Cine-Dispositives: Essays in Epistemology Across Media 9789048523443

This collection brings together a number of leading scholars in film studies to explore viewing and listening dispositiv

166 85 2MB

English Pages 386 [412] Year 2015

Report DMCA / Copyright

DOWNLOAD PDF FILE

Table of contents :
Contents
Acknowledgments
Questioning The Word “Dispositif”
Foreword
I. Dispositives Programs
The Dispositive Does Not Exist!
Between Knowing And Believing
II. Dispositives Issues
“You Do Not Even Know Where You Are”
Marey And The Synthesis Of Movement
Notes On The Bergsonian Cinematograph
The Stereopticon And Cinema
On Some Limitations Of The Definition Of The Dispositive “Cinema”
The Moment Of The “Dispositif”
The “Dispositive Effect” In Film Narrative
III. Dispositives Histories
The Social Imaginary Of Telephony
Between Paradoxical Spectacles And Technical Dispositives
Forms Of Machines, Forms Of Movement
The Amateur-Dispositive
Two Versions Of The Television Dispositive
Reality Television As Dispositive: The Case Of French-Speaking Switzerland
Dispositive And Cinepoetry, Around Foucault’S Death And The Labyrinth
Archaeology And Spectacle
About The Authors
Index Of Titles
Index Of Names
Recommend Papers

Cine-Dispositives: Essays in Epistemology Across Media
 9789048523443

  • 0 0 0
  • Like this paper and download? You can publish your own PDF file online for free in a few minutes! Sign Up
File loading please wait...
Citation preview

Cine-Dispositives

Cine-Dispositives Essays in Epistemology Across Media

Edited by François Albera and Maria Tortajada

Amsterdam University Press

This publication was supported by Réseau Cinéma CH, Université de Lausanne (UNIL), as well as the Faculté des Lettres and the department of Film History and Aesthetics at the UNIL.

Translations by Franck Le Gac. Cover illustration: Still from the lost film Voyage de noces en ballon (Honeymoon in a balloon) directed by Georges Méliès (1908). Cover design: Kok Korpershoek, Amsterdam Lay-out: Crius Group, Hulshout Amsterdam University Press English-language titles are distributed in the US and Canada by the University of Chicago Press. isbn 978 90 8964 666 8 e-isbn 978 90 4852 344 3 nur 670 © F. Albera, M. Tortajada / Amsterdam University Press B.V., Amsterdam 2015 All rights reserved. Without limiting the rights under copyright reserved above, no part of this book may be reproduced, stored in or introduced into a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means (electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise) without the written permission of both the copyright owner and the author of the book.

Contents Acknowledgments 9 Questioning the Word “Dispositif”

Note on the Translation François Albera and Maria Tortajada (editors); Franck Le Gac (translator)

11

Foreword 15 François Albera and Maria Tortajada

I. Dispositives: Programs The Dispositive Does Not Exist!

21

Between Knowing and Believing

45

François Albera, Maria Tortajada

The Cinematic Dispositive after Cinema Thomas Elsaesser

II. Dispositives: Issues “You Do Not Even Know Where You Are”

75

Marey and the Synthesis of Movement

93

Dispositive and Dizziness Patrick Désile

The Reconstruction of a Concept Maria Tortajada

Notes on the Bergsonian Cinematograph

115

The Stereopticon and Cinema

129

Elie During

Media Form or Platform? Charles Musser

On Some Limitations of the Definition of the Dispositive “Cinema”

161

The Moment of the “Dispositif”

179

The “Dispositive Effect” in Film Narrative

195

André Gaudreault

Omar Hachemi

Philippe Ortel

III. Dispositives: Histories The Social Imaginary of Telephony

217

Between Paradoxical Spectacles and Technical Dispositives

249

Forms of Machines, Forms of Movement

275

The Amateur-Dispositive

299

Two Versions of the Television Dispositive

319

Fictional Dispositives in Albert Robida’s Le Vingtième Siècle and the Archeology of “Talking Cinema” Alain Boillat

Looking Again at the (Serpentine) Dances of Early Cinema Laurent Guido

Benoît Turquety

François Albera

Gilles Delavaud

Reality Television as Dispositive: The Case of French-Speaking Switzerland 341 Charlotte Bouchez

Dispositive and Cinepoetry, around Foucault’s Death and the Labyrinth 359 Christophe Wall-Romana

Archaeology and Spectacle

379

About the Authors

393

Index of Titles

399

Index of Names

403

Old Dispositives and New Objects for Surprised Spectators Stopping by the Museum Viva Paci

Acknowledgments The editors are grateful to Thomas Elsaesser for making this publishing project possible. They would like to emphasize that the University of Lausanne (UNIL), the Faculty of Humanities of the UNIL and the Réseau/Netzwerk Cinema CH contributed to the realization of this project. They would also like to thank the editors at AUP, and especially Jeroen Sondervan, for their help with producing this book.



Questioning the Word “Dispositif” Note on the Translation François Albera and Maria Tortajada (editors); Franck Le Gac (translator)

Since the nineteenth century, the term “dispositif” has been used extensively in French, from the most trivial sense to the most theoretically sophisticated. Its function as a concept developed within what has been called “French theory” in the anglophone world – and more specifically within the work of Michel Foucault, where it appears next to that of “archeology” in The Archaeology of Knowledge, before taking hold in Discipline and Punish. In film studies, the notion of “dispositif” was central to the theorizations referred to as “apparatus theory” that emerged in the 1970s. In French, however, the term frequently designates a technical setup – the basis for a mechanical arrangement, a small appliance or the most complex machinery – while also pointing to any concrete or abstract system. It also shares its original meaning in the legal domain with the English “dispositive,” which, unlike its French counterpart, is rarely used. As for “dispositif” in its technical sense, in English it is translated as “appliance,” “device,” “setup,” “system” or, in some cases, “apparatus.” Finally, some of the theoretical senses of the term appear as “apparatus” in English, notably in the discourse of ideological film criticism in the 1970s and in some translations of Foucault. Still, some other translations of the philosopher’s work simply repeat the French “dispositif,” a choice fully justified by the specificity of the Foucauldian concept, which implies both a method for discursive analysis supported by an epistemological practice and a conception of processes involved in power. The present collection of essays sets out to explore different uses of the term “dispositif,” starting from its polysemy in French, and aims to open the field to new forms of theorizations of viewing and listening dispositives by exploiting the rich potential of the notion. One particular aim is to move away from the historically circumscribed use of “dispositif” by apparatus theory – not to overshadow it, but rather, to revitalize the concept by opening it up to new approaches. During the translation of most of the studies in this book into English, we met with several difficulties. The first is the complex history of the translation of the term “dispositif” in English, a translation wavering

12 

FR ANÇOIS ALBER A AND MARIA TORTA JADA

between several formulations, forcing those who confront it to reposition themselves. A second obstacle was to take stock of the very different uses of the notion of “dispositif” in the two linguistic spaces that force francophone and anglophone scholars into starkly contrasting positions. In French, the term “dispositif” is polysemic and, in spite of available synonyms, it may be found in all kinds of writings in the most diverse fields, in scientific as well as common usage; in English, the notion invites specification, and assumes multiple guises (the terms “apparatus,” “device,” “appliance” or even the French “dispositif,” as we already pointed out). A last issue was that we were confronted with two strong theoretical uses of the term “dispositif,” already mentioned, which brought the risk of restricting notions that we wanted to make available for new reappropriations. This is the challenge that has been met by the contributors to the book, each of them in his or her own way, yet always with the historicity of the term in mind. The question remains, then: how to translate the polysemy and the conceptual diversity of the French term “dispositif” in English? We abstained from systematic use of the French “dispositif,” convinced that the violence done to a language is justified only when the foreign term, in a neologism of sorts, refers to an extremely structured concept in its source language. Philosophy is familiar with this practice, which is justified where Foucault is concerned. On the other hand, “apparatus” appeared marked by its very dated use in apparatus theory; while it may have technical aspects, it is not as broad as the French term “dispositif” as arrangement. We are therefore putting forward a radical proposal, playing on the connections between French and English, the history of the two languages, in which many words have common roots and sometimes even similar spellings. “Dispositif” and “dispositive” are cousins; brothers even, perhaps, in the sounds conveyed by language, in their etymology, as well as in their original legal definition. In our view, “dispositive,” once reappropriated, could account for the specificity of the French term, thanks to these origins and proximity. Some may see in our proposition another form of violence, consisting in the redynamization of a word within the same language, a word that in itself perhaps “spoke” very little. Still, this is a common method in all living practices of language, one that is not only legitimate but also necessary in a theoretical or historical project. We wanted to see the polysemic theater of the French use of the term play out in the English versions of the studies presented here. With the issue of translation, the volume travels the passage between the two languages: what does it mean to theorize in French and in English? Or to work through concepts in their historical value across languages? Our answer is partial yet pragmatic. It was not

Questioning the Word “Dispositif”

13

enough to underscore the French origin of the word “dispositif”: the plurality of notions tied to the term in English also had to be taken into account. English synonyms for “dispositifs” have thus been added to the English term “dispositive” when specification was imperative. In short, with this dual choice, we sought to keep explicit the tension between two aims whose contradiction is only apparent: an emancipation from the historical uses of the French term and the development of new uses and methods with regard to these historical uses. In our view, this liminal choice, on the edge of two languages, presents yet another advantage. Freeing the translation of “dispositif” from its historical uses, “dispositive” accounts for the very diverse work of the authors within their own practices. They cooperated at every stage, beyond even the translation of texts, since Charles Musser and Thomas Elsaesser agreed to subject the original versions of their articles to the global project of the book’s translation, ensuring its overall coherence. From a practical standpoint, and by way of recapitulation, we proceeded as follows. In keeping with the distinctions we wished to maintain or establish between the different notions linked to “dispositifs,” the French dispositif has been kept in English but italicized when referring to the Foucauldian notion, itself distinct from the psychoanalytical apparatus of 1960s and 1970s film theory. Still, in many of Foucault’s texts involving the notion, the English translation is “apparatus,” as some quotations in several chapters make clear. We opted to preserve the integrity of these quotations, even though their choice of terminology was at odds with ours. Conversely, even though the word “apparatus” is frequently used in English in the sense of a machine, a set of equipment designed for a particular function – especially in the context of early cinema – we preferred “device” or “appliance” in these cases, for the sake of clarity. Because the other concern of the editors was to preserve the polysemy of the French word “dispositif” while clearly signaling a shift away from apparatus theory in film studies, we have accordingly used the English term “dispositive,” whose legal meaning in English overlaps with one definition of the French “dispositif.” In this volume, “dispositive” refers to simple or complex mechanical arrangements, that is, as a synonym for “appliance” or “device” in that sense; and to a spatial organization of elements, mechanical or not, producing a specific position for an observer, user or spectator. This concerns technical arrangements, scientific experiments and scenic setups (exhibitions in museums or galleries, scenic arrangements in the theater or scenic situations in literature, to name but a few).

14 

FR ANÇOIS ALBER A AND MARIA TORTA JADA

“Dispositive” was also used to translate the editors’ own, more recent development and specification of the notion. Finally, in passages of the text where the authors transition from one inception of the term to another (which occasionally corresponds to a change in the English word used as an equivalent), the French “dispositif” appears as such, between quotation marks. For further information, see “The Dispositive Does Not Exist!” The translations that are not referenced in the English edition are the translator’s own.

Foreword François Albera and Maria Tortajada The purpose of the present volume is to (re-)examine the question of viewing and listening dispositives, from the emergence of the notion in the field of film studies in the late 1960s to the more limited – technical and descriptive – use that followed, as well as the parallel elaboration on the term by Michel Foucault, on a completely different scale, in Discipline and Punish, up to more recent developments in literature and art. The book also aims to confront approaches and perspectives in the very different context that is ours today: the generalization of new technologies, the digital era and the appearance of new theoretical developments around these phenomena, new models of knowledge generally situated in the field of media (we are thinking of Jonathan Crary, Friedrich Kittler and Lev Manovich, among others). The emergence of the notion of “dispositif” in film studies was tied to a model of cinema and film corresponding to the “classical” period of the medium, previously examined with different tools by Christian Metz and the various semiological trends. Theoreticians of the “dispositif” intended to move beyond these approaches by focusing on spectators and their place in the cinematic event. Starting in 1978, however, the historiographic turn in film studies towards early cinema brought a starkly different model of cinema and film to the fore, challenging an important part of the historical and theoretical legacy that had dominated the study of cinema for decades. The context of new technologies has shifted the boundaries and spaces of “cinema” yet again. The (ongoing) research on “early cinema” has probably done much to prepare researchers for the current situation, which, as has often been stated, shares a number of characteristics with that of the beginnings of cinema (heterogeneity, intermediality, attraction, incompletion, variability in reception, and so forth). Traits of this “past” cinema resurfaced and could then be reconstructed in light of the present (experimental cinema, then new media), in a sort of “backward movement of the true.” At the same time, processes of remediation, technological transfers or the translation of models from one media to another (that of sound with respect to the image, for instance, or, more recently, of the computer with regard to the editing table and new modes of sharing) are remapping the field of study. Within these diverse frameworks and environments, is an approach in terms of “dispositifs” still relevant and effective? Does the obsolescence of the original apparatus theory point to the need to move beyond any

16 

François Albera and Maria Tortajada

apprehension of the cinema in these terms? In other words, is the notion still elastic enough to remain pertinent in relation to its object(s), or should we consider that it is linked to an epistemic situation, a historical state of viewing and listening machines? These questions provided some of the rationale for the international conference organized at the Université de Lausanne, “Dispositifs de vision et d’audition: épistémologie et bilan.” Locally, the event took place within the logic of a general line of research and teaching in the university’s department of Film History and Aesthetics, with a possible prospective program sketched out as early as 2002 with “L’Épistémè 1900,” delivered at the seventh Domitor conference (“Cinéma des premiers temps: technologies et dispositifs”).1 It is within this area, gradually developed and enriched, that a number of projects were undertaken in the department, materializing in three collective publications.2 At an international level, two conferences had preceded the one on viewing and listening dispositives: the first in Louvain-la-Neuve in April 1998 (“Dispositifs et médiations des savoirs,” co-organized by the Université Paris 8 - St-Denis - Vincennes, the FNRS in Belgium, the CNRS in France and the European Commission), and the second in Marne-la-Vallée in October 2006 (“Les Dispositifs,” with the ENS Louis Lumière, the Université de Marne-la-Vallée and the LISAA).3 Both showed the success enjoyed by 1 The contribution appears in Le Cinéma, nouvelle technologie du XXe siècle/The Cinema, A New Technology for the 20th Century, André Gaudreault, Catherine Russell and Pierre Veronneau, eds. (Lausanne: Payot, 2004). Other interventions at the conference, which epitomized a “return” to a functional, descriptive sense of “dispositifs” and to some degree a refusal to problematize the notion, were published in Cinema & Cie 3 (2003), “Les technologies de représentation et le discours sur le dispositif cinématographique des premiers temps,” and in CiNéMAS 14.1 (2003), “Dispositif(s) du cinéma (des premiers temps).” 2 In order of publication: Cinema Beyond Film. Media Epistemology in the Modern Era, François Albera and Maria Tortajada, eds. (Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press, 2009), with contributions from the editors as well as Alain Boillat, Laurent Guido and Olivier Lugon; La Télévision, du téléphonoscope à YouTube. Pour une archéologie de l’audiovision, Mireille Berton and Ann-Katrin Weber, eds. (Lausanne: Antipodes, 2009), with contributions from the editors, François Albera, Stefan Andriopoulos, Christina Bartz, Alain Boillat, Gilles Delavaud, Laurent Guido, Kurd Lasswitz, Lynn Spiegel, Maria Tortajada, William Uricchio, Siegfried Zielinski and others; Between Still and Moving Images, Laurent Guido and Olivier Lugon, eds. (Herts, U.K.: John Libbey, 2012), with contributions from the editors as well as François Albera, Alain Boillat, Mireille Berton, Christa Blümlinger, Wolfgang Brückle, Myriam Chermette, Clément Chéroux, Michel Frizot, Tom Gunning, Maria Tortajada, Valérie Vignaux and others. 3 The Louvain conference resulted in a publication in the periodical Hermès. See Hermès 25, “Le dispositif entre usage et concept” (Paris: Editions du CNRS, 1999). Contributions from the Marnela-Vallée conference appeared in issue 4 of Cahier Louis-Lumière (2007), titled “Les dispositifs.”

Foreword

17

the notion, which for some had become a “meta-concept,” while for others the “dispositif” had supplanted “structure” or was close to the Deleuzian rhizome.4 A philosopher also asked the radical question of what a “dispositif” was.5 The confrontation between the researchers attending the conference, who came from different disciplines and “schools of thought,” gave rise to exchanges that proved fruitful and convinced us of the renewed vitality and fertility of a theory of “dispositifs.” Most of the papers presented at the conference have been rewritten to form the substance of this book. A few later contributions have been added; they were part of a cycle of lectures around the issue of “dispositifs,” which started in 2011. Open to international scholars, the cycle was also connected to the doctoral school and to ProDoc programs financed by the FNS. The studies included here have been divided into three parts: Programs, Issues and Histories. The first part presents two types of programmatic projects related to two institutions of higher education that collaborate with each other while maintaining their distinctive characteristics: the department of Film History and Aesthetics at the Université de Lausanne (François Albera and Maria Tortajada, “The Dispositive Does Not Exist!”) and the department of Visual Studies at the University of Amsterdam (Thomas Elsaesser, “Between Knowing and Believing: The Cinematic Dispositive after Cinema”). The second part questions the notion of the dispositive by confronting it with one or several objects: spectacles in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries (Patrick Désile), the stereopticon (Charles Musser), the praxinoscope-theater (André Gaudreault); the theoretical corpus of a thinker such as Bergson (Elie During) and a scientist like Marey (Maria Tortajada); or its own theoretical elaboration (Omar Hachemi) and the relation it establishes between two fields, for instance with the “dispositive effect” in film narrative (Philippe Ortel). The third part brings together studies that start from a concrete technical object or set of objects, such as the crank in different viewing or listening machines (Benoît Turquety) or the dispositives of early serpentine dance films (Laurent Guido); from imaginary objects, telephony as imagined by Robida (Alain Boillat) and Raymond Roussel’s machines as seen through 4 Bernard Vouilloux, “Critique des dispositifs,” Critique 718 (March 2007). 5 Giorgio Agamben, What Is an Apparatus? (Stanford: Stanford U. P., 2009). More recently, the word has been used in the context of a restrictive definition of cinema: Raymond Bellour, La Querelle des dispositifs. Cinéma - installations, expositions (Paris: POL, 2012).

18 

François Albera and Maria Tortajada

the prism of Foucault’s analyses (Christophe Wall-Romana); and from an institutional ensemble ranging from amateur cinema in the 1920s (François Albera) to television (Gilles Delavaud) and reality television in Frenchspeaking Switzerland (Charlotte Bouchez), to installations in the space of the museum (Viva Paci).

I. Dispositives Programs



The Dispositive Does Not Exist! François Albera, Maria Tortajada

Five ways to approach the dispositive emerge from the texts that appear in this volume; none is exclusive of the others, some are conjoined or articulated, some are separate. In French, the term ”dispositif” refers to a plurality of meanings, from the simple mechanism of a device, instrument or machine, to the epistemological construction liable to produce effects of power and knowledge – the disciplinary dispositif or the dispositif of sexuality. From its most concrete to its most abstract definition, the “dispositif” involves the common signification of arrangement. Still, the different meanings of the notion subject it – and its users – to a considerable conceptual stretch, between empiricism and epistemology. We thus propose to examine these meanings so as to explain our own “programmatic” proposition, which is epistemological in nature.

Five Definitions of the Notion of “Dispositif” The most common definition refers to “the way in which the organs of a device are placed” (circa 1860), soon supplemented by another meaning, that of sets of mechanical elements combined with a view to an effect, a result (Littré, 1874). Until then, the word had only assumed its (original) meaning in the judicial domain (as the part of a legislative text that settles a type of case imperatively); and, more recently, in the field of military science (as a set of measures, of means organized towards a strategic end).1 As it appeared in the technical field, the word thus pointed to a degree of complexity, the relation of elements constitutive of a device, assembled and arranged, and the pursuit of an effect. Within this usual definition, a “dispositif” differs from a tool (pliers, be they universal), an instrument (the dentist’s drill), a machine (a band saw) or even an appliance (the telephone), in spite of the fact that it tends to substitute metonymically for this latter 1 Quite evidently, these levels are not hermetic, which from a methodological standpoint represents one of the difficulties of our approach. Even the genealogy of the word may shed light on later uses: the “military,” and more particularly the “strategic” dimension, is present in Foucault’s appropriation of the notion; similarly, Giorgio Agamben has re-appropriated the legal aspect of the notion.

22 

François Albera, Maria Tortajada

object. Indeed, all of these examples are given “in one piece,” as a whole, in a linear relation to their user (as an extension of the hand) or, in the case of complex machines (even more so nowadays with computers), as what Bruno Latour calls “black boxes.” This is not to say that they may not constitute a “dispositif” or involve one or several internal “dispositifs” (the on/off switch being one example); or that they may not become a part in a “dispositif” we call external in senses we will specify further on. It all depends on the perspective adopted, on the object produced by the scholar. In early cinema, the term “dispositif” recurred quite frequently in reported speech or in writings by the Lumière brothers themselves: patents, descriptions of their invention, various narrations. Its characterization as a combination of several mechanisms is evident in Auguste Lumière’s evocations of his brother Louis’ invention. Louis, in his view, did not come up with a device in one piece, a machine; rather, he reused some preexisting systems, improved on others, and ended up combining Edison’s kinetoscope and the system ensuring alternate immobilization and advance in sewing machines.2 The system of intermittent stops allowing the projection of a chronophotographic strip of film could thus be found within the appliance called the “cinématographe.”3 Yet when the appliance – and its internal systems – were in operation at the time of shooting or, conversely, in a theatrical space in front of a screen and in the presence of spectators, it instituted a dispositive connecting different agents: the cinematograph. Two technical levels in the definition of ”dispositifs” thus emerge: 1. the systems internal to the machine, a number of mechanisms operating with 2 Mechanisms are mentioned throughout the main patent (nº 245 032, dated February 13, 1895). On page 4, the sentence “it ensues from this disposition” indicates the positioning of different elements as part of the mechanism. This term, “disposition,” is repeated in patent nº 323 667 for the continuous-run projector registered in 1902, in which the term “dispositif” also appears: “[…] we claim as our own the invention […] of a dispositive designed to stabilize the projection of each frame on the screen and, reciprocally, to form images of each point in space on the same points of the mobile film, the said dispositive consisting in two flat mirrors forming a right angle […].” In later texts, patents as well as catalogs, the term frequently appeared: “the dispositives introduced in the latter in order to obtain negatives and print positives” (1904); “We shall see how, thanks to the dispositives used in the frame, the cinematograph fitted with claws can drive the film in one direction or the other […]. Another particularity of the appliance […] is the dispositive that makes it possible, simultaneously, to move the viewer in which the operator follows the scene being photographed, and the frame bounding the image on the film” (Patent nº 410 495, Appliance to make cinematographic views with a reversible frame, 1910, signed Carpentier; our emphasis). 3 “I have devised a special dispositive of pins fitting into the perforations of the film…” See Louis Lumière, Sciences et voyages [1921], quoted in Bernard Chardère, Le Roman des Lumière (Paris: Gallimard, 1995) 284.

The Dispositive Does Not Exist!

23

their own coherence; and 2. the machine itself, or the appliance, as an assembly of various clusters of mechanisms, of different internal systems. The machine is not the sum of these parts, but the assembly allowing the mechanical and energetic connection of distinct internal systems. A third meaning is elaborated out of the first two. However, it is no longer limited to the operations of the appliance, the machine being considered or to the resulting effect: here the dispositive relates them to their users, to other appliances or machines, and defines a situation. Describing the dispositive built by engineer John T. Isaacs for Leland Stanford, which made possible a rather elaborate analysis of animal movement, Muybridge explained that thirty cameras with electric shutters had been built to take photographs of the horses and placed at about twelve inches from one another. In the same breath, he proposed to capture all imaginable attitudes of athletes, horses, oxen, dogs and other animals in movement. Echoing this, Michel Frizot writes of Marey’s photographic arrangement “as not simply a camera but as the whole experimental area that Marey set up in the Bois de Boulogne,”4 part of an “experiment” meeting a protocol: a dark shed, a black background, a subject dressed in white, a track, a mobile cabin on a rail, electric cables transmitting synchronizing signals and a rapidly rotating clock placed in the field of vision. In short, there is the arrangement of the appliance and the heterogeneous set of elements of which it becomes part, but there is also the individual for whom or by whom the dispositive operates: the scientist, or whoever experiments. This constitutes the third level in terms of technical arrangements, and consequently our third definition of “dispositif”: the new disposition in which the appliance or the machine as systems find their place, a disposition determined by a finality and a practice, and in which users, like the machines, are themselves elements. This dispositive is external. Much like the model of the machine as reconstructed by Gilbert Simondon, dispositives are ceaselessly caught up in new assemblies, themselves referred to as dispositives. In a sense, the relation which extends “the way in which the organs of a device are placed” to include complex, heterogeneous sets, is akin to a machination. The term connotes artifice and cunning as well as trickery (the conjuring table of magicians), but also refers to an ingenious disposition or mechanism in its original sense (machinatio). Similarly, the words “machine” and “machiner” (“to arrange”) are used in French about a painting

4

Michel Frizot, A New History of Photography (London: Könemann, 1998) 249.

24 

François Albera, Maria Tortajada

or a narrative composed with a given effect in mind.5 Beyond the strictly technical arrangement – or rather, in relation to it – other potential dimensions of the notion unfold. Retroactively, one may call dispositives the arrangements of mirrors detailed by Jurgis Baltrusaïtis,6 and which led visitors to imagine themselves as monsters; or even this situation of thwarted exhibitionism related by Jean-Jacques Rousseau early in his Confessions: One day, however, walking in the Contrà Nova pretty early in the morning, I saw, through a shop window, a young tradeswoman with such good grace and appealing air that, despite my timidity with ladies, I entered without hesitation. […] She was doing embroidery by a window, facing the side of the room in front of the door. She could not see me come in, nor could she hear me because of the noise of wagons in the street. Her finery came close to coquetry. Her attitude was graceful, her slightly lowered head let her white neck show; she wore her hair up elegantly and had adorned it with flowers. Her whole figure was pervaded with a charm which I had the time to consider, and which put me beside myself. I threw myself on my knees at the entrance of the room, stretching out my arms in a passionate movement, quite certain that she could not hear me, doubting that she could see me: but by the fireplace stood a mirror which betrayed me. Which effect this transport had on her I do not know; she did not look at me; but, half-turning her head, with a mere movement of the finger, she pointed at the mat at her feet. Startling, letting out a cry, rushing forward to the spot she had marked for me were all but the same thing to me: what is more difficult to believe, however, is that from then on I did not dare to take further initiatives or say a single word or look at her or even touch her to lean for one moment on her knees, even as I was in such an uncomfortable position. I was struck dumb, I kept still, though assuredly there was nothing quiet about me: everything in me spoke to agitation, joy, gratefulness, ardent desires uncertain in their object and 5 When Apollinaire stated that one had “to mechanize poetry as the world has been mechanized” (Selected Writings, New York, New Directions, 1971, p. 237), he was playing on the different meanings assumed by the word by moving the artistic “machine” (“a composition in which the painter introduces a number of objects whose felicitous combination requires genius,” according to an eighteenth-century dictionary) onto the side of the industrial machine and technology: the world being arranged or mechanized by railroads, the telegraph, electricity grids, etc. See Claude-Henri Watelet and Pierre-Charles Levesque, Dictionnaire des arts de peinture, sculpture et gravure, vol. 3, entry titled “Machine” (Paris: Prault, 1792) 355. 6 Jurgis Baltrusaïtis, Le Miroir, essai sur une légende scientifique (Paris: Le Seuil, 1978).

The Dispositive Does Not Exist!

25

contained by the fright of displeasing the person about whom my young heart could not be put at rest.7

The scene does not put viewing and listening machines into play, even as it has a place in the “new regime of imagination” which, according to Max Milner, “only the optical devices perfected during the eighteenth century and transferred by Robertson and others from the domain of ‘amusing physics’ to that of spectacle made it possible to describe.”8 Still, the scene does show the construction, the disposition to which a subject may be assigned in a setup that involves seeing, a pre-technological one in this instance. All in all, though indirectly technical, these examples fall within the third level of our definition, which makes the functioning of the mechanical “dispositif” (machine, appliance) more complex by including its user and its effect, linking them together according to the relation to the mirror, for instance.9 Indeed, within literary representation, fiction often takes as its objects dispositives organized around viewing or listening (the notable representatives of this vein are Cyrano de Bergerac, Villiers de l’Isle Adam, Jules Verne, and so forth). Besides the question of the seeing subject involved in these mechanical or specular dispositives, a second aspect whereby the setup is implied in literature – at the level of the very production of fiction – also belongs in this third level of our definition. The book becomes a dispositive like the exhibition and organizes the text on the model of an arrangement including the reader in a “machine” not limited to the textual, as Structuralism did postulate. Paul Valéry already wrote of a dispositive as he looked at the pages composed by Mallarmé for Un coup de dés; there the book became a “brand new machine”10 put into play by the poet on the occasion of his readings as part of a spectacular “ideographic” dispositive founded on the voice, light and occlusion behind a curtain (“Dernière visite à Mallarmé”).11 When in turn Francis Ponge used the term “dispositif” about Lautréamont in 1946, he was thinking of a genuine machine to transform text – that of Lautréamont’s Poésies, which turned the statements of great authors inside out – with extra-textual effects as a consequence (the library, literature as an institution). Ponge parodied an advertisement for a mechanical device 7 Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Confessions (1728; Paris: Gallimard, 1947) 71, 75. 8 Max Milner, La Fantasmagorie (Paris: PUF, 1982), 11. 9 This sense may also apply to other dispositives involving a spectator in relation to a representation: scenic setups such as those presented by museum or gallery exhibitions or scenic arrangements in theater. 10 Paul Valéry, “Le coup de dés,” Variétés II (Paris: Gallimard, 1930) 178. 11 Valéry, “Le coup de dés”: 189-90.

26 

François Albera, Maria Tortajada

akin to collapsible beds or bookcases.12 Again, the book then became a dispositive whose own “technique” made it comparable to arrangements in our third level, that is, involving a user in an assembly defined by its finality. This is probably where Bernard Vouilloux’s phrase proves the most pertinent: the dispositive is a structure in movement. The specific mention of whom the device operates for seems to us to define a fourth use of the notion of “dispositif,” found in what has been called “apparatus theory” in the United States. Jean-Louis Baudry put forward two versions of it. His first theorization, “Effets idéologiques produits par l’appareil de base,” published in issue 7/8 of Cinéthique (1970),13 did not involve the apparatus, unlike his 1972 article in Communications. The machine and the arrangement presupposing it are given as producing ideology. In this context, the apparatus and its technical-ideological analysis are primarily referred to the subject addressed by representation. In both cases, the notion of apparatus rests on the theory of representation, with the basic apparatus instituting a situation where the spectator is invited to vest belief in an impression of reality. This impression is caused by the type of representation projected on the screen, following the rules of monocular perspective. The emphasis on the perspective developed during the Quattrocento and its pictorial model (with Marcelin Pleynet and later Jean-Louis Comolli, starting from the work of Pierre Francastel14) was to grow within studies on painting as well, in particular with Louis Marin, whose concerns followed from Benveniste’s research on questions of enunciation and his theory of discourse.15 12 “Fit your personal library with the only device making it possible to scupper it and refloat it at will. […] Open Lautréamont! And there you have literature turned inside out like an umbrella! Close Lautréamont! And everything immediately falls back into place… To enjoy complete intellectual comfort at home, try and adapt the MALDOROR/POEMS device to your library.” See Francis Ponge, “Le dispositif Maldoror-Poésies,” reprinted in Méthodes (Paris: Gallimard, 1961) 210-11. Chance alone presided over the encounter, or the proximity, of this umbrella and the Lumière brothers’ sewing machine above. 13 Translator’s note: in its English version, however, the term chosen to translate “appareil” and “dispositif” was the same: “apparatus.” Baudry’s text was translated by Alan Williams and published as “Ideological Effects of the Basic Cinematographic Apparatus” in 1974. See Film Quarterly 28.2 (Winter 1974-1975): 39-47. His article titled “Le Dispositif” appeared as “The Apparatus,” trans. Jean Andrews and Bertrand Augst, Camera Obscura 1.11 (Fall 1976): 104-26. 14 See La Réalité figurative (Paris: Gonthier, 1965), La Figure et le lieu. L’ordre visuel du Quattrocento (Paris: Gallimard, 1967), as well as his courses at the Institut de filmologie, with which he started collaborating in 1947. 15 “Placed at the point of view of the perspectival apparatus [“dispositif perspectif”], the immobile spectator receives and may contemplate only one moment in the narrative which the painter has staged. […] In classical history painting, the spectator is structurally included

The Dispositive Does Not Exist!

27

As Baudry shifted from the basic apparatus [“appareil de base”] to the apparatus [“dispositif”], his approach to the spectator entered the Freudian and Lacanian metapsychological framework (the mirror stage for the child) and evolved from the impression of reality to the real-effect, articulated by Jean-Pierre Oudart. Cinema could no longer be reduced to its technological dimension. Pursuing this line of thought, Christian Metz also offered a critique of it, defining cinema as a symbolic apparatus in The Imaginary Signifier. These approaches shared a heuristic finality: to emphasize the place of the spectator in his status of presence-absence as regulated by the theory of representation, which, with perspective as its epitome, was precisely determined by a technical apparatus. The definition of the centered subject imposed by the theory could then spread through figurative as well as narrative arts, where “techniques” were also involved – in relation to speech and narration this time – founding the very use of the term “dispositif” in this context. The fifth meaning, elaborated by Foucault from Discipline and Punish on,16 introduces the issue of subjection. Subjection substitutes for “subjectivity” to underline the central, organizing place given to the subject, which lies at the center of approaches previously mentioned (Baudry, Marin, Metz). It was initiated by Althusser in his article on Ideological State Apparatuses and his concept of interpellation of individuals as subjects.17 In his course notes for the Collège de France, Foucault writes: “The psychological subject [of panopticism, discipline, and normalization] whose appearance is attested at the time […] is but the other side of this process of subjection.”18 However, in the perspectival apparatus which regulates any pictorial representation. He is included in it as a point of view, and as we know the position of this point in its relation to the representative screen and to the vanishing point determines the whole construction of the represented space. […] The perspective is the formal structure of representation, both as the production of painted appearances and as their reception by the contemplating eye. It is the metaphor of the apparatus of discourse in the iconic realm. […] From then on, the perspectival apparatus makes possible the inscription of the iconic narrative, but the latter neutralizes its own condition of inscription. The perspectival apparatus is posited as providing the narrative with its scene and its setting, the space where the narrated event is given to see, but it is concealed by narrative figuration. In the story, events seem to self-narrate in the sense that the narrator is no longer present in the narrative.” Louis Marin, “La fonction du spectateur et le dispositif perspectif,” in the entry “Représentation narrative,” Encyclopædia Universalis, CD-ROM (Paris: Encyclopaedia Universalis, 2004). 16 Michel Foucault, Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison, trans. Alan Sheridan (New York: Vintage, 1995). 17 Louis Althusser, “Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses” [1970], in Cultural Theory and Popular Culture: A Reader, ed. John Storey, 3rd ed. (Harlow, England: Pearson, 1994) 336-46. 18 Michel Foucault, Résumés des cours 1970-1982 (Paris: Julliard, 1989) 49-50.

28 

François Albera, Maria Tortajada

objecting to the State and its institutions as agents, a central argument of Althusser’s, and instead of analyzing the apparatus exercising power (i.e., the localizable, expansionist, repressive and legal institutions), Foucault analyzes the mechanisms (dispositifs) that have sapped the strength of these institutions and surreptitiously reorganized the functioning of power: “minuscule” technical procedures acting on and with details, redistributing a discursive space in order to make it the means of a generalized “discipline” (surveillance).19

A second phase of elaboration then situates the question of the institution of the subject – ”subjectivation” – on the side of techniques of the self that do have to do with governmentality, but unfold in the relation of oneself to oneself and of oneself to others, and are a condition of the social functioning of power. As we already stated, the various approaches to and uses of the notion of “dispositif” remain distinct yet merge, they may be mutually inclusive or presuppose one another. They start with the smallest arrangement (1) and extend to assemblages determined by situations of experimentation (3), in the meantime also going through devices-machines or appliances (2) to expand and include a representational problematization of apparatuses (4) or the implication of issues of power (5). While these five levels variously refer to the technical dimension of the notion of “dispositif,” the first three, more directly tied to mechanical-motor arrangements, are organized according to a common logic of “assemblage of assemblages.” The last two develop a potential involved in the third definition, which leads to a diversified thought on the subject in the “dispositif” – either all-powerful and deceived, or subjected.

Propositions In common discourse, “dispositif,” in its various meanings, refers to dated historical objects – rejects, even. Still, if we are to move beyond them, we 19 Michel de Certeau, The Practice of Everyday Life, trans. Steven Randall (Berkeley, Los Angeles: The University of California Press, 2011) xiv. Translator’s note: in the English edition quoted here, the word “apparatus” is the translation for the French “appareils” (in the plural in the original text).

The Dispositive Does Not Exist!

29

cannot content ourselves with a “dispositif” limited to a “meta-concept” or a “floating signifier,” a fashionable word used by every exhibition curator in a manner as ill-defined as it is extensive. The definitions – Foucault’s own, first and foremost – interest us on several levels as we attempt to elaborate a working method to draw up the conditions of possibility for viewing and listening dispositives. For some time, the assumption was that a reversal of its polarities opened the possibility of challenging the “coercive” dimensions of Foucault’s dispositif: with the advent of the digital age, “dispositifs” (computers, interfaces and networks) had allegedly become the sites of interactivity and exchange. Foucault was criticized for conceiving the dispositif as follows: “applying to the body of the individual, and as a consequence his/her mind, [while remaining] outside it; it produces subjectivity but is not produced by subjectivity.”20 As it happens, the great originality of Discipline and Punish, as well as later works by Foucault, certainly lies in the place given to freedom and autonomy in the social system of control and productivity. In other words, Foucault shows that the emancipation of the subject is part of his or her subjection. We reckon, with Giorgio Agamben, that our time belongs in the episteme described by Foucault. Automatically associating the issue of power with the notion of the “dispositif” becomes a problem, however, from the moment when research on “dispositifs” ceases to aim to outline the way power operates – which was Foucault’s project – or to take up the demonstration already produced by Foucault himself. In a way, we have to move away from Foucault to better shed light on a method which he paradoxically makes it possible to design. Indeed, through his analysis of processes of subjection, Foucault decisively furthered the notion of the “dispositif”; beyond the question of the said coercion, the notion is relevant to us in the analysis of viewing and listening dispositives. Rereading Foucault from the standpoint of his historical position in the French tradition of an epistemology of sciences, it is possible to lay the foundations of a method that would allow us to work with the notion of viewing and listening dispositives, a point to which we will return. The interest of the notion of the dispositive and the importance of further refining it also has to do with the reference to the field of techniques, appliances, the possible reintegration of the technical history of cinema within film history in a different mode than as an isolated narrative, a catalog, a list of inventions and geniuses. Necessary though this catalog may be, its limits (patents, for the most part) have given license to theoreticians, 20 André Berten, “Dispositif, médiation, créativité: petite généalogie,” Hermès 25 (1999): 35.

30 

François Albera, Maria Tortajada

critics and estheticians to circumvent it and confine their approach to the framework of representation or its sole social effects. The technical dimension, approached through the question of the dispositive, brings together a) the spectator, the environment, the user; b) the machine, the appliance or appliances; and c) the institution or institutions. These point to three areas which film studies keeps separate: sociology and economy, technical history and patents, and aesthetics. Yet these three areas interact at the level of the production of images and sounds as much as their reception, even if some analysts privilege one of the two poles. In 1935 Lucien Febvre spelled out a program in Les Annales. Historians of techniques such as Maurice Daumas and Bertrand Gilles were to refer to this agenda in the 1960s and 1970s (as were Leroi-Gourhan and Haudricourt, among others): 1) a technical history of technique (the study of processes, sets of tools, technical activities); 2) a study of these sets of processes, tools, activities of making as they are affected by an evolutive history in which progress raises questions about their realization (theory and practice, science and technical invention); 3) a study of the relations between technical activity and other human activities (religion, art, politics) from which “it may not be isolated”; in short, how technique is affected by general history and how in turn it influences it – a discipline which only the convergence and collaboration of scientists, technicians and historians can create.21 The study of cinema needs this technical history of techniques and the construction of the network of discourses, practices and institutions relating them to the representation that cinema is too often limited to (aesthetics). For instance, linking the evolution of techniques of the moving image to research on fixing a soap bubble or analyzing walking – which two scholars at the Department of History and Philosophy of Sciences at the University of Cambridge, Simon Schaffer and Andreas Mayer,22 have set out to do – makes a number of elements visible: the web of research experiments in physics and physiology, but also pictorial or fictional representations with optical toys, stop-motion shooting, approaches to cinema through categories of thought (“evanescence,” “ephemerality,” “fixation,” etc.) and social practices (scientific popularization, techniques of the body…). 21 See Les Annales 36 (30 Nov. 1935): 531-35. This renewal started in part with authors like Simondon, Dagognet, Ellul, Beaune and Latour, to name a few, but has not concerned film studies in spite of some efforts – far too rare and tending towards vague extrapolations or, conversely, empirical description. 22 Simon Schaffer, “Une science de l’éclat. Les bulles de savon et l’art de faire de la physique à l’époque victorienne,” and Andreas Mayer, “Faire marcher les hommes et les images. Les artifices du corps en mouvement” [2004] in Terrains 46 (2006), “Effets spéciaux et artifices.”

The Dispositive Does Not Exist!

31

Finally, the domain of the techniques and technology of cinema involves a large area, most often considered from the standpoint of the “futuristic,” or “fantasy”: still, what has been tentatively named “projected cinema”23 interacts very seriously with the issues of technical invention and social imaginary forming the “milieu” where these genres appeared. Often fanciful, or pertaining to amusing popularization, these extrapolations devised by literary authors or columnists, especially in the nineteenth century (but also until very recently with science fiction), took inspiration from existing or experimental technologies, which they “actualized” fictionally, generalized, combined and multiplied (Villiers de l’Isle Adam, Verne, Robida and so many others, down to Barjavel). These texts systematically expanded the functions granted to existing technical objects, just as they showed little respect for their assumed “specificity.” On the contrary, crossing characteristics, they turned these objects into technical hybrids. These are precious indications for the technical imagination or the conceptual and social frameworks (categories, ideologies) that may have been dominant at the moment when these techniques were “imagined,” even as later specializations encouraged us to believe that these techniques had been created in the restrictive, autonomous, specific perimeter that has come to define them – or stands to define them. In his work on technical objects, Gilbert Simondon refers to everything that belongs to this ensemble of anticipation-simulation-invention under what is probably an unfortunate expression, “psychology of invention” (for he is thinking of a psychology “without subject,” “transductive”). These elements are brought together into a “genesis” and constitute “mental objects.” Simondon’s thoughts on the definition of the technical object intersect with Georges Canguilhem’s investigations on the history of sciences, which emphasize the origin of a concept rather than its beginning – the origin always owing to external causes, not to what would be a “logic of science.” The concept of reflex thus appeared, not within scientific discourse as if through an internal generation (of the Hegelian type), but under the conditions of pathology and the clinic. Under which condition, Simondon asks, may the technical object be so called? It is not as I contemplate it, nor is it when it is simply being used, nor even when it is considered objectively from the standpoint of its usage and functions or when it is considered according to its physical structures: it is the knowledge of the process of 23 See François Albera, “Projected Cinema (A Hypothesis on the Cinema’s Imagination),” in Cinema Beyond Film. Media Epistemology in the Modern Era, François Albera and Maria Tortajada, eds. (Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press, 2009).

32 

François Albera, Maria Tortajada

concretization of the technical object that constitutes it as such. In this genesis, one finds imagination, the project, conception: Simondon calls this ensemble an “imaging genesis” and sees a virtual dimension in it. The interest of narrative fictions thus lies not so much in the fact that they “foretell” or “prefigure” what is to come (after the model of the prophecy), as in their participation in this genesis, probably more on the side of a syncretic, hazy, profuse “creativity” in fact – whereas “invention” is discontinuous and stretches out in time and in history. Besides, these fictions – insofar as they borrow and experiment, on paper at least, starting from the state of knowledge or ongoing projects – may shed light on some dimensions of existing techniques omitted by a catalog-like history, which privileges an enduring usage or collapses a range of possibilities under a dominant one. These dimensions are twofold, at a minimum: they involve the potentialities characteristic of the medium or the machine (from the moment when the artisanal stage or the prototype gives way to generalization); and the social, imaginary or pragmatic expectations faced with these potentialities and tapping into them. “The dispositive does not exist,” then, in more ways than one. As the more strictly epistemological dimension of the question is examined, it appears that the dispositive remains to be constructed as a notion, as an epistemic schema de-centered from its reality as an object. At stake is the reconstitution of concepts associated with viewing and listening dispositives at the moment of the emergence of cinema, in order to grasp the changes in these dispositives, the transformations not captured initially and which open onto epistemological work. Concretely, starting from primary sources – Etienne-Jules Marey, Henri Bergson and Alfred Jarry, among others24 – this approach aims to give visibility to the conceptual networks and the practices implicit in the definition of dispositives. The dispositives of “cinema” – that is, the configurations that may be linked to “cinema” out of a number of definitional traits and variables – are central. Still, they cannot be thought of in isolation. What about the concepts of movement, time, instant? What of the notions of repetition, instantaneousness, decomposition and synthesis of movement? Of the idea of projection or visual perception, or of the illusion of truth? Or even of mechanization and automation with respect to the human body? How do these notions play a part in the constitution and the transformation of dispositives? They may be accounted for in several ways and, depending on the case, they may involve very different concepts. As it happens, they are central to debates 24 On these figures, we refer the reader to our respective contributions in Cinema Beyond Film.

The Dispositive Does Not Exist!

33

on dispositives, for these conceptual variations impose modif ications with historical import on the conception of dispositives. The attention of epistemological work bears on specific dispositives, whether attaching to “cinema,” “photography,” “television,” and others, for their histories are particularly interwoven. With the 1900 episteme, needless to say, research requires huge collective work in which cinema does not enjoy preeminence. Still, the demonstration requires that we stop and consider methodological premises. There are many “dispositifs” around the world (objects) and the most different texts from the late nineteenth century feature them in abundance (discourses). We will here consider the “dispositive” as a methodologically constructed object allowing the conceptual questioning of an effective as well as discursive reality. Our epistemology of viewing and listening dispositives, ever in the process of elaboration as it confronts new sources, is Foucauldian in inspiration, but some problems in Foucault’s thought may also be overcome through a rereading of his texts in the light of Gaston Bachelard’s historical epistemology. Accordingly, as we put our methodology into place, we will focus more precisely on the analysis of these major propositions.

For An Epistemology of Dispositives: A Program Viewing and listening dispositives may be defined as what allows spectators to attend to a representation, from machines to machinery, from production to monstration to reception, from techniques to practices to institutional or symbolic constraints.25 The three terms of the dispositive are not enough, though: to reconstruct the knowledge associated with dispositives, it is necessary to go into the detail of their operations. Three levels may be

25 Viewing and listening dispositives involve three essential terms: the spectator, the representation and the machinery which, while it implies the viewing machine as technical object, also refers to all the means implemented to give the representation to see and to hear. The means in question may play a part at the very moment of reception by the spectator or in the making, the production of the representation. The cinematographic machinery thus includes the screen and the projection, the chemical process of photography, and even institutional, economic and social arrangements. The definition allows for the widest range of practices, from the theater to the scientific use of the microscope. See François Albera and Maria Tortajada, “The Episteme 1900,” in Albera and Tortajada, Cinema Beyond Film. Thus phrased, the definition further specifies what we have called the third level in the definition of dispositives. We intend to develop it by apprehending the three terms (spectator, representation, machinery) within their network of relations. In that sense, the notion of dispositive is supported by a method.

34 

François Albera, Maria Tortajada

derived from the approach; they concern three types of notions calling for explanation. First, what we call the concrete elements of the dispositive. For instance, when it comes to the machinery, it should be possible to think what the notions of film frame, the run of film in the camera, the projector, the instant photograph or projection are at a given historical moment. Second, the abstract notions associated with the dispositive or with the concrete elements constituting it: notions of series, repetition, periodicity should be questioned in relation to the film frame, but also to the decomposition and synthesis of movement, for example. So should instantaneity, which implies a constituted dispositive, that of photography. These notions themselves presuppose other concepts, which underlie them. The third level is that of key notions or types-notions, abstract or concrete, which at a given historical moment come to define a given dispositive: they are then instituted as references. They convey a certain idea of cinema or photography, the phonograph, television, the radio, and so forth. The key notion consists in the crystallization of a specific definition of a dispositive based on its quality or function. It appears primarily as what is known and admitted about a given dispositive. Recurrent in discourses, this crystallization is presented as self-evident most of the time, because it is widely acknowledged, either in a discipline or a field, or sometimes with a mainstream audience. Still, the type-notion has a history, which is that of its “making”: as a consequence, its use should be historicized and de-naturalized. A number of key notions may be isolated in cinema: truthfulness, one of whose particular instances is the authenticity of the film image, and which is tied to the idea of the indexicality of photography.26 The principle of automation and the mechanical character of the process also come to mind. Still another example is the crystallization that associates cinema and imagination in a famous equation between cinema and dream or hallucination. Epistemological work precisely consists in making apparent what founds these notions. These concrete, abstract and key notions should be reconstituted in their relation to a series of concepts sampled from analyzed discourses. Schemas of dispositives may then be constructed. To describe dispositives in this manner is already to borrow 26 François Brunet has written about the historical construction of photography as a figure of accuracy. He uses the term “paradigm” to refer to what is called key notion, type-notion or idea here, to be distinguished from the paradigm as a complex term, which for Thomas Kuhn involves several definitions linked to an epistemological approach. See François Brunet, La Naissance de l’idée de photographie (Paris: PUF, 2000) 281.

The Dispositive Does Not Exist!

35

from Foucault, who analyzed his favorite objects, knowledge and power, by reconstituting networks of relations.

Foucault’s Dispositifs To successfully reconstitute networks of concepts associated with dispositives, a requisite is the rigor of a concrete approach in reading sources.27 This is the first lesson of Foucault, perfectly expressed in his analysis of Jeremy Bentham’s Panopticon.28 Foucault describes the architectural object physically, materially, as he could the parts of a machine: […] at the periphery, an annular building; at the centre, a tower; this tower is pierced with wide windows that open onto the inner side of the ring; the peripheric building is divided into cells, each of which extends the whole width of the building; they have two windows, one on the inside, corresponding to the windows of the tower; the other, on the outside, allows the light to cross the cell from one end to the other.29

However, the physical-technical description is not enough. Most decisive is the construction by Foucault of the architectural whole as a dispositif, at once reconstructing the play of gazes and non-gazes, observed spaces instituted as representations, whose global operation produces effects of power: It is enough, then, to assign a guard to the central tower and to lock up a mad person, a sick person, a convict, a worker, or a schoolboy in each cell. With the effect of backlighting, the sharp outlines of small captive figures in peripheral cells may be glimpsed from the tower. These cages are as many tiny theaters where each performer is alone, perfectly individualized and constantly visible.30

27 Michel Foucault, “Nietzsche, Genealogy, History” [1971], in The Postmodern History Reader, ed. Keith Jenkins (London: Routledge, 1997) 124-26. 28 Panopticon or The Inspection-House. The Works of Jeremy Bentham, published under the Superintendence of his Executor, John Bowring, Edinburgh, William Tait, 1838-1843. 11 vols. See vol. 4, available at http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/1925 as of October 28, 2012. This is the source Foucault refers to. 29 Foucault, Discipline and Punish 200. 30 Foucault, Discipline and Punish 200.

36 

François Albera, Maria Tortajada

The source itself specifies the architectural conditions and the advantages they entail.31 Foucault draws the principles and creates a system out of them. Let us mention that power operates from the very fact that the prisoner is the object of the gaze of the controlling agent located in the tower, but that the prisoner is also a point of view on this center where she or he knows that a gaze may be positioned. This bi-directionality of the gaze is what guarantees the automaticity of the effect of power, whether or not there is someone in the tower. What produces the effect of power is the dispositif, not the effective presence of a guard. The user-spectator is not placed in front of the dispositif; she or he literally belongs in it. Each term is defined by the place it occupies in the dispositif and its relations with other elements. When Foucault defines the positions of the gaze in the Panopticon, he refers to the information provided in the very source defining this specific dispositif. At this point he does not refer to the legal codes in force at the time. If Foucault’s commentary is to serve as a model in the elaboration of a method to analyze dispositives, then merely reading contemporary theories on the subject or techniques of construction of a given machine is clearly not enough to define the spectator in a specific dispositive. The presuppositions associated with the spectator postulated in these dispositives and in the very sources evoking these dispositives have to be considered first.32 The Panopticon and the analytical method applied to it offer an excellent example for the development of an epistemology of viewing and listening dispositives. Foucault himself refers to the Panopticon as a dispositif. The term, which he started developing in the mid-1970s in Discipline and Punish and The Will to Knowledge, allowed him to identify the disciplinary dispositif, a dispositif of alliance and a dispositif of sexuality, all having the particularity of producing effects of power. What interested Foucault quite specifically at the time was to show that power is not one but is instead derived from a network of relations and may be traced through its effects. Still, the Panopticon is not the equivalent of the large schemas producing effects of power: it is not by itself the disciplinary dispositif, even as it is certainly emblematic of 31 Bentham, Panopticon or The Inspection-House, letters V and VI, http://oll.libertyfund.org/ title/1925. 32 Some dispositives are barely sketched out, either because the “machine” is merely mentioned or the various elements appear as fragments. It is appropriate, then, to reconstitute the general dispositive, if that is possible and if it is indeed the objective. Some dispositives are described from the beginning as such [“en dispositif”]; Marey’s experiments, for example. Indeed, the description of the scientific experiment implies the presentation of its complete dispositive. The first “spectator” then becomes the scientist himself.

The Dispositive Does Not Exist!

37

this dispositif in the demonstration, the forceful synthesis it offers of it. In the end it remains a mere element, a part. The disciplinary dispositif is a dispositif in the sense Foucault stated in this oft-cited passage: […] a thoroughly heterogeneous ensemble, consisting of discourses, institutions, architectural forms, regulatory decisions, laws, administrative measures, scientific statements, philosophical, moral and philanthropic propositions – in short, the said as much as the unsaid. Such are the elements of the apparatus.33

All in all, Foucault uses the term dispositif in two ways: 1. the dispositif as a case of viewing and listening dispositives in the sense intended here; the Panopticon, for instance; 2. the dispositif – which we will call dispositif-episteme to avoid any confusion34 – referring to the schemas of relations between heterogeneous elements. These schemas – the disciplinary dispositif for example – may include viewing and listening dispositives. It so happens that in Foucault’s analysis, the particular case of vision and audition presented, the “Panopticon,” operates within what is constructed as a disciplinary dispositif. For all that, they are not one and the same. The Panopticon is not by itself panopticism. The combination of these two terms, dispositif-episteme, requires an explanation. Each speaks to a different period in Foucault’s work: while the episteme is central to The Archeology of Knowledge (1969), the dispositif was developed in the mid-1970s. The two terms are intrinsically linked: the dispositif and the episteme involve a network of relations between elements structured by correspondences, and Foucault’s dispositifs taken in the strong sense are epistemes of sorts.35 Foucault’s second lesson is to make a network of relations the characteristic of the object to build: not a stagnant pool of autonomous elements, but a dynamic network transformed by the addition or disappearance of one of its components and by the relational disposition in which elements intervene: 33 Michel Foucault, “The Confession of the Flesh,” in Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings 1972-1977, ed. Colin Gordon (London: Vintage, 1980) 194. 34 Gilles Deleuze opted for the term “diagram,” which he advanced in his Foucault, trans. Seán Hand (London, New York: Continuum, 2006). 35 “What I call an apparatus [“dispositif”] is a much more general case of the episteme.” Foucault, Power/Knowledge 197.

38 

François Albera, Maria Tortajada

By episteme, we mean, in fact, the total set of relations that unite, at a given period, the discursive practices that give rise to epistemological figures, sciences, and possibly formalized systems […]. The episteme is not a form of knowledge […] or type of rationality which, crossing the boundaries of the most varied sciences, manifests the sovereign unity of a subject, a spirit, or a period; it is the totality of relations that can be discovered, for a given period, between the sciences when one analyses them at the level of discursive regularities.36

And Foucault characterizes large dispositifs through a series of dynamic interrelations: In short, between these elements, whether discursive or non-discursive, there is a sort of interplay of shifts of position and modifications of function which can also vary very widely.37

Dispositif and episteme remain distinct, though, and Foucault explains in what way. First, the episteme is a discursive dispositif, whereas dispositifs such as the disciplinary dispositif are at once discursive and non-discursive.38 Second, the episteme outlines the constitution of a body of knowledge, whereas the dispositif is entirely centered around power effects. And a body of knowledge is developed in relation to power. Assuming this to be the case, the relevance of research on the epistemology of viewing and listening dispositives should be specified. This research does not aim to reconstitute power games or disciplinary procedures. In that respect, the notion of the dispositif of power – such as the disciplinary dispositif or the dispositif of sexuality – may not serve as a model. Yet the analysis of the Panopticon as a specific viewing and listening dispositive should be maintained as a reference, though the analysis in question constitutes the dispositive mainly in its effects of power.39 What is to be done with this issue of power? Should it be imposed as an immediate given of viewing and listening dispositives? 36 Michel Foucault, The Archaeology of Knowledge, trans. Rupert Swyer (London: Vintage, 1982) 191. 37 Foucault, Power/Knowledge 195. See also how the dispositif of sexuality is conceived in terms of a “cluster of relations” in The History of Sexuality, vol. 1, The Will to Knowledge, trans. Robert Hurley (1978; London: Vintage, 1990) 139-41. 38 Foucault, Power/Knowledge 197. 39 Even then, Foucault establishes a link between Barker’s panorama and the Panopticon without further developing the idea (Foucault, Discipline and Punish 317, n. 4).

The Dispositive Does Not Exist!

39

Besides, if the episteme is a discursive dispositif, what is in fact meant by “discursive”? Should we understand that there is, on the one hand, the episteme, the discursive, what is found in “texts,” and on the other hand the “concrete of history,” machines, techniques, practices, institutions, the heterogeneity of the dispositif ? This would amount to a reduction of the discursive to “analyzed sources,” overlooking the fact that, if one is to know the “concrete of history,” a passage through discourses is notably needed. The discursive would then refer to the written word, at best to the totality of oral, iconic or other discourses produced by a society. And it would amount to ignoring the very special use Foucault made of the notion of discourse, which refers to what is to be constructed out of discourses given by sources, that is, the recurring statements that together constitute a body of knowledge. The discursive is this very knowledge, which characterizes the episteme. The question, then, is the following: should this knowledge be conceived as detached from any tie with institutions, social practices, concrete objects whose traces may still be found in museums? To answer these two questions, on power and on the discursive, we turn to Gaston Bachelard.

Bachelard: The Explanation of Concepts Foucault devised his own method with reference to the French tradition of the epistemology of sciences, represented by Bachelard and Canguilhem, and defined as a historical epistemology. In The Archeology of Knowledge, he outlined his own area of research in relation to this epistemology, and prefacing the English edition of Canguilhem’s The Normal and the Pathological, he described it as a philosophy of rationality, knowledge and concept, referring once more to Bachelard. 40 Foucault clearly inscribes his work in this tradition when he attempts to produce a form of rationality (or positivity, as he calls it). What these thinkers share is the ambition to write the history of the “formation of concepts.”41 Bachelard’s rationalism is not only an explicit reference to the epistemological history of sciences with regard to which Foucault could define his 40 Foucault opposes this philosophy to the philosophy of experience, meaning and the subject, represented by Jean-Paul Sartre and Maurice Merleau-Ponty. See “Introduction by Michel Foucault” [1978], in Georges Canguilhem, The Normal and the Pathological, trans. Carolyn R. Fawcett (Brooklyn: Zone, 1991) 7-24. 41 Michel Foucault, “Introduction by Michel Foucault,” in Canguilhem, The Normal and the Pathological 9.

40 

François Albera, Maria Tortajada

practice. In other respects, it could also appear as a structuring model for the Foucauldian method, whose core would then be Bachelard’s definition of the scientific concept. For Bachelard, the concept is different from the usual meaning given to the term: it is a denomination and a definition, or, in other words, “a noun pregnant with meaning.”42 To Bachelard, signification has to be put aside if the epistemological explanation of a term is to be drawn. The explanation is no longer the denomination of a notion: it becomes the analysis of a fact put back in the context of its production and experimentation, thereby making it possible to overcome the epistemological obstacles that interfere with it and exclude it from rationality. Only then are we dealing with a concept: The same word can at the same period in time have within it very many different concepts. What misleads us here is the fact that the same word both denotes and explains. What is denoted stays the same but the explanation changes. 43

The explanation implies that the conditions of possibility for concepts be emphasized, taking into account the context in which they are used, the finality of the practice in which they are situated and the intention guiding concrete experience. 44 The rejection of the empirical approach, of “a phenomenology of the first take,” is thus justified as follows: “While the empirical concept is a concept of classification, the rational concept is a concept of interconnections, of absolutely reciprocal relations.”45 As with Foucault later, the principle is indeed that of the relation. The concept is not simply defined by its understanding and its extension, at least not insofar as these terms point to a cumulative set of data, a sum, a classification at best. The essential point in the structuring of the concept lies in the relations actively forged between the “basic notions” or the “fundamental variables” 42 In his article on “reflex movement,” Canguilhem starts from the common definition of the concept: “We know that we have encountered a concept because we have hit upon its definition – a definition at once nominal and real.” See “The Concept of Reflex” [1964], in Georges Canguilhem, A Vital Rationalist: Selected Writings from Georges Canguilhem, ed. François Delaporte, trans. Arthur Goldhammer (New York: Zone, 1994) 188. 43 Gaston Bachelard, The Formation of the Scientific Mind, trans. Mary McAllester Jones (Manchester: Clinamen Press, 2002) 28. 44 Summarizing Bachelard’s thought, Canguilhem writes: “The synthesis within which the concept lies – that is, both the conceptual context and the intention presiding over experiments or observations – this synthesis has to be reconstituted.” See “Gaston Bachelard,” Etudes d’histoire et de philosophie des sciences (Paris, Vrin, 1990) 177. 45 Gaston Bachelard, Le Rationalisme appliqué (1949; Paris: PUF, 1994) 145.

The Dispositive Does Not Exist!

41

of a phenomenon. 46 Correlations are also to determine the coherence of a higher-level entity, “the body of concepts,” which founds a domain of rationality, that is, what may also be called a scientific domain. The relation, as it turns out, is a structural principle that may be generalized. It defines the concept as well as “rationality.” The structural homology between various levels of definition for scientific coherence in Bachelard may be traced in Foucault’s archeology: it is blatant in the case of the episteme, which was developed exactly this way, as well as for various elements of knowledge. 47 The principle of the relation extended to “positivity” and, later, to dispositifs producing effects of power, disciplinary effects and effects of sexuality, to mention but a few. Bachelard’s def inition of the concept, centering on the correlation of associated notions, may apply outside a strictly scientific coherence. Foucault did perform this transfer, 48 but Bachelard had paved the way, if only through an extra-scientific example allowing the scientific concept to be understood. As a matter of fact, he took the example of a listening dispositive, the telephone: The telephone for instance is understood in very different ways by the subscriber, the operator, the engineer, and the mathematician concerned with the differential equations of the telephone current. 49

Though minimal, this effective example makes the second essential point in the definition of the concept very concrete: the concept is intrinsically linked to the practice defining it. In short, the telephone is about communicating through speech, or setting up a connection between lines, or calculating equations. Depending on which option is considered, the idea of the telephone may be completely different. According to this model, the constitution of a body of knowledge associated with viewing and listening dispositives may be defined as unthinkable 46 Bachelard, Le Rationalisme appliqué 185, 188. 47 See for instance the “object” or “group of objects” in Foucault, The Archaeology of Knowledge 50-56. 48 There are several coherences of knowledge, which echo one another or sometimes contradict one another. Some determine the conditions of possibility for sciences: this is what epistemologists such as Bachelard or Canguilhem study. Those interesting Foucault directly have to do, not with sciences, but with less strictly constituted spaces of knowledge, “domain[s] of scientificity,” fields of relations by which a type of knowledge constitutes itself, defined by objects of knowledge, types of enunciation, theoretical corpuses, relations between concepts (this is the terminology used in The Archaeology of Knowledge). 49 Bachelard, The Formation of the Scientific Mind 28.

42 

François Albera, Maria Tortajada

without linking these dispositives and a form of experience or practice. What are the intentions motivating the use of a notion at a given historical moment? Which other concepts are correlated to this notion within analyzed discourses presenting dispositives? These are the two main questions in the work of historical reconstitution of concepts. Studying their formation will occasionally make it possible to identify conceptual transformations or epistemological modifications. Rereading Foucault out of Bachelard underlines how tied to practice the concept is. The “discursive” in Foucault, understood as the domain of knowledge, might then just as well be said to make sense only when considering the aims of the users of concepts and the processes of application of notions. The aims are to be found, not so much on the side of the subjectivity of speech – though Bachelard writes of intentions – as on the side of a pragmatics of discourse at the crossroads between the institutional context making these discourses possible; the scientific, technical and artistic projects framing them; the characteristics of the practice or experimentation they involve; and the ideological presuppositions underlying them. At this level, one should accordingly move beyond the opposition between episteme and dispositifs (dispositifs-epistemes), which Foucault himself seems to introduce with his critique of the discursive. The discursive itself may be understood in the confrontation with practices, known from the sources describing them or from any other historical reconstitution. The relation between the discursive and the non-discursive is a decisive and complex one.50 50 Defining the two terms in relation to each other, Foucault says more specifically: “If you like, I would define the episteme retrospectively as the strategic apparatus [“dispositif”] which permits of separating out from among all the statements which are possible those that will be acceptable within, I won’t say a scientific theory, but a field of scientificity, and which it is possible to say are true or false. The episteme is the ‘apparatus’ which makes possible the separation, not of the true from the false, but of what may from what may not be characterised as scientific” (Foucault, Power/Knowledge 197). Deleuze works most particularly through this difference between the discursive and the non-discursive, the episteme and the dispositif, knowledge and power, in short between The Archaeology of Knowledge and Discipline and Punish. He articulates the distinction in a very illuminating manner: “What The Archaeology recognized but still only designated negatively, as non-discursive environments, is given its positive form in Discipline and Punish, a form that haunted the whole of Foucault’s work: the form of the visible, as opposed to the form of whatever can be articulated.” He continues: “If knowledge consists of linking the visible and the articulable, power is its presupposed cause; but, conversely, power implies knowledge as the bifurcation or differentiation without which power would not become an act” (Deleuze, Foucault 28, 33). However, the Deleuzian terminology, introducing the term “visible” in comparison to the Foucauldian “statement,” risks masking the constant heterogeneity of the two domains. This is the case for the example in which the Panopticon, given as a visible

The Dispositive Does Not Exist!

43

The detour through Bachelard also shows that the notion of power should be kept separate from the questioning of viewing and listening dispositives, even if it means reintroducing it at a further stage. The Panopticon and its analysis by Foucault may have been referred to as a model: yet effects of power are indeed being constructed there. Foucault is often reread and quoted in analyses that mechanically apply the notion of power to viewing and listening dispositives, as though these were representatives of dispositifs-epistemes. But if we turn to the analysis of Bentham’s text by Foucault, it appears that the constitution of the idea of power is inscribed as an aim in the source itself. When Foucault describes a dispositif to reconstruct the notion of power, he teases out the practice and the project in which the description of the dispositif is caught up. For Bentham, the Panopticon is a prison indeed – not only an instrument of power but the means to rethink the exercise of power from a utilitarian and economic standpoint. To be sure, as his whole analysis shows, the disciplinary dispositif also aims to free the individual from the direct, brutal power that obtains through chains and through the whip (Foucault’s “Great Confinement”) what disciplinary power obtains through a technique of incorporation by the subject of the automatic effects of power. At stake in Discipline and Punish is this paradox: to free the individual from a power, another way for power to operate is created, insidious, indirect and apparently in the service of the greater freedom of the subject. Nevertheless, it is a process of constraint, a remarkable model of which Bentham explicitly constructs with the Panopticon. Foucault may be said to apply Bachelard’s method to the letter. Power is tied to this specific viewing dispositive, and it is even the reason why it belongs to Foucault’s corpus. Yet any viewing and listening dispositive is not at once inscribed in a practice and a finality that turn it into an instrument or a relay of power. It is essential that this finality not be defined mechanically for any viewing and listening dispositive. Rather, the finality of each dispositive should be drawn from the context of its use as expounded by the sources mentioning it. Effects of power may eventually prove to be decisive in a given practice; but they are to be constructed epistemologically at first. arrangement, is from that standpoint opposed to criminal law, which is linked to the order of the statement. Deleuze omits the fact that the Panopticon, before being a visible architectural arrangement, is a discourse describing this arrangement and implying utterances of a discursive order that make it possible to build this instance of the disciplinary dispositif. This being said, on the question of practices, Deleuze’s formulation remains relevant: “There are only practices, or positivities, which are constitutive of knowledge: the discursive practices of statements, or the non-discursive practices of visibilities” (Deleuze, Foucault 59).

44 

François Albera, Maria Tortajada

If the dispositive does not exist, it is because, in an epistemology of viewing and listening dispositives, it is not an “object” to be found around the corner on a path followed by the scholar, an object already made and which may be grasped in its material concreteness. The dispositive is a schema, a dynamic play of relations which articulates discourses and practices with one another; a schema which is to be elaborated out of this basis, this apparently modest work tool describing the dispositive in three terms which, in each case, in every research project, have to be entirely redefined and understood in their reciprocal relations: the spectator, the machinery, the representation. The dispositive does not exist, but its construction should be effected (and desired).



Between Knowing and Believing The Cinematic Dispositive after Cinema Thomas Elsaesser

Introduction The Imagined Futures research project, coordinated with two of my colleagues (Wanda Strauven at the University of Amsterdam, and Michael Wedel at the University of Film and Television, Potsdam), concerns itself with the conditions, dynamics and consequences of rapid media transfer and transformation. “Media” in our case refers in principle to all imaging techniques and sound technologies, but cinema has provided the conceptual starting point and primary historical focus. While changes in basic technology, public perception and artistic practice in sound and image media may often evolve over long historical cycles, our main working assumption is that there are also factors, not of steady and gradual process, but moments when transfer occurs in discontinuous, unevenly distributed fashion, during much shorter periods of time, and with mutually interdependent determinations. Imagined Futures initially identified two such relatively abrupt periods of transformation taking place across a broad spectrum of media technologies and social developments: the period between the 1870s and 1900, and the period between 1970 and 2000. The first witnessed the popularization of photography, the emergence of cinema, the international, transatlantic use of the telegraph and the domestic use of the telephone, the invention of radio and of the theories as well as the basic technology of television. The second period saw the consolidation of video as a popular storage medium and avant-garde artistic practice, the rise of installation art and its hybridization with cinema, the universal adoption of the personal computer, the change from analogue to digital sound and image, the invention of the mobile phone and the emergence of the Internet and the world wide web. A key characteristic of such periods of rapid media change is the volatility, unpredictability and contradictory nature of the dynamics between these technologies’ practical implications (such as industrial uses and the resulting potential for economic profit), their perception by the popular imagination (in the form of narratives of anxiety, of utopia, dystopia and fantasy) and the mixed response (eager adoption or stiff resistance) from artists, writers and intellectuals. These shifting configurations among dif-

46 

Thomas Elsaesser

ferent agents offer a rich field of investigation for cultural analysis, posing methodological challenges and requiring specific case studies. As far as the earlier period is concerned, our research has identified a number of iconic figures and their historical contexts: Filippo Tommaso Marinetti and Italian Futurism (Marinetti and Marconi: speed; radio and the wireless; cinema as the “destroyer” of art and of the museum; cinema, war and aviation as major agents of modernization); 1 Oskar Messter and the three S/M practices of early German cinema (the chief promoter of a film industry in Germany since the 1910s, as well as the first systematic proponent of what I have elsewhere called the three S/M practices of the cinematic dispositive2 – science and medicine, surveillance and the military, sensor and monitor – all of which play their part in the formation of early German cinema, obliging us to recast what we consider to be its particular identity);3 and Eadweard Muybridge versus Etienne-Jules Marey: photography in motion versus the visualization of data, a project where we compare Muybridge, who initially devoted himself to the art-historical issue of how to represent movement in the still image, and Marey, who was one of the first scientific photographers to capture, record, measure and represent living phenomena and processes (i.e. biological, atmospheric, geological) in real time, graphically as well as iconographically, with the aid of the cinematic dispositive. 4 Finally, our overall project is driven by another consideration: we see neither the need nor the wisdom of making the history of the cinema begin in 1895 and end a hundred years later with the dominance of the digital image. In other words, we do not endorse the much-discussed “death of cinema,” which assumes the break between photographic and post-photographic cinema to be fundamental. No more than in earlier times, when such breaks 1 See Wanda Strauven, Marinetti e il cinema: tra attrazione e sperimentazione (Udine: Campanotto, 2006). 2 Thomas Elsaesser, “Digital Cinema and the Apparatus: Archaeologies, Epistemologies, Ontologies,” in Cinema and Technology: Cultures, Theories, Practices, Marc Furstenau, Bruce Bennett and Adrian Mackenzie, eds. (London: Palgrave, 2008) 226-40; and Wanda Strauven, “S/M,” in Mind the Screen, J.Kooijman, P. Pisters and W. Strauven, eds. (Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press, 2008) 276-87. 3 The German cinema of the silent period is usually identified with Expressionism and fantasy subjects. For a revision of this perception, see Kino der Kaiserzeit, Thomas Elsaesser and Michael Wedel, eds. (Munich: edition text + kritik, 2002); and Michael Wedel, Der deutsche Musikfilm Archäologie eines Genres 1914 – 1945 (Munich: edition text + kritik, 2007). 4 Thomas Elsaesser, “Kontingenz und Handlungsmacht,” in Unmenge - Wie verteilt sich Handlungsmacht? Ilka Becker, Michael Cuntz and Astrid Kusser, eds. (Munich: Fink, 2008) 157-90.

Between Knowing and Believing

47

were posited (several such deaths of cinema have been foretold) – notably with the coming of sound, the emergence of television or the invention of the video-cassette – do we believe that a new technology introduced in one specific area (of what is always a constellation of overlapping, mutually amplifying but also interfering dispositives) is the cause of radical change by itself. Insofar as such ruptures (in technology or cultural practice) do occur, we believe that they are also welcome opportunities to revise one’s habitual ways of thinking and to test one’s implicit assumptions.5 To give conceptual muscle and a body of empirical evidence to our particular perspective, we are engaged in three kinds of “revisionism.” The first we call “media-archaeology,” which entails a re-investigation into the “origins” of the cinema and the cultural context of so-called pre-cinema, while also pushing for a history of the discourses generated by the different debates around the cinematic dispositive. The second revisionism is of a more theoretical and conceptual kind. Re-reading key thinkers on the cinema, such as André Bazin and Siegfried Kracauer, but also Hugo Münsterberg, Béla Balázs and Rudolf Arnheim, Sergei Eisenstein and Jean Epstein, we attempt to recover a more comprehensive view of the cinema – whether based on notions of Gesamtkunstwerk or “anti-art,” on cinematic anthropomorphism or animation; whether committed to formalism and abstraction, or to an aesthetics genuinely belonging in the ephemeral, the instant, the contingent and the multiple (elaborating on Baudelaire’s “riot of details” as well as on Walter Benjamin’s “optical unconscious”). In short, our second revisionism re-maps the semantic field of relevant concepts as well as methods in our discipline. Evidently, we can only conduct such a review in the light of the present, which is to say, mindful of the media environment of the twenty-first century.6 Thus, the reading of the “classics” is complemented by similarly “holistic” or crisis/ emergency-driven attempts at reading the cinema from within the digital domain by contemporary scholars such as Friedrich Kittler, Lev Manovich, David Bolter and Richard Grusin, Sean Cubitt, Mary Ann Doane, Jeffrey Sconce, Garrett Stewart and others. Classic texts, as we know, have to be re-read: they have to be put in dialogue with contemporary practices and re-assessed in a wider conceptual 5 For an extended argument, see Thomas Elsaesser, “Early Film History and Multi-Media: An Archaeology of Possible Futures?” in New Media, Old Media: A History and Theory Reader, Wendy Hui Kyong Chun and Tom Keenan, eds. (New York: Routledge, 2005) 13-26. 6 One of the results has been a new approach to (classical and modern) f ilm theory. See Thomas Elsaesser and Malte Hagener, Film Theory: An Introduction through the Senses (New York: Routledge, 2010).

48 

Thomas Elsaesser

network. This bi-focal perspective on the cultural mesh of cinema around 1900 and 2000 is what we are collectively proposing to elaborate. Hence the suitably open title Imagined Futures, which includes the “history of imagined futures in the past,” and the “rewriting of the past in light of the future.” Even as we refrain from identifying “the future” with the “digital era” as such, we think that the inclusion of sound and telephony or the extension of the corpus to scientific and non-fictional films, for instance, significantly enlarges our understanding of “what is cinema.” Likewise, our special attention to how the cinema has affected the perception of time and the experience of place and space will allow us to redefine the cinematic dispositive without being either reductive or all-inclusive. The third revisionism concerns the application, appropriation and implementation of cinematic techniques, technologies and ways of seeing in fields other than the mainstream of film. While alternatives to the narrative feature f ilm usually see themselves in terms of antagonism, critique and resistance, our revisionism is less interested in addressing the division between high culture and popular culture (the ideologicalpolemical thrust of postmodernism) or the split between arts and hard sciences (the “two cultures” of C. P. Snow). Instead we focus on breaking down the division between an avant-garde at the margins or in opposition, and the technological-industrial mainstream. What we are trying to explore is how sound and image media and other information technologies have contributed to or even spearheaded changes in the relation between an artistic practice said to be hostile to any kind of application or transfer to the realm of industry, commerce and functional use, and an industrial practice, supposedly concerned merely with mass-production and maximizing profit. Whether we call it “design and advertising,” “post-Fordism” or “research and development,” the twenty-first century has seen a shift or even a reversal in the balance of power between an entrepreneurial avant-garde and an avant-garde entrepreneurism. The parallels between avant-garde art and industrial application are often surprisingly evident and direct, just as the marketing skills of artists and curators easily bear comparison with those of industrial conglomerates and commercial companies. We would be arguing – on the basis of the episteme 1900 – that the cinema needs to be understood in its double role in this respect. It emerged at a time of crisis for the self-understanding of the first industrial revolution, where the spectacle of moving images was meant to mediate between technology, education and entertainment. Such a division had not existed during the ascendancy of the bourgeoisie earlier in the nineteenth century and may no longer exist today. Indeed, one way of understanding the rapid rise of the cinema would

Between Knowing and Believing

49

be to highlight the role it played as both symptom (of the division between education about the world and entertainment extracted from the world) and cure (in that it seemed to heal the breach between work and leisure), a role also played by the large world fairs in London (1851), Chicago (1893), Paris (1889, 1900) and St. Louis (1904), which sought to reconcile the split between industry, technology, the public sphere and everyday life. Thus, our third revisionism tries to track a trend that, from the 1970s onwards, has seen these divisions between high-tech, entertainment and information – but also between the avant-garde and the mainstream – as increasingly blurred and merging, “returning” us to the period prior to the 1890s. Although we have not yet fully conceptualized the dynamics and forces that are bringing style, design, advertising, technological breakthroughs, avant-garde and the mass market together, we note that the result is infotainment, advertising-driven education, design following technology and “theory” becoming design. To the extent that we are concerned with often counter-intuitive associations, heterogeneous networks and non-convergent connections, we are sympathetic to the idea of re-investigating the concept of “dispositif.” Its capacity to think in terms of bricolage and assemblages, its renewed regard for the conditions of reception (envisaging “agents” with different roles and functions) and its interest in new pedigrees and genealogies all reaffirm the concept’s value and uses. For instance, the proposal to draw upon genealogies that can “distinguish between successive mechanical and military paradigms and theatrical, libidinal models” 7 would seem to be quite close to our aims as well. It is by attending to non-technological factors, drawing connections between agents, sites and practices usually not associated with each other, that the more recent term dispositive, central to this volume, opens up valuable discursive space, by identifying common denominators between and across media. However, “dispositif” – if merely translated as cinematic apparatus in British or American English – is less useful to our research, since it fails to account fully for what we think is the complexity of the present situation. The same goes for the historical period preceding “the cinema”: only if we think of “dispositif” as neither synonymous with the technological apparatus nor analogous to the Freudian psychic Apparat, and retain Jean Louis Baudry’s distinction between “appareil de base” and “dispositif,” with the latter signifying different kinds of assemblages and arrangements, can we adequately understand the nature of the interac7 François Albera and Maria Tortajada, call for papers, conference on “Viewing and Listening Dispositives,” Université de Lausanne, Switzerland, May 29-31, 2008.

50 

Thomas Elsaesser

tions, the degrees of antagonism and the kinds of interdependencies we are tracking for the period around 1900.

The Dispositive Cinema: Conditions of Possibility In what follows I want to stress one of the main lessons to retain from the history of “apparatus theory,” the name by which the discussions around the “dispositif cinéma” have come to be known in Anglo-American criticism. Rather than repeating the well-known definitions8 and subsequent polemics9 surrounding this particular ocular-centric arrangement of screen, projector and spectator, we need a more comprehensive understanding of the complex interactions that bring different media together into relations of interdependence, competition and complementarity, as they appear to us in the twenty-first century. Therefore it cannot be our purpose to conf ine ourselves primarily to a given (audio-visual) technology and construct around it a new “dispositif” without also elaborating a coherent and historically sound model for grasping their mutually interacting dynamics. Put differently: it is clearly desirable to have a better account of what constitutes the character and historical specificity of the “dispositif cinéma,” “dispositif photographie,” “dispositif vidéo,” “dispositif télévision,” “dispositif téléphone.” At the same time, however – and mindful of the phrase that “technology is the name for stuff that doesn’t yet work” – one should remember that the study of a “dispositif,” theorized around a basic technology, cannot by itself specify its cultural impact and consequences. Rather, media technologies tend to be culturally most productive where, besides their performativity, their disruptive and failure-prone dimensions are also taken into consideration. Borrowing from systems theory, one might argue with Niklas Luhmann that an “irritant” (Störfaktor) can act as stabilizing or energizing element in a given system.10 Hence the attention paid in Imagined Futures to dystopias, anxieties and panics as cultural indicators of media change. If we want to understand the place of cinema in the digital environment today – as just such an irritant, stabilizing force and counter-practice – 8 Representative collections in English are The Cinematic Apparatus, Teresa de Lauretis and Stephen Heath, eds. (London: Macmillan; New York: St Martin’s, 1980) and Narrative, Apparatus, Ideology: A Film Theory Reader, ed. Philip Rosen (New York: Columbia UP, 1986). 9 For a useful summary of the polemics, see Richard Allen, Projecting Illusion: Film Spectatorship and the Impression of Reality (Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1997). 10 Niklas Luhmann, Die Wissenschaft der Gesellschaft (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1990).

Between Knowing and Believing

51

amidst the expanded field of the media interaction typical of the episteme 2000 (and retrospectively also making a good case for the episteme 1900), then we need to study the constitutive parts of the classic “dispositifs” in their separate developments, as well as identify their analogues or functional equivalents across a range of media technologies and practices. With this in mind, we have been undertaking separate studies of the “archaeology of the camera,” the “archaeology of the screen and frame,” the “archaeology of projection and transparency,” the “archaeology of motion and stillness,” the “archaeology of sound and color,” and so forth. Such studies are the methodological consequences of speaking of media “transfer” or media “change” in the context of what I have termed a Medienverbund, that is, a tactical alliance of media practices: not a “transfer” or “change” of the properties of one medium into another, be it photographic, video or digital, nor the assumption that these are historically successive modes of production, be they hand-crafted, mechanical, electronic, replacing each other in a trajectory of linear progress.11 Rather, what the idea of a Medienverbund requires is the ability to bring to the debate a different level of generality or abstraction, on the strength of which fresh comparisons can be made and new genealogies generated. Lev Manovich has done this in his book The Language of New Media (2001); Edward Branigan has tried to do it in Projecting a Camera (2006), as has Sean Cubitt in The Cinema Effect (2005). None of them use the word “dispositif,” but their efforts (just as ours in Amsterdam, around the archaeologies of screen, projection, camera, frame) are consonant with re-situating “apparatus theory,” still valuable and an indispensable reference point, not least because it was the first attempt at a comprehensive theoretical-philosophical articulation of the cinema. In the same spirit, the Imagined Futures project has as its working assumption the notion that a viewing and listening dispositive is predicated on several dimensions, working together: it implies a spatial extension, it involves a temporal register and it has a subjective reference as historically variable but conceptually indispensable elements. Our approach specifies that a dispositive is a dispositive only when it entails a – material – medium (most often a combination of technologies), an image (a representation, including a sound representation) and a spectator (liable to be solicited,

11 Thomas Elsaesser, “Archives and Archaeologies: The Place of Non-Fiction Film in Contemporary Media,” in Films that Work: Cinematic Means and Industrial Ends, Vinzenz Hediger and Patrick Vonderau, eds. (Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press, 2009) 19-34.

52 

Thomas Elsaesser

subjectified, addressed or affectively and cognitively engaged).12 Such a conception of the dispositive echoes, for instance, the definition proposed by Hans Belting. Arguing from the perspective of a post-art history, Belting advocates “a new approach to iconology” as part of his image-anthropology: “[…] W.J.T. Mitchell [uses] the terms image, text, ideology. […] I also use a triad of terms in which […] image remains but now is framed by the terms medium and body.” Belting goes on to explain that images can only be understood if one takes account of other, non-iconic determinants, and that medium needs to be understood “in the sense of the agent by which images are transmitted, while body means either the performing or the perceiving body on which images depend no less than on their respective media.”13 These attempts at re-description across the humanities underline the variable nature of what is to be understood by “image,” “medium” and “the moving image” today. What film studies can contribute are conceptual precisions and historical clarifications. For instance, in Belting’s definition, the term “framed” seems to me a problematic metaphor in two respects: it brings back the picture frame, and thus the picture, as opposed to the image; and it is a static-geometrical term, when what is required is a term that can encompass processual and time-based phenomena that are in flux. A similar caveat applies to the term “dispositif”: it seems to imply a fixed assemblage rather than a dynamic, ongoing process of re-alignment and interaction. On the other hand, Belting’s definition of the body as both “performing” and “perceiving” is helpful in that it is also clearly in line with major trends in film studies, where “agency” is now applied to characters within the fiction, to spectators/viewers/users, but also to objects and machines.14 This brings me to another general point: the debate about the cinematic apparatus, with its emphasis on subject position as a consequence of miscognition and disavowal, seems (negatively) predicated on a notion of the cinema as ideally a source of secure knowledge about the world. When theorists ask “how we know what we know” in the cinema – or, to quote Christian Metz’s famous words, want “to understand how films 12 Each of these terms refers to a different theoretical paradigm: “subjectified” belongs to the psychoanalytic terminology of miscognition or disavowal; “addressed” recalls Marxist cultural studies, via interpellation and negotiation; while “affectively and cognitively engaged” comes from studies of narrative comprehension and cognitivist film theory. 13 Hans Belting, “Image, Medium, Body. A New Approach to Iconology,” Critical Inquiry 31.2 (Winter 2005): 302-19, 302. 14 Discussions around “agency” seem to point to the influence of Bruno Latour, Reassembling the Social: An Introduction to Actor-Network Theory (Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press, 2005).

Between Knowing and Believing

53

are understood”15 – are they not committing themselves too exclusively to an epistemological theory of film centered on “realism,” even as they denounce its realism as an ideological effect? By extension, some of the difficulties and deadlocks – not only of apparatus theory in the 1980s but also of film theory at its present conjuncture (where cognitivists are ranged on one side, Deleuzians and phenomenologists on the other, united only in their rejection of psychoanalysis and semiotics) – might be due in part to an insufficiently articulated debate as to the status of cinema between “ontology” and “epistemology.” Cognitivism tends to assume a positive relationship between representation, knowledge and truth, depending on pre-formed expectations, evidence and ocular verification. By contrast, psycho-semiotics subscribes to such an epistemology mainly in its negative mode, critiquing films for failing to live up to this presumption of realism: the very term “illusionism” requires a faith in “realism” as its foil, as does the charge that film produces its “effects of the real” through fetishism. Feminist theory equates scoptophilia with epistemophilia, attacking both, while in the discourse of social constructivism and cultural studies, epistemic pretensions of films capable of speaking the truth are no less firmly and no less negatively implied (for instance, when accusing Hollywood of misrepresentations, stereotyping, etc.). A tendency towards cinephobia, in other words, underpins a radical epistemic critique of cinema, largely ignoring both the aesthetic value that “mere appearance” or the so-called “illusion of presence” might have, and the possibility, put forward by Deleuze and others, that in the cinema we do not so much gain knowledge about the world, as we learn about ourselves being in the world (which would amount to an “ontological” position).

Dispositive Mark 1: What Was Cinema The problem, here, is perhaps a broader one, namely the need to reflect once more quite fundamentally about what is cinema/what was cinema, and to try and locate its place or purpose within human history in general and the history of what is called “modernity” in particular. My suggestion is that we should, for the sake of clarification, differentiate between anthropological, philosophical and aesthetic theories of the cinema, if we are to find a level of generality where dispositives are not defined solely 15 Christian Metz, “Problems of Denotation in the Fiction Film,” in Film Language, trans. Michael Taylor (New York: Oxford UP, 1974) 145.

54 

Thomas Elsaesser

by their basic technology. Evidently these are not mutually exclusive approaches. Anthropological theories, for instance, comprise a wide range of views, including André Bazin’s ideas about the cinema as photographically based, and of photography being related to the bodily imprint: hence his references to mummies, the Turin shroud, plaster casts and other forms of effigies. But it also encompasses Walter Benjamin’s ideas about cinema and modernity, his influential concept of the optical unconscious and his notion that cinema “trains” the senses, in order for us to cope with the shocks and traumata of modern urban life. Also under a broadly anthropological perspective, one can count the implications drawn from Foucault’s theories of the disciplinary and self-monitoring effects of vision machines, notably his theory of the Panopticon, which has been revived – around surveillance – as a generalized paradigm of vision in the twenty-first century, replacing both window and mirror as the “epistemes” of the twentieth century. The epistemological theories already alluded to would fall under the more generally philosophical approaches to the cinema. Film philosophy ranges from phenomenological theories to cognitivist ones and also includes various ontologies of the cinema (as attributed to Bazin, as proclaimed by Stanley Cavell or as imputed to Gilles Deleuze), while the third general category would be aesthetic theories of the cinema, whether these call themselves “poetics” and are derived from Aristotelian theories of drama, or “formalist” as influenced by Russian semiotics, whether they stem from “theatricality” as first defined by Plato, or more specifically have to do with Romantic theories of play, of appearance and presence, and concern themselves with the status of the image in the arts or with the representation of movement and motion.16 In most theories of the cinema proposed over the past eighty years or so, there is an overlap between epistemological and aesthetic categories, as in the different theories of realism, or in the different ideological critiques, where epistemological questions and anthropological concerns are not easily kept apart. Likewise, ontological theories tend to overlap with aesthetic ones, as do phenomenological ones. But the advantage of making such distinctions at all is that they encourage another look at existing theories 16 The publications alluded to here are André Bazin, “Ontology of the Photographic Image,” What is Cinema? vol. I, ed. Hugh Gray (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1967) 9-16; Stanley Cavell, The World Viewed: Reflections on the Ontology of Film (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971); Gilles Deleuze, Cinema I. The Movement Image, trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1985) and Cinema II. The Time Image, trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Robert Galeta (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1989); David Bordwell, Narration and the Fiction Film (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1985); and Sam Weber, Theatricality as Medium (Fordham: Fordham University Press, 2004).

Between Knowing and Believing

55

in light of present concerns, notably the media change we are concerned with here. Past theories can be productively studied for how they formulate the problems, even if one does not agree with their answers. The question “what was cinema,” formulated across these distinctions between anthropological, philosophical and aesthetic “regimes,” would determine the agenda for our second type of revisionism, one that re-reads the history of film theory. An example of how such a revision might work involves André Bazin, one of the undisputed founders of our discipline. Bazin has been chided as a misguided epistemologist of realism, when another look at his writings suggests a) that he was the most inter-disciplinary thinker imaginable; b) that his anthropological conception of cinema is still pertinent, since it even allows for a “cinema after cinema”; and c) that there are quite different ways of understanding what he meant by “realism.” Re-reading Bazin in 2008, on the fiftieth anniversary of his death, I could find little that would indict him as a naïve realist, and much that showed him to be a sophisticated advocate of illusionism – not only as a matter of aesthetics, but also as a matter of belief and mutually negotiated rules of the game – rather than as a dogmatic idealist.17 In short, the current state of theory leaves a number of unresolved issues, which complicates a historically grounded and theoretically consistent approach to the “episteme 1900” and its contemporary analogue, the “episteme 2000.” The very idea of “episteme” evidently implies a broadly Foucauldian approach: “the machine (its technology), its location and the place given to the spectator/hearer form in this way a three-unit structure.”18 In such a formulation, the dispositive is associated with power, “and especially with the coercive, disciplinary or controlling power of libidinal assemblages.” On the other hand, this idea of a contact space or contact zone between human perceptual faculties and mechanical elements may lead one to opt, not for “dispositive,” but instead for the term “interface,” understood as a boundary across which different systems meet, act on, interfere or communicate with one another.19 As indicated, ontological theories have also been revived in order to overcome what is now seen as the historicity of the technology that formed 17 Thomas Elsaesser, “A Bazinian Half-Century,” Opening Bazin, ed. Dudley Andrew, with Hervé Joubert-Laurencin (New York: Oxford University Press, 2011) 3-12. 18 François Albera and Maria Tortajada, call for papers, conference on “Viewing and Listening Dispositives.” 19 See for instance Lev Manovich, “Cinema as a Cultural Interface,” http://www.manovich. net/TEXT/cinema-cultural.html (last accessed on February 4, 2013) and Seung-hoon Jeong, Cinematic Interfaces: Film Theory After New Media (New York: Routledge, 2013).

56 

Thomas Elsaesser

the basis of the cinematic dispositive in its classical articulation: namely, the photographic image, projection and the fixed spectator. Accommodating its importance without being limited by the specificity of the dispositive, such an ontological approach places greater emphasis on “belief” or “trust” rather than on “knowledge” or “truth.” Such trust in the “image” (as a field of forces and intensities, rather than a “representation” with a particular “reference”) is secured either as an existential choice or as an interpersonal, pragmatic value, and does not depend on a particular “essence” of cinema or on photographic indexicality in explaining what binds the film spectator to the world (of images). Recent work in aesthetics has challenged the ocular-centric geometry of the cinematic dispositive on several fronts, as part of yet another critique of perspectival projection, with “infinity” as the implied vanishing point and the “singular source” or solitary observer as the necessary point of view.20 Other objections concern the fact that the cinematic “cone of vision” privileges space and stasis (“staging in depth”) over time and process; that it relies too much on the bounded frame (off-screen/on-screen) or on the centrifugal frame (in cinema) versus the centripetal (picture) frame (in painting); that it assumes as a given the upright, frontal orientation of human vision and the image, and that it tends to “freeze” the individual frame, thus reducing the cinematic image to the still image, mechanically animated, rather than start from the moving image, temporarily stilled in the photograph. The “new art history,” in particular, turned to cinema as a vital element of visual culture in the late 1980s.21 In the 1990s, however, overtly Marxist and/or psychoanalytic epistemological critiques of apparatus theory began to give way to ideas about vision and the observer that revived the multi-perspectival theories of the different avant-gardes, while also acknowledging the influence of video and installation art and the general opening up of museum culture to include the moving image. In the process, the “archaeological” interest in early cinema gained new traction and topical relevance: its dispositive – once considered “primitive” because it focused more on performance and less on narrative – could now be understood as a kind of “deconstruction” of monocular perspective, as if a return to the origins of cinema would be

20 Among the many critiques of the “Albertian window” applied to the cinema, see Victor Burgin, “Geometry and Abjection,” Public 1 (Winter 1988): 12-30; and Anne Friedberg, The Virtual Window: From Alberti to Microsoft (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2006). 21 Norman Bryson, “The Gaze in the Expanded Field,” Vision and Visuality, ed. Hal Foster (Seattle: Bay Press, 1988) 87-113.

Between Knowing and Believing

57

a case of reculer pour mieux sauter, of stepping back for a new leap forward, towards cinema and the moving image in the twenty-first century.

Dispositive Mark 2: Early Cinema The turn/return to early cinema has proved fertile in many different ways. Besides documenting the enormous variety of entertainment and scientific uses of the Cinématographe in the urban environment of evolving modernity (the anthropological aspect) and identifying a different aesthetics, whether called a “primitive mode of representation” (Burch) or “the cinema of attractions” (Gunning and Gaudreault),22 early cinema studies also recovered an epistemological dimension that tended to be lost in the negative epistemology of the 1970s: the close alliance of chronophotography with the empirical and observational sciences. As already noted, pioneers like Jules Janssen, Etienne-Jules Marey and even the Lumière Brothers (who from 1902 onwards devoted their best energies to experiments with color, with echographic topology and with medical appliances for war veterans) have returned as important figures in a genealogy of new media and expanded cinema. In France, a belatedly recognized hero has emerged in Georges Demenÿ, who dreamed up, explored and tested many applications of the moving image for sports training, teaching lip-reading to the deaf and more generally for educational, military and medical uses. In Britain, the multi-talent of R.W. Paul is beginning to be recognized,23 and in Germany, it was Oskar Messter who received special attention from scholars working on documentary and non-fiction film, but also on more adventurous aspects of the dispositive such as sound-image synchronization, color and 3-D projection.24 Messter holds a special place in our project and his extensive oeuvre allowed me to speak of the S/M practices of the apparatus, meaning: the scientific and medical imaging dispositive (his work for hospitals touched upon by Lisa

22 See the essays by Burch, Gunning and Gaudreault in Early Cinema: Space Frame Narrative, ed. Thomas Elsaesser (London: British Film Institute, 1990) and a new contextualization of these positions in The Cinema of Attractions Reloaded, ed. Wanda Strauven (Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press, 2007). 23 See Ian Christie, sleeve notes, biography and filmography in R.W. Paul, The Collected Films 1895-1908 (London: BFI DVD Edition, 2006). 24 Oskar Messter, Erfinder und Geschäftsmann, ed. Martin Loiperdinger, KINtop 3, special issue (Basel: Stroemfeld/Roter Stern, 1994).

58 

Thomas Elsaesser

Cartwright),25 the surveillance and military dispositive (linking Messter to Paul Virilio’s War and Cinema),26 the sensory-motor-schema dispositive (showing him to be a contemporary of Henri Bergson), and the sensoring and monitoring dispositive (pioneered, besides Marey, by Albert Londe and documented, among others, by Siegfried Zielinski27). In other words, by going back to early and pre-cinema, and duly noting the non-entertainment uses of the cinematic apparatus, one can advance the proposition that “the cinema has many histories, only some of which belong to the movies.”28 Evidently, at least in part, it is the topicality of the non- or para-entertainment uses at the turn of the twenty-first century that has once more given prominence to these earlier applications of the moving image and the cinematograph. While the historical and theoretical studies of Virilio and Friedrich Kittler helped to make the connections between war and cinema much more present in our minds, this new awareness was helped by the daily news bulletins about smart bombs during the first Iraq War, which in turn found their resonance in Harun Farocki’s work. For three decades, his films and video installations have been examining the different genealogies of what he calls “operational images” from the late nineteenth century, when photography was used for measuring the elevation of buildings, through gathering reconnaissance footage from spotter planes during WWII, all the way to the use of surveillance cameras in Californian prisons and the data-gathering sensors in Berlin supermarkets. Farocki’s investigations of hand, eye and machine are exemplary in showing how the cinematic dispositive – especially in its observational, monitoring and controlling functions – has become a pervasive presence in our everyday lives, joining art and entertainment with the industrial and bureaucratic uses of the moving image.29 In this sense, Farocki is returning to Muybridge’s time-and-motion studies, to which his own researches into social routines, stress tests and service-industry training exercises provide a contemporary update.30 25 Lisa Cartwright, Screening the Body: Tracing Medicine’s Visual Culture (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1995). 26 Paul Virilio, War and Cinema: The Logistics of Perception (London: Verso, 1989). 27 Siegfried Zielinski, Audiovisions: Cinema and Television as Entr’actes in History (Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press, 1999). 28 Harun Farocki – Working on the Sight-Lines, ed. Thomas Elsaesser (Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press, 2004) 17. 29 Harun Farocki, Auge/Maschine (video-installation, 23 mn, 2000) http://www.farocki-film. de/augem1.htm (last accessed on February 4, 2013). 30 See Harun Farocki, Reconnaître et poursuivre (Paris: Théâtre Typographique, 2002).

Between Knowing and Believing

59

New media theorists, on the other hand, have benefited from another look at Marey, whose work can now be re-appreciated as part of the archaeology of data-visualization and pattern recognition, which is beginning to get close consideration not just in the analysis of surveillance footage, but also among film scholars and theorists of the articulations of cinematic time and the management of real-time data.31 Imagined Futures has a number of projects that investigate time and temporality in relation to mainstream cinema and installation art, as well as looking at the locative aspects of film history and the archive.32 One of my own attempts at an epistemoanthropological analysis is an essay on so-called “Rube” films (or Uncle Josh films), arguing that earlier views of the phenomenon might have missed a crucial aspect, a double layer of reflexivity and agency. Uncle Josh films – in which a simpleton mistakes the representation on the screen for physically present objects and people and personally intervenes in the action, only to destroy the spectacle – pose several questions to the modern viewer.33 Are they intended, as is often claimed, to be didactic parables, teaching a rural or immigrant audience how not to behave in the cinema, by putting up to ridicule someone like themselves? Yet it is doubtful that there ever existed such an audience, or a moment of “infancy” and simplicity in the history of the movies, where such an ontological confusion with regard to objects and persons might have occurred. To me, then, these films imply a meta-level of self-reference, in order to explore, not the epistemic conundrum of reality versus representation or truth versus fiction, but the anthropological one, namely of how to “discipline” an audience through comedy and laughter. Do the Rube films not teach their audience how not to use their bodies as spectators by allowing them to enjoy their own superior form of spectatorship, even if that superiority is achieved at the price of self-censorship and self-restraint? The audience laughs at a simpleton and village idiot, thereby flattering itself with a self-image of urban sophistication. The punishment meted out to Uncle Josh by the projectionist is both allegorized as the reverse side of cinematic pleasure (watch out, “behind” the screen lies the figure of the “master”) and internalized as self-control: in the cinema – as elsewhere 31 Mary Ann Doane, The Emergence of Cinematic Time (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2001). 32 Among the various projects of the Imagined Futures group, see especially Jennifer Steetskamp, “Specters of Lessing: The Time-Spaces of the Moving Image Installation,” doctoral diss., University of Amsterdam, 2012; Pepita Hesselberth, “Chronoscopy: Affective Encounters with Cinematic Temporalities,” doctoral diss., University of Amsterdam, 2012. 33 Thomas Elsaesser, “Discipline through Diegesis: The Rube Film between ‘Attractions’ and ‘Narrative Integration,’ ” in Strauven, The Cinema of Attractions Reloaded 205-26.

60 

Thomas Elsaesser

in the modern world of display of commodities, and the self-display of bodies – the rule is “you may look, but don’t touch.”34 Adding a further twist, one can argue that the figure of the Rube has returned, and re-appears in our contemporary media-world, this time as the incarnation of the visitor/user, not in the cinema, but in the gallery space and also on the net, in the latter case learning how to be an “avatar” or to behave as a “fan,” a “nerd” or an “activist.”35 The same ambivalence applies to the museum, where visitors no longer know how to respond when confronted with, say, video installation art. Under the regime of “relational aesthetics,”36 the visitor’s role is destabilized by works that are like an enigmatic appliance or a gadget, but lacking the instruction manual: they invite participation, or require a special mental act for their comprehension or completion, while giving little or no overt clue about how they “want to be understood.” The “epistemological” aspect seems like a lure or tease, an invitation to a more ludic form of engagement, but on the other hand, it implies a reflexive turn that is epistemic in intent. In fact, there is now a general uncertainty about what role to play as spectators in the art world, just as there is in the media world of television and video-games: are we “witnesses” or “bystanders,” “players” or “users,” “observers” or “dupes” (Rubes), inadvertently delivering “data” to machine archives? My “return of the Rube” would thus be a specific or “situated” instance of the more general (and generally productive) problematic category of “agency” which, as André Gaudreault has pointed out, should be understood to comprise both agitant and agité in early cinema.37 Yet this shift from the “old” Cartesian subject-object divisions to something closer to an actor-network theory does not altogether resolve the question of the spectator’s emotional investments, so central to apparatus theory, but also to any appreciation of the aesthetics of cinema. If scholars are now more cautious about speaking of “mis-cognition” and “disavowal” as the features typical of cinematic subjectivity, there are still good arguments 34 See Wanda Strauven, “Re-Disciplining the Audience: Godard’s Rube-Carabinier,” Cinephilia: Movies, Love and Memory, Marijke de Valck and Malte Hagener, eds. (Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press, 2005) 125-33; and Wanda Strauven, “Touch, Don’t Look,” I cinque sensi del cinema/The Five Senses of Cinema, Alice Autelitano et al., eds. (Udine: Forum, 2005) 283-91. 35 Thomas Elsaesser, “Archaeologies of Interactivity: Early Cinema, Narrative and Spectatorship,” Film 1900: Technology, Perception, Culture, K. Kreimeier and A. Ligensa, eds. (Luton: John Libbey, 2009) 9-21. 36 The term “relational aesthetics” was made famous by Nicolas Bourriaud. See his Relational Aesthetics (1998; Paris: Les Presses du Réel, 2002). 37 See also the preface by François Albéra in Alain Boillat, Du Bonimenteur À La Voix-Over Voix-Attraction et Voix-Narration Au Cinéma (Lausanne: Antipodes, 2007).

Between Knowing and Believing

61

for characterizing the cinema as a dispositif for subjectification. This is not so much because of the particular spatial arrangement (projection), but thanks to the cinema’s temporal dimension, marked by “delay” and ”interval” in the sense of re-inscribing duration into the cinematic experience (the time image, energy, modulation, in Deleuzian language; “entropy,” “intermittence” in the language of cybernetics). This also makes it possible to distinguish cinema from “real-time” electronic media on the basis of “delay” and “deferral,” i.e. on the basis of a phenomenological distinction (if we take these terms in their Derridean sense) rather than a technological one (as the difference between photographic and electronic images). We thus would have to add “time” to “agency” in order to build up a model of a dispositive that does not privilege a particular technology and still proves relevant to both photographic and non-photographic moving images.

Dispositive Mark 3: Installation Art and the Moving Image Temporality and time economies, in particular, raise a further dimension in our consideration of the dispositive, which conveniently leads us to re-investigate the aesthetic theories of the cinema, albeit in only one, admittedly prominent, manifestation: that of the “entry” of the cinema and the moving image onto the scene of contemporary art, where the cinema now seems to have a permanent place, however ambiguous a place it may appear in practice. One of the most significant phenomena in the history of the “dispositive cinema” is the way the moving image has taken over and has been taken over by the museum and gallery spaces. From the mid-1990s onward, major shows in London, Los Angeles, Paris, Oxford, New York, Vienna and other cities aff irmed the museums’ intention to “represent” the cinema and claim it as “art.”38 Despite the success of such exhibitions, matters are not straightforward when the moving image enters the museum. Different actor-agents, power relations and policy agendas, different competences, egos and sensibilities, different elements of the complex puzzle that is the contemporary art world and its commercial counterpart inevitably come 38 Some of the landmark exhibitions were “Spellbound” (Hayward Gallery, London, 1995), “Art and Cinema since 1945: Hall of Mirrors” (Moca, Los Angeles, 1996), “Notorious – Alfred Hitchcock and Contemporary Art” (Museum of Modern Art, Oxford, 1999), “Hitchcock et l’art: coïncidences fatales” (Montreal/Paris, 2000/2001), “Into the Light: The Projected Image in American Art, 1964 – 1977” (Whitney Museum, 2001), “X-Screen – Filmic Installations from the 1960s and 70s” (MuMoK, Vienna, 2004).

62 

Thomas Elsaesser

into play. However easy it might be to project a film inside a gallery with just a few mobile walls and lots of dark fabric, the museum is no cinema and the cinema no museum: mainly because of the different time economies already alluded to, which oblige the viewer in the museum to “sample” a film, rather than make it the occasion for “two hours at the movies.” Time is thus one of the reasons why cinema and museum constitute two quite distinct, and in the past often mutually exclusive, dispositives. The fact that cinema and the gallery space are, both historically and philosophically, two antagonistic visual arrangements and spatial dispositives is usually expressed in the juxtaposition of “black box” and “white cube.” Each space is culturally pre-determined, has its own historically conditioned but deeply ingrained traditions, and follows particular architectonics, ordering principles or “logics” which amount to distinct ontologies. As we saw, the classical (or “black box”) cinematic dispositive requires a unique layout and geometry, in the way that screen-space, auditorium space and projector are aligned in relation to one another for the “cinema-effect” to occur. The museum/gallery (or “white box”) is itself a specific dispositive. With its white walls, its preference for “natural” light and its emphasis on smooth surfaces, it organizes space in such a way that the objects visible to the spectator are brought close and maintain their distance at the same time. The placing and hanging of pictures subtly privileges the upright, forward orientation of our gaze, directed at the formation of an “picture,” distinctly framed and positioned at eye-level. Still paying tribute to the “open window” of Renaissance perspective, the white wall into which the image space is cut allows for generous margins and empty surfaces to surround each picture, while the heavily gilded frames are a reminder of the fundamental difference between the picture, what it contains, the look it retains and the space that surrounds it. In the museum, there is never any off-screen space, to speak in the language of cinema: the classical oil painting is wholly contained – self-contained, indeed – within the frame, while cinema lives from the tension between off-screen and on-screen, what the frame delimits and what it creates a passage for. As I already pointed out, it was André Bazin who famously distinguished the “centrifugal” cinema frame from the “centripetal” painting frame.39 The difference between these vectors helps explain why the gallery and the cinema are distinguished by the mode of attention they afford their respective viewers. The kind of presence produced by standing in front of 39 André Bazin, “Painting and Cinema” [1959], What Is Cinema? vol. 1, trans. Hugh Gray (Berkeley: University of California Press 1967) 164-69.

Between Knowing and Believing

63

a work of art in a museum or a gallery carries very strong indices of time and place (of a “now” and a “here”), which in turn imply a special type of viewing subject, highly aware of itself and its surroundings and thus receptive to reflection, introspection and auto-reflection. Walter Benjamin famously called this presence “aura” and was careful to specify its conditions of possibility, along with the slippages the aura undergoes in the age of mechanically reproducible images and the commodity form. Speculating on the mode of presence typical of the cinema, Benjamin speaks of the desire to touch and the simultaneous barring of this desire, generating the cycles of disavowal and fetish-formation which psychoanalytic film theory famously identified, albeit via a different route of analysis. Simplifying a little, one could say that the museum produces a particular kind of presence (a “me,” a “here” and a “now”), whereas the cinema produces a split self-presence of multiple temporalities (a “me/not me” in an endlessly deferred “here/not here” and “now/not now”): Roland Barthes, in his several essays devoted to photography and the cinema, highlighted some of these differences in terms of tense. 40 In their distinctive logics, the dispositives “cinema” and “museum” entail a further set of differential coordinates, which come into play or conflict when the moving image enters the museum: a fixed image and a mobile spectator (museum) have to be aligned with a moving image and a fixed spectator (cinema). From what has been said about the cinematic apparatus, the combination of the moving image and the mobile spectator drastically redefines, if not destroys the “cinema-effect,” while for the contemplativereflexive spectator of the picture gallery, the moving image is a distraction and an irritation. Painting and sculpture are about the representation of movement, not its instantiation. The encounter of cinema and museum thus obliges even art history to rethink the place and role of the viewer in front of an artwork, as well as examine the kinds of self-enclosure or “exposure” afforded to the moving image not just by the physical display (the monitor or screen), but also by the manner in which the look of the image frames the viewer’s gaze in the gallery’s surroundings. 41 The new configuration of cinema/museum also affects what Belting calls “the body,” i.e. the respective degrees of embodiment of the “spectator” and the “visitor.” Compared to the 40 Roland Barthes, Camera Lucida. Reflections on Photography (1981) and Roland Barthes by Roland Barthes (1977), trans. Richard Howard (New York: Hill and Wang, 2010). 41 One may recall the famous scene in Hitchcock’s Vertigo, where Scotty watches – in the sense of “spying on” – “Carlotta”/Judy looking at – in the sense of “contemplating” – the painting of her “ancestor.”

64 

Thomas Elsaesser

cinema’s originally disembodied look, the gallery’s default value is always embodied perception, aware as we are of our surroundings and other bodies. Also part of “the body” are the different relations of size, scale and detail in the museum and on the cinema screen. A further disruption or transgression is implied by the entry of sound and sound-spaces into the museum, traditionally a site of silence and stillness (in both senses of the word). In other words, there are some fundamental antinomies between cinema and museum that require serious consideration by both film scholars and art historians.

Dispositive Mark 4: Encounter and Event Yet the salient argument to make here is that these apparent incompatibilities (and the many contradictory relations that obtain between the respective dispositives) are precisely among the theoretically most fruitful and in practice most productive factors about the fine arts and visual culture today, not only enabling but necessitating the new kinds of encounter alluded to, as moving image and museum enter into sustained and no doubt permanent contact and alliance with each other. For is it not the case that these starkly distinct dispositives are themselves “on the move” and in flux, each in its own way undergoing internal transformation, and for reasons that at first glance do not seem to be interconnected or mutually dependent? Take as one example the upright forward orientation, the prevalence of the wall, the rectangle cut out like a window: modern art, at least since the 1950s, has subverted or ignored this arrangement with artists like Jackson Pollock, Carl Andre, Andy Warhol, Joseph Beuys and many others. In very different ways, these artists have made the floor, rather than the wall, the site of display, not least because it challenges the canonical model of bodily-perceptual orientation and thus creates a new “moment” of art: a challenge only very gradually taken up by the cinema. More drastic, but also more banal (because they are so often commented upon) are the changes that the cinematic dispositive has undergone: television long ago subverted it, merely by substituting the small screen for the movie theater and phosphoric glow for projection, provoking in turn different kinds of re-assertions of the power of the projected image, whether through Cinemascope (in the 1950s) or the Dolby surround-sound design (in the 1970s). Since then, screens have become both bigger and smaller, but above all, they have become more “mobile”: in their proliferation as monitors on every table top, in the home and at work, in their locations

Between Knowing and Believing

65

(such as urban screens, electronic notice-boards, airplanes, motor-cars or public transport) but also embedded in the hand-held devices we carry on our bodies, such as music players or mobile phones. This means that the opposition between “collective reception” in ranked and regimented seating (cinema) and “individual absorption” in a state of solitary contemplation (museum) is no longer valid, at least not in any absolute way. Meanwhile, and notably for the blockbuster shows that international museums habitually organize, the throng of massed visitors makes the solitary study of individual works a thing of the past or of another era, as more and more let their eyes be guided by portable “audio-tours.” The black box and the white cube are thus, strictly speaking, no longer either an oppositional or a complementary pair: we are, as it were, in the “grey room.” Their similarities and differences come into play at another level of generality that exceeds both types of dispositive, generating new sets of parameters and taxonomies. What, for instance, is the status of projection, now that the moving image is mostly digital, and illumination means something quite different? In what sense can we still speak of a light cone and “scopic vision” (cinema) versus diffused light and “ambient vision” (museum)? A cinephile may regard projection as the defining feature of cinema and logically conclude that without projection, there is “no more cinema.” Or one might decide that the litmus test, as it were, of “what is cinema” lies with luminosity, achieved through transparency, and not with illumination as a layering effect. In either case, one would have to seriously revisit familiar genealogies: traditionally, a (tenuous) line of continuity could be drawn from the light-sensitive silver salts of photography to the electrons hitting the cathode ray tube, and from the vertical scan-lines of a television set to the pixel-grid of the digital image – in the sense that in each case, a surface is impacted by light, leaving the particular arrangement of traces or the pattern of particles that we call an image. At the same time, a radical break is posited between photographic index and digital code. Yet arguably, at least as fundamental a break occurred in the switch from luminosity through transparency (which still photography and cinema have in common) to luminosity through refraction, opacity and saturation. In this respect, the “opacity” of the digital pixel is closer to the opacity of pigment in painting than either is to photography, leading to the many – admittedly also deceiving – painterly metaphors used to describe or advertise computer-generated image-processing software, or

66 

Thomas Elsaesser

to the “slippages” between the media of photography and painting in the work of an artist like Jeff Wall. 42 Contrasting the dispositive of installation art with that of the cinema on the basis of these precise but diverse parameters presents several further advantages: first of all, it de-emphasizes technological determinism (the technological fix which I see as so problematic in the theories that posit a radical break between photographic and digital cinema), allowing instead for very different technologies and materials to achieve similar effects and experiences. Secondly, it de-centers the “performing and perceiving” subject (Belting), thus redirecting our thinking toward the relations that exist in the realm of images – between humans and things, humans and plants, humans and machines, machines and machines, all considered as agents (the reverse side and complement of the famous anthropomorphism discussed by the avant-garde under the heading of photogénie or celebrated in the “science is fiction” films of Jean Painlevé and others). Perhaps most crucially, however, an installation – especially one involving the moving image – has a particular relation to time and temporality, in the sense that many such installations introduce a structural non-alignment between their own temporality and that of the spectator’s time economy of the gallery visit, producing (as suggested above) typical effects of “subjectification”: the anxiety of missing the crucial moment, the potential conflict between curiosity and boredom when confronted with a video, signaling a duration ranging anywhere from three minutes to three hours. In this non-alignment, the encounter of viewer and installation acts as both a continuation and a critique of the cinematic dispositive, not only in the way that installations can deviate from the frontal orientation and Renaissance perspective already discussed, but also in the manner they subvert the temporal regime of both the cinema (where I know in advance that I commit a substantial portion of my time, and where narrative maps the order of succession and closure) and the art gallery (where the amount of time I choose to spend in front of a painting or sculpture is my own decision, unstructured, and not in any way pre-given by the work). The (video-)installation, by contrast, suspends me: I wait for the proverbial shoe to drop, for the unique moment of rupture, I attach myself to or fantasize para-narrative elements; I experience a configuration of time-space, which puts me in a different relation to self-perception and body-awareness – no longer the kairos or chronos of linear narrative, but 42 See, for instance, Sven Lütticken, “The Story of Art According to Jeff Wall,” in Sven Lütticken, Secret Publicity: Essays on Contemporary Art (Rotterdam: NAi Publishers, 2005) 69-82.

Between Knowing and Believing

67

an un-pulsed time of “too much” and “not enough.” Elements that appear to my eyes as contiguous in space may have to be read as successive in time, or vice versa: their succession has to be retroactively reconstructed as spatially distinct. In any case, there is no longer a “norm” by which to measure the deviations, the extremes or the excesses, while any sense of the work’s overall shape and extension necessarily escapes me, forcing a radical reconsideration of the relation between fragment and totality so crucial to Western aesthetics, but also to the cinema (“montage”/editing), and challenging any notion of spatial capture or closure, even as the black box mimics the darkened movie theater. Yet in some ways this anxiety of the “too much/not enough” of installation art, turned into an aesthetic effect, is reminiscent of one of the panic discourses in early cinema, when movie theaters switched from short programs to full-length features, with doctors warning about eyestrain, physiological damage and nervous disorders that might result from watching a continuous action on screen for more than a few minutes.

Conclusion: the Dispositive as Interface? The detour via the museum and installation art has been necessary in order to explain – including to myself – where I think the term “dispositif” might be problematic, and where it offers scope for clarifying the situation we find ourselves in, the episteme 2000, when compared to the episteme 1900. With the emphasis now on parameters such as temporality, duration, process, “relationality,” contact, mobility, event and encounter, the traditional definitions (and translations) of “dispositif,” even without the question of “technology,” become problematic because they are too fixed spatially (beholden to Euclidian geometry) and too vague epistemologically (what is the status of film as semiotic object, if time intervenes and bridges the binary pair absence/presence?). Furthermore, the “dispositif” thus conceived still keeps the “subject” in a disciplinary-libidinal double bind (the “subject effect” of fetishism and disavowal, as theorized by Lacan, being replaced by the “subject effect” of power, knowledge, discourse, as analyzed by Foucault). What might nonetheless make it worth adopting the term dispositive is its semantic flexibility and metaphoric openness (compared to “apparatus”). If I am right in thinking that, besides being defined by “image,” “medium,” and “body” (Belting) and “the machine, its location and the place given to the spectator/hearer” (Albera/Tortajada), the cinema today should also be

68 

Thomas Elsaesser

regarded as an “event and encounter, taking place” (my definition, intended to both supersede and contain the idea of films as “works” and “texts”), a term (or set of terms) is needed that can establish a viable conjunction between the variables “agency,” “time,” “space”/“place.” Can dispositive connote this, while still covering these other meanings? In The Language of New Media, Lev Manovich puts forward the term “interface” to designate this meta-space, i.e. the different kinds of contact zones, spatial relations or visual surfaces that cinema audiences have in common with computer users and their interaction with the software, but also for the kinds of encounters between object, space, duration and beholder that I have sketched as “taking place” in the museum. Manovich sees the cinema as an important set of references for the new media environment, what he calls “the cinema as cultural interface”: despite frequent pronouncements that cinema is dead, it is actually on its own way to becoming a general purpose cultural interface, a set of techniques and tools which can be used to interact with any cultural data. […] “Cinema” [here] includes mobile camera, representation of space, editing techniques, narrative conventions, activity of a spectator – in short, different elements of cinematic perception, language and reception. Their presence is not limited to the twentieth-century institution of fiction films, they can already be found in panoramas, magic lantern slides, theatre and other nineteenth-century cultural forms. 43

Manovich’s eminently pragmatic approach tries to give some historical depth as well as breadth of applicability to “interface.” Yet where “dispositif” (as “apparatus”) seemed overly restrictive, “interface” looks unduly capacious. If, like myself, one travels in the opposite direction and comes to contemporary media practice from the study of cinema, one of the questions that concern me is: under what circumstances or conditions (culturalhistorical, technological-industrial or aesthetic-formal) is it conceivable that the moving image no longer requires as its main medium the particular form of time/space/agency we know as “narrative” (perhaps the most “viable conjunction” of these variables so far developed), while still managing to establish a coherent “world,” which is to say, turn an “event” (a singular time/space occurrence) into an “encounter” (addressing a spectator in his/ her here-and-now)? Is a time/space continuum possible that is differently 43 Lev Manovich, The Language of New Media (Cambridge: MIT Press, 2001) 86. See also http:// www.manovich.net/TEXT/cinema-cultural.html (last accessed on February 4, 2013).

Between Knowing and Believing

69

organized, yet still accommodates the “body” and gives the impression of “virtual presence”? What forms of indexicality (material link, pointer) or iconicity (mimesis, resemblance) are available, for combinations of sounds and images to credibly mark a “here” and “now,” while also relating them to a “me”? In other words, I am looking for a term that captures this “here-now-me” as the variable “grounding” of my cinematic experience. Whether I watch a Hollywood blockbuster on my iPod or see a mere five minutes of Douglas Gordon’s 24 Hour Psycho in a gallery, I can call either a “cinematic” encounter and event, not because of questions of LCD-screen vs. projection, digital vs. photographic image, black box vs. white cube, film vs. video, optical vs. haptic, fragment vs. totality; but because in each case, I can specify that the relation of a “here,” a “now” and a “me” constituted a consistent spatiotemporal world, whose “rules” I understand and whose effects I experience as “presence,” under conditions of assent that I can call “belief” (which, of course, includes the “suspension of disbelief” as well as the “as-if” belief of the fictional contract). What is also clear, however, is that with such a definition of “dispositif,” I am no longer in the realm of epistemological questions to put to the cinema. Rather, I am on the road to “(re-)ontologizing” the cinema: experiencing it not as a way of knowing the world, or seeking to attribute to it a specific meaning, but instead, living the cinema as a particular way of being-in-the-world, and participating in its disclosure, its unfolding, its becoming-present: with all the affects, cognitive dissonances or bodily states that this might entail. If this sounds unexpectedly Deleuzian, I feel bound to point out that for me, such a def inition of the “dispositif” actually rests as much on media-archaeological foundations as it does on philosophy, and that it has its own genealogy and pedigree in early and pre-cinematic practice. Suppose we went back to the laterna magica of Athanasius Kircher, as the agreed ancestor of cinematic projection. Yet instead of tracing its mode of representation via Renaissance perspective to the rigid geometry of the cinematic apparatus, where do we arrive at, if we choose an alternative route? What if, from the laterna magica, we derived in the first instance Étienne-Gaspard Robert’s (or Robertson’s) phantasmagoria as the most popular, but also conceptually most challenging precursor of cinema? We might then find ourselves in a position to argue that a direct line runs from phantasmagoria to Pepper’s Ghost and other spectral productions of presence in the nineteenth century to certain genres of cinema, mainly those featuring special effects, with horror and fantasy, but not only: the lineage of phantasmagoria also initiates a form of cinema that does not project itself as

70 

Thomas Elsaesser

a window on the world, nor requires fixed boundaries of space like a frame. Rather, it functions as an ambient form of spectacle and event, where no clear spatial divisions between inside and outside pertain, and where there are strong indices of presence, while its temporality reaches into past and future (calling up the dead, soothsaying and predicting events yet to come), while the senses are anchored and the body situated in a “here and now.” As such, phantasmagoria would be the dispositive that also most closely approximates the genealogical ancestor of what I described as installation art above, one that does not depend on the frame or even on the upright forward orientation, one that furthermore takes “sound” into account, but also the one whose epistemological effects are, as it were, grounded in an aesthetics of appearance as presence, rather than the other way round. However, the modification I am proposing has not one, but two nodes in the nineteenth century: besides that of the phantasmagoria, as it comes down to us via Robertson’s adaptation of the magic lantern, this cinematic dispositive also includes the work of Marey, notably insofar as he pioneered the non-human, dare I say “spectral” visualization of data, both photographing and graphing statistical (mathematical, numeric), optical (visible to the machine eye, but too fast or too slow for the human eye) and dynamic phenomena (emanating from organisms and sentient beings). I can here only hint at this aspect – which might involve reconsidering the Kantian “sublime” as a crucial dimension or property of this dispositif. Still, as I said at the beginning, Marey remains a key reference point for our project, due to its inherently ontological scope. Although his efforts, experiments and ambitions would normally be called “epistemological” (aimed at producing new knowledge about the world), considered from the standpoint of making all emanations of life manifest, Marey’s thinking also introduces a new taxonomy of things, of what exists and what does not, of what is visible and what is not, and of what is actual and what is virtual – linking him, with Bergson, to Gilles Deleuze. I come to my conclusion. My initial proposition has been that, in order to understand what the episteme 1900 and the episteme 2000 have in common, we need to overcome the division between photographic and post-photographic cinema, and see it, not as a break, but as an occasion for revising our previous notion of “what is cinema.” If for some thirty or forty years, the answer to “what is cinema” has involved some version of the dispositive cinema (such as “cinematic apparatus”), then the task inter alia is to redefine this central concept. This is what my essay has attempted to do: first I reviewed the canonical definition, as it has been specified around the particular geometry of representation that Jean-Louis Baudry

Between Knowing and Believing

71

was the first to identify with the parable of Plato’s cave, with Renaissance perspective and with the Freudian psychic apparatus. Following references to the various critiques of this formation, I proposed and discussed several other possible articulations of the dispositive cinema, whose properties were more institutional than technological, more time-based than geometrical, more anthropological than ideological and more “ontologizing” than epistemological. Starting out from early cinema, making a leisurely detour via installation art and the museum and a brief one through digital media and interface, I ended up by returning to pre-cinema: the double and possibly improbable pedigree of Robertson’s phantasmagoria joined to Marey’s chronophotography. The trajectory has provided me with a set of parameters and priorities that in my opinion need to inform our definition of the “dispositif,” for which notions of space, time and agency (the “here-now-me”), as well as of “belief,” “appearance” and “presence” play as great a role as the semiotics of absence and presence, the dynamics of voyeurism and disavowal or the notion of “vision-knowledge-power” (voir, savoir, pouvoir). This “perspective correction”44 has led me to posit a further proposition or rather, to formulate a challenge, namely that we may have to supplement our traditional epistemological interest in the cinema (around “realism,” the subject-object split, questions of ideology, illusionism, power) with a tentatively ontological view (as well as a renewed aesthetic investigation) of the cinema – here called, perhaps somewhat imprecisely, “cinema as event and encounter, taking place.” Another way of highlighting the difference of emphasis, again in a somewhat rough-and-ready fashion, would be to suggest that whereas our Renaissance ocular-centric orientation has infinity as its vanishing point (the all-seeing God of the Dollar Bill, or of Bishop Berkeley’s esse est percipi: to be is to be seen) and the singular source as its point of view, the orientation I am trying to identify has as its salient feature, not Euclidean space, but ubiquity. I would define ubiquity as the felt presence of pure space, whose temporality is neither chronos nor kairos, but an “indefinite,” reversible time, and whose ocular counterpart would be not be surveillance as sight, knowledge, power, but as the unlocalizable experience of sight without an eye and as the human-machine equivalent of Nicolas de Cusa’s God: “to be at the centre of the world and yet at every point of its circumference,” i.e. the paradox (or mystery) of an un-located situatedness. Such ubiquity, in other words, produces its own forms of embodiment 44 I borrow the phrase “perspective correction” from Rod Stoneman, “Perspective Correction: Early Film to the Avant-Garde,” Afterimage 8/9 (Spring 1981): 50-63.

72 

Thomas Elsaesser

and agency in response to unrepresentability and to the unlocalizable sense of presence. Ubiquity gives imagined vision and sight to non-sentient objects, to machines, organisms or “things,” as these enter the realm of the visible in seemingly contradictory forms: as effigies (imprints, moulds, installations, photographs) and as apparitions (ghosts, revenants, zombies and other post-mortem creatures). Together, the effigy (as index) and the apparition (as presence) constitute elements of a new modality of evidence and authenticity, sometimes called “the virtual,” but which I prefer to regard as constitutive for all cinema. The conclusion I would draw, then, is that such a post- or para-epistemological idea of cinema means accepting, not only the groundless ground of cinematic “representation” and its dispositive in the way that Foucault, for instance, deconstructed the Renaissance painterly dispositif in Velasquez’s Las Meninas. It would require a further step of “renegotiating” belief, appearance and presence, in the full knowledge that such a “belief in the cinema” inherits and accommodates both the hopes and the skepticism of the epistemological view, rather than denying or transcending it. A cinematic dispositive grounded in “belief” and “presence” is contradictory and counter-intuitive, but it would see time, space and agency as the (necessary) relational terms for any form of cinema, whose impure and mixed, mechanical and spiritual, material and mental, semiotic and mimetic “nature” alienates us from our bodies and senses, takes us away from the “here-and-now” – in the very act of constituting possibly their most historically potent and in all likelihood most permanent manifestations.

II. Dispositives Issues



“You Do Not Even Know Where You Are” Dispositive and Dizziness Patrick Désile

The countless efflorescences of more or less recent uses of the word “dispositif” fall into areas as diverse as law, diplomacy, the art of warfare, sociology, plastic arts, literary criticism, film theory (obviously), and many others. Being careful not to venture in every direction, here I will limit my own use of the term to two meanings: first, the standard usage of “a set of elements arranged with a view to a specific goal,” to quote a definition from Trésor de la langue française; 1 spectacular dispositives in this instance, more specifically from the late eighteenth century and the early nineteenth century, a time that seems like the beginning of so many things, with so many relations surfacing between them. Second, in a return of sorts to Foucault – if I may put it that way – I will address the issue of whether or not what I set out to describe may be considered a dispositif in his sense of the term, that is, whether or not the concept of “dispositif,” which by every indication remains current, may be instrumental in the intelligibility of this ensemble, and under which conditions. By spectacular, I do not mean “what pertains to the arts of spectacle or at least, I do not only mean this.” Like the Latin word spectaculum, spectacle involves both a general and a more specialized meaning here: first, that of a “set of things that attract the look” and, as early as the thirteenth century and especially from the Renaissance on, that of “entertainment presented to the public.” According to the Dictionnaire de Trévoux, spectacle thus refers to “an extraordinary object that attracts looks, arrests vision, and which one considers with some emotion,”2 as well as “public performances […], particularly theatrical performances.”3 A spectacular dispositive may accordingly be regarded as an arrangement that draws, orients, guides and informs the look. It may be a theater, of course – notably in the broad sense of this word in the eighteenth century4 1 “Dispositif,” Trésor de la langue française, vol. 7 (Paris: CNRS/Gallimard, 1979) 294. 2 Dictionnaire universel françois et latin, vulgairement appelé Dictionnaire de Trévoux, 7th ed., vol. 7 (Paris, 1771) 825. 3 Dictionnaire de Trévoux 825. 4 “Theatre: elevated place where performances or spectacles are given.” Dictionnaire de Trévoux, vol. 8 (Paris, 1771) 7.

76 Patrick Désile

– but it may also consist of a layout in a garden, a mirror such as the Claude glass used by painters and walkers in the eighteenth century, or even a prescriptive description. In fact, while my subject essentially has to do with collective, established spectacles designed for an audience that has expressly convened or gathered, I do not believe these can be dissociated from the tight network of innumerable spectacles offered by the world. In the last decades of the eighteenth century and the first decade of the nineteenth century, a number of spectacles thus appeared in Europe. Limiting myself to the case of Paris, I will attempt to describe and trace relations between several of these spectacles considered as novelties by their contemporaries. At the end of the eighteenth century, Paris was the city-world, “round as a pumpkin,”5 an expanding city seized by the “frenzy of building,”6 in Mercier’s words. It was a complicated city, rife with crooks and nooks, often presented at the time as muddy, stinky, noisy and dark; that is, still poorly lit and poorly known (the first accurate map of Paris by Verniquet appeared in the last years of the century). It was an unstable city as well, with a changing, unpredictable population. It was a violent city: fights were frequent, an integral part of the spectacle of the streets. The blood of oxen slaughtered in public flowed onto the pavement7 and people enjoyed watching a goose hanged on a gallows being clubbed to death by men,8 or mastiffs tearing a donkey to pieces in amphitheaters dedicated to animal fights. In this dubious city, as we might call it, procedures of organization, regulation and control were put into place: the population was monitored, more or less, by commissioners-examiners who served as the “judges’ eyes,”9 by inspectors, and above all by “observers,”10 in other words, informers. Moreover, maps were drawn up, street names were inscribed, gradually houses were numbered, urban lighting was improved. Some of these initiatives gave rise to hostility, to the degree that some operations, such as house numeration, had to be carried out at night.11 5 Louis-Sébastien Mercier, Tableau de Paris, vol. 1 (Amsterdam, 1782) 17. 6 Mercier, Tableau de Paris, vol. 8 (Amsterdam, 1783) 190. 7 Mercier, Tableau de Paris, vol. 1, 123, vol. 5 (1783) 28. 8 “Variétés,” Journal de Paris 6 Oct. 1785: 1150. 9 Nicolas de La Mare, Traité de la Police, vol. 1 (Paris: Jean and Pierre Cot, 1705) 200. 10 La Police de Paris en 1770, mémoire inédit composé par ordre de G. de Sartine (Paris, 1879) 70. 11 On eighteenth-century Paris, see Daniel Roche, The People of Paris. An Essay in Popular Culture in the 18th Century (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1987); Arlette Farge, Vivre dans la rue à Paris au XVIIIe siècle (Paris: Gallimard, 1979) and Effusion et tourment, le récit des corps. Histoire du peuple au XVIIIe siècle (Paris: Odile Jacob, 2007).

“You Do Not Even Know Where You Are”

77

In this city seemingly attached to its unruliness, spectacles cropped up in the 1770s and the 1780s, some of which at least appeared to propose models of order or, at any rate, to raise the issue of order – the order of the world, the order of society. For the sake of clarity, I roughly categorize these new spectacles into three groups: spectacles that raised the issue of movement and life, spectacles that raised the question of identity, and spectacles that addressed the position of subjects in the world and their relation to truth. In the 1780s, a new spectacle boasted its display of order and regulation: the circus. It would only become known under this name in France twenty years or so later. In a kind of anticipation, a correspondent wrote a letter to the Journal de Paris in 1781 to denounce the “ferocious spectacle”12 of animal fights, an “Algonquin tragedy,”13 and called for “the training of the most intelligent animals” and their presentation in “a workshop, a circus.”14 “The people will flock to it,” he added.15 The following year, in 1782, Philip Astley set up his Manège anglais for a month on the Rue du Faubourg du Temple, where he presented a horseriding and acrobatics show lauded for its boldness and precision. After a brilliant military career, Astley had opened an equestrian establishment in London in 1768. The place featured a ring; it accommodated spectacles and served as a riding school.16 The association of the spectacular, the military and the educational was a recurring trait of the circus throughout the nineteenth century. Other English riders had preceded Astley in Paris, but the exercises he introduced were still considered as belonging to a “new genre of spectacle in this Capital”17 and met with considerable success – so much so that in 1783 Astley opened a permanent establishment, an Amphithéâtre equipped with a ring surrounded and overlooked by the audience. Owing to the Revolution, Antonio Franconi moved into the place, founding a dynasty that dominated the circus in Paris during the first half of the nineteenth century at the helm of several successive establishments. These went by the name of Cirque olympique after 1806.

12 “Variétés,” Journal de Paris 19 Apr. 1781: 441. 13 “Variétés,” Journal de Paris 19 Apr. 1781: 441. 14 “Variétés,” Journal de Paris 19 Apr. 1781: 442. 15 “Variétés,” Journal de Paris 19 Apr. 1781: 442. 16 On the beginnings of the circus in London and Paris, see Caroline Hodak, “Du théâtre au cirque: une entreprise si éminemment nationale. Commercialisation des loisirs, diffusion des savoirs et théâtralisation de l’histoire en France et en Angleterre,” diss., EHESS, 2004. 17 “Manège Anglois,” Journal de Paris 1 Nov. 1783: 1257.

78 Patrick Désile

What did the spectacle of circus consist of during the first three or four decades of its existence? It should at once be mentioned that the circus was considered a theater in Paris, and that before long a stage was adjoined to the ring. A part of the show involved a theatrical performance. I have already touched on the military character of the circus: as a matter of fact, the plays often reproduced episodes from wars, and under the Empire they were sometimes directly inspired by the bulletins of the Grande Armée. However, the circus was above all a pure equestrian spectacle whose main purpose was to display the ascendancy of man over animal, the mastery by man of the movements of the animal body – through free dressage exercises with the ringmaster standing at the center of the ring, or haute école exercises exhibiting the absolute submission of the horse to the rider. The circus originated in the figure of the horse, which is central to it: the daily companion of man, immensely useful socially, the horse is the animal of movement, perfectly controllable for anyone with the proper skills, but it may also prove stubborn as well as powerful and skittish, liable at any moment to rear up, bolt, become uncontrollable again. The presentation of wild animals that are further removed from man may be an even better illustration of the project of dominating animal life and channeling its instinctive movements: these animals were trained to adopt behavior that was the opposite of that supposedly dictated by nature. Thus the stag, a fearful animal par excellence, would remain impassive as gunshots were fired close by;18 and the massive, frightening elephant would delicately stroke the cheek of an infant, then play music and dance.19 Still, the intent was not just to show the control of man over beast, but also the control of man over himself, the mastery he may acquire over his own body and his fear when performing acrobatic exercises. The comics themselves were riders and acrobats who amused mainly through the incongruity of their physical prowess. Yet the bird-man could fall and the performing animal become fierce again: the circus was the spectacle of the – always precarious – mastery over movement and life. Other spectacles contemporary with the emergence of the circus focused on movement and its mastery, but quite differently: scientific or parascientific spectacles presenting phenomena tied to electricity, an object of fascination in the last decades of the eighteenth century. Demonstrations 18 See Mme B**, née de V**, Les Animaux savants ou Exercices des chevaux de MM. Franconi, du cerf Coco, du cerf Azor, de l’éléphant Baba, des serins hollandois, du singe militaire… (Paris: Didot l’aîné, 1816) 47. 19 Mme B**, née de V**, Les Animaux savants 49-53.

“You Do Not Even Know Where You Are”

79

were made in courses in experimental physics, which were really spectacles, as well as on the Boulevard du Temple. Thus “doctor” Comus, whose real name was Nicolas Philippe Ledru (“a street charlatan,”20 according to Diderot), presented a spectacle he claimed was scientific in the 1770s and 1780s. The show featured “electric experiences” and therapeutic sessions through electricity, which soon became the main attraction. The Journal de Paris regularly reported on them; in 1784, for instance, it expounded Comus’s “theory,” a synthesis of sorts of ordinary discourses on electricity tinged with mesmerism, but presented as completely idiosyncratic. This Physicist rejects most existing [theories] and instead allows of a universal fluid, the soul of the world and the principle of all movement. […] This fluid produces all electric phenomena; it occupies the space and the interstices of all created bodies. The perfection of living beings results from the equal distribution of this fluid in their constituent parts. Its uneven distribution causes acute or chronic diseases in the animal kingdom. Spread in the expanse of humors, it circulates with them; if it meets with resistance through some kind of disturbance in the organization, then the liquids, left to themselves and deprived of the movement whose soul is this fluid, form engorgements.21

Armed with this theory, Comus treated patients, mainly epileptics and paralytics. Indeed, these cases presented the highest chances that a treatment would prove effective, by his account and those of other demonstrators.22 The goal was in effect to reestablish through electricity the fluidity and regularity of the universal movement there where it was being upset or held up. Upholding his thesis of “the Analogy of Electricity with the nervous fluid,”23 Comus also operated on dead bodies, to which he restored a fleeting appearance of life – this before Galvani’s works were published and the experiences of galvanism in turn appeared in the program of spectacles such as Robertson’s.

20 Denis Diderot, letter to Sophie Volland, 28 July 1762, Correspondance II, in Œuvres complètes, vol. 19 (Paris: Garnier frères, 1875-1877) 83. 21 “Médecine,” Journal de Paris 22 Jan. 1784: 97. 22 Father Sans thus announced in 1784 that from then on he would treat “only two types of diseases, Paralysis and Convulsions” in his Versailles “electric practice.” “Médecine,” Journal de Paris 17 Nov. 1784: 1349-50. 23 “Physique,” Journal de Paris 9 May 1782: 514.

80 Patrick Désile

Movement is therefore at stake here once again: the movement of life carried along by the universal movement, its pauses, its disorders, but also its resumptions, factors of a possible régénération – then a new word, at least in its general meaning,24 and a recurring theme over the period. Still other spectacles raised the issue of movement, in a sense, but in a very different manner: the “fleeting tableaux” or “paintings set in motion.”25 At a given moment in a dramatic action, all the characters would freeze and imitate a famous painting: in 1761, for instance, in Carlin’s Les Noces d’Arlequin, characters composed Greuze’s L’Accordée de village, the sensation of the previous Salon. A fashionable salon entertainment as well, fleeting tableaux may be compared to the “attitudes” of Lady Hamilton and her epigones, which consisted in striking consecutive poses inspired from Antiquity, notably figures on vases.26 These spectacles of frozen, sometimes merely suspended movement, of immobilization more than immobility, question representation and its ambiguities as much as movement and life. Often, the spectacles that arguably raised the issue of identity also involved the suspension of movement, and always had some form of relation to death. For the first that I will evoke, the connection could not be more obvious. Even as contemporaries often referred to it as a spectacle, it is anything but frivolous: the guillotine is the spectacle of death par excellence. In 1792 the never-ending spectacle of suffering and of life running out, during which “the people looked at the dial of city hall and counted the hours being struck,”27 gave way to the spectacle of sudden death. Striking acts of torture may have been replaced by incarceration, but also by the instantaneous suppression of lives. An instant, as decisive as it may be, does not make a spectacle, which explains why the ritual then instituted was preceded by a preliminary phase and followed by a conclusive one, as Daniel Arasse once made evident.28 First, the condemned would follow the route from the jail to the scaffold along which the crowd gathered, some breaking into a “guillotine song,” others dancing, still others laughing. The condemned would then mount the scaffold and the execution, the moment of death would come, a temporal 24 See Léonard Snetlage, Nouveau Dictionnaire français (Gottingen: Jean Chrêtien Dieterich, 1795) 183. 25 See Bernard Vouilloux, “Le tableau vivant, un genre ambigu,” 48-14, La Revue du musée d’Orsay 11 (Fall 2000). 26 See Kirsten Gram Holmström, Monodrama, Attitudes, tableaux vivants. Studies on Some Trends of Theatrical Fashion, 1770-1815 (Stockholm: Almqvist och Wiksell, 1967). 27 Mercier, Tableau de Paris, vol. 3 (1782) 269. 28 Daniel Arasse, The Guillotine and the Terror (New York, London: Penguin, 1991).

“You Do Not Even Know Where You Are”

81

point almost invisible. Yet this passage without duration from life to death was unsettling on several accounts. In the 1780s the Journal de Paris reported one case after another of apparent deaths and resurrections, notably after asphyxiation or drowning. The Encyclopédie describes death as a process slow enough that someone might come round from it and, like the Journal de Paris, mentions cases of premature inhumations. This was one of the time’s great anxieties, and the figure of the individual buried alive, scraping the dark, narrow coffin where she or he lay dying served as the antithesis to the individual of the Enlightenment, yearning for clarity, transparency and circulation. There was such a thing as an uncertain death, then, a death that could be cured: a partial death. In 1801 Bichat put forward the notion that bodies had two lives in them, animal and organic; while the former worked from without and was voluntary, the latter operated from within and was permanent. As it happened, “the organic life to a certain point may subsist, the animal life being extinct.”29 Life and death, in the end, were not a matter of all or nothing. As a consequence, there were legitimate grounds for asking whether the guillotined person was absolutely killed on the instant or whether the severed head might still feel for some time, with the subject happening to know the unknowable as a witness of his or her own death. There was talk of heads continuing to speak or Charlotte Corday’s face blushing. The spectacle of the guillotine was thus a singularly troubling one, as instant death substituted for or overlapped with the process of ordinary death, which was stretched in time. Finally, the third phase of the spectacle, the headsman holding up the severed head dripping with blood, was the subject of many engravings. The spectacle of the guillotine was therefore not only the spectacle of death, but also the spectacle of the head, separated from the body and bearing the most individual traits. The spectacle of death as the end of the individual also proved to be the spectacle of his/her identity, represented by his/her head. Other, less dreadful spectacles may be viewed as spectacles of identity without being completely extraneous to the theme of death. A play titled L’Heureuse Pêche, whose manuscript is dated 1767, was presented as a “comedy for shadows with changing scenes.”30 In the preface, its anonymous 29 Xavier Bichat, Physiological Researches on Life and Death (Boston: Richardson and Lord, 1827) 175. 30 L’Heureuse Pêche, comédie pour les ombres à scènes changeantes (1767), Rondel RO théâtre d’ombres, BnF (French national library).

82 Patrick Désile

author introduces the genre as “new in Paris”31; it consisted in having the actors perform between a lighting source and a white screen and assumed that the spectator “[would go] along with the illusion of seeing only Shadows, acting, behaving, and pursuing interests just like men.”32 Indeed, the simple operation – correlating shadow and man – was not immediately self-evident. That was a new game, which rested on the representation of people through what was not them, their absence, their shadow – a shadow whose immateriality and ductility also made magical effects of deformation, apparition and disappearance possible in the theater. These shadows with changing scenes offered a spectacle of identity, with the uncertainties tied to it and the uncertainties of representation. Death still loomed: shadows are a negation of the individual as much as they are its trace, and in the eighteenth century the expression “the shadows” referred more or less to the shadows of death. The genre was short-lived – despite Grimm who, in a letter dated August 1770, called for “a complete theater of such plays”33 sooner than later. Experiments with shadows developed in other directions. On the one hand, a shadow theater called “ombres chinoises” and addressed at children appeared. On the other hand, the interrogation on identity intensified with the reviviscence of the myth of Rebutades, which questioned the origin of representation; the vogue of silhouettes; and Lavater’s new physiognomy, in which the precise and faithful shadow of the profile became a projection of the most intimate part of the individual, a revelation in just a few lines of the authentic self hidden away beneath the social mask. In all these cases, attention was concentrated on the head, skull and face. The dispositive presented by Lavater to delineate the profile of faces (and make the individual transparent, in a way) was not without analogy to the physiognotrace, which did away with the shadow and focused solely on the lines of the profile. The physiognotrace was praised for the absence of human intervention in the process of representation: in that respect, it was the counterpart of the guillotine, whose quality as a machine guaranteed neutrality. And in a sense, both were machines designed to produce sincere portraits, whether the mask was removed by means of lines or by means of

31 L’Heureuse Pêche 3. 32 L’Heureuse Pêche 4. 33 Friedrich Melchior Grimm, Correspondance littéraire, philosophique et critique, 1753-1773, vol. 9 (Paris: Garnier frères, 1877) 110.

“You Do Not Even Know Where You Are”

83

death.34 In fact, parallels may be drawn between physiognotrace portraits and the portraits of guillotined individuals already mentioned. These practices also call to mind those of ceroplastic techniques, which were ancient but took a new turn at the end of the eighteenth century, as they gave rise to a form of spectacle. Wax effigies, whether or not their realization involved taking a cast (of the face, for instance), were meant to be not only lifelike portraits, but also accurate reproductions. Since Julius von Schlosser,35 it has been a well-known fact that the wax portrait has a long tradition linked to funeral practices of representing the deceased. According to Mercier, in the 1770s and the 1780s “kings, great writers, pretty women and famous thieves”36 could be admired in Curtius’s wax figure cabinet. Indeed, Curtius exhibited portraits of remarkable individuals, including criminals, to everyone’s eye. During the Revolution, his niece (or natural daughter), the future madame Tussaud, constituted a series of portraits of guillotined individuals by taking casts of the faces. In 1800 casts were also taken of the faces of the members (or “chauffeurs”) of the Orgères gang after their execution. Collections of heads of unconventional individuals were started. Other wax figure cabinets, leaving aside the exterior aspect of the body, exhibited the inside; wax anatomical models, a sort of counterpart to automatons, contributed to the emergence of a new sense of the body as a mysterious place of life. A last, blunt spectacle of identity, one that was also the spectacle of death, was the Morgue, since it responded to the concern for identifying individuals through the display of their corpse.37 The Morgue existed in the Ancien Régime, but in the 1780s objections had been raised to its location, a former underground prison whose small size and darkness did not allow a distinct view of the dead. During the Revolution, projects were launched, but the new Morgue did not open until 1804. Naked corpses were exhibited to everyone behind a glass pane, with zenithal lighting. For the authorities, the objective was clearly to put a name on a body and avoid abandoning any individual to the obscurity of anonymity, even after death. Yet this was also a spectacle, often referred to as such. 34 On physiognomy, the physiognotrace and transparency, see Antoine de Baecque, The Body Politic. Corporeal Metaphors in Revolutionary France (1770-1800) (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1993). 35 Julius von Schlosser, History of Portraiture in Wax [1911], in Ephemeral Bodies. Wax Sculpture and the Human Figure, ed. Roberta Panzanelli (Los Angeles: Getty Research Institute, 2008). 36 Mercier, Tableau de Paris, vol. 3, 42. 37 On the Morgue, see Bruno Bertherat, “La Morgue à Paris au XIXe siècle (1804-1907). Les Origines de l›Institut médico-légal ou Les métamorphoses de la machine,” diss., Université de Paris 1, 2003.

84 Patrick Désile

Fig. 1. To restore through electricity the universal fluidity… (Abbé Sans, Guérison de la paralysie par l’électricité, ou Cette expérience physique employée avec succès dans le traitement de cette maladie… , Paris, Cailleau, 1772).

I have said that other spectacles did in a sense raise the question of truth: they did so by contrasting it with illusion. Towards the mid-eighteenth century, conjurers became physicists. The Paysan de la Noort-Holland, and more importantly Pinetti a little later, resurrected birds and made trees blossom: palingenesis was one of the favorite themes of these demonstrations. Physicists sometimes also showed automatons, which raised the question of the secret of life as much as they illustrated the theme of the mastery of movement.

“You Do Not Even Know Where You Are”

85

Fig. 2. Enthusiasm at last, seeing everything, dominating everything… (Balloon ascending the Tuileries, 1784: To lovers of physic, Bibliothèque nationale de France).

In 1784 Decremps published La Magie blanche dévoilée:38 from then on, it essentially became a matter of setting the record straight. Robertson, who pretended to conjure up specters and bring the dead back to life, belonged to this trend. Yet a new anxiety then appeared: These ghosts created on demand, which can move, these false appearances amuse the common herd and make the philosopher dream. What is the specter of the mirror, or in the mirror? Does it exist, or not? What a prodigious subtlety of colored rays! What an amazing intermediary between the matter we feel and the spirit we cannot touch!39

Even though in both cases the point was to create an illusion, it may be argued that the panorama contrasts with the phantasmagoria: both appeared at about the same time in Paris, but while the former relied on a perfect image of the real, tangible world, the latter invoked imaginings and ghosts. The panorama pertained to new relations between the subject and the perceived world, with the dominating subject assuming an omniscient look. Aerostatic flights thus elicited enthusiastic and proud descriptions on 38 Henri Decremps, La Magie blanche dévoilée (Paris: Langlois, 1784-1785). 39 “Fantasmagorie,” in Louis Sébastien Mercier, Néologie, ou vocabulaire de mots nouveaux (Paris: 1801) 259.

86 Patrick Désile

the part of aeronauts: “It seemed as though I held sway over everything,”40 Lallemand de Sainte-Croix declared after his September 1791 flight. However, what the subject dominated was but an autonomous world from which she or he might just as well have been absent. Saint-Preux, describing the “theater” of the Alps with rapture, ended up disappearing, dissolving in it: “the spectacle has something indescribably magical, supernatural about it that ravishes the spirit and the senses; you forget everything, even yourself, and do not even know where you are.”41 The spectator of the panorama was, in a certain way, both imperial and evanescent. The circle of the panorama leads back to the circle of the circus. While the gaze of the spectators converges towards the ring where, under the eyes of the master, horses move around in an orderly manner, in the panorama, the eyes of the – potentially lonely – spectator, who performs a circular movement, scan the still representation of a section of the world. The play with circles and the gaze are reminders of the prominent place of the figure of the circle in the last decades of the eighteenth century; it also points to the omnipresence of the figure of the eye, and the associations between the circle and the eye in Bentham’s panopticism and in other places are well-known. The circle is the perfect figure in that it is the most simple, the least false, the most natural; a figure of equality and serenity, of unimpeded circulation, of the universal movement of stars, of harmony. “Everything is a circle in nature,”42 Claude-Nicolas Ledoux wrote, citing the concentric circles made by stones falling into water, satellites, planets… As for the eye, itself a globe, it stands at the centre of circles and spheres drawn by the looks it casts. In revolutionary iconography, it was notably the eye of radiating reason, but also that of surveillance. “I have a thousand eyes, a thousand openings, a thousand telescopes,”43 the first issue of Rougyff ’s journal read. Rougyff, an alias for Armand-Benoît-Joseph Guffroy, depicted himself as a sentinel ever on the alert. I suspend my description at this point without bringing it to a close. As succinct and incomplete as it may be, it should allow us to begin answering the

40 Lallemand de Sainte-Croix, Procès-verbal très intéressant du voyage aérien qui a eu lieu aux Champs-Élysées le 18 septembre 1791, jour de la proclamation de la Constitution (Paris, 1791) 5. 41 Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Julie, or the New Heloise. Letters of Two Lovers Who Live in a Small Town at the Foot of the Alps [1761], Philip Stewart and Jean Vaché, trans. and ed. (Lebanon, N. H.: Dartmouth College Press, University Press of New England, 1997) 65. 42 Claude-Nicolas Ledoux, L’Architecture considérée sous le rapport de l’art, des moeurs et de la législation, vol. 1 (Paris: 1804) 223. 43 Rougyff, ou le Frank en vedette 1 (July 1793).

“You Do Not Even Know Where You Are”

87

question of whether these spectacular dispositives, between which multiple relations become apparent, form a dispositif in Michel Foucault’s sense. A well-known definition from the interview “The Confession of the Flesh” is an unavoidable reference here: What I’m trying to pick out with this term is, firstly, a thoroughly heterogeneous ensemble consisting of discourses, institutions, architectural forms, regulatory decisions, laws, administrative measures, scientific statements, philosophical, moral and philanthropic propositions – in short, the said as much as the unsaid. Such are the elements of the apparatus. The apparatus itself is the system of relations that can be established between these elements. 44

The almost automatic recurrence of a definition as though set in stone may surprise, on several grounds. Still, there is good reason to believe that it retains something of the moment and circumstances of its utterance. If any reminder is necessary, the definition is a citation from an interview, and a particular one at that, since Michel Foucault was confronted by psychoanalysts about his singular, short, thought-provoking book, The Will to Knowledge, which was certainly not likely to have appealed to them. In a way, the definition was the prelude to a battle. Besides, this “firstly” is followed by a more rarely quoted “secondly” (on the instability of the relations between the elements of the dispositif), and “thirdly” (on the fact that a dispositif responds to an “urgent need” and has “a dominant strategic function”). The long interview allows Michel Foucault to clarify further the primary definition as well as indicate the paths it opens and the questions it raises. And evidently, other pieces of his work, The Will to Knowledge first and foremost, should also be used in working towards a finer, more complete definition of the concept. Assuming this to be the case, I am still going to rely on this now somewhat canonical definition to try and answer the question of whether the set of spectacles I have described may be considered as a dispositif. First, it undoubtedly meets the primary condition: it is obviously a heterogeneous whole. The way these spectacles operate does suppose scientific discourses and statements, as has already been glimpsed; it draws on philosophical, moral, or philanthropic propositions, it is the subject of official reports, it is controlled through regulatory decisions and supported by institutions, and for the most part it assumes – sometimes essential – architectural arrangements. 44 “The Confession of the Flesh” (1977), in Power/Knowledge. Selected Interviews and Other Writings, ed. Colin Gordon (Brighton: The Harvester Press, 1980) 194.

88 Patrick Désile

Nevertheless, this could be argued to be a sort of loose conglomeration more than a dispositif. Indeed, does this whole have a “dominant strategic function”? Something akin to a project may certainly be uncovered. These new spectacles were not simply given: their public could not just come across them, as they assumed a voluntary step and often the appropriation of an explanatory discourse. In that sense, they may be called modern, contributing as they did to educating spectators, altering their outlook on the world, the body, themselves, and thereby also sharing in the constitution of the modern spectator – of the modern subject, even. In fact, the pedagogical and political concern was explicit in the discourse of promoters or commentators for most of the spectacles I have evoked, even as they aimed to be recreational. I have mentioned that the Cirque olympique presented itself as a model of order and went as far as to propagandize for the Empire. Yet the regulatory project of the circus was not incidental: it was foundational. One of the first books devoted to the circus, Les Animaux savants, thus read: If we have succeeded in imparting to children an idea of perseverance, of the repeated efforts necessary to turn naturally distrustful and wild creatures into affectionate and docile ones, we have gotten them to sense, even approximately, both the price of their own education and the just tribute they should pay to their schoolteachers throughout their life. 45

Farther on, the spectacle of riders jumping and juggling is said to “constitute the best explanation of the Copernican system.”46 What is at stake here is the order of society and the order of the world. Similarly, as we have seen, demonstrations of electricity did not only have therapeutic or orthopedic qualities: they also had symbolic power. The neologism électriser (“to electrify”) entered political vocabulary47 and it is worth remembering Benjamin Franklin’s immense fame in France, equal to that of Voltaire or Rousseau. In a well-known formula variously ascribed to Turgot and d’Alembert, “Eripuit coelo fulmen sceptrumque tirannis,” “he seized lightning from the heavens and the scepter from tyrants,” an obvious allusion to his dual role in science and politics. Aerostatic spectacles also had an explicit political dimension. Lallemand de Sainte-Croix, from whom I have already quoted a few words, took off to great 45 Mme B**, née de V**, Les Animaux savants V. 46 Mme B**, née de V**, Les Animaux savants 35. 47 Snetlage, Nouveau Dictionnaire français 78.

“You Do Not Even Know Where You Are”

89

cheering from “a huge crowd”48 with the 1791 Constitution in hand, the very day it was proclaimed. There, again, the event actualized a general project. This project, characterized in a few words and in a necessarily incomplete, crude, and in fact provisional manner, could be said to consist in giving the spectator the spectacle of himself or herself, his/her situation or limitations. A free and sovereign subject, capable of surveying everything with a dominating look, of telling truth from falsehood, of taming the forces of nature, s/he also became an isolated individual from then on (“isoler quelqu’un,” “to isolate someone,” or “s’isoler,” “to isolate oneself,” were new expressions at the time49), held to human nature (s/he is neither a machine nor an animal), assigned to an obscure body, susceptible to the order of the world and participating in the great universal movement whose flow s/he should not hamper, bounded on all sides, marked by his/her identity even beyond death, and compelled by the countless gazes of others. Such would be, in the first analysis, the project of the dispositif relative to the spectacles I have begun to describe. Talking of a “strategy” does seem relevant in this case, since what is involved is one of “the great anonymous, almost unspoken strategies,”50 “for which it is no longer possible to identify a person who conceived it.”51 The fact remains that a dispositif, as it appears notably in the examples given by Michel Foucault, seems to present a rather strong unity. The point is, at least initially, to obtain a given effect through given means – preventing the mobility of workers through the implementation of a number of techniques, for instance.52 And yet the ensemble I have described is fragmented, scattered; the project assigned to it remains very general and does not preclude internal tensions. It would of course be possible to identify several dispositifs in it, each of which would then be easier to characterize and would have its own coherence: the circus, the panorama, the guillotine or the Morgue thus admittedly constitute full-fledged dispositifs, and one could investigate how they are articulated and perhaps mesh with one another. However, this would clearly leave many more isolated, more ordinary spectacles unexamined and would amount to ignoring a complexity that appears only if researchers agree to consider the vast numbers of spectacles and the vast numbers of their relations.

48 Lallemand de Sainte-Croix, Procès verbal très intéressant 4. 49 Snetlage, Nouveau Dictionnaire français 119. 50 Michel Foucault, The History of Sexuality, vol. 1, An Introduction (New York: Vintage, 1990) 95. 51 Foucault, “The Confession of the Flesh,” Power/Knowledge 203. 52 Foucault, “The Confession of the Flesh,” Power/Knowledge 203.

90 Patrick Désile

As it happens, the very nature of this kind of network excludes restricting it to the coherence of a strategy. It constitutes a necessarily open object of inf inite complexity. Innumerable other elements could incorporate themselves in the object I have set out to outline: theaters, celebrations, pleasure gardens, to mention but recreational spectacles… It would therefore be misleading to approach the dispositive as a kind of closed system: while it probably shows some consistency, the dispositive is a network, and notions of closure, circumscription and even unity would be associated with it only at the risk of misinterpretation. Deleuzian definitions of Foucault’s dispositif insist on this point: But what is a dispositif ? In the first instance it is a tangle, a multilinear ensemble. It is composed of lines, each having a different nature. And the lines in the apparatus do not outline or surround systems which are each homogeneous in their own right, object, subject, language, and so on, but follow directions, trace balances which are always off balance, now drawing together and then distancing themselves from one another.53

Bernard Vouilloux recently adopted the same perspective. Pointing out that “not only is the dispositif a network, but dispositifs are themselves also networked together,”54 he advanced that “the image accounting the best for this network of networks […] is that of the rhizome.”55 The network I have set out to describe, if the absence of closure does not disqualify it and if it may be said to be oriented by a strategy, may thus still be considered as a dispositif. Yet Michel Foucault insists on the fact that the dispositif assumes “a coherent, rational strategy,”56 if an anonymous one. And while recreational spectacles are the object of a restrictive institutional framework, while their existence depends on authorizations and their genre may be predetermined, while they may be subject to censorship, while they are narrowly 53 Gilles Deleuze, “What Is a dispositif ?” in Michel Foucault Philosopher, trans. Timothy J. Armstrong (New York: Routledge, 1991) 159. Available online at http://www.scribd.com/doc/44431489/ Deleuze-What-is-a-Dispositif as of February 9, 2011. Translator’s note: “which are homogeneous in their own right” should be understood in the conditional (“supposedly homogeneous”). Also, “…trace balances” is very likely a typographical error and should read as “…trace processes.” Finally, while the translator of Deleuze’s text starts with the word dispositif and goes on to use “apparatus,” both words do refer to the same word, “dispositif,” in French. 54 Bernard Vouilloux, “La critique des dispositifs,” Critique 718, “Pensée du style, style de pensée” (March 2007): 165. 55 Vouilloux, “La critique des dispositifs”: 165. 56 Foucault, “The Confession of the Flesh,” Power/Knowledge 203.

“You Do Not Even Know Where You Are”

91

monitored and heavily taxed, their content may not be said to result from coherent, rational decisions, nor may their effects be taken as premeditated, particularly with regard to the – mostly – spectacles of curiosity dealt with here. And while institutions such as the guillotine or the Morgue were all the more strictly controlled and the decisions involving them presented as coherent and rational, it is obvious to everyone how obscure and uncertain were both their operation as a spectacle and the craze they gave rise to. Spectacles are not the hospital, the barracks, the school, the prison or the factory, and while they count normalization as one of their effects, this is not due to any coercion they might exercise directly over bodies. They attract without forcing, they please and, at least for recreational spectacles, they have to appeal if they are to survive. Contractors do not seek to bring spectators into subjection but to allure them. In a way, spectators do make the spectacle, grabbing the mirror held out to them, but their motivations, like those of promoters, are largely irrational. If I sought to explain a project earlier, it was not without some artifice, for all this remains not only implicit but also mysterious. Spectators make the spectacle, and their steps lead them not only towards what entertains or instructs, but towards what troubles and disorients as well. The circus was without a doubt a spectacle of order, but it was an insecure order: it was also a spectacle of danger, of the danger of death, and it showed the ascendancy of man over animal only by humanizing the animal and blurring the limits of the species. The demonstrations of electricity presented something about which almost nothing was known, save for the fearsome power observed by all, and to which cripples and children were still subjected. The spectacles of physicists claimed to bring out the truth through the play of fascinating deceptions. And what to say of the sublime spectacle of the guillotine, which gave rise to the impossible thought of a being both alive and dead; or of the murky spectacle of the Morgue, which brought wrecked, naked, nameless bodies back into a blunt light? Even the clear spectacle of the panorama initially created confusion, a perceptual indecision, and an almost physical malaise, as noted in 1800 in the report of the Institut national des sciences et des arts: “The first impression upon entering a Panorama is that of a vast but confused view, all of whose points present themselves to the dazzled eye at once and in no order…”57 Does the necessity of allowing this obscure and ambiguous dimension to play out still make it possible to speak of a dispositif in relation to the 57 Rapport fait à l’Institut national des sciences et des arts sur l’origine, les effets et les progrès du panorama, 28 fructidor an VIII (15 Sept. 1800) 5.

92 Patrick Désile

Fig. 3. The EYE of reason, the EYE of surveillance (engraving, 1793-1795, de Vinck collection, Bibliothèque nationale de France).

network of spectacles I have begun to describe here? There again, recent reconsiderations of the concept, widening its definition, may help free any thinking from contingent rigidities. Further expanding the already large class of Foucauldian apparatuses, I shall call an apparatus literally anything that has in some way the capacity to capture, orient, determine, intercept, model, control, or secure the gestures, behaviors, opinions, or discourses of living beings.58

This very clean definition, which preserves the essential but prejudges as little as possible, does seem to allow us to think of the ensemble I have described as a dispositif – without obscuring its specific traits, but by considering it as a proliferating network, never completed, shot through by enigmatic desires. Still, a question remains. The modern spectator issued from anxiety, doubt and uncertainty about the world and the self. From dizziness – a physical dizziness brought by heights, infinite space, indefinite perceptions; but a dizziness that may just as well be called existential when so many limits have become indeterminate. Accordingly, how may the concept of dispositif do justice to such dizziness, which has something inaugural, foundational even, to it and which may in many respects still be our own?

58 Giorgio Agamben, What Is an Apparatus? (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2009) 14.



Marey and the Synthesis of Movement The Reconstruction of a Concept Maria Tortajada

“Cinema is the moving image”: the idea, which has become a commonplace, coalesced around 1900 as photography was being referred to as the still image. The opposition between photography and cinema made it possible throughout the twentieth century, and to this day, to assign distinct tasks in the representation of reality to each of these emblematic dispositives of modernity. Still, the association still/moving also structured the cinematographic dispositive as such as early as the late nineteenth century. Indeed, photography was not the other of cinema at the time, but a means used by “cinema” in its chronophotographic stage to reconstitute movement: the moving image was the result of a preliminary decomposition of the movement of a moving object or body into a series of instantaneous photographs. Chronophotography – most particularly in its scientific inception, which Etienne-Jules Marey contributed through his work – established the regularity of intervals between frames as the condition of possibility for the synthesis of movement. This technical characteristic revealed two visions of cinema throughout the twentieth century: on the one hand, the insistence on the centrality of the f ilm frame, scansion, decomposition; on the other hand, the idea of a cinema wholly defined by the continuous flow of movement whose projection produces the illusion or reconstitution. Roland Barthes, an advocate of the f ilm frame, may in that respect be opposed to André Bazin, who structured his “ontology of cinema” through the division between the two media along the question of the reproduction of movement, precisely. Gilles Deleuze also emphasized the continuous flow with what he called the “movement-image,” that is, the expression of Bergsonian duration in its capacity for change. While the apology of continuity was dominant in the film production as well as the theorization of film of the second half of the twentieth century, the idea of cinema still remained structured by the new, underlying opposition between synthesis and decomposition – irreducibly so, it seemed. The synthesized image was thus conceived through the repression of the part played by the film frame in decomposition or the explanation of its own construction as image: either way, this synthesized image was indebted to the film frame and was opposed to

94 

Maria Tortajada

it. However, the discontinuity inherent in cinema was not always limited to the series of film frames. Discontinuity may be thought of differently, as Marey’s work related to chronophotography shows. This leads us to reevaluate the status of the synthesis of movement at the turn of the twentieth century. Synthesis as a notion def ines cinema, but one should ask on which conditions. Does reconstituted movement refer to the continuity and flow produced by the illusion of movement, as most often heard these days in “the idea of the cinematographic”? Or could synthesis be thought of differently? This is what was at stake in Marey’s work at the exact moment when the very possibility of cinema was forming technically and conceptually.

The Virtues of the Synthesis of Movement Marey was both the historian of chronophotography and the scientist who promoted it to the rank of a method for the decomposition and analysis of movement. Marey’s images are famous; his chronophotographs document different modes of human or animal locomotion: walking, running, leaping, flapping wings or fins, and so forth. They present series of frames recorded on a fixed plate or on a mobile strip of film. These images firmly anchor Marey in the history of photography, but he also belongs in the history of cinema. Marey’s interest in the synthesis of movement is occasionally played down on the grounds that he did not achieve the technical solution making it possible to realize what he had imposed on a theoretical level: the equidistance of frames, the condition of possibility for the reconstitution of movement. The solution chosen was Lumière’s, for it ensured the regularity of the film’s run and the intermittent stop of frames in front of the lens. Lumière opted for the claws to feed the perforated film and the eccentric triangular cam, a piece that made it possible to transform a continuous movement into a discontinuous one. This argumentation, revolving as it does around technique alone, is perfectly suited for a conventional, genealogical history of cinema justifying the date of the “origin,” 1895. While noting the technical peculiarities of Marey’s appliances, Laurent Mannoni insists for his part on the importance of Marey’s “film work.” Against the hegemony of the Lumières, he argues in favor of a rehabilitation of the scientist as a “filmmaker” in the history of cinema. The importance of the synthesis of movement is thus vindicated through the number of

Marey and the Synthesis of Movement

95

films made as well as their aesthetic value.1 Since the beginning of this century, the issue of the synthesis of movement has clearly been at stake in the debate on “the invention of cinema,” in which symbolic values in the constitution of a history of the medium play out. From the moment it appeared as the defining element of cinema, “the moving image” has been a privileged site for argumentation, either in the competitive game for the title of “inventor of cinema,” or at the center of a reflection problematizing the issue of a “single” birth to advocate a progressive and collective process of technical invention – an idea conveyed through the emphasis of various “pioneers” of technical innovation, for instance.2 Starting from an epistemological concern, Michel Frizot argues differently to dispute the classic narrative of the “birth” of cinema. This leads him to play down the importance of the synthesis of movement in Marey’s work: chronophotography is primarily a method for the analysis of movement and does not have as its aim to produce a moving image.3 The synthesis, Frizot explains, is a part of the scientific method and only a control procedure: Marey analyzed movement by breaking it down before checking the result by synthesizing it. The reversibility of appliances was a guarantee for scientific validation. François Dagognet had previously defended the same position. 4 Within this logic, synthesis is not a finality.5 Marey’s very 1 See Laurent Mannoni’s reference work, Etienne-Jules Marey. La mémoire de l’œil (Milan, Paris: Mazzotta/La Cinémathèque française, 1999), as well as his The Great Art of Light and Shadow. Archaeology of the Cinema (Exeter: The University of Exeter Press, 2000), ch. 13, and “Marey cinéaste,” in E.-J. Marey. Actes du Colloque du centenaire, Dominique de Font-Réaulx, Thierry Lefebvre and Laurent Mannoni, eds. (Paris: Arcadia, 2006) 15-36. 2 In that respect, the title of the exhibition catalog of the Musée Marey in Beaune is significant: Marey, pionnier de la synthèse du mouvement (Beaune: Musée Marey, 1995). See more particularly Virgilio Tosi’s contribution, “Etienne-Jules Marey and the Origins of Cinema,” 13-20. The debates on “the invention” have been commented on several times. Again, I refer the reader to Laurent Mannoni’s previously mentioned work, but also to Michel Frizot’s exhibition catalog, E.-J. Marey: 1830/1904. La photographie du mouvement (Paris: Centre national d’art et de culture Georges Pompidou/Musée national d’art moderne, 1977) 87-90; and to Marta Braun, Picturing Time: The Work of Etienne-Jules Marey (Chicago, London: University of Chicago Press, 1992) 254-62. 3 Michel Frizot, Etienne-Jules Marey chronophotographe (Paris: Nathan/Delpire, 2001) 258. 4 Dagognet showed the originality of Marey’s approach, which is specific to the dispositive founding his experiences: “a sensitive sensor, a transmitter whose inertia is negligible, an inscription device adapted to sinuous writing, and a synthesizing device to be used for verification. There was a leitmotif in Marey’s work taken from Marcellin Berthelot, the synthetic chemist: we only have real knowledge of what we ourselves have reconstructed.” See François Dagognet, Etienne-Jules Marey. A Passion for the Trace, trans. Robert Galeta, with Jeanine Herman (New York: Zone Books, 1992) 56. 5 See Michel Frizot, “Les opérateurs physiques de Marey et la réversibilité cinématographique,” in Arrêt sur image/fragmentation du temps, François Albera, Marta Braun and André Gaudreault,

96 

Maria Tortajada

terms support this thesis since, well before chronophotography (in 1868), he defined the two “powerful levers in the service of the human mind”: “analysis, which is used for research, and synthesis, for the verification of the results of the analysis or for exposing more simply a discovered truth.”6 Marey defines synthesis in more detail in the following chapter: You already know that this is not a research method. You have seen that a science that would tend to be founded on synthesis, starting from principles established beforehand, would expose itself to much aberration. Yet it is no longer the case when the analysis has completed its work and has provided us with a great number of well-established facts. This is when the role of synthesis begins. Synthesis is the opposite of analysis; it reconstitutes what had been decomposed.7

The notion of verification should first be understood in relation to what precedes it, the establishment of concrete facts. The value of synthesis depends on the rejection of preconceived ideas devoid of analytical foundations. In no way should it be concluded that synthesis is secondary to analysis, for verification is also a validation. One only needs to follow Marey as he looks at chemistry and points out that Marcellin Berthelot proved “that, starting from inorganic elements detected by analysis in organized substances, one could reproduce through synthesis a very large number of substances found in vegetables.”8 The example of chemistry shows very concretely that synthesis could become the aim. Marey concluded that it was necessary to develop the amount of work devoted to the synthesis and creation of what he called schemas, that is, “demonstration appliances” eds. (Lausanne: Payot, 2002) 99-100. Concerning Marey, Frizot writes: “[…] synthesis is not one of his objectives. On the other hand, synthesis is the practical consequence of a Mareysian operator, the control over the method, and more precisely a reversible control that stipulates that, to control the good progression of an analysis, the procedure must be reverted in order to re-compose some parameters of the phenomenon out of the elements obtained in the analysis. Marey calls this procedure ‘experimental synthesis’ and, further on, he writes that ‘visual synthesis is only a control procedure’.” See also Frizot, Etienne-Jules Marey chronophotographe 110. Frizot reviews Marey’s practices from the standpoint of the issue of synthesis, including the synthesis of movement. 6 Etienne-Jules Marey, Du mouvement dans les fonctions de la vie. Leçon faite au Collège de France (Paris: Germer Baillère, 1868) 24. Michel Frizot quotes the passage. 7 Marey, Du mouvement dans les fonctions de la vie 40-41. 8 Marey, Du mouvement dans les fonctions de la vie 42. Berthelot writes: “From this we can see that, while it is true to say that analysis provides chemistry with its starting point, it does not mark its goal and its destination: chemistry is also the science of synthesis.” See Berthelot, La Synthèse chimique (Paris: Germer Baillière, 1876) 2.

Marey and the Synthesis of Movement

97

capable of proving a phenomenon.9 It comes as no surprise, then, that Dagognet would also claim without hesitation that the phase of synthesis, along with that of the sensitive capture of movement, is the most important of Mareysian dispositives: “Marey indeed considered work on synthesis, that is, artificial reproduction, to be as indispensable as that on analysis and data collection.”10 Control, validation and demonstration necessarily define synthesis in the method, but for all that, they do not invalidate the heuristic dimension of the synthetic experiment. When Marey exposed various examples drawn from physics and biology, it appeared that the “experimental synthesis,” as a demonstration, had as its function not only to verify, but also to understand what had not been understood, to grasp what the senses had not been able to perceive.11 Marey advocated the use of these schemas, genuine constructions meant to imitate, reproduce, simulate a physical or biological phenomenon.12 Synthesis should thus not be understood in a narrow sense: on the contrary, its importance within the scientific approach cannot be overstated, as validation procedures are involved in the production of knowledge. Why, then, do positionings become more complicated when the synthesis of movement is related to Marey’s place in film history? If Marey moved away from synthesis at the moment when he was close to finding the technical solution, it is, in both Dagognet’s and Frizot’s view, precisely because he rejected the imitation of natural vision, the illusion of movement produced by animated views in popular spectacles. Marey preferred to concentrate on the analysis of the decomposition of movement.13 Frizot’s and Dagognet’s entire work make it possible to integrate the technical question within an epistemological approach to Marey’s work. Their studies also show how vain a teleological vision of the history of cinema may be, with nineteenthcentury viewing dispositives leading to the cinematograph following a certain, if disavowed, finality – the illusion of movement.14 Still, they directly apply the argument of illusion, of an identical imitation of what our senses perceive, to the logic of spectacle. This unified conception of spectacle, at a moment when we are dealing with the history of cinema, makes it possible 9 Marey, Du mouvement dans les fonctions de la vie 65, 44. 10 Dagognet, Etienne-Jules Marey. A Passion for the Trace 54. 11 Marey, Du mouvement dans les fonctions de la vie 43-44. 12 Marey, Du mouvement dans les fonctions de la vie 44, 47-48. 13 “The fact is that he preferred analysis to synthesis; the latter rendered visible what had first been made invisible.” Dagognet, Etienne-Jules Marey. A Passion for the Trace 156. 14 See Dagognet, Etienne-Jules Marey. A Passion for the Trace 139-41.

98 

Maria Tortajada

to oppose the scientific position – allegedly defined by the preponderance of analysis – and the projection of animated views, where illusion would be the rule.15 In this context, the marginalization of synthesis dominates, even if chronophotography has otherwise been acknowledged as a wholly scientific method in Marey’s sense, one combining analysis and synthesis. Everything happens as though the mimetic illusion belonged exclusively to spectacle, as if spectacle was founded solely on illusion, or a certain kind of illusion. Everything happens as though questions of representation never reached the space of science. Yet even as part of a first approach, one cannot help but note that turning the illusion into the exclusive category of spectacle remains problematic. It is certainly partial to consider that any spectacle only relies on the illusion produced through the imitation of a real or imaginary phenomenon, as phantasmagoria could for instance claim to do. Dispositives of representation and their aims are much more complex and multiple as to their effects and contexts of use, whether scientific or belonging in the order of the spectacular. Isn’t scientific synthesis itself defined through simulation? Simulation requires an imitation of the analyzed model, reproducing exactly the significant parameters of the experiment. Rather than marginalize or relativize the synthesis of movement to counter the teleological postulate of the history of cinema, I would like to cast the issue in different terms and try to bring out what was playing out in the defense or the rejection of synthesis by Marey. The argument laid out above holds some truth, but it obscures a genuine problematization of the notion of movement from an epistemological standpoint. To understand what synthesis amounts to, it is necessary to clarify what is meant by illusion of movement and examine how the issue of spectacle is in turn affected. Initially, one can only agree with the argument justifying Marey’s rejection of synthesis through his own scientific approach, different from the projection of animated views. Marey himself said so much around 1900, either in the preface to Eugène Trutat’s La Photographie animée (1899) or in the text accompanying the exhibition of chronophotographic instruments he himself organized at the 1900 World Fair. In 1899 he even articulated very clearly the opposition between scientific chronophotography and the “charming illusions” of spectacles with “animated projections.”16 However, 15 It is also in this sense that Christian Pociello explains Marey’s position: if the scientist “rejects projection,” “it is for scientific reasons.” See Christian Pociello, La Science en mouvements. Etienne Marey et Georges Demenÿ (1870-1920) (Paris: PUF, 1999) 279. 16 “Préface,” in Eugène Trutat, La Photographie animée (Paris: Gauthier-Villars, 1899) V-VI.

Marey and the Synthesis of Movement

99

in the text written for the exhibition, Marey includes the machines that reconstitute movement in chronophotography and whose history he recounts: the Lumière cinematograph is put on a par with the instruments invented and perfected by Marey not only to decompose movement, but also to synthesize it.17 It should be pointed out that, as late as 1898, he was still working to improve chronophotographs with projection. The synthesis of movement is part of chronophotography, in which Marey, with his global approach, appears as a central figure. His position is thus ambiguous, to say the least, and that is precisely what needs to be clarified. In examining how the notion of reconstituted movement developed, Marey’s great texts on chronophotography prove particularly useful. 18 Indeed, they show how he inscribes his research in a finality, redefines his priorities, specifies the operating concepts and highlights the results that appear the most significant to him. In short, Marey introduces his own approach with some analytical distance, emphasizing what seems most important to him. And not only does it appear that, from the very beginning, the synthesis of movement was an integral part of his work on chronophotography, but also that Marey rarely explains the methodological function of control linked to synthesis.19 This is intriguing, since Marey was 17 The “Cinématographe de MM. Lumière, 1895,” n°12, comes after “Projecteur chronophotographique, 1893” (nº10) and the “Kinétoscope d’Edison, 1894” (nº11). The “Chronographe analyseur et projecteur; Marey, 1898” appears as nº16. See Étienne-Jules Marey, “Exposition d’instruments et d’images relatifs à l’histoire de la chronophotographie,” in Musée centennal de la classe 12 (photographie) à l’Exposition universelle internationale de 1900 à Paris, Métrophotographie et chronophotographie (Saint-Cloud: Belin, undated) 20-22. An English translation of the text appeared as “History of Chronophotography” in the Smithsonian Report for 1901 (Washington, DC: Government Printing Office, 1902) 326-28. Marey did not include any presentation of his 1896-97 analyzing-projecting chronophotograph, mentioned in Frizot, E.-J. Marey: 1830/1904. La photographie du mouvement 68. It should be noted that, strangely enough, the text presenting the exhibition does not have a nº13, as if there had been an “omission.” Number 13 does appear on the reference illustration (fig. 1 in Marey, Musée centennal; fig. 9 in “History of Chronophotography”) for strips presenting horse locomotion. Marey also mentions the previous use of the “electrically operated” zoetrope for the synthesis of movement in his own research and his intention to improve the results (that is, to shoot longer scenes). See Marey, “History of Chronophotography” 326. 18 Besides “Exposition d’instruments et d’images relatifs à l’histoire de la chronophotographie,” translated as “History of Chronophotography,” already cited, these include Développement de la méthode graphique par l’emploi de la photographie. Supplément à La Méthode graphique dans les sciences expérimentales (Paris: Masson, 1885); Le Vol des oiseaux (Paris: Masson, 1890); Le Mouvement (Paris: Masson, 1894; Nîmes: Jacqueline Chambon, 2002), which was published in an English translation by Eric Pritchard as Movement (London: William Heinemann, 1895). 19 Concerning notation, let us still mention a passage from Movement about “the application of the zootrope to the study of horses’ paces,” published in 1864 with drawn images: “This was

100 

Maria Tortajada

very concerned about underlining the various aspects of his method and its applications. It is therefore interesting to take another look at how his major writings handle the synthesis of movement. In these texts, synthesis mainly appears either as a means to present the results before several observers, or as a heuristic process that makes it possible to ascertain some results. It is in this sense that Marey systematically describes the various methods for synthesis.

The Synthesis of Movement, Illusion and Increasing Knowledge From the early stages of his chronophotographic work, Marey used devices that synthesized movement, such as the phenakistiscope and the zoetrope. These are founded on the principle of the persistence of vision and make it possible to reconstitute movement out of still images, turning separate images into the animated image of a continuous movement. So it goes with Marey’s zoetrope, built for the observation of flight and in which the scientist placed three-dimensional figures of the seagull or the pigeon (1887). In 1885 Marey mentioned his use of the phenakistiscope to animate the images obtained with the photographic gun. In a five-page note on the gun, he exposed the finality of this reconstitution of movement: Placing photographs of birds on a phenakistiscope, you get a fair reproduction of the appearance of the movements of the flight, but the images corresponding to each revolution of the wing are still too few to allow for a good analysis of its movements. Their number will therefore have to be increased, for instance by doubling the speed of the movement of the plate and shutters, which I was able to do with the same gun, and still have enough light for the production of images of shapes […].20

At that point, Marey was contemplating improvements to capture movement based on the f inality of his research: the analysis of movement. Analysis thus also played a part in synthesis and was clearly associated with what Marey was looking for: to be able to distinguish significant the concrete demonstration of the sequence expressed by the chronographic charts.” See Marey, Movement 308. In the text for the World Fair, he also wrote: “We sought to obtain through Plateau’s method the reproduction of analyzed movements.” The formulation stresses prior analysis. See Marey, “History of Chronophotography” 326. 20 Marey, Développement de la méthode graphique par l’emploi de la photographie 16.

Marey and the Synthesis of Movement

101

changes in the position of the wing in reconstituted movement. To that end, the number of images made had to be increased. Analysis and synthesis were not dissociated in this instance.21 Marey stressed the importance and usefulness of the instruments making it possible to observe slowed-down movement.22 Thanks to the zoetrope, he wrote in Le Vol des oiseaux, he had been able “to compare these two types of flight [the pigeon’s and the seagull’s].” He then “noted that, behind some apparent dissemblances, they presented deep analogies.”23 The study of flight continued in the observation of reconstituted movement: The instrument, once set in motion, gave the perfect illusion of a series of seagulls flying one after the other following a closed circle. The very great advantage of three-dimensional figures is that they make it possible to see the bird from every possible angle. Indeed, thanks to the circular arrangement of the small figures, each appears to the observer from different successive angles. […] So that, depending on the part of the circuit you focus on, you see the bird moving away, passing or approaching: with these three aspects, you may study the movement of wings at will, slow it down as you wish by slowing down the rotation of the zoetrope to a greater or lesser extent.24

Slow motion, which was considered by Marey himself as a stopgap solution by 1900, was still presented with enthusiasm at that point (1890). Four years later, synthesis was highlighted in exactly the same way in Movement: This method invented by Plateau seems likely to extend our knowledge as regards all kinds of phenomena. But the future of the method is dependent on the possible correction which can be effected in the distortion of the images, and on the discovery of a satisfactory means of projecting a number of moving figures on a screen, so as to be visible to a large 21 Along the same lines, the beginning of paragraph 111 in Le Vol des oiseaux, “Adaptation des f igures en relief au zootrope,” comes to mind: “To take the most advantage from these three-dimensional figures, relatively to the analysis of the movements of the flight, they had to be examined with Plateau’s device […].” See Marey, Le Vol des oiseaux 180 (my emphasis). 22 Or speeded-up movement, in fact – the change in the speed of the reconstituted movement remained essential. In 1894 Marey mentioned “a curious line of research” proposed by Ernst Mack: “the stages of a man’s existence would pass in review before the gaze of the onlookers in the form of a strange and marvellous metamorphosis.” See Marey, Movement 312, 313; and his “Préface” to Trutat, La Photographie animée VIII. 23 See Marey, Le Vol des oiseaux 182. 24 See Marey, Le Vol des oiseaux 181-82 (my emphasis).

102 

Maria Tortajada

audience. And, further, it will be necessary to augment the number of successive photographs, so as to represent a performance of considerable duration.25

Marey thus granted the synthesis of movement an important place, to the extent that he presented it as a means to establish new scientific facts. The question of the function of control, while probably unquestionable, was not predominant. Marey concluded his great work on chronophotography with the presentation of a chronophotographic projector of his own making (that of 1893).26 From the standpoint of finality, Marey described it as belonging to Plateau’s method, as an improvement on the phenakistiscope and the zoetrope, situating it within the same logic despite essential technical differences (the use of the reel and the strip of film). In short, the synthesis of movement was relevant for the methos even in heuristic terms. What of the illusion of movement? Unsurprisingly, Marey referred enthusiastically to the effect of the synthesis he presented. The description he gives of his zoetrope for three-dimensional figures in Le Vol des oiseaux is proof enough. The instrument, he writes, “gave the perfect illusion of a series of seagulls flying” (see quotation and note 24). Marey uses the same expression to introduce the phenakistiscope: The persistence of impressions of light on the retina has as a result that this object seems to perform continuous movements returning regularly and periodically. […] Windows were cut out in the disc at suitable intervals and the disc, set in motion in front of a mirror, produced the perfect illusion of a bird flapping its wings.27

Every time Marey presented what he called “Plateau’s method,” he insisted on the value of the result obtained: the illusion of movement, which he defined as continuous. In 1894, the phenakistiscope was credited with giving “the illusion of genuine movement,” and as for his zoetrope, Marey specified

25 Marey, Movement 313 (my emphasis). 26 “Du projecteur chronophotographique,” in Marey, Movement 317-18. The book ends with a complete openness to the research on projecting appliances, after noting their technical limitations and notably the lack of stability of projected images: “Having arrived at this point in our researches, we learned that our mechanic had discovered an immediate solution of this problem, and by quite a different method; we shall therefore desist from our present account pending further investigation.” Marey, Movement 318. 27 Marey, Le Vol des oiseaux 164 (my emphasis).

Marey and the Synthesis of Movement

103

that “the illusion was complete.”28 In 1900 Marey distanced himself from the term “illusion.” The issue of synthesis was then addressed only in the description of appliances. It was still introduced through the description of Plateau’s method, but in not so many forms: synthesis then was literally “the reproduction of analyzed motions,” which is the strict scientific formulation of control synthesis.29 The notion of illusion came into play, but in the presentation of the Lumière Cinematograph and after Edison’s Kinetoscope! In 1900, and in this context only, “presenting a perfect illusion” was the objective.30 Still, Marey’s interest in the synthesis of movement prior to 1900 cannot be questioned. Marey did not reject the illusion of movement as unscientific then; he even presented it as an aim because he still saw it in relation to slow motion. Slow motion made up for a deficient sense – a constant finality in Marey’s scientific approach. In itself, the observation is admittedly not new. But it should be emphasized that slow motion is associated with an affirmed practice of synthesis. Until 1894, Marey underscored slow motion as one modality of the synthesis of movement, as a form of synthesis, defined as the illusion of continuous movement, as the appearance of movement, whatever the speed of the observed subject.

The Synthesis of Movement as Decomposition of Movement: Phases What the synthesis of movement meant for Marey is better understood through the nature of the results it allowed him to achieve. Marey did not simply want to know the movement of a mobile by establishing the various instants of its path, represented by a series of film frames; nor did he simply want to decompose the movement of the mobile into a discontinuous trajectory. As a physiologist, he sought to explain how human and animal locomotion functioned. In 1894, when he listed the specific qualities of chronophotography compared to other methods such as the graphic method, he wrote: Chronophotography was useful when a general idea of the movement was desired; it was also the only means by which the movements of an isolated

28 Marey, Movement 311. 29 Marey, “History of Chronophotography” 326. 30 Marey, “History of Chronophotography” 328.

104 

Maria Tortajada

point could be expressed, when the movement was not accompanied by the development of a certain amount of force.

He added: […] the true interest of chronophotography lies in the fact that it can provide a complete picture of the bird in the various attitudes it assumes during the act of taking a stroke with its wings.31

The place of measurement is essential in Marey’s practice: more often than not, it is the measurement that is actually remembered, for the knowledge of movement rested on a direct measure – on chronophotographs or on the working drawings Marey made out of them – of the distance covered by a mobile, of the time elapsed with respect to this distance, on the calculation of the speeds, of muscular work, but also on a measure of the speeds of cogwheels in machines used for experimentation. The measurement was at once a result of the research and a decisive condition in the precision of the chronophotographic experience. However, as a physiologist, Marey was also interested in the moving body as a whole: the form of muscles, the physical and visual transformation imposed by movement, the position of a limb in relation to the previous one or to the rest of the body. Measurement is certainly involved there, but not only. Besides measurement, a physical characterization of movement is essential.32 Marey’s work involved a whole practice of describing bodies in movement, which made it possible to establish a knowledge needed by physiological science. And this aspect of his research happened to mobilize Marey when he analyzed still chronophotographic images as well as when he experimented with the synthesis of movement. What Marey attentively observed in the synthesis and thanks to slow motion was the phases of movements. This question, central for Marey, went hand in hand with emphasizing slow motion. After presenting several different zoetropes, he thus wrote:

31 Marey, Movement 232. 32 See the series of annotated drawings in sub-chapter §102, “Attitudes successives des ailes et du corps de l’oiseau pendant un coup d’aile” (Marey, Le Vol des oiseaux 158-61). Here is an eloquent excerpt: “Fig. 92. The joints of the wing are flexed and the large remiges reach out; at the same time as they pivot and allow air between them. Fig. 93. The abduction of the wing becomes more and more pronounced; the remiges are clearly apart from one another; the front edge of the wing goes up.” Marey, Le Vol des oiseaux 160-61.

Marey and the Synthesis of Movement

105

All these applications would be simply childish if they were limited to the reproduction of phenomena which could be observed by the eye in the case of living creatures. They would be attended, in fact, by all the uncertainties and diff iculties which embarrass the observation of the actual movement. […] But a combination of the zoetrope and chronophotography has further possibilities, for it enables the observer to follow movements, which would otherwise be impossible to examine, by slowing down the motion to any desired rate. […] Under these conditions, […] the eye can follow […] all […] phases, whereas, in a living bird, only a confused flutter of the wings can be distinguished.33

Marey’s whole chronophotographic research aimed to increase the number of images in a series so as to be able “to know the greatest possible number of phases in movement.”34 What characterizes the phase is the change in the body’s position or in the position of the part of the body being examined.35 For instance, Marey would pinpoint the moment when the wing of the bird went up or down. One of the levels in the knowledge of a movement forms when the order of succession of its phases is established. For Marey the phase was part of the concept of movement; the notion was a component in the type of movements he primarily studied in animal locomotion: periodic and repetitive movements. Phases could be read and studied directly in the chronophotographic series, at the analytical stage. Yet Marey insisted on the usefulness of observing phases in the movement reconstituted in slow motion. He could then spot changes, look for breaks, in short, track down discontinuity. It was not the discontinuity of film frames that interested him, but the discontinuity in the synthesized image, in reconstituted movement. For phases were what allowed the decomposition of the global, apparently continuous movement of the mobile within synthesized movement. What Marey noted in synthesis was not merely the good functioning of the reversion of the phenomenon. Here again, something in the analysis of movement entered the observation of the synthesized movement. In other words, there was no control synthesis that did not replay the analysis; hence the necessity of finding anew, and seeing, the decomposition of movement in the synthesis of movement. The movement of synthesis affirmed as continuous was then thought as a discontinuous continuity. The notion of movement 33 Marey, Le Mouvement 311-12 (my emphasis). 34 Marey, Développement de la méthode graphique par l’emploi de la photographie. Supplément à La Méthode graphique dans les sciences expérimentales 31. 35 Marey, Le Vol des oiseaux 158.

106 

Maria Tortajada

involved at that point then stands in radical opposition to another concept of movement, understood as a continuous, indivisible flow that cannot be decomposed. This Bergsonian definition of movement was decisive in different domains of knowledge from the early twentieth century on, in art history and the history of cinema, and remains pervasive to this day. By contrast, Marey was looking for the discontinuity of phases within reconstituted movement – an essential discontinuity, though one distinct from the discontinuity of film frames. This apprehension of movement as synthesized – that is, continuous, and yet discontinuous, thought and perceived as such, and analyzed – informs the status of vision implied in the synthesis of movement in Marey’s first approach. Starting from the identification of phases and the decomposition of synthesized movement, the observer’s learning process becomes possible: The slowing down of movement makes the phenakistiscope so valuable, as it allows the eye to follow with ease all the phases of an action that would otherwise elude direct observation. Little by little, as the speed of the disc’s rotation increases, the eye – familiarized with the movement it has just observed – continues to make out its phases in spite of their shorter duration. One’s sight thus becomes trained and soon some details which used to escape attention are captured. I have noted this about myself, with the horse’s gaits, man’s race and even the flight of some birds.36

Marey, most particularly in Le Vol des oiseaux, elaborated what may be called a didactics of the look, that of the scientist as well as that of the lay person. 1. The observer should learn to see reality, and this learning process involves the use of viewing dispositives allowing the manipulation of movement and learning by the same observer. This is the first thesis on vision. The issue of didactics was especially important for Marey, on two accounts. 36 Marey, Le Vol des oiseaux 165-66 (my emphasis). The chapter on the synthesis of movement begins with the training of the scholar’s eye and its function in scientific approaches. Chronophotography, according to Marey, presents series of attitudes in which “the object appears to be motionless, and movements, which are successively executed, are associated in a series of images, as if they were all being executed at the same moment. The images, therefore, appeal rather to the imagination than to the senses. They teach us, it is true, to observe Nature more carefully, and, perhaps, to seek in a moving animal for positions hitherto unnoticed. This education of the eye may, however, be rendered still more complete if the impression of the movement be conveyed to the eye under conditions to which it is accustomed.” Marey, Movement 304 (my emphasis).

Marey and the Synthesis of Movement

107

First, in the scientific method itself, the moment of synthesis was also a moment dedicated to “demonstration”: the demonstration of a wellfounded analysis, but also the demonstration as an argument liable to convince peers. Moreover, research and the acquisition of knowledge were coupled: as can be seen, the first educative result of the scientific method concerned the scientist himself, as he learned to decompose movement by observing it in its synthesis. However, the transmission of knowledge and scientific popularization were never overlooked by Marey, who was a man of his century in that respect, as was notably shown in his publications in the periodical La Nature or in the 1894 presentation of the synthesis of movement in relation to the issues of the communication of results, of publication or of “public demonstration.”37 2. A second thesis on vision was implicit in the approach. With the study of phases, it seems as though what was to be taught to one’s own perception was the direct integration of the decomposition of movement. What was to be learned was the movement of the real phenomenon as a whole, structured in various moments from the outset, just as the ability to recognize it in its discontinuity should be practiced: in short, a sort of analytical apprehension of the world should be reached. To that end, the observer should have first trained his look in front of a mobile’s movement synthesized in slow motion. Yet in the 1890 text quoted here, the exercise is clearly explained; it involves a learning that assumes to gradually reestablish the synthesized movement at a speed closer and closer to direct perception: “Little by little, as the speed of the disc’s rotation increases, the eye – familiarized with the movement it has just observed – continues to make out its phases in spite of their shorter duration.”38 The observer is then ready to apply analytical vision to the continuous movement of reality, which he will then perceive in its inherent and structural discontinuity. This exercise shows how the synthesis of movement, without slow motion, just as it is “normally” perceived, as the outcome of the gradual acceleration of the run of images – and once it has itself become analytical through the faculties of the observer – is also part of the process and is not dismissed as irrelevant. It is, one might say, tamed, re-appropriated, reread according to the decomposition of movement.

37 See the sub-chapter “Reproduction, enlargement, and reduction of chronophotographs,” in Marey, Movement 123. 38 See footnote 36, Le vol des oiseaux.

108 

Maria Tortajada

One Expression, Two Concepts But of course, Marey did not hold the same position in 1900: Of late years, chronophotography has taken another direction – that of the synthesis of motion. The analytic images are made to appear before the spectators’ eyes in uniform sequence, so as to reproduce the appearance of the motion itself.39

A few pages further, Marey adds: Animated projections, interesting as they are, are of little advantage to science, for they only show what we see better with our own eyes. At best, they serve to slow a motion which is too quick for direct observation, or to accelerate it if its extreme slowness causes us to miss some of its features. 40

The synthesis of movement, though it was part of chronophotography, was primarily associated with popular spectacle by 1900. Slow motion seemed to have lost its importance and appeared as a detail. Synthesized movement was not only discredited because it brought nothing more than the ordinary vision of movement, but also because it was not as sharp. All the characteristics that had made the synthesis of movement valuable were passed over: a moment in the scientific approach, the validation stage continuing the analysis, promoting demonstrative and didactic qualities. Reading Marey, it seems as though the generalized social practice of the synthesis of movement imposed the prominence of one use and notion of synthesis over another. Marey appeared to react to this state of affairs by turning away from the synthesis of movement to privilege geometric analysis and working drawings. 41 Yet the reversal took place at the cost of a shift in the concept of synthesis, as indeed two notions of the synthesis of movement, associated with two distinct practices, were implied in Marey’s writing. That in which the synthesis of movement was thought of in relation to the decomposition of movement seemed to fade away, to the benefit of the other. 39 Marey, “History of Chronophotography” 317. 40 Marey, “History of Chronophotography” 329. 41 While the end of Movement opened onto the research on the synthesis of movement, the 1900 text came to a close with the working drawing of movement, that is, on the geometric analysis plotted on paper and based on film frames, and it privileged the still plate. The change in positioning is obvious.

109

Marey and the Synthesis of Movement

I: Synthesis emphasized before 1900 and considered as a stopgap option from then on

II: Synthesis of “animated views” in 1899-1900

Slow motion (speeded-up motion) “The appearance of movement itself” Seeing more than in direct observation Seeing less Learning to see Common perception Phases “in movement”: synthesized movement as discontinuous Analysis of movement – Manipulation of movement – Scientific practice Non-scientific practice The Two Syntheses of Movement according to Marey

It is therefore essential to underline the fact that, at a given historical moment, Marey conceived of synthesized movement as discontinuous and considered it valuable. Synthesis was not automatically associated with continuity and the flow of movement, which some were later to consider as the privilege of cinema. To understand the rejection of synthesis by Marey around 1900, it is accordingly not enough to note simply that he was no longer interested in synthesis. Rather, it should be emphasized that, when he spoke of synthesis in 1900, he was referring to something else, a notion which was totally useless in his method and which he associated to a practice that had become generalized by then. What is original is the fact that, rejecting this common form of synthesis, he also minimized synthesis to ends of control and decomposition, in which slow motion played a part – in the presentation text for the World Fair, for example. Marey’s reversal may be explained through the reformulation of the principles of his method, resulting in the perception of validation synthesis as less valuable as a whole. This thesis, which would imply a revolution in Marey’s approach, would have important implications from the point of view of the history of sciences. At the moment, it appears ill-founded. A different explanation, more limited in range, would amount to claiming that the synthesis of movement was no longer part of the framework of the method as a synthesis for control, and was disqualified as a result. I have not been able to find anything in Marey’s writing that would confirm either version, though the presentation text for the 1900 exhibition, centered on the working drawing and on the analytical translation of film frames, would seem to point us to the latter direction. The most obvious explanation, provided by Marey in person and repeated in his wake, does not go into this type of consideration. Rather, it involves a new distribution of roles between science and popular practice around

110 

Maria Tortajada

the issue of synthesis. Should we simply come to the conclusion that Marey could no longer resort to a scientific method he had developed himself, the synthesis of movement, from the moment when synthesis was used “outside the scientific institution”? Was the institutional division between science and spectacle the main explanation for his reversal? This is questionable. Indeed, throughout the nineteenth century, the recourse to synthesized movement was not limited to scientific circles. Marey’s first notion of synthesis, in which synthesized movement itself was thought of as discontinuous in the field of science, should be compared to contemporary practices of play and spectacle in the nineteenth century, notably those involving the phenaskistiscope and the zoetrope. The synthesis of movement then flaunted the mechanics, the moment of composition and decomposition of movement, the link between continuity and discontinuity, for the enjoyment of spectators. The “analytical continuity” – the discontinuous continuous – was part of the social context, in a way. Still, the circulation of popular practices involving synthesis and the manipulation of movement over the period did not dissuade Marey from enhancing the synthesis of movement in his method. 42 Science and spectacle were not opposed in the absolute when it came to the synthesis of movement, according to the implicit reading Marey seemed to make in 1900 – though this opposition may suit classical film history all too well in consolidating the idea of the primacy of the Lumière cinematograph in the “birth” of cinema as a spectacle, relegating Marey to the reserved space of science. One explanation remains, however, and it goes beyond Marey himself, even as the positioning of the scientist may have played a part in the context and may now serve to shed light on it. The hypothesis in question is that Marey’s reversal took into account a more global, diffuse change attested in the generalization of the practice of “animated views.” The institutional split affirmed by Marey – science vs. popular practice – may have drawn on a decisive modification, the gradual transformation of the notion of movement as it started to circulate in the social space. Marey’s rejection of synthesis may indeed be interpreted as a sign of the transformation of what was understood as movement, and more specifically as synthesized movement, at the turn of the century. Marey no longer saw synthesized movement as valuable because the said movement no longer appeared as evidently as a decomposed, analytical movement. The beginning of a change in epistemological status for the synthesis of movement seems 42 In Movement, Marey specified that “the original form of this instrument was a plaything” before proceeding to explain the scientific interest of the phenakistiscope. See Marey, Movement 306.

Marey and the Synthesis of Movement

111

to have occurred in the last years of the century. Or rather, synthesis assumed two statuses at that point, which Marey’s work articulated. In this hypothesis, the opposition between science and popular practice, which Marey seems to suggest explains his positioning, was combined with a process of transformation of the notion of synthesis, noted by him just as he made it concrete through his new stance. This transformation, which cancelled the analytical dimension of synthesized movement, was the premise of a process leading to the generalization of a definition of movement whose radical formulation Bergson provided and which was to have a strong impact in the arts and the thought on film in the twentieth century. Bergson saw movement as the continuous, indivisible flow of the reality of the world, which was completely incompatible with the notion of movement in Marey’s first use of synthesis. Applying the Bergsonian definition of movement to the synthesized, projected image would have meant a shift to another epistemological model of the synthesis of movement, something done by neither Marey nor Bergson – who wrote little on the synthesized image as such. 43 The epistemological passage in question was realized in the writing of André Bazin or Gilles Deleuze, for instance, with the impact of their discourses in the field of cinema, but it undoubtedly took place well before them. Two polar notions of the synthesis of movement should be introduced at this stage: one that still dominated at the end of the nineteenth century, that of “the animated image,” in which synthesized movement was thought of in relation to the decomposition of that very movement and its analytical apprehension (there lies the first enthusiastic use of the synthesis of movement by Marey as well as playful and spectacular uses of the animated image); the other, that of “the moving image,” involved movement as a continuous flow, by definition opposed to any decomposition. This second notion fully crystallized in the twentieth century, but its gradual historical construction 43 Elie During stresses the importance of movement in the machine at the moment of synthesis when he analyzes the cinematographic dispositive: “the emphasis is on the artificial continuity of the uniform run of film and on the idea of time it commands, rather than on the discontinuity tied to the fragmentation of film frames and their ‘stroboscopic’ (intermittent) reproduction.” See “Notes on the Bergsonian Cinematograph” in this volume, as well as the entry on Bergson in Dictionnaire de la pensée du cinéma, Antoine de Baecque and Philippe Chevallier, eds. (Paris: PUF, 2011). This approach to the Bergsonian text sheds light on an aspect often forgotten in commentaries on the question of film in Bergson: the interest in the machine and in the process of production of images in the constitution of his cinematographic model. While the movement involved in the projecting machine is indeed essential, the projected image itself, the moving image, which belongs in simulated movement, remains “off” the philosopher’s concrete analysis of the dispositive.

112 

Maria Tortajada

began in the late 1890s, notably following the variations of dispositives linked to the “cinema.” It did not simply cancel out analytical synthesis. In the early twentieth century, this synthesis still appeared in discourses on cinema or in projection practices. The projections of animated images by the first cinematographs and chronophotographs until the early twentieth century belonged in this logic, despite the distance taken by Marey. 44 It is remarkable, for instance, that these appliances and spectacular practices were presented recurrently as instruments that were to allow the study of movement, notably thanks to slow motion, at the same time as they were objects of spectacle. Analytical synthesis was still part of the field of “cinema” in the early twentieth century, as is attested in Georges Méliès’s description of the Cinematograph in terms of phases and decomposition of movement.45 There was no outright shift to a new paradigm, but a gradual transformation, a change of dominant characteristic that affected not only the field of cinema and its history, but Marey’s science as well. When the practice of animated views – which was still fundamentally marked by the analytical conception of synthesis, the thought of movement in terms of phases, and the play with the manipulation and decomposition of movement – no longer appeared to Marey as involving the discontinuous essential to analysis, he came to reject the synthesis of movement. The cinematographic paradigm coalesced around 1900, transforming the relation to the idea of a synthesis of movement. It implied a double renouncement, of a didactic model of the look and of a concept of movement that did not separate the perception of a phenomenon undergoing a continuous movement from its analytical decomposition. This paradigm was accompanied by a sharp affirmation of the separation between science and spectacle, a separation which presupposed the modification of the notion of synthesis. A provocative formula is always striking: if the question of the synthesis of movement is considered foundational for cinema, then the event, from an 44 A contemporary example is the resistance of projectionists to the adoption of the engine and the resulting homogenization of movement, as the crank allowed variations that had to do with its decomposition. See Benoît Turquety’s article in this volume, “Forms of Machines, Forms of Movements.” 45 See Georges Méliès, “Cinematographic Views” (1907), trans. Stuart Liebman, in French Film Theory and Criticism: A History/Anthology, vol. 1: 1907-1929, Richard Abel, ed. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1988) 35-47. On a different level, Jean Epstein’s definition of photogénie could also be mentioned, as it highlights both the analytical and the experimental approach of the cinematographic art and the decomposition performed by the close-up. See Jean Epstein, “Bonjour cinéma” (1921), in Ecrits sur le cinéma, 1921-1953, vol. 1: 1921-1947 (Paris: Seghers, 1974) 94-97. Yet this takes us to the order of editing, another type of discontinuity.

Marey and the Synthesis of Movement

113

epistemological standpoint, is not the advent of the Lumière Cinematograph as a technique or social fact. The event is the change – more diffuse, to be sure – that affected discourses, notably Marey’s, which re-elaborated the explanation of the method and accordingly the status of the notion of synthesis of movement. This research still shows that, in the epistemological approach to viewing and listening dispositives, technique, social practice, the finality of research, and concepts are always tied together through the mediation of discourses.



Notes on the Bergsonian Cinematograph Elie During

We know how Gilles Deleuze turned the commonplace inside out: Bergson, so it went, had “missed” cinema, contenting himself with a critique of its dispositive – the mechanism of the projecting device called the “cinematograph,” to be specif ic. Before the critique of the “cinematographic illusion,” developed for the most part in 1907 in Creative Evolution,1 there was indeed the doctrine of real movement, whose touchstone was the pure perception of movement as an act or progression rather than as a relation distributed in the spatial order. Movement unfolds in time, not in space. This bold thesis, exposed in Matter and Memory, gave a very singular conception of the plurality of rhythms of duration within an evolving universe. That Bergson thereby offered precious resources for thinking about cinema or the cinematographic experience was what Deleuze attempted to show in the brilliant analyses of Time-Image and Movement-Image. In so doing, he sanctioned another commonplace conveyed by critics and philosophers – namely, that cinema was, in essence, a Bergsonian art. One can see how far back the idea goes by looking at debates between Paul Souday, Marcel L’Herbier and Émile Vuillermoz in the late 1910s, at later texts by Elie Faure, Jean Epstein and Béla Balázs, or even at this pronouncement by a young Sartre in 1924: “Cinema provides the formula for a Bergsonian art. It inaugurates mobility in aesthetics.”2 More fundamentally, the assessment points to the musical paradigm that drives certain discourses on the flow of cinematographic images, but also on the contrapuntal or symphonic composition involved in editing. Deleuze chose the second direction and shifted the emphasis to a metaphysical ground, irreducible to any aesthetic of the flow. On the way, however, the dispositive was lost: it was about cinema, or rather about

1 In fact, the cinematograph was mentioned for the first time in the 1902-1903 Collège de France lectures devoted to “the history of the idea of time,” alongside other optical devices such as the magic lantern. 2 Jean-Paul Sartre, Écrits de jeunesse, Michel Contat and Michel Rybalka, eds. (Paris: Gallimard, 1990) 389.

116 

Elie During

images and ideas “in” cinema, but no longer at all – or barely – about the cinematograph.3 Beyond Deleuze’s reappropriation, it may be useful, questioning Bergson’s actual contribution to thinking on cinema, to go back to the point of view that was originally his, starting with a few obvious elements. First, it was never Bergson’s ambition to think through cinema, a medium that he did not actually know very well, besides attending screenings like everyone else, so to speak. 4 This comes as no surprise for a philosopher generally prone to approach metaphysical inquiry on the side of contemporary sciences rather than artistic creation. A simple consequence ensues, which should be kept in mind as a kind of methodological safeguard. In the analogy introduced in the fourth chapter of Creative Evolution, the cinematograph is in the position of a comparing element, not that of an element being compared. Accordingly, it does not make sense to wonder which dimensions Bergson missed in real cinema, in the actual uses of its dispositive – if the said dispositive may even be referred to in the singular and univocally over the very first years of the twentieth century, which remains to be established. Bergson may just as well be criticized for not writing a book on f ilm! In truth, it is exactly the opposite: what Bergson did not note regarding the actual situation of cinema should instead be ascribed to the remarkable work of invention that presided over the development of the cinematographic analogy.5 With this device, the philosopher availed himself of a kind of precision optical tool, a speculative instrument liable to raise certain questions anew – questions that had seemingly nothing to do with the art of “animated views” soon to be known as “cinema.” To have a clearer understanding of this and attempt to describe the specific problem that motivated the resort to the analogy of the cinematograph, it may be useful to start by setting things straight. This should allow us to understand in which direction the analogy may operate and suggest new paths for research.6 Indeed, as Bergson evoked the operation of the 3 On this paradoxical relay between Bergson and Deleuze, see Paul Douglass, “Bergson and Cinema: Friends or Foes?” in The New Bergson, ed. J. Mullarkey (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 2006), as well as my entries, “Bergson” and “Travelling,” in Dictionnaire de la pensée du cinéma, Antoine de Baecque and Philippe Chevallier, eds. (Paris: PUF, 2012). 4 On this aspect, see Michel Georges-Michel’s testimony, En jardinant avec Bergson (Paris: Albin Michel, 1926) 13-14. See also Les Grandes Époques de la peinture moderne, de Delacroix à nos jours (New York: Brentano’s, 1945) 47-8. 5 The analysis is so precise and follows the development of the image so closely that the term “analogy” seems fully justified in this instance. Analogy, then, rather than image or metaphor. 6 On the function of the image in the definition of problems, see the interview with Bergson reprinted in Lydie Adolphe, La Dialectique des images (Paris: PUF, 1951) 4.

Notes on the Bergsonian Cinematograph

117

cinematograph, he sought to bring to light a mechanism that was much more fundamental – in his view – than the one he was emphasizing in the comparing element organizing the analogy. In fact, the cinematograph was to allow the identification of the workings of an “inner cinematograph” that spontaneously directed the thought of movement, down to its most elaborate constructions. This thought was already at work in natural perception: in that respect, equipped perception only effected a passage at the edge of natural perception. Its full expression was achieved in the representation of movement by physics. From this standpoint, it becomes clearer that Bergson did not content himself with an ingenious metaphor: it is barely an exaggeration to say that he literally invented the cinematograph as we know it today. The cinematograph he was dealing with was primarily a philosophical or, more precisely, a conceptual object – not a cultural object to which philosophical reflection would be applied from the outside, on the model of interpretation or analysis, but an ideal instrument, a catalyst for a thought which to some extent could have tapped into starkly different domains to achieve the same end. Neither concepts nor the tools of thought are found “ready made”; they have to be tailored to suit particular purposes. In the end, even an analogy has to reconstruct the fulcrums it relies on in reality. And on closer examination, Bergson manifestly built an object out of this “cinematograph,” an object which, on one decisive aspect, differs from most of the devices for the projection of animated views that were in use at the time he was writing. This point generally went unnoticed: there is every indication that the mechanism described in Creative Evolution is completely automatized, with the hand magically absent. This is all the more surprising as, at the time Bergson was writing Creative Evolution, devices for the projection of animated views still involved operation by hand to a massive extent, with operators skilled at turning the crank, slowing down and speeding up the run of the film to enhance the action, intensify a given dramatic moment, exhibit the details of a particular movement or condense an entire scene in a flurry of images. Almost no projectors were fitted with an electric motor in the projection sites that began to appear. In France, the “professional” model produced by Pathé, which was the most widely used in the 1910s, still required projectionists to turn the crank at a pace of 16 to 20 images per second. By and large, this was actually still the case after the war, until the advent of synchronous sound and the generalization of the electric motor

118 

Elie During

imposed the constant speed of the famous 24 images per second.7 To be sure, as early as 1901, Pathé catalogs advertised the merits of some automatized devices for domestic use, equipped with a multiple-speed motor capable of maintaining a regular run of images. Yet these were clearly meant to relieve projectionists of a tiresome effort of attention rather than replace them outright. Cinema overwhelmingly remained an art of the crank.8 One may certainly wonder about the part played by the high-precision techniques of chronophotography or scientif ic cinematography in the elaboration of the Bergsonian image. Bergson and Marey were colleagues at the Collège de France, and this is not an insignificant fact.9 Other contemporary devices may have served as models – Edison’s kinetoscope in particular, with its electric motor. But basically, what Bergson may or may not have seen matters little. The cinematograph as he describes it is his own invention and conforms to his method. The nodal point of the analogy, what drives it from beginning to end, is the uniform character of the film run made possible by the automatization of the device. Bergson did not even need to evoke the presence of a motor explicitly to suggest uniform motion. The decisive element was that the mechanism of the cinematograph only had to be “set going.”10 Once the movement was launched, the hand no longer had anything to do with it and the mind of the operator could attend to something else, indifferent to the variety of real movements that the machine, left to its own mechanism, reproduced on the screen by running film frames before a beam of light.11 7 As a reference, let us mention Georges Sadoul’s Histoire générale du cinéma: “In 1920, the largest French movie theaters still used hand-cranked projectors for film screenings. The rhythm of the projection could thus be adjusted, and even devices equipped with an electric motor could be slowed down and speeded up thanks to a rheostat.” See Georges Sadoul, Histoire générale du cinéma, vol. 5, L’Art muet, 1919-1929 (Paris: Denoël, 1975) 84. 8 See Benoît Turquety’s text, “Forms of Machines, Forms of Movement,” in this volume. 9 The ambivalence of Marey’s chronophotographic experiments makes them all the more interesting from a Bergsonian perspective. See Georges Didi-Huberman, “L’image est le mouvant,” in Intermédialités 3 (Spring 2004): 11-30; Georges Didi-Huberman and Laurent Mannoni, Mouvements de l’air: Étienne-Jules Marey, photographe des fluides (Paris: Gallimard/Réunion des musées nationaux, 2004); Pasi Väliaho, Mapping the Moving Image: Gesture, Thought and Cinema circa 1900 (Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press, 2010); Maria Tortajada, “Évaluation, mesure, mouvement: la philosophie contre la science et les concepts du cinéma (Bergson, Marey),” in Revue européenne des sciences sociales XLVI.141 (2008): 95-111. 10 Henri Bergson, Creative Evolution, trans. Arthur Mitchell (London: McMillan, 1911) 323 (online version available at http://archive.org/details/creativeevolutio00berguoft, last accessed on February 18, 2013). 11 In that respect, a rather illuminating approach consists in situating the cinematograph within the larger context of a kind of generalized cinema where, alongside the best-known

Notes on the Bergsonian Cinematograph

119

Thus, the emphasis was on the artificial continuity of the uniform run and on the idea of time such continuity commanded, rather than on the discontinuity linked to the fragmentation of film frames and their “stroboscopic” (intermittent) reproduction. I have already elaborated upon this point in detail elsewhere,12 and will therefore limit the present argument to the main insights which an attentive reading of the texts featuring a cinematographic reference in the Bergsonian corpus may very simply yield. But what is meant by the term “uniform,” to begin with? In the case in point, the run of the celluloid filmstrip at a rigorously constant speed proves rather secondary. As has already been pointed out, Bergson did not explicitly mention a motor, though the description he gave of the device clearly seemed to integrate the principle of the automatic run. What really matters here is that the movement should be mechanical, that is, indifferent or arbitrary. This intrinsic indetermination implies that arbitrary speeds may be applied to it, that it may be speeded up or slowed down without affecting in any way what is projected on the screen.13 In a sense, the device represents a system isolated from the movements it is supposed to reproduce, a system that owes nothing to the variations in intensity accounting for the singularity of these movements. The speed of the film’s run may well be modified at will through a rheostat; for all that, the nature of the projection will remain radically different from a hand-cranked projection. Notwithstanding the variations resulting from tiredness, the natural lack of precision of the gesture or economic pressures to cut screenings short, the projectionist clearly speeded up or slowed down the run of the film strip optical devices, one would find all sorts of “cinematic machines” developed in the field of artistic techniques and methods, including literature. See Maria Tortajada, “Machines cinématiques et dispositifs visuels. Cinéma et ‘pré-cinéma’ à l’œuvre chez Alfred Jarry,” 1895 40 (2003): 5-23; and Jimena Canales, A Tenth of a Second (University of Chicago Press: Chicago, 2009). 12 See Elie During, “Vie et mort du cinématographe: de L’Évolution créatrice à Durée et Simultanéité,” in Bergson, ed. C. Riquier (Paris: Cerf, 2012). 13 This holds, of course, only if one assumes the position of the screen, not as an exterior spectator, but as an observer involved in the nexus of relations organizing concrete becomings. The motif of a proportional increase of all speeds in the universe was an experience of thought often discussed in Bergson’s time. Built on the model of geometric transformations by “similarity,” it aimed to bring out the relative character of measured time to better emphasize – by contrast – the absolute character of lived duration. Pushing this line of reasoning to its limit, Bergson contemplated an infinite acceleration, where everything would be given at once: as he observed, nothing would be fundamentally altered for the purpose of scientific analysis. See Henri Bergson, Creative Evolution 9-10, 357; Duration and Simultaneity, trans. Leon Jacobson (Manchester: Clinamen Press, 1999) 40-41; and La Pensée et le mouvant, published in English as The Creative Mind. An Introduction to Metaphysics, trans. Mabelle L. Andison (1946; New York: Citadel Press, 2002) 13.

120 

Elie During

according to what took place in the projected scene or the action whose unfolding he accompanied and scanned. On the other hand, it did not matter whether or not the automatic device was set to the durations whose artificial synthesis it presented; it uniformly subjected them to its own duration, that of a mechanical system artificially isolated from universal becoming and over which time could only glide, as Bergson wrote in the first pages of An Introduction to Metaphysics. Indeed, this system conformed to patterns of repetition in which duration was stripped of any efficiency. This neutralized duration, it should be noted, also assumed the function of a natural medium for the arbitrary cuts represented by the film frames.14 “Uniform,” then, connotes not so much the literal constancy or invariance of speed as the homogeneity of a time indifferent to what takes place in it. In short, what the cinematographic mechanism of thought performs – since this is what mattered to Bergson, after all – is the extraction of a “single representation of becoming in general”15 out of the variety of effective becomings. “An infinite multiplicity of becomings variously colored, so to speak, passes before our eyes: we manage so that we see only differences of color, that is to say, differences of state, beneath which there is supposed to flow, hidden from our view, a becoming always and everywhere the same, invariably colorless.”16 In the analogy of the cinematograph, this becoming “in general” (Bergson sometimes uses the expression “duration in general” in the same – unfavorable – sense), this indefinite becoming that is not the becoming of anything in particular (except precisely of an outside mechanism, indifferent from the standpoint of images) corresponds to a movement, “always the same, […] hidden in the apparatus.”17 The section to which one should always return, because it provides the key to reading Bergson’s montage, is the following: “The process then consists in extracting from all the movements peculiar to all the figures an impersonal movement abstract and simple, movement in general, so to speak: we put this into the apparatus, and we reconstitute the individuality of each particular move14 See François Albera, “Pour une épistémographie du montage: le moment Marey,” in Arrêt sur image, fragmentation du temps, François Albera, Marta Braun and André Gaudreault, eds. (Lausanne: Éditions Payot, 2002) 40-41. 15 Bergson, Creative Evolution 324. 16 Bergson, Creative Evolution 321. Incidentally, this should stop us from identifying, without further precision, Bergsonism to a sort of Heracliteanism celebrating the “flow” or “becoming” in general (in contemporary literature, Heracliteanism takes the form of a defense of the irreducible dimension of the abstract “passage” of time, which would have greatly amused Bergson). Bergsonism is a philosophy of durations – of the coexistence of durations – and that is a completely different matter. 17 Bergson, Creative Evolution 330.

Notes on the Bergsonian Cinematograph

121

ment by combining this nameless movement with the personal attitudes. Such is the contrivance of the cinematograph.”18 Indeed, to what does the cinematograph owe its remarkable effectiveness, if not to the fact that, subjecting the film strip to a global run of instantaneous photographs, it recomposes and reproduces in one piece the varied movements that make up the filmed subject, the content of animated views? There lies the essence of its process. Transposed to the level of the operations of thought, the cinematographic mechanism can be defined by two complementary substitutions: 1) the substitution of a pure mechanical movement, an analogon of “movement in general,” that is, a universal equivalent for all concrete movements, for the infinitely diverse movements of the real; 2) the substitution of an absolute time – a frametime meant to coordinate and link together all the temporal fibers into a homogeneous form of representation, laying out relations of simultaneity far and wide across space19 – for the web of proper durations, the multiplicity of singular, differentiated becomings. From the standpoint of the scientif ic representations of time – and this is ultimately what Bergson’s analysis as a whole is directed at – the promotion of cinematographic time amounts to a shift from a parametertime for local use, liable to follow change at least superficially, surveying its nuances and inflections step by step, to a rather particular use of dimension-time known as coordinate-time: a time capable of identifying two arbitrary instants and providing a measure of their temporal gap, but in a way that makes this measure indifferent to what occurs in the 18 Bergson, Creative Evolution 322. 19 The substitution evidently meets a principle of economy as well: in Creative Evolution, before introducing the cinematograph, Bergson evoked another way of rendering extensive becoming, one more faithful to the diversity of real movement and flows of duration, but also much more painstaking. Positing the movement of a parade of soldiers, Bergson explained that one could “cut out jointed figures representing the soldiers,” “give to each of them the movement of marching, a movement varying from individual to individual,” and “throw the whole on the screen.” (Bergson, Creative Evolution 321) This possibility corresponds to the local or dynamic approach mentioned above. In the language of physics, we may say that each line in the flow of movements can be described through a parameter of evolution homeomorphic to an open interval of real numbers. This parameter finds a natural interpretation as the “proper time” measured between events affecting a single portion of matter. Let us note that, in practice, variations affecting the coordinates associated to a system of axes used to identify the different moments in an evolution may always be expressed according to a parameter. This points to the fact that, between the local and the global approaches, there is more of a duality of tendencies, or a difference in orientation, than a systematic incompatibility. On these questions, see Peter Kroes, Time: Its Structure and Role in Physical Theories (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1985).

122 

Elie During

interval itself.20 It was through the cinematograph that time became for good a “fourth dimension of space,” in an operationally clear sense. Bergson had announced this promotion of spatialized time as early as his Essai sur les données immédiates de la conscience.21 Yet beyond the metaphors assigned to suggest the “spatialization” of time, it is only with coordinate time that the distribution of time over space is effected – and this implies coordinating heterogeneous durations associated with movements that can be brought together on one single plane of simultaneity, regardless of their separation in space. This frame-time, it should be noted, corresponds very precisely to the scheme of four-dimensional space-time analyzed in chapter 6 of Duration and Simultaneity.22 In this sense, the cinematograph appears as the technical allegory of the false movement by which we picture becoming by animating instantaneous spatial configurations. Going even further, one might say that the cinematograph provides the operating condition for such an artificial recomposition of becoming – by giving an account of the constitution of those instantaneous sections of becoming in which a class of events or simultaneous states can be said to coexist in the same instant. The sections are global: they define planes of simultaneity as vast in principle as the universe itself. Still, the whole interest of the cinematograph lies in its suggestion that, far from being self-sustained (who has ever “seen” the scene represented on a film frame?), these ideal sections have no existence independently of the milieu in which the succession of planes is ordered, no reason to exist outside the “cinematography of the universe”23 as a whole. This temporal milieu is made up of a foliation of states or configurations of 20 See Bergson, Creative Evolution 9, 23, 348, 355-58. What does it mean for time to be indifferent to what occurs “in the interval”? The formula may seem imprecise. It is useful to view it in relation to a specific mathematical concept Bergson did not necessarily have in mind, that of an exact differential whose expression results solely from the datum of extremal terms. Relativity theory thus distinguishes between the concept of “proper time,” always relative to the space-time path connecting two successive events, and the concept of “coordinate time,” relative to a system of reference – yet capable of providing, from that standpoint, a direct expression of the temporal difference between two dates corresponding to two events, and of doing so independently of the infinitely diverse movements which are liable to connect them “in the interval.” The famous “twin paradox” associated with Langevin’s name only draws the conclusions from this disjunction between two uses of time in physical theory. It amounts to the fact that “proper time” cannot be expressed by an exact differential. 21 The essay appeared in English as Time and Free Will: An Essay on the Immediate Data of Consciousness, trans. F. L. Pogson (1910; Whitefish, MT: Kessinger Publishing, 1995). 22 Bergson, Duration and Simultaneity 103-4 ff. See During, “Vie et mort du cinématographe” and Bergson et Einstein: la querelle du temps (Paris: PUF, 2012). 23 Bergson, Duration and Simultaneity 108.

Notes on the Bergsonian Cinematograph

123

the universe. We call it “frame-time” – or “framed time” – because it cuts only by framing, that is, by coordinating events or synchronizing clocks, which in the end always comes down to establishing relations of distant simultaneity. Our reading hypothesis may then be summed up simply: frame-time is what the cinematograph aims at. What is at stake in this particular figure of time is a principle of equivalence or commensurability for all durations, rather than the familiar linear time-dimension which serves – in Kant and others – as the homogeneous milieu of succession in general, dotted with instants analogous to points. Bergson probably happened to stress things differently in other contexts. The cinematographic illusion would then be translated in two ways, depending on what was underlined: the run of the film strip, which implies a prior winding of recorded and fixed views on the reel; or the fact of discontinuity itself, expressed in the juxtaposition of instantaneous images and the imperceptible fits and starts of a device that has the film strip jerk forward – we may remember here that the original projector of the cinematograph was occasionally compared to a sewing machine. In the first case, what is at stake is the “ready made” nature conferred on becoming by spatialized time: everything is virtually given and only has to unfold, like the film strip or the reel featuring the successive phases of a development.24 The illusion then consists in thinking that the succession “marks a deficit,” “a weakness in our perception, which is forced by this weakness to divide up the film image by image instead of grasping it in the aggregate.”25 In the second case, the illusion takes the form of an inversion of the real genesis – in an attempt to recompose what moves, out of immobile elements, 26 just as instantaneous views give the illusory impression of a continuous movement when projected at sufficient speed.27 It may seem at times that the “cinematographical method”28 amounts to just that: the desperate attempt to regain mobility from static snapshots. However, Bergson did not wait for the revelation of the cinematograph to develop these motifs: they started appearing in his philosophy with the 1889 Essai sur les données immédiates de la conscience29 and were supported by a whole array of images, some of 24 Bergson, Creative Evolution 357. 25 Bergson, The Creative Mind 18. 26 Bergson, Creative Evolution 163, 325 ff. 27 See Henri Bergson, “Conférence de Madrid sur la personnalité,” in Écrits (Paris: PUF, 2010) 513. 28 Bergson, Creative Evolution 323. 29 Bergson, letter to Émile Borel, August 20, 1907, in Écrits 340. The passage deserves quoting in its integrality: “In Time and Free Will [Essai sur les données immédiates de la conscience], I insisted on the necessity for intelligence to consider only moments in time, only states in

124 

Elie During

which may in fact be more directly suggestive. The examples that come to mind are those of the fan snapped open30 and the pearls strung into a necklace connecting them.31 These are two ways of expressing the same fundamental fact: we tend to think of the successive stages of becoming as so many images placed side by side along the film strip, waiting to be unrolled. But what is the use of the cinematographic analogy if the fan and the necklace already convey the idea? As we seek to find out which singular dimension the cinematographic analogy brings with it when compared to this series of competing images, the idea of mechanical movement inevitably resurfaces: undetermined movement, movement without quality, capable through its very abstraction of making the most heterogeneous durations commensurate, of making them coexist in the form of the simultaneous.32 Hence, in the image of the pearl necklace, the problem does not lie with the pearls, but with the string. The simultaneous states assume a consistency only through the temporal weft supporting them. Let us be quite clear about this: it is true that the motif of the uniform movement concealed in the device is in fact inseparable from the stroboscopic – or “kaleidoscopic” – condition figured in the series of instantaneous images. In the famous passage of Creative Evolution which serves as our guide here, the image of the kaleidoscope very quickly relays that of the cinematograph: it points to its phenomeno-technical condition, equivalent in that respect to the process of photographic recording on which the cinematograph as a whole depends.33 But from Bergson’s standpoint, becoming, only positions in movement, and then reconstitute mobility artificially, combining immobilities with one another. I did not qualify this process as cinematographic at that point, but the cinematograph had not yet been invented. Regardless, and whatever the name given to it, this mechanism inherent in our intelligence is, in my view, the true cause of our tendency to eliminate concrete duration from the real, to take into account only mathematical time, to see only arrangements, derangements, and rearrangements of parts there where an undivided and irreversible becoming exists. This just shows how I put to use the second remark, like the first, to demonstrate the artificial character assumed by mechanistic schemas when they serve to represent the evolution of consciousness and life.” 30 Bergson, The Creative Mind 20. 31 “Introduction to Metaphysics,” in Bergson, The Creative Mind 185. 32 I could mention by way of example a given shading in the gradual transition from green to blue (qualitative change), a given step in the process of transformation of the flower into a fruit, or the larva into a nymph (evolutive change), a given phase in an activity such as drinking, eating, fighting (extensive change). See Bergson, Creative Evolution 320. 33 Hence the proximity of the whole issue to the discussion of Zeno’s paradoxes on movement. On this tangle of questions, see Maria Tortajada, “Photography/Cinema: Complementary Paradigms in the Early Twentieth Century,” in Between Still and Moving Images, Laurent Guido and Olivier Lugon, eds. (Herts, UK: John Libbey, 2012) 33-46.

Notes on the Bergsonian Cinematograph

125

following the logic of the analogy, the cinematograph comes first with respect to photography because it opens the transcendental plane where the issue of the coexistence of durations may be formulated – albeit in a way fraught with illusion. Some time later, in Duration and Simultaneity, Bergson was to refer to the same issue as the “simultaneity of flows,” pointing to a different path towards the extensive weaving of durations. Contrary to what an analytical understanding of the matter may lead one to think, the analysis of movement effected in the recording phase (section, capture, immobilization) presupposes, and in that sense anticipates the mechanical synthesis effected by projection – even though the latter actually comes second in the technical evolution of the dispositive. The historical dissociation of the recording device and the projector, the resulting autonomization of the moment of projection, mark a decisive step in the purely mechanical rendering of movement. They also indicate that, where photographic shots could still paint from life, cutting out, so to speak, from the subject – one may recall that photographic impression already served as a template for the operation of perception in Matter and Memory – the images fixed on the cinematographic strip are just abstract units, two degrees removed from the real and condemned to be imparted movement from the outside, through a kind of artificial animation.34 This slightly paradoxical relation of presupposition between photography and cinematography may be better understood if one remembers that Bergson’s concern is not so much homogeneous and mathematical time, the abstract dimension underlying the uses of time as a parameter. Nor is it length-time (“temps-longueur”) or spatialized time in general. Rather, Bergson is interested in the particular intellectual illusion on which the scientific mind must rely to make the coordination of flows effective: it is frame-time as distinct from fiber-time; it is universal time as distinct from the plurality of interlocking local durations, with their particular rhythms or degrees of tension. Thus, cinematographic motion logically comes prior to the photographic image, just as frame-time is presupposed by the cutting out of frames as abstract units of becoming. The nature of the question, the order of reasons underlying the cinematographic analogy, suggest that we give up the common-sense maxim that rules out synthesizing anything not 34 These observations should be tempered or complexified by André Gaudreault’s insightful comments on the intrinsically serial character of the film frame. In ordinary circumstances, one never deals with single frames in isolation. The moving image presents itself as a sui generis unit. See André Gaudreault, “Du simple au multiple: le cinéma comme série de séries,” Cinémas: revue d’études cinématographiques 13.1-2 (2002), especially 38-42. Still, keeping these points in mind, the general line of my argument holds.

126 

Elie During

previously reduced through analysis. It is only in retrospect that synthesis seems to presuppose analysis. In the present case, the artificial synthesis of movement (the false movement par excellence) comes first and the elements of the synthesis (the still frames as putative “fragments” of motion) turn out to be artifacts of the very attempt to obtain movement through recomposition in the first place. No movement is to be produced out of the immobile: so goes the Bergsonian leitmotiv. But there would be no talk of illusion here if we were not convinced of the contrary in practice – better still, if we did not ceaselessly do the opposite.35 The theoretical illusion would not be so powerful if it could not be substantiated by operations which prove to be effective and hinge on reality in some sense. Whatever else may be said of the cinematographic method, it does the trick. While the method may rest upon a fundamental illusion, it is nonetheless a method. Its active component, as we saw earlier, is the abstract movement encapsulated in the idea of frame-time. For if actual movement is to be reconstructed out of still views sampled from it, there is no other choice but to introduce movement surreptitiously somewhere in order to get the process started:36 [I]f we had to do with photographs alone, however much we might look at them, we should never see them animated: with immobility set beside immobility, even endlessly, we could never make movement. In order that the pictures may be animated, there must be movement somewhere. The movement does indeed exist here; it is in the apparatus.37

Yet it is also necessary to check that the operation may indeed be generalized, and notably that it makes it possible to represent together a diversity of movements in their parallel unfolding, following an order of simultaneities that allows them to be brought together in their very dispersion. That is what the cinematograph accomplishes, subjecting photographic sections to the law of uniform run. In other words, it indexes them to a homogeneous time that is not reducible to any of their proper durations or even to any of 35 Likewise, pure duration may not be measured, and yet we do measure something which we call “time.” 36 Similarly, for us to measure anything beyond space, our measuring operations have to be supported by some “real time” participating, in some sense, in the lived duration of a concrete consciousness. This is a recurring theme in Duration and Simultaneity. 37 Bergson, Creative Evolution 322. See Henri Bergson, La Pensée et le mouvant (Paris: PUF, 2007) 7 fn. Author’s note: stunningly enough, all the footnotes appearing in the original French edition have been omitted in the English translation.

Notes on the Bergsonian Cinematograph

127

their spatialized idealizations (timelines, local parameter-times), and allows them to be held together and compared from the standpoint of measurement. Zeno’s paradoxes would seem to us mere mathematical speculations, they would lose much of their grip if they did not consistently rely on such a global framing of the situation. It is because the local movements of Achilles and the tortoise are first projected and seized in the framework of a global, undifferentiated time that makes them commensurable that they may then be treated as space, that their paths may be described as an indefinite series of stages, and so forth. As far as the chronophotographic method is concerned – and Marey’s experiments arguably provided a host of models for devising the Bergsonian “cinematograph” – it is essential to acknowledge that “in setting the temporal variable of the photographic shot, that is, frequency, Marey imposed the fundamental temporal basis with respect to which the uniform movement of the mobile or the variations of its speed may be measured.”38 However, in the “cosmological” perspective that prevails in Creative Evolution, the main function of this temporal basis is to ensure that a diversity of movements, of durations singularized by specific rhythms, find something like a common denominator that enables them to be treated in extension. Absolute time and its uniform flow, introduced by Newton in the General Scholium of his Principia, provided the metaphysical formula of a method commonly adopted by classical mechanics: in the absence of direct access to absolute space, an ideal clock and a privileged system of reference tied to fixed stars made it possible – in principle at least – to frame the world and describe its universal course. The Bergsonian cinematograph and its associated figurative methods (the graphs and space-time diagrams discussed in Duration and Simultaneity) prove instrumental in laying bare the mathematical and conceptual assumptions that make this kind of representation of extensive becoming possible in the first place. Now the orientation of Bergson’s critique will not particularly surprise those who are a little familiar with his philosophy: the problem with frametime is, very simply, that it does not last – it does not retain anything from the hesitation and unpredictability inherent in real change. Yet again, it does not last, not because it is constituted of immobilities, but more deeply because it is not the time of anything in particular. An absolute movement is necessarily an undetermined or “undefined” one, as Bergson puts it.39 If it appears to be discontinuous, or if it may be arbitrarily decomposed ad 38 See Tortajada, “Évaluation, mesure, mouvement” 104. 39 Bergson, Creative Evolution 321.

128 

Elie During

infinitum (which amounts to the same thing), it is in virtue of its being abstract and unreal in proportion. Leibniz intended something similar when he observed that the continuity or infinite divisibility of mathematical time was a sure mark of its ideal character. But in Bergson’s case it is the very form of the problem that leads to this abstraction: cinematographic time appears as science’s answer to the question of knowing by which means a diversity of durations associated to heterogeneous changes – whose local movement is only the most superficial manifestation – may be represented and thought about together. Following Merleau-Ponty, Deleuze identified this issue of coexistence as central to Bergsonism and showed that cinema could take it up, this time positively, provided that one focused on the moving image projected onscreen rather than on the mechanical functioning of the device. For Bergson himself, the cinematograph appeared in its mediating function, at once a foil, a negative image, an epistemological obstacle in Bachelard’s sense, 40 and an instrument of conceptual precision designed to bring attention to the fine differentiation between two senses of time, in conformity to a duality of tendencies running through the heart of the scientific view of the universe: global time (homogeneous, absolute, generic) and local time (differentiated, relational, individual).

40 I elaborate upon this idea in During, “Vie et mort du cinématographe.”



The Stereopticon and Cinema Media Form or Platform? Charles Musser

Today, many academics working in the Humanities and Social Sciences are pursuing a broad interest in media studies. At least at Yale University, where we have created an interdisciplinary seminar in this area, what we mean by media studies – our actual focuses and concerns – differ substantially. In the English Department, for instance, Media Studies foregrounds the study of the book and the move from the scroll or codex. In the more contemporary context, Michael Warner and Jessica Pressman are clearly interested in the way the digital media and the Internet are impacting the book and print culture more generally. Part of this re-orientation de-centers poetry and literature and embraces the study of low and quotidian forms of culture for which aesthetic concerns are far from primary: the sermon, the newspaper, the broadside or even the form (typically a document with spaces for the writer to fill in information).1 History of Art has sometimes moved in similar directions, as Oliver Grau and others have investigated the history of the image.2 However, as Thomas Elsaesser suggests, the field has also explored the ways in which new media forms have entered and often transformed artistic practices as presented in the museum and art gallery through installation art. These approaches are connected only in a highly attenuated way with notions of “the media” in political science and sociology. The media refers to the press: the newspaper, the telegraph, then radio, television and now the Internet – in short, the mass media. In this conception of media studies, film is barely acknowledged.3 When talking about the nineteenth- and twentieth-century dissemination of the news, newsreels and film more generally are typically never mentioned.

1 Lisa Gitelman, “A Brief History of _____,” Theory and Media Studies Colloquium sponsored by the Yale English Department, 12 Nov. 2009. 2 Oliver Grau. Virtual Art: From Illusion to Immersion (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2003). See also David Joselit, Feedback: Television against Democracy (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2007). 3 In Sociology at Yale, an active interest in Media Studies has been pursued by Ron Eyerman and by Jeffrey C. Alexander, who recently published The Performance of Politics: Obama’s Victory and the Democratic Struggle for Power (New York: Oxford University Press, 2010).

130 

Charles Musser

Film Studies, which perhaps started to fill a gap between History of Art and Literature/Language departments, expanded to embrace television and then, in a peripheral way, radio. Walter Benjamin, with his essay “The Work of Art in the Age of Its Technological Reproducibility,” soon became a touchstone, which allows for a more fully developed media studies that includes photography and the phonograph. And now, it has expanded again to include digital media, the Internet and an array of screens – on cell phones and in airline terminals. 4 Although there are divisions in Film Studies at Yale, Francesco Casetti and Thomas Elsaesser are among those pushing Film Studies in a Media Studies direction.5 There is, however, yet another approach to media studies that comes out of Anthropology and Performance Studies – disciplines that are themselves closely aligned in the United States.6 In fact, Performance Studies has its antecedents in Theater Studies; and the move from Film Studies to Media Studies in one discipline is matched by the move from Theater Studies to Performance Studies in the other. Here, the broad field of performance includes oratory, theater, sports, religious and state rituals as well as parades, demonstrations and the performance of self in everyday life. Although this has sometimes led to a certain fetishism of “liveness,” it brings attention to forms of communication and artistic production in which the “dispositif,” or apparatus, of technological reproducibility is less central and even absent. At Yale this orientation is well represented by Joe Roach and Paige McKinley.7 When dealing with the nineteenth century (but other time periods as well), employing a broad conception of media – one that does not assume technological reproducibility as a prerequisite – and placing the media form under investigation within a broader media formation are crucial. Media Studies brings with it a new set of terms, most of which are ambiguous and fraught (as the different approaches to Media Studies itself might predict). The term “apparatus” has had a quite narrow definition in the world of media and film – referring to a specific machine such as a 4 William Boddy, “Any platform. Any media. Anywhere: Targeting Contemporary Television’s Dispersed Audience,” presentation, Yale University, 26 Feb. 2009. 5 Francesco Casetti, “Filmic experience,” Screen, 50.1 (Spring 2009): 56-66. Others working in this direction include John MacKay, J. D. Connor and Aaron Gerow. 6 NYU’s Theater Studies Department, under the leadership of Richard Schechner, was transformed into Performance Studies in the 1990s with the addition of faculty members such as Barbara Kirshenblatt-Gimblet, who received her Ph.D. in Folklore, and Michael Taussig, who received his Ph.D. in Anthropology. 7 Joseph Roach, Cities of the Dead: Circum-Atlantic Performance (New York; Columbia University Press 1996); Paige McGinley, “Sound Travels: Performing Diaspora and the Imagined American South,” diss., Brown University, 2007.

The Stereopticon and Cinema

131

camera or a projector. In this respect, the motion picture system invented by Edison was a system of apparatuses involving cameras, printers, developing and drying systems for film, and projectors (even rewinds). In the 1970s and 1980s film scholars often looked toward Jean-Louis Baudry and the “apparatus theory,” which saw cinema as an ideological machine defined by its mechanics of representation. This reductive approach, which seemed a fine example of infantile leftism for those of us who were working in social-issue documentary, borrowed something from Louis Althusser’s analysis of Ideological State Apparatuses (ISAs), which include the educational system, the media (perhaps most specifically the mass media) and so forth. In an era where it is felt to be intellectually more current and perhaps politically safer to be a Foucauldian than a Marxist, François Albera and Maria Tortajada follow Giorgio Agamben and his evocation of Foucault to revitalize Baudry’s notion of apparatus, giving it new valences and increased flexibility in relation to the kinds of media forms to which such an approach can be applied (i.e., beyond the cinema apparatus). 8 In an era when media technologies are seemingly in constant flux, there is value in approaches that do not assume stable media forms and media specificities. Yet at what point do closely related dispositives (the term chosen by Albera and Tortajada) constitute a de facto media form? Another category, itself open to variable definitions, involves platforms. These are points to which this essay will return. One approach which many media scholars at Yale University and the University of Lausanne share with Lisa Gitelman is an interest in the changing media formations in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries and in the late twentieth and early twenty-first centuries.9 For the early twenty-first century, the vast array of screens – differing in sizes, technologies, locations and purposes – has become of central concern.10 The screen was an important cultural platform in the nineteenth century; and while it has enjoyed considerable antiquarian interest, screen practices in this earlier episteme have continued to be under-examined within contemporary academic discourse. Part of the problem may be that the screen’s status is uncertain. At its base, screen practice involves a dispositive which 8 Giorgio Agamben, What is an Apparatus? and Other Essays (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2009); Cinema Beyond Film: Media Epistemology in the Modern Era, François Albera and Maria Tortajada, eds. (Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press, 2010). 9 Lisa Gitelman, Always Already New: Media, History, and the Data of Culture (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2008). 10 Anne Friedberg, The Virtual Window: From Alberti to Microsoft (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2006).

132 

Charles Musser

includes 1) an image on a support material (glass, celluloid, video tape) 2) projected by a lantern onto 3) a surface (“the screen”) and 4) a viewer who realizes that s/he is watching an (audio-)visual representation and not real life (i.e., magic). (Among other things, this description largely effaces both image production and the showman/exhibitor.) Is the magic lantern – the screen’s initial configuration – a minor, antiquated media form or is the lantern better thought of as a platform? Furthermore, as screen practitioners were rapidly expanding their cultural reach during the second half of the nineteenth century, terminology as well as function changed and were reordered. The magic lantern was largely relegated to the child’s playroom as a toy. In this respect, new technologies that generated modes of screen practice with nomenclature such as “stereopticon” or “optical lantern” deserve closer scrutiny. “Stereopticon,” a term that was widely utilized in the US in the second half of the nineteenth and the first decades of the twentieth centuries, referred to a particular melding of media with platform – that is, the stereopticon was a state-of-the-art magic lantern that projected photographic slides. To sketch its presence as well as its place in a changing media formation, this study uses random word searches (RWSs) for “stereopticon” and a set of related terms such as illustrated lecture, magic lantern, and stereoscope (see table 1). Although RWSs of various newspapers produce some variation in word usage, my efforts for this article are largely confined to The New York Times for the US and, to offer some trans-Atlantic comparisons, The Manchester Guardian and The Observer in the UK. An RWS for the term “stereopticon” generated 295 hits in The New York Times during the period from 1863 (when the term first appeared in the newspaper) to 1879.11 An RWS of “magic lantern” yielded 100 hits in The New York Times between 1851 (the year the newspaper began publication) and 1879, while a related term, “illustrated lecture,” produced 43 items between 1853 and 1879. One must emphasize that this search engine provides only an approximation of usage and generally undercounts the occurrence of such terms (though there are some terms that produce massive overcounts). If the word “illustrated” appears on two lines with a hyphen, it will not show up. Moreover, printing imperfections mean words cannot be read by the machines. I have stumbled upon quite a few such examples from the 11 By way of comparison, an RWS of “stereopticon” in The New York Tribune generated only 24 items in the same period. For whatever reason, The New York Times covered photography and other cultural activities more than the Tribune in the nineteenth century – as a comparative search for news items mentioning Eadweard Muybridge makes clear.

The Stereopticon and Cinema

133

pre-1880 period, which would add significantly to these totals, but have not figured them into this article’s calculations. Some word variants also conceal the degree of usage. For instance, John L. Stoddard, perhaps the premier illustrated lecturer in the US in the 1880s and early 1890s, used the term “stereoptic views,” not “stereopticon views.”12 This suggests that “stereopticon” was such a popular term that it could support affectionate contractions – as “moving pictures” supported and generated the term “movies.” Although the terms “stereopticon” and “illustrated lecture” did not appear in the same New York Times article or advertisement before 1880, “stereopticon” and “lecture” appeared together 90 times (just over 30% of the time when “stereopticon” appeared). This may well have been because the term “stereopticon,” when employed with the term “lecture,” meant “illustrated lecture” and the latter coupling would have offered unnecessary redundancies. In contrast, “magic lantern” and “lecture” appeared together nine times and typically were not directly linked. Thus John MacMullen ran a school in which he gave “Familiar Lectures on History and Geography, every Tuesday and Thursday” and “Magic Lantern and Microscopic Exhibitions every Friday.”13 The English and the Americans may seem to speak the same language, but our linguistic differences are underscored in this study. RWSs in The Manchester Guardian and The Observer indicate that the term “stereopticon” was not used in the UK. It did not appear in these papers until 1903 and only then in dispatches from the US. Rather, the term “magic lantern” retained its prominence, being used in these British publications 758 times between 1826 and 1879. Although the term “illustrated lecture” appeared in the British periodicals 42 times, the terms “illustrated lecture” and “magic lantern” did not appear in the same item before 1880. In contrast, somewhat simplified searches found that the terms “magic lantern” and “lecture” appeared together in 41 items, while the terms “lantern” and “lecture” generated 139 hits. Subsequent RWSs have been broken down by decade: in the 1880s the term “stereopticon” generated 297 hits in The New York Times, “illustrated lecture” produced 890 hits, and the two were cited together a modest ten 12 “Amusements,” New York Times 20 Mar. 1881: 11. A search for the term “stereoptic” also generated some uses of the term “stereopticon” which suffered printing imperfections. 13 Advertisement, New York Times 18 Dec. 1858: 3. Or, they might be used in reports from Europe where the term Stereopticon was not employed. See “The Voltaire Centenary,” New York Times 16 June 1878: 4.

134 

Charles Musser

times. Consistent with previous usage, the term “lecture” was linked with “stereopticon” much more frequently – 122 times (about 40% of the time that “stereopticon” appeared). The stereopticon was being used heavily for lectures and these might involve wording such as “The Rev Dr. Eccleston Will deliver his new lecture on ST. PAUL’S CATHEDRAL illustrated with 50 stereopticon views.”14 The term magic lantern appeared 58 times but once again it never appeared in conjunction with the term “illustrated lecture.” Indeed, “magic lantern” only generated six hits in conjunction with the term “lecture” in the 1880s, as the magic lantern was more and more associated with non-lecture uses. As the accompanying table shows, the American newspaper used the term “stereopticon” with increased frequency in the 1890s (generating 526 hits) and perhaps stabilized in the following decade with 405 citations before its use began to decline. By the 1930s, the media formation in the US had undergone profound transformations, including but hardly limited to the arrival of sync sound motion pictures and the emergence of new terms such as “documentary” in the late 1920s.15 The term “slide projector” began to appear in The New York Times at the same time – generating three references in 1926-7. This included an advertisement for a “film slide projector” accompanied by a letter from Douglas Fairbanks declaring “I think the idea of using films in place of glass slides is an excellent one.”16 Writing to the Times, one educational film professional referred to “the stereopticon slide projector.”17 Four more references appear between 1935 and 1939, including an article referring to the use of “lantern slide projectors” – rather than stereopticons.18 Such usage suggests that writers were becoming less comfortable with the term “stereopticon,” perhaps because its nineteenth-century connotations did not adequately characterize the specific configurations of the contemporaneous lantern dispositive. In 1940, Macy’s ran advertisements selling the Keystone 35mm slide projector, and 14 “Amusements,” New York Times 19 Jan. 1880: 7. 15 The term “documentary” or “documentary films” seems to have been imported to the US from French-speaking parts of Europe. In “Vatican Repudiates Attack on Our Movies,” the Catholic Church applauded “instructive documentary films” being made in Belgium. New York Times 29 July 1927: 17. 16 Advertisement, New York Times 2 May 1926: SM23. 17 “Educational Motion Pictures,” New York Times 14 Nov. 1926: X16. 18 “Our Parks as Teachers,” New York Times 26 May 1935: X25. Classified ads for “lantern slide projectors” can be found in The Chicago Tribune and other newspapers by 1919. Photographic journals occasionally provide advertisements, such as one for the Ingento Stereopticon, which is described as “the most perfect and complete lantern-slide projector on the market.” Advertisement, Photo Era 1 Feb. 1913: 2.

The Stereopticon and Cinema

135

from this point onward, the term “slide projector” appeared more regularly with 127 mentions in The New York Times during the 1940s and 676 during the 1950s.19 The term “slide show” appeared two or three times a decade from the 1890s to the 1940s, suggesting its use as a chance description; but it became popularized in the 1950s, and was used with considerable frequency from the 1970s to the 1990s. Such shifts in technology and nomenclature contributed to the rapid decline in the usage of “stereopticon,” its employment only continuing after World War II in a few residual categories. Although discourse between the American Civil War (1860s) and World War II clearly recognized that the stereopticon involved the same basic kind of projecting device as the magic lantern and was one of its descendents, it also made clear that the two possessed distinct characteristics. One reporter, writing in 1869, explained: The common magic-lantern is usually made of tin, has an oil-lamp inside, and is provided with a chimney to carry off the smoke. One of the two large lenses, ground to a curve of short radius and called bulls’ eyes, are [sic.] placed in front of the lamp, and beyond this is a common colored picture on glass. Then comes one or two more smaller lenses, throwing an image of this picture on the wall, and, as well, too, the equally diffused light of the lamp. […] The so-called stereopticon is virtually the same thing, only instead of a comparatively weak, feeble lamp-flame, the powerful hydro-oxygen lime-light is used; in place of the common lenses, the perfected achromatic lenses as used for photographic portraiture; and finally instead of a common glass picture, a photographic glass slide like those used for the stereoscope. The stronger the light, the more perfect the lenses and the microscopic finish of the picture, the greater is the degree of the magnifying power that may be employed. In this case it is of course much greater than is possible when the common magic lantern is used.20

The two terms were rarely confused. “Stereopticon” was the new, dynamic and modern term that was explicitly connected to photography. The magic lantern was pre-photographic and associated with painting and somewhat related representation techniques (such as lithography). For instance, in 1886 a New York Times critic complained of “the injudicious use of the magic lan19 Advertisement, New York Times, 25 Dec. 1940: 9. 20 “The Magic-Lantern,” The Manufacturer and Builder: A Practical Journal of Industrial Progress 1 July 1869: 199.

136 

Charles Musser

tern for purposes of projecting pictures of flying Walkyries on the clouds” in the Metropolitan Opera’s production of Wagner’s Die Walküre.21 Sometimes “magic lantern” was used generically, as the underlying term, but it was more generally associated with children’s tales as well as representations of ghosts and the supernatural – tied in some ways to the phantasmagoria performances that became popular in the 1790s.22 What were the comparable dynamics in the UK? First, changes in terminology were more gradual, with some shifts beginning before photography was projected by the lantern circa 1850. For the 1880s, the two British periodicals generated 212 mentions of “magic lantern,” while “magic lantern” and “lecture” appeared together twenty times and “lantern” with “lecture” 88 times. As this might suggest, the term “magic” was sometimes dropped and “lantern” began to be modified by other terms. In an advertisement from 1825, an optician was offering to give instructive lectures on astronomy using a “Phantasmagoria Lantern.”23 In 1852, a Mr. Turner was using Vincent Beechey’s trinoptric lantern.24 In 1855, the Institutional Association for Lancashire and Cheshire had bought an oxy-hydrogen lantern.25 Indeed, lecturers often boasted of using an “oxy-hydrogen lantern,” which conveyed a type of projector with a stronger light source than the average magic lantern.26 Somewhat later Herbert Birch offered a lecture, Rambles in Greece, which was “illustrated by Photographs shown by lime-light lantern.”27 In this promotion and organization of the dispositive, the British placed emphasis on the lantern as a platform for projecting images of various kinds – photographs, in Birch’s case. In specifying the kind of lantern to be used, the British sought to indicate one of the key variables of the evening’s presentation.28 In the US, the term Stereopticon suggested a more radical 21 “Metropolitan Opera House,” New York Times 6 Mar. 1886: 5. 22 See Charles Musser, The Emergence of Cinema: The American Screen to 1907 (1990; Berkeley, Los Angeles: The University of California Press, 1994). 23 Advertisement, The Observer 27 Mar. 1825: 3. 24 “Local and Provincial,” The Manchester Guardian 21 Jan. 1852: 5. 25 “Institutional Association for Lancashire and Cheshire,” The Manchester Guardian 17 Nov. 1855: 5. 26 “Marylebone Institution,” The Observer 26 April 1863; “Lecture on Mount Sinai,” The Manchester Guardian 18 Dec. 1874: 6. 27 “Rambles in Greece,” The Manchester Guardian 25 Oct. 1881: 1. 28 A partial and minor exception was the term “optical lantern,” which enjoyed a vogue at the turn of the century with 49 hits in the 1890s and 24 in the following decade. “Optical” referred, I believe, not only to the optics of the lantern itself but referenced the optics of the photographic process as well. The term was first mentioned in these periodicals in 1881 when the Manchester Photographic Society offered “a display of views by the aid of the optical lantern.” “Manchester Photographic Exhibition,” The Manchester Guardian 28 Nov. 1881: 8.

The Stereopticon and Cinema

137

reorganization of production, and the embrace of something akin to a new media form.29

The Stereopticon: Early History The early history of the stereopticon – its formation as a dispositive – was closely linked with the stereoscope with which it was occasionally confused. The latter was a popular instrument for viewing photographic images that owed its immense popularity to the illusion of depth that was created when the spectator looked at two pictures of an object, each taken from a slightly different perspective.30 As Jonathan Crary makes clear, this viewing mechanism, invented in England by Charles Wheatstone in 1838, was developed completely independent of photography.31 Nevertheless, The Manchester Guardian mentioned the stereoscope only once in passing in 1838 (The Observer not at all) and not again until it became popular when Sir William Brewster developed an inexpensive viewer in 1850.32 By this time, the stereoscope was linked to photography: it was one of several platforms that could be used for its exhibition and dissemination. (Moreover, stereographs or stereoscopic photographs were certainly considered a special kind of photography.) London-based photographer Antoine Claudet was the first to advertise views for the stereoscope in The Observer of 1851. Selling his “stereoscopic daguerotype [sic] views” of the London Crystal Palace Exhibition, he also offered to take “stereoscope portraits from life”: “Uncoloured they are no longer pictures, but real statues, and when coloured they appear life itself. The illusion of solidity is startling and persons looking at these new productions, the result of Professor Wheatstone’s beautiful discovery of binocular vision, cannot but think that they have before their eyes real tangible models.”33 RWSs of “stereoscope” in The Manchester Guardian and Observer produce 256 items between 1851 and 1859, 369 items in the 1860s, but only 39 in the 1870s and 36 items in the 1880s. The stereoscope’s 29 Valentine Robert has indicated that in France, the term “projections lumineuses” emerged as an alternative to “lanterne magique,” to cover the use of the lantern with photographs and illustrated lectures. E-mail to the author, 18 May 2011. 30 John Jones, Wonders of the Stereoscope (New York: Alfred A Knopf, 1976). 31 Jonathan Crary, Techniques of the Observer (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1990) 9, 118. 32 “British Association for the Advancement of Science,” The Manchester Guardian 29 Aug. 1838: 1. 33 “Public Announcements,” The Observer 16 Nov. 1851: 1. See also “Public Announcements,” The Observer 23 Nov. 1851: 1.

138 

Charles Musser

fluctuating popularity in the US is suggested by an RWS of the term in The New York Times: 99 items between 1852 and 1859, 75 items in the 1860s (versus 89 for stereopticon), 54 in the 1870s (versus 206 for the stereopticon) but 152 in the 1880s, followed by a big drop in subsequent decades. Although the term “stereopticon” appeared more often than “stereoscope” in The New York Times from the 1860s onward, a shift did not occur in many other US newspapers until the 1880s.34 The development of photography did not give lanternists initial access to projected photographic images: this had to wait for the development of the albumen and collodion processes in the late 1840s. These new photographic techniques enabled a photographic image to be transferred to a glass surface while earlier processes (Daguerrotypes and Talbotypes) had used either a silver-plated copper surface or paper as a base. When John A. Whipple and William B. Jones of Boston patented an albumen process (using egg whites as an adhering agent) in June 1850, they had apparently been using it for several years.35 The Langenheim Brothers, William and Frederick, had also been working with the albumen process and played an important role in the introduction of photographic lantern slides.36 During the 1840s, the Langenheims facilitated the introduction of several new photographic processes into the US. Interested in the process of paper photography developed by William Henry Fox Talbot, they became its exclusive agents in the US. While licensing the Talbotype process was not commercially rewarding, the venture encouraged them to adopt and to improve the albumen process. Employing glass as a support for the emulsion, the Langenheims began making photographic lantern slides. In introducing these new slides the brothers claimed: The new magic-lantern pictures on glass, being produced by the action of light alone on a prepared glass plate, by means of the camera obscura, must throw the old style of magic lantern slides into the shade, 34 The Baltimore Sun provides one example. An RWS of the terms stereoscope/stereopticon yields: for 1852-1959: 75/0; 1860-1869: 285/42; 1870-1879: 293/33; 1880-1889: 9/74; and 1890-1899: 29/255. The overwhelming number of citations for the stereoscope were advertisements for consumer purchase. 35 Patent no. 7,458, Improvement in Producing Photographic Pictures upon Transparent Media, issued 25 June 1850. 36 Louis Walton Sipley, “The Magic Lantern,” Pennsylvania Arts and Sciences 4 (Dec. 1939): 3943+; Louis Walton Sipley, “W and F. Langenheim-Photographers,” Pennsylvania Arts and Sciences (193?), 25-31. The crucial work on the magic lantern in the United States remains Xenophon Theodore Barber, Evening of Wonders: A History of the Magic Lantern Show in America, diss., New York University, 1993.

The Stereopticon and Cinema

139

and supersede them at once, on account of the greater accuracy of the smallest detail which are drawn and fixed on glass from nature, by the camera obscura, with a fidelity truly astonishing. By magnifying these new slides through the magic lantern, the representation is nature itself again, omitting all defects and incorrectness in the drawing which can never be avoided in painting a picture on the small scale required for the old slides.37

By 1851 they were exhibiting slides at London’s Crystal Palace Exhibition, where these Hyalotypes received extensive praise.38 Views were of buildings and landmarks in Philadelphia (United States Custom House, Penitentiary of Pennsylvania), Washington (Smithsonian, the Capitol), and New York (Croton Aqueduct) as well as portraits of well-known Americans. Their early positive pictures on glass slides were mounted in rectangular wooden frames that were 35/8 x 67/8 inches with a 23/4 inch or 3 inch circular opening for the image. Many were hand colored and they cost $4 to $5 a piece. The Langenheims thus saw their introduction of photograph slides as an extension of existing magic lantern practices. The progress made in photographic processes moved back and forth between Europe and the US as the Langenheims’ innovations were adapted to the stereoscope. The move from daguerreotypes to more modern photographic images for the stereoscope was not straightforward. Writing for the Philadelphia Photographer, M.A. Root reported that Mr. Niepce’s process of making negative pictures by using albumen in combination with iodide of potassium, was published in the early part of 1848. In this, his process, he states distinctly that the positive pictures are always best taken on paper. Mr. Langenheim informs me that he, “by modifying Niepce’s process, obtained the first positive pictures on glass to be viewed by transmitted light, in 1848.” And “in 1849” he says, “I exhibited for the first time such positive glass pictures by means of the magic lantern in the Merchants’ Exchange at Philadelphia. While in Paris, in 1853, I was introduced to the celebrated optician Dubosque-Soleil, to whom I showed some of my magic lantern pictures, made by me in Philadelphia. He was delighted with them, and asked my 37 The Langenheims, quoted in The Art-Journal (London) Apr. 1851: 106. 38 See “The King of Arms,” The Observer 4 May 1851: 3.

140 

Charles Musser

permission to show them in a scientific magic lantern exhibition, which he had to give in one of the public institutions, and during this exhibition he showed these pictures, stating to the audience that they were the first pictures of the kind ever shown in Paris. In conversation, Mr. Dubosque told me that when he was engaged in 1851, to arrange the display of his articles for the “World’s Fair” in London, he saw my photo magic lantern pictures, the first he had ever seen, and thinking that such photo-positive pictures on glass might be used to supersede the daguerreotype pictures, until then manufactured for him by Mr. Ferrier; he had at once written to Mr. Ferrier, to come over to London to examine my transparent positive pictures taken on glass, and that since then they had tried and made such transparent positive pictures on glass for the stereoscope.”39

Photographers in France and England soon enjoyed a booming business in making glass slides for the stereoscope, but this innovation happened somewhat later in the US. It was again the Langenheims who responded to European developments by making the first stereoscopic glass slides in the US during the summer of 1854. 40 Nevertheless, in the latter part of 1858 the production and sale of stereoscopic glass slides was still getting started in New York City, with landscapes on paper selling from $6 to $9 per dozen and landscapes on glass from $15 to $30. 41 Antoine Claudet tried to project individual halves of a stereoscopic slide and retain or re-create a 3-D effect in 1857. 42 The resulting achievement, which he called the Stereomonoscope, received significant attention in the press and among scientific journals. The Chicago Press and Tribune reported: M. Claudet, the veteran photographer, has accomplished a particularly [impressive] result in his art, enabling him to produce the stereoscopic illusion by the agency of a single picture. In the centre of a large black screen, there is a space filled with a square of ground glass, upon which, by some light managed behind the screen, is thrown a magnif ied photographic image representing a landscape, a portrait, or any other 39 M. A. Root, “The Magic Lantern. Its History and Uses for Educational and Other Purposes,” The Philadelphia Photographer 1 Dec. 1874: 11. 40 Frederick Langenheim to H. H. Snelling, 19 Sept. 1854, in “Personal and Fine Art Intelligence,” Photographic and Fine Arts Journal 1 Oct. 1854: 319. 41 “The Stereoscope,” New York Tribune 9 Nov. 1858: 3. 42 “Photographic Inventions,” Scientific American 25 May 1861: 326.

The Stereopticon and Cinema

141

object. When the observer looks naturally at the object or picture, with the two eyes, without help of any optical instrument, an extraordinary phenomenon takes place – the picture is seen in perfect relief, as when two different pictures are looked at through a stereoscope. […] By this remarkable discover [sic], M. Claudet has solved a problem which has always been considered an impossibility by scientif ic men – for the stereomonoscope, by its very name, must sound like a paradox to the ears of those who are versed in the knowledge of the principles of binocular vision, until they have had the opportunity of repeating the experiments by which M. Claudet has found a new fact which they had not noticed or explained before. 43

In fact, although projecting a single photographic image did not produce a 3-D effect, viewers did experience a visceral sense of depth that was much stronger than if a photograph was merely viewed on paper or a metal surface. Claudet believed (wrongly) that projecting a photographic image onto a ground glass was the key to retaining a three-dimensional sense of depth. Chemist John Fallon of Lawrence, Massachusetts, apparently acquired one of Claudet’s lanterns and, after refiguring and discarding elements, offered what was referred to as an “improved stereopticon,” which he exhibited in the 1860s. According to one press report, Although the stereopticon was exhibited for a time in the Polytechnic Institute, and in the Hall of Illustration, Regent’s Park, London, yet it did not advance beyond the first discovery. J. Fallon, Esq., of Lawrence Mass, the chemist of the Pacific Mills, who has devoted thirty years to photology, imported from England one of these instruments for his own family. But under his hands it was developed into something so perfect that his friends desired that others might have the pleasure which he enjoyed. He has sent it forth on a charitable mission, and for churches, Sabbath schools, and sanitary commissions its charities can be counted by thousands. In Massachusetts, such men as Prof. Agassiz, Longfellow, Hillard, Holmes, Rev. Dr. Park, and many other leading representative men “assisted” with delight at many of the exhibitions, and the first two aided in delineating the scenes. 44 43 “New Inventions,” Chicago Press and Tribune 14 May 1859: 3. 44 “An Optical Wonder,” Louisville Daily Journal 29 Apr. 1863: 1. The same basic review was also reprinted in The Merchants’ Magazine and Commercial Review 48 (May 1863): 430.

142 

Charles Musser

By January 1861, announcements for the Stereopticon were appearing in such American periodicals as the Saturday Evening Post, which remarked that “[I]t produces in a wonderful degree the impression that you are gazing upon the real scenes and objects represented.”45 Arthur’s Home Magazine hailed this “triumph of science and art combined” and declared, “No picture or dioramic view is comparable with the ‘Stereopticon’ in giving a just idea of scenery or architecture. You seem to stand in the very place that is represented, and to see everything just as it exists, in all its true portions.”46 After being exhibited in the Boston area and in nontheatrical venues, Fallon’s Stereopticon opened at Toro Hall in Hartford, Connecticut, on December 23, 1862, where the effects were declared to be “brilliant and startling, and the representations singularly truthful.”47 It then moved to Hartford’s larger and more prestigious Allyn Hall for a week in midJanuary. 48 Exhibitor J. Leyland supervised the Brooklyn, New York, debut of this “scientific wonder of the age” at the Atheneum on April 14, 1863. Although audiences were embarrassingly small at first, the city’s leading citizens (including Mayor M. B. Kablefleisch and Charles J. Sprague) urged Fallon and Leyland to remain “so that all may enjoy its beauties and profit by its instructions.”49 It ultimately ran almost continuously for six weeks with a 25¢ admission fee. The evening debut consisted of “a choice selection of landscapes, architectural views and sculptures gathered from travels in the most illustrious parts of Europe, Asia and our own country.”50 The mistaken belief that “half of a stereoscopic view could be made to present a solid (i.e., stereoscopic) effect” persisted.51 The New York Journal of Commerce commented that the Stereopticon has been developed in something so brilliant and beautiful that the pictures produced are as much beyond the ordinary photograph as that, in fidelity and beauty, is beyond the old fashioned engraving. In short, 45 “The Stereopticon,” Saturday Evening Post 5 Jan. 1861: 2. 46 “The Stereopticon,” Arthur’s Home Magazine April 1861: 17. Whether all these stereopticons can be attributed to Fallon is unclear: a stereopticon was shown at Temperance Temple in Baltimore on February 4, 1862, but it was quite possibly a renamed magic lantern and not Fallon’s. “Temperance Temple,” Baltimore Sun 4 Feb. 1862: 2. 47 “Amusements,” Hartford Courant 18 Dec. 1862: 2. 48 Advertisement, Hartford Courant 12 Jan. 1863: 3; “The Stereopticon,” Hartford Courant 14 Jan. 1863: 2. 49 Mayor M. B. Kablefleisch et al. to John Fallon, 25 Apr. 1863, reprinted in Brooklyn Eagle 4 May 1863: 17. 50 “The Stereopticon at the Atheneum,” Brooklyn Eagle 15 Apr. 1863: 3. 51 The New York Journal of Commerce as quoted in Louisville Daily Journal 29 Apr. 1863: 1.

The Stereopticon and Cinema

143

the delight which one person has in looking through the stereoscope, a thousand persons can have at once – so that there is sympathetic and social pleasure. The Stereopticon, as it is called, takes the ordinary glass stereoscopic view, and by fine lenses and the most intense of artificial lights, throws and magnifies the miniature view upon a canvas to such an extent that every one in a building as vast as the Academy of Music can see with distinctness each scene. There is no straining of the vision; there is no wearying of the eye as in the stereoscope, but one merely sits and gazes upon the sublime scenery of the Alps, the renowned old abbeys, the busy streets of London, Paris[,] Naples, and Grand Cairo; the grand, awe-striking remains of Egypt, and the solemn instructive scenes of Palestine. In the same manner and with the same ease that we look upon a real landscape from the deck of a Hudson River steamer. The distant and the rare are brought to us – or rather like a magic mat of the Arabian tale we are borne on swift and brilliant wings to the ends of the earth. The treasures of statuary art from the Louvre, the Vatican and the Museo Borbonico are ours. Nothing seems so dream-like as the Apollo Belvedere, the Venus de Medici, and the chefs d’oeuvre of the great Thorwalden, which appear upon the scene in all their roundness and beauty.52

Another reviewer echoed many of the same sentiments, remarking that “you can imagine yourself borne away on the enchanted carpet of the Arabian tale, and brought where you can look down upon the veritable Paris, and Rome, and Egypt.”53 Leyland soon made almost daily program changes, devoting each illustrated lecture to a specific country or region: Great Britain, France, Switzerland and the Rhine, and Italy.54 For another popular program, the “wall photographer” exhibited photographs of statuary. These evening shows – with Wednesday and Saturday matinees at a reduced fee – were “attended by the learned and scientific portion of society as well as others.”55 A combination of factors contributed to the sense that the stereopticon was a new and important media form. The powerful illusory effect of the stereopticon was similar to the experience that spectators would have with the first projected films – the sense of being transported to a different 52 53 54 55

The New York Journal of Commerce as quoted in Louisville Daily Journal 29 Apr. 1863: 1. “Modern Miracles,” Brooklyn Eagle 15 Apr. 1863: 3. Brooklyn Eagle 29 Apr. 1863: 1 and 15 May 1863: 1. “The Stereopticon,” Brooklyn Eagle 7 May 1863: 3.

144 

Charles Musser

place (and time). Commentators were impressed by the realism and the immediacy of the image – with the sense of “being there.” These “wonderful exhibitions” produced “brilliant and startling” effects as well as representations that were “singularly truthful.” “The Old World and the New, are brought in all their beauty and grandeur to our very doors.”56 Francesco Casetti has argued that a key aspect of media involves principles of relocation.57 And certainly this was an unprecedented aspect of the stereopticon. Public spaces, sculpture and so forth were relocated onto the screen as if from life. Statuary was particularly notable because the stereopticon emphasized three-dimensionality and both were static in nature. The use of a newly powerful projector and light source sharpened the image and its distinctiveness, adding to a sense of a new media dispositive. Why then did the stereopticon fail to be recognized as a new media form over time? One way to address this question is by comparing its dispositive to that of motion pictures or the cinema itself. Put another way, the stereopticon did not involve a sufficiently distinctive practice. Those who made photographic slides for the stereopticon, artists such as the Langenheims, were photographers. The making of stereopticon slides was directly connected to the making of images for the stereoscope. A glass slide for the stereoscope could be cut in half and turned into two stereopticon slides. So the production of stereopticon slides was part of a larger practice. And it was easy for these images to be used in other media forms. We have significant records of nineteenth-century illustrated lectures because many of them were relocated – reproduced – in heavily illustrated books. In contrast, from the beginning, motion picture production was distinct. There is also the issue of projection technology – of the stereopticon itself, which was not as distinct as its enthusiasts would have it. The stereopticon was a lantern that could easily project non-photographic slides – slides made with lithography, those that were painted or hand-drawn or even slides of things in nature placed between two pieces of glass (the wing of a fly, a flower, etc.). It could be readily adapted to show a kaleidoscope or a narrow aquarium. More generally, from the point of view of exhibition and also reception, stereopticon presentations fell under the larger category of the illustrated lecture and the illustrated lecture was part of a larger category of lectures in general. That is, stereopticon presentations brought together

56 “Touro Hall,” Hartford Courant 24 Dec. 1862: 2. 57 Francesco Casetti, “Elsewhere. The relocation of art,” in Valencia09/Confines (Valencia: INVAM, 2009) 348-51.

The Stereopticon and Cinema

145

a number of different, overlapping practices, but these never formed their own distinctive field. This returns us also to the importance of examining a phenomenon such as stereopticon exhibitions within a larger media formation. On one hand, there is the field of photography, which is a distinct media form, and on the other there is the lantern projector, which is a distinct platform. However, the process and the sites of exhibition were connected to the lecture in general. Moreover, the lecturer was a performer and presented as the central “author” of the exhibition, whether or not he or she was responsible for taking the photographs and making the slides. These photographs were said to illustrate the lecture, making them subservient in principle if perhaps not always in practice to the oratory of the lecturer. It is important to recognize that the lecture was one of the dominant media forms of the nineteenth century and had its own conventions, practices and economic infrastructure. (See, for instance, reports on Major Pond’s own illustrated lecture on representing the stars of the lecture circuit.58) Media scholars, concerned with the emerging dispositives of modernity – of technological reproducibility – fail to appreciate its importance. And yet, one category of illustrated lecture that should interest them is the scientific or technological demonstration. In fact, the first uses of the term “illustrated lecture” that appeared in The New York Times were of this general type: for instance, Dr. Robert A. Fisher gave an illustrated lecture on “Gunpowder, Cannon and Projectiles” for which he used diagrams, models, shells and chemical experiments.59 The lecture, moreover, was only one genre of oratory in the nineteenth-century public sphere, which would also include the sermon and the political speech. The stereopticon, with its illustrated lecture, participated in a range of media formations that varied with genre and shifted over time – all aligned with the discourse of sobriety that has been discussed by Bill Nichols in a somewhat later context.60 Beyond oratory itself, it was increasingly connected to various forms of print culture – books, magazines, newspapers and a range of ephemera (circulars, broadsides and so forth). Photography – with the stereoscope and accompanying stereographs for home use – was also of some note. Undoubtedly the best-known and most popular genre during the nineteenth century was the travel lecture with its books and 58 “Major Pond’s Memories,” New York Times 18 Jan. 1896: 5. 59 “Lecture at Plymouth Church,” New York Times 11 Jan. 1862: 3. 60 Bill Nichols, Representing Reality: Issues and Concepts in Documentary (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1991).

146 

Charles Musser

increasing ties to the emergent tourist industry. Other illustrated lectures were religious in nature: as Professor J. Leonard Corning of the Chautauqua University remarked, every pastor should have a stereopticon “to illustrate Bible scenes.”61 Such stereopticon lectures were more connected to the sermon and a still vibrant church-based Protestant culture that was opposed to theater and other forms of amusement. Yet a third genre of illustrated lecture was a form of political speech and embedded in the world of politics and newspapers. One prominent instance of this involved President Benjamin Harrison’s 1892 presidential campaign. This was the last US presidential election before cinema appeared and contributed to the ongoing reconfiguration of the media landscape.

The Stereopticon and the 1892 Presidential Election The stereopticon in general, and its use for the illustrated lecture in particular, played an active if previously unexamined role in the 1892 political campaign in which the “Bourbon Democrat” and former President Grover Cleveland was running against President Benjamin Harrison, a Republican. As it turned out, the key battle ground states for electoral victory were New York and, to a lesser extent, Illinois. The candidate who won New York had won the presidency in previous elections – and would do so again in 1892. Campaign activities in New York and its surroundings thus possessed a relevance and urgency that make them an appropriate focus of study. The magic lantern or stereopticon was employed for campaign purposes in unequal ways.62 Republicans used it extensively to give illustrated lectures that focused on a key feature of their party’s platform: tariffs and the value of protectionism. These illustrated lectures functioned as an extension of political oratory, but added a visual dimension that could bolster their rhetorical effectiveness. A number of different lecturers operated in the Northeastern states, most of whom were coordinated through a central Speakers’ Bureau. By mid-October Judge John L. Wheeler of New Jersey had been giving his illustrated lecture on the tariff question for eleven weeks and had “nightly 61 “C.L.S.C. Round-Table,” The Chautauquan (May 1882): 489. 62 In the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, Democrats, Republicans and the city’s newspapers used the stereopticon to project information about the vote on election night so that gathering crowds could follow the returns. See, for instance, “Many Thousands Read the Signals,” New York Herald 9 Nov. 1892: 7.

The Stereopticon and Cinema

147

spoken to an audience which filled the houses to overflowing.”63 The New York Tribune, a Republican newspaper, devoted the most coverage to Elijah R. Kennedy, a well-known insurance broker and locally prominent Brooklyn Republican.64 According to the Tribune, One of the most brilliant engagements of the brilliant campaign which is being fought to restore New Jersey to Republican rule took place at South Orange last night. Major Elijah R. Kennedy, of New York, was in command of the Republican forces. […] It was in the nature of an artillery duel, and Major Kennedy fired solid shot from a double-barreled stereopticon into the ranks of the Democracy, and followed that up with a rattling volley of statistics and arguments.65

Kennedy began with a lengthy speech in which he asserted, “The United States has applied Protection more thoroughly than has any other nation, and has been more highly prospered.” Then, At this point the hall was darkened and the pictorial illustrations of Mr. Kennedy’s argument began. To show the less fortunate condition of people in other countries, views were given which had been taken by Mr. Kennedy with his own Kodak, showing women yoked in harness with cows and dogs, to do the work of horses and oxen; also women carrying enormous burdens through the streets of the most brilliant capitals of Europe, acting as load-carriers in Vienna, and doing all the street-cleaning in Munich. […] Then a portrait of Bismarck was shown, followed by a view of Bismarck’s statement that “the prosperity of America is mainly due to its system of protective laws.”

Kennedy went on to use images as evidence to refute the Democratic Party’s disparagement of tariffs as effective in stimulating local industries, with tin plate manufacture being his prime example. As the brief quotes I have offered here suggest, Kennedy’s lecture was very extensively covered – I almost want to say “relocated” – by the reliably Republican New York Tribune into newspaper form. Indeed, newspapers routinely reported on and 63 “Good Work Through the State: Judge Wheeler Uses the Stereopticon Effectively at Middletown,” New York Tribune 16 Oct. 1892: 2. 64 “A New Brooklyn Park Commissioner,” New York Tribune 31 Jan. 1888: 1. Kennedy was a member of the insurance brokers’ firm of Weed and Kennedy. 65 “Protection Illustrated,” New York Tribune 25 Oct. 1892: 3. This rare, detailed description of an early campaign documentary-like program deserves extensive quotation.

148 

Charles Musser

reprinted campaign speeches, as print and oratory culture worked hand in hand. Complementing the oratory was political pageantry – parades and so forth – also prominently covered in newspapers that shared the same political orientation. The enthusiasm of Kennedy’s assertions was questioned by the proCleveland New York Times, which cited a “letter to the editor” that Kennedy had written to the Tribune in 1890. In it, Kennedy was quite critical of the McKinley tariff, particularly as it might impact on Republican chances in the 1892 presidential election. Minnesota and other western states strongly opposed it.66 Kennedy’s earlier concerns proved well founded, for Cleveland won New York State and gained a second, nonconsecutive term as president. The many illustrated lectures on the tariff were part of an unsuccessful media campaign that contributed to a Republican defeat.

Motion Pictures or Cinema: What is a Media Form? The beginnings of cinema remains a fraught subject – not because we are still concerned with a nationalist rivalry over “firsts,” but precisely because it has affected our conceptions of the media form and the terminology that goes with it. In the US, commercial motion pictures projected in a theatrical setting – what has become known as the cinema – effectively began on April 23, 1896, with the debut of Edison’s Vitascope at Koster & Bial’s Music Hall in New York City. In Europe its beginnings are traditionally associated with the Lumière Cinématographe opening at the Salon Indien of the Grand Café on December 28, 1895. Of course, the introduction of modern motion pictures began somewhat earlier – perhaps with the demonstration of Edison’s Kinetoscope at the Brooklyn Institute on May 10, 1893, or the opening of a kinetoscope parlor in New York City on April 14th, 1894 – events and a practice that had much more visibility in the US. The issue of such beginnings can be complicated further by definitions of “motion pictures” or modern motion pictures. If Edison’s motion pictures, with the peep-hole kinetoscope, offered an initial system of inventions that constituted a nascent media form, it became something more than a passing technological novelty (such as Reynaud’s Praxinoscope) when motion pictures were yoked to the lantern platform and projection. When placed in a theater, projected motion pictures eventually became known as the “cinema” (though in the 66 “For the Stereopticon,” New York Times 28 Oct. 1892: 4. The New York Times editorial was referring to a letter published as “Party Policy and the People,” New York Tribune: 9 Aug. 1890: 7.

The Stereopticon and Cinema

149

US this was only one of many commonly employed terms, including moving pictures, movies, motion pictures and film). In this respect, the stereopticon and the cinema involved the incorporation of innovations in photography within (or onto) the lantern platform. Here again we may encounter an interesting difference between French and American perspectives. The French have tended to see “cinema” as a media form, while Americans have tended to have more ambiguous and even contradictory notions, ones that even depend on imprecision. The ubiquitous use of the term “movies” is one sign of this. We might conceptualize at least one strand of American usage as imagining motion pictures (or film) as a media form, with projection via the lantern as one platform (undoubtedly the dominant one) and cinema – projected motion pictures in a theatrical setting – as a further subcategory (again dominant between roughly 1906 and the late 1940s). If the stereopticon was never fully recognized as a media form, then why, how and when did motion pictures or the cinema gain recognition? One reason is that motion picture production and exhibition required their own unique technologies, including motion picture cameras, printers and projection equipment. All these required their own special knowledge. Motion picture practices were not merely at the intersection of various other established practices, they constituted their own practice from the outset. As is often the case with so-called chicken and egg questions, it is impossible to determine which came f irst. As the system of motion picture production and exhibition was invented, motion picture practices constituted themselves. In this respect, I disagree with André Gaudreault: cinema, or at least motion pictures as a field, did exist from the outset. And not only because it was a distinct techne: motion pictures transformed many different fields of endeavor – photography, theater, sports, politics, news and the newspaper, advertising, the arts and eventually religion and medicine. Moreover, it transformed social mores and our daily lives, often in an explicit and aggressive manner. Even during its initial introduction, cinema created a series of disruptions that anticipated these later transformations. Although cinema’s biggest immediate impact was on screen practices, the stereopticon hardly disappeared over night, but in fact continued to expand. How to best conceptualize and name this new practice and emergent media form was not immediately evident. In the US, where Edison’s peep-hole kinetoscope had enjoyed extensive media coverage, many saw projected motion pictures as an adaptation of Edison’s motion picture system to the lantern. Scientific American thus labeled its front-page article on various early projecting machines as “The Kinetoscope Stereopticon”:

150 

Charles Musser

Ever since the kinetoscope was brought to public attention and proved to be so popular, inventors have been striving to perfect the apparatus for successfully projecting these miniature images upon a screen by means of a stereopticon producing the same effect of motion as in the kinetoscope. […] [T]he problem in the kinetoscope stereopticon was to successfully magnify these little images several times and secure sufficient illumination on the screen to make them appear distinct and clear.67

If cinematography was a special form of photography, then cinema was a special form of the stereopticon. At least, this is the apparent logic behind the Scientific American article. The breakthrough of projected motion pictures generated greater discontinuities than this logic could sustain, and the term was otherwise avoided. In fact, motion pictures could not simply be shown on the stereopticon: they needed a special device and transport system to be placed in front of the lantern. In this respect, the reluctance to apply the term “stereopticon” to the lantern when nonphotographic slides were shown may have reinforced the sense that it was not appropriate to apply it to a device that projected motion pictures. When the Scientific American article was otherwise reprinted in American Amateur Photographer, the term “kinetoscope stereopticon” was changed to “kinetoscope lantern.”68 In the US, a wide variety of names were given to specific projectors and exhibition services – Vitascope, Phantoscope, Biograph, Cinématographe, Kineopticon and so forth. Forced to offer a general term for the new device, commentators in the 1890s might call it a “screen machine” or simply a “projecting machine.”69 The prevalent term became “moving picture machine,” a term that was in use by the end of 1896, when the Western Phonograph Company placed a small classified advertisement proclaiming that the reader could “make money fast and easy exhibiting new moving picture machine, same as the Vitascope.”70 The term first appeared in The New York Times at the end of 1897, again in classified ads. Its first use in an article was in February 1899. An RWS of The New York Times identif ied thirteen appearances of the term in the 1890s, 116 in the 1900s, 220 in the 1910s, 102 in the 1920s and 107 in the 1930s. By the 1930s its continued use was largely due to news items 67 “The Kinetoscope Stereopticon,” Scientific American 31 Oct. 1896: 325. 68 “The Kinetoscope Lantern,” American Amateur Photographer 1 Dec. 1896: 535. 69 Smith Clayton, “Photographs That Live and Move,” Atlanta Constitution 20 Dec. 1896: 21; “E.B. Dunn’s Invention,” New York Times 1 Sept. 1899: 12. 70 “Business Chances,” Chicago Tribune 1 Jan. 1897: 11.

The Stereopticon and Cinema

151

about the projectionists’ union known as the Moving Picture Machine Operators of the United States and Canada.71 The shift from “machine” to “projector” began in the late 1910s with moving picture projector: 19101919: three hits, 1920-1929: eleven hits, 1930-1939: fourteen hits, 1940-1949: seventeen hits, and 1950-1959: six hits; motion picture projector: 1910-1919: eight, 1920-1929: 60, 1930-1939: 67, 1940-1949: 110, and 1950-1959: 75; or film projector: 1910-1919: thirteen; 1920-1929: 109, 1930-1939: 225; 1940-1949: 436; and 1950-1959: 541. The terminological shift from “machine” to “projector” began in the late 1910s as the Classical Hollywood Cinema was being established.72 There are a number of films and programs produced during cinema’s novelty period in which the cinema’s disruptions of established cultural practices are noteworthy. With The John C. Rice-May Irwin Kiss, the cinematic tail wagged the theatrical dog as Rice upstaged his osculatory partner and Irwin had him fired. Nevertheless, the 20-second film turned the middle-aged actor into a kissing star and did much to make kissing an accepted public display of romantic affection. Two evening-length programs in 1897 – The Corbett-Fitzsimmons Fight and The Horitz Passion Play (followed by The Passion Play of Oberammergau early in 1898) – had profound impacts on the sport of boxing and on religion. The Biograph Company’s official debut program in October 1896, which was also a major Republican campaign rally, had a substantive political impact. Rather than a chance experiment, this event was a continuation of – and thus a response to and departure from – earlier uses of the lantern platform by the Republican Party, notably the use of the illustrated lecture in 1892.

Cinema and the 1896 Presidential Election Given that commercial projected motion pictures were only a few months old, it is perhaps surprising that they played a prominent if circumscribed role in the 1896 presidential election between Republican William McKinley and Democrat William Jennings Bryan. However, 71 See, for instance, “Film Deliveries Go On,” New York Times 30 Mar. 1939: 26. 72 This move from “machine” to “projector” preceded somewhat the consolidation around the term “film projector,” which coincided with the emerging popularity of the term “slide projector” in the 1940s and 1950s: thus citations in The New York Times for “slide projector” were: 1920-1929: 3; 1930-1939: 4; 1940-1949: 127; and 1950-1959: 580.

152 

Charles Musser

because New York City was the center of the nascent film industry and pivotal in terms of the election, this conjunction facilitated a dynamic engagement. Certainly Republicans remained interested in exploring innovative ways to use the lantern platform in their campaign. Bryan was a renowned orator and one reason William McKinley conducted a front porch campaign from his home in Canton, Ohio, was to avoid a head-tohead comparison of their rhetorical talents. It was no coincidence that the Republican candidate’s brother, Abner McKinley, was an investor in the most ambitious of the new motion picture enterprises: the American Mutoscope Company. The Biograph had its “official” premiere on Monday evening, October 12, at Hammerstein’s Olympia Music Hall on Broadway between 44th and 45th streets, New York City, as McKinley at Home was shown for the first time. But it was also going to be a political rally and that morning, The New York Herald initiated the feedback loop between event and newspaper coverage by running four line drawings “From Instantaneous Photographs Taken for the Biograph. To Be Exhibited at the Olympia Theatre, Under the Auspices of the Republican National Committee.” These images were said to illustrate “Incidents in Major McKinley’s Life in Canton, Ohio.”73 While Biograph’s program of films at the Olympia consisted of a number of “attractions” – and so seemingly conforms to Tom Gunning’s “cinema of attractions” paradigm – it is hard not to feel that such a label conceals as much if not more than it reveals. The filmmakers’ careful organization of one-shot films produced a highly effective political rhetoric. Biograph’s showmen not only constructed this film program around principles of variety, but more importantly those of associational and contrast editing. The final program has as much affinity to Eisenstein’s concept of “montage of attractions” as it does to “cinema of attractions”: Eisenstein saw montage of attractions as a new editing form “in which arbitrarily chosen images, independent from the action, would be presented not in chronological sequence but in whatever way would create the maximum psychological impact.”74 As an exhibition service, Biograph programmed, sequenced and edited these one-shot films. And they did so to powerful, calculated effect–-including a test audience. The program’s focus was on the McKinley films. The New York Tribune reported that 73 New York Herald 12 Oct. 1896: 4. 74 “Sergei Eisenstein,” Russian Archives on Line, http://www.russianarchives.com/gallery/ old/eisen.html.

The Stereopticon and Cinema

153

The biggest part of the enthusiasm began when a view of a McKinley and Hobart parade in Canton was shown. The cheering was incessant as long as the line was passing across the screen, and it grew much greater when the title of the next picture appeared: “Major McKinley at Home.” Major McKinley was seen to come down the steps of his house with his secretary. The secretary handed him a paper which he opened and read. Then he took off his hat and advanced to meet a visiting delegation.75

Showing a film of the Empire State Express train was a brilliant conclusion. It might be seen as Biograph’s version of the advancing brow of the battleship, which concluded Sergei Eisenstein’s Potemkin. The Empire State Express is moving full speed ahead for McKinley. Or, like the express train, the Republican candidate was an unstoppable force. And yet – here American film programs were already ambiguous and open to multiple, often mutually inclusive interpretation – the train was also like the Biograph motion picture system: an impressive technological marvel that was hailed for the absence of flicker and “jump” noticeable in its competitors. The repetition of The Empire State Express moved the program beyond McKinley (without, however, leaving him behind) to reassert and equate the power of American technology and industry with the Biograph motion picture system – even as the superior technology was linked to the “Sound Money” politics of the Republicans. The fortunes of Biograph’s high-quality exhibitions and the businessman’s candidate were linked. “No good Republican or upholder of sound money doctrine can afford to miss the lifelike representation of their champion on the lawn of his home at Canton,” declared the Mail and Express.76 Theatergoers who had been distracted by politics were brought back into the vaudeville house as paying customers to glimpse their candidate “in the flesh.” McKinley’s front porch served as a modest counterpart to the Olympia’s stage, which it seemed to momentarily replace. McKinley’s virtual self served as a surrogate for his absent self. His absent presence could miraculously appear on stage (on screen) at the front of the theater, acting as a relay between the man in Canton and the spectators in the theater. This was an astute and original way to promote both McKinley and the Biograph exhibition service.

75 “A Moving Picture of M’Kinley,” New York Tribune 13 Oct. 1896: 7. 76 “Vaudeville,” New York Mail and Express 17 Oct. 1896: 13.

154 

Charles Musser

The Biograph’s debut at the Olympia Music Hall seemingly was a mixture of careful planning and last-minute improvisation. A reliably Republican newspaper only revealed Biograph’s coup on the very afternoon of the event. McKinley, who was rooted in Canton, Ohio, was to make an almost miraculous visit to New York City and be greeted by his in-the-flesh vicepresidential running mate Garret Hobart. Moreover, the candidate’s beloved homestead would travel with him. Hobart may not have attended in the end, but many prominent Republicans were there. Some were associated with New York Senator Thomas C. Platt, who had opposed McKinley’s nomination, which suggests that the event served as a public display of party unity. Other patrons were associated with the New York Central Railroad – and Empire State Express was certainly a film they had sponsored. These people were more directly connected to this Republican event than one might assume, since several of the prominent Republicans were also railroad executives. The event thus brought together powerful business and political representatives, who were often one and the same. To follow McKinley with an image of the onrushing Empire State Express was certainly fraught with meaning. The Biograph left Hammerstein’s theater unexpectedly after a two-week run (October 12-24) and promptly reopened at Koster & Bial’s Music Hall on October 26–-again with little advance notice.77 As Election Day approached, political demonstrations reached a fevered pitch – inside as well as outside the theater. McKinley’s silent, virtual self was once again one of the candidate’s most effective surrogates and turned an evening at the theater into a campaign rally. If we consider the Biograph presentation in terms of the lantern platform, the screening revived the sense of immediate presence that audiences experienced when first witnessing the stereopticon. At the same time, the program did not make use of a lecturer – something that was not always the case with other film screenings in 1896-1897. In this and other ways, the program broke from earlier Republican uses of projected images. Nevertheless, it would be a mistake to isolate these changes within a narrow genealogy of screen practice, something of which I have been guilty in the past.

77 This offers a modest correction to The Emergence of Cinema, in which I mistakenly indicate the Biograph reopened at Koster & Bial’s a week later, on November 2. Koster & Bial’s advertisements and publicity notices running in the Sunday newspapers of October 25 failed to mention that the Biograph would be on its bill in the coming week. It was obviously a last-minute addition.

The Stereopticon and Cinema

155

An Assessment The new, 1896 media formation was transformative rather than additive. One way to assess this is to consider the changed relationship between political and theatrical cultures. Cinema moved political theater into New York’s entertainment venues – a place where politicians had rarely gone in previous elections. It was not only that McKinley’s virtual self made appearances in these theaters – on the same programs as risqué dancing girls, breaking down some of the distinctions between the platform of political oratory and the realm of amusement. The dynamic between the press and political culture was transformed as well, expanded to include the theater in ways that would prove potent. Those who saw McKinley and his front porch in the music halls might then read newspapers about him and the delegations that came to express their homage. One lengthy report in the New York Sun suggested McKinley was a humble man, adored by citizens who made the pilgrimage to Canton. It is they who provided the dynamism while he offered stability. These news items avoided the specifics of policy and party, carrying such headlines as “M’Kinley Preaches Hope. He Says He Has no Part in the Doctrine of Hate.” Predictably, he embraced patriotism: “Stand up for America, and America will stand up for you,” he told the Republication Press Association of West Virginia.78 The mute motion picture of McKinley, its virtual but disembodied presence had a vision-like quality that made him seem momentarily transcendent. Properly contextualized – which was Biograph’s achievement – it provided an effective icon which endowed the candidate with a new sincerity and power. More generally, the politicized feedback loop between vaudeville screenings and the press, which McKinley at Home helped to establish, had powerful consequences around events leading up to the SpanishAmerican War.79 Newspaper mogul William Randolph Hearst – who 78 “William McKinley,” http://www.allthingswilliam.com/presidents/mckinley.html. 79 Elsewhere, I have analyzed the opening night Vitascope program at Koster & Bial’s (23 April 1896) and argued that this was not, in fact, a miscellaneous collection of views but offered a metaphorical narrative that had a clear, heavily nationalistic meaning. See Musser, “1896-1897: Movies and the Beginnings of Cinema” in American Cinema 1890-1909: Themes and Variations, ed. André Gaudreault (New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press, 2009) 52-54; “Introducing Cinema to the American Public: The Vitascope in the United States, 1896-1897,” Moviegoing in America, ed. Gregory Waller (Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishers, 2002) 13-27; and “At the Beginning: Motion Picture Production, Representation and Ideology at the Edison and Lumière Companies,” Silent Cinema Reader, ed. Lee Grieveson (London: Routledge, 2003) 25-56.

156 

Charles Musser

showed films on election night at his headquarters – supported Bryan, but must have been aware of the Biograph’s potent rhetoric and its impact on audiences. When seeking a similar kind of result, he funded the taking of “war films” in the winter and spring of 1898. These pictures of the sunken battleship “Maine” and the like were shown in New York’s vaudeville theaters, which served as a space where citizens could express the prowar sentiments that were being fostered by the jingoistic press. These newspapers in turn covered these “spontaneous” and patriotic displays as evidence of the American desire for intervention, thus helping to impel the US to war with Spain in April 1898. In short, film was rapidly integrated into a media system in circumscribed but powerful ways. Pro-McKinley and pro-imperialist forces had control of this new media form and used it very effectively. To do this, one might add, exhibitors structured their programs of short one-shot films in ways that made effective use of their control of editorial method – the construction of narrative, the use of contrast for inflammatory purposes, the careful juxtaposition of image and word. The politically oriented feedback loop between audio-visual projections and the press had already been well established for campaign purposes in 1892 and was one element of continuity between these two distinct but historically related formations. The shift from long-form screen programs involving the projection of slides (non-moving images) in 1892 to the projection of a selection of short, one-shot moving images was part of this far-reaching transformation. The illustrated lectures focused on a central political issue, emphasizing policy and programs, not personality. In contrast, the short film of McKinley was silent as to specif ic programmatic content but featured a personality and showed the essence of his campaign style. In this respect, it might be considered a “pregnant instance,” along the lines discussed by Maria Tortajada. 80 McKinley at Home offered a brief moment that captured the dominant or representative essence of the candidate’s campaign. McKinley was always at home (just as his rival William Jennings Bryan was seemingly always campaigning from the train). The film could serve as a cipher that audiences could fill with their own associations. Sound Money Democrats who supported McKinley despite their traditional party allegiances were able to embrace a personality rather than a set of developed policy 80 M. Tortajada, “Le statut du photogramme et l’instant prégnant au moment de l’émergence du cinéma,” XVIth International Film Studies Conference - Permanent Seminar on History of Film Theories, “In The Very Beginning, At The Very End,” Udine, 24 March 2009.

The Stereopticon and Cinema

157

agendas addressing the tariff and other issues for which they continued to have serious reservations. The move from political oratory to political pageantry and the embrace of the bicycle, the first use of the telephone for news gathering on election eve, and even the initial adoption of the phonograph by the McKinley campaign contributed to a notable transformation of prior media practices in 1896. The move away from discourses of sobriety and long forms is one dimension of this reformulated usage of media forms.

When Did Cinema Become Cinema? When did cinema become cinema? Certainly, motion picture practices were changing rapidly from 1894 (pre-cinema) up until about 1920 – and then beyond. This makes me instinctively resistant to the notion that cinema did not become institutionalized until about 1910, as André Gau­ dreault proposes with his “second birth of cinema.” Why 1910? Cinema had become a form of mass communication and of mass entertainment and culture in 1908 with the introduction of the regular release schedule and an emergent mode of representation that was more accessible and consistent in meaning (through the use of intertitles and a strong linear form of narrative organization).81 In 1905-06, the nickelodeons provided the motion picture industry with its own specially designated exhibition sites. To have specialized motion picture houses or cinemas but no cinema seems odd. However, if I were to answer this question in a way that was not redundant or dismissive – that is, with the answer 1895-96 – I would look to a series of interconnected changes in the dispositive that occurred from mid- to late 1903. These would include the introduction of the three-blade shutter on motion picture machines, which sharply reduced the flicker effect and made spectatorship much more pleasurable. Before this moment, the cutting back and forth from slides to film was not only common but desirable. As we saw, even in October 1896, Biograph was alternating between titles slides and motion picture films. Title slides provided the spectators’ eyes with a rest; and since motion picture film was expensive, it also reduced the costs of materials. What this meant was that until 1903, exhibitors who showed f ilms were also showing slides. The projecting machines were typically combination stereopticons and moving picture 81 See Charles Musser, Before the Nickelodeon: Edwin S. Porter and the Edison Manufacturing Company (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1991) 372.

158 

Charles Musser

machines, in which the operator would swivel his media carriage back and forth as he alternated between the two. Moreover, this meant that post-production was physically occurring in the course of exhibition. Even as the three-blade shutter was introduced in the US, the Edison company began to sell its longer films – Uncle Tom’s Cabin (July 1903) was the first – with head titles and intertitles. Post-production became centralized inside the production company – a process that had begun somewhat earlier but had been impeded by these established exhibition procedures. Once the projectionist was simply showing a reel of film, distributors could rent said reels rather than a service (which included operator, projector, slides and films). Again, this occurred in the later part of 1903. It was also at this moment that narrative fiction began to dominate in vaudeville and elsewhere. There were multiple reasons for this shift to story films, but certainly reduced flicker facilitated the kinds of pleasures one associates with fantasy and f iction. The moving picture houses that soon followed could then be given names such as Bijou Dream and Dreamland. This shift also meant that lanterns were redesigned just to show films: they became motion picture machines. Although perhaps not the only moment when “cinema” became “cinema,” the year 1903 was a decisive moment – as projectionists in vaudeville houses only showed films as part of the program. An equivalent moment never occurred with the stereopticon. Exhibitors using the stereopticon could always show non-photographic images as well as photographic lantern slides. In this respect, although devotees of the stereopticon may have wanted it to achieve a status as a media form, it remained in the end the intersection of several media forms with the lantern platform, a particular kind of screen practice. In contrast, motion picture technologies and practices were separate and distinct from the outset but achieved a solidity and coherence in the early 1900s, perhaps most dramatically between 1903 and 1908. Finally – and this is a topic for further research – the stereopticon, unlike cinema, was never presented as a distinct art form. It remained based in the discourse of sobriety, which has often been opposed to art. As historians of media and culture, we should be sensitive to the ways in which the dominant component of this new media form (“the cinema”) was constituted as an art form – to the exclusion of ephemera (shorts, trailers, newsreels, etc.), which for many years were not considered worthy of serious study or even preservation. In fact, in the American context, “cinema” was perhaps a term that defined a media form as an art form.

159

The Stereopticon and Cinema

Table 1: Random Word Searches of Key Terms in Audio-Visual Media. Figures are for number of articles cited. For the New York Times and (combined in parentheses) the London Observer and Manchester Guardian. Years

Stereopticon/magic Illustrated lecture lantern

Both terms—with “lecture” only

1863/1851 (1826) to 1879* 1880-1889

295(0)/100 (758)

43(42)

0/0–90/9 (0/41-[139])

297(0)/58 (212)

890 (13)

1890-1899

526 (0)/98 (112)

746 (53)

1900-1909

405 (2)/113 (111)

341 (96)

1910-1919

313(1)/42 (87)

535 (116)

1920-1929

207(1)/57 (69)

406 (72)

10/0–– 122/6 (0/20-[88]) 24/0—326/15 (0/21-[333] 16/0 ––192/5 (1/10[539]) 9/0––161/6 (0/5-[509]) 1/0––66/1 (0/7-[773])

1930-1939

114(0)/49 (76)

798(119)

1940-1949

61 (0)/31 (33)

354 (41)

1/0––33/2 (0/13[846]) 1/0––10/2 (0/2- [284]

1950-1959

42 (0)/72 (42)

255 (173)

1/0––3/0 (0/2-[135])

1960-1969

20(0)/170 (60)

268 (93)

0/0––3/2 (0/11-[73])

1970-1979

39(2)/82

241 (134)

0/0––1/1 (0/2-[47])

* The New York Times start publishing in 1851, but the first mention of the term “Stereopticon” was in 1863. The Observer was first published in 1791 and the Manchester Guardian in 1821.

Table 2: Random Word Searches of Key Terms in Audio-Visual Media. Figures are for the number of articles cited in the New York Times. Years

StereStereoopticon scope

Moving Slide Docushow mentary pictures & motion & theater pictures

1863/1854 295 to 1879

228

1880-1889 297

152

0

1890-1899 526

18

1900-1909 405

19

Movie & Motion film pictures & (theater)/motion pictures

-

0

0

_

2

0

0

3

_

118

23/33

0

2

_

742

143/206

10

160  Years

Charles Musser

StereStereoopticon scope

Moving Slide Docushow mentary pictures & motion & theater pictures

Movie & Motion film pictures & (theater)/motion pictures

1910-1919 313

15

2

_

2501

2,022/5,663

222

1920-1929 207

24

3

31

2133

6,132/20,100

395

1930-1939 114

40

2

163

1044

5,893/22,042

430

1940-1949 61

117

2

659

466

5,793/20,122

501

1950-1959 42

44

90

646

188

4,332/19,644

816

1960-1969 20

38

151

477

53

3,712/17,204

731

1970-1979 39

15

658

1074

39

1,392/10,248

745

1980-1989

50

1157

668

130

2,159/9,240

642



On Some Limitations of the Definition of the Dispositive “Cinema”1 André Gaudreault

If we were Artists We would not say the cinema We would say the cine But if we were old professors from the provinces We would say neither cinema nor cine But cinematograph Guillaume Apollinaire, excerpt from “Avant le cinéma,” 19172

At the conference at which this paper was presented, two participants made a reference to Guillaume Apollinaire without consulting each other beforehand. François Albera first pointed out that, according to the author of “The New Spirit and the Poets,” poets wanted to be able some day “to mechanize poetry as the world has been mechanized.”3 For my part, I projected an excerpt of the poem used here as an epigraph and straightforwardly titled “Before the Cinema.” No intention or planning, no machination should be read into this coincidence, which is first and foremost the result of chance. 1 This text was written as part of the research work of the GRAFICS (Groupe de recherches sur l’avènement et la formation des institutions cinématographique et scénique) at the Université de Montréal. The GRAFICS receives funding from Canada’s Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council and the Fonds québécois pour la recherche sur la société et la culture. The GRAFICS belongs to the Centre de recherche sur l’intermédialité (CRI). The author wishes to thank Jean-Marc Lamotte and the Institut Lumière for the photograph of the Lumière device (fig. 1). 2 Guillaume Apollinaire, Oeuvres poétiques, Marcel Adéma and Michel Décaudin, eds. (Paris: Gallimard, NRF/Bibliothèque de La Pléiade, 1965) 362. 3 Selected Writings of Guillaume Apollinaire, ed. Roger Shattuck (New York: New Directions Publishing Corporation, 1971) 227-37, 237. Apollinaire’s text comes from a lecture given in November 1917, the very year when the poem “Avant le cinéma” was published (a few months earlier, in April to be specific). In his talk, Albera referred to “The New Spirit and the Poets” within a larger argument on the prevalence of the model of the machine in the arts at the end of the nineteenth century, a time when the “machine ‘cinema’” was the driving force displacing the old categories of creation (see his contribution in this volume).

162 

André Gaudreault

Still, the coincidence has a certain necessity to it. Indeed, the cinema holds an essential place in the work of the French poet, as Francis Ramirez has shown in a particularly inspired article on the question: Cinema long behaved like an illegitimate child, looking for fathers, finding godfathers. Among them, Guillaume Apollinaire. At a time when dominant artists, particularly in France, showed contempt for cinema, the poet adopted it and emphatically greeted the art of movement in what he called “the new spirit.” 4

In his poem (the one ending with the famous “My glass broke like a burst of laughter”), Apollinaire lists the variety of terms used during the period to refer to the cinema. In 1917, the vulgum pecus would have said “the cinema” whereas artists (the particular kind that are actors and actresses) would have preferred “the cine,” and “old professors from the provinces,” “the cinematograph.” For the record, here is the complete poem: And tonight we will go To the cinema Artists who are they then They are no longer the ones who cultivate the Fine Arts They are not the ones who take care of Art Poetic Art or music as well The Artists are actors and actresses If we were Artists We would not say the cinema We would say the cine But if we were old professors from the provinces We would say neither cine nor cinema But cinematograph So my goodness do we need to have taste 4 Francis Ramirez, “Apollinaire et le désir de cinéma,” Cahiers de l’Association internationale des études françaises 47.1 (1995) 371. Available at http://www.persee.fr/web/revues/home/ prescript/article/caief_0571-5865_1995_num_47_1_1883, last accessed on September 28, 2012.

On Some Limitations of the Definition of the Dispositive “Cinema”

163

My glass is full of a wine that shimmers like a flame Listen to the slow song of a boatman Telling of seven women he saw in the moonlight Twisting their long green hair hanging to their feet Stand up sing higher while dancing in a ring So that I no longer hear the boatman singing And place by me all the blond maidens With their fixed stare their braids folded back The Rhine the Rhine is drunk where the vineyards are mirrored All the gold of the nights falls shimmering reflected in it The voice is still singing, rattling itself to death These fairies with green hair incanting the summer My glass broke like a burst of laughter5

This question of which term to privilege when referring to (and naming) the new “medium” was topical in the second decade of the twentieth century. Indeed, the year Apollinaire published his poem, Louis Delluc wrote a rather enlightened opinion along the same lines: “We are in want of words, I mean brief and precise words […] to replace cinématographe, which is heavy, endless, ugly, and does not apply very well to what it is meant to refer to.”6 For the extoller of photogénie, the word cinématographe thus started to sound stale. What the supposed inventor of the word cinéaste sensed in 1917 was basically that the word had simply become outdated when it came to designating film activity as a whole. It is as though Delluc had a clear intuition that the situation had changed and that a new paradigm had emerged; as though he had a vague impression that, as the process of institutionalization of cinema irreducibly moved forward, the old term was increasingly at odds with the course of events, the state of things. The issue of naming the new media was obviously not just a French affair at the time. Comparable questioning was taking place in the United States, one example being the well-known hesitation in the 1910s between mov5 Apollinaire, Oeuvres poétiques 362. 6 Louis Delluc, Le Film 12 Nov. 1917, in Jean Giraud, Le lexique français du cinéma. Des origines à 1930 (Paris: CNRS, 1958), entry on “cinématographe,” 90. This was also the month when Apollinaire gave his talk on “The New Spirit.”

164 

André Gaudreault

ing pictures and motion pictures, as reported by William Paul.7 Similarly, the attempt to introduce “photoplay” proved short-lived. Though it has registered in our memories through one of the first theoretical works on the cinema published by Hugo Münsterberg in 1916,8 the term has long become obsolete. One thing for certain is that the choice between two words in French (cinématographe and cinéma) to refer to the same historical object9 causes much confusion, as will be demonstrated here once again. In fact, we will see that, as Guy Béart’s song goes, “the poet spoke the truth…” Indeed, Apollinaire’s poem contains the key word in the main proposition I am to make toward the end of my argument. Thinking ahead to the conclusion, I thus chose to title the present text “On Some Limitations of the Definition of the Dispositive ‘Cinema’,” not “On Some Limitations of the Definition of the Cinematographic Dispositive.” Apparatus theory has been through difficult times lately – at least, that is what Nicolas Dulac and I put forward on the occasion of a recent conference.10 It has been criticized on two counts: first, its lack of historical 7 William Paul, “Uncanny Theater. The Twin Inheritances of the Movies,” Paradoxa 3.3-4 (1997): 321-47. On this question, see also André Gaudreault and Philippe Marion, “En guise d’ouverture sur la problématique cinéma/bande dessinée,” Cinema e fumetto. Cinema and Comics, Leonardo Quaresima, Laura Ester Stangalli and Federico Zecca, eds. (Udine: Forum, 2009) 23-29. 8 Hugo Münsterberg’s The Photoplay: A Psychological Study was first published by D. Appleton and Company (New York/London, 1916). Most people working in the field of film studies know it under the title of a new edition that appeared in the early 1970s, The Film: A Psychological Study (New York: Dover, 1970), which omitted “photoplay” and replaced it with “film.” The latest life of the work in question (in a recent, new publication) marked the return of the word “photoplay,” though the title contains the word “film” so that the “customer” knows what the book deals with: Hugo Münsterberg on Film. The Photoplay: A Psychological Study and Other Writings, ed. Allan Langdale (London: Routledge, 2002). In a review of the book, Ann M. Gibb wrote, “Are movies art, or entertainment? Does watching violent films encourage violent behavior in teenagers? Should movies be censored? A new book, above, by art historian Allan Langdale, collects all the writings on film by Hugo Münsterberg, an early film theorist. These questions are being debated today, but they were also posed nearly 100 years ago by Hugo Münsterberg, a German psychologist who came to America and fell under the enchantment of the new medium called the ‘photoplay’” (my emphasis). See Ann M. Gibb, “Book shows that debates over the role of films are nothing new,” UC Santa Cruz Currents Online 3 June 2002 http://www.ucsc.edu/currents/01-02/06-03/ film.html, last accessed on September 28, 2012. 9 In actuality, it is not always the same historical object which is being referred to, even when only one term is available, since words never completely correspond to things and there never is a total adequation between reality and language (but that is a whole other story…). 10 International conference “Les dispositifs,” Université de Marne-la-Vallée and École nationale supérieure Louis-Lumière, France, 2006. See N. Dulac and A. Gaudreault, “Dispositifs optiques et attraction,” Cahier Louis-Lumière (Les dispositifs) 4 (June 2007): 91-108.

On Some Limitations of the Definition of the Dispositive “Cinema”

165

foundations; second, its inadequate picture of film reception. In its classical version at least, the theory has been described as lacking a proper historical grounding, as it rests on a theoretical construction that completely overlooks the diversity of practices and technologies developed in cinema since the “dispositif” was perfected. Besides, its assumption of a monolithic audience has been blamed for its inadequate account of film reception. Jumping the gun on some aspects of the apparatus, theoreticians ended up crossing paths with historians (notably historians of early cinema) and other theoreticians (notably those working from a cognitivist or feminist perspective), who soon pointed out the inadequacies of some of their hypotheses. More and more historians are opting for a pragmatic-historical approach to the “dispositif” nowadays,11 thus conceiving new analytical models anchored in the diachronic flow of the historical continuum. It has been shown that many spectatorial practices went against the model assumed by apparatus theory, and that the film “dispositif” did not constitute a unitary, inert entity cast in stone any more than did the spectator. Besides, recent research and discussions have brought to light many practices that help us better understand the relation between spectator, “dispositif” and representation. The more the film “dispositif” loses its apparent uniqueness, the more the strictly ideological or technological explanation loses ground, revealing the complexity of the basic “dispositif ” – if I may call it that. Accordingly, there have been conferences on the notion of the “dispositif” before the one whose proceedings appear in this book, just as there will obviously be many others on the same theme over the next few years. Indeed, this notion lies at the center of the preoccupations of many dynamic research groups, whether in Switzerland, in the Netherlands, in France or in Quebec. Admittedly, since the turn of the century – not so long ago – the “dispositif” has made a much noted comeback on the intellectual scene that takes the cinema and moving images as its object.12 11 See Frank Kessler, “La cinématographie comme dispositif [du] spectaculaire,” Cinémas 14.1 (Fall 2003): 21-34. 12 I would like to allow myself a short digression here, a “futurological” one, if you will. You probably noted the care with which I choose my words when I write of the intellectual work “that takes the cinema and moving images as its object.” Given the new context in which we are currently immersed, with the proliferation of digital technologies and the dissemination/ multiplication of screens and media, I am convinced that this tendency toward caution in the choice of words, which articulates the particular (cinema) with the more general (moving images), will be more and more frequent – this until the day when the particular term “cinema” is abandoned and only the generic term “moving images” remains. Already, the multiplication of expressions such as “images mouvantes,” “images en mouvement,” or “image animée” in French

166 

André Gaudreault

The revival of the notion in advanced thinking on cinema (and moving images…) is itself not extraneous to the turbulence brought about by the advent of digital technologies, which have redrawn the maps once used with a bit of intuition to navigate the – then smaller – world of mere filming. It comes with its share of joy and sorrow – the latter somewhat linked to the semantic inflation produced by the notion of “dispositif.” Judging by the literature of the past few years, the concept may seem to thicken and the notion to lose its clarity gradually, as if everyone, myself included, had passed the word round to put their own twist on the notion. Scholars, however, are not necessarily responsible for this inflationary trend: the term itself is an invitation to all kinds of derivatives (and just as many tangents…). “Dispositif” as a term has therefore become definitely polysemic, which in itself is not necessarily a problem. This short text I put together shows the extent to which the word lends itself to multiple meanings and levels of meaning:13 Probably drawing on the social and industrial infrastructure that was the Lumière company at the end of the nineteenth century in France, the Lumière brothers were able to find the means to develop their Cinematograph, a technical dispositive for which they filed an application in February 1895 as part of the legal framework designed for patents. The Cinematograph went down in history as the origin of the film dispositive. It should be mentioned, however, that the real invention of the Lumière brothers is limited to the sole small mechanical device known as the triangular eccentric cam, which made it possible to take photographs intermittently. Besides, it should pointed out that the ingenious shooting dispositive of the Cinematograph was also designed for use as a projection dispositive in public screenings whose dispositive was blatantly and spectacularly reminiscent of the dispositive imagined by Plato in his famous allegory of the cave. In addition, these shows marked the beginning of a cultural series whose theoretical understanding was to culminate in the has become perceptible in written discourse over the past few years. From my point of view, it is a clear symptom of the search for suitability between language and the new extra-linguistic reality. The situation is slightly different in English, of course, as the use side by side of two “clausulas,” both bearing on “pictures” which are “moving,” could amount to tautology. In English, I noted a tendency to use expressions such as “moving image studies” or “scholars of the moving image,” with the aim to avoid limiting discourse to cinema alone and excluding other instances of images in movement. 13 Translator’s note: the italics in the indented self-quotation that follows, found in the original source, refer to instances when the author uses the word “dispositif” in French.

On Some Limitations of the Definition of the Dispositive “Cinema”

167

Fig. 1. The Lumière brothers’ famous eccentric cam (on the left, the sliding frame that bears the claws, and whose two alternative conveyance movements are performed by the triangular eccentric cam placed at its center; on the right, the drum which, once assembled on the same axis as the eccentric cam’s and interdependent with it, makes it possible – thanks to the ramps positioned on its rim –­ to command the alternating coming and going of the claws in the sprocket holes of the film). Photograph: Jean-Marc Lamotte (Institut Lumière).

1970s with the advent of a rather convoluted theoretical system known as apparatus theory – but not until the basic apparatus had undergone a few important modifications, including the addition of a sound apparatus.

As this shows, “dispositif” refers to a number of different notions. Accordingly, we are quite justified in making a number of distinctions, as JeanPierre Sirois-Trahan has already suggested with his material dispositive, mental dispositive, production dispositive, reception dispositive and distribution dispositive.14 As difficult as the task may prove, I believe that we should build a theoretical model for each definition of the word “dispositif,” which branches off into technological, discursive, material, psychological, ideological and linguistic directions, to name but a few. Some day, we should also come to distinguish sharply and rigorously between “dispositive,” “apparatus,” “device,” “process,” and other thingies. 14 Jean-Pierre Sirois-Trahan, “Dispositif(s) et réception,” Cinémas 14.2-3 (Fall 2003): 149-76.

168 

André Gaudreault

This is far from simple, since the boundaries between each of these terms do not always appear clearly when the moment comes to designate the object of our thought. This may also be observed in English, as “apparatus,” also used to translate “dispositif,” is a rather vague equivalent for the word, which also translates as “device,” for instance. Some, like Frank Kessler,15 purely and simply propose that the French word “dispositif” be maintained in English. A “dispositif” may thus be a concrete thing, but it may also be abstract. It may be a big or large thing, just as it may be a very small one. I asked researcher Jean-Marc Lamotte, who is in charge of collections at the Institut Lumière in Lyons, for further information on the “thingy that made all the difference in the Cinématographe.”16 Here is what he answered: In fact, the “Lumière claw system” constitutes a complete device [“dispositif”]: indeed, it includes the eccentric cam (whether it is round or triangular basically does not make any difference). The cam is the mechanical piece that transforms the rotation of the crank into an alternating movement which it then transmits to a frame bearing the driving claws. The frame thus goes up and down. Yet the drum with the two ramps, which is interdependent with the cam, is just as essential: it controls the coming and going of the claws in the sprocket holes, thereby allowing the frame bearing the claws to come back up empty, leaving the film still even so briefly – the very principle of the intermittent advance of film.17

This specialist of the Lumière Cinematograph, who considers what I call the Lumière thingy (the eccentric cam) to be more than a mere thingy, thus used the word “dispositif” in an unbiased way. Lamotte even added: This is all to say that we (in fact, almost everybody when speaking from memory) slightly simplify when we speak only of the cam, when in fact the Lumière system is a whole, a dispositive by which a continuous movement of rotation (the axis bearing the cam, the drum and the shutter) is turned into two alternating conveyance movements: a vertical movement, controlled by the cam mounted on the rotating camshaft 15 Frank Kessler, “La cinématographie comme dispositif [du] spectaculaire,” Cinémas 14.1 (Fall 2003): 21-34. 16 I did write “bidule” (“thingy”) in my query to Jean-Marc Lamotte. At no point did I mention the word “dispositif.” 17 E-mail to the author, 25 May 2008 (my emphasis).

On Some Limitations of the Definition of the Dispositive “Cinema”

169

and transmitted to a frame bearing mobile claws; a horizontal movement controlled by two ramps on the rim of the drum also mounted on the rotating camshaft, and transmitted to the claws […].18

This manifestly belongs to the category of technical dispositive, one degree above my somewhat unreliable “category” of the “thingy” – a technical dispositive that was to make it possible for the Lumière Cinematograph to shoot intermittently. This intermittence allows for the taking of shots that may be projected later by the Cinematograph, once it is turned into a technical screening dispositive within the material and social dispositive of the screening room, which implies the “co-presence” in the same space of a projector, a projectionist, a screen, a film and spectators. All of these essential conditions were in turn to make it possible for French film theoreticians to found the so-called, metaphorical “apparatus theory” after the dispositive had been in social use for eighty years. These various manifestations and materializations of the notion of “dispositif” take us from the world of the extremely technical to the more simple technical world, then to the social world and finally to the world of ideas. It is also a shift from the smallest to the much larger, the immeasurable even; from the concrete to the abstract; and, last of all, from the empirical to the speculative. It takes place by simply moving the same term, the same lexical unit from one sphere to another, along the same chain, each time conferring an additional meaning, if not a new spirit, on it. By the way, what is so special about the first element in this chain, the smallest and apparently the most insignificant of all, and yet the first cause in what I propose to call the “chain of the ‘dispositif’”? This more-thana-thingy, these mere pieces of metal assembled and arranged in quite a specific way, forming a dispositive, and which inadvertently made it possible to produce gains as algorithmic as they are exponential and unexpected? It undoubtedly has to be a little marvel, a marvelous device to arouse – or rather, to unleash – as many passions (this cam may have been called “eccentric” for a reason…). It must be a little marvel indeed, and yet it remains the place par excellence of the contradiction specific to the cinematographic, as I will attempt to demonstrate. The Lumière brothers thus owe this cam their reputation in history as the inventors of the cinema. Not shying away from grand statements, let us also reckon here that this first-rate recognition should similarly make them the designers – rather unconsciously and unintentionally – of the film 18 E-mail to the author, May 25, 2008.

170 

André Gaudreault

apparatus in the sense given to the expression by French film theory. They would certainly never have dared to claim as much, since they invented neither the film apparatus described by Baudry nor the dispositive cinema. Indeed, as I have been professing for a while, the Lumière brothers have been abusively considered the inventors of cinema.19 Basically and quite simply, the Lumière brothers only came up with a machine to shoot views – extraordinary and brilliantly designed, to be sure, but a machine all the same. One thing is certain, we should acknowledge that the dispositive-thingy of the Lumière brothers proved priceless for them. 20 Just as certainly, it earned them their share of attacks. Over the past few years, many have raised questions about the brothers’ primacy in the race to the so-called invention of cinema. Some have even argued that what I identify as the dispositive-thingy, the eccentric cam – whose invention dates back to late 1894 – should in no way be considered an essential requirement for a projection dispositive to become established as such. To those holding this position, the dispositive-thingy is in the end a phony device, no more, no less… Still others consider the dispositive-thingy to be rather small to elicit so much praise, given all the preexisting technologies used alongside it in the Lumière device. Michel Frizot claims, for instance: “Still, [the] rather complex description [of the Cinématographe] reveals but little invention on the part of the Lumière brothers, as most of the processes comprising it existed beforehand.”21 Those who made the year 1995 the terminal point of the first century of cinema generally hold in very high esteem the device-thingy in question, since it is really what made it possible to identify the starting point of the “series” whose centenary was being celebrated. For some, as is well-known, the “foundational” event is the invention of the Lumière device and the registration of the patent on February 13, 1895, in the wake of the development of the dispositive-thingy. On these grounds, speaking of “the century of cinema” without elaborating further amounted to dispensing with the demonstration that would justify the equivalence between cinematograph 19 I refer the reader interested in further developments on my position on this issue to my Film and Attraction. From Kinematography to Cinema, trans. Timothy Barnard (Champaign, IL: University of Illinois Press, 2008). 20 That this machine made it possible for them to produce films with undeniable intrinsic qualities is another story altogether. 21 Michel Frizot, “Qu’est-ce qu’une invention? (le cinéma). La technique et ses possibles,” Trafic 50 (summer 2004), P.O.L., Paris, 2004: 319.

On Some Limitations of the Definition of the Dispositive “Cinema”

171

– the Lumière cinematograph, to boot – and cinema (and between cinema and cinematograph). For others, the starting point would tend to be the famous Premier Paying Public Projection (PPPP) on December 28, 1895, at the Grand Café in Paris (since this took place during the same calendar year, 1895, it does not affect the terminal point, 1995). The question we may ask, then, is the following: is this PPPP really the very Premier PPP? Indeed, the “premier” nature of the event has frequently been contested, particularly of late, since a number of new facts have been dug out since classical historians of cinema last closed the matter. Recent, well-documented research does show evidence that the paying public projection of December 28, 1895, unquestionably and indisputably had precedents. I will mention only the three most important cases here, those of Latham’s Panoptikon (United States), Armat and Jenkins’s Phantoscope (United States), and the Skladanowsky brothers’ Bioskop (Germany): – On May 20, 1895, the Latham family (father Woodville and his sons Otway and Grey) used their Panoptikon (also known as Eidoloscope, sometimes spelled Pantoptikon or Panopticon) to project the film of a boxing match (between Young Griffo and Charles Barnett) to a paying audience on Broadway, New York City. This paying projection apparently took place repeatedly over several months. The Lathams also showed their film from time to time in several towns in the United States. – In late September 1895, C. Francis Jenkins and Thomas Armat also showed films to a paying audience thanks to their Phantoscope at the Cotton States Exhibition in Atlanta, Georgia. Armat was to sell the rights to his Phantoscope to Edison after making several alterations to it (Edison presented the device under a different name, Vitascope, and under his own name as he launched his own film screenings on April 23, 1896, four months after the Salon Indien projection at the Grand Café). – On November 1, 1895, a program of eight films was presented to a paying audience at the Wintergarten, a Berlin variety hall, by brothers Emil and Max Skladanowsky (cinema seems to have been a matter of siblings then), thanks to their Bioskop (sometimes spelled Bioskope, Bioscope or Bioscop).22

22 The reader interested in this question may refer to André Gaudreault and Tom Gunning, “Introduction: American Cinema Emerges (1890-1909),” in American Cinema, 1890-1909. Themes and Variations, ed. André Gaudreault (New Brunswick, N.J.: Rutgers University Press, 2009) 1-21; and to Deac Rossel, Living Pictures: The Origins of the Movies (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1998).

172 

André Gaudreault

Each of the devices that made these paying public projections possible involved particular characteristics distinguishing them from one another as well as from the Lumière Cinematograph (and of course, none was quite as well designed as the latter): 1) The Latham family’s Panoptikon did not feature any mechanism for the intermittent advance of the film, or any other system to make up for its absence. Accordingly, the screening of each image had to be as brief as possible to avoid any blur, which in turn required a larger film surface, given the need to beam light more strongly on images. In fact, the Panoptikon was not as efficient as hoped for, if we are to believe the report of a journalist present at one of the demonstrations: “There is considerable room for improvement and many drawbacks have yet to be overcome.”23 2) As to Jenkins and Armat’s Phantoscope, which was equipped with an intermittent mechanism, it gave much more satisfying results than the Lathams’ Panoptikon. This quite evidently explains its fortune with Edison the following year under a borrowed name (Vitascope). 3) Finally, the Skladanowsky brothers’ Bioskop, founded on a rather complex projection system, did not enjoy much success. Everything came in pairs in the German dispositive: light sources, driving mechanisms, films (two prints of the same film, actually), lenses. The main concern was to synchronize the two prints perfectly, since each of them was alternately masked by a central shutter. Appearing on the screen in alternation, then, were an image from print A and an image from print B. In a sense, the systematic alternation between the two emulated the intermittent movement lacking in the Bioskop. Due to the extreme complexity of its dispositive, not offset with any other advantage over the systems using the intermittent advance of a single film, the machine was short-lived and did not have much of a legacy. In this obstacle race to determine where priority lies in the invention of the dispositive, historians should first ask themselves what matters first and foremost. At bottom, the issue is whether public projection should be the decisive criterion (and whether it should be a paying show), or the mere invention of the device is enough. Serious historians may also wonder whether the search “for the One, Definite and Definitive invention,” to

23 Article in Photographic Times, quoted by Stephen Herbert at http://www.victorian-cinema. net/latham.htm (last accessed on September 28, 2012).

On Some Limitations of the Definition of the Dispositive “Cinema”

173

quote Michel Frizot again,24 is a game worth the trouble – or an incredibly vain exercise, in the end. In any case, if projection alone – to a limited public and at no charge – was deemed legitimate as the decisive criterion, a strong case could be made for the precedence of the Lumière brothers due to their first semi-private (hence semi-public!) screening on March 22, 1895, two months before the Lathams’ own projection.25 However, this in turn raises a series of questions, to which I will return. Besides, in the name of which principle should the projection of moving images (private or public, paying or not) be considered the necessary starting point – and the inaugural moment – of what is called “cinema”? Is a simple viewing (private or public, paying or not) not enough? This is an essential question. The notion of a starting point is a key idea running throughout the twentieth century and gaining ground into souls and consciousnesses, so much so that many specialists now take it for granted. In his Histoire du visuel, Laurent Gervereau writes for instance that “[…] cinema, whose characteristic is indeed the public projection in the theater as inaugurated by the Lumière brothers (not the individual viewing in a cabinet launched by Edison), expanded considerably from the First World War on.”26 Furthermore, why should this first projection be both public and paying to be considered as the first cause in the “cinema” series, as some claim? Should we understand that, if the famous (or supposed) PPPP of the Grand Café had taken place on January 1, 1896, we should then have celebrated its centenary in 1996? That is apparently the assumption. But then, which status should we grant the very first projection of the clever dispositive that is Émile Reynaud’s Théâtre optique, a projection of moving images that took place on October 28, 1892, over three years before the invention of the Cinématographe

24 Michel Frizot, “Qu’est-ce qu’une invention?”: 319. 25 It took the Lumière brothers quite some time (nine months!) before their f irst paying projection, simply because they wanted to be ready to face potential demand on the day when their invention would be made available to the general public. Before the public, paying show on December 28, 1895, they set up about ten screenings to demonstrate the “capacities” of the dispositive in front of non-paying, hand-picked audiences: photographers, industrialists, scientists, journalists, etc. – an audience who could appreciate what they were seeing and accordingly praise it in some popular scientific periodicals. The Lumière brothers also had to be able to launch their invention on a large scale and master the whole supply chain (film, dispositives, operating network, etc.). In other words, they were nosed out – temporally, not qualitatively speaking – by their many, less patient and less perfectionist competitors because they held themselves up for strictly commercial reasons. 26 Laurent Gervereau, Histoire du visuel au XXe siècle (Paris: Seuil, 2003) 34-35 (my emphasis).

174 

André Gaudreault

Lumière? What should these projections inaugurate? Should they serve as the starting point of the cultural series of “light projections with movement”? The October 28, 1892 screening was in a way a genuine PPPP (premier paying public projection). In truth, though, it was a PPPDI (public paying projection of drawn images) rather than a PPPPI (public paying projection of photographic images), like the Lumière brothers’. Indeed, Reynaud’s dispositive projected, not photographic images, but drawn material. This explains why teleological historians have ostracized Reynaud, all the more since he committed a “capital sin.” Indeed, for his praxinoscope and its various avatars, Reynaud “dared” to opt for a “regressive” direction, rejecting the system of slit shutters of the Zoetrope and Phenakistiscope (the principle of the shutter being rightly or wrongly considered as one of the fundamental bases of cinema). Reynaud instead privileged a system of mirrors placed around a polygonal crown, a process deemed anti-cinematographic by traditional historians of cinema, who forget that it was fashionable for quite a long time in these very cinematographic editing benches, including Steenbeck machines… Not ci-ne-ma-to-gra-phic, the polygon of mirrors? Not literally so, evidently, since it was invented before the word ci-ne-ma-to-graph became prevalent… Is the fact that Reynaud did not use photographic images enough to count him out so summarily? Shouldn’t the recent advent of digital technologies make us aware that, as far as cinema is concerned (assuming we find ourselves over and over again in that paradigm), photographic technology is not always there? If DVD viewing (no projection whatsoever) and computer-generated f ilms (no photographic trace whatsoever) are included within the contemporary sphere of cinema, how not to grant a retrospective certificate of “authenticity” and primacy to Reynaud’s Théâtre optique? It lacks photographic credentials, to be sure, yet it is founded on an orthodox projection “dispositif” that would enthrall Baudry. This is all the more true if one takes into account the early mise en abyme of the film spectator in the film titled Autour d’une cabine: it features a Peeping Tom who, through a keyhole and without the slightest shame, eyes up a lady taking her clothes off. Considering how historians have treated Reynaud and his invention, the publication of a book as anti-establishment and disputable as Bernard Lonjon’s scathing attack comes as no surprise. In his recent Émile Reynaud. Le véritable inventeur du cinéma,27 the author goes as far as to dub the city 27 Bernard Lonjon, Émile Reynaud. Le véritable inventeur du cinéma (Polignac: Éditions du Roure, 2007).

On Some Limitations of the Definition of the Dispositive “Cinema”

175

of Le Puy-en-Velay, which Reynaud used as a base, “the mother city of the cinematograph” (word for word, with cinematograph taking a lower-case “c,” of course!). This would be as early as June 1875… The invention of the cinema in 1875 in Le Puy-en-Velay: the mind boggles. While this type of assertion certainly verges on the ultimate degree of hyperbole, historians of cinema have been so lax that this type of backfiring serves them right; they have little choice but to take stock of it. Lonjon’s foregone conclusion even represents, I should say, a return of the repressed: since Reynaud’s Théâtre optique did not have the place it deserved in histories of cinema, an advocate of Reynaud’s was almost bound to go in the same direction as Lonjon’s some day. Historical and theoretical thinking has never taken Reynaud’s dispositive into account; this dispositive, it should be said, inaugurates something in the order of the “animated film,” yet no one knows exactly how to affiliate the latter to the former. Be that as it may, Reynaud did well and truly carry out paying public projections of moving images (assembled on a perforated film strip, to boot) 38 months before December 28, 1895. That took some doing… Let us return for a few moments to the Lumières and examine the text of the commemorative plaque affixed to the exterior walls of the Grand Café in 1926: “On December 28, 1895, this was the site of the first public projections of animated photography with the Cinematograph a device invented by the Lumière brothers.”28 (fig. 2) We know well what the plaque wants (and is meant) to commemorate: a genuine first (plaques are rarely affixed to celebrate “second times”). The “first public projections of animated photography” in the entire history of humankind thus reportedly took place at the Grand Café on December 28, 1895. Which, as is now well-known, is fundamentally inaccurate. Still, looking at it a bit closer, another signification may be read into the text of the plaque – a signification which, in my eyes at least, would prove its author one hundred percent right. What the plaque may mean is that what took place on December 28, 1895, in the place where it is affixed, is not “the first public projections of animated photography” in the entire history of humankind but “the first public projections of animated photography” ever to have been done with-the-Cinématographe-Lumière. This admittedly verges on truism! Yet this is what the text of the plaque spells 28 1925 is often reported as the date for the unveiling of the plaque, but the event did in fact take place in 1926 (on March 17), a date confirmed in the March 18, 1926, issue of the periodical Comœdia. See also the account of the ceremony in issue 520 of L’Écran, the journal of the French federation of film theater owners, dated March 20, 1926. I wish to thank Jean-Marc Lamotte for providing me with these details.

176 

André Gaudreault

Fig. 2. Commemorative plaque affixed in 1926 on the façade of the building that housed the Salon Indien of the Grand Café (14, boulevard des Capucines in Paris).

out (for lack of commas): “first public projections of animated photography with the Cinematograph…”29 This second interpretation is as implacable as it is tautological, but any attempt to understand the role of the Lumière brothers in the invention of the cinema leads to frequent brushes with tautology. Thus understood, the text of the plaque remains forever indisputable: it was indeed on December 28, 1895, that the Cinématographe Lumière was used for the first time before a paying audience. Why such a recurrence of tautological thoughts in the case of the Lumières? I think it may be explained as follows: this strong tendency may result from the confusion felt by everyone about the invention of cinema, but also from the dominance of the Lumière brothers’ device over all its 29 It should be noted that, contrary to expectation and – dare I say – without much regard for the rules of punctuation, the text does not include any commas at all. One comma at least would be indisputably called for – on the penultimate line, between the word “cinématographe” and the word “appareil.” As can be observed, the text is printed exclusively in capital letters – a frequent occurrence with this kind of exercise, in which a new line may in some cases give the text its rhythm and substitute for possible commas. The rule of the new line as a substitute for the comma does not hold throughout the text, however, since the shifts from line 2 to line 3 and from line 3 to line 4 do not involve the replacement of any comma whatsoever. That is not the case with the shift from line 4 to line 5, though: there may be a comma between “de photographie animée” and “à l’aide du Cinématographe,” just as there may be none at all, depending on what is meant. If a comma is introduced, the second signification I suggest does not hold water… Could it be that the comma possibly missing here amounts to an acte manqué?

On Some Limitations of the Definition of the Dispositive “Cinema”

177

main competitors. The word “cinematograph” became established in such a way that, instead of strictly referring to what it was initially meant to designate (a shooting device, a machine among others), it met with a clearly “synecdochic” fate and ended up referring to the spectacle of the projection of moving images itself – regardless of the device used – and by extension to the whole industry of production of moving images. In the early twentieth century, the word “cinematograph” covered a vast number of semantic fields, which is no longer the case at all these days. Indeed, a century later, we are back to square one, since in the early twenty-first century the word “cinematograph” may no longer designate anything else than the device of the Lumière brothers, as it did in 1895. This is in fact what all common dictionaries teach us. Nowadays, as has been the case for several decades, the word “cinema” assumes the multiple uses formerly assigned to the word “cinematograph.” According to the Le Robert dictionary, the word “cinema” covers five meanings and may simultaneously designate: 1) the “technology that allows the photographic recording and projecting of moving images”; 2) the “art of composing and making films” and, by extension, the “industry of cinematographic spectacles”; 3) the cinematographic projection; 4) “affected demonstrations, for instance in order to see a whim gratified,” as attested in the expression “Arrête ton cinéma!”; 5) the “theatrical space where cinematographic films are projected.”30 With the entry word “cinématographe,” the same edition of Le Nouveau Petit Robert refers the reader to the Lumière-designed device while mentioning a late occurrence of the word with a famous and not too dated author referring to the art of film: Dispositive invented by the Lumière brothers, which can reproduce movement through a succession of photographs. O. Cinema. “The cinematograph is an art.” (Cocteau)

“O.” (“Vx” in French) stands for “old,” or “vieux”: “word, meaning or use in the old language, incomprehensible or little comprehensible nowadays and never used, except as a stylistic effect: archaism.”

30 “Cinéma,” Le Nouveau Petit Robert de la langue française, electronic edition (Paris: Le Robert, 2007).

178 

André Gaudreault

It now seems rather obvious that many contrarieties (and contradictions) may be avoided in this whole story of the so-called “invention” of cinema if we stuck to the facts, and only the facts. What exactly did the Lumière brothers invent? Unanimous answer: the Cinématographe. Better still: the Cinématographe Lumière (tautology, when you have us in your grip)! Who invented cinema? Answer: the cinema cannot be invented (there is no patent to be registered): it becomes established, gradually and collectively… In other words, let us not mix up cinematograph and cinema any longer. The fusion of the two entities creates some confusion and causes unfortunate misunderstandings. It is in fact to avoid any such ambiguity that I indicated early on that this text had been rather pertinently titled “On Some Limitations of the Definition of the Dispositive ‘Cinema’ ” and not “On Some Limitations of the Definition of the Cinematographic Dispositive.” Had I written “cinematographic dispositive,” I would have risked sowing some confusion: within the framework of my reflection, readers may have wondered whether I meant by this expression the “dispositive of cinema” or the “dispositive of the cinematograph” – since “cinematographic” may indeed mean one or the other, as most will easily acknowledge. I sometimes wonder whether, in order to dispel all the confusion that characterizes the matter, we should not use the epithet “cinematic” or even return to the former, and so charming term used by Dulac, L’Herbier and company, “cinegraphic.” Not that I entertain any illusions: this is a losing battle. I hardly see myself suggesting to my colleagues in the Département d’histoire de l’art et d’études cinématographiques of the Université de Montréal, to which I am attached, that the name of the unit be changed to “Département d’histoire de l’art et d’études cinématiques” or “Département d’histoire de l’art et d’études cinégraphiques”… Still, this would bring a little poetry in the world and would reconcile us with Apollinaire, for whom it was imperative “to mechanize poetry as the world has been mechanized.” We only need to reverse his formula to suggest that nowadays, we should poeticize the machine just as the cinema poeticized the world…



The Moment of the “Dispositif” Omar Hachemi

If the “dispositif” constitutes a “moment,” it is not so much in accordance with its theoretical unity as with its scattered persistence in film theory. This persistence of the word necessarily brings up the question of its provenance: of which theoretical formation is this notion the standard? The word appeared in the 1970s at the intersection of key concepts – the unconscious, ideology, the signifier – which found the topological model of their functioning in cinematographic technique. Through the primacy given to arrangements, the notion of the “dispositif” fostered a spatial distribution of concepts: the topology of the “scenographic cube” revealed by monocular perspective, the cave-like space of the dark theater, the “other scene” of technique, and so forth. Between concepts and their spatialization, from the imaginary scene to the real scene, analogical relations and semantic slippages developed, altering the outlines of the notion. At this point, it is difficult to deny that the moment of the apparatus1 in 1970 has become a theoretical commonplace. Within the already wellcharted field of film theory, Jean-Louis Baudry is an important landmark. Regularly cited to didactic ends to evoke the model of “filmic continuity” from the angle of its deconstruction, Baudry is now part of the doxa. What is remembered from his brief foray in the field of cinema is the conception of a cinematographic technique that, far from being neutral, was held to subject the spectator to the order of fiction. The mention of his name leads by association to the image of a passive spectator plunged in the darkness that characterizes movie theaters. Baudry’s work presumably shows us the way followed by a film industry mastering the art of illusionism and constantly seeking artifices susceptible to immerse the spectator completely in the world of fiction.

1 In an article devoted to the way the concept of apparatus came into being, Guido Kirsten situates the emergence of this “theoretical paradigm” between 1969 and 1972 and traces it back to two sources: on the one hand, reflection on the perspective within the “optical system” (a reference to Pierre Francastel); on the other hand, Althusser’s theory of ideologies. I find the chronology as well as these references perfectly relevant, but here I will privilege the psychoanalytic reference, which Kirsten does not deal with in much depth. See Guido Kirsten, “Genèse d’un concept et ses avatars. La naissance de la théorie du dispositif cinématographique,” Cahier Louis-Lumière 4, “Les Dispositifs” (June 2007).

180 

Omar Hachemi

Still, few theoreticians claim to adhere to this model nowadays. Baudry is often quoted, but primarily because he is a good object for critique. In the issue of Cahiers Louis-Lumière devoted to “dispositifs,” for instance, André Gaudreault and Nicolas Dulac evoke the Baudry/Metz model, but in order to distance themselves from it. In the very gap that separates them from this theory, they define the notion of a “dispositif” conceived in the plural.2 I am therefore tempted to suggest (in Bachelardian terms) that the obvious fortune of the notion may be measured in terms of the successive critiques backing away from the “primary image” constituted by the Baudry model. It is always constructive to examine the way in which a field of research (the field of cinema, in this case) coordinates by individuating its figures, its “great models,” through a process of abstraction that favors their use. These modelizations are evidently needed, for without them we would be condemned to silence by the absurd task of describing how each concept advanced on the checkerboard of theory came into being. It would become impossible to move pawns. The role of epistemology, however, is to study the formation of these models and the strategies they fulfill. I thus propose to open this “black box”3 labeled “Baudry,” accordingly setting the “Baudry model” against the texts and their ramifications.

Apparatus/Basic Apparatus4 “Ideological Effects of the Basic Cinematographic Apparatus,” published in 1970 in Cinéthique, is commonly considered as the foundational moment for the concept of apparatus in the field of film studies (and even in sociology, apparently5). That this was the first occurrence of the word does not imply 2 André Gaudreault and Nicolas Dulac, “Dispositifs optiques et attraction,” Cahiers Louis Lumière 4: 92. 3 Bruno Latour put forward the concept of the “black box” to refer to the way in which, within science and its operations, some units get used once developed without their mechanism being called into question afterwards. See Bruno Latour, Science in Action (Cambridge: Harvard U.P., 1988). 4 Translator’s note: in the film theory of the 1970s, widely translated in English, “dispositif” and “appareil de base” were translated as “apparatus” and “basic apparatus.” Here as elsewhere (with apparatus theory), and for reasons of historical continuity and overall comprehension for the reader, we have opted to maintain these terms even as our own choices of terminology for this volume differ substantially. See the “Editors’ and translator’s note” at the beginning of this book. 5 In an article on the evolution of the notion of the “dispositif” in the f ield of sociology, Jean-Samuel Beuscart and Ashveen Peerbaye observe, on the basis of a statistical study, that

The Moment of the “Dispositif”

181

that it corresponded to a new concept. The pitfall of nominalism should be avoided, which is why I will privilege the question of strategy over that of origin. The questioning opening my analysis starts from the premise that, far from arbitrary, the advent of a concept always takes place as a response to a problem. This necessity, taken to be part of the incipiency of any concept, will guide my analysis: to which problem did the concept of apparatus respond in the early 1970s in the field of film theory? Which conceptual lack did it come to offset?6 In his article, Baudry extended the reflection initiated in Cinéthique to cinematographic technique as a whole. His aim, true in that respect to the materialist project of the periodical, was to take apart the ideology determined by the machinery allowing films to be made. The notion of basic apparatus proposed in the first part of the text accordingly has as its function to establish “the place of the instrumental base in the set of operations which combine in the production of a film.”7 This new notion was to allow and extend a reflection which in the first issues of Cinéthique had focused on the camera alone. Baudry took up the idea according to which the camera, insofar as it reproduced the monocular perspective of the Quattrocento, “specifie[d] in return the position of the subject.”8 With one difference, though: the camera was now part of the synthetic category basic apparatus, along with editing (which produces continuity out “dispositifs” are “everywhere on the different f ields of social sciences.” The two authors do mention Baudry’s article when tracing back the notion to its origins. See Jean-Samuel Beuscart and Ashveen Peerbaye, “Histoires de dispositifs,” Terrains et travaux 11 (2006): 3-15. 6 Derrida formulated a similar question about the notion of structure: “To know why one says ‘structure’ is to know why one no longer wishes to say eidos, ‘essence,’ form, Gestalt, ‘ensemble,’ ‘composition’ […]. One must understand not only why each of these words showed itself to be insufficient but also why the notion of structure continues to borrow some implicit signification from them and to be inhabited by them.” Jacques Derrida, “Force and Signification” [1963], in Writing and Difference, trans. Alan Bass (London: Routledge, 1978) n301. 7 Jean-Louis Baudry, “Ideological Effects of the Basic Cinematographic Apparatus” [1970] in Narrative, Apparatus, Ideology. A Film Theory Reader, ed. Philip Rosen (New York: Columbia University Press, 1986) 286-98. 8 Baudry, “Ideological Effects”: 289. These thoughts, which imply that the homogeneous space configured by monocular perspective assign the spectator a central position corresponding to the modern conception of the subject, partly come from Pierre Francastel’s work on painting (Peinture et société: naissance et destruction d’un espace plastique de la Renaissance au cubisme, 1951; La Figure et le lieu. L’ordre visuel du Quattrocento, 1967), as well as from Jurgis Baltrusaïtis on perspective distortion (Anamorphoses ou Thaumaturgus Opticus, 1955) or Jean-Louis Schefer (Scénographie d’un tableau, 1969). In France, these thinkers expanded on the work of Erwin Panofsky on perspective, itself in a relation of continuity with Ernst Cassirer’s neo-Kantian philosophy of symbolic forms.

182 

Omar Hachemi

of fragments) and projection (which subjects the spectator to the specular order). According to Baudry, these three poles (shooting, editing, projection) contribute to the “subject-effect” in that they conceal their operation to enhance filmic continuity. The analogy with the Lacanian unconscious comes into play at this level, though it also runs throughout the article: as we shall see, this analogy gives Baudry’s theory a paradoxical inflection. After noting that discontinuity, inherent to the fragmentary nature of cinema, is denied by the work of editing, Baudry evokes the “disturbing effects” which follow without fail from “breakdowns in the recreation of movement” (during screening). In his view, the consequence of these breakdowns is that “the spectator is brought abruptly back to discontinuity – that is, to the body, to the technical apparatus which he had forgotten.” The analogy with the slips of the tongue, which manifest the unconscious on the surface of language through breaks, opens immediately afterwards: We might not be far from seeing what is in play on this material basis if we recall that the “language” of the unconscious, as it is found in dreams, slips of the tongue, or hysterical symptoms, manifests itself as continuity destroyed, broken, and as the unexpected surging forth of a marked difference.9

The term “language,” between quotation marks in the text, follows from the slogan that summarizes the Lacanian conception of the unconscious: “The unconscious is structured as a language.”10 This analogy with the Lacanian unconscious situates the basic apparatus at the exact position of 9 Baudry, “Ideological Effects”: 291. 10 Lacan’s contribution with regard to the unconscious was largely conditioned by structural linguistics. According to Lacanian theory, the unconscious is not a hidden entity: it is a matter of surface. It does not elude the attention of the subject by hiding in some depths so much as by being present in a dazzling proximity. The unconscious is structured like a language insofar as it fits within the category of the signifier which, in language, does not seem to be at the forefront: the signifier is repressed, the signified played up. To illustrate this proximity of the signifier, Lacan takes his example from The Purloined Letter, a letter concealed all the better by its thief as it is left in plain view. The example leads Lacan to refer to Heidegger and conclude that nothing hides more than what unveils. In other words, the subject is built on not knowing what constitutes it. Lacan interestingly translates the Freudian notion of “unconscious” (das Unbewusst) as “une-bévue” [“a blunder”], a play on the signifier that initially seems to take place to the detriment of meaning. Yet “une-bévue,” insisting as it does on the unpredictable aspect of the slip of the tongue (as of a blunder), stresses the unconscious only in that it is manifest. Against the “Romantic” conception of the unconscious, Lacan conceptualizes a depthless unconscious, according to Serge Cottet. See Serge Cottet, “Je pense où je ne suis pas, je suis où je ne pense pas,” Lacan (Paris: Bordas, 1987) 13.

The Moment of the “Dispositif”

183

the signifier insofar as, in Lacanian theory, the latter is the vector of the unconscious on the surface of language. Far from marginal, this analogy between the basic apparatus and the unconscious comes at the close of Baudry’s article. After identifying the appearance of the instrument “in flesh and blood” in film with the “return of the repressed,” Baudry concludes that “to this unconscious would be attached the mode of production of film, the process of work in its multiple determinations […].”11 In fact, the basic apparatus – whose primary function was to extend the reflection opened by Cinéthique and once focused on the camera alone to include cinematographic technique as a whole – squares with the category of the signifier under the effect of the analogy with the Lacanian unconscious. Namely, the “basic apparatus” interests Baudry only from the angle of its visible manifestations within the finished product. This reduction of technique to the Lacanian concept of signifier has theoretical implications, one of which being that the distinction previously established between apparatus and basic apparatus loses its relevance. Indeed, as the article progresses, the moment of projection (apparatus) completely rules out the genesis of the film (basic apparatus). Baudry was in fact to discard the second notion and stick to the apparatus in the article he later published in Communications.12

Suture, The Zero Signifier In 1969, one year prior to Baudry’s article, Jean-Pierre Oudart imported the concept of suture from psychoanalytic theory into the field of film studies.13 This concept is akin to that of apparatus in that it posits the spectator as the result of a subjection produced by representation and 11 Baudry, “Ideological Effects”: 296. 12 Before doing away with the notion of basic apparatus, Baudry redefined it as follows: “In a general way, we distinguish the basic cinematographic apparatus, which concerns the ensemble of the equipment and operations necessary to the production of a film and its projection, from the apparatus, discussed in this article, which solely concerns projection and which includes the subject to whom the projection is addressed.” See Jean-Louis Baudry, “The Apparatus: Metapsychological Approaches to the Impression of Reality in Cinema” [1975], in Narrative, Apparatus, Ideology. A Film Theory Reader, ed. Philip Rosen (New York: Columbia University Press, 1986) 317. 13 The article was published in two parts in Cahiers du cinéma 211 (first part) and 212 (second part), April and May 1969. An English translation of the two parts appeared as “Cinema and Suture” in Cahiers du cinéma 1969-1972. The Politics of Representation, ed. Nick Browne (Cambridge: Harvard U.P., 1989) 45-57.

184 

Omar Hachemi

its techniques. Oudart’s article, by relating to Jacques-Alain Miller’s text (also titled “Suture”),14 refers to the Lacanian axiom of the subject spelled out in Écrits (1966): “a signifier is what represents the subject to another signifier.”15 For Oudart the signifier is fundamentally plural, an element in a series that involves several, and whose subject constitutes the central link as a result of suture. At the center of representation, the subject occupies the position of an empty square according to which signifiers are distributed and configured. This “place of the absent” is reified in cinema by what Oudart calls “the fourth side”: with the field limited by framing – the scenic space of cinema – identified with a cube, the screen facing the spectator becomes a (fourth) side.16 The other side of framing and depth of field is the place of the spectator whose gaze is inscribed negatively, through this symmetry, at the center of representation. As a consequence, the subject is none other than the lack inscribed in representation, “the place of the absent.” For Oudart this lack is the condition of possibility for classical representation, whose construction rests on a solar conception of the subject: “At a certain moment of the reading all the objects of the filmic field combine together to form the signifier of its absence.”17 Suture is this articulation between images, between shots, in that it operates through the subject, an empty square needed for meaning to circulate. It is accordingly the adaptation for cinema of the Lacanian logic of the subject: the subject exists only in the suture it performs between signifiers. “Cinema and Suture” may be traced back to Francastel’s work on monocular perspective as much as to Foucault’s analysis of Velasquez’s painting Las Meninas or Lacan’s own analysis of Holbein’s The Ambassadors. Both 14 Jacques-Alain Miller, “Suture (Elements of the Logic of the Signif ier)” [1966], Screen 18 (1977-1978). 15 Jacques Lacan, Ecrits. The First Complete Edition in English, trans. Bruce Fink (New York: Norton & Company, 2005) 694. This axiom is at the root of the theory of “intersignifierness” [“intersignifiance”], which replaces the phenomenological notion of intersubjectivity. 16 Oudart, “Cinema and Suture” 46. It seems as though this topology of the cube was borrowed from Pierre Francastel, who used a similar schematization to evoke painting founded on the perspectival code of the Renaissance: “Founded on a thoughtful knowledge of Euclid’s laws – the codification of the rules for ‘normal’ operating vision in humankind – the method, from that point on, had images inscribed within Alberti’s window as within a cube open on one side. The laws of physics and optics of our world govern within this representational cube, this kind of miniature world.” See Pierre Francastel, Peinture et société (Lyons: Audin, 1951) 40. As to Panofsky, he put forward the concept of “space box” (Raumkasten) to refer to the phenomenon by which the materiality of the painting became secondary by comparison with its representation of volume. See Erwin Panofsky, Perspective as a Symbolic Form, trans. Christopher S. Wood (Cambridge: Zone Books, 1996) 39. 17 Oudart, “Cinema and Suture”: 46.

The Moment of the “Dispositif”

185

Foucault and Lacan problematize the issue of the spectator as defined in relation to pictorial representation. Lacan shows that the anamorphosis of the skull situated at the feet of the ambassadors, once perceived from the angle out of which it is set out, exposes the artifice specific to perspective, reflecting “the subject as annihilated”18 to the looking subject. The sudden appearance of the skull, or signifier (phallus), betrays the failure of representation as a trap: “[…] we are literally called into the picture, and represented here as caught.”19 Lacan concludes that any painting constitutes “a trap for the gaze,”20 as “the subject […] is caught, manipulated, captured in the field of vision.”21 As for anamorphosis, it reveals the artifice. The anamorphosis of the skull, catching as it does the oblique gaze, also liberates it from the trap instituted by frontal perspective. For his part, Foucault shows that the mirror play at the center of Velasquez’s painting organizes representation around an inaccessible place – outside the painting but “prescribed by all the lines of its composition.”22 The representation as a whole presumably converges towards the point where the gaze of the spectator, that of the painter and that of the model (the sovereigns) overlap: These three “observing” functions come together in a point exterior to the picture: that is, an ideal point in relation to what is represented, but a perfectly real one too, since it is also the starting-point that makes the representation possible.23

Foucault considers Las Meninas as “the representation […] of Classical representation”: the staging of pictorial gesture in response to the posture of the model. With this specular method, the canvas imperiously indicates the “essential void” that constitutes it, “the necessary disappearance of that which is its foundation.” This void is none other than the place of the

18 Jacques Lacan, The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis, ed. Jacques-Alain Miller, trans. Alan Sheridan (New York: Norton, 1998) 88. The text was established on the basis of the seminar of February 26, 1964. 19 Lacan, The Four Fundamental Concepts 92. 20 Lacan, The Four Fundamental Concepts 89. 21 Lacan, The Four Fundamental Concepts 92. 22 Michel Foucault, “Las Meninas” [1966], in The Order of Things. An Archaeology of the Human Sciences (London: Routledge, 2002) 15. On what this analysis of Las Meninas owes to Panofsky’s theory, see Lucien Vinciguerra, “Comment inverser exactement les Ménines: Michel Foucault et la peinture à la fin des années 1960, des formes symboliques aux dispositifs,” in Le Moment philosophique des années 1960 en France, ed. Patrice Maniglier (Paris: PUF, 2011). 23 Foucault, “Las Meninas” 16.

186 

Omar Hachemi

subject, the opening of the painting to “what is intimately foreign to it.”24 Foucault’s analysis, like Lacan’s, integrates the subject in the painting in the negative form of a blind spot that makes representation possible. This conception is central to Oudart’s article.25 “Cinema and Suture” thus appears to be part of this first moment in apparatus theory insofar as it configures critical thought around monocular perspective, on the one hand, and the concept of the signifier, on the other. Rereading Baudry’s text in the continuity of “Cinema and Suture” proves all the more worthwhile as it – unsuccessfully – attempts to move away from it, precisely, by rejecting the notion of the signifier. Baudry’s refusal of the concept comes after his project of systemizing technique (hence the notion of basic apparatus). However, the theoretical approach contradicts the project immediately after it has been formulated: since technique is apprehended only from the angle of the spectator, Baudry’s position does in fact come close to Oudart’s symptom-based approach. With one difference: in “Cinema and Suture,” because of its autonomy from the Althusserian concept of ideology, the concept of signifier involves a dynamic function which Baudry was not to maintain.26

Photology: The Hegemony of the Eye In an article co-authored with Oudart, “Travail, lecture, jouissance,” Serge Daney deals with “the ideology of the visible” which dominates Western culture and its metaphysical tradition. In his view, the ideological function of cinematographic technique may be traced back to a period preceding 24 Foucault, “Las Meninas” 17-18. 25 In his text on Structuralism, Gilles Deleuze insists on the central part played by the “empty square,” choosing the example of Foucault’s commentary on Las Meninas and Miller’s “Suture” to illustrate the decisive function of this empty square (which he also calls object=x) in the structural approach. This “eminently symbolic” object, of which Deleuze writes that it is “missing from its place,” “always displaced in relation to itself,” is what gives the structure its openness. Gilles Deleuze, “How Do We Recognize Structuralism?” [1967], trans. Melissa McMahon and Charles J. Stivale, in Charles J. Stivale, The Two-Fold Thought of Deleuze and Guattari. Intersections and Animations (New York: The Guilford Press, 1998) 251-82. 26 In an article titled “L’Effet de réel,” in the continuity of the premises of “Cinema and Suture,” Oudart brings up Foucault’s analysis of Las Meninas, making the main assumptions of the text his own. Oudart notably puts forward the notion of scenic apparatus to mark the implication of the spectator in the space of representation. See Jean-Pierre Oudart, “The Reality Effect” [1971], trans. Annwyl Williams, in Cahiers du cinéma 1969-1972. The Politics of Representation, ed. Nick Browne (Cambridge: Harvard U.P., 1989) 189-202.

The Moment of the “Dispositif”

187

the perspective of the Quattrocento, in the “hegemony of the eye” that characterizes Western culture, a culture which places “quite [a] blind trust in the visible.”27 Daney uses the term “photology” in reference to Derrida to designate the supremacy of the visible of which cinema is a part. Indeed, cinema is a matter of gaze: “I see, therefore I am aware” may well be the very logic of cinema, according to Daney, who adds that “the logic of sight and oversight” may come to an end that can already be “discern[ed].” The end in question may be disclosed by the advertising film, which makes the equation “real = visible” its ultimate slogan.28 If Daney, referring to Derrida’s article “Force and Signification,” evokes the “photology” that dominates Western metaphysics and criticizes the role played by cinema in this idealism, he leaves aside the fact that this argument, in Derrida’s article, is part of a critique addressed at Structuralism.29 For Derrida, the structural method proceeds from a synchronic reduction of the studied object – a reduction of “force” to “form” which presupposes a teleological approach. Dealing with cinema, Daney reclaims Derrida’s argument of photology against Structuralism: “The cinema is therefore connected to the Western metaphysical tradition, a tradition of seeing and sight for which it fulfills the photological vocation.”30 Daney’s position is very close to those of Cinéthique in this instance: through its photological vocation, cinema neutralizes duration and force (work, film genesis) to privilege “the illusion of simultaneity and form” (the film as finished product) – this inasmuch as “light effaces its traces; invisible itself, it renders visible.”31 In the first part of his series of articles “Technique and Ideology,”32 JeanLouis Comolli points out – on the argument of photology advanced by Daney 27 Serge Daney and Jean-Pierre Oudart, “Work, Reading, Pleasure” [1970], trans. Diana Matias, in Cahiers du cinéma 1969-1972. The Politics of Representation, ed. Nick Browne (Cambridge: Harvard U.P., 1989) 116. The first part, “On Salador,” on which I concentrate here, is by Serge Daney. 28 Daney and Oudart, “Work, Reading, Pleasure”: 116, 117. 29 On photology, see Jacques Derrida, “Force and Signification” 27. The article as a whole turns on Jean Rousset’s text “Form and Signification,” which Derrida considers a perfect example of the Structuralism he sets about to critique. 30 Daney and Oudart, “Work, Reading, Pleasure”: 116. 31 This quotation, unreferenced in Daney’s text, comes from Maurice Blanchot’s Infinite Conversation [1969]: “Light effaces its traces: invisible, it renders visible; it guarantees direct knowledge and ensures full presence, all the while holding itself back in that which is indirect and suppressing itself as presence.” Maurice Blanchot, Infinite Conversation, trans. Susan Hanson (Minneapolis: The University of Minnesota Press, 1993) 163. 32 Jean-Louis Comolli, “Technique and Ideology: Camera, Perspective, Depth of Field,” parts 1 and 2 [1971], trans. Diana Matias, in Cahiers du cinéma 1969-1972. The Politics of Representation, ed. Nick Browne (Cambridge: Harvard U.P., 1989) 213-47.

188 

Omar Hachemi

on cinema – the paradox that undermines all theories founded on the equivalence between technique and ideology, namely, that these theories are based on modalities which they condemn. In that sense, Daney’s article is symptomatic of the “theoretical paradox” already at work in Cinéthique, and the ideology of the visible is repeated by the gesture that claims to deconstruct it: […] the reduction of the hidden part of technique to its visible part carries the risk of reasserting the domination of the visible, i.e. the ideology of the visible (and what it implies: the masking and effacement of work).33

Concentrating on the “photology” that dominates cinema, Daney thus ends up screening all the better the ideology of the visible that undermines film theory. In other words, photology does not only concern film production and its techniques: it also dominates the theory that reduces the hidden part of cinema to what is visible of it. The photology diagnosed about cinema lies at the center of the theoretical tool that makes the diagnosis possible in the first place. This first part of my analysis, devoted to Baudry, calls for a few observations. First, the “photology” that hovers over the theory of the apparatus is also a symptom of its unspoken dependence on the concept of the signifier which – after a deep transformation – has been exported towards psychoanalysis and cinema. Starting from this assessment, I looked for antecedents, one of which was “Cinema and Suture,” with its massive (and explicit) reliance on this concept. By contrast, save for a few passing allusions, it turned out that the notion of signifier was cleverly circumvented at Cinéthique.34 Still, it seemed to me that, while the word was being avoided, the concept remained rather active: the basic apparatus, endorsing as it did the structural category of the signifier, seemed a perfect instance of the hegemony of the “Structuralist” paradigm in the early 1970s. The conclusion of these observations may be stated as follows: the “theoretical paradox” noted by Comolli at the center of the technique/ideology equivalence resulted from the attempt to cut loose from concepts of signifier and structure while remaining within the field of their conceptual system. The invention of 33 Comolli, “Technique and Ideology”: 218. 34 Baudry, criticizing the absence of a study devoted to the analysis of ideological determinations of cinematographic technique, notes the exclusive interest of theory in the “field of the signified.” In this passage, the basic apparatus, opposed to the “field of the signified,” is clearly identified with the signifier. See Baudry, “Ideological Effects”: 287.

The Moment of the “Dispositif”

189

the new lexicon, then, would have had as its aim to hide a conceptual lack with regard to cinematographic technique, since the lack in question could not seem to be filled. I could go even further and venture that the “theoretical paradox” pointed out by Comolli at the center of the theory of the apparatus was identical to that noted by Derrida in his “Force and Signification,” with one difference: Derrida puts the paradox down to the structural method, whereas Comolli remains more cautious on that account. Derrida spells out the paradox as follows: […] light is menaced from within by that which also metaphysically menaces every structuralism: the possibility of concealing meaning through the very act of uncovering it. To comprehend the structure of a becoming, the form of a force, is to lose meaning by finding it.35

The equation set down by Comolli – which, referring to Derrida’s text, identified form to the finished product (the film) and force to the production process (work, technique) – has as its result that film theory becomes captive to the paradox uncovered by Derrida within Structuralism. Indeed, doesn’t film theory try to understand force in relation to form, the genesis of the film out of the structure of the finished product? Baudry is accordingly confronted with a dizzying paradox when, referring to Vertov, he emphasizes the appearance of the camera “in flesh and blood”36 within the film. That is, the exposure of the camera, far from producing the expected demystifying effect, conceals the camera actually filming all the better (meaning is concealed “through the very act of uncovering it”). Rather than breaking the illusion of reality, the method further amplifies it.37

From Symptomal Reading to Archaeological Approach When Comolli points out “the reduction of the hidden part of technique to its visible part”38 central to the theory developed by Cinéthique, he puts

35 Derrida, “Force and Signification” 26. 36 Baudry, “Ideological Effects” 296. 37 Incidentally, “Cinema and Suture,” which fully acknowledges the concept of signifier, openly deals with this paradox considered as the blind spot, the empty core any representation needs. 38 Comolli, “Technique and Ideology” 218.

190 

Omar Hachemi

his finger on the teleology inherent in that approach.39 This criticism of teleology becomes more pronounced in the second part of “Technique and Ideology,” when Comolli’s historiographic thought touches on theoretical discourses on deep focus. He then de-centers the argument developed by Cinéthique on the Quattrocento perspective, noting that, far from being essentially cinematographic, this perspectivist code has to do with deep focus, and therefore the choice of lenses. Comolli goes in detail over the technical setting that allows an optimal reproduction of the perspectivist code of the Renaissance (wide angle, small diaphragm aperture) and dwells on the normative function of any theory (notably Marcelin Pleynet’s) that tends to essentialize one use and exclude all others. Indeed, in the theory of Cinéthique, a break in the perspectivist code – inasmuch as it has the effect of also breaking the illusion of reality and reminding spectators of their condition – is apprehended as a slip revealing the materialist essence of cinema. Once again, the parallel with “Force and Signification” is obvious. According to Derrida, a rigorous structural method ought “to refuse to relegate everything that is not comprehensible as an ideal type to the status of aberrational accident.”40 Even though Cinéthique considered these accidents to be as many breaks in the cinematographic telos, as many salutary blunders shattering the ideological screen of technique, they were still taken to be breaks in a structuring process, as far as method was concerned. Baudry thus mentions the unfulfilled continuity that defines the return of the repressed (the disclosure of the equipment). For Comolli as for Derrida, effects of rupture thwarting the structure are still part of another structuring process which also calls for analysis: “The pathological itself is not the simple absence of structure. It is organized.”41 Similarly, 39 The critique of teleology is central to Derrida’s text: “Whether biology, linguistics, or literature is in question, how can an organized totality be perceived without reference to its end, or without presuming to know its end, at least?” See Derrida, “Force and Signification” 30. Likewise, according to Comolli, “cinema’s historical scene” is apprehended “from its scene in the present.” See Jean-Louis Comolli, “Technique and Ideology,” parts 3 and 4, in Narrative, Apparatus, Ideology. A Film Theory Reader, ed. Philip Rosen (New York: Columbia University Press, 1986) 421-43, 426. 40 Derrida, “Force and Signification” 26. 41 Derrida, “Force and Signification” 26. This argument is at the center of Derrida’s critique of Foucault’s thesis on madness. Derrida reproaches Foucault with relegating madness – considered as “silence,” “absence of a work” – outside any structuring process. See “Cogito and the History of Madness” [1963], in Writing and Difference (London: Routledge, 1978). Foucault answered Derrida’s critique in a text titled “My Body, This Paper, This Fire,” published as an appendix to the second edition of History of Madness by Gallimard in 1972. See Michel Foucault, History of Madness (London: Routledge, 2006) 550-74.

The Moment of the “Dispositif”

191

on a historiographic level, Comolli refuses to conceptualize the history of (pre)cinema in a linear manner. He borrows the concept of differential historical temporality from Althusser, a concept which advocates a perspective taking multiple determinations into account, against “the model of a continuous and homogeneous time.”42 “Cinema” thus finds itself at the crossroads between several histories: optics, photography, mechanics, the arts of spectacle. The entity “cinema” is disseminated in multiple histories governed by distinct temporalities; and these temporalities are irreducible to a homogeneous process aimed at the fulfillment of its own essence. 43 Even though the notion of apparatus was not systematically repeated by Comolli, it was used occasionally from the third part of “Technique and Ideology” on, as well as in other issues of Cahiers du cinéma. The object of variations, its plurality made possible the deconstruction of the myth of origins at work in the history of cinema: “technical devices,” for instance, cannot be dissociated from “signifying practices” of which they are the causes as well as the effects; and these devices depend on their environment. 44 Invoked by Bonitzer to stress the importance of “the place as scenic apparatus” in his analysis of The Ceremony, 45 the notion is otherwise used to designate the structure of narrative hollowed out in its center by “a hole eating it away and engendering it.” In this “wedding without a bride,” the “impressive ceremonial deployment, the fixed gestures of the ritual”46 thus have no other function than referring to the central absence of the bride – also “the empty square,” “the dummy hand” [“la place du mort”] at the center of the film, which “articulates a circulation of genealogical and sexual conjectures.”47 As for Oudart, he uses the notion in his article “L’Effet 42 See Louis Althusser and Etienne Balibar, Reading Capital [1968], trans. Ben Brewster (London, New York: Verso, 2009) 110. 43 According to André Gaudreault and Tom Gunning, Comolli’s arguments contributed to establishing the bases for the “new film history” with which they associate themselves. See André Gaudreault and Tom Gunning, “Le cinéma des premiers temps: un défi à l’histoire du cinéma?” in Histoire du cinéma, nouvelles approches (Paris: Colloque de Cerisy-Publications de la Sorbonne, 1989) 53. 44 Jean-Louis Comolli, “Technique and Ideology,” in Narrative, Apparatus, Ideology 429, 425. 45 Nagisa Ōshima, The Ceremony (Japan, 1971). 46 Pascal Bonitzer, “A propos de ‘La Cérémonie,’ ” Cahiers du cinéma 231 (Aug.-Sept. 1971): 6-7. 47 Bonitzer, “A propos de ‘La Cérémonie’ ”: 11. Deleuze emphasizes the central function of this “empty square” in structuralism: “Lacan invokes the dummy hand in bridge, and in the admirable opening pages of The Order of Things, where he describes a painting by Velasquez, Foucault invokes the place of the king, in relation to which everything is displaced and slides, God, then man, without ever filling it. No structuralism is possible without this degree zero.” See Deleuze, “How Do We Recognize Structuralism?” 275. Lacan does indeed refer to the “dummy hand” in bridge, but in a very allusive manner. See Jacques Lacan, Ecrits 492-3.

192 

Omar Hachemi

de réel” as well as in the series titled “Notes for a theory of representation”48 which continues it. The notion of apparatus, prompting a reflection on space, allows Oudart to broach the question of representation through the topology of the stage, at the intersection of theater, painting and cinema. Incidentally, in this as in previous cases, the notion is not the object of any definition: it makes sense immanently, according to its use.

The “Dispositif”: A Concept Missing from Its Place? If the current use of the notion of “dispositif,”49 in its multiple variations, owes anything to Baudry’s theory, it may be primarily the extent to which the latter revealed the conceptual blur involved in the notion, as soon as it was imported in the field of cinema. The moment of the “dispositif” was the place of an intense debate where heterogeneous types of knowledge met around a common issue. In Baudry, this issue resonates in the form of a paradox revealing the absence of a suitable theoretical tool for a genuine materialist approach to cinema. In short, the project of conceptualization aimed at the cinematographic technique did not only make use of the – then new – notion of apparatus, but also – in response to the problems brought up by the notion – a new historiographic perspective capable of thinking about technique from the angle of its genesis. The notion of apparatus was initially put forward by Baudry to refer to technique and its ideological effects on the spectator. It then came with the notion of basic apparatus which, according to his description, involved film technique as a whole and therefore encompassed the apparatus – which designated only the moment of projection and its arrangement. The organization of these two notions seems functional, except that the psychoanalytic reference causes a gradual reversal to occur in the text: cinematographic technique, insofar as it is comparable to the unconscious, interests Baudry only from the standpoint of its visible manifestations in the film. And these manifestations are assumed to produce the same effect as the return of the repressed in the psychoanalytic cure… Eventually, since technique is apprehended only from the limited angle of the spectator, 48 Jean-Pierre Oudart, “Notes for a Theory of Representation” [1971], trans. Annwyl Williams, in Cahiers du cinéma 1969-1972. The Politics of Representation, ed. Nick Browne (Cambridge: Harvard U.P., 1989) 203-12. 49 Translator’s note: this current use is translated as “dispositive” in this volume. See the “Editors’ and translator’s note.”

The Moment of the “Dispositif”

193

the apparatus supplants the basic apparatus and paradoxically ends up including what was to include it. The paradox was to be cleared up only later through a historiographic reflection led by Comolli, which opened onto a conception of technique immanent to its genesis, that is, irreducible to its visible traces within the film. The notion of signifier lends itself well to psychoanalytic praxis – the unconscious of the psychoanalyzed being inseparable from the “fluctuating” attention of the psychoanalyst, attuned to “blunders” appearing on the surface of language (leading Lacan to state that the unconscious did not exist outside the cure). Yet cinema itself undeniably exists independently from the spectator’s gaze. This existence is none other than the genesis of the film, precisely that which Comolli’s perspective incorporates. In fact, de-centering film studies is necessary, whether the work to be done is a rigorous reflection on technique and work ahead of the film or the development of “a materialist history of film.”50 The teleological perspective that reduces force to form and sees the essence of cinema in the film proves untenable. Its deconstruction by Comolli has as its result two postulates, one on the scale of history, the other on the scale of the film. First, film history may not be reduced to the films punctuating it; second, film production (technique and its use) may not be apprehended from the sole standpoint of the completed film. All in all, in the early 1970s, the “dispositif” was singularly missing from its place. Though the word was advanced by Baudry as part of a tangled logic, the concept came into being only as Comolli cleared up the paradox that made it inconsistent. However, once the concept was freed from the contradictions that weakened it, it was the word that was missing… Indeed, though frequently used issue after issue in Cahiers du cinéma, the notion of “dispositif” does not come with a definition: its meaning is subordinated to its use.

50 Comolli, “Technique and Ideology”: 422.



The “Dispositive Effect” in Film Narrative Philippe Ortel

Like the idea of structure, the notion of the “dispositif” does not pertain to a single level of analysis: it applies to specific objects, such as the mechanism of a watch, but also to large ensembles, as in Foucault’s work, where it came to substitute for the episteme in the late 1970s. By contrast to the episteme, focused too narrowly on the utterances produced by a society, Foucault’s dispositif refers more widely to the totality of discourses, social practices, technical inventions, architectural creations instituting, at a given time, the partition between the true and the false in the domain of knowledge, the legitimate and the illegitimate in the sphere of power.1 There now seems to be general agreement on the term “arrangement,” used liberally to describe “dispositifs,” insofar as it conveys both their constitutive heterogeneity and their power of organization.2 For Bernard Vouilloux, for instance, a “dispositif” is an “arrangement that actualizes and integrates elements with an objective in sight,”3 which may apply to an administrative measure, a military strategy, or a pedagogical practice; but also in a very different context, as far as Foucault’s model is concerned, since the heterogeneous factors instituting knowledges and powers (this would be the arrangement) are shot through by individual or collective, conscious or unconscious strategies leading to the promotion of enunciable discourses and legitimized powers. 1 On this definition of the dispositif, see the interview given by Foucault to periodical Ornicar in 1977, “Le jeu de Michel Foucault,” translated in English as “The Confession of the Flesh” and published in Power/Knowledge. Selected Interviews and Other Writings, ed. Colin Gordon (Brighton: The Harvester Press, 1980). Foucault developed the notion of the dispositif starting with Discipline and Punish (1975), then with the first part of The History of Sexuality (1976). On the subject, see Bernard Vouilloux, “La critique des dispositifs,” in Discours, image, dispositif, ed. Philippe Ortel (Paris: L’Harmattan, 2008) 16-31, as well as Alain Brossat’s clarification, “La notion de dispositif chez Michel Foucault,” in Miroirs, appareils et autres dispositifs, ed. Soko Phay-Vakalis (Paris: L’Harmattan, 2008) 199-207. Brossat insists on the two scales of the dispositif in Foucault’s thought, the network and the identified mechanism that enters this network (“large dispositifs entail increasing the effect of a whole series of specific micro-dispositifs,” 205). For example, social security could be considered as a part within a larger “security dispositif.” 2 See issue 25 of periodical Hermès (1999), which has come to serve as a point of reference, “Le dispositif entre usage et concept,” ed. Geneviève Jacquinot-Delaunay and Laurence Monnoyer. 3 Vouilloux, “La critique des dispositifs”: 24.

196 Philippe Ortel

When, as part of more limited “dispositifs,” a technical arrangement – or any reality endowed with the same function4 – regulates relations between subjects,5 two other dimensions come into play: a pragmatic dimension, obvious in the case of communication tools since they mediate our exchanges, but also a symbolic dimension, in the current sense of “values,” for a “dispositif” would hold no meaning or legitimacy without the semantic and axiological values pervading it. The movie theater considered as a media pragmatically regulates the relation of filmmakers to their audience and serves as a vehicle for “some” symbolic content insofar as a film generally produces a direct or indirect discourse on the world: if it did not, the public would likely spurn it sooner than later. Likewise, taken as a social ritual, the same show regulates the relation of the crowd with itself and marks – between other values immanent in the invention – the emergence of a democratic mass culture whose constitution was noted by Louis Delluc as early as 1920: “Cinema is more theatrical than theater insofar as it talks to the whole world. Its audience is made up of the crowd, of all crowds.”6 These three components – technical (which will be referred to as I), pragmatic (II), and symbolic (III) – come up in a number of disciplines, but in a sometimes partial or implicit manner. To turn them into a unified model may allow us to better analyze certain social practices and the way representation functions, as we will see. Regarding cinema, analyses by Jean-Louis Baudry and Christian Metz have shown in different words to what extent the material conditions for viewing a film (I) regulated the way in which the film’s message was received (II) and deciphered (III). Metz notably insisted on the fact that secondary processes in the understanding of film originated in a dreaming state, itself the result of the relative immobility of spectators and their immersion in darkness.7 On a more limited scale, studies from the same period also showed how the optics of the camera (I) reproduced the classical perspective, as in photography, and through it a certain relation of the subject to the world characterized by a 4 To give the model some plasticity, I am expanding it here to include any agency with a visible conditioning power. 5 On this interaction, see Giorgio Agamben, What Is an Apparatus? (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2009). 6 Louis Delluc, “La foule au cinéma” (1920), in Le Cinéma. Naissance d’un art, texts selected by Daniel Banda and José Moure (Paris: Flammarion, 2008) 506. 7 For the fourth part of The Imaginary Signifier (1977), he assigns himself the task of analyzing the “primary operations floating on the surface of the ‘secondarised’ chain of filmic discourse.” Christian Metz, “Film and Dream: Degrees of Secondarisation,” The Imaginary Signifier. Psychoanalysis and the Cinema (Bloomington, Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1986) 125.

The “Dispositive Effect” in Film Narrative

197

central, omnipotent position (II) pervaded by a genuine ideological system (III). For Baudry the classical perspective, by making spectators the sole visual origin of the visible world, reinforced them in their prerogatives as subjects,8 and with no de-centering to speak of, except in the case of radical aesthetic choices by a few filmmakers looking to prevent the primary identification of the eye to the camera. These thoughts have since been reformulated and further examined in publications such as the issue of Cahier Louis Lumière on “Les Dispositifs,” which takes into account new technologies around cinema, or the periodical Cinémas in an issue devoted to early cinema.9 It may be interesting, however, to return to the way in which the notion has been applied to the fictional form and content of the films themselves, that is, to their poetics. Some compositional modes, such as the choral form, which are meeting with success at the moment (41 feature films were listed in this category on the site Allociné.com as of March 2009) or, on a more thematic level, films such as Alfred Hitchcock’s Rear Window (1954) or Steven Spielberg’s The Terminal (2004), show that some works put forward formal or material arrangements, with their action depending on these.10 Far from being mere settings, places like windows or airports, which regulate human activities, may impose their own logic on the narrative – to the point of thwarting traditional narrative processes, sometimes completely. Besides, the fact that many filmmakers (Victor Erice, Abbas Kiarostami, Chantal Akerman, Agnès Varda…) indulge in the practice of art installations in parallel to their activity in cinema shows well enough the attraction which the “dispositif” as a form exerts on them. Consequently, this form may not be limited to the technological conditions of production and reception of films alone, since it plays a part in their very development. I will therefore try and fashion a common model for all these phenomena, proposing an aesthetic continuation of the apparatus theory of the 1970s.

8 Jean-Louis Baudry, L’Effet-cinéma (Paris: Editions Albatros, 1978). For a synthesis of what was sometimes called “apparatus theory” in the 1970s, see Guido Kirsten’s thorough analysis “Genèse d’un concept et ses avatars. La naissance de la théorie du dispositif cinématographique,” Cahier Louis Lumière 4, “Les dispositifs” (July 2007): 8-16. 9 “Dispositif(s) du cinéma (des premiers temps)” Cinémas 14.1 (Fall 2003). 10 On this type of approach, see for instance François Albera, “La position du voyeur couché: Hitchcock avec Klossowski,” Cinémathèque 13 (Spring 1998): 91-100; and Maria Tortajada, “Dispositifs de vision et modèles de pouvoir: ‘Devant la loi’ de F. Kafka,” Revue européenne des sciences sociales 44.133 (2006): 37-52.

198 Philippe Ortel

Tensions in Representation Narrative theories are still strongly marked by the linguistic model, at least in France. Like discourse, which unfolds in a linear manner, carefully articulating the befores and the afters (“First…”, “then…”), causes and effects (but also the means and the end, the conditions and their result, and so on), narrative is approached from the standpoint of the logical and chronological model of argumentation. This holds all the more true as a novel or a film often produces a discourse on the world through the indirect path of fiction. Without denying the sway of the logical-discursive process (or its deconstruction), the point in this instance is to de-center our point of view on representation, narrative or not, examining the share of the dispositive in it prior to teasing out any implicit discourse. This amounts to locating our three components – technical, pragmatic and symbolic – on multiple levels in the representation and examining how they are arranged together. Whereas the discursive approach treats the film as a succession producing semantic and axiological values, the “dispositive approach” ties up this symbolic level with the two others and looks at the interplay occasionally appearing between the three. The choral form provides a good example of poetic dispositive and, as I have pointed out previously, a rather successful one at the moment. Technically, it is a type of composition (I) – in this particular case, an arrangement of filmed traces fitted into one another at the editing stage. Like any enunciation, this type of composition regulates the relations between author and spectators, since the latter often perceive the expressive intention (II) that also conveys values (III), which change from an artist, a film or a period to another, but still result from this very choral form. Needless to say, for the effect to take place the process should evidently not be a way to narrate like any other. For the choral form to produce a marked dispositive effect, a tension should occur between this scriptural arrangement (I) and the two other levels in the dispositive of representation: on the pragmatic level, the traditional narrative pact according to which the story should be told to the spectator in a chronological and logical order; and, on the symbolic level, the fact that the film should mark positively or negatively the events narrated. Indeed, my hypothesis is that a dispositive becomes banal in the absence of an internal disturbance, sometimes even ceasing to be perceived as a dispositive because, despite its own form, it only conveys fictional contents. While many films draw average effects from the interdependence of these three levels, others found this effect on a crisis and have a stronger impact on spectators. This is the case of Gus Van Sant’s 2003 Elephant, which deals with the 1999 Columbine high school killing. More forcefully

The “Dispositive Effect” in Film Narrative

199

than in other films, the choral form impedes the sequence of events as spectators expect them to be represented, since the construction keeps returning to the hours preceding the slaughter rather than furthering the action. It is not until the last fifteen minutes (out of a total of 75 minutes) that the tragedy takes place before our eyes. Given the fact that the work is inspired from a tragic news story generally known by the audience, the tension between the choral composition and the spectators’ expectation proves all the more intense. A discrepancy then arises between the writing (I) and the set of values (III) the film is supposed to convey: filming from behind the high school students who are to be subjected to the violence of their peers, juxtaposing the sequences devoted to each of their movements in the high school or nearby, the filmmaker imposes a horizontal perception of the facts which not only suppresses causal relations between sequences (since the drift towards the tragedy occurs out of the parallel schedules of the students), but also has the effect of giving victims and killers the same status, as all are filmed in the same way. This horizontality produces a form of symbolic depression, underscored by other components of the film, such as the choice of Beethoven’s Moonlight Sonata on the soundtrack. Performed by one of the two killers, its insistent recurrence conjures up the nocturnal side of a world that may have been thought of as without shadows or, on a fictional level, the absence of responsible or understanding adults capable of standing for a just social order. It is tempting, as a consequence, to distinguish between two types of narrative: the ‘narrativized’ plot, dominated by the traditional logical and discursive order, and the plot ‘with dispositive’, in which the technical, pragmatic and symbolic components of representation are no longer welded to one another but separate, as though laid flat, no matter the level of analysis considered. Still, insofar as the dispositive effect may operate at any time, including in the most classically narrative film, it would make more sense, strictly speaking, to move the slide and place it within the narrative itself, thus distinguishing two different narrative modes: transitive narration, which is subject to the traditional logical and discursive order, and intransitive narration, which occurs any time an arrangement disturbs a sequence and brings succession back within the domain of contiguity.

The Poetics of Dispositives Accordingly, there is no such thing as ‘plots that narrate’, on the one hand, and plots with dispositives on the other (with choral films, for instance).

200 Philippe Ortel

Rather, there exists a tendency towards dispositives within any narrative, filmic or literary, more or less marked depending on the author, the aesthetic, or the period considered, and liable to affect all levels. This does not mean, however, that differences in the ways these two narrative modes operate should be underestimated. When a filmmaker uses the dispositive effect as a narrative principle, she or he makes the analytical categories developed by classic narratology since the 1960s almost ineffective: indeed, these are best suited for transitive narration founded on the direct succession of befores and afters, causes and effects. The wanderings of teenagers in the high school of Elephant do not concur to build any genuine plot, for example. No real helper or opponent from the classical actantial model are to be found in the film; no necessary stages for initiatory purposes either, with an acquisition of competence, a qualifying test, a decisive test and a glorifying test; finally, it is difficult to speak of the choral form in terms of narrative speed, as though tension simply arose from a gap between story time and plot time (with its scenes, pauses, ellipses and summaries, to borrow from Gérard Genette’s categories for literary narratives, partly reused by film criticism11). The heuristic value of these tools proves limited, for in the film the trap reality sets for the characters becomes the object of an approach that is more topological than discursive on the part of the filmmaker: following the high school students, the camera goes through the future or potential places of the killing (library, cafeteria, kitchen, classrooms, hallways), weaving a web between positions that partly does away with chronology and logic. The rhizome-like construction of some sequences, in which the camera abruptly changes course to follow another high school student met in the hallway, emphasizes this topological method of composition, creating spatial points of intersection. Occasionally, the intersection is also temporal: following a student, the camera may show – from his or her point of view – a scene seen earlier in the film by the protagonists she or he runs into, and who were then the main focus. The de-centering thus produced is due to the fact that each movement filmed from the back forms a subjective chronological line, distinct from the time lived by other characters, even as the moment they share by crossing one another’s paths is really the same. 11 Gérard Genette, Narrative Discourse. An Essay in Method (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1983) 86-112. These categories were devised for literary texts and deal with the relations between the way of narrating (the plot) and the story to tell. They may still be useful in cinema, except precisely when the plot is no longer the central element: do the comings and goings of the high school students constitute pauses or scenes with respect to the story to be told? Put in these terms, the question is not truly relevant when the transitive narrative ceases to be the dominant norm.

The “Dispositive Effect” in Film Narrative

201

In this specific case, the disjunction occurs within time itself, between two ways of living the same moment, as if teenagers circulated in parallel worlds that could connect only objectively. The dispositive effect then issues from the caesura introduced at the very heart of temporality, since this temporality, previously unique, linear and unified, breaks down into multiple, simultaneous, and juxtaposed temporalities.12 Not only does the topological composition of the film keep taking the plot back to its starting point, but the motivations prompting the characters to act remain undetermined, whereas in a classical narrative the causal sequence of actions calls for psychological or sociological explanations as guarantees for plausibility. Besides the labyrinth,13 a well-known topological model structures Elephant: the map. Taking us from one point to another, reducing the story to a series of short trips leading each character from a random moment of his or her life to the fateful moment, the filmmaker draws up the map of a news story based on the dual dimension of space and time. The DVD of the film explicitly refers to this, providing the map of the high school and the paths taken by the students. Yet this cartography happens to draw its power of fascination from the fact that, reducing the story to a network of spatial, but also temporal points, it shows the events without giving us any insight in the motivations of the protagonists of the tragedy. In so doing, it stresses – among other things – the unfathomable nature of chance, since the distribution of students between victims and survivors hangs on whether or not their paths cross the murderers’. Crossroads and intersections circumscribe this incomprehensibility 14 without explaining 12 Identifying our three agencies – technical, pragmatic and symbolic – whenever a caesura is observed may prove rather tedious. In an example such as this one, it is enough to show how the traditional sequence of time has become a spatialized arrangement of parallel individual temporalities, and how contiguity increasingly competes with succession. 13 As Alexandre Tylski has shown, also evoking the model of the zoo because of the title, the bull appearing on John’s t-shirt is a direct allusion to the Minotaur of mythology (John is the blond teenager who serves as a thread throughout the narrative). See Alexandre Tylski, “Gus Van Sant et le Minotaure,” Aug. 2003, Cadrage.net, http://www.cadrage.net/films/elephant/ elephant.html [last accessed on Apr. 28, 2011]. 14 This is Stéphane Lojkine’s expression. Lojkine writes: “What has to be reduced is the uncircumscribed. The structural stake of this kind of modelization consists in exiting narration as the basic structure in the novel to consider setting up dispositives whose function is to identify, to circumscribe the unforeseeable in the real, the rustle of circumstances.” See “Représenter Julie: le rideau, le voile, l’écran,” in L’Ecran de la représentation. Théorie littéraire. Littérature et peinture du 16e au 20e siècle, ed. Stéphane Lojkine (Paris: L’Harmattan, 2001) 37. Stéphane Lojkine has since developed this point and now talks of a “narrative dispositive.” See http://galatea. univ-tlse2.fr/pictura/UtpicturaServeur/Dispositifs/SeminaireED2009.php [last accessed on Apr. 28, 2011].

202 Philippe Ortel

it, which is also one of the functions of dispositives in representation, in contrast with the order of reasons in the classical transitive narrative. The transitivity on which the spectators’ expectation rests on a pragmatic level may be contested in many other ways than the choice of a choral form: besides the work on editing, the filmmaker may for instance cultivate still framing, to the point of creating a conflict with the ordinary unfolding of the story as expected by spectators. In From the Other Side (2003), Chantal Akerman’s prolonged shots of the wall and the desert separating Mexico from the United States partition time off. A tension arises between them and the stories of emigration that, because of the classical narrative contract, are expected in the form of images or through the testimonies of individuals met by the filmmaker. This partition formally expresses the objectively dispositive-related nature of a space that the American government has turned into an instrument of control (I) for migration flows (II).15 As was suggested earlier, the pressure exerted on the traditional narrative pact may also come from the filmic utterance, that is, from objects featured in the fiction and to which a preponderant place is granted. For this to be possible, they should be able to force their own logic upon narration, that is, their own internal dispositive, with our three components. The objects in question can then carve their own fictional space at the center of the film, a fictional space which sometimes becomes that of the film as a whole. In The Terminal, for instance, Spielberg contains the story and its hero in a place, all of whose possibilities he exploits. The classical transitive narrative has a place in it, but there are cases in which the dispositive-like logic of the place, or the object at the heart of the film, impede the traditional narrative to the point of completely neutralizing it. So it goes for what is commonly referred to as a ‘scene’: it only takes the filmmaker to dwell on its internal components to the detriment of the featured event and its repercussions for spectators to feel deprived of the information narrative logic had led them to expect. Another logic then takes precedence, that presiding over the operations of the “stage dispositive,” as any scene involves an internal space (I), actors and possibly spectators interacting (II) as well as social or moral values in the name of which the scene takes place (III). In a scene of Stanley Kubrick’s Eyes Wide Shut, Victor Ziegler (Sydney Pollack) reveals to Doctor Hartford (Tom Cruise) that he was present at the very private evening party into which Hartford 15 This dispositive-related dimension may be found in a part of the video installation derived from her film by the filmmaker and titled “From the other side,” which is also the English title of the film.

The “Dispositive Effect” in Film Narrative

203

intruded. The ritual of conversation with its glasses of whisky, the stations near the pool tables which are not to be used, the armchairs in which one sits down and from which one stands up again, comings and goings: all of this, mixed with silences, creates prevarication and hesitation which slow down the flow of confessions and revelations and thwart the expectation among spectators that Ziegler will get more quickly to what he knows. Far from revealing emptiness, this expectation forces the audience to grapple with bodies, a setting, and social etiquette deeply contradictory to the transgressive episode whose protagonists have such a hard time talking about, and whose evocation is still necessary for the story to proceed. The dispositive effect resulting from the conflict between theatrical form and narrative dynamic also reveals its figurative value here, mimicking as it does the act of unmasking. Indeed, the social ritual of conversation plays the same role as the mask Doctor Hartford was asked to remove during the famous evening when his presence was found out. In both cases a veil is lifted, so that the hero of the story is unmasked twice: by the brotherhood on the very evening of his intrusion, by his interlocutor by the pool table. In this case, the aesthetic value of the dispositive comes from the fact that, formally figuring the mechanism of unmasking, it implies spectators quite intimately in the workings of the process. At first a mere theme treated in the fiction, the mimicked process – unmasking, in this instance – becomes an experience to be lived by the audience. What holds true for a social ritual is also valid with a mere prop: instead of blending into the movement of the narrative, its use may take over and condition human relationships within the story rather than simply regulate them – and accordingly disturb, once again, the expectation of spectators at the upper levels of narrative structure and filmic communication. The revolving door of the palace in Murnau’s The Last Laugh (1924), in front of which the tragedy of the film plays out, occupies this higher position as the prop becomes a narrative operator. Sacked from his prestigious position as a doorman because of his age, the character played by Emil Jannings will do everything he can to keep his shiny livery and his job at the entrance of the hotel. The revolving door thus not only conditions his action and his relations with his environment, but also introduces a kind of stagnation (one always returns to the door). This stagnation is emblematic of the dead-end that aging represents for the main protagonist, as well as the more positive capacity of humankind to resist the ineluctable. In a film such as Abbas Kiarostami’s Ten (2002), the effect is even more powerful, since the ten dialogues to which the title refers (a nice enunciative dispositive) take place in a car (a dispositive in the form of an utterance).

204 Philippe Ortel

The driver, a modern young Iranian woman, has successive conversations with her son (who criticizes her for divorcing and re-marrying), a friend, a sanctimonious old woman, a prostitute who claims she enjoys her, and so forth. In this context, the car is far more than a theme. In 10 on Ten, a documentary on the film, Kiarostami describes things as follows: Ten gave me the opportunity to use a fixed camera in a moving space – like this car, my favorite space. Two very comfortable seats, a very friendly conversation between two people who do not face each other but sit side by side and move. This sitting position side by side, it seems to me, makes the two participants comfortable and creates peaceful conditions for a conversation to begin. If necessary, they can of course look at each other. In other words, in this position, we are together. Better still: each one is at once with himself or herself and with the other… and with himself or herself again. This type of dialogue allows us not to face our interlocutor, to look straight ahead. We can look at him or her when we expect a response or a reaction. Its presence also gives the camera a particular place. It is absent, fixed and in motion at the same time. This form of dialogue, as I have just said, presents the advantage of creating a feeling of safety between two individuals.16

The three components of our def inition appear here in an exemplary fashion: the physical arrangement of the seats placing the driver and her passenger side by side (I) fosters dialogue (II) by giving the participants the sense of safety necessary for the expression of their points of view on life (III). Put differently, the technical arrangement of the seats regulates human relations and conveys values. These values, it should be noted, run through the entire dispositive: indeed, the heroine’s taste for independence is expressed by the very fact she drives, also extending to her gestures, the elegance of her clothes (an elegant light headscarf replaces the traditional chador) and, quite obviously, the words she speaks. Because it serves as a complete dispositive, the car (like the scene from Eyes Wide Shut on a smaller scale) imposes its own operation on the film, notably on its narrative form and its enunciative mode. The filmmaker only has to divide the work in ten dialogues (Ten), setting aside the linear dimension of the story and anticipating the habits of spectators better to confound them. 16 Abbas Kiarostami, dir., 10 on ten, 2002, DVD, MK2 éditions, 2004, chapter 5/11, 25’57’’. Translator’s note: this is the translation of a transcription of Mojdeh Famili’s oral translation in French.

The “Dispositive Effect” in Film Narrative

205

What is called “poetics of dispositives” here falls into two processes: first, the poetic choices in the strict sense of the filmmaker’s perspective, that is, all the means used in the development of the film (editing, mise en scène, manner of filming), without which the scene or the key prop would not expend their intrinsic powers as dispositives; second, the powers of these same objects to serve as dispositives, insofar as filmmakers are able to identify them and rely on them to play down the arbitrary dimension of their creation. I would therefore argue in favor of an expanded poetics here, one that would not be reduced to a stock of pre-established forms (a film rhetoric), but would result from the combination of a know-how and pre-cinematographic realities, in a way – forms which, like the filmmaker, could through their own technical means (I) regulate human interactions (II) and crystallize values (III). Between filmic enunciation and the filmed object as the mere theme of the fiction, an intermediary space thus appears. It is a meta-fictional space, since it comprises objects or situations capable of generating a sizable share of the material that constitutes the film, like the high school of Elephant or the car in Ten. By having the characters engage in talking, the car becomes an “enunciating” force in the very heart of the fiction, relaying as it does filmic enunciation by framing, as would a camera, the characters enclosed within its material boundaries and encouraging them to speak. The dispositive, then, is the theme (social ritual, vehicle, building…) become form. To be sure, Kiarostami’s statement shows quite well that, without work on the manner of filming,17 the car in Ten would be reduced to its ordinary social use and function only partially as a dispositive. By limiting the orientation of the digital camera to two positions, one towards the driver, the other towards the passenger, the f ilmmaker considerably reinforces the role played by the cramped compartment and the juxtaposition of seats in the progress of the dialogue: In Ten, based on the subject, I tried to restrict the setting as much as possible. At the beginning, however, I did not plan to limit the dispositive to two angles and two lenses. After viewing the first sequence, I understood that any change in angle and focal length just for the sake of variation would be harmful to the order or the structure of the film, which for me 17 I want to thank François Albéra for bringing to my attention the importance of the way an object is filmed in enhancing its potentialities to serve as a dispositive. His comment and the discussion in which it occurred are available online on the website of the University of Lausanne: http://www.unil.ch/cin/page56362.html.

206 Philippe Ortel

is more important than the subject or the story. For this reason, I put the camera back in its initial place and remained faithful to the stifling and tense feeling generated by a room of two meters by two. The choice of a closed space had been made in keeping with the particularly painful situation in which the characters found themselves.18

Still, the mise en scène reinforces or reveals in the object (the car) generative or organizational properties that are peculiar to it, even if daily life manifests these properties in a more diffuse manner. Automobiles are, for example, privileged places for confiding in someone, as one of his friends once told the filmmaker: her most important conversations with her husband generally took place in the car. Kiarostami also declared that he wanted to show how the confined, moving space of the car fostered introspection among passengers as they talked to each other: speech often occurred only after deep absorption into oneself. “Dispositive films” thus play an analytical role, breaking down the apparent homogeneity of phenomena (a mere ride in a car) to reveal the hidden articulation of their various technical, pragmatic and symbolic components – which, conversely, may not be reduced to the mise en scène but are still revealed by it. These films also show the link between all these components and the incomprehensible reality they are meant to channel, the interiority of the characters in Ten, for instance.19 In a more traditional narrative, high school, doors, and cars generally are realities among others. They are part of the setting without being the matrix of the fictional content conveyed by the work.

Caesura and Variable More precisely, where does the mutual dependence of our three levels in dispositives in fiction (or in utterances), such as those just analyzed, come from? The dispositive effect is possible only if each level involves a variable, that is to say, a principle liable to create variations in the other two, thus opening up the field of possibilities. The arrangement of seats in Ten, for instance, though physically fixed, makes a vast number of combinations 18 Kiarostami, 10 on ten, chapter 5/11, 29’28’’. 19 On the links between the real and the incomprehensible in Kiarostami’s work, see Philippe Ragel, “Est-ce que l’on sait où l’on va,” in Abbas Kiarostami. Le Cinéma à l’épreuve du réel (Toulouse: Université de Toulouse-Le Mirail, Yellow Now-Côté cinéma, 2008) 7-18. On the relations between dispositives and the incomprehensible, see L’Incompréhensible. Littérature, réel, visuel, ed. Marie-Thérèse Mathet (Paris: L’Harmattan, 2003).

The “Dispositive Effect” in Film Narrative

207

possible on the pragmatic level. The variable here lies in the reciprocity of the exchange, which such a layout makes optional, but also susceptible of gradation. Words may remain as parallel as the seats, which does happen when each of the two characters, within the conversation itself, does in fact engage in a monologue. Indeed, Kiarostami had initially thought about centering the film around a psychoanalyst who had to see her clients in her car after a complaint to authorities had forced her to close her practice. The author eventually abandoned this idea for the script, precisely to avoid reducing his film to monologues by patients. Yet words may also intersect whenever a balanced dialogue takes place between the two participants, as is the case in the discussion between the driver and the prostitute. At other times, the driver has the upper hand in the exchange, as when she gives a telling-off to a friend depressed by a break-up. At the crossroads between the material world and human relations, the variable turns the dispositive into a creative object: the structure of the places, with their technical constraints, reveals the circumstances of a rich and diverse reality. So it goes at a higher level, with the exchange between protagonists (II) and the values this exchange conveys (III). The intonation of the voice does, for example, involve a variable, the tone used, from which all axiological marks may be expressed: approval, disapproval, detachment – again, with all the imaginable degrees in between. Through the variation of tones and attitudes, the fascinating instability of human relations is given for us to see in the course of the same conversation, something that a writer like Nathalie Sarraute turned into a theme in France in the 1950s under the name “tropisms.”

To Interpret and To Look Now, what is the difference between transitive narratives and “narratives with dispositive” for the spectators of the film? The effect of suspense created by traditional narration, closely linked to its temporal, linear nature, projects spectators forward, leading them to anticipate events, whereas the dispositive settles them and immerses them in a given situation, as could a ritual. A few years after Ten, Jacques Rivette’s The Duchess of Langeais (2007), an adaptation from Balzac, was released. There are few dispositives in this film – which tells the love war waged in Paris by the Duchess of Langeais (Jeanne Balibar) against the Marquis of Montriveau (Guillaume Depardieu) – but quite a lot of events. Through the subtlety of the dialogue and the acting, the least modulation of the voice, the least

208 Philippe Ortel

movement in space, the least shift in conversation matters, driving spectators to look ahead and anticipate the methods by which the Duchess will succeed, come the next moment, in resisting Montriveau without desisting from her seduction of him. Few apparent dispositives, then, if only because the places, instead of conditioning the action as in the car in Ten, simply serve as a setting: during the scene of the encounter, the living room of the Countess of Sérizy is soon left behind for a more intimate room. The camera takes us from one space to the next with a fluidity that is not very favorable to matricial relations between bodies and settings. The dispositive, if one had to be found, would rather lie at the enunciative level with the presence of intertitles at each important step of the narrative. Placing spectators at the intersection of the story to read and the filmed story, and therefore of literature and cinema, these intertitles and the effects of citation they produce give the audience a ‘binocular’ vision of the story, adding depth to it like a stereoscope. It is a temporal depth, to be specific, for these titles mediate the pleasure experienced in following the film through the slightly regressive feeling of moving back towards a now distant book culture20 or, more intimately, towards our adolescent reading. In both cases, the pleasures brought by The Duchess of Langeais are those of a “graphosphere”21 which is moving away from us, yet draws its very charm from this increasing distance. Besides a permanent mental anticipation, traditional narration requires a work of interpretation from the public. Narrativity and hermeneutic activity are consubstantial insofar as, before claiming the status of symbol, meaning merges with the very movement of the narrative. Where does M go at night in Fritz Lang’s M (1931)? What does he do to the little girls whose paths he crosses? What is his degree of responsibility when the inner voice driving him to commit crimes makes itself heard? What did the filmmaker seek to show of the social and ideological malaise in the Germany of the 1930s? The different levels of interpretation created by the film, from the mere movement in space to the deep motivations of characters to the values of an era correspond to the three material, pragmatic and symbolic levels, but instead of being put in mutual tension as in the dispositive effect, they merge together here, simply forming the mesh of a transitive narrative. Yet this hermeneutic activity happens to be postponed when the logic of the dispositive dominates in a narrative. Nobody truly cares about where 20 At least as a dominant cultural form. 21 I borrow the term from Régis Debray, who uses it in many of his works. See for instance his Transmitting Culture (New York: Columbia University Press, 2004).

The “Dispositive Effect” in Film Narrative

209

the car in Ten is headed in the many trips it takes and whether or not the young boy incensed at his mother will some day make peace with her. Indeed, before probing the meaning of things, the “film with dispositive” gives us their existence to see. In the absence of a structured chronological narrative, we do not seek to anticipate or interpret but instead live the performance of actors in the present. The meaning of words uttered and the values asserted or suggested are themselves given to see: the hermeneutic activity, if it never really disappears on the side of spectators, accompanies the film but does not ultimately constitute its end. In the last dialogue of Ten, the relation between the mother and her young son has not evolved: to mark his disapproval, the child asks again to spend the evening at his grandmother’s rather than with his mother. The filmmaker shows us the tension between the two protagonists, not to bring it to a resolution as would a transitive narrative, but to keep emphasizing it. Accordingly, the dispositive invites a vertical rather than horizontal reception of the work: in Ten, as I already pointed out, we are invited to sense, under the appearance of perceptible phenomena, the interior world in whose depths the hypnotic rhythm of the vehicle puts each character, and to which the dispositive of a car conversation alone may here give access. This is due to the impossibility for the filmmaker to represent the world of affects directly. The consequences for the philosophy of the narrative as developed by Paul Ricoeur have deep ramifications in this instance, for where Ricœur shows the hermeneutic role of the transitive narrative (which makes time human by configuring it and endowing it with signification22), the “filmic narrative with dispositive” differs in its sensorial and existential function. Framing the performance of actors within a given situation, it chiefly aims to show what is. Moreover, whereas traditional narratives readily capture our attention through the mise en scène of enigmas, events whose meaning calls for elucidation, the dispositive, as we saw with chance and violence in Elephant, reveals the incomprehensible, that which by definition will never fully make sense.23

22 “Time and Narrative: Threefold Mimesis,” in Paul Ricœur, Time and Narrative, vol. I (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1984) 52-90. 23 On the novel, Marie-Thérèse Mathet notes: “Contrary to the secret and the enigma, the incomprehensible lurks in the heart of the story. It is not reliant on narrative strategies or modes, which it transcends, even as it uses them.” “Incompréhensible et structure narrative,” L’Incompréhensible. Littérature, réel, visuel, ed. Marie-Thérèse Mathet (Paris: L’Harmattan, 2003) 194.

210 Philippe Ortel

Transitivity and Dispositive: Two Co-Extensive Modes of Narrative It is not rare, however, for a film to simultaneously lend itself to both types of reading, one founded on anticipation and interpretation, the other sensitive to dispositive effects. This is the case when a sequence of actions also constitutes an almost autonomous performance with respect to the rest of the story. In the most famous scene of Safety Last (1923), Harold Lloyd’s vertical journey on the façade of a Los Angeles skyscraper initially follows the linear and chronological order of the classical narrative, since it raises the traditional question of the outcome of the chase: will the hero make it to the last floor, the condition for him to receive the bonus from the store whose publicity he ensures through his feat as he stands in for his friend Bill, inconveniently chased by a policeman? However, the sequence emphasizes the space of the façade to such an extent that the principle of variation specific to some dispositives doubles and absorbs the principle of evolution that characterizes transitive narration. As time elapses, we no longer only project ourselves in thought towards the outcome of the amazing effort, but we also remain fascinated by the relations emerging between the hero and the building. Instead of blending into each other, the space (I) and the action, which here is the interaction (II) between the main protagonist and his immediate environment, are at odds. The façade is not a mere setting, nor even an actant of the “opponent” type within an actantial model: it is, rather, the matrix of potential interactions, the most spectacular of which features Lloyd hanging from the hands of a clock. The narrative sequence, while still anchored in a chronology, thus also poetically opens up the field of possibilities: the paradigmatic axis of all the acrobatic feats this type of situation is liable to produce gradually emerges in the minds of spectators outside the chronology. As to the symbolic dimension, it feeds into our fascination by casting light on the disproportion instituted in twentiethcentury cities between their residents and buildings no longer on their scale. Transitive narration and intransitivity are also coextensive whenever a f ilm is seen again. Once the outcome and the steps leading to it are known, the perspective on the work becomes more tabular, as it would in a critical analysis. The retrospective look makes the different stages of the narrative simultaneous and, rather than considering them in their succession, establishes a comparative relation between them that mediates the passage from one to the other through the memory we have of the film as a whole. Juxtaposed in the minds of spectators, then, are the transitive filmic narration and an agency larger than the narrative – the ideal space

The “Dispositive Effect” in Film Narrative

211

of creation, where the parts of the work lie side by side rather than follow each other because a global intuition of what she or he does is assumed on the author’s part. Upon viewing The Duchess of Langeais a second time, the role played by hangings is more noticeable, whether it is over the gate separating the choir from the public area in the convent where Montriveau meets the Duchess long after the Parisian years, or in Paris at the heroine’s apartment. The monastic effect produced by these windows blind to the outside world announces the Duchess’s future religious calling while expressing her feeling of oppression at a passion of which she refuses to be captive. These various screens may themselves be associated with the many shawls, veils, and dresses the Duchess makes use of to seduce Montriveau while keeping him at bay. To trained observers, the return of the same places or props situates the latter at the intersection of two logics: within a transitive narration, they serve as temporal marks, highlighting what has changed from one instance to the next. An example is the living room where the encounter took place, and which will also be the place of the break-up. In the ideal space of creation, however, the return of places or props is the source of poetic variations separate from spatial and temporal coordinates. Superimposed, the different sofas on which the Duchess lounges may thus retrospectively turn out to be as many traps whose effects vary according to circumstances. The matrices of potential interactions, these props – when considered retrospectively – function as dispositives. Our two logics should therefore be organized into a hierarchy: either one constitutes a dominant element depending on the author, the period or the aesthetic involved; or on whether the film is seen for the first time or is the object of subsequent viewings.

Inventing Dispositives There remains the case of when the film single-handedly invents dispositives without equivalent in social life. These then owe their existence solely to the conjunction of a way of filming and realities to which the filmmaker assigns a new, mysterious function destined to fade with the last images of the film. Abbas Kiarostami magnificently achieves such magic in some of the five sequences from Five (2004), a set of short films which prove closer to video art than to traditional cinema. In the fourth sequence, the most playful of all, some ducks are shown waddling in a row at different paces on the seashore, first in one direction, then in the other. At once comic and poetic, the performance arises from the conjunction of our three factors.

212 Philippe Ortel

Materially speaking, the horizon, the line of the water and the strip of sand, shot frontally, outline the path taken by the feathered creatures (I). This outline appears to condition the parade effect (II) that makes their passing so comical, based on several variables lying at the intersection of material reality and the intentionality that may be attributed to the protagonists of the film. The speed of the web-footed birds, their number, the distance between them, or the orientation of their stride – mostly rectilinear, at times astray – thus all vary. In turn, starting from the principle of regularity, their behavior opens onto multiple variations on the superior level of values (III): alienation of the individual from the group, or on the contrary manifestation of independence in the case of a deviation from standard demeanor, for the message of this little film is subtly political. Lines of horizon and seafront (I), alignment of animals (II) and lines of conduct (III) thus overlap in a unified whole that has no referent in real life, since no specific ritual corresponds to it. For this very reason though, this whole opens the minds of spectators to the pleasure “without concept” (Kant) of analogies: these ducks, who are as moving as they are laughable, walking over a backdrop of infinity towards some mysterious destination before eventually turning back chaotically and precipitately, are also a comical and poignant image of human destiny, with its advances and its reversals, its arrogance and its doubts, in a mix of the grotesque and the sublime resulting from the unexpected encounter between the very limited world of animals and the boundless space of the sea. If he does not narrate anything, Kiarostami still rediscovers one of the traditional underpinnings of fables: speaking of humans through animals, without even having to endow them with the ability to speak, in this particular case. Why is our time so sensitive to this dispositive effect, which may be found at other moments in the history of cinema, but less intensely than today? Probably because we are living in a time when mediations are shown and the distinctive feature of a “dispositive aesthetic” is to have the components of representation mediate one another, precisely, rather than merge them into the movement of a transitive narrative. To be sure, this mediation proceeds without any genuine tension, for social life always harmonizes its means according to an end that is beyond them; yet this mediation involves an omnipresence and a visibility never seen before. The politician calling on a mediator to bring some conflict to a resolution explicitly puts the symbolic sphere of power in a situation of dependence on a pragmatic mediation. Whoever communicates through the Internet makes the same pragmatic relation depend on a technical mediation whose constraints she or he knows perfectly well. What society does on a large scale, mimesis does

The “Dispositive Effect” in Film Narrative

213

on a small scale, with its own means. The dispositive effect, which plays a critical and poetic role with great filmmakers, is therefore not immune to a certain conformism, in the literal sense of the word: it also conforms to what society invents and shares the dynamism as well as the limitations of this partly unconscious collective invention. It comes as no surprise, then, that mainstream films are taking it over: the choral form is a good example, as in the very typical Hollywood product Vantage Point (2008), which tells the story of an assassination attempt on the President of the United States; or in 11:14 (2003), a little thriller skillfully going round in circles by showing the same spatio-temporal framework from the point of view of several characters – this until the character seen at the beginning, apparently exterior to the story, turns out to be its keystone in the last sequence. In Vantage Point, which begins in a mobile television studio meant to cover the President’s speech, the choral form perfectly follows, thanks to its circularity, the 360-degree perception our society of control produces of itself at this point. It simply expands to time itself the principle of an all-seeing power performed by surveillance cameras in space, as it has us relive the event several times. As to 11:14, though it uses the same method as Elephant to show youths confronted with transgression and death, it obviously has nothing to do with Gus Van Sant’s film. While Elephant analyzes, suspends interpretation, lets loose the sequence of causes and effects, the other film, on the contrary, synthesizes several chains of events through the choral form to celebrate the magic of coincidences and create spectacle. The dispositive effect is thus not a guarantee of originality or depth, for it is obviously not the method that makes the work, but the way in which artists position themselves with respect to what they show us, in a position so singular each time that no critical model could hope to account for it entirely.

III. Dispositives Histories



The Social Imaginary of Telephony Fictional Dispositives in Albert Robida’s Le Vingtième Siècle and the Archeology of “Talking Cinema”1 Alain Boillat

What I propose to do here, within a perspective involving both epistemology and the archaeology of media, is to approach “talking cinema” through the examination of discourses produced in the last two decades of the nineteenth century, that is, almost fifty years prior to the generalization of talkies and the institutionalization of practices related to sound in the domain of cinema.2 Beyond this specific medium, I will examine the series of machines of audiovisual representation, one of whose many actualizations was “talking cinema” (which is why quotation marks are fitting here, with regard to “cinema” as well as “talking”). Among the many inventions from which various experimentations with “talking cinema” may be said to derive, I will emphasize the technique of telephony. Indeed, its study presents the advantage of encompassing a number of auditive or audiovisual dispositives that are often much more difficult to reduce to their place in the genealogy of (institutionalized) cinema than viewing dispositives. On a methodological level, de-centering the point of view is precisely what appears productive to me, as the discussion of the place given to the voice within various audio(visual) dispositives constitutes the theoretical horizon of my observations.3 1 Translator’s note: the French expression “cinéma parlant” (literally, “talking cinema”) is usually translated as “sound cinema” in English, but given the focus of this chapter and the existence of the term “talkies” in English, it is translated as “talking cinema” here. 2 The attention given to “talkies before (the institutionalization of) talkies” should be placed in the context of recent research on “the archaeology” of the pairing between moving images and synchronized sound. On this point, see Edouard Arnoldy, Pour une histoire culturelle du cinéma. Au-devant de “scènes filmées”, de “films chantants et parlants” et de comédies musicales (Liège: Céfal, 2004) as well as the contributions published in Le Muet a la parole. Cinéma et performance à l’aube du XXe siècle, Giusy Pisano and Valérie Pozner, eds. (Paris: AFRHC, 2005). 3 This reflection, one dimension of which is being considered here, started in other places, in particular in Du bonimenteur à la voix-over. Voix-attraction et voix-narration au cinéma (Lausanne: Antipodes, 2007); and in “The lecturer, the image, the machine and the audio-spectator. The voice as a component part of audio-visual dispositives” and “On the particular status of the human voice. Tomorrow’s Eve and the cultural series of talking machines,” both published in Cinema Beyond Film: Media Epistemology in the Modern Era (Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press, 2010), 215-31 and 233-51, respectively.

218 

Alain Boillat

It seems rather improbable that the telephone, considered today as belonging in the sphere of telecommunications, and whose invention is usually credited to Alexander Graham Bell (who registered a patent for it in February 18764), would cross paths with the series of moving images, even when these come with recorded sounds. Some differences touching on the relations established between representation and addressee of the vocal (or audiovisual) message would at the very least cast doubts on the possibility. These differences may be spelled out thanks to the following, necessarily basic classification, whose oppositional pairs should not be seen as hermetically separate, at least if the hybridity of phenomena tied to the emergence and constitution of the media in question is to be taken into account:5 Telephone

Cinematograph

Listeners-Users Domestic space, individual use Simultaneous interactive communication Reversibility of the poles of communication: listener/speaker

Spectators Public space, collective participation Unidirectional, deferred transmission Reversibility of the Lumière appliance: recording/projection6

When considering these different features and the traditional and monolithic conception of the two media they assume, the unidirectional communication with a collective audience (projection) implied in the film show proves very different from the dominant use of the telephone, which consists in an interactive communication carried out by a user in a private space. However, just as the “cinema” met with very heterogeneous conditions of exhibition,6 the telephone – especially when combined with other 4 Elisha Gray or Antonio Meucci have also been credited with the invention, and this disputed paternity is indicative of the more general relation between research on the electric distance transmission of a voice and the spirit of an era, when similar experiments were being carried out concurrently. 5 On this account, I could make the following observation my own: “Classifications, it seems to us, appear tenuous when their aim is to define media out of univocal functions, at all costs, even if it means overshadowing both their hybrid nature and their uses, and precluding thinking on their intersections, their geneses, and their developments.” François Albera and Maria Tortajada, “Prolégomènes à une critique des ‘télé-dispositifs’,” in La Télévision, du téléphonoscope à YouTube. Pour une archéologie de l’audiovision, Mireille Berton and Anne-Katrin Weber, eds. (Lausanne: Antipodes, 2009) 39. 6 All the more so when considering, as Rick Altman does, the changeable character of experiments with sonorization. See Sound Theory, Sound Practice, ed. Rick Altman (New York, London: Routledge, 1992).

The Social Imaginary of Telephony

219

devices – gave rise to a wide variety of distinct uses and dispositives which may not be reduced solely to the parameters mentioned above. A convincing example could be the first Kinetophone, commercialized by Edison in 1895, which resulted from a combination of the Phonograph and the Kinetoscope previously exploited in the same parlors7 (if in a totally independent manner: customers would listen to music on one side, watch animated views on the other). These places of mass entertainment thus housed separately two techniques meant for specific uses, and which were later combined in a single system thanks to the synchronization of the Phonograph’s cylinder and the film running in the Kinetoscope. Like the telephone booth, then, the Kinetophone required the user to handle an audio receiver in a public space. This type of convergence highlights the importance of diachronic variations affecting different cultural series in which a given technology may find a place (successively or simultaneously).8

Thinking About the Way Uses Were Thought Up Telephony had various applications in its history, and according to the situation, these brought about distinct dispositives.9 Inscribed in the spectacular context of the presentation of a technical “attraction,” Bell and Watson’s historic call between New York and Malden on October 9, 1876, chronicled in the March 17, 1877 issue of La Nature, epitomizes the diversity of uses for the telephone, which were to lead to specific dispositives later. Indeed, besides the individual conversation, the following contents succeeded one another as part of the same demonstration:10 information on the stock exchange, already one of the main uses of the telegraph 11 (in fact, the piece in La Nature refers to the telephone as a “talking telegraph”); 7 See the illustration reproduced in Georges Sadoul, Histoire générale du cinéma, vol. 1 (Paris: Denoël, 1946) 268. 8 The notion of “cultural series” is borrowed from André Gaudreault, and notably his “Les vues cinématographiques selon Georges Méliès, ou: comment Mitry et Sadoul avaient peut-être raison d’avoir tort (même si c’est surtout Deslandes qu’il faut lire et relire)…,” in Georges Méliès, l’illusionniste fin de siècle? Jacques Malthête and Michel Marie, eds. (Paris: Sorbonne Nouvelle, 1997). 9 “Dispositive” here refers to a set of interactions between the poles of machinery, representation and spectator. On this conception, see Maria Tortajada and François Albera, “L’Epistémè ‘1900’,” in Le Cinématographe, nouvelle technologie du XXe siècle, André Gaudreault, Catherine Russell and Pierre Véronneau, eds. (Lausanne: Payot, 2004). 10 “Le télégraphe parlant,” La Nature 198 (17 Mar. 1877): 251. 11 For a narrative use of this kind of application, see Alexandre Dumas’s Le Comte de MonteChristo (vol. II, chapters LX to LXVI).

220 

Alain Boillat

the reading of daily newspapers, prefiguring news reports on the radio and on television; questions addressed to the interlocutor by dumbfounded observers, evoking the context of conjuring or séances (surprisingly, one person did in fact ask the interlocutor to predict the future!); finally, the transmission of music, “as if we had been in a concert hall.” This precision by the writer echoes the function Philippe Reiss (Germany) had foreseen for the telephone, and which was assumed by photographic technique, precisely. In his praise of talking pictures, a form of filmed speech that introduced the series of the first Vitaphone Shorts, William Hays also considered that the primary function of sound cinema lay in a wider access to classical music.12 These different media had clearly been devised for similar uses, even as other directions more specific to each of them later developed. The diversity of uses considered for the telephone in the 1870s and the 1880s points to an intermedial phase in Rick Altman’s definition of the term, that is, as a temporary “crisis of mediality” later resolved in the autonomy gained by the media. Altman significantly brings up this situation of intermediality in relation to the period when sound cinema became widespread, which he distinguishes from the two previous decades, more stable in that respect: “From the 1910s on, cinema appeared as such in the great book of media, next to the telephone, the phonograph, and the radio.”13 The mention of the telephone is interesting since there was no clear-cut separation between the uses of telephony and those of the cinematographic spectacle over the period 1895-1910. Indeed, as Patrice Carré has underlined, the applications of this invention remained to be 12 On Hays’s oral performance in this film projected on August 6, 1926 in New York, see Alain Boillat, Du bonimenteur à la voix-over 296-98. A transcription of the speech may be found in The Dawn of Sound, ed. Mary-Lea Bandy (New York: Museum for Modern Art, 1989) 17. Here I am referring more particularly to the following passage: “In the presentation of these pictures, music plays an invaluable part. The motion picture is a most potent factor in the development of a national appreciation of good music. That service will now be extended as the Vitaphone shall carry symphony orchestras to the townhalls of the hamlets.” The films following this introduction did in fact include only instrumental performances or opera singers. The choice matched the substance of Hays’s address, since the president of the MPPDA never touched on the talking cinema he was then “actualizing” through his recorded speech, only evoking the possibility of reproducing the performance of great music. On the Vitaphone Shorts, see Edouard Arnoldy, Pour une histoire culturelle du cinéma 63-73. As to Albert Robida, he pointed out in his fiction Le Vingtième Siècle: “The spectator is not just one in a restricted Paris or Brussels audience; all viewers, even in the comfort of their own home, are part of the great international public.” See Albert Robida, The Twentieth Century (Middletown, CT: Wesleyan University Press, 2004) 54. 13 Rick Altman, “Technologie et textualité de l’intermédialité,” Sociétés & représentations 9 (2000): 12.

The Social Imaginary of Telephony

221

defined, and as Ithiel de Sola Pool has shown, countless predictions were made in the nineteenth century about telephony and the possible changes it would involve for society 14 – many largely determined by the social space of reception: “In the late nineteenth century, it was still unclear to what use the telephone should be put. An auxiliary to the telegraph, a complement to the phonograph? Consumers were to make the decision.”15 The combination of the telephone and the phonograph may seem unusual if these technologies are considered only from the standpoint of their autonomy as media: indeed, the telephone has been limited to direct communication, while the phonograph was intended for keeping a record of sounds. Still, this conception of an interaction between devices, which was in fact recurrent at the time, reveals the lack of a strict division between functions that later tended to be classified in distinct or even opposite paradigms. According to James Lastra, the two major criteria governing the reception of technologies since the nineteenth century and feeding the social imaginary they generate (and which in return generates them) have been inscription – the record of an (audio)visual manifestation on a medium – and simulation (in the sense of the production of a representation that serves as a simulacrum).16 Properly speaking, the telephone does not involve either in the dominant uses of it that became established in the early twentieth century, since it mainly belonged in a third paradigm, communication.17 However, to demonstrate the extent to which categories allowing us to think about a technology at a given moment of its history have an effect on the uses of that same technology, James Lastra brings up the example of telephony,18 precisely, and more specifically, two ways in which it was apprehended. On the one hand, the telephone was considered as an extension of the ear, as a device mostly devoted to listening to a concert or actualités in a program (a use similar to that of the recording of sounds, put

14 Ithiel de Sola Pool, Forecasting the Telephone: A Retrospective Technology Assessment (Norwood, NJ: Ablex, 1983). 15 Patrice Carré, Le Téléphone. Le Monde à portée de voix (Paris: Gallimard, 1993) 33. On the use of the phonograph as a component in the telephonic system, see de Sola Pool, Forecasting the Telephone 31-35. 16 James Lastra, Sound Technology and the American Cinema. Perception, Representation, Modernity (New York, Chichester: Columbia University Press, 2000). 17 On the pair simulation/communication, see my article “Faire pour la vue ce que le téléphone fait pour l’ouïe. Rencontres entre l’image et la voix dans quelques anticipations de la télévision,” in La Télévision, du téléphonoscope à Youtube, Berton and Weber, eds., 80, 88-90. 18 Lastra borrows this example from Carolyn Marvin, When Old Technologies Were New (Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press, 1988) 222-31.

222 

Alain Boillat

in the service of entertainment in the form of a show).19 On the other hand, it was viewed as an interpersonal means of communication substituting for the physical co-presence of two interlocutors, which means that it was inscribed in the paradigm of the simulation of the human.20 Lastra’s comment points to the need to take into consideration what Patrice Flichy, a sociologist of technologies of communication, calls the frame of reference of a technological innovation: At the roots of a socio-technical context we find a whole series of imagined technological possibilities which seem to warrant investigation, not as the initial matrix of a new technology, but rather as one of the resources mobilized by the actors to construct a frame of reference.21

In the phase when uses specific to a media become defined, a whole set of conditions of possibility is thus determined by what Flichy considers – within a perspective akin to epistemology, though he does not openly claim this influence – as an ensemble of “technical imaginaries.” One of the privileged sites of this type of discursive formations happens to be novelistic fiction, which can afford to integrate hypothetical devices and uses in the counter-factual world it proposes. One of the objects of study recommended by Flichy lies in what François Albera has tentatively called “projected cinema”22 – the projection, in the form of technical extrapolations in literary (or para-literary) texts of a cinema to come, or more largely, as I suggest here, of a dispositive featuring a machinery as one of its components. As such, one of the works by French novelist and draftsman Albert Robida, The Twentieth Century (1883), constitutes a good object to approach the “frames of reference” prevalent at the time telephony appeared, and which shaped discourses and practices. Admittedly, the reference to this work has become a topos in discourses on the archaeology of media because it 19 One could say that the aspects mentioned by Lastra are tied to a more general conception of technology as a prosthetic development of the human. This conception already held true for the telegraph, as the following citation (dated 1860) illustrates: “[You only need] to repeat this movement in Strasbourg, absolutely as though the hand of the person located in Paris could stretch as far as Strasbourg to set in motion directly the sounder of the receiver.” Le Magasin pittoresque (1860), quoted in Carré, Télégraphes. Innovations techniques et société au 19e siècle 41. 20 Lastra, Sound Technology and The American Cinema 21. 21 Patrice Flichy, Understanding Technological Innovation: A Socio-Technical Approach (Glos, U.K., Northampton, MA: Edward Elgar Publishing, 2007) 120. 22 François Albera, “Le cinéma ‘projeté’ et les périodisations de l’histoire technique du cinéma,” in Le Età del Cinema/The Ages of Cinema, Enrico Biasin, Roy Menerani and Federico Zecca, eds. (Udine: DAMS Gorizia, 2008) 393-400.

The Social Imaginary of Telephony

223

features an imaginary device, the telephonoscope, which in the novel makes it possible to add the image of the interlocutor in telephone conversations (a function later actualized with the videophone or videoconferences over the Internet through software like Skype). Still, commentators most often content themselves with the mention of the novel in passing, even though it would deserve a more careful examination. Accordingly, it will serve as the focus for my case study and the thread in my argument.

A Reticular Conception In Robida’s fantasy, the telephonoscope – like the Internet today – is clearly designed as an extension of the telephone, whose network it inherits23 (the telephone was still rare in France in 1883, when The Twentieth Century was published24). As Patrice Carré has shown in several texts and books (notably on Robida’s fictions), the generalization of the telegraph and later of the telephone contributed to familiarize users with a new way of approaching interpersonal communication based on the concept of “network,” from that point on. Alternating shots on the frightened telegraphist wiring a distress signal with images of the engine driver coming to her rescue at full speed, D. W. Griffith’s 1911 The Lonedale Operator relates the two main factors of a renewed apprehension of speed, whether resulting from the physical movement of a mobile on the railroad network or from the communication of information through the telegraphic network.25 In The Culture of Time and Space, Stephen Kern has shown how these technological inventions produced a new apprehension of time, notably in terms of capturing the

23 “Subscribers ordering the new service could have the apparatus adapted to their telephones for an extra monthly fee.” Robida, The Twentieth Century 51. 24 According to Joseph Libois, the f irst devices appeared in France in 1881 and numbered no more than 3,500 units for the whole country in 1883. See Libois, Genèse et croissance des télécommunications (Paris: Masson, 1983). The statistical table is reprinted in Perriault, La Logique de l’usage 174. 25 A comparative study remains to be done on discourses on telephonic audition and visual stimuli experienced in train travel in the first years of the twentieth century. On train travel, see Wolfgang Schivelbusch, The Railway Journey: The Industrialization of Time and Space in the Nineteenth Century (1977; Berkeley, Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1986); Livio Belloï, Regard retourné. Aspect du cinéma des premiers temps (Québec/Paris: Nota Bene/Méridiens Klincksieck, 2001); Mireille Berton, “Train, cinéma, modernité: entre hystérie et hypnose,” Décadrages 6: 8-21.

224 

Alain Boillat

present moment in a world taken over by speed and simultaneity.26 It is not by chance, then, that the first invention characters marvel at in The Twentieth Century is that of a means of transportation run by electricity and called “the tube,” which supplants the railroad after the railroad itself has supplanted the stagecoach.27 Robida’s description of the urban landscape has the city governed by a generalized organization in networks: telephone wires “crisscross[ed] in all directions, at all levels, in front of houses, over rooftops, creating a dense network of patterns over both buildings and sky,” while objects are transported thanks to an underground tube that “silently collects and distributes all sorts of packages, boxes, bundles, merchandise, and various items, through thousands of arteries buried beneath the streets.”28 A possible hypothesis is that, in the minds of late nineteenth-century users, the reticular conception of telephony was modeled after more rudimentary, tangible systems such as running water29 and central heating, these other factors of domestic comfort in an urban setting whose functioning relied on the interconnection of different places (through pipes, in this instance). Some expressions appearing in the novelist’s prose do in fact show that he conceived telephony similarly to these techniques. The musical pieces to which telephonoscope subscribers listen at home are “kept in tubes until the stage’s prompter turns on the valve in his box,”30 and incidents occur when the mouthpiece has not quite been shut off. Incidentally, in 1878 Henri Giffard, a friend of Robida’s and the author of publications illustrated by him, imagined a futuristic application of telephony which he explicitly compared to the system of the stove: We like to think that in the year 2000 the telephone will have the magnitude of the much more simple invention that is the stove. This is the most humble example that may be used. Let’s say that the large-size generating telephone is in the Théâtre français for instance, near the footlights. Through a hundred or a hundred and twenty wires it conveys everything being uttered at the theater to a hundred or a hundred and twenty telephone mouthpieces laid out in apartments like our current 26 Stephen Kern, The Culture of Time and Space: 1880-1918 (London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson, 1983). 27 Robida, The Twentieth Century 3-14. 28 Robida, The Twentieth Century 48, 50. 29 Due to the need for refueling points for steam engines, the development of running water was partly tied to that of the railroad. 30 Robida, The Twentieth Century 55n (my emphasis).

The Social Imaginary of Telephony

225

hot-air vents. In these private apartments, the telephone’s mouthpiece is placed near a piece of furniture, not far from the mantelpiece.31

Giffard exposes a specific frame of reference here: the intention is not to develop the practice of a “point to point” conversation, but to connect an emitting exchange to a number of addressees. Interpersonal communication is thus not dissociated from a multidirectional emission out of a center, as both uses are performed through a similar system. Besides, even in a more complex inception – as with the addition of the moving image by Robida – telephony gives rise to a dispositive that becomes integrated in the furniture and the domestic sphere, like the radio and the television set later, when manufacturers tried to bring much care to the design so these devices could constitute elements of interior decoration. This is why, even though it is not explicitly correlated with the telephonoscope, the episode narrated in The Twentieth Century, in which the apartment of a subscriber to the food company is flooded after a pipe dysfunction, represents a “concrete,” literal variation of the representation of the telephone network: subscribers receive their food as they do their information, from a distance (Fig. 1). Distance communication as contemplated by Robida was therefore much less interactive than it was to become over the twentieth century: like Giffard in his treatise, Robida saw it as guided by the unidirectional principle of a tool for home delivery. The absence of emphasis on the properly conversational dimension, obvious in the novel as a whole, tends to establish a parallel between the use of the telephone and spectacular practices. However, the domestic dimension of telephony represents a considerable difference from the uses of cinema, which was meant for a collective audience (if one excludes non-professional projection devices sold to private individuals, whose use was close to that of the magic lantern and more generally of optical toys).

Telephony as Intrusion into the Domestic Space When Robida imagines the telephone as a means of transmission for news or actualités, its informational function is presented as an intrusion into the private sphere of one of the heroines, Hélène, who discovers the invention at the same time as the reader. On the first night she spends in the house 31 Henri Giffard, Le Téléphone expliqué à tout le monde (1878), quoted in Alec Mellor, La Fabuleuse Aventure du téléphone (Paris: Montparnasse, 1975) 12.

226 

Alain Boillat

Fig.1. Albert Robida, Le Vingtième siècle (1883).

of her guardian, the young woman is woken by ringing. Frightened, she looks for the source of the bothersome sounds and understands that these come from a telephone receiver hidden under her pillow (Fig. 2). Later on, Hélène will constantly be woken by the unrequested news reaching her through telephone transmission. The novelist takes advantage of the supposed incompetence of the novice user to explain the various functions of the device to the contemporary reader. Despite his repeated expressions of admiration for the various applications of the telephone, in these particular instances Robida stresses the intrusive dimension of the sudden appearance of the Other in the private sphere. The representation of telephony in these pages of Robida’s novel involves a technophobic dimension that may be considered as recurrent throughout the twentieth century in narratives whose structure is based on scenes of phone conversations,32 particularly in film. I am therefore taking the liberty 32 This type of verbal interaction starts with the phone call, which linguist Catherine KerbratOrecchioni does not hesitate to characterize as a “territorial violation” and a “sound assault.” See C. Kerbrat-Orecchioni, “Théorie des faces et analyse conversationnelle,” in Le Parler frais d’Erving Goffman, ed. Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe (Paris: Minuit, 1989) 158.

The Social Imaginary of Telephony

227

Fig. 2. Albert Robida, Le Vingtième siècle (detail).

of a detour through later figurations, which in my view epitomize some constants in the imaginary associated with the uses of the technology in question. When telephony elicits doubts, two major trends may be noted: either the technological mediation interferes with an affective relationship, in a comedic mode with Sacha Guitry’s light comedy (1916) and film (1936) Faisons un rêve, in a dramatic mode with Cocteau’s La Voix humaine (1930) and its film and television adaptations;33 or it becomes the vehicle for an assault verging on rape on a female character, as in horror thrillers of the slasher type in which, from Fred Walton’s 1979 When A Stranger Calls through Simon West’s 2006 remake to Wes Craven’s Scream trilogy (19962000), a baby-sitter is verbally assaulted over the phone (or horrified by the phone ringing repeatedly), before a physical assault takes place. Filmmaker Wes Craven has in fact used the telephonic threat in an obsessive manner, for instance with the sudden appearance of a phallic tongue (Fig. 3a-3c) in Wes Craven’s New Nightmare (1994),34 in which the telephone is later 33 These are Amore (Roberto Rossellini, 1948) and The Human Voice (Ted Kotcheff, 1966). I would like to mention a few sentences in this one-act monolog by Cocteau, in which the conditional is the last protection in the face of despair and where the life of the female protagonist, brokenhearted by a separation, hangs by a thread, the wire of the telephone and the last contact with her lover: “If you did not love me and were shrewd, the phone would become a frightening weapon. A weapon that leaves no trace, a silent weapon…” Farther on: “This phone call became like a real blow you were dealing me and I fell; or a neck, a neck being strangled, or […] I was connected to you through a breathing device and I implored you not to cut it off […].” Jean Cocteau, La Voix humaine, in Romans, poésies, œuvres diverses (Paris: Le Livre de Poche, 1995) 1104, 1108. Translator’s note: the original French text plays on words and their homophony in a way that gets lost in English: “coup de fil” means “phone call,” “coup” means “blow,” while “cou” is “neck.” 34 In a way, this is a literal application of Avital Ronell’s remarks on the schizophrenic dimension of the “tongue” in the Heideggerian sense, where it becomes one and the same with this

228 

Alain Boillat

Fig. 3a-3c. Wes Craven’s Nightmare (Wes Craven, 1994) © New Line Cinema.

relayed by the television set as the vehicle for a passage from the real world to the world of nightmares. In that respect, it should be noted that Robida also has the young woman woken from a deep sleep by the device hidden under her pillow. After being frightened by a flood of tragic wire stories, Hélène “started to wonder whether she was dreaming or awake.”35 Tom other human prosthesis that is the telephone. Avital Ronell, The Telephone Book. Technology, Schizophrenia, Electric Speech (Lincoln, NE, London: University of Nebraska Press, 1991) 168. 35 Robida, The Twentieth Century 28. The dream provides access to a beyond – the baleful creature created by Wes Craven is in fact dead in the “real” world – which makes a sequence

The Social Imaginary of Telephony

229

Gunning has shown that the positive representation of technology in D.W. Griffith’s 1909 Lonely Villa,36 a famous instance of last-minute rescue made possible by a telephone communication, is haunted by a technophobic subtext, like many other films of the period. A contemporary French Grand Guignol play, De Lorde’s Au téléphone (1902, adapted for film by Pathé in 1906 under the title Terrible angoisse),37 actualizes this subtext: in the play the patriarch, far from restoring order as he does in Griffith’s film, is unable to prevent the assassination of his family and hears their cries over the telephone receiver. Even if, in the social imaginary, the telephone is associated with the comfort resulting from technological progress, it involves a threatening component and, for fiction writers, dramatic potential. As Claude S. Fischer points out, telephony has been considered in an ambivalent manner by sociologists, some associating it with a situation of alertness and tension, others taking it as essential to a feeling of safety.38 In that respect, the film Lonely Villa belongs in a reassuring discourse characteristic of promotional campaigns for the telephone set in the United States. The phone was, for instance, presented as a means of making homes located in rural areas safer, as illustrated in an advertisement for the Illinois Telephone Association in the 1930s (Fig. 4).39 However, fiction writers generally appear to have exacerbated, if not the harmful, at least the dangerous effects of the phone on the psyche. In The Twentieth Century, young Hélène struggles with an anthropomorphic telephone and attempts (in vain) to section the rubber pipe of the device with a pair of scissors. 40 In Alfred Hitchcock’s 1954 Dial M for Murder, a similar situation echoes this passage in Robida’s novel, evoking castration. In the film, the woman assaulted at home manages to wriggle out of her assailant’s grip as the man, hired by her husband, tries to strangle her with the telephone wire. She stabs him in the back with a pair of scissors, killing him. Still, with Hitchcock this turnaround in the situation is meant to surprise and plays with a horizon of expectation defined by the domisuch as this one evoke the spiritualist imaginary of the electric transmission of a voice, further reinforced with the generalization of wireless telephony. On this aspect, see Jeffrey Sconce, Haunted Media: Electronic Presence from Telegraphy to Television (Durham: Duke University Press, 2000). 36 Tom Gunning, “Heard over the phone: The Lonely Villa and the De Lorde tradition of the terrors of technology,” Screen 32.2 (1991): 184-96. 37 André De Lorde and Charles Foley, Au téléphone (1902; Paris: Librairie Molière, 1909). 38 Claude S. Fischer, America Calling. A Social History of the Telephone to 1940 (Berkeley, Los Angeles, Oxford: University of California Press, 1992) 25. 39 Quoted in Fischer, America Calling 165. 40 Robida, The Twentieth Century 31.

230 

Alain Boillat

nant archetype of the phallic aggression carried out with a technological instrument (in the film, its mechanical dimension is underlined through shots of an automated telephone exchange). With Robida, as in some Hollywood films, the telephone does constitute an interference, a violation of the private sphere. The same holds at a later stage of The Twentieth Century, when Mr. Ponto takes the liberty of checking through the telephonoscope that his son Philippe is indeed in his bedroom and not at the opera, where he thought he had spotted him on his screen. Since audiovision based on the telephonic model is reversible, communication may also turn into distance surveillance unbeknownst to the user; but for Robida, this constitutes a marginal use and it is presented as deviant. I should still point out that the novelist takes care to mention that this involves human errors (the maid responsible for cleaning up Hélène’s room forgot to turn off the telephone completely, just as Philippe omitted to deactivate his telephonoscope), which lessens the impression of technophobia detected thus far. This kind of situation, characterized by the voyeurism41 of a protagonist (or the pleasure of eavesdropping), emphasizes the degree to which desire was an integral part of the telephonic imaginary of the late nineteenth century – no less than in the twentieth century, when McLuhan noted that “no more unexpected social result of the telephone has been observed than its elimination of the red-light district and its creation of the call-girl.”42 Robida kept this function under control, seeing the telephone as an effective means to maintain the moral order by shielding young women from the ardor of their suitors. 43 By contrast, Le Téléphone (1889), a saucy story by Marc de Montifaud (a pseudonym for Marie-Aurélie Chartroule), openly links the telephone conversation with the sexual act – and the appliance with the phallus – as it tells the tale of a naive young woman warned by her aunt against the dangers to virtue represented by “modern inventions” (and particularly the telephone, “which could be used for reprehensible conversations”). 44 In the same breath she refuses to own a telephone set and to be possessed by the man she recently married; her husband has to

41 In another passage in the story, Mr. Ponto tells how, because of the mistake of a clerk at the central office, he was able to catch a young woman as she was getting out of bed. Robida, The Twentieth Century 66. 42 Marshall McLuhan, Understanding Media: The Extensions of Man (1968; Cambridge: MIT Press, 1994) 266. 43 In the French edition, the caption to plate nº31 (a full-page color drawing) reads, “Morality, tranquillity, felicity. – Telephone courtship.” 44 Marc de Montifaud, “Le Téléphone,” Nouvelles drolatiques (Paris: B. Simon et Cie, 1889) 933.

The Social Imaginary of Telephony

231

Fig. 4. Advertisement, 1930s (Illinois Telephone Association).

resort to the metaphor of the telephone to achieve his ends. 45 The telephone is associated with private secrets and intimate interpersonal conversation – this relation of desire between two disembodied voices runs through Duras’s Navire Night (1979) – and therefore pertains to an imaginary quite removed from the cinematographic spectacle, destined for a large audience gathered in the same space. 46 While some developments of the telephone 45 To his wife, who fears she may have “to learn how to use [it] the hard way,” the husband answers, “No, your role could perfectly consist in listening to me; I will… speak to you first; you will then answer me using the same method; and you will see, we will get along as though we had done it our entire life.” De Montifaud, “Le téléphone,” Nouvelles drolatiques 959. 46 McLuhan stressed – failing to take into account the context of the period, def ined as “strange,” as though institutional uses were self-evident – how telephony was oriented toward other uses than those contemplated at the end of the nineteenth century because of the relation of intimacy it establishes with the user: “Curiously, the newspaper of that time saw the telephone as a rival to the press as a P.A. system, such as radio was in fact to be fifty years later. But the

232 

Alain Boillat

were specifically tied to the commerce of eroticism (the sex chat lines with the Minitel and the computer-telephone integration, for instance), a better equivalent of this private use would be the home consumption of films. Jacques Perriault indicates that in 1980, 75% of the VHS tapes sold in France were pornographic. This type of production decisively contributed to the creation of a video market, which quickly became diversified afterwards. 47 Films such as Videodrome (David Cronenberg, 1982), Next of Kin (Atom Egoyan, 1984), Sex, Lies and Videotape (Steven Soderbergh, 1989), or more recently Lost Highway (David Lynch, 1997), have problematized this resolutely intimate aspect of the VCR, comparable in that respect to the telephone.

Audition and Audiovision of Theatrical Spectacles The visual dimension of the telephonoscope, a device primarily considered as a provider of audiovisual spectacles in The Twentieth Century, may appear to occupy a prime, central place for the novelist, since the extrapolation with respect to the system of telephony lies there. However, even as the “audiovisualization” of the speaker by the media is emphasized by Robida as the height of technological advances of the coming century, the transmission of speech constitutes the main function of his telephonoscope, as the first mention of the system in the book suggests: the author indicates that the character of Mr. Pronto, “sacrificing the one or two acts of French, German, or Italian opera on the telephonoscope […] dozed off in his armchair […].”48 The vision which this device, still unknown to the reader, gives access to is not mentioned explicitly, so that at this stage it may be taken to be an equivalent of the Théâtrophone, an invention that undoubtedly served as a model to the novelist. Presented by Clément Ader at the 1881 World Fair, two years before the novel was published, this system strongly contributed to legitimizing the applications of telephonic technology in the late nineteenth century by offering a specific use: the transmission of the sounds of stage performances to the home. The frame of reference of telephony was thus telephone, intimate and personal, is the most removed of any medium from the P.A. form. Thus wire-tapping seems even more odious than the reading of other people’s letters.” McLuhan, Understanding Media 269. 47 Perriault, La Logique de l’usage 167. 48 Robida, The Twentieth Century 11. Translator’s note: the word “audition,” emphasized by the author in Robida’s original text in French, is omitted in the English translation.

The Social Imaginary of Telephony

233

associated – like that of the cinematograph – to the sphere of entertainment, spectacle and the recording of artistic practices. The precedence given by Robida to audition is not only the consequence of a genealogical perspective that would have the invention of sound transmission come before “television.” The fact that most commentators have tended to neglect the dimension of sound in the telephonoscope certainly has to do with the presence of illustrations by the author of The Twentieth Century in which the visual representation provided by the “crystal screens” of the device is emphasized. Still, staying clear of teleologism requires a departure from the preconception that as an invention, audiovisual communication (or representation) should unavoidably come after strictly visual and auditory technologies and be more complex than these, owing to the mere fact that it combines both dimensions. The rendering or the transmission of speech may indeed very well constitute the main use assigned to some machines at a given moment in the history of the technologies in question. In an article on La Guerre au vingtième siècle in the periodical devoted to Robida, Le Téléphonoscope, André Lange phrased the issue as follows: The absence of the “telephonoscope” in La Guerre au vingtième siècle (1887) may surprise, as it had previously appeared in The Twentieth Century, published in 1883. Two inventions from The Twentieth Century are still present here, the “telephonic gazette” and the “telephonograph.” But no telephonoscope to be found…49

Lange’s surprise at the absence of the telephonoscope in La Guerre au vingtième siècle stems from the assumption that this later novel should feature an invention deemed more advanced than the “telephonic gazette.” Yet if the telephonoscope is taken as one possible development of telephonic technique, Robida could understandably limit himself to strictly auditory technologies of communication four years later, with the image an optional component50 mainly considered in relation to the home transmission of theatrical performances in The Twentieth Century. Outside the period outlined by the epistemological undertaking proper, the frame of reference of Robida’s novel and that of the first decade of the twentieth century may also be compared. The primacy of the dimension of sound then appears to become less marked in futuristic texts, in which an 49 André Lange, “En attendant la guerre des ondes, les technologies de communication dans les anticipations militaires d’Albert Robida,” Le Téléphonoscope 11 (May 2004): 8-10. 50 See my study “Faire pour la vue ce que le téléphone fait pour l’ouïe,” more particularly 84-88.

234 

Alain Boillat

imaginary more strongly influenced by the model of “television” emerges. In that respect, a significant lexical change may be noted in La Guerre infernale by Pierre Giffard, a novelist who was also the author of popular scientific works. In this novel, published in 1908 and illustrated by Albert Robida, the appliance corresponding to the telephonoscope of The Twentieth Century is called the “telephotograph,” a term whose Greek etymology does not refer to sounds at all. One hypothesis is that the generalization of moving images with the cinematograph contributed to shift the frame of reference for extrapolations of telephony toward a more visual model, which until then dominated only in representations associated with the exteriorization of mental images51 or the visualization of ghosts, especially in the vogue of spiritualism.52 To deal with the different frames of reference of these technologies, I propose three main lines, often interdependent, but distinguished to analytical ends here: communication, inscription, and simulation.53 While the subjects transmitted through the telephonoscope are diverse in Robida’s novel (the attack of the Tuaregs filmed by a reporter is often cited as a forerunner of television news, for example), the frame of reference in which the novelist conceives this technology pertains to both communication and simulation. The latter comes “first,” if only because of the order and the number of times applications of the telephonoscope come up in the narrative. The Théâtrophone, which inspired Robida with the dominant use of the telephonoscope, does not so much fall within the paradigm of what 51 See the short story L’Encéphaloscope (Der Gehirnspiegel, 1900) by Kurd Lasswitz, trans. Stefania Maffei, in La Télévision, du téléphonoscope à Youtube 99-106. 52 On the subject, see Henri Azam’s essay “Télégraphie sans fil et médiumnité,” published monthly between March 1925 and December 1926 as a series of articles in La Revue spirite, and whose first text was presented by the editors as follows: “With the breakthroughs of science in the domain of radio-telegraphy, heeding the scientists specializing in this area becomes highly interesting, as does – when they are also spiritualists – the study of the parallelism, the analogy of physical and psychical worlds.” La Revue spirite. Journal d’études psychologiques et de spiritualisme expérimental, Paris (Feb. 1925): 66 (my emphasis). Allan Kardec, the founder of La Revue spirite in 1858, explained what the relation with the invisible world of spirits consisted in, comparing it with what the transatlantic electric wire could have taught Europeans about Amerindian peoples before the discovery of America. See Allan Kardec, Qu’est-ce que le spiritisme? Introduction à la connaissance du monde invisible par les manifestations des esprits (1859; Paris: Editions Vermet, 2005) 51. On the relations between spiritualism and telephony, see my study of Villiers de l’Isle-Adam’s novel Tomorrow’s Eve, “On the particular status of the human voice. Tomorrow’s Eve and the cultural series of talking machines,” Cinema Beyond Film 240-42, and more generally Jeffrey Sconce, Haunted Media: Electronic Presence from Telegraphy to Television. 53 These appear in increasing order of potential intersections with related systems of talking cinema.

The Social Imaginary of Telephony

235

was later to be called “telecommunications” as within that of simulation, audition being associated with a “virtual” image (actualized in Robida’s fiction). Giusy Pisano notes that with the Théâtrophone, the principle of two transmitters (one for each ear) made possible a lateralization of sounds, prefiguring stereophony, thanks to the variations in sound intensity brought about by the distribution left/right and which activated a mental representation of the space and the movements of performers on stage for the listener. This partial acoustic reproduction of the original space underscores the representational dimension of this type of system. The nodal presence of this cultural referent – the first telephonic message is the account of a show at the Comédie-Française – is not surprising if one recalls the intense theatrical activity in Paris in the 1870s and 1880s as well as Robida’s implication in that area. Indeed, one of his favorite subjects as a caricaturist (for Le Journal amusant, La Vie parisienne and later La Caricature)54 was the chronicle of Parisian stage life at the time. In that respect, it seems important to me to take into account the type of spectacles Robida refers to in The Twentieth Century, where descriptions are often satirical. The futuristic character of the telephonoscope does not lie only in the dispositive it mobilizes, but also in the very nature of the transmitted spectacle. A correlation may in fact be established between these two aspects around the notion of “attraction” as defined by theoreticians of early cinema:55 a “technological attraction,” to be sure, because of the enthusiasm shown by the narrator and characters for the wonders of the telephonoscope (it is a “novelty period”56 only for the focal character of the narrative, as other characters are used to handling the system); but a “stage attraction” as well, since Robida takes care to mention that “modern” directors would add attractions to classical plays, and Antonio Salieri’s 1786 Les Horaces becomes, for instance, a “tragedy in five acts and five attractions.” Each of the thrilling interludes is meant to arouse the attention of an audience bored by “old plays” – Robida constantly points out the lack of interest in literary culture on the part of a society prizing speed and sciences. An interlude consists, for instance, in a ballet, a tableau

54 See Sandrine Doré, “Albert Robida, critique en image de l’actualité théâtrale des années 1870-1880,” in Albert Robida, du passé au futur, ed. Daniel Compère (Paris: Belles-Lettres, 2006). 55 See Tom Gunning, “The Cinema of Attractions. Early Film, Its Spectator and the AvantGarde,” Wide Angle 8.3-4 (1986): 63-70. 56 The term was proposed by Tom Gunning to refer to a first phase in the use of the cinematographic dispositive. See Tom Gunning, “The Scene of Speaking: Two Decades of Discovering the Film Lecturer,” Iris 27 (1999): 67-79.

236 

Alain Boillat

vivant or an “equestrian and pedestrian dramatic pantomime,”57 which the public of the future, as the author calls it with irony, honors as the height of theatrical art. The heroine attends “a circus pantomime with a great entrance of clowns”58 from her place and the telephonic account surprising her in the middle of the night has as its subject the premiere of a play featuring a “lion-tamer”59 at the Comédie-Française. The novelist emphasizes the changeable and heterogeneous dimension of programming in theaters, which constantly have to renew their “attractions”: “Theater halls are no longer exclusively devoted to one genre like they used to be; they must offer variety to keep audiences interested. […] It [a theater] must then transform itself, switch genres, renew its personnel, and find new attractions to stay afloat financially.”60 In the novel, no explicit connection is made between this new type of play and distance audiovision, but both involve the representation of a mass spectacle, as some subheadings indicate in the fifth chapter. Transmitted by the telephonoscope, the plays imagined by Robida therefore present some similarities with most of the subjects chosen by the pioneers of talking cinema and subsequently over the first years of the talkies, at the time of the so-called “talking and singing” films.61

Communication Within the “Machinery” A singular manifestation of Robida’s reticular conception appears in The Twentieth Century when the novelist explains the resort to orchestras for the audiovisual transmission of theatrical plays: […] other theaters have worked out an agreement whereby they share a common orchestra, located in a special room designed according to scientific principles and linked to all theaters through telephonic wires. Each evening, the central orchestra plays four pieces transmitted through the cables to subscribing venues.62

The telephone link not only makes it possible to connect subscribers to the place of the show: it also connects two institutions internal to the produc57 Robida, The Twentieth Century 60. 58 Robida, The Twentieth Century 206. 59 Robida, The Twentieth Century 35. 60 Robida, The Twentieth Century 195 (my emphasis). 61 See my Du bonimenteur à la voix-over, chapter V. 62 Robida, The Twentieth Century n55.

The Social Imaginary of Telephony

237

Fig. 5. Advertisement from the company Pathé frères.

tion space of the audiovisual representation, the different theater halls and the “auditorium” where the orchestra is located. This was one of the major preoccupations of the pioneers of sound cinema, as they sought to establish the synchronization between the visual and auditory components associated with separate spaces. In the early 1920s these attempts led to the use of systems such as Charles Delacommunes’s Ciné-Pupitre,63 but even in spoken early cinema, lecturers for magic lantern shows64 or for the cinematograph needed to be connected to the projectionist, sometimes even using semi-mechanical systems.65 The explanation provided by Robida in this passage restricted to the margins of the narrative – a footnote – may well support Giusy Pisano’s hypothesis on the Théâtrophone, namely that this system “must have encouraged […] the pioneers of synchronism, who 63 See Laurent Guido, L’Âge du rythme (Lausanne: Payot, 2007)  404-408; and Boillat, Du bonimenteur à la voix-over 92, n162. 64 A 1909 column on a specific projection system thus highlighted the interest of “bringing the lecturer and the lantern projectionist closer” and “the ease for them to communicate during the performance.” “Projections dactylographiques,” in Ciné-Journal 37 (29 Apr. - 5 May 1909). 65 “In front of the lecturer was a row of small knobs and a mysterious and silent dialogue existed between the booth and him, a dialogue punctuated with red, white, green or blue lights. These meant, ‘Show a still view, start the film.’ Or they indicated that the orchestra should stop, start again, change the score.” See Rodolphe-Maurice Arlaud, Cinéma Bouffe (Paris: Editions Jacques Melot, 1945) 79 (my emphasis).

238 

Alain Boillat

saw in its success the possibility of combining the cinematograph and the phonograph through a telephone wire.”66 In these experiences of projection of moving images with sound, transmission does not occur between the representation and the audience – that axis is still governed by the paradigm of simulation (of a diegetic world) – but rather between two agents in the space of production of the representation. This type of system was available at Pathé when the company commercialized its Ciné-Phono around 1906: interestingly, one of the advertising posters for this kind of spectacle (Fig. 5)67 features an egg-shaped projected image (as in Robida’s illustrations of the telephonoscope, but in this instance most certainly to refer to the firm’s logo, a medallion featuring a rooster). The projection seems to result from a beam of light issuing from the phonograph’s horn, as though sound came first (and in fact, the slogan puts “to hear” before “to see”). The distinction proposed by François Albera and André Gaudreault between the bonimenteur and the conférencier in early cinema,68 displaced onto this context, suggests an interpretation of this image as a phonographic audition accompanied with images rather than a cinematographic projection with sound. Another contemporary illustration, reproduced without commentary in Giusy Pisano’s book, features the Pathé device designed for the projection of “cine-phonographic scenes” (Fig. 6).69 It clearly shows that this system of live synchronization, akin to the Phono-Cinéma-Théâtre presented by Clément-Maurice in 1900, allowed a connection to the projection booth and the phonograph located in the spectatorial space, thanks to a telephone receiver. The projectionist set the projection speed to the sounds produced by the cylinder of the phonograph. This representation of a film show in a 1905 Pathé catalog is unusual in that it does not seem to be a public projection site but a screening for a limited number of spectators. This is suggested by the paintings and the chandelier, which, like the dress and the posture of spectators, point to a bourgeois home or the privacy of a curio cabinet, and contrast quite a lot with the commercial presence of the cinematograph in fairs. Since amplification constituted a major problem for sound cinema at the time, it is not surprising that the show would be imagined in a relatively cramped space. An operator stands in each of the spaces; the person in charge of the 66 Giusy Pisano, Une archéologie du cinéma sonore (Paris: CNRS, 2004) 159. 67 The poster is reprinted in Jacques Kermabon, Pathé, premier Empire du cinéma (Paris: Centre Pompidou, 1994) 22. 68 See François Albera, André Gaudreault, “Apparition, disparition et escamotage du ‘bonimenteur’ dans l’historiographie française du cinéma,” Le Muet a la parole 169-70. 69 Giusy Pisano, Une archéologie du cinéma sonore 267.

The Social Imaginary of Telephony

239

Fig. 6. Excerpt from the Pathé catalog, 1905.

phonograph becomes idle after the machine starts but may conceivably intervene as a lecturer, or bonimenteur, in the absence of a phonographic recording. A partition separates the place where the projectionist stands from the space of reception, probably so that the noise of the projector does not drown out the sounds emitted by the phonograph.70 Here the telephone is reduced to a unidirectional transmission not addressed at the spectators of the audiovisual representation, but used instead backstage to coordinate the two sides of the machinery. This is to be distinguished from a system such as the Phonorama (invented by Berthon, Dussaud and Jaubert in 1898), which had spectators place a telephone receiver on one of their ears to be able to listen to the sound accompanying the projected image and literally integrated telephony into the cinematographic spectacle. Finally, on the subject of these “Scènes Ciné-Phonographiques,” I should note that one of the films commercialized by Pathé and mentioned by Giusy Pisano takes on a particular signification, compared with the techniques involved in this system. Titled Au téléphone and made in 1904, it showed and allowed one to hear a monologue by music-hall artist Félix Galipaux. In this instance, as 70 Martin Barnier has noted that projection booths were common in early cinema and that mechanical noise could have become a nuisance only as motorized projectors became widespread during the First World War, not at the time when the projectionist turned a crank, as is the case here. See Martin Barnier, Bruits, cris, musiques de films. Les projections avant 1914 (Rennes: PUR, 2010) 144-45. The issue of projector noise repeatedly comes up in discourses on “silent” cinema: see Boillat, Du bonimenteur à la voix-over 130-48.

240 

Alain Boillat

in filmic examples punctuating this discussion, what is represented echoes the machinery needed for the very production of the representation.

The Paradigm of Inscription: Telephony and Phonography In Robida’s futuristic story, oral transmission over the telephone replaces writing, and more generally all mediums used to record speech, forestalling Paul Zumthor’s comment in the era of sound media that “primitive orality is making a strong comeback,” or rather, that “its continuity […] is suddenly resurfacing after centuries of predominance of modes of written communication.”71 Robida’s technological extrapolations attest to a will to depict, in a dystopian mode, the total conversion of writing to oral modes of expression. Letters are no longer written in The Twentieth Century: instead, oral messages are recorded on the cylinder of a phonograph. Newspapers editors do jot down their text on paper, but they transmit it orally only, as “the articles sound spicier when read by their own authors. Through varied inflexions and skillful intonations, they can add dimension to innuendos and thus imply to subscribers what is not quite spelled out.”72 Given the primacy of orality, whose immediacy contributes to play down the medium, it comes as no surprise that here and there Robida’s illustrations include balloons that were to become widespread some fifteen years later in comic strips. Thierry Smolderen has demonstrated how radically different they were from their predecessors (“phylacteries”) in that they resulted from a new conception of speech as a sound phenomenon, a movement of air.73 Like the phonograph, which appeared two years before it, the telephone constituted the site of an exacerbation of speech as an acoustic phenomenon. One might think that phonography, unlike the telephone, is not associated with the notion of simultaneity, but in fact the distinction between 71 Paul Zumthor, “Le geste et la voix,” Hors-cadre 3 (1985) 73. 72 Robida, The Twentieth Century 187. 73 The sequence of images by draughtsman R. F. Outcault, The Yellow Kid and His New Phonograph (New York Journal, 25 Oct. 1896), which in Smolderen’s view marked a paradigmatic shift, uses precisely this phonographic technique – even if counterfeited, displaced onto a living being, since a parrot is hiding in the body of the appliance. The first four “vignettes,” which are not framed with a line, belong in the paradigm of writing (the text uttered by the character of the “Yellow Kid” appears on his nightshirt), whereas the last one, in which the child’s surprise is expressed in a balloon, marks the passage towards what Smolderen calls “the phonographic paradigm of the speech balloon.” See Thierry Smolderen, “Of labels, loops, and bubbles. Solving the historical puzzle of the speech balloon,” Comic Art 8 (Summer 2006). From the same author, see also Naissances de la bande dessinée (Brussels: Les Impressions Nouvelles, 2009) 119-27.

The Social Imaginary of Telephony

241

inscription and communication was not clear-cut at the time. Significantly, combining the telephone with the phonograph was often contemplated, as early as Edison, who noted in his memoirs (1878): At the moment, the telephone necessarily has a limited role because exchanged messages, not being recorded, are reduced to a mere conversation which does not present the needed guarantees. […] With the telephone combined with the phonograph, things would be different for preliminary discussions would be recorded and the textual reproduction of everything agreed upon would be available.74

Since the usefulness of the “mere conversation” had not yet been acknowledged, Edison thought of an association with the phonograph with a view to a professional use of telephony, in particular in the domain of finance, where the new device could play a role similar to that of the telegraph. Robida himself imagined some combinations of these two techniques. Despite the term used, his “telephonograph” has no relation to the recording of sound, since the phonograph is limited to the function of a megaphone: sound amplification simply allows the interlocutor to do without a pipe connected to the device. It is a sort of “hands-free” system, as the expression goes today with respect to cellular phone capabilities (it is one of the profiles for the Bluetooth standard). In other places, the novelist turns the phonograph into a means of communication: for instance, after a shipwreck, the captain throws six phonographs out to sea, with a distress message recorded on each of them.75 The phonographic recording thus mitigates spatial distance, compensating it with a delayed transmission. In this case, the recording of voices is subject to an objective, communicating information, and thus appears in devices akin to voice mail or the Dictaphone. Robida is rather critical of this semblance of communication, for several times he emphasizes the lack experienced due to the absence of an interlocutor in the flesh and the possibly deceptive simulation produced by techniques

74 Cited in French translation in Théodore Du Moncel, Le Téléphone, le microphone et le phonographe (Paris: Librairie Hachette, 1879) 302-3. Translator’s note: the quotation given here is a translation from this French source, not from the original text where it could not be found. See Frederick J. Garbit, The Phonograph and Its Inventor, Thomas Alvah Edison. Being a Description of the Invention and A Memoir of Its Inventor (Boston: Gunn, Bliss, and Co., 1878), available at http://archive.org/stream/phonographandit00garbgoog#page/n1/mode/2up, last accessed on July 23, 2012. 75 Robida, The Twentieth Century 334.

242 

Alain Boillat

of inscription and transmission of sounds.76 Indeed, phonography and telephony, despite the immediacy they institute with sound occurrences, whether fixed or transmitted, give rise to representations:77 the interlocutor is fundamentally absent for the addressee of the message when it is delivered, either because the expression took place beforehand or is taking place from elsewhere. As Jacques Perriault emphasizes, “It is not the voice that is being heard over the phone but a more or less faithful reconstitution, without the gestures accompanying it, moreover.”78 Even if the telephone does not provide the image of gestures, it aims to create a simulacrum of presence by reproducing, on the side of reception, the variations of sound waves produced on the side of emission. This question leads us directly to the third paradigm, which will be considered succinctly,79 that of simulation (of a human presence).

Simulation: The False Presence of the Other The author of The Twentieth Century underlines the deterioration of interpersonal relations in a technological society where “close” relatives are contacted only “from a distance” – what Freud later stigmatized in Civilization and Its Discontents (1930). At the beginning of the novel, Robida thus cynically describes the attitude of parents for whom “telephonographic” messages have as their function to substitute for their actual presence by their children’s side. When they come back home to Paris after eight years in a provincial high school, Barbe and Barnabette are 76 Robida admittedly evokes the positive effects of the telephonoscope, since he mentions that the device makes it possible to suppress absence. Nevertheless, that is an incidental comment by a candid Hélène, which the narrative tends to contradict through the multiplication of negative effects linked to the use of telecommunications. In fact, when Hélène brings up the fact that “the telephonoscope reunites faraway loved ones,” the more experienced Mr. Ponto replies, “Almost.” Robida, The Twentieth Century 65. 77 The representational nature of sound is rarely taken into account in media theories, probably due to its less manifest character (except in the case of technical problems, which reveal it, precisely), and in any case less than the representational nature of the image, two-dimensional even when monochrome. On the subject, see Alan Williams, “Is Sound Recording Like a Language?” Yale French Studies 60 (1980); and Boillat, Du Bonimenteur à la voix-over 396-420. 78 Perriault, La Logique de l’usage 53. 79 For a more in-depth examination of this question, I refer the reader to my comments on the “Android” in the novel Tomorrow’s Eve, “L’Eve future et la série culturelle des ‘machines parlantes.’ Le statut singulier de la voix humaine au sein d’un dispositif audiovisuel,” in Cinémas 17.1 (Fall 2006): 10-34; as for the links between “tele-vision” and “talking portraits,” see Boillat, “Faire pour la vue ce que le téléphone fait pour l’ouïe”: 78-84.

The Social Imaginary of Telephony

243

not “welcomed with open arms and anxious hearts by their father and mother,”80 as imagined by Hélène, the orphan accompanying them. On the contrary, they are “surprised that neither their father nor their mother was there to greet them”81 and learn coldly from a concierge speaking through a telephonograph that their parents are not home yet. The father, who is busy at the stock exchange, joins them later; to find out where his wife is, he asks a servant to bring him “Mrs. Ponto’s phono.” The “dialogue” between the young women and the recorded voice of their mother unfolds as follows: – Remember to change the flowers in the living room, said the telephonograph. – That’s Mama’s voice, exclaimed Barnabette, always the same. – Go to the Trocadero for their samples of Régence satin and their noodles from Colmar… Change the water in the aquarium… I’ll be back around eleven… – A h! exclaimed Barbe and Barnabette. – … I am having lunch at the English Café with a few political lady friends. The telephonograph stopped. – That’s all? asked Barnabette. Nothing for us?82

The first sentence, whose grammatical subject is the machine, not the individual uttering the words, produces a dehumanization that reinforces the feeling of an absence of the mother, busy with other tasks. In a society that has seen the emancipation of women, the wife of the rich banker, depicted with a degree of misogyny by Robida, is very active politically. The dashes signal that characters speak in turns, even though no genuine conversation is initiated, since the mother’s recorded speech does not allow for any interaction. In fact, the lines of the young women act as commentaries, allowing the novelist to signify their disappointment. While Barnabette does find some pleasure in the recognition of her mother’s voice, which brings a human dimension – the inalienable features of the voice’s texture make it possible to reconstruct the presence of the speaker in part – she is dumbfounded that no declaration is addressed to her, excluding her defini-

80 Robida, The Twentieth Century 6. 81 Robida, The Twentieth Century 9. 82 Robida, The Twentieth Century 10.

244 

Alain Boillat

tively from any relation of communication.83 Communication technologies involving sound alone are the only ones that fail to make distance irrelevant between beings84 – unlike the telephonoscope, whose visual component ensures a gain in presence.85 Robida even specifies that with this device, “the illusion is complete, absolute.”86 Sound plays a part in the creation of this “telephonoscopic” representation of a stage performance, however, since the novelist also imagines a “chamber theater” in which actors play merely by having their voices heard over the telephone.87 Indeed, telephony and phonography both result from a set of anthropocentric and demiurgic attempts to reproduce the human through “speaking machines”: as Jacques Perriault has noted, “what communication machines have to offer [is] the circulation of simulacra, or ‘effigies,’ when it comes to individuals.”88 The disembodied voices that reach us through the telephone receiver are often vested with a power of presentification. Presence requires the present of simultaneity, which is why phonography, postponing as it does the transmission of the message, partly fails to meet the compensatory role assigned to “regulatory machines,” to borrow Jacques Perriault’s term.89 In the De Lorde play previously mentioned, the husband goes as far as to forget the distance separating him from his wife – until dramatic facts remind him of it, before a definitive, deadly separation. Indeed, audition over the telephone makes his interlocutor as present to him as is possible: “Do you not think it so admirable: you are close to me… I can sense the least inflections of your voice… of your gestures… I can almost see you… Yes, I can see you, my love… My dear love… (He kisses her over the phone.).”90 With the mental image produced by the recognition of the voice, this passage is reminiscent of Robida’s characters and their outpourings over the telephonoscope (Fig. 7). Each scientific or 83 I want to point out that epistolary correspondence in The Twentieth Century also goes through the phonograph, following a use that Du Moncel had contemplated. See Du Moncel, Le Téléphone, le microphone et le phonographe 299-300. 84 The phonograph also provides quite a pathetic trace of the unfaithful Mr. Montgiscard to his spouse-to-be, who in his absence has the device repeat the pledges of love he has recorded with it. Robida, The Twentieth Century 217. 85 As to the phone conversation, it turns out to be a deception in the case of Jules Montgiscard’s proposal, as if the absence of the interlocutor’s image enabled him to conceal his dishonesty. Robida, The Twentieth Century 213-16. 86 Robida, The Twentieth Century 53. 87 Robida, The Twentieth Century 66. 88 Perriault, La Logique de l’usage 55. 89 “The project of realization [of an invention] is linked to the perception of an imbalance […] [which] may be a lack of information, absence, loneliness, war, disability or handicap.” Perriault, La Logique de l’usage 62. 90 De Lorde and Foley, Au téléphone 30.

The Social Imaginary of Telephony

245

Fig. 7. Albert Robida, Le Vingtième siècle.

theoretical discourse, each discourse of imagination negotiates in its own way the ambivalent status of the presence-absence of the interlocutor on the telephone: to mention but a few examples, which should be put in a specific context of discursive production, it seems that many texts like the passage from De Lorde give the voice a very strong power of presence, but they coexist with the field of media theory, where Marshall McLuhan asserts that the user of the telephone is unable to effect an act of visualization91 and Jean-François Lyotard stigmatizes the disembodiment telecommunications entail.92 It does not come as a surprise, then, that cinema frequently seized on the motif of the telephone,93 as early as the “silent” era or, as it is called in French, the “mute” era – a period in which cinema called for virtual speech,94

91 McLuhan, Understanding Media 267-68. 92 Jean-François Lyotard, “Something Like: ‘Communication… without Communication’,” in The Inhuman: Reflections on Time, trans. Geoffrey Bennington and Rachel Bowlby (Stanford: Stanford U.P., 1991). 93 See Ned Schantz, “Telephonic Film,” Film Quarterly 56.4 (2003) 23-35. 94 See Rick Altman’s theses, “Quelques idées reçues sur le son du cinéma muet qu’on ne saurait plus tenir,” Le Muet a la parole 81-99, some of which notably apply to films representing a phone conversation.

246 

Alain Boillat

or speech actualized by the lecturer during the screening,95 in fact. Cinema then took advantage of its “ability to involve all of them [technical media] by representing or using them within itself,”96 according to François Albera, thereby producing a discourse on these media: for Tom Gunning, “[i]f the telephone had not existed, film would have had to invent it.”97 In return, the figuration of the telephonic medium and its uses, related to the removal of any spatial limit and the institution of simultaneity, was not without effect on film language and film narration,98 particularly with regard to the practice of crosscutting.99 A recent example could be 24 (Robert Cochran, Joel Surnow and Howard Gordon, 2001-2010), one of the most famous television series of the decade: its narrative premises depend on the generalization of cellular telephony, which appears in various applications throughout the episodes (distance conversation, teleconference, geolocation, microphone, remote control, etc.). Indeed, some choices, both formal (multiplication of split screens) and narrative (supposed equivalence between time of the plot and time of the story), are founded on the omnipresence of cellular phones in the diegesis. In fact, the interest of the present study in the links between moving images and telephony in the late nineteenth century is inevitably informed by the contemporary context. As Maurizio Ferraris has shown with regard to mobile telephony,100 we find ourselves again in a hybrid era, between orality and record, an era of intermediality characterized by a permeability of practices in telecommunications and recording technologies. This is why 95 See Martin Sopocy’s comments on James Williamson’s Are You Here: Martin Sopocy, “Un cinéma avec narrateur. Les premiers films narratifs de James A. Williamson,” Les Cahiers de la Cinémathèque 29 (Perpignan, 1979): 108-25. 96 François Albera, “Le cinéma ‘projeté’ et les périodisations de l’histoire technique du cinéma,” Cinema Beyond Film 393. In a note, the author brings up the example of the “role of the telephone in film narrative.” 97 Tom Gunning, “Fritz Lang Calling: The Telephone and the Circuits of Modernity,” in Allegories of Communication. Intermedial concerns from cinema to digital, John Fullerton and Jan Olsson, eds. (Rome: John Libbey, 2004) 23. 98 See Eileen Bowser, “Le coup de téléphone dans les primitifs du cinéma,” in Les Premiers Ans du cinéma français, ed. Pierre Guibbert (Perpignan: Institut Jean Vigo, 1985); Jan Olsson, “Calling the Shots: Communication, Transportation and Motion Picture Technologies in the Teens,” in Le Cinématographe 273-81; by the same author, on the technique of the split screen, see “Framing Silent Calls: Coming to Cinematographic Terms with Telephony,” in Allegories of Communication 157-92. 99 See Philippe Gauthier, Le Montage alterné avant Griffith. Le cas Pathé (Paris: L’Harmattan, 2008) 113-15. 100 Maurizio Ferraris, T’es où? Ontologie du téléphone mobile (2005; Paris: Albin Michel, 2006), part I.

The Social Imaginary of Telephony

247

Fig. 8. The movie theater comes with the telephone. ®Etienne Lavallée.

I have occasionally given myself license, in a perspective inspired at times by Friedrich Kittler,101 not to limit this research to discourses from the late nineteenth century. I also wanted, on the sidelines of this archaeological enterprise, to use its frame of reference to weave together connections between several distinct periods. The aim was to propose a comparative study that could widen the scope of observations on an archaeology of sound cinema and start a reflection on their fruitfulness in the form of ways into a few specific aspects. Nowadays cellular technology is not used only for communication, but also to look up a schedule or a list of contacts, to write messages, to go on the Internet, to take pictures or shoot videos, to view these images, etc. The improbable machine created by Canadian computer graphics artist Etienne Lavallée, which appears on the cover of the 2001 edition of Understanding Media in the “Bibliothèque québécoise” (Fig. 8), thus says something of the reversal that seems to have occurred. In this hybrid machine, the movie theater is included in the form of a black-andwhite image in a circular screen replacing the dial of an old telephone, as if to remind us that, on an epistemological level, (talking) “cinema” is perhaps not (or no longer) necessarily the entity encompassing other media, even if its centrality as a dispositive remains a measuring stick when thinking about them.

101 Friedrich Kittler, Gramophone, Film, Typewriter (Stanford: Stanford U.P., 1999).



Between Paradoxical Spectacles and Technical Dispositives Looking Again at the (Serpentine) Dances of Early Cinema Laurent Guido

When trying to grasp the complex relationships between dance and moving images, during the emergence of the cinematic medium, one can hardly avoid noticing the necessity of investigate, once again, the films dedicated to the famous number of “serpentine” dance developed and started in 1892 by music-hall performer Loïe Fuller. The phenomenal craze created by this original stage spectacle ended up imposing it as one of the motifs characterizing artistic expression at the turn of the twentieth century. Countless variations have attested to this, at least until the First World War, in areas as diverse as sculpture, painting, architecture, furniture, or even poetry and literature. Over the period, the serpentine dance continuously exerted its influence over the most innovative aesthetic currents, from the heirs of Symbolism through the Futurists to decorative trends typical of Art Nouveau. Seeking to explain this stunning success, several studies have shown how Fuller’s performances were made possible by important epistemological changes following the emergence of a large ensemble of scientific and technical dispositives.1 On the one hand, the serpentine dance, like other spectacles designed by Fuller, featured a stylized apprehension of a form of mobility constantly tending toward abstraction, on the model of new rationalized perceptions of the human body. On the other hand, the same Fullerian shows expressed a symbiosis, unknown until then, between artistic and technological dimensions of art and technology. Indeed, through their incorporation of projections of artificial light with multiple changing colors, of pyrotechnical effects, of complex mechanisms 1 On these questions, see Elizabeth Coffman, “Women in Motion: Loie Fuller and the ‘Interpenetration’ of Art and Science,” Camera Obscura, 17.1 (2002): 73-105; Rhonda Garelick, Electric Salome: Loie Fuller’s Performance of Modernism (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2007); Gabriele Brandstetter and Brygida Maria Ochaim, Loïe Fuller: Tanz, Licht-Spiel, Art Nouveau (Freiburg im Breisgau: Rombach, 1989); Giovanni Lista, Loïe Fuller. Danseuse de l’Art Nouveau (Paris: Réunion des Musées Nationaux, 2002), and Loïe Fuller. Danseuse de la Belle Epoque (Paris: Hermann Editeurs des Sciences et des Arts, 2006), an expanded version of the first edition (Paris: Somogy/Stock, 1994).

250 

L aurent Guido

or even of the combinations of a mobile magic lantern, they tapped into the most spectacular signs of a modern expressivity firmly anchored in the new world of electricity, machines and industrialization. This is how the famous quotation from Stéphane Mallarmé should be understood: in a text he reprinted in his Divagations (1897), he writes of Fuller’s show as the representation of an “inebriation by art” and “simultaneously, an industrial accomplishment.”2 This remarkable articulation between the dimensions of aesthetic emotion and scientific technicality has largely been acknowledged over the past twenty years, not only within cultural studies, but also on the occasion of large exhibitions devoted to the history of visual arts. Whether in regard to abstraction (Musée d’Orsay, 2004) or visual movement (Centre Pompidou, 2007), the serpentine dance has frequently been taken to epitomize, in an instantaneous and startling manner, the new rhythmic and geometric conceptions of mobility that appeared at the dawn of the twentieth century. To illustrate this motif in the most representative way possible, the same series of short films with “imitators” (a sanctioned term in Fuller’s historiography) has generally been mobilized, most of them made between 1894 and 1908. This list of short films has definitely settled in the contemporary imagination, not only through the rooms of museums where they are shown, but also in the form of videos uploaded on the web. Many appropriations of this motif may thus be found on YouTube with more or less inspired video remixes that are hardly ever referenced correctly. Despite its widespread distribution, this body of films does not seem to have ever been considered for itself, but rather as an illustration by default, seen as unfortunate by specialists of Loïe Fuller. Elisabeth Coffman, for instance, insists on pointing out the gap between these various film recordings and Fuller’s scenic performances: “Dozens of films of this same sort were made over the next twenty years – most following a predictable set of expectations about costume, mise-en-scène, and bodily movement – but nothing like Fuller’s Fire Dance.”3 Fuller’s imitators clearly never enjoyed means similar to those put at the disposal of the famous American, who mobilized up to a hundred technicians and was assigned an entire building for the 1900 World Fair. As Giovanni Lista, one of Fuller’s better experts, also notes, “[Fuller] alone was able to move beyond the ‘dance of the veil’ to reach an art of immateriality focusing on movement, plastic form and the color of 2 Stéphane Mallarmé, “Crayonné au théâtre,” Divagations (1897), in Œuvres complètes, vol. II (Paris: Gallimard, 2003) 174. 3 Coffman, “Women in Motion”: 86.

Between Paradoxical Spectacles and Technical Dispositives

251

light. Indeed, none of these short films illustrates what contemporary texts and iconography convey about Loïe Fuller’s work […].”4 To account for the lack – in the current state of research – of any film recording of the creator of the serpentine (by contrast, several photographs have come down to us), Lista raises the issue of the limits of representation on film at the time, compared with the richness and complexity of the grand spectacle offered by Fuller: “Contemporary filmmakers could only acknowledge the technical impossibility of filming the highly sophisticated Fullerian version of the serpentine dance. For Loïe Fuller as well, cinema could only constitute a substantial reduction of the magic of her spectacles.”5 While thoroughly describing most of these films, Lista minimizes their specific potential.6 Nevertheless, he makes a point of qualifying his position: “Loïe Fuller’s experimental project had moved completely beyond the boundaries of cinema, in spite of the deep and secret similarities between the two approaches.”7 If the medium of the cinematograph could not quite match the innovative potential of the serpentine, it still involved underlying relations with Fuller’s aesthetic, implicit but truly significant – or so the argument goes. This idea, largely accepted within Fullerian historiography, is founded on a common displacement according to which “similarities” between cinema and Loïe Fuller’s spectacles should be grasped in the artistic potential of either form of expression rather than in their shared real conditions of 1900 – a teleological, or at the very least essentialist, deviation. It has therefore been possible to identify experimentations exploring abstract forms in movement, more or less modeled on the perspectives opened up by Fuller’s spectacles of light, from the mid-1910s on and in the following decade, mainly in avant-garde circles (Ginna’s and Corra’s Futurist cinema, and later German filmmakers such as Walter Ruttmann and Hans Richter working in abstract animation). Fuller has also been claimed as a source of inspiration by various French avant-garde filmmakers, later collectively labeled “Impressionists”: Louis Delluc, Marcel L’Herbier and more particularly Germaine Dulac.8 4 Lista, Loïe Fuller. Danseuse de la Belle Epoque 370. 5 Lista, Loïe Fuller. Danseuse de l’Art Nouveau 74. 6 Though he appreciates the “closer vision” (“vision rapprochée”) provided by some of these f ilms, Lista regrets their general “lack of cinematic style” (“aucun effet d’écriture cinématographique”). Lista, Loïe Fuller. Danseuse de l’Art Nouveau 365, 357 respectively. 7 Lista, Loïe Fuller. Danseuse de l’Art Nouveau 375. 8 See my book L’Age du rythme. Cinéma, musicalité et culture du corps dans les théories françaises, 1910-1930 (Lausanne: Payot, 2007), chapter 7.6 (“Vers un art de la ‘fulgurance électrique’: le cas Loïe Fuller”).

252 

L aurent Guido

Among the studies pointing out this lineage, the work of Tom Gunning stands out with its attempt to bring out the more immediately contextual relations between the Fuller phenomenon and the emergence of cinema. According to Gunning, both seem to be part of a general questioning of some scales of values, not only between the dimensions of art and science, but also between a high-brow culture and popular culture.9 Still, Gunning himself devotes just a few lines to the films concretely showing the serpentine dance in action. Despite the constantly repeated claim of an underlying connection between Fuller and cinema, early films of serpentine dances have mostly been considered incidentally and in isolation. They have not yet been approached as belonging in the specific dispositives they involve, whether from the standpoint of their form or the multiple conceptual frameworks in which they may be situated. This is the gap I would like to help to fill through a shift in the object of my research, from the individual figure of Loïe Fuller to the many cinematographic appropriations of her serpentine dance. The fact that the films in question feature imitators, that is, artists whose activity largely operates in a secondary relation of appropriation, makes a greater distance all the more necessary toward the highly legitimized framework surrounding the serpentine dance. This greater distance allows a better understanding of a whole array of phenomena based on re-use, imitation, copying and variation. These connected principles all seem to characterize the mass culture emerging and rapidly becoming institutional at the turn of the twentieth century. As we shall see, the motif of the serpentine dance circulated not only in the main film studios (Edison, Biograph, Lumière, Pathé, Gaumont and Méliès), but also and simultaneously in the so-called “popular” forms of spectacle available in music halls, theaters or circuses. Cinema initially grew in a context of fairground attractions or variety shows, as an 1896 news item from the spectacles page of daily newspaper Le Gaulois indicates. A new conjuring number titled “The Flying Woman” is announced at the Alcazar theater, an attraction which, in the eyes of the reporter, “goes beyond the surprises of the famous serpentine dance and the cinematograph in terms of novelty and originality.” The two media appear side by side, but they are also explicitly placed on the same level, like two equal occurrences within the same paradigm, that of attractions. In the very early period of the emergence of this paradigm, generally referred to as novelty by historians, cinema 9 Tom Gunning, “Loïe Fuller and the Art of Motion,” La decima musa il cinema e le altri arti/ The Tenth Muse cinema and other arts, Leonardo Quaresima and Laura Vichi, eds. (Udine: Forum, 2000) 25-53.

Between Paradoxical Spectacles and Technical Dispositives

253

and the serpentine dance may indeed have been apprehended jointly, as two forms of spectacle doomed to be replaced with even more impressive propositions (such as “The Flying Woman”), at least in the opinion of some. One of the aims of this study is to demonstrate that experimentation with specific technical processes in early cinema paradoxically rested on this kind of intermediality, that is, a constant relation to forms of expression situated outside the area of the cinematograph proper. This is not simply to point out the existence of different systems for the mechanical recording of movement that preceded and accompanied the emergence of the cinematograph (the films produced for some devices projecting chronophotographic views, for the phonoscope, for the Edison kinetoscope, for the Bioskop of the Skladanowsky brothers, etc.). Most importantly, I would like to show how spectacles of moving images were then fully part of a genuine “theatrical culture,” in Charles Musser’s words,10 that is, a common culture of spectacle concerning film as well as performing arts like theater and dance. As a consequence, focusing on films of serpentine dances means not only examining per se the few extant prints and assessing them in relation to production documents, but also comparing films with discourses of their time. In the absence of a specialized film press, these may be teased out in scientific publications or print sources related to music hall or theater circles. This study accordingly falls within the scope of the research program proposed by François Albera and Maria Tortajada in the chapter opening this volume. Indeed, the films devoted to the serpentine dance are considered from the standpoint of dispositives they elicit in cinema, taking into account not only a series of technical processes, but also “the construction of the network of discourses, practices, institutions relating them to representation.”11 The constant attention given to dances in early cinema, far from being explained away through the emphasis on a single conceptual framework, refers to complex set of relations that need to be apprehended at the crossroads of several dispositives. These certainly relate to aesthetics, yet they are also rooted in the domains of science, technique, social utilitarianism and – first and foremost – the spectacular.

10 Charles Musser, “Towards A History of Theatrical Culture: Imagining An Integrated History of Stage and Screen,” Screen Culture: History and Textuality, ed. John Fullerton (London: John Libbey, 2004) 3-19. 11 See François Albera and Maria Tortajada, “The Dispositive Does Not Exist!”

254 

L aurent Guido

The corpus of serpentine dance films shot between 1894 and 1908 may be divided into two distinct, successive groups.12 I will deal only with the more important one here, around a dozen of moving views where the solitary physical performance represents the only recognizable visual element.13 As for the second group, which is more limited and much less known in spite of its immediate attractiveness, it mostly involves films divided in several tableaux where dance is one of several parameters (diegetic spectators, more complex sets, the resort to tricks…) that depend on narrative or spectacular motivations. These few films, some directed by Georges Méliès or Segundo de Chomon,14 which I have discussed in another study,15 most often depict situations of metamorphoses and doubles with a self-reflexive dimension. Though they resort to a number of “tricks” characteristic of the genre, such as stopping the camera to make a character appear or disappear, these films also refer to numbers previously presented on stage. Méliès’s 1899 The Pillar of Fire (Star Film, nº188) thus features a serpentine dance, echoing a show by Loïe Fuller herself, music hall spectacles offered by some of her first-rate imitators, and aspects of a magic number once presented at the Théâtre Robert-Houdin. According to the regime of spontaneous intermediality theorized by André Gaudreault and Philippe Marion,16 which defines early cinema prior to the institutional turn around 1908, this idea of adaptation for the screen of a similar stage number was best expressed in the first few films devoted to the recording of serpentine dances. The primary dispositive of the stage never completely vanishes even as it is reconfigured in the secondary form of the screen. This idea did lead to the recording of Annabelle Whitford Moore’s particularly cheerful and youthful performances at Edison’s Black Maria studio in August 1894 (Annabelle Butterfly Dance, Annabelle Serpentine

12 Giovanni Lista makes a distinction between “two kinds of images” (“deux genres d’images”): “muscular prowesses of female dancers” (“exploits musculaires de danseuses”) and “phantasmagorias” (“fantasmagories”). Lista, Loïe Fuller. Danseuse de la Belle Epoque 357. 13 See the precious filmography provided by Giovanni Lista in Loïe Fuller. Danseuse de la Belle Epoque 616-36. It comprises more than 80 entries from before 1910. 14 Notably the outstanding Création de la serpentine (Chomon, 1908), which is closer, in Lista’s opinion, to Fuller’s art thanks to its use of concealing, multiplication or abstraction effects. Lista, Loïe Fuller. Danseuse de la Belle Epoque 367-369). 15 See the proceedings of the conference Méliès: carrefour des attractions (Cerisy, France, July 25 - August 1, 2011), forthcoming. 16 André Gaudreault and Philippe Marion, “Un média naît toujours deux fois,” Sociétés & représentations, vol. 9 (Paris: CREDHESS, 2000) 21-36.

Between Paradoxical Spectacles and Technical Dispositives

255

Dance, Annabelle Sun Dance).17 (Fig.1) The modes of representation characterizing these films are quite elementary, but show great concern for legibility and closure: a long shot makes it possible to show the whole body within the frame; a single take records the choreography in its continuity; 17 These films bear the numbers 48 to 50 in the reference filmography, Charles Musser, Edison Motion Pictures, 1890-1900 An Annotated Filmography (Pordenone: Le Giornate Del Cinema Muto/ Smithsonian Institution Press, 1997) 111-12. New versions of the three dances were shot with Annabelle in February 1895, and again in the summer of the same year. On these, see Musser, Edison Motion Pictures 173, 188-89.

256 

L aurent Guido

a set reduced to a few lateral markers focuses the whole attention on the performance of the body; finally, the profilmic subject is placed in a direct and frontal position with respect to the camera. Even if these unipunctual films, most of them lasting under a minute, are rather similar in their composition, it is possible to observe variations in angle, layout, set, tints, and so forth, between films. Indeed, the absence of editing (in the sense of joining several shots) does not necessarily entail stylistic and figurative deficiency. The argument that dance films of early cinema are but passive recordings of a profilmic reality entirely predefined, dear to some theoreticians who came after the advent of editing,18 does not withstand an internal analysis of the films. While it may seem evident in the case of recordings of serpentine dances or other music hall numbers – typical early subjects for Edison’s kinetoscope, as we will see later – the assessment also holds for the first views recorded “from life” by Lumière cameramen (Bal espagnol dans la rue by Gabriel Veyre, Mexico City, August 6, 1896; Los Aïnos à Ueso by Constant Girel in October 1897; Cynghalais: danse des couteaux by Alexandre Promio, Paris, September 1897…). An astounding dance of contortions by Ashantis filmed in 1897 on the occasion of an ethnographic exhibition in Lyons thus belongs in the same spectacular logic, organized according to a Western eye, as the Sioux dances of the Edison catalog featuring elements from Buffalo Bill’s touring show.19 In Danse du sabre (Lumière, nº 441), two Africans fight in front of their fellow men gathered around them in a scene staged in depth. The audience commands one of the dancers to turn his face towards the camera and alternately brandish his weapon in the same way, that is, towards these Western spectators for whom the show has been designed and staged. Similarly, the Danse tyrolienne (Lumière, nº 31, September 1896) shot by Constant Girel in Germany20 does relate to a model that was to remain untouched for the countless dance films21 produced by major film companies until their institutionalization around 1908: a unipunctual view in long shot partly reusing the frontal proscenium 18 Lev Kuleshov, for instance, was to devalue the single take for choreographic gestures in his experiment on “created dance,” privileging instead a “dance of images” closer to the specific demands of the medium of film, in his opinion. See Lev Kuleshov, “The Banner of Cinema” [1920], in Lev Kuleshov. Fifty Years in Films. Selected Works (Moscow: Raduga, 1987). 19 Musser, Edison Motion Pictures 125-29. 20 Denise Böhm-Girel, “Constant Girel, Lumière-Operateur in Deutschland (1896),” KINtop, vol. 5 (1996): 170-76. 21 See Laure Gaudenzi, “Une filmographie thématique: la danse au cinéma de 1894 à 1906,” in Les vingt premières années du cinéma français, Jean A. Gili, Michèle Lagny, Michel Marie, Vincent Pinel, eds. (Paris: AFRHC/Sorbonne Nouvelle, 1996) 361-64.

Between Paradoxical Spectacles and Technical Dispositives

257

of the scenic dispositive and aiming to address the audience directly. This mode of recording the body in movement is not specific to these films: more fundamentally, it is part of a direct lineage in ways of filming systematized earlier by chronophotographers. The connection to chronophotography appears in a series of images made by Georges Demenÿ in 1893 and devoted to a ballerina from the Paris Opera doing an entrechat22 and presenting exactly the same visual characteristics. A closer look at the determinations shaping these films brings a gradual awareness of the particular articulation between different factors playing out in those same years. Beyond their scientific aspect (the physiological research carried out by Demenÿ at the Station physiologique in Paris with Etienne-Jules Marey23), these images refer to aesthetic factors. One of the pioneers of the rational study of gesture, Georges Demenÿ was not solely motivated by utilitarian and social perspectives. His artistic convictions also ran deep: he was of the opinion that “both the minds of the artist and the physiologist, starting from different points, should meet before nature” and praised “rhythm” and “harmony” as ways to identify the “perfect effort” as well as conditions for the “beauty of movement.” His discourse matches that of various hygienist and body culture movements at the turn of the twentieth century (hébertisme in France, Lebensreform in Germany). Concerned with uncluttered representations (“the line and the plane should prevail over teeming details”), Demenÿ pleaded for a regeneration of bodies through a conformity to the physical canons of ancient statuary, the key of a new “simplicity of gesture.”24 His theoretical writings on gymnastics and body movements were thus explicitly part of an emerging Neo-Antique rhythmic movement that was to mark a deep reform of bodily expression some ten years later, favoring the appearance of modern dance and various systems of musical-gestural expression (with Isadora Duncan, Ruth Saint Denis, Emile Jaques-Dalcroze, Rudolf Laban and, more

22 See Laurent Mannoni, Marc de Ferrière and Paul Demenÿ, Georges Demenÿ, Pionnier du cinéma (Douai: Cinémathèque française/Pagine/Université de Lille 3, 1997) 74. 23 On the utilitarian mission assigned to the Station through subsidies it received from the State (the study of walking, running or jumping to improve the performances of soldiers or workers), see Laurent Mannoni, Etienne-Jules Marey: la mémoire de l’œil (Paris/Milano: Cinémathèque française/Mazzotta, 1999) 191. 24 Georges Demenÿ, L’éducation de l’effort. Psychologie - physiologie (Paris: F. Alcan, 1914) 129-32. The scientist also states that “Humankind regains control of itself and comes back to itself as it admires ancient masterpieces.” See Georges Demenÿ, Les bases scientifiques de l’éducation physique (Paris: Librairie Félix Alcan, 1920) 160.

258 

L aurent Guido

generally, the movement labeled New Kinaesthetic25 by American cultural historian Hillel Schwartz. The reference to Antiquity is as straightforward as possible in the images of the ballerina made by Demenÿ in 1893, since these photographs are part of a series shot at the Station physiologique for a specialist of ancient dance, Maurice Emmanuel, and were reproduced in the form of photographic plates as well as analytical drawings in the 1896 published version of his dissertation.26 Through chronophotography, Emmanuel sought to check the validity of the dance steps he had inferred from the analysis of ancient bas-reliefs or figurative monuments. In his evocation of the symbiotic relation between art and industrial accomplishment produced by Loïe Fuller’s spectacles, Stéphane Mallarmé himself had associated the serpentine dance to a paradoxical Antiquity. In the first version of his commentary, published in the English newspaper The National Observer in 1893 but not reprinted in its entirety in Divagations, he made a rather original observation: “That this prodigy springs from America does not surprise, and it is Greek. Classical insofar as modern, quite.”27 As it turns out, for the poet, the figure of Fuller then does not only express the interpenetration of art and science on the eve of the twentieth century, but also the sudden appearance of archaic structures in the very heart of modernity, an aspect also perceptible within the work of chronophotographers. This articulation between innovation and archaism has nothing original to it; on the contrary. It appears as one of the emblematic aspects shared by the various conceptions of the body around 1900 and refers to the general position of an era in which the most groundbreaking dimensions of the modernization and increasingly technical nature of social life are ceaselessly perceived as opportunities to make traditional issues resurface. This is not only a reassuring attempt to cover over the newest characteristics of new media with familiar concepts – as if to absorb the traumatic shock of industrialization and urbanization – but also a mythology imparting form to the very field of technical research and inventions. Beyond their scientific, aesthetic and cultural determinations, a spectacular dimension more openly linked to commercial pursuits also appears in this research and these inventions. In 1893, the visit of Opera ballerinas 25 Hillel Schwartz, “Torque: The New Kinaesthetic of the Twentieth Century,” Incorporations (New York: Zone, 1992) 71-127. 26 Maurice Emmanuel, The Antique Greek Dance, After Sculptured and Painted Figures (Charleston, SC: Forgotten Books, 2012). 27 Stéphane Mallarmé, “Considérations sur l’art du ballet et la Loïe Fuller,” The National Observer 13 May 1896, in Mallarmé, Œuvres complètes 314.

Between Paradoxical Spectacles and Technical Dispositives

259

at the Station physiologique, considered by Marey himself with aloofness,28 took place in the context of a decisive step for Georges Demenÿ. With the foundation of the Société du phonoscope and a commercial and spectacular ambition he acknowledged openly, Demenÿ was moving towards a split from physiology strictly speaking. One manifestation of this approach was the choice of scenes involving music hall artists, recorded in 1894 in his own laboratory with a more palpable intention to entice.29 Besides the creation of eye-catching views featuring French cancan dancers, Demenÿ also tapped into the exhibitionist potential of the moving image of the ballerina. (Fig. 2) When he reused the “scientific” images of the entrechat from the series made by Maurice Emmanuel and placed them on a phonoscopic disc, his motivations indirectly echoed Eadweard Muybridge’s when reusing an old photograph, Pirouette, to attach it to a slide30 or using it to make a plate for 28 The scheduled presence of dancers at the Station only elicited the comment by Marey that they may bring “some gaiety” to the place. Letter dated Dec. 6, 1892, in Lettres d’Etienne-Jules Marey à Georges Demenÿ 1880-1894, Thierry Lefebvre, Jacques Malthête, Laurent Mannoni, eds. (Paris: AFRHC, 1999) 422. A session took place in July the following year. Letter dated July 14, 1893, in Lettres d’Etienne-Jules Marey à Georges Demenÿ 442. 29 Mannoni, de Ferrière and Demenÿ, Georges Demenÿ, Pionnier du cinéma 72-76. 30 Paul Hill, Eadweard Muybridge (London: Phaidon, 2001) 118-19.

260 

L aurent Guido

his Zoopraxiscope (nº34: Grecian Dancing Girls) in the form of a drawing. (Fig. 3) Similar images, moved from one context to another, assumed other significations, other statuses and other values. This key principle of the period is also present in the work of another, German chronophotographer, Ottomar Anschütz, whose Schnellseher (or Elektrotachyskop), was massproduced in an automatic version over the years 1892-1895 and circulated in scientific conferences as well as novelty shows or World Fairs (Chicago in 1893, for instance). For these demonstrations, Anschütz drew about sixty images from his available stock of chronophotographic studies: soldiers, animals (horses, dogs, camels, elephants…), athletes, acrobats and, of course, dancers swirling their skirts.31 An advertisement for the presentation of the Schnellseher at the Crystal Palace in London in April 1893 emphasizes the scope of an entertainment form then listed under “Permanent Attractions”: “The Electrical Wonder combining the latest development in instantaneous photography with electrical automatic action. Skirt dancing, Gymnastics, Boxing, Steeple-Chasing, Flat-Racing, Haute-Ecole Stepping Horses, Military Riding, Leaping Dogs, Camels, Elephants in motion, Indians on the war path, etc.” While the word “attraction” refers to the program as a whole here, that is, to the technical process itself, the position at the top of the list of dancers showing their legs as well as sporting feats indicates the predominance of physical performances already organized in numbers. The characteristics of these chronophotographic images, which show the continuity affecting the series of moving images at the turn of the twentieth century, may also be noted in the first films shot by William Laurie Dickson with the stars of music halls, fairgrounds and variety shows for the Edison kinetoscope. The serpentine dance of Annabelle Whitford appears next to German body-builder Eugen Sandow and dancer Carmencita, as well as boxing champions.32 The kinetoscope, which enjoyed significant coverage and publicity in the media from the very moment it was launched in the United States, was presented in London in October 1894, in Paris the follow-

31 Announcement by Anschütz published in Photographische Nachrichten 49 (1890): 758. See also the proceedings of the Berlin Photography Society meeting on 18 Jan. 1890, in Photographische Nachrichten (1889): 67-69, quoted by Friedrich Von Zglinicki, Der Weg des Films (Hildesheim/ New York: Olms Presse, 1979) 188; and Deac Rossell, Ottomar Anschütz and his Electrical Wonder (London: The Projection Box, 1997). 32 Charles Musser’s reference book on the subject, Edison Motion Pictures, lists over fifty films featuring various dances.

Between Paradoxical Spectacles and Technical Dispositives

261

ing month, then in Berlin in March 1895.33 A French publicity leaflet from the company The World’s Phonograph Co., based in Amsterdam, points out “the great variety of scenes” immortalized by the kinetoscope and the fact that “the most famous artists and actors in the world are continuously photographed to that end: dancers, fighters, boxers, etc.” Before the advent of more imposing and more legitimate productions from the theater and the opera, the number of short forms issuing from the music hall surged among the films made at the Black Maria and later marked the first projections in the United States. The inaugural show of the Vitascope at the Koster and Bials music hall in New York City, given by Thomas Armat on April 23, 1896, thus included – besides vaudeville and burlesque boxing routines – a Skirt Dance and an Umbrella Dance, as well as a Butterfly Dance.34 The attention of the press focused on these choreographic numbers. The New York Daily News reported that the show started with a “lively air” played by the orchestra before “there flashed upon the screen the life-size figures of two 33 In Berlin it was frequently compared with the chronophotographic work of Anschütz. See Von Zglinicki, Der Weg des Films 206-7. 34 Musser, The Emergence of Cinema: The American Screen To 1907 (1990; Berkeley, Los Angeles: The University of California Press, 1994) 122-24.

262 

L aurent Guido

dancing girls who tripped and pirouetted and whirled an umbrella before them.”35 This striking image was in fact the one that Raff & Gammon, the company running the Vitascope, had chosen for its letterhead. The drawing represents a packed orchestra with spectators riveted by a stage where the projected moving image of a ballerina is shown, its size comparable to the host of the show standing by the screen. All public exhibitions of chronophotographic films and later of short films evidently involved a spectacular aspect, whether they showed mechanisms invisible to the naked eye through the presentation of a gesture broken down in phases or produced the illusion of movement through the animation of the same views by optical machines. This spectacular aspect depended on both the fascination aroused by a technological novelty capable of bringing a new type of images to the public and the sporting, choreographic or acrobatic performance recorded by the camera, staged and framed through a dispositive based on a frontal proscenium. The “attractional” value of the subject was added to that of the process of animation itself, which literally had “images dance.”36 In his reflection on the modes of filmic attraction in early cinema, Frank Kessler expressed this idea very precisely.37 To account for the way in which this kind of ambivalence runs through the films of serpentine dances, and more specifically Edison films, it should be pointed out that like most views devoted to the motif, they involve a privileged relation between the attraction of the technical dispositive itself and the attraction constituted by the unfolding performance, framed by the camera. Two aspects, color and circularity, attest more keenly to this. Indeed, Annabelle’s performances for Edison have come down to us in hand-colored versions, like many serpentine dance films, which are some of the first films in color in history. The fact that this particular motif 35 “Amusements,” New York Daily News, 24 April 1896. Quoted by Charles Musser, Before the Nickelodeon: Edwin S. Porter and the Edison Manufacturing Company (Berkeley, Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1991) 62. 36 The expression was to enjoy much currency in discourses on moving images. Edison already used it to emphasize the playful dimension of the kinetoscope: “a silly little device for making pictures that would dance.” Quoted by Joseph H. North, The Early Development of Motion Pictures 1887-1909, diss., Cornell University, 1949 (New York: Arno Press, 1973) 13. Within the film avantgardes of the 1920s, dance took the value of ideal metaphor for montage. See chapter 7 (“Du corps rythmé au modèle chorégraphique”) in my book L’Age du rythme. 37 Frank Kessler formulated the division, between “cinematography as a spectacular dispositive, within which the ability of the machine to capture and reproduce movement predominates; and cinematography as a dispositive of spectacle, where the filmed spectacle itself constitutes the main attraction.” See Kessler, “La cinématographie comme dispositif (du) spectaculaire,” Cinémas 14 (Fall 2003): 21.

Between Paradoxical Spectacles and Technical Dispositives

263

was immediately included in the genres selected for coloring – and as a consequence, sold at a higher price – reveals the premium then put on it. What is more, this technique undeniably used the medium’s own potential, since tints were applied with a brush on each of the several hundred frames that made up the films – as many still images which produced the illusion of movement once projected at a high speed. Still, the addition of color should not be reduced to a quest for specificity, that is, to a will to play with the illusionistic, almost magical properties of the cinematographic dispositive. Far removed from such concerns, this technical innovation also aimed to render an essential feature of the serpentine dances as they were really performed on stage at the time: the projection of colored lights on the fabrics brought to life by the arms of the dancers and their swirling dresses. Color similarly played a part in a number of variations then referred to as “kaleidoscopic dance,” “magic coat” or “magical clothing.”38 These dances, which combined corporeal movements and projections of colored lights, relied on equipment akin to that of magicians. A 1901 advertisement for the De Vere store (one of the most important specialized businesses in Europe), addressed at spectacles founded on tricks and pyrotechnical conjuring, praised certain equipment for physics and technique. The ad publicized, for instance, “oxyhydrogen and electrical devices for projections, serpentine dances and fire dances” for which “gelatins of all colors” as well as “painted glass for kaleidoscopic dances” were also proposed.39 Among the prestigious patrons that De Vere boasted of supplying were Loïe Fuller and Valentine Petit, both given the same importance in the ad. Petit’s kaleidoscopic dance number then toured throughout Europe. A few years before, she had performed in Berlin’s main music hall, the Wintergarten, as part of a groundbreaking program, since on that same evening the Skladanowsky brothers’ Bioskop had been introduced (one of the first public projections of moving photographic images, on November 1, 1895, in a show otherwise exclusively composed of variety numbers, including… a serpentine dance). The collusion between para-cinematographic spectacles and kaleidoscopic dances owes little to chance, since both forms of expression often cohabited in the world of fairgrounds. A famous poster for a fair, the Théâtre Salon des Visions d’Art (1899), thus featured a mechanical system for the reproduction of moving images, “Professor Potel’s Gioscope (moving photography)” next to a kaleidoscopic dancer (“Miss 38 See Jacques Deslandes and Jacques Richard, Histoire comparée du cinéma, vol. 2 (Tournai: Casterman, 1968) 90. 39 L’Industriel forain 596 (January 6-12, 1901).

264 

L aurent Guido

Darling Chromo in Her Marvelous Multicolor Transformations / Innovation in the Application of Projections with Electricity and Light”). 40 (Fig. 4) In 1904, another fairground poster similarly praised the qualities of a Palais de l’Art Nouveau dedicated to new electric shows, once again juxtaposing “cinematographic scenes” with the “light projections of the magic coat and of the serpentine dance,” pointing out that they “show us the harmonies of color along with its splendors.” Pointing once again to the indissoluble relation between the attraction of the performance reproduced on the screen and that arising from the medium itself, the bond between dance and color marked many films in early cinema. 41 However, the application of multicolor tints on serpentine dance films does not only stem from an intention to transpose effects already produced on stage. In those same years, it may also have referred to other technical dispositives based on the animation of still images. Danse serpentine de Loie Fuller, published around 1894, thus appears among the subjects intended for the folioscope, also known as the kinéographe or flip book, whose movement consists in quickly flipping the pages of a booklet in which a series of images have been assembled. This happened to be a booklet whose 90 numbered photographs were colored in nine different 40 L’Industriel forain 596 (January 6-12, 1901): 144-45. 41 This is, for instance, the case in spectaculars or with The Great Train Robbery (Edison, 1903), where the movements of the dancers’ skirts assumed the value of an attraction comparable to that of explosions, which were also colored. See Tom Gunning, “Colorful Metaphors: the Attraction of Color in Early Silent Cinema,” in Il colore nel cinema, Monica Dall’Asta and Guglielmo Pescatore, eds. (Bologna: Libraria Universitaria, 1995) 249-55.

Between Paradoxical Spectacles and Technical Dispositives

265

tints. Some businesses, which then commercialized this type of process at the same time as they were involved in the commerce of film views, were able to use their subjects for one or the other medium (flip book on the one hand, film for projection on the other). This was precisely the case for the Skladanowsky brothers with their Serpentintanz (the recording of a Miss Ancion), shown during Bioskop programs. 42 Since no color print of the film is available today, the only source indicating that this serpentine dance was indeed colored is a memory of Max Skladanowsky: “The effect of speed of the dance was further accentuated by the light reflections of painted colors.”43 This reference to the flip book leads us to take into consideration one of the traditions extended by cinema, which coexisted with it, that of optical toys founded on the illusion of movement. The motif of dance was always central to these. When magician Ludwig Döbler inserted the image of a “parading dancer” in his projections of moving drawings at the Vienna Josephstadt Theatre in 1847, 44 he was only continuing a rather widespread practice. The use of choreographic figures was quite frequent in the lists of subjects for a number of optical toys and systems for the reproduction of movement out of still images such as the zoetrope45 and, most of all, the phenaskistiscope and its variations (the Phantascope used by Döbler or the English Fantascope, which offered a couple of waltzers in the 1830s). 46 On his first disc for the phenakistiscope (1832), one of the main designers of this device, Joseph Plateau, had in fact placed a dancer pirouetting, an example the researcher had chosen to explain in detail in his scientific correspondence.47 For those projecting moving photographs, the motifs used (a couple waltzing and the pirouette of a Japanese acrobat for American 42 This film was shot a little later than other subjects for the Bioskop, which for the most part were recorded in the summer of 1895 with natural light and in front of a white backdrop. See Von Zglinicki, Der Weg des Films 242; and Joachim Castan, Max Skladanowsky oder der Beginn einer deustchen Filmgeschichte (Stuttgart: Füsslin Verlag, 1995) 43-45, 57. With the original lost, the film was reconstructed by computer in 1994-1995 from a contact sheet representing phases of the action. The image is featured in C. W. Ceram, Archaeology of the Cinema (San Diego: Harcourt, Brace & World, 1965) and in von Zglinicki’s Der Weg des Films, among other titles. 43 Quoted in Castan, Max Skladanowsky oder der Beginn einer deustchen Filmgeschichte 218. Translator’s note: this is a translation from the author’s own French translation of the German source. 44 Deac Rossell, “The Public Exhibition of Moving Pictures before 1896,” KINtop 14/15 (2006): 159-95, 168, 178-79. 45 An undated advertisement for The Zoetrope Wheel of Life presented a gymnast and an acrobat among available subjects. See Deslandes, Histoire comparée du cinéma (vol. 1) 39. 46 Deslandes, Histoire comparée du cinéma 38. 47 See Laurent Mannoni, The Great Art of Light and Shadow. Archaeology of the Cinema, trans. Richard Crangle (Exeter: University of Exeter Press, 2001).

266 

L aurent Guido

Henry R. Heyl’s Phasmatrope in 1870, 48 children waltzing for Jean Aimé Le Roy’s high-speed slides, made in 187649) remained resolutely within the realm of the typical catalog for phenakistiscope discs. The same repertoire was later exploited by Emile Reynaud, whose first single subjects for the phenakistiscope around 1877 comprised a tightrope walker, a trapeze artist and a juggler,50 and even by Eadweard Muybridge in some of his drawings for the zoopraxiscope (including a couple of waltzers, an image drawn from plate 197 in Animal Locomotion). This permanence of the choreographic element in shows presenting moving images certainly owes something to the aesthetic qualities specific to the graceful stylization of the rhythmic gesture, but it may also be explained through its practical, condensed and universal character. The power of seduction emanating from the dancing body generally rests on the development of a repetitive scansion based on brief, elementary movements. Drawing one of its most spellbinding effects from this iterative dimension, dance has naturally proved to be one of the privileged subjects of spectacular processes founded on the reiteration or looping of a single action for several seconds. Whether aiming for aesthetic contemplation or sheer visual enjoyment, this spectacularity is not the only value assigned to moving images, which from the beginning were also marked by essentially pedagogical or scientific determinations. As already noted, this frequent articulation between the “pleasure of the eyes” and “teaching”51 was more pronounced among chronophotographers working in the wake of Eadweard Muybridge in the last twenty years of the nineteenth century. The reference to optical toys introduces the issue of circularity or, rather, that of looping images, which is one of their main characteristics. In the first shows where moving images were projected, the practice of repeating the film was frequent. The music hall numbers filmed and shown in the screenings of the Skladanowsky brothers are known to have been repeated several times each. Likewise, an 1896 brochure for the Vitacope process (Edison) asserts that the same subject could well be shown “for ten or fifteen 48 Deslandes, Histoire comparée du cinéma 77. 49 Von Zglinicki, Der Weg des Films 213-14. 50 See Gérard Talon, Emile Reynaud (Paris: Avant-Scène du Cinéma, 1972) 491, 497; and Deslandes, Histoire comparée du cinéma 47. 51 I borrow these terms from Henry Du Mont, the author of a project to animate successive photographs featuring the “movements of a dancer, one or several soldiers, a machine, etc., either for the pleasure of the eyes or teaching.” See Bulletin de la Société Française de Photographie (1862) 35-36. Quoted by Deslandes, Histoire comparée du cinéma 79-80. See also Mannoni, The Great Art of Light and Shadow. Archaeology of the Cinema.

Between Paradoxical Spectacles and Technical Dispositives

267

minutes if desired, although four or five minutes is better.”52 This repetition of gesture does refer to the will to “see better” already central to the approach of physiologists concerned with the discovery of the most subtle phases of a movement53 through its chronophotographic decomposition, and often its verification by machines making its synthesis possible. This act of viewing a “looped” action was at the heart of the dispositive of the phonoscope devised by Demenÿ, that is, “an appliance making it possible to see the phases of a closed movement periodically and slow it down as one wishes.”54 Most of the first films of serpentine dance, like optical toys and some dispositives used by chronophotographers, also conf igured the bodily performance so that looping it would appear as fluid as possible. The action thus seemed to unfold continuously thanks to different strategies: absence of pronounced shifts in position (one of the salient aspects of the serpentine dance is precisely the development of a sense of excess dynamism out of the sole extension of the arms, without the lower half of the body deviating from its static position) or of a genuine closure or conclusion (as would happen with an entry and/or an exit from the frame). Other, more technical parameters may have been used to that same end. A Lumière film produced in 1897, Danse serpentine (nº 765) (Fig. 5)55 involves, for instance, a surprising particularity. The film is made up of two prints of the same shot edited together, which is rare within the corpus of single-shot early views – even as these widely used effects of “single-frame editing,” such as intentional jump cuts during shooting or stopping the camera for trick effects.56 The moment of return to the beginning of the action already shown is not directly perceptible, even to the trained eye. Two factors explain this: first, the body of the dancer is close to the starting point, which masks the “cut” taking us back to the beginning of the film; second, other colors were applied to the second print of the shot, which fosters the impression of an ongoing action with new gestures. The more varied series of movements 52 Musser, Before the Nickelodeon 63. 53 Guido, L’Age du rythme 297-98. 54 Demenÿ, Les Bases scientifiques de l’éducation physique 274-75. 55 This appears as n°31 in G. Lista’s filmography (Lista, Loïe Fuller. Danseuse de la Belle Epoque 618-19). It was first an Italian film (the dancer being Teresina Negri). Featured in the Lumière catalogs since the end of 1897, it was finally integrated in 1905 as Lumière n° 765. 56 André Gaudreault, for instance, proposes that this characteristic, one of a kind in its corpus, was most likely considered “to add duration to the gyrating, and literally attractional movement of the dancer.” See Gaudreault, “Fragmentation et segmentation dans les “vues animées,” in Arrêt sur image, fragmentation du temps, François Albera, Marta Braun and André Gaudreault, eds. (Lausanne: Payot, 2002) 238.

268 

L aurent Guido

performed in this film comparatively with other variations considered thus far partly justifies this kind of operation. Indeed, this slightly more complex choreographic sequence is evidently more difficult to memorize and, as a consequence, can withstand a repetition directly included in the final print. Joining two prints of the same film end to end to constitute a single catalog title thus plays on an effect of looping, but with a view to lengthening the action, in a way. Here the objective was the reiteration of the same, but also the production of a novelty through the addition of new colors and the possibility of perceiving in a new way images already shown. Taking these determining factors into account makes it possible, therefore, to understand better – as François Albera and Maria Tortajada point out – that the defining aspects generally referred to under the term “cinema” may not be grasped in isolation, but rather that they belong in clusters of more or less abstract “configurations” attached to the cinematographic medium. This study has notably shown that the detailed examination of material objects, technical processes and sources related to serpentine dance films led to fundamental issues, whether these bring up “concepts of movement, time, instant” or “notions of repetition, instantaneousness, decomposition, and synthesis of movement.”57 In early cinema, the motif of the serpentine dance accordingly carries a rich set of ambivalent appropriations, including through technical work on two key parameters, color and circularity. In fact, the serpentine dance always remained tied to other aspects involving technological development: with Edison58 or Oskar Messter,59 the Fullerian motif was integrated at once into mechanical processes of audiovisual synchronism launched by each of these important producers. Still, the films considered in this study should not be assessed in terms of their technical nature alone: as I also indicated, the modalities of the representation of the space where the number recorded by the film camera takes place should always be taken into account. If Lumière’s Danse serpentine strongly resembles those previously produced by Edison or Skladanowsky, it differs from them due to the much more asserted presence of the stage itself. Indeed, the movement of the dancer’s body to the right of the frame leads to the creation of a much 57 See in this volume Albera and Tortajada, “The Dispositive Does Not Exist!” 58 L’Industriel Forain (dated 13 Oct. 1895) points out the “marvelous effects” of the Edison kinetophone, and more specif ically of the “ballet lady dancing the serpentine. None of her graceful movements went unnoticed and the orchestra’s music could be heard very clearly.” 59 An advertisement for Messter’s Kinematographisch-phonographische Vorführungen in Berlin in 1896 opens with a “SerpentinTanz.” Reproduced in Von Zglinicki, Der Weg des Films [Bildband, n. p.].

Between Paradoxical Spectacles and Technical Dispositives

269

more concrete spatiality than the extreme minimalism and the ghostly, almost de-realizing character of the Edison films. In this Lumière view, it is the scenic dispositive that is being explicitly imported in the cinema, in a straightforward affirmation of theatricality. This still timid manifestation of a closure may be found more clearly in other, later films. The serpentine dance of Lina Esbrard (1902), produced by Gaumont and attributed to Alice Guy, thus opens with the lateral entrance of the artists and concludes with an insistence on her exit, as she greets and blows kisses to the audience.60 60 On the subject, see my analysis of the Danse Tyrolienne produced by Lumière in 1896: “ ‘Auf die Bühne gezaubert, dass man erstaunt’: cinéma, danse et music-hall au tournant du 20e siècle,”

270 

L aurent Guido

(Fig. 6) The logic of circularity noted about other titles, whether in the construction of the films or in their public uses, is not present here: the ritual of the number is respected in its adaptation for the screen. This concern is a response to a dominant logic of the time, as films took place in programs resolutely organized on the model of music hall shows, that is, in the form of a sequence of numbers that by and large remained autonomous, even as they were distributed in a larger structure that took into account their respective atmospheres and dynamics. This close relationship with the world of so-called “popular” stages (circus, music hall, mime shows, etc.) brings many research prospects to the study of early cinema, most uncharted at this point. One example could be the more unconventional recordings of parodies of and variations on the serpentine dance performed by comics or even quick-change artists (Little Tich, Fregoli). Among the many oddities directly borrowing from the world of the stage, a Danse serpentine dans la cage aux lions (1900) explicitly refers to a famous number mentioned in contemporary accounts and announcements. (Fig. 7) in Moving Pictures, Moving Bodies: Dance in German and Austrian Film 1895-1933, Michael Cowan and Barbara Hale, eds., Seminar 46.3 (Toronto) Sept. 2010: 220.

Between Paradoxical Spectacles and Technical Dispositives

271

In that respect, the many appropriations of the serpentine dance at the time seem limitless. A close examination of the specialized press reveals the recurrence of variations: the number, it turns out, was performed on a tight rope, on horseback or even by performing dogs (as a Lumière film, nº987, shows). A poster for the summer Alcazar of 1896 even publicizes an astounding crossover, the “serpentine dance of fire dogs.” (Fig.8) This constitutes an implacable demonstration of the “interference of series,” a generating principle for the comical theorized by Henri Bergson61 in the 61 Henri Bergson, Laughter. An Essay on the Meaning of the Comic, trans. Cloudesely Brereton and Fred Rothwell (1899; Rockville, MD: Arc Manor, 2008) 46-52.

272 

L aurent Guido

same years. In fact, the concept seems ideal, not so much to describe the mechanisms at play in the production of laughter (were these films even supposed to elicit laughter in the first place?) as to outline a larger situation of de-hierarchization and of a crisis of ideas. This ambivalent juxtaposition of opposites does indeed comprise the various conceptual pairs we have continually come across in the present study: art and science, highbrow culture and popular culture, archaism and modernity, the visible and the invisible, the material and the immaterial, original and copy, specificity and intermediality, and even human and animal. The serpentine dance, immediately identifiable and effective, thus appears as the symbol of all these interfering series, of these indistinct boundaries characterizing the turn of the twentieth century. The explanation of its success and its durability as a reference motif embracing the complexity of a period probably lies there. More generally, the various cases studied here reveal that the “intermedial” connection between dance and cinema, which started out in the late nineteenth century, cannot be apprehended only through the traditional paradigms of recording, continuity or overtaking, which have for a long time dominated reflections on stage/screen relations. A number of other parameters should also be taken into account. The first are the obvious constraints imposed by the chronophotographic and cinematographic

Between Paradoxical Spectacles and Technical Dispositives

273

dispositives on filmed performances, which from the start had to adapt to specific shooting conditions such as framing boundaries or the fixed duration of filmstrips. The new modes of corporeal expressivity appearing between 1880 and 1930 also deserve consideration. Besides the serpentine, gymnastics, modern dance, Ausdruckstanz, and eurhythmics (to mention but a few) were part of the same epistemological turn as the cinematic medium – a turn towards a vast redefinition of movement, related to a novel techno-scientific context. Lastly, the fascinating ambivalence provoked by supposedly “specific” devices (color, tricks…) used in early films dedicated to dance originated quite paradoxically in the wish to imitate the stage, to find cinematic equivalents of effects which were carried out on stage through typically theatrical means. Thus the idea of making a serpentine dancer appear or disappear during magical numbers might have served as an inspiration for filmmakers using cinematic tricks. Likewise, the will to emulate the color variations of kaleidoscopic shows of the time led others to rely on one of the basic principles of cinema (the animation of still images), in order to add color on each photogram, going as far as artificially extending a performance by aggregating two prints of the same film.62 This peculiar dynamics, a constant back and forth between two media deeply affected by reciprocal and non-hierarchical influences, has been central to the fascinating relations between dance and cinema for more than a century.

62 The same ambivalent process occurs in slapstick (see studies by Henry Jenkins or Robert Knopf on Buster Keaton) as well as in Hollywood musicals. Some technical, supposedly “specific” innovations (in framing, editing or space design) often resulted from the wish to find cinematic equivalents for ambitious effects achieved in Broadway. For instance, far from “avant-garde” concerns, the main goal of choreographer Busby Berkeley was arguably to transpose on screen the geometrical evolutions of Ziegfeld Girls placed on risers or mobile sets.



Forms of Machines, Forms of Movement Benoît Turquety

for Hadrien

Fac-similes In a documentary produced in 1996-1997, American filmmaker Stan Brakhage, who spent much of his life painting and scratching film, stated that One of the major things in film is that you have 24 beats in a second, or 16 beats or whatever speed the projector is running at. It is a medium that has a base beat, that is intrinsically baroque. And aesthetically speaking, it’s just appalling to me to try to watch, for example, as I did, Eisenstein’s Battleship Potemkin on video: it dulls all the rhythm of the editing. Because video looks, in comparison to the sharp, hard clarities of snapping individual frames, and what that produces at the cut, video looks like a pudding, that’s virtually uncuttable, like a jello. It’s all ashake with itself. And furthermore, as a colorist, it doesn’t interest me, because it is whatever color anyone sets their receptor to. It has no fixed color.1

Each optical machine produces a specific mode of perception. Canadian filmmaker Norman McLaren also devoted an essential part of his work to research on the material of film itself, making films with or without camera through all kinds of methods, drawing, painting, scratching film, developing a reflection on what a film frame is and what happens in the interval between two images. Yet today his work is distributed by the National Film Board of Canada only in digital format, and such prestigious institutions as the Centre Pompidou in Paris project it that way – even as the compression of digital files required by their transfer on DVD pretty much abolishes the fundamental cell that is the single frame.

1 Brakhage on Brakhage, dir. Colin Still, 1996-1997, in By Brakhage: An Anthology, DVD set, Criterion, 2003.

276 

Benoît Turquety

Beyond these singular cases, the discontinuation of film as a medium to the benefit of digital media raises a number of issues at the moment. As it happens, these issues – originating in equal parts in audiences, critics and professionals dealing with a transformation of their tools, methods and general professional structures – start from a common premise: “one can barely tell the difference” between film and digital. The stakes of the transition between formats are mostly economic, occasionally practical, sometimes tied to sporadic differences in rendering, but in the end these are just moving photographic images – or so the assumption goes. Still, differences are crucial because the modes of production of these moving images lead to singular modes of perception, at a level rarely explored by analysis. The transition between media should be thought in the context of the “facsimile” as developed by Erwin Panofsky in a 1930 text: […] I wish and I hope that we will learn to improve and will continue to make “better” facsimile reproductions. It is because of these advances, and not despite them, that we will be increasingly adept at distinguishing the original from its facsimile reproduction. Furthermore, it is because of these advances, and not despite them, that we will increasingly regard facsimile reproductions with benefit and, even, enjoyment.2

The film watched in video is a facsimile of the original, a certain amount of “information” or characteristics of which it conveys, while some others disappear or undergo transformation. At any rate, it may not be defined as anything but a facsimile.3 Still, as Panofsky also points out, 4 the nature and the scope of transformations remain to be evaluated for each work according to the degree of dependence of form on the material that embodies it. If we are to grasp what is at stake in this shift to digital, we need to understand and identify with accuracy the specificities of each machine and the viewing conditions it produces, and more generally expand this research to the history of dispositives of moving or of animated images – if these two notions do in fact refer to the same thing. This necessity was already spelled out by Jonathan Crary in his Techniques of the Observer (1990): 2 Erwin Panofsky, “Original und Faksimilereproduktion,” Der Kreis. Zeitschrift für künstlerische Kultur (Spring 1930), available in English as “Original and Facsimile Reproduction,” trans. Timothy Grundy, in Res. Anthropology and Aesthetics 57-58 (Spring-Autumn 2011): 337. 3 On this question and some of its implications for film studies, see the “Statement on the Use of Video in the Classroom” issued by the Society for Cinema Studies Task Force on Film Integrity, chaired by John Belton, Cinema Journal 30.4 (Summer 1991): 3-6. 4 Panofsky, “Original und Faksimilereproduktion”: 337-38.

Forms of Machines, Forms of Movement

277

[…] there is a tendency to conflate all optical devices in the nineteenth century as equally implicated in a vague collective drive to higher and higher standards of verisimilitude. Such an approach often ignores the conceptual and historical singularities of each device.5

Indeed, each machine involves in its very form a certain conception of its task, its ends and the means to achieve them, and in return, these means have consequences on the nature of the result. Each machine is thus potentially rich in theoretical lessons, be it through visual experience or through an epistemological reflection on the historical conditions of its conception. Taking into account the technical level, machines and practices, from the camera to the script, from flatbed editing machines to the architecture of movie theaters, is rather rare in film theory (except in archival literature, for some aspects6) and raises specific methodological problems. The technological analysis of machines should be confronted with their production, with the discourses around them and with their concrete uses, whether dominant or marginal. When it comes to the evolution of technical objects themselves, it should also relate the respective logics of conception, usage and industrialization.

The Form of a Machine: A Surprising Zoetrope The clinical study of a singular case, based on some important technical aspects in the representation of moving images shared by nineteenthcentury optical toys and the first cinematographic machines, will help shed light on a few issues. Charles Francis Jenkins was one of the first important “pioneers” in the technologies of cinema and television. With Thomas Armat, he notably invented a projector, the Phantoscope, which was presented to the public in September 1895. In 1916, he was also the founder of one of the most impor5 Jonathan Crary, Techniques of the Observer: On Vision and Modernity in the Nineteenth Century (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1990). Crary unfortunately does not apply this principle with much precision, contenting himself with a general scheme of the camera obscura without distinguishing its various historical concretizations. Also, when it comes to the nineteenth century, he only particularizes the stereoscope, the kaleidoscope and devices for the analysis and the synthesis of movement, merged into a third category. 6 Among these, I will mention the evolution of mediums (nitrate film, acetate cellulose film), the chemistry of coloring processes or “natural” colors, projection speeds, aspect ratios, etc. See for instance Paolo Cherchi Usai, Silent Cinema: An Introduction (London: BFI, 2000).

278 

Benoît Turquety

tant professional institutions of technicians, in film and later in television, the Society of Motion Picture Engineers.7 The organization immediately published a periodical,8 for which Jenkins himself wrote one of the earliest historical pieces in October 1920, “History of the Motion Picture.” The contribution begins with what was already becoming common practice: going back to the dawn of time to search for a lost origin of cinema and trace it in more or less relevant and even improbable phenomena. According to Jenkins, the “first motion picture mechanism we have any record of”9 was the Zoetrope, whose origin he dated back to Lucretius. He briefly describes the optical toy that “you all doubtless well know,” presenting an illustration without commenting on it.10 However, the interest of the illustration (Fig. 1) is that the machine it features is not at all a “common specimen” of the Zoetrope, to use the language of taxonomists. The Zoetrope is an optical toy invented independently in 1834 by William George Horner (Great Britain) and Simon von Stampfer (Austria), both mathematicians (that fact alone deserves a closer look). For reasons that remain to be identified, it was commercialized only in 1867. The Zoetrope comprises a cylinder with slits cut at regular intervals, which can rotate around its axis; within the cylinder, a sequence of images placed between the slits present a series of patterns describing a given subject in movement. When the cylinder is spun and the viewer looks through the slits, the images in the series appear to move. Yet the Zoetrope presented in Jenkins’s article involves two unusual characteristics. First, its cylinder is oriented vertically, which was extremely rare. In principle, the cylinder in a Zoetrope is horizontal, primarily because the strips of images have to be easy to change and should fit the edges of the cylinder perfectly. In a spinning vertical cylinder, the strips risk falling off or have to be fastened carefully, which complicates the operation with no apparent benefit. Second, one might add that there is a logic 7 Today the organization is called the SMPTE, or Society of Motion Picture and Television Engineers. 8 First titled Transactions of the Society of Motion Picture Engineers, it later became the Journal of the SMPE, then the Journal of the SMPTE. 9 Charles Francis Jenkins, “History of the Motion Picture,” Transactions of the Society of Motion Picture Engineers (Oct. 1920), in A Technological History of Motion Pictures and Television: An Anthology from the Pages of The Journal of the Society of Motion Picture and Television Engineers, ed. Raymond Fielding (Berkeley, Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1967) 1. 10 Jenkins, “History of the Motion Picture,” in Fielding, A Technological History of Motion Pictures and Television 1.

Forms of Machines, Forms of Movement

279

Fig. 1. “The Zoetrope,” in Charles Francis Jenkins, “History of the Motion Picture,” Transactions of the SMPE, (October 1920): 37.

to the horizontal cylinder tied to the fact that most of the movements presented – typically, the gallop of a horse – are horizontal. This is in no way a technical constraint (horizontal movement can be represented on a strip running vertically), but rather a matter of conceptual coherence. The possibility of placing the cylinder vertically appeared in one model only, a late variant developed by Ottomar Anschütz from Germany around 1890 under the name of Tachyscope or Schnellseher (Fig. 2) and featuring a series of phototypes (Anschütz had come to these matters through an initial interest in chronophotography). The cylinder could be placed horizontally or vertically, depending on the band to be viewed. The copy preserved at the Cinémathèque française comes with a box of ten strips, two of which only run vertically.11 This choice has to do with the fact that some subjects required a wider rather than a taller frame: the strip taken vertically thus made it possible to arrange more images. It was also the result of an insight described in Anschütz’s December 1891 German patent: The vertical position of the cylinder results in a peculiar arrangement of images, which proves important in the representation of discontinuous and non-periodical processes, among other examples (a horse jumping over a fence, etc.). In this case, the constant vision of several animated 11 Collection of machines, inv. AP-95-1202 (Schnellseher) and inv. AP-94-0985 (box of strips). See Laurent Mannoni, Le Mouvement continué. Catalogue illustré de la collection des appareils de la Cinémathèque française (Milan: Mazzotta, 1996) 270-71.

280 

Benoît Turquety

Fig. 2. Tachyscope, or Schnellseher, Ottomar Anschütz, after 1890, collection of the Cinémathèque française (vertical layout).

images at different stages of the movement, as happens with common stroboscopic devices, often proves a distraction for the eye. It is much preferable to see the object move across the field of vision at its natural speed, and this can be done in the most simple way by positioning the cylinder vertically. In this way, images representing a single, differentiated action are no longer found side by side, but one on top of the other.12

Mentioning the flaws noted in the use of “usual” devices and describing the solution brought to them are common developments in the rhetoric of 12 Ottomar Anschütz, German patent n° 60285, 19 Dec. 1891. Translator’s note: this an English translation of the author’s own translation from the German to the French.

Forms of Machines, Forms of Movement

281

patents. Anschütz articulates a technical thought on the form to be given to the machine with a series of observations that belong in the psychology of perception. Like the Phenakistiscope, to which I will return, the Zoetrope presents several animated images to the spectator at the same time. This effect is typically considered a fundamental given of the device, especially for the Phenakistiscope, and as an even more admirable aspect of the device in question. In “Morale du joujou,” Baudelaire thus wrote: The speed of rotation transforms the twenty openings into a single circular opening through which you watch twenty dancing figures reflected in the glass – all exactly the same and executing the same movements with a fantastic precision. Each little figure has availed itself of the nineteen others.13

The cylindrical form of the Zoetrope transforms this effect to some degree, since the perspective of the viewer results in singling out a limited number of animated figures, one of which is central, others more lateral, being distorted by the drum. Anschütz was to confirm this evolution and reinforce it, in relation to a more general observation: some types of movements, “discontinuous and non-periodical processes,” have as their central characteristic not to repeat themselves. It is thus disturbing – visually if you will, but the criterion is cognitive – to see them occur several times simultaneously. Placing these parasitic images vertically rather than before and after horizontally thus represents a gain in comfort and solves the problem. Indeed, for Anschütz, the machine does not have as its goal to animate images, but to observe one animated image and one only, which is a rather original conception. Besides, the criterion of non-continuity and non-periodicity, which is the base for the importance of the uniqueness of the image as spectacle, is in the end nothing else than a criterion of narrativity: for the German inventor, when the animated image becomes the source for a narrative (something unique occurs and breaks circularity), it becomes imperative for that image to be the only spectacle and the device has to be modified accordingly. Ultimately, the form of the movement to be depicted commands the form of the machine. The Tachyscope, it should be noted, did not have a crank; and the crank happens to be the other characteristic distinguishing the machine featured 13 Charles Baudelaire, “A Philosophy of Toys,” original French text first published in Le Monde littéraire (17 Apr. 1853), English trans. Jonathan Mayne (1970), in The Painter of Modern Life and Other Essays (London: Phaidon, 1995) 202.

282 

Benoît Turquety

in the illustration of Jenkins’s article from the zootropus vulgaris. Zoetropes with cranks were extremely rare; most of them seem to have been moved directly by hand. When they happened to have cranks, these did not have that shape at all: they were smaller, placed differently, etc. Two questions arise here: – First, why did so few Zoetropes use a crank? And why a certain form of crank rather than another? I will return to this aspect. – Second, why did Jenkins’s article represent the Zoetrope in this odd form, one which I believe may not even have actually existed? In fact, the drawing is entirely teleological; what it represents is not really a Zoetrope but a “pre-camera” or a “pre-projector,” just as some talk of “pre-cinema.” Until the 1920s, a typical film camera or projector featured a crank configured similarly, with the film strip running vertically. This warrants a few observations. First, in history, teleology may sometimes be found in unexpected places. Then, in 1920, the members of the prestigious Society of Motion Picture Engineers already seemed to have forgotten – contrary to what Jenkins wrote – what kind of machine the Zoetrope actually was, or already seemed to see it only as a prefiguration of cinema, seen through its prism, overlooking it as an autonomous machine. Finally, in the very form of the machine drawn for the article, the fusion between Zoetrope and projector articulates a system of analogies common in the historiography of cinema as a whole.

The Disc and the Strip One of them is epitomized by Georges Sadoul in the first volume of his 1946 Histoire générale du cinéma: The Zoetrope is a new form of Plateau’s slit disc […]. The strip of images is its most remarkable aspect, for this long piece of flexible Bristol board pref igures f ilm. The idea of indef initely lengthening it certainly led Reynaud, and perhaps Marey and Edison, to conceiving modern film.14

The crucial historiographic idea here is the emphasis on an evolution: the Zoetrope was preceded by the Phenakistiscope, a device invented 14 Georges Sadoul, Histoire générale du cinéma, vol. 1, L’Invention du cinéma. 1832-1897 (Paris: Denoël, 1946) 21-22.

Forms of Machines, Forms of Movement

283

independently in 1832 by Belgian physicist Joseph Plateau and Simon von Stampfer. This toy – which for Sadoul literally made history, since its invention provided the starting point for his Histoire générale du cinéma – took the form of a disc. The disc was dark on one side; on the outer edge of the other, it featured a series of images representing the different stages of a decomposed movement alternating with a series of slits. With the eye placed on the dark side, looking through the slits at the images reflected in a mirror, the figures could be seen coming to life. The principle is therefore the same – alternation between shutter and images through a system of regular slits allowing to produce the illusion of movement – but the medium changes from a disc to a strip: for Sadoul, this is the decisive point for what was to come, “modern film.” These two toys did involve a few substantial differences, the main being that with the Zoetrope several spectators could see the phenomenon simultaneously, which was not the case with the Phenakistiscope. Yet this traditional history of optical toys, which sees progress running from the form of the disc to the form of the strip, then to film, calls for more complexity. Indeed, the form of the disc did not disappear with the advent of the Zoetrope, as though the latter had made it manifestly “primitive”: it long remained an alternative to the strip, as the list of a few devices relying on the principle of the disc shows: the Electrotachyscope, also invented by Anschütz, in the 1880s and 1890s; the Phonoscope, by Étienne-Jules Marey’s assistant Georges Demenÿ in 1892 (commercialized under the name Bioscope by Gaumont in November 1895); Leonard Ulrich Kamm’s Kammatograph, on the market from 1898 to 1900; or the Spirograph, invented by Theodore Brown in 1907 and exploited by Charles Urban around the early 1920s with a catalog worth several hundred titles… Finally, another, more recent medium should be mentioned: the DVD. Of course, it does not carry images in the same way as the previous examples (i.e., analogically), but its place in the series is still justified by ergonomic and industrial considerations. The disc as a medium is neither too fragile nor too cumbersome, relatively cheap to manufacture, and most of all easy to handle for the user – a decisive criterion for non-professionals, even more relevant in the case of mainstream users. It should also be remembered that for Marcel Duchamp, thinking on (from, around, with) cinema, epitomized in his 1926 masterpiece Anemic Cinema, was part of a larger investigation around machinations of vision, the questioning of a tradition of monocular perspective, as well as discs and wheels of all kinds.

284 

Benoît Turquety

I will not further develop this issue of the disc/strip alternative here. Let us just recall that it also structured the sound industry (including in movie theaters) and the music industry, the industry of computer and digital mediums, and that this alternative also carried economic, industrial, mechanical and aesthetic options. Still, the topos of the shift from disc to strip is one of the key points most strongly structuring the historiography of “pre-cinema,” and will have to be revisited.

With or Without Cranks At any rate, neither the Phenakistiscope nor the Zoetrope involved cranks, for the most part. We should dwell on this question of the crank a little more at this point, as it is more central than it may first seem. Some viewing dispositives contemporary with the two already cited did have these appendices: with the slides for “views set in motion,” which spread from the mid-nineteenth century on, for instance, the crank made it possible to produce colored, abstract rosaces or to animate a specific part of a projected image. A remarkable example of optical machine using a crank was John Arthur Roebuck Rudge’s magic lantern, manufactured around 1882, in which the crank drove the change of view, along with a shutter system, and through a triangular cam – supposedly a specific contribution of the Lumière brothers’ own machine. Interestingly, when Will Day had a copy of this lantern made in 1922 (now held in the collections of the Cinémathèque française), the only license he took with the original was to move the crank from its initial position before the lens to a lateral position, probably more convenient in his view, and once again similar to that on a film projector. Another fascinating machine comes to mind, even as it has been largely neglected by history, the Anorthoscope, the first optical device invented by Joseph Plateau before the Phenakistiscope. Through the combined movement of a black disc with slits rotating in one direction, and behind it, a disc with an anamorphic image rotating in the other direction, the device shows a corrected image when looked at against the light. It is fundamentally a crank-based machine, since the two discs have to be driven together and at correlative speeds. Fascinatingly, in his instructions for using the machine, Plateau did in fact recommend that the person turning the crank and the person observing the phenomenon not be one and the same.15 15 See Joseph Plateau 1801-1883. Leven tussen Kunst en Wetenschap, Vivre entre l’art et la science, Living between Art and Science, ed. Maurice Dorikens (Gent, Provincie Oost-Vlaaanderen, 2001).

Forms of Machines, Forms of Movement

285

Looking at something being difficult work, two things could not be done seriously at once. Besides, Plateau was not just interested in optics, but also in the statics of liquids. In that field, he carried out an experiment that bears his name, founded on a machine that he had built and which was operated by a rotating crankshaft. Depending on the speed imparted by the experimenter/spectator, the form of the oil sphere in suspension in the water solution was transformed…16 The attention given to the crank as such re-establishes “Plateau’s machine” among nineteenth-century viewing dispositives – a place it deserves considering that it was also relatively widespread, notably in schools, until the first quarter of the twentieth century. That the experiment was appreciated certainly had to do with its visual dimension – or should we say to its dimension of attraction? At any rate, the machine is completely absent from the entire historiography of these dispositives, massively written from the standpoint of “pre-cinema.” And indeed, the form of the movement performed in this instance through these spheres in suspension radically differs from the medium to come: no two-dimensional images, no analytical sequence of decomposition/ recomposition, etc. This is what actually makes it interesting today within the perspective of an archaeological reconsideration of these machines outside any teleological linearity. In fact, there had been crank-operated optical machines for a long time already, since some could be found in the first, 1646 edition of the famous Ars Magna Lucis et Umbrae by Father Athanasius Kircher: the “metamorphosis machine,” for instance, in which the crank drove a series of images laid out on a cylinder running vertically (even though with Kircher, one can never be certain that the machines he described actually existed and that their effects conformed to the descriptions given…). So, if almost no Phenakistiscope or Zoetrope had a crank, the crank must have been dispensable on these machines. Interestingly, there were not even “de luxe models” of these toys that would have used a crank, unlike what was to happen for the Praxinoscope a few years later.

A New Form: The Praxinoscope The Praxinoscope (Fig. 3) was invented by Émile Reynaud and patented in 1877, more than forty years after the Phenakistiscope and the Zoetrope, which were invented almost at the same time, and more than ten years 16 Dorikens, Joseph Plateau 100 sqq.

286 

Benoît Turquety

Fig. 3. Crank-operated Praxinoscope, La Nature 296 (February 1, 1879): 133.

after the Zoetrope was commercialized. The Praxinoscope has almost been confused with the Zoetrope by traditional historiography and presented as a relatively minor improvement on it. In truth, it seemed to be based on the same principles: a (horizontal!) cylinder and a series of drawings around it representing a decomposed movement, with the rotation of the cylinder showing spectators the image in movement. Yet the principle of the alternation of images was different: instead of slits, the machine presented a central block comprising a prism of mirrors with as many sides as there were drawings on the strip. The passage from one side to another instantaneously replaced the reflection of an image with that of another one in the same place, making the illusion possible. The idea was quite clever and accordingly constituted an important step. Indeed, it solved an internal antagonism inherent in the Zoetrope and which also concerns the Phenakistiscope. An image continuously moving normally appears blurry and streaked. To appear sharp, it should be perceived as immobile by the eye. In that respect, the principle of rotation with slits causes a problem: the finer the slits, the more briefly the image appears to the eye (almost instantaneously in fact), and the more it is perceived as almost immobile and thus sharp, without streaks – a necessary condition in the reproduction of movement. But the more briefly the image appears to the eye, the less time the eye has to distinguish its outlines precisely and the less luminous the image is. In a way, the better the movement is seen, the worse the image is seen. This fundamental problem for the Zoetrope is repeated at another level: the faster the cylinder rotates, the briefer the perception of each image will be. As a consequence, the rendering of movement and luminosity, animation and the precision of outlines, find

Forms of Machines, Forms of Movement

287

themselves in contradiction. Marey was in fact one of the few to describe this contradiction in his 1894 book Le Mouvement.17 Since the Praxinoscope did not require a shutter, the moving image produced was much more luminous and solved this contradiction to a large degree, even if minor flaws remained: the image was still slightly shorter due to a cylindrical anamorphosis, which Marey disliked, 18 and it underwent a slight lateral oscillation caused by the rotation of mirrors.19 Still, the spectator could see a more luminous and sharper moving image more comfortably, and the speed of that image could be adjusted without consequences for the very visibility of the motif. This made it possible to improve the driving system of the machine so that the spectator could fully enjoy the spectacle – or, if you will, so that the handler could gradually become a spectator… While most Praxinoscopes remained hand-operated machines, some featuring a crank 20 or even an electric engine could nonetheless be found. The advertising posters designed by Reynaud did in fact mention that these engines allowed a two-way rotation (though obviously the strips were meant to be seen in a specific way) as well as speed variation 21 – in the latter case, the operation did not seem so simple. This new luminosity was also to simplify the projection of images with the projecting Praxinoscope imagined by Reynaud as early as 1877 in the original patent, 22 and whose illustration in the journal La Nature23 in 1882 (Fig. 4) proves very interesting: the screen is drawn, showing an image where moving characters and still setting have a different status, a distinctive aspect of the dispositive. The device is also shown, as well as 17 See Étienne-Jules Marey, Le Mouvement (Paris: G. Masson, 1894), notably p. 308: “as the sharpness of movements may be obtained only through the extreme brevity of instants in which each image is disclosed, the quantity of light emitted is accordingly too low to provide clear enlarged projections, even with a powerful source of light.” Marey returns to this problem several times in the final chapter of the book on the “Synthesis of Movements Analyzed by Chronophotography.” 18 Marey, Le Mouvement 303. 19 Indeed, before the passage from a mirror to the next replaces an image with the next one, the rotation of the prism causes a slight rotation effect for each image. 20 This is the case of the copy preserved by the Cinémathèque française under the classification mark AP-95-1720. 21 See Georg Füsslin, Optisches Spielzeug (Stuttgart: Füsslin Verlag, 1993) 92. 22 See the “Dessins annexés à la description d’une invention faite par E. Reynaud, professeur de sciences, au Puy, 30 août 1877,” a document f iled with the patent application, in Jacques Deslandes, Histoire comparée du cinéma, vol. 1, De la cinématique au cinématographe, 1826-1896 (Tournai: Casterman, 1966) 303 sqq. 23 Reproduced in Deslandes, Histoire comparée du cinéma 51.

288 

Benoît Turquety

Fig. 4. Projecting Praxinoscope, La Nature 492 (November 4, 1882): 35.

a simple, fine hand elegantly turning a small crank near the edge of the frame; the bodies of the handler and spectator(s) are not represented in the image. Other variants for the driving mechanism appeared in imitations of these objects, notably those made by Ernst Planck from Germany, sold around 1898 (which suggests that, two years after the success of the Cinématographe, the Praxinoscope could still prove attractive to a counterfeiter). Copies of what was called the Kinematofor remain – some with a crank, others with a steam engine or even a hot-air engine!24 The issue of luminosity was to play a decisive role in the first machines involving a moving photographic image: the dialectic was repeated in exactly the same way between Edison’s Kinetoscope and the Lumière Cinématographe. The principle of the Kinetoscope was in fact similar to that of the Zoetrope: a strip moving continuously in front of which was a shutter with a very narrow slit (each image was seen for about 1/6000 sec.). As with the Zoetrope, the resulting moving image was too dark to allow projection. The Cinématographe solved this tension by adopting the intermittent movement of film for projection as well as for “the production of the negatives,” as the Lumières put it. The image remained still a lot longer 24 See Füsslin, Optisches Spielzeug 94 sqq.

Forms of Machines, Forms of Movement

289

before the lamp (roughly 1/25 sec.), which produced more than enough light for the projection. Interestingly, the Kinetoscope is not a crank-operated machine, which is the case for the Cinématographe.

Cranks, Movement, Spectacle For the time being, however, let us return to Praxinoscopes. A majority of them did not come equipped with cranks, although a greater proportion of them did so than Zoetropes (even in the case of the Praxinoscopes produced by Émile Reynaud, which attests to a conceptual coherence on the part of the inventor). However, taking a closer look at these cranks as they appear and questioning their form (placement, size…) seems necessary. The cranks are placed under the cylinder, where they are the least in the way – the least visible, too (which is not insignificant). Also, with the “classical” Praxinoscope as well as the projecting machine, cranks are small and have a limited rotation diameter. Why do they have that shape? What, in the conception of a machine, may determine the addition of a crank and the choice of a form over another? Cranks can fulfill several possible functions, sometimes simultaneously and, depending on the function, they can assume different forms. They prove necessary when there is a need for driving several elements at the same time, as in the Anorthoscope, or elements that can be heavy, as with Rudge’s lantern. The same holds true when elements out of hand’s reach have to be driven, as is the case again with some lanterns or with animated slides; when a very fast movement has to be produced, as in Newton’s appliances for experiments on colors, which require a very quick rotation for the disc with colored areas to produce its effect and are thus equipped with a crank driving a belt; or when movement is to be controlled. Small cranks do not allow an acceleration of the movement, be it through pulley differential or through a faster action of the arm or wrist. Turning such a small crank so quickly without causing the Praxinoscope to collapse must be very difficult. The point of using a crank is to control movement, rather, or even to slow it down, to make it possible to modulate rhythm, change directions, etc., within certain limits. The concrete form of the crank conditions a type of hand movement, which in turn points to a “good pace” for the movement to be produced, the scene to be represented – a “natural” speed, that of the drawn subject, whose own movement is broken down according to the motif.

290 

Benoît Turquety

The presence of a crank does in fact completely transform the relation to the machine. Without it, the handler/spectator, once the disc or the strip has been set up, will start or restart the machine and possibly stop it.25 Between these punctual interventions, he is busy observing it. However, he cannot physically give a constant speed to the machine: rotation occurs only according to the inertia of the medium and therefore follows a “natural” slope, gradually slowing down… Only the presence of a crank permits real control over the rotation speed, if one that is relative in terms of precision. The counterpart is that the operator/spectator has to turn the crank for the whole show (or later, for the whole period of shooting with a camera). The form of the movement he sees is then no longer that of a slowing down characteristic of the machine, but the form of his own gesture: he can do his utmost to correct it until a perfect regularity is attained, or he can playfully alter it to observe the effects on the moving image or on fellow spectators. Indeed, while the Praxinoscope as a dispositive involves several spectators, one of them still has a particular status: the spectator operating the machine. The role is even more specific when a crank has to be turned… Whether a crank is added to the machine or not thus effects a series of transformations in what is given to see and in the position of the spectator(s). A Zoetrope, a Praxinoscope without a crank are not so much machines presenting spectacles of moving images as they are machines setting images in motion. Starting and restarting the cylinder before slowly returning to immobility means that the cylinder always organizes the very animation of images and makes the machine operate like a comparative toy, between the series of still images to which it always returns and the ephemeral “moving tableau”: transition is the point of the game. As to the machines equipped with a crank, they present a spectacle with a given duration, determined by the handler, where not only the setting in motion, but also the prettiness of the scene, the subtlety of the drawing and the perfection of the execution can be admired. On this point, in fact, the form of machines institutes yet another difference between Zoetrope and Praxinoscope. In the latter, the block of the central prism masks the strip as soon as it is placed in the cylinder: the image can then only be seen reflected in the mirrors. In the Zoetrope, by 25 Very interestingly, Werner Nekes, demonstrating the Praxinoscope in Was geschah wirklich zwischen den Bildern? ([Federal Republic of] Germany, 1986), the first film in his series Media Magica, shows not only the strips coming to life, but also the whole assembly of the toy – opening the box, placing the candle and, after a few other steps have been performed, the moment when moving images finally appear. This whole operation of assembling the machine should be considered as part of the dispositive.

Forms of Machines, Forms of Movement

291

contrast, the strip can still be seen even when the cylinder rotates, until the eye is placed exactly at the level of a slit. The form of the Zoetrope therefore involves a comparative vertical movement (of the eye or the hand) between seeing the streak of the strip and seeing the moving image through a slit. In fact, another detail should be pointed out here, since an important difference between models of Zoetrope bears on this: Zoetropes with a low cylinder emphasize this comparative effect, while those with a higher cylinder tend to mask the strip to privilege a more important “effective” angle of vision. This vertical comparative movement is incompatible with the very form of the Praxinoscope. Anschütz – again – was to take advantage of this vertical movement of the spectator’s eye in an interesting model of his Tachyscope, whose cylinder featured three series of slits at different levels and slightly different intervals. In this way, if the strip represented a galloping horse, for instance, the viewer could see the animal move forward through the top row of slits, run without moving forward through the middle row of slits, and move backward through the bottom row… The model is also one of the very few Zoetropes with a crank and has another exceptional characteristic: it was owned by Étienne-Jules Marey.26 The whole issue of the relation between still and moving image is thus embodied in the choices made in the conception of the machines, the question of the presence of the elementary image in the moving image. This is also why filmmaker and artist Robert Breer, who early on became interested in the status of the film frame27 in his own films, ended up making Mutoscopes28 from the 1950s on, sometimes with the assistance of Jean Tinguely… Essentially, the Mutoscope was an instrument with a crank thanks to which the spectator, fascinated but always physically active, could view the very composition given by the form of the gesture to animated movement. Indeed, while Gaumont initially commercialized its version of the Mutoscope in 1900 (one with a spring-loaded mechanism based on the Kinora patent registered by the Lumière brothers in 1896), the company soon opted for a crank-driven version…29 26 Cinémathèque française, collection of machines, inv. AP-95-1733. See Mannoni, Le Mouvement continué 270. 27 Most notably in 1956-57 with what probably remains his most famous film, Récréation (16 mm, color, 2 mn, commentary by Noel Burch). 28 See Robert Breer: Films, Floats & Panoramas, Brigitte Liabeuf and Nathalie Roux, eds. (Montreuil: Éd. de l’œil, 2006) 48-49. 29 Gaumont produced “Kinoras à main,” hand-held and crank-driven, until 1910 (the George Eastman House in Rochester, N.Y., owns a copy dated the same year by the G. E. House).

292 

Benoît Turquety

Fig. 5. Notice sur le Cinématographe Auguste et Louis Lumière (Lyon: Société anonyme des plaques et papiers photographiques A. Lumière et ses fils, 1897) 19.

Other artists were to produce their own versions of these optical machines, starting from very different principles and sometimes devising rather original driving solutions: the Mini Rotary Psycho Opticon, created in 2008 by Canadian artist Rodney Graham, gets its power from pedaling!30 As to motor-driven systems, they involve yet a different balance: on the one hand, with the possibility of a given duration at constant speed, they are comparable to crank-driven systems; on the other hand, the intervention of the handler remains punctual as the machine gets started and turned off, making their use quite similar to that of machines operated by hand…

The Cinématographe, Art of the Crank The issue of driving mechanisms remained central after 1895 and constituted a common problem for all the optical machines involving movement, from optical toys to the cameras, projectors and flatbeds in a cinema on its way to cultural institutionalization and industrial rationalization. As I have already pointed out, the issue also represents one notable difference between Edison’s machines, with their electrical engines, and the crank-operated Lumière Cinématographe (Fig.5). This should be related to differences in exhibition modes and target audiences: the Kinetoscope presented a spectacle while the Cinématographe was initially designed

30 This bicycle drives a series of abstract discs whose mechanism is reminiscent of Marey’s odograph. It was presented during the exhibition HF/RG [Harun Farocki/Rodney Graham], curated by Chantal Pontbriand, at the Jeu de Paume (Paris), April 7-June 7, 2009. It was unfortunately forbidden to operate the machine on that occasion…

Forms of Machines, Forms of Movement

293

for the amateur photographer, unfazed by the crank and even likely to appreciate the subtleties involved in handling it. Machines manufactured by competitors generally favored the crankdriven mechanism, and much effort went into finding the most suitable place and shape. German inventor Max Skladanowsky set the crank for his Bioskop at the front, under the shutter, which put the operator in the position of looking after the machine rather than at the screen. Louis Lumière positioned the crank of the Cinématographe at the back, slightly to the left of the device. This choice may first appear as rather inconvenient, but the machine has to be considered as a whole: the camera did not have a viewfinder and framing (like focusing) was set before shooting, with the camera open, looking through the printing gate. The film was then positioned, the camera closed back, and the operator stood while “cinematographing,” looking directly at the subject. With this type of crank, the body was at a good distance from the camera: the cameraman was not “glued” to it. As far as I know, only the professional Pathé camera had its crank positioned at the back afterwards. Popular from 1908 on and into the 1920s, it was adopted by Billy Bitzer, D. W. Griffith’s famous cameraman. Englishmen Robert William Paul and Birt Acres placed their own crank on the side, a choice that later became the most common, and to the right, which allowed the body of the cameraman to come much closer to the machine, particularly after viewfinders appeared. In the end, it would hardly be an exaggeration to say that the history of cameras largely consisted in gradually “merging” the machine and the body of the cameraman… whereas the history of projectors and the disappearance of cranks from projecting booths, by contrast, were about allowing projectionists to move away from their machines, or exhibitors to have only one projectionist for several machines. Of course, other options for the placement of the crank were sometimes adopted – under the machinery, for instance, and manipulated by three people in the case of Raoul Grimoin-Samson’s panoramic Cineorama, in which ten cameras were driven simultaneously to cover a total field of 360 degrees. Here as elsewhere, Étienne-Jules Marey appears to have been the exception: he did not like crank-driven mechanisms very much, privileging spring-loaded engines, weight engines or electrical engines, which ensured more precision and made possible a wider range of speeds and prompter starts. His machines sometimes had cranks, but these were meant to wind up the mechanism, not to drive it directly (Fig. 6).

294 

Benoît Turquety

Fig. 6. Dark room on wheels with cameras inside, Étienne-Jules Marey, La Nature 535 (September 1, 1883) 229.

The driving system which was adopted sometimes brought about surprises: it so happened that the mechanism of the Lumière Cinématographe was one of the few to work backwards. This fact every operator, Louis Lumière being perhaps the first, was to discover as an unplanned oddity in the machine allowing for rather amusing games – a demolished wall rebuilding itself as if by magic, for instance.31 The form of his machine thus led Lumière to leave behind the “paradigm of capture-rendering”32 that had apparently been the framework for his thinking until then. The position and proportion of the crank ended up stabilizing. It remained the preferred mode for driving cameras and projectors for the entire so-called “silent” era until the late 1920s. A lot of questions obviously came up as to how it should be handled, emphasizing the tension inherent in 31 Démolition d’un mur is one of the views Louis Lumière credited himself in the catalog he gave Georges Sadoul in 1946. The destruction of a wall in the Lumière factory may be seen in the film, two versions of which are known today, dated early 1896 and numbered 690 and 691 in the catalog published by Michelle Aubert and Jean-Claude Seguin, where several quoted accounts confirm that they were frequently projected forward, then backward. See Michelle Aubert and Jean-Claude Seguin, La Production cinématographique des frères Lumière (Paris: Mémoires de cinéma, 1996) 215-16. 32 On this paradigm, see André Gaudreault, Cinéma et attraction. Pour une nouvelle histoire du cinématographe (Paris: CNRS éditions, 2008) 102 sqq.

Forms of Machines, Forms of Movement

295

cinema between the theoretical reversibility camera-projector and the actual asymmetry orienting each practice and each machine differently – a tension already very strong with Marey.33 Manuals and directions for movie cameras insisted on the difficult and unfairly derided art of the crank, the absolute need for regularity, whether a turtle or a horse race, a funeral or a ball were being filmed. The art was all the more tricky as camera tripods were soon to allow panoramic and tilting movements thanks to… two additional cranks. A cameraman thus needed three hands, which created a few problems solved here and there through a more or less cumbersome human or electric assistance… This art of the crank demanded, for instance, that the machine be occasionally weighted so as to add stability to it, an aspect already considered in the directions for the Lumière Cinématographe in 1897: the crank had to be turned, “making sure to hold the appliance firmly with the left hand, pressing on the stand to avoid vibrations.”34 In this one case, the legendary lightness of the Lumière machine backfired… Manuals for projectionists also highlighted regularity for the “naturalness” of the movement, but kept the door open to speed variations, sometimes even suggesting them to “expressive” ends. The degree of subversion of Dziga Vertov’s 1923 statement can be grasped only when this distinction between shooting and projecting is maintained: Until now many a cameraman has been criticized for having filmed a running horse moving with unnatural slowness on the screen (rapid cranking of the camera) – or for the opposite, a tractor plowing a field too swiftly (slow cranking of the camera), and the like. These are chance occurrences, of course, but we are preparing a system, a deliberate system of such occurrences, a system of seeming irregularities to investigate and organize phenomena.35

In this textual “montage,” Vertov amusingly combines the Muybridgian topos of the galloping horse with the agricultural mechanization so crucial for the USSR – through the action of his crank, he reverses the traditional association of speed with the horse and slowness with the tractor, giving a more politically “progressive” version of it. If the film industry on its way to 33 See Marey, Le Mouvement 309. 34 Notice sur le Cinématographe Auguste et Louis Lumière (Lyons: Société anonyme des plaques et papiers photographiques A. Lumière et ses fils, 1897) 19. 35 “The Council of Three” (1923), in Kino-Eye. The Writings of Dziga Vertov, Annette Michelson, ed., trans. Kevin O’Brien (Berkeley, Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1984) 15-16.

296 

Benoît Turquety

institutionalization banned these speed variations during shooting, it was also because it was impossible to correct them: no speed variation during projection – or in the laboratory – could produce a “natural” movement if the shooting speed had been too high. This kind of power, with the explosive political potential expressed by Vertov here, could not possibly be granted to cameramen. The crank allowed even more than speed variations: it did not require any settings to be chosen beforehand, nor did it involve a “default” pace. It also made the machine reactive and autonomous, independently of available electricity outlets. The electrical motor became generalized when the advent of synchronized sound imposed a constant, automatic pace of 24 images/sec. This resistance of cameramen to electrification had to do with the “margin of indeterminacy” which, according to Gilbert Simondon, gave a machine its real value, as opposed to automatism: Idolators of the machine generally assume that the degree of perfection of a machine is directly proportional to the degree of automatism. […] Now, in fact, automatism is a fairly low degree of technical perfection. In order to make a machine automatic, it is necessary to sacrifice many of its functional possibilities and many of its possible uses. Automatism […] has an economic or social, rather than a technical, significance.36

The Presence of Machines Observing machines in detail, taking into account their uses, the discourses concerning them, but also their forms, does not necessarily lead to stress the continuity of an abstract principle – the production of an illusion of movement out of a series of still images – over time. Rather, it means identifying as precisely as possible the conditions of perception produced specifically by each machine, and discovering discontinuities between concrete viewing situations, between forms of movement which these machines make visible. From Phenakistiscopes to Zoetropes, from Zoetropes to Praxinoscopes, from models using a crank to models dispensing with it, featuring an electric engine or a spring-loaded engine, a wide or narrow cylinder, the diversity of machines materializes divergences in the conception of what it is to see 36 Gilbert Simondon, On the Mode of Existence of Technical Objects [1958], trans. Ninian Mellamphy (University of Western Ontario, June 1980) 3-4, available at http://english.duke.edu/ uploads/assets/Simondon_MEOT_part_1.pdf, last accessed on July 11, 2012.

Forms of Machines, Forms of Movement

297

a moving image. These divergences should not be brought to a resolution or even too linearized if the protean wealth of the medium(s) examined is to be grasped, and the theoretical, historiographic and epistemological consequences are to be assessed. This dismissal of linearization should lead us to take into account marginal processes and practices as well as dominant ones, Anschütz (to whom this contribution is a homage of sorts, in the end) as well as Lumière, because their existence, like their marginality with respect to the industry, may give us a better understanding of the history of the medium – machines, perception, art. However, research on machines also involves another, parallel level. American poet Williams Carlos Williams wrote in 1944: To make two bold statements: There’s nothing sentimental about a machine, and: A poem is a small (or large) machine made of words. When I say there’s nothing sentimental about a poem I mean that there can be no part, as in any other machine, that is redundant. […] As in all machines its movement is intrinsic, undulant, a physical more than a literary character. In a poem this movement is distinguished in each case by the character of the speech from which it arises.37

In 1944 these paragraphs summed up the contribution of the most radical side of American poetic modernity, in a way. To approach a work of art as a machine has rather important implications for its analysis, for considering the place of its reader or spectator, and quite simply for understanding what is at stake for us in the experience of its form.

37 W. C. Williams, “‘Author’s Introduction’ to The Wedge” (1944), in Selected Essays of William Carlos Williams (New York: Random House, 1954) 256.



The Amateur-Dispositive François Albera

The issue of the “amateur” or “amateurs” is more topical than ever these days, because of the easier access to equipment produced by new technologies, its miniaturization and availability, with mass industrial production making it affordable for a large majority of people. The phenomenon has been widely taken into account in the field of photography studies, where it always went hand in hand with the other – learned, expert, professional – tradition, from Foto-Auge in 1929 to the exhibition “Tous photographes” (Lausanne, 2007) or “From here on” (Arles, 2011). However, the same phenomenon is now assuming a whole other dimension, in particular with sociologists.1 Despite the economic and social importance of cinema, this question – which runs through the history and the “prehistory” of the medium – has not been given a significant place so far in different discourses, whether critical or academic. It should probably be rephrased in terms of private uses or even “techniques of the self” to find a field of study that would liberate it from the narrow range of its “object.” Only in “utopian” literature – to which I would rather refer as “literature of extrapolation” – has this issue been apprehended within a larger framework, where “cinema” is considered not only as an art, but also as a medium.2 As a consequence, it may prove an “ideal” object when it comes to fully developing the question of the “dispositif” – from the most humble mechanical device, the machine used for shooting with its accessories, the 1 See Patrice Flichy, Le Sacre de l’amateur. Sociologie des passions ordinaires à l’ère numérique (Paris: La République des Idées/Éditions du Seuil, 2010). 2 The various audiovisual utopias (Jules Verne or Albert Robida, for instance) have in common the availability of each “mechanical” means of communication, recording or representation, their adaptation for the home, be it in the form of a domestic access to spectacles (war in Africa for information, ballets and theater for entertainment), personal communication (dialoguing across distances with another individual), announcements or public mobilization, or the control over one’s body. With respect for the latter, for instance, all inhabitants in Verne’s The Floating Island are equipped with Marey’s experimental machines: “Every inhabitant knew his constitution exactly, his muscular force measured by the dynamometer, his pulmonary capacity measured by the spirometer, his power of cardial contraction measured by the sphygmometer, his degree of vital force measured by the magnetometer.” This availability, which implies miniaturization, simplification and large-scale production, rests on a process which, starting from the collective (the public) and a dedicated space (the theater), proceeds to the individual and to private space, which are also obviously part of a social space. All prospective fictions follow this progression. See Jules Verne, The Floating Island (Rockville, Maryland: Wildside Press, 2009) 57-58.

300 

François Albera

projector, the way they operate, to a social dimension, with the role, usage, and place of this machinery in family life, the intimacy of subjects, their imaginary, and finally at the level of the general organization of viewing and listening machines in society. It lies at the intersection between the general norm, indexed on technical knowledge and the rules of representation, and individual autonomy from this norm, which may still be verified in it and feeds on it – neither one really preceding the other, each presupposed in the other. The “paying public projection,” which was chosen as the beginning of “the history of cinema,” summons a crowd, all the crowds in the world, simultaneously if possible, by assigning them the place of the spectator: this is a well-known narrative. But this axis, along which a whole series of “moments” deemed relevant by historians line up – institutionalization, theaters, the advent of narration, the recognition of film as art, and today, for some, the entrance into the museum and the gallery, among other examples – is “doubled” with another axis in which image and sound machines are domestic, private, family-oriented, individual objects (optical toys, cameras, gramophones, telephones, television, smartphones…). “Doubled” is the right word, for all the appliances and dispositives mentioned in the second group presuppose that the individual or the limited group using them belong to collectivities, to a crowd. Symmetrically, these crowds do not merge their constituents into a whole that would subsume them; on the contrary, they require them to remain individuals. Boris Eikhenbaum already noted that the film spectator was alone; unlike the spectator at the theater, he did not blend in a collective entity. In short, audio and visual spectacles since the nineteenth century (the diorama, the panorama, the Praxinoscopetheater and the cinematograph), if they aimed at a mass audience, still individualized the spectator in the theater, who as a consequence was not different from his complement, the private user. The two are moments of the same individual, two modes of subjectification.3 The economy of these appliances aims at both: technological changes produce these individual 3 “Even the very concept of ‘mass art’ in connection with cinema needs a whole series of qualifications. […] [I]f we force ourselves to think it over calmly then the mass art of cinema is not a qualitative concept but a quantitative one which is not connected with the essence of cinema. […] [C]inema does not in itself in any way require the presence of the mass, even if theatre does. Anyone with a projector can watch a film at home and therefore be one of the mass of cinema spectators even without entering a cinema. Apart from that we do not, in essence, feel ourselves to be members of a mass at all, or participants in a mass spectacle, when we are sitting in a cinema; on the contrary – conditions at a film-show induce the spectator to feel as if he were in total isolation.” Boris Eikhenbaum, “Problems of Cine-Stylistics,” trans. Richard Sherwood, in Boris Eikhenbaum, The Poetics of Cinema, ed. Richard Taylor (Oxford: RPT Publications/The University of Essex, 1982) 10.

The Amateur-Dispositive

301

uses and the corresponding market while developing the spectacular and collective dimension of film (Scope, 3-D, stereo sound). That the “theatrical release” is now seen mainly in the private space (television, DVD) or on an individual player (laptop, smartphone…) that may also be used in public space (in the street or on the train…) shows this reversibility of places and porosity of “boundaries.”4 Within this approach, the notion of “amateur” is obviously “off,” and even out of date. The phenomenon exceeds the distinction between the professional and the dilettante from which it proceeds. Still, the amateur is a “fact” and some of the questions mentioned thus far may start being answered on that basis.

The Amateur-Dispositive The film amateur, or cinema lover, is commonly defined either as a spectator or as a non-professional practitioner: she or he consumes film or produces it. Yet again, these aspects are not mutually exclusive: the private spectator is requested as a projectionist for the Pathé Kok, a manipulator for the kinora, just as she or he was for the phenakistiscope or zootrope, the gramophone or the theatrophone. This is even more the case with the computer, with downloading, “piracy,” viewing, video extraction, copying, and so forth. Some technical skills are even needed for the maintenance of the equipment and its proper operation; electronics has further emphasized the phenomenon by which the user has to upgrade or repair the machine, possibly by talking to a specialist over the phone. As to amateur filmmakers, they are also spectators of course – of their own films, to begin with. Here the amateur-dispositive refers to the social dispositive which integrates amateur filmmaker and industrial production equipment in a configuration that makes it possible to articulate the different definitions of the “dispositif”: a) the technical definition, in the restricted sense of the combination of parts into an appliance as described in the patent;5 4 Gilles Lipovetsky and Jean Serroy refer to this phenomenon under the term “global screen.” See L’Ecran global. Du cinéma au smartphone (2007; Paris: Seuil, 2011). 5 Auguste Lumière, narrating the invention of the cinematograph by his brother, spoke of “dispositif” to refer to the decisive “detail” that made possible the development of the appliance: “One morning, as I came to his bedside to see how he was doing, he told me that during his insomnia he had kept turning the problem over and thought he had found a rational solution. The idea was to resort to a dispositive gripping the film at rest, carrying it in a speeded-up, then a slowed-down movement, until it came to rest again – at which time the projection had to take

302 

François Albera

b) that by which a modus operandi comes with the appliance and has to be implemented by the amateur following the instructions for use; c) the cinematographic dispositive proper, which determines the relations of the director or spectator to the machine and to the representation (aimed at or perceived), and with which the amateur complies;6 and finally, d) the social dispositive, which the cinematographic dispositive is a part of and belongs to. In this case, the social dispositive is particularly easy to identify: in the set of prescriptive discourses – technical (a) as well as normative (b), referring to groups of values which are not only technical or even just aesthetic – and in the procedures subjecting the amateur to the whole. What surfaces here is the articulation characterizing “liberal” societies according to Foucault, in which the autonomy, the individual freedom and subjection play a part in the good integration and the good functioning of the socio-economic system (liberal capitalism and the productivity it seeks).7 It appears all the more clearly as the individual addressed by this ensemble of discursive utterances and practices to implement is an “amateur” combining unselfishness and chosen attraction, but also possibly fickleness and even negligence.8 Indeed, the amateur is required to be free and sovereign, unlike the professional, who has to abide by strict rules designed according to desired effects established by other people (she or he only carries things out) and place. This cyclical operation had to be repeated fifteen times per second. […] I immediately understood that this dispositive was to perform the desired effect and left the problem to my brother, who had just found the solution in one night.” See Auguste Lumière, Mes travaux et mes jours, 1953, quoted in Bernard Chardère, Le Roman des Lumière (Paris: Gallimard, 1995) 286 (my emphasis). 6 As Louis Lumière explained: “I built an appliance of this kind [the kinetoscope] and, after many attempts, I managed to implement a dispositive which allowed the image to stay still for 1/25 of a second and made possible the projection of these images on a screen – and in front of several people. My dispositive was the cinematograph.” See Louis Lumière, interview by Régis-Leroi, Minerva 31 Dec. 1935, quoted by Chardère, Le Roman des Lumière 284. Lumière moves from the mechanical system in the appliance (the film stopping in front of the shutter) to the dispositive of the appliance as a whole, to the screen and to the spectator (the cinematograph). 7 “The psychological subject [of panopticism, discipline and normalization] whose appearance is attested at the time […] is but the other side of this process of subjection.” See Michel Foucault, Résumés des cours 1970-1982 (Paris: Julliard, 1989) 49-50. 8 The 8th edition of the Dictionnaire de l’Académie (1932-1935) defined the amateur as follows: “Someone who is fond of something, has a taste for it […]. It [the term] refers absolutely to individuals who like the fine arts without practicing them or having them as their profession. He is not an artist, he is an amateur. This is the talent of an amateur, the work of an amateur. It is also used to refer to those who, having to do something, go about it carelessly. He studies amateur[ishly]. Finally, it applies to those who practice sports without earning any financial profit for it.”

The Amateur-Dispositive

303

profitability in every sense of the word. This injunction to be free is consubstantial with the figure of the amateur, who is at once heavily criticized and praised for the free will she or he shows. A caricature of the father of the photography “for everyone,” George Eastman, shows him passing by the bank where he was an employee, pursuing his hobby, weighed down by the cumbersome equipment needed to shoot a mere “instantaneous” photograph.9 Beyond this “material” aspect, which was very important in the discourse on the popularization of and access to the photographic – and to some extent, cinematographic – medium, the amateur was always called on to play a part where she or he “counterbalanced” or stimulated professional practice. To reconcile the two contradictory sides of this injunction, institutional discourses – the manufacturers’ instruction manual and related literature (publicity, magazine articles) – engaged in the naturalization of technical procedures. These could not be declined, since they were self-evident and were the only ones possible. The conceptual framework of this operation of naturalization mobilized “values” – aesthetic, involving “good taste,” uses, “good form,” and so forth – which limited possible practices in the name of this proper operation. As a consequence, since the amateur was supposedly released from a number of economic (or commercial) constraints and did not work towards the creation of a “product” for a market, she or he always already encapsulated a number of traits – in the negative, one might say. Some of these traits are to be found in contemporary artistic practices, as these integrate image and sound appliances without agreeing to the respect of the norms in question, but this time with the prospect of renewing the “supply” on the art market. That is the case with the discourse on the so-called “emancipatory” arrangements of installations, which succeeded their “deconstruction,” itself tapping into apparatus theory (see Dan Graham in particular).10 Indeed, as Roger Odin has shown, amateur cinema requires interactivity and proposes unfinished, ductile productions allowing oral interventions, interruptions, flashbacks, freeze frames on demand, and so forth. He compares these

9 Reproduced in Friedrich von Zglinicki, Der Weg des Films (Berlin: Rembrandt, 1956) 159. 10 Beyond the often unstructured comments in the discourses of art critics, curators, or artists, Olivier Quintyn has been developing a theory that seeks to articulate textual dispositive and social dispositive by relying on Lévi-Strauss’s notion of bricolage. His main concern is collage as a dispositive always founded on disjunction and generating possible epistemo-critical tactics. See Olivier Quintyn, Dispositifs/Dislocations (Paris: Al Dante, 2007).

304 

François Albera

characteristics to those of experimental cinema; today they are related to new media (cell phones, computers, digital cameras, etc.).11 More generally, De Certeau’s hypotheses on “the arts of practice” outline what he calls an “alternative,” “the network of an antidiscipline” allowing the deployment of the “dispersed, tactical, and makeshift creativity of groups or individuals already caught in the nets of ‘discipline’.”12 Still, these uses, either private or collective, outside what could be “the” standard cinematographic dispositive (the tiered theater, the seat where the spectator is immobilized, darkness, the screen and the projection by an invisible, silent machine13), were considered immediately after communication, recording, and diffusion devices appeared: from the standpoint of hybridization on the one hand, from that of individual appropriation on the other. The ongoing development of media and intermedia studies has retrospectively shed light on these intersections and exchanges between different media (telephone, gramophone, kinetoscope, photography, radio, etc.). By contrast, “theory” has relentlessly turned the respective properties of these media into as many distinctive, autonomized traits in order to found them as arts14 – a quest for specificity that has played out again recently with video or other media, through cell phone film festivals, for example. The turn which took place in France in 1961-1962, with the end of the Institut de Filmologie and the emergence of the Centre d’études de communication de masse, was significant in that respect: the driving principle behind Cohen-Séat’s undertaking was to take into account the dimension of 11 It is partly with a view to renewing artistic practices that exhibitions in museums or related institutions (festivals) open themselves to amateurs or celebrate their “consecration,” actually paving the way for their “canonization,” to use Shklovsky’s terminology. Despite its undoubtedly unfinished nature, the Soviet effort of “de-professionalization” – in photography, literature, and cinema, notably – started from different premises, since its aim was to transform everyday life. See Maria Zalambani, L’arte nella produzione. Avantguardia e rivoluzione nella Russia sovietica degli anni Venti (Ravenna: Longo Angelo, 1998). 12 Michel de Certeau, The Practice of Everyday Life (Berkeley, Los Angeles: The University of California Press, 1984) xiv-xv. 13 “The theater, a centrifugal art, an art of expansion, an open-air art, is marked by contagion. But the cinema will always require this dark, closed space where spectators withdraw into themselves and concentrate; an inner art, in which everything comes together and condenses; the screen soon seems to be set up in the very center of the mind; there I contemplate the universe in the innermost part of myself.” See Jacques Rivette, “Les malheurs d’Orphée,” La Gazette du cinéma 5 (Nov. 1950): 2. 14 See François Albera and Maria Tortajada, “Prolégomènes à une critique des télé-dispositifs,” in La Télévision, du téléphonoscope à YouTube. Pour une archéologie de l’audiovision, Mireille Berton and Ann-Katrin Weber, eds. (Lausanne: Antipodes, 2009).

The Amateur-Dispositive

305

cinema as a media. It involved a split in cinema considered as an art with the division film/cinema, which Metz was to use to further autonomize and to identify a core even more essential to his object in Language and Cinema.15 However, it left cinema in a central position – not as a “model,”16 as Lev Manovich advocates nowadays, but as an object.17 The audiovisual field was thus considered as a whole with much “delay” (Adorno and Horkheimer had defined television as the assembly of radio and cinema in the 1940s, and Gunther Anders had further outlined it shortly afterwards 18). This notably affected apparatus theory as it was consolidated from 1969 to 1978 with Jean-Louis Baudry, among others, fixated as it was on a “state” of cinema as an autonomous medium – which at the time was no longer the only one and was not even dominant, if it had ever been.19 Still, this “split” in cinema may be verified in a less elitist press that took it into account, as with a 1961 issue of Magnum devoted to television.20 The new medium and media is compared with previous spectacles (the engraving of a Robertson phantasmagoria and a television studio, “Wunderlampe und Elektronauge,” magic lantern and electronic eye) or with “anticipations.” Countless references to Robida’s drawings, excerpted from his Le Vingtième Siècle, appear 15 See Christian Metz, Language and Cinema, chapters 1 [“Within the Cinema: The Filmic Fact”] and 2 [“Within the Filmic Fact: The Cinema”] (Berlin: De Gruyter Mouton, 1974). 16 “The theory and history of cinema serve as the key conceptual lens through which I look at new media.” See Lev Manovich, The Language of the New Media (Cambridge, MA/London: The MIT Press, 2001) 8-9. 17 Barthes noted this in his account of the first international conference on visual information that took place in Milan (July 9-12, 1961), published in the first issue of Communications the same year. He denounced “the imperialism of cinema over other means of visual information,” a domination “doubtless justified ‘historically’” but which “cannot be justified epistemologically.” See Roland Barthes, Communications 1 (1961): 223-24. The quotation appears in François Albera and Maria Tortajada, “Introduction to an Epistemology of Viewing and Listening Dispositives,” in Cinema Beyond Film. Media Epistemology in the Modern Era, François Albera and Maria Tortajada, eds., trans. Lance Hewsom (Amsterdam: Amsterdam U.P., 2010) 22 fn. 18 Theodor Adorno, Max Horkheimer, Dialektik der Aufklärung [1944], published in English as Dialectic of Enlightenment (Palo Alto: Stanford U.P., 2007); Gunther Anders, Die Antiquiertheit des Menschen 1. Über die Seele im Zeitalter der zweiten industriellen Revolution [1956-1980], published in French as De l’obsolescence de l’homme (Paris: Ivrea-Encyclopédie des nuisances, 2001; Fario, 2011). The idea of combination is inherent in technical invention and its explanation. In his scientif ic column in Le Gaulois (1 Jan. 1896), E. Hospitaber, an engineer in “Arts and Manufactures,” introduced the kinetoscope and the cinematograph as well as the animated panorama, a “fortunate combination” of cinema and colonel Moëssant’s photographic panorama. 19 Indeed, this stripped-down model was founded on the diachronic as well as synchronic repression of cinema’s entire intermedia dimension and of all the diversified forms of its uses and functions (didactics, surveillance, mixed entertainment, documentation and archive, etc.). 20 See “Faktum Fernsehen” [“the television factor”], Magnum 34 [Cologne] Feb. 1961.

306 

François Albera

in the magazine (pages 7, 22, 23, 26).21 Television as a new dispositive is thus considered within a history predating the advent of cinema.22 The emphasis is on the place of spectators (the domestic space) on the one hand, and on the conditions of production (studio, equipment) on the other, rather than on images “in themselves” as in the aesthetic approach to cinema. Regarding television, this emphasis attests to the consciousness of a mixed use and of the dimension of social dispositive that had gradually been overshadowed – or played down, at the very least – in the case of cinema.

Le Gaulois and the Easter Egg Barely two years after the f irst public screenings, the first page of the Easter issue of Le Gaulois (a newspaper where Raymond Roussel penned the Sunday serials) featured the drawing of a huge egg that supposedly contained twelve surprises to be given out after a draw from the newspaper’s subscribers.23 The prizes were a house that could be dismantled, a steampowered tricycle, a bike, a Larousse dictionary in 17 volumes, an outdoor gymnastics equipment and – ranked fifth on the list – a cinematograph. “Everybody can do photography; the use of the cinematograph can be learned quickly,” according to the newspaper. To this effect, the Lumière appliance was chosen for its practical aspect (it could record, develop and project). From today’s perspective, handling the cinematograph does not seem as practical as the newspaper claimed, far from it: the appliance did not have a viewer, it was operated with a crank, thereby requiring the use of a tripod and a projective approach to the edges of the frame. In spite of these aspects and the briefness of the films, Le Gaulois listed a series of subjects that could be shot by “the amateur” (though the term was actually never used in the text): a comic scene, an interesting movement, a ball, an air show, a scene involving sea swimming, a comic scene at the castle, hunting scenes (blowing the horn at the hunt to signal that the kill is near or that 21 As early as 1972, the Kassel Documenta (on the theme “today seen from yesterday”) devoted a room to Robida, whose reference was to become central with the advent of intermediality. See Jurgen Müller and William Uricchio, among other scholars, and Alain Boillat in this volume. 22 William Uricchio proposed to substitute the narrative of the advent of television (starting from the camera obscura), founded on live broadcasting, for that of the advent of cinema (with its antecedents and various manifestations), defined by recording, storage, and reproduction. Yet this would still consist in distinguishing between media on the basis of the restrictive specialization of their uses. 23 Supplement to Le Gaulois 17 April 1897: 1.

The Amateur-Dispositive

307

a hunted animal is hitting the water, a quarry), a wedding at the village, the monument of a railway station, a pilgrimage, and so forth. “Is there anything the cinematograph cannot reproduce?” It was at once credited with a) several functions – keeping memories, staging, documenting; b) a sort of immediacy – “in the evening, the developed images will be shown on the screen with the animation of reality;” and c) adjustability, as “there are many ways to add to [filmed, visual] reality through sound, song, or music.” This offer is proof of the availability of the appliance on the market, even as it took some time for the Lumières to develop their invention, initially reluctant to commercialize it so as to maintain their monopoly over its exploitation. After the kinora, which made it possible to visualize a series of 600 prints attached to a rotating cylinder thanks to a single lens (1896, manufactured and commercialized by Gaumont from 1900 on), the socalled “family” or “home” projectors became increasingly available in the 1900s (the Kinemathome, etc.), as did toys (the cinematograph of families, a version of the Phototachygraphe). In 1907, after a short-lived attempt by Gaumont-Demenÿ, the “‘Kino’ amateur cinematograph” was made available commercially, and in 1912 the Pathé company, an industrial and commercial “empire” founded on the phonograph and cinema, further developed the idea of a “cinema at home” with the Pathé Kok, a projector fitted with a dynamo which allowed a well-off clientele to view a collection of movies published in reduced format (28 mm) on nonflammable film in their own salon. The Kok camera followed shortly thereafter, again with the amateur as a target. However, the cost of film and laboratory processing meant that the appliance was not easily affordable.

The Pathé-Baby Ten years later, after the division of his “empire” (phonographs and phonographic equipment on one side, Pathé Consortium Cinéma for the distribution and exhibition on another and Pathé Cinéma for the production of film as well as the manufacture of appliances for shooting and projecting), Charles Pathé had not given up on catering to the greatest number of customers, as the gramophone had shown how lucrative this activity could be. For Christmas 1922, he launched the “Pathé-Baby,” an appliance designed for the projection at home of small-format films (9.5 mm). It met with considerable success. The March 1924 issue of L’Informateur photo stated that, “if we still lived in the time of fairy tales, all of us, adults and children, should place the Pathé-Baby in the realm of dreams.” The projector

308 

François Albera

was apprehended both as a tool for scientific popularization and as accessible to children due to the simplicity of its use. As with the Pathé-Kok, an amateur appliance for shooting films became available shortly afterwards. Developed by manufacturer Pierre-Victor Coutinsouza, it was in turn praised in L’Informateur photo: the camera could be used “without notions about photography, for little money, in simple and practical ways.” The appliance was small, compact and light, it could be easily loaded and in plain daylight thanks to its case system; while it only had one – nonreflex – viewfinder, its “extra-luminous” lens did not require focusing from 5 feet to infinity, and it cost less than its predecessors (385 francs). Amateur cinema took off in France in the wake of the Pathé-Baby. The phenomenon, which enabled the “newcomer” of cinema to challenge the domination of the other arts, took place within the artistic field itself: either within the perspective of the destruction of established aesthetic values (as with the avant-gardes) or with the modernist prospect of a new foundation for a “new spirit.” Interest in these new techniques, these new mediums, these new addressees was from then on combined with the interest for “non professional” appropriations liable to shake up the “canons.” This movement towards amateurs was observed even more in the USSR (at first a part of the Proletkult’s sphere of influence, it soon won over the literary, photographic and cinematographic avant-garde around the LEF, which advocated factualism and the “deprofessionalization” of art 24) than in Germany (be it on the side of the Bauhaus and modernist movements or on the side of socio-political movements such as trade unions and far-left parties). In France, Cinéa-Ciné pour tous, a cinephilic periodical, regularly published articles on the phenomenon, hoping that a renewal in themes and styles would originate in these amateurs with no artistic certainties learned in the fine arts, literature or theater. In 1927 Pierre Henry asserted that with the Pathé-Baby, “the amateur photographer now [had] its equivalent in the cinematograph”: on the one hand, “what was done until now with a Kodak and the photo album [was] going to become far more lively and striking with the moving image,”25 while on the other hand,

24 See Aya Kawamura, “La création collective dans le documentaire soviétique: photographie, cinéma et ‘correspondants-ouvriers’,” 1895. Revue d’histoire du cinéma 63 (Spring 2011). 25 Pierre Henry, “Le cinéma d’amateur,” Cinéa-Ciné pour tous 85 (15 May 1927): 26-27.

The Amateur-Dispositive

309

amateur cinegraphy opens the way to future performers curious about photogeny, future operators, future directors, artists who, tomorrow perhaps, will give new impetus to this art still looking for its way. Is it not evident that the great filmmakers of tomorrow will not be crossovers from literature, the stage or so many other careers, but truly amateur filmmakers…26

Yet beyond families and individual amateurs, schools and Catholic youth clubs became the major players in this medium. The phenomenon resulted in a genuine parallel distribution network for Pathé. The company became aware of a very tangible reality: in the France of the 1920s and 1930s, rural space was completely ignored by film distributors, who mostly relied on theaters located in cities. Enthusiasm for light equipment, small formats and amateur appliances in the countryside thus led to the Pathé-rural, a distribution system for the 16 mm Pathé catalog.27 As can be seen, amateur practice, while it could prove true assertions such as Roh’s, extolling outsiders in the renewal of professional photography, was simultaneously regulated in two ways: first, by instructions for use and their prescriptions (internal norm), which influences aesthetic choices; second, by mediating social institutions, which dispense knowledge or doctrines (external norm) that influence the choice of subjects and uses. The first of these norms will be examined here.

26 Pierre Henry, “Le cinéma d’amateur,” Cinéa-Ciné pour tous 86 (1 June 1927): 14-15. These last words, which Louis Delluc had had about amateur scripts a few years earlier, echo Franz Roh’s: “The Werkbund exhibition [“Film und Foto,” Stuttgart, 1929], the most important event of these last few years in the visual field, presented almost no productions by professional photographers, so often petrified in conventional mannerism. Here we have more evidence of the fact that outsiders free of any prevention are precisely often those who achieve the necessary progress and rejuvenation in the most diverse domains of life, art, or science. And this new flowering of the photographic art also belongs… [in] the unknown history of the general productivity of amateurs.” See “Mechanism and Expression,” in Foto-Auge, 76 Fotos der Zeit, Jan Tschichold and Franz Roh, eds. (Stuttgart: Akademischer Verlag Dr. Fritz Wedekind & Co., 1929). Translator’s note: this translation from the French is my own. An English translation of the full text may be found in Germany. The New Photography, 1927-1933. Documents and Essays, ed. David Mellor (Arts Council of Great Britain, 1978). 27 This has to be added to the several thousand small-format f ilms circulated in families by Pathé. Both phenomena show to what extent an important share of the cinematographic phenomenon is not considered in commentaries concentrating on the period.

310 

François Albera

The Internal Constraint Several levels in prescriptive, evaluative, promotional and critical discourse thus define and outline the conditions for an amateur practice of cinema (in this case, the “Pathé-Baby”). They partly overlap with and sometimes contradict one another. The discourse of the patent would be situated on the first level. In this case, we will take the instance of a description of the appliance commonly referred to as “Motocaméra Pathé Baby,” which will come up again in our argument, and which in the patent is called “advanced cinematographic appliance for shooting.”28 According to the final summary, the invention concerns improvements in the “mechanism driving the film, [the] system controlling the shutter, [the] regulating brake, [the] command spring, [the] channel and [the] on/off system” (p. 3). Before the technical description proper and its explanatory figures, the text states that “the object of the present invention is to realize a cinematographic shooting appliance that would not be too unwieldy, would not weigh much and would be easy to operate.” The main characteristic of the model is that it comes with a mainspring allowing the film to be driven and replacing the hand-driven crank of the previous model. Given the particular use made of this spring in the barrel where it is set (an involute circle with a radius increasing over one half of its length and the form of a decreasing involute over the other half), it has less power than a regular spring when completely wound up, but more power when partly unwound. As a consequence, it ensures uniform driving throughout operation. The shift from the crank to the mainspring, then to the electric motor later, was not linear,29 despite the use of the term “improvements” and, far from presenting only “advantages,” it also involved limitations in the possibilities once offered by the crank. Uniform driving did not totally preclude a whole range of other recording speeds for the film (slow motion/ speeded-up motion) or experimentation with this parameter in relation to posing time (and accordingly to lighting matters). In this particular 28 We are referring to patent n° 608.815 here. It was registered by the company Pathé Cinéma on December 30, 1925 and issued on April 30, 1926 (its publication occurred on August 3) by the services of industrial property attached to the Ministry of Commerce and Industry of the French Republic (a registration request was also filed in England in February 1925). The document was signed (through a power of attorney) by Lavoix, Mosès, and Gehet. It was consulted at the département des Appareils (Cinémathèque française). 29 See Benoît Turquety’s contribution in this volume.

The Amateur-Dispositive

311

instance, however, it still made these “cases” somewhat exceptional and indeed limited them, as appears in the “instructions” below. At this level of the manufacturer’s discourse, the user for whom the appliance had been designed or the kinds of possible uses are not mentioned. Only aspects such as handiness and easy operation come up. With the “instructions” appearing in the user’s booklet for the Motocamera (a second level of discourse), the amateur arrives on the scene and is assigned a number of gestures, attitudes and objectives. Addressing the user directly (“you”), the manual begins with an outline of the place occupied by the appliance in everyday life for everyone (“we”) and the anthropological consequences this implies: How can the pleasure of animated photography be conveyed, when it represents those we love the most? It is time being half-defeated, our own life running in front of us, it is, at last, the past kept alive.

It should be noted that the statement is close to the dominant discourse that greeted the Cinematograph, notably with the well-known articles published in the press after the first screenings. Accessibility for the amateur, the novice being targeted is then extolled: This joy is available to all today, PATHE-BABY gives it to you, the MOTOCAMERA brings it within your reach without requiring special knowledge about photography, and at little cost, through simple and practical means.

Third, this accessibility is associated to technical characteristics and to improvements brought to the appliance in terms of simplification and automatism: “No set-up, not even a crank to rotate, no more unwieldy tripod.” The elements brought up here thus are the same as the “advantages” evoked in the patent, but “in situation,” in the very practice of the user. Finally, the instructions set things into motion, prompting the user to take action: “Take the trouble to read the following lines and already the MOTOCAMERA will be ready to shoot, fixing the pleasure of the first success for you.” The instructions, advice, and recommendation that follow the short description of the appliance and its handling (loading and unloading the film casings, shooting, etc.: the do’s and don’ts) then define a series of rather circumscribed precepts that combine technical arrangements, uses and effects of an aesthetic nature to be sought (or obtained):

312 

François Albera

So as to avoid that the photographed subject exits the frame, we strongly recommend that the area where one or several characters will move about be drawn with chalk on the ground; and that heads always be maintained in the frame, unlike feet and legs, which may be cut off by the lower part of the frame. For portraits shot at very close range (within 5 ft), keep the chin of the cinematographed person at the level of the base of the viewer’s window, that is, slightly tilt up the camera and use the supplementary lens in that case. The more distant the subjects, the easier it is for them to move laterally without moving outside the frame, but it is nonetheless advisable to identify the edges thanks to objects placed nearby. […] We even recommend that beginners shoot their first views with one or more seated characters, in front of a table for instance, to simply make an animated portrait. A face photographed at a range of 2.5 ft or 3 ft will fill up the whole frame, with the slightest changes in expression being perceptible, whereas the pace, the gait, the gestures will be faithfully rendered in the case of characters shot full-length. It should in fact be noted that movements across the frame (lateral) are much less apparent than movements in depth. Also, the foreground is much more expressive than subjects from a distance and it is the art of the “filmmaker’s mise en scène” to alternate properly between the two. To shoot panoramic views, the user will attempt to move the Motocaméra in a smooth and regular movement. When too swift, a movement makes all images completely blurry and produces horizontal “streaks.” In the course of making a film, for the shooting of still objects such as statues, monuments, landscapes featuring no movement, etc., a second take will be enough and will provide a dozen images, the best of which will be immobilized thanks to a notch during screening.30

Some recommendations or remarks directly refer to technical capabilities of the appliance not mentioned in the patent. It is thus indicated that, in the cases when the subject “does not move much,” or for “animated portraits,” it is possible to shoot a little more slowly to increase posing time. Indeed, one of the “pernicious” effects of motorization is to make the play with the relation speed/posing time less apparent. 30 My emphasis.

The Amateur-Dispositive

313

The speed produced by the mechanism (2 rotations per second) corresponds to the standard pace, but it may be safely reduced to 90 rotations per minute without producing excessively jerky movements by pressing the knurled knob above the power lever to increase posing time in winter weather or for indoor views (with seated character), views in the woods, or even in fair weather if subjects move about slowly.

Others are tied to a process posterior to shooting, that of development, which retroactively implies constraints during the shooting: It is recommended that several scenes be shot as part of the same film to avoid “overlong” passages, but subjects should then all be lit in the same way, for films are developed as a whole and any differences in lighting in the same film cannot be corrected during development.

A “technical” problem thus determines choices of an aesthetic nature as well as choices involving subjects. These different levels come up together again later: 2° It is not necessary to shoot with the sun behind you, on the contrary: depth and the beauty of the result are emphasized with the sun on the side. 3° Do not shoot scenes with starkly different lights on the same film, as it is impossible to develop a film other than as a whole.

These “limitations” either lead to the development of new accessories or the opening of new practices for the amateur: “in these exceptional cases where amateurs would like to perform this work on their own, we have designed adapted, portable developing equipment which will be provided with detailed instructions.” As we have seen, the terms “photographer” and “photography” (“without requiring special knowledge about photography”) appear several times. In this specific sub-sector of cinema that is amateur cinema, the reference to the amateur photographer was indeed imperative, for it represented an antecedent offering the example of a social and commercial success. The comparison was particularly apt when it came to the work on development, with which amateur photographers had been familiar since the nineteenth century. As to accessories, the posograph or the various posometers put on the market made it possible to calculate the exposure needed according to the

314 

François Albera

available light thanks to very precise tables, but also along very normalized notions of the types of possible “views.” The posograph is a small calculation table designed to determine exposure time and the speed at which the crank should be turned: on one side, the information on the weather, the place, the nature of the contemplated subject are “entered,” and on the other the number to select on the setting ring then appears. This device reviews all possible situations in detail and was a convenient way to calculate this parameter until the photo-electric cell appeared.

Journalistic Discourse, Expert Discourse These two types of discourse originating from the manufacturer (the patent and the explanatory leaflet, to which the promotional discourse of advertising could be added; see fig. 7) were both confirmed and amplified in critical or journalistic discourse as well as in popular books paraphrasing them. Occasionally, these discourses also contested them: for instance, after periodical Cinéa twice evoked amateur cinema, the industry’s organ La Cinématographie française opened its pages to A. P. Richard, a technician who tempered this enthusiasm: “Amateur cinema gave rise to enormous hopes, but it seems that at the moment it is going through a slight crisis which hinders its evolution.” Besides the price of film stock, which made it “impossible to contemplate an intense popularization of amateur cinematography,” technical difficulties awaited the amateur, and these did not appear in the directions for use: “Clever salesmen thought it was enough to turn a crank in any conditions and in any way whatsoever,” Richard objected. “This unfortunate mistake only produced disappointing results. It’s high time every camera buyer was provided with a reliable guide with information on the do’s and the don’ts,” a vade mecum that would feature “something else than sales patter.”31 The “sales patter” targeted by Richard is the promotional discourse of advertising (“the moving image accessible to all,” “shooting a film with the Caméra-Pathé is as simple as taking a random picture with the most simple of standard photographic cameras”32), which points to all the instruc31 A. P. Richard, “L’opinion d’un technicien,” Cinéa-Ciné pour tous 1 Sept. 1927: 24-25, reprinted from La Cinématographie française. 32 These formulas appear in advertisements for the Pathé-Baby (undated, département des Machines, collection of the Cinémathèque française).

The Amateur-Dispositive

315

tions we have already examined. These set norms that facilitated the task of amateur operators, but also led them to conform to a certain type of representation derived from pictorial and photographic representation, to an ideal of stability and duration of the image, to a measure of contrasts and distances. In that respect, an aesthetic may be inferred from the advice and the steps to follow provided by the expert-technician as well as the manufacturer.33 The “dictatorship of posing time” which Richard laments was thus dealt with by Pathé through explanatory tables appearing in the instructions and with the posograph; these were supported by a reference to artistic genres.

A Classic Example: Edvard Munch and the Pathé-Baby In 1927, painter Edvard Munch acquired a camera and a Pathé-Baby projector in Paris. Over the summer, he shot four 9.5 mm films in Dresden, Oslo and Aker, for a total of 10 meters or so lasting just a few minutes. Munch had been a film lover as a spectator and had close ties to Halfdan Nobel Roede, a producer, distributor, and exhibitor, back in the 1910s. Roede had exhibited his paintings in one of his theaters.34 Munch had also had an interest in photography, practicing and studying it, helping his sister Inger to master it, using it himself. How was he to deal with “animated photography”? The Pathé-Baby camera which he purchased was the second model of the brand; it had been created in 1925-1926 and was equipped with an auxiliary driving mechanism using a spring – the Motocaméra already examined.35 Slightly heavier than the previous one, this model still did not involve an optical viewer; it simply featured a frame placed at the front of the camera with a small hole at its center – a hole that had to be aligned with the one

33 This kind of demand, which runs against promotional discourse, may be found throughout the history of amateur cinema. Here is one example: “Do not think there are other, apparently more simple ways, even for a beginner, even equipped with the most automated appliances. The satisfaction you will experience in cinema will be proportional to the care, the attention, the efforts even, which you will bring to your pastime.” 34 See Ingebjørg Ydstie, “Les galeries d’art cinématographiques d’Edvard Munch et Halfdan Nobel Roede,” catalog for the exhibition “Munch. L’Œil moderne,” Centre Pompidou, Sept. 22, 2011 - Jan. 9, 2012. 35 Pathé later commercialized a third model of Motocaméra with the motor integrated to the case, whose elements had been made more compact. A single rewinding was enough to unwind a whole roll of film. “As a consequence, the appliance is always ready for use.”

316 

François Albera

near the operator’s eye (the eyepiece) when aiming the camera after placing it against the cheek, “taking care to hold it in a vertical position.”36 The subjects Munch dealt with seemed to meet the “program” defined for amateurs in the leaflets. His films include the urban views, automobile traffic, tramways, carts and passers-by of the Lumière cinematograph, as well as landscapes, houses, portraits of close relatives, a playlet, and a self-portrait – but the results are different. Was it a deliberate gesture of “transgression” of imposed norms on Munch’s part? An “artistic” gesture similar to Man Ray’s when he deliberately handled the camera without conforming to accepted norms while shooting Return to Reason – throwing the camera up in the air after turning it on, for instance, exposing film directly on the model of the photogram in photography and so forth, seeking out randomness and chance effects? Or should these differences be imputed to the clumsiness of the beginner, who did not master the machine? It is impossible to say, just as it is probably pointless to try and determine it one way or the other. Indeed, these sketches, these trials by Munch, shown end to end by the laboratory that developed the films, attest to the ambiguity of the relations between amateurs and innovators extolled by Roh and Henry. What does appear in these “failures” (over- or underexposure, ghost images, blurs, blacks, proximity making it impossible to identify the object, very swift movements, etc.) is what characterizes the machine. As we have seen, instructions made a type of relation explicit in the handling of the appliance, defining a bodily discipline of the user: “place the Motocaméra against the cheek as indicated in figure 5, taking care to hold it in a vertical position”; “with the right index finger, pull back the start-up lever to trigger rolling immediately. From that moment on, the camera should no longer move…”; “at any rate, avoid movements that would be too quick…” Munch’s films do not show an observance of “technical” recommendations, as the f ilming mode is primarily gestural, against prescribed immobility. Following moving objects or panning on urban buildings or spaces, he did not respect norms, be they about stability, focus, distance or light. Each shot, often brief, involves an abrupt, sometimes back-andforth movement akin to the “tricks” of the kaleidoscope, this paradoxical viewer which, far from allowing “to see better” like its model, the telescope, opens onto imagination, as Baudelaire pointed out. To the reproduction of things in their likeness, to this embalming of passing time, to all these 36 Pathé, Motocaméra, instructions for use.

The Amateur-Dispositive

317

functions related to memory, archiving, entertainment and wonderment, what ultimately makes these analogical and familiar representations possible is added: the deceiving mechanism (everything is founded on some form of illusion – movement, depth, color, scale, sound), but above all the homology of this mechanism with the very mechanism of perception, and even more, of the psyche. Cinema, capturing through the discontinuity of its thousands of photographs the appearance of exterior movement, of “life,” of streets, places, and trains, of smoke and waves, was apprehended by psychologists and philosophers of knowledge and the psyche as the model of inner life at the dawn of the twentieth century. Or, to be more specific, of an inner life restructured by a hectic modern life on the mode of discontinuity, precisely: fits and starts, caesuras, about-turns, simultaneity, fragmentation. The screen rendered the visible world in the form of psychism, day dream, recollection. Félix Le Dantec wrote: “what you call your life is a series of successive momentary lives, analogous to the images of a cinematograph…”37 The year before, Jules Claretie had been struck by his first experience of the cinematograph at the Grand Café, its reality at once truthful and ghostly, but also its fits and starts.38 In one of his exemplary Parisian columns of 1897, he depicted a situation where the “modern brain” is threatened by the “jerky movements” not only physical (the railroad) but also linked to the discontinuity of “this hectic cinematograph which modern life has become,” a “succession of electrical currents” where “characters appear and disappear.”39 Turning his back on the “mastery” advocated in the instruction leaflets prescribing this discipline of the body as a condition for effective, satisfying – “profitable” – filming, Munch did not so much free himself from these as he subjected himself to the appliance and its arbitrariness. 40 If 37 Félix Le Dantec, Le Conflit. Entretiens philosophiques (Paris: Armand Colin, 1901) 166. 38 Jules Claretie, La Vie à Paris, 1896 (Paris: Fasquelle, 1897) 58-60. 39 Jules Claretie, “Trop d’émotions! – Le cerveau moderne,” La Vie à Paris, 1896, chap. XXXVI, 416-17. 40 And as he subjected himself to the signifying effects spectators could not fail to produce, as the skills they had acquired through the viewing of standard films allowed them to decode any “straying away” from the norm. Due to this very set of body movements undoing the representative order, of this overexposure “burning” the image or this underexposure shrouding it in darkness, of this excessively “hasty” movement blurring it, associations surface across films. Within the frame, a relation is thus instituted between an inscription (“Marie”) and the coming and going of a woman, “a passer-by,” its continuation in the following image, shot from a window; or this scathing framing of King Albert of Saxony, reduced to his spurs, the hooves and the bellyband of his bronze horse on a square.

318 

François Albera

the prescribed image met norms and conventional characteristics fixed by pictorial tradition (the portrait, the self-portrait, the landscape, the genre scene, etc.), its “transgression” revealed the crisis of a subject destined for the unintentional, the slip, the random effects of an appliance.



Two Versions of the Television Dispositive Gilles Delavaud

The new gadget seems magical and mysterious. It arouses curiosity: How does it work? What does it do to us? To be sure, when the television sets will have appeared on the birthday tables and under the Christmas trees, curiosity will abate. Mystery asks for explanation only as long as it is new. Let us take advantage of the propitious moment. Rudolf Arnheim, “A Forecast of Television,”1 1935

Many debates on the identity of television as a medium and as an art accompanied its expansion in the United States in the late 1940s and in France in the early 1950s. In 1948, Jack Gould mentioned the fact that television found inspiration in preexisting arts to argue that, precisely because it combined “[…] the close-up of the motion picture, the spontaneity of the living stage and the instantaneousness of radio” and was “the fusion of these three elements,” it was absolutely unique. 2 Reviewing the 1949 season, Flora R. Schreiber was even more assertive: “I am seeking an idiom that belongs peculiarly and uniquely to television. I am not interested in a program that is illustrated radio, or miniature movies, or a photographed stage play.”3 In 1950, anxious about the influence of the Hollywood model in the direction of some shows, Gilbert Seldes warned that in the long term, as the evolution of cinema and the radio showed, a medium could succeed only “by using its particular techniques, by doing what it can do better than any other medium can.”4 In France, the first studies devoted to the new medium appeared in La Revue du cinéma. In 1947, in an article titled “Problèmes de la télévision,” Jean Thévenot endeavored to offer a detailed response to two questions: “What 1 Rudolf Arnheim, Film as Art (1957; Berkeley, Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1997) 188. 2 Jack Gould, “Matter of Form, Television Must Develop Own Techniques If It Is To Have Artistic Vitality,” in Watching Television Come of Age. The New York Times Reviews by Jack Gould, ed. Lewis L. Gould (Austin: University of Texas Press, 2001) 36. 3 Flora R. Schreiber, “Television: A New Idiom,” Hollywood Quarterly (Winter 1949): 191. 4 Gilbert Seldes, “The Twist. Can Hollywood Take over Television,” The Atlantic Monthly, 186.4 (Oct. 1950): 51.

320 Gilles Delavaud

kind of programming will be available on this Television whose advent is no longer in doubt?” “To what aesthetic will they belong? That of cinema? Or one based on principles and rules that will be its own? If so, what would these be?”5 Two years later, the second question was central to an article by George Freedland, “Télécinéma. Essai sur la syntaxe de la télévision,” presented by its author as a “first essay on a new material.”6 From 1952 on, André Bazin made Thévenot’s and Freedland’s questioning his own as he assigned himself the critical task of “inquiring quite modestly,” program after program, into what suited the small screen.7 Each of his articles provided him with the opportunity to wonder what television could do. A similar conception of television emerges from the different discourses on its possibilities and powers and the examination of programs deemed adequate by both the professionals of the new medium and its most attentive observers: television was understood at once as a dispositive for remote viewing and as a dispositive of observation.

1.

Television as a Dispositive for Remote Viewing: The Television Viewer as Observer

Television Proper In his article in La Revue du cinéma, George Freedland, using the American experience as evidence, distinguishes between two modes of remote viewing: television proper (or tele-vision) and the telecinema. To illustrate the expressive possibilities of television proper, that is, the “remote viewing of current events,”8 Freedland gives the example of the major political and media event that was the broadcast of the Republican convention in Philadelphia in June 1948.9 Conscious of addressing a readership of cinephiles not familiar with the new medium, he describes the 5 Jean Thévenot, “Problèmes de la télévision,” La Revue du cinéma 8 (Fall 1947): 59. 6 George Freedland, “Télécinéma. Essai sur la syntaxe de la télévision,” La Revue du cinéma 19-20 (Fall 1949): 122. 7 André Bazin, “Le commissaire Belin doit-il faire les pieds au mur?” Radio-Cinéma-Télévision, 4 Jan. 1953: 2. On the way Bazin approached television, see my article “André Bazin, critique de télévision,” in L’Œil critique. Le journaliste critique de télévision, Jérôme Bourdon and Jean-Michel Frodon, eds. (Brussels: Ina/De Boeck, 2003) 47-56. 8 Freedland, “Télécinéma”: 124. 9 The event was broadcast on the East Coast. On that occasion, NBC, CBS, ABC, and DuMont pooled their technical means.

T wo Versions of the Television Dispositive

321

crucial moment when the television viewer learned that Thomas Dewey had been chosen to face the Democratic candidate10 in the presidential elections of the fall: On their sets the spectators could see in succession – and therefore, according to the rules of film editing, simultaneously: – Dewey the candidate nervously pacing up and down his hotel room; – the convention discussing the candidacies; – the crowd waiting impatiently in the street; – Dewey in his room, staring at the telephone; – the convention announcing the result of the unanimous vote; – Dewey rushing to the phone as it rings; – the delegates at the other end of the line, informing him of his victory; – Dewey putting the phone down, walking to the door; – the crowd in the convention hall, applauding the results; – Dewey’s car leaving, escorted by motorized police; – the hall filled with delegates; – the tribune where the committee prepare to welcome the winner; etc. As we have shown, four shooting appliances were placed in the most important locations: A, Dewey’s room; B, the street in front of his hotel; C, the convention hall; D, the speaker’s platform in close shot.11

If, as Freedland points out, the director “edits in a spontaneous and continuously improvised manner, following the syntax of parallel editing given currency by Griffith,”12 it would be erroneous to conclude that the new means of expression simply mimics cinema. The sequence of actions was probably dictated by the strong influence of a cinematographic code whose narrative and dramatic effectiveness had proved itself, and by the concern not to challenge the spectators’ perceptive habits. Still, this description should first and foremost be heeded for another essential characteristic of the program. Besides the fact that the broadcast made it possible to follow the event as it unfolded, the important aspect was that, as Freedland puts it, one could “observe it better and with more details from a remote position than on the very sites where it was taking place.”13 10 Harry Truman was chosen by the Democratic convention a few months later, also in Philadelphia. 11 Freedland, “Télécinéma”: 123. 12 Freedland, “Télécinéma”: 123. 13 Freedland, “Télécinéma”: 123.

322 Gilles Delavaud

Freedland adds that spectators could see “successively, and therefore simultaneously.” Contrary to the effect which film editing aims at, the succession and alternation of points of view – A, B, C, D – are not meant here to signify the simultaneity of actions. This simultaneity is a given: while cinema organizes succession so as to signify simultaneity, here the aim is to order simultaneity into a succession. Unlike the director of the broadcast, spectators do not have the benefit of several screens side by side corresponding to the different cameras positioned in different places; as a consequence, they do not have access to simultaneity as such and have to reconstruct it, in a way, thanks to the mediation of the director. The most gripping demonstration of simultaneous tele-vision was given to the American public by CBS on November 18, 1951, on the occasion of the launch of the famous news program See It Now, co-produced by Edward R. Murrow and Fred W. Friendly.14 In the opening sequence, before a number of filmed reports were shown, Edward R. Murrow addressed television viewers, explaining that he would host this new weekly program from the very control room of the New York studio where he happened to be, in the middle of machines seen around him. He then turned round to face two monitors, and for almost four minutes viewers were left hanging on his every word: MURROW (turned back, his head looking up at the two monitors). We are, as newcomers to this medium, rather impressed by the whole thing; impressed, for example, that I can turn to Don Hewitt here (leaning over to the director sitting on his left) and say: Don, will you push a button and bring in the Atlantic coast? (An expanse of water immediately appears on the right-hand monitor.) REPORTER (voice). This is camera one at a point of vantage on Governor’s Island. We are looking down into New York Bay on the Atlantic. (The camera closes in: the Statue of Liberty may now be distinguished.) MURROW. There you have the East Coast of the United States… Now, on monitor two, may we have the Pacific Coast, please? (A very blurry image appears on the left-hand monitor.)

14 Produced by Edward M. Murrow and Fred W. Friendly, directed by Don Hewitt, See It Now was the first live program taking advantage of the transcontinental coaxial cable connecting the East Coast and the West Coast after AT&T put it into service. In his Good Night, and Good Luck (2005), a film devoted to the figure of Edward R. Murrow, George Clooney, who played the part of Fred W. Friendly, faithfully reconstructed the conditions in which the show was produced.

T wo Versions of the Television Dispositive

323

REPORTER (voice). Hello, New York. This is the Golden Gate, the waters of San Francisco Bay leading on to the Pacific Ocean. It’s rather hazy out here, Mr Murrow. (The camera closes in on the blurry image on the left-hand monitor.) MURROW. That’s fine, San Francisco. May we have the San Francisco Bay bridge, please? REPORTER (voice). O.K. (The camera tilts up to reveal the suspension bridge.) MURROW. Now, San Francisco, could you use what you call, I think, a Zoomar lens and close in on the bridge a little? REPORTER (voice). Gotcha! (The camera zooms in until it gets to a close view of the left pylon.) MURROW. Ah, that’s fine, thank you, San Francisco. Just stand by for a moment, will you? Hello, New York? REPORTER (voice). Yes. MURROW. May we have the Brooklyn Bridge, please? REPORTER (voice). Coming right up, Mr Murrow. (A very long panning movement to the right follows.) There she is. (The panning shot ends with a slight zoom-in on the right pylon.) MURROW. Brooklyn Bridge. Thank you very much, Eddy Scott. Hold it, please, will you? Now, San Francisco, will you pan over Alcatraz for us, please? REPORTER (voice). Yes, sir… (The camera pans away from the Golden Gate Bridge, to the left, slowly scanning the coast, then the surface of the water to Alcatraz Island.) There it is. (A boat siren may be heard.) MURROW. Can you move in on Alcatraz a little? (slow zoom-in) That’s fine. Excellent. Hold it, please… Now back on monitor one. New York, may we have the New York skyline, please, Eddie Scott? […] (The camera pans away from the Brooklyn Bridge, to the left, revealing the Manhattan skyline.) Now, New York, can you swing us out toward the Narrows, where you look right out at the ocean? REPORTER (voice). We’ll try, Ed… There, we’re going down beyond, by Staten Island. Ah, there are the Narrows, right down that way. There’s where the big ships sail out to Europe and all the ports of the world. MURROW. Good. Thank you very much… Now, San Francisco, can you go out to the Golden Gate Bridge and look straight out to the ocean there? REPORTER (voice). All right… (The camera slowly pans from the buildings on the hill to the harbor; the city is in the foreground, the ocean in the distance.) There it is.

324 Gilles Delavaud

MURROW (turned back, facing the two monitors). Thank you very much indeed, gentlemen. We, for our part, are considerably impressed by the first time man has been able to sit at home and look at two oceans at the same time. […]

The fact that direct, “immediate” television does not go without mediation or selection, and that the selection can be performed only out of a limited number of points of view (four in the report on the Republican convention, two in the opening sequence of See It Now) only stresses the singular status of television viewers. In their private space, in front of a single “monitor,” they are fundamentally observers. As such, they enjoy a double ubiquitousness: occupying successively/simultaneously the different points of view determined by the positions of the cameras on the scenes of the action, they still remain the remote witnesses to whom images are individually addressed as they face their reception screen. Spectators of fiction are no less observers than spectators of news events in front of the small screen. The direction of a live drama also falls within reporting. To borrow from Freedland’s terminology, it consists of the remote viewing of an event – not journalistic but artistic, and in this case televisual, since this kind of event (the staging in the studio of a text written and performed by actors who previously rehearsed it) only takes place to be broadcast, in contrast to the Republican convention, for example. On French television, the broadcast in 1954 of the drama Sixième étage, directed by Marcel Bluwal, may be considered as a model televisual event.15 Sixième étage is a play by Alfred Gehri, which, through a sentimental plot, depicts the lives of the tenants on the top floor of a building of furnished apartments in a popular Parisian neighborhood. The main set involves a corridor on which eight doors open, four on one side, four on the other. At one end of the hallway is the staircase, at the other a window opening on the street. While occupants come in and out of their rooms or apartments, run into one another in the hallway, visit one another, the spectator has “access” only to two private spaces, a room on one side and an apartment on the other, leaving the six remaining living spaces off-screen. The choice of this stage work by a director reflecting on the technical potential of his instrument (the live television studio) and eager to explore its aesthetic possibilities is easily understandable: rather than its intrinsic qualities, the fact is that an action unfolding simultaneously in several contiguous spaces lent itself perfectly to a direction devised in terms of 15 The program was broadcast on May 15, 1954.

T wo Versions of the Television Dispositive

325

transmission. Two cameras operated in the hallway and could follow the comings and goings of this or that character to one of the doors. Then, either the character stepping into a room closed the door behind them and temporarily disappeared from view; or, at the moment she or he stepped into the room, a third camera already there showed him or her coming in from inside the room. As with the broadcast of the Republican convention described by Freedland, cameras ceaselessly took turns to build an orderly, continuous visual unfolding akin to that customary in cinema, on the basis of a given space and an imposed time (“real” time). While viewers are not unsettled (visual continuity follows the codes of the continuity style, with all takes impeccably linking up), something nevertheless becomes obvious to them: on the one hand, all cameras operate simultaneously, in parallel, so as to “cover” the ongoing action as well as possible; on the other hand, the passage from a space to another one (from a take to the next) does not involve a cut but a commutation. Put differently, all these characters moving about under the spectators’ eyes, exiting the frame of a camera to enter the frame of another one, create an increasing sense of surveillance. Remote Viewing and Telecinema In contrast with television proper (or tele-vision), George Freedland refers to any program recorded on film prior to broadcasting as telecinema (or telefilm). He devotes most of his article in La Revue du cinéma to this second form of television. His primary concern is to show in what ways the conditions of reception of televised spectacles differ from those of cinematographic spectacles, and to raise the issue of how the conditions of programming and reception by directors of telefilms may eventually lead to a perceptible transformation of the language of film. The close examination of the material and psychological conditions of the reception of television provides Freedland with the chance to raise a series of questions – most of them related to the delicate problem of the control of a non-captive audience – and consider the responses that in his opinion would be appropriate. After explaining why and how film language should evolve – in terms of continuity, mise en scène, the direction of actors, editing – he comes to the conclusion that film, as conceived for television, will have a pace both slower and more fluid, and that everything in the direction will have to contribute “in the most direct manner” to guiding the spectator’s attention.16 He then proceeds to give more specific examples: 16 Freedland, “Télécinéma”: 128.

326 Gilles Delavaud

A simplification of syntax will ensue from this, and it will reduce the telecinematographic style to the simple work of the human eye, which looks at what goes on around it through “tracking shots” when the individual moves, suddenly interrupted by more or less bumpy still shots or panning shots, with a constant subjective continuity. Television will thus truly be what its name indicates, “remote viewing.”17

What should be understood here by “remote viewing,” with respect not to tele-vision but to televised cinema? A footnote about the expression “subjective continuity” provides a hint. Freedland briefly refers to two recent films which, he suggests, may constitute a kind of model for the foreseeable evolution of film language and its necessary renewal: Robert Montgomery’s 1947 Lady in the Lake and Alfred Hitchcock’s 1948 Rope. The latter, Freedland writes, “shot by Alfred Hitchcock in the studio in twelve days after long weeks of rehearsals, comprises nine reels and… nine shots, that is, nine tracking shots of 1000 feet each.”18 It makes sense that the film, contemporary with the first television programs, caught the attention of the pioneers of the new medium through its “constant continuity,” and in Hitchcock’s own admission, this was in fact one of the points. In 1950, arriving from Great Britain where he had just shot Stage Fright, Hitchcock was interviewed aboard the Queen Mary in the port of New York by Jack Mangan for his program Ship’s Reporter:19 MANGAN (on the ship’s deck next to Hitchcock, holding out a microphone). It’s an old friend, Alfred Hitchcock, the famous motion picture director. Hello Mr Hitchcock. HITCHCOCK. How are you? MANGAN. I just read in the columns recently an article about you in which they said: Gee, we hope that Alfred Hitchcock comes to television because he can bring so much suspense and so much [sic] new, shall we say, trick production methods. HITCHCOCK. Well, I have actually tried a bit of television in a movie, you know. MANGAN. Not on television itself? 17 Freedland, “Télécinéma”: 128. 18 Freedland, “Télécinéma”: 128. 19 The program, featured on the New York channel WJZ (an ABC affiliate), involved interviewing celebrities arriving in the United States and filmed aboard the Queen Mary. The episode mentioned here also included an interview of Jane Wyman, who had worked under Hitchcock’s direction in Stage Fright. Archives of the Paley Center for Media, New York, n.d.

T wo Versions of the Television Dispositive

327

HITCHCOCK. No, no, but I made a movie called Rope, you know, which was shot with one camera all the way through without any cutting. And that in a sense was a kind of preview of television technique. […] That’s what I tried to do in this Rope picture, to give some preview of what would happen on television in the future […].

Film critics and theoreticians have often compared Rope and Lady in the Lake because of the radical choices of very long sequence shots in both cases (24 shots in the former and – exactly – eleven in the latter 20). Yet what Freedland stresses is their common “attempt at a subjective narration.” However, while the mise en scène of Lady in the Lake is indeed based on the systematic use of the point-of-view shot, with everything seen through the eyes of the protagonist (and told in first-person voice-over), the principle guiding the direction of Rope is, by contrast, that of a recording that may be described as objective insofar as the action represented is given to see in itself, in a way, as if there were no narrator. Accordingly, why write of a subjective narration? Probably because in Rope as in Lady in the Lake, though differently, the fluidity of continuous takes and the permanent mobility of the camera give the impression of dealing with the point of view of a “subject” ever alert, seized in the very act of seeing. As it happens, this subject is the spectator. Even as what she or he sees may also be seen by one of the characters, what the spectator sees does not fade to the benefit of what one character sees, any more than what a character sees substitutes for what the spectator sees: at every instant, it is the spectator who sees.21 From a camera movement to the next, shooting proceeds. Until the last minutes, the camera seems to “follow” the action, never to precede it: its performance must remain unobtrusive. This choice of continuity and camera mobility meets a strategy of intensification of seeing, hence the insistence, in critical discourse, on “the camera” – a term that may be taken as a synonym for “spectator”: The camera never comes to rest, never skips from one character to another. It wanders slowly, slowly, to the very rhythm of the action. […] This calculated slowness, this meticulous attention, this commitment not

20 On the découpage of Rope, see David Bordwell, Poetics of Cinema (New York: Routledge, 2008) 32-43. 21 Rope still includes four cuts to a character looking, cuts that correspond to reel changes during the projection. See Bordwell, Poetics of Cinema 33-36.

328 Gilles Delavaud

to miss anything that may be said between the performers, everything creates an extraordinary presence.22

At once close and remote, spectators are the inevitable witnesses of the inexorable progress of the action and the behavior of the characters, who are never out of sight. They can watch out for the least reaction (are the two criminals going to give themselves away, and will their hosts understand that they are being manipulated?). At the same time, they do not see everything: deprived of a feeling of ubiquity usually brought by editing, their field of vision constantly remains in check, relative to the position occupied in space, constrained by the uniqueness of a point of view that appears embodied. What the spectators of Lady in the Lake or Rope experience is thus not so much attending a spectacle as seeing in action. This explains the comparison with the “simple work of the human eye,” which is by definition characterized by a “constant subjective continuity.” Confronted with these two films, I am aware, in either case, of experiencing an “I see.” The look of the camera both precedes and extends my own look (which “looks at what goes on around it through ‘tracking shots’”). The expression “remote viewing,” used by Freedland about telecinema, refers to this mediation.

2.

Television as an Observation Dispositive: Close Viewing and Distanced Look

The Taste for Faces The mediation of the (tele-vision or telecinema) camera did not only make it possible to see far away, but also to see close by, and even very close by. The consistency and recurrence of a metaphor in the discourse of television professionals in the 1940s and 1950s can only impress: television cameras are tirelessly compared to microscopes, radiography (X-rays) or scalpels. No matter the variants, whether understood literally, physiologically or in a psychological sense, the metaphor tells us clearly that the specificity of television, and consequently its calling, lies with its power of penetration

22 A. F., “La Corde,” rev. of Rope, dir. Alfred Hitchcock, Le Monde 1 Mar. 1950: 9.

T wo Versions of the Television Dispositive

329

to ends of observation.23 American producer Edward Barry Roberts said as much in 1952: More than prose, more than the stage, more than motion pictures – oh, so much more than radio – television, with its immediacy, gets to the heart of the matter, to the essence of the character, to the depicting of the human being who is there, as if under a microscope, for our private contemplation, for our approval, our rejection, our love, our hate, our bond of brotherhood recognized.24

The head of programming of French television in the 1950s, Jean d’Arcy, spoke in similar terms of the famous literary show Lectures pour tous (1953), which he had initiated: Under the scalpel of television, one could see the personality of interviewed authors reveal itself in an extraordinary way. I am convinced that nobody truly remembered what the poor authors had said during their introspection, yet we had become deeply familiar with their personality, their heart, their soul, their brain. Hence the success of the program.25

The producer of the show, Pierre Dumayet, summed up the reason for the success of Lectures pour tous in one word: television viewers were “face readers.”26 All critics shared this idea, conscious that television both developed and satisfied what François Mauriac called the “taste for faces” in his L’Express column: “the taste for seeing them close by, for sight-reading them like scores.”27 When Mauriac left the weekly newsmagazine in 1962, his successor Morvan Lebesque revealingly felt the need to start anew from the same acknowledgment: 23 I set out this idea in a previous text, “Le dispositif télévision. Discours critique et création dans les années 1940 et 1950,” in La Télévision du Téléphonoscope à YouTube. Pour une archéologie de l’audiovision, Mireille Berton and Anne-Katrin Weber, eds. (Lausanne: Antipodes, 2009). I am developing it and expanding it here, using other examples. 24 Edward Barry Roberts, quoted by William Boddy, Fifties Television. The Industry and Its Critics (Chicago: University of Illinois Press, 1990) 81. 25 Jean d’Arcy parle, thoughts collected and edited by François Cazenave (Paris: INA/La Documentation française, 1984) 160. 26 Pierre Dumayet, Autobiographie d’un lecteur (2000; Paris: LGF/Livre de poche, 2001) 102. 27 “La chronique de François Mauriac,” L’Express 21 Apr. 1960: 30. Reprinted in François Mauriac, “On n’est jamais sûr de rien avec la télévision”. Chroniques 1959-1964, ed. Jean Touzot, with the collaboration of Merryl Moneghetti (Paris: Bartillat, 2008) 105.

330 Gilles Delavaud

To claim that television has no competitor when it comes to revealing amounts to the most banal of commonplaces. Still, I would like to devote my first column to this commonplace. In life, in the street, anyone can wear a mask. On television, your soul is all over your features […].28

Where did television hold this power to reveal? Pierre Dumayet answered from his own turf – the situation of an interview, in which the interviewee was completely exposed: Completely exposed, that is, exposed at the moment when he ponders what he is going to say, exposed in the intimacy of his silence, exposed with his glasses, his tie, the pimple on his nose, his hair. […] When you are completely exposed, the result is unpredictable. The interviewee cannot plan his facial expressions, the impatient motion of his hands, the way he crosses his legs, the word he is going to forget. And it is rare, outside of television, to be exposed completely for ten minutes in a row.29

For the same reason – “the television camera reveals humans like no other instrument”30 – André Bazin took an interest in all kinds of programs, game shows for instance. Subjected to the test of the game, pressed with questions, candidates still reveal to us, in spite of themselves, their strength of character as well as their weaknesses.31 And when a candidate wins the opportunity of playing on for several weeks in a row, this revelation “becomes deeper and richer […] to the point of sometimes giving us the feeling of an intimate discovery.”32 The same goes for politicians in an electoral period: television viewers are not only sensitive to their arguments, but they also assess the way in which these politicians try to convince them. Without denying that “the powers of conviction of television may be used to negative ends,” Bazin still thinks that the medium provides a kind of resistance to being used as a means of propaganda: if, with television viewers watching, politicians cannot help but reveal something about themselves, then television “is in essence a technique of sincerity.”33

28 Morvan Lebesque, L’Express 1 Feb. 1962. 29 Pierre Dumayet, “L’interview télévisuelle,” Communications 7 (1966): 53. 30 André Bazin, “L’avenir esthétique de la télévision,” Réforme 17 Sept. 1955: 7. 31 André Bazin, “Le jeu et la règle,” Radio-Cinéma-Télévision, 9 Mar. 1958: 7. 32 André Bazin, “Psychologie du Gros lot,” Radio-Cinéma-Télévision 12 Oct. 1958: 9. 33 André Bazin, “Télévision, sincérité, liberté,” Radio-Cinéma-Télévision 5 Oct. 1958: 7. The article is devoted to the campaign for the referendum on the constitution of the Fifth Republic.

T wo Versions of the Television Dispositive

331

Some directors were to actively exploit all the advantages inherent in this vision of television, which emphasized technical mediation, that is, the indelible presence of the camera. The Art of Being Sincere In 1956, coming from cinema, Pierre Cardinal was given the responsibility of producing a documentary series featuring portraits of comedians in the form of interviews.34 He had enough confidence in “the surprising power of television to reveal”35 to let go of the convention of the interview, keep to the background, and leave the comedians to themselves, alone in front of the camera. The program, titled Gros plan [“Close-up”], was prepared methodically: a text was written by the comedian, worked on again in collaboration with the director, then, at the time of the shooting at the home of the comedian, delivered informally to television viewers in a semiimprovised mode.36 Each comedian, while talking about himself or herself, evoking his or her career, work and encounters, was led not only to expose himself or herself, but also to engage in an exercise in sincerity. This was one of the lessons of the series: how each subject accepted – or not – the risk of speaking genuinely through the fiction of a direct address (the program was filmed prior to broadcast). At the beginning of the episode devoted to him, Jean Marais thus points out the strange situation in which he happens to be and how this “conversation” with television viewers puts him in an awkward position: I am at your place at this moment and [yet] I am not. You may be having dinner and you are not inviting me. You are sitting and you are leaving me standing… And as I speak, you may even be criticizing me and talking about me as if I were not here. Is it not a false situation?37

In a more serious tone, smiling mildly to the camera but visibly unsettled, Maria Casarès starts speaking:

34 As a f ilmmaker, Pierre Cardinal had directed Au cœur de la Casbah (1951) and Fantaisie d’un jour (1954). He had also taught at the IDHEC (Institut des hautes études cinématographiques). 35 Télé-Revue 351 (24 Sept. 1961): 15. 36 For an analysis of the series Gros Plan, see Gilles Delavaud, L’Art de la télévision (Brussels: Ina/De Boeck, 2005) 164-70. 37 Gros Plan, program broadcast on March 21, 1959.

332 Gilles Delavaud

You see, I do not like to soliloquize. As for thinking, I would rather not do it aloud. But I know you are there. Oh yes I do! It even takes my breath away. Yet I also know that, while you can see me, look at me, hear me, you still cannot interrupt me or even express through reactions or an eloquent silence your rejection or your approval… It makes me feel terribly uncomfortable and hinders my ability to talk to you.38

The comedian then explains what the infinitely painful experience of cinema represents for her, preferring the theater as she does. As she speaks, looking television viewers in the eye, her words sound like an implicit commentary on the experience she is living through, here and now, as well as an invitation to reflect on the violence of the television apparatus, of which television viewers are a part: Nothing, no one to address directly, no presence to help you but, on the contrary, in front of you, the implacable eye of the camera with its terrible probes and monstrous magnifications, which searches you to the soul.

At the beginning of his self-portrait, Paul Meurisse addresses television viewers as if performing his own self, “deadpan and sententious,” in the words of a critic39: Because of the roles I have played on screen for quite a few years, because of films for which I have been honored to be used, some kind of mystery hovers around my person. I have not sought it, but you have to admit that mystery is addictive: you get caught in it, you start taking pleasure in it, and soon you have become a captive of your persona. Then, a few days ago, the eminent producer of this program, our distinguished friend Pierre Cardinal, came to see me and told me: “I beg you, maestro, lift the veil on the mystery that surrounds you.” I accepted, I understood that such was my duty, and I decided to reveal everything to you, to reveal myself completely in front of you. 40

A double truth emerges from these few examples: sincerity is a test, sincerity is a game.

38 Gros Plan, program broadcast on February 8, 1958. 39 Gilbert Salachas, “Gros plan sur Paul Meurisse,” Radio-Cinéma-Télévision 12 Oct. 1958: 9. 40 Gros Plan, program broadcast on October 4, 1958.

T wo Versions of the Television Dispositive

333

Following these two lines and furthering his portraits of comedians, Pierre Cardinal then directed his first fictional piece for television, Gros plan sur la célébrité (RTF, 1961), after a short story by André Maurois. An epistolary narrative, it consisted of an exchange of letters between a famous writer and his two successive wives. After the death of the writer, both women publish their memoir. An American film producer buys the rights to adapt the two competing accounts but, for moral reasons, asks the two rivals for their characters to be condensed in a single one. In Pierre Cardinal’s mise en scène, the three characters of the short story are played by Pierre Dux, Renée Devillers and Blanchette Brunoy, filmed in their respective homes. They succeed one another in close-up on the screen, looking to the camera as they read the text of a letter. However, as the three characters are gradually revealed, from confidences to confessions, from insinuations to disclosures, television viewers – as readers of faces – progressively come to question a sincerity that appears too ostensible. Observation and Cruelty In the late 1960s Pierre Schaeffer, referring to programs that notably aimed to denounce the myth of an “authentic” voice, coined the expression “research dispositive.” In many respects, this may be seen as a form of radicalization of the conception of television commonly understood as an observation dispositive in the 1950s. The series Vocations (ORTF, national French public radio and television, 1969), created by Jean Frappat within the Service de la recherche headed by Schaeffer, epitomized this approach. 41 Personalities interviewed by Pierre Dumayet were invited to talk about their profession and analyze the birth of their vocation. In the empty studio, with dimmed lights, the interviewer and the interviewee (an actress, a psychiatrist, a lawyer, a philosopher, a priest, a writer…) first had an informal conversation to prepare the interview. The guests evoked some of the themes they wished to develop, provided one or more facts they wanted to comment on. This first sequence was recorded without their knowing. The studio would then light up, cameramen would position themselves behind the cameras, and the interview proper would begin. Finally, the interviewer would admit to interviewees that they had been “tricked,” offering to watch and compare the recording of the preparatory interview and the interview that followed to have them observe the difference in behavior depending on whether they were aware of being on 41 Program broadcast from February 2, 1969 on.

334 Gilles Delavaud

the record or not, that is, whether they tried or not to control their own image. Discussing the series from the experimental approach that was his, Pierre Schaeffer defined the dispositive as follows: The dispositive may be compared to the trap set for the human animal to be captured and observed. Television professionals have sometimes invented dispositives with no other aim than spectacle in mind. La Caméra invisible provides us with the best example of this and, despite all the precautions taken, one of the most cruel. 42

The use of the hidden camera to observe ordinary people without their knowing appeared with television itself. In the first installment of the series Candid Camera (NBC, 1949), 43 one of the sequences took place in a New York department store. Three female customers came one after the other to return the hat they had bought and ask for a refund. Confronted with the refusal of the employee (none other than the host of the show), they found themselves pressured into a lengthy explanation and a justification. The “spectacle” given to television viewers appeared in a simplified form: three close-ups of several minutes each, three faces in tight shots seething with increasingly sharp and embarrassed reactions. 44 Less “candid” (and more sly) was the spectacle proposed almost thirty years later by Jean-Luc Godard and Anne-Marie Miéville’s documentary series France Tour Détour Deux Enfants (INA, 1977-1978). Television, which the authors proposed in some way to reinvent, 45 was explicitly presented as an observation dispositive in the series. In several of the interviews that constitute the core of most episodes, the two children (alternatively a little boy and a little girl, both nine years old) were observed a first time, not by a hidden camera, but by an invisible director questioning them from a distance, through a monitor. Alone in front of the camera, deprived of the presence and the look of their interviewer, unprotected, they were “completely exposed,” sometimes for more than fifteen minutes. They were then observed a second time by the two hosts in the studio who, facing another monitor, commented on their behavior. As Godard put it, “We 42 Pierre Schaeffer, Machines à communiquer 2. Pouvoir et communication (Paris: Seuil, 1972) 158. 43 Imported in 1948 from the radio, produced and hosted by Allen Funt, the program was first broadcast on ABC under the title Candid Microphone, changing to Candid Camera as it moved to NBC in 1949. 44 Program broadcast on May 29, 1949. 45 By modestly doing what they called “de la télévision de quartier,” or “neighborhood television.”

T wo Versions of the Television Dispositive

335

would place them in a situation where everyone had to make a decision so his/her capacity for decision could be seen, without too much time to think. Television makes this possible…”46 Television makes even more possible, though. Its power of “penetration” does not only bear on the subject observed in situation (tight shots, uninterrupted takes, a questioning sometimes deemed intrusive47) but also – and here is perhaps the greatest violence – on the recorded image of his or her body in movement, which the scalpel-television makes it possible to slow down, break down, freeze: in a word, to observe anew. 48 The Unobtrusive Observer Approached as an observation dispositive, television provides authors and directors with a new field for experimentation. The challenge presented to them may be phrased as follows: how to articulate observation and narration, mise en scène (that is, calculating the place of spectators) and conducting the plot. In the American television of the 1940s and 1950s, Fred Coe was probably the most talented and inventive producer. In June 1946, six months prior to the release of Robert Montgomery’s famous Lady in the Lake, he directed “First Person Singular,” the first episode in the series Lights Out! (NBC), integrally in point-of-view shots. In 1949, for the same series, he produced “Long Distance,”49 a kind of televisual equivalent to Griffith films featuring a phone call with a “last-minute rescue”: in New York, a woman desperately seeks to save her imprisoned husband, who has been sentenced to death and is about to be executed. Yet instead of the parallel editing perfected by Griffith, the phone conversation is represented visually through a split screen, reviving a method used in films in the early 1900s:

46 Jean-Luc Godard par Jean-Luc Godard, ed. Alain Bergala (Paris: Editions de l’Etoile/Cahiers du cinéma, 1985) 407 (my emphasis). 47 Godard and Miéville admitted to the restrictive dimension of interviews through the commentary of the two studio hosts, in particular the pressure exerted on the little girl: “It must have been difficult for her […], it is our fault.” 48 On the series, and more specifically on the mise en scène of interviews and the relation to spectators implied by Godard’s conception of television as an observation dispositive, see my article “La place du spectateur,” Godard et le métier d’artiste. Actes du colloque de Cerisy (1998), Gilles Delavaud, Jean-Pierre Esquenazi and Marie-Françoise Grange, eds. (Paris: L’Harmattan, 2001) 121-38. 49 “Long Distance,” Lights Out!, season 2, episode 3, prod. Fred Coe, dir. Kingman T. Moore, perf. Jan Miner, NBC, August 2, 1949.

336 Gilles Delavaud

The first image is an extreme close-up of a phone. A backward tracking shot reveals the hand holding the handset, then the face of the woman, Mrs Jacks, who is prey to a great agitation. Mrs Jacks is shown frontally, sitting at a table, and occupies the left side of the frame. Behind her, a few books and a small clock marking 9 o’clock may be seen on shelves. Mrs Jacks informs the director of the prison that she has just found a letter clearing her husband. She begs him to halt the execution, which is set to take place… half an hour later. At the very moment when the director of the prison picks up the call, he appears from the side, sitting at his desk, in the right side of the frame. He explains to her that it is too late and that only the judge may stop the execution at that point. Mrs Jacks hangs up; the image of the director disappears. Mrs Jacks flips feverishly through the phone book, then dials the judge’s number. A ring may be heard. The judge’s wife picks up the phone, appearing in turn in the right half of the frame, from the side, standing. She tells Mrs Jacks that the judge is in San Francisco and gives her the phone number of his hotel. Mrs Jacks hangs up, the judge’s wife disappears. Mrs Jacks dials a number. A switchboard operator appears from behind in the right part of the frame. Mrs Jacks asks for the San Francisco hotel where the judge is staying. The operator has her repeat the name and address of the hotel, asks her to spell out the judge’s name and spells it out herself, then asks her to wait… The routine calm of the operator stands in sharp contrast with the nervousness tinged with anger of Mrs Jacks who, exasperated with the wait, requires to talk to the chief operator. In the right part of the frame, the chief operator, seen face on, appears in the place of the first operator. Mrs Jacks has to reiterate her request and spells out the judge’s name again. The chief operator encounters some difficulties in setting up the connection with San Francisco… Stark contrast between the professional calm of the operator and Mrs Jacks’s growing anxiety…

T wo Versions of the Television Dispositive

337

Eventually, the image of the San Francisco operator appears in the left part of the frame, replacing the image of Mrs Jacks. For a moment, Mrs Jacks can no longer be seen, but she is still there, intervening in the exchange between the two operators. Mrs Jacks reappears on the left side of the frame. The operator asks her to hang up and wait to be called back; her image then disappears. Anxious wait for Mrs Jacks, who now appears alone in the frame… Behind her, the face of the small clock marks 9:10.

At this stage in the story, ten minutes into the episode, there are twenty more minutes until the execution takes place – and the program ends. The protagonist will still meet many obstacles before she manages to reach the judge… in the last minute. For the first time on American television, an entire fiction was made using the technique of the split-screen.50 On the screen, the alternation and the swift succession of images went hand in hand with an absolute continuity. Throughout the program, the tremulous face of the heroine was visible to the viewers, except in a few rare moments when her image on the left side of the screen was briefly “covered over” by that of a different character. The greatest physical and emotional proximity combined with both the geographic distance (the characters appearing in the right half of the frame) and the distanciation imposed by the very process of the split-screen (with its juxtaposition of two images). Spectators, placed once and for all in front of a woman involved in a desperate struggle, were maintained for an extended time in a relation of exteriority to the screen, their attention wavering between adherence to the drama lived by the character and detached observation of the performance of the actress. In 1953, returning to the principle of point-of-view shooting with which he had experimented from 1946 on, Fred Coe co-produced the series First Person with director Arthur Penn for NBC.51 In all episodes, the action was seen through the eyes of a character-narrator, out of frame but always

50 The New York Times critic then wrote: “By this method, used to show simultaneous action at separated points, two different pictures are transmitted at the same time, each taking one-half of the television screen.” Val Adams, “NBC Offers Two Series of Drama Shows, ‘Academy Theatre’ and ‘Lights Out’,” New York Times 7 Aug. 1949: X7. 51 Six out of the eight episodes were directed by Penn.

338 Gilles Delavaud

present in the scene, and whose interior monologue allowed the viewers to share in observations and thoughts. As the title of the episode “I’d Rather Be a Squirrel”52 indicates, its narrator is a squirrel. Its first sentence defines the position of viewers: “The nice thing about being a squirrel is that you can run up a tree anytime you want to and get a sense of detachment.” When the squirrel moves down a branch and approaches the nearby house, we observe “through its eyes” the daily life of a couple through an open window. The man sympathizes with the squirrel, gives the animal some nuts, talks to it, expresses yearning for a similar life. Because he does not share his wife’s taste for parties and disdains the material comfort she aspires to (she wants to purchase a television set), he eventually moves to the tree to isolate himself, read Thoreau’s Walden, or Life in the Woods, and meditate. From his observation post, he can in turn watch his wife’s guests come and go in his own house. In “Tears of My Sister,”53 Cecilia, the narrator, is a young teenager worried about the fact that her sister Bessie, who is about to marry a rich, older man, cries at night. Her mother tells her that she will understand later that Bessie cries out of happiness. Cecilia, who ignores that her older sister secretly loves another man, always observes her, scrutinizes her face, interprets her least expression, questions her, desperately trying to understand a behavior that remains enigmatic to her. The camera occupies the place of Cecilia, who remains invisible, at once amazingly watchful and effaced. In “Crip,”54 Alan, the narrator, is a seventeen-year old disabled boy who, as a consequence of an accident he had as an infant, can neither walk nor speak. Since he cannot speak, his mother keeps treating him like a child. From his wheelchair, he observes – through the front door – the house which workers are renovating on the same street; and later, at night, through the lit-up windows, the family who have just moved in. His young neighbor Jane visits him and makes out his sensibility and his intelligence. She confides in him and thanks to her, escaping the grip of his mother, he utters his first words. Through Alan’s eyes, we see his mother and Jane, together or in turn, leaning over him and talking to him, confined to his wheelchair as he is. Even though the technique of point-of-view shooting may be deemed contradictory with the classic film dispositive, its use in First Person proves particularly relevant. Indeed, the point is not to reinforce, let alone impose, 52 “I’d Rather Be a Squirrel,” First Person, writ. Harry Muheim, dir. Bob Costello, NBC, July 10, 1957. 53 “Tears of My Sister,” First Person, writ. Horton Foote, dir. Arthur Penn, NBC, August 14, 1953. 54 “Crip,” First Person, writ. Stewart Stern, dir. Bob Costello, NBC, August 21, 1953.

T wo Versions of the Television Dispositive

339

the identification of viewers to characters, to ensure that spectators put themselves “in the place” of characters: it is, on the contrary, to put characters in the place of spectators, so to speak, to conceive them as background observers and thus build the fiction of a model tele-spectator. To the nagging question of the control of viewers which, in early television, preoccupied the authors of fiction as well as directors (how to keep a non-captive audience, how to elicit their participation, how to involve them in what is represented), the episode “Long Distance” in the series Lights Out! and the various episodes of First Person bring a similar answer: betting, not on identification and immersion, but on the concentration of attention and observation. This assumes, each time, the invention of an adequate mise en scène which, while varying considerably from one series to the next and even from one episode to the other, relies on a few elementary principles that represent as many breaks from the mode of representation of classical cinema and the perceptual habits attaching to it: – a strictly oriented, polarized space – the poles of action and observation may not be interchanged, and no reverse shot is possible; – an axial mise en scène organized along an axis perpendicular to the screen, either in depth or projected in the direction of the spectator,55 with no lateral exits from the frame possible; – an audiovisual continuity characterized by very long takes, with switches from one camera to the other masked by cuts on the same side of the axis of action; and by an insistent interior voice that supports visual continuity by accompanying it with an uninterrupted stream of consciousness; – an outright frontality: in the episode “Long Distance,” for example, spectators are clearly placed in front of the image; in the series First Person, they are situated on the threshold of the image, on the edge of the frame, in this fore-frame where the space of the fiction and the space of reception partially overlap, encroach upon each other and, at one point (the point of view), are superimposed and coincide. Not only does a mise en scène ordered in this way assign a determined place to spectators, but it also constitutes them as experimental subjects in their

55 In First Person, such projections arise with characters looking to the camera and regularly approaching the lens, to the point where they appear in extreme close-up. In another series, Cameo Theatre (NBC, 1950), producer and director Albert McCleery did away with the set and had the performers act in front of a black background so as to give the impression that they stood out against the screen.

340 Gilles Delavaud

own perceptual activity: they know that what is given for them to see is given as (already) looked at. The different examples considered, whether involving live or filmed programs, reality of fiction, shed light on the way in which television was apprehended in the early phase of institutionalization, first and foremost by those who “made” it. Understood as a viewing (and listening) dispositive, it did not exactly belong to spectacle as a category. Writers and directors, trained in theater (in the United States) or in cinema (in France), invented a mode of representation which, far from being a simple mix of one or the other, escaped the logic – and the aesthetic – of either. On the one hand, the dispositive for “remote viewing” cancelled distances, turning the spectator in a privileged observer; on the other hand, it made a close vision possible while allowing the observer to maintain a distanced look even in the greatest proximity. The author wishes to thank the Inathèque de France (Paris) and the Paley Center for Media (New York).



Reality Television as Dispositive: The Case of French-Speaking Switzerland Charlotte Bouchez

While scholars are sometimes confronted with the ignorance of their interlocutors about their field of research, anyone who has ambitions to work on “reality TV” is in exactly the opposite situation. The mere mention of the term conjures up an impression of self-evidence, as reality television does not immediately appear to be complex subject matter. Still, a simple look at the phenomenon already reveals a variety of objects. Starting from a study carried out on reality television in French-speaking Switzerland,1 this study questions how the term “reality television programming” has come to make sense within social exchange and examines the nature of this kind of generic category. If reality television does indeed exist, it does so within discourses articulating a definition of it so that their enunciators may enact strategies of social and institutional positioning. I want to take a closer look at the conceptual tools available for the scholar to describe this kind of object, following an approach inspired by the model of the dispositive developed by François Albera and Maria Tortajada.2 I will then proceed to present the most important aspects brought out in the study, which make it necessary to rethink the hypothesis of a single definition and emphasize the specificities of reception in French-speaking Switzerland.

From Ontological Questions to the Model of the Dispositive My point of departure consisted in identifying what the term “reality television” referred to in discourses published in the general Francophone

1 The research concerned the totality of programs produced by regional channel TSR (Télévision Suisse Romande) and branded as “reality TV” in the Francophone Swiss press: Génération 01 (2001), Le Mayen 1903 (2003), Y’a pas pire conducteur en Suisse romande (2004), Super Seniors (2005), L’Etude (2006), Dîner à la ferme (2008 and 2009). 2 François Albera, Maria Tortajada, “Epistémè 1900,” in Le Cinématographe, nouvelle technologie du XXe siècle, André Gaudreault, Catherine Russell and Pierre Véronneau, eds. (Lausanne: Payot, 2004) 45-62.

342 

Charlotte Bouchez

Swiss press.3 I followed Dominique Boullier’s approach, starting from the premise that the reception of a cultural product can be examined only through discourses produced on it. 4 Beyond the pragmatic aspect of this initial stage in the research project, the particular status of discourses in reception processes should be assessed and integrated in a description of reality television that takes account of the very equivocal character of the referent. Indeed, while it often comes up in common conversation or the press, the term “reality TV” refers to many concrete realities as well as several uses and meanings related to the discursive situation of which it is a part. Trying to understand what a reality television program entails thus involves paying attention to the program broadcast on terrestrial television networks, its Internet version – and even to satellite channels in some instances – while analyzing peculiarities in the reception modes involved in these mediums. The analysis of programs themselves may bear on the technical shooting setup as well on the distribution of content, approached in terms of writing and execution; but it may also involve looking at the modes of their diffusion, their frequency, their place in the daily schedule, and their promotion. My assumption is that it is also necessary to take into account the conception of programs at the production stage, to analyze 3 This was based on a corpus of articles from the general-interest Francophone Swiss daily newspapers (24 heures, Le Temps, Le Matin, La Tribune de Genève, Le Nouvelliste, L’Express), the week-end listings supplements and two magazines dealing with social issues (L’Hebdo and L’Illustré). Articles were selected thanks to the search and indexation engine Swissdox, by grouping sources that featured one or several of the following terms: “real TV,” “téléréalité,” “Big Brother,” and “Loft Story” over a period running from 1996 to 2008. Translator’s note: all articles referred to in the study were originally published in French, but their titles, which provide information central to the author’s argument, have been translated in English here. 4 Introducing his field study on the role of conversations about television in the construction of a local public opinion, Boullier writes: “A diff icult and radical reassessment then looms: reception exists socially only in the form of discourses, and research on reception itself does not proceed differently.” See Dominique Boullier, “La fabrique de l’opinion publique dans les conversations télé,” Réseaux 126 (2004): 126. Indeed, field studies, conversations, newspaper articles or television and radio reports and programs on reality television constitute many socially determined situations in which discourses are produced on this object. While only print articles are considered here, these situations as a whole give discourses a common finality: to express, preserve or produce the social interaction deemed adequate by its protagonists – an interaction elaborated through the mastery of social codes that allow protagonists to relate in an appropriate manner some of the notions associated with the referent “reality TV.” More is thus at stake in the study of discourses than the sole study of reception – in the restricted sense of the recipient(s) of the program – since what is taken into consideration, more generally, is both the way the object of study is socially integrated and the specific role discourses play in these processes.

Reality Television as Dispositive: The Case of French-Speaking Switzerland

343

working documents and to interview people involved at that point. Finally, discourses published on “reality TV” or programs, whether on forums or in the general-interest and specialized press, should also be included in the analysis. The way Albera and Tortajada approach cinema in “L’Epistémè 1900” makes it possible to articulate these different aspects together. In their view, the notion of the dispositive, as an “arrangement assigning a place to these protagonists,”5 makes it possible to distinguish between a) the machinery, or the set of elements resulting in representation; b) representation, or what is seen and heard by the spectator; and c) reception.6 Modeling through a dispositive, while it presents an initial advantage, formalizing the most comprehensive description possible, also brings attention to what allows its constitutive elements to coexist in a whole. In other words, it makes it possible to outline the relations developing between the machinery (which has to do with production) and the completed representation (the program), but also between the program and its reception, or between a particular program and other cultural productions present in its field of diffusion. From this standpoint, the dispositive of a reality television program thus refers to the system of relations being established between concrete elements and immaterial elements (concepts), especially the strategies of protagonists relative to objects as well as toward one another, which contribute to the

5 Albera and Tortajada, “L’Epistémè 1900”: 46. To avoid reading a causal logic in the sentence (the dispositive as an “arrangement assigning a place to these protagonists”), I want to emphasize the term “protagonists,” which refers to participants involved before the creation of the program as well as from the moment it is distributed. This avoids privileging a modeling that would approach the program as vectorized in a one-dimensional manner – from production through representation to reception – to instead acknowledge the fact that producers position themselves and are positioned by the dispositive. This leads to consider the dispositive as comprising the program without being limited to it. 6 That the configuration of reality TV programs imposes a given attitude on the spectator is a widespread idea in discourses thematizing the moral danger supposedly represented by a type of program designed to place the audience in a voyeuristic position. A number of works take this approach into consideration from a critical standpoint, including Olivier Aïm, “Une télévision sous surveillance. Enjeux du panoptisme dans les ‘dispositifs’ de télé-réalité,” Communication et langages 141 (2004): 49-59. This primary meaning of the notion of dispositive as what arranges (“dispose,” in French) should be expanded as a concept to encompass the conditions for a given dispositive to emerge and become concrete. On this specific point, taking up the perspective outlined in “The Epistémè 1900” for cinema provides an opportunity to reckon with what exists around the program and allows its reception, without limiting the explanation of its operation to the description of its internal system (which is referred to as representation in this model).

344 

Charlotte Bouchez

situation of the program’s reception.7 As a consequence, the program is approached as the intersection between several meaning-making strategies defined by these protagonists who, at every stage or level (production, shooting, diffusion and reception), determine and justify their actions according to what they think they know about the other levels involved, but also their perception of the situation in which they operate. At the level of machinery, for instance, the program is conceived on the basis of the producers’ perception of the field of television production, and more particularly its economic structure. 8 The formats9 of reality TV are designed to meet as closely as possible the conditions of diffusion brought about by the deregulation of media markets in the late 1980s as well as social and cultural evolutions related to globalization. Reality TV, whether considered a type of commercial product or a televisual genre,10 thus seems to epitomize televisual production in an age of transformation for Western societies.11 A decisive contribution of cultural studies 7 My argument is that the dispositive is polarized toward reception. However, this perspective does not exclude cases where a dispositive is not actualized and remains in the state of a project. Quite the opposite: given the way the production of this type of program works (what is sold to television channels is a format, that is, a description of the program), it is also interesting to analyze this mode of existence for a program – even as the format itself is structured precisely with a view to reception. 8 For an overview of the structural changes in a globalized televisual economy, see Chris Barker, Television, Globalization and Cultural Identities (1999; London: Open University Press, 2003) and Contemporary World Television, Sinclair John and Greame Turner, eds. (London: British Film Institute, 2004). 9 In the glossary appearing at the end of their article, Guy Lochard and Guillaume Soulez propose the following definition of the word format: “a set of parameters for a program, described from a technical or economic standpoint (selection of candidates, process of elimination, living rules for the candidates, diffusion and commercialization).” See “Une mondialisation inachevée: limites, non-frontières de la télé-réalité. Essai de synthèse,” Médiamorphoses, special issue (Mar. 2003): 167. 10 François Jost has worked extensively on this issue of reality TV as a genre, showing that these programs come within the tradition of other televisual genres from which they borrow formal elements and use them as markers or indicators to guide interpretation. For Jost, the particularity of reality television programs lies in their mobilization of elements traceable to different genres, which as a consequence opens them to variable readings. See François Jost, La Télévision du quotidien: entre réalité et fiction (2001; Brussels: De Boeck Université, 2003); Le Culte du banal: de Duchamp à la télé-réalité (Paris: CNRS, 2007); and L’Empire du Loft (la suite) (Paris: La Dispute, 2007). 11 Much research rests on an interpretation of reality television programs as particularly representative of the cultural orientations of Western societies. According to Olivier Aïm, “From reality TV to television series, exhibition and the mise en scène of the self, which go with modern injunctions to visibility, transparency, free, unfettered speech, are the true distinctive signs and the technical-economic foundation stone of an aestheticized operation of symbolic

Reality Television as Dispositive: The Case of French-Speaking Switzerland

345

approaches, developed in the wake of Arjun Appadurai’s work on media globalization,12 has been to highlight the relations between the perception of a globalized world and the rising demand that regional identities be taken into account. This parallels the tension between an increased standardization of cultural products meant to improve their circulation and an opposite logic of adaptation and singularization to ensure that they take hold in their areas of diffusion. Reality television programs are built on this logic: for producers, the challenge is to anchor a program in reception contexts specific to the different cultural spaces in which it circulates.13 Considering how the sales of reality television programs take place at an international level, French-speaking Switzerland constitutes a rather original case, since the totality of reality TV programs distributed by regional Francophone channel TSR was designed in-house: none of these is a variation on or the adaptation of a preexisting format. However, the tension between innovation and integration within the lineage of a standard model clearly appears through their reception in the press. As I will argue, this articulation is akin to that playing out between the global and the local – with the global referring to the space where standard reality TV productions originate and the local pointing to the TSR’s own supply.

Dispositive / Discourse / Reception For the spectator, the reception of a program implies processes of reinscription in the continuity of previous cultural productions present in the cultural space where it is diffused. Otherwise, it may not even be

expropriation.” See Olivier Aïm, “La culture populaire aux prises avec ses circuits: le cas de la télévision,” Mouvements 57 (Jan.-Mar. 2009): 22. 12 Arjun Appadurai, Modernity at Large. Cultural Dimensions of Globalization (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1996). 13 The way formats of reality TV function led to a comparative study of the different versions of Big Brother, published in a special issue of Médiamorphoses, “La Téléréalité, un débat mondial. Les métamorphoses de Big Brother.” Médiamorphoses, special issue 3 (June 2003). Other publications adopting a comparable perspective include Les Temps télévisuels: “Big Brother”, ed. François Jost (Paris: L’Harmattan, 2004); Elodie Kredens, “La téléréalité, entre adaptabilité des formats et particularités nationales,” proceedings of the ICIC conference (Paris, 2006), available at http:// www.observatoire-omic.org/colloque-icic/omic_icic_atelier22.php [last accessed on July 28, 2012]; Frau-Meigs Divina, “Big Brother et la téléréalité en Europe, fragments d’une théorie de l’acculturation par les médias,” in “Image(s) et Société,” Les Cahiers du Circav, Michel Chadelier and Isabelle Roussel-Gillet, eds. (Lille: CIRCAV, 2004): 15-24.

346 

Charlotte Bouchez

identif ied by its potential viewers.14 Indeed, programs are not born ex nihilo: their producers as well as people receiving them situate them in the lineage of other objects, other dispositives,15 whether televisual – as with the relation between Loft Story (France, M6, 2001) and a sitcom like Friends16 – or coming from other areas – as with the connections between Big Brother and Biosphere II, a scientific experiment that reportedly inspired it,17 or between the recording apparatus of Big Brother and its relation to electronic surveillance.18 While these relations are present in the program, 14 One of the few systematic investigations carried out on the reception of reality TV in Great Britain has shown that these programs are clearly perceived by their spectators from a perspective that makes it possible to situate them in relation to other television productions. See Annette Hill, Restyling Factual TV. Audiences and News, Documentary and Reality Genres (London: Routledge, 2007). However, because the individuals interviewed for the research discussed reality TV on the basis of a list of programs, it is impossible to determine whether or not the programs in question would spontaneously have been placed in that category, or even if the program is the most relevant unit to qualify reality TV (a criterion such as “the fact of being filmed uninterruptedly” may be more decisive, and in that case webcams would have to be included in the research). 15 This hypothesis may be put into perspective with some aspects of the notion of epistemic scheme developed by Albera and Tortajada for the cinematographic dispositive. Reality television would then be considered as “belonging [itself] in a network, a larger epistemic configuration,” a definition “in inclusion” where the dispositive of reality television would be related to other objects, concepts and practices which have existed before it, and which it would involve in a new configuration. “As a scheme, it would then produce a use for a model, not only within the restricted field of visual dispositives, but also beyond,” in the areas of telecommunications, the theater, political life, etc., which would form an “expansive” definition of it. See Albera and Tortajada, “L’Epistémè 1900”: 49. 16 In his book on Loft Story Olivier Razac gives a very detailed analysis of similarities between the two programs with regard to sets and the “stereotyping” of characters, showing that Loft Story borrows elements that already belong in a specific televisual tradition and can thereby be more easily apprehended by audiences. Olivier Razac, L’Écran et le zoo: Spectacles et domestication, des expositions coloniales à Loft Story (Paris: Denoël, 2002). 17 Sylvie Kerviel, “Aux origines de Loft Story,” Médiamorphoses, special issue 3: 10-12. While this lineage with the Biosphère experiment has been established in a few sources, it is hardly mobilized in this corpus as a whole – unlike the comparison of participants in these programs to “laboratory rats” or the description of programs as “experiments,” frequent in these articles. 18 Many publications in scientific literature take as their subject the analogy between reality television and electronic surveillance, and more largely between reality television and Bentham’s panopticon as a dispositive. See Ctrl [space]: Rhetorics of Surveillance from Bentham to Big Brother, Thomas Levin, Ursula Frohne and Peter Weibel, eds. (London: Routledge, 2002). According to Pascal Froissart, “No matter the language or culture, the ‘panoptic’ dispositive predominates […]. This was to be expected: the surveillance apparatus is a constant in the game, to the point of becoming a genuine rhetorical ploy in it. Unlike traditional audiovisual production, in which the dispositive tries to play down its technical dimension, cameras here are shown, exposed (and most of the time, they look down, as in a surveillance apparatus, precisely). One can say with confidence that they serve as an identity marker, and even as a visual epitome.” Pascal

Reality Television as Dispositive: The Case of French-Speaking Switzerland

347

“engraphed”19 in it, they also result from discourses framing the program, which make it possible for these associations serving as landmarks or guides for reception to be reinforced and legitimized. What allows us to define a given program as “reality TV” is thus not necessarily indicated by the program itself, but also by discourses, “official” or “private,” which through a set of descriptive as well as normative elements contribute to elaborate a reception framework. What is to be understood is how spectators localize what they see in a history/memory which they can share in part with others,20 with the press acting as an available resource to build this territorialized cultural sense of belonging. For the scholar, these discourses are so many elements providing indications on the cultural imaginary with which reality television is associated, and to the development of which it contributes.21

The Construction of “Reality TV” as a Genre in French-Speaking Switzerland The examination of print articles in the corpus also points to the need for a diachronic perspective: the gradual construction of a generic category, “reality TV,” in French-speaking Switzerland may thus be shown in detail, Froissart, “Archivages du panoptisme, la téléréalité sur internet, Médiamorphoses, special issue 3: 15. 19 I borrow the term from Eric Macé, Les Imaginaires médiatiques, une sociologie postcritique des médias (Paris: Editions Amsterdam, 2006). The author uses “engrammé” to refer to processes by which a cultural product is marked with significations tied to the social imaginary of the community in which it is diffused. 20 The feeling or the belief for the spectator to take part in collective life through the shared consumption of television programs seems to constitute a motivation, a gratification which should be taken into account to understand the “enthusiasm” for reality television. 21 The status of the general-interest press and of television in its strictly informative activity makes them privileged sites to analyze what belongs in an imaginary, that is, a set of beliefs and knowledge on a world believed to be shared – and in this perspective, reality television is only one object out of which these operations form. Indeed, print media function as intermediaries between producers and distributors of programs and their potential spectators. This position translates into the circulation of discourses and may be noted in a critical approach, as discourses in the press often repeat those of producers verbatim, perhaps insufficiently taking into account the change of discursive register (from promotion to information) involved in the shift from production to journalism. On this point, see Pierre Bourdieu, Langage et pouvoir symbolique (Paris: Seuil, 1982); Cornelius Castoriadis, L’Institution imaginaire de la société (Paris: Seuil, 1975); and Patrick Charaudeau, Les Médias et l’information. L’impossible transparence du discours (Brussels: De Boeck, 2005).

348 

Charlotte Bouchez

with its use by the main cultural players (the press and regional television) as a medium to position themselves. My analysis of the French-speaking corpus in Switzerland validates the thesis that the perception of the global as a horizon of reference necessarily comes with a symmetrical reinforcement of a position anchored in the local. The integration of reality television in a local cultural imaginary takes place in three main stages: the relation of programs with social practices outside reality television, but which rest on a crystallization of logics of social control; the characterization of a standard for reality television (epitomized by Loft Story) concomitant with the emergence of discourses constructing Francophone Swiss cultural identity as a reaction to this production and the social excesses it represents; and the progressive construction of a French-speaking Swiss standard for reality television that respects the dual identity characterizing the channel producing the programs in question (the status of a public service and the fact that it is anchored in French-speaking Switzerland). I should mention that, while it is possible to outline three main periods in the reception of reality television in French-speaking Switzerland, these still overlap to some degree. Discourses that articulate comparisons between reality television and other dispositives more likely to be associated with it (whether these are dispositives of social control or spectacular dispositives like the theater) are frequent over the entirety of the period examined. However, the stabilization of a standard for the genre mostly took place on the occasion of the diffusion of Loft Story in France (April 2001), a period when the first occurrences of the term “reality TV” appear in the sources consulted. The notional content of the term, which was used mainly from that moment on, had been elaborated over the previous years: the semantic field of reality television thus partly overlapped with that of “real TV,” “reality shows,” and concepts associated with the term “Big Brother.” When the program Big Brother was launched in the Netherlands in 1998, the term was already present in discourses to refer to some changes affecting social practices, notably the increasing resort to electronic surveillance and an intensification of modalities of control management applying to private businesses as well as the state. The term “Big Brother” gradually became pivotal in the semantic relation established between the program and these practices,22 in particular for what was connected with the regime of 22 In that respect, the title of the first article on the Dutch program which appeared in Le Temps is telling: “Nine people spied on day and night: a Dutch television channel reinvents Big Brother,” Le Temps 22 Sept. 1999: 12.

Reality Television as Dispositive: The Case of French-Speaking Switzerland

349

looking implied by the program, in which spectators “spied on” participants through the cameras.23 The emphasis on this voyeuristic position founded the relation between televisual entertainment and the social manifestations of “Big Brother.” The first reality television programs were thus related to one another over a backdrop of representations and practices associated with new technologies of communication and surveillance, whether these were considered as instruments of social control or emancipation, but also with the increase in cultural productions conferring a form of star-value on the anonymous.24 However, this perception of reality television amounted to criticism from the outside, since in the early years such production did not concern the French-speaking cultural space in Switzerland. The diffusion of Loft Story in France was to provoke more committed reactions among Francophone Swiss cultural and intellectual players, with an inflation in discourse manifested in the extensive discussion of the program. Indeed, Loft Story gave rise to important press coverage, quantitatively and qualitatively.25 Despite this profusion, what stands out is the regular repetition of the same type of statement in most sources to describe the new program,

23 “The nine “happy few” (there were 3,000 applicants in the Netherlands) will be spied on 24/7 by 24 cameras, including several infrared cameras operating at night, as well as 59 microphones. No chance to elude the watchful eye of the camera: no blind spot, even in the shower.” “Nine people spied on […],” Le Temps 22 Sept. 1999: 12 (my emphasis). An article on the Spanish version of the program similarly refers to it as “this program celebrating voyeurism.” “In turn, Spain is swept along by the ‘Big Brother’ effect,” Le Temps 9 May 2000: 21. 24 Without claiming to be exhaustive, I want to mention the following sources: “How the media can lead to fascism,” La Tribune de Genève, 10 Nov. 1997: 2; “Wiretapping. Banks and Far-Reaching Ears,” Le Matin 13 Jan. 1998: 12; “Surveillance: Thinking of Big Brother,” Le Matin 5 July 1998: 10; “From Vennes to Ecublens, Let’s Drive Smoothly: Big Brother Is Going to Take Care of Us,” 24 heures 17 June 1998: 12; “Big Brother Opens the Mail. These E-mails That Give You Away,” La Tribune de Genève 18 Nov. 1998: 22; “Eyes upon the Users,” La Tribune de Genève 4 Dec. 1998: 5 (the article deals with the installation of video cameras on Swiss trains); “Big Brother at the Stewards’,” La Tribune de Genève 16 Dec. 1999: 26; “Buses in Annemasse Get Equipped, ‘Loft Story’-Style,” La Tribune de Genève 4 July 2001: 28. 25 Le Matin, for instance, devoted 23 articles to Loft Story during the period of its diffusion, from April 26 to July 6, 2001. In that respect, newspaper headlines – which function not only as visual attractions, but also as ways to signal a phenomenon which readers/television viewers should know about to express their belonging in the community – are one discursive element of note. Loft Story was thus the subject of ten newspaper headlines, all mediums included. Sources also show a kind of (sometimes indirect) injunction to the reader to take part in, or at least to be aware of the existence of, reality television programs. An article published in Le Temps, for instance, defined Big Brother as a “social phenomenon,” thereby also contributing to bestow that status on the program. “In turn, Spain is swept along […],” Le Temps 9 May 2000: 21.

350 

Charlotte Bouchez

especially from the standpoint of its technical apparatus. 26 Adopting a form of technological determinism, these sources systematically highlight the number of cameras used to monitor participants, endorsing the premise that the supposed transparency of the recording allows an augmented realism, and that the number of cameras guarantees a kind of total capture matched afterwards by the so-called uninterrupted diffusion of the taped content. Seen as a guarantee of realism, the apparatus is also denounced as morally problematic, for participants as well as producing institutions and television viewers. Reality television comes across as anxiety-provoking, the sign of a cultural evolution that leads to a form of social exclusion: individuals risk becoming alienated in a system where they are worth only as much as their competitive abilities; they risk losing their identity due to media overexposure; and these programs are taken as the sign of an aging, fin de siècle civilization, depending for its entertainment on humiliation, the celebration of boredom and unrestrained voyeurism.27 Over the same period, “reality television” as a referent becomes more stable, referring to a clearly identified televisual production, one just as clearly condemned by its legitimized commentators.28

26 As the program was being launched, most sources on Loft Story started with a brief formula reiterating its main characteristics. An excerpt from an article published in 24 heures thus reads: “The principle is well-known: five women and five men are locked inside an apartment for 10 weeks, without newspapers, radio, television or telephone. In short, without contact with the outside world but under the permanent watch of 26 cameras (including three infrared cameras) and of the public in charge of eliminating them week after week.” “Truth can be stranger than affliction,” 24 heures 28-29 Apr. 2001: 34. Another piece explains: “Cameras are planted all around the loft (except in the toilets), no fewer than 26 of them, including three infrared cameras, as well as 50 mikes (11 clip-ons, one per participant), with 134 people mobilized 24/7 to run the technology!” “French ‘Big Brother,’ ” Le Matin 26 Apr. 2001: 16. 27 Some articles draw a comparison between reality TV programs and circus games in ancient Rome, pointing out the decadent character of the latter and, by analogy, of contemporary productions. 28 By way of example, this article was published in 24 heures the day before the first episode of Loft Story aired: “Loft Story represents the first version of this reality TV that has been invading small screens all over the world for the past two years (see Big Brother). M6 is the first major Francophone channel that dares to step into ‘keyhole television,’ that genre that turns us into voyeurs.” “No to ‘keyhole television’ and to ‘trash programming,’” 24 heures, 24 Apr. 2001: 18. I emphasize the use of the deictic (“this reality TV”), as it expresses the idea that the reader already has some kind of knowledge on the type of program Loft Story belongs to. The journalist’s statement also conveys the idea that the program is designed to place spectators (writer included) in a voyeuristic position (“that genre that turns us into voyeurs”).

Reality Television as Dispositive: The Case of French-Speaking Switzerland

351

The TSR’s Reaction to French Programming: Cultural Issues and Institutional Positioning Loft Story thus represented an opportunity to produce a body of knowledge in the press. It served as a standard of sorts for reality television, a standard taken to apply to world production as a whole. However, even as reality television was clearly presented as a type of transnational program, the origin of the programs was systematically brought up.29 In the case of Loft Story, the origin of the program even became a central issue in discourses: the border between France and Switzerland, nonexistent when it comes to televisual diffusion, was metaphorically redrawn to correspond with the outlines of a cultural space of resistance. In discourses, the TSR symbolized this locally determined identity, with its institutional positioning expressed through a form of division in the definition of reality television (“there is French reality TV, then there is the reality TV we produce”). This made it possible to construct the channel as the embodiment of a certain cultural identity threatened by the “invasion” of reality television as it existed on a global level.30 The (few) statements made by the representatives of the TSR on French reality television between 1998 and 2001 express a categorical dismissal of this type of program on the grounds that it would be incompatible with the institutional status of the channel.31 Positioning itself in 29 In his book on the history of public-sector television in Europe, Jérôme Bourdon deals with this theme of the reception of reality television: “For channels, whether public or private in this instance, it has been a frequent habit to define reality TV in national terms (even though the genre quickly became global). This rhetoric of the national has functioned in both directions: to reject the genre as ‘foreign,’ unsuitable in ‘our culture,’ or conversely, to stress the inferiority of ‘our television,’ engaged in reality TV where foreign televisions ‘resist’ better.” Jérôme Bourdon, Du service public à la télé-réalité. Une histoire culturelle des télévisions européennes 1950-2010 (Paris: INA Editions, 2011) 200. 30 It should be noted, at the risk of exaggerating this factor of the competition from French programs, that the period coincided with the arrival of Gilles Marchand at the helm of the channel. The “event,” marked by a press conference, was covered in several articles that noted the director’s will to assert the French-speaking Swiss identity of the TSR, as the following excerpt shows: “[Gilles Marchand] stated how strongly he valued this relation of trust with French-speaking television viewers, an ‘added value’ linked to an identity on which the TSR was planning to rely in its ‘struggle against the competition of French channels, among others.’ This regional localization should be found ‘in all programming.’ Not to worry: the cultural, political, economic and linguistic identity Gilles Marchand advocates is ‘modern, tolerant, open on the world, rife with projects.’” La Tribune de Genève 10 Aug. 2000: 18.  31 “[Gilles Marchand] has not changed his opinion and is sticking to his claim that the Frenchspeaking channel will not diffuse that kind of ‘real TV.’ To face the tough competition of French channels, the TSR plans to keep trying to establish a long-term relationship with its audience. Gilles Marchand underlined that it was going to highlight regional programming increasingly

352 

Charlotte Bouchez

ethical terms, the TSR combined this identity of “public service” with its localization in French-speaking Swiss culture, whose values its programs purportedly reflected.32 However, this stance evolved in 2001 with the airing of Génération 01, the first reality TV program produced by the channel.33 This provided the TSR with an opportunity to defend a middle-of-the-road position, between censuring the methods of reality television and adopting them. Indeed, the program involved fundamental differences compared to what was supposedly the standard of the genre.34 Only through discourses could these differences be made to signify and be inscribed in an argument presenting them as deliberate choices to “bend” the standard to the norms of public-sector television. Functioning as the “signs” of the specificities of public-sector television, these characteristics were also integrated at a second level, in a discursive logic that made it possible to define and proclaim an identity specific to the TSR as an institution: its status, not only as a public-sector channel, but also as a channel for French-speaking Switzerland. In most sources, Génération 01 was accordingly described using a list of similarities to and differences from Loft Story, which situated it within a logic of continuity and distinction by comparison to reality television on private commercial channels. These sources indirectly provide information on the norm of reference holding sway in the press at the time. Their analysis points to some invariants in the presentation of the programs: the confinement of participants in a closed place, the uninterrupted recording of their behavior, the organization of their living quarters according to the modalities of recording, the daily diffusion of events having taken place that day, the Internet version of the program, the audience’s vote to pick so as to convey the cultural diversity of Francophone Switzerland.” “The TSR’s Overall Ratings Declining. Loft Story Is Here,” La Tribune de Genève 27 July 2001: 91. 32 Among the strategies supposed to help construct this identity for the TSR, a form of anthropomorphic tendency may be noted in these sources, with moral positions as well as affects being attributed to the channel. This aspect of discourses does not concern the TSR alone, however, as expressions tending to construct television channels as unified agents, endowed with intentionality and moral consciousness, are after all quite common in everyday speech. 33 I will privilege the reception of the program in the press here. For a thorough description of Génération 01, see Gaëten Clavien’s detailed article, “La réplique du service public en Suisse romande,” Médiamorphoses (June 2003): 109-15. 34 Génération 01 did not offer non-stop diffusion and the program aired once the shooting was over. Though designed as a game show, the program did not feature internal elimination between participants but a system of votes by television viewers, who elected the winner at the close of the one-to-last episode.

Reality Television as Dispositive: The Case of French-Speaking Switzerland

353

the winner in the final. The TSR’s head of programming still insisted on a point that was to allow the channel to take a moral stance: the rejection of a principle of elimination of participants. However, journalists at La Tribune de Genève soon revealed that Génération 01 was a fake, entirely scripted and performed by actors, designed to stir a “debate” on reality television. The last scheduled episode began like the final of the contest but, once the real nature of the program had been disclosed, it continued as a debate between the representatives of several European public-sector channels (France 2, RAI) as well as a sociologist and a psychologist. The conclusion of this exchange between legitimized participants was the affirmation that reality television programs were not appropriate on television channels with a public service mandate. This allowed the TSR to position itself against private channels but with other public-sector channels reacting similarly in their own area of diffusion. For the TSR, Génération 01 was thus clearly an opportunity to brand itself as a company characterized by its identity as a public service provider radically different from its French private competitors. This positioning was to evolve in 2003, when the TSR aired Mayen 1903, a reality television program whose presentation in the press offered an opportunity to build an identity no longer defined in relation to alterity, but in and of itself, with the program functioning as a medium to flaunt positive cultural specificities.

Mayen 1903: The First Attempt at a TSR “Homemade” Reality Television Following a logic similar to that of Génération 01, Mayen 1903 was introduced in the press as an adaptation of the formal characteristics of reality television to the institutional missions of public-sector television. The program, which was supposed to foster reflection on the heritage of French-speaking Switzerland, was defined in discourses through its sociological and historical purpose35: The issue is twofold: historical, since the point is to reconstitute the living environment and conditions of 1903; and sociological, because it will give a family the chance to experience a life close to nature.36 35 This pedagogical ambition was reinforced by the collaboration of sociologist Bernard Crettaz in the design of the program, which the sources presented as a scientific guarantee for the legitimacy of Mayen 03. 36 “They Are Going to Live As People Did in 1903,” Le Matin 12 July 2003: 16.

354 

Charlotte Bouchez

Besides this characterization of the program as part of a pedagogical approach, a predominant place was given to the figure of Béatrice Barton, the producer and designer of the program. Most sources directly credited Mayen 03 to her (“her concept,” “Béatrice Barton’s new program”), with a frequent emphasis on the connection between her personal history and her choices in terms of program design. Serving as a privileged enunciator for the intentions of the TSR, she was presented in the press as a sensitive personality, a quality often mentioned as a guarantee for the standard of programs developed by her. This becomes apparent when the choice of a shooting location is motivated by the fact that the producer “fell in love” with it,37 or in the interviews of some participants justifying their decision to take part in the TSR’s program because of their trust in Béatrice Barton. Such insistence on the sensitivity and personal involvement of the producer in her work also contributed to the personalization of the TSR as a company defined by the coherence of its programming, its ethical dimension and its privileged ties with the French-speaking Swiss audience. The tension between an inscription of Mayen 03 in the continuity of reality television programs produced by private French channels up to that point and a divergence from these was clearly a theme in discourses examined. Doing away with some characteristics, while making the positioning of the program as reality television more problematic, was thus justified as the result of an adaptation of the genre to the channel’s moral imperatives. An article published in Le Temps, for example, began with a description in the negative – namely, what the program was not – then proceeded with a characterization in line with the cultural orientation of the TSR: This is not a game: there is no elimination, no competition, not even spectacular accomplishments. It is not a “Loft” in the altitudes either. Participants are not completely cut off from the world, cameras do not track them down 24/7, but they have to work hard to support themselves. This is Swiss-style reality television, that is, a television that respects participants and relies on a pedagogical project combining entertainment and learning.38

The wish to offer innovative programming while claiming to do so within the framework of reality television as a genre was also obvious in the creation of an ad hoc designation for the program. The TSR’s press release (and 37 “I looked for this Mayen all winter long!” Le Matin 12 July 2003: 21. 38 “Reality TV: French-speaking Switzerland takes the plunge,” Le Temps 10 Sept. 2003: 12.

Reality Television as Dispositive: The Case of French-Speaking Switzerland

355

most sources) introduced it as a “documentary series” or a “sociological serial.” In the quote that follows, the new term chosen brings together the two televisual genres at whose intersection the program is situated, and which it is supposed to unite: I would say that we are making a doc-serial [“feuilleton-docu”]. Doc, because the goal is to revisit history, to turn a memory into words and describe what the existence of Valais peasants was like a century ago. Serial, because we are using the tricks of fiction, for example with the cast embodying characters whom the audience can identify with.39

The TSR’s Version of Reality Television: Stabilization of a Formula and Variations on It Articles sometimes feature two contradictory discourses, as the focus shifts back and forth between the journalist as enunciator and the channel. Still, these discourses never stop paralleling each other over the whole period examined. Even though discourses originating in the TSR seem to have as their purpose to assert a specificity of the channel’s programs and an important break away from the standards and practices of reality television on a global scale (including French productions), the discourse of journalists – while relaying this position – also maintains a second network of inscription, in which the programs are presented within a stronger continuity with these standards. This aspect shows in the adoption of a double terminology to qualify the TSR’s programs. While most articles use the terms proposed by the channel, pointing to the singularity of its programs compared to standard productions, they also express their lineage with French productions. Some articles devoted to Mayen 1903 refer to the program as an “Alpine Loft” and Super Seniors is sometimes called the “Star Ac’ of Seniors.”40 Situating the program in a logic of succession diverging from that proposed by the TSR, journalistic enunciation also produces a positioning of its own in relation to other news media, television and the readers/viewers it addresses. 39 “Le Valais en 1900,” La Tribune de Genève 9 Aug. 2003: 26. 40 “The TSR Launches a Rural Loft,” Le Matin 9 July 2003: 10. The term is also used in “Béatrice Barton, reine de l’information-divertissement,” Le Matin 20 June 2003: 18; and in “Reality TV: Now, the Seniors,” Le Temps 10 May 2005: 12. Translator’s note: Star Ac’ refers to Star Academy, a mix of pop music talent contest and reality television, which in France aired on private channel TF1 for eight seasons (2001-2008).

356 

Charlotte Bouchez

A tendency, reinforced by the launch of Super Seniors, may in fact be noted: French-speaking Swiss reality television became commonplace as one of the versions of the genre, even as “TSR reality television” as a category was simultaneously undergoing a gradual stabilization. 41 This re-inscription of the TSR’s programming in the televisual choice available (or at least assumed to be well-known) in the French-speaking area of Switzerland also played a part in the relation between newspapers and their readership. Affirming the position of a – potentially critical – viewer toward the TSR, journalistic enunciation sided with those watching not only the Francophone channel, but television as a whole (“we watch the same channel, but also French channels”): French-speaking Swiss readers and television viewers. The TSR’s production was underlined as a form of sub-genre, “publicsector reality television.” Thus it corresponded to an evolution noted in the programs themselves, which appeared as variations on the same standard, formally as well as in their concept or progression. Several elements contributed to this logic of variation. Already mentioned is the fact that all these programs were designed and produced by the same person, Béatrice Barton. Her “presence” in the press was a factor in the affective reception of programs, whose moral coherence was guaranteed by this almost tutelary figure. Béatrice Barton would appear more and more in the programs, in the image as well as through the voice-over commentary characterizing most of them. The “concept” for the programs also lent itself to an apprehension in terms of classification: the pedagogical or sociological dimension of programs was systematically stressed in discourses and amounted to a trademark for the channel. This could involve documenting the lifestyle of Valais people in the early twentieth century (Le Mayen 1903), heightening public awareness of road safety issues (Y’a pas pire conducteur en Suisse romande), showing a positive image of dynamic senior citizens (Super Seniors), analyzing how young workers enter the job market (L’Etude) 41 A special report on reality television in a French-speaking Swiss weekly is telling in that regard, “Reality TV: The Reasons Behind An Unbelievable Success,” L’Hebdo 15 Sept. 2005: 16-24. In what is presented as an assessment of reality television, the TSR’s programs are set apart from others and mentioned in an insert, but they are integrated in the mosaic of screens appearing on the first page of the report. The local identity of the magazine is obvious, since the survey mostly comprises profiles of the Francophone Swiss who took part in French reality shows. The focus on participants, whether in French or Swiss programs, is constant in the sources and evokes a parallel with the evolution of print media towards celebrity coverage. Some scholars have shown that this trend may be concomitant with the emergence of reality television. See for instance Valérie Gorin, “Le cas de l’information-people en Suisse romande: spécificités d’un microcosme régional,” Communication 27.1 (2009): 84-104.

Reality Television as Dispositive: The Case of French-Speaking Switzerland

357

or providing information on the lifestyle of farmers in French-speaking Switzerland (Dîner à la ferme). The cantonal origin of participants, which was a selection criterion, was also one notable factor of continuity: Le Mayen 1903 featured just one family, whose origin in the Jura, a valid criterion for the TSR, 42 often comes up in the sources; 43 other programs always included seven participants, or one for each of the French-speaking cantons of Switzerland, and cantonal identities and their peculiarities increasingly became a theme of the programs themselves. 44 Important similarities between programs may also be noted on an iconographic level as well as with credit sequences, the graphic design of the programs’ written content or the interfaces of dedicated Internet websites. The formula of a “TSR-made reality television” gradually stabilized, as each new program was inscribed in a sort of continuity with previous ones and became another exemplar of the genre that might be called “public-service reality television.” The tautological relation to identity, which founded the channel’s relation to its audience in the discourse of its director, was confirmed. 45 The strategy did seem to ensure success, since Le Mayen 1903 and Dîner à la ferme brought the TSR its best ratings in the years of their diffusion. If the genre of reality television was defined in relation to a standardized program model (symbolized by Loft Story) at the beginning of the period examined (2000-2002), the following years saw the emergence of formats moving away from that model, but whose reception gradually moved back to that of the genre of reality television, widening its definition as a result. The study of reality television in French-speaking Switzerland thus stresses the need to broaden the analysis beyond the programs strictly speaking (the appropriate focus for an internal analysis) and take into 42 From the standpoint of stereotyping identities, the TSR used an interesting argument to justify its choice of a Jura family: “This living laboratory would be run by a family from outside the Valais so as to avoid the cult of one’s own home and the nostalgia of the Vieux-Pays.” Béatrice Barton, Le Mayen 1903 (Lausanne: TSR/Editions Favre, 2003) 5. 43 The fact that the family came from the Jura actually led to reactions by television viewers in the press, with some criticizing the choice as undermining the authenticity of the program. 44 In Super Seniors, every Sunday represented the opportunity for a participant to organize a day-long “field trip” in his or her canton. In Dîner à la ferme, farmers put together the meal to which other participants were invited and systematically highlighted the specialties of their land. The website did in fact feature a page listing the addresses of producers mentioned in the program and suggested tourist activities. 45 “What works on the TSR, first and foremost, is programs for the Swiss, designed by the Swiss, and made in Switzerland,” according to Raymond Vouillamoz, quoted in “La der de Raymond Vouillamoz,” 24 heures 20 Aug. 2003: 10.

358 

Charlotte Bouchez

consideration the discourses and representations associated with them. The approach through dispositives offers a better account of the conditions and issues governing the emergence and the perpetuation of reality television, a generic category whose problematic character has been demonstrated here. The interpretive latitude allowing journalists as well as producers and readers to defend different approaches of the same object shows how equivocal it is. However, through a permanent operation of re-inscription performed by journalists and producers, programs are also situated in a lineage, a (dis)continuity with other objects or phenomena forming a network of significations within which these programs may be apprehended. As a genre, reality television, which results from a gradual construction and is partly determined by issues related to the various players in the dispositive, cannot be thought of as a unified category, but rather as a referent out of which these players make decisions about their activities and justify them. Considered as a set of resources for viewers, print discourses inform to some degree the framework for the interpretive autonomy of that referent, tingeing it with some determinism. The systematic nature of these processes of inscription leads us to consider them as one characteristic of genre, which is supported by the logic of standardization-repetition/localization-divergence that constitutes its main articulation. The importance of claims to cultural specificity which, as I have shown, was one of the main stakes in discourses, reinforces the hypothesis that has reality television epitomize social logics at work in the context of a globalization of trade – whose functioning the genre partly reveals, in particular when it comes to the relation of individuals and communities to television as a media.



Dispositive and Cinepoetry, around Foucault’s Death and the Labyrinth Christophe Wall-Romana

In a farcical piece titled “The Maldoror-Poems Dispositive,” Francis Ponge mockingly invites us to draw a use value from Lautréamont: Open Lautréamont! And there you have literature turned inside out like an umbrella! Close Lautréamont! And everything immediately falls back into place… To enjoy complete intellectual comfort at home, try and adapt the MALDOROR/POEMS dispositive to your library.1

This 1946 text implicitly refers to the famous umbrella of The Songs of Maldoror, which reads: “as beautiful as the random encounter between an umbrella and a sewing machine upon a dissecting table.”2 Yet Ponge, dismissing the fantastic element, extracts a domestic technique, a procedure of mechanical standardization from the metaphor that served as a talisman for Surrealism. Since a similar procedure informed Ducasse’s Poems, precisely, composed as they were through the systematic recasting of classical maxims by Pascal or Vauvenargues, the Maldoror-Poems dispositive likewise conceals a theoretical argument under its advertising patter: namely, that the poetry of Surrealism and its metaphorical fantasticality had come to an end by 1946, opening the way for the age of the “dispositive” in the postwar period. That culture had become a matter of home furnishing, and literature a matter of umbrellas, suggests that the intersection of the discursive and the non-discursive, designated by the dispositif according to Foucault, should be thought of in parodic mode. Indeed, starting in the 1950s, the material rhetoric of Ponge’s objeu,3 and later the naturalism of language in 1 Francis Ponge, “Le dispositif Maldoror-Poésies,” in Oeuvres complètes, vol. 1 (Paris: Gallimard, 1999) 634-35. 2 Le Comte de Lautréamont, The Songs of Maldoror, trans. R. J. Dent (Washington, D.C.: Solar Books, 2011). 3 Translator’s note: “objeu” is obviously a portmanteau word in French, combining “objet” and “jeu” (“game,” or “play”) in a new, hybrid form. The second reference is to Francis Ponge’s La fabrique du pré (1971).

360 

Christophe Wall-Romana

the fabrique [“manufacture”] of Ponge’s poem Le pré, inaugurated a genuine poetics of the “dispositif” in the poet’s work. 4 This essay has its departure point in modern poetry, more specifically in the invention of experience by the poetic text. I will try and argue for the hypothesis that the genesis of the notion of the dispositive – with Foucault, but not only – as a network of relations between the discursive and the non-discursive, rested on a new understanding of the textual and the poetic tied to the emergence of cinema. More concisely, the condition of possibility for thinking the dispositive is the interweaving of cinema and poetic texts (cinepoetry). While I am not so concerned with the critical effectiveness of the notion of the dispositive of audio-vision, I do not mean to suggest that the dispositive is merely an effect of the text. On the contrary, the issue is to think about the extent to which exchanges between writing and systems of audio-vision have contributed to cinema as a dispositive and to the conceptual genesis of the dispositif in Foucault. Let us take the example of the phantasmagoria: Laurent Mannoni and Tom Gunning recently re-inscribed it in the immediate lineage of the basic apparatus (in the sense of technical and technological film equipment) and the apparatus (in the sense of an immaterial arrangement producing a point of view) of cinema. Both scholars documented the spread of techniques used by Robertson: magic lanterns on wheels with a sliding lens, rear projection in the dark, superimposition of images, harmonica and sound effects, and so forth.5 Max Milner has pointed out the importance of English Gothic literature in the genesis of what may be called the pre-apparatus “phantasmagoria,” and in particular of Edward Young’s famous Night Thoughts.6 Milner has also demonstrated that, while phantasmagoria disappeared from the annals of spectacle in the 1820s, it was transfigured into a new

4 Christophe Hanna defines “the textual apparatus” in Ponge as “…an arrangement of textual elements of various forms and natures, sampled from a source-context and situated in a targetcontext.” Poésie action directe (Paris: Al Dante, 2003) 91. 5 Laurent Mannoni, The Great Art of Light and Shadow: Archaeology of the Cinema, trans. Richard Crangle (Exeter: University of Exeter Press, 2001); Tom Gunning, “Phantasmagoria and the Manufacturing of Illusions and Wonder: Towards a Cultural Optics of the Cinematic Apparatus,” in The Cinema, A New Technology for the 20th Century, André Gaudreault, Catherine Russell and Pierre Véronneau, eds. (Lausanne: Payot, 2004) 31-44. Apparatus = projection + spectator; basic apparatus = camera + editing + apparatus. These two terms tend to blend into the equation apparatus = camera + editing + projection + spectator. See Jean-Louis Baudry, L’effet cinéma (Paris: L’Albatros, 1978) 31, n. 1. 6 Max Milner, L’envers du visible. Essai sur l’ombre (Paris: Le Seuil, 2005) 400-1.

Dispositive and Cinepoetry, around Foucault’s Death and the L abyrinth

361

scenographic imaginary in Romantic and fantastic literature.7 Michel Viegnes’ study of the importance of the fantastic in nineteenth-century French poetry confirms Milner’s findings. The study describes the components in the production of a fantastic situation, from graveyards and ruins to hallucinations indoors or in an urban setting to the part played by darkness and ghosts to a general poetics of the spectral appearance of voice and sight/vision. Without referring to Milner at all, Viegnes still goes through all the main aspects of phantasmagoria as a technical horizon, as though the Gothic was remediated by phantasmagoria and turned into the fantastic. Finally, Philippe Hamon and Philippe Ortel have shown evidence for the contribution of material images to literature throughout the nineteenth century – through the multiple intrusion in the organization of the text (and not simply its theme) of images and situations of observation (Hamon) and of photography in all its technical aspects and models (Ortel).8 If the notion of the “post-phantasmagoria, pre-cinema” dispositive holds, all its fundamental aspects should also be acknowledged as interwoven with the imaginary of the modern literary text. The central section of The Painter of Modern Life, “The Artist, Man of the World, Man of the Crowd, and Child,” provides an illustration. Baudelaire brings up Constantin Guys’s watercolor as a pretext for an aesthetic manifesto of the modern based on a global perception (“spiritual citizen of the universe”9), childlike (“childhood recovered at will”10) and popular. Baudelaire’s text also happens to involve two intriguing deviations. Resolutely theoretical, this section veers a first time in its penultimate paragraph when it turns into a report from life, in an omniscient mode, and presents the painter gleaning the visual impressions to be synthesized in the work: “When Monsieur G. wakes up and opens his eyes […] watches […] marvels at […] delights in […] and in an instant Monsieur G. will already have seen […].”11 The paragraph ends with a QED: “And in a few moments the resulting 7 Max Milner, La fantasmagorie. Essai sur l’optique fantastique (Paris: PUF, 1982). See also Marina Warner, Phantasmagoria: Spirit Visions, Metaphors, and Media in the Twenty-First Century (Oxford: Oxford U.P., 2006). 8 Michel Viegnes, L’envoûtante étrangeté. Le fantastique dans la poésie française (1820-1924) (Grenoble: PUG, 2006); Philippe Hamon, Imageries, littérature et image au XIXe siècle (Paris: José Corti, 2001); Philippe Ortel, La littérature à l’ère de la photographie, enquête sur une révolution invisible (Nice: Jacqueline Chambon, 2002). 9 Charles Baudelaire, The Painter of Modern Life and Other Essays, ed. and trans. Jonathan Mayne (London: Phaidon, 1964): 7. 10 Baudelaire, The Painter of Modern Life 8. 11 Baudelaire, The Painter of Modern Life 11.

362 

Christophe Wall-Romana

‘poem’ will be virtually composed.”12 Yet a double ambiguity arises here: does the watercolor suddenly change into a poem, or should we understand “poem” as a metaphor?13 And is the image/poem effectively composed, or does it remain in a virtual state? At first glance, the following paragraph seems to leave these questions unresolved: But now it is evening. It is that strange, equivocal hour when the curtains of heaven are drawn and cities light up. The gas-light makes a stain upon the crimson of the sunset. Honest men and rogues, sane men and mad, are all saying to themselves, ‘The end of another day!’14

Still, reading these lines, one cannot help but think that this might be the beginning of a poem, as they are strongly reminiscent of the tone of prose poems in Le Spleen de Paris – a title first used by Baudelaire a few months after the publication of The Painter of Modern Life in November and December 1863. Isn’t this “the poem” promised “virtually” in the preceding paragraph, and which becomes reality almost unbeknownst to us? Baudelaire goes on, describing how Guys sets about his work: So now, at a time when others are asleep, Monsieur G. is bending over his table, darting on to a sheet of paper the same glance that a moment ago he was directing towards external things, skirmishing with his pencil, his pen, his brush […]. And the external world is reborn upon his paper, natural and more than natural, beautiful and more than beautiful, strange and endowed with an impulsive life like the soul of its creator. The phantasmagoria has been distilled from nature.15

Dimming the light of day, the dusk put an end to the collection of daytime images, and “virtually” is then understood as the fact that Guys still had to synthesize in a single work, in the darkened room and in the camera obscura of his soul, all the sketches drawn from life. It is evident, however, that the individual skirmishing with his pencil and his pen on paper is none other than Baudelaire, just as he alludes to “ma fantasque escrime,” “my fanciful skirmishing,” in his poem “The Sun.” When Baudelaire compares the image/ 12 Baudelaire, The Painter of Modern Life 11. 13 Translator’s note: in English, Jonathan Mayne answered this question by bracketing the word “poem” with single quotation marks in his translation. 14 Baudelaire, The Painter of Modern Life 11. 15 Baudelaire, The Painter of Modern Life 12.

Dispositive and Cinepoetry, around Foucault’s Death and the L abyrinth

363

poem to “the soul of its creator,” then, we are entitled to think that this is no longer, or no longer exactly, about Guys, but about the author of the poem just read: Baudelaire himself. Baudelaire thus uses the term “phantasmagoria” because he simultaneously has to maintain the reality effect of visual reportage, acknowledge the virtual character of the painting-poem, and explain, in the final sentence which glosses over his conclusion, that the painting-poem is organized almost automatically, in the duration of the memory of a ghost entity – the child: All the raw materials with which the memory has loaded itself are put in order, [ar]ranged and harmonized, and undergo that forced idealization which is the result of a childlike perceptiveness – that is to say, a perceptiveness acute and magical by reason of its innocence!16

Phantasmagoria returns, not as a figure, a vague term associated with hallucination and non-knowledge, but as the denotation of a cognitive and perceptual process of focalization of images, mobile and multiple, directed by an agency both past and surviving, the memory-childhood. One may then suggest that a pre-cinema dispositive is at work in the term “phantasmagoria,” which Baudelaire unfolds more than metaphorically, in that the term signals and accompanies a specific optical technique – an imaginary synthesis of multiple images arranged sequentially on an axis of duration – invoked as the origin of both a visual work and the virtual poem analyzing it. Thus understood, the term “pre-cinema” means not only the wide technical base of devices and arrangements within which the historical cinema Marey-Edison-Lumière was to emerge, but also an imaginary scheme for a sequential synthesis of images that parallels contemporary equipment and anticipates the general direction historical cinema was to follow towards the end of the 1880s. Poet Charles Cros17 illustrates in detail this imaginary pre-cinema in a tale published in 1872 and titled “An Interastral Drama.” In the tale, a young man by the name of Glaux, whose father, an astronomer, is in contact with an astronomer from the planet Venus, falls in love with the latter’s daughter through their respective fathers’ telescopes:

16 Baudelaire, The Painter of Modern Life 12. 17 On Cros as a writer and photographic inventor, see Philippe Ortel, La littérature à l’ère de la photographie 69-74.

364 

Christophe Wall-Romana

They thought they would overcome the distance that separated them by exchanging the most comprehensive traces of their persons. They sent each other their photographs in series large enough for relief and movement to be reproduced. Glaux […] would lock himself up in a room and reproduce the moving image of his beloved upon smoke or dust, an impalpable image made of light alone.18

The scene is certainly phantasmagorical (a dark room, smoke as a threedimensional screen, an unattainable but surviving agency), but the imaginary technique it displays foretells both chronophotography, analytical in nature, which Muybridge developed only in 1877-1878, and his synthesis of moving images thanks to praxinoscopes and zooscopes around 1879. The haptic dimension of the desire to touch-see (“traces of their persons,” “relief,” “impalpable”) should also be noted, as it accompanies the advent of new technologies of moving images, be they cinema or the immersive simulation of virtual reality. In September 1873, Cros presented his “Project to Communicate with the Inhabitants of Venus” before the French Academy of Sciences. Astronomer Jules Janssen was probably in attendance; the following year Janssen developed his photographic revolver in preparation for the transit of Venus in 1874 precisely so as to take “photographs in series.”19 As is well-known, Muybridge was to take inspiration from this device, in turn inspiring Marey, whose findings Edison learned of. The text by Cros is remarkable in that it attests to an imaginary of chronophotographic synthesis preceding even the first phase of the analytical dispositive of chronophotography. In laying out their research program on the “1900 episteme,” François Albera and Maria Tortajada posit a Foucauldian epistemological scheme that both underpins and expands the discourses and actualizations of the cinematographic “dispositif.” In their view, this scheme includes “literary discourses that produce variations of the dispositive within an imaginary world (Verne, Villiers de l’Isle-Adam, Jarry, Apollinaire, Roussel).”20 My research on what I refer to as “cinepoetry,” a practice which grafts a range 18 See also a recent translation in The Supreme Progress, ed. Brian Stableford (Hollywood Comics, 2011). 19 See Monique Sicard, “Passage de Vénus: le revolver photographique de Jules Janssen,” Études photographiques 4 (May 1998): 53. http://etudesphotographiques.revues.org/index157.html. Last accessed on Dec. 16, 2012. 20 François Albera and Maria Tortajada, “The 1900 Episteme,” trans. Lance Hewson, in Cinema Beyond Film, François Albera and Maria Tortajada, eds. (Amsterdam: Amsterdam U. P., 2010) 31.

Dispositive and Cinepoetry, around Foucault’s Death and the L abyrinth

365

of imaginary cinematographic dispositives onto the poetic text and has continued from the 1890s to the present, confirms and illustrates – in a limited way, admittedly – the validity of this program.21 Still, in the present essay I would like to try and think through the significance of the Foucauldian “epistemological scheme” and dispositif. First, the scheme does imply the efficiency of a discursive matrix, coming before literary practices. Texts would be variants of this matrix, in whose formation they would accordingly not directly take part. The issue, as the example of Cros shows, is not to opt for a critical approach that would turn the literary into a reflection, and the technical imagination into a theme, but rather to choose a model of co-evolution and co-imbrication of literature and cinematographic schemes. Milner, for instance, proposes – with much relevance, in my view – that a new order of imagination took over with the emergence of Phantasmagoria: from the Aristotelian imaginatio as mimesis, and from the Romantic imagination as over-creative: This new form of imagination could be described only by the optical dispositives perfected during the eighteenth century and transferred by Robertson, among others, from the domain of “amusing physics” to the domain of spectacle […].22

This interweaving of the quasi-dispositive Phantasmagoria and the poetic imagination was encapsulated in Baudelaire’s own term “phantasmagoria.” This is not a mere metaphor but a functional process which rearranges the text by engendering a prose poem in the middle of an essay – a prose poem given as the virtual equivalent to the phantasmagoric synthesis of multiple sketches into a single drawing in Guys’s work. As to the concept or complex of the dispositif itself, as Foucault gradually developed it in relation to his analyses of the panopticon, of power/knowledge and of sexuality, I would like to go back over one of its genealogical axes, which goes through the imaginary cinema “in” literature, precisely, thereby calling into question any absolute precedence given to the cinematographic dispositif (in Foucault’s sense of the word) over its later literary variants. Let us mention immediately that the program of the “1900 épistémè” is not at issue here, since it proposes an analytical framework wide and precise enough to avoid arguments in which causalities and modes of emergence 21 Christophe Wall-Romana, Cinepoetry: Imaginary Cinemas in French Poetry, 1890-2008 (Fordham, NY: Fordham U. P., 2012). 22 Max Milner, La fantasmagorie. Essai sur l’optique fantastique 23.

366 

Christophe Wall-Romana

remain narrow or monolithic. Let us also point out that the dispositif is defined by Foucault as “the system of relations that can be established” within “a thoroughly heterogeneous ensemble” that involves “the said as much as the unsaid,” mainly consisting of “discourses, institutions, architectural forms.”23 A dispositif produces more or less predictable strategic effects, such as the constitution of a delinquent environment handled by the prison apparatus in the nineteenth century and which later appears as such in political discourse. Foucault also explains that the dispositif compensates for the episteme, which remains “a specifically discursive apparatus, whereas the apparatus in its general form is both discursive and non-discursive.”24 My analysis of the genealogy of Foucault’s idea of dispositif involves this specific point, for the idea implies a clear, preliminary distinction between the discursive and the non-discursive. Foucault’s project to set up the literary text as pure discourse and pure language – that is, to dispose of its other, the non-discursive, even if that means recombining the two later in dispositifs – may be traced to his admirable study on Raymond Roussel, Death and the Labyrinth (1963). It seems to me, however, that Roussel’s texts resist; and at the same time that Foucault himself acknowledges in fine that, to a certain extent, these texts display non-discursive elements – and as such work like the lineaments of a dispositif. The book on Raymond Roussel is at once presented by Foucault as akin to a hapax. His only work of literary criticism, and what is more, eponymous with an author (at least in French), the book came out in May 1963, just a few days after Birth of the Clinic (Foucault wanted them to be released on the same day). Foucault curiously insists on the fact that “it doesn’t have a place in the sequence of my books,”25 as though it could have been written at any time, independently from his own theoretical evolution. Still, the two books overlap, since Birth of the Clinic, the first attempt to conceive a dispositif of power/knowledge (without naming it that way), is “about space, about language and about death; it is about the act of seeing, the gaze,”26 whereas in Death and the Labyrinth Foucault refers writing to the formula, “things, words, vision and death, the sun and language make

23 Michel Foucault, “The Confession of the Flesh,” in Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings, 1972-1977, trans. Colin Gordon (Brighton: Harvester Press, 1980): 194. 24 Michel Foucault, “The Confession of the Flesh” 197. 25 Michel Foucault, Death and the Labyrinth: The World of Raymond Roussel, trans. Charles Ruas (London, New York: Continuum, 2004):187. 26 Michel Foucault, The Birth of the Clinic: An Archaeology of Medical Perception, trans. A. M. Sheridan Smith (New York: Vintage, 1994): ix.

Dispositive and Cinepoetry, around Foucault’s Death and the L abyrinth

367

a unique form […].”27 In both books, language alone has all the powers for Foucault, for “[…] without names to identify them, things would remain in darkness […],”28 another way to hint at “[…] the secretly linguistic structure of the datum […].”29 In any case, these two statements, taken from each of the books, seem perfectly interchangeable. Foucault maintained that it was by chance that he had come across a first edition of La Vue, a two-thousand-line poem published in 1902, in the bookshop of publisher José Corti, and that he had never heard of Roussel before. His book was reportedly written very quickly, in just a few weeks. All this stresses the intended exteriority of the study, as though it lay outside the great epistemological work, while suggesting that this is not the case at all. The reading of Roussel’s writings by Foucault, who on this occasion would give free rein to his most literary prose, comes down to a great intuition or central thesis. Roussel’s secret, his famous metagram, by which letters are substituted for one another, an open secret unveiled in How I Wrote Certain of My Books, discloses but one thing: Roussel’s writing reveals the profusion of language in the absence of a subject or function of author. It is a literature of bare language, mechanically bare and without reference to the real world, at once the totality of meaning and the nothing of death. With Roussel’s suicide as a premise and perhaps haunted by it, Foucault already draws up, if dimly, the logic of the end of man presented in The Order of Things. Still, if Foucault manages, following a rather traditional exegetic approach, to interpret all great novels and novellas relying on a “process,” as he calls the Rousselian “machinery of language,”30 a form of autopoiesis,31 he comes up against La Vue, which at first glance seems to be the exception to this logic. In La Vue, a narrator describes – in hyperrealistic manner, one might say – the microphotograph of a panoramic beach scene inserted behind a magnifying lens set in the body of a penholder invented by René Dagron. A camera-pen of sorts before the camera-pen of Alexandre Astruc, the microphotographic scene unfolds like the small Chinese paper dipped in a bowl of water in Proust and, through this enlargement, gradually, hundreds of lines, a monstrous change in scale, a demiurgic zoom give the landscape the proportion, not only of a photographic panorama on a human scale, but 27 Foucault, Death and the Labyrinth 168. 28 Foucault, Death and the Labyrinth 167. 29 Foucault, The Birth of the Clinic 199. 30 Foucault, Death and the Labyrinth 38. 31 On the concept of autopoiesis, see Humberto R. Maturana and Francisco Varela, Autopoiesis and Cognition: The Realization of the Living (New York: Springer, 1991).

368 

Christophe Wall-Romana

also of an immersive environment that surrounds the observer. The problem for Foucault is twofold: how to minimize this optical mise en scène, with its reality effect both corporeal and mediated, and how to show that the hyperrealism of La Vue does not constitute an exception to the disintegration of language carried out by Roussel in Locus Solus and New Impressions of Africa. Foucault meticulously deconstructs the optical situation elaborated in La Vue to demonstrate that Roussel’s hyperrealism is only sheer illusion: the real and the living shrivel to a thin layer, the immobilization of the visible, “a descriptive epidermis” which finds itself “completely frozen at the heart of its apparent animation.”32 The drive behind the illusion, according to Foucault, amounts to the organization of La Vue around verbs, the verb “to be” in particular, whereas later texts undermined the ontological operators that verbs are (as they always conceal the verb “to be”), to give in to a purer form of repetition. The language of being has not yet given way to the autopoetic productivity of impersonal language. The demonstration, however, has the disadvantage of minimizing the literary (and plausibly, affective) importance of La Vue for Foucault. He accordingly proceeds to devote himself to the transmutation that forms the core of his book: he transforms the optical mise en scène of La Vue into the very figure of the metagrammatic process of later books: How I Wrote Certain of My Books can be likened to the lens of La Vue: a minuscule surface that must be penetrated by looking through it in order to make visible a whole dimension disproportionate to it, and yet which can neither be fixed, nor examined, nor preserved without it.33

Foucault repeats this metaphorization of the lens several times and even gives the title “The Empty Lens” to the decisive chapter on Solus Locus and New Impressions of Africa, which confirms the definitive break with the ontology of La Vue.34 Foucault is thus able to dismiss an embarrassing genetic problem, namely that New Impressions of Africa was precisely thought of by Roussel as “[…] a follow up to my poem La Vue.”35 The stakes are also high when it comes to the genealogy of the dispositif. By transforming the ocular-textual dispositive of La Vue into a figure or pre-figure of the process, 32 Foucault, Death and the Labyrinth 139, 138. 33 Foucault, Death and the Labyrinth 8. 34 Foucault is not much of a Hegelian, but there is an illustration of the Aufhebung, the Derridian relève. 35 Foucault, Death and the Labyrinth 126. Foucault cites Roussel in this passage.

Dispositive and Cinepoetry, around Foucault’s Death and the L abyrinth

369

Foucault aimed to rid the textual of what he later called the non-discursive, that is, in this instance, a panoptic architectural arrangement which, though imaginary, distributes and regulates the sensible of the text from the inside, as it were. This desire to isolate a pure literary discourse in a borderline text thus assumes an eminently paradoxical character, since it foresees and in a way circumscribes the outline of the non-discursive to come. Still, it remains to be seen whether the originality of La Vue lies precisely in this mix within the very text of the discursive and what exceeds it, that is, of poetry and the cinema dispositive. This is where Foucault’s book, once again, is engaged in a tacit debate with itself, a debate which suggests that it is precisely against this possibility of the cinema as media and immersive experience that the rise of the camera-pen to the status of a figure occurs. Research on Roussel leaves no doubt as to the omnipresence of cinema in his work.36 On the other hand, as is well-known, it is by pushing to the extreme the instantaneity of photography – below the threshold of 1/20 of a second – that the synthesis of chronophotographic prints may produce the phi effect of cinema. Hence the paradox of photographic instantaneity in La Vue, since describing the beach scene amounts to minutely making visible the suspension of any natural, human and animal animation, stumbling against each arrested movement, narrating the immediate past and future of every gesture, in short, painting the kinetic and cinematic picture from which the snapshot was suddenly snatched to be frozen. Let us note that it is in large part the extreme length of the poem which reintroduces duration in the photographic panorama: though anti-lyrical and non-figural, the language of the poem ceaselessly leads back to movement as the description progresses. From 1902 on, however, any photograph could also be said to convey the potential shadow of cinema. Indeed, after the emergence of cinema in its phase as “attractions,” that is, focusing the attention of spectators on the very monstration of a film – not least by launching a projection from a still image gradually set in motion by the operator turning the crank – a potential of “becoming-film” was attached to any instantaneous photograph. In fact, in 1902, a film was not yet called a film, but a “moving view” or simply a “view,” and the title of the poem may well refer to this expressly. 36 Michel Rebourg, “Entre graphe et scope: Roussel au cinéma,” Europe 714 (Oct. 1988): 131-38; Kenji Kitayama, “Raymond Roussel et le cinéma des origines,” in Raymond Roussel 1, Anne-Marie Amiot and Christelle Reggiani, eds. (Paris: Lettres modernes Minard, 2001): 157-81; Masachika Tani, “La tentation du ralenti, l’image comme laboratoire de la mémoire roussellienne,” in Raymond Roussel 2, Anne-Marie Amiot and Christelle Reggiani, eds. (Paris: Lettres modernes Minard, 2002): 47-60.

370 

Christophe Wall-Romana

Foucault engages in several joint operations to demonstrate that the view is “a universe without perspective […] without consideration of reciprocal proportion,”37 where everything is organized according to “surface effects, not effects of depth.”38 He thus sets aside all effects of cinematographic animation and volume, such as magnification, slow motion, superimposition of shots found in the cinema of the time, in films like Georges Méliès’s 1902 The Man with the Rubber Head or Richardson’s 1901 The Big Swallow. Besides, and more directly, Foucault rejects the possibility that an optical and technical mediation might operate within and on the text: “Although access to it is through a glass lens […] it’s not to stress the interception of an apparatus between the eye and what it sees,”39 that is, there is no camera effect, no glass eye as evoked by Jean Epstein. Still, and almost unwillingly, Foucault describes the sensible architectonics of the text in terms that today inevitably bring to mind the so-called pre-cinematographic period: This spectacle has an equivocal motion (half inspection, half parade) where everything appears still, both eyes and landscape, but where without guidelines, or design, or motor, they never stop moving, each in relation to the other. 40

The mobile panoramas of the 1900 World Fair come to mind: the maréorama on a Mediterranean liner, the cinéorama with several film projectors reproducing an ascent in an aerostat or Pyasetsky’s simple unfolding panorama of a journey on the Trans-Siberian railway. 41 One may wonder whether Foucault knew of these precedents and had them in mind. An answer in the negative would indicate how sharp his reading is, since they almost contradict his argument. However, Foucault makes no mention of two capital dimensions of Roussel’s poem: the play of gazes and the meta-commentary of the poem on itself, which are connected, in my view. Here is an excerpt devoted to a boy throwing a stick to his dog: On the beach, a child stands by the edge; he throws With speed, almost with violence A bad piece of wood, coming from who knows where; 37 Foucault, Death and the Labyrinth 109. 38 Foucault, Death and the Labyrinth 110. 39 Foucault, Death and the Labyrinth 107. 40 Foucault, Death and the Labyrinth 111. 41 See Stephan Oettermann, The Panorama: History of a Medium (New York: Zone Books, 1997).

Dispositive and Cinepoetry, around Foucault’s Death and the L abyrinth

371

A dog whom pleasure and wait drive crazy, Ahead of his toy, darts off Towards the sea; in fact the piece of wood leaves The right hand of the child at that very moment; It is a thin fragment of board with a split At one end; closing up tightly, the split Forms a curve, following a slight slope, But without stretching over much length. 42

We are thus in an absolute immobility, but on the verge of the motion, as if on the reverse side of duration. Let’s note that the scene is described through enlargement, since it zooms in from a long shot to a medium long shot to an extreme close-up on the split on the piece of wood. Simultaneously, a shift occurs from a simple ekphrasis to a description that takes the form of a commentary on itself, as “without stretching over much length” is exactly the opposite of the poem and its extreme length (69 pages!) or of the passage on the stick leaving the boy’s hand (85 lines). The word “décrivant” (“following”43), in “following a slight slope,” serves as a kind of pivot, since it points to both the descriptive poem and a ballistic movement – the trajectory of the stick, even if we will never “see” it – inscribing these two spectral movements in the grain of the piece of wood itself. Roussel comes back to this image of the stick leaving the boy’s hand three times, as in a sort of crosscutting stressing the imminent yet impossible throw of the object. More than 1,500 lines later, after surveying the scene, the poem presents a group of vacationers fascinated by the sight of the same boy throwing his stick to the dog, one more time, we might say, since it is after all a game of repetition: “The four spectators, frozen, seem to be waiting/From the edge of the jetty, above, for the outcome/Of its [the dog’s] next dive” (lines 2038-2040). This freezing, the temporalization of the moment, obviously brings back to mind another jetty, Chris Marker’s La Jetée (the film was released in 1962 as Foucault was writing his book). The same fascination, the same astonished look freezes the observers: “[…] the great sincerity/Of the interest keeping them in place is betrayed/In the gazes of all three of them” (lines 2028-2030). The passage, it should be noted, mentions three spectators even as the other cited excerpt, which follows it a few lines further down, indicates four. Foucault states that the poem, pure language, 42 Raymond Roussel, Oeuvres, vol. 4 (Paris: Éditions Pauvert/Fayard, 1998) 37. 43 Translator’s note: in French the verb “décrire” means both “to describe” and “to follow” (a trajectory, for instance).

372 

Christophe Wall-Romana

displays a “visibility separate from being seen.”44 It would seem, rather, that in this excess spectator, Roussel would reserve a place for readers/ spectators so as to attract them and move them within the immersive, quasi-cinematographic space of the poem. Besides, an eyeline match is involved in the passage, since the observers are described first, before the observed scene is, separately, off the preceding frame. This eyeline match, still unknown in the cinema in 1902, thus designates a dispositive insofar as it brings together three types of “graphic methods,” to use Étienne-Jules Marey’s expression: photography, cinematography and stylography. Roussel insists on this, describing another child using binoculars to invite the readers themselves explicitly to match this child’s visual target through an imaginary dispositive: Following through the air, in thought, The fictitious straight line, supposedly Described by its visual ray One gets through a continuous path To the opposite end; the view is blocked Very far on the right, by a long jetty. 45

Not only are we back to the jetty, from which the characters, now including us, look at the boy who is and is not throwing his stick; the match is also established with “the fictitious straight line […] described,” which once more evokes the long poem, its long jetty of a text in verse. The dispositive thus consists in this eyeline match, which connects to the meta-commentary of the poem on itself through a new type of textual apprehension that may be called cinepoetics. What is more, line 1461 cites the title of the poem, “the view,” suggesting that it is a film since it is “blocked,” or frozen. By flattening the language of the poem in a visible without depth, it does seem as though Foucault overlooked its dimension of cinepoetic dispositive so as to better conclude: It is the pen of La Vue, and none other, that will write the works using the process, because it is the process, or to say it more precisely, its rebus: a machine to show the reproduction of things, inserted within an instrument for language. 46 44 Foucault, Death and the Labyrinth 107. 45 Raymond Roussel, lines 1457-1462, Oeuvres 71. 46 Foucault, Death and the Labyrinth 117.

Dispositive and Cinepoetry, around Foucault’s Death and the L abyrinth

373

And especially not the other way round: the language which cinema, the “machine to show the reproduction of things,” would open on a new order of meaning and sensibility. Answering a critical article on Discipline and Punish in 1980, and speaking of Bentham’s panopticon, Foucault insisted on the fact that “the automaticity of power, the mechanical character of dispositifs that embody it is absolutely not the thesis of the book.” He added that what was “automatic” was “precisely the machines planned, thought out, imagined, dreamed perhaps, by people who by contrast did have a quite specific identity.”47 It seems that Foucault, as early as his Death and the Labyrinth, was anxious to neutralize the prosthetic, autonomous character of the machinery involved in a dispositive, in order to focus on the way his “language machines” operated. I outline Foucault’s notion of dispositif in relation to poetry and its new cinepoetic imaginary to make the argument that to reject poetry and literary criticism in a secondary, refracted sphere would amount to truncating any thinking on the dispositive in order to give a prime position to the epistemological framework and posit viewing and listening dispositives as the privileged schemes of this framework. The (relative) neglect of the cinepoetic in Death and the Labyrinth served as a point of departure for Foucault in a new articulation of language, the visible and the living thanks to which he was to move away from a systemic Structuralism, towards a post-Structuralism of discursive formations and dispositifs. Certainly, the theoretical slippage out of Structuralism and the slippage out of the systemlanguage seemed to go hand in hand with the emergence, the necessity of the notion of dispositif. In the introduction to a recent text by Olivier Quintyn, poetry theoretician Christophe Hanna proposed a double genealogy of the “dispositif,” starting from Foucault on the one hand, from Lévi-Strauss on the other, with the notion of bricolage. In his text, Hanna affixes a micropolitical and poetic “dispositif” for recycling, de-linking and re-assembling to the macropolitical dispositif of constraint and dictation present in Foucault. 48 As it happens, these two complementary poles are present in the genealogy of the “dispositif” going back to the critical transformation of the notion of text separating post-Structuralism from Structuralism. This is, for instance, where Jean-François Lyotard’s Des dispositifs pulsionnels (1973) may be situated, as the work extends towards the affect the “reversal” it 47 Michel Foucault, Dits et écrits, vol. 2 (Paris: Gallimard - Quarto, 2001) 836-37. 48 Christophe Hanna, “Des collages comme tactiques critiques,” in Dispositifs/Dislocations, ed. Olivier Quintyn (Marseille: Al Dante, 2007) 13-14.

374 

Christophe Wall-Romana

saw at work between discourse and the materialism of the visible and the corporeal in Discourse, Figure (1971), which openly broke with Structuralism. It thus seemed that the line was thin between this stance and Jean-Louis Baudry’s article, “The Apparatus: Metapsychological Approaches to the Impression of Reality in the Cinema,” which revolutionized film studies in 1975 and defined cinema as a paradigmatically technical, psychological and ideological apparatus. 49 Still, this is perhaps going too fast, leaving aside the Nouveau Roman, in particular Robbe-Grillet’s The Voyeur (1955), whose original title was to be La Vue – as a tribute to Roussel, precisely – and whose influence Foucault acknowledged several times. It is also often forgotten that Jean-Louis Baudry is a novelist and literary critic. In 1964 for instance, under Foucault’s direction and along with Claude Ollier, Jean-Pierre Faye, Philippe Sollers, Marcelin Pleynet and a few others, he took part in a debate in Cerisy on the issue of realism in the Nouveau Roman and in poetry, a debate that seemed pervaded by the still vague realization that this new realism had to do with a re-mediation through film. By Foucault’s own admission in “The Language of Space,”50 published shortly after the event, the Nouveau Roman represented a new type of text permeated by the film apparatus. He thus detected a mobile gaze, a camera’s gaze in Claude Ollier’s Été indien, for “some of these movements are extended, they reverberate, they are displaced or frozen by photographs, still views, film fragments.”51 We should in fact wonder what these “still views” refer to, as they are reminiscent of the title of Roussel’s poem and strangely come in between photo and cinema. Foucault continues: For this gaze is not neutral; it seems to leave things where they are; in fact, it “samples” them, virtually detaching them from themselves in their thickness, in order to make them enter in the composition of a film that does not exist and whose scenario itself is not chosen. These “views,” undecided but “optioned,” between the things they no longer

49 Jean-François Lyotard, Discourse, Figure, trans. Antony Hudek and Mary Lydon (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2011), and Des dispositifs pulsionnels (Paris: Galilée, 1994); Jean-Louis Baudry, “The Apparatus: Metapsychological Approaches to the Impression of Reality in Cinema,” trans. Jean Andrews and Bernard Augst, Camera Obscura 1 (Fall 1976), reprinted in Film Theory and Criticism, Gerald Mast, Marshall Cohen and Leo Braudy, eds. (Oxford: Oxford U. P., 1992). 50 Michel Foucault, “Le langage de l’espace,” Dits et écrits, vol. 2, 338-406. 51 Foucault, “Le langage de l’espace,” Dits et écrits, vol. 2, 410.

Dispositive and Cinepoetry, around Foucault’s Death and the L abyrinth

375

are and the film that is not yet, form the framework of the book, along with language.52

Even as the work of the camera is called “prise de vues” (“taking of views”) in French, the trade term would be “rushes” rather than “views”: one may wonder whether Foucault, analyzing Ollier’s writing in the very terms of the imaginary cinepoetics he had denied Roussel, is not acknowledging – after the fact – that Roussel’s “view” already detached things from the thin layer of the visible left or traced by language alone, to imagine this “virtual” and this “not yet” as a filmic non-discourse, which would then compose “with language” to form a proto-dispositif. The early 1960s were to be marked by the publication of two important works in the history of the place of the film dispositives in writing, RobbeGrillet’s “cine-novel,” Last Year in Marienbad (1961), and the published and revised script of Hiroshima Mon Amour by Marguerite Duras, both novelizations of films by Alain Resnais. This did not represent a major innovation, however, as novelization was an old genre dating back to the 1910s and a f ilmmaker such as Jean Cocteau had authored a beautiful novelization of Blood of a Poet in 1947.53 Moreover, the publication of a script with a theoretical bent in the postwar period came from Lettrism, as Maurice Lemaître novelized Has the Film Already Started? in 1952, with a preface by Isidore Isou every bit as theoretical.54 The difference is that Resnais’s novelizations were released by major publishers and reached a wide audience. Accordingly, experiences of intermedial grafts of the film “dispositif” on literature thus became a sign of the period; this, in my view, led thinkers such as Baudry and later Foucault to expand the notion – as “apparatus” and as dispositif, respectively. Derrida should be credited with formulating this extension, or rather, dissemination of the “dispositif,” as well as complicating its putative historicity. In “The Double Session” (1969), reprinted as part of Dissemination (1973), Derrida engages in a complex and multivalent meditation centered on the notion of the “dispositif” as a junction between the text and its outside. Derrida questions the place and status of the preface with respect to the text (in Hegel and Novalis), while prefacing his own cross-reading of the 52 Foucault, “Le langage de l’espace,” Dits et écrits, vol. 2, 410. 53 Jean Cocteau, Two Screenplays: Blood of a Poet and The Testament of Orpheus (London: Marion Boyars, 2000). 54 Maurice Lemaître, Le film est déjà commencé? séance de cinéma (Paris: Éditions André Bonne, 1952).

376 

Christophe Wall-Romana

works of Mallarmé and Philippe Sollers. To Derrida, the issue is also to dispel the misunderstanding on the “outside of the text,” absurdly interpreted as a denial of reality by his critics, as he writes for instance that “the text affirms the outside […]” insofar as it refuses to be an “inside” tamed by referential reduction and the ontological discrediting of literature. At issue is the opening of the text to the outside of the text, but within the text, to find “a different placement of the effects of opening and closing”55 between the text and the outside. Derrida thus defends a view of the literary text as a “dispositif” intervening between the text and the outside of the text, contrary to thematic criticism for instance, in which any power to draw the line between text and outside is reserved for the (outside) world of the critic. In a sense, it is this new ontological status of the actantial text which Derrida summarizes in his preface with the formula “the apparatus explains itself.”56 More specifically, it is a self-quotation of his own commentary on Sollers’s Nombres: This apparatus explains itself. Its self-explanatoriness does not imply, however, that one can explain it, that it can be comprehended by an outside observer: rather, it itself explains itself and already comprehends any observer whatever.57

This interaction or inter-inclusion thus brings together “the defining constants of viewing and listening dispositives – the spectator, the machinery and the representation,” as Albera and Tortajada write.58 These components turn the text into a dispositive explained in Derrida, and which approaches both Roussel’s more implicit dispositive and the virtual dispositif identified by Foucault in Ollier. The works of Mallarmé and Sollers for which Derrida shows more particular interest have to do with a spectacle, or better still, with a protocol that involves turning the text into a spectacle – this being performed by the text itself. Yet for Derrida this spectacle exceeds the model of the theater to appear closer to the film dispositive – with a cinema inter-grafted with writing, the materiality of the book and the polysemy of the text. Thus the “outside of the book” of the preface becomes, in “the double session,” 55 Jacques Derrida, Dissemination, trans. Barbara Johnson (London, New York: Continuum, 2004) 28. The emphasis is Jacques Derrida’s. 56 Derrida, Dissemination 38. 57 Derrida, Dissemination 299. 58 Albera and Tortajada, “The 1900 Episteme” 35.

Dispositive and Cinepoetry, around Foucault’s Death and the L abyrinth

377

the fourth side of the theatrical cube, as well as the veil, the hymen, the projection of images and finally the screen, a word which bridges between Mallarmé and Sollers. This leads Derrida to refer to a text by Mallarmé on dance as “cinematographic acrobatics”59 and note Mallarmé’s 1897 statement on cinema, a statement overlooked by the entire Mallarmean criticism. Without even being aware of the scope of the far-ranging meditation around cinema as a dispositive in which Mallarmé engaged in his last poetics,60 Derrida thus posited the film dispositive as the interface, internal to the text and enabling it to negotiate its own relations with its outside. My point here is not to explain Derrida’s dispositive-book further. I simply want to suggest that his own notion of the dispositive allows him to recognize in the cross-poetics of Mallarmé and Sollers what Foucault came close to acknowledging in Roussel’s poetics: the interweaving of poetry and techniques specific to the film dispositif as such – and consequently of the discursive and the non-discursive. By way of conclusion, I would say, on the one hand, that the interwoven cinepoetics in Roussel and its paradoxical reading by Foucault fully belong in the genealogy and historicity of the “dispositif”; and on the other hand, that this genealogy and historicity also involves, with Cros and Baudelaire, a mode of epistemic inclusion of the film dispositive inscribed in the archeology of “pre-cinema,” but which does not solve the telic difficulties that the term keeps raising.

59 Derrida, Dissemination 248. 60 See Christophe Wall-Romana, “Mallarmé’s Cinepoetics: The Poem Uncoiled by the Cinématographe,” PMLA 120.1 (Jan. 2005): 128-47.



Archaeology and Spectacle Old Dispositives and New Objects for Surprised Spectators Stopping by the Museum1 Viva Paci

To examine the notion of the dispositive and identify its place in contemporary practices at the intersection of two institutions, Cinema and the Museum, this text proposes a progression through a few individual cases, with the outlines of a study. This may appear as lacking in discipline with regard to the call for papers for the conference “Dispositifs de vision et d’audition” (Université de Lausanne, May 29-31, 2008), which was the first step in the present work. The call underlined how the study of a series of isolated cases would risk “perpetuating the ambiguity of encounters in which epistemological questioning remains peripheral to descriptive, factual presentations that do not allow us to get the measure of this new configuration of knowledge involving our objects.” For my part, I see case studies as a rather necessary approach when it comes to analyzing contemporary trends and more particularly the rich, booming trend of the cinema “going to the museum.” A second step consists in analyzing how the bounds of the cinematographic institution may more generally be exceeded; this text constitutes an initial benchmark in this research program.

1 The talk presented in Lausanne in 2008 is part of a research project, “Entre attractions et musée: cinéma, exposition et nouvelles technologies,” which was made possible by a two-year post-doctoral fellowship (Aug. 2008-Aug. 2010) from the Fonds québécois de la recherche sur la société et la culture (FQRSC). My research project is affiliated with the Department of Art History and Communication Studies at McGill University, and more specifically with William Straw’s work. This talk was also part of the research carried out at the GRAFICS (Université de Montréal). I wish to thank Ernie Gehr, Ron Magliozzi (Film Study Center, Department of Film and Media, MoMA) and Alberto Zotti (Università di Padova, Museo del precinema, Collezione Minici Zotti), for the iconographic material necessary in the preparation of this article; and Haidee Wasson and Martin Lefebvre (Concordia University) for their comments.

380 Viva Paci

Attraction (as Prism or as Shutter) A theoretical category,2 that of attraction – which was central to my doctoral dissertation3 – provides a viable point of entry to examine the new media configurations exceeding the institution of film and putting into play the now unalienable relations between cinema and digital technologies (including in the specific context of the exhibition). I developed the category out of Eisenstein’s canonical texts and the debates on the new historiography on early cinema, but also from a set of other writings, Shklovsky’s writings on poetic language and literary theories of description, the writings of the school of photogeny or the debates on distanciation in the theater. “Attraction” allowed me to examine things in great detail and to think of cinema from a standpoint distinct from its capacity for storytelling. I studied its original qualities as a seeing machine, one that generated a new, fragmentary, astounding way of seeing – and as a result engendered a true epiphany of the world: a machine producing vision and making it possible to look at things, but also as a machine to see, which early on (as well as today, but in a different way) was the thing to see. Indeed, the cinematograph itself, a machine to tame reality, domitor,4 was one of the many attractions of a late century and its legacy of amazing artifacts and innovative machines… The qualities of seeing machine and machine to see are the original qualities of cinema, which looks at things and shows them. Besides bringing attention on its own machinery, it exposes its technique; makes cuts into space and extols fragments of it; stops time, captures it and faithfully reproduces it for the spectator of the film as pure presence; transforms a continuous flow into bits of present, ephemeral yet repeatable; stretches out the time of seeing and magnifies some aspects and qualities of reality in the eyes of the spectator, thereby singling them out; addresses spectators by assaulting their senses, meanwhile ordering, governing, arranging (“disposant,” in French); finally, to echo some definitions of the apparatus, from Jean-Louis 2 In this instance, “category” refers both to a fundamental concept of understanding and the common meaning of “class” (the expression “cinema of attractions” proposes a true class, albeit one with irregular outlines, which I will be specifying throughout this research). 3 Viva Paci, “De l’attraction au cinéma,” diss., Université de Montréal, 2007. 4 It is a well-known fact today that one of the names proposed by Antoine Lumière for the new appliance that was to be the Cinématographe was “domitor” (the “triumphant victor,” in Latin): taming, and therefore subjecting and ordering a real that had remained wild and uncontrollable until the advent of this regulative device. See Philippe Dujardin, “Domitor ou l’invention du quidam,” in L’Aventure du cinématographe, proceedings of the World Conference on Lumière (Lyons: Aléas, 1999): 265-77.

Archaeology and Spectacle

381

Baudry5 to Jean-François Lyotard,6 cinema projects the fantasies of the audience onto a screen. In my reading, the dispositive of cinema, by its “nature,” works as an attraction – an attraction which may well live on and not be exhausted past its f irst decades and common narrative forms (even if, for the new historiography, the model of a cinema of attractions was primarily the model best suited to account for the f irst years of cinema). Some practices related to cinema, some moments in its history, some genres are certainly more likely to reveal this genuine attractional “nature” of the dispositive. What is taking place these days with the increasingly important place of the cinema in the museum, following the thread that connects cinema and attraction, is a phenomenon which, precisely, maintains a strong connection between cinema and attraction. My thinking on “cinema, exhibition, and museum”7 is thus positioned in a different lineage than that founded on classifications and on very contemporaneous discourses on the relations cinema/museum, often pervaded by the hierarchies of the contemporary art world.8 These discourses mainly emphasize a definition of the “new” related to the new technologies allegedly creating immersive environments. Instead, the relation ought to be thought of in terms of archaeology: each new technology, in its own time, shares something with other contemporary

5 Jean-Louis Baudry, “The Apparatus: Metapsychological Approaches to the Impression of Reality in Cinema” [1975], in Narrative, Apparatus, Ideology. A Film Theory Reader, ed. Philip Rosen (New York: Columbia University Press, 1986) 299-318. 6 Jean-François Lyotard, “Acinema,” in Narrative, Apparatus, Ideology. A Film Theory Reader, ed. Philip Rosen (New York: Columbia University Press, 1986) 349-59. On Lyotard, cinema and apparatus, see Aut Aut 338, Antonio Costa and Raoul Kirchmayr, eds., “L’acinema di Lyotard” (Apr.-June 2008). 7 Considering the growing contribution of cinema and filmmakers to the museum – a contribution sought by museums all over the world, for various reasons – it seems more and more pressing to question this relation as broadly as possible, a task so far partly taken up by a few scholars who have occasionally examined some of the boundaries between the two modes of expression and the two worlds that are cinema and the museum. See, for instance, Dominique Païni, Le Temps exposé. Le cinéma de la salle au musée (Paris: Cahiers du cinéma, 2002); Giuliana Bruno, Public Intimacy. Architecture and Visual Art (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2007); Fluid Screens, Expanded Cinema, Janine Marchessault and Susan Lord, eds. (Toronto: U of Toronto Press, 2007); Alison Griffiths, Shivers Down Your Spine: Cinema, Museums, and the Immersive View (New York: Columbia University Press, 2008). 8 See “Cinéma et art contemporain,” ed. Philippe Dubois, Cinéma & Cie 8 (Fall 2006); and “Cinéma et art contemporain II,” ed. Philippe Dubois, Cinéma & Cie 10 (2008).

382 Viva Paci

technologies, and each new technology should be thought of in its own present historicity.9 A few examples of exhibitions of film and on film shed light on the phenomenon: “Projections. Les transports de l’image” (Le Fresnoy, 1998); “Future Cinema. The Cinematic Imaginary after Film” (Zentrum für Kunst und Medientechnologie, ZKM, Karlsruhe, 2002-2003); “X-Screen. Film Installations and Actions of the 1960s and 1970s” (Museum Moderner Kunst, MUMOK, Vienna, 2003-2004); “Cinema Like Never Before” (Generali Foundation, Vienna, 2006); “Beyond Cinema: the Art of Projection. Films, Videos and Installations from 1963 to 2005” (Hamburger Bahnhof, Berlin, 2006-2007); “Visual Tactics” (Museum für Gegenwartskunst, Siegen, 20082009).10 A summary consideration of this list of exhibitions and their main features suggests that they involve different forms of exhibiting novelties. These novelties put three temporalities into play simultaneously. Each of the exhibited dispositives is related to other, past dispositives; each attests to the technological present that made its manufacturing possible; and at the same time, each seems to want to prefigure future technical possibilities. The technological bric-a-brac related to cinema, when exhibited in the context of a museum, is often staged as experimentation on the future possibilities of cinema. However, in my reading, it appears as the content of a display cabinet of yesteryear where finds from the past are exhibited, a link to the past of cinema. This cinema going to the museum, for reasons and in ways I will start mapping out here, repeats the original characteristics of the dispositive, when everything was founded on the attraction.

9 See Haidee Wasson, “New and Now: A Plea for Historiography and Technology,” Reconstruction 4.1, “Technology & Historiography, or, The Science Fiction of Everyday Life” (Spring 2004); and Lisa Gitelman and Geoffrey B. Pingree, “What’s New About New Media,” in New Media 1740-1915, Lisa Gitelman and Geoffrey B. Pingree, eds. (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2003) XI-XXII. 10 Incidentally, the museal institutions that organized these exhibitions are different in nature: contemporary art museums, centers specializing in current art, private galleries. The presence of cinema in all these usual spheres of contemporary art stresses the now inseparable associations between the two worlds of cinema and art exhibitions, regardless of the judgments placed on these associations.

Archaeology and Spectacle

383

Passages (from Cinema to the Museum) Besides these collective and highly technological exhibitions, a range of modalities exists for “exhibited cinema.”11 A first modality involves contemporary directors (Marker, Varda, Kiarostami, Erice, Godard, Greenaway, and so forth) moving into the museum or the gallery as an extension of their practice as filmmakers, sometimes exhibiting re-mediations or fragments of their film work. Another modality consists in the mise en scène of cinema in the museum (with the exhibitions on Hitchcock, Cocteau, Disney, Warhol, and so forth). A third modality would include the use of film images by visual artists (Pierre Huyghe, Pipilotti Rist, Douglas Gordon, Matthew Barney). In spite of their diversity, these phenomena may be compared to one another in the way they emphasize the centrality of the cinematographic dispositive in the exhibited work, its status as a disclosed element, the center of attention and an object of the look (here “dispositive” is also considered in its complex interweaving of recording, projection and reception, and consequently of an imaginary dimension…). In all three typologies of the presence of cinema in the museum, it is possible to outline a phenomenon of “reuse of cinema” in various forms, and in particular of the cinema as novelty. Through the remodeling of the dispositive, the cinema is thus reduced to “a new invention,” even a hundred years after its invention, and presented as an attraction. This phenomenon is particularly evident and self-conscious in exhibitions such as the ones I have previously mentioned (“Projections. Les transports de l’image,” “Future Cinema. The Cinematic Imaginary after Film,” “X-Screen. Film Installations and Actions of the 1960s and 1970s,” “Cinema Like Never Before,” “Beyond Cinema: the Art of Projection. Films, Videos and Installations from 1963 to 2005,” and “Visual Tactics”), as well as in a significant number of other exhibitions over the past ten years. These collective, spectacular, and highly technological exhibitions seem to draw from the memory of World Fairs: with their small-scale production, exhibited objects, even though they evoke possible practices, are often (if not always) on the side of the prototype, of dispositives not designed for 11 On “exhibited cinema” (in the sense of a museum exhibition), see François Albera, “Archéologie de l’intermédialité: SME/CD-ROM, l’apesanteur,” in Cinémas 10.2-3, “Intermédialité et cinéma” (2000): 27-38; Projections. Les transports de l’image, ed. Dominique Païni (Paris: Hazan/ Le Fresnoy, 1997); Dominique Païni, Le Temps exposé. Le cinéma de la salle au musée (Paris: Cahiers du cinéma, 2002); Philippe Dubois, La Question vidéo. Entre cinéma et art contemporain (Brussels: De Boeck Université, 2007).

384 Viva Paci

industrial mass-production. These exhibitions thus propose a new, more ample spatialization of the nineteenth-century curio cabinet: they are presented as contexts where the conditions of an emphasis on cinema as a “machine to see,” and therefore as an attraction, play out. The principle of the exhibition commands the very idea, first, of the cinematograph, later, of cinema. On the one hand, exhibiting the writing of movement on a two-dimensional surface was quite simply what constituted attraction. On the other hand, originally, the machine to project images was often exhibited as an attraction. Then, the movie theater (once it became institutional, with the institution imposing a discipline on the spectators) was the place where the film itself was exhibited. These days, now that it has moved outside the screening space and f inds itself in various exhibition spaces – or on mediums for individual viewing, which is not unrelated to what interests me here – cinema no longer addresses spectators univocally. Instead, spectators are each time asked to adopt a new posture: moving, looking through complex dispositives to see the image, using one’s own body to activate the image, or being confronted with the microscopic or macroscopic dimensions of the moving image. Spectators, who often become visitors, no longer have to be absorbed in the story of a film, yet they are captivated and even assaulted by fragments of spectacle, surprised by what is exhibited before their eyes and the sophistication of technology. Faced with technique, these visitors are much more in a position of contemplation (technique becomes apparent, in a manner not unlike the process of singularization articulated by Shklovsky, and produces distance) than in one of immersion, as technopop discourses on the relations between arts and technologies tend to suggest. The works presented in the aforementioned exhibitions were introduced through a deliberately conspicuous use of the technology on which they were built. These technologies, presented in a majority of cases as the “future of cinema,” did in fact quite explicitly refer to its origins.

Origins (in a Dispositive) The pivotal idea in my reading of the notion of the dispositive, one that is to give it specificity, is that the origins of cinema have been revived by works that are apparently inscribed in a representation of the future. A dispositive, which is more than a machine, also holds an imaginary; and the archaeology of cinema does indeed belong in the imaginary of cinema.

Archaeology and Spectacle

385

André Gaudreault has argued that the cinematograph as a dispositive has a lot to do with other dispositives, and that the resulting ensemble has little to do with the CINEMA of the institution that followed the years of the cinematograph. While I find this reading quite appealing, I still want to emphasize that, even after cinema consolidated as an institution, CINEMA never stopped looking back and holding fast to a past, the attraction, for all kinds of reasons (historical, technological, fetishistic, and in my view, ontological). The attraction thus became its past, a rather pre-cinematographic past even, sometimes quite different from the paying public projection of photographic elements… I would add that no teleology is to be found in this proposition; on the contrary, it involves reflecting on anachronism and the return of history. Since the scenography of dispositives calls up memory and fantasies, I want to discuss two examples to better identify the phenomena and symptoms of this return to origins. They involve two exhibitions presented at the Museum of Modern Art (MOMA) in New York by its Department of Film and Media. The MOMA, evidently a museum institution, also has a long history of accommodating cinema in the museum: its Film Library was founded in 1934, two years before the Cinémathèque française.12 Presented almost at the same time, these two exhibitions on cinema, “Artscape and Zoetrope” (Pixar, MOMA, 2005) and “Ernie Gehr’s Panoramas of the Moving Image” (Ernie Gehr, MOMA, 2006) come from two very distinct “film institutions,”13 commercial animation film and experimental cinema. Simply examining the keywords in the titles, zoetrope and panorama, suggests which imaginary is evoked by the two exhibitions. In the relation to the spectator, these put back in play the original conditions of cinema as a “machine to see,” using the technology that supports them in a deliberately ostentatious manner. Interestingly, these technologies, while shown as part of cinema (from two different domains, both equally cinematographic, experimental film and animation), are actually revived from an archaeology called pre-cinema. Again, this aspect complements my proposition as to the definition of a dispositive: the dispositive involves more than a machine, for 12 See Heidee Wasson, Museum Movies. The Museum of Modern Art and the Birth of Art Cinema (Berkeley, Los Angeles: University of California Press, 2005); and Ronald S. Magliozzi, “Film Archiving as a Profession: An Interview with Eileen Bowser,” The Moving Image 3.1 (Spring 2003): 132-46. 13 The expression is borrowed from Roger Odin, who has proposed that the different kinds of film production be approached in terms of “institutions.” See Roger Odin, “Sémio-pragmatique du cinéma et de l’audiovisuel: modes et institutions,” in Toward a Pragmatics of the Audiovisual, ed. Jürgen E. Müller (Münster: Nodus, 1994): 33-47.

386 Viva Paci

the arrangement with a view to an effect and the assurance of a controlled and orderly operation could just as well be performed by a machine. The exhibitions I have examined, and which have helped me outline this idea of the dispositive, show how dispositives deploy a whole arsenal of references to the past, archaeological evocations, diachronic relations between past and future. They present machines that incidentally “fantasize” original dispositives. Indeed, the dispositive – besides enjoying the prerogatives of a machine – also meets the need to give an imaginary a new lease of life and to produce ideas (this follows in the same direction as that opened by Jean-François Lyotard’s thought on dispositifs pulsionnels, or affective systems).

“Artscape and Zoetrope” (Pixar, MOMA, 2005) “Artscape” and “Zoetrope” are two original works conceived by Pixar Studios to be shown in a large exhibition on the art of digital animation at the MoMA (also promoted by the same studios), “Pixar: 20 years of animation.” Seeing the event as the last word in merchandising would not be far from the truth. After all, Pixar has been part of a discourse on the future of images and has positioned itself at the cutting edge in the creation of computer-generated images since the 1980s (not to mention the market of tie-in products, from video games to toothbrushes…). However, on the occasion of the exhibition, the representation of the company and museum policy had Pixar’s brand of animation inscribed in an old tradition and turned toward the past. Pixar was thus working towards its legitimization, associating itself with the horizon of the craftsman-creator, the Bazinian “do-it-yourself man” of the origins of cinema,14 to carve out a place for itself in the space of the museum. The studio also went quite far back in a history that had to do with the dispositive of cinema, its memory and its imaginary. Any caesura between the strips of an 1833 zoetrope or the discs of an 1879 zoopraxinoscope, exhibited in any museum nowadays, and Pixar’s “cels,” thus disappeared… While, on the one hand, optical toys are to be related to animation, in a lineage which actually skips cinema and its projection of

14 In “The Myth of Total Cinema,” Bazin refers to the “inventors” of cinema as “monomaniacs […] do-it-yourself men.” See André Bazin, What Is Cinema?, vol. 1, trans. Hugh Gray (Berkeley, Los Angeles: University of California Press, 2004): 17.

Archaeology and Spectacle

387

moving photographic images,15 on the other hand, cinema, in this instance, clearly asks for ancestors when stopping by the museum… The two works call for a brief description. A widescreen projection and a panorama of sorts, “Artscape,” created by Andrew Jimenez (image) and Gary Rydstrom (sound), presents a few forms central to the first images of the cinematograph. The famous first accounts of the Lumière views reported that what astounded and created emotion was – among other things – the movement of the leaves in the trees. In the 3D panorama of “Artscape,” nature is evidently not what appears and is celebrated; rather, technology itself is shown, underlined, extolled even for its ability to produce a random movement. “Artscape” is indeed a new type of panorama in which movement is part of what is represented: a transformation of the relations between the various illustrations of this panorama occurs through a transformation of the “pictorial” image into the colored fragments of a kaleidoscope. A spate of images occupies the space of the projection and recombines in a new panorama. “Zoetrope” is a carrousel comprising three-dimensional figurines (characters from Toy Story). Through rotation and the addition of a strobe lighting serving as the equivalent of a zoetrope slit, the carrousel creates a perfect impression of fluid and continuous movement 16 as it plays with persistence of vision and the phi effect.17 The polygonal glass booth in which the carrousel is placed evokes the form of the polygonal mirrors inside the praxinoscope.

15 In his talk at the Lausanne conference in 2008, Michel Frizot argued along the same lines, pointing out that it was possible to draw a straight line from chronophotography to 3D images. 16 For video recordings of the animated work, see private videos such as the one available here: http://youtube.com/watch?v=OrIgwSxZDcc&feature=related [last accessed on August 12, 2012]. 17 A visual artist who had already worked on the same imaginary is Gregory Barsamian (http://www.gregorybarsamian.com/). An heir to the zoetrope and an explorer of the phi effect, Barsamian made three-dimensional animated models with plaster figurines of angels, helicopters and other objects in Putti (1993). Animation and continuity were produced for the spectator thanks to the phi effect; 13 sculptures per second rotated above spectators in a dimly lit space, with strobe lighting filling in the gaps between one image and the next to give the impression of a continuous motion turning the little angels into helicopters. There, as in cinema, sculpture became an art of time taking shape through rhythm. See my text, “Cinematographic Traces,” in Images from the Future: Lost and Found in the Images du Futur collection (2004), available at http://www.fondation-langlois.org/html/e/page.php?NumPage=690 [both sites were last accessed on August 12, 2012].

388 Viva Paci

“Ernie Gehr’s Panoramas of the Moving Image” (MOMA, 2006) The name of experimental filmmaker Ernie Gehr is a reminder of the relation between experimental cinema and the origins of cinema, already pointed out several times. The fondness of filmmakers of the 1960s American avant-garde for views in early cinema should certainly be partly understood as a break away from Hollywood’s industrial codification. But it is mostly these filmmakers’ interest in the original qualities of the dispositive that oriented underground film towards the Cinématographe. One of the careful observers of this return to early images and the advent of cinema, Tom Gunning, gave a lecture at the Whitney Museum some thirty years ago and proposed a scientific metaphor to define this familiarity between early cinema and American avant-garde film (and more particularly Ken Jacobs, Ernie Gehr, and Hollis Frampton). He ironically suggested that the phenomenon should be named pseudomorphism. Indeed, in science, a mineral is defined as pseudomorphic when its appearance is identical to that of another mineral even if its molecular structure is completely different…18 In other words, experimental cinema, as seen through the lens of the “cinema of monstrative attractions,” to borrow Gaudreault and Gunning’s term, reveals aspects which would otherwise remain concealed. The contributions of theoreticians-historians such as Paul Adams Sitney or Bart Testa should also be mentioned for their comparative approach between early cinema and experimental film. Likewise, some curators have speculated on this parallel. On the occasion of a 2005 retrospective at the Anthology Film Archives in New York, Bruce Posner did, for instance, present early films and avant-garde films side by side, so to speak – not to outline a hierarchy or an evolution, but to emphasize their similarities.19

18 Tom Gunning, “An Unseen Energy Swallows Space: To Space in Early Film and Its Relation to American Avant-Garde Film,” in Film Before Griffith, ed. John L. Fell (Berkeley, Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1983): 356. Gunning also said that he had come to compare the American avant-garde and early cinema because many of the experimental filmmakers he was looking at included fragments of early films in their own work (again, Ken Jacobs, Ernie Gehr, Hollis Frampton). He added that his own encounter with the underground also gave him a different outlook on early films. 19 A seven-DVD set came out of the Anthology’s 2005 retrospective, as well as a publication by the same title: Unseen Cinema: Early American Avant-Garde Film 1893-1941, ed. Bruce Posner (New York: Anthology Film Archives, 2005).

Archaeology and Spectacle

389

Creators themselves have this proximity as a motivation and look for it in some cases. Jonas Mekas is fond of the Lumière views,20 for instance, and once dedicated Walden (1969) to Lumière: the six-reel film comprises shots joined end to end – in short, views, often unipunctual and edited in vivo, in the camera itself. Mekas is a filmmaker-cameraman, almost manually so, someone filming as in the time period of the Lumière brothers, not in the manner established by the industry later. The relations to early cinema generally revolve around the re-appropriation by underground filmmakers of an imaginary of cinema in which adventures of perception predominate, to borrow Stan Brakhage’s expression,21 and where the very act of seeing is emphasized. Indeed, another trend of the underground, called structural film,22 also maintains close ties with the state of early cinema, a state strongly related to its dispositive. These films were made with a number of dispositive-related effects: camera on tripod, a looped series of film frames, flicker, re-recording of images projected on a screen and re-photographing with an optical printer. Ernie Gehr’s films do belong in this category and the films he made in direct relation to early films, from Lumière through Méliès to the urban views of the Biograph/Mutoscope, include The Astronomer’s Dream (2004), Essex Street Market (2004), Workers Leaving the Factory (After Lumière) (2004),23 Cotton Candy (2002), Side/Walk/Shuttle (1991), Eureka (1974). Duration, but more particularly the point of view and the construction of space, are areas of research for Gehr,24 just as they were decisive sites in the 20 Scott McDonald notes this in Avant-Garde Film. Motion Studies as he points out Mekas’s interest for the imaginary field opened by home movies, notably the films featuring the Lumière family, addressing a private sphere but whose use is both private and public. Views by Lumière and Mekas are the views of do-it-yourself men. See Scott McDonald, Avant-Garde Film. Motion Studies (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993) 11. 21 “Imagine an eye unruled by man-made laws of perspective, an eye unprejudiced by compositional logic, an eye which does not respond to the name of everything but which must know each object encountered in life through an adventure of perception.” Stan Brakhage, Metaphors on Vision (1963; New York: Film Culture, 1976): unpaginated. In short, this is cinema in which the act of seeing is underlined by the emphasis on a “machine to see,” films before which the spectator is confronted directly to the disclosure of the mechanical look that produced the film. 22 In Visionary Film: The American Avant-Garde 1943-2000, Paul Adams Sitney def ines the formal characteristics of the structural film. 23 This seminal view of the Lumière brothers repeatedly left its mark on the imaginary of experimental cinema. See for instance Harun Farocki’s film Workers Leaving the Factory (1995) and his video installation Workers Leaving the Factory in Eleven Decades (2006). 24 On Gehr’s work, see Films of Ernie Gehr (San Francisco Cinematheque, 1993), with texts by Tom Gunning, Daniel Eisenberg, Susan Thackrey, Robert Becklen and program notes by Ernie

390 Viva Paci

elaboration of early cinema. Side/Walk/Shuttle is a perfect example and may be considered as the experimental reuse of Panorama of Flatiron Building (1903), produced by The American Mutoscope and Biograph Company, evoked by Tom Gunning.25 What happens when, in order to celebrate a filmmaker, a museum such as the MoMA invites the filmmaker in question to present his work? Ernie Gehr arrived at the MoMA with his collections of “fragments of dispositives” from the nineteenth century, like a trail of bread crumbs followed by cinema to go back in its history, to the origins, and get exhibited. The central element of the exhibition was the digital projection – five horizontal projections on the same screen – of details from magic lantern plates (simple or double, and moving) with a digital reproduction of the old mechanical movement which the projection of multiple plates with the magic lantern could produce. Next to this multi-screen projection, another – flat – screen showed two chromatrope effects set up in parallel. Besides these projections and the transmission of a given movement by optical toys, a series of glass display cases presented zoetrope and praxinoscope strips as well as phenakistoscope discs. This old mode of specimen presentation, coming after taxidermy, is reminiscent of a certain “mummy complex” which cinema, according to Bazin, could not dispense with… I am comparing the exhibition mode of these bits of dispositive with taxidermy simply because the modern museum practice of taxidermy26 consists in freezing life, as though caught in the midst of a movement,27 to exhibit it and prolong it. Likewise, when André Bazin wrote of cinema as “change mummified” in “The Ontology of the Photographic Image,” he associated these same qualities: preserving life in its most vivid actions to exhibit it by showing it. “Ernie Gehr’s Panoramas of the Moving Image” was an exhibition where cinema showed and staged its dispositive, with all the imaginary and the memory mobilized by it. Even if the exhibition was originally meant to celebrate cinema in the museum through the work of a filmmaker (as was Gehr; and Bart Testa, Back and Forth. Early Cinema and the Avant-Garde, already mentioned. 25 Again, I refer the reader to Tom Gunning, “An Unseen Energy Swallows Space: To Space in Early Film and Its Relation to American Avant-Garde Film.” 26 I presented a paper on the subject, “Taxidermie: réflexions sur cinéma et musée,” at the Eleventh International Conference of the Research Center on Intermediality (CRI), “Muséalité et intermédialité: nouveaux paradigmes des musées,” Oct. 28-31, 2009, Society for Arts and Technology (SAT), Montreal. 27 See Carl Akeley’s dioramas of natural habitats in the late twentieth century. See also Mark Alvey, “The Cinema as Taxidermy: Carl Akeley and the Preservative Obsession,” Journal of Film and Media 48.1 (2007): 23-45.

Archaeology and Spectacle

391

the exhibition on the production of an animation studio), the objects of pre-cinema exhibited, optical toys, are not really related to the institution of film. They did not involve a paying public projection of moving photographic images. What is more, optical toys were a form of bourgeois pastime, whereas cinema was a popular spectacle. Still, for us today, these materials of pre-cinema belong to the memory and imaginary of cinema. For both the Pixar and the Ernie Gehr exhibitions, and for various reasons, the issue was to show elements of the dispositive of cinema. For Pixar, the connection with cinema – through its imaginary, where optical toys have a place – provided a point of entry into “highbrow” culture (cinema and its history, now able to enter the museum), while establishing a link with craftsmanship to stress how even computer-generated animation films are the product of human genius. For Ernie Gehr’s exhibition, again, the idea of exhibiting the cinema within the museum turned into the monstration of its dispositive. In this dispositive of the origins, the experimental filmmaker also seemed to find the very roots of his work, where the decomposition of movement and the reconstruction of an effect occupy a place as central as it was in his structural cinema. My aim in this article has been to observe and study the directions followed by cinema when “going to the museum.” The phenomenon is also, more generally, contemporary with the fact that film is stretching beyond the limits of the institution of cinema. The theme involves many territories besides the museum. It is possible, in my view, to question the role and the place of spectacle, of some new hybrid objects, between media and mediums, used in the distribution of moving images – from cell phones to mp3 players that make it possible to store and to view these moving images. In a long history of spectacular uses of technical objects, formal lineages could then emerge. When exhibited outside the boundaries of its institution, at the museum for instance, and even in the case of futuristic dreams made palpable by exhibitions such as Future Cinema or Cinema Like Never Before, cinema stages dispositives that date back to its origins. Drawing from the imaginary of what has been called pre-cinema, it re-presents itself as a dispositive issuing from these origins and acknowledges itself in this projection toward the past which – at the same time – seems to hold promises for its future.



About the Authors

François Albera is Professor of Film History and Aesthetics at the Université de Lausanne (Switzerland) and project director at the FNS (Swiss National Science Foundation). A member of the AFRHC (Association française de recherche en histoire du cinéma), he is the editor of 1895 Revue d’histoire du cinéma. His publications include L’Avant-garde au cinéma (2005) and Glass House d’Eisenstein. Du projet de film au film comme projet (2009). He has also served as editor or co-editor of Les Formalistes russes et le cinéma (1995, 2009), Arrêt sur image, fragmentation du temps (2002), La Filmologie de nouveau (2009), Cinema Beyond Film. Media Epistemology in the Modern Era (2010), Ciné-dispositifs: spectacle, cinéma, télévision, littérature (2011), and Modernidad e vanguardia do cinema (2012). Alain Boillat is Professor in the Department of Film History and Aesthetics at the Université de Lausanne. He is also the chair of Réseau Cinéma CH. His research mainly focuses on the history of film theories, narration and scriptwriting practices in cinema and comics, and on the question of orality and intermediality in audiovisual dispositives. He is the author of Du bonimenteur à la voix-over. Voix-attraction et voix-narration au cinéma (Antipodes, 2007) and has recently co-edited two collections of essays, Les Cases à l’écran. Cinéma et bande dessinée en dialogue (Georg, 2010) and Jésus en représentations. De la Belle Epoque à la post-modernité (Infolio, 2011). Charlotte Bouchez is a doctoral candidate at the Université de Lausanne, in the doctoral school “Cinéma et dispositifs audiovisuels: discours et pratiques” (a ProDoc project of the FNS, the Swiss National Science Foundation). The subject of her thesis is “The imaginary of ‘reality TV’ in the footsteps of cinema? Between a local model, the French-speaking world and standardization.” Gilles Delavaud is Professor at the Université Paris 8 - Vincennes - St-Denis. His publications include L’Art de la télévision. Histoire et esthétique de la dramatique télévisée (1950-1965) (INA/De Boeck, 2005); “Penser la télévision avec le cinéma,” Cinémas 17.2-3 (Spring 2007); “Le dispositif télévision. Discours critique et création dans les années 1940 et 1950,” in La Télévision du téléphonoscope à YouTube, M. Berton and A.-K. Weber, eds. (Lausanne: Antipodes, 2009); and “Les débuts télévisuels d’Alfred Hitchcock,” in Cinéma et audiovisuel se réfléchissent (Paris: L’Harmattan, 2012); “L’écran

394 

About the Authors

expérimental d’Alfred Hitchcock”, Ecrans 1 (2013); “La télévision selon Alfred Hitchcock. Une esthétique de l’émergence”, CiNéMAS 23.2-3 (Spring 2013). He has edited or co-edited Télévision: le moment expérimental. De l’invention à l’institution (1935-1955) (Rennes: INA/Apogée, 2011) and Permanence de la télévision (Apogée, 2011). Patrick Désile holds a doctoral degree in Art and the Sciences of Art from the Université Paris 1 – Panthéon - Sorbonne. He is an associate researcher at the Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique (UMR - ARIAS, Atelier de recherche sur l›intermédialité et les arts du spectacle, France). A member of the AFRHC (Association française de recherche en histoire du cinéma), he is the author of Généalogie de la lumière (2000) as well as several studies on spectacles in the nineteenth century. Elie During is Associate Professor in Philosophy at the Université de Paris Ouest – Nanterre and teaches a seminar at the École Nationale Supérieure des Beaux-arts in Paris. His research on the forms of space-time involves several areas: aesthetics, metaphysics, philosophy of sciences and technique. His publications include Faux raccords: la coexistence des images (Actes Sud, 2010) and Bergson et Einstein: la querelle du temps (PUF, forthcoming). He has worked on the critical edition of Bergson’s works published by Presses Universitaires de France (Durée et Simultanéité, 2009; Le souvenir du présent et la fausse reconnaissance, 2012) and co-edited two collections of essays on contemporary art, In actu: de l’expérimental dans l’art (Presses du réel, 2009) and À quoi pense l’art contemporain? (special issue of Critique, August-September 2010). Thomas Elsaesser is Professor Emeritus in the Department of Media and Culture of the University of Amsterdam. From 2006 to 2012, he was a visiting professor at Yale University; since 2013, he has been a visiting professor at Columbia University. He has authored, edited and co-edited some twenty volumes, several of which have been translated into German, French, Italian, Polish, Hungarian, Hebrew, Korean and Chinese. Among his recent books as author are: Terror und Trauma (Berlin: Kadmos, 2007); Film Theory: An Introduction through the Senses (New York: Routledge, 2010, with Malte Hagener) and The Persistence of Hollywood (New York: Routledge, 2012). André Gaudreault is Professor in the Department of Art History and Film Studies at the Université de Montréal, where he chairs the GRAFICS (Groupe de recherche sur l’avènement et la formation des institutions

About the Authors

395

cinématographique et scénique). Gaudreault has been Visiting Professor at several universities (Bologna, Buenos-Aires, Paris, São Paulo, Lausanne, Rennes and Santiago de Compostela) and has published works in film narratology (From Plato to Lumière: Narration and Monstration in Literature and Cinema, 2009) and film history (American Cinema, 1890-1909, as editor, 2009; Film and Attraction: From Kinematography to Cinema, 2011; and The Blackwell Companion to Early Cinema, as co-editor, 2012). He also serves as the director of scholarly review CiNéMAS. Laurent Guido is a film historian. He is Professor at the Université de Lille - Nord de France. He has also taught in Montreal (UdeM), Nanterre (Paris X), Brussels (ULB) and Lausanne (UNIL). His work addresses the relations between cinema, music and dance, focusing on the rhythmical representations of bodily movement in modern mass culture and media. His most recent books and edited volumes include L’Âge du rythme (Payot, 2007; L’Âge d’homme, 2014); Aux sources du burlesque (AFRHC/Giornate del Cinema muto, 2010, co-edited with Laurent Le Forestier); Rythmer/ Rhythmize (Intermédialités 18, Fall 2010, co-edited with Michael Cowan), Between Still and Moving Images (John Libbey/Indiana University Press, 2012, co-edited with Olivier Lugon). He is currently completing a book on Richard Wagner’s influence on film theory and history, and research about dance in early cinema. Omar Hachemi is a doctoral candidate at the Université de Lausanne, in the doctoral school “Cinéma et dispositifs audiovisuels: discours et pratiques” (a ProDoc project of the FNS, the Swiss National Science Foundation). The subject of his thesis is “The ‘dispositif,’ from the structure to the rhizome. Presuppositions of a notion, diachrony of a question.” Charles Musser is Professor of Film Studies and American Studies, and Acting Chair of the Theater Studies Program at Yale University. His debut book, The Emergence of Cinema: The American Screen to 1907 (Scribners, 1990), received the Jay Leyda Prize, the Theater Library Award and the Katherine Singer Kovacs Prize. Others include Edison Motion Pictures, 1890-1900: An Annotated Filmography (Cineteca del Friuli, 1997) and (edited with Pearl Bowser and Jane Gaines) Oscar Micheaux and His Circle: African American Filmmaking and Race Cinema of the Silent Era (Indiana University Press, 2001). His films include Before the Nickelodeon: The Early Cinema of Edwin S. Porter (1982) and Errol Morris: A Lightning Sketch (2012).

396 

About the Authors

Philippe Ortel is Associate Professor at the Université de Toulouse-Le Mirail (France) and a member of the research group “Lettres, langages et arts” (LLA CREATIS). He is the author of La Littérature à l’ère de la photographie (2002) and the editor of Discours, image, dispositif (2008). He also took part in the collective reflection in the research group “La scène,” whose work has appeared in four volumes of essays: La Scène, L’Ecran de la représentation, L’Incompréhensible and Littérature et brutalité. Maria Tortajada is Professor of Film Aesthetics and History at the Université de Lausanne. She headed the project CUS Réseau Cinéma CH 2006-2013 and currently serves as project director at the FNS (Swiss National Science Foundation) as well as on the film database project “Cinémémoire.ch. Une histoire orale du cinéma suisse. La production en Suisse romande à l’époque du ‘nouveau cinéma.’” She is the author of Le Spectateur séduit. Le libertinage dans le cinéma d’Eric Rohmer et sa fonction dans une théorie de la représentation filmique (1999) and several studies on the epistemology of viewing and listening dispositives in periodicals and collections of essays. She has co-edited Cinéma suisse: nouvelles approches (2000), Histoire du cinéma suisse, 1966-2000, vol. 1-2 (2007), Cinema Beyond Film. Media Epistemology in the Modern Era (2010) and Ciné-dispositifs: spectacle, cinéma, télévision, littérature (2011). Viva Paci is Professor of Film Studies at the École des médias (Université du Québec à Montréal), where she also serves as the director of the MA program “Cinéma et images en mouvement.” She is a member of the Centre for Research on Intermediality (CRI) and the Groupe de recherche sur l’avènement et la formation du spectacle cinématographique et scénique (GRAFICS). Paci is the author of Il Cinema di Chris Marker (2005) and co-author (with Ronald de Rooy and Beniamino Mirisola) of Romanzi di deformazione: 1988-2010 (2010). She is the editor (with André Habib) of Chris Marker et l’imprimerie du regard (2008) and has co-edited an anthology on the street in contemporary European cinema with Michael Cowan and Alanna Thain (CiNéMAS 21.1, 2010). Her recent books are La comédie musicale et la double vie du cinéma (2011) and La machine à voir. À propos de cinéma, attraction, exhibition (2012). Benoît Turquety is a Senior Researcher and Lecturer in the Department of Film History and Aesthetics at the Université de Lausanne (Switzerland). A member of the AFRHC, he specializes in the history of techniques. His publications include Danièle Huillet et Jean-Marie Straub, “objectivistes” en

About the Authors

397

cinéma (2009), Inventer le cinema. Epistémologie: problèmes, machines (2014) and several studies on the relations between cinema and poetry, the notion of objectivity and the work of a number of filmmakers in periodicals and collections of essays. Christophe Wall-Romana is Associate Professor in the Department of French and Italian at the University of Minnesota, Minneapolis (United States), where he teaches courses and seminars on French poetry, modern literature, silent cinema and philosophy. He is the author of Cinepoetry, Imaginary Cinemas in French Poetry (2013), which deals with the forms of French-language poetry that incorporate in an intermedial manner one or several aspects of the dispositive of cinema; and a monograph on filmmaker and theorist Jean Epstein (2013). He is also working on several books, one on astronomy, cinema and affect, another on the renewed relation between modern poetry and philosophy.



Index of Titles

Index of titles (films, pictures, journals, exhibitions, theater and ballet, novels, poems, books-source – except references being only in footnotes) 24 Hour Psycho (Gordon) 69 Accordée du village (L’) (Greuze) 80 Ambassadors (The) (Holbein) 184 American Amateur Photographer, 150 Amphithéâtre (Astley) 77 Anemic Cinema (Duchamp) 283 Animal Locomotion (Muybridge) 266 Animaux savants (Les) (Mme B**) 88 Annabelle Butterfly Dance (Edison) 254 Annabelle Serpentine Dance (Edison) 254 Annabelle Sun Dance (Edison) 255 Annales (Les) 30 Archaelogy of Knowledge (Foucault) 37-38, 41-42 Ars Magna Lucis et Umbrae (Kircher) 286 Arthur’s Home Magazine 142 Artscape and Zoetrope (MoMA) 385 Astronomer’s Dream (Gehr) 389 Au téléphone (Lorde) 229, 239 Avant le cinéma (Apollinaire) 161 Bal espagnol dans la rue (Lumière) 256 Beyond Cinema : the Art of Projection. Films, Videos and Installations from 1963 to 2005 (Hamburger Bahnof) 382 Big Brother 346 Big Swallow (The) (Richardson) 370 Biosphere II 346 Birth of the Clinic (Foucault) 366 Butterfly Dance (Armat) 261 Cahiers du cinéma 191, 193 Cahiers Louis-Lumière 180, 197 Candid Camera (NBC) 334 Ceremony (The) (Oshima) 191 Chicago Press and Tribune (The) 140 Cinéa-ciné pour tous 308, 314 Cinema Effect (The) (Cubitt) 51 Cinéma et suture (Oudart) 184-186, 188 Cinémas 197 Cinématographie française (La) 314 Cinéthique 26, 180-181, 183, 187-190 Cirque olympique (Franconi) 77, 88 Civilization and Its Discontents (Freud) 242 Communications 26, 183 Confessions (Rousseau) 24-25 Cotton Candy (Gehr) 389 Creative Evolution (Bergson) 115-117, 124 Culture of Time and Space (Kern) 223

Cynghalais: danse aux couteaux (Lumière) 256 Danse du sabre (Lumière) 256 Danse serpentine (Lumière) 267-269 Danse serpentine dans la cage aux lions 271 Danse serpentine de Loie Fuller 264 Danse tyrolienne (Lumière) 256 Death and the Labyrinth (Foucault) 366, 373 Des dispositifs pulsionnels (Lyotard) 373, 386 Dial M For Murder (Hitchcock) 229 Dictionnaire des arts de peinture, sculpture et gravure (Watelet, Levesque) 24 Dictionnaire de Trévoux 75 Dîner à la ferme (RTS) 356-358) Discipline and Punish (Foucault) 16, 35, 36, 43 Discourse, Figure (Lyotard) 374 Dissemination (Derrida) 375 Divagations (Mallarmé) 250, 258 Duchess of Langeais (The) (Rivette) 207208, 211 Duration and Simultaneity (Bergson) 122, 125 Ecrits (Lacan) 184 Elephant (Sant) 198, 200-201, 205, 209, 213 Emile Reynaud. Le véritable inventeur du cinéma (Lonjon) 174 Ernie Gehr’s Panoramas of the Moving Image (MoMA) 385 Essai sur les données immédiates de la conscience (Bergson) 122-123 Essex Street Market (Gehr) 389 Été indien (Ollier) 374 Etudes d’histoire et de philosophie des sciences (Bachelard) 40 Fantasmagorie (La) (Milner) 25 Eureka (Gehr) 389 Eyes Wide Shut (Kubrick) 203-204 Faisons un rêve (Guitry) 227 Fire Dance (Fuller) 250 First Person (Penn) 337-339 Five (Kiarostami) 211 Force et signification (Derrida) 187-189 Forecast of Television (A) (Arnheim) 319 Formation of the Scientific Mind (Bachelard) 40-41 France Tour Détour Deux Enfants (GodardMiéville) 334 From The Other Side (Akerman) 202

400 

Index of Titles

Future Cinema. The Cinematic Imaginary after Film (ZKM) 282

Mouvement (Le) (Marey) 287 Movement (Marey) 102-103

Gaulois (Le) 252, 306 Génération 01 (TSR) 352 Grecian Dancing Girl (Muybridge) 260 Gros plan (Cardinal) 331 Gros plan sur la célébrité (Cardinal) 333 Guerre au vingtième siècle (La) (Robida) 233 Guerre infernale (La) (Giffard) 234

Naissance de l’idée de photographie (Brunet) 34 National Observer (The) 258 Nature (La) 107, 219, 287 Navire Night (Duras) 231 New Impressions of Africa (Roussel) 368 New York Daily News (The) 261 New York Herald (The) 152 New York Journal of Commerce 142 New York Sun (The) 155 New York Times (The) 132-134, 145, 148, 150, 159 New York Tribune (The) 147, 152 Next of Kin (Egoyan) 232 Night Thoughts (Young) 360 Noces d’Arlequin (Les) (Carlin) 80 Nombres (Sollers) 376 Normal and the Pathological (The) (Canguilhem) 39 Notes for a theory of representation (Oudart) 192

Has the Film Already Started? (Lemaître) 375 Hermès 29 Heureuse Pêche (L’) 81 Hiroshima Mon Amour (Resnais) 375 Histoire générale du cinéma (Sadoul) 282-283 History of the Motion Picture (Jenkins) 278 Horaces (Les) (Salieri) 235 How I Wrote Certain of My Books (Roussel) 367 Ideology and Ideological Apparatuses (Althusser) 27, 131 Informateur photo (L’) 307 Interastral Drama (An) (Cros) 363 Introduction to Metaphysics (An) (Bergson) 120 Jetée (La) (Marker) 371 Journal amusant (Le) 235 Journal de Paris 77, 79, 81 Lady in the Lake (Montgomery) 326-328, 335 Language and Cinema (Metz) 305 Language of New Media (Manovich) 51, 68 Last Laugh (The) (Murnau) 202 Last Year in Marienbad (Resnais) 375 Lectures pour tous (Dumayet) 329 Light Out ! (Coe) 335, 339 Loft Story (M6) 346, 348-349, 351, 358 London Observer (The) 159 Lonedale Operator (The) (Griffith) 223 Lonely Villa (Griffith) 229 Los Aïnos à Ueso (Lumière) 256 Lost Highway (Lynch) 232 M (Lang) 208 Magie blanche dévoilée (La) (Decremps) 85 Magnum 305 Mail and Express (The) 153 Maldoror-Poems Dispositive (The) (Ponge) 359 Manchester Guardian (The) 132-134, 159 Manège anglais (Astley) 77 Man With the Rubber Head (Méliès) 370 Matter and Memory (Bergson) 115, 125 Mayen (TSR), 1903 353-358 Meniñas (Las) (Velasquez) 72, 184-185 Miroir (Le) (Baltrusaïtis) 24 Moonlight Sonata (Beethoven) 198 Morale du joujou (Baudelaire) 281

Observer (The) 132-134 Order of Things (The) (Foucault) 367 Painter of Modern Life (The) (Baudelaire) 361362 Panopticon or the Inspection-House (Bentham) 35-36 Panorama of Flatiron Building (MutoscopeBiograph) 390 Philadelphia Photographer (The) 139 Photographie animée (La) (Trutat) 98 Pillar of Fire (The) (Méliès) 254 Pirouette (Muybridge) 259 Poems (Ducasse) 359 Poésies (Lautréamont) 25 Practice of Every Life (The) (Certeau) 28 Projections. Les transports de l’image (Fresnoy) 382-383 Principia (Newton) 127 Rationalisme appliqué (Le) (Bachelard) 40 Reading Capital (Althusser-Balibar) 191 Rear Window (Hitchcock) 197 Return to Reason (Man Ray) 316 Revue du Cinéma (La) 319-320, 325 Rope (The) (Hitchcock) 326-328 Rougyff (Guffroy) 86 Safety Last (Lloyd) 210 Saturday Evening Post 142 Sciences et voyages (Lumière) 22 Scientific American 149-150 Scream (Craven) 227 Serpentintanz (Skladanowsky) 264 Sex, Lies and Videotapes (Soderbergh) 232 Ship’s Reporter 326 Side/Walk/Shuttle (Gehr) 389

401

Index of Titles

Signifiant imaginaire (Le) (Metz) 27 Sixième étage (Bluwal) 324 Skirt Dance (Armat) 261 Songs of Maldoror (The) (Lautréamont) 359 Spleen de Paris (Le) (Baudelaire) 362 Super Seniors (TSR) 341, 355-356 Technique et idéologie (Comolli) 187-191 Techniques of the Observer (Crary) 276 Téléphone (Le) (Montifaud) 230 Téléphonoscope (Le) 233 Temps (Le) 354 Ten (Kiarostami) 203-208 Terminal (The) (Spielberg) 197 Terrains 30 Terrible angoisse (Pathé) 229 Time-Image and Movement-Image (Deleuze) 115 Toy Story (Pixar) 387 Travail, lecture, jouissance (Daney) 186-188 Trésor de la langue française 75 Tribune de Genève (La) 353 Twentieth Century (Robida) 222-247 Umbrella Dance (Armat) 261 Uncle Tom’s Cabin (Edison) 158 Un Coup de dés (Mallarmé) 25 Understanding Media (McLuhan) 247

Vantage Point (Travis) 213 Videodrome (Cronenberg) 232 Vie parisienne (La) 235 Vingtième Siècle (Le) (Robida) 305 Visual Tactics (Museum für Gegenwartskunst) 382 Vocations (Frappat) 333 Voix humaine (La) (Cocteau) 227 Vol des oiseaux (Le) (Marey) 101, 106 Voyeur (The) (Robbe-Grillet) 374 Vue (La) (Roussel) 367-377 Walden (Mekas) 389 Walden (Thoreau) 338 War and cinema (Virilio) 58 Wes Craven’s New Nightmare (West) 227 When A Stranger Calls (Craven) 227 Will of Knowledge (The) (Foucault) 36, 87 Work of Art in the Age of Its Technological Reproductibility (The) (Benjamin) 130 Workers Leaving the Factory (After Lumière) (Gehr) 389 X-Screen. Films Installations and Actions of the 1960s and 1970s (MUMOK) 382



Index of Names

Except names being only in footnotes Acres, Birt 293 Adorno, Theodor W. 305 Agamben, Giorgio 17, 21, 29, 92, 131, 196 Akerman, Chantal 197, 202 Albera, François 16-17, 31, 33, 49, 55, 60, 67, 95, 120, 131, 161, 197, 205, 218-219, 222, 238, 246, 253, 267-268, 304, 305, 342-343, 346, 364, 376, 383 Althusser, Louis 27, 28, 131, 179, 186, 191 Altman, Rick 218, 220, 245 Anders, Gunther 305 Andre, Carl 64 Annabelle 254 Anschütz, Ottomar 260-261, 279, 280-281, 283, 291, 297 Apollinaire, Guillaume 24, 161-164, 178, 364 Appadurai, Arjun 345 Arasse, Daniel 80 Arcy, Jean d’ 329 Armat, Thomas 171-172, 261, 277 Arnheim, Rudolf 47, 319 Astley, Philip 77 Astruc, Alexandre 367 Bachelard, Gaston 33, 39-43, 128, 182 Balázs, Béla 47, 115 Baltrusaïtis, Jurgis 24, 181 Balzac, Honoré de 208 Barney, Matthew 383 Barthes, Roland 63, 93, 305 Barton, Béatrice 354-357 Baudelaire, Charles 47, 281, 316, 361-363, 365, 377 Baudry, Jean-Louis 26-27, 49, 70, 131, 170, 174, 179, 180-183, 186, 188-193, 196-197, 305, 360, 374-375, 381 Bazin, André 47, 54-55, 62, 93, 111, 320, 330, 386, 390 Béard, Guy 164 Beechey, Vincent 136 Beethoven, Ludwig von 199 Belting, Hans 52, 63, 66-67 Bell, Alexander Graham 218-219 Benjamin, Walter 47, 54, 63, 130 Bentham, Jeremy 35-7, 43, 86, 346, 373 Benveniste, Emile 26 Bergson, Henri 17, 32, 58, 70, 93, 106, 111, 115-128, 271, 394 Berkeley, Busby 273 Berkeley, George 71 Berthelot, Marcellin 95-96 Beuys, Joseph 64

Bichat, Marie François Xavier 81 Birch, Herbert 136 Bitzer, Billy 293 Bluwal, Marcel 324 Bolter, David 47 Bonitzer, Pascal 191 Boullier, Dominique 342 Brakhage, Stan 275, 389 Branigan, Edward 51 Brewster, William 137 Brunet, François 34 Brunoy, Blanchette 333 Bryan, William Jennings 151, 156 Buffalo Bill (William Frederick Cody) 256 Canguilhem, Georges 31, 39-41 Cardinal, Pierre 331-333 Carlin, Carlo Antonio Bertinazzi 80 Carré, Patrice 220-223 Cartwright, Lisa 58 Casarès, Maria 331 Casetti, Francesco 130, 144 Cavell, Stanley 54 Certeau, Michel de 28, 304 Chartroule, Marie-Aurélie see Montifaud Chomon, Segundo de 254 Claretie, Jules 317 Claudet, Antoine 137, 140-141 Clément-Maurice 238 Cochran, Robert 246 Cocteau, Jean 177, 227, 375, 383 Coe, Fred 335, 337 Coffman, Elizabeth 249-250 Cohen-Séat, Gilbert 304 Comolli, Jean-Louis 26, 187-191, 193 Comus (Doctor) 79 Corra, Bruno 251 Corday, Charlotte 81 Corning, Leonard 146 Corti, José 361, 367 Coutinsouza, Pierre-Victor 308 Craven, Wes 227-228 Crary, Jonathan 15, 137, 276-277 Cronenberg, David 232 Cros, Charles 363-365, 377 Cubitt, Sean 47, 51 Cusa, Nicolas de 72 Cyrano de Bergerac (Savinien) 25 Dagognet, François 30, 95, 97 Dagron, René 367

404  Daney, Serge 186-188 Daumas, Maurice 30 Day (Will) 284 Debutade 82 Decremps, Henri 85 Deleuze, Gilles 37, 42-43, 53-54, 70, 90, 93, 111, 115-116, 128, 186, 191 Delluc, Louis 163, 196, 251, 309 Demenÿ, Georges 57, 98, 257-259, 267, 283, 307 Derrida, Jacques 181, 187, 189-190, 375-377 Devillers, Renée 333 Dewey, Thomas 321 Disney, Walt 383 Doane, Mary Ann 47, 59 Ducasse, Isodore see Lautréamont Duchamp, Marcel 283, 344 Dulac, Germaine 178, 251 Dulac, Nicolas 164, 180 Dumayet, Pierre 329-330, 333 Duncan, Isadora 257 Duras, Marguerite 231, 375 Dux, Pierre 333 Eastman, George 303 Edison, Thomas 99, 103, 118, 131, 148-149, 155, 158, 171-173, 219, 241, 252-256, 260, 262-263, 266, 268-269, 282, 288, 292, 363-364 Egoyan, Atom 232 Eikhenbaum, Boris 300 Eisenstein, Sergei 47, 152-153, 275, 380 Elsaesser, Thomas 13, 17, 46-47, 51, 55, 57-60, 130 Emmanuel, Maurice 258-259 Epstein, Jean 47, 112, 115, 370, 397 Erice, Victor 197, 383 Esbrard, Lina 269 Fallon, John 141-142 Farocki, Harun 58, 292, 389 Faye, Jean-Pierre 374 Febvre, Lucien 30 Ferraris, Maurizio 246 Fischer, Claude S. 229 Fisher, Robert A. 145 Flichy, Patrice 222, 299 Foucault, Michel 11-13, 15, 18, 21, 27-29, 33, 35, 36-43, 54, 72, 75, 87, 89-90, 131, 184-186, 190-191, 195, 302, 359, 360, 365-377. Frampton, Hollis 388 Francastel, Pierre 26, 179, 181, 184 Franconi, Antonio 77-78 Franklin, Benjamin 88 Frappat, Jean 333 Freedland, George 320-322, 324-328 Fregoli, Leopoldo 270 Freud, Sigmund 27, 49, 71, 182, 242 Friendly, Fred W. 322 Frizot, Michel 170, 173 Fuller, Loïe 249-254, 258, 263-264, 267-268

Index of Names

Galipaux, Félix 239 Galvani, Luigi 79 Gaudreault, André 16-17, 57, 60, 95, 120, 125, 149, 155, 157, 164, 171, 180, 191, 220, 238, 254, 267, 294, 341, 360, 385, 388 Gaumont, Léon 252, 269, 283, 291, 307 Gehr, Ernie 379, 385, 388-391 Gehri, Alfred 324 Genette, Gérard 200 Gervereau, Laurent 173 Giffard, Henri 224-225, 234 Gilles, Bertrand 30 Ginna, Arnoldo 251 Girel, Constant 256 Gitelman, Lisa 129, 131 Godard, Jean-Luc 60, 334-335, 383 Gordon, Douglas 383 Gordon, Howard 246 Gould, Jack 319 Graham, Dan 303 Graham, Rodney 292 Greenaway, Peter 383 Greuze, Jean-Baptiste 80 Griffith, David (Wark) 223, 229, 246, 293, 321, 335, 388 Grimm, Friedrich Melchior 82 Grimoin-Samson, Raoul 293 Grusin, Richard 47 Guffroy, Armand-Benoît-Joseph see Rougyff Guitry, Sacha 227 Gunning, Tom 16, 57, 152, 171, 191, 229, 235, 246, 252, 264, 360, 388-390 Guy, Alice 269 Guys, Constantin 361-363 Hamon, Philippe 361 Hanna, Christophe 360, 373 Harrison, Benjamin 146 Haudricourt, André-Georges 30 Hays, William 220 Hearst, William Randolph 155 Henry, Pierre 308-309, 316 Heyl, Henry R. 266 Hitchcock, Alfred 61, 63, 197, 229, 326-328, 383 Horkheimer, Max 305 Horner, George 278 Huygue, Pierre 383 Kamm, Leonard Ulrich 283 Kant, Immanuel 70, 123, 212 Kennedy, Elijah R. 147-148 Kern, Stephen 223-224 Kessler, Frank 165, 168, 262 Kiarostami, Abbas 197, , 203-207, 211-212, 383 Kircher, Athanasius 69, 285 Kittler, Friedrich 15, 47, 54, 58, 247 Kracauer, Siegfried 47 Kubrick, Stanley 202

405

Index of Names

Isaacs, John T. 23 Jacobs, Ken 388 Janssen, Jules 57, 364 Jaques-Dalcroze, Emile 258 Jarry, Alfred 32, 119, 364 Jenkins, Charles Francis 171-172 Jimenez, Andrew 387 Jones, William B. 138 Laban, Rudolph 257 Lacan, Jacques 27, 67,182-186, 191, 193 Lamotte, Jean-Marc 162, 167, 168, 175 Lang, Fritz 208, 246 Lange, André 233 Langenheim, Brothers (Frederick and William) 138-140, 144 Lastra, James 221-222 Latham, Woodville 171-173 Latour, Bruno 22, 30, 52, 180 Lautréamont, Isodore Ducasse 25-26, 359 Lavallée, Etienne 247 Lavater, Johann Kaspar 82 Lebesque, Morvan 329-330 Le Dantec, Félix 317 Ledoux, Claude-Nicolas 86 Ledru, Nicolas Philippe see Comus Leroi-Gourhan, André 30 Le Roy, Jean Aimé 266 Lévi-Strauss, Claude 303, 373 Leyland, J. 142 L’Herbier, Marcel 115, 178, 251 Little Tich (Harry Relph) 270 Littré, Emile 21 Lloyd, Harold 210 Londe, Albert 58 Lonjon, Bernard 174-175 Lorde, André de 229, 244-245 Lucretius, Titus Carus 278 Luhmann, Niklas 50 Lumière, Brothers (Antoine and Louis) 94, 99, 103, 110, 113, 148, 155, 161, 166-177 Lynch, David 232 Lyotard, Jean-François 245, 373-374, 381, 386 Mallarmé, Stéphane 25, 250, 258, 376-377 Mangan, Jack 326 Mannoni, Laurent 94-95, 118, 257, 259, 265-266, 279, 291, 360 Manovich, Lev 15, 47, 51, 55, 68, 305 Man Ray (Emmanuel Rudzitsky) 316 Marais, Jean 331 Marconi, Guglielmo 46 Marker, Chris 371, 383 Marey, Jules-Etienne 17, 23, 32, 36, 46, 57-59, 70-71, 93-113 Marin, Louis 26-27 Marinetti, Tomaso 46

Marion, Philippe 164, 254 Mauriac, François 329 Maurois, André 333 Mayer, Andreas 30 McKinley, Paige 130, 148 McKinley, William 151-157 McLaren, Norman 275 McLuhan, Marshall 230-232, 245 Mekas, Jonas 389 Méliès, Georges 112, 219, 252, 254, 370, 389 Mercier, Louis-Sébastien 76, 80, 83, 85 Messter, Oskar 46, 57-58, 268 Metz, Christian 15, 27, 53, 180, 196, 305 Meurisse, Paul 332 Miéville, Anne-Marie 334-335 Miller, Jacques-Alain 183-186 Milner, Max 25, 360-361, 365 Mitchell, W.J.T. 52 Montgomery, Robert 326, 335 Montifaud, Marc de 230 Moore, Annabelle Whitford 254 Munch, Edvard 315-317 Münsterberg, Hugo 47, 164 Murnau, Friedrich Wilhelm 203 Murrow, Edward R. 322-324 Muybridge, Edweard 23, 46, 58, 132, 259, 266, 364 Nekes, Werner 290 Niepce, Nicéphore 139 Ollier, Claude 374-376 Ortel, Philippe 361, 363 Oudart, Jean-Pierre 27, 183-184, 186-187, 191-192 Painlevé, Jean 66 Panofsky, Erwin  181, 184-185, 276 Pathé, Charles 117-118, 229, 237-239, 246, 252, 293, 301, 307-311, 314-316 Paul, R. William 57, 164, 293 Penn, Arthur 337 Perriault, Jacques 223, 232, 242, 244 Petit, Valentine 263 Pisano, Giusy 217, 235, 237-239 Planck, Ernst 288 Plateau, Joseph 100-103, 265, 282-285 Plato 54, 71, 166 Pleynet, Marcelin 26, 190, 374 Pollock, Jackson 64 Pond, Major 145 Ponge, Francis 25-26, 359-360 Posner, Bruce 388 Pressman, Jessica 129 Proust, Marcel 367 Pyasetsky 370 Quintyn, Olivier 303, 373 Ramirez, Francis 162 Resnais, Alain 375

406  Reynaud, Emile 148, 173-175, 266, 282, 285, 287, 289 Richard, A. P. 314-315 Richter, Hans 251 Ricœur, Paul 209 Rist, Pipilotti 383 Rivette, Jacques 207, 304 Roach, Joseph 130 Robbe-Grillet, Alain 374-375 Robert, Etienne-Gaspard 69 Roberts, Edward Barry 329 Robertson, Etienne 25, 305, 360, 365 Robida, Albert 31, 217-245 Roede, Halfdan Nobel 315 Roh, Franz 309 Root, M.A. 139-140 Rougyff 86 Rousseau, Jean-Jacques 24-25, 86, 88 Roussel, Raymond 306, 364, 366-377 Rudge, Arthur Roebuck 284, 289 Ruttmann, Walter 251 Rydstrom, Gary 387 Sadoul, Georges 118, 219, 282-283, 294 Saint Denis, Ruth 257 Sainte-Croix, Lallemand de 86, 88-89 Salieri, Antonio 235 Sandow, Eugen 260 Sant, Gus Van 198, 201, 213 Sartre, Jean-Paul 39, 115 Schaffer, Simon 30 Schaeffer, Pierre 333-334 Schlosser, Julius von 83 Schreiber, Flora R. 319 Schwartz, Hillel 258 Sconce, Jeffrey 47, 229, 234 Seldes, Gilbert 319 Shklovsky, Victor 304, 380, 384 Simondon, Gilbert 23, 31-32, 296 Sitney, P. Adams 388-389 Skladanowsky, Brothers (Emil and Max) 171172, 253, 263, 265, 268, 293 Smolderen, Thierry 240 Snow, C.P. 48 Soderbergh, Steven 232 Sollers, Philippe 374, 376-377

Index of Names

Souday, Paul 115 Spielberg, Steven 197, 202 Stampfer, Simon von 278, 283 Stewart, Garrett 47 Stoddard, John L. 133 Surnow, Joel 246 Talbot, William Henry 138 Thévenot, Jean 319-320 Thoreau, Henry-David 338 Tinguely, Jean 291 Tortajada, Maria 16-17, 31, 33, 49, 55, 67, 118, 124, 127, 131, 156, 218-219, 253, 268, 304-305, 341, 343, 346, 364, 376 Trahan, Pierre-Sirois 167 Trutat, Eugène 98, 101 Valéry, Paul 25, Varda, Agnès 197, 383 Velasquez, Diego 72, 184-185, 191 Verne, Jules 25, 31, 299, 364 Verniquet, Edme 76 Vertov, Dziga 189, 295 Viegne, Michel 361 Villiers de l’Isle Adam, Jean-Marie-MathiasPhilippe-Auguste de  31, 234, 364 Virilio, Paul 58 Vouilloux, Bernard 17, 26, 80, 90, 195 Vuillermoz, Emile 115 Wagner, Richard 136 Wahrol, Andy 64 Walton, Fred 227 Warner, Michael 129 Watson 219 West, Simon 227 Wheatstone, Charles 137 Wheeler, John L. 146-147 Whipple, John A. 138 Williams, Williams Carlos 297 Young, Edward 360 Zeno 124, 127 Zielinski, Siegfried 16, 58 Zumthor, Paul 240



Film Culture in Transition

General Editor: Thomas Elsaesser Thomas Elsaesser, Robert Kievit and Jan Simons (eds.) Double Trouble: Chiem van Houweninge on Writing and Filming, 1994 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 025 9 Thomas Elsaesser, Jan Simons and Lucette Bronk (eds.) Writing for the Medium: Television in Transition, 1994 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 054 9 Karel Dibbets and Bert Hogenkamp (eds.) Film and the First World War, 1994 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 064 8 Warren Buckland (ed.) The Film Spectator: From Sign to Mind, 1995 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 131 7; isbn hardcover 978 90 5356 170 6 Egil Törnqvist Between Stage and Screen: Ingmar Bergman Directs, 1996 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 137 9; isbn hardcover 978 90 5356 171 3 Thomas Elsaesser (ed.) A Second Life: German Cinema’s First Decades, 1996 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 172 0; isbn hardcover 978 90 5356 183 6 Thomas Elsaesser Fassbinder’s Germany: History Identity Subject, 1996 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 059 4; isbn hardcover 978 90 5356 184 3 Thomas Elsaesser and Kay Hoffmann (eds.) Cinema Futures: Cain, Abel or Cable? The Screen Arts in the Digital Age, 1998 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 282 6; isbn hardcover 978 90 5356 312 0 Siegfried Zielinski Audiovisions: Cinema and Television as Entr’Actes in History, 1999 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 313 7; isbn hardcover 978 90 5356 303 8

Kees Bakker (ed.) Joris Ivens and the Documentary Context, 1999 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 389 2; isbn hardcover 978 90 5356 425 7 Egil Törnqvist Ibsen, Strindberg and the Intimate Theatre: Studies in TV Presentation, 1999 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 350 2; isbn hardcover 978 90 5356 371 7 Michael Temple and James S. Williams (eds.) The Cinema Alone: Essays on the Work of Jean-Luc Godard 1985-2000, 2000 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 455 4; isbn hardcover 978 90 5356 456 1 Patricia Pisters and Catherine M. Lord (eds.) Micropolitics of Media Culture: Reading the Rhizomes of Deleuze and Guattari, 2001 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 472 1; isbn hardcover 978 90 5356 473 8 William van der Heide Malaysian Cinema, Asian Film: Border Crossings and National Cultures, 2002 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 519 3; isbn hardcover 978 90 5356 580 3 Bernadette Kester Film Front Weimar: Representations of the First World War in German Films of the Weimar Period (1919-1933), 2002 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 597 1; isbn hardcover 978 90 5356 598 8 Richard Allen and Malcolm Turvey (eds.) Camera Obscura, Camera Lucida: Essays in Honor of Annette Michelson, 2003 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 494 3 Ivo Blom Jean Desmet and the Early Dutch Film Trade, 2003 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 463 9; isbn hardcover 978 90 5356 570 4 Alastair Phillips City of Darkness, City of Light: Émigré Filmmakers in Paris 1929-1939, 2003 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 634 3; isbn hardcover 978 90 5356 633 6

Thomas Elsaesser, Alexander Horwath and Noel King (eds.) The Last Great American Picture Show: New Hollywood Cinema in the 1970s, 2004 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 631 2; isbn hardcover 978 905356 493 6 Thomas Elsaesser (ed.) Harun Farocki: Working on the Sight-Lines, 2004 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 635 0; isbn hardcover 978 90 5356 636 7 Kristin Thompson Herr Lubitsch Goes to Hollywood: German and American Film after World War I, 2005 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 708 1; isbn hardcover 978 90 5356 709 8 Marijke de Valck and Malte Hagener (eds.) Cinephilia: Movies, Love and Memory, 2005 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 768 5; isbn hardcover 978 90 5356 769 2 Thomas Elsaesser European Cinema: Face to Face with Hollywood, 2005 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 594 0; isbn hardcover 978 90 5356 602 2 Michael Walker Hitchcock’s Motifs, 2005 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 772 2; isbn hardcover 978 90 5356 773 9 Nanna Verhoeff The West in Early Cinema: After the Beginning, 2006 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 831 6; isbn hardcover 978 90 5356 832 3 Anat Zanger Film Remakes as Ritual and Disguise: From Carmen to Ripley, 2006 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 784 5; isbn hardcover 978 90 5356 785 2 Wanda Strauven The Cinema of Attractions Reloaded, 2006 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 944 3; isbn hardcover 978 90 5356 945 0

Malte Hagener Moving Forward, Looking Back: The European Avant-garde and the Invention of Film Culture, 1919-1939, 2007 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 960 3; isbn hardcover 978 90 5356 961 0 Tim Bergfelder, Sue Harris and Sarah Street Film Architecture and the Transnational Imagination: Set Design in 1930s European Cinema, 2007 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 984 9; isbn hardcover 978 90 5356 980 1 Jan Simons Playing the Waves: Lars von Trier’s Game Cinema, 2007 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 991 7; isbn hardcover 978 90 5356 979 5 Marijke de Valck Film Festivals: From European Geopolitics to Global Cinephilia, 2007 isbn paperback 978 90 5356 192 8; isbn hardcover 978 90 5356 216 1 Asbjørn Grønstad Transfigurations: Violence, Death, and Masculinity in American Cinema, 2008 isbn paperback 978 90 8964 010 9; isbn hardcover 978 90 8964 030 7 Vinzenz Hediger and Patrick Vonderau (eds.) Films that Work: Industrial Film and the Productivity of Media, 2009 isbn paperback 978 90 8964 013 0; isbn hardcover 978 90 8964 012 3 François Albera and Maria Tortajada (eds.) Cinema beyond Film: Media Epistemology in the Modern Era, 2010 isbn paperback 978 90 8964 083 3; isbn hardcover 978 90 8964 084 0 Pasi Väliaho Mapping the Moving Image: Gesture, Thought and Cinema circa 1900, 2010 isbn paperback 978 90 8964 140 3; isbn hardcover 978 90 8964 141 0 Pietsie Feenstra New Mythological Figures in Spanish Cinema: Dissident Bodies under Franco, 2011 isbn paperback 978 90 8964 304 9; isbn hardcover 978 90 8964 303 2

Eivind Røssaak (ed.) Between Stillness and Motion: Film, Photography, Algorithms, 2011 isbn paperback 978 90 8964 212 7; isbn hardcover 978 90 8964 213 4 Tara Forrest Alexander Kluge: Raw Materials for the Imagination, 2011 isbn paperback 978 90 8964 272 1; isbn hardcover 978 90 8964 273 8 Belén Vidal Figuring the Past: Period Film and the Mannerist Aesthetic, 2012 isbn 978 90 8964 282 0 Bo Florin Transition and Transformation: Victor Sjöström in Hollywood 1923-1930, 2012 isbn 978 90 8964 504 3 Erika Balsom Exhibiting Cinema in Contemporary Art, 2013 isbn 978 90 8964 471 8 Christian Jungen Hollywood in Canne$: The History of a Love-Hate Relationship, 2014 isbn 978 90 8964 566 1 Michael Cowan Walter Ruttmann and the Cinema of Multiplicity: Avant-Garde Film ‒ Advertising ‒ Modernity, 2014 isbn 978 90 8964 585 2 Temenuga Trifonova Warped Minds: Cinema and Psychopathology, 2014 isbn 978 90 8964 632 3 Christine N. Brinckmann Color and Empathy: Essays on Two Aspects of Film, 2014 isbn 978 90 8964 656 9