claims are false and designed to make the audience think poorly of the accused in ways t hat inluence his or her ability to f unction in public life. his single word conveys a complex set of interacting and shiting social perspectives. To evaluate whether or not a st atement is libelous, we have to assume the perspective of the accused, the purported l ibeler, a nd t he audience t o e valuate t he v arious cla ims and possible counterclaims. All of this requires continual integration and shiting of social roles and mental acts. Verbs l ike promise, forgive, admire, a nd persuade al so e ncode multiple relations of expectation, beneit, evaluation, and prediction between soc ial ac tors. To e valuate t he u ses of t hese verbs requires lexible perspec tive t aking a nd coo rdination. W ithin t his la rger group of me ntal s tate ve rbs, one d imension of c ontrast i s k nown as “ implicit causality.” Sentence 70 illustrates the implicit causality coniguration of t he ex periencer-stimulus verb admire. he causal coniguration is revealed in the second clause where the subject (she) is t he c ause o f t he ad miration. I n s entence 7 1, w ith t he st imulusexperiencer verb apologize, causality remains with the subject of the irst clause (John). 70. John admired Mary i, because shei was calm under stress. 71 . Johni apologized to Mary, because hei had cracked under stress.
According to the perspective hypothesis, shits in causality should lead to s hits i n perspec tive. To t rack t hese sh its experimentally, McDonald and MacWhinney (1995) asked subjects to listen to sentences like 70 and 71, while making a cross-modal probe recognition judgment. Probe targets included old nouns (John, Mary) new nouns (Frank, Jill), old verbs (admire, apologize), and new verbs (criticize, resemble). he probes were placed at various points before and ater the pronoun (he and she). he task was to j udge whether the probe was old or new. McDonald and MacWhinney found that stimulusexperiencer verbs like apologize in 71 tend to p reserve the reaction time advantage for the irst noun (John) as a p robe throughout the sentence. I n ter ms o f t he perspec tive h ypothesis, t his m eans t hat
394
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
perspective is not shited away from the starting point in these sentences. However, experiencer-stimulus verbs like admired in 69 tend to force a shit in perspective away from the starting point (John) to the stimulus (Mary) right at the pronoun. his leads to a per iod of time a round t he pr onoun du ring w hich Mary ha s r elatively fa ster probe recognition times. However, by the end of the sentence in 70, the advantage of the irst noun reappears. he fact that these shits are bei ng processed i mmediately on-line i s e vidence i n support of the perspective hypothesis. In addition to encoding implicit causality, verbs can also encode information regarding implicit source of knowledge. 72. 73. 74. 75.
Minnie told Dorothy that she knew Superman. Minnie asked Dorothy if she knew Superman. Minnie reminded Dorothy that she knew Superman. Minnie told Dorothy that she made Superman cry.
In 72, we assume that Minnie has access to knowledge about herself which she provides to Dorothy. In 73, on the other hand, we assume that Dorothy must be t he source of t he i nformation, since M innie would certainly have access to her own knowledge. A lthough both 74 and 75 could be read ambiguously, the most probable reading in each case is one that maintains the perspective of the starting point. Adults are able to maintain the viewpoint of the initial subject even in t he co mplement cla use. A t t he s ame t ime, t hey u se fac ts abo ut the verb ask to sh it perspec tive i n 73. However, be tween 5 a nd 8 , children (Franks & Connell, 1996) are more likely to shit to the perspective of Dorothy in all of these sentences. his tendency to shit perspective arises from a general preference for local attachment evident at this age. It is possible that children are not able to coordinate the dual perspectives of the main and subordinate clause eiciently for these structures during this age range (Huttenlocher & Presson, 1973).
Perspectival Overlays In t he p receding s ections, w e ha ve f ocused o n t he w ays i n wh ich grammatical devices provide cues that help listeners track shits o f perspective. hese shits have i nvolved t he ac tions a nd motions of agents, as they operate on other objects. his system of causal action
How Mental Models Encode Embodied Linguistic Perspectives
395
marking i s at t he core of perspec tive t racking a nd it i s t he s ystem that is marked most overtly through grammatical constructions and forms. However, t here are at least ive other systems of perspective shiting that function as linguistic overlays on this basic system of perspective tracking. hese include the systems for marking perspective in space, time, empathy, evidentiality, and metaphor. Although these s ystems a re of g reat i mportance for mental model construction, t hey h ave r elatively li ttle im pact o n gr ammatical s tructure, relying instead on marking through individual lexical items.
Space Spatial l ocalization i s f undamental t o perspec tive t racking. he linguistic ma rking o f spac e r elies o n p repositions, m otion v erbs, and names for landmarks. Sometimes t he marking of location can involve perspe ctival a mbiguity. C onsider t his c lassic i llustration from Cantrall (1974): 7 6. he adults in the picture are facing away from us, with the children behind them.
In this example, we see a competition between alternative reference points. If we take the perspective of the adults as our reference point, then t he children are located between t he adults and t he v iewer of the picture. If we take the perspective of the viewers of the picture as the reference point, the children are located on the other side of the adults, farther away from us. Ambiguities of this type are reminiscent of the shits in reference point in sentences like 35 where we can imagine either imagine ourselves lying to New York or else see the Grand Canyon lying to New York. However, on a structural level, 76 is not ambiguous, whereas 35 is. In other words, the ambiguities we ind in spatial perspective taking are not relected in the grammar. However, they are clearly relected in our mental models. his is why we can consider perspective taking in space as an overlay on grammar. Perspectival competitions can arise even from what seems to be a single reference point. For example, i f we a re ly ing down on our backs in a h ospital bed, we might refer to the area beyond our feet as in f ront o f me , e ven t hough t he a rea be yond t he f eet i s u sually
396
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
referred to as under me. To do this, we may even imagine raising our head a b it to correct t he reference ield, so t hat at least our head is still upright. Because spatial reference is so prone to ambiguity of this type, we have developed many linguistic devices for reducing such ambiguities. One way of reducing ambiguity is to use a third position as the reference point. For example, i f we describe a pos ition a s bei ng 50 yards behind the school, it is not clear whether we are taking our own position as the reference point for behind or whether we are using the facing of the school as the reference point. To avoid this problem we can describe the position as 50 yards toward the mountain from the school. In this case, we are taking the perspective of the mountain, rather than that of the speaker or the school. We then construct a temporary Cartesian grid based on the mountain and perform allocentric projection to the school. hen we compute a d istance of 50 yards from the school in the direction of the mountain. Languages such as Guugu Yimithirr (Haviland, 1993) and Mayan take this solution yet one step fa rther by setting up per manent maplike coordinates against which all locations can be pinpointed.
Time Perspective t aking i n t ime i s closely a nalogous t o perspec tive t aking in space. Like space, time has an extent through which we track events in terms of their relation to reference moments. Just as spatial objects have positions and extents, events have locations in time and durations. Just as we tend to view events as occurring in front of us, rather than behind us, we also tend to view time as moving forwards from past to future. As a result, it is easier to process sentences like 77 with an iconic temporal order than ones like 78 with a reversed order. However, sentences like 79 which require no foreshadowing of an upcoming event are the most natural of all. 77 . Ater we ate our dinner, we went to the movie. 78. Before we went to the movie, we ate our dinner. 79. We ate our dinner and then we went to the movie.
Temporal r eference i n na rrative a ssumes a st rict i conic r elation between the low of the discourse and the low of time. Processing of
How Mental Models Encode Embodied Linguistic Perspectives
397
sequences that violate temporal iconicity by placing the consequent before the antecedent is relatively more diicult (Zwaan, 1996). However, in practice, it is diicult to describe events in a fully linear fashion a nd we need to ma rk lashbacks a nd ot her d iversions t hrough tense, aspect, and temporal adverbials.
Empathy he third system of perspectival overlays involves marking for empathy. Here, Tenny and Speas (2002) have conducted a useful survey of devices used by various languages. Among the most marked of these devices a re e valuative adjectives such a s beloved or damned. C onsider these examples: 80. John was looking for Sarah’s beloved cat. 81. John was looking for Sarah’s damned cat.
In 80, the cat is beloved from Sarah’s point of view. In 81, however, the cat is damned from either John’s point of view or the speaker’s point of view. Language is laden with evaluative perspectives of this type. However, much of the evaluation we convey in everyday interaction is encoded equally well through intonation and gesture—areas that lie outside the scope of our current exploration.
Evidentiality A fourth area of perspectival overlay involves the marking of the evidence sources a nd t ypes. For ex ample, we may k now some t hings because we saw them directly with our own eyes, whereas we know others t hings bec ause w e ha ve h eard t hem f rom t rusted so urces. Oten, w e s imply ma ke a ssertions w ithout p roviding i nformation regarding e vidence. In other c ases, we may a sk questions, i ndicate doubt, express belief, and so on. An example of the role of evidential perspective is t he contrast between statements and questions. Consider the contrast between 82 and 83: 82 . he bicyclist appears to have escaped injury. 83. Did the bicyclist appear to have escaped injury?
398
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
8 4. he re porter s aid t hat t he b icyclist app eared to ha ve e scaped injury. 8 5. he re porter a sked i f t he b icyclist app eared to ha ve e scaped injury.
In 82 the evidence is evaluated on the basis of evidence available to the speaker. In 83, on the other hand, the evidence is evaluated on the ba sis of e vidence available to t he l istener. E xamples 8 4 a nd 85 display a similar asymmetry. In English, the marking of iner d imensions o f e videntiality i s conveyed by particles and adverbs such a s well, sure, still, and just. In other languages, these same forms can appear as markings on the verb. Some languages pay close attention to ine distinctions in the source a nd na ture of t hese e vidences. Japanese d isplays a pa rticularly interesting restriction on evidence relected in 86 and 87: 86. You are sick. 87. You seem sick.
In Japanese, one cannot say 86, because it is presumptuous to imagine that one has access to inner states of another person. In fact, it might e ven be a b it i nappropriate t o p roduce 8 7. his constraint, known as “speaker’s territory of knowledge” (Kamio, 1995), involves aspects of both evidentiality and empathy. he tracking of evidential perspectives occurs primarily on the level of t he f uller discourse or narrative. On t his level, we use particular constructions to help our listeners locate objects in their own mental models. In efect, we construct mental models of the mental models of our listeners a nd use t hese to determine t he marking of evidentiality. As Givon (2005) puts it, speakers select grammatical constructions on the basis of their “mental models of the interlocutor’s current deontic and epistemic states.”
Metaphor A it h area of perspectival overlay on language involves the use of metaphor. he production and comprehension of metaphors, similes, and analogies has been a lively topic now for nearly three decades in both the linguistic and psychological literature. Examples 88 and
How Mental Models Encode Embodied Linguistic Perspectives
399
89 illustrate some of the typical patterns studied in this vast descriptive and experimental literature. 8 8. 89. 90. 91.
he road runs down to the river. Headline: Congress stumbles in debate on tax reform. Stocks took a plunge at the end of the day. His marriage was like a glacier.
Everyday conversational speech makes very little use of metaphor, but other genres, ranging from inancial reporting to pop psychology, rely heavily on extensions of the type illustrated in 89 and 90 to liven up otherwise boring prose. Lakof and Johnson (1980) have shown how a small set of core metaphors, based on embodied cognition, dominates our construction of mental models. Fauconnier and Turner (1996) have further described the blending of multiple perspectives t hat oc curs i n mental models. Perhaps t he most remarkable of t hese blends a rise i n d rama a nd poe try when we t rack t he perspectives of actors in plays within plays within stories, as in Macbeth and he Story of the Tailor in he Arabian Nights. he processing of perspec tive i n metaphors a nd blends i nvolves conceptual overlays on language, much like the processing of perspective in space, time, empathy, or evidentiality. Like these other systems, the processing of metaphor makes no direct contact with grammar, f unctioning i nstead t hrough s emantic ex tension o f t he meanings of individual words such as stumble or glacier. However, it would be a m istake to ig nore t he ramiications of t hese t ypes of processing for our theories of neuronal encoding of perspectives in mental models. he perspectival complexity of Macbeth or he Arabian Nights marks only the beginning of complex mental models that must be en coded i n verbal form. For t ruly d azzling levels of complexity we can turn to Grigori Perelman’s solution of the Poincaré conjecture or the chains of reasoning in cases argued at the Supreme Court of the United States.
Production and Integration Having examined the marking of perspective through grammar, we are now ready to consider how language integrates across these various levels or layers of perspective taking. he best way to explore this
400
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
issue is to consider snippets of actual narratives and conversations. Consider this passage from an Associated Press release in 2001. 92. A c yclone ha mmered t he B angladesh c oast M onday w ith t he force of “hundreds of demons” leveling entire villages of mud and thatch huts, looding crops, and killing at least six people.
his passage beg ins f rom t he perspec tive of t he c yclone. It t hen uses a metaphorical image to allow the storm to act as an agent that wields a hammer. he past tense sui x on the verb hammered places this ac tion i nto t he pa st. he object of t he ha mmering is t he Ba ngladeshi coast. he coast is brought on stage, but there is no shit of perspective away from the cyclone and its hammering. Immediately ater coast we have the introduction through Monday of a temporal overlay. hen, t he metaphor of hammering is linked to the force of hundreds of demons. he perspective of the cyclone continues with leveling,looding, and killing. In each case, our attention moves briely to the objects without really shiting away from the cyclone. In this sentence, there is a rich combination of images from many modalities. he c yclone i s a v isual i mage, t he ha mmer i s a v isual image l inked t o motor movements of t he a rm a nd perceptions of noise and percussion. he image of the Bangladesh coast brings to mind the position of Bangladesh on a map of the Bay of Bengal, along with a t race o f t he del ta f ormed b y t he B rahmaputra. he image of Monday forces us to refer to our recent calendrical memory to locate this event in a spatial analog to time. he images of demons bring to mind scenes from Indian art with black demon faces lying through the air and stories from the Vedas. We do not count out the demons i n detail, but roughly i magine a n a rray of ma ny demons, perhaps ex tending o ver a w ide p hysical spac e a long t he coa st t o accommodate their great number. When we link entire to villages, we have to engage in a mental activity of leveling that is completive and leaves no huts standing. Similarly, when we lood the crops, we have to imagine a whole scene with plants under water and when we envision the killing, we actually envision six dead bodies, although we are not exactly sure how they died. Together, the construction of the image for just this sentence relies on diverse cognitive systems for motor action, space, time, enumeration, quantiier scope, visual imagery, s emantic me mory, me taphor, ge ography, ge ometry, a nd biology.
How Mental Models Encode Embodied Linguistic Perspectives
401
Some might like to t hink of t hese systems as cognitive modules (Pinker, 1997). It is certainly true t hat t hese diverse cognitions a re supported by widely separated brain regions with highly diferentiated functions, but it is misleading to think of language as popping together beads produced by encapsulated modules, as suggested by Carruthers (2002). I nstead, la nguage a llows d iverse a reas t o w ork in concert and to achieve communication by writing to the “blackboard” of the sentence currently under construction. In this sense, language does i ndeed promote i ntegration ac ross t hese nonmodular cog nitive s ystems i n a w ay t hat c an promote cog nitive g rowth (Spelke, 2002). In fact, it makes sense to think of language as providing a springboard for recent human cultural evolution, by allowing us to construct integrated mental models (MacWhinney, 2005; Mithen, 1996) t hat led t o t he f urther elaboration of consciousness (Dennett, 1991), social structure, and religious imagination (Campbell, 1949). he se relections regarding information integration through perspective taking have been grounded so far on the single example sentence 92. his same passage continues with the material in 93. 9 3. hree men and two children were crushed under collapsed buildings o r h it by lying p ieces o f t in ro ofs i n t he s outhern p ort o f Chittagong. One man died in Teknaf, about 110 miles down t he coast, when he w as blown of h is roof, while t rying to s ecure it. he storm roared in from the Bay of Bengal with wind gusts of 125 mph, forcing a half-million people to lee their huts and huddle in concrete shelters. Many power and telephone lines were down, so a full account of casualties and damage was not available.
In this continuation, we shit from the initial perspective of the cyclone in 92 to the perspective of people being crushed. his involves a passive perspective, as marked by the -ed sui x. he actual causal agents follow later. he irst agent is totally missing, since the fact that it was the cyclone that caused the buildings to collapse is not expressed. For the set passive verb hit the agent is lying pieces of tin roofs. Here, we begin with the notion of lying even before we know what might be lying. We soon realize that what is lying are pieces of tin roofs, and we try to imagine how the cyclone pulled these pieces of of their roofs. As we read through a pa ssage quickly, we may decide not to perform the extra mental work needed to ill out this further detail
402
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
of t he mental model. Even before we shit t o the perspective of the lying pieces, we must s ee t he v ictims c rushed u nder buildings or being hit. We do not know which victims were crushed and which were hit by lying pieces of roof, so we just imagine some of each in both positions without trying to do any actual count. Next we s hit from Chittagong to Teknaf. he shit i n spac e i s accompanied by the introduction of the new perspective of one man. For this man, we irst imagine him dead, then we see how he is passively blown of his roof by t he c yclone as t he u nmentioned agent, and then we must put him back on his roof and imagine him trying to secure the roof. his order of events is the opposite of the actual order and building up a mental model in opposite order can be dificult. An alternative version of this sentence would read as in 94. 94. In Teknaf, 110 miles down the coast, a ma n was trying to s ecure his roof when the cyclone blew him of to his death.
Next we shit perspective back to the storm as in now acts not just on six people, but half a million. Finally, we move to viewpoint of the reporter, who explains that it was not possible to give a full report of the casualties because telephone lines were down. his analysis of a news story selected at random illustrates the extent to which language weaves together diverse cognitions into the common grid of the sentence. Sentences achieve this integration by mixing together adjectives, lexical metaphors, quantiiers, descriptive v erbs, n umerals, t emporals, p repositional p hrases, p assives, omitted subjects, participles, adverbs, conjunctions, and a wide variety of other grammatical devices. Some of these devices mark referents, some mark perspective shits, and others add spatial, temporal, and evaluative overlays to the basic causal grid. If we move beyond examples like this, to examination of spontaneous conversation, the landscape changes markedly. Instead of weaving together places, times, and actors, conversations weave together diverse v iewpoints, u nderstandings, a nd g oals. C onversations a re heavily dedicated to the maintenance of interpersonal relations and the e stablishment o f mutual k nowledge. Ag ainst t his back ground, perspective t racking st ill plays a n i mportant role, but t he perspective being tracked is one that is under continual negotiation between the conversational participants. A fuller examination of these issues is c urrently u nderway i n t he context of a nalyses of conversational interactions in classrooms (Greeno & MacWhinney, 2006).
How Mental Models Encode Embodied Linguistic Perspectives
403
Cultural Transmission Vygotsky (1934) believed that children’s conversational interactions played a fundamental role in their cognitive development. He viewed these interactions as setting a model for mental structures that children would then internalize as “inner speech.” He characterized inner speech in terms of processes such a s topic-comment structure and ellipsis, but provided no additional linguistic or cognitive detail. he perspective hypothesis can be viewed as an elaboration of the initial Vygotskyan program. he idea here is that, by tracking perspective in conversations and narratives, children construct mental models that encode perspectival patterns in long term memory. Because these models are extracted from adult input, the perspective tracking and causal reasoning they contain will relect the st andards o f t he ad ult co mmunity. F or ex ample, i f fa iry t ales begin w ith p hrases s uch a s once upon a time , f ar, f ar a way, t hen children will also learn to construct mental models for fairy tales in a cognitive space t hat is far away or imaginary in space and time. If the eforts of the valiant prince lead eventually to happiness and marriage, t hen ch ildren w ill b uild m ental m odels i n wh ich t hese expectations are linked. If the eforts of a determined little locomotive allow it to pull a train up a hill, children will also imagine that they c an ach ieve g oals t hrough de termination. I n e fect, children will use perspectivally constructed models extracted from conversation and narrative as a method for learning the systems and values o f t heir c ulture. I n t his p rocess, t he l inks de veloped t hrough perspective t aking on a ll t he levels we have d iscussed a re c rucial. Without language and the perspective tracking it allows, this level of cultural transmission would not be possible. Developmentalists have extended the Vygotskyan vision by linking the construction of mental models to play (Eckler & Weininger, 1989), games (Ratner & Bruner, 1978), narration (Bruner, 1992; Nelson, 1998), apprenticeship (Lave, 1991), learning contexts (Rogof, 2003), and conversational sequencing (Bateson, 1975). What is common in all of these accounts is the idea that children are exposed to interactions in which they track the logical low of ideas perspectivally. From this process, they extract internalized mental models that are speciic to their cultures and social groups (Spradley, 1972) that they can then transmit to others (Blackmore, 2000).
404
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Conclusion In this paper we have examined the ways in which the perspective hypothesis c an o fer n ew ex planations f or a v ariety o f pa tterns i n grammar a nd s entence p rocessing. I n t his n ew f ormulation, t he links in mental models are viewed as inherently perspectival and grounded on simulated, embodied cognition. his cognitive system relies on a wide range of neuronal structures for body image matching, spatial projection, empathy, and perspective tracking. Language uses t his u nderlying s ystem to ach ieve st ill f urther cog nitive i ntegration. W hen spe akers p roduce s entences, t hey u se g rammatical devices to integrate diverse perspectives and shits. When listeners process t hese s entences, t hey u se g rammatical ma rkers, co nstructions, and lexical forms to decode these various shited and overlaid perspectives. Because perspective taking and shit ing are fundamental to communication, language provides a wide array of grammatical devices for speciically marking perspective and perspective shit. Language a llows u s t o i ntegrate i nformation f rom t he d omains o f direct experience, space, time, plans, causality, evidentiality, evaluation, empathy, and mental acts. Across each of these dimensions, we assume and shit between perspectives in order to construct a f ully human, uniied conscious awareness.
Acknowledgments hanks t o W illiam O ’Grady, J ames Gr eeno, R oberta K latzky, a nd Marnie Arkenberg for their comments on this paper. his work was supported by NSF Award SBE-0354420.
References Adolphs, R . ( 2003). C ognitive n euroscience o f h uman s ocial b ehavior. Nature Reviews of Neuroscience, 4, 165–178. Adolphs, R., & Spezio, M. (2006). Role of the amygdala in processing visual social stimuli. Progress in Brain Research, 156, 363–378. Avenanti, A., Bueti, D., Galati, G., & Aglioti, S. (2005). Transcranial magnetic s timulation h ighlights t he s ensorimotor s ide of e mpathy for pain. Nature Neuroscience, 8, 955–960.
How Mental Models Encode Embodied Linguistic Perspectives
405
Bailey, D ., C hang, N., F eldman, J., & N arayanan, S . ( 1998). E xtending embodied lexical development. Proceedings of the 20th Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society, 20, 64–69. Ballard, D. H ., Ha yhoe, M . M ., P ook, P. K ., & R ao, R . P. (1997). Dei ctic codes f or t he emb odiment o f c ognition. Behavioral and Br ain S ciences, 20, 723–767. Bateson, M. (1975). Mother–infant exchanges: he epigenesis of conversational interaction. In D. Aaronson & R. Rieber (Eds.), Developmental psycholinguistics an d c ommunication di sorders ( pp. 1 12–140). N ew York: New York Academy of Sciences. Blackmore, S. (2000). he power of memes. Scientiic Ame rican, October, 64–73. Booth, J. R ., MacWhinney, B., hulborn, K. R., Sacco, K., Voyvodic, J. T., & F eldman, H . M . (2001). De velopmental a nd le sion e fects during brain ac tivation f or s entence c omprehension a nd m ental ro tation. Developmental Neuropsychology, 18, 139–169. Bruner, J. (1992). Acts o f m eaning. C ambridge, M A: Ha rvard U niversity Press. Budiu, R., & A nderson, J. (2004). Interpretation-based processing: A u niied theory of semantic sentence comprehension. Cognitive S cience, 28, 1–44. Campbell, J. (1949). he hero with a thou sand faces. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Cantrall, W. (1974). View point, relexives and the nature of noun phr ases. he Hague: Mouton. Carruthers, P. (2002). he cognitive functions of language. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 33, 657–674. Chomsky, N. (1957). Syntactic structures. he Hague: Mouton. Chomsky, N. (1975). Relections on language. New York: Random House. Chomsky, N. (1982). Some concepts and consequences of the theory of government and binding. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Cohen, M. S., Kosslyn, S. M., Breiter, H. C., DiGirolamo, G. J., homp son, W. L., Anderson, A. K. et al. (1996). Changes in cortical activity during mental rotation. A mapp ing study using functional MRI. Brain, 119, 89–100. Dennett, D. (1991). Consciousness explained. New York: Penguin Press. Donald, M. (1991). Origins of the modern mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Eckler, J., & Weininger, O. (1989). Structural parallels between pretend play and narratives. Developmental Psychology, 25, 736–743. Fauconnier, G., & Turner, M. (1996). Blending as a central process of grammar. In A. Goldberg (Ed.), Conceptual structure, discourse, and language (pp. 113–130). Stanford, CA: CSLI.
406
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Franks, S. L., & Connell, P. J. (1996). Knowledge of binding in normal and SLI children. Journal of Child Language, 23, 431–464. Frazier, L. (1987). Sentence processing: A t utorial review. In M. Coltheart (Ed.), Attention an d pe rformance (Vol. 1 2, pp . 6 01–681). L ondon: Erlbaum. Gernsbacher, M. A. (1990). Language comprehension as structure building. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Gibson, E . (1998). Linguistic complexity: Locality of syntactic dependencies. Cognition, 68, 1–76. Givon, T. (2002). he v isual i nformation-processing s ystem a s a n e volutionary precursor of human language. In T. Givon & B. Malle (Eds.), he evolution of language out of pre-language (pp. 3–51). Amsterdam: Benjamins. Givon, T. (2005). Context as other minds: he pragmatics of sociality, cognition, and communication. Philadelphia: Benjamins. Greeno, J., & Mac Whinney, B . ( 2006). Perspective s hiting in cl assroom interactions. Paper presented at the AERA Meeting. Grodzinsky, Y., & Amunts, K. (2006). Broca’s region. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Grodzinsky, Y., & Reinhart, T. (1993). he innateness of binding and coreference. Linguistic Inquiry, 24, 187–222. Harris, C. L., & Bates, E. A. (2002). Clausal backgrounding and pronominal c orefence: A f unctionalist a lternative to c -command. Language and Cognitive Processes, 17, 237–269. Hausser, R. (1999). Foundations of computational linguistics: Man-machine communication in natural language. Berlin: Springer. Haviland, J. B. (1993). Anchoring, iconicity, and orientation in Guugu Yimithirr pointing gestures. Journal of Linguistic Anthropology, 3, 3–45. Huttenlocher, J., & Presson, C. (1973). Mental rotation and the perspective problem. Cognitive Psychology, 4, 277–299. Jeannerod, M . ( 1997). he co gnitive n euroscience o f acti on. C ambridge, MA: Blackwell. Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1983). Mental mod els: Towards a c ognitive sc ience of language, inference, and consciousness. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Just, M. A., Carpenter, P. A., Keller, T. A., Eddy, W. F., & hulborn, K. R. (1996). Brain activation modulated by s entence comprehension. Science, 274, 114–116. Kakei, S., Hof man, D. S., & Strick, P. L. (1999). Muscle and movement representations in the primary motor cortex. Science, 285, 2136–2139. Kamio, A . (1995). Territory o f i nformation i n E nglish a nd J apanese a nd psychological utterances. Journal of Pragmatics, 24, 235–264.
How Mental Models Encode Embodied Linguistic Perspectives
407
Kempen, G., & Hoenkamp, E. (1987). An incremental procedural grammar for sentence formulation. Cognitive Science, 11, 201–258. Kintsch, W., & Van Dijk, T. (1978). Toward a model of text comprehension and production. Psychological Review, 85, 363–394. Lakof, G., & Johnson, M. (1980). Metaphors we live by. Chicago: Chicago University Press. Lave, J. (1991). Situated learning: Legitimate peripheral participation. New York: Cambridge University Press. MacDonald, M. C., Pearlmutter, N. J., & S eidenberg, M. S. (1994). Lexical nature of syntactic ambiguity resolution. Psychological Review, 101(4), 676–703. Macrae, C., Heatherton, T., & Kel ley, W. (2004). A s elf less ordinary: he medial prefrontal cortex and your. In M. Gazzaniga (Ed.), he cognitive neurosciences (Vol. 3, pp. 1067–1076). Cambridge: MIT Press. MacWhinney, B. (1977). Starting points. Language, 53, 152–168. MacWhinney, B. (1987a). he competition model. In B. MacWhinney (Ed.), Mechanisms o f la nguage a cquisition ( pp. 2 49–308). H illsdale, N J: Erlbaum. MacWhinney, B . (1987b). Toward a p sycholinguistically pl ausible p arser. In S. hom ason (Ed.), Proceedings of the Eastern States Conference on Linguistics (pp. . Columbus, Ohio: Ohio State University. MacWhinney, B. (2005). Language evolution and human development. In B. E llis & D . Bjorklund (Eds.), Origins of th e s ocial min d (p p. 3 83– 410). New York: Guilford. Marslen-Wilson, W. D., & Tyler, L. K. T. (1980). he temporal structure of spoken language understanding. Cognition, 8, 1–71. Martin, A., Wiggs, C. L., Ungerleider, L. G., & Ha xby, J. V. (1996). Neural correlates of category-speciic knowledge. Nature, 379, 649–652. McClelland, J. L. (1979). On the time-relations of mental processes: An examination of systems of processes in cascade. Psychological Review, 86, 287–330. McDonald, J. L., & MacWhinney, B. J. (1995). he time course of anaphor resolution: E fects o f i mplicit v erb c ausality a nd g ender. Journal of Memory and Language, 34, 543–566. McNeill, D. (1992). Hand an d min d: Wh at ge stures reveal about thoug ht. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Meltzof, A. N. (1995). Understanding t he i ntentions of others: Re-enactment of intended acts by 18-month-old children. Developmental Psychology, 31, 838–850. Meltzof, A . N., & De cety, J. ( 2003). W hat i mitation tel ls u s a bout s ocial cognition: A rapprochement between developmental psychology and cognitive neuroscience. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B, 358, 491–500.
408
Embodiment, Ego-Space, and Action
Middleton, F. A., & Strick, P. L. (1998). Cerebellar output: Motor and cognitive channels. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 2, 348–354. Miller, G ., & J ohnson-Laird, P . ( 1976). Language a nd p erception. C ambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Mitchell, D. C. (1994). Sentence parsing. In M. Gernsbacher (Ed.), Handbook of ps ycholinguistics (pp. 3 75–405). S an D iego, C A: A cademic Press. Mithen, S. (1996). he prehistory of th e mind: he cognitive origins of ar t, religion, and science. London: hames & Hudson. Nelson, K. (1998). Language in cognitive development: he emergence of the mediated mind. New York: Cambridge University Press. O’Grady, W. (2005). Syntactic carpentry. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. O’Grady, W. (2006). he syntax of quantiication in SLA: An emergentist approach. In M. O’Brien, C. Shea, & J. A rchibald (Eds.), Proceedings of t he 8t h Gene rative A pproaches t o Second L anguage A cquisition Conference (GASLA 2006) (pp. 98 –113). Somerville, M A: Cascadilla Press. Parsons, L. M., Fox, P. T., Downs, J. H., Glass, T., Hirsch, T. B., Martin, C. C. et a l. (1995). Use of i mplicit motor i magery for v isual shape d iscrimination as revealed by PET. Nature, 375, 54–58. Pecher, D., & Z waan, R . (Eds.). (2005). Grounding cog nition. C ambridge: Cambridge University Press. Pelphrey, K. A., Mitchell, T. V., McKeown, M. J., Goldstein, J., A llison, T., & M cCarthy, G . (2003). B rain ac tivity e voked by t he p erception o f human walking: Controlling for meaningful coherent motion. Journal of Neuroscience, 23, 6819–6825. Pelphrey, K. A., Morris, J. P., & M cCarthy, G. (2005). Neural basis of eye gaze processing deicits in autism. Brain, 128, 1038–1048. Pelphrey, K. A., Viola, R. J., & McCarthy, G. (2004). When strangers pass. Psychological Science, 15, 598–603. Pinker, S. (1997). How the mind works. New York: Norton. Ramachandran, V. S. (2000). Phantom limbs and neural plasticity. Neurological Review, 57, 317–320. Ramachandran, V. S., & H ubbard, E . M. (2001). Synaesthesia: A w indow into p erception, t hought a nd l anguage. Journal of C onsciousness Studies, 8, 3–34. Ratner, N., & Bruner, J. (1978). Games, social exchange and the acquisition of language. Journal of Child Language, 5, 391–401. Reinhart, T. (1981). Deinite NP anaphora and c-command domains. Linguistic Inquiry, 12, 605–635. Reinhart, T. (1983). Anaphora and semantic interpretation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
How Mental Models Encode Embodied Linguistic Perspectives
409
Rizzolatti, G., Fadiga, L ., Gallese, V., & F ogassi, L . (1996). Premotor cortex and the recognition of motor actions. Cognitive Brain Research, 3, 131–141. Rogof, B . ( 2003). he c ultural n ature of hum an d evelopment. O xford: Oxford University Press. Spelke, E. (2002). Developing k nowledge of space: Core systems and new combinations. In S. Kosslyn & A. Galaburda (Eds.), Languages of the brain (pp. 239–258). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Spradley, J. ( Ed.). (1972). Culture an d c ognition: Rul es, m aps, an d pl ans. New York: Chandler. Stanield, R . A ., & Z waan, R . A . (2001). he efect of i mplied orientation derived from verbal context on picture recognition. Psychological Science, 12, 153–156. Stein, D ., & W right, S . ( Eds.). ( 1995). Subjectivity and subjec tivisation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Tenny, C., & Sp eas, P. (2002). Conigurational properties of point of view roles. In A. DiSciullo (Ed.), Asymmetry in g rammar. A msterdam: Benjamins. Vygotsky, L. (1934). hought and language. Cambridge: MIT Press. Zwaan, R . A . (1996). P rocessing na rrative t ime sh its. Journal of E xperimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 22, 1196–1207.
Author Index
A Abravanel, E., 86 Adams, F., 209 Adelman, P. K., 96 Adelson, E. H., 116 Adolph, K. E., 277, 278, 279, 281, 283, 285, 286, 288, 289, 290, 293, 294, 295, 297, 298, 299, 300, 301, 302, 306, 307, 308, 310, 311, 312 Adolphs, R., 370, 372 Aguirre, G. K., 32 Ahlström, V., 120 Albright, T. D., 208, 230 Aldridge, J. W., 226, 229 Alexander, G. E., 225, 229 Allen, G. L., 17 Allison, T., 133 Allport, D. A., 218, 231 Alyan, S., 32 Amano, S., 341 Ambady, N., 134 Andersen, R. A., 208, 219, 220, 247 Anderson, A. K., 136 Anderson, J. R., 45 Andre, J., 4, 6, 7, 8, 26 Anisfeld, M., 357 Arbib, M. A., 231 Arkenberg, M., 404 Ash, M. G., 120 Ashby, W. R., 209 Ashmead, D. H., 8, 9 Astaiev, S. V., 256, 267 Atkinson, A. P., 93, 94, 95 Avenanti, A., 371 Averbeck, B. B., 229 Avraamides, M. N., 14, 15, 153, 161, 172 B Bailey, D., 371 Baldwin, D. A., 339
Ballard, D. H., 210, 371 Bangert, M., 54 Baron-Cohen, S., 358 Barresi, J., 47, 48, 83 Barrett, T. E., 162 Barsalou, L. W., 71, 82 Basso, M. A., 221, 222 Bastian, A., 223 Bateson, M., 403 Beardsworth, T., 59, 327 Bechara, A., 226 Beer, R. D., 209 Bekkering, H., 181, 335 Berger, S. E., 304, 305, 312 Bergson, H., 209 Berkowitz, L., 96 Berns, G. S., 225 Bernstein, N., 276, 277 Bertenthal, B. I., 120, 281, 291, 294, 296, 311, 326, 328, 329, 337, 347, 348, 349, 350, 354, 355, 356 Berti, A., 185, 248, 262 Best, J. B., 207 Beurze, S. M., 256, 267 Beusmans, J. M. H., 29 Bhalla, M., 189 Bichot, N. P., 222 Bingham, G. P., 7 Binkofski, F., 253, 258 Blackmore, S., 403 Blake, R., 124 Blakemore, S. J., 46, 48, 58, 84, 102, 325 Blanchard, R. J., 80 Block, N., 207 Bly, L., 281 Bock, O., 265 Bonatti, L., 83 Bonda, E., 128 Böök, A., 2, 14 Booth, A., 351, 352, 353
411
412
Author Index
Booth, J. R., 390 Boraud, T., 226 Bosbach, S., 69 Botvinick, M., 132 Boynton, G. M., 217, 218, 232 Brain, W. R., 2 Brass, M., 326, 337 Bremmer, F., 262 Bridgeman, B., 30 Bril, B., 285 Bristow, D., 267 Broadbent, D. E., 218 Brooks, R., 209 Brothers, L., 136 Brown, J. W., 225 Bruner, J. S., 335, 403 Buccino, G., 326 Budiu, R., 374 Bullock, D., 214, 229 Bülthof, I., 128, 130 Buneo, C. A., 219, 220 Burbaud, P., 219 Burnod, Y., 214 Burt, P., 121 Butterworth, G., 340, 346 Buxbaum, L., 84 C Calton, J. L., 217, 220, 251 Calvo-Merino, B., 54, 55, 126, 325, 336 Caminiti, R., 220 Campbell, J., 401 Campos, J. J., 286, 292, 293, 307 Cantrall, W., 395 Carello, C. D., 221 Carey, D. P., 31, 188 Carlson, V. R., 4 Carruthers, P., 401 Casile, A., 56, 57, 59, 126 Castiello, U., 187, 218, 222, 223, 231, 326 Cavina-Pratesi, C., 253, 259 Chaminade, T., 327, 345 Chan, M. Y., 311, 312 Choamsky, N., 206 Chomsky, N., 375, 378, 379 Chong, R. K., 226 Chouchourelou, A., 134, 136 Churchland, P. S., 209 Cisek, P., 204, 212, 213, 215, 218, 221, 223, 225, 227, 229, 230, 231, 232, 233 Clark, A., 48, 204, 209, 227, 276 Clarke, T. J., 119, 134
Clower, W. T., 230 Coe, B., 221 Cohen, L. R., 92, 120, 132, 265 Cohen, M. S., 370 Colby, C. L., 208, 216, 217, 220, 232, 247, 248, 251, 262 Cole, J. D., 69, 70 Connolly, J. D., 252, 256, 267 Constantinidis, C., 219 Cooke, D. F., 248 Corkum, V., 339 Corlett, J. T., 7 Cowey, A., 185 Crammond, D. J., 221 Creem, S. H., 31, 188, 197 Creem-Regehr, S. H., 2, 7, 189 Cross, E. S., 57 Csibra, G., 324, 358 Cuijpers, R. H., 5 Culham, J. C., 209, 219, 247, 251, 252, 253, 255, 258 Cutting, J. E., 7, 59, 120, 180, 184, 348 D Da Silva, J. A., 4 Darwin, C., 81, 94 Dassonville, P., 31 Dawson, G., 98 de Jong, B. M., 257, 267, 268 de Vries, J. I. P., 277 Deak, G. O., 339 Decety, J., 46, 52, 125, 323, 326, 356 Dechent, P., 256, 267 Dennett, D., 401 DeRenzi, E., 85 Desjardins, J. K., 80 Desmurget, M., 214, 221 DeSouza, J. F. X., 31, 252, 265 DeSperati, C., 50 Dewey, J., 209 di Pellegrino, G., 226, 248 Diamond, A., 331 Diamond, R., 91 Diedrich, F. J., 334 DiFranco, D., 253 Dimberg, U., 97 Dittrich, W. H., 59, 134 Dodd, D. H., 207 Dokic, J., 48 Domini, F., 180 Donald, M., 372 Dorris, M. C., 219, 220, 221
Author Index
413
Downing, P., 83, 84 Dretske, F., 210, 233 Dulcos, S. E., 96, 97 Durgin, F. H., 20, 21
Frith, C. D., 133, 323 Fukusima, S. S., 12, 13 Funk, M., 51, 85, 127, 131, 132 Fuster, J. M., 226
E Eby, D. W., 7 Eckler, J., 403 Edwards, M. G., 326 Ellard, C. G., 20, 22 Elliott, D., 7, 8 Engel, A. K., 217 Enright, J. T., 148 Eppler, M. A., 292 Epstein, W., 4, 191, 221 Erlhagen, W., 231 Eskandar, E. N., 251 ESPNmag. com, 196 Ewert, J-P., 231
G Gail, A., 251 Gallagher, S., 84 Gallese, V., 46, 210, 233, 325 Galletti, C., 251, 268 Garciaguirre, J. S., 286, 303, 311, 312 Gaunet, F., 173 Gauthier, L., 91 Gazzaniga, M. S., 208, 230 Gentile, A. M., 312 Georgopoulos, A. P., 232 Gergely, G., 345, 358 Gernsbacher, M. A., 377 Gibson, E., 128, 275, 377 Gibson, E. J., 278, 290, 291, 307 Gibson, J. J., 45, 81, 179, 209, 212, 215, 223, 233, 260, 278, 288 Giese, M. A., 128, 130 Gilinsky, A. S., 4, 5, 22 Givon, T., 372, 398 Glenberg, A. M., 71, 82, 210 Glimcher, P. W., 213, 232 Gnadt, J. W., 31 Gogel, W. C., 3, 4, 5, 18 Gold, J. L., 213, 222, 227, 232 Goldman, A., 48 Goltz, H. C., 262 Gonzalez, C. L., 187 Goodale, M. A., 31, 197, 198, 217, 247 Gottlieb, J., 219, 220 Graton, S. T., 252 Graziano, M. S. A., 220 Greeno, J., 402, 404 Greenwald, A. G., 46, 325 Grekes, C., 247, 252 Grezes, J., 58, 70, 323, 326, 355 Grodzinsky, Y., 379, 391 Grön, G., 32 Grosjean, M., 52, 53 Grossman, E. D., 84, 102, 128, 133 Grush, R., 48
F Fadiga, L., 215, 326 Fagg, A. H., 231 Fantz, R. L., 83 Farrell, M. J., 19 Farroni, T., 340, 341 Fauconnier, G., 399 Fazendeiro, T., 100 Felleman, D. J., 216, 232 Ferraina, S., 219, 220 Ferrari, F., 339 Fetz, E. E., 210, 211 Field, T., 83 Fitts, P. M., 50, 52, 207 Flach, R., 51, 62, 68, 327 Flanders, M., 156, 174 Fleury, M., 70 Flores d’Arcais, J-P., 61 Fodor, J. A., 113 Fogassi, L., 46, 325 Foley, J. M., 4, 6, 7, 25, 29, 30, 265 Fontaine, R., 357 Fox, R., 86 Frak, V., 252 Franchak, J. M., 278, 279 Frankenburg, W. K., 281, 284, 285 Franklin, N., 173 Franks, S. L., 394 Franz, V. H., 31 Frazier, L., 386 Freedland, R. L., 283 Frey, S. H., 258
H Hafenden, A. M., 31 Haggard, P., 148 Halligan, P. W., 185, 248 Halverson, H. M., 253
414
Author Index
Hamilton, A., 59, 69, 126 Hardcastle, V. G., 209, 233 Hari, R., 267 Harlow, H. F., 308 Harnad, S., 81, 233 Harris, C. L., 380, 381 Harris, P., 48 Harvey, I., 209 Harway, N. I., 34 Hasebe, H., 263 Haslinger, B., 54 Hasson, U., 133, 261 Hatield, E., 94, 95 Haueisen, J., 54 Hauser, M. D., 226 Hausser, R., 386 Haviland, J. B., 396 Haxby, J. V., 102 He, Z. J., 7, 9, 30 Heide, W., 31 Hendriks-Jansen, H., 204, 209, 227, 231 Henriques, D. Y., 265 Heptulla-Chatterjee, S., 87, 122, 132 Hertenstein, M. J., 95 Heyes, C., 326 Hildreth, E., 116 Hinde, R. A., 218 Hiris, E., 120 Hobson, P. R., 98, 100 Hofer, T., 338, 358 Hofstadter, D. R., 207 Hommel, B., 46, 48, 210, 347 Hood, B. M., 340, 341 Horak, F. B., 226 Horwitz, G. D., 221 Hoshi, E., 226, 227 Houghton, G., 231 Howard, I. P., 3 Hubbard, T. L., 51 Hubel, D., 115 Humphreys, G. W., 223, 231 Hutchison, J. J., 5, 12, 32, 33 Huttenlocher, J., 394 I Iacobini, M., 47, 124, 133, 325, 326 Iriki, A., 184, 198, 248, 261 Israël, 17 J Jackson, J. H., 209 Jackson, R. E., 195
Jacobs, A., 125, 126, 128, 134, 349 James, W., 45, 46, 81, 325 Janssen, P., 219, 220, 221 Jeannerod, M., 48, 58, 131, 252, 324, 370 Joh, A. S., 290, 306 Johansson, G., 59, 118, 119, 127, 130, 328, 348 Johnson, M. H., 83, 85 Johnson, M. L., 281 Johnson, P. B., 220 Johnson-Laird, P. N., 207, 387 Jordan, M. I., 328 Just, M. A., 391 Juurmaa, J., 17 K Kail, R., 279 Kakei, S., 370 Kalaska, J. F., 212, 213, 215, 217, 218, 219, 220, 221 Kalivas, P. W., 225 Kamio, A., 398 Kandel, S., 51, 67, 327 Karnath, H. O., 253 Kawashima, R., 252 Kawato, M., 328 Keele, S. W., 221 Keller, ??, 68 Kelly, J. W., 4, 5, 6 Kempen, G., 386 Kendrick, K. M., 81 Kermadi, I., 226, 229 Kertzman, C., 252 Kerzel, D., 51 Kieras, D., 45 Kilner, J. M., 327, 337 Kim, J-N., 213, 226 Kinsella-Shaw, J. M., 306 Kintsch, W., 374 Kiraly, I., 324 Klatzky, R. L., 14, 15, 145, 148, 149, 150, 151, 152, 159, 161, 172, 173, 371, 404 Knapp, J. M., 2, 4, 6, 7, 10, 12, 13, 23 Knoblich, G., 48, 51, 58, 60, 65, 66, 130, 132, 137, 327, 345, 372 Koch, C., 2, 183, 198 Kohler, E., 46, 56, 60 Kornblum, S., 231 Korte, A., 51, 120 Koski, L., 47, 326 Kozlowski, L. T., 134 Krebs, J. R., 181
Author Index Kudoh, N., 29 Kuhl, P., 83 Kurata, K., 223 Kusunoki, M., 219, 220, 232 L Lacerda, F., 324 Lacquaniti, ??, 50 Ladavas, E., 248 Lakof, G., 399 Lampl, M., 281, 282 Land, M. F., 180, 181 Landy, M. S., 180 Langdell, T., 98 Larsen, A., 175 Larsen, R. J., 96 Lavadas, E., 184 Lave, J., 403 Law, I., 266 Lazarus, R. S., 94 Legerstee, M., 83 Lehar, S., 2 Leo, A. J., 297 Leung, E. H., 339, 347 Levin, C. A., 29 Lhermitte, F., 357 Liberman, A. M., 46 Linkenauger, S. A., 186, 198 Loarer, E., 14 Lockman, J. J., 296 Longo, M. R., 325, 326, 331, 332, 333, 336, 347, 358 Loomis, J. M., 2, 3, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9, 12, 13, 14, 15, 16, 17, 18, 19, 23, 26, 27, 28, 29, 30, 33, 34, 159, 371 Louis-Dam, A., 345 Loula, F., 60, 92, 129, 130, 349 Luo, Y., 324, 345 M MacDonald, M. C., 384 Macrae, C., 370 MacWhinney, B., 71, 373, 377, 384, 386, 401 Maguire, E. A., 32 Malach, R., 261 Maratos, O., 357 Maravita, A., 248 Marconi, B., 220 Marcovitch, S., 331, 334 Marey, E. J., 118 Mark, L. S., 306, 313 Marlinsky, V. V., 17
415
Marr, D. C., 3, 113, 207, 216, 324 Marslen-Wilson, W. D., 386 Martin, A., 370 Martin, R. A., 80 Mast, F. W., 179 Matelli, M., 217 Maturana, H. R., 209 Maurer, D., 85, 88 May, M., 172, 175 Mazzoni, P., 219 McClelland, J. L., 376 McCready, D., 4 McDonald, J. L., 393 McGoldrick, J. E., 88 McGraw, M. B., 357 McIntosh, D. N., 95, 96, 97 McNeill, D., 373 McPeek, R. M., 222 Mead, G. H., 209 Medendorp, W. P., 14, 31 Meltzof, A. N., 86, 95, 131, 137, 356, 357, 370, 372 Merleau-Ponty, M., 45, 209 Merriam, E. P., 146 Messing, R., 7 Miall, R. C., 328 Middleton, F. A., 225, 229, 232, 370 Miller, E. K., 226 Miller, G. A., 207, 221, 374 Millikan, R. G., 209, 233 Milner, A. D., 30, 31, 189, 197, 198, 217, 232, 247 Milner, D. A., 187 Mink, J. W., 225, 226 Mitchell, D. C., 386 Mithen, S., 401 Mittelstaedt, M. L., 17 Mohler, B. J., 20, 21 Mondschein, E. R., 301 Montepare, J. M., 133 Moody, E. J., 95 Moore, C., 82, 100 Moore, K. L., 277, 280 Moran, J., 217, 218, 232 Morris, J. P., 133 Mountcastle, V. B., 219 Munakata, Y., 334, 337 N Nakagawa, A., 357 Nakamura, K., 220, 230 Neggers, S. F., 265
416
Author Index
Nelson, K., 403 Neumann, O., 218, 231 Newell, A., 45, 205, 207, 208, 209, 224 Niedenthal, P. M., 96, 101 Noonan, K. J., 281 Núñez, R., 209 O O’Grady, W., 377, 386, 387, 404 O’Regan, J. K., 210 Ogden, J. A., 85 Ohira, H., 96 Ooi, T. L., 3, 5, 17, 18, 19, 20, 29, 30, 32, 33, 34 Oram, M. W., 128 Orliaguet, J-P., 345 Ounsted, M., 280 Oyama, T., 4 Ozonof, S., 100 P Palmer, C. E., 280 Palmer, C. F., 290 Pani, J. R., 174 Panksepp, J., 93, 94 Paré, M., 220 Parsons, L. M., 370 Passingham, R. E., 217, 218 Paus, T., 266 Pavlov, I., 205 Pavlova, M., 329, 349 Pecher, D., 71, 375 Pegna, A. J., 185 Pellijef, A., 257, 267 Pelphrey, K. A., 323, 372 Petit, L. S., 162 Philbeck, J. W., 2, 4, 6, 8, 9, 10, 12, 13, 16, 17, 18, 19, 20, 25, 31, 32 Piaget, J., 45, 81, 82, 204, 209, 227 Pinker, S., 207, 401 Pinto, J, 86, 120, 132, 349, 350, 355 Pisella, L., 214 Pitzalis, S., 250, 252, 257, 268 Plamondon, R., 52 Platt, M. L., 208, 213, 219, 220, 221, 222 Plumert, J. M., 314 Pollick, F. E., 59, 119, 129, 134 Portin, K., 256, 267 Posner, M. I., 340 Post, R. B., 31 Powell, K. D., 219 Powers, W. T., 209
Prado, J., 252, 256, 267 Prasad, S., 131, 132 Prechtl, H. F. R., 357 Premack, D., 358 Previc, F. H., 248 Price, E. H., 85 Prinz, W., 45, 46, 57, 60, 71, 124, 125, 126, 130 Proitt, D. R., 1, 12, 32, 180, 183, 188, 189, 190, 191, 348 Puce, A., 136 Pylyshyn, Z., 113, 207, 208 Q Quinlan, D. J., 262 Quinn, P., 83 Quintana, J., 226 R Rader, N., 292 Rainer, G., 226 Ramachandran, V. S., 370 Ratner, N., 403 Redgrave, P., 225 Redish, A. D., 32 Reed, C. L., 84, 86, 87, 88, 89, 91, 95, 99, 132 Reed, E. S., 277 Reinhart, T., 379, 383 Repp, B. H., 62, 63, 64, 65, 68, 327 Reynolds, J. H., 208, 233 Richards, J. E., 292 Richardson, A. R., 20, 22, 23 Richter, H. O., 263 Riecke, B. E., 172 Riehle, A., 223 Riener, C. R., 196 Rieser, J. J., 7, 8, 14, 20, 21, 34, 159, 173, 175, 192 Riskind, J., 96 Rizzolatti, G., 46, 47, 58, 84, 124, 132, 220, 324, 325, 326, 339, 347, 356, 371 Ro, T., 83 Robinson, S. R., 277, 311, 312 Rocha, C. F. D., 182 Rogof, B., 403 Romo, R., 221, 232 Rose, J. L., 347 Rossetti, Y., 31 Rowe, J. B., 226 Ruf man, T., 334 Runeson, S., 59, 70, 119, 129, 133 Russell, B., 2 Rutherford, M. D., 99
Author Index S Sahm, C. S., 2, 7, 10, 11, 19, 23, 32 Sawamoto, N., 226 Saxe, R., 84, 102, 323 Saygin, A. P., 355 Scaife, M., 339 Schall, J. D., 221, 222 Schmidt, R. A., 285, 312 Schoield, W. N., 335 Schultz, W., 226 Schwoebel, J., 84 Searle, J., 233 Sebanz, N., 55, 71 Sedgwick, H. A., 4, 180, 191 Sereno, M. I., 31, 262 Shadlen, M. N., 220 Shannon, C. E., 206 Shelton, A. L., 148, 154, 155, 173 Shen, L., 221 Shepard, R. N., 113 Shif rar, M., 50, 60, 87, 116, 117, 118, 121, 122, 124, 127, 130, 137, 349 Sholl, M. J., 17 Sinai, M. J., 9 Singer, W., 208, 217, 233 Singhal, A., 253 Sirigu, A., 162 Skinner, B. F., 206 Slaughter, V., 83, 85, 87, 88 Smeets, J. B., 253 Smith, L. B., 331, 332 Smith, P. C., 7 Smythies, J. R., 2 Snyder, L. H., 208, 219, 220, 232, 251 Sommerville, J. A., 358 Speigle, J. M., 8, 9 Spelke, E., 401 Spivey, M., 48 Spradley, J., 403 Stanield, R. A., 375 Stankowich, T., 182 Steenhuis, R. E., 7, 8 Stefanucci, J. K., 191, 195 Stein, D., 375 Stein, J. F., 208, 216, 219, 220 Stekelenberg, J. J., 89 Stengel, E., 357 Stepper, S., 96 Sterelny, K., 209 Stetten, G., 166, 167 Stevens, J. A., 51, 124, 125, 349 Stevenson, H. W., 308
417
Still, A., 209 Strack, F., 96 Sugrue, L. P., 219, 220 Sumi, S., 329, 349 Swendsen, R., 164 T Tai, Y. F., 327 Takikawa, Y., 226 Tanaka, J. W., 88, 91 Tanji, J., 226 Tenny, C., 383, 384, 397 helen, E., 82, 204, 209, 227, 277, 331, 354 hompson, E., 209 hompson, W. B., 2, 10, 12, 13, 21, 23 homson, J. A., 7, 8, 14, 18, 159 horndike, E., 205 hornton, I. M., 49, 57, 59, 122 Tipper, S. P., 222, 223, 231 Titchener, E., 204 Titzer, R., 292 Toates, F., 231 Tolman, E. C., 206 Tomasello, M., 330, 356 Toye, R. C., 29 Tracy, J. L., 95 Treue, S., 217, 218, 232 Trevarthen, C., 82 Turati, C., 85 Turing, A. M., 206, 207 Tversky, B., 155 U Umiltà, M. A., 46 Ungerleider, L. G., 208, 216, 232 V Valenza, E., 85 Valyear, K. F., 187, 198 van Donkelaar, P., 265 van Hof, P., 335 Van Sommers, P., 60 Vanni, S., 267 Vereijken, B., 285 Verfaillie, K., 329 Virji-Babul, N., 123, 126 Viviani, P., 50, 125, 130, 329 Vogt, S., 326 Volkmar, F., 97 von der Malsburg, C., 208, 233 von Hofsten, C., 253, 324, 340 Vygotsky, L., 403
418
Author Index
W Wagner, M., 29, 148 Walk, R. D., 291, 292 Wall, J., 192 Wallach, H., 116 Wapner, S., 335 Warren, W. H., 213, 278, 290, 306 Watson, J. B., 206 Weinstein, S., 85 Weiskrantz, L., 30 Weiss, P. H., 249 Welsh, T. N., 222 Wenger, K. K., 226 Went, F. W., 195 Wertheimer, M., 120 Wesp, R., 197 Whitshaw, I. Q., 32 Willbarger, J., 97 Wilson, H., 116, 124, 125 Wilson, M., 45, 47, 48, 49, 52, 54, 65, 71, 82, 83, 84 Winston, J. S., 133 Wise, S. P., 220
Witherington, D. c., 292 Witt, J. K., 1, 20, 32, 183, 184, 191, 193, 196, 198 Wolf, W., 59 Wolpert, D. M., 48, 214, 328 Wong, E., 31 Woodward, A. L., 324, 339, 345 Worsley, C. L., 32 Wraga, M. J., 173 Wray, R. E., 45 Wu, B., 3, 5, 7, 8, 19, 29, 30, 32, 167, 168 Wundt, W., 204 Y Yarbus, A., 180 Ydenberg, R. C., 182 Yin, R. K., 88 Z Zahorik, P., 8 Zelazo, P. D., 331 Zwaan, R. A., 397
Subject Index Numbers in italic refer to igures or tables
A Action, 204 characterized, 45 cognitively mediated vs. perceptually guided, 165, 165–169, 166 distance perception, 6–10 intention, 55–56 Action coordination, action prediction, 67–69 Action identiication, self-generated actions, 58–65 Action perception, 45–71 body sense, 69–70 continuous, graded representations, 48 expertise, 53–58 motor laws, 49–53 apparent body motion, 51–52 Fitt’s law, 52–53 two-thirds power law, 50–51 new skill, 56–58 spatial perception, 6–10 Action prediction action coordination, 67–69 handwriting, 66–67 own vs. other’s action, 65–66 Action representations, 46 Action selection, 212–213, 213 evolutionary elaborations, 215 parameters, 212–213, 213 Action simulation, 48, 326–326 Action speciication, 212–213, 213 afordance competition hypothesis, 205, 218–230 cognitive ability, 227–247 decision making through distributed consensus, 224–227 simultaneous processing of potential actions, 221–224 fronto-parietal network, 205, 218–230 parameters, 212–213, 213
Action understanding deaferentation, 69–70 deined, 324 human movement structure perception, 328–329, 329 modes, 324–325 motor knowledge development perspective, 323–359 perseverative errors in searching for hidden objects, 331–338, 332, 333, 336, 338 point-light display perception of biological motion, 348–356, 349, 351, 352, 353, 354 visual orienting in response to deictic gestures, 339–348, 342, 343, 344, 346 prediction of efects of action, 327–328 covert imitation, 327–328 proprioception, 69–70 sensory neuronopathy, 69–70 touch, 69–70 Adaptation path integration, 20 perceptually directed action, 20–25, 22 distance-speciic adaptation, 22–23 Afordance competition hypothesis, 211–234 action speciication, 205, 218–230 cognitive ability, 227–247 decision making through distributed consensus, 224–227 simultaneous processing of potential actions, 221–224 cerebral cortex, 214–215, 215 fronto-parietal network, 205, 218–230 visual processing, 216–218 Afordances, 278–280 deined, 278 development, 280–288
419
420
Subject Index
Afordances (continued) body growth, 280–281, 282 environment, 287 motor proiciency, 281–287, 284, 285 new perception-action systems, 281– 287, 284, 285 infant perception, 288 bridges, 303–306 bridges using handrail, 303–306, 304 bridges with wobbly and wooden handrails, 305, 305–306 clifs, 290–293, 292 gaps, 293–297, 294, 298 perceptual problem, 288–290 slopes, 297–380, 299 slopes crawling vs. walking, 300–301 walking with weights, 302, 302–303 motor action, 278–280 thresholds, 278–279, 279 Alignment allocentric layer, 172–173, 174, 175 accessibility ordering, 173 bridging from actor’s representation to other coordinate systems, 169–170 frames of reference, 145–175 alignment load taxonomy, 171–175, 174 coordinate transformation, 157–158 imaginal walking, 170–171 parameter remapping, 157–158 right-hand rule, 171 ultrasound, 171 obliqueness, 173–174, 174, 175 Allocentric layer, 172 alignment, 172–173, 174, 175 accessibility ordering, 173 body-in-environment frame, 172 deined, 146 environmental frame of reference, 172 frames of reference, 172–173, 174, 175 accessibility ordering, 173 identiication, 150 set of measures, 149 imagined frame, 172 Ambiguity, perspective tracking, 384–387 relativization, 382–384, 389–392 scope, 387–389 Aperture problem, 115, 115–118, 117 Attractor space, 48 Audition, blind walking, 8–9, 9 Auditory distance perception, 23–25, 24 Auditory stimulus, self-identiication, 62–65
Autism, social perception, 97–100 atypical face and conigural processing, 98–99 body perception, 99 diiculties in social adjustment, 98 mimicry, 98 perceiving emotion from movement, 100 rule-based approach of emotional perception, 99–100 social-emotional perception, 99–100 template-based processes, 99, 100 B Balance, infant, 281–282 Ball or bean bag throwing, 7 Behavior cognitive processes, 205, 212 motor processes, 205, 212 perceptual processes, 211–212 Behaviorism, 206 schematic functional architectures, 205 Belly crawling, 283, 284 Blind walking, 7–11, 8, 18 audition, 8–9, 9 efect of feedback, 21–22 full-cue conditions, 9–10, 10 recalibration, 21–22 reduced-cue conditions, 9–10, 10 visually-directed, 9–10, 10 visual perception, gain, 21 Body growth, 280–281, 282 fetus, 280 infant, 280–281 Body image matching, projection, 370–371 Body-in-environment frame, allocentric layer, 172 Body inversion paradigm, 88–89, 89, 90 Body movement, see also Speciic type anatomically plausible movement path, 51 multimodal body schema, 51–52 Body perception conigural processing continuum, 88–89 creating self-other correspondences, 83–93 multimodal body schema, 51–52 spatial perception, 181–183 action-speciic perception, 181 behavioral ecology, 180–182 specialized body processing, 87–90 sources, 90–92 specialized body representations, 84–86 using one’s own body to organize information from others, 86–87
Subject Index Body posture, 80–81 feelings, 96–97 importance, 81 understanding others, 94–97 Body processing, specialized, 87–90 sources, 90–92 Body representations, specialized, 84–86 Body sense, action perception, 69–70 Brain, 205–206, see also Speciic part macaque monkey brain, 247–249 peripersonal space, 248 Bridges, 303–306 C Central executive, 224 Cerebral cortex, 208 afordance competition hypothesis, 214–215, 215 Clapping, identiication of one’s own, 62–63 Clifs, 290–293, 292 Cognition embodiment, relationship, 203–204 general architecture, 45 schematic functional architectures, 205 Cognitive development, language, 403 Cognitive neuroscience, 208 Cognitive psychology, 208, 209 Color vision, 3 Common coding theory of perception and actions, 46 drawing, 60–62 embodiment, 47 handwriting, 60–62 motor skill acquisition, 58 representation, 47–48 vs. radical interactionism, 47 Computation, 206 Computer metaphor, 205, 207 Concept-measurement relationship, perception, 3–4 Converging measures, distance perception, 32–33 Coreference, 379–380 Cortical visual processing, two visual streams framework, 30–32 Crawling, infants, 283–285, 284, 285 Cue integration, 180 current models, 180 Domini et al.’s model, 180 perceiver’s goals, 180–181 perceiver’s intent, 180–181 weighted averaging models, 180
421
D Dancers, expertise in action perception, 54–55, 57–58 Deaferentation, action understanding, 69–70 Deictic gestures, visual orienting in response to deictic gestures, 339– 348, 342, 343, 344, 346 Delaying commitment, 380–382 Descriptive representations, 210–211 Development afordances, 280–288 body growth, 280–281, 282 environment, 287 motor proiciency, 281–287, 284, 285 new perception-action systems, 281– 287, 284, 285 ate r infancy, 312–314 evidence for observation–execution matching system, 330–356 motor knowledge and action understanding, 323–359 Direct matching system, 325, 327 developmental evidence, 330–356 Distance perception, 1–33 action, 6–10 converging measures, 32–33 indirect methods, 4 intention to act, 1 judgments of collinearity, 5 judgments of perceived exocentric extent, 5 meaning of, 1 methods for measuring, 4–12 perceived exocentric distance, distortions, 29–30 perceived shape, distortions, 29–30 perception of exocentric direction, 5 percept-percept couplings, 4 perceptually directed action model, 12–19 calibration role, 12–13, 19–25 processing stages, 13–15, 14–15 reasons for error, 1 scale construction, 5 spatial updating, 1, 2, 6–10 accuracy, 1–2 triangulation methods, 10–12, 11, 13 two visual systems, action-speciic representations, 30–32 verbal report, 4, 5 Dorsal processing, spatial perception, 188, 189
422
Subject Index
Dorsal stream, 247–248 Drawing common coding theory of perception and actions, 60–62 mirror systems, 60–62 point-light displays, 60–62 Dualism, 204 schematic functional architectures, 205 Dynamical theory, 209 E Efector-speciic areas, 248–249 Egocentric distance, verbal reports, spatial updating to correct for bias, 25–29, 27 Egocentric frames identiication, 150 set of measures, 149 Embedded action fetus, 276–277 infant perception, 276–277 Embodied action fetus, 276–277 infant perception, 276–277 Embodied cognition, 203–204, 209 action context, 82 action goal, 82 sensorimotor roots, 81–82 social perception, added complexities, 81–83 in social world, 81 Embodied framework for behavior, 210–215 Embodied linguistic perspectives, mental model encoding, 369–404 Embodied motion perception, visual sensitivity, 113–137 Embodiment, 91 characterized, 45–46 common coding theory of perception and actions, 47 deined, 203 meaning, 203–204 mirror systems, 47 theoretical assumptions, 45–46 Emmert’s Law, size-distance invariance, 5 Emotional body perception, 93–97 Emotional contagion, 95–96 Empathy, 397 projection, 372 Environmental frame of reference, allocentric layer, 172 Evidentiality, 397–399
Expertise, 91 action perception, 53–58 Extinction, peripersonal space, 248 F Face, 88 relative location of features, 85 Face inversion efect, 88–89, 90 Facial expression, 80 efect of facial movement on afective experience, 96 induced corresponding emotional states, 96 understanding others, 94–97 Falling, spatial perception, 194–195 cost of injury, 195 slant perception, 195 vertical distance overestimation, 195–196 Fetus body growth, 280 embedded action, 276–277 embodied action, 276–277 Fitt’s law, 52–53 Frames of reference, see also Speciic type alignment, 145–175, 157–158 alignment load taxonomy, 171–175, 174 coordinate transformation, 157–158 imaginal walking, 170–171 parameter remapping, 157–158 right-hand rule, 171 ultrasound, 171 allocentric frames, 148–151, 149 identiication, 150 set of measures, 149 allocentric layer, 172–173, 174, 175 accessibility ordering, 173 coordination across body-deined, 146 deined, 146 egocentric frames, 148–151, 149 identiication, 150 set of measures, 149 mechanisms, intermediate levels of description, 169–170 methods to identify parameters, 151 errors spatially biased by frame, 155–156 parameter values easiest to report, 154–155, 155 what is reported?, 151–154, 152, 153 multiple, 145–175
Subject Index changes in egocentric parameters under imagined locomotion, 158– 161, 160, 161 cognitively mediated action vs. perceptually guided action, 165, 165–169, 166 coordinating physical frames of reference, 169 current positional cues, 159 embodied actor in, 158–169 imagined updating, 159–161, 160, 161 ongoing movement cues, 159 right-hand rule, 162–164, 163 spatial thinking through action, 161–164 obliqueness, 173–174, 174, 175 parameters, 147 processes, 147–148 reference-frame parameterization studies implications, 156–157 task demands, 145 Fronto-parietal network action speciication, 205, 218–230 afordance competition hypothesis, 205, 218–230 Full-cue conditions, blind walking, 9–10, 10 Functional magnetic resonance imaging, 247–268 superior parieto-occipital cortex, 247–268 activation from arm transport during reaching actions, 249–258, 250, 254, 256–257 in humans, 247–268 preference for near gaze, 262–266, 264 preference for objects within arm’slength, 259–262, 260 G Gait, 56–57 infant perception, 350–354, 351, 352, 353, 354 point-light displays, 59–60 self-generated actions, 59–60 self-recognition, individualistic styles, 60 symmetrical patterning, 350–354, 351, 352, 353, 354 Gaps, 293–297, 294, 298 Grammar perspective hypothesis coreference, 379–380
423
delaying commitment, 380–382 noncentrality, 380 structure vs. function, 378–384 perspective taking clitic assimilation, 392 empathy, 397 evidentiality, 397–399 implicit causality, 393–395 metaphor, 399 perspectival overlays, 395–399 space, 395–396 time, 396–397 perspective tracking, 373 maintenance, 378 modiication, 378 shit, 378 Grasping neurophysiology, 187–188 spatial perception, 186–188 let-handed people, 187 right-handed people, 186–187 H Handwriting action prediction, 66–67 common coding theory of perception and actions, 60–62 mirror systems, 60–62 own vs. other’s recognition, 66–67 point-light displays, 60–62 trajectory, 51 velocity, 61–62 Heading, 147 Hidden objects, perseverative errors in searching for, 331–338, 332, 333, 336, 338 Hitting, spatial perception, 196–197 Human motion object motion comparing perception, 114–123 visual system in, compared, 114–137 visual analysis, 113–137 visual system action perception vs. object perception, 121–137 aperture problem, 115, 115–118, 117 bodily form, 131–133 controlling for viewpoint-dependent visual experience, 130–131 level of analysis, 116–117, 117 local measurements inherently ambiguous, 116
424
Subject Index
Human motion (continued) motion integration across space, 115–123 motion integration across time, 120–123, 123 motor experience vs. visual experience, 128–133 motor expertise, 124–127 multiple apertures, 118 perceptual sensitivity to emotional actions, 136–137 point-light displays, 118–120, 119 social context and apparent human motion, 134–136, 135 social-emotional processes, 133–137 visual expertise, 127–128 I Ideomotor principle, voluntary action, 46 Imaginal walking, 170–171 Imagined frame, allocentric layer, 172 Infant perception, 275–315 afordances, 288 bridges, 303–306 bridges using handrail, 303–306, 304 bridges with wobbly and wooden handrails, 305, 305–306 clifs, 290–293, 292 gaps, 293–297, 294, 298 perceptual problem, 288–290 slopes, 297–380, 299 slopes crawling vs. walking, 300–301 walking with weights, 302, 302–303 embedded action, 276–277 embodied action, 276–277 everyday experience, 311–312 gait, 350–354, 351, 352, 353, 354 learning in development, 306–314 learning sets, 308–310 perception of point-light displays of biological motion, 348–356, 349, 351, 352, 353, 354 perseverative errors in searching for hidden objects, 331–338, 332, 333, 336, 338 visual orienting in response to deictic gestures, 339–348, 342, 343, 344, 346 Infants balance, 281–282 body growth, 280–281 crawling, 283–285, 284, 285
locomotion, 283–287 everyday experience, 311–312 learning in development, 306–314 learning sets, 308–310 perceptually guided action, 275–315 perception-action studies development, 276 learning, 276 perception-action systems, 286–287 spatial body representation, 85–86 supramodal body scheme, 86 walking, 285–286 Information, 206–207 Information processing system, schematic functional architectures, 205 Intention, 323 action, 55–56 distance perception, 1 self-other relationships, 82 Inter-location relations, parameters, 147 Inversion efects, 92 J Joint attention, visual orienting in response to deictic gestures, 339–348, 342, 343, 344, 346 L Language, 206, 373–404 cognitive development, 403 integration, 400–403 mental model encoding, 369–404 production, 400–403 Lateral intraparietal area, 219–220 Let-handed people, 187 Listening, 54 Localization, projection, 371 Locomotion, infants, 283–287 everyday experience, 311–312 learning in development, 306–314 learning sets, 308–310 Luminous igures, judgments of shapes, 18 M Machine theory, 206 Magnetoencephalography, superior parieto-occipital cortex, 256–257 Metaphor, 399 Mimicry, 95–96, 98 Mirror neurons, 325–326 Mirror systems, 46 drawing, 60–62
Subject Index embodiment, 47 handwriting, 60–62 motor skill acquisition, 58 parietal cortex, 46–47 premotor cortex, 47 Motor action afordances, 278–280 perceptual guidance, 275–276 Motor knowledge, action understanding development perspective, 323–359 perception of point-light displays of biological motion, 348–356, 349, 351, 352, 353, 354 perseverative errors in searching for hidden objects, 331–338, 332, 333, 336, 338 visual orienting in response to deictic g estures, 339–348, 342, 343, 344, 346 Motor laws, action perception, 49–53 apparent body motion, 51–52 Fitt’s law, 52–53 two-thirds power law, 50–51 Motor skill acquisition, 57–58 common coding theory of perception and actions, 58 mirror systems, 58 Multimodal spatial body representation, 86–87 Musicians, self-identiication, 64–65 N Naïve realism, 2 Near space, characterized, 184 Neural data, pragmatic perspective interpretation, 216 Neuroimaging studies, peripersonal space, 247–268 Neurophysiology, 209 grasping, 187–188 New skill, action perception, 56–58 Noncentrality, 380 O Object, deined, 147 Object motion human motion comparing perception, 114–123 visual system in, compared, 114–137 visual system action perception vs. object perception, 121–137 aperture problem, 115, 115–118, 117
425
bodily form, 131–133 controlling for viewpoint-dependent visual experience, 130–131 level of analysis, 116–117, 117 local measurements inherently ambiguous, 116 motion integration across space, 115–123 motion integration across time, 120–123, 123 motor experience vs. visual experience, 128–133 motor expertise, 124–127 multiple apertures, 118 perceptual sensitivity to emotional actions, 136–137 point-light displays, 118–120, 119 social context and apparent human motion, 134–136, 135 social-emotional processes, 133–137 visual expertise, 127–128 Obliqueness alignment, 173–174, 174, 175 deined, 146 frames of reference, 173–174, 174, 175 Observation-execution matching system, 325 developmental evidence, 330–356 Occipito-parietal cortex, 247–268 Open-loop behavior, 7 P Parameters frames of reference, 147 inter-location relations, 147 types, 147 Parietal cortex, 209 mirror systems, 46–47 Path integration, adaptation, 20 Perceived egocentric distance, measurement, 1–33 Perceived exocentric distance, distance perception, distortions, 29–30 Perceived shape, distance perception, distortions, 29–30 Perception, 204, see also Speciic type action continuous, graded representations, 48 expertise, 53–58 characterized, 45 concept-measurement relationship, 3–4 representational nature, 2–3
426
Subject Index
Perception-action studies, infant perception development, 276 learning, 276 Perception-action systems, infants, 286–287 Perception of others, inherently social, 79 Percept-percept couplings, distance perception, 4 Perceptually directed action, 7, 12–19 adaptation, 20–25, 22 distance-speciic adaptation, 22–23 angular declination, 17, 20 calibration, 12–13, 19–25 infant locomotion, 275–315 on-line modiications, 18–19 spatial updating, 19 systematic error, 19–20 Perceptual representations, 46 Peripersonal space, 248 brain, 248 characterized, 184 extinction, 248 neuroimaging studies, 247–268 spatial encoding, 265–268 Personal space, characterized, 184 Perspective hypothesis, 373–376, 403 claims, 373–374 grammar coreference, 379–380 delaying commitment, 380–382 noncentrality, 380 structure vs. function, 378–384 Perspective taking, grammar clitic assimilation, 392 empathy, 397 evidentiality, 397–399 implicit causality, 393–395 metaphor, 399 perspectival overlays, 395–399 space, 395–396 time, 396–397 Perspective tracking, 376 ambiguity, 384–387 relativization, 382–384, 389–392 scope, 387–389 grammar, 373 maintenance, 378 modiication, 378 shit, 378 projection, 372–373 sentence comprehension
competition, 377 cues, 377 incremental interpretation, 376 load reduction, 376–377 principles, 376–377 role slots, 377 starting points, 377 Phenomenal world, 2 Philosophy, psychology, relationship, 204 Pitch, 147 Point-light displays, 118–120, 119 drawing, 60–62 gait, 59–60 handwriting, 60–62 Positron emission tomography, superior parieto-occipital cortex, 256–257 Posterior parietal cortex, 218–220 Postperceptual processes, 12 Pragmatic representations, 210–211 Premotor cortex, mirror systems, 47 Projection, 370–373 body image matching, 370–371 empathy, 372 localization, 371 perspective tracking, 372–373 Proprioception, action understanding, 69–70 Psyche, 204 Psychology history of, 204–210 neglected body, 204 philosophy, relationship, 204 Purpose, spatial perception, 183 Putting, spatial perception, 196–197 R Radical interactionism, 45–46 vs. common coding theory of perception and actions, 47 Rats in maze, 206 Reaching spatial perception, 184–186 extending reach with tool, 184 tool efe ct, 184, 185 superior parieto-occipital cortex, 249– 258, 250, 254, 256–257 preferential response to objects within reachable space, 259–262, 260 Recalibration blind walking, 21–22 general form, 23 verbal reports, 21–22
Subject Index Reduced-cue conditions, blind walking, 9–10, 10 Relativization, 382–384, 389–392 Representation, common coding theory of perception and actions, 47–48 Representative realism, 2 Right-hand rule, 162–164, 163, 171 Roll, 147 S Scale, virtual reality systems, uniform scale compression, 2 Scale construction, distance perception, 5 Searching, perseverative errors in searching for hidden objects, 331–338, 332, 333, 336, 338 Self-generated actions action identiication, 58–65 gait, self-recognition, 59–60 Self-identiication, auditory stimulus, 62–65 Self-other mapping, 83–93 Self-other relationships, intentionality, 82 Self-recognition, gait, individualistic styles, 60 Sensory neuronopathy, action understanding, 69–70 Sentence comprehension, perspective tracking competition, 377 cues, 377 incremental interpretation, 376 load reduction, 376–377 principles, 376–377 role slots, 377 starting points, 377 Shared representation, 355 Simulation, 48 Situated cognition, 46 Situated robotics, 209 Size-distance invariance, 4–5 deined, 4–5 Emmert’s Law, 5 Slant perception, 189–191, 195 Slopes, 289–290, 297–380, 299 Social-emotional processes, 133–137 Social perception, 79–102 autism, 97–100 atypical face and conigural processing, 98–99 body perception, 99 diiculties in social adjustment, 98
427
mimicry, 98 perceiving emotion from movement, 100 rule-based approach of emotional perception, 99–100 social-emotional perception, 99–100 template-based processes, 99, 100 body-speciic representations and processes, 81 creating self-other correspondences, 83–93 deicits in understanding others, 97–100 embodied cognition, added complexities, 81–83 importance, 80–81 specialized body processing, 87–90 specialized body processing sources, 90–92 specialized body representations, 84–86 using one’s own body to organize information from others, 86–87 Spatial image nonperceptual input, 15 path integration, 16 updating, 16, 16 Spatial perception action, 6–10 action-speciic approach, 183–199 body, 181–183 action-speciic perception, 181 behavioral ecology, 180–182 characterized, 179 dorsal processing, 188, 189 falling, 194–195 cost of injury, 195 slant perception, 195 vertical distance overestimation, 195–196 grasping, 186–188 let-handed people, 187 right-handed people, 186–187 hitting, 196–197 purpose, 183 putting, 196–197 putting together what, where, and how, 197–199 reaching, 184–186 extending reach with tool, 184 tool efe ct, 184, 185 spatial updating, 6–10 throwing, 193–194 anticipated efort, 194
428
Subject Index
Spatial perception (continued) efort associated with, 193 intention of throwing, 193 ventral processing, 188, 189 visually speciied environment, 179–181 walking, 188–193 behavioral ecology, 192–193 perceiving distances, 192 psychophysical response compression, 190 slant perception, 189–191 surface layout of ground, 188–189 Spatial thinking, 170 Spatial updating distance perception, 1, 2, 6–10 accuracy, 1–2 perceptually directed action, 19 spatial perception, 6–10 Split treadmill, 354–355 Structuralism, 204 Substance dualism, 204 Superior parieto-occipital cortex activation foci, 266–268, 267 functional magnetic resonance imaging, 247–268 activation from arm transport during reaching actions, 249–258, 250, 254, 256–257 in humans, 247–268 preference for near gaze, 262–266, 264 preference for objects within arm’slength, 259–262, 260 magnetoencephalography, 256–257 positron emission tomography, 256–257 reaching, 249–258, 250, 254, 256–257 preferential response to objects within reachable space, 259–262, 260 visual perception, preference for near gaze, 262–266, 264 T Tasks, frames of reference, 145 own intrinsic frame of representation, 146 Teleoperator systems, 3 hro wing, 7 spatial perception, 193–194 anticipated efort, 194 efort associated with, 193 intention of throwing, 193 Timing information, 62–64 Tools, 186 Touch, action understanding, 69–70
Trajectory, velocity, 50–51 Triad judgments, 154–155, 155 Triangulation methods, distance perception, 10–12, 11, 13 Two-thirds power law, 50–51 Two visual systems debate about, 1 distance perception, action-speciic representations, 30–32 U Ultrasound, 171 Understanding others body posture, 94–97 facial expression, 94–97 V Velocity handwriting, 61–62 trajectory, 50–51 Ventral processing, spatial perception, 188, 189 Ventral visual pathway, 324–325 Verbal reports distance perception, 4, 5 efect of feedback, 21–22 egocentric distance, spatial updating to correct for bias, 25–29, 27 recalibration, 21–22 systematic underreporting bias, 26–29, 27, 28 Vertical distance overestimation, 195–196 Virtual reality, 172–173 uniform scale compression, 2 Visual attention, action-speciic, 181 Visual distance perception, 23–25, 24 Visual expertise, 91 Visually directed pointing, 7 Visually speciied environment, spatial perception, 179–181 Visual perception, see also Visual system blind walking, gain, 21 learning new motor task, 56–57 superior parieto-occipital cortex, preference for near gaze, 262–266, 264 Visual processing, 216–218 afordance competition hypothesis, 216–218 Visual space perception, 3 Visual stimulus, above-ground plane, 17, 17–18
Subject Index Visual system, 113, see also Visual perception human motion action perception vs. object perception, 121–137 aperture problem, 115, 115–118, 117 bodily form, 131–133 controlling for viewpoint-dependent visual experience, 130–131 level of analysis, 116–117, 117 local measurements inherently ambiguous, 116 motion integration across space, 115–123 motion integration across time, 120–123, 123 motor experience vs. visual experience, 128–133 motor expertise, 124–127 multiple apertures, 118 perceptual sensitivity to emotional actions, 136–137 point-light displays, 118–120, 119 social context and apparent human motion, 134–136, 135 social-emotional processes, 133–137 visual expertise, 127–128 modular understanding, 113 object motion action perception vs. object perception, 121–137 aperture problem, 115, 115–118, 117 bodily form, 131–133 controlling for viewpoint-dependent visual experience, 130–131
429
level of analysis, 116–117, 117 local measurements inherently ambiguous, 116 motion integration across space, 115–123 motion integration across time, 120–123, 123 motor experience vs. visual experience, 128–133 motor expertise, 124–127 multiple apertures, 118 perceptual sensitivity to emotional actions, 136–137 point-light displays, 118–120, 119 social context and apparent human motion, 134–136, 135 social-emotional processes, 133–137 visual expertise, 127–128 Visual virtual reality, perceptual errors, 10, 11 Voluntary action, ideomotor principle, 46 W Walking infants, 285–286 spatial perception, 188–193 behavioral ecology, 192–193 perceiving distances, 192 psychophysical response compression, 190 slant perception, 189–191 surface layout of ground, 188–189 Y Yaw, 147