American Law in the Age of Hypercapitalism: The Worker, the Family, and the State 0814715621, 9780814715628

Since the fall of communism, laissez-faire capitalism has experienced renewed popularity. Flush with victory, the United

261 21 32MB

English Pages 268 [269] Year 1998

Report DMCA / Copyright

DOWNLOAD PDF FILE

Recommend Papers

American Law in the Age of Hypercapitalism: The Worker, the Family, and the State
 0814715621, 9780814715628

  • 0 0 0
  • Like this paper and download? You can publish your own PDF file online for free in a few minutes! Sign Up
File loading please wait...
Citation preview

"Every membe r o f Congress , an d ever y judge , shoul d rea d this book . Rut h Colke r cut s throug h th e rhetori c o f laissez faire economic s tha t dominate s legislativ e an d judicial deci sion-making and exposes its theoretical fallacies and practical harms. Why d o we consider th e worker, th e family , an d th e state t o b e thre e separate , independen t units ? Colke r chal lenges u s t o conside r a n Americ a i n whic h th e stat e play s a more active role in ensuring th e health an d well-being o f it s families an d workers. Instea d o f th e regressiv e an d punitiv e policies of the recent Congress, in areas ranging from welfare to disabilit y payment s t o immigration , Colke r offer s u s a vision of a country that combines capitalism and nurturance . Her boo k come s a t a critical juncture i n ou r nationa l debat e on socia l welfar e an d policy . Le t u s hop e it s lesson s ar e absorbed by our leaders." —Chai R. Feldblum Director, Federa l Legislation Clini c Georgetown Universit y La w Center

Other Book s b y Rut h Colke r

Hybrid: Bisexual, Multiracials, and Other Misfits under American Law (1996) Pregnant Men: Practice, Theory and the Law (1994) Abortion & Dialogue: Pro-Choice, Pro-Life and American Law (1992)

AMERICAN LA W I N TH E AG E OF HYPERCAPITALIS M The Worker, the Family , and the Stat e

Ruth Colke r

NEW YOR K UNIVERSIT Y PRES S New York and Londo n

NEW YORK UNIVERSIT Y PRES S New York an d Londo n Copyright © 199 8 by Ne w Yor k Universit y All rights reserve d Library o f Congres s Cataloging-in-Publicatio n Dat a Colker, Ruth . American la w in th e ag e of hypercapitalis m : the worker, th e family, an d th e stat e / Rut h Colker . p. cm

. — (Critica l America )

Includes index . ISBN 0-8147-1562-1 (clot h : alk. paper). ISBN 0-8147-1563- X (pbk . : alk. paper ) 1. Labor law s an d legislation—Unite d States . 2. Discriminatio n in employment—La w an d legislation—Unite d States . 3. Critica l legal studies—United States . 4. Capitalism—Unite d States . 5. Law and economics . 6. Sociological jurisprudence. I . Title. II. Series. KF3455.Z9C65 199

8

344.7301—dc2i 94-3395

9 CIP

New Yor k University Pres s books ar e printed o n acid-fre e paper , and their bindin g material s ar e chose n fo r strengt h an d durability . Manufactured i n th e United State s o f Americ a 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2

1

for Sammy , Julia, and Sasha , and the other babies of 1997 May they thrive in a society tha t genuinely respect s its childre n

CONTENTS

Preface ix Acknowledgments xiii 1 Th e Tattered Safet y Ne t 1 2 Affirmativ e Actio n 2 7 3 Disabilit y Discriminatio n 6 2 4 Famil y an d Medica l Leav e 10 0 5 Sexua l Orientatio n Discriminatio n 15 5 6 Unprotecte d Workers 18 2 7 Medina' s Stor y 20 7 Notes 22

1

Index 24 5 About the Author 25 1

PREFACE

The ide a fo r thi s boo k bega n t o develo p i n th e fal l o f 198 8 when I visited th e Universit y o f Toront o Facult y o f Law . Like most Americans , I kne w ver y littl e abou t Canadia n la w an d society. I did no t expec t Canada' s lega l regim e t o diffe r muc h from ours , and I did expec t it s lega l syste m t o reflec t a respec t for ou r tw o hundre d year s o f constitutiona l jurisprudence . What I learned abou t Canadia n constitutiona l la w was tha t it s protection o f individua l right s differe d markedl y fro m th e American model . Fo r example , whil e th e Unite d State s wa s involved i n a bitte r figh t ove r affirmativ e action , Canada' s Charter o f Right s protecte d it . Whereas th e Unite d State s wa s considering whethe r t o adop t an y federa l famil y leav e polic y at al l (and , o f course , onl y unpai d leave) , th e governmen t o f Ontario wa s expandin g it s alread y generou s famil y leav e leg -

X

Preface

islation t o encompass th e possibility o f nearly on e year o f pai d leave. The possibilit y o f a differen t balanc e amon g th e state , th e employer, and the family became even more apparent when I was asked to give the keynote address at a disability rights conferenc e sponsored by Griffiths Universit y in Brisbane, Australia, in 1996. Visiting Australia gav e m e a n opportunit y t o lear n mor e abou t how othe r commo n la w countrie s ha d develope d law s regardin g disability discrimination . M y researc h o n th e law s o f Australia , Canada, an d th e recentl y passe d la w o f Grea t Britai n reveale d great divergenc e amon g thes e countries . Althoug h th e Unite d States wa s th e firs t o f thes e countrie s t o pas s a comprehensiv e statute t o protect agains t disabilit y discrimination , as interprete d by th e court s it s curren t protection s ar e ofte n th e narrowes t o f these countries . I als o hear d a differen t styl e o f rhetori c i n Australia , com pared wit h th e Unite d States , in regar d t o th e state' s obligatio n to persons with disabilities . Whereas th e United States ' rhetori c is ofte n base d o n th e presumption s o f a laissez-faire economy , Australia's rhetori c usually presumes that th e state should hav e an activ e role in th e live s of al l its citizens . This opportunit y t o stud y th e lega l system s o f Canad a an d Australia gav e me a new perspective on the presumptions o f th e American lega l system . I t ha s becom e commonplac e i n Ameri can law schools to presume tha t "la w and economics" will dom inate legal decisions with thei r consideratio n o f utility an d effi ciency. Increasingly, we have no t aske d our student s t o conside r the human value s that underli e ou r choice s within th e law. This presumption als o extends t o the political arena, in which politi cians compet e ove r ho w muc h the y ca n cu t bac k o n ai d to poo r mothers, without considerin g the impact on our next generatio n

Preface

xi

of children. The debate abou t socia l welfare i n Canad a an d Australia seem s mor e embedde d i n th e huma n value s o f lov e an d compassion towar d ou r presen t an d nex t generation . The subtitl e o f thi s book— The Worker, the Family, and the State—reflects th e tripartit e divisio n tha t w e usually se e in th e United State s whe n w e discus s th e worke r an d th e family . Although ou r usua l presumptio n i s tha t thes e categorie s ar e three separat e units , it is time tha t w e began t o se e that parent ing is work an d tha t th e stat e should pla y a crucial rol e i n eas ing th e famil y responsibilitie s o f parents , regardles s o f ho w much mone y the y ear n outsid e thei r home . Othe r countrie s have a more integrated notio n o f the worker, the family, an d th e state, but withou t movin g towar d a socialist economi c system . These comparativ e observation s le d m e t o conclude , reluc tantly, tha t th e Unite d State s ha s move d towar d wha t i n thi s book I term hyper capitalism—a capitalis m tha t is overly enam ored wit h laissez-fair e economic s an d insufficientl y concerne d with ou r healt h an d well-being . Fortunately , th e tid e ma y b e turning. Even financie r Georg e Soro s recentl y criticize d Amer ica's devotio n t o hypercapitalism . Accordingly , I hope tha t thi s book arrives a t a good moment i n ou r nationa l debat e about th e relationship between the citizen and the state and that I can help put bac k th e need s o f peopl e int o th e America n mode l o f capi talism.

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

The proble m wit h writin g acknowledgement s i s tha t on e i s bound to forget t o thank lots of people who were of tremendou s assistance. Casual conversation s wit h colleague s a t conferences , brief conversation s i n th e hall s o f th e la w school , insightfu l comments fro m semina r students , an d hel p i n th e librar y fro m whoever wa s a t th e referenc e des k a t th e momen t helpe d mak e this book possible, yet my memories ar e not sufficiently specifi c to offe r appropriat e thanks . So , first , thank s t o al l th e peopl e who provid e th e backgroun d suppor t i n m y lif e tha t I probabl y take too easil y fo r granted . As fo r thos e peopl e who m I especially wan t t o name , let m e start with my edito r a t New York University Press , Niko Pfund . Even afte r becomin g directo r o f th e press , Niko staye d faithfu l to m y project . He' s probabl y rea d som e chapter s mor e ofte n

xiv

Acknowledgments

than I have. He sen t me books and articles a s well as captivatin g ideas. I hope I have been a s responsive t o his man y suggestion s as he has been responsiv e t o my never-endin g queries . Theresa ("Tish" ) Zimmerman , m y researc h assistan t a t th e University o f Pittsburg h Schoo l o f Law , also offere d enormou s assistance. I wrote the first draf t o f this book while pregnant an d had littl e inclinatio n t o wal k al l ove r th e Pit t campu s t o fin d books an d researc h material . Tish thu s ofte n serve d a s my legs , spending man y hour s i n th e Economic s Librar y findin g mater ial fo r me . Afte r I gav e birth , he r diligenc e continue d a s sh e brought materia l t o m y hom e whil e I was o n maternit y leav e from th e office . My colleague s Jule s Lobe l (law ) an d Lis a Brus h (sociology ) also deserve a special note of thanks. On ou r runs together, Jules helped me conceptualize the basic idea behind this book throug h his critiqu e o f capitalism . Lisa introduced m e t o writers i n soci ology wh o als o us e a sophisticate d economi c analysis . Bot h o f them listene d t o my hypothese s an d insight s wit h patienc e an d inquisitiveness. I hop e thi s fina l produc t doesn' t disappoin t them. And the n ther e ar e th e countles s peopl e wh o hear d m e deliver draft s o f variou s chapter s a t conference s an d wer e gen erous wit h thei r responses . Chapte r 2 received som e assistanc e from m y Canadia n colleague s at the University o f Alberta, wh o invited m e t o writ e tha t chapte r fo r a symposiu m o n U.S . and Canadian constitutiona l law . My Australian colleagues , whom I met a t a symposiu m o n disabilit y right s a t Griffit h Universit y in Queensland , helpe d wit h th e argumen t develope d i n chapte r 3. Brian Doyle, a professor i n Great Britain, also offered valuabl e assistance with that chapter . A workshop sponsore d by the Uni versity o f Illinoi s La w School gave me invaluabl e assistanc e fo r

Acknowledgments

xv

both th e firs t an d thir d chapter s an d particularl y helpe d m e develop m y definitio n o f capitalism . The participant s a t a sym posium sponsore d b y th e Yale Journal of Law and Feminism i n the fal l o f 199 6 wa s critica l t o th e developmen t o f th e idea s i n chapters 4 and 6. The participants a t a symposium sponsore d b y the Hastings Law Journal i n th e winter o f 199 7 also helped m e formulate th e thesi s o f chapte r 5 . Finally Danie l Posi n (Tulan e University) offere d m e a wonderfull y constructiv e "blind " review a t th e fina l stage s o f th e project . Thus , wit h hel p fro m colleagues in Canada , Great Britain, and Australia, as well as the United States , I fee l fortunat e t o hav e bee n abl e t o writ e thi s book in a truly multinationa l context . The Document Technology Cente r a t the University o f Pitts burgh Schoo l o f La w made a typically fin e contributio n t o thi s project. The hig h qualit y o f its work couple d wit h a miraculou s turnaround tim e mad e writing pleasurabl e instea d o f drudger y The financial suppor t o f the School of Law for this project is also greatly appreciated . Dea n Pete r Shan e allowe d m e t o us e extr a research assistanc e a t a time o f fisca l austerit y an d wa s flexibl e with my maternity leav e so that I could finish thi s project. I was fortunate t o finis h thi s projec t wit h th e suppor t o f m y ne w home—the Ohi o Stat e Universit y Colleg e o f Law . Dea n Gre gory William s agree d t o suppor t thi s projec t eve n befor e I ha d moved m y famil y t o Columbus , Ohio , an d therefor e mad e i t possible fo r m e t o finis h thi s projec t i n Pittsburg h eve n whil e organizing a relocation t o Columbus . And as always, I would like to thank my famil y fo r thei r sup port while I wrote this book. My husband, Edward Eybel, helped take car e o f th e childre n an d th e househol d chore s whil e I pounded awa y o n th e keyboard ; my five-year-old , Car a Colker Eybel, learned t o respec t m y offic e spac e s o that sh e coul d pla y

XVI

Acknowledgments

computer game s withou t ruinin g m y work , an d m y infant , Samuel Colker-Eybel , cooperate d b y sittin g quietl y i n hi s chai r while I typed away. I feel fortunate t o have been able to combin e family, work, pregnancy, and childbirth whil e writing this book . I hop e tha t w e ca n develo p policie s tha t giv e mor e peopl e th e opportunities tha t I have had, to spend tim e with thei r childre n while experiencin g a fulfilling career .

1 THE TATTERE D SAFET Y NE T

Isabelle Dumont, a legal immigrant to the United States from Haiti, works for the Bayer family. In return for taking care of their children while they are at work each day (from at least 8 A.M. until 6 P.M.), she is paid $250 per week. When the family goes on vacation, she has her own (unpaid) vacation. Because she is not a U.S. citizen, Isabelle is not eligible for Medicaid, and she cannot afford private health insurance on her modest wages. Isabelle brings her own daughter, Medina, to work with her each day and finds it exhausting to juggle the child care responsibilities of another family's children along with those of her own. Isabelle is worried about retiring someday because the Bayers do not contribute to Social Security on her behalf When she asks about this, Mrs. Bayer tells her it is in her best interest that they do not, because if

2

The Tattered Safet y Ne t

they did, Isabelle would also be responsible for Social Security taxes. When Isabelle heard that the federal minimum wage was being raised, she asked Mr. Bayer if she was entitled to a pay increase. Mr. Bayer smiled and said, "You're not covered by federal wage and hour laws because you are a domestic worker/' Because Isabelle's immigration status is dependent on her being employed with the Bayers, she has to look the other way when Mr. Bayer makes lewd comments or touches her in ways that she finds unwelcome. Isabelle lives on the margins of American society. If she becomes pregnant again, she can expect no assistance from the state. Even if she becomes a U.S. citizen, she would have to work for an employer who employed more than fifty people in order to qualify for twelve weeks of unpaid leave (which she could never afford) after giving birth. Even her poor, native Haiti has better maternity benefits than the rich United States does. And her quality of life would fall even lower if she developed any of the disabilities that seem to run in her family —diabetes and hypertension in particular —because of the few health insurance benefits and work opportunities available to her. Even though Isabelle keeps hearing that America has great civil rights laws, they do not apply to her because she is part of the underpaid contingent workforce. She is hoping that her daughter will do well enough in school to win a college scholarship someday, but she has been warned that the special scholarship programs for racial minorities have been eliminated in her state following a recent Supreme Court decision. It does not seem fair to her that the Bayers are confident that their children will attend Harvard someday, since both parents are alumni of that institution. When Mr. Bayer sends in his contri-

The Tattered Safet y Ne t

3

bution to the school each year, he chuckles that it is really his children's insurance policy. Isabelle has considered trying to juggle school with a parttime job in order to become a licensed practical nurse. It is unlikely, however, that she would find the conditions in that profession any better than those in her current situation. Not only do licensed practical nurses have to perform more and more menial jobs because of the continual layoffs of nurses, but they also are not allowed to unionize because at their $ 7 per hour wage, they are considered to be "supervisors" exempt from the labor law's protection. Ironically, highly paid professional employees like airline pilots are allowed to join a union. In the United States, it is hard to understand who is worker and who is management. Isabelle has heard that the best nanny jobs these days involve working for people with political aspirations. Such employers actually seem to fear that they may someday be criticized for shirking their responsibilities to pay Social Security taxes. But these people also are not hiring recent immigrants. Indeed, some of them are actually hiring unemployed white elementary schoolteachers to cradle their infants. Isabelle has seen these high-priced nannies at the park—they have no idea how to calm a screaming infant or discipline a bratty child. Their academic degree, she realizes, makes them qualified in a way that she cannot match, despite her decades of child care experience. She is determined that her own daughter will have the credentials that matter in this capitalist society so that she, too, can hire someone to take care of her children. America is the land of opportunity, she remembers. Whose opportunities, she wonders.... Isabelle's friends who emigrated to Canada report a different story. They have health insurance, and those who live in Quebec

4

The Tattered Safet y Ne t

receive some state support if they have children. In Canada, immigrants can work in child care centers where they actually earn a living wage with several paid weeks of vacation each year. (Isabelle has inquired about working at the local child care center, but the conditions and benefits are no better than at the Bayer residence.) From Isabelle's perspective in Haiti, North America looked like a uniform monolith. She is now beginning to wish she had heeded people's warnings that despite its thriving economy, America's version of capitalism is actually impoverished. Isabelle's stor y goe s virtuall y unhear d i n th e Unite d States . When Zo e Baird and Kimba Wood were unable t o be confirme d as U.S. attorney genera l because the y ha d employe d noncitize n nannies, the political response was to expand the Social Securit y exemption fo r thes e wealth y employer s rathe r tha n t o tr y t o improve th e nannies ' workin g conditions . Littl e though t wa s given t o th e fac t tha t th e Unite d States ' treatmen t o f domesti c workers harm s th e workers themselve s a s well as the country' s next generatio n o f children . Workin g parent s scrambl e every day to find saf e an d nurturin g environment s fo r thei r children , with almos t n o federa l subsid y o f chil d care , whereas wealth y parents receiv e increasin g subsidie s fo r thei r us e o f low-pai d immigrant labo r i n thei r homes . This boo k tell s Isabelle' s sid e o f th e story . Chapte r 2 question s why affirmative actio n for privileged white people in the form of alumni preference s g o unnotice d whil e affirmativ e actio n fo r racial minoritie s i s criticize d an d sai d t o contribut e t o th e "stigmatization" o f racial minorities. Why i s no stigm a attache d to th e privilege s extende d t o th e ultrarich ? I n chapte r 3, 1 com pare judicia l interpretation s o f th e American s wit h Disabilitie s

The Tattered Safety Net

5

Act with interpretations o f similar statute s in Canada, Australia, and Grea t Britain . Although th e Unite d State s wa s historicall y the leade r i n enactin g protectio n agains t disabilit y discrimina tion i n employment , th e Unite d State s i s th e onl y on e o f thes e countries tha t sometime s exclude s fro m coverag e peopl e wit h insulin-dependent diabete s or hypertension. Why d o U.S. courts render suc h narro w interpretation s o f disabilit y discriminatio n law? I n chapte r 4 , I discus s pregnancy-relate d issues , i n whic h the Unite d State s consistentl y fail s t o provid e meaningfu l pro tection t o pregnan t women , fetuses , o r newbor n children , i n comparison wit h Canad a an d wester n Europe . Wh y doe s th e United State s no t sho w mor e concer n fo r th e well-bein g o f th e next generation ? Chapte r 5 connect s th e homophobi a underly ing America n la w an d th e country' s militaristi c an d moralisti c style of capitalism. Why d o the principles of laissez-faire capital ism disappea r whe n issue s involving ga y men an d lesbians aris e under th e law? In chapter 6 , Isabelle's plight is connected to tha t of all unprotected worker s i n th e Unite d States—th e contingen t workforce consistin g o f nearl y one-thir d o f al l American work ers and especiall y women, the poor , racial minorities, and recen t immigrants. Wh y doe s th e Unite d State s consistentl y exclud e the mos t underprivilege d worker s fro m meaningfu l workplac e protection? Th e las t chapte r consider s th e stor y o f Isabelle' s daughter, Medina . Sh e will be sorel y disappointe d i f sh e expect s the principle s o f laissez-fair e capitalis m t o appl y t o he r dream s and aspiration s a s th e daughte r o f a legal immigrant . Bu t i f w e use ou r imagination , we can conjur e u p a better lif e fo r Isabelle , Medina, an d al l o f u s wh o striv e t o combin e famil y an d wor k with th e assistance o f our governmen t an d society . In eac h chapter , we se e that th e uniquel y American respons e to the needs of the worker an d the family i s sometimes justifie d

6

The Tattered Safety Net

under th e rubri c o f laissez-fair e capitalism— a capitalis m tha t I believe shoul d mor e aptl y b e terme d hyper capitalism. Thi s hypercapitalism i s finall y beginnin g t o receiv e long-du e criti cism from source s as diverse as philanthropist-financier Georg e Soros, who sounded the alarm in a 1997 Atlantic Monthly cove r story; 1 t o Rober t Kuttner , whos e criticall y acclaime d book , Everything for Sale, i s subtitled th e Virtues and Limits of Markets;2 t o th e lat e Leonar d Silk , economic s reporte r fo r th e New York Times an d Newsweek, a self-avowe d capitalis t wh o simi larly questione d th e unrelentin g an d single-minde d manifesta tion o f American capitalis m afte r th e col d war. 3 This emerging critique, however, has not yet reached the U.S. Congress. A Republican Congres s swep t into office i n 1992 proclaiming "laissez-faire" capitalism , even though thei r version of capitalism ha s littl e similarit y t o a pur e laissez-fair e model . They proposed rolling back federal regulator y power and reducing federa l outlay s fro m one-thir d t o one-hal f i n orde r t o advance "th e simpl e idea that peopl e shoul d be trusted t o spen d their ow n earning s an d decid e their ow n futures/' 4 A t th e sam e time, Congres s recommende d increasin g th e federa l militar y budget wit h it s inefficien t subsid y o f industries . These propos als woul d supposedl y hel p creat e a "jus t an d compassionat e society" but ca n easil y be unmasked a s corporate welfar e a t th e expense o f th e workin g class . Although th e Republica n revolu tion was not entirel y successful , i t did push Presiden t Bil l Clin ton t o endors e a welfare refor m packag e tha t radicall y depart s from ou r previou s understandin g o f th e relationshi p betwee n the stat e and th e famil y American-style capitalis m help s perpetuat e th e clas s inequities amon g Americans whil e als o undermining th e inter ests o f ou r econom y a s a whole. We cannibaliz e ou r mos t pre -

The Tattered Safet y Ne t

7

cious resource—th e healt h an d well-bein g o f th e nex t genera tion—to serve the interests of the ultrarich. Although America n politicians applau d suc h result s in the name of laissez-faire eco nomics, n o othe r Wester n industrialize d country—no r eve n Adam Smith—woul d recogniz e thes e policie s a s laissez-faire . The answer , however , i s no t t o striv e t o tur n American-styl e capitalism int o a pure r laissez-fair e model . Th e answe r i s t o introduce a mora l componen t int o America n capitalis m tha t protects th e mos t disadvantage d member s o f ou r societ y rathe r than onl y th e ultrarich . Suc h a capitalism dominate s th e legal economic landscap e o f Canada , wester n Europe , Grea t Britain , and Australi a t o a greate r exten t tha n i t doe s i n th e Unite d States. Law school s an d lega l educatio n i n th e Unite d State s ofte n disregard th e legal-economi c structure s o f othe r countries . The proponents o f the fiel d labele d "la w an d economics " frequentl y rely o n a distorted versio n o f laissez-fair e economic s an d mak e little referenc e t o economi c an d lega l system s outsid e thos e o f the Unite d States . I n th e purporte d nam e o f laissez-fair e capi talism, the y applau d th e hodgepodg e o f inadequat e protectio n for American worker s an d families . Their distorte d vie w of laissez-faire economic s ha s als o seepe d int o America n lega l deci sions and statutor y law . The belief tha t governmen t interventio n i n th e workplac e i s inherently inefficien t greatl y influence s man y judge s o n th e courts o f appeal s a s wel l a s th e justice s o f th e U.S . Suprem e Court. Why w e shoul d car e mor e abou t th e economi c freedo m of entrepreneur s tha n th e need s o f workers i s rarely addressed . As Jules L. Coleman noted in a stinging critique of the economi c analysis of Judge Richard Posner's work, y/ [T]here is a differenc e between saying—i f yo u wan t t o promote utilit y o r wealth the n

8

The Tattered Safety Net

these ar e th e rule s yo u shoul d adopt—an d saying—becaus e these rule s woul d promot e utilit y o r wealt h i n th e abstrac t w e should adop t them/' 5 Bu t a s a schola r an d a s a judge, Posne r repeatedly assume s tha t a rule i s appropriat e simpl y becaus e i t maximizes utilit y o r wealth . American law needs a more humane economic basis. The prevailing economic s i n la w mus t b e expose d s o that w e ca n ques tion America' s mindles s devotio n t o it s hypercapitalism . Wha t exactly i s th e America n versio n o f capitalism ? Shoul d i t pro mote efficiency an d utility at the expense of all other values? O r is it possible to maintain a private marketplace while also recognizing th e inheren t limitation s o f entrepreneur s a s decisio n makers? Doe s American la w consistentl y follo w a laissez-fair e approach to the workplace, or is it inconsistently laissez-faire , t o the detriment o f the most underprivileged member s of our society? Wh y d o we withdra w benefit s fro m welfar e mom s unde r the assumptio n tha t the y ar e laz y an d selfis h and , a t th e sam e time, increas e benefit s t o middle-clas s parent s unde r th e assumption tha t the y deserv e mor e leisur e tim e an d economi c assistance i n orde r t o be effective parents ? And wh o i s harme d by thes e policies—onl y th e poo r o r th e entir e middl e class ? Finally, ca n w e structur e stat e interventio n s o that utilit y doe s not becom e selfishnes s an d efficienc y doe s not becom e greed ? This boo k doe s no t challeng e th e inheren t valu e o f capital ism, however . Prediction s tha t capitalis m wil l inevitabl y self destruct see m especiall y il l founde d thes e days . Nearl y ever y Western natio n i s base d o n a capitalis t economy , an d th e fe w remaining Communis t regime s continu e t o founder. Moreover , many Wester n countrie s ar e turning t o the Unite d State s a s a n economic mode l an d ar e considerin g abandonin g thei r long standing suppor t o f the famil y an d worker. If there i s one thin g

The Tattered Safet y Ne t

9

that we can safely predict, it is that the United States will remai n firmly capitalisti c an d serv e a s a model fo r othe r countrie s try ing to attain economi c success . Although th e American version of capitalism is far fro m pur e laissez-faire becaus e i t tolerate s stat e interventio n i n th e mar ketplace, the American version is generally less protective of th e worker an d famil y tha n ar e th e version s use d i n othe r part s o f the Western world. Not al l kinds of capitalism, however, assum e that utilit y an d efficienc y fo r th e entrepreneuria l clas s must b e the dominan t principles . Som e favo r th e welfar e o f th e worke r out of the conviction that suc h policies benefit bot h workers an d the econom y a s a whole. But th e appropriatenes s o f the Ameri can version o f capitalis m i s rarel y questione d i n jurisprudence , perhaps because so little work on American law makes referenc e to other lega l regimes . Laissez-faire argument s ar e advance d i n th e Unite d State s most aggressivel y whe n lawmaker s o r activist s see k t o exten d protections t o th e les s privilege d member s o f ou r society , an d they ar e ignore d whe n politician s an d other s recommen d greater protectio n fo r middle-clas s Americans . America n la w reflects neithe r a laissez-fair e econom y no r a socia l welfar e state; instead, it has a capitalistic perspective that disproportion ately benefit s th e entrepreneuria l clas s an d ofte n relie s o n a moralistic agenda . Other countrie s provid e a larger socia l safet y ne t t o familie s and workers , not simpl y ou t o f a desire t o achiev e greate r clas s equity, but fro m a conviction tha t suc h policie s benefi t al l soci ety. Today's child who receives nurturing car e from parent s wh o have been provide d wit h healt h insuranc e an d paid materna l o r paternal leav e wil l b e tomorrow' s responsibl e membe r o f th e community. Bu t eve n thoug h suc h program s benefi t th e long -

10

The Tattered Safet y Ne t

term interest s o f society , it is unrealistic t o expect employer s t o provide fo r fre e thos e benefit s fo r th e well-bein g o f society . Rather, such decisions can be made only at a governmental leve l because "eve n i n a market econom y ther e ar e realms o f huma n life wher e market s ar e imperfect , inappropriate , o r unattain able/' 6 Furthermore , th e Unite d State s i s virtuall y th e onl y Western capitalis t econom y t o leav e th e developmen t o f suc h policies primarily i n the hands o f entrepreneurs . The poin t o f thi s boo k i s no t tha t th e Unite d State s shoul d blindly adop t th e policie s o f wester n Europea n countrie s o r Canada. Instead, the point is that a comparative investigatio n o f the policie s o f othe r capitalis t countrie s shoul d lea d us t o mod ify ou r versio n o f capitalism . B y lookin g a t example s o f othe r capitalist economies, we can see the inequities and limitations of American capitalism . As I will show , eve n Ada m Smit h woul d give a failing grad e t o the economic s underlyin g American law .

Laissez-Faire Lega l Economic s

Although publi c interes t la w gre w substantiall y i n th e 1970 s and early 1980 s with a sharp critiqu e of the state' s treatment o f the poor , th e las t decad e ha s brough t a heightene d interes t i n laissez-faire economi c principles in law. Nearly every law school in the United State s has added a course on law and economics t o its curriculum. In some schools, this is even a required cours e i n which student s ar e taugh t ho w t o appl y economi c principle s t o law, under th e assumptio n tha t American la w has—and shoul d have—a laissez-faire , capitalisti c perspective . Th e teachin g materials i n thi s are a seldo m offe r an y critiqu e o f thi s increas ingly dominant philosophy , and in the meantime, the law of th e welfare stat e ha s vanishe d fro m man y la w schoo l curricula . As

The Tattered Safet y Ne t

11

governmental assistanc e fo r society' s les s privilege d member s has becom e mor e unpopular , la w school s hav e reorganize d t o focus o n the law of the entrepreneurial clas s rather tha n th e law of th e poor . Student s graduat e fro m la w schoo l understandin g the economics underlying the tax code (with its subsidies for th e rich) bu t knowin g nearl y nothin g abou t th e economic s under lying th e ne w welfare laws . The origin s o f la w an d economic s i n America n la w school s can b e trace d t o Richar d Posner , currentl y a judge o n th e U.S . Court o f Appeals fo r th e Sevent h Circuit . In 1973 , he publishe d the first textboo k treatise on the economic analysis of legal rules and institutions. Now in it s fourth edition / thi s book aspire s t o make his brand o f law and economics the foundational principl e for th e entir e lega l system . Unbalanced i n the extreme , Posner's work presumes tha t th e principles o f value , utility , an d efficienc y shoul d gover n th e analysis o f la w fro m a n economi c perspectiv e base d o n th e assumption tha t huma n behavio r i s rational . Acknowledgin g that a reader might have trouble with this view of human ratio nality, Posne r offer s som e (unsubstantiated ) generalization s about the predictive power o f law and economics an d concludes : "[S]o perhaps the assumption tha t people are rational maximiz ers of their satisfaction i s not s o unrealistic as the noneconomis t might a t firs t think." 8 Wh y w e shoul d choos e th e concept s o f value, utility, and efficiency t o measure th e appropriateness o f a particular se t of laws is not somethin g tha t Posne r eve n care s t o address. Posner's wor k i s parochial; he neve r refer s t o example s out side the United States , and much o f his economic support is outdated a s well . Fo r example , i n hi s brie f discussio n o f Ai d fo r Families wit h Dependen t Childre n (AFDC) , he state s tha t suc h

12

The Tattered Safet y Ne t

programs "hav e been foun d t o have surprisingl y larg e negativ e effects o n participation i n the labor force—i n th e case of AFDC, participation by mothers/' 9 His sole support i s a chapter writte n by Marti n Anderso n i n a boo k publishe d i n 197 8 i n whic h Anderson summarize s previousl y complete d studie s o f behav ior i n th e Unite d States . These "facts' ' ar e suppose d t o be suffi cient to allow the reade r t o assess the efficienc y o f AFDC. The actua l relationshi p betwee n AFD C benefit s an d th e mothers o f youn g childre n seekin g pai d employmen t i s muc h more complicate d tha n Posne r suggests . Examinatio n o f th e social welfare program s i n the United State s an d Franc e reveal s that w e mus t als o weig h th e efficienc y o f socia l welfar e pay ments within the structure o f all assistance provided to the stat e for mother s o f youn g children. 10 Franc e effectivel y integrate s women int o th e pai d labo r forc e afte r thei r childre n reac h th e age of three, by offerin g a system o f time-limited transfe r pay ments alon g wit h a syste m o f extensiv e suppor t t o workin g families throug h universa l publi c da y care , universa l medica l insurance, universal famil y allowances , and federall y mandate d maternity leave . These program s ar e no t exclusivel y base d o n need. Rather, they wer e create d ou t o f a conviction tha t al l children—rich an d poor—benefi t fro m developin g nurturin g rela tionships wit h thei r parent s i n th e firs t severa l years o f life . The recently enacted Personal Responsibility and Work Oppor tunity Act incorporate d on e piece of th e Frenc h system—time limited transfe r payments—withou t incorporatin g th e broade r picture o f genera l stat e suppor t fo r al l families . Th e economi c assumption underlyin g this change is that AFDC payments cre ated a disincentive fo r poor single mothers t o seek paid employ ment. Although time-limited transfer payment s are supposed t o eliminate thi s disincentive , withou t a n accompanyin g socia l

The Tattered Safet y Ne t

13

safety net , the y ar e unlikel y t o achiev e th e effectivenes s o f th e French model . Poor, single mothers wil l still be unlikely t o pur sue paid employmen t whil e thei r childre n ar e young. What ar e they t o do with thei r childre n while they ar e at work? Ca n the y expect t o ear n mor e tha n thei r chil d care , transportation , an d medical cost s (sinc e thei r childre n wil l los e acces s t o free med ical care after thei r mother accept s employment i n an uninsure d industry)? An d wher e ar e thes e jobs tha t the y ar e suppose d t o be abl e t o find ? Shoul d thes e peopl e serv e a s domesti c worker s in othe r people' s household s whil e abandonin g thei r ow n chil dren durin g th e day ? A comparative examinatio n als o reveals that U.S.law , despite its "profamily " rhetoric , i s generall y muc h les s supportiv e o f parenting than ar e the laws of other countries . We must wonde r why U.S . policy i s generally s o determined t o push th e parent s of youn g childre n int o pai d labor . I n Sweden , incentive s t o mothers to join the paid labor force d o not appear until the chil d reaches th e ag e o f eightee n months. 11 I n France , incentive s t o enter th e pai d labo r forc e ar e offere d onl y afte r childre n reac h the ag e o f three . Bu t th e Unite d State s offer s littl e suppor t t o any familie s (poo r o r middle class ) fo r a parent t o sta y hom e t o care for a child. As a result , th e Unite d State s ha s th e highes t rat e o f an y country o f labor forc e participatio n by young mothers, with th e net result being a marked decline in their sleep and free time. On average, married, college-educated, working women with youn g children hav e seve n fewe r hour s o f passiv e leisur e an d slee p than d o thei r mal e partners . On e ca n onl y imagin e th e slee p deprivation o f th e man y poo r wome n wh o rais e childre n o n their own . Th e qualit y o f lif e fo r wome n an d thei r children , however, has no place in law and economics. In the name of effi -

14

The Tattered Safet y Ne t

ciency, the Unite d State s encourage s al l adult s t o participat e i n the pai d labo r forc e whil e offerin g littl e stat e suppor t fo r chil d care. The disproportionat e negativ e consequence s fo r th e qual ity o f life fo r wome n an d their childre n receiv e scan t attention . Why shoul d w e a s a societ y encourag e parent s o f youn g children t o ente r th e pai d labo r forc e i n large r numbers ? A common respons e i s tha t w e shoul d b e encouragin g primar y parents, wh o ar e disproportionatel y women , t o retur n t o th e labor forc e i n orde r t o promot e economi c equalit y betwee n women an d men . Gap s i n labo r forc e participatio n arguabl y hurt women' s economi c earning power, although thi s respons e assumes tha t men' s live s are the norm t o which women shoul d aspire. Alternatively , w e coul d tr y t o creat e policie s tha t encourage fathers an d mothers to spend equal amounts o f tim e caring fo r thei r children . Instea d o f encouragin g wome n t o work withou t interruption , w e coul d encourag e me n t o inter rupt thei r labo r forc e participation . Thi s solutio n woul d improve th e qualit y o f car e availabl e t o childre n an d als o increase th e primar y parent' s leisur e time . I t i s a solutio n premised o n th e need s o f al l parent s an d thei r children , no t just th e parent s an d childre n o f a particula r socioeconomi c class. Most othe r Western countrie s have chosen to value the qual ity o f lif e o f wome n an d childre n ove r thei r coerce d entr y int o the pai d labo r force . Sweden , fo r example , ha s trie d t o creat e social an d economi c policie s tha t hel p father s spen d mor e tim e with thei r children . Le d b y th e unrealisti c assumption s o f la w and economics, U.S. welfare policie s contribute to the deteriora tion o f th e live s o f wome n an d children . Oddly , la w an d eco nomics ignore s th e qualit y o f ou r nex t generatio n a s the exter nal effec t o f this policy .

The Tattered Safet y Ne t

15

Readers who are interested i n alternative perspectives o n law and economic s currentl y hav e fe w source s o f guidanc e i n law . Nearly al l th e publishe d teachin g material s ar e structure d around consideration s o f efficienc y an d utilit y maximization , with n o comparison s wit h othe r economi c system s o r jurispru dential perspectives. 12 The only modest exception to this trend is a slim paperback b y Robin Paul Malloy entitled Law and Economics: A Comparative Approach to Theory and Practice. This book' s notio n o f "com parative " is to share with th e reade r a variety o f theoretical per spectives tha t on e migh t us e i n thinkin g abou t th e connectio n between law and economics. It does not rely exclusively on a laissez-faire, capitalisti c perspective but , instead, expose s th e reade r to liberalism, communitarianism , libertarianism , an d othe r eco nomic philosophies . Si x page s ar e eve n devote d t o critica l lega l theory, and othe r section s o f the book attemp t t o reveal the ide ological bias of conservative law and economics. All the cases that are chose n fo r th e readers ' examination , however , ar e fro m th e United State s an d ten d t o reflec t a laissez-faire vie w o f la w an d economics. It is unlikely that student s coul d offer a sophisticated critique o f law and economics based o n these scan t materials . As each of these books states in its preface o r introduction, la w and economics is an increasingly popular are a of study in American law schools. Some believe that "law and economics is the most important development in the field of law in the last fifty years/' 13 But wha t ha s no t bee n sai d ofte n enoug h i s tha t thi s fiel d i s parochial an d narro w i n it s consideratio n o f th e relationshi p between law and economics. In this book, I respond to the narrowness of the field by examining some core areas of American law in comparison wit h tha t o f othe r countrie s t o sho w ho w America n law purports t o favo r laissez-fair e policie s while, in fact , protect -

16

The Tattered Safety Net

ing the rich at the expense of the quality of life for most member s of ou r society . Rathe r tha n applau d th e applicatio n o f economi c principles to law, I will show the inconsistent an d morally offen sive ways i n whic h thes e principle s hav e been applie d t o American law. It is time to add a discussion o f fairness an d equity to th e study of law and economics rather tha n focus exclusivel y on effi ciency and utility. The quality o f our lives depends on it.

Laissez-Faire Lega l Decision s

Law and economics is not just a n academic discipline. Judge Posner's ascendanc y t o the bench reflect s it s direct influence o n th e law. In the hand s o f conservativ e judges, principles o f efficienc y and utility are used to the disservice of all and especially the less privileged member s o f ou r society . Th e dramati c influenc e o f these principles on law is documented throughout thi s book, but a few brief example s giv e a hint o f their impact . Justice Antoni n Scali a enlist s thes e principle s t o argu e tha t the governmen t shoul d no t b e allowe d t o implemen t affirma tive actio n program s becaus e n o grou p i n societ y ca n clai m t o have been subjecte d t o an acute disadvantaged statu s in the pas t that entitles it to preferential treatmen t today . In a racial reverse discrimination cas e brough t b y a whit e contracto r agains t th e city o f Richmond , Virginia, Scali a wrote: The relevant proposition i s not that it was blacks, or Jews, or Irish who were discriminated against, but that it was individual me n an d women , "create d equal/ ' wh o wer e discrimi nated against . . . . Racia l preference s appea r t o "eve n th e score" (i n som e smal l degree ) onl y i f on e embrace s th e proposition tha t ou r societ y i s appropriatel y viewe d a s divided into races, making it right tha t a n injustice rendere d

The Tattered Safety Net

17

in the past to a black man shoul d be compensated fo r by discriminating against a white. Nothing is worth that embrace. 14 Similarly, i n a gende r revers e discriminatio n cas e brough t b y Paul Johnson , a mal e blue-colla r worker , agains t a cit y trans portation authority , Scali a argue d tha t th e stat e ha s n o righ t t o decide t o protec t th e employmen t interest s o f Dian e Joyce , a female blue-colla r worke r ove r Johnso n a t th e defendant' s workplace. O n behal f o f Johnson , Scali a noted : "Th e iron y i s that thes e individuals—predominantl y unknown , unaffluent , unorganized—suffer thi s injustic e a t th e hand s o f a Court fon d of thinkin g itsel f th e champio n o f the politicall y impotent/' 15 Justice Scalia' s opinion s consistentl y protec t th e affluen t a t the expens e o f th e disadvantaged . Fo r example , h e woul d hav e been willing to allow the stat e of Virginia t o maintain it s exclu sively male military college 16 (nevertheless in 1997, the Virginia Military Institute admitted women a s part of its freshman class ) while forbiddin g a transportatio n agenc y fro m providin g th e most modes t preferenc e t o allow , fo r th e firs t time , a femal e blue-collar worke r t o see k a supervisor y position. 17 Bu t wh y should th e stat e o f Virgini a b e allowe d t o privileg e me n ove r women wh o see k militar y training ? Suc h a result i s inefficient , presuming th e inheren t superiorit y o f me n ove r women . An d certainly no coherent historical argumen t ca n be made that me n need or deserve such special protection. Scalia's concern fo r fair ness an d efficienc y enter s hi s decision s onl y whe n th e grou p challenging preferentia l treatmen t i s whit e men . Scali a shoul d be abl e t o us e hi s laissez-fair e len s t o se e tha t i t i s inefficien t for th e governmen t t o den y militar y trainin g opportunitie s t o women unde r th e stereotypica l assumptio n tha t the y ar e inher ently unqualifie d fo r militar y service . It i s not simpl y unfai r t o women t o deny the m thes e opportunities , but accordin g to lais-

18

The Tattered Safety Net

sez-faire principles , th e long-ter m interest s o f societ y suffe r from suc h inefficien t policies . Judge Fran k Easterbrook , wh o sit s with Judg e Posne r o n th e Seventh Circuit , invoke d th e mos t strikin g statemen t o f th e efficiency principle , i n a n employmen t la w case : "Greed i s th e foundation o f much economi c activity, and Adam Smit h tol d u s that eac h person' s pursui t o f hi s ow n interest s drive s th e eco nomic system to produce more and better goods and services fo r all."18 Citing that principle, Easterbrook side d with a n entrepre neur agains t a worker whos e loyalt y wa s demande d despit e hi s employer's blatantl y illega l behavior . Easterbrook, lik e Scalia and Posner , however, misreads Ada m Smith. Smit h neve r romanticize d th e rol e o f th e stat e i n th e economy. Nor di d h e romanticiz e wha t w e ca n expec t fro m th e entrepreneurial class . Rather, he propounded a laissez-faire per spective becaus e h e believe d tha t th e entrepreneuria l clas s would tr y t o dominate th e stat e fo r it s own benefit, an d indeed , America's distorte d invocatio n o f laissez-fair e economic s ha s proved Smit h t o b e largel y correct . Eve n th e court s ar e some times complici t i n th e conspirac y t o ai d th e entrepreneuria l class. In the hands of law and economics, we get the worst of laissez-faire economics—lega l protection o f only the entrepreneur ial class—to th e detrimen t o f the long-ter m interest s o f societ y as a whole.

Laissez-Faire Statutor y La w

Although man y part s o f th e 199 5 Republica n Congress' s Con tract with America were premised on laissez-faire capitalism , the Personal Responsibilit y an d Wor k Opportunit y Act , enacte d i n 1996, is the best example o f its influence o n American statutor y

The Tattered Safet y Ne t

19

law. This statut e radicall y change d America' s respons e t o poo r families b y eliminatin g financia l assistanc e a s a n entitlement . Federal assistance now is given t o the state s in the form o f block grants that specif y ho w this money ca n be allocated. The center piece of the legislation is the requirement tha t assistance be time limited. Anyone who fails to find employmen t within a specifie d time period (usually two years) will be denied further assistance , even i f that perso n i s responsible fo r raisin g young children . Children rights ' advocate s ar e holdin g thei r breath , waitin g to find out what the consequences for America's children will be. At first , Speake r o f th e Hous e New t Gingric h suggeste d tha t more childre n coul d ente r orphanages , proceedin g fro m hi s naive assumptio n tha t orphanage s ar e health y an d economica l places i n whic h t o rais e children . (On e wonders , give n Gin grich's antigovernmen t sentiments , wh y h e believe s tha t th e government shoul d pa y peopl e t o tak e car e o f childre n i n orphanages rather than provide financial assistanc e to parents so that the y ca n rais e thei r ow n children. ) I t i s no w generall y assumed tha t foste r car e ma y hav e t o dea l wit h th e overflo w children, since foster car e assistance ha s not (yet ) been include d as par t o f th e states ' bloc k grants . (I t i s stil l par t o f th e federa l budget's "entitlements." ) Increasing th e expenditure s fo r foste r car e whil e decreasin g the expenditure s fo r welfare , however , doe s no t squar e wit h al l laissez-faire economists . Some laissez-faire proponent s objec t t o any state intervention o n behalf o f children, including state support fo r foste r care . Whe n confronte d wit h th e dir e conse quences o f suc h a n approach , however , on e free-marke t econo mist was forced t o admit that "o f course , some children will die" while their parents tried t o learn the lessons of free-market eco nomics and limit the production o f children. 19 This apparently is

20

The Tattered Safety Net

an acceptabl e resul t i n a system i n whic h laissez-fair e econom ics is the onl y recognize d value . The long-ter m interest s o f ou r children i s irrelevant . Although othe r countrie s hav e use d time-limite d assistanc e to poo r families , n o othe r Wester n countr y ha s trie d t o d o s o within a syste m o f extrem e laissez-fair e capitalism . Instead , they hav e create d effectiv e program s tha t nearl y guarante e employment t o parent s afte r thei r younges t chil d reache s th e age of two o r three. Cash assistanc e i s eliminated becaus e othe r programs, like state-subsidized chil d care and job training, hav e taken thei r place . These program s targe t al l parent s ou t o f th e conviction tha t th e stat e i s responsibl e fo r safeguardin g th e health an d well-being o f the nex t generation . An overvie w o f governmenta l interventio n int o th e live s o f workers an d th e famil y ca n revea l th e value s tha t underli e American socia l policy. American la w benefits th e interest s o f a small elit e i n America n society . That is , American la w ha s tw o tiers. Programs o f socia l insuranc e lik e Socia l Securit y ar e val ued highl y i n th e Unite d States , an d program s o f socia l assis tance lik e AFD C ar e disparaged . A comprehensiv e revie w o f American socia l policy shows that middle-class men and wome n who confor m t o traditiona l gende r role s ofte n benefi t unde r American socia l policy a t the expens e o f other , less valued indi viduals an d families . Althoug h thes e "others"—racia l minori ties, poor people, single mothers, and gays and lesbians—consti tute a majority o f peopl e i n ou r society , American socia l polic y is ofte n trappe d i n a nineteenth-centur y conceptio n o f societ y that "fit[s ] an d reinforc e [s] th e famil y wag e system , wit h me n as breadwinner s an d wome n a s primar y caretakers , domesti c workers an d secondar y wag e earners." 20 It is time t o mov e int o the twenty-firs t centur y wit h a more flexibl e understandin g o f

The Tattered Safety Net

21

the famil y an d th e individua l person , with socia l programs tha t satisfy thi s socia l reality .

Capitalism I s Not Capitalism I s Not Capitalis m

The U.S . Constitution wa s base d o n a particular bran d o f capi talism—that o f Ada m Smith 21 —with it s laissez-fair e expecta tions tha t th e governmen t woul d no t interfer e wit h th e privat e ownership o f capital . Hence , th e Fift h Amendmen t t o th e U.S . Constitution protect s people' s righ t t o ow n an d contro l privat e property. Adam Smith' s mode l ha s littl e i n commo n wit h th e curren t Gingrich-style economi c model . Smith' s objectio n t o govern ment interferenc e i n th e econom y reste d o n th e assumptio n that merchant s woul d contro l governmen t an d thereb y impos e restraints tha t woul d serv e thei r self-interest . H e worrie d tha t government interferenc e i n the marketplace " unchains th e self ishness o f humanit y an d permit s i t t o d o harm t o th e commu nity rathe r tha n workin g fo r th e publi c benefit/' 22 Smit h "feared monopol y powe r fa r mor e tha n h e feare d unwarrante d government interventio n i n th e marke t mechanism." 23 Smit h lived i n th e day s o f robbe r baron s an d worrie d abou t thei r monopoly influenc e o n governmen t an d society . If th e govern ment ha d no t been a government o f merchants bu t instea d rep resented th e workin g people , Smit h migh t no t hav e bee n a s opposed t o governmenta l interventio n i n th e workplace . I t i s wrong, therefore , t o us e Smith' s philosoph y a s a n excus e t o undermine th e limited protections legislate d o n behalf o f work ers and the family . Yet while purporting t o draw on the work of Adam Smith , modern American capitalis m ha s not been willin g to us e th e stat e a s a weapon agains t th e selfishnes s o f th e mer -

22

The Tattered Safety Net

chant class . Instead, American la w i s premise d o n th e assump tion tha t welfar e moms , not entrepreneurs , ar e selfish . American hypercapitalis m mirror s th e evil s tha t concerne d Adam Smith . It s interventio n ofte n doe s th e greates t disservic e to th e mos t underprivilege d member s o f ou r society . For exam ple, i f w e loo k mor e closel y a t governmen t interventio n i n th e workplace, we see that the most disadvantaged workers—domes tic an d agricultura l workers—ar e usuall y exclude d fro m cover age. When Presiden t Clinto n ha d troubl e findin g a nominee fo r attorney genera l wh o ha d complie d wit h th e minima l protec tions provide d b y Socia l Securit y la w fo r domesti c employees , Congress reacted by broadening the exclusion (fo r th e benefit o f the upper class) without eve n considering its impact on domesti c workers. Th e much-heralde d Famil y an d Medica l Leav e Ac t applies only to those workers who can afford t o take unpaid leave and als o happen t o work fo r th e 5 percent o f American corpora tions tha t emplo y more tha n fift y employees . Meanwhile, b y reducin g cas h payment s an d imposin g tim e limitations o n benefits, the new welfare la w makes it even mor e difficult fo r poo r wome n t o choos e t o sta y hom e an d car e fo r their youn g children . This is treatment blatantl y preferential t o the uppe r clas s in contras t t o th e poor . ( I say uppe r clas s rathe r than middl e clas s becaus e i t i s generall y onl y th e uppe r clas s that ca n affor d t o pa y fo r th e service s o f domesti c worker s o r take extende d unpai d leave s fro m work . The need s o f th e mid dle class for universa l healt h insurance , government-subsidize d childcare, and pai d parentin g leav e hav e no t bee n addresse d b y Congress o r th e president. ) I f suc h policie s tha t disproportion ately benefit th e uppe r clas s are th e inevitabl e resul t o f laissez faire economics , then one must questio n the morality o f laissezfaire economics . I f suc h policie s ar e no t inevitable , the n the y

The Tattered Safet y Ne t

23

should b e noted an d change d t o creat e a more equitabl e society . No othe r Wester n industrialize d natio n tip s th e balanc e s o fa r against th e interest s o f th e poo r an d th e middl e clas s a s th e United State s does . Some economists—whos e wor k i s ignore d b y conservativ e law an d economics—hav e a mor e realisti c assessmen t o f th e way i n whic h th e econom y works . The Britis h economis t Joh n Maynard Keynes , fo r example , di d no t accep t th e premis e tha t unemployment fo r qualifie d worker s was antithetical to capitalism. Nor di d he accep t the premise tha t wage s were determine d entirely rationall y unde r a capitalis t system . Nonetheless , American la w i s base d primaril y o n assumption s contrar y t o how the "econom y i n which w e live actually works/' 24 Academic economist s hav e carefull y explore d th e validit y o f those assumption s o n whic h proponent s o f laissez-fair e eco nomics rely . They hav e conclude d tha t ther e is no evidenc e tha t social protection program s negativel y affec t th e labo r market' s flexibility o r th e spee d o f th e labo r market' s adjustment . I n addition, they hav e conclude d tha t th e absenc e o f socia l protec tion policies—lik e mandator y healt h insurance—doe s hav e a negative impac t o n people' s well-being. 25 I n othe r words , gov ernment interventio n i n the workplace ca n serv e the long-ter m interests o f al l society . La w an d economic s i s wrong t o assum e that government interventio n i n the private marketplace neces sarily detract s fro m th e efficienc y o f the market . Similarly, academic economists have disputed the Republicans' claim that "welfar e spendin g and other form s o f social protection inevitably lea d t o inefficien t allocatio n o f resource s an d under mine economic growth."26 The social market economies of north ern Europ e hav e consistentl y produce d highe r gros s domesti c products (GDP ) tha n th e Unite d States ' o r Grea t Britain' s econ -

24

The Tattered Safet y Ne t

omy has. Although on e might argu e that thes e economies woul d have operated eve n better ha d they use d more laissez-faire prin ciples, th e evidenc e doe s no t suppor t thi s claim . Socia l marke t arrangements hav e actuall y facilitate d wag e restrain t a s wel l a s contributed t o economi c efficienc y an d growt h throug h worke r training an d othe r investment s i n huma n capital . Th e Unite d States has not facilitate d long-ter m investmen t i n human capita l through socia l market protection . If ou r choice s were base d o n a careful stud y o f th e experienc e o f othe r countrie s rathe r tha n unexamined rhetoric, we might make different an d more human e choices. We might make choices that benefit both workers and the long-term interest s o f society . It i s possible t o incorporate huma n value s int o capitalis m b y providing basi c right s t o workers . Canada , Australia, an d vari ous Europea n countrie s hav e attempte d t o structur e thei r soci eties base d o n tha t understanding . (Grea t Britai n appear s onc e again t o be in a transition—away fro m [Milton ] Friedman-lik e economics an d bac k toward Keynes. ) Recen t U.S . statutory la w accompanied b y narro w interpretation s o f tha t law , however , has made suc h a reconciliation virtuall y impossible . It is time t o learn fro m ou r tradin g partner s wh o hav e managed t o combin e healthy capitalisti c economie s wit h basi c protections fo r work ers. Only i n th e parochia l literatur e o f la w an d economic s doe s laissez-faire capitalis m exis t in the United States . But other ver sions o f capitalis m ar e wel l accepte d b y academi c economist s and ar e thriving i n countrie s outsid e th e United States .

The Futur e

Law and economic s ofte n presume s tha t a free marke t wit h lit tle or no state intervention i s in society' s best interest becaus e a

The Tattered Safet y Ne t

25

free marke t best allow s workers an d owner s to use their huma n capital. Bu t a n employe e wh o i s identifiabl e a s a membe r o f a racial minorit y grou p ma y no t b e give n a n opportunit y t o demonstrate hi s o r he r abilities . Similarly, a person's disability , family responsibilities , o r pregnanc y ma y mak e i t difficul t fo r him o r he r t o participat e effectivel y i n th e labo r market . Doe s capitalism mea n tha t w e mus t structur e ou r employmen t rule s under th e assumption tha t thos e problems d o not reall y exist o r that the y ar e relativel y unimportant ? O r ca n capitalis m incor porate a n understandin g o f thes e problem s an d develo p a n effective response ? Finally , i s i t eve n fai r t o describ e America n capitalism a s evenhandedly followin g a laissez-faire model ? The Unite d State s nee d no t abando n capitalis m t o provid e appropriate protection s fo r employee s a t the workplace. But cit izens and workers i n the United State s are often unawar e o f th e choices availabl e i n capitalism . Capitalis m nee d no t b e based o n assumptions contrar y t o th e worl d i n whic h w e live . A s i n Canada and much o f western Europe , capitalism ca n be based o n the understandin g tha t worker s fac e arbitrar y discrimination , disability an d illness , and chil d car e an d famil y responsibilities . The law of employment ca n make capitalis m operat e more effi ciently by enabling employees to shoulder thes e responsibilitie s effectively rathe r tha n denyin g tha t thes e responsibilitie s ar e commonplace fo r most American workers. A humane capitalis m should b e possible. To develop suc h a capitalism i n th e United States , we need t o expand th e voice s tha t ar e considere d t o includ e thos e schoole d in th e practica l implication s o f la w an d socia l policy. Economis t Alan Enhrehal t argue s tha t suc h voice s ar e crucia l t o thi s dis cussion becaus e the y d o no t rel y o n unrealisti c postulate s bor rowed fro m theoretica l economics :

26

The Tattered Safety Net Market economic s enshrine s choic e an d lionize s th e individ ual. Carried to its furthest extreme , it all but suggests that anything the individual really feels like doing can't be wrong. . . . As th e mantr a fo r million s o f Americans , perhap s mos t o f a generation, thi s se t of ideas is entitled t o some respect. But it need not be taken at face value, and mastery of algebra should not be a prerequisite for discussing it. 27

This boo k describe s th e economic s tha t underlie s America n law, but withou t formula s o r charts. The picture tha t i t paints i s taken fro m th e rea l worl d i n whic h w e live , no t fro m a se t o f assumptions abou t th e behavio r o f fictiona l humans . We mus t examine thi s pictur e closel y i f we ar e t o creat e a more human e capitalism. Only then will Isabelle's side of the story be reflecte d in ou r nationa l policie s concernin g worker s an d families .

2 AFFIRMATIVE ACTIO N

In th e eighteent h century , upper-clas s Bosto n familie s coul d send thei r nearl y illiterat e childre n t o Harvar d University 1 Until th e 1920s , admissio n t o elit e institution s ofte n wa s restricted to those males who could afford t o pay the tuition an d had take n course s generall y onl y availabl e i n privat e school s such a s Latin. 2 Today , money continue s t o bu y privileg e i n th e United States. Despite the extent of economic privilege in American society, we continue t o cling to the myt h o f equal opportu nity, viewing the notion of economic privilege "a s a radical, dangerous idea, or an idiosyncratic throwback to the past, conjurin g up countrie s with monarchies , nobility, serfs , and peasants/' 3 In th e lat e twentiet h century , som e institution s o f highe r education institute d affirmativ e actio n program s fo r som e members o f racial minorities (al l the while continuing their pol-

28

Affirmative Actio n

icy o f alumn i preferenc e fo r privilege d whites) . But affirmativ e action ha s an d continue s t o receiv e muc h criticism , wit h th e result o f stigmatizin g it s beneficiaries. When upper-clas s mem bers of society receive benefits, no one notices, but when minor ity member s receiv e benefits , everyon e notice s an d criticize s these benefits. In 1985 Harvard University Presiden t Dere k Bo k commented o n thi s distinctio n whe n h e aske d wh y white s resent affirmativ e actio n fo r black s but d o no t expres s " similar resentments agains t othe r group s o f favore d applicants , such a s athletes an d alumn i offspring/' 4 Embedded i n th e affirmativ e actio n debat e ar e two assump tions—that affirmativ e actio n mean s tha t unqualified , o r les s qualified, person s ar e selecte d ove r mor e qualifie d individual s and tha t a negativ e relationshi p exist s betwee n affirmativ e action an d workforce productivity. 5 I n othe r words , the princi ples o f laissez-fair e capitalis m reinforc e th e backlas h agains t affirmative actio n o n behal f o f disadvantage d group s i n th e United State s whil e condonin g affirmativ e actio n fo r privi leged member s o f ou r society . "Affirmative actio n fo r th e chil dren o f Foundin g Father s jus t doesn' t see m t o carr y th e stigma/' 6 Laissez-faire capitalis m help s maintai n America n law' s hyp ocritical perspectiv e o n affirmativ e actio n an d help s propertie d whites gai n acces s t o educationa l institution s o r employmen t settings whil e criticizin g comparabl e device s tha t suppor t African Americans . Hiding behind laissez-fair e capitalism , wit h its emphasi s o n efficienc y an d persona l autonomy , thi s fiel d o f law reflect s disturbin g stereotypica l attitude s towar d race . Effi ciency an d persona l autonom y ar e cite d onl y whe n racia l minorities o r wome n see k societa l protection ; suc h concept s rarely ar e used t o question societa l protection fo r whit e males .

Affirmative Actio n

29

Anti-Affirmative Actio n Economic s

The dogm a o f efficienc y ha s selectivel y infiltrate d th e la w o f discrimination. Richard Posner argues that an affirmative actio n program designe d t o achiev e a proportiona l representatio n o f racial minorities at institutions o f higher educatio n is inefficien t because i t distort s th e result s o f preexistin g persona l prefer ences: "[TJhi s sor t o f interventio n would , b y profoundl y dis torting th e allocatio n o f labo r an d b y drivin g a wedge betwee n individual meri t an d economi c and professional success , greatly undermine th e syste m o f incentive s o n whic h a fre e societ y depends/' 7 The dogm a o f persona l autonom y ha s permitte d Richar d Epstein t o questio n th e validit y o f th e government' s authoriz ing or requirin g affirmativ e actio n fo r a subgroup o f society : There i s n o externa l measur e o f valu e tha t allow s th e lega l system o r the public at large to impose its preferences o n th e parties i n thei r ow n relationship . There i s thus n o reaso n t o have t o decid e whether w e shoul d weig h th e nee d fo r meri t in employmen t decision s agains t th e nee d fo r diversit y i n workers.8 Similarly, Posne r contend s tha t affirmativ e actio n o n behal f o f racial minorities ha s "no logical stopping point" short o f a stan dard of "perfect equality." 9 The government interfere s wit h per sonal autonom y whe n i t impose s o n employer s it s view s o f which subgroup s ar e entitle d t o affirmative action . Posner's concer n fo r efficienc y appear s t o wane , however , when suc h argument s ar e use d t o suppor t race-base d affirma tive action. It might be efficient, fo r example , to offer race-base d preferences t o help an entire class of people overcome decades of entrenched poverty . Bu t whe n confronte d wit h suc h a n argu -

30

Affirmative Actio n

ment, Posne r backs away from hi s overarching concern fo r effi ciency: "To sa y tha t discriminatio n i s ofte n a rational an d effi cient form o f behavior i s not to say that it is socially or ethicall y desirable/' 10 Eve n i f race-base d affirmativ e actio n i s th e mos t efficient wa y t o achiev e socioeconomi c equality , Posne r assert s that give n the cost s of acquiring individualized information , w e should no t permi t th e state' s us e o f race-base d categories . A t this point , Posner become s a staunch forma l equalit y o r " colorblind" theorist, arguin g that w e must no t confus e wha t i s "effi cient" with wha t i s "good" or "right. " Posner's occasiona l recitatio n o f forma l equalit y principles , however, i s inconsisten t wit h hi s us e elsewher e o f th e persona l autonomy principle . A forma l equalit y theoris t believe s tha t th e government mus t no t permi t th e privat e marketplac e t o deviat e from race-blin d principle s whe n creatin g policie s eve n i f privat e actors sincerely believe that race-conscious policies are necessary, for example , to overcom e centurie s o f racia l subordination . This view i s inconsisten t wit h th e persona l autonom y principl e because it permits the moral principle of formal equalit y to trump an employer's autonomy interests in defining his or her own hir ing policies . B y hidin g behin d th e purporte d principl e o f effi ciency, Posne r an d othe r theorist s ca n selectivel y suppor t som e governmental policies while criticizing others. These inconsisten t strands of law and economics have created a patchwork of case law that disserve the interests of African Americans desiring access to higher educatio n o r employment i n the workplace.

Educational Affirmative Actio n

Educational institution s o f highe r educatio n hav e neve r relie d exclusively on the "merit" principle in deciding whom t o admit .

Affirmative Actio n

31

Until th e 1920s , the onl y "merit " requiremen t wa s tha t appli cants tak e a lis t o f course s availabl e onl y a t privat e schools . These requirements , however , soo n cam e unde r attac k becaus e they allowe d immigran t Jew s and Catholic s t o ente r thes e elit e institutions. Harvar d Presiden t A . Lawrenc e Lowel l trie d t o respond t o thi s proble m i n th e 1920 s b y imposin g a ceilin g o n the number o f Jews admitted, but he backed down from thi s proposal when h e received a barrage o f public criticism. Instead, h e established a n alumn i preferenc e polic y tha t discriminate d against childre n o f immigrants , man y o f who m wer e Jewis h o r Catholic. Lowell therefor e use d a n indirec t rathe r tha n a direc t method o f discrimination . A s a resul t o f thi s policy , a t leas t a quarter of Harvard's entering classes were the sons of graduates, a figure tha t ha s remaine d relativel y stabl e eve r since. 11 Although Harvar d ha s presumabl y discontinue d it s practic e of overtl y discriminatin g agains t Jewis h o r Catholi c applicants , it ha s neve r discontinue d it s preferenc e fo r alumni . This polic y offers th e childre n o f alumn i a procedura l an d substantiv e advantage i n th e admission s process . Procedurally , al l othe r applications g o t o a n admission s committe e fo r revie w befor e reaching th e des k of the dea n o f admissions. The application s o f children o f alumni , however , g o directl y t o th e dea n o f admis sions fo r reading . The dea n the n write s suc h comment s o n th e file as "Not a great profile bu t just stron g enough #'s and grade s to get the tip from lineage." 12 The alumni preference i s clearly a "preference": betwee n 198 3 an d 1992 , a n admitte d nonlegac y candidate, on average , scored thirty-fiv e point s highe r tha n di d an admitte d legac y candidate . Whereas racia l minoritie s ar e ofte n accuse d o f obtainin g a n unfair advantag e i n th e admission s process , legac y candidate s are give n a n equa l o r greate r advantage . I n 1988 , fo r example ,

32

Affirmative Action

approximately tw o hundre d applicant s receive d alumn i prefer ence—a figur e tha t exceede d th e tota l numbe r o f blacks, Mexi can Americans, Puerto Ricans, and Native Americans enrolled in the freshma n class . The legac y preference wa s originall y introduce d t o discrimi nate agains t recen t immigran t groups , suc h a s Jew s an d Catholics. Today, it ha s a disparate impac t o n Asian American s and othe r minorit y group s tha t ar e unlikel y t o b e abl e t o tak e advantage o f an alumn i preference . I n response t o a discrimina tion complain t file d b y Asia n America n applicant s t o Harvar d University, th e Offic e o f Civi l Rights o f the U.S. Department o f Education conclude d tha t alumn i preference , couple d wit h a preference fo r athletes, created a higher admission rate for whit e applicants ove r similarl y qualifie d Asia n America n applicants . (Nonetheless, their complain t wa s found t o be without merit. ) In th e 1970s , elit e America n universitie s bega n t o chang e their admissions policies to present an image of more racial, ethnic, religious , an d geographi c diversity . Man y institution s tha t historically ha d bee n restricte d t o whit e me n wer e opene d t o women an d variou s racia l minorities . Despit e thes e changes , however, som e remnant s o f earlie r admission s practice s remained in place, and new ones were added. Alumni preferenc e continued t o benefi t a subse t o f whites , althoug h fo r th e firs t time, femal e applicant s coul d benefi t fro m thi s preference . (A t state schools , politica l connection s rathe r tha n alumn i prefer ence wer e ofte n favored.) 13 Athleti c preference s helpe d mal e athletes who , a t som e institution s lik e Harvard , wer e als o pre dominantly white . A new admission policy that emerge d in this time period was increased relianc e o n grade s an d especiall y tes t scores . Whereas graduation fro m elit e secondar y school s an d a n abilit y t o pa y

Affirmative Actio n

33

the tuitio n wer e th e sol e admission s criteri a befor e th e 1920s , the post-World War I I era sa w the emergence o f so-calle d meri t criteria o f grade s an d tes t scores . I n th e 1960s , whe n scholar ships eventuall y becam e availabl e fo r student s fro m impover ished backgrounds, many African Americans were still unable to attend elit e institution s becaus e o f thes e recentl y invoke d "merit" criteria . Admissions testin g originall y bega n a s a n attemp t t o hel p make threshol d judgment s abou t candidates ' abilitie s t o suc ceed. Over time , however, these tests evolve d "fro m a threshol d to a relative measure " and , i n turn , le d t o th e disproportionat e rejection o f Africa n America n applicant s a t exactl y th e tim e they becam e formall y eligibl e fo r admissio n an d financia l aid. 14 By th e 1970s , competitiv e admission s testin g becam e standar d at nearl y al l institution s o f lega l education. 15 Today , i t i s esti mated tha t onl y 5. 9 percen t o f college-boun d hig h schoo l seniors ca n mee t th e competitiv e criteri a use d b y elit e institu tions, with onl y 0. 4 percent o f college-boun d African America n seniors meetin g thes e criteria. 16 What meri t criteri a d o thes e test s see k t o measure ? Earl y attacks b y minorit y group s o n th e LSA T (La w Schoo l Admis sion Test) focused o n the test's inability to predict success in law school. The empirical evidence suggested that the tests predicte d success equall y fo r minorit y an d majorit y students , although i t was no t a particularly goo d predicto r fo r eithe r group . Becaus e no evidence o f predictive inequality was found, "thi s significan t flaw [i n its predictability fo r an y group] was lost in the pressur e to have som e testin g instrument." 17 Als o los t i n th e debat e wa s how importan t i t wa s t o predic t first-yea r grade s i n la w schoo l as a criterion fo r admissions , rathe r tha n succes s i n th e profes sion.18 The obsession with testin g that began t o overtake Amer -

34

Affirmative Actio n

ican cultur e i n th e 1970 s therefor e cause d institution s t o b e blind t o th e accurac y o r relevanc e o f testin g whil e als o dis counting the significance o f the impact against racial minorities. Even whe n institution s attemp t t o diversif y thei r studen t body, they almos t neve r abando n thei r prim e relianc e on grade s and test scores. As Derrick Bell eloquently argued: "The decisio n to maintai n grade s an d tes t score s a s th e prim e criteri a fo r admission advantage s th e uppe r clas s an d ensure s tha t th e nation's economicall y privilege d wil l continu e t o occup y th e great majorit y o f th e highl y sought-afte r seat s i n prestigiou s colleges, medical, and law schools/' 19 In th e 1970s , therefore, tw o divergen t transformation s too k place i n America n thinkin g abou t admission s t o educationa l institutions. On th e on e hand , Americans increasingl y believe d that admission s wer e base d largel y o n "merit, " placin g grea t weight o n the reliabilit y o f standardize d test s to evaluate it . O n the othe r hand , Americans bega n t o believ e tha t racia l minori ties were the onl y group sometime s t o gain admission s withou t meeting suc h objectiv e criteria . "While tirade s agains t affirma tive action regularly fill the pages of magazines and newspapers, the mos t disturbin g for m o f affirmativ e action—preferenc e given t o childre n o f alumni , know n a s 'legacies'—i s usuall y ignored b y critics." 20 Onl y racia l minoritie s wer e targete d a s a group undeservin g o f admission s o n meri t ground s alone . Minority student s d o not have the political or academic connections t o provid e th e suppor t networ k o f th e preferentiall y admitted majorit y students. 21 Minority grou p member s wer e single d ou t a s receivin g "preferential" treatment , bu t majorit y grou p members , wh o were eve n mor e likel y t o hav e bee n give n preferentia l treat ment, wer e no t subjec t t o criticis m o r stigma . On e migh t sim -

Affirmative Actio n

35

ply sa y tha t variou s criteri a wer e use d fo r admission s pur poses—test scores , parents' educational status , political connec tions, talent i n mal e sports , and race . One woul d no t necessar ily labe l an y o f the m a s mor e o r les s appropriat e o r problem atic. Yet American societ y cleverl y group s thes e criteri a alon g racist lines, not questionin g th e criteri a tha t benefi t white s an d males but questionin g thos e criteri a tha t benefi t racia l minori ties. When th e Office o f Civil Rights investigated whether Har vard's us e o f legac y preferenc e discriminate d agains t Asia n American applicants , th e offic e uphel d Harvard' s us e o f th e legacy preferenc e despit e it s advers e impact , becaus e thes e preferences wer e "long-standin g an d legitimate." Alumni pref erence i s thu s defende d a s a n appropriat e organizationa l prin ciple, wherea s race-base d affirmativ e actio n come s unde r increased attack . The poin t her e i s no t t o argu e tha t race-base d affirmativ e action is entirely goo d or that alumn i preference i s entirely bad . Rather, th e poin t i s tha t th e publi c perceptio n o f admission s policies is filtered throug h a racist lens . When th e grou p tha t i s targeted fo r assistanc e shift s fro m a predominantly whit e mal e economic elite to an African America n subclass , the public take s notice an d complain s abou t th e derogatio n o f th e meri t princi ple. There i s n o uniforml y applie d meri t principl e operatin g i n American society . Instead , a meri t myt h i s invoke d whe n th e color o f the beneficiary grou p start s t o darken . Laissez-faire economic s has played a role in this inconsisten t development o f th e la w of preferential treatment . The cas e tha t best capture s thi s rol e i s Hopwood v. State of Texas. 22 Relyin g on th e scholarshi p o f Richar d Posner , th e Fift h Circui t over turned a racial criterion i n admission s whil e affirmin g a prefer ence for whites . It concluded tha t a university ma y no t conside r

36

Affirmative Actio n

an individual' s rac e i n th e applicatio n proces s bu t ca n conside r an applicant' s "relationshi p t o schoo l alumni/ ' The alumn i facto r i s a blatant preferenc e fo r whites ; t o wit , the Universit y o f Texas exclude d black s fro m consideratio n fo r admission unti l 1950. 23 As recentl y a s 197 1 th e Universit y o f Texas Schoo l o f La w admitte d n o blac k students . Almost ever y child o f ever y alumn i fro m tha t yea r i s white, but i n th e nam e of formal equality , the Fift h Circui t approve d a n alumn i prefer ence whil e disapprovin g a minorit y racia l preference . I n con cluding that affirmativ e actio n doe s not eve n serv e the interest s of racia l minorities , who ar e its targete d beneficiaries , th e Fift h Circuit cite d a 197 4 la w revie w articl e b y Richar d Posne r tha t made unsubstantiate d claim s abou t th e stigm a agains t racia l minorities. The articl e entirel y ignore d th e bod y o f scholarshi p since 1974 on the subject o f stigma, and it never questioned wh y alumni childre n d o no t suffe r fro m stigm a du e t o thei r prefer ential treatment . "Never have white judges, relying exclusively on the work of white scholars , spoken s o authoritatively abou t th e blac k expe rience in America/' sai d Professor Lelan d Ware in criticizing th e decision o f th e Fift h Circui t Cour t o f Appeal s i n Hopwood v. State ofTexas. 24: Rather tha n focu s o n extensiv e scholarshi p by racia l minori ties concernin g stigma , th e Fift h Circui t relie d exclusivel y o n scholarship b y whites. Richard Posner' s 197 4 law review articl e on th e DeFunis cas e was cite d three time s with approva l b y th e court, but a request by the Thurgood Marshall Legal Society and the Black Pre-Law Association to intervene was denied. Posner's work establishe d th e propositio n (whic h thes e predominantl y black organizations were not permitted to attempt to contradict ) that "[t]h e us e o f a racial characteristi c t o establis h a presump -

Affirmative Actio n

37

tion tha t th e individua l als o possesse s other , an d sociall y rele vant, characteristics exemplifies , encourages, and legitimizes th e mode of thought an d behavior that underlies most prejudice an d bigotry i n moder n America." 25 Why , then , didn' t alumn i chil dren als o face suc h prejudice an d bigotry ? Posner's conjectur e abou t prejudice , havin g bee n uttere d i n 1974 without empirica l support, became a settled fact more tha n twenty year s late r whe n quote d b y th e Fift h Circuit . Ha d th e court quote d blac k scholar s lik e Randal l Kennedy , the y instea d would hav e had t o deal with sophisticate d response s like , "[t]h e problem wit h thi s vie w [tha t affirmativ e actio n entrenche s racial divisiveness] i s that intens e white resentmen t ha s accom panied ever y effor t t o undo racia l subordination n o matter ho w careful th e attemp t t o anticipate an d mollif y th e reaction/' 26 A s for th e stigm a argument , Professo r Kenned y responds : "In th e end, the uncertain exten t to which affirmative actio n diminishe s the accomplishment s o f black s mus t b e balance d agains t th e stigmatization that occurs when blacks are virtually absent fro m important institution s i n th e society . . . . This positiv e resul t o f affirmative actio n outweigh s an y stigm a tha t th e polic y causes/' 27 Why, on e mus t wonder , was Judg e Posner' s 197 4 law revie w cited a s an authorit y o n th e effect s o f affirmativ e actio n o n ou r society, rathe r tha n Professo r Kennedy' s 198 6 la w revie w arti cle, whic h als o discusse s th e issu e i n "cost-benefit " terms ? I f Posner i s correct , wh y d o s o man y Africa n American s suppor t affirmative action ? Ar e the y jus t plai n stupid ? O r ar e the y a s smart as white alumni in recognizing the value of a degree fro m a well-respected institution , regardles s o f th e admission s crite ria? Th e importanc e o f th e Hopwood opinio n i s tha t i t make s clear what earlier one might have been able only to suggest cyn -

38

Affirmative Actio n

ically—that la w and economies' supposed concern for efficienc y and persona l autonom y i s deploye d i n a wa y tha t dispropor tionately serve s th e interest s o f propertied whites . Let u s preten d fo r a moment tha t alumn i preference s wer e held t o th e sam e stric t scrutin y standar d a s racia l preferences . Under th e Constitution , policie s tha t ar e subjecte d t o stric t scrutiny mus t mee t a means/en d justification . Th e end s tha t they see k to accomplis h mus t b e "compelling, " an d th e mean s used t o achiev e thos e end s mus t b e narrowl y tailore d t o achieve thos e ends . If alternativ e mean s ar e availabl e t o attai n the stated objective that ca n avoid using the tainted category — in thi s case , alumni preference—the n thos e alternativ e mean s must b e used. In the language o f law and economics, we shoul d not permit th e use of an inefficient criterion—alumn i status — as a proxy fo r anothe r characteristi c tha t w e want t o measure . We shoul d insis t o n usin g highly accurat e indicators . Employ ing such reasoning with respec t to the racial criterion, the Fift h Circuit say s tha t i t i s offensiv e t o us e a racia l preferenc e a s a proxy fo r anothe r characteristic , suc h a s diversit y o f view point, becaus e th e preferenc e doe s no t mee t th e narrowl y tai lored portion o f the constitutiona l standard . We shoul d see k t o use criteri a tha t mor e perfectl y matc h th e characteristi c tha t we purpor t t o measur e i n orde r t o bette r attai n th e state d objective. Under thi s standar d o f efficiency , w e canno t justif y th e alumni preference i f it is being used inefficiently a s a proxy fo r another characteristic , suc h a s donation s o r academi c excel lence. Donation s ca n b e directl y measured ; n o prox y i s neces sary or efficient. Moreover , giving weight to alumni giving contradicts th e state d admission s criteri a tha t ar e suppose d t o b e "need blind/' Ho w can a process be need blind while also givin g

Affirmative Actio n

39

weight t o alumn i children , becaus e o f it s beneficia l effec t o n fund-raising? I f w e justify th e legac y preferenc e o n a financia l basis, then "i t migh t sav e time an d troubl e simpl y t o sel l diplomas fo r thei r childre n t o ric h alumn i parent s throug h th e mail/' 28 Academic excellenc e i s ofte n use d t o justify thi s preference . Harvard's dea n o f admissions , Willia m Fitzsimmons , justifie d the preference i n 199 1 by statin g tha t "[c]hildre n o f alumn i ar e just smarter ; the y com e fro m privilege d background s an d ten d to gro w up in home s where parent s encourag e learning/' 29 Th e empirical evidence , however , doe s no t suppor t thi s claim , sinc e on average , thes e admittee s hav e lowe r grade s an d tes t score s than do nonlegacy admittees. In addition, the standard measure s of excellence (grade s and test scores ) probably alread y overstat e the abilities of this group because they are likely to have had th e economic resource s t o maximiz e thei r performanc e o n thes e measures. I n an y event , th e equatio n o f alumn i childre n wit h superior academi c excellenc e (beyon d th e prediction s tha t would otherwis e b e mad e fro m grade s an d tes t scores ) i s no t logical, rational , o r efficient . Th e las t tim e tha t Harvar d com pared th e performanc e o f legac y an d nonlegac y classmate s wa s in 195 6 whe n a stud y "showe d Harvar d son s hoggin g th e bot tom o f the grad e curve." 30 Alternatively, on e migh t argu e tha t th e alumn i preferenc e i s not intende d t o stan d a s a prox y fo r somethin g else , tha t i t stands fo r itself , that a university preferentiall y value s the chil dren o f it s alumn i becaus e o f thei r previou s experienc e a s chil dren o f alumn i a t tha t institution . Thos e childre n hav e some thing in common—they hav e grown up in a household in which one of the parents graduated fro m tha t institution. It is true tha t the compositio n o f thi s grou p ha s bee n sociall y constructed .

40

Affirmative Actio n

One i s no t inherently—biologically—a n alumn i child ; on e becomes an alumni child because of something that one's paren t has don e eithe r befor e o r afte r one' s birth . On e the n acquire s this trait throug h one' s parent . But how valuable is a group identity tha t ha s existed for pos sibly only one generation? And does being the child of an alum nus o r alumn a reall y shap e his o r her identit y i n an y meaning ful way ? Ca n i t mee t a compelling stat e interes t standard ? I t i s hard t o justify a n alumn i preferenc e tha t come s clos e t o estab lishing a compelling, or even strong, state interest. Legacy preferences are simply affirmative actio n for th e rich, pure an d sim ple, wit h n o nobl e purpose. 31 I n th e languag e o f la w an d eco nomics, there i s no objectiv e basi s fo r thi s preference . Justifications fo r racia l affirmativ e actio n are , i n fact , muc h stronger. A s wit h th e alumn i category , i t i s no w commonl y acknowledged tha t rac e i s a sociall y constructe d experience . Anthropologically, racia l difference s amon g human s d o no t genuinely exist . But historically, we have create d a meaning fo r certain characteristics tha t we label race. The social constructio n of thos e trait s make s the m n o les s real . An institutio n migh t value havin g someon e presen t a t a universit y wh o gre w u p identified a s a member o f a particular racia l group . And unlik e the alumni preference, thi s for m o f self-identity ma y have bee n passed on for many generation s an d learned at an early age. The views o f th e member s o f thi s grou p nee d no t b e identica l i n order fo r thei r presenc e t o b e valuabl e o r noteworthy . I n fact , the difference s i n thei r viewpoint s migh t hel p rebu t socia l stereotypes suc h a s "al l black s thin k alike. " But thei r presenc e reflects th e realit y o f a genuine socia l category . When he spoke about the effect o n prejudice and bigotry, Posner misunderstoo d th e justification fo r mor e than toke n partici -

Affirmative Actio n

41

pation b y a racial minorit y grou p a t a n institution . The poin t i s not that al l blacks think alike , and so we do not need more blacks to attain diversity in viewpoint. Rather, the point is that all blacks do not thin k alike , but thi s fac t wil l no t b e apparen t unti l mor e than a token numbe r o f blacks attend a n institution . Posner is fond o f reciting formal equalit y arguments t o over turn affirmativ e action , but i t i s misleading t o sugges t tha t th e law o f educationa l admission s i s reall y formall y equal . Alumn i preference policie s ar e no t subjec t t o judicial challenge , despit e their disparat e impac t agains t racia l minorities , becaus e dis parate impac t theor y unde r th e Constitutio n o r Title V I o f th e Civil Right s Act o f 196 4 require s proo f o f "intent " t o discrimi nate racially, which the courts have ruled is not available in suc h situations. Hence , th e Offic e o f Civi l Right s rule d agains t th e Asian America n complainant s i n th e racia l discriminatio n cas e against Harvar d Universit y tha t challenge d alumn i preferences . Even thoug h a disparat e impac t agains t Asia n American s ma y have existed , n o direc t evidenc e o f inten t t o exclud e Asia n Americans was found. The historical evidenc e that alumn i pref erence wa s originall y create d t o exclud e othe r immigran t groups—Jews an d Catholics—wa s considere d sufficien t evi dence o f lawfu l intent . Racia l preferenc e policie s fo r racia l minorities, however , ar e subjec t t o judicia l challeng e becaus e they purportedl y har m white s intentionally . Forma l equalit y results i n unequal justice when white s ar e given preference an d blacks ar e not . Posner' s versio n o f la w an d economic s require s blacks to justify th e obviou s benefit s o f more tha n toke n diver sity (withou t considerin g black scholarship) an d permits white s to perpetuate segregatio n withou t justification . Thi s i s not for mal equality ; i t i s the maintenanc e o f a white, propertied socia l and economi c structure .

42

Affirmative Actio n Employment Affirmative Actio n

Particular employmen t decisions , lik e particula r educationa l admissions decisions , requir e tha t th e criteri a fo r selectio n b e specified. In the employment area , such criteria ar e often consid ered to be based on merit unless they involve race-based affirma tive action . Nonetheless , man y o f thes e criteri a benefi t whites , even though the y do not correlate significantly wit h the capacit y to perfor m th e jo b i n question . The criteri a tha t disproportion ately favor whites include word-of-mouth recruiting , high school or college diploma requirements, and " general intelligence" tests . When challenge d as giving an unfair advantag e to nonblack can didates for employment, these devices are often applaude d by law and economics theorists despit e little evidence of fairness o r effi ciency By contrast, when an y syste m i s imposed to favor a black candidate for employment, these same theorists criticize the preference by hiding behind concern s for forma l equality . These employmen t criteri a hav e no t bee n consisten t ove r time. Standardized testin g i s a twentieth-century phenomeno n that bega n t o b e commonplac e i n civi l servic e employmen t a s overt rac e an d gende r barrier s wer e eliminated . Suc h test s ar e presumed t o test a n applicant' s abilit y t o perform a job when i n fact, bot h thei r predictiv e abilit y an d thei r abilit y t o compar e candidates i s limited. 32 A s black s cam e t o hav e mor e schoolin g in the 1970s, a college education became increasingly important , although th e actua l value o f a college degre e i s often presume d rather tha n empiricall y established . B y 1980 , the averag e blac k person ha d 12. 0 year s o f school , compare d wit h 12. 5 year s fo r whites, bu t fel l behin d i n colleg e education . I n 1980 , 17. 1 per cent o f white s ha d receive d colleg e diplomas , compare d wit h only 8. 4 percent o f blacks. 33

Affirmative Actio n

43

Whites hav e th e opportunit y t o benefi t fro m examinatio n and educatio n requirements , regardles s o f whethe r thos e crite ria correlat e wit h positiv e workplac e performance . America n culture simpl y presume s suc h a correlation. Fo r example, whe n Epstein defend s educationa l requirements , h e doe s no t rel y o n empirical evidence . Instead , h e refer s t o th e "globa l socia l per ception tha t education , lik e goo d persona l habits , i s alway s jo b related/' 34 An d a s is typica l o f suc h assertions , Richar d Epstei n relies o n th e wor k o f Richar d Posne r t o suppor t hi s statement . Posner, i n turn , base d hi s correlatio n o n "judicia l an d profes sional experience with educational requirements i n law enforce ment/' 3 5 I n fact , th e court s tha t hav e examine d th e empirica l evidence concernin g educationa l requirement s hav e no t share d Judge Posner' s presumptio n o r conclusion. 36 Hence , a s i n th e Hopwood case , such presumptions have been created by Richar d Posner's unsubstantiated scholarship . As Randall Kennedy asked , "Would anyon e clai m tha t Henr y For d I I was hea d o f th e For d Motor Compan y becaus e h e wa s th e mos t qualifie d perso n fo r the job?" 37 One are a o f employmen t tha t i s ofte n considere d merito cratic but i s based o n a history o f exclusionar y tactic s i s admis sion to the legal bar. In th e earl y nineteent h century , admissio n standards wer e greatl y reduce d t o permi t nearl y an y eligibl e man t o practic e law. 38 Women an d black s were , o f course , for mally exclude d fro m th e practic e o f law. 39 When th e America n Bar Associatio n unknowingl y admitte d thre e blac k lawyer s t o membership i n 1912 , i t immediatel y passe d a resolutio n pre cluding furthe r associationa l miscegenation , thu s ensurin g it s "lily-white membershi p fo r th e nex t half-century/' 40 By th e lat e nineteent h century , thi s practic e bega n t o com e under attac k when article s complained that "hord e upon horde "

44

Affirmative Actio n

were "connecte d wit h th e practice of s o noble a profession/'41 I t was at this time that Christophe r Columbu s Langdell' s views of legal education began to dominate American culture . Two explanations fo r Langdell' s influenc e o n the profession ar e his ties t o Harvard an d his "scientific" justification o f legal education. The elitist value s o f la w an d economic s tha t emerge d durin g th e Industrial Revolutio n wer e partl y responsibl e fo r th e develop ment o f more formal standard s fo r admissio n t o the bar. In 192 1 and agai n i n 1971 , the American Ba r Association approve d th e bar examinatio n a s a criterio n fo r admissio n t o th e bar . Today, only th e stat e o f Wisconsi n relie s o n th e diplom a privileg e fo r bar admission , eschewin g th e ba r examination . Hence , relianc e on th e ba r examinatio n fo r admissio n t o th e ba r i s a phenome non o f th e lat e twentiet h century . Th e rol e o f th e lega l ba r t o weed ou t th e "hordes " who wante d t o practic e la w als o was a n expression o f over t clas s bias . This clas s bia s persist s toda y a s "bar association s ten d t o concentrat e o n low-statu s attorney s who hav e committe d improprieties , turnin g a blind ey e t o th e abuses o f nam e partner s a t prestigious firms/' 42 In th e eighteent h an d nineteent h centuries , forma l barrier s excluded Africa n American s an d wome n fro m th e practic e o f law, wherea s today , th e ba r exa m disproportionatel y exclude s African American s fro m th e practic e o f law. Although on e can not prov e directl y tha t th e examinatio n requiremen t wa s cre ated t o wee d ou t Africa n Americans , circumstantia l evidenc e does support thi s view. For example, the stat e of South Carolin a eliminated th e diplom a privileg e an d institute d th e ba r exami nation requirement exactl y three years after th e state opened its first blac k la w school. 43 The n th e "readin g th e bar " rul e wa s eliminated i n 1957 , shortl y afte r a blac k applican t use d thi s method t o gai n admission . Th e stat e o f Sout h Carolina , o f

Affirmative Actio n

45

course, defends eac h o f thes e change s o n race-neutra l grounds . Similarly, i n Philadelphia , applicant s fo r admissio n t o th e ba r were photographed , an d blac k applicant s wer e seate d sid e b y side in the sam e row "to facilitate th e grading o f their examina tions/' 44 The raciall y consciou s gradin g o f th e ba r examinatio n followed a covertl y discriminator y preceptorshi p an d registra tion syste m unde r whic h no t a single black was admitte d t o th e Pennsylvania ba r betwee n 193 3 an d 1943 . Hence, the ba r exa m (with it s racial impact) i s of recent vintag e i n the United States . The ba r exa m persist s a s a selectio n device , despit e it s dis parate impact , becaus e i t i s though t t o wee d ou t incompeten t applicants to the bar. There is no evidence, however, that th e ba r exam test s one' s abilit y t o b e a lawyer; instead , i t i s essentiall y an achievement test . It simply verifies a student's prior privileg e "that [has ] alread y bee n teste d fo r a t leas t thre e time s i n a law student's career , namely , durin g undergraduat e training , th e LSAT, an d la w schoo l training." 45 Recognizin g th e correlatio n between grade s i n la w schoo l an d passag e o f th e ba r examina tion, th e Fourt h Circui t stated : "A n applican t fo r th e Ba r wh o has graduate d fro m a n accredite d la w schoo l arguabl y ma y b e said to stand before the Examiners armed with law school grades demonstrating tha t h e possesse s sufficien t job-relate d skills . Why, then, an y bar examinatio n a t all?" 46 If th e ba r exa m wer e require d t o withstand a rigorous stan dard o f justification , i t i s doubtfu l tha t i t woul d pas s muster . Commenting o n th e selectio n o f a cutof f passin g scor e o n th e bar exam , fo r example , th e Fourt h Circui t noted : "W e ten d t o agree wit h appellants ' exper t that , i f thi s secon d syste m i s uti lized i n th e precis e manne r describe d b y th e Ba r Examiners , i t would b e almos t a matte r o f pur e luc k i f th e '70' thereb y derived corresponde d wit h anybody' s judgmen t o f minima l

46

Affirmative Action

competence/' 47 An d whe n upholdin g th e constitutionalit y o f the ba r exa m unde r a very lenien t constitutiona l standard , th e Fourth Circui t acknowledged : "Tha t i s no t t o sa y tha t suc h a n unprofessional approac h leave s us with muc h confidenc e i n th e precise numerica l result s obtained/ ' Despit e th e apparen t imprecision o f th e ba r examination , i t persist s a s the predomi nant selectio n device . Its continued us e reflects th e Langdellia n trend towar d tryin g t o introduc e scientifi c principle s int o th e selection o f lawyers , regardles s o f th e validit y o f thos e princi ples. The ba r exa m i s a uniquel y America n phenomenon . Othe r countries often requir e prospective lawyers to " article" in orde r to gai n experienc e practicin g la w before bein g allowe d t o wor k on thei r own . But the y d o not rel y o n a n invalidate d multiple choice exam to test students ' substantiv e knowledg e o f law an d also t o exclud e a distinct portio n o f thos e wh o hav e graduate d from la w school. In the United States , although Wisconsin doe s not requir e a ba r exa m fo r individual s wh o hav e graduate d from a state institution , n o on e has complaine d abou t th e rela tive competenc y o f lawyer s i n tha t state . The moder n persis tence o f the ba r exa m thu s represent s a state-sanctioned intru sion int o th e workplac e tha t canno t b e justifie d o n efficienc y grounds. Ironically, whe n th e la w trie s t o forc e employer s t o justif y examination o r education requirements , scholar s in th e fiel d o f law an d economic s complai n loudly . The case tha t exemplifie s this phenomenon i s Griggs v. Duke Power, 48 whic h was decide d under Titl e VI I o f th e Civi l Right s Ac t o f 196 4 rathe r tha n under th e Constitution . A s i n th e ba r examinatio n example , Griggs i s a n excellen t demonstratio n o f ho w educationa l an d testing requirement s chang e a s over t entr y barrier s t o black s

Affirmative Actio n

47

are eliminated . I n Griggs, a n employe r change d th e rule s fo r promotion fro m laborer-leve l jobs into higher-level jobs o n th e very da y tha t Titl e VI I wen t int o effec t (Jul y 2 , 1965). For th e first time , employees were required to pass a high schoo l equiv alency progra m i n orde r t o b e promoted . Thei r performanc e could be confirmed onl y by earnin g a set scor e on the Wonder lie general intelligence tes t or the Bennett AA general mechan ical test . The U.S . Suprem e Cour t conclude d i n th e Griggs cas e tha t such device s have a disparate impac t o n blacks an d coul d not b e justified b y busines s necessit y i n thi s case. 49 (Unde r th e busi ness necessit y rule , an employe r ca n us e a selection devic e tha t produces a disparate impact on the basis of race or sex only if th e employer ca n demonstrat e tha t th e tes t i s necessar y fo r th e businesses efficien t operation . In th e case of a test, a n employe r must demonstrat e validit y unde r th e standard s accepte d b y social scientist s i n th e fiel d o f testing.) Becaus e employer s suc h as Duk e Powe r hav e bee n unabl e t o construc t th e evidenc e o f test validit y require d unde r thi s standard , the y n o longe r rou tinely us e genera l intelligenc e test s t o selec t employees. 50 On e might hav e expected law and economics scholar s to applaud thi s result, a s i t encourage s employer s t o choos e efficient , job related selection devices rather than rely on presumptions abou t correlations betwee n tes t score s an d jo b performance . Instead , this lin e o f case s ha s bee n roundl y criticize d a s makin g i t to o expensive fo r employer s t o use testing and educational require ments tha t ca n withstand judicial scrutiny . Richard Epstei n ha s le d th e charg e agains t requirin g valida tion o f suc h tests , claimin g tha t testin g serve s a valuabl e pur pose. Hi s sourc e fo r thi s clai m i s th e industr y tha t create s an d promotes thes e tests :

48

Affirmative Actio n

Notwithstanding thei r embattle d statu s unde r Titl e VII , there i s a widespread belie f o n th e par t o f thos e who desig n and use general employment tests that these provide accurate and essential predictions of job success for individual workers and shoul d therefor e b e regarded a s an important, indee d a n indispensable, aid in hiring and promotion decisions. 51 Epstein's reasonin g i s circular. He insists that w e should per mit educationa l an d testin g requirement s t o giv e young peopl e an incentiv e t o obtai n mor e education . "[B] y reducin g th e returns o n education , i t remove s on e o f th e incentive s tha t young people have to expend money, time, and effort o n acquir ing a n education/' 52 Bu t w e coul d als o cautio n youn g peopl e from thinkin g tha t mor e educatio n alway s lead s t o mor e employment opportunities . The y ma y wan t t o conside r othe r reasons fo r seekin g higher education , such as the intrinsic satisfaction gaine d o r th e differin g type s o f job s tha t ma y becom e available. Young people who choos e to pursue a doctoral degre e in th e humanitie s mus t recogniz e tha t the y migh t ear n mor e money simpl y b y completin g a n inexpensiv e certificat e pro gram i n th e healt h car e field , ye t presumabl y the y mak e thei r choice fo r it s intrinsi c value . Carrie d t o it s logica l conclusion , however, Epstein' s argumen t woul d permi t employer s t o ba r from low-leve l employmen t anyon e wh o coul d not obtai n hig h test score s or a college diploma, regardless o f his or her aptitud e for that particular job. But many employer s would be quite mistaken i n assumin g tha t la w professors , fo r example , wh o scor e well o n genera l intelligenc e test s woul d b e competen t t o fulfil l the kin d o f mechanical positio n tha t wa s a t stak e in Griggs. Another employmen t devic e tha t ofte n harm s th e employ ment opportunitie s o f black s i s word-of-mouth recruiting . Th e American labo r forc e i s heavil y segregate d alon g racia l lines .

Affirmative Actio n

49

Because o f segregatio n i n friendshi p an d housin g patterns , word-of-mouth recruitin g help s perpetuat e thos e segregate d patterns a t th e workplace . A s th e Fift h Circui t conclude d i n 1973, word-of-mout h recruitin g "operate s a s a 'built-in-head wind' t o blacks" at a workforce i n which onl y 7. 2 percent o f th e employees ar e black. 53 Similarl y a 199 4 Universit y o f Min nesota stud y o f poo r youth s i n Bosto n foun d tha t th e black s i n the sample had more schooling but lower wages than th e white s did, becaus e th e white s ha d bette r employmen t contacts . "Whites wh o foun d job s throug h relative s earne d 3 8 percen t more tha n th e blacks who did . But fo r thos e who go t jobs with out contacts , the white-black earnin g gap was only 5 percent." 54 Word-of-mouth recruiting , therefore , affect s bot h employabil ity an d wages. Word-of-mouth recruitin g ha s bee n uphel d a s "efficient " even whe n th e evidenc e demonstrate s tha t i t woul d hav e bee n equally efficien t t o notif y th e stat e unemploymen t servic e o f a job opening. Then, however, the applicants would have been disproportionately black , given th e disproportionatel y hig h rat e of unemployment i n th e blac k community . Unemploymen t b y a particular racia l grou p i s easil y perpetuate d i f word-of-mout h recruiting rathe r tha n notificatio n o f th e stat e unemploymen t office i s the primary method o f recruitment fo r entry-leve l jobs. This i s a n exampl e o f unconsciou s racis m tha t als o serve s a s a self-perpetuating for m o f discrimination . A n employe r ma y choose to pursue a n application proces s that minimize s it s costs, but wil l i t choos e t o notif y th e stat e unemploymen t office , o r will it encourage its employees t o tell their friend s an d relative s about th e job openings ? Although bot h mechanism s ar e chea p an d thu s efficient , th e first proces s usually result s in large numbers o f minority appli -

50

Affirmative Actio n

cants, and the secon d usually doe s not (tha t is, not in an alread y segregated workplace). Hence a s early a s 1968, Professor Alfre d Blumrosen, who also worked for the Equal Employment Oppor tunity Commissio n (EEOC) , suggeste d tha t " a requiremen t outside o f th e Sout h tha t al l employers utiliz e the employmen t service with respec t t o al l jobs will benefit Negr o job seeker s t o a proportionall y greate r exten t tha n white , an d shoul d b e imposed/' 55 A searc h fo r efficiency , combine d wit h eithe r con scious o r unconscious racism , may resul t i n th e choic e of word of-mouth recruitment . Th e Sevent h Circui t ratifie d word-of mouth recruitmen t a s consisten t wit h th e principle s o f effi ciency an d thereb y presume d tha t i t i s also consisten t wit h th e principle o f nondiscrimination . Th e EEOC s argumen t i n thes e cases that stat e employmen t service s were not , but shoul d hav e been, used for employmen t advertisin g was ignored. There is no reason t o equat e efficienc y wit h nondiscrimination . Severa l efficient source s fo r employee s exist . Why, then , wa s thi s par ticular devic e chosen ? When word-of-mout h recruitmen t result s i n fe w blac k applicants, the Seventh Circui t blames the black applicants rather tha n the employer' s recruitmen t practices . Thus, in EEOC v. Chicago Miniature Lamp Work, 56 th e Sevent h Circui t hel d agains t th e black plaintiff s (reversin g th e tria l court' s decision ) i n a cas e i n which th e plaintiffs ha d complained o f discrimination i n recruit ment. The Sevent h Circui t foun d tha t becaus e the factor y wa s in a Hispanic and Asian part o f Chicago , it was unrealistic to expec t blacks to want t o work there . It blamed th e lo w application rate s for blacks on their lack of interest in such jobs rather than o n an y affirmative action s b y th e employer . I n th e court' s words : "[The company] is not liable when it passively relies on the natural flo w of applicants fo r it s entry-level positions. "

Affirmative Actio n

51

Eight year s later , i n EEOC v. Consolidated Service Systems, the Miniature holdin g was transformed int o the conclusion tha t word-of-mouth recruitmen t i s inherentl y "efficient " an d "cheap." 57 This time , the compan y wa s located i n th e majority black cit y o f Chicago . Relianc e o n word-of-mout h recruiting , however, resulte d i n a smal l Africa n America n applican t pool . Despite th e apparen t irrationalit y o f th e applican t pool , Judg e Posner, writing fo r th e Sevent h Circuit , wa s heavil y persuade d by th e efficienc y o f Consolidated' s hirin g practices . N o fewe r than fou r times , Posne r repeate d tha t Consolidate d picke d th e cheapest an d mos t efficien t metho d o f hiring , tha t is , word-ofmouth recruitment . As he stated, "[I]t is clear[,] as we have been at pains to emphasize, [tha t it is] the cheapest an d most efficien t method o f recruitment , notwithstandin g it s discriminator y impact." Posner' s nonempirica l assertio n abou t efficienc y entirely overlooke d th e efficienc y o f notifyin g th e stat e unem ployment offic e o f job openings . Posner's unsupported assertion s als o recently appeared agai n in a dissenting opinion by Seventh Circui t Judge Daniel Manion , another proponen t o f conservativ e economi c principles . Thi s case also reflected seriou s problems with a n employer' s recruit ment an d hirin g process , wit h th e resul t tha t absolutel y n o blacks wer e hire d i n a six-yea r period , eve n thoug h th e plan t was locate d i n a predominantl y blac k neighborhood . Manio n chose t o ignor e th e overwhelmin g statistic s i n th e case , con cluding tha t "English-speakin g jo b seeker s ma y no t wan t t o work in an environment o f predominantly foreig n languages." 58 As i n th e Chicago Miniature Lamp Works case , h e conclude d that th e lack of interest b y blacks in th e are a was more likel y t o explain the low rate of black employment tha n was an act of discrimination b y th e employer , O& G Sprin g & Wire Forms .

52

Affirmative Actio n

The onl y evidenc e confirmin g th e interes t o f black s i n suc h employment contradict s Manion's assertion. A complaint of discrimination file d wit h th e EEOC resulted i n a dramatic increas e in application s b y Africa n American s a t th e company 59 Di d African American s suddenl y becom e intereste d i n workin g alongside non-English-speakin g employees ? A s wit h th e affir mative actio n cases , Judg e Manio n mad e assumption s abou t blacks that one would not make about whites. This case reflecte d an employment settin g in which Polish Americans and Spanish speaking American s worke d sid e b y side . Although thes e tw o groups o f white s di d no t hav e a commo n language , the y appeared t o b e comfortabl e wit h eac h othe r i n th e workplace . Judge Manio n assumed , however , tha t African Americans , wh o spoke yet a different language , would no t be comfortable work ing alongside thes e tw o groups . Manion als o overlooked th e argument s availabl e i n thi s cas e concerning economi c rationality . Unlik e th e Consolidated Services case , O& G wa s locate d i n th e hear t o f a predominantl y black neighborhood . I t wa s therefor e economicall y rationa l fo r blacks t o see k employmen t there . Accordingly , sinc e Manio n could no t clai m economi c rationality , h e invente d nationa l ori gin o r languag e animu s o n th e par t o f African Americans , bu t with n o testimon y o n recor d t o suppor t it . I t wa s fa r easie r t o blame unemploye d black s fo r thei r lo w employmen t recor d than t o blame O&G' s management . Manion's them e strongl y reflect s th e values o f efficiency an d objectivity foun d i n law and economics . To bolster hi s efficienc y argument, h e quote d Judg e Posner' s opinio n i n Consolidated Service: "It would be a bitter irony if the federal agency dedicate d to enforcin g th e antidiscriminatio n law s succeede d i n usin g those laws to kick these people off the ladder by compelling the m

Affirmative Actio n

53

to institute costly systems of hiring/' 60 According to this "logic," word-of-mouth recruitin g shoul d b e tolerated becaus e it is pur portedly th e cheapes t method , eve n i f i t knowingl y result s i n a loss of employment opportunitie s fo r African Americans . Applying th e principle of objectivity, Manio n contende d tha t there wa s n o wa y t o argu e wh y on e subgrou p deserve s prefer ential treatment ove r another subgroup . "By not taking the lan guage facto r int o consideratio n th e EEO C ha s i n effec t pu t a quota o n on e vulnerabl e grou p a t th e expens e o f another. " Bu t the "languag e factor " wa s Judg e Manion' s invention , becaus e the evidenc e showe d tha t i t di d no t dete r th e employmen t o f two groups o f whites a t that workplace . The cleve r mov e i n Judg e Manion' s opinio n wa s t o twis t a requirement fo r equa l treatment—givin g black s an d other s a n equal opportunity to hear about openings and be hired at O&G— into a "quota " tha t apparentl y pitte d "on e vulnerabl e group " against another . Affirmativ e actio n i s considere d inefficien t because i t reflect s non-merit-base d preference s fo r blacks , bu t word-of-mouth recruitmen t fo r nonblack s i s considered permis sible because it is efficient, eve n though it grants non-merit-base d preferences t o nonblacks. The measure o f efficiency i s the exten t of blac k employment . Whe n black employmen t rises , w e mus t attribute it to "quota madness " rather tha n th e removal o f barriers toward advancement. 61 But when white employment declines, we must attribute it to affirmative action . Black employment thu s is inefficient, wherea s white employmen t i s efficient .

The Canadian Experienc e

The Unite d States ' evocatio n o f th e meri t principl e i s no t inevitable. Canada, for example , seems to have escape d many o f

54

Affirmative Actio n

the problem s surroundin g th e hirin g an d educationa l practice s in the United States. Testing for educatio n o r employment i s not as widespread i n Canad a a s i t i s i n th e Unite d States . Affirma tive actio n i s constitutionally protecte d fo r member s o f histori cally disadvantage d groups . Not onl y has th e affirmativ e actio n principle bee n extende d t o wome n an d racia l minorities , bu t claims b y gay s an d lesbian s hav e als o bee n recognize d unde r this principle . Canadia n universitie s ar e generall y publi c insti tutions an d d o no t shar e th e money-consciou s perspectiv e o f elite American privat e universities. A formal ba r exa m doe s no t serve a s a barrier t o admissio n t o th e Canadia n bar ; instead , a more practice-oriented proces s is used to determine who is qualified t o practice law. Unlike American jurisprudence o n equalit y issues , Canadia n jurisprudence i s comparative i n nature. The experienc e o f othe r countries a s wel l a s internationa l huma n right s convention s influence th e decision s rendere d b y Canadia n judges. Although U.S. precedent is often cited , Canadian court s often refus e t o fol low i t becaus e i t i s ou t o f ste p wit h th e jurisprudence o f othe r Western nations . Thus , th e lega l perspectiv e plu s substantiv e conclusions b y Canadia n judge s diffe r markedl y fro m thos e o f U.S. judges, eve n thoug h th e tw o countrie s hav e simila r histo ries and geographies . The sourc e o f th e substantiv e difference s betwee n Canadia n and America n equalit y jurisprudenc e ca n b e foun d i n thei r respective constitutions . Th e Fourteent h Amendmen t t o th e U.S. Constitution state s that "al l persons" are entitled to "equa l protection unde r th e law. " Thi s approach , whic h i s usuall y described a s "formal equality, " permits judges t o treat claim s of discrimination brough t b y whit e me n i n th e sam e wa y a s the y do claim s o f discriminatio n brough t b y African-America n

Affirmative Actio n

55

women. I n addition , thi s approac h subject s affirmativ e actio n measures o n behal f o f wome n o r racia l minoritie s t o discrimi nation claim s b y whit e men . And a s we hav e seen , judges wh o subscribe t o extrem e laissez-fair e principle s ar e ver y sympa thetic to these revers e discriminatio n claims . Reverse discriminatio n claim s ar e generall y no t recognize d in Canadia n jurisprudence. The righ t t o equa l treatmen t i s protected unde r Sectio n 1 5 o f th e Canadia n Charte r o f Right s an d Freedoms. Par t 1 o f Sectio n 1 5 i s simila r t o th e Fourteent h Amendment o f th e U.S . Constitution. I t provide s fo r th e indi vidual right t o equa l treatmen t unde r th e law . Canadian courts , however, hav e interprete d thi s rul e differentl y tha n hav e U.S . courts. Proof o f discriminatio n ma y com e through proo f o f dis criminatory purpos e (a s in th e Unite d States ) o r throug h proo f of discriminator y effec t (unlik e th e Unite d States) . Thus, in th e previous exampl e involvin g a claim o f discriminatio n b y Asia n Americans by the use of the alumni preference rule , a Canadia n court woul d conside r thos e plaintiff s t o hav e invoke d a prim a facie cas e o f racia l discriminatio n base d solel y o n th e effec t o f the rule . Canadian courts , however , hav e impose d a n additiona l requirement o n a discrimination clai m tha t i s no t foun d i n th e United States. Plaintiffs wh o allege discrimination must demon strate that thei r clai m o f discriminatio n i s based o n a n enumer ated or analogous ground to a disadvantaged group. Enumerated grounds includ e race , nationa l o r ethni c origin , color , religion , sex, age , o r menta l o r physica l disability—whic h ar e specifie d directly i n Par t 1 o f Sectio n 15 . Analogous ground s ar e addi tional characteristic s tha t th e court s hav e foun d similarl y ste m from disadvantag e an d therefor e shoul d b e protected fro m dis crimination. Marita l status , sexua l orientation , citizenship , an d

56

Affirmative Actio n

being adoptiv e parents o r adoptiv e childre n hav e been foun d t o constitute analogou s grounds . Thus, not al l "persons" can brin g claims o f discrimination ; the y mus t b e abl e t o demonstrat e a history o f disadvantage d treatment . If a Canadia n plaintif f establishe s a prim a faci e cas e o f dis crimination, th e burde n o f proo f shift s t o th e governmen t o r other part y upholdin g th e law . Tw o defense s ar e recognize d under Canadia n la w Th e governmen t ca n argu e tha t th e chal lenged rul e implement s a n affirmativ e actio n progra m permit ted under Par t 2 of Section 1 5 or that the violation o f the equal ity provisions i s reasonably an d demonstrably justified i n a fre e and democrati c societ y a s permitte d unde r Sectio n 1 o f th e Charter. Section 15, Part 2, was included in the Charter in order to save applicable affirmativ e actio n program s fro m a finding o f consti tutional invalidity. Part 2 operates to excuse the violation of Section 15 , Part 1 , if the persons in favor o f whom th e distinction i s made ar e disadvantage d an d th e objec t o f th e discriminatio n i s the amelioratio n o f tha t disadvantage . Par t 2 state s tha t Par t 1 "does no t preclud e an y law , program o r activit y tha t ha s a s it s object th e amelioratio n o f conditions o f disadvantaged individu als o r group s includin g thos e tha t ar e disadvantage d becaus e o f race, national o r ethni c origin , color, religion, sex , age o r menta l or physica l disability/ ' Canadia n court s hav e develope d thre e principles t o assis t i n th e applicatio n o f Sectio n 15 , Par t 2 : (1 ) There mus t b e a rationa l connectio n betwee n th e preferentia l treatment an d th e disadvantage ; (2 ) ther e mus t b e a rea l nexu s between th e objec t o f th e progra m a s declare d b y th e govern ment an d it s for m an d implementation ; an d (3 ) th e burde n o f proof unde r thi s par t rest s o n th e part y seekin g t o invok e thi s part t o demonstrate it s application. 62

Affirmative Actio n

57

The applicatio n o f thes e thre e principle s reflect s a compro mise o n affirmativ e action . I t wa s no t intende d t o sav e fro m scrutiny al l legislation intende d t o hav e a n ameliorativ e effect . Instead, i t wa s include d t o silenc e th e debat e tha t rage s i n th e United State s an d elsewher e concernin g th e legitimacy o f affir mative actio n whil e requirin g tha t affirmativ e actio n program s pass muster onl y when the y are reasonably effective an d appro priately tailore d programs . In the Canadia n courts , nearly al l the case s challenging affir mative actio n programs hav e been unsuccessful . And unlike th e United States , mos t o f th e case s hav e no t involve d race-base d affirmative action . Gender an d disabilit y case s have als o playe d a prominen t rol e i n th e developmen t o f thi s lin e o f cases . I n those case s tha t loo k mos t lik e th e Unite d States ' revers e dis crimination cases—claim s brought by able-bodied white men — the court s hav e been resoundingl y unsympatheti c t o the plain tiff.63 Those case s that give n th e court s paus e have been one s i n which bot h th e plaintif f an d th e intende d beneficiar y clas s under th e affirmativ e actio n pla n wer e member s o f a disadvan taged group . In suc h cases , the court s hav e trie d t o wrestle wit h what the content of an affirmative actio n program would be that benefits a s many disadvantage d group s a s possible. A recent Ontario case , Schafer v. Attorney General 64 reflect s a tension between two disadvantaged group s as well as a sophisticated analysi s o f th e tensio n betwee n Part s 1 and 2 of Sectio n 15. The opinio n reflect s a n attemp t t o create a social policy tha t benefits a s much o f societ y a s possible while no t assumin g tha t government interventio n itsel f i s objectionable . The plaintiffs challenge d Canada's Unemployment Insuranc e Act with respec t t o it s rule s regardin g maternit y an d chil d car e benefits. Th e plaintiff s wer e adoptiv e parent s wh o wer e give n

58

Affirmative Actio n

less pai d leav e unde r th e Unemploymen t Insuranc e Ac t tha n were similarly situated biological parents. The biological parents received fiv e additiona l week s o f chil d car e benefit s tha t wer e not mad e availabl e t o parents wh o adopte d thei r childre n whe n they were under th e ag e of si x months. Biological parents coul d receive up to twenty-five week s of maternity an d child care benefits, compare d wit h te n week s fo r adoptiv e parents . The cas e reflected a tension betwee n Part s 1 and 2 of Sectio n 15 o f th e Canadia n Charte r becaus e th e governmen t defende d the progra m b y arguin g tha t th e maternit y an d chil d car e ben efits rul e ha d bee n enacte d t o ameliorat e th e condition s o f women wh o ar e disadvantaged , tha t is , unable t o work, becaus e of thei r se x o r becaus e o f thei r physica l disabilit y du e t o preg nancy an d childbirth . Bein g awar e o f th e requiremen t tha t a valid progra m unde r Par t 2 mus t b e reasonabl y relate d t o it s ameliorative purposes , the governmen t furthe r argue d tha t th e rule was effective i n achieving its objective an d that ther e was a direct relationshi p betwee n th e caus e o f th e disadvantag e an d the for m o f th e ameliorativ e action . Sinc e wome n wh o giv e birth fac e a perio d o f physica l disability , th e governmen t con tended tha t adoptiv e parents ar e not similarl y situate d i n need ing the ameliorativ e treatment . The firs t par t o f the analysi s require d th e cour t t o determin e when plaintiff s ha d a cognizable clai m o f discriminatio n unde r Part 1 o f Sectio n 15 . To hav e a proper clai m unde r Par t 1 , th e plaintiffs neede d t o establis h tha t the y ha d a claim o f discrimi nation o n th e basi s o f a n enumerate d o r analogou s ground . Because adoptiv e parent s an d childre n ar e no t specificall y enu merated i n Par t 1 of Sectio n 15 , they ha d t o pursu e th e analo gous groun d arguments . To support the claim that they were a group deserving antidis-

Affirmative Actio n

59

crimination protectio n unde r Par t 1 of Sectio n 15 , the plaintiff s referred t o internationa l convention s a s wel l a s th e practic e i n other countries . Bot h th e Universa l Declaratio n o f Huma n Rights an d the Conventio n o n the Right s o f the Chil d stat e tha t special measures o f protection an d assistance shoul d be taken o n behalf o f al l children , withou t discriminatio n o n th e basi s o f parentage. In addition , thes e convention s recogniz e th e nee d t o provide paid leave to mothers followin g th e birth o r adoption o f a child . Surveyin g th e practice s o f othe r Wester n countries , th e court als o note d tha t mos t o f the m provid e fo r pai d maternit y leave consistent wit h th e various international conventions . The United States, however, the court noted, does not provide for fed erally mandate d pai d maternity leav e and ha s als o not endorse d the Internationa l Labo r Organization' s Maternit y Protectio n Convention. Base d o n thi s comparativ e examination , th e Cana dian cour t conclude d tha t adoptiv e parent s an d thei r childre n should be protected fro m discriminatio n unde r Par t 1 of Sectio n 15 becaus e thei r nee d t o b e protecte d fro m discriminatio n ha s been widely recognize d i n th e Western world . Having foun d tha t th e plaintiff s di d establis h a prim a faci e case of discrimination, the court had to determine whether suc h discrimination coul d be justified unde r Par t 2 of Sectio n 1 5 (th e affirmative actio n exception ) o r unde r Sectio n 1 (th e exceptio n for rules that are reasonably and demonstrably justified i n a free and democrati c society) . Turning firs t t o th e affirmativ e actio n justification, th e Ontario cour t rejected th e argument tha t ther e was a close nexus between th e program an d the cause of the disadvantage, because the leave rule provided greater benefits tha n are necessar y i n th e grea t majorit y o f case s t o respon d t o th e physical disabilit y o f pregnancy . I n othe r words , th e progra m provided direc t financia l suppor t durin g famil y formation ,

60

Affirmative Actio n

which woul d b e a s usefu l t o biologica l parent s a s t o adoptiv e parents. The fact that the program had an ameliorative objectiv e did no t sav e i t unde r Par t 2 o f Sectio n 1 5 becaus e th e cour t found tha t th e allege d benefit wa s only a collateral effec t o f th e program. Th e primar y benefi t wa s providin g financia l suppor t during famil y formation . The analysi s o f Par t 2 was no t th e en d o f th e inquir y unde r Canadian constitutiona l law . Th e governmen t als o ha d th e opportunity t o defen d th e progra m a s reasonabl y an d demon strably justifie d i n a free an d democrati c society . Here , th e analysis focuse d o n th e goo d t o societ y o f th e progra m rathe r than o n th e discret e har m t o th e plaintiffs . A t thi s point , bot h the governmen t an d th e plaintiff s agree d tha t th e objective s o f the progra m wer e substantial—tha t th e child , family , an d soci ety benefite d fro m program s tha t facilitate d famil y formation . The governmen t argue d tha t cos t consideration s shoul d permi t it to limit t o biological familie s th e scop e of policies designe d t o facilitate famil y formation . Bu t th e cour t rejecte d thi s argu ment, statin g that cos t factors shoul d no t be given much weigh t under Sectio n 1. In the court's words: "If the government i s able to ge t awa y wit h violatin g a constitutionall y protecte d righ t because o f cos t consequences , o f wha t us e i s th e Charte r ?" Rather tha n star t fro m th e presumptio n o f laissez-fair e eco nomics, th e Canadia n cour t starte d fro m th e presumptio n tha t government interventio n i s appropriat e and , i n som e cases , should be mandated. The result o f this particular lega l challeng e was t o requir e th e governmen t t o exten d it s unemploymen t insurance benefits t o adoptive parents. Rather tha n strik e dow n an ameliorativ e progra m fo r biologica l mothers a s being incon sistent wit h affirmativ e actio n principles , i t extende d th e ame liorative progra m t o anothe r disadvantage d class . It sough t t o

Affirmative Actio n

61

maximize th e benefit s o f famil y suppor t program s fo r al l o f society while also guarding against unnecessary discrimination . The Canadia n experienc e show s tha t stat e intervention nee d not exclusivel y serv e th e interest s o f th e propertie d class . State intervention ca n instea d tr y t o overtur n a history o f discrimi nation agains t disadvantage d classe s i n society . Suc h interven tion i s accepte d no t simpl y becaus e i t assist s underprivilege d members o f societ y bu t becaus e i t serve s th e interest s o f al l of society fo r peopl e to achieve their huma n potential . By examining diverse areas of the law such as alumni preferenc e in admissio n t o educationa l institution s an d word-of-mout h recruitment i n employmen t settings , w e ca n uncove r value s that otherwis e migh t remai n hidden . Alumn i preference s fo r white childre n an d word-of-mout h recruitin g fo r whit e employees ar e practice s tha t hel p perpetuat e a clas s advantag e for a subgroup o f whites i n ou r societ y Despit e the inefficienc y of disruptin g th e meri t principl e b y limitin g th e applican t poo l or creatin g a two-tiered definitio n o f merit , thes e practice s ar e upheld a s praiseworthy. When black s try t o change th e rule s s o that they , too, can gain access to education o r employment, the y are tol d b y white s tha t the y ar e perpetuatin g stereotype s an d stigma through affirmativ e actio n or "quota madness/' It is time for white s t o examin e thei r ow n source s o f privilege d affirma tive action—from privat e schools to safe neighborhoods t o good nutrition—and as k whether thei r succes s i s reall y base d solel y on "merit/ ' Fo r la w t o be trul y colo r blind , we mus t locat e an d describe white privilege, not simply criticize modest attempts b y blacks to attempt t o eve n th e score .

3 DISABILITY DISCRIMINATIO N

Wall Street Journal columnis t Jame s Bovar d ridicule d th e Americans wit h Disabilitie s Ac t (ADA ) b y suggestin g tha t claustrophobia an d cocain e addictio n ar e covere d disabilities , invoking reasonabl e accommodatio n protection. 1 H e tell s a story of a motorist attempting to use claustrophobia as a defense for a seatbel t violatio n bu t fail s t o mentio n tha t th e motorist' s case wa s dismisse d an d brough t stron g negativ e commentar y from th e court. 2 Similarly , Bovar d report s tha t a hig h schoo l guidance counselo r use d th e AD A t o challeng e hi s cocaine related discharge , neglectin g t o mentio n tha t th e stat e cour t action3 di d no t (an d coul d not ) includ e a n ADA claim , becaus e the ADA exclude s curren t user s o f illega l drug s fro m statutor y coverage. Wall Street Journal reporte r Stephani e Meht a mad e the unfounde d accusatio n tha t "th e cos t o f [ADA ] complianc e

Disability Discriminatio n

63

has probabl y affecte d man y smal l busines s profi t margins/' 4 ignoring the fact that most private employers were already sub ject t o simila r standard s unde r stat e disabilit y discriminatio n law lon g before th e ADA wa s passed . A San Francisco Chronicle editoria l state d tha t th e ter m disability a s use d unde r th e ADA i s " a highl y questionabl e definitio n tha t fail s t o differen tiate betwee n peopl e i n wheelchair s an d junkies/' 5 plainl y ignoring th e statutor y definitio n o f a person wit h a disabilit y Law and economic s schola r Richar d Epstei n argue d tha t peo ple wit h disabilitie s woul d benefi t mor e fro m governmenta l noninterference tha n fro m disabilit y discriminatio n laws , stat ing, "Lik e everyon e else , the disable d shoul d b e allowe d t o sel l their labo r a t whateve r price , an d o n whateve r terms , the y se e fit/'6 Mandator y affirmativ e actio n o r reasonabl e accommoda tion requirements, he says, are ineffective an d unjustifiable tools . He describes the supporters of such remedial devices as " antilibertarian, antiutilitarian, an d antimarket i n their orientation." 7 Why thi s campaig n o f lie s an d distortions ? Wh y thi s onslaught agains t the ADA by some proponents o f law and economics? The simple answer is that vigorous enforcement o f disability discriminatio n la w stand s i n oppositio n t o laissez-fair e economics. Hence, the Wall Street Journal enlist s an y possibl e tactic t o undermin e th e public' s confidenc e i n th e ADA . Employing mor e rationa l arguments , th e supporter s o f a la w and economics perspective attemp t t o demonstrate tha t antidis crimination la w is inefficient an d unprincipled . Resistance t o state-sanctione d remedia l actio n o n behal f o f people with disabilities—and , i n essence, all members o f histor ically disadvantage d group s i n th e Unite d States—i s partl y a reflection o f a laissez-fair e economi c perspective . According t o free-market principles , the state should not requir e that th e pri -

64

Disability Discriminatio n

vate secto r us e preferentia l program s t o improv e th e employa bility o f member s o f disadvantage d group s becaus e ther e i s n o objective wa y t o determin e wh o i s historicall y disadvantage d and becaus e stat e interventio n i n privat e market s i s a n ineffi cient remed y fo r an y socia l problem . As applie d t o th e la w o f disabilit y discrimination , thi s per spective yield s tw o arguments . First , i t contend s tha t th e stat e should no t defin e on e subgroup—peopl e wit h disabilities—a s deserving special , statutor y protection . Second , i t assert s tha t the stat e shoul d no t mandat e reasonabl e accommodation s fo r people wit h disabilitie s becaus e suc h program s constitut e pref erential measures . The firs t argumen t i s mad e possibl e becaus e o f a distinctiv e feature o f disabilit y discriminatio n law . Rather tha n protectin g any person who can claim discrimination (includin g reverse discrimination) o n th e basi s o f disability , th e AD A protect s onl y those persons who qualify a s "person[s] with a disability/' There are no reverse discrimination claim s under th e ADA; the statut e recognizes claim s o f discriminator y treatmen t onl y b y person s with disabilities . Thi s featur e i s distinctiv e becaus e i t i s no t shared b y Title VII o f th e Civi l Right s Act o f 1964 . Under Titl e VII, anyon e ca n fil e a clai m o f discriminatio n o n th e basi s o f race, sex, national origin , o r religio n becaus e eac h perso n ha s a race, sex, national origin , an d religion . One doe s no t hav e t o b e a woma n o r racia l minorit y t o brin g a claim o f discrimination ; reverse discriminatio n claim s are cognizable by white men . The Title VI I approac h i s mor e consisten t wit h laissez-fair e princi ples than i s the ADA approach becaus e i t does not defin e a subgroup a s deservin g specia l statutor y protection . Laissez-fair e proponents thu s questio n th e legitimac y o f th e state' s deter mining tha t a particula r subgroup—peopl e wit h disabilities —

Disability Discriminatio n

65

deserve statutor y protectio n tha t i s no t availabl e t o other s i n society. The secon d argumen t i s mad e possibl e becaus e reasonabl e accommodations ar e reall y a type o f affirmativ e action . Propo nents o f disability discriminatio n la w have tried to hide this fac t by arguin g tha t reasonabl e accommodatio n doe s no t constitut e "affirmative action/ 7 Bu t i n fact , som e form s o f reasonabl e accommodation, suc h a s job restructurin g o r job reassignment , can b e considere d a type o f affirmativ e action . (Hence , law an d economics proponents ar e correct to consider reasonable accom modation t o b e a typ e o f affirmativ e action. ) Th e backlas h against these and other form s o f reasonable accommodation ca n theoretically b e tied to the backlash agains t race - and sex-base d affirmative action—a n attemp t t o us e laissez-fair e economi c arguments t o challeng e th e appropriatenes s o f mandate d pref erential measure s fo r an y subgrou p i n society . Whe n see n i n this light , th e stor y o f ho w th e courts , society , an d th e medi a have responde d t o th e la w o f disabilit y discriminatio n i n th e United State s furthe r illuminate s th e rol e of hypercapitalism i n attacking affirmativ e actio n principles . In th e Unite d States , hostility towar d affirmativ e actio n ha s grown greatl y i n th e las t decade , with lega l decision s followin g this politica l trend . I n th e las t decade , th e U.S . Supreme Cour t has foun d i n favo r o f whit e claimant s i n severa l recen t leadin g cases.8 Racism—o r th e denia l o f it s magnitude—i s th e typica l liberal explanation fo r thi s trend. Accordingly, Justice Thurgood Marshall chastise d the majority i n a reverse discrimination cas e for failin g t o acknowledg e th e relevanc e o f th e legac y o f dis crimination i n Richmond , Virginia , th e forme r capita l o f th e Confederacy: "A s muc h a s an y municipalit y i n th e Unite d States, Richmond knows what racial discrimination is ; a century

66

Disability Discriminatio n

of decision s b y thi s an d othe r federa l court s hav e richly docu mented th e city's disgraceful histor y o f public and private racia l discrimination." 9 Ignorin g thi s histor y th e Suprem e Cour t ruled that th e cit y of Richmond coul d not institut e a policy tha t gave preference t o contractors who promised to utilize minorit y subcontractors whe n workin g fo r th e cit y Although th e denia l o f racis m i s certainl y a facto r i n th e backlash t o affirmativ e action , i t i s no t th e onl y importan t explanation. Affirmativ e actio n an d laissez-fair e economic s stand in tension with eac h other. Free-market principle s conflic t with th e impositio n o f broad-based remedia l program s t o assis t members o f specified , historicall y disadvantage d groups . A s applied t o th e Americans wit h Disabilitie s Act, thes e principle s call fo r resistanc e t o reasonabl e accommodatio n measure s an d an unwillingnes s t o defin e a subgrou p i n societ y a s deservin g special statutor y protection . The varying commitment o f the United States, Great Britain , Canada, and Australia t o a pure laissez-faire mode l can also help us understand th e difference s i n their suppor t o f the law of disability discrimination . The Unite d State s an d Grea t Britai n ar e relatively mor e laissez-fair e (i n recen t times ) tha n ar e Canad a and Australia . Th e Unite d State s ha s neve r ha d a stron g labo r party, has no system o f nationalized healt h insurance , and has a relatively wea k labo r unio n movement . Grea t Britain' s Labou r Party only recently emerge d fro m twent y year s o f disfavor, an d the labor union movement i s still suffering fro m a sharp decline. Great Britai n doe s have nationalize d healt h insurance , but tha t fact ca n be tie d t o th e Labou r Party' s earlie r powe r rathe r tha n its current strengt h in British politics. In recent years, labor par ties i n Canad a an d Australi a hav e wo n majo r election s a t th e federal o r regiona l level . Th e Ne w Democrati c Part y wa s

Disability Discrimination

67

recently i n powe r i n Ontario , Canada , an d th e Libera l govern ment i s i n powe r a t th e federa l level . Australia's Labou r Part y recently ende d a n extende d perio d o f part y dominanc e a t th e federal level . Lik e Grea t Britain , Canad a an d Australi a hav e nationalized healt h insurance . Canad a als o has a small militar y and di d no t engag e i n th e col d war . I t ha s fa r les s hostil e rela tions wit h th e emergin g socialis t an d communis t regime s o f other countrie s tha n doe s th e Unite d State s o r Grea t Britain . The tw o countrie s wit h th e stronges t commitmen t t o laissez faire economics—Unite d State s an d Grea t Britain—ar e th e most resistan t t o what the y perceiv e t o be affirmative actio n o r special treatmen t (includin g reasonabl e accommodatio n fo r people with disabilities) . Admittedly, th e economi c distinction s amon g thes e fou r countries ar e small . Nonetheless , man y American s misunder stand th e dept h o f th e difference s i n philosoph y an d economic s between th e Unite d State s an d it s neighbor , Canada . As we wil l see, th e difference s betwee n America n an d Canadia n disabilit y jurisprudence ar e stark . This inquir y als o give s u s adde d insigh t int o th e connectio n between la w and politics. In the United States , the imposition o f reasonable accommodatio n requirement s unde r disabilit y dis crimination la w ha s ha d littl e effec t o n th e scop e o f protectio n for peopl e wit h disabilities . Lega l decision s imbue d i n laissez faire economic s hav e badly warpe d th e underlyin g structur e o f disability discriminatio n law . For example , although reasonabl e accommodation i s require d unde r U.S . law an d onl y permitte d under Canadia n law , the court s hav e mor e vigorousl y enforce d a reasonable accommodation requiremen t i n Canada than in th e United States . Of course , languag e i s no t entirel y meaningless . U.S . court s

Disability Discrimination

68

have ha d t o (reluctantly ) impos e som e reasonabl e accommoda tion requirement s an d have not been able to permit revers e discrimination suits , since able-bodied persons have no standing t o bring suit . Nonetheless , th e interpretatio n o f thes e statute s i s more a reflection o f th e politic s o f economic s tha n o f statutor y language.

Reasonable Accommodatio n a s Affirmative Actio n

Consider th e followin g si x related terms : • Nondiscriminatio n • Reasonabl e accommodatio n • Positiv e action • Preferentia l treatmen t • Affirmativ e actio n • Revers e discriminatio n These ar e their conventiona l definitions : Nondiscrimination reflect s th e remova l o f blatan t stereo types and prejudices s o that people can be treated based on their merit . Reasonable accommodation reflect s th e remova l o f barrier s that societ y ha s create d s o tha t qualifie d person s ca n demonstrate thei r merit . Preferential treatment, positive action, an d affirmative action reflect th e redefinition o f merit t o enable the trait s and abilitie s o f member s o f historicall y disadvantage d groups to be given greater value. Reverse discrimination reflect s the awarding of an automati c advantage t o a membe r o f a historicall y disadvantage d group s o tha t thi s perso n ca n hav e a greate r opportu nity o f being selecte d fo r a position.

Disability Discriminatio n

69

These term s describ e program s designe d t o improv e th e employability o f historicall y disadvantage d group s i n ou r soci ety. As we move acros s thes e categories , we move fro m genera l legal and social acceptance to legal and social disapproval. In par ticular, whether a program i s defined a s reasonable accommoda tion or affirmative actio n is often considere d to signal its acceptability o r legality . Fo r example , a s (British ) Professo r Bria n Doyle stated : "The idea of reasonable accommodatio n ha s ofte n been misunderstoo d an d mistake n a s a for m o f preferentia l treatment o r positiv e action . . . . The erroneou s associatio n o f reasonable accommodatio n wit h form s o f preferentia l treat ment, however , wil l b e a difficul t perceptio n t o eras e i n th e minds o f many employers." 10 Although Doyle' s statemen t ma y be politicall y expedien t (i n justifyin g reasonabl e accommoda tion rule s a t th e tim e o f a n affirmativ e actio n backlash) , i t i s technically incorrect . Affirmative actio n shoul d als o be consid ered t o be a type o f reasonabl e accommodation . An exampl e demonstrate s th e elusivenes s an d politica l sig nificance o f thes e categories . I n Johnson v. Transportation Agency,11 th e Suprem e Cour t considere d th e constitutionalit y of a promotion tha t was awarded in accordance with a n affirma tive actio n plan . Both Dian e Joyce and Pau l Johnson applie d fo r a promotio n fro m a roa d maintenanc e worke r t o a roa d dis patcher. Unti l 1975 , Joyc e ha d worke d i n th e traditionall y female jo b classificatio n o f accoun t clerk . When sh e applie d fo r a promotio n i n 197 4 t o a roa d dispatche r position , sh e wa s denied i t becaus e sh e ha d no t serve d i n th e traditionall y mal e job classificatio n o f roa d maintenanc e worker . The definitio n o f merit—experience a s a roa d maintenanc e worker—preclude d her fro m occupationa l advancement . I n 197 5 Joyc e the n trans ferred fro m a senio r accoun t cler k positio n t o a roa d mainte -

70 Disabilit

y Discriminatio n

nance worker in order to qualify fo r the dispatcher position. She was the first woman to fill the road maintenance position. While serving i n thi s position , sh e wa s initiall y no t issue d th e wor k clothes that were routinely issued to men, and she was describe d as a "rebel-rousing skirt-wearin g person/ ' Afte r servin g i n th e road maintenanc e positio n fo r fou r years , Joyc e applie d fo r a promotion t o roa d dispatcher . A majo r facto r i n th e selectio n process was an interview, conducted by three supervisors, two of whom ha d been involve d i n th e discriminator y incident s previ ously mentioned . Joyc e received a score o f 7 3 on th e interview . Paul Johnson , a ma n wit h les s roa d maintenanc e experience , received a scor e o f 7 5 o n th e intervie w an d wa s recommende d for th e promotion . When Joyc e learne d tha t Johnso n ha d bee n recommended fo r th e promotion , sh e contacte d th e affirmativ e action officer . Base d on the affirmative actio n officer' s interven tion, Joyce was promoted t o the position . Johnson the n challenge d Joyce' s promotio n a s violatin g hi s rights unde r Title VII of the Civi l Rights Act o f 1964 . A divide d Supreme Cour t rule d tha t th e promotio n di d no t violat e Titl e VII. Althoug h a majorit y o f th e Cour t conclude d tha t th e county ha d take n int o accoun t Joyce' s se x i n determinin g wh o should be awarded the promotion, it concluded tha t thi s explici t use of sex was appropriate because it followed a "moderate, flex ible, case-by-case approac h t o effectin g a gradual improvemen t in th e representatio n o f minoritie s an d women i n th e Agency' s work force. " In its statemen t o f the facts , the Cour t emphasize d the evidenc e that Joyc e had been a direct victim o f se x discrimi nation whil e servin g a s a road maintenanc e worker . On e coul d therefore vie w the intervention b y the affirmative actio n office r as simpl y ridding th e promotio n proces s o f explici t sex-base d discrimination.

Disability Discriminatio n

71

Justice Sandr a Da y O'Connor' s concurrenc e describe d th e selection proces s a s on e i n whic h Joyc e wa s give n a "plus " because of her se x but argue d tha t Joyce was not "automaticall y and blindly " promote d becaus e o f he r sex . O'Connor therefor e considered th e applicatio n o f th e affirmativ e actio n pla n i n thi s instance t o be an exampl e o f preferential treatmen t rathe r tha n reverse discrimination . I n a bitin g dissent , Justic e Antoni n Scalia, joined b y Justice s William Rehnquis t an d Byro n White , complained tha t a statute designed to establish a color-blind and gender-blin d workplace has thus been converted into a powerful engin e of racism an d sexism , no t merel y permitting intentiona l race and sex-base d discrimination , bu t ofte n makin g it , throug h operation of the legal system, practically compelled [T]h e only losers in the process are the Johnsons of the country, fo r whom Titl e VI I ha s bee n no t merel y repeale d bu t actuall y inverted. For the dissenters, this cas e was a classic example o f reverse dis crimination, i n which a male blue-collar worke r wa s th e victi m of a non-merit-based decision . These opinion s reflec t th e numerou s way s i n whic h a pro gram designe d t o improv e th e employabilit y o f wome n an d minorities ca n be described as a case of nondiscrimination, pref erential treatment, affirmative action , or reverse discrimination , depending o n one' s legal , economic , an d politica l perspective . The categorie s ar e arguabl y interchangeable , offerin g differen t ways for the state to require that private employers take steps to improve the employability o f historically disadvantaged groups . For example , a typical explanatio n i s tha t rathe r tha n prefer ential treatment, people with disabilitie s ofte n nee d accommoda -

72

Disability Discriminatio n

tions that remov e barriers a t the workplace: "Reasonable accom modation involves the making of modifications o r adjustments t o the employment proces s and to the workplace environment s o as to ensure that disable d persons are not discriminate d against , but may enjo y equa l opportunitie s wit h others/' 12 Thus , i f a work place has fiv e step s leading to the entrance , those step s become a barrier to employment fo r a person who uses a wheelchair. A reasonable accommodatio n woul d b e removin g th e barrie r (an d probably replacin g it with a ramp). But it would not resul t i n th e disabled person's being given a "plus" so that h e or she might b e hired ove r a n equall y qualified , nondisable d employee , which i s the common understandin g o f affirmative action . Affirmative actio n o n th e basi s o f rac e o r gender , however , can als o b e considere d withi n th e "remov e th e barrier " metaphor. Fo r example , som e citie s hav e modifie d thei r fire fighter selectio n examination s i n orde r t o giv e wome n o r minorities greate r opportunitie s t o obtai n employment; 13 school district s hav e modifie d thei r workplac e rule s i n orde r t o eliminate a barrie r t o minoritie s retainin g thei r job s durin g a layoff;14 an d counties , a s i n th e Johnson case , have disregarde d subjective criteri a i n orde r t o enhanc e women' s employmen t opportunities. Disabilit y accommodation s ma y ofte n requir e the remova l o f physica l barriers , bu t th e operationa l practic e under rac e and sex discrimination la w is analogous—modifyin g rules t o create equa l opportunit y whe n thos e rule s ar e no t nec essary t o the job. In fact , th e defense s availabl e t o employers i n reasonable accommodatio n case s ar e fundamentall y simila r t o the defense s availabl e t o employer s unde r th e busines s neces sity doctrin e develope d b y th e U.S . courts fo r disproportionat e impact case s in Griggs v. Duke Power 15 an d codifie d b y th e U.S. Congress in the 1991 Civil Rights Act.16 According to these the -

Disability Discriminatio n

73

ories, those rule s tha t operat e a s barriers t o employmen t mus t be modifie d i f the y canno t b e justifie d b y busines s necessit y The remova l o f thes e barrier s ca n b e describe d a s affirmativ e action o r reasonabl e accommodation . By considerin g reasonabl e accommodatio n t o b e a typ e o f affirmative action , we ca n bette r asses s th e source s o f th e lega l and politica l resistanc e t o affirmativ e actio n whe n a stereotypi cal "quota" syste m i s not a t issue . ( I use th e ter m stereotypical because I believe that race - and gender-base d affirmativ e actio n is often misunderstoo d b y the public. Since Regents of the University of California v. Bakke 17 wa s decided , quota s hav e bee n disfavored an d rarely used. Yet when I ask my student s to defin e "affirmative action, " "quotas " i s usuall y thei r firs t response. ) Courts sometime s rejec t claim s fo r reasonabl e accommodatio n as inappropriate request s fo r "affirmativ e action. " Conservativ e theorists fro m th e fiel d o f la w an d economic s ofte n d o no t dis tinguish betwee n reasonabl e accommodatio n an d affirmativ e action when arguin g that civi l rights law should be repealed; liberal theorist s als o hav e t o b e awar e o f th e connectio n betwee n these principles . Nonetheless, the equation o f reasonable accommodation wit h affirmative actio n i s particularl y controversia l becaus e reason able accommodatio n i s a term usuall y applie d onl y t o disabilit y cases. In th e Unite d States , however, affirmativ e actio n i s a ter m usually applie d onl y t o rac e an d gende r cases . This patter n doe s not exis t i n Canada . Instead , Canad a develope d th e principl e o f reasonable accommodatio n fo r religion , age, and pregnanc y dis crimination case s nearly a decade before this concept was applied to disability cases. The concept of reasonable accommodation als o exists in American la w for religiou s discrimination cases , but th e definition o f reasonabl e accommodatio n i s quite narrow , in par t

74

Disability Discriminatio n

because o f ou r antiestablishmen t clause. 18 An antiestablishmen t clause does not exis t in the Canadia n constitution . To understand th e concep t o f affirmativ e actio n i n th e lega l traditions of different countries , it is important to recognize tha t this ter m reflect s a particula r country' s determinatio n o f wh o has face d historica l discrimination . I n th e Unite d States , fo r example, we usually think o f racial discrimination whe n we discuss affirmativ e action . I n Canada , b y contrast , affirmativ e action discussion s ofte n focu s o n gende r equalit y issue s o r th e historical situatio n o f Nativ e Canadians . Race discriminatio n i s not th e primar y metaphor . Grea t Britai n doe s no t hav e a tradition o f affirmativ e actio n (o r a s th e Britis h cal l it , positive action) pertainin g t o race or gender. As we will see in chapter 4, however, afte r Worl d Wa r II , Great Britai n enacte d a n affirma tive quot a syste m fo r hirin g peopl e wit h disabilities . Thus i t i s too simplisti c to say that a country tha t doe s not adop t extrem e laissez-faire economi c view s accept s affirmativ e actio n fo r al l potentially disadvantage d group s i n it s society . Th e country' s attitude toward the appropriateness o f affirmative actio n is tempered by its historical understanding o f which group s in societ y have face d historica l discrimination .

United States Case La w INTRODUCTION

Disability discrimination la w is a new area of civil rights protection i n the United States . The movement fo r disabilit y right s i n the Unite d State s ha s bee n influence d b y th e movement s fo r civil rights o n th e basis o f rac e and sex , but it s model o f protec tion i s quite different : i t tolerate s preferentia l treatmen t exclu sively fo r member s o f a historically disadvantage d class .

Disability Discriminatio n

75

Preferential treatmen t fo r historicall y disadvantage d group s is legall y disfavore d unde r rac e an d se x antidiscriminatio n la w in th e Unite d States , but "revers e discrimination " claim s hav e virtually overtake n rac e an d gende r antidiscriminatio n law . Nearly all the cases on discrimination issue s decided by the U.S. Supreme Cour t i n th e las t severa l term s hav e been revers e dis crimination cases . In cas e afte r case , the Suprem e Cour t foun d for th e whit e plaintiff . B y contrast , mos t o f th e claim s brough t by women an d minorities wer e unsuccessful . Such development s mad e m e snidel y inquir e whethe r w e should objec t t o a Republica n Congress' s tryin g t o repea l antidiscrimination law , since in recent years, it rarely has serve d the interests of women o r minorities. 19 Ironically, Epstein woul d agree with m e tha t affirmativ e actio n migh t flouris h mor e eas ily i n th e absenc e o f antidiscriminatio n law , sinc e revers e dis crimination lawsuit s would no longer be recognized: "Were discrimination allowe d a s a matte r o f course , th e greates t victor y for th e civi l right s movemen t woul d b e t o se e it s ow n positio n prevail i n a n atmospher e wholl y free fro m an y threa t o f gov ernment coercion." 20 Epstei n doe s no t argu e tha t affirmativ e action itsel f i s a ba d idea ; rather , h e believe s tha t governmen t should no t impos e affirmativ e actio n o n th e privat e sector . Such preferentia l treatmen t i s ofte n calle d reverse discrimination. Titl e VI I o f th e Civi l Right s Ac t o f 196 4 say s tha t i t i s unlawful fo r a n employe r t o discriminat e agains t a n "individ ual" becaus e o f suc h individual' s race , color , religion , sex , o r national origin . Because we eac h hav e a "race" or "sex, " we ar e covered b y th e statute , regardles s o f whethe r w e ar e a histori cally disadvantage d rac e o r sex . Similarly , th e Fourteent h Amendment t o th e U.S . Constitution state s tha t n o stat e shal l "deny t o any person within it s jurisdiction th e equa l protectio n

76

Disability Discrimination

of th e laws/ ' Becaus e we eac h ar e "persons, " we ar e covere d b y the Constitutio n regardles s o f ou r particula r rac e o r sex . Rac e and se x antidiscriminatio n la w is therefore a n "antidifferentia tion" approac h rathe r tha n a n "antisubordination " approach. 21 As a n antidifferentiatio n approach , it seek s t o eliminat e al l distinctions o n th e basi s o f rac e an d se x rathe r tha n t o respon d t o the need s o f historically disadvantage d groups . By contrast , disabilit y discriminatio n la w require s preferen tial treatmen t throug h reasonabl e accommodation . Th e AD A defines a "qualified individua l wit h a disability" who is entitle d to nondiscrimination protectio n t o include "an individual with a disability who , with, or without reasonabl e accommodatio n ca n perform th e essentia l function s o f th e employmen t positio n that suc h individua l hold s o r desires. " It doe s not tr y t o requir e only neutral nondiscrimination. It is embedded in an antisubor dination rathe r tha n a n antidifferentiatio n approach . It seeks t o improve th e employabilit y o f a historicall y disadvantage d group—people wit h disabilities—rathe r tha n t o eliminat e al l disability distinction s fro m society . The class of people protected unde r rac e and sex antidiscrim ination la w and disability discrimination la w is also quite differ ent. Title VI I doe s no t limi t coverag e t o member s o f a histori cally disadvantage d group . Any individual ca n brin g a lawsui t under rac e an d se x antidiscriminatio n law . In a n earl y case , th e Supreme Cour t decide d tha t thi s individua l coul d b e a whit e man wh o was claiming "reverse" discrimination. 22 Thus, nearl y any individual who has an employment relationshi p with a covered employer ca n bring suit under rac e and sex antidiscrimina tion law . Disability discriminatio n law , however , allow s onl y thos e individuals wh o ar e "qualifie d individual s wit h disabilities " t o

Disability Discriminatio n

77

file a claim o f discrimination . A qualifie d individua l wit h a disability i s a n "individua l wit h a disability wh o satisfie s th e req uisite skill , experience, education an d othe r job-related require ments o f th e employmen t positio n suc h individua l hold s o r desires, an d who , wit h o r withou t reasonabl e accommodation , can perform th e essential functions o f the job/' To be considere d disabled, a person typically must demonstrat e tha t he or she has an impairment tha t substantially limit s a major lif e activity. The term disability mean s (1 ) a physical o r mental impairmen t tha t substantially limit s on e o r mor e o f a n individual' s majo r lif e activities o r (2 ) a recor d o f suc h a n impairmen t o r (3 ) bein g regarded a s havin g suc h a n impairment . Claim s o f discrimina tion ar e therefor e availabl e onl y t o member s o f a historicall y disadvantaged group ; there i s no suc h thin g a s a "reverse" dis crimination disabilit y claim . Although disabilit y discriminatio n la w explicitl y incorpo rates a n antisubordinatio n approach , an d rac e an d se x discrimi nation la w formall y favo r a n antidifferentiatio n approach , bot h areas o f American la w favor th e antidifferentiatio n approac h i n practice. Courts in th e United State s have undermined th e pref erential treatmen t principle s underlyin g disabilit y discrimina tion law , despit e th e clea r statutor y languag e t o th e contrary . They als o hav e narrowe d th e categor y o f potentia l claimant s entitled t o statutor y protection . Becaus e th e statut e doe s no t permit a n evenhande d approac h i n whic h al l individual s ca n claim disabilit y discrimination , th e court s hav e ha d t o under mine th e exclusiv e focu s o n peopl e wit h disabilitie s b y drasti cally limiting the scop e of that class . Only a small subset o f people with disabilitie s ar e eligibl e fo r th e statute' s antisubordina tion protection . On e ca n therefor e fin d a commo n anti affirmative actio n threa d runnin g throug h bot h disabilit y an d

78

Disability Discrimination

race and sex antidiscrimination la w in the United States , despite the differin g statutor y language . REASONABLE ACCOMMODATION CAS E LAW

Title I of th e ADA protect s agains t employmen t discriminatio n of " qualified individual s wit h a disability/' A " qualified individ ual wit h a disability" is a person wit h a disability wh o "wit h o r without reasonabl e accommodatio n ca n perfor m th e essentia l functions o f th e employmen t positio n suc h individua l hold s o r desires." Th e ter m reasonable accommodation include s "reas signment t o a vacan t position. " Th e controvers y surroundin g whether th e AD A i s a n "affirmativ e action " statut e ha s some times centere d o n tha t requirement . What priorit y fo r example , might a person wit h a disability be entitle d t o ove r peopl e seek ing th e sam e position ? Wha t obligatio n doe s a n employe r hav e to facilitat e tha t reassignment ? T o th e exten t tha t th e AD A i s interpreted t o require affirmativ e actio n suc h as priority consid eration fo r a reassignment, i t conflicts wit h hypercapitalism . To understan d th e possibl e scop e o f th e reassignmen t requirement, on e firs t mus t understan d i t i n th e contex t o f th e ADA. The reasonable accommodation concep t is part of the def inition o f a qualified individua l with a disability Fo r example, if individual A ha s insulin-dependen t diabetes , tha t individua l usually i s considere d a perso n wit h a disabilit y I f th e perso n were seeking a job as a secretary he or she might have to reques t periodic breaks durin g th e da y t o tak e insuli n injections . Thos e periodic breaks woul d b e a "reasonable accommodation. " Sinc e the individua l coul d perfor m th e jo b wit h tha t reasonabl e accommodation, h e or she becomes a qualified individua l with a disability Havin g met the criteria for a qualified individua l wit h a disability , th e perso n i s als o entitle d t o th e statute' s nondis -

Disability Discriminatio n

79

crimination protections . The employe r coul d not , fo r example , fire al l insulin-dependent diabetic s (despit e thei r abilit y t o per form th e jo b wit h a reasonabl e accommodation ) an d retai n everyone else . But now let us assume tha t th e employer' s need s chang e afte r the insulin-dependen t diabeti c i s hire d a s a secretary . Thes e changes mea n tha t th e diabeti c will no longe r b e able to take th e breaks that are essential to his or her safe functioning a t the workplace. No reasonabl e accommodation s a t tha t particula r worksit e are possible to allow the person to be a qualified individua l with a disability at his or her current job classification. According to Title I of the ADA, the employer nonetheless has an obligation to make the reasonable accommodation o f " reassignment t o a vacant position/' Thi s obligatio n i s no t define d a s a nondiscriminatio n requirement but as a reasonable accommodation requirement . The differenc e betwee n a nondiscriminatio n requiremen t and a reasonable accommodatio n requiremen t i s relevant t o th e concept o f affirmativ e action . I f th e dut y t o reassig n a n employee t o a vacan t positio n wer e a nondiscrimination requirement, th e employe r coul d no t discriminat e agains t th e secretary seekin g t o b e reassigne d afte r h e o r sh e become s unqualified fo r hi s or her presen t position . The secretar y woul d be give n equa l priorit y wit h othe r incumben t employee s wh o sought reassignment . Bu t i f reassignmen t i s a reasonable accommodation, the n th e employer' s obligatio n i s mor e tha n nondiscrimination; it must be an affirmative attemp t to reassig n the employe e t o a vacant position. The scop e of that affirmativ e obligation, however, is not specifie d i n th e regulation s o r inter pretive guidance , so it is unclear . The case s construin g th e reassignmen t requiremen t hav e often restate d th e requirement a s if it were a nondiscriminatio n

Disability Discrimination

80

rather tha n a reasonabl e accommodatio n requirement . Fo r example, i n Daugherty v. City of El Paso, 13 th e Fift h Circui t found tha t th e city' s failur e t o reassig n a n insulin-dependen t diabetic to another position on the city payroll did not violate its reasonable accommodatio n obligatio n unde r th e ADA , "absen t evidence that the city treated the employee differently fro m an y other part-tim e employe e whos e jo b wa s eliminated/ ' Thi s holding, i n fact , relie d o n a misstatement o f th e actua l facts i n Daugherty. Daugherty' s jo b wa s no t "eliminated" ; rather , Daugherty wa s discharge d fro m hi s job whe n hi s diabete s ren dered hi m unqualifie d t o compl y wit h Departmen t o f Trans portation rule s fo r bu s drivers . Becaus e h e ha d no t bee n dis charged for cause , he sought t o take advantage of the reasonabl e accommodation/reassignment rul e jus t described . Th e cour t described his situation as a job "elimination" in order to hide the disability aspect s of his case. In rulin g agains t Daughert y o n th e reassignmen t issue , th e court distinguishe d betwee n nondiscriminatio n an d affirmativ e action: Stated anothe r way , w e d o no t rea d th e AD A a s requirin g affirmative actio n i n favo r o f people with disabilities , i n th e sense o f requirin g tha t disable d person s be given priorit y i n hiring o r reassignmen t ove r thos e wh o ar e no t disabled . I t prohibits employmen t discriminatio n agains t qualifie d indi viduals with disabilities , no more and no less. The court overlooke d th e fact tha t th e reassignment/reasonabl e accommodation rul e i s a rule regardin g priorit y consideration . Similarly, in Fussell v. Georgia Ports Authority,24 th e distric t court conclude d tha t th e defendant s di d no t violat e th e AD A when they failed to tell the plaintiff abou t an opening in anothe r

Disability Discrimination

81

department, fo r whic h h e ma y hav e bee n qualified , withi n ninety day s o f hi s disability-relate d discharge . Th e cour t granted th e defendant' s motio n fo r summar y judgment , con cluding that no further factua l inquir y was needed to assess lia bility, because it construed the reassignment/ reasonabl e accom modation rul e t o require n o priority consideration . In bot h cases , the court s glosse d ove r th e fac t tha t th e reas signment rul e i s containe d i n th e reasonabl e accommodatio n section o f th e statute . The courts , however , di d conten d tha t i t was the plaintiffs' lawyers , not the courts, who were misreadin g the ADA. As the Fussell cour t declared , [It i s doubtful ] whethe r Congress , i n it s wildes t dream s o r wildest nightmares , intende d t o tur n ever y garde n variet y worker's compensation clai m into a federal case... . [0]n e of the primar y beneficiarie s o f [th e ADA] will be trial lawyer s who will ingeniously manipulate [th e ADA's] ambiguities t o consistently broade n it s coverag e s o that federa l court s ma y become mire d i n employmen t injur y cases , becomin g littl e more than glorified worker' s compensatio n referees. 25 But th e Fussell court , lik e th e Daugherty court , mad e mis leading statements in order to arrive at its conclusion. The para graph fro m it s opinion just quoted was taken from anothe r case, Pedigo v. P.A.M. Transport, Inc., 26 an d was taken completel y ou t of context . I n Pedigo, th e plaintif f wa s a truc k drive r unti l h e suffered a heart attack and underwent a n angioplasty procedure . He wa s terminate d whil e o n medica l leave . The jury foun d fo r the plaintiff becaus e it concluded that the defendant ha d not sufficiently attempte d t o accommodat e hi m b y reassignin g hi m t o a vacant position. (Everyone agree d that h e was no longer qual ified to drive an over-the-road truck. ) After th e jury rule d in th e

82

Disability Discriminatio n

plaintiffs favor , th e defendan t aske d th e cour t t o overtur n th e verdict because the evidenc e was insufficient a s a matter o f law. As recite d b y th e Fussell court , th e distric t cour t i n Pedigo di d suggest tha t th e AD A wa s no t servin g th e publi c interes t through it s reassignment requirement . Nonetheless , after care fully examinin g th e legislativ e history , th e Pedigo cour t con cluded tha t Congres s di d inten d t o requir e reassignmen t a s a reasonable accommodation . The Fussell cour t quote d Pedigo ou t o f contex t t o conclud e that court s shoul d narrowl y constru e th e reassignmen t rule . The Pedigo cour t mad e thi s statemen t i n th e contex t o f a rea sonable accommodation/reassignmen t case in whic h i t rule d i n favor o f th e plaintiff . Afte r examinin g th e legislativ e histor y under th e ADA , th e Pedigo cour t ultimatel y decided : "[I] t appears that legislative history indicates that Congres s intende d to com e dow n o n th e sid e o f th e administrativ e agencie s whic h generally require d th e employe r t o conside r reassignment , rather than on the side of the federal court s which had generall y denied that th e employe r wa s obligate d t o d o so." 27 The Fussell court relie d o n a deceptive citatio n t o rule otherwise . Many court s ar e therefor e construin g th e AD A t o eras e th e reassignment/reasonable accommodatio n rule . Rathe r tha n debate th e prope r scop e o f th e reassignmen t requirement , the y are pretending tha t th e requiremen t doe s not exis t a t all . This is being done in the name of not making the ADA into an affirma tive action statute. As we will see, Canada and Australia are more generous i n interpreting thi s requirement i n their statutes . SCOPE O F COVERAG E

Introduction. Becaus e disabilit y discriminatio n la w explicitl y requires reasonable accommodation, courts cannot dismantle it s

Disability Discriminatio n

83

affirmative actio n element s entirely . Bu t on e techniqu e tha t they ca n us e t o limi t th e scop e o f th e disabilit y discriminatio n law's affirmativ e actio n potentia l i s t o limi t th e scop e o f claimants permitte d t o brin g suit . Thus , a s w e wil l see , th e United State s an d Grea t Britai n emplo y a muc h narrowe r understanding o f wh o ca n brin g sui t fo r disabilit y discrimina tion than d o Canada and Australia. These differences ar e consistent wit h thei r differin g version s o f capitalism . Two interpretation s o f th e AD A hav e helpe d achiev e a nar row understanding o f who ca n bring a disability discriminatio n claim. First, some courts have used an exceedingly stringen t tes t to determin e whethe r a person ha s a substantial limitatio n i n a major lif e activity . In particular , the y hav e use d a stringent tes t when the major lif e activity that is limited is the ability to work. Second, som e court s hav e adopte d a ver y restrictiv e tes t t o determine whethe r th e impairmen t i s sufficientl y substantial . They hav e evaluated th e substantialit y o f the limitation after — rather tha n before—a perso n has used mitigating measures (fo r example, medication , eyeglasses , hearin g aid , wheelchair) . Th e first narro w interpretation i s arguably supporte d by the regula tory languag e unde r th e ADA , bu t th e secon d interpretatio n flatly contradict s th e regulations . Substantial Limitation in the Life Activity of Working. Th e ADA typically provide s coverag e fo r a person wh o ca n demon strate that he or she is substantially limite d in a major lif e activ ity. Fe w would disagre e tha t "working " i s a major lif e activity , but th e requiremen t o f proof o f a substantial limitatio n fo r thi s major lif e activit y is more rigorou s than fo r th e othe r lif e activ ities specified i n the regulations: "caring for oneself , performin g manual tasks , walking , seeing , hearing , speaking , breathing ,

84

Disability Discrimination

[and] learning/ ' Th e genera l regulatio n fo r substantia l limita tion i s that th e person i s unable t o perform a major lif e activit y tha t th e averag e per son i n th e genera l populatio n ca n perform ; o r significantl y restricted a s t o th e condition , manne r o r duratio n unde r which an individual can perform a particular major lif e activity as compared t o the condition, manner , o r duration unde r which the averag e person i n the general population ca n per form tha t sam e major lif e activity . With respec t t o th e lif e activit y o f working , th e regulation s promulgated b y th e Equa l Employmen t Opportunit y Commis sion (EEOC ) contai n a n additiona l requirement : The ter m substantiall y limit s mean s significantl y restricte d in the ability to perform eithe r a class of jobs or a broad range of jobs i n various classe s a s compared t o th e averag e perso n having comparable training, skills and abilities. The inability to perform a single, particular job does not constitut e a substantial limitation i n the major lif e activity of working. As a n exampl e o f th e applicatio n o f thi s rule , th e Interpretiv e Guidance explain s tha t a professiona l basebal l pitche r wh o ha s developed a bad elbow would be precluded from bringing a lawsuit under th e ADA when h e is no longer abl e to perform thi s highl y specialized job. Common sens e might sugges t that when a person with extraordinar y physica l aptitud e becomes disabled s o that h e can no longer perform a t an extraordinaril y hig h leve l of compe tence, he should be not be able to use the ADA to be characterize d as "disabled/7 The EEOC therefore carved out this special rule with respect t o th e lif e activit y o f workin g t o achiev e thi s result , although th e statut e doe s no t specif y tha t "working " shoul d b e treated differently tha n othe r covere d major lif e activities.

Disability Discriminatio n

85

The EEOC , however, di d no t hav e t o promulgate thi s specia l rule t o reac h tha t intende d result . Th e AD A doe s no t exten d protection t o al l individual s wit h disabilities , onl y t o qualified individuals with disabilities . If two people are applying fo r a job as a professional basebal l pitche r an d on e person ha s a n injure d elbow tha t preclude s hi m fro m pitching , th e AD A woul d con clude tha t h e wa s no t a qualified individua l wit h a disabilit y (under th e assumptio n tha t n o reasonabl e accommodatio n would make him otherwis e qualified). One would not even hav e to appl y th e majo r lif e activit y o f workin g rul e t o exclud e hi m from statutor y coverage . Bu t i f h e wer e alread y workin g a s a baseball pitche r whe n h e injure d hi s elbow , then i t i s tru e tha t the reassignment/reasonabl e accommodatio n rul e woul d oper ate. Without th e specia l majo r lif e activit y rule , a baseball tea m might hav e to consider whether th e pitcher coul d work a t othe r positions o r in th e fron t offic e befor e dischargin g hi m fro m th e organization. Th e majo r lif e activit y rule , however , eliminate s the nee d t o appl y th e reassignment/reasonabl e accommodatio n rule, becaus e th e perso n i s exclude d fro m th e definitio n o f a n individual with a disability. Like th e reassignment/reasonabl e accommodatio n rule , th e major lif e activit y o f working rul e is particularly detrimenta l t o the job securit y o f incumben t employees . The court s hav e als o interpreted thi s requiremen t harshl y t o preclude man y incum bent employee s fro m obtainin g th e benefit s o f disabilit y dis crimination law . For example , in Bolton v. Scrivner, 28 th e cour t awarded summar y judgmen t t o th e defendant s becaus e th e plaintiff faile d t o produce evidenc e tha t h e coul d no t perfor m a class of jobs. Bolton wa s no t a baseball pitcher ; he was a n orde r selector i n a grocer y warehous e befor e h e suffere d a work related injur y t o hi s feet . Although i t i s possible tha t a reason -

86

Disability Discriminatio n

able accommodatio n migh t hav e permitte d Bolto n t o perfor m his job, the court of appeals ruled that the district court was cor rect i n holdin g tha t "Bolton' s inabilit y t o retur n t o hi s particu lar jo b withou t som e accommodatio n doe s no t demonstrat e a substantial limitatio n i n th e majo r lif e activit y o f working/' H e was exclude d fro m th e definitio n o f a n individua l wit h a dis ability an d therefor e wa s no t entitle d t o reasonabl e accommo dation protection. Other person s who sought o r held low-statu s jobs hav e bee n denie d statutor y coverag e unde r suc h reason ing.29 B y relyin g o n th e specia l requiremen t fo r th e majo r lif e activity of working, the courts have been abl e to avoid the mor e probing questio n o f whethe r a reasonabl e accommodatio n might hav e permitted thes e people to maintain thei r jobs. Use of Mitigating Measures. Mitigating measures ar e assistiv e devices (lik e a hearing aid , medication, wheelchair ) tha t peopl e use to lessen th e effect s o f thei r disabilitie s o n thei r dail y func tioning. A n interpretiv e questio n unde r disabilit y discrimina tion law is how one should determine whether a n individual has a "substantia l impairmen t o f a majo r lif e activity, " thereb y meeting th e definitio n o f a n individua l wit h a disability befor e or after th e use of mitigating measures. A broad definition o f a n individual wit h a disabilit y woul d asses s th e degre e o f impair ment before mitigatin g measure s ar e used , wherea s a narro w definition woul d asses s the degre e of impairment after mitigat ing measures ar e used . Because th e AD A i s silen t o n thi s question , i t ha s bee n resolved throug h EEO C regulation s an d judicial decisions . The EEOC ha s promulgate d a broa d rule : "Th e determinatio n o f whether a n individua l i s substantiall y limite d i n a majo r lif e activity mus t b e made o n a case by cas e basis, without regar d t o

Disability Discriminatio n

87

mitigating measures such as medicines, or assistive or prostheti c devices/' Th e EEO C offer s n o furthe r guidanc e o r example s regarding thi s rule . As w e wil l see , som e court s hav e rejecte d this broad rule . Whether th e substantialit y o f th e limitatio n i s determine d before mitigatin g measures ar e used has important implication s for th e breadth o f statutor y coverage . Let us assume , for exam ple, that a person work s a t a company tha t ha s a strict rul e gov erning employe e breaks . An employe e ha s on e fifteen-minut e break i n th e morning , on e hal f hou r a t lunchtime , an d on e fif teen-minute brea k in the afternoon . Le t us furthe r assum e tha t an insulin-dependen t diabeti c employe e canno t complet e dur ing thes e break s al l th e monitorin g an d intak e o f foo d an d insulin require d fo r hi m o r he r t o avoi d diabeti c symptoms . I f we measure d th e substantialit y o f th e impairmen t befor e th e use of mitigating measures, this person would obviousl y be disabled. H e o r sh e woul d the n b e abl e t o reques t a reasonabl e accommodation t o facilitat e th e injectio n o f insulin . Bu t i f w e viewed th e employe e afte r th e us e o f mitigatin g measure s (although i t i s not eve n possibl e t o use mitigating measure s o n that job) , h e o r sh e migh t no t hav e a n opportunit y t o see k a modest reasonabl e accommodation . The appropriateness o f the EEOCs rul e has repeatedly arise n in case s involvin g peopl e wit h insulin-dependen t diabetes. 30 I n several recen t cases , the court s hav e rejecte d th e EEOC s miti gating measure s rul e an d foun d tha t th e plaintiff s ha d t o plac e facts int o evidenc e regardin g th e substantialit y o f their impair ment afte r th e us e o f mitigatin g measures. 31 I n on e o f thes e cases, th e cour t di d no t eve n permi t th e introductio n o f mor e evidence afte r th e plaintif f relie d o n th e EEO C guideline s fo r support tha t insulin-dependen t diabetic s ar e pe r se disable d

88

Disability Discriminatio n

because o f thei r dependenc e o n insuli n i n orde r t o function . Rather, th e cour t hel d tha t th e plaintif f ha d no t demonstrate d that h e wa s disabled. 32 I n futur e cases , when plaintiff s ar e o n notice that such evidence is necessary, the courts will have raised their litigation cost s by making them pu t medical facts int o evi dence. The rejectio n o f th e mitigatin g measure s rul e i s jus t on e more attemp t t o limi t th e categor y o f peopl e wh o ca n brin g claims unde r th e ADA . Rathe r tha n decid e whethe r the y gen uinely hav e claim s o f discrimination—an d man y o f the m appeared to have very strong claims—the courts have closed th e door o f litigatio n i n thei r face . N o othe r countr y ha s adopte d such a narrow mitigatin g measure s rule . Other Narrowing Devices. Th e ADA also narrows it s statutor y scope throug h mor e direc t methods—b y mean s o f statutor y exclusions. Title V o f th e AD A list s thos e condition s tha t ar e specifically exclude d fro m coverage : homosexuality, bisexual ity, transvestism , transsexualism , pedophilia , exhibitionism , voyeurism, gender identit y disorder s not resultin g fro m phys ical impairments, othe r sexua l behavio r disorders , compulsiv e gambling, kleptomania , pyromania , psychoactiv e substanc e use disorder s resultin g fro m th e curren t illega l us e o f drugs , and curren t illega l us e o f drugs . I n addition , alcoholic s ca n obtain onl y limite d statutor y coverage . Impairment s ar e cov ered onl y i f they ar e "substantial " an d have a long-term effec t on a person's life : "Advanced age , physical o r personality char acteristics, an d environmental , cultural , an d economi c disad vantages ar e not impairments. " Both Canad a an d Australia ar e much les s restrictiv e i n th e lis t o f disabilitie s covere d b y thei r statutes.

Disability Discriminatio n 8

9

Canada REASONABLE ACCOMMODATION CAS E LAW

The Canadia n constitutio n explicitl y recognize s an d protect s affirmative action , and th e Canadia n Huma n Right s Act explic itly mention s tha t affirmativ e actio n i s permitted : It i s no t a discriminator y practic e fo r a perso n t o adop t o r carry out a special program, plan or arrangement designe d to prevent disadvantage s tha t ar e likely to be suffered by , or t o eliminate o r reduc e advantage s tha t ar e suffere d by , an y group o f individual s whe n thos e disadvantage s woul d b e o r are based on or related to the . .. disabilit y of members of that group by improving opportunities respecting goods, services, facilities, accommodatio n o r employmen t i n relatio n t o tha t group.33 Provincial legislatio n als o contain s simila r protection . Thi s language protect s affirmativ e actio n program s fro m "revers e discrimination" challenges. Section 14(1) of the Ontario Huma n Rights Act, fo r example , provides tha t a n equalit y righ t i s "no t infringed b y th e implementatio n o f a special program designe d to relieve hardship or economic disadvantage or assist disadvan taged person s o r group s t o achiev e o r attemp t t o achiev e equa l opportunity o r tha t i s likely t o contribut e t o the eliminatio n o f the infringemen t o f right s unde r Par t I. " The Ontari o Cour t o f Appeal interpreted thes e provisions to mean tha t a "reverse discrimination" clai m canno t b e mad e unde r Canadia n law , although on e could challenge a disability affirmative actio n program fo r discriminatin g agains t anothe r disadvantage d group. 34 Ironically, however , th e Canadia n disabilit y discriminatio n statute (whic h i s part o f it s genera l huma n right s statute ) doe s

90

Disability Discriminatio n

not explicitly require reasonable accommodation. That duty was impliedly foun d t o exis t i n th e 1980 s i n case s involvin g reli gious, age, and pregnancy discrimination. 35 Despit e the absenc e of a n explici t statutor y requiremen t t o reasonabl y accommo date, Canadian courts have been more generous than U.S. courts in interpretin g th e reasonabl e accommodation/reassignmen t rule i n case s involving disabilit y discrimination . Reflecting o n the federa l disabilit y discriminatio n legislatio n in Canada , Bria n Doyl e describe d th e scop e o f reasonabl e accommodation mor e narrowl y tha n I did: "Although employ ers ar e permitte d t o tak e specia l actio n t o prevent , eliminat e o r reduce disadvantag e face d b y disable d individual s i n employ ment opportunities , thi s provide s blessin g onl y t o voluntaril y conceded reasonabl e accommodation/' 36 Relyin g o n religiou s discrimination cas e law involving the duty of reasonable accom modation fro m th e Unite d States , Doyl e speculate d tha t th e Canadian court s wil l interpre t th e reasonabl e accommodatio n requirement narrowl y i n th e disabilit y context . Th e religiou s cases from th e United States , however, offer th e courts very dif ferent problem s because o f their specia l constitutional status . In the Unite d States , th e court s hav e resiste d importin g th e reli gious reasonabl e accommodatio n ruling s int o disabilit y dis crimination law . An illuminating exampl e of the liberal Canadian approach t o reasonable accommodatio n i s R e Province of Manitoba and Manitoba Government Employees' Union. 37 A unio n file d a grievance regardin g a n employee' s righ t t o b e reassigne d afte r he wa s n o longe r abl e t o perfor m th e dutie s o f hi s position . (The applicabl e Huma n Right s Cod e state s tha t discriminatio n means th e "failur e t o mak e reasonabl e accommodatio n fo r th e special need s o f an y individua l o r group , if thos e specia l need s

Disability Discriminatio n

91

are based upon an y [disability ] characteristic/') 38 The grievant , Mr. Ulasy, became disable d an d was informed tha t h e would b e given priorit y consideratio n fo r othe r vacan t position s i n th e civil service . Bot h th e plaintif f an d th e defendan t agree d tha t reassignment a s a for m o f affirmativ e actio n wa s appropriate , so the disput e centere d o n th e scop e o f tha t preferentia l treat ment. Althoug h th e defendan t governmen t ha d interviewe d the grievan t fo r severa l positions, the arbitrato r conclude d tha t further step s t o accommodat e hi m wer e required . The arbitra tor require d th e defendant s t o conduct a more up-to-date med ical assessment o f the plaintiffs abilitie s to perform job-relate d tasks, wit h consideratio n give n t o medica l rehabilitatio n o r retraining; t o loo k a t necessar y modification s o f jo b position s before th e plaintiff' s intervie w fo r a particular position ; an d t o consider a trial period fo r a new position t o assess whether th e plaintiff wa s qualifie d t o perfor m it . The arbitrato r conclude d that suc h proposal s migh t allo w th e plaintif f t o compet e o n a more "leve l playin g field/ ' I n othe r words , affirmativ e actio n would creat e equa l opportunity . Thi s case i s reflectiv e o f Canada's libera l approac h t o th e reassignmen t rule.

39

Although reassignmen t i s not liste d in the Canadia n statut e a s an exampl e o f reasonabl e accommodation , arbitrator s hav e gone quit e fa r i n dictatin g o f what th e dut y consists , as long a s it i s no t a n undu e hardship . Althoug h require d b y statut e t o consider reassignmen t a s a reasonabl e accommodation , th e American court s hav e offere d a much narrowe r interpretatio n of tha t rule . SCOPE O F STATUTOR Y COVERAG E

The coverag e o f peopl e wit h disabilitie s i s muc h broade r i n Canada tha n i n th e Unite d States . Fo r example , th e Ontari o

92

Disability Discriminatio n

Human Right s Code , which include s protectio n agains t handi cap discrimination , doe s no t contai n th e "substantia l impair ment" languag e foun d i n America n law . The Canadia n statut e defines "becaus e o f handicap " to includ e a person wh o has , has had, or is believed t o have ha d any degree of physical disability, infirmity, malformatio n o r disfigurement tha t is caused by bodily injury, birt h defec t o r illness—a conditio n o f menta l retardatio n o r impairment , a learning disabilit y o r a dysfunctio n i n on e o r mor e o f th e processes involvin g i n understandin g o r usin g symbol s o r spoken language, a mental disorder, or an injury o r disability for which benefits wer e claimed or received under the Workers' Compensatio n Act. 40 (This languag e i s in direc t contras t t o the American court s tha t have resiste d makin g th e ADA into a n expande d worker's com pensation statute. ) Th e "an y degree " language i s much broade r than th e "substantia l impairmen t o f a major lif e activity " lan guage foun d i n America n law . Similarly, th e Canadia n Huma n Rights Ac t quit e broadl y define s peopl e wit h a disabilit y an d specifically list s "previou s o r existin g dependenc e o n alcoho l o r a drug." 41 In addition , th e Ontari o cod e specificall y list s disabilitie s included unde r tha t definition : "diabete s mellitus , epilepsy, an y degree o f paralysis , amputation , lac k o f physica l coordination , blindness o r visua l impairment , deafnes s o r hearin g impedi ment, muteness o r speech impediment, or physical reliance on a guide do g o r o n a wheelchai r o r othe r remedia l applianc e o r device." Obviously, insulin-dependen t diabetic s ca n obtai n cov erage under the Ontario statute. There is also little question tha t

Disability Discrimination

93

the issu e o f whether on e is handicapped i s measured before th e use of mitigating measure s becaus e a dependence o n mitigatin g measures make s on e disabled . Not surprisingly , th e cas e la w i n Ontari o reflect s thi s broa d definition. On e arbitrato r presume d tha t a person wh o suffer s from kleptomani a woul d b e covere d b y th e law,

42

wherea s

another arbitrato r conclude d tha t a n alcoholi c wa s covere d b y the Ontari o statut e b y referrin g t o th e mor e specifi c languag e from th e Canadia n Huma n Right s Act concernin g th e coverag e of alcoholics. 43

Great Britai n REASONABLE ACCOMMODATION CAS E LAW

In Great Britain, affirmative actio n (or what is usually called positive action) i s not currentl y a well-favored principl e i n th e are a of race or gender discrimination . Thus, the concept of reasonabl e accommodation i s narrowl y define d unde r Grea t Britain' s ne w disability discriminatio n legislation . Grea t Britain' s fifty-yea r statutory quot a system, in which employers were obliged by law to maintain a 3 percent quot a o f people with disabilitie s i n thei r workforces, was repealed when the antidiscrimination provision s of Part 2 of the new disability discrimination statute s too k effec t in 1996. 44 It i s to o earl y t o kno w ho w th e court s wil l interpre t th e recently enacte d disabilit y rule s i n Grea t Britain , bu t i t doe s appear that the statute presumes a narrow interpretation o f rea sonable accommodation . Th e Britis h statut e call s a reasonabl e accommodation a n "adjustment " an d state s that whe n arrange ments o r physical featur e

94

Disability Discrimination place th e disable d perso n a t a substantial disadvantag e i n comparison with persons who are not disabled , it is the dut y of the employer to take such steps as it is reasonable, in all the circumstances of the case, for him to take in order to prevent the arrangements o r feature havin g that effect .

The statut e offer s th e followin g example s o f suc h "arrange ments" tha t relat e t o reassignment : "transferrin g hi m t o fil l a n existing vacancy " an d "assignin g hi m t o a differen t plac e o f work." B y limitin g th e transfe r t o a n existin g vacancy , th e British mode l certainl y seem s les s generou s tha n th e Canadia n model, whic h seem s t o entai l extensiv e consideratio n fo r reas signment ove r a lengthy tim e period . The Britis h mode l i s als o more attentive to cost considerations, although th e details of th e regulations have yet to be worked out. By being attentive to costs and offerin g a narro w scop e o f reasonabl e accommodation , th e British mode l appear s t o b e deferentia l t o th e need s o f employ ers i n a capitalisti c society , reflectin g th e conservativ e politica l regime tha t enacte d th e legislation . I n addition , th e Britis h statute explicitl y state s tha t i t i s not intende d t o requir e prefer ential or favorable treatmen t fo r a person with a disability. Nonetheless, peopl e wit h disabilitie s migh t b e reassigne d i n Great Britai n unde r th e genera l principle s o f employmen t law . Under Britis h commo n la w th e employment-at-wil l principl e has eroded , s o tha t mos t employee s wit h a t leas t tw o year s o f work experienc e ar e protecte d agains t bein g lai d of f i f the y become disable d onc e o n th e job. There i s therefor e a seemin g conflict betwee n Grea t Britain' s recen t enactmen t o f disabilit y discrimination protectio n an d it s preexisting commo n la w pro tection fo r al l workers . Th e curren t disabilit y la w mirror s th e

Disability Discriminatio n

95

conservative economic influences i n Great Britain, and the com mon la w reflects earlie r suppor t fo r th e labo r movement .

SCOPE O F STATUTOR Y COVERAG E

The recently enacte d Britis h statut e i s even narrower tha n th e U.S. statut e i n providin g coverag e t o peopl e wit h disabilities . The effect o f a disability mus t b e both "substantial " and "lon g term" an d mus t affec t "norma l day-to-da y activities. " Ther e is no "record of " o r "regarded as " expansion o f this definition , as there i s in th e Unite d States . In addition , Schedul e 1 of th e act provide s fo r furthe r limitatio n o f impairment s tha t ma y qualify a s disabilities . Th e Britis h Disabilit y Discriminatio n Act o f 199 5 define s a disabilit y a s " a physica l o r menta l impairment whic h ha s a substantia l an d long-ter m advers e effect o n hi s abilit y t o carr y ou t norma l day-to-da y activi ties." Fo r example , a mental impairmen t "include s a n impair ment resultin g fro m o r consistin g o f a menta l illnes s onl y i f the illnes s i s a clinicall y well-recognize d illness. " Nonethe less, the Britis h statut e clearl y state s tha t a court shoul d con sider whethe r on e i s disable d before th e effec t o f mitigatin g measures i s take n int o consideration , unles s th e correctiv e measures ar e spectacle s o r contac t lenses . "A n impairmen t which woul d b e likel y t o hav e a substantial advers e effec t o n the abilit y o f th e perso n concerne d t o carr y ou t norma l day to-day activities , bu t fo r th e fac t tha t measure s ar e bein g taken t o trea t o r correc t it , i s t o b e treate d a s havin g tha t effect." Thus , eve n th e conservativ e Britis h Parliamen t rejected th e mitigatin g measure s rul e adopte d b y som e court s in th e Unite d States .

Disability Discrimination

96

Australia REASONABLE ACCOMMODATIO N

The cas e law fro m Australi a wit h respec t t o reasonabl e accom modation i s stil l a t a n earl y stag e an d s o i s somewha t har d t o evaluate. In an earl y cas e interpreting th e disabilit y discrimina tion la w o f Ne w Sout h Wales , the suprem e cour t wa s very def erential to an employer's assertion a s to what constitutes a "reasonable" accommodatio n i n a n employmen t applicatio n case. 45 Nonetheless, more recent decisions appear to be deferring muc h less t o employer' s assertion s concernin g th e economic s o f it s workforce.46 SCOPE OF STATUTORY COVERAGE

The Australia n Disabilit y Discriminatio n Ac t o f 199 2 define s disability broadly : (a) total o r partial loss of the person's bodily o r mental func tions; or (b) total or partial loss of a part of the body; or (c) the presence in the body of organisms causing disease or illness; or (d) the presenc e i n th e bod y o r organism s capabl e o f causin g disease or illness; or (e) the malfunction, malformatio n o r disfigurement o f a part o f the person's body; or (f ) a disorder o r malfunction tha t result s i n th e perso n learnin g differentl y from a person without the disorder or malfunction; o r (g) a disorder, illnes s o r diseas e tha t affect s a person' s though t processes, perception of reality, emotions or judgment o r that results in disturbed behavior; and includes a disability that; (h) presently exists; or (i) previously existed but no longer exists; or (j) may exist in the future; o r (k) is imputed to a person.47 Unlike the ADA's requirement, th e disabilit y nee d not substan tially limi t a majo r lif e activity . Provin g th e existenc e o f a n

Disability Discriminatio n

97

impairment tha t fits into one of seven categories is sufficient fo r coverage. In addition, protection exist s fo r people for whom the disability currentl y exists , previousl y existe d bu t n o longe r exists, may exist i n the future, o r is imputed. Australian court s appear to be applying thes e definition s broadly. 48 The breadt h o f statutor y coverag e i n thes e fou r countrie s therefore correspond s t o th e strengt h o f thei r reasonabl e accommodation protection . Great Britain has the narrowest def inition o f disability an d the most limite d reasonabl e accommo dation protection . Canad a an d Australia offe r broa d reasonabl e accommodation protectio n and , accordingly, offer a broad defin ition o f disability. The United State s offer s a broader definitio n than doe s Grea t Britain , a s well a s broader reasonabl e accom modation protection , bu t is narrower o n both ground s tha n i s Canada o r Australia. One might sa y that i t is ironic that countrie s with broad def initions o f disabilit y offe r broa d reasonabl e accommodatio n protection becaus e thi s combinatio n coul d b e quit e expensiv e for employers . Thi s trend , however , doe s fi t m y thesi s wit h regard t o a willingness t o appl y principle s tha t ar e somewha t inconsistent wit h hypercapitalism . Countrie s tha t ar e willing to act inconsistentl y wit h extrem e laissez-fair e economic s offe r broad protection at every turn; they do not seek to accommodate the employer' s cos t considerations . One migh t argu e tha t th e America n court s ar e correc t t o offer suc h a narro w definitio n o f a perso n wit h a disabilit y because suc h a narro w definitio n i s consisten t wit h America n law and economics. But the fact tha t eve n Grea t Britai n offer s a considerably broade r definitio n o f a perso n wit h a disabilit y should mak e a conservative juris t paus e fo r furthe r reflection . Through th e adoption o f the ADA, eve n th e Republican-domi -

98

Disability Discriminatio n

nated Congres s probabl y intende d t o provid e meaningfu l pro tection t o peopl e wit h a disability . But , fo r example , excludin g insulin-dependent diabetic s from statutor y coverag e is not con sistent with suc h intentions . Remarkably, th e AD A wa s passe d b y a bipartisa n Congress . Even mor e remarkably , i t i s frame d o n a n antisubordinatio n approach tha t grant s right s onl y t o peopl e wit h disabilities . Despite the hostility o f many employer s t o affirmative action , it goe s muc h furthe r tha n Titl e VI I i n orderin g employer s t o make reasonabl e accommodation s fo r peopl e wit h disabili ties. The backlas h ha s bee n quic k an d decisive . The scop e o f th e reasonable accommodatio n obligatio n ha s bee n narrowe d fa r beyond the statutory language, and the categories of people who can bring claims under the statute has been confined beyon d th e intentions o f Congres s o r th e EEOC . Moreover , conservativ e newspapers hav e fueled thi s backlash by exaggerating th e scop e of succes s for claimant s unde r th e ADA. Why ha s ther e bee n thi s quic k backlas h t o a congressiona l bipartisan effort ? Capitalis m canno t accommodat e affirmativ e action eve n whe n rac e an d gende r issue s ar e no t a t stake . I n Canada, most disabilit y case s are decided a s arbitrator decision s involving unio n grievance s o n behal f o f disable d employees . The labo r contract s typicall y contai n thei r ow n protectio n fo r workers wh o becom e disable d an d thereb y serv e t o strengthe n the applicabl e disabilit y statute . Since a strong labor movemen t is indicative of a more socialist economy it is consistent with m y thesis tha t thes e arbitratio n decision s protec t peopl e wit h dis abilities, ofte n providin g the m wit h wha t I hav e terme d affir mative actio n protection .

Disability Discriminatio n

99

What typ e o f stat e interventio n bes t serve s th e interest s o f people wit h disabilities ? T o begi n t o answe r tha t question , w e must recogniz e tha t man y differen t form s o f stat e interventio n existing in this area of the law deserve close examination. America's parochial lens often prevent s suc h a wide-ranging analysis .

4 FAMILY AN D MEDICA L LEAV E

Kimberly Her n Troup e wa s employe d a s a saleswoma n i n th e women's accessorie s departmen t a t Lor d & Taylor.1 She experi enced extrem e nause a whil e pregnan t an d frequentl y reporte d to wor k lat e o r ha d t o leav e early . Although he r employmen t record ha d bee n perfec t befor e sh e becam e pregnant , sh e wa s fired th e da y befor e he r maternit y leav e wa s t o commence . Troupe brough t sui t allegin g tha t he r employe r fire d he r because of her pregnancy an d would have tolerated a similar illness if experienced by a male employee. Her lawsuit was unsuccessful, wit h th e cour t blamin g Troup e fo r he r nausea , seem ingly buyin g th e stereotyp e tha t nause a occur s durin g preg nancy onl y i n th e morning . Thus , th e cour t o f appeals—i n a decision writte n b y Judg e Richar d Posner—blame s he r fo r th e "morning sickness " by suggesting that sh e caused it to last unti l

Family and Medical Leave

101

noon "becaus e sh e slep t late r unde r th e ne w schedule , s o tha t noon was 'morning' fo r her. " The Troupe decision i s typical o f the hostility tha t U.S . courts have show n t o suit s brought b y pregnan t women . Rejecting th e notion that pregnancy-based discriminatio n i s based on sex, U.S. courts have refused t o consider such discrimination a s part of the constitutional la w o f se x discrimination. 2 Othe r countries , suc h as Canada , have , however , incorporate d pregnanc y discrimina tion case s int o th e la w o f sex discrimination. 3 An d whe n th e Pregnancy Discrimination Act (PDA) 4 was passed to specify tha t pregnancy-based discriminatio n i n employmen t shoul d b e con sidered sex-base d discrimination , som e U.S . court s impose d impossible burden s o f proo f o n femal e plaintiffs. 5 Othe r court s have used the PD A as an opportunit y t o rule fo r mal e plaintiffs , overturning "special treatment" rules for pregnant women. 6 U.S. antidiscrimination la w ha s no t give n pregnan t wome n muc h substantive protection , regardles s o f th e conten t o f suc h laws , especially whe n th e case s hav e bee n decide d b y judges wh o ar e sympathetic to extreme laissez-fair e arguments . U.S. law also does little to protect fetuse s fro m hazard s a t th e workplace whil e wome n ar e pregnant . Federa l antidiscrimina tion la w require s n o accommodation s fo r pregnan t women . Interpretations o f the PDA combined with interpretations o f the Occupational Safet y an d Healt h Act 7 (OSHA ) hav e resulte d i n no meaningful federa l guideline s to make the workplace safe fo r fetuses. Instead , th e privat e marketplac e set s standard s i n thi s area in the name of laissez-faire economics . Canada and wester n Europe, by contrast , have foun d way s t o accommodate bot h th e health o f the fetu s an d th e right s o f th e pregnan t worker . Finally, the Unite d State s stand s alon e i n th e Western worl d in failin g t o requir e employer s t o provid e pai d maternit y leav e

102

Family and Medical Leave

following th e birt h o f a child. Until 1993 , South Afric a an d th e United State s wer e th e onl y industrialize d nation s tha t di d no t have a federa l maternit y o r parenta l leav e policy. 8 Unti l quit e recently, wome n wh o too k unpai d medica l leav e followin g th e birth o f a child coul d b e fired . After nearl y a decade o f politica l struggle, women who work for large employers are now entitle d to twelve weeks o f unpaid leav e following th e birth o r adoptio n of a child, 9 whic h provide s fe w genuin e option s fo r th e over whelming numbe r o f poo r o r eve n middle-clas s wome n wh o cannot affor d t o tak e unpai d leav e an d stil l pa y th e bills . Their only solac e i s tha t if they work for a large employer, the y a t least wil l hav e a job t o whic h the y ca n retur n afte r takin g th e most minima l possibl e medica l leave . The limite d protection s fo r pregnan t wome n i n th e Unite d States have received stron g criticism fro m th e leaders of laissezfaire economics . On th e issu e o f legall y impose d "specia l treat ment^ fo r pregnan t wome n unde r antidiscriminatio n law , Professor Richar d Epstei n commented , Because pregnanc y i s desired , an d becaus e wome n largel y control whethe r an d whe n t o become pregnant , th e eviden t moral hazard makes pregnancy a poor candidate for any for m of insurance . . . . The legislativ e an d judicia l insistenc e o n their [pregnancy's ] specia l status , however , canno t obscur e the socia l losse s incurre d b y thei r implementation , wit h pregnancy a s elsewhere. 10 He furthe r criticize s th e Pregnanc y Discriminatio n Ac t a s using "th e antidiscriminatio n nor m a s a tool fo r redistributiv e ends/' Epstei n wrot e thos e word s i n respons e t o th e us e o f antidiscrimination la w for th e benefit o f pregnant women ; on e can onl y imagin e wha t h e migh t sa y abou t a blatantly prefer -

Family and Medical Leave

103

ential treatmen t polic y lik e th e Famil y Medica l an d Leav e Ac t (FMLA). Economic discours e ha s dominate d th e discussio n o f th e treatment o f pregnan t wome n i n th e Unite d States . Will socia l welfare program s caus e poo r wome n t o bea r mor e children ? (While th e Unite d State s seek s to limit th e amoun t o f financia l support t o poo r wome n wit h children , man y Europea n coun tries continu e thei r subsidizatio n progra m fo r al l familie s wit h children. Fo r example , German y provide s monthl y benefit s o f approximately $39 5 pe r mont h t o th e famil y unti l th e chil d reaches si x months an d the n offer s a somewhat reduce d benefi t until th e chil d reache s twenty-fou r months . Another progra m then provide s a subsidy unti l a child reache s th e ag e of twenty seven months.) 11 Woul d mandate d insuranc e coverage , pai d leave, o r accommodation s fo r pregnanc y bankrup t businesses ? Based o n fe w empirica l dat a bu t muc h speculatio n b y la w an d economics scholars , th e free-marke t proponent s hav e largel y won the debate in the United States . Any schem e of pregnancy related benefit s o r accommodation s i s largel y a matte r o f bar gaining between employee s and employers, because the govern ment ha s imposed fe w standard s i n thi s area . This discussio n i s uniquely America n fo r tw o reasons . First , it is dominated b y th e discours e o f laissez-faire economics . Second, i t virtuall y ignore s th e need s an d interest s o f youn g chil dren. (Eve n whe n author s argu e tha t me n shoul d hav e mor e access to parental leave, they spea k from th e perspective o f ho w such leav e benefits th e parents—tha t is , it gives men a n oppor tunity t o develo p parentin g skill s an d alleviate s women' s dis proportionate chil d care burden—rather tha n fro m th e perspec tive of how such leave benefits th e children.) 12 Health insuranc e for pregnan t wome n result s i n increase d acces s to prenatal car e

104

Family and Medical Leave

which i n turn reduce s the incidence o f low-birth-weight babies . Paid leave for parents also facilitates breast-feedin g an d parenta l care for th e firs t yea r o f a child's life . There i s ample evidenc e tha t nearl y al l forms o f nonparenta l care i n th e firs t yea r o f lif e ar e inferio r t o th e car e offere d b y good parents. 13 Ye t th e Unite d State s ha s take n n o step s t o improve th e qualit y o f nonparenta l car e offered t o infants o r t o help parents provid e tha t car e themselves. This secon d proble m can als o b e attribute d t o th e negativ e effect s o f capitalis m o n American life . The free-market , autonom y principle s underly ing American capitalis m prevent us from bein g "other directed " in ou r consideratio n o f socia l problems . I t i s a s i f w e hav e for gotten tha t pregnan t wome n usuall y giv e birt h a t th e en d o f their pregnancies . The shor t perio d o f medica l leav e tha t the y might receiv e afte r th e birt h o f a chil d doe s no t eve n begi n t o address the need s of the infant wh o has just bee n born an d is in his o r he r mos t dependent , an d possibl y mos t important , stag e of development . The discours e i n othe r countries , eve n othe r capitalis t coun tries, ha s bee n vastl y different . Th e need s o f pregnan t wome n are built around the understanding that a child will soon be born who needs special assistance. When a society offers assistanc e t o parents in the form o f paid leave, insurance, or accommodation s away fro m workplac e hazards , th e rea l beneficiarie s o f tha t assistance shoul d b e considere d th e child , no t th e pregnan t woman. Th e whol e "specia l treatment " debat e i n th e Unite d States ha s been warpe d b y a misunderstanding o f who receive s and need s tha t specia l treatment . Throughout U.S . history, w e hav e alway s lumpe d togethe r "women an d children" in our discourse as if they were a unitary entity an d a s if th e woma n hersel f neede d paternalisti c protec -

Family and Medical Leave

105

tion. Thi s traditio n continue s i n ou r moder n discours e abou t pregnancy discriminatio n an d pregnanc y leave . In thi s chapter , I tr y t o separat e th e need s o f pregnan t wome n an d childre n t o argue tha t specia l treatmen t i s an d shoul d b e offere d t o th e newly born child (or the fetus in utero). I t is conceptually wron g to view that treatmen t a s having been extende d t o the pregnan t woman.

The Economic Debat e

Economic discours e ha s dominate d th e argument s bot h fo r an d against pai d parentin g leav e an d healt h insuranc e coverag e fo r pregnant women . Richar d Epstein' s discussio n o f mandate d insurance coverag e fo r pregnan t wome n rest s entirel y o n eco nomic argument s concernin g th e stabilit y o f voluntar y insur ance systems. He contends that disability insurance system s will inevitably "disintegrate " i f coverag e fo r pregnanc y i s required ; therefore, i t i s i n everyone' s interes t t o exclud e pregnanc y i n order t o maintai n th e viabilit y o f th e insuranc e disabilit y mar ket.14 According to his economic analysis, any insuranc e syste m that cover s pregnancy shoul d falte r becaus e women woul d the n choose t o become pregnan t an d s o take advantag e o f thes e pro grams, thereby creatin g a substantial increase d cos t tha t woul d undermine the system's economic viability. Epstein's argument s are entirel y theoretical—h e offer s n o empirica l suppor t con necting th e availabilit y o f an y o f thes e benefit s an d women' s behavior. Hi s theoretica l argument s ar e base d o n hi s initia l assumption tha t "pregnanc y i s desired , an d . . . women largel y control whethe r an d whe n t o becom e pregnant." 15 Similarly , The Wall Street Journal regularl y publishes editorials ridiculin g the FMLA , wit h headline s suc h a s "Family-Leav e La w Ca n B e

106

Family and Medical Leave

Excuse fo r a Day Off." 16 Thes e article s complai n tha t th e $67 4 million pric e ta g fo r th e statute , a s predicte d b y th e Genera l Accounting Office , wil l be much highe r i n practice . Judge Richar d Posne r ha s mad e n o secre t o f hi s hostilit y t o the PD A an d mandate d maternit y leav e i n hi s academi c writ ings, arguing that the PDA may not even benefit mos t women. 17 Nonetheless, Posne r i s force d t o acknowledg e tha t th e cos t o f laws suc h a s the PD A may b e offse t "b y gain s no t measure d i n an economi c analysis—gain s i n self-esteem. " Neve r doe s h e consider, however , whethe r th e benefit s o f suc h law s migh t b e measured i n th e well-bein g o f ou r nex t generation . Hi s failur e to conside r thi s argumen t i s somewha t surprisin g becaus e h e does seem fascinate d wit h romanti c notions o f women's mater nal role . For example, he state s earlie r i n the article : It is possible that the greater propensity of women than me n to take time out of the labor force is itself a product of sex discrimination, bu t I am skeptica l o f tha t proposition— I thin k child-rearing i s a n are a wher e natur e dominate s culture — and I do not accep t it for purposes of my analysis. 18 Not surprisingly , Posner' s hostility to the PDA is reflected i n his decisions as a jurist, although som e economists hav e misun derstood Posner' s positio n o n th e PDA . Fo r example , Irvin g Michelman, a forme r corporat e executiv e an d advise r t o th e Federal Reserv e Boar d an d th e U.S . Department o f Commerce , cites Posner' s dissen t i n International Union v. Johnson Controls19 a s reflectin g a "morally-based , efficienc y alternative " which woul d "fin d a way t o interpre t anti-discriminatio n law s . . . t o include feta l protection." 20 Michelma n suggest s tha t Pos ner's analysis reflects hi s sensitivity to the business communit y as well a s to feta l safet y an d women' s welfare . Ho w h e reache s

Family and Medical Leave

107

that conclusio n fro m Posner' s analysis , however , i s har d t o fathom. The issue in the case was whether a n employer coul d preven t all fertil e wome n fro m workin g i n it s battery-manufacturin g plant i n a positio n wit h a hig h exposur e t o lead . Completel y ignoring the Pregnancy Discrimination Act (PDA), the majorit y concluded tha t suc h a polic y wa s lawful . Th e U.S . Suprem e Court ultimately reversed the district court and court of appeals, concluding tha t th e polic y wa s a pregnancy-base d distinctio n that expressl y violate d th e PDA . Although Judg e Posne r dissente d fro m th e opinio n o f th e court o f appeals , hi s opinio n hardl y reflect s muc h concer n fo r the positio n o f women a t th e workplace . He preface s hi s analy sis wit h th e assumptio n take n fro m Gar y Becker' s 197 1 book , The Economics of Discrimination, tha t "fe w privat e employer s discriminate withou t havin g som e reaso n fo r doin g so ; competition tend s t o driv e fro m th e marke t firm s tha t behav e irra tionally/' 21 Bu t Becker' s assessmen t depend s o n a full-employ ment econom y an d certainly doe s not appl y to low-level jobs a t a batter y plan t wher e th e poo l o f worker s i s enormous . (Th e presumably rationa l employe r i n thi s cas e assume d tha t an y woman unde r th e ag e of seventy i s fertile!) Unlik e the majorit y opinion, Posne r doe s actuall y acknowledg e tha t Titl e VI I wa s amended i n 198 2 t o includ e th e Pregnanc y Discriminatio n Amendment, whic h define d se x discriminatio n t o includ e dis crimination o n th e basi s o f pregnancy . Nonetheless , h e refuse s to interpret thi s amendment liberall y (consistent , as we will see, with all his interpretations o f the PDA) to forbid a n employer t o deal with th e proble m o f safet y a t the workplace b y refusin g t o hire fertil e women . Instead, he say s that a n employe r shoul d b e able to show evidence of the potential cost of tort liability, moral

108

Family and Medical Leave

qualms about endangering the child, or the effect o n public relations of revealing the safety hazard s at its workplace. Thus, Posner suggest s tha t th e cour t shoul d reman d th e case back to th e district cour t "t o enabl e th e compilatio n o f a n adequat e eviden tiary record/ ' Even thoug h Posne r indicate s tha t thi s defens e i s a narro w one, on e woul d expec t th e distric t cour t judg e i n thi s case t o rule onc e agai n fo r th e defendan t employer . After all , the dis trict court , wit h spars e evidenc e o n a summar y judgmen t motion, ha d alread y rule d onc e fo r th e employer , s o with addi tional evidence, one would expec t the distric t cour t t o rule onc e more fo r th e defendant . (Th e Suprem e Cour t sidesteppe d thi s possibility b y rulin g authoritativel y fo r th e plaintiffs , withou t leaving ope n th e possibilit y o f a victor y fo r th e defendan t employer o n remand. ) Nonetheless , Posne r i s praise d b y a n economist wh o doe s no t see m t o appreciat e tha t Posne r virtu ally neve r reache s lega l decision s tha t protec t th e employmen t interests o f pregnant women . As we will se e when w e examin e the policie s o f othe r countries , ther e ar e fa r bette r solution s t o this proble m tha n Posner's , base d no t o n th e presume d eco nomic rationalit y o f employer s bu t o n th e importanc e o f safe guarding both women's economic security and the health of th e fetus. Arguments supportin g increase d benefit s fo r pregnan t women als o ofte n spea k i n purel y economi c terms . Fo r exam ple, Samue l Issacharof f an d Elys e Rosenblu m cit e Presiden t Clinton's "nannygate " episod e i n tryin g t o fin d a qualifie d (female) attorne y genera l a s exemplifyin g th e nee d fo r a national maternit y polic y tha t ca n accommodat e th e need s o f working women. 22 "[W]ithou t accommodatio n fo r pregnancy , women experienc e a n elevate d leve l o f earl y departur e fro m

Family and Medical Leave

109

the wor k forc e an d a n associate d failur e t o develo p wha t econ omists ter m jo b specifi c capital—tha t is , th e enhance d skill s and productivit y tha t com e fro m experienc e o n th e job/ ' Exploring th e relationshi p betwee n wage s an d continuou s workplace participation , the y insis t tha t th e Unite d State s needs a model similar to the one used in Canad a s o that wome n would receiv e unemploymen t insuranc e fo r twelv e week s postpartum s o long a s they ha d worke d fo r thei r employe r fo r at leas t te n week s befor e becomin g pregnant . Unlik e Epstein , they bas e thei r proposa l o n empirica l evidenc e connectin g women's childbearin g decision s an d th e availabilit y o f insur ance systems . Bu t unlik e Epstein , the y d o no t presum e tha t women hav e childre n i n orde r t o collec t pregnanc y leav e ben efits. Havin g begu n wit h a differen t premise , the y arriv e a t a different economi c solution . (M y surve y o f th e existin g statis tics o n birthrates , pregnanc y leav e policies , an d women' s par ticipation i n th e workforc e suggest s n o connectio n amon g these factors . Germa n an d Italy , fo r example , which hav e gen erous pregnancy-base d policie s als o have th e lowes t birthrate s in Europe—te n pe r on e thousan d population—compare d wit h the Unite d States ' relativel y hig h birthrate—sixtee n pe r on e thousand population.) 23 Issacharoff an d Rosenblum' s progra m woul d certainl y improve women' s economi c situatio n followin g th e birt h o f a child but is unlikely to have any appreciable impact on the "nan ny gate" problem tha t introduce s thei r article . The women wit h "nanny" problem s wer e no t impede d i n thei r career s b y a lack of compensation fo r twelv e weeks of pregnancy leave . In Marc h 1986, Kimb a Woo d hire d a n illega l alie n fro m Trinida d t o car e for her infant son . The employment wa s actually lawful becaus e at tha t time , federa l la w permitte d illega l alien s t o b e hire d i n

110

Family and Medical Leave

such positions . Furthermore, th e nanny becam e a legal residen t in 1987 , thus allowin g Wood t o continu e t o emplo y he r legally . Wood also paid all required Socia l Security taxes on the nanny' s wages. Sh e worke d fo r th e famil y fo r man y years , permittin g both Woo d an d he r husban d t o continu e workin g i n time-con suming an d highl y pai d positions. 24 Th e politica l reactio n against Woo d ca n mos t likel y b e explaine d b y th e fac t tha t sh e hired a non-American, no t tha t sh e acte d i n a n unlawfu l man ner. Wood' s career , however , wa s certainl y no t impeded , a s Issacharoff an d Rosenblu m suggest , becaus e sh e coul d no t tak e sufficient medica l leave following the birth of her son. Similarly, Zoe Bair d an d he r husban d hire d a foreign coupl e a s a babysit ter an d drive r fo r a length y perio d o f time . Th e coupl e wer e obviously alleviatin g th e burden s o f combinin g pai d employ ment an d chil d care , but thei r presenc e was no t fo r th e purpos e of alleviating a short-term nee d fo r medica l leave following th e birth o f a child. Understanding th e importance o f continuous workplac e par ticipation to success in high-powered careers , these women too k a minimal break from th e workplace following th e birth o f thei r children. Their "nanny " problem s wer e cause d by thei r limite d options fo r high-qualit y car e fo r thei r childre n afte r the y returned t o pai d employment . Lik e man y parents , the y con cluded tha t a group chil d car e situatio n wa s no t optima l i n th e first yea r o f s o o f thei r child' s life . Tha t lef t the m wit h tw o choices: the parent s coul d wor k ou t a schedul e tha t permitte d them t o sta y hom e wit h th e child , o r the y coul d hir e someon e else t o com e int o thei r hom e t o tak e car e o f th e child . Eve n though eithe r optio n i s much mor e expensiv e fo r mos t parent s than grou p da y care , man y parent s mak e th e (uneconomical ) decision t o use one o f these arrangements . Why ?

Family and Medical Leave

111

Laissez-faire economic s canno t provid e a n answe r here . Par ents, who supposedl y decid e t o have childre n dependin g o n th e disability insuranc e schem e availabl e fo r th e si x weeks follow ing th e birt h o f thei r child , ar e als o makin g blatantl y uneco nomical decisions—the y ar e payin g mor e tha n $1,00 0 pe r month t o someone els e to take car e of their chil d o r forgoin g a t least tha t muc h mone y i n incom e b y takin g car e o f th e chil d themselves rathe r tha n payin g about $50 0 per month fo r grou p care for their child. The answer is that parents do not make chil d care (or pregnancy) decision s on a purely economic basis. If the y did conside r economic s seriously , mos t adults , of course , woul d forgo parentin g altogether . But even after decidin g to partake of the psychi c an d emotiona l reward s o f parenting , the y d o no t always see k t o minimiz e th e cost s o f parenting . Tha t is , the y sometimes choos e highl y uneconomica l option s i n th e earl y years o f a child' s lif e ou t o f thei r concer n fo r th e child' s well being. Thi s endurin g fac t wil l surviv e an y tinkerin g wit h th e paid leav e polic y i n th e Unite d States . I t wil l endur e becaus e even i n thi s highl y capitalisti c society , parent s ar e an d wil l b e motivated b y force s othe r tha n economics . Poor women' s decision s ca n als o be understood a s reflectin g decisions abou t chil d car e rathe r tha n abou t economics . Som e working-class wome n wh o ear n th e minimu m wag e find tha t i t makes mor e sens e to qui t thei r jobs an d g o on welfare afte r th e birth o f a child tha n t o sta y a t pai d work . With th e inadequat e system o f chil d car e an d healt h insuranc e tha t i s availabl e t o poor women, staying at home to raise their child is the only wa y to safeguard thei r child's well-being. Their decision s parallel th e decisions sometime s mad e by upper-class women—that is , they choose a n uneconomica l optio n i n orde r t o safeguar d th e well being o f thei r children . Th e languag e o f th e welfar e debate ,

112

Family and Medical Leave

however, condemn s the m a s bad mother s withou t understand ing the rationalit y o f their decision s fro m th e perspective o f th e child's well-being . The proposa l offere d b y Issacharof f an d Rosenblu m has , i n fact, fe w similaritie s t o th e actua l scop e o f leav e benefit s avail able in Canada . In 1990, Bill C-21 became federal la w in Canada , thereby creatin g fifteen week s of maternity benefits fo r the biological mothe r an d a ten-wee k parentin g benefi t tha t coul d b e taken by either parent. 25 (Th e provinces have their ow n paralle l statutes governin g som e employmen t no t covere d b y th e fed eral statute . I n Ontario , fo r example , th e Employmen t Stan dards Ac t entitle s a woma n t o tak e seventee n week s o f preg nancy leave and either parent to take eighteen weeks of parenta l leave.)26 Canadia n parent s receiv e compensatio n fo r nearl y si x months o f leav e followin g th e birt h o f a child , no t th e twelv e weeks proposed by Issacharoff an d Rosenblum. Parents ca n also take their benefits o n a part-time basis, spreading them ou t ove r fifty-two weeks . Finally , a portio n o f thi s leav e i s availabl e t o either parent; the justification i s not simpl y the biological need s of the pregnant woman. The effect o f the Canadian legislatio n is to hel p enabl e parent s t o car e fo r thei r childre n themselve s fo r the first si x months an d possibly first yea r o f life. It is the inter ests o f th e youn g child , no t th e pregnan t woman , tha t justif y such a lengthy leav e period fo r eithe r parent . European la w i s ofte n comparabl e t o th e la w o f Canad a i n helping parents tak e paid leave for muc h o f the child's first yea r of life . For example , Italy passe d it s Equa l Treatment Ac t (ETA ) in 1977 , which buil t o n the preexisting 197 1 maternity la w an d provided th e followin g benefit s t o ne w parents : a three-mont h leave fo r th e mothe r a t 8 0 percent pa y afte r th e birt h o r adop tion o f a chil d an d a n optiona l six-mont h additiona l leav e tha t

Family and Medical Leave

113

can b e take n b y eithe r paren t a t 3 0 percen t pay. 27 Workin g mothers wer e als o guaranteed res t period s durin g th e firs t yea r of a child's life . Owing to legal action in 1987 , Italian la w was soon equalize d to provid e mor e comparabl e benefit s fo r mal e an d femal e par ents. Th e plaintiff s wer e father s o f newbor n childre n whos e mothers ha d die d in childbirt h o r were infirm an d immobilized . These men successfull y argue d tha t they, too, should be entitle d to th e three-mont h postpartu m leav e an d res t period s i n accor dance wit h th e la w o f equa l treatment . I n rulin g fo r th e mal e plaintiffs, th e Constitutiona l Cour t note d tha t th e rational e o f the maternit y la w reflecte d a growin g publi c concer n "fo r th e child's affectiv e an d psychologica l well-bein g a s well a s its bio logical needs/ ' Although th e maternit y la w may hav e been ini tially passed in 195 0 out o f a concern fo r th e frailt y o f pregnan t women an d a desir e t o mak e breast-feedin g easier , it s curren t structure reflect s a n increasin g concer n fo r th e welfar e o f th e young child . As a result o f another lega l challenge in 1991 , by a father whos e wif e wa s health y bu t di d no t wan t t o tak e th e three-month leav e t o car e fo r th e child , th e Constitutiona l Court agai n rule d tha t th e statute' s protection s mus t b e extended t o fathers . Th e cour t recognize d tha t th e purpos e o f the legislation was to address the "relational an d affective need s that ar e connecte d t o the developmen t o f th e personalit y o f th e child."28 Th e purel y biologica l justification s fo r th e legislatio n were outmoded . Nearly every European country provides women with at least eight weeks o f paid leave following th e birth o f a child, which i s then followe d by a period of paid parental leave. 29 It is clear fro m the languag e o f thes e statute s tha t eve n th e maternit y leav e i s justified i n par t b y th e need s o f th e child . Fo r example , i n Ger -

114

Family and Medical Leave

many, Norway , Poland , an d Luxembourg , maternit y leav e i s lengthened i f the baby i s born prematurel y o r the woman ha s a multiple birth . Som e countries , lik e Poland , als o lengthe n th e maternity leav e i f ther e i s alread y anothe r chil d i n th e house hold. And unlik e the United States , none o f the Europea n coun tries exempt s smal l businesses fro m statutor y coverage . Suggestions tha t th e Unite d State s mov e towar d a paid sys tem o f leave followin g th e birt h o f a child produce s th e follow ing kind o f reaction fro m economi c conservatives : What w e nee d i s anothe r welfar e scheme , thi s on e fo r jo b holders. What a concept. Now, push th e baby carriag e dow n to th e FML A offic e an d pic k u p you r "wag e replacement " check once a week for th e next three months. Maybe they'l l electronically mail it to your banking account. Is this country great, or what? Insane, comes to mind. 30 By contrast , Professo r Edwar d Zigler , who lobbie d i n favo r o f a bill tha t woul d hav e require d a six-mont h pai d leav e fo r ne w parents describes the FMLA act as "awful/' "It' s especially awfu l when you sto p to consider that Ghana has a paid leave; Haiti has a paid leave , for God' s sake . When ar e we goin g t o join th e res t of th e world?" 31 One' s versio n o f what' s "insane " seem s t o depend o n one' s vie w o f economic s an d consideratio n o f th e well-being of children. Only in the United State s is the require ment tha t employer s offe r pai d leav e t o parent s followin g th e birth o r adoption o f a child considere d t o be insane .

Special Treatment/Equa l Treatmen t Discours e

A secon d ke y aspec t o f th e pregnanc y debat e i n th e Unite d States i s it s focu s o n th e specia l treatment/equa l treatmen t

Family and Medical Leave

115

issue. The questio n tha t ha s bee n pose d fo r nearl y a century i s whether mandate d leav e legislatio n followin g th e birt h o f a child will help or hinder women's positio n i n society. This argu ment, lik e th e economi c on e just discussed , ha s largel y ignore d the need s an d interest s o f the youn g child . Instead, it presume s that th e woma n rathe r tha n th e fetu s o r youn g chil d i s receiv ing the specia l treatment . PROTECTING TH E CHIL D AFTE R BIRT H

Equal Treatment Cases. The Pregnanc y Discriminatio n Ac t ha s generally bee n interprete d t o incorporat e a n equa l treatmen t rather than a special treatment model . In doing so, the act sometimes help s preven t over t discriminatio n agains t pregnan t women but never helps accommodate th e needs of the child fol lowing birth . A cas e tha t reflect s thi s patter n i s Maganuco v. Leyden Community High School District 212. 32 Plaintif f Mag anuco wa s a pregnan t schoolteache r wh o wante d t o us e he r accumulated pai d sic k leav e befor e takin g a n unpai d maternit y leave. Bu t schoo l polic y forbi d someon e wh o too k maternit y leave t o combin e i t with pai d sic k leave . Maganuco argue d tha t this rule violated the PDA by creating a disparate impact agains t women i n th e workplace . Drawin g a distinctio n betwee n th e plaintiffs medica l needs and her child care needs, the court rule d against th e plaintiff : Teachers who choose not to take maternity leave , and decide instead t o return t o teaching as soon as their perio d o f pregnancy-related disabilit y ends , ar e unaffecte d b y th e polic y that Maganuc o challenges . Th e impac t o f th e leav e polic y that Maganuc o contests , then , i s dependen t no t o n th e bio logical fac t tha t pregnanc y an d childbirt h caus e som e perio d of disability, but on a Leyden schoolteacher's choice to forego

116

Family and Medical Leave

returning to work in favor of spending time at home with her newborn child . However , thi s choic e i s no t th e inevitabl e consequence of a medical condition related to pregnancy, and leave policie s tha t ma y influenc e th e decisio n t o remai n a t home afte r th e perio d o f pregnancy-relate d disabilit y ha s ended fall outside the scope of the PDA. 33 The Sevent h Circuit' s descriptio n o f Maganuco' s "choice " t o stay hom e wit h he r newbor n bab y make s i t soun d lik e sh e i s staying home to play games. (Maybe the cour t shoul d als o have mentioned he r "choice " in not relinquishin g th e chil d for adop tion s o that sh e would not have any child care needs at all.) Ear lier i n it s opinion , th e cour t describe d Maganuc o a s needin g only "1 0 day s o f post-deliver y recuperation " t o recove r fro m her pregnancy . Presumably , sh e shoul d the n hav e returne d t o work ful l time , althoug h n o da y car e cente r wil l eve n conside r taking a child unti l h e o r sh e is at leas t si x weeks old . Once te n days have passed and her medica l needs have supposedly ended , the PDA' s concern fo r th e ne w mother's treatmen t a t the work place expires . Thi s uncarin g an d callou s consideratio n o f th e needs of the newborn an d the new mother is entirely possible in the equa l treatmen t regim e o f th e Unite d States , i n whic h w e can overlook th e fac t tha t mos t pregnan t wome n giv e birth t o a child who will have significan t chil d care needs. Canadian court s hav e reache d th e opposit e conclusio n base d on simila r facts . Canadia n plaintif f Carlind a D'Alimont e als o was a pregnant schoolteache r wh o wanted t o combine sic k leave and maternity leav e following th e birth o f her child, in violation of he r company' s personne l policies. 34 A boar d o f arbitratio n upheld th e employer' s position . Bu t o n appeal , th e Ontari o Divisional Cour t conclude d tha t suc h a coerce d choic e violate d the law against se x discrimination. Citin g an earlie r decisio n b y

Family and Medical Leave

117

the Canadia n Suprem e Court , th e Ontari o cour t emphasize d that a findin g o f discriminatio n wa s necessar y i n orde r t o redress a basic disadvantag e tha t wome n fac e a t th e workplac e and in societ y a t large. "It [th e rule ] would sanctio n imposin g a disproportionate amoun t o f th e cost s o f pregnanc y upo n women. Remova l o f suc h unfai r imposition s upo n wome n an d other group s i n societ y i s a key purpos e o f anti-discriminatio n legislation." The Ontari o cour t viewe d pregnanc y a s benefitin g society a s a whole an d s o expecte d employer s an d societ y a s a whole t o bea r som e o f thos e costs . Rathe r tha n viewin g th e plaintiffs pregnanc y a s a private choice , the cour t viewe d i t i n the contex t o f mutual socia l responsibility . Until th e passag e o f th e Famil y an d Medica l Leav e Act, fed eral law in the United State s provided no protection fo r worker s who neede d t o mis s wor k becaus e o f illnes s o r becaus e o f fam ily responsibilities suc h as child care. Canadian law , by contrast , offers protectio n t o worker s unde r bot h it s antidiscriminatio n law (bot h disabilit y an d sex-based law) and its generous parent ing leav e law . Furthermore, worker s ar e ofte n protecte d unde r collective-bargaining agreement s tha t d o not permi t the m t o be discharged fo r illness-relate d leav e unles s th e employe r ca n demonstrate tha t th e employe e i s incapabl e o f regula r atten dance in th e future. 35 Canada an d th e Unite d State s operat e unde r differen t premises regarding the role of the state in workers' lives. Canada is accustomed t o intervening , unde r it s version o f capitalism , t o provide minimum level s of protections fo r workers, whereas th e United State s doe s s o quite begrudgingly. Fo r example, in a typical Canadia n cas e involvin g a unio n grievance , th e arbitrato r deferred t o the judgment o f the employee' s physicia n whil e rec ognizing tha t th e "evidenc e places the grievo r o n th e borderlin e

118

Family and Medical Leave

and i t may tur n ou t t o have been to o optimistic/' 36 A U.S. court is unlikely t o interpret a close case in favo r o f the employee . The onl y federa l statut e tha t applie s a "special accommoda tion" principle—the Americans wit h Disabilitie s Act—does no t cover suc h requests by pregnant wome n becaus e pregnancy i s a "normal" rathe r tha n "disabling " condition. 37 Federa l la w thereby impose s n o standard s o n th e workplac e t o enabl e women t o giv e birt h t o health y newborn s wh o wil l then , i n turn, have an opportunity t o obtain good care in the first yea r of life. Because ther e ar e n o nonpregnan t employee s wit h compa rable responsibilities fo r another' s life , employers ar e permitte d to ignor e entirel y th e need s an d interest s o f fetuse s an d new borns when settin g workplace policies . Some states , however , hav e begu n t o implemen t legislatio n that woul d provid e pregnan t wome n wit h bette r choice s a t th e workplace. For example, under Connecticu t law , it is a discriminatory employmen t practic e . . . fo r a n employer, b y himself o r hi s agent : . . . ( e ) t o fai l o r refus e t o mak e a reasonable effor t t o transfe r a pregnant employe e t o an y suit able temporary positio n whic h ma y b e available i n an y cas e in which a n employe e give s written notic e of her pregnanc y to her employer and the employer or pregnant employee reasonably believes that continue d employmen t i n the positio n held b y th e pregnan t employe e ma y caus e injur y t o th e employee or fetus. 38 This law , however, contemplate s onl y on e typ e o f accommoda tion—a temporar y transfe r t o a suitable temporary position . As the Connecticu t court s ruled , "[T]h e employe r nee d no t tak e any othe r actio n t o accommodat e th e employe e becaus e th e statute, quite simply , does not requir e it." 39

Family and Medical Leave

119

One fundamenta l proble m wit h th e equa l treatmen t approach tha t dominate s U.S . case law on the rights o f pregnan t workers under the PDA is that it forces plaintiffs t o engage in an impossible compariso n wit h nonpregnan t person s wh o fac e similar problems . A cas e that illustrate s thi s proble m i s Troupe v. May Department Stores?® which wa s cite d a t th e beginnin g of this chapter and whose opinion was written by Judge Richar d Posner. T o repeat , th e plaintiff , Kimberl y Her n Troupe , wa s employed a s a saleswoma n i n th e women' s accessorie s depart ment a t Lor d & Taylor. He r employmen t recor d wa s " entirely satisfactory" until she became pregnant an d began to experienc e what th e cour t calle d "mornin g sicknes s o f unusua l severity/ ' Her nausea , however , doe s no t appea r t o hav e bee n limite d t o the morning . Eve n whe n he r schedul e wa s adjuste d s o that sh e did no t nee d t o repor t t o wor k unti l noon , sh e frequentl y reported late to work or had to leave early. She was fired th e da y before sh e was to begin he r maternit y leave . Citing a statemen t by her supervisor , Troupe argue d tha t sh e was fired becaus e he r employer di d no t wan t t o leav e he r positio n ope n durin g he r maternity leave . Th e lowe r cour t grante d th e defendant' s motion fo r summar y judgment, an d Troupe appealed. The cour t of appeal s affirmed , concludin g tha t sh e ha d faile d t o sustai n a prima faci e case o f discriminatio n becaus e "sh e coul d no t fin d one nonpregnant employe e o f Lord & Taylor who had no t bee n fired whe n abou t t o begin a leave simila r i n lengt h t o hers. " The ton e o f th e Troupe opinio n i s t o plac e al l th e blam e o n plaintiff fo r her problems at work and in litigation. For example, the cour t explain s he r "mornin g sickness " b y suggestin g tha t she caused it to last until noon "because she slept later under th e new schedule , s o tha t noo n wa s 'morning ' fo r her. " O f course , the cour t doe s not explai n wh y sh e also frequently ha d t o leav e

120

Family and Medical Leave

work earl y owin g t o he r nausea . Wa s sh e nappin g a t th e cos metic counter ? As fo r he r inabilit y t o provide comparativ e evi dence of discrimination, th e cour t " doubt [s] that findin g a comparison group would be that difficult Sh e either did not look , or di d no t find/ ' Bu t wha t wa s sh e suppose d t o find— a non pregnant employe e wit h a sudde n recor d o f tardines s afte r a nearly spotles s wor k recor d wh o als o ha d schedule d a length y leave? Othe r tha n a pregnan t woman , i t i s har d t o imagin e a similar subject . Yet Troupe is blamed fo r no t looking, just a s she was blamed fo r havin g nause a beyon d th e mornin g hours . It i s also no t clea r wh y sh e shoul d b e compare d wit h a "tardy " employee because the record suggests that the plaintiff di d offe r medical justification s fo r he r lateness . Thus , unde r th e employer's ow n wor k rules , Troupe's latenes s shoul d hav e bee n considered excuse d rathe r tha n unexcuse d absences. 41 The ton e o f th e court' s opinio n i s not surprisin g give n Judg e Posner's admitte d stereotypica l view s o f pregnan t women . I n a 1989 law review article, he professed th e belief tha t "child-rear ing is an area where nature dominate s culture " and that se x discrimination i s no t a likel y explanatio n fo r women' s depresse d wages a t th e workplace. 42 Posne r wa s therefor e willin g t o assume tha t plaintif f Troupe' s "nature " cause d he r problem s a t the workplac e rathe r tha n he r employer' s discriminator y atti tudes. A sympatheti c economi c perspectiv e migh t hav e aske d wha t business justificatio n a n employe r coul d hav e fo r dismissin g Troupe a day before he r pregnanc y leav e would begi n (an d he r tardiness woul d certainl y end) . Sinc e sh e ha d a satisfactor y work recor d befor e becomin g pregnant , i t i s highl y likel y tha t she woul d hav e returne d t o wor k wit h a satisfactor y wor k record afte r th e completio n o f he r pregnanc y leave . If th e pur -

Family and Medical Leave

121

pose o f punitiv e actio n agains t employee s i s t o correc t thei r behavior, i t appear s tha t Lor d & Taylor ha d littl e caus e fo r con cern i n Troupe' s case . B y voluntaril y acceptin g a part-tim e schedule an d makin g ever y effor t t o be o n tim e despit e terribl e nausea, Troupe demonstrate d tha t sh e was a devoted employe e who coul d no t affor d t o qui t he r job . Bu t th e Sevent h Circui t sympathized entirel y wit h th e defendan t employer , thereb y blaming Troupe fo r being lazy. The capitalist la w and economic s orientation o f Judg e Posne r an d hi s associate s o n th e Sevent h Circuit apparently made it impossible for them t o judge the cas e from an y perspectiv e othe r tha n tha t o f th e employer . (On e must als o wonde r wh y a n entit y tha t specialize s i n sellin g women's clothin g woul d wan t t o hur t it s publi c imag e b y fla grantly mistreatin g a female employee. ) In fact , however , comparativ e evidenc e i s no t require d i n al l PDA cases; direct evidence of pregnancy-related animu s can also prove unlawfu l discrimination . Ha d Posne r no t insiste d o n a n unreasonably narro w interpretation o f the PDA, direct evidenc e of pregnanc y animu s shoul d hav e brough t th e cas e to th e jur y (or judge) fo r ultimat e decisio n unde r wha t i s termed a mixedmotives theory —that a n impermissibl e facto r alon g wit h a n arguably permissibl e facto r motivate d he r discharge. 43 Instead , the Sevent h Circui t neve r eve n considere d th e possibilit y o f a mixed-motives theory , pretending tha t th e PD A permits a find ing o f liabilit y onl y throug h th e introductio n o f comparativ e evidence.44 Although th e Troupe cas e is technically a termination case , it can also be seen as a pregnancy leav e case. Troupe was doing he r utmost t o maintain pai d employment unti l the date of her preg nancy leav e (whe n sh e woul d mos t likel y no t b e earnin g com pensation). Her tardines s an d earl y departure s fro m wor k sug -

122

Family and Medical Leave

gest tha t pai d employmen t ha d becom e extremel y difficul t fo r her. Ye t sh e continue d t o tr y t o work . Why ? Sh e probabl y needed th e money , especiall y anticipatin g he r increase d cost s and forthcomin g leav e o f absenc e du e t o childbirth . The conse quence o f th e discharg e wa s t o leav e he r withou t a jo b upo n completing he r pregnanc y leave . In othe r words , her employe r made i t impossibl e fo r he r t o combin e jo b securit y an d chil d care. The pric e o f he r decisio n t o tak e maternit y leav e afte r th e birth o f her chil d was her employment . If her terminatio n wer e lawful, eve n th e FML A would no t protec t he r righ t t o return t o work afte r a n unpai d pregnanc y leave . Whereas the Seventh Circui t narrowly construe d pregnanc y discrimination case s t o preclud e wome n fro m receivin g an y mandated accommodation s durin g thei r pregnancy , som e Canadian court s hav e broadl y interprete d thei r ow n compara ble statut e t o requir e accommodation . Fo r example , i n Emrick Plastics v. Ontario, 45 a n Ontari o cour t applie d a reasonabl e accommodation mode l t o th e case o f a pregnan t woma n wh o sought reassignmen t t o avoi d workin g i n a n are a wher e sh e would b e expose d t o fume s fro m spra y paint . Applying a dis parate impac t model , th e cour t conclude d tha t a failur e t o accommodate pregnan t wome n woul d effectivel y exclud e th e employment o f pregnant spra y painter s an d therefor e violate d the rul e agains t se x discrimination foun d i n the Huma n Right s Code. The cour t impose d o n th e employe r th e burde n o f justi fying th e failure t o accommodate a s reasonable and bona fide i n the circumstances . This resul t wa s achieved without relyin g o n any statutor y reasonabl e accommodatio n language ; it was sim ply a n interpretatio n o f settle d case la w unde r th e Huma n Rights Code . Like the PDA , the Ontari o Huma n Right s Act an d th e Cana -

Family and Medical Leave

123

dian Human Right s Cod e state that pregnancy-based discrimina tion i s sex discrimination. The Canadia n statute s contai n n o rea sonable accommodatio n requiremen t for pregnanc y o r se x dis crimination.46 Ye t th e court s hav e implie d a resasonabl e accom modation requirement . The Canadia n courts , however, hav e no t been uniformly flexible i n providing accommodations that would benefit th e fetu s o r newborn. For example, in Re Ontario Hydro and Canadian Union of Public Employees, Local 1000, 47 an arbi tration pane l refused t o grant a man's reques t fo r paternit y leav e following th e birt h o f hi s secon d child . He wa s expecte d t o fin d paid chil d car e fo r hi s childre n whil e hi s wif e wa s incapacitate d because of her deliver y rathe r tha n t o provide that car e himself. In cas e after case in th e Unite d States , judges wh o subscrib e to the philosophy o f laissez-faire capitalis m rende r narrow decisions i n discriminatio n case s that fai l t o protect th e interest s o f pregnant wome n o r thei r newborns . Thes e theorist s ofte n opposed th e adoptio n o f th e PD A an d FMLA , and thei r judicia l decisions reflect a total disregard fo r th e substantive protection s offered b y those statutes . Special Treatment Cases. Eve n whe n th e PD A wa s flexibly interpreted to , arguably, accommodat e specia l treatment , i t di d so under the guise of considering only the needs of the pregnan t woman. That is , the fact s wer e distorte d t o hide th e actua l ben efits t o the child . In California Federal Savings & Loan Association v. Guerra, 48 th e U.S . Suprem e Cour t wa s face d wit h whether California' s Fai r Employmen t an d Housin g Ac t wa s inconsistent wit h th e PDA 49 b y requirin g tha t Californi a employers offe r wome n fou r month s o f unpai d disabilit y leav e following th e birt h o f a child eve n i f the y di d no t offe r disabil ity leav e fo r an y othe r condition . Thi s wa s dubbe d a "specia l

124

Family and Medical Leave

treatment" cas e because Californi a wa s requirin g tha t a benefi t be provide d t o (formerly ) pregnan t wome n tha t wa s no t pro vided to othe r employees . The U.S. Supreme Cour t interprete d th e PDA to permit suc h "special treatment " whil e als o definin g th e specia l treatmen t narrowly t o includ e onl y th e interest s o f th e pregnan t woman . "We emphasiz e th e limite d natur e o f th e benefit s §i2945(b)(2 ) provides. The statute is narrowly drawn to cover only the perio d of actual physical disability o n account of pregnancy, childbirth , or relate d medica l conditions." 50 The language o f the statute an d facts o f the case, however, ar e inconsistent wit h thi s interpretatio n o f th e statute . The statut e required up to four months of leave following the birth of a child, which it termed "disabilit y leave." Yet there was no requiremen t that th e woma n provid e medica l certificatio n fo r thi s leave . The court o f appeal' s opinio n reflect s tha t Lillia n Garlan d "too k a four-month pregnanc y disability leave" but contains no evidence that sh e ha d a medica l reaso n fo r fou r month s o f leave. 51 O f course, it i s possibl e tha t sh e ha d substantia l medica l complica tions following th e birth of her child, but it is far more likely that she coul d no t fin d an y suitabl e alternativ e chil d car e arrange ment fo r tha t tim e perio d an d decide d tha t i t wa s i n th e bes t interest o f th e chil d fo r he r t o sta y hom e an d suppl y tha t car e herself. Interestingly, the Seventh Circui t presumed that wome n need onl y te n day s t o recove r fro m childbirth , wherea s th e Supreme Cour t fantasize d tha t i t take s women' s bodie s fou r months t o recove r fro m childbirth . Accordingly , th e Suprem e Court ignore d a likel y rational e o f th e Californi a statute—t o facilitate chil d care in the first fou r month s o f a child's life. Thus, the Suprem e Court' s "specia l treatment " holdin g ignore d th e real beneficiaries o f special treatment—the children .

Family and Medical Leave

125

Canadian courts have not been hampered by the special treat ment/equal treatmen t debate . For example , in Alberta Hospital Association v. Parcels, 52 th e Albert a Cour t o f Queen' s Benc h was confronted wit h th e questio n o f whether i t was discrimina tory t o den y sic k leave benefits t o women wh o wer e o n mater nity leave . Sic k leav e benefit s wer e somewha t mor e generou s than maternit y benefits , bu t a s in th e Maganuco case , employ ees wer e no t allowe d t o us e maternit y an d sic k leav e benefit s sequentially. An employe e ha d t o choos e on e o r another . Plain tiff Susa n Parcel s ha d electe d maternit y benefit s becaus e the y were longe r i n duratio n bu t wante d t o tak e advantag e o f sic k leave benefit s fo r tha t perio d o f he r maternit y leav e i n whic h she was physically incapacitated . The Alberta cour t foun d tha t Parcel s did have a valid clai m of sex discrimination becaus e the employer's policy posed a burden to wome n a t th e workplace . Th e employe r wa s no t entitle d t o consider maternit y leav e a s onl y a n exampl e o f genera l non health-related leav e withou t recognizin g it s uniqu e health related aspects . The cour t rule d tha t maternit y leav e " cannot b e neatly pigeon-hole d becaus e o f it s hybri d nature . . . . I t i s a unique situation. As a result, maternity leav e should be remove d from th e leav e of absence article in the collectiv e agreement an d placed i n a category b y itself/ ' Rathe r tha n adop t a comparativ e approach, the Alberta cour t analyze d th e situatio n fro m th e per spective o f the well-being o f both women an d children . [Tjhose wh o bea r childre n an d benefi t societ y a s a whol e should not be economically o r socially disadvantaged b y thi s activity. . . . [I] t is unfair t o impose all of the costs of procreation on one-half o f the population. The function o f anti-discrimination legislatio n i s to remove thi s unfair burde n fro m women.

126

Family and Medical Leave

Women wil l stil l b e th e one s wh o underg o th e physica l an d emotional burdens o f pregnancy, but th e Parcels decisions help s spread those burdens throughou t society . PROTECTING TH E FETU S DURIN G PREGNANC Y

In those cases that have directly raised the issue of the health of fetuses—cases involvin g reproductiv e hazard s a t th e work place—U.S. court s hav e amazingl y manage d t o decid e thes e cases withou t reall y offerin g an y meaningfu l protectio n t o fetuses. Thes e case s hav e require d th e court s t o interpre t th e Occupational Safet y an d Health Administration (OSHA ) o r th e PDA. I n Oil, Chemical and Atomic Workers International Union v. American Cyanamid Company, 53 th e D.C . Cour t o f Appeals, consisting o f Judge s Rober t Bork , Antonin Scalia , an d Stephen Williams, ruled tha t American Cynami d Compan y di d not violat e OSH A b y creatin g a rule tha t femal e employee s o f childbearing ag e could no t hol d jobs tha t expose d the m t o hig h levels o f lead unless the y coul d sho w tha t the y ha d bee n surgi cally sterilized. Because surgical sterilization i s a medical procedure tha t ca n b e physicall y harmfu l t o a woman , OSH A ha d found tha t America n Cyanami d ha d violate d th e genera l dut y clause o f th e Occupationa l Safet y an d Healt h Ac t b y failin g t o "furnish employmen t an d a plac e o f employmen t whic h wer e free fro m recognize d hazards that were causing or were likely to cause death o r seriou s physical harm t o employees/' 54 The D.C. Court o f Appeal s affirme d th e decisio n o f th e Occupationa l Safety an d Healt h Revie w Commission , whic h ha d foun d tha t American Cyanami d ha d no t violate d OSHA' s genera l dut y clause because "a n employee' s decisio n t o undergo sterilizatio n in orde r t o gai n o r retai n employmen t grow s ou t o f economi c and socia l factor s whic h operat e primaril y outsid e th e work -

Family and Medical Leave

127

place. The employer neithe r control s nor create s these factors a s he create s o r control s work processe s an d materials/ ' Like the Seventh Circuit' s decision in Maganuco, th e D.C. Circuit hel d tha t women' s "choices " canno t subjec t employer s t o legal liability Just as the plaintiff Maganuc o could have "chosen " to return to work ten days after givin g birth without jeopardizing her employmen t situation , the plaintiffs i n American Cyanamid could hav e "chosen " t o see k employmen t elsewher e rathe r tha n jeopardize their health through a sterilization operation. Employers ar e not responsibl e fo r th e chil d car e problems o f a newbor n infant o r th e healt h consequence s o f sterilization . A s lon g a s women hav e genuin e "choices, " w e canno t hol d employer s responsible fo r th e socia l consequences o f their decisions . Because th e American Cyanamid decisio n tolerate d th e exclusion o f wome n fro m th e workplac e a s a solutio n t o th e problem o f reproductive hazards, it set the stage for a PDA challenge to this policy Amazingly, the Suprem e Cour t manage d t o decide the PD A case without considerin g th e health interest s o f the fetu s a t all . I n International Union v. Johnson Controls, 55 the Suprem e Cour t rule d tha t Johnso n Control s violate d th e PDA b y excludin g fro m lead-expose d job s wome n wit h child bearing capacity . This resul t seem s appropriat e unde r th e U.S . perspective tha t trie s t o ignor e tha t pregnan t wome n usuall y give birt h t o a child . Federa l antidiscriminatio n law , however , requires u s t o vie w th e pregnan t woma n i n isolatio n fro m th e fetus o r newbor n child . Thus, the Suprem e Cour t ca n rul e tha t employers ma y no t exclud e wome n fro m th e workplac e ou t o f concern fo r thei r reproductiv e healt h whil e no t providin g women with any acceptable, safe option s at the workplace. After Johnson Controls, a woma n mus t choos e betwee n unemploy ment an d workin g i n a n environmen t wher e sh e migh t expos e

128

Family and Medical Leave

a fetus t o harm. The employe r i s under n o obligatio n t o accom modate th e need s o f wome n b y makin g th e workplac e safe . I t can simply requir e he r t o sig n a waiver disclaimin g her righ t t o sue if a disabled chil d is born a s a result o f reproductive hazard s at the workplace . Other countrie s hav e sough t t o solv e th e proble m o f repro ductive hazard s a t th e workplac e throug h direc t regulatio n rather tha n leavin g th e solutio n t o th e privat e marketplac e o f coerced consent . I n Finland , fo r example , pregnant worker s ar e entitled to a special, paid maternity leave if the employer canno t ensure tha t th e workplace meet s a minimum leve l o f safet y fo r the fetus. 56 The Europea n Unio n ha s adopted a directive requir ing th e removal , bu t wit h n o reductio n i n pay , o f pregnan t o r breast-feeding wome n fro m position s entailin g exposur e t o fetal healt h hazards. 57 The United States' failure t o find a n acceptable solution to the problem o f reproductiv e hazard s a t th e workplac e i s sympto matic o f it s unwillingnes s t o mandat e an y accommodation s fo r pregnant women in the workplace. The PDA is, at most, an equa l treatment mode l fo r pregnan t women . Tha t is , the y mus t b e treated th e sam e a s similarl y situated , nonpregnan t employees . The PD A therefor e impose s n o dut y t o accommodat e pregnan t women i f th e employe r doe s no t hav e a policy o f accommodat ing other workers with health- or family-related problems . Thus, an employe r ha s n o responsibilit y t o excus e a pregnan t nurs e from treatin g patients in isolation who might expose the fetus t o harm, eve n whe n a n accommodatio n coul d easil y b e mad e tha t would permit the pregnant woman to continue working safely. 58 In on e cas e involvin g a pregnan t nurse , th e plaintif f argue d that a failur e t o modif y he r wor k assignment s whil e pregnan t would force her t o "choose betwee n her job and the health o f th e

Family and Medical Leave

129

fetus."59 I n th e nam e o f forma l equality , th e Elevent h Circui t Court o f Appeals foun d tha t suc h a "choice" was consistent wit h federal antidiscriminatio n law : "Based o n th e fact s o f this case , a pregnant employee, concerned about these increased risks yet still able to continue t o work, is faced with a difficult choice . It is precisely thi s choice , however difficult , tha t i s reserved t o th e preg nant employe e unde r th e PD A an d Johnson Controls/' U.S . law imposes no duty on employers to make workplaces saf e for preg nant women while at the same time allowing pregnant women t o "choose" t o wor k i n environment s tha t pos e risk s t o th e fetus . That "choice " is suppose d t o be a positive expressio n o f ou r for mal equality principl e because a s the Elevent h Circui t noted , th e "[pjlaintiff's claim s of discrimination ar e more accurately viewed as an effort t o secure preferential treatmen t for pregnant employ ees." But o f course , it is the fetus , not th e pregnant woman , wh o needs specia l treatmen t becaus e i t i s th e fetus , no t th e pregnan t woman, who faces ill health effects fro m opportunisti c infections . Similarly, i n case s i n whic h pregnan t wome n wan t t o per form lighte r wor k i n orde r t o avoi d a miscarriage, they ar e pri marily concerne d abou t th e healt h o f th e fetus , no t thei r ow n health. Federal law offers suc h women n o statutory entitlemen t to a work environmen t tha t i s saf e fo r th e fetus. 60 Onl y a society that operates from a laissez-faire economi c perspective coul d fail t o systematically protec t th e well-being o f women an d chil dren throug h law .

Family Medical an d Leav e Act STATUTORY LANGUAGE

The Americans with Disabilitie s Act was one of the first statute s explicitly to provide accommodations fo r some employees in pri-

130

Family and Medical Leave

vate workplaces. Employees who wanted t o miss work to receiv e medical treatment o r recove r fro m illness , however, have gener ally no t foun d th e court s receptiv e t o thei r accommodatio n requests. If the y ar e repeatedl y absen t fro m work , the y ar e no t considered t o b e "qualified " fo r employment. 61 (B y contrast , Canadian court s ofte n fin d tha t employee s wit h significan t absentee record s ca n still receive the protection o f disability dis crimination law.) 62 And workers who canno t fi t th e definitio n o f a "person with a disability/' suc h as pregnant women o r worker s with temporar y medica l conditions , canno t mak e a clai m fo r accommodation unde r th e ADA.63 Similarly, the Pregnancy Discrimination Amendment t o Title VII protects against pregnancy based discriminatio n bu t doe s no t us e a n affirmativ e actio n o r reasonable accommodatio n mode l fo r pregnan t women . I t i s modeled entirel y o n a "formal equality " perspective o n discrim ination, thereb y requirin g pregnan t wome n t o b e treate d th e same a s similarl y situate d men , who m I hav e elsewher e calle d "pregnant men " to emphasize thei r nonexistence. 64 Because o f th e absenc e o f statutor y protectio n fo r worker s who nee d t o mis s wor k becaus e o f illnes s o r family-relate d responsibilities, i n th e lat e 1980 s Congres s bega n t o conside r proposals fo r a federa l leav e statute . The ultimat e outcom e o f this discussio n wa s th e Famil y an d Medica l Leav e Act o f 199 3 (FMLA),65 whic h give s eligibl e employees 66 o f a covere d employer 67 th e righ t t o tak e unpai d leav e fo r a period o f u p t o twelve workweeks i n any twelve-month perio d fo r on e or mor e of the followin g reasons : (A) Because of the birth of a son or daughter of the employee and in order to take care of such son or daughter . (B) Because o f th e placemen t o f a son o r daughte r wit h th e employee for adoptio n o r foster care .

Family and Medical Leave

131

(C) In order to care for the spouse, or a son, daughter, or parent, o f th e employee , i f suc h spouse , son , daughter , o r parent ha s a serious health condition . (D) Because o f a seriou s healt h conditio n tha t make s th e employee unable to perform th e functions o f the position of such employee . The statut e define s a "seriou s healt h condition " a s a n "ill ness, injury , impairment , o r physica l o r menta l conditio n tha t involves (A ) inpatien t car e i n a hospital, hospice , o r residentia l medical car e facility ; o r (B ) continuin g treatmen t b y a healt h care provider. " Par t (A ) o f th e definitio n i s relativel y eas y t o interpret, a s i t seem s t o requir e a n overnigh t sta y a t a medica l institution. Par t (B) , however, i s more ambiguou s an d ha s bee n interpreted throug h regulation s promulgate d b y th e Depart ment o f Labor . These regulation s specif y tha t a medical condi tion constitute s "continuin g treatmen t b y a healt h car e provider" i f it involve s (1) a period o f incapacity . . . o f more than thre e consecutiv e calendar days, and any subsequent treatment o r period of incapacity relatin g t o th e sam e condition , tha t als o involves: (a) treatment two or more times by a health care provider ... o r (b) treatmen t b y a healt h car e provide r o n a t leas t on e occasion whic h result s i n a regimen o f continuin g treat ment under th e supervision o f the health car e provider. (2) any period of incapacity due to pregnancy, or for prenata l care. (3) any period o f incapacity o r treatment fo r suc h incapacit y due to a chronic serious healt h condition . A chronic serious health conditio n is one which:

132

Family and Medical Leave

(a) requires periodi c visits fo r treatmen t b y a health car e provider. . . . (b) continues over an extended period of time . . . and (c) may caus e episodic rather tha n a continuing period of incapacity. . . . (4) a period o f incapacit y whic h i s permanen t o r long-ter m due to a condition fo r which treatment ma y not be effec tive. The employee o r family membe r mus t b e under th e continuing supervision of , bu t need not be receiving active treatment by, a health care provider... . (5) any perio d o f absenc e t o receiv e multipl e treatment s (including any period of recovery therefrom) b y a health care provide r . . . either fo r restorativ e surger y afte r a n accident o r injury , o r fo r a conditio n tha t woul d likel y result in a period of incapacity of more than three consecutive calendar days in the absence of medical intervention or treatment. 68 Although th e FML A wa s passe d despit e stron g oppositio n b y the business community , i t has, in fact , provide d littl e job secu rity fo r man y employee s wit h famil y o r medica l leav e request s for accommodation . The terms o f the statute , coupled with nar row judicial interpretations, hav e cause d this result . The terms of the statute expressl y provide only limited cover age. Onl y person s wh o hav e worke d fo r thei r employe r fo r a t least on e yea r ar e covered , an d onl y employer s wit h mor e tha n fifty employee s ar e covered. Individuals ar e also excluded if the y are among the top 10 percent in salary and benefits compensatio n at a particular wor k site . The statut e therefor e cover s only 5 percent of corporations in the United States. 69 And of that 5 percent, only one-third were actually required to make adjustments t o be in complianc e wit h th e act. 70 And o f course , the leav e i s unpaid , which make s i t financiall y infeasibl e fo r man y employees . B y

Family and Medical Leave

133

contrast, European countries, as well as Great Britain and Canada , offer pai d leave . For example, the typica l Europea n countr y pro vides six weeks o f paid sick leave, usually a t 100 percent o f gros s earnings.71 This leave is in addition to paid maternity an d parent ing leave, as well as unpaid sic k leave, usually fo r u p to a year. Family leav e t o car e fo r childre n unde r th e FML A i s limite d to the first yea r of the child's life (o r placement with the family ) unless th e chil d has a "serious healt h condition. " Thus, a parent who ha s chil d car e problems afte r th e firs t yea r o f a child's lif e can rarel y tak e advantag e o f th e statute' s protections . Beyon d the child' s firs t yea r o f life , leav e i s limite d t o " serious healt h conditions," whic h th e court s hav e interprete d a s no t coverin g many o f th e healt h condition s tha t caus e many parent s t o mis s work t o care for thei r children . CASE LA W

Serious Health Conditions. Th e legislatur e histor y an d regula tions concernin g th e definitio n o f "seriou s healt h conditions " suggest tha t neithe r Congres s no r th e Department o f Labor ha s done a good job i n constructin g a definition tha t woul d provid e meaningful protectio n t o worker s wh o fac e jo b securit y issue s because o f healt h impairment s o f themselve s o r thei r children . The Senat e Report , for example , states tha t the ter m "seriou s healt h condition " i s not intende d t o cove r short-term condition s fo r whic h treatmen t an d recovery ar e very brief. It is expected that suc h conditions will fall withi n even the most modest sick leave policies. Conditions or medical procedure s tha t woul d no t normall y b e covere d b y th e legislation include minor illnesses which last only a few days and surgical procedures which typically do not involve hospitalization an d require only a brief recover y period. 72

134

Family and Medical Leave

The Senat e Repor t the n offer s example s o f suc h conditions . Many o f the examples—"heart attacks , heart condition s requir ing hear t bypas s o f valv e operations , mos t cancers , back condi tions requirin g extensiv e therap y o r surgica l procedures , strokes, sever e respirator y conditions , spina l injuries"—fre quently require far more than twelve weeks of leave from work , especially i f th e employe e ha s alread y use d u p som e FML A leave before selectin g a course o f treatment fo r th e condition . The coverag e o f leave during pregnanc y i s ambiguous unde r the FMLA . Obviously, the FML A covers leave fo r eithe r paren t following th e birt h o f a child, but i t i s no t s o clear a s t o ho w i t treats leave during pregnancy. The Senat e Report' s list of possible "seriou s healt h conditions " include s "ongoin g pregnancy , miscarriages, complications o r illness related to pregnancy, suc h as severe morning sickness, the need for prenatal care, childbirth and recovery fro m childbirth. " The regulations promulgate d b y the Departmen t o f Labor , however , d o no t regar d "ongoin g pregnancy" a s a sufficien t basi s fo r medica l leave . Instead, th e regulations stat e tha t ther e mus t b e a "period o f incapacit y du e to pregnancy, o r fo r prenata l care." 73 The court s hav e therefor e interpreted th e FML A a s requirin g a woma n t o hav e medica l proof tha t he r pregnanc y i s abnorma l an d incapacitatin g i n order for her to invoke FMLA leave before delivery . Thus, plaintiff Michael a Gudenkau f wa s found no t t o be eligible for FML A protection whe n sh e requeste d part-tim e wor k followin g a n episode of contractions in what her physician classifie d a s a normal pregnancy. 74 Th e medica l mode l underlyin g th e FML A therefore display s littl e concer n fo r th e norma l discomfort s o f pregnancy, despit e it s allege d concer n fo r th e burden s o f preg nancy an d childbirth . The Departmen t o f Labor' s regulation s cove r condition s

Family and Medical Leave

135

lasting more than three consecutive calendar days but als o state that th e regulation s ordinaril y exclude , "unles s complication s arise, the common cold , the flu, ea r aches." A flu patient may , of course, be sic k fo r a week, an d a child wit h a n earach e ma y b e home fro m chil d car e fo r severa l days , but bot h condition s ar e excluded fro m th e regulations . The regulation s d o not mentio n common childhoo d illnesse s suc h a s diarrhea, chicke n pox , an d "pink eye, " whic h ma y requir e exclusio n fro m chil d car e ye t not nee d continuin g treatmen t b y a healt h car e provider . Th e assumption i s that employer s woul d no t fir e parent s wh o hav e periodic needs to stay home an d care for childre n with commo n childhood illnesses . Th e FML A help s parent s stayin g hom e with their children during the first yea r of the child's life (whe n they ca n tak e twelv e week s o f leav e withou t demonstratin g that th e chil d is ill) but doe s little fo r parent s whe n th e chil d i s likely to be attending grou p da y car e or preschool an d is at sig nificant ris k o f contractin g childhoo d diseases . An d whe n a n employee misse s wor k t o car e fo r a terminall y il l parent , th e FMLA covers his o r her absenc e unti l th e paren t dies . No leav e is availabl e fo r th e time-consumin g activitie s relatin g t o th e funeral an d estate. 75 The assumptio n tha t employer s woul d no t fir e parent s wh o miss wor k t o tak e car e o f childre n wit h commo n childhoo d ill nesses i s no t born e ou t i n th e cas e law . For example , OshKos h B'Gosh, a manufacture r o f children' s clothing , trie d t o termi nate Lill y Cris p afte r sh e staye d hom e wit h he r three-year-ol d daughter wh o had had a persistently hig h feve r fo r severa l day s and ha d bee n unde r a doctor' s car e durin g a visi t t o a n emer gency room. 76 Cris p wa s abl e t o prevai l i n a FML A challenge , since th e medica l record s demonstrate d tha t th e daughte r ha d had a persistent feve r fo r severa l day s an d was under a doctor' s

136

Family and Medical Leave

care, but sh e was not abl e to get FML A protection fo r sic k leave a mont h earlie r whe n sh e ha d flulike symptom s an d misse d three day s o f work . Despit e a physician' s testimon y tha t i t would b e reasonable t o be absen t fro m wor k fo r thre e an d one half day s wit h suc h a n illnes s (especiall y sinc e on e o f th e pre scribed medications migh t hav e affecte d he r abilit y t o operate a sewing machine safel y a t work), the cour t foun d tha t Cris p ha d not sustaine d he r burden o f proof tha t sh e did not work becaus e of a seriou s healt h condition . I n bot h instances , th e plaintif f faced th e sam e problem—a n employe r wit h a n inflexibl e leav e policy—but on e o f he r request s fo r leav e fel l o n th e sid e o f statutory protectio n an d th e othe r di d not . Numerous othe r plaintiff s hav e los t case s despit e bein g dis charged fro m wor k becaus e o f thei r ow n o r a family member' s medical problems , becaus e the y coul d no t mee t th e "seriou s health condition" hurdle. Chronic sinusitis bronchitis, 77 a child's ear infection, 78 an d foo d poisoning 79 hav e bee n foun d no t t o constitute a "seriou s healt h condition, " althoug h i n eac h case , the employe e ha d littl e choic e bu t t o mis s wor k i n respons e t o the healt h condition . I t wa s no t sufficientl y seriou s t o evok e statutory coverage , but it was sufficiently seriou s to cause thes e people to lose their jobs. The burden-of-proo f rule s impose d o n th e plaintif f i n th e OshKosh cas e also ar e insensitiv e t o th e realitie s o f th e live s of employees wh o nee d FML A protection . Th e regulation s pre sume tha t individual s hav e doctor s whom the y se e for continu ing supervisio n whe n the y hav e healt h car e problems . I n th e Oshkosh case , for example , the plaintiffs daughte r sa w a physician at the emergenc y roo m o f the local hospital fo r a conditio n that probabl y di d not requir e emergenc y treatment . The plain tiff di d se e a physician i n hi s offic e fo r he r earlie r illness , but i t

Family and Medical Leave

137

also appear s tha t sh e di d no t hav e a close personal relationshi p with th e physician . H e wa s abl e t o testif y onl y abou t wha t hi s notes disclose d from th e visit; he had no personal memory o f it . Because of the vagueness o f his notes and recollection, the cour t found tha t the plaintiff ha d not sustaine d her burden o f proof o f showing tha t sh e had had a serious healt h conditio n durin g he r absence fro m work . Regardles s o f ho w sic k th e plaintif f ha d been a t tha t time , it i s hard t o imagine tha t sh e coul d hav e me t her burde n o f proo f unles s sh e visite d a hospita l emergenc y room. Repeated studie s hav e show n tha t poo r peopl e receiv e infe rior medical care, compared with middle-class people, regardless of whethe r the y hav e healt h insurance. 80 Furthermore , th e FMLA embodie s a middle-clas s expectatio n fo r th e doctor patient relationship . Bu t ironically , middle-clas s person s ar e likely t o hav e libera l leav e policie s a t wor k an d n o nee d t o us e the FMLA . Instead , i t i s working-clas s employee s lik e Penn y Brandon wh o nee d t o us e th e FMLA , an d the y hav e troubl e complying wit h th e medica l mode l tha t underlie s th e FMLA. 81 Brandon an d othe r FML A plaintiff s frequentl y us e hospita l emergency room s fo r routin e medica l problem s rathe r tha n a private physicia n wit h who m the y hav e a long-standin g rela tionship. 82 To comply with the FMLA, they are required to make two visits t o the docto r fo r condition s suc h a s chicken pox—fo r which doctor' s visit s ar e usuall y no t encouraged . Bu t i f the y miss wor k fo r mor e tha n thre e day s an d fai l t o visi t a docto r twice, the n the y ma y b e denie d statutor y coverage . Thus , William Georg e prevaile d unde r th e FML A fo r hi s si x day s o f leave t o recove r fro m chicke n po x becaus e h e visite d bot h th e hospital emergenc y roo m an d a clini c thereafter , bu t Audre y Seidle wa s no t abl e t o prevai l becaus e he r so n visite d a docto r

138

Family and Medical Leave

only on e tim e t o b e treate d fo r hi s ea r infection. 83 I n anothe r case, Christopher Baue r was unable to demonstrate tha t his rectal bleedin g constitute d a seriou s healt h conditio n becaus e h e missed hi s secon d doctor' s appointmen t i n orde r t o avoi d bein g absent fro m wor k i n violation o f company policy. 84 Ironically, i t i s the Unite d States—whic h relie s primaril y o n private healt h car e fo r th e treatmen t o f employees—tha t imposes such stringent certificatio n requirement s o n employee s seeking t o tak e illness-relate d leave . N o paralle l rule s exis t i n Canada o r Europea n countrie s wher e a syste m o f nationa l health insuranc e als o exists . Th e FML A primaril y cover s employers wh o provide th e most minima l benefit s a t the work place (most likely not including health insurance ) an d then ask s those employees to document the illnesses—for whic h they will have t o bea r th e documentatio n expenses . I n othe r words , th e FMLA is premised o n a different healt h deliver y mode l tha n i n fact exist s fo r working-clas s employees . It i s als o extremel y difficul t fo r employee s t o mee t th e cau sation standard s require d unde r th e FML A t o sho w tha t thei r use o f thei r right s unde r th e FML A motivate d a discharge . Applying th e rigid burden-of-proof rule s develope d under Titl e VII, courts ar e requiring direc t evidenc e o f a n illegal motive fo r an employe e t o prevai l unde r th e FMLA . Circumstantia l evi dence i s insufficient . Thus , Donal d Day' s evidenc e tha t h e wa s discharged o n th e da y tha t h e returne d t o full-tim e wor k fol lowing hear t surger y wa s insufficien t t o prov e a n illega l dis charge unde r th e FMLA. 85 Th e federa l cour t insiste d tha t i n order t o prevail, Day should be able to produce "admissibl e evi dence, based o n persona l knowledge/ ' Employees , however, ar e unlikely t o have stronge r evidenc e tha n tha t the y wer e fire d a s soon a s the employe r learne d the y ha d a serious healt h condi -

Family and Medical Leave

139

tion, since employees ar e rarely a t meetings a t which suc h decisions ar e made . Even whe n defendant s conced e tha t th e plaintiffs ' reques t triggered thei r discharg e decision , courts hav e ruled agains t th e plaintiffs unde r the FMLA. For example, Pat Tuberville was fire d two day s befor e sh e wa s schedule d fo r a hysterectomy. 86 I n accordance wit h th e FMLA , sh e ha d give n he r employe r thre e weeks' notic e o f he r nee d fo r surgery . He r employe r the n use d this notice as an excuse to terminate her, the rationale being tha t Tuberville wa s o n notic e tha t sh e woul d b e discharge d unles s her offic e improve d it s wor k performance . " Since th e plaintif f would b e on leav e the fina l tw o weeks o f the month an d unabl e to assis t i n turnin g th e offic e around/ ' i t decide d t o discharg e her whe n he r leav e wa s schedule d t o commence . Although th e court conclude d "tha t th e timing o f the leave was a major facto r used i n makin g th e terminatio n decision, " i t rule d agains t th e plaintiff becaus e i t conclude d tha t sh e woul d hav e nonetheles s been eventuall y discharged . Onerou s proo f rule s ca n therefor e undermine statutor y guidelines . In Europ e an d Canada , b y contrast , thes e statutor y mini mums ar e usuall y writte n int o th e union-employmen t con tract. Whe n German y trie d t o cu t bac k it s compensatio n fo r sick leave , th e union s challenge d wha t the y perceive d t o b e modifications o f th e employmen t contract. 87 Similarly , th e unions hav e responde d wit h widesprea d strike s whe n Franc e has tried to cut back on employment rights . But the highly cap italistic structur e o f th e Unite d State s mean s tha t fe w worker s have guarantee d jo b right s an d tha t a union's respons e t o cut backs cannot be anticipated. The employe e ca n use the union t o grieve about a failure t o follow thes e rules . Although th e unio n can both educat e an d advocat e fo r th e employee , because o f th e

140

Family and Medical Leave

decline o f unionizatio n i n th e Unite d States , this possibilit y i s relatively rare . A typica l exampl e i n Canad a tha t wa s resolve d i n th e employee's favo r wa s a dispute betwee n Ann e Frenc h an d Bel l Canada.88 Frenc h wa s fire d afte r takin g severa l week s o f sic k leave whe n sh e wa s experiencin g emotiona l strai n becaus e o f her mother' s seriou s illness. Although he r emotiona l strai n wa s apparently heightene d b y he r heav y drinkin g durin g thi s period, th e employe r di d no t disput e tha t he r emotiona l strai n caused he r t o b e eligibl e fo r illnes s disabilit y benefits . Rather , her employe r criticize d French' s employmen t histor y becaus e she continue d t o work a t he r secon d job durin g thi s perio d an d lied whe n aske d i f sh e ha d a second job. Although Bel l Canad a policy did not forbi d employee s fro m holdin g secon d jobs, it di d forbid the m t o clai m sic k leave o n day s durin g whic h the y ha d worked a t anothe r job . French claime d tha t he r emotiona l dis tress precluded he r fro m answerin g telephon e call s as an opera tor fo r Bel l Canad a bu t di d not preclud e he r fro m workin g i n a solitary positio n durin g th e da y a s a mail carrier . The court' s resolutio n o f th e case reflect s th e way s i n whic h Canada's labo r la w differ s fro m tha t o f th e Unite d States . Th e case i s a labor grievance . Thus, Frenc h ha d a union arguin g o n her behalf (an d presumably without compensation) . French als o had documentatio n fro m a n apparentl y sympatheti c physicia n who woul d hav e treate d he r unde r Canada' s nationa l healt h insurance system . Her famil y docto r wrot e a letter i n which h e stated tha t Frenc h "ha s bee n unabl e t o manag e he r demandin g duties a s a Bell operator, althoug h sh e was stil l quite capable , in my opinion , o f managin g he r les s demandin g dutie s a t Canad a Post." Rather tha n a vague recollection , he offere d specific , use ful informatio n tha t helpe d suppor t he r clai m fo r disabilit y sic k

Family and Medical Leave

141

leave. Finally, th e standar d fo r "illness " allowe d a physician t o make fairl y vagu e supportin g statement s i n orde r fo r a n employee t o qualif y fo r sic k leav e benefits . French' s docto r never eve n gav e he r conditio n a name . H e jus t sai d tha t "thi s lady has been unde r m y care " and tha t "sh e has been unabl e t o manage he r demandin g duties. " N o furthe r documentatio n o f illness wa s required . Althoug h Bel l Canad a employe d it s ow n physician to monitor sic k leave requests, the company physicia n verified he r entitlement t o sick leave without examinin g Frenc h and without speakin g with her family physician . Ultimately, th e plaintiff prevaile d i n thi s cas e because th e cour t di d not believ e that he r conduc t had been intentionall y fraudulen t an d thereb y could no t b e a proper basi s fo r discharge . The burde n o f estab lishing frau d wa s place d o n th e employer , i n shar p contras t t o U.S. cas e law , whic h place s al l th e burden s o f proo f o n th e employee. This decisio n reflect s a very differen t conceptualiza tion of the employer-employee relationshi p than i s embodied i n the United State s under th e FMLA . Twelve Weeks. The FMLA uses one leave period—twelve weeks— which i s suppose d t o b e sufficien t t o protec t worker s fro m dis charge fo r al l thei r famil y an d medica l leav e problems . A woman's pregnanc y leave , a s wel l a s he r famil y an d medica l needs, mus t com e ou t o f thi s twelve-wee k period . Thus , i f sh e finds i t too difficult t o work i n the last month o f her pregnancy , she wil l hav e onl y eigh t week s o f leav e fo r al l he r famil y an d medical need s followin g th e deliver y o f he r child . (I n addition , she may fin d tha t sh e canno t qualif y fo r an y FML A leave unti l the bab y i s born becaus e he r pregnancy—despit e it s man y dis comforts—is considere d t o b e "normal." ) I n compariso n wit h European countries , twelve weeks i s an extremel y sting y num -

142

Family and Medical Leave

ber. Nearly every European country provides at least six months of leave for pregnanc y alone , with som e o f that leav e permitte d before deliver y of the baby. Medical leave and parenting leave is in additio n t o this si x months . Although th e FML A is purportedly geare d t o providing par ents wit h adequat e famil y leave , i t i s har d t o se e ho w twelv e weeks ca n meet tha t nee d i n th e firs t yea r o f a child's life. Afte r a woman has taken a minimum o f six weeks to recover from he r pregnancy, sh e i s left wit h a maximum o f si x weeks o f parent ing an d sic k leave . The twelve-wee k figur e coul d b e see n a s a minimum amoun t o f tim e t o car e fo r th e chil d followin g it s birth befor e a paren t return s t o th e workplace , bu t thi s allow s for n o absences due to the sicknes s of the parent o r child for th e remainder o f the year. No European o r British countr y has suc h an unrealisti c expectatio n o f goo d healt h i n th e firs t yea r o f a child's life. 89 Seventee n o f ninetee n Europea n o r Britis h coun tries provid e fo r pai d sic k leave, with mos t countrie s no t speci fying th e time period fo r suc h leave. Of th e countries tha t spec ify th e lengt h o f leave , onl y on e country—Germany—ha s a limitation equivalen t t o that o f the United States. 90 These coun tries als o offe r sic k leav e i n additio n t o leav e fo r maternit y o r parenting. Th e Unite d States , b y contrast , specifie s a twelve week perio d fo r al l form s o f leav e combined . Th e U.S . mode l presumes tha t mos t wome n d o and ca n work unti l th e momen t they giv e birth. We have impose d tha t rul e o n ou r understand ing of what i s "normal/ ' The existin g twelve-wee k rul e emerge d a s a legislative com promise i n th e earl y stage s o f th e draftin g o f th e FMLA . Th e original bill , introduced b y Congresswoma n Patrici a Schroede r in 1985 , provide d fo r eightee n week s o f unpai d leav e ove r a twenty-four-month perio d for the birth, adoption, or serious ill-

Family and Medical Leave

143

ness o f a child , an d twenty-si x week s o f unpai d leav e ove r twelve-month perio d fo r a n employee' s ow n seriou s healt h condition.91 I n 1987 , thes e tim e period s wer e reduce d t o te n weeks and fiftee n weeks , respectively, but th e two separate tim e periods were maintained. 92 Then in 1989 when the bill was rein troduced, th e tim e period s wer e shortene d t o te n an d thirtee n weeks, respectively93 Finally, when the first floo r vote was taken in the House in 1990, the leaves were combined into one twelveweek leav e perio d pe r year. 94 Thi s bil l wa s twic e passe d b y th e Congress an d vetoe d b y Presiden t Georg e Bush 95 befor e bein g reintroduced afte r Clinto n wa s electe d president. 96 The bill that Clinto n signe d maintained thi s earlie r legislativ e compromise, with no attempt to return th e bill to its more gener ous an d separat e tim e periods . The legislativ e debat e abou t fam ily and medical leave was therefore shape d at an early stage by the expectation tha t ther e woul d b e on e combine d leav e perio d fo r both family an d medical leave. This is a uniquely American com promise and can be described a s a cynical attempt t o pass legisla tion withou t providin g meaningfu l protectio n fo r man y Ameri can workers. Twelve weeks might b e seen a s minimally coverin g the chil d car e obligations immediatel y followin g birt h bu t doin g little t o provid e job securit y t o workin g parent s wh o ma y hav e other famil y o r medica l leav e need s i n th e yea r tha t a chil d i s born. The statut e migh t b e name d th e Famil y or Medical Leav e Statute, bu t i t hardl y ca n b e characterize d a s a statut e tha t responds to both a family's dependen t car e and medical needs. The testimon y offere d b y chil d car e expert s durin g hearing s on th e FML A reflects tha t twelv e weeks i s insufficient eve n fo r parenting leave , let alon e al l combine d leaves . For example , Dr . T. Berry Brazelton, a world-renowned pediatrician , testified tha t a newborn need s a minimum o f four month s o f care from a par-

144

Family and Medical Leave

ent i n orde r fo r appropriat e bondin g t o tak e place. 97 The Advi sory Committe e o n Infan t Car e Leav e o f th e Yale Bush Cente r in Chil d Developmen t an d Socia l Polic y recommende d a mini mum o f six months fo r parenting leave. Others testified tha t th e standard recommende d leav e fo r parent s wishin g t o adop t chil dren i s six months . Despite thi s testimony , a twelve-week figur e fo r al l forms o f leave was adopted. In hearings before th e Committe e o n Educa tion an d Labor , Congressma n Willia m For d explaine d wh y thi s figure wa s chosen . The sponsor s o f the legislatio n bega n wit h a twenty-six-week figur e becaus e "tha t wa s consistent wit h wha t all ou r tradin g partner s i n th e Fre e Worl d do . I t wa s stil l les s than Canada , less than Germany , and less than othe r major trad ing partners/' 98 He then observe d tha t over th e year s tha t numbe r wa s compromise d dow n no t because 12 weeks made any more sense to the original spon sors o f thi s legislatio n tha n 26 , because w e coul d get mor e people t o vote fo r 1 2 weeks tha n w e coul d fo r 26 , includin g members of this committee who didn't support the bill at the very beginning but bega n t o suppor t th e bill after w e modified the number o f weeks involved. In other words, the number o f weeks chosen had to do with pol itics, no t th e need s o f th e peopl e wh o woul d qualif y fo r leav e under th e FMLA. And the number tha t was selected was admit tedly muc h lowe r tha n th e number chose n by ou r tradin g part ners a s well a s the numbe r o f weeks minimall y neede d b y ne w parents fo r th e benefit o f thei r children . Notice. Whe n a leave is foreseeable, the FMLA requires tha t th e employee giv e th e employe r no t les s tha n tha n thirt y days '

Family and Medical Leave

145

notice before th e dat e o n which th e leav e is to begin. If the dat e of th e treatmen t require s th e leav e t o begi n i n les s tha n thirt y days, the employe e mus t provid e suc h notic e a s is practicable. " Some court s hav e applie d thi s rul e stringently , requirin g a n employee t o invok e th e ter m FML A when requestin g leave , i n order t o specif y statutor y coverage . Bu t eve n th e conservativ e Fifth Circui t Cour t o f Appeal s ha s recognize d tha t thi s rul e departs fro m Congress' s intent . "Congres s i n enactin g th e FMLA did not inten d employee s . . . t o become conversan t wit h the lega l intricacie s o f th e Act/' 100 Jun e Manua l misse d abou t a month o f wor k followin g treatmen t fo r a health conditio n an d was fire d fro m he r job. She challenge d he r discharg e unde r th e FMLA an d los t i n th e tria l court . Sh e ultimatel y prevaile d b y taking he r cas e t o th e Fift h Circui t Cour t o f Appeals . I t too k enormous effor t fo r he r t o wi n bac k th e righ t t o wor k a t he r blue-collar job , fo r whic h sh e probabl y receive d n o compensa tion for her medical leave of absence. And had she not learned of the existenc e o f th e FML A afte r he r discharge , he r employe r would hav e gotte n awa y with ignorin g it s requirements. 101 Other employee s hav e bee n les s fortunate . Wayn e Johnso n requested a month's leave without pay because he was "forced b y circumstances t o [atten d to ] a matter . . . o f significan t financia l importance to [his] immediate and extended family." 102 After hi s leave reques t wa s denied , Johnso n wa s repeatedl y absen t fro m work an d wa s ultimatel y terminated . A t hi s trial , Johnso n explained tha t h e neede d th e tim e of f t o monito r hi s son , wh o had asthma. The son's grandmother ha d previously care d for th e child whe n h e wa s ill , but sh e ha d recentl y died . The so n ha d a record o f hospitalizatio n fo r hi s asthma . Becaus e Johnso n ha d previously receive d a two-week leav e when hi s so n was il l wit h asthma, th e cour t conclude d tha t "h e canno t shiel d himsel f

146

Family and Medical Leave

behind inexperienc e o r naivet e t o excus e th e allege d draftin g error [tha t is, not mentioning medica l condition] fo r his case differs fro m tha t o f a n inarticulat e individua l who i s disinclined t o reveal persona l matter s suc h a s famil y illness/ ' Althoug h th e FMLA does not require employees to invoke the FMLA by nam e and doe s no t requir e notic e whe n leav e i s unforeseeable , th e plaintiffs attemp t t o forese e hi s nee d fo r leav e wit h a genera l request fo r leav e was used against him under the statute. Had h e made n o advanc e reques t bu t foun d himsel f requirin g emer gency day s t o dea l wit h hi s son' s illness , th e cour t woul d hav e had t o rul e i n hi s favor . Hi s artles s attemp t t o provid e notice , however, precluded him fro m qualifyin g fo r FML A leave. Notice also works in the other direction. Employers are obligated to inform thei r employee s o f their right s under th e FMLA . These notic e rule s ar e importan t becaus e man y employee s ar e not familia r wit h th e specific s o f th e FMLA . Fo r example , Lis a Fry, who worked a s a head telle r fo r a bank, took sixtee n week s of famil y leav e afte r th e birt h o f he r child. 103 Th e employe e handbook specifie d tha t suc h leav e wa s permitte d withou t th e loss o f one' s employment . Befor e th e FML A wa s passed , how ever, th e employer' s polic y wa s no t t o guarante e tha t a n employee be reinstate d i n his o r her prio r position . The FMLA , by contrast , state s tha t employee s mus t b e reinstated i n a comparable position upon their return fro m covere d leave. Thus, the employer woul d b e obligate d t o compl y wit h th e FML A fo r those employees who took only twelve weeks of leave but coul d not b e require d t o compl y fo r thos e employee s wh o too k between twelv e an d sixtee n week s o f leave . No t realizin g tha t the FMLA' s right s wer e limite d t o twelv e week s o f leave , Fr y mistakenly though t sh e woul d b e guarantee d he r ol d positio n back even i f sh e took sixtee n weeks o f leave.

Family and Medical Leave

147

Substantively, Fr y ha d n o argumen t unde r th e FML A tha t she wa s entitle d t o b e reinstate d i n he r forme r positio n i f sh e took th e ful l sixtee n week s o f leave . But procedurally , th e cour t found tha t he r employe r wa s obligate d t o explai n t o he r th e FMLA's consequence s o f takin g mor e tha n twelv e week s o f leave—that sh e would no t b e guaranteed bac k her ol d position . In the words o f the court : We conclud e tha t suc h clai m state s a vali d caus e o f actio n under th e FML A sinc e adequat e notic e t o employee s con cerning thei r FML A righ t t o reinstatemen t i n ligh t o f an y additional leav e permitte d b y th e employe r i s necessar y t o enable them to exercise their statutory right to reinstatement by electin g t o reques t onl y twelv e week s o f famil y leave , if the employer's policy so provides. Lisa Fr y i s on e o f th e fortunat e fe w t o persuad e a cour t t o strictly enforce th e notice requirements tha t the FMLA imposes on employers . Mor e often , employee s ar e penalize d fo r thei r lack o f sophisticate d knowledge , wit h littl e consideratio n give n to ho w the y ar e suppose d t o acquir e suc h knowledge . I n th e absence o f a strong unio n presenc e i n th e workplace , it is unre alistic fo r employee s t o kno w muc h abou t thei r rights . Coun tries lik e Canada , wit h a stron g unio n movement , hav e lowe r expectations fo r employees ' knowledg e tha n doe s th e Unite d States, wher e employees ' sol e sourc e o f educationa l materia l usually i s limited to posters a t the workplace .

Unemployed Parent s

U.S. policy ha s neve r considere d i t necessar y o r appropriat e t o provide assistanc e t o all parents. When th e Aid to Families wit h

148

Family and Medical Leave

Dependent Childre n (AFDC ) program wa s instituted i n 1935 , it was conceive d a s a temporar y measur e fo r widow s unti l the y could receive survivor's insurance. 104 Long-term dependenc e o n public assistanc e wa s no t contemplated . Th e curren t trend—i n which, o n average , half o f AFDC recipient s receiv e benefit s fo r seven years—i s considere d t o b e politicall y an d sociall y unde sirable. Because long-ter m dependenc e o n governmenta l assis tance t o rais e childre n i s considere d t o b e unacceptable , poo r mothers ar e being encourage d (o r coerced ) t o participate i n th e paid labo r forc e a s soo n a s possible afte r givin g birth t o a child . Conservative economist s ar e urgin g th e state s t o encourag e these wome n t o ente r th e pai d labo r forc e si x months afte r th e birth o f a child o r "eve n before—becaus e i t send s th e righ t sig nal abou t th e importanc e o f responsibl e behavior/' 105 Bu t stat e support fo r chil d car e fo r thes e wome n i s no t necessaril y endorsed unde r th e rational e tha t th e "large-scal e us e o f infor mal arrangements " make s suc h stat e sponsorshi p unnecessary . In othe r words , there i s no reaso n t o guarante e t o poo r wome n the same quality of child care arrangements availabl e to middleclass women a s we pus h the m fro m parentin g t o pai d employ ment. By contrast , th e la w o f th e middl e clas s provide s financia l assistance unti l a child reache s th e ag e of eightee n throug h th e dependency deduction in the Federal Income Tax Code. (There is no requiremen t tha t bot h parent s b e employe d i n orde r t o receive thi s deduction. ) Moreover , middle-clas s parent s ca n receive subsidizatio n fo r chil d car e throug h thei r employer' s flexible spendin g plan o r through a child care credit on their ta x form whe n bot h parent s ar e i n th e pai d labo r force . The maxi mum allowanc e o f $6,00 0 alleviate s a substantia l portio n o f most parents ' chil d car e costs . Interestingly , thi s allowanc e i s

Family and Medical Leave

149

available onl y i f th e parent s ar e usin g a n establishe d chil d car e center o r ar e employing someon e who declare s his or her earn ings t o th e federa l government . "Informa l arrangements " ar e not recognize d under thi s program, even though thes e informa l arrangements ar e considered sufficien t fo r poo r parents . The recentl y enacte d Persona l Responsibilit y an d Wor k Opportunity Reconciliatio n Ac t o f 199 6 codifie s thes e conserv ative views. The Reconciliatio n Ac t eliminate s th e entitlement based Aid to Families with Dependen t Childre n framewor k an d replaces i t wit h a bloc k gran t fo r "temporar y assistanc e fo r needy families. " Foster car e and adoption ar e left a s entitlemen t programs (meanin g that all persons are entitled to use those ser vices o r programs) , bu t ai d t o need y familie s become s a time limited an d financiall y limite d program . A s th e statut e says , "This par t shal l no t b e interprete d t o entitl e an y individua l o r family t o assistance under an y Stat e program funde d unde r thi s part." 106 This ne w progra m i s suppose d t o en d "welfar e a s w e kno w it." To receive the federal mone y t o be disbursed t o eligible poor families, a stat e mus t prepar e a plan tha t require s " a paren t o r caretaker receivin g assistanc e unde r th e progra m t o engag e i n work . . . once th e paren t o r caretake r ha s receive d assistanc e under th e progra m fo r 2 4 month s (whethe r o r no t consecu tive)." Th e state s ar e als o require d t o demonstrat e tha t the y have a chil d suppor t enforcemen t progra m a s wel l a s a foste r care and adoption assistanc e program, but the y ar e not require d to demonstrat e tha t the y hav e a n adequat e arra y o f chil d car e available for poo r families . The only grou p o f poor persons wh o are partiall y exempte d fro m thes e rule s ar e person s wh o hav e become impoverishe d whil e escapin g domesti c violence . (Domestic violenc e i s narrowl y define d a s bein g "battere d o r

150

Family and Medical Leave

subjected t o extrem e cruelty/' ) The y apparentl y ar e considere d to be the " deserving poor/ ' compare d wit h nonbattere d wome n who merel y fin d i t difficul t t o combin e parentin g an d pai d employment. The Reconciliatio n Act als o offers t o the state s som e interest ing financia l incentives . State s ar e entitle d t o receiv e a "bonus " for each year in which they demonstrate a net decrease in out-of wedlock births whil e als o demonstrating a lower rat e o f induce d pregnancy terminations . (Thi s rul e seem s premise d o n th e inac curate stereotyp e tha t women o n welfare have , on average , more children tha n d o other women . It als o suggests tha t the y shoul d not us e a lawful mean s o f preventin g childbirt h an d shoul d ge t married, regardless o f the qualit y o f their marita l relationship. ) Although mos t marrie d wome n wh o hav e pai d employmen t while raisin g youn g childre n wor k o n a part-tim e basis , th e Reconciliation Ac t incorporate s a mode l o f nearl y full-tim e employment. For the purpose of defining whether a recipient "i s engaged i n work," the goa l by the year 200 0 is for th e parent i n a single-paren t famil y t o b e workin g a t leas t thirt y hour s pe r week. Eve n i f a woman i s fortunat e enoug h t o hav e a job tha t parallels th e hours o f a school day and to have children who ar e old enoug h t o atten d school , i t i s impossibl e t o wor k thirt y hours per week and be home when childre n leave for schoo l an d arrive hom e a t th e en d o f th e day . Of course , the state s ar e no t required t o creat e after-schoo l o r before-schoo l program s fo r parents whose workday does not perfectly matc h the school da y (There i s a modes t exceptio n fo r a singl e paren t wit h a chil d under th e ag e of six : in tha t case , the wor k requiremen t i s low ered to twenty hour s pe r week. ) One has to wonder what kind of work Congress expected par ents of young childre n would be able to find tha t would make i t

Family and Medical Leave

151

possible fo r the m t o affor d th e necessar y chil d car e an d othe r expenses o f employment . Congres s does , however , defin e "work," thu s givin g u s som e insigh t int o thei r thinking . On e activity that count s as "work" is "the provision o f child care ser vices to a n individua l wh o i s participating i n a community ser vices program. " Wome n ar e require d t o leav e thei r childre n a t home t o tak e car e o f th e childre n o f othe r wome n wh o ar e engaging i n low-payin g communit y servic e work . Thi s rul e i s comparable t o th e genera l exclusio n o f domesti c worker s fro m minimum wag e laws . When th e governmen t interfere s i n th e economy, i t alway s trie s t o ensur e tha t i t doe s no t eliminat e a source of low-paid domesti c labor . The public rhetoric on behalf o f the Reconciliation Act is that U.S. policy needs t o change th e cultura l attitude s o f the poo r s o that w e ca n brea k th e cycl e o f poverty . Forcin g familie s wit h young childre n of f publi c assistanc e withi n tw o year s i s sup posed t o promot e a n appropriat e wor k ethic . Nowher e i n thi s discussion doe s there appea r to be concern fo r th e quality o f lif e that w e wil l b e creatin g fo r children . Wherea s middle-clas s mothers ar e made t o feel guilt y i f they plac e too high a priority on work, poor mothers ar e told to find pai d employment eve n if it is detrimental t o the well-being o f their children . But th e policie s underlyin g th e ne w welfar e la w d o not sim ply consis t o f withdrawin g fro m poo r peopl e publi c suppor t fo r parenting. The policie s als o pus h a moralistic agend a tha t thes e women shoul d ge t married , hav e fewe r children , an d no t hav e abortions. (I n addition , th e chil d suppor t enforcemen t rule s require mother s t o divulg e th e paternit y o f th e fathe r o f thei r child, regardles s o f whethe r h e coul d suppor t th e chil d finan cially.) As in the gay rights area, we see a combination o f capitalism and moralism that is functionally unnecessar y t o capitalism .

152

Family and Medical Leave

Amazingly, eve n capitalist s woul d hav e troubl e justifyin g these ne w rule s i n th e nam e o f economi c efficiency . I t i s openl y predicted that these rules will create greater use of the foster car e and adoptio n systems—bot h o f whic h ar e fa r mor e expensiv e than welfare . And give n th e evidenc e of the questionabl e qualit y of th e foste r car e an d adoptio n systems , ther e i s littl e reaso n t o believe tha t thes e expensiv e change s woul d benefi t children . Children in middle-class families will benefit fro m th e family la w presumption tha t i t i s i n thei r bes t interes t t o liv e wit h an d b e raised by their biological parents. But children in poor families ar e openly penalized fo r thei r parents ' poverty—they eithe r becom e poorer o r participate i n foste r car e drift. Neithe r resul t i s exactl y in their best interest despit e the "profamily" rhetoric . No othe r Wester n natio n trie s t o instill work-ethic values i n parents b y penalizin g thei r children . N o othe r countr y make s such a sharp distinction between th e rights o f poor childre n an d the right s o f middle-clas s children . Other countrie s offe r bene fits t o al l parents an d the n tr y t o help the transition t o work b y providing chil d car e an d universa l healt h insurance . The resul t is a lower rat e o f labo r marke t participatio n b y mother s i n th e early years of a child's life but a higher rat e of labor market par ticipation i n late r years . France, for example , has a more generou s financia l assistanc e program fo r singl e parents with young children 107 than doe s the United States , and th e employmen t rat e fo r singl e parents wit h children unde r ag e thre e i s lowe r i n Franc e tha n i n th e Unite d States (4 3 percent versu s 50 percent). But th e employmen t rat e of singl e parent s wit h childre n age d thre e t o fiv e i s highe r (66 percent versu s 6 1 percent) i n Franc e tha n i n th e Unite d States . Current America n welfar e la w presume s tha t mor e tha n tw o years o f dependenc e o n publi c assistanc e foster s long-ter m

Family and Medical Leave

153

unemployment amon g singl e parents , bu t th e Frenc h experi ence shows that singl e parents ca n be helped, with grea t success, to return t o work after thre e years of public assistance. The beneficiaries ar e the children a s well as the mothers who do not fac e an impossibl e balancin g ac t betwee n wor k an d home . Whe n feminists note , as they have in Sweden, that women ar e the one s who ar e disproportionatel y leavin g th e workforc e t o car e fo r children, th e respons e i s to tr y t o increase th e incentive s t o ge t men t o sta y hom e wit h th e childre n rathe r tha n t o ge t mor e women bac k into th e labo r marke t mor e quickly. 108 America's versio n o f hypercapitalis m ha s cause d i t t o avoi d governmental interventio n o n behal f o f parents . Thus, we hav e little guaranteed leav e for working parents an d a limited schem e of benefit s fo r nonworkin g parent s tha t i s shrinkin g further . These result s ma y b e consisten t wit h a laissez-fair e attitud e toward labor market intervention but are not consistent with th e best interest s o f the childre n o r thei r parents . By assuming tha t parents who receiv e public financial assistanc e inevitably hav e a poor work ethic , U.S. policy has consistently faile d t o offer posi tive incentive s t o parent s o f olde r childre n t o ge t the m int o th e paid workforce . Bu t th e experienc e o f othe r countrie s suggest s that suc h policie s ar e possibl e an d ar e mor e effectiv e tha n th e punitive approac h currentl y embodie d i n the ne w welfare law . In th e Unite d States , i t i s virtuall y unthinkabl e tha t w e woul d mandate pai d leav e fo r pregnan t wome n an d thei r partners , require accommodation s durin g pregnancy , an d insis t o n th e availability o f pregnancy-relate d insuranc e benefit s fo r al l women. Ye t thes e kind s o f benefit s an d mor e ar e routin e i n Canada an d western Europe . The basic style o f discours e i n dis cussing thes e pregnancy-relate d issue s i n th e Unite d State s i s

154

Family and Medical Leave

unique. U.S. law regarding pregnancy and childbirth reflect s th e tenets o f laissez-fair e economics—tha t w e shoul d solel y con sider the autonom y right s o f corporations o r adults in ou r soci ety when decidin g whether t o mandate benefits . In Canad a an d wester n Europe , b y contrast , th e startin g premise is quite different. Th e needs of children both before an d after birt h ar e a t th e cente r o f th e discussion , althoug h th e equality right s o f wome n an d me n i n societ y ar e als o empha sized. This focu s o n children , withou t th e expectatio n tha t w e will pas s o n al l th e cost s o f childbearin g an d childrearin g t o women an d their partners , results i n a n entirel y differen t se t of social policie s tha n w e se e i n th e Unite d States . Workplac e accommodations durin g an d afte r pregnanc y becom e possibl e not a s special treatment fo r wome n bu t a s special treatment fo r fetuses an d newborns. Adhering to a strict capitalist philosophy , the Unite d State s i s no t simpl y passin g o n th e cost s o f preg nancy and childbirth t o parents, especially female parents, but is endangering th e welfare o f ou r children . My poin t i s not tha t w e shoul d ignor e th e equalit y interest s of adult women an d men but that we should also work harder t o incorporate the needs of children into those equality rights. Parenting leav e i s no t simpl y givin g wome n a chanc e t o recove r from th e physica l demand s o f pregnanc y an d childbirt h bu t i s also facilitating th e car e of childre n followin g birth . Accommodating pregnant wome n a t the workplace i s not simpl y protect ing thei r righ t t o wor k whil e pregnan t bu t i s als o creatin g a workplace tha t i s saf e fo r fetuses . Canad a an d wester n Europ e have managed to find solution s that protect the interests of children a s well as female employees . But this conversation ha s no t even begu n i n th e United States .

5 SEXUAL ORIENTATIO N DISCRIMINATIO N

When Perr y Watkins , a n Africa n America n ga y man , wa s drafted b y th e U.S . Army i n 196 7 durin g th e Vietnam conflict , he had no idea that h e would eventuall y hav e to bring a lawsuit to retai n a position i n th e arme d forces. 1 Despit e indicatin g o n his preinductio n physica l for m tha t h e ha d "homosexua l ten dencies/' he was found qualifie d fo r admission and inducted int o the arme d forces . A yea r afte r enterin g th e army , Watkin s sought discharge by again statin g that he had "homosexual ten dencies" and ha d eve n committe d "sodomy " wit h othe r mem bers o f the military . After a brief investigation , th e arm y foun d him qualifie d t o b e retained . I n 1975 , however , althoug h th e army attempted to discharge Watkins based on his sexual orien tation, a review board conclude d tha t "ther e i s no evidence sug gesting that hi s behavior ha s had eithe r a degrading effect upo n

156

Sexual Orientation Discriminatio n

unit performance, moral e or discipline, or upon his own job per formance/' 2 At first , Watkins' s rac e seem s t o hav e cause d th e arm y t o overlook hi s sexua l orientation : "Ever y white perso n I kne w from Tacoma who was gay and had checked [th e homosexuality ] box 'Yes' did not have to go into the service. They were called in and asked, 'What doe s this mean?' They said , Tt means I' m ga y I lik e t o suc k dick / Tine , Yo u ca n go/" 3 Similarly , i n 1968 , Watkins observes : "There wa s anothe r perso n wh o wen t t o hi s commander an d told him the same damn thing and they let hi m go home. Of course , he was white. Which I think also had some thing t o do with it—h e wa s white an d I was black. " The army' s polic y o f overlookin g Watkins' s homosexuality , however, change d i n 198 1 as the col d war bega n t o wind down . Although Watkins no w wanted t o stay in the military, which h e regarded a s his career, the arm y commence d discharg e proceed ings against him based entirely o n evidence that had been avail able to it at the 1968 and 1975 discharge proceedings. This time, the review board decided that Watkins was not fit for service and should b e discharged. 4 Hi s sexua l orientatio n becam e a mor e dominant concer n of the army a s its need for military personne l declined. An openly gay African American soldie r was no longer acceptable, regardless o f his servic e record . Watkins's 198 2 discharg e becam e th e subjec t o f a length y court proceeding that was not resolved until 1989. His legal battle i s wel l know n i n th e ga y an d lesbia n communit y becaus e Watkins is one of a few gay plaintiffs t o prevail in a federal lega l proceeding. What i s distinctive abou t Watkins's cas e is the per sistent attemp t b y th e court s t o fashion a victory fo r hi m with out creatin g legal advances for ga y men an d lesbians in the mil itary o r elsewhere .

Sexual Orientation Discriminatio n

157

Watkins prevailed on "estoppel" and "double jeopardy"5 grounds, but not because the military's treatment o f gay men was uncon stitutional. (Th e original Ninth Circui t opinio n tha t decide d hi s case on the merits was ultimately vacated by an en banc panel of the Nint h Circuit. ) When Michae l Hardwic k wa s arreste d fo r drinkin g i n publi c a s he lef t hi s employmen t a t a gay ba r i n Atlanta, h e ha d n o ide a that thi s sam e polic e office r woul d late r arres t hi m i n hi s ow n bedroom fo r a sodomy violation. 6 Bu t i n a complicated twis t o f errors—a mistak e o n a hearin g notice , a n expire d warran t fo r his arrest , an d a sleep y frien d i n th e livin g roo m wh o mistak enly directe d a polic e office r t o hi s bedroom—Michae l Hard wick becam e th e plaintif f i n a landmar k civi l right s lawsui t t o challenge Georgia' s sodom y la w Hardwick' s "crime " wa s engaging i n mutua l ora l se x with anothe r ma n i n hi s ow n bed room. Hi s "crime " mad e hi m subjec t t o arres t becaus e h e wa s openly identifiabl e a s a gay ma n throug h hi s employmen t a t a gay bar. Had Michae l Hardwic k bee n employe d i n a less "ghet toized" setting and resided in a more private situation, he woul d not have been arrested for engaging in mutual oral sex. Whereas Watkins's lega l problem s bega n whe n a s a n Africa n America n man, h e foun d himsel f coercivel y subjecte d t o th e draft , Hard wick's lega l problem s bega n whe n a s a working-clas s man , h e found himsel f a victim o f police harassment. In both cases, these men were vulnerable t o the state' s coercion because they were a particularly disadvantage d subclas s o f the gay and lesbian com munity. When W , an Australian lesbian , ha d tw o childre n a s a result o f artificial inseminatio n i n th e lat e 1980 s whe n livin g wit h he r

158

Sexual Orientation Discriminatio n

partner, G , she , too, had n o ide a tha t sh e would becom e a wellknown figur e i n th e ga y an d lesbian communit y becaus e o f he r legal battles. 7 Like Watkins an d Hardwick , W wa s no t a highl y privileged membe r o f societ y Aside fro m a position a s a kenne l hand an d counte r clerk , she had been mostl y unemploye d sinc e the mid-1980s. G, too, had minimal income until her fathe r die d in 1994 , leaving he r a substantia l estate . When W an d G sepa rated in 1994, G refused t o assist financially i n the raising of th e children tha t ha d bee n born e t o W wit h G' s allege d encourage ment. In the first decisio n of its kind in a common la w legal system, the Suprem e Cour t o f New Sout h Wales ordered G to provide a lum p su m paymen t t o b e use d t o purchas e annuitie s t o help suppor t th e children. 8 W , a working-clas s lesbia n wh o found hersel f i n financia l distress , wa s abl e t o obtai n relie f through lega l proceedings i n Australia . Similarly, ga y me n an d lesbian s hav e bee n abl e increasingl y to us e th e Canadia n lega l syste m t o gai n relie f i n case s involv ing their famil y an d employment situations . In 1992, the Cana dian Federal Court foun d tha t a discharge from th e military fol lowing a n admissio n o f homosexualit y violate d th e plaintiff s equality right s unde r th e Canadia n Charte r o f Right s an d Free doms.9 I n Haig v. Canada, 10 th e Ontari o Cour t o f Appeal con cluded tha t i t wa s discriminator y fo r th e Canadia n Huma n Rights Act to omit "sexua l orientation" fro m it s list of ground s of unlawful discrimination . Applying that rule, it concluded tha t it was unlawful fo r a captain in the Canadia n arme d force s t o be denied eligibilit y fo r promotio n an d caree r trainin g whe n h e revealed tha t h e was a homosexual . U.S. Suprem e Cour t precedent , a s enunciate d i n Bowers v. Hardwick,11 ha s lef t ga y men an d lesbian s outsid e constitutiona l protection. Judge s lik e Nint h Circui t Judg e Stephe n Reinhard t

Sexual Orientation Discriminatio n

159

have found themselve s bound by Bowers an d therefore unabl e t o rule on behalf o f homosexual plaintiffs. Reinhard t dissente d fro m the decision in Watkins II while acknowledging that"homosexu als have been unfairly treate d both historically an d in the Unite d States today " an d tha t "prope r interpretatio n o f constitutiona l principles" would give them constitutional protection.12 Nonetheless, he felt bound by the Supreme Court' s 198 6 decision in Bowers, which leave s homosexual s outsid e constitutiona l protection . Reinhardt's dissen t acknowledge s th e obvious—tha t equalit y principles d o not exten d t o constitutiona l decisio n makin g whe n the plaintiffs ar e gay men o r lesbians in the United States . A clos e examinatio n o f ga y right s litigatio n i n th e Unite d States reveal s th e twi n theme s o f militarism an d moralism tha t underlie American-styl e capitalism . Militaris m ha s a compli cated relationshi p t o America n capitalism , an d th e dispropor tionate subsidization o f the military has a long-standing histor y in American politics . During th e Ne w Dea l era, America briefl y experimented wit h becomin g a social welfare stat e i n whic h al l workers could be guaranteed minimu m wage s and benefits. Following Worl d Wa r II , however , th e socia l welfar e policie s became minima l excep t fo r veterans . Hence th e wa r brough t wha t th e Ne w Dea l reformer s ha d hoped to avoid: a special welfare stat e for a substantial secto r of th e populatio n deeme d especiall y deserving . Th e socia l reformism o f th e Ne w Dea l ha d bee n channele d int o expanded public provision for veterans, making it hencefort h less likely that establishment of a national welfare stat e could be completed. 13 Even today , with th e en d o f th e col d war, th e Republica n Con gress has resisted attempts to close bases and radically limit mil -

160

Sexual Orientation Discriminatio n

itary spending . B y contrast , Grea t Britai n enacte d sweepin g social reforms durin g thi s sam e period, which wer e availabl e t o all members o f society , not just veterans . The United State s ha s continued t o expan d it s subsidizatio n o f th e militar y whil e largely abandonin g it s Ne w Dea l aspiration s o f a social welfar e state. ^[TJh e Ne w Dea l drea m o f nationa l socia l an d economi c policies t o meet th e man y need s o f al l Americans ha d been dis solved b y th e domesti c politic s o f th e wa r years . Th e drea m would no t soo n reappear , an d never agai n i n the sam e way/' 14 In mor e recen t times , whil e th e Republica n Congres s ha s attempted t o en d government-sanctione d suppor t o f industr y by eliminatin g th e Departmen t o f Commerce , i t ha s als o insisted o n approvin g mor e mone y fo r militar y spendin g tha n proposed b y th e Clinto n administration . Laissez-fair e Republi cans have not been willing to acknowledge the lessened need fo r military spendin g a t the end of the cold war. Newt Gingrich , fo r example, has insisted that th e world is full o f "clever countries " that ar e trying to "learn how to cope with a n American militar y force."15 But his real reason t o support outmode d an d unneede d military technolog y i n th e post-col d wa r er a i s t o kee p th e B- 2 contractors i n business . Thus, althoug h a large military-indus trial comple x ma y b e historicall y understoo d a s a respons e t o Communism, it currently has a life of its own. And that life con tradicts th e laissez-fair e principle s o f capitalis m b y standin g a s the most subsidize d segmen t o f the American economy . The treatmen t o f gay s i n th e military , however , canno t b e explained solel y by American deferenc e t o the military' s state d needs. After all , excluding individuals lik e Watkins deprive s th e military o f highly qualifie d personne l an d make s littl e sens e i n a country devote d to a powerful military . To explain the advers e treatment o f gay s i n th e military , w e thu s nee d t o refe r t o th e

Sexual Orientation Discriminatio n

161

moralism underlyin g American-style capitalism . House major ity leader (Republican ) Dic k Armey argue s tha t democrac y an d capitalism deriv e fro m a highe r power. 16 Irvin g Kristol , th e father o f neoconservatism , claim s tha t an y attac k o n religio n i s an attac k o n capitalism , a moralisti c perspectiv e tha t ha s pre vented th e United State s fro m openin g th e door s o f privilege t o all its members . Legal moralis m i n th e Unite d State s ha s no t bee n limite d t o claims involvin g militar y service . When ga y me n an d lesbian s tried t o us e th e lega l system' s promis e o f gende r equalit y t o have marriag e extende d t o the m o n th e sam e basi s a s hetero sexuals, the Wall Street Journal publishe d a n editoria l criticiz ing th e court' s interventio n i n a matter tha t shoul d b e decide d by th e people. 17 As a proponent o f laissez-fair e capitalism , th e Wall Street Journal should , fo r consistency' s sake , hav e pub lished a n articl e describin g th e economi c inefficienc y o f allow ing some members o f our society , but no t others , to take advan tage of the economic advantages of marriage. Capitalists preten d that extendin g benefit s t o ga y me n an d lesbian s constitute s "special protection " rathe r tha n forma l equality , s o a s t o avoi d applying laissez-fair e principle s t o gay men an d lesbians . Legal academic s suffe r fro m th e sam e blin d spot . Richar d Posner's willingness to accede to moralistic arguments i s appar ent i n hi s book Sex and Reason. I n discussin g th e ga y marriag e issue, Posner acknowledge s tha t " authorizing homosexua l mar riage woul d hav e man y collatera l effects , simpl y becaus e mar riage i s a statu s ric h i n entitlements/' 18 Afte r recognizin g tha t granting thes e benefit s t o ga y me n an d lesbian s woul d hav e moral and political implications, he concludes: "These question s ought to be faced on e by one rather tha n elide d by conferring al l the right s o f marriag e i n a lum p o n homosexual s willin g t o

162

Sexual Orientation Discriminatio n

undergo a weddin g ceremony/ ' Laissez-fair e principle s wer e abandoned i n th e nam e o f deferrin g t o moralis m whe n th e rights o f gay an d lesbian peopl e were a t stake . Capitalism an d homophobi a d o no t hav e a n inheren t func tional relationship . Capitalis m i s base d o n laissez-fair e princi ples tha t see k t o attai n economi c efficienc y b y allowin g eac h person i n societ y t o realiz e hi s o r he r potentia l withou t inter ference b y th e state . But American la w is not evenhande d whe n it consider s th e rights o f ga y an d lesbia n peopl e i n compariso n to heterosexuals . Indeed , America n capitalis m i s a peculiarl y moralistic an d militaristi c versio n o f capitalism . Rathe r tha n make moral arguments, such as gay people deserve to be treate d worse tha n others , American capitalist s ofte n hid e thei r mora l disgust wit h specia l treatment arguments . There i s on e seemin g contradictio n i n thi s account— Romer v. Evans—the Colorad o ballo t initiativ e cas e i n whic h th e U.S . Supreme Cour t conclude d tha t animu s agains t homosexual s was no t a legitimat e basi s fo r denyin g the m lega l rights . Nonetheless, a s we will see , this cas e is consisten t wit h Ameri can-style laissez-fair e capitalis m becaus e it refuses t o recogniz e the historical mistreatment o f gay men an d lesbians and render s its decisio n i n a wa y tha t uphold s th e anti-affirmativ e actio n bias o f American law . Its decisio n leave s i n plac e th e moralis m and militarism underlyin g American law .

Constitutional La w THE BAD NEWS

It shoul d no t surpris e u s tha t Michae l Hardwick , th e ga y bar tender, lost his constitutiona l clai m t o privacy unde r th e Amer ican Constitution i n Bowers v. Hardwick.19 No t abl e to afford t o

Sexual Orientation Discriminatio n

163

purchase privac y i n hi s life , h e coul d no t expec t th e court s t o give him constitutiona l protection. Although a strict applicatio n of laissez-fair e principle s shoul d preven t th e governmen t fro m interfering wit h the private sexua l practices of gay men an d lesbians—just a s it does not interfere wit h th e private sexua l practices o f middle-clas s heterosexuals 20 —the Cour t refuse d t o extend thes e principle s t o gay s an d lesbians . The state' s justifi cation fo r it s sodom y la w in Bowers wa s th e "belie f o f a major ity o f th e electorat e i n Georgi a tha t homosexua l sodom y i s immoral an d unacceptable/' The Suprem e Cour t conclude d tha t this justification wa s sufficient t o uphold a law that infringes o n the private sexua l activit y o f adults . As Chie f Justic e Warren Burge r state d i n hi s concurrenc e i n Bowers: "T o hol d tha t th e ac t o f homosexua l sodom y i s some how protected as a fundamental righ t would be to cast aside millennia o f mora l teaching. " Th e Cour t therefor e refuse d t o extend t o homosexual s th e laissez-fair e doctrin e o f privac y a s developed i n th e contraceptio n an d abortio n cases . As th e dis sent noted, "The legitimacy o f secular legislation depend s . . . o n whether th e Stat e ca n advanc e som e justificatio n fo r it s la w beyond it s conformit y t o religiou s doctrine . . . . A Stat e ca n n o more punis h privat e behavio r becaus e o f religiou s intoleranc e than i t ca n punish suc h behavior becaus e of racial animus." The dissent's argumen t woul d b e vali d i f ga y me n an d lesbian s received constitutiona l protection . Bu t becaus e thei r claim s li e outside constitutiona l protection , mora l argument s ar e allowe d to justify infringemen t o n thei r libert y interests . Similarly, the courts have continuously denie d claims by ga y men an d lesbian s tha t the y shoul d b e entitle d t o ente r militar y service o n th e sam e basi s a s d o heterosexuals . I n th e case s brought unde r equalit y doctrine (unlik e Watkins), th e plaintiff s

164

Sexual Orientation Discriminatio n

have consistentl y lost . The Fourt h Circui t Cour t o f Appeals, fo r example, accepte d th e argumen t tha t "sexua l tension s an d attractions could play havoc with a military unit's discipline an d solidarity/' 21 Relying on the precedent o f Bowers, th e court als o noted, "Give n i t i s legitimat e fo r Congres s t o proscrib e homo sexual acts , it i s als o legitimat e fo r th e governmen t t o see k t o forestall thes e sam e danger s b y tryin g t o preven t th e commis sion o f suc h acts. " As the dissen t observes , these kind s o f argu ments use d t o suppor t whit e mal e supremacy . " v Unit cohesion ' is a facile wa y fo r th e in s t o put a patina o f rationalit y o n thei r efforts t o exclud e th e outs . Th e concep t ha s therefor e bee n a favorite o f those who, through th e years, have resisted th e irre sistible erosio n o f white mal e dominatio n o f th e arme d forces. " The U.S. Constitution, however , has not ye t been interprete d t o protect ga y me n an d lesbian s fro m th e force s o f "whit e mal e domination." Free-speec h argument s unde r th e Firs t Amend ment hav e als o been unavailabl e t o gay men an d lesbians in th e military, despite the explicit silencin g of speec h intended b y th e current "don' t ask , don't tell " policy 22 Until recently , the Canadia n court s als o refused t o allow ga y men an d lesbian s t o receiv e constitutiona l protection . I n 1993 , the Ontario court (Genera l Division) ruled in a two-to-one deci sion that i t did not violate the equalit y provisio n i n the Charte r of Right s fo r tw o men t o be denied th e righ t t o see k a marriag e license.23 I n a curiou s tur n o f logic , the cour t foun d tha t ther e was n o sexua l orientatio n discriminatio n becaus e th e marriag e law doe s no t prohibi t ga y peopl e fro m marrying , i t onl y pro hibits them from marryin g someone of the same sex. (The argument doe s no t appea r t o hav e bee n mad e tha t th e rul e consti tuted sex discrimination.) A month earlie r in 1993, the Suprem e Court o f Canad a conclude d tha t i t di d no t constitut e unlawfu l

Sexual Orientation Discrimination

165

"family status " discrimination fo r a man t o be denie d bereave ment leav e t o atten d th e funera l o f th e fathe r o f hi s same-se x partner, althoug h th e cour t clearl y lef t ope n th e questio n whether suc h a rul e woul d constitut e sexua l orientatio n dis crimination. 24 I n a stingin g dissent , Justic e Clair e L'Heureux Dube surveyed the literature on the structure o f the urban blac k family i n the United State s an d argued , "While th e structur e o f the famil y ma y b e a question o f choic e fo r some , for other s th e structure o f famil y ma y b e i n par t a natural respons e t o socia l and politica l pressures. " Sh e sa w th e connectio n betwee n eco nomics an d famil y structur e an d di d not presum e tha t th e stat e should us e it s powe r t o coerc e peopl e int o conventiona l famil y arrangements i n orde r t o make claim s fo r benefits . In 1995 , the Suprem e Cour t o f Canad a rule d i n Egan v. The Queen,25 tha t th e infringemen t o f equalit y wa s justifiable i n a case involving th e federa l old-ag e securit y legislation . This leg islation provides an allowance to the spous e of a pensioner, wit h a spous e define d a s a person o f th e opposit e sex . Although th e court foun d tha t thi s definitio n di d violate the righ t t o equalit y as guaranteed by Sectio n 1 5 of the Charter , the court als o foun d that suc h discriminatio n wa s constitutiona l unde r Sectio n 1 of the Charter . The majority acknowledge d tha t th e purpose o f th e rule wa s t o suppor t th e "heterosexua l famil y unit. " "I t i s th e social uni t tha t uniquel y ha s th e capacit y t o procreat e childre n and generall y care s fo r thei r upbringing , an d a s suc h warrant s support b y Parliament t o meet it s needs [T]hi s is the unit i n society tha t fundamentall y anchor s othe r socia l relationship s and other aspect s of society." Like the cases in the United States , this case merge d moralis m wit h laissez-fair e capitalism . Although a s acknowledged b y the court , the general rul e was t o extend benefit s withou t regar d t o sexua l orientation , th e cour t

166

Sexual Orientation Discriminatio n

allowed th e governmen t t o violate tha t rul e i n orde r t o benefi t the traditional , heterosexua l famil y uni t compose d o f a wag e earner, dependent spouse , and children . Nonetheless, i n th e las t severa l year s i n Canada , usin g con stitutional litigation, there have been man y successfu l attempt s to secur e same-se x partne r supplementa l healt h car e benefits . One of the first successfu l challenge s came from th e province of Manitoba. Sinc e 1973, Chris Vogel had been a regular full-tim e employee o f th e governmen t o f Manitoba. 26 I n 1974 , he partic ipated i n a marriag e ceremon y conducte d b y th e Unitaria n Church, but becaus e his partner wa s o f the sam e sex , the regis trar o f vita l statistic s refuse d t o registe r th e marriage . Som e o f his employment benefit s include d benefits t o his "spouse/' suc h as denta l insurance , a semiprivat e hospita l plan , a n extende d health plan , an d variou s pensio n an d survivor' s benefits . Th e Manitoba cour t conclude d tha t th e exclusio n o f homosexua l partners fro m th e employe e benefit s progra m constitute d dis crimination o n th e basi s o f sexua l orientatio n an d referre d th e case back to the human right s adjudicato r fo r a decision. Recognizing that it might be difficult fo r th e legislature t o change th e law, the Manitoba cour t admitted, "We can't say we are too busy with othe r thing s o r that th e issu e is too politically sensitiv e o r set up a Royal Commission. We do our duty and decide." Rather than duc k th e issue , th e cour t applie d traditiona l principle s o f equality doctrin e t o conclud e tha t sexua l orientatio n discrimi nation underla y th e employe e benefit program . Similarly, i n M . v. H., 17 th e Ontari o tria l cour t conclude d i n 1996 that i t was unconstitutional fo r th e spousa l suppor t legis lation to exclude same-sex couples from coverage . In this case, it was clea r that th e court s achieve d a result tha t wa s not possibl e in th e legislature . I n 1993 , the Ontari o La w Refor m Commis -

Sexual Orientation Discriminatio n

167

sion recommende d tha t same-se x couple s receiv e som e legisla tive recognition . I n 1994 , th e Equalit y Right s Statut e Amend ment Act , bil l 167 , was pu t forwar d i n th e Ontari o legislature . The bil l wa s defeate d an d ha s no t bee n reintroduced . Further more, th e government' s action s wit h respec t t o thi s litigatio n show how har d i t is to achieve governmenta l consensu s o n thi s issue. Initially, th e attorne y genera l intervene d i n thi s cas e an d supported th e plaintiff s case . Then afte r th e electio n o f 1995 , the attorney genera l file d anothe r brie f i n suppor t o f the defen dant. As the court found , "I t is simply not realisti c to regard th e current stat e o f Ontari o la w pertainin g t o spousa l suppor t a s merely par t o f a process o f legislativ e reform. " Afte r consider ing variou s argument s fo r judicia l deference , th e cour t decide d to move forwar d an d gran t relie f t o the plaintiff . In more recen t cases , the Canadia n court s hav e been increas ingly willin g t o accor d same-se x couple s th e famil y right s o f married partners , by examinin g th e case s a s sexua l orientatio n cases. In a 199 5 decision , Re Metro Toronto Reference Library and C.U.P.E., hoc. 1582 ,28 th e arbitrato r resolve d th e issu e lef t open b y Mossop —whether a denia l o f bereavemen t leav e t o a same-sex partner constitute d sexua l orientation discrimination . The arbitrato r answere d thi s questio n i n th e affirmative . Whil e U.S. courts hav e consistentl y refuse d t o recogniz e th e inappro priateness o f discriminatio n o n th e basi s o f sexua l orientation , Canadian court s hav e increasingl y recognize d th e histor y o f prejudice an d hatred against gay and lesbian people. Rather tha n try t o twis t ga y right s argument s int o gende r arguments , the y deal with the m directl y a s argument s base d o n th e inappropri ateness of sexual orientation discrimination . They are not afrai d to confront directl y the moral arguments supportin g sexual orientation discrimination .

168

Sexual Orientation Discriminatio n

Despite som e earl y losse s i n arbitratio n cases, 29 th e curren t trend is also to extend rights to same-sex couples in that judicial arena. I n Re Bell Canada and Canadian Telephone Employees' Association,30 th e arbitrator rule d that spousa l benefits mus t b e accorded to same-sex couples in order to comply with the Cana dian Human Right s Act. Those benefits include d a pension plan , survivor protectio n benefits , an d variou s healt h car e benefit s beyond thos e offere d automaticall y b y th e government . Th e arbitrator conclude d tha t ther e ha d bee n unlawfu l discrimina tion o n th e basis of sexual orientation. Likewise , in Re Treasury Board (Environment Canada) and Lorenzen, 31 th e arbitrato r concluded tha t a n employe r violate d th e collective-bargainin g agreement an d th e Canadia n Huma n Right s Ac t b y no t allow ing bereavement an d famil y leav e to be accorde d t o a same-se x partner. The arbitrato r di d not hav e to reach th e Huma n Right s Act issu e becaus e h e conclude d tha t a s use d i n th e collective bargaining agreement , th e ter m spouse coul d includ e same-se x couples. In th e absenc e o f th e term s husband an d wife, h e con cluded that suc h a n interpretation wa s reasonable . Although Australian court s hav e not gon e s o far a s to decid e that same-se x relationship s shoul d b e directl y recognize d a s marriages, the y hav e extende d th e benefit s o f th e la w o f mar riage t o same-se x couple s i n divorcelik e proceedings . An exam ple is the previously cited Wv.G case, 32 the female plaintiff wh o sued he r femal e partne r fo r chil d suppor t unde r a n equitabl e estoppel theory , wit h th e Suprem e Cour t o f Ne w Sout h Wale s ruling i n favo r o f the plaintiff . The Australian decisio n is , in man y respects , a classic exam ple o f laissez-fair e decisio n making . Th e sexua l orientatio n o f the partie s playe d n o rol e i n th e decision . Th e cour t simpl y applied long-standin g equitabl e principle s t o a case involving a

Sexual Orientation Discriminatio n

169

same-sex couple . Moralisti c argument s di d no t influenc e th e judgment, thereb y allowin g th e cour t t o exten d th e protectio n of th e la w i n a n evenhande d manner . N o cour t i n th e Unite d States ha s bee n willin g t o appl y suc h equitabl e principle s t o cases involvin g childre n raise d b y same-se x couples . The Aus tralian decisio n i s therefore remarkabl e fo r wha t i t doe s not do : It doe s no t appl y mora l blinder s t o preven t same-se x couple s from receivin g th e benefits o f the law . But th e Ne w Sout h Wale s decisio n als o ha s limite d implica tions. This i s no t a cas e i n whic h a n intac t same-se x coupl e i s trying t o tak e advantag e o f benefit s accorde d t o heterosexua l couples, such a s health insuranc e an d ta x benefits . Instead , thi s is a cas e i n whic h on e membe r o f a relationshi p ha s a clai m against anothe r member . Thus a victory fo r th e lesbian plaintif f is a los s fo r th e lesbia n defendant . Th e cour t ha s therefor e allowed standar d lega l principles t o gover n th e income redistri bution a s betwee n tw o lesbians . I t woul d b e a fa r mor e radica l step fo r th e cour t t o allo w a same-sex coupl e t o tak e advantag e of general societa l benefits tha t ar e exclusively reserved for het erosexuals. Then th e ga y o r lesbia n plaintiff s woul d b e makin g a clai m agains t th e resource s o f societ y i n general , rathe r tha n against th e resource s o f the member s o f their ow n community . THE GOO D NEW S

The decisio n b y th e Hawai i Suprem e Cour t t o appl y equalit y doctrine to a marriage clai m by a same-sex coupl e has been her alded a s a great victor y i n th e ga y an d lesbia n community . Bu t the Hawaii court couched its decision in gender rather tha n sex ual orientatio n term s an d therefor e di d no t hav e t o confron t directly th e mora l argument s use d i n th e Unite d State s t o justify sexua l orientatio n discrimination . I n Baehr v. Lewin, 33 th e

170

Sexual Orientation Discrimination

Hawaii Suprem e Cour t rule d tha t th e Hawai i marriag e statut e presumptively constitute d unconstitutiona l discriminatio n based o n sex . The court' s decisio n completel y ignore d th e peti tioners' sexual orientation; in fact, it was not eve n considered t o be relevan t t o th e Court' s decision . Observin g simpl y tha t a n individual coul d marr y a ma n onl y i f sh e wer e a woman , th e court conclude d tha t th e marriag e rul e constitute d a sex-base d rule. The fac t tha t th e historica l origin s o f suc h a rule reflecte d animus o n th e basi s o f sexua l orientatio n rathe r tha n gende r was not relevan t t o the court' s decision . Its decision reflecte d a n analysis of the language, rather than the intent or history, of th e challenged statute . B y employin g suc h a n analysis , th e cour t was able to rule fo r th e petitioners without reachin g the thorn y question o f whether discriminatio n o n the basis of sexual orien tation shoul d be tolerated . In 1996 , the U.S . Supreme Cour t hande d ga y rights activist s their firs t majo r victor y befor e th e highes t cour t i n a six-to three decision in Romer v. Evans.34 Th e Court held that the vot ers of the stat e o f Colorad o acte d unconstitutionally whe n the y approved a n amendmen t t o thei r stat e constitutio n tha t woul d prohibit al l legislative, executive, or judicial action s designe d t o protect th e right s o f an y gay , lesbian, or bisexual perso n o n th e basis o f hi s o r he r sexua l orientation . Althoug h ga y right s activists hav e heralde d Romer v. Evans a s " a landmar k civil rights ruling," 35 th e Suprem e Court' s decisio n i n tha t cas e i s actually consisten t wit h it s tren d towar d acceptin g th e princi ples o f forma l equalit y an d avoidin g mora l issue s i n ga y right s cases. This cas e ca n b e understoo d a s consisten t wit h th e anti affirmative actio n backlas h describe d i n previou s chapters . I t may reflec t a short-term victor y fo r ga y and lesbian people, but it als o reflect s a long-term tren d towar d underminin g affirma -

Sexual Orientation Discriminatio n

171

tive action . I t als o say s nothin g abou t overturnin g Bowers v. Hardwick, therefor e stil l leaving ga y me n an d lesbian s withou t constitutional protection . The Wall Street Journal ha s graspe d thi s connection . I n a n editorial followin g th e Romer decision , th e Journal sai d tha t i t was "cheered " t o se e Justic e Anthon y Kenned y recit e th e famous lin e from Plessy v. Ferguson tha t the Constitutio n "nei ther know s no r tolerate s classe s amon g citizens" 36 because tha t statement clarifie s tha t th e Cour t "i s startin g t o mak e color blindness a reality." 37 As the Journal noted , the doctrin e under lying Romer bette r reflect s th e anti-affirmativ e actio n backlas h than a positiv e statemen t abou t th e right s o f ga y an d lesbia n people. Th e autho r o f th e Court' s opinion , Justic e Kennedy , applied th e forma l equalit y principle s tha t h e ha d previousl y applied t o revers e discriminatio n case s in orde r t o overtur n th e Colorado amendment . Th e doctrin e tha t h e applie d wa s no t novel; wha t wa s nove l wa s hi s willingnes s t o exten d tha t doc trine t o a case that involve d ga y an d lesbian petitioners . The surprisin g resul t fo r someon e who expect s the Cour t t o follow principle s o f forma l equalit y an d laissez-fair e capital ism i n a n evenhande d manne r i s tha t Justice s Antoni n Scalia , William Rehnquist , an d Clarenc e Thoma s file d stron g dis sents. Despite thei r stanc e a s th e stronges t proponent s o f for mal equalit y doctrin e o n th e Court , the y coul d no t leav e asid e their moralisti c impulse s t o exten d thos e principle s t o ga y men, lesbians , an d bisexuals . The y ha d t o lum p th e cas e int o the "specia l treatment " categor y i n orde r t o rationaliz e th e failure t o apply principles o f formal equalit y to gay and lesbia n petitioners. "The amendmen t prohibit s specia l treatmen t o f homosexu als, and nothing more," 38 argued Justice Scalia in vigorously dis-

172

Sexual Orientation Discriminatio n

senting fro m th e majority' s holding . "Th e principle/ ' h e con tended, tha t underlie s th e majority' s opinio n is that on e who i s accorded equa l treatmen t unde r th e laws, but canno t a s readily as others obtai n preferentia l treatmen t under the laws, has been denied equal protection o f the laws. If merel y statin g thi s allege d "equa l protection " violatio n does not suffic e t o refute it , our constitutiona l jurisprudenc e has achieved terminal silliness . Scalia, whos e opinion s ar e usuall y know n fo r thei r clos e reading o f the text , must ignor e completel y th e language o f th e challenged amendmen t t o arriv e a t tha t conclusion . I t i s tru e that th e amendment woul d prohibit specia l treatment o n behal f of gay, lesbian, and bisexual people, since it prohibits any "quot a preferences" fo r suc h groups. But it is also true tha t th e amend ment prohibit s antidiscriminatio n protectio n a s well. I t clearl y states tha t branche s o f governmen t ma y no t "enact , adop t o r enforce an y statute , regulation , ordinanc e o r polic y whereb y homosexual, lesbia n o r bisexua l orientation , conduct , practice s or relationship s shal l constitut e o r otherwis e b e th e basi s o f o r entitle an y perso n o r clas s o f person s t o hav e . . . claim o f dis crimination." As th e majorit y stated , the resul t o f th e adoptio n of th e amendmen t woul d b e t o invalidat e nondiscriminatio n ordinances passed by the cities of Denver and Boulder. It took no grand constitutiona l analysi s t o apply the plai n languag e o f th e amendment to the plain language of the local ordinances. In fact , although Scali a accuse s th e majorit y o f "termina l silliness, " h e offers n o alternative interpretation o f the amendment a s applied to th e Boulde r an d Denve r ordinances . Nondiscriminatio n ca n no longer be offered t o gay, lesbian, and bisexual people after th e adoption o f Amendment 2 . It is this nondiscrimination principl e

Sexual Orientation Discriminatio n

173

that Justice Kennedy's opinio n claimed must be protected by th e Equal Protection clause , no more an d n o less. Scalia set s u p th e case a s a specia l protectio n cas e s o tha t h e does no t hav e t o distinguis h i t fro m th e lon g lin e o f forma l equality case s tha t h e ha s followe d s o passionately . Th e lega l question tha t h e see s a s underlying thi s cas e is "whethe r ther e was a legitimate rationa l basis for th e substanc e of the constitu tional amendment—for th e prohibition o f special protection fo r homosexuals/' He then chide s the majority fo r avoidin g discus sion o f thi s question , "sinc e th e answe r i s s o obviousl y yes. " Scalia i s correc t tha t virtuall y n o group , an d certainl y no t a group compose d o f ga y me n an d lesbians , can mak e a constitu tional clai m fo r specia l protection unde r existin g jurisprudence . The majority fail s to ask that questio n because it is irrelevant t o the cas e befor e th e Court . Amendmen t 2 i s unconstitutiona l under existin g doctrin e no t becaus e i t prohibit s specia l treat ment fo r ga y me n an d lesbian s bu t becaus e i t als o invalidate s laws tha t promis e equa l treatment . Scali a fail s t o explai n wh y gay men an d lesbians ar e not "persons " who, like white hetero sexual men , ar e entitle d t o th e equa l protectio n o f th e law s a s guaranteed b y th e Fourteent h Amendment . The majorit y an d dissentin g opinion s i n Romer ar e ship s passing i n th e nigh t becaus e the y as k an d answe r entirel y dif ferent questions . Jurisprudentially, however , they actuall y see m to agree o n a core principle—that ga y men an d lesbian s ar e no t entitled t o specia l protection . Bot h th e majorit y an d minorit y opinions are premised o n a commitment t o formal equality . The dissent i s forced t o distort th e plain meaning o f the amendmen t to take it ou t o f forma l equalit y doctrine . The dissent distort s the amendment's languag e to placate th e moralism o f Colorad o voters . Even Scali a has t o admi t tha t th e

174

Sexual Orientation Discrimination

Colorado voter s wer e tryin g t o "preserv e traditiona l sexua l mores" through th e passag e o f Amendment 2 although h e als o tries t o hid e thei r moralis m b y describin g the m a s " seemingly tolerant/' Had Scali a bee n trul y committe d t o th e value s o f laissez faire capitalism , rathe r tha n th e value s o f th e so-calle d mora l majority, he would have had to note the inefficiency o f allowin g the Colorad o voter s t o enforc e thei r sexua l prejudice s throug h law. Tolerance i s a basic value unde r laissez-fair e capitalism , s o this exampl e o f direc t disregar d fo r toleranc e shoul d hav e dis turbed Scalia . Thus, not onl y doe s h e misrea d th e amendment , but h e als o goe s s o fa r a s to misstat e th e attitud e o f th e voter s by callin g the m "tolerant " whil e the y tr y t o enforc e thei r ow n sexual prejudices . The dissonanc e containe d i n Scalia' s opinio n rings loudl y despit e hi s attemp t t o us e rhetorica l flourishe s t o distract th e reade r fro m th e underlyin g inconsistenc y i n hi s opinion. There is no better exampl e of the inconsistency o f Americanstyle laissez-fair e capitalis m tha n Scalia' s opinio n i n Romer. I t exposes th e tru e value s tha t underli e hi s often-state d commit ment t o formal equality . Sexual moralism excuse s adherenc e t o the constitutiona l principle s o f equalit y unde r th e law. Statutory La w SEX DISCRIMINATION 39

When Ernes t Dillon an d Mari o Carreno 40 wer e subjecte d t o repeated graffit i wit h statement s suc h as "Dillon give s head" o r had thei r genital s an d buttock s caresse d b y coworkers , the y were denied protection unde r Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964 because their claim s were considered to be based on sexua l

Sexual Orientation Discriminatio n

175

orientation rathe r tha n gender . (Title VII prohibits employmen t discrimination o n th e basi s o f sex. ) The y wer e no t allowe d t o use Title VII t o gai n protectio n fo r themselve s a s gay men . Yet when Robi n McCoy , a female , brough t sui t unde r Titl e VI I because he r femal e superviso r allegedl y rubbe d McCoy' s breasts, rubbe d betwee n McCoy' s legs , an d force d he r tongu e into McCoy' s mout h whil e als o callin g McCo y " stupid poo r white trash " an d "stupi d poo r white bitch, " McCoy prevailed. 41 Instead o f branding th e cas e as one based o n sexua l orientation , the cour t foun d tha t i t fi t th e standar d rule s fo r sexua l harass ment. U.S . court s hav e therefor e allowe d Titl e VI I t o b e use d against lesbia n o r ga y mal e supervisor-employee s bu t hav e no t allowed Title VII to be used o n thei r behalf . This complicate d we b o f casela w make s sens e whe n on e appreciates th e moralisti c agend a underlyin g th e courts ' inter pretation o f Titl e VII . Titl e VI I i s interprete d t o protec t th e chastity o f heterosexua l wome n an d protec t heterosexua l me n from sexua l advance s fro m othe r men . But i t is not designe d t o extend an y comparabl e protectio n t o ga y me n an d lesbians . N o matter ho w horrendousl y the y ar e sexualize d a t the workplace , they d o no t receiv e protectio n fro m suc h sexualizatio n b y th e courts. It is only thos e person s wh o ar e perceived b y th e court s to be heterosexuals wh o receiv e protection fro m sexualization . Application o f pur e laissez-fair e principle s would , o f course , result i n th e repea l o f Title VII. And Richar d Epstein , a s a pur e proponent o f suc h principles , doe s cal l fo r th e repea l o f al l antidiscrimination laws. 42 Bu t Epstein' s approac h i s no t th e dominant approac h unde r America n law . Instead , th e court s interpret existin g antidiscriminatio n doctrin e t o advanc e a homophobic, moralistic agenda . This awkwar d interpretatio n o f Titl e VI I i s no t inevitabl e

176

Sexual Orientation Discriminatio n

under capitalism . Canadian courts have not excluded gay and lesbian worker s fro m th e la w o f sex discrimination . Wherea s U.S . courts hav e refuse d t o fin d tha t ga y an d lesbia n peopl e ar e pro tected agains t same-se x harassmen t a t th e workplace , Canadia n courts have found tha t suc h harassment i s unlawful. I n Re Cami Automotive Inc. and Canadian Auto Workers, Local 88, 43 th e arbitrator assume d tha t sexua l harassment discriminatio n woul d violate th e collective-bargainin g agreement . Th e onl y issu e i n dispute was a technical one—whethe r th e grieve r ha d give n suf ficient notic e o f his inability t o work because o f the harassment . While findin g tha t h e had not give n sufficien t notic e at the time, the arbitrato r foun d tha t h e shoul d hav e been reinstate d whe n a psychiatrist finall y provide d justification mor e tha n si x month s later. Unlike the United States , here the context for th e arbitrato r was tha t bot h th e collective-bargainin g agreemen t an d th e human right s ordinance forbid sexua l orientation discrimination . EMPLOYMENT NONDISCRIMINATIO N ACT

Because th e court s hav e refuse d t o interpre t th e U.S . Constitu tion o r Titl e VI I a s extendin g protectio n t o ga y me n an d les bians, the only legal recourse fo r ga y men an d lesbians has bee n to persuade th e legislature t o pass new statutes t o protect them . In th e las t severa l years, a key strateg y o f the ga y right s move ment ha s been to gain passage of the Employment Nondiscrim ination Act (ENDA)— a federa l statut e designe d t o provide pro tection fro m employmen t discriminatio n fo r ga y me n an d les bians. To gain passag e o f this statut e unde r a Republican Congress , the proponent s hav e ha d t o draf t th e statut e quit e narrowl y t o make i t minimall y acceptabl e t o America n politicians . The y have tried to structure the statute around laissez-faire principle s

Sexual Orientation Discriminatio n

177

by havin g i t reflec t principle s o f forma l equalit y an d intrud e a s little a s possible int o th e econom y o f the workplace . Knowing that an y affirmative rights fo r ga y and lesbian peo ple woul d immediatel y receiv e a stron g negativ e response , th e drafters o f END A carefull y eliminate d an y vestige s o f affirma tive treatmen t i n th e statute . Thu s th e statut e generall y pro vides tha t employer s no t b e permitte d t o " discriminate agains t an individual o n the basis of sexual orientation." The two possible "specia l treatment " argument s tha t ma y hav e bee n mad e against th e statut e wer e specificall y eliminate d throug h th e statutory language . First , Sectio n 5 o f th e statut e provide s tha t it "doe s no t appl y t o th e provisio n o f employe e benefit s t o a n individual fo r th e benefit o f suc h individual' s partner. " I n othe r words, employer s ca n continu e t o offe r healt h insuranc e bene fits t o th e partner s o f heterosexual s bu t no t t o th e partner s o f gay peopl e despit e th e passag e o f ENDA . Second , Sectio n 7 of the statut e provide s tha t a "covere d entit y shal l no t adop t o r implement a quota o n th e basi s o f sexua l orientation " an d tha t a "covere d entit y shal l no t giv e preferentia l treatmen t t o a n individual o n th e basi s o f sexua l orientation. " Eve n voluntar y affirmative actio n become s unlawfu l unde r ENDA , althoug h i t is not entirel y unlawfu l unde r Title VII. Not onl y doe s th e statut e no t requir e (o r eve n permit ) an y type o f "specia l treatment, " bu t i t als o exempt s th e arme d ser vices an d religiou s institution s fro m coverage , thereb y honor ing th e twi n principle s o f moralis m an d militarism . Th e ne t effect o f thes e exclusion s an d qualification s i s that man y o f th e gay right s issue s tha t ar e currentl y bein g hotl y litigated—gay s in th e militar y an d health insuranc e benefit s fo r same-se x cou ples—are no t affecte d b y th e passag e o f ENDA . Nonetheless , during th e 199 6 presidential electio n campaign , Senato r Rober t

178

Sexual Orientation Discriminatio n

Dole, th e Republica n candidate , criticize d EN D A a s a "specia l treatment" statute . When aske d durin g th e secon d presidentia l debate whether he supported the "Employment Nondiscrimina tion Act" (ENDA) (whic h would ban discrimination o n the basis of sexual orientation i n the workplace), Senator Dol e responde d that h e di d no t favo r "specia l right s fo r an y group," 44 strongl y implying tha t END A constitute d "specia l treatmen t legisla tion." But o f course, ENDA cannot be arguably characterize d a s special treatment legislation . An interesting question is what the implications of the exclu sions and exceptions foun d i n the curren t versio n o f ENDA are. Can an y classwid e effect s b e discerne d fro m th e compromise s that wer e mad e i n th e hop e o f ENDA' s eventua l passag e unde r American capitalism ? The employee benefit exclusio n is impor tant t o thos e member s o f th e ga y communit y wh o liv e i n a household i n whic h on e perso n hold s healt h insuranc e benefit s and th e othe r perso n doe s not . Sinc e middle-clas s full-tim e employees ar e mor e likel y t o hav e healt h insuranc e benefits , this problem i s usually the most seriou s in households i n whic h one partner hold s a blue-collar job, works part time, or is unem ployed. Women , o n average , hav e les s lucrativ e job s tha n d o men. Thus , a relationshi p consistin g o f tw o wome n i s muc h more likel y to fac e thi s problem tha n a household consistin g o f two men. The AIDS crisis has also, of course, disproportionatel y affected ga y men . T o th e exten t tha t th e AID S crisi s ha s als o impoverished household s afte r on e partne r become s unabl e t o work bu t stil l mus t see k medica l treatment , thi s exclusio n wil l affect man y poo r household s consistin g o f two men . The AIDS crisi s has cause d man y peopl e i n th e ga y commu nity t o begin t o suppor t a system o f nationalize d healt h insur ance, because they no w realize how important th e health insur -

Sexual Orientation Discriminatio n

179

ance issu e i s t o basi c survival . Bu t whe n th e ga y communit y itself propose s nationa l antidiscriminatio n legislation , i t ironi cally finds tha t i t canno t mentio n healt h insuranc e fo r fea r tha t such a measure would derai l the entir e bill. In other words , capitalist oppositio n t o nationa l healt h insuranc e seep s int o th e debate abou t a nondiscriminatio n bil l tha t cover s th e privat e sector. (I n the sam e presidentia l debate , Senator Dol e was care ful t o link the Democrats with suppor t o f national health insur ance—something h e thought fle w i n the fac e o f American capi talism fo r mos t voters . He therefor e wa s playing th e capitalis m card.) The impac t o f affirmativ e actio n languag e migh t als o be fel t on a class-define d basis . First , w e mus t ask , Wher e doe s affir mative actio n currentl y exis t tha t i t migh t end ? Fe w main stream employer s hav e an y kin d o f affirmativ e actio n progra m that include s ga y people . I n th e ga y community , on e migh t argue that gay-owned businesses such as bars, clubs, and restau rants hav e affirmativ e actio n policie s i n tha t the y ar e likel y t o want t o hire "on e o f thei r own " t o work a t establishment s tha t cater t o th e ga y communit y Furthermore , suc h businesse s probably offe r salarie s a t th e lo w en d o f th e wag e spectrum , since servic e jobs ar e usuall y lo w paying . The effec t o f END A might b e t o generat e revers e discriminatio n case s agains t gay owned establishments . Eve n i f thes e establishment s di d no t have any forma l o r informal polic y of favoring ga y applicants, a heterosexual ma y b e abl e t o convinc e a conservativ e judg e o r jury tha t suc h a policy existed. (Given the way that Title VII has been use d t o har m ga y me n an d lesbians , this resul t woul d no t be surprising.) Thus , ENDA might foste r a n attack on gay insti tutions while having a disproportionate impac t o n gay men an d lesbians wh o hol d suc h service-industr y jobs . (Fo r example ,

180

Sexual Orientation Discrimination

Michael Hardwick' s job a s a bartender i n a gay bar woul d b e i n jeopardy.) Nondiscrimination legislatio n o n the basis of sexual orienta tion i n Canad a ha s no t suffere d fro m thes e kind s o f class-base d problems. Unlik e th e America n model , i n whic h a ne w statut e was drafte d t o respon d t o sexua l orientatio n discrimination , Canadian province s tackle d th e proble m o f discriminatio n against ga y me n an d lesbian s b y amendin g thei r existin g nondiscrimination legislatio n t o includ e sexua l orientation . Since the existin g nondiscriminatio n law s in Canad a d o protec t affirmative action , the amendment o f those laws to include sex ual orientatio n doe s not preven t affirmativ e actio n o n th e basi s of sexua l orientation . The healt h car e issu e i n Canad a doe s no t pose th e sam e leve l o f proble m fo r ga y an d lesbia n peopl e i n Canada a s it doe s i n th e Unite d States , because al l people hav e health insuranc e throug h thei r provincia l government , regard less o f thei r employmen t o r familia l status . Family-relate d issues aris e onl y wit h respec t t o supplementa l benefits , fo r instance, dental o r visio n insurance , tha t ma y no t b e offere d a s part o f th e minimu m provincia l plan . These supplementa l ben efits ar e sometime s provide d throug h employer s and , a s in th e United States , no t necessaril y mad e availabl e t o th e same-se x partners o f employees . At firs t glance , the American la w o f sexua l orientatio n appear s to be chaotic. But whe n on e examine s th e la w through th e len s of moralis m an d militarism , i t come s int o focus . Whe n face d with a n issue affecting ga y men an d lesbians, conservatives lik e Justice Scali a abando n laissez-fair e economi c principles . An d when the American military needs to be defended, th e U.S. Congress an d th e court s abando n laissez-fair e economi c principles .

Sexual Orientation Discriminatio n

181

But thes e result s ar e not inevitabl e unde r capitalism . Althoug h other capitalis t countrie s ar e managing t o extend constitutiona l and statutor y protectio n t o ga y me n an d lesbians , there i s littl e sign o f chang e i n th e Unite d States , notwithstandin g th e deci sion in Romer v. Evans an d the progress being made toward th e passage o f ENDA .

6 UNPROTECTED WORKER S

In the late 1980s, Michael Anthony Billiar d worked fo r Bigelo w Holding Company , a renta l compan y i n th e stat e o f Nevada. 1 Bullard believe d tha t th e compan y ha d a renta l polic y o f dis criminating agains t Africa n Americans . O n on e occasion , h e feared tha t th e company was planning to physically assaul t tw o black me n wh o ha d entere d th e propert y i n orde r t o ge t the m out. When hi s coemployee, Carol Swenson, radioed his supervi sor, Donna Dollman, about the presence of the black men o n th e property, Bullar d sai d t o Swenson , "Black s hav e rights , too/ ' After Swenso n reporte d tha t remar k t o Dollman , Dollma n entered th e offic e an d sai d t o Bullard : "What' s you r fuckin g problem?" " I don' t hav e a problem, " replie d Bullard . Dollma n said, " I thin k yo u do . I think you'r e a fuckin g nigge r lover . Si t your Go d dam n as s dow n o n tha t fuckin g stool , shu t you r

Unprotected Worker s

183

mouth, an d d o you r fuckin g work/ ' Les s the n a minut e later , Dollman added, "On secon d thought, get your fucking as s out of here. I don't wan t yo u workin g fo r m e anymore/ ' Bullard, a blue-collar, nonunion employee , sued his employe r for unlawfu l discharge . Although a jury wa s sympatheti c t o hi s case an d awarde d damage s fo r a discharge tha t wa s contrar y t o public policy, the Suprem e Cour t o f Nevada reverse d th e rulin g in a 199 5 decision , declarin g tha t Bullard' s discharg e wa s no t governed b y federa l nondiscriminatio n la w an d tha t h e di d no t have an y contractua l protectio n fro m arbitrar y discharge . Lik e most American workers, he was employed "a t will" and could be discharged fo r an y reaso n a t all . Accordin g t o th e Nevad a Supreme Court , Bullard could be discharged simpl y because th e employer considere d hi m t o a "a bad person, a person wh o wa s sympathetic t o African-Americans. " Few people in the United State s receiv e federall y mandate d protection fro m arbitrar y treatmen t a t th e workplace . Although Titl e VI I o f th e Civi l Right s Ac t o f 196 4 protect s against discriminatio n o n th e basi s o f race , sex , nationa l ori gin, an d religion , thes e claim s ar e rarel y successfu l excep t fo r reverse discriminatio n claim s brough t b y whit e men . B y imposing a n impossibl e threshol d o f proo f o n th e plaintiffs , judges dispos e o f man y discriminatio n claim s brough t b y women an d minoritie s b y renderin g summar y judgment s i n favor o f th e defendants , thereb y precludin g thes e case s fro m even goin g t o th e jury. 2 Similarly , th e American s wit h Dis abilities Act purport s t o protec t agains t discriminatio n o n th e basis o f disability , ye t a s w e sa w i n chapte r 3 , narro w lega l decisions hav e rendere d mos t o f thes e claim s t o be unsuccess ful eve n whe n stron g evidenc e o f discriminatio n exists . Mandatory arbitratio n clause s hav e als o prevented man y vie -

184

Unprotected Workers

tims o f discriminatio n fro m receivin g thei r "da y i n court/' 3 Instead, the y hav e bee n subjecte d t o employer-biase d arbitra tors. 4 An d thos e employee s whos e discharg e claim s tha t li e outside America n antidiscriminatio n la w hav e virtuall y n o legal recourse . The Unite d State s i s th e onl y Western industrialize d natio n that stil l operate s unde r th e premise s o f th e "employmen t a t will" doctrine , b y whic h employer s nee d no t demonstrat e "cause" to fire a n employee . (The United State s als o is the onl y Western natio n no t t o ratif y Conventio n 15 8 o f th e Interna tional Labo r Organization , whic h forbid s employer s fro m ter minating employee s withou t jus t cause.) 5 I n th e hand s o f con servative judges, this doctrin e give s nearly unlimite d leewa y t o employers t o fir e employees . I n on e case , Judg e Posne r con cluded tha t a chief executiv e office r wa s a "master o f vengeful ness" as well as a "bad man" but nonetheless was justified i n fir ing a sixty-two-year-ol d employe e wh o refuse d t o pledg e loy alty t o hi m becaus e th e chie f executiv e wa s stealin g fro m th e firm.6 Laissez-fair e economic s seem s t o requir e n o respec t fo r basic human o r civi l rights a t the workplace . The employment-at-will doctrin e is only one of several policies tha t leave s man y employee s withou t meaningfu l protec tion a t the workplace. Unpaid an d underpaid domesti c workers, part-time employees , an d employee s wh o wor k fo r smal l employers ar e ofte n exclude d fro m th e protectio n o f federa l law As economists Barr y Blueston e an d Bennett Harriso n asked , "How d o we buil d a stable, humane, equitabl e communit y an d still have economi c growth? And ho w d o we go about th e busi ness o f constructin g a productiv e econom y whic h produce s livelihoods withou t destroyin g lives?" 7 Unfortunately , th e

Unprotected Worker s

185

response o f America n capitalis m t o thes e question s ha s bee n disappointing; community ha s been sacrifice d fo r capital .

Underpaid Domesti c Worker s

In Marc h 1986 , a native o f Trinidad, was hired a s the babysitte r for Judg e Kimb a Wood's infan t son . Because th e babysitter wa s not a legal resident o f the United States , domestic work was on e of th e onl y occupation s fo r whic h sh e coul d legall y qualify—i t was not unti l late r tha t yea r tha t Congres s passe d a law makin g it illegal to employ illega l aliens a s domestic help. 8 By then, he r employer ha d complete d th e necessar y paperwor k t o emplo y her legally . Th e sitter' s residen t status , however , depende d o n her retainin g he r jo b a s a babysitter . Unlik e mos t babysitters , her employe r eve n pai d her Socia l Securit y taxes . Zoe Baird' s babysitte r wasn' t treate d quit e a s well. She, too, was a n illega l alie n wh o wa s pai d $25 0 per wee k t o car e fo r he r infant. Unlik e Kimb a Wood , he r employe r faile d t o pa y Socia l Security taxe s and workers' compensation taxe s (unti l her non payment becam e politicall y embarrassing) . Lik e Wood , how ever, Baird an d he r husban d sponsore d th e woman fo r statu s a s a lawfu l resident , givin g he r th e opportunit y t o sta y i n thi s poorly pai d job. The Baird and Wood incidents put the spotligh t o n the pligh t of illega l alien s wh o wor k a s domesti c hel p i n ric h people' s households. The politica l response , however , wa s t o reliev e th e burden o n ric h peopl e by extendin g th e Socia l Securit y exemp tion fo r domesti c wor k rathe r tha n t o improv e th e situatio n o f illegal alien s wh o hav e fe w employmen t opportunitie s othe r than potentiall y exploitiv e domesti c work . (Coul d thes e illega l aliens hav e complaine d abou t unlawfu l o r eve n crimina l treat -

186

Unprotected Workers

ment?—Not i f the y wante d t o sta y i n th e Unite d States. ) N o attempt wa s mad e t o broade n th e enforcemen t o f th e Socia l Security o r Immigration law s to protect th e interests o f domes tic workers . Eve n th e Nationa l Organizatio n fo r Wome n (NOW) di d no t se e thi s episod e a s a n opportunit y t o commen t on th e deplorabl e condition s fo r domesti c workers . Instea d Patricia Ireland , NOW' s president , complaine d abou t thi s inci dent a s "jus t to o clea r a n exampl e o f a doubl e standar d bein g used t o keep women ou t o f power/' 9 Th e solutio n i s apparentl y to allow women t o exploi t domesti c labor a s much a s men hav e historically exploite d it . That is , laissez-faire economic s i s suc h a powerful disciplin e in the United States that even the Nationa l Organization fo r Wome n ha s troubl e seein g pas t it s distorte d consequences. American household s hav e little to fear fro m employin g ille gal aliens (unless one of the parents decides to seek a highly publicized political appointment) becaus e the Immigration an d Nat uralization Servic e (INS ) doe s not target households fo r investi gation. Moreover, the fines rarely exceed $1,000. Thus, American households ca n affor d t o ignor e immigratio n la w (an d al l othe r laws) whe n hirin g househol d help , wherea s illega l alien s hav e few othe r employmen t options . The Immigratio n Refor m an d Control Act of 1986 (making unlawful th e hiring of illegal aliens as domestic workers) couple d with th e Immigratio n Ac t o f 199 0 (greatly increasin g th e waitin g perio d fo r househol d worker s t o obtain permanen t status ) an d th e INS' s polic y o f no t enforcin g its law s agains t household s leave s a patchwork o f subsidizatio n for upper-clas s America n household s an d exploitatio n fo r poo r women fro m Thir d World countries . The Bair d an d Woo d incident s ar e onl y som e o f th e mos t recent examples of overlooked exploitation of domestic workers.

Unprotected Worker s

187

American la w an d politic s ha s historicall y disregarde d th e con ditions o f domesti c work. The Fai r Labo r Standard s Act (FLSA ) was firs t passe d i n 1938 , but ove r a storm o f laissez-faire oppo sition. Like the modern-da y Famil y an d Medica l Leav e Act, th e original FLS A wa s mor e promis e tha n action . I t se t a twenty five-cents-per-hour federa l minimum wage for som e employee s working i n interstat e commerce , whic h affecte d th e wage s o f only 300,00 0 employee s i n th e Unite d States . Larg e classe s o f employees wer e exempte d fro m th e statute : worker s i n intrastate industrie s (suc h a s domesti c workers) ; worker s i n executive, administrative, professional o r local retail; workers i n retail o r servic e industrie s operatin g i n intrastat e commerce ; seamen, air carrier workers; workers in the fishing an d seafood processing industry; anyone i n agriculture ; people in dairy pro cessing; worker s fo r smal l newspapers ; loca l bu s o r trolle y workers; an d learners , apprentices , an d handicappe d workers . Predominantly femal e occupation s suc h as those o f hotel work ers, retai l clerks , janitors , nurses , an d domesti c worker s wer e excluded fro m coverage . The agricultura l exclusio n dispropor tionately affecte d souther n Africa n Americans . "Becaus e o f these exemptions , th e employee s protecte d b y th e FLS A wer e predominantly white, male, industrial-class workers. Indeed, the 1938 FLS A wa s politicall y crafte d t o exclud e man y worker s from it s minimum-wag e coverage , particularl y wome n an d southern African-American workers/' 10 Although today , som e o f thes e initia l gap s i n coverag e hav e been filled , th e FLS A stil l exempt s employee s o f seasona l amusement businesses , people i n outsid e sales , domestic work ers, some agricultura l an d seafoo d workers , som e employee s o f small newspapers , an d som e retai l an d servic e workers . Whe n the Clinto n administratio n supporte d raisin g th e minimu m

188

Unprotected Worker s

wage, no consideratio n wa s give n t o fillin g i n thos e gaps . Thus, minimum wag e law s leav e domesti c worker s underpai d an d underprotected b y th e law. Minimum wag e law s ar e no t th e onl y law s that fai l t o appl y to domesti c workers . Man y state s exclud e domesti c worker s along wit h othe r contingen t worker s fro m unemploymen t insurance programs. 11 Similarly , th e Occupationa l Safet y an d Health Act (OSHA ) doe s not cover domestic workers if they ar e not considere d " employees'" o r i f thei r immediat e worksit e i s not a n "employer ' unde r th e law . Th e restrictiv e tenur e an d vesting requirement s mak e th e Employe e Retiremen t Incom e Security Ac t unavailabl e t o domesti c workers . Al l th e federa l legislation tha t contain s requirement s fo r minimu m number s of employees—suc h a s Title VII o f the Civi l Rights Act o f 196 4 (fifteen employees) , the Americans with Disabilities Act (fiftee n employees), an d th e Famil y an d Medica l Leav e Ac t (fift y employees)—also exclude s domesti c workers . Thus, fro m 193 8 onward, we se e a continuing tren d t o exclude domesti c worker s from an y statutor y protection . The immigratio n la w support s th e abus e o f domesti c work ers, a s i t make s i t almos t impossibl e fo r unskille d worker s (which i s ho w domesti c worker s ar e classified ) t o immigrat e legally t o th e Unite d State s t o secur e employment. 12 Eve n i f they hav e a household sponsor , i t typicall y take s te n year s fo r their applicatio n t o b e approved . A househol d employe r wh o needs a domesti c worke r ca n rarel y affor d t o wai t tha t long . Consequently, a s " Nanny gate" revealed, many household s hir e aliens illegall y t o work i n thei r household s because , in practice , the employer s o f domesti c worker s ar e rarel y targete d fo r "employer sanctions/ ' or I-9, violations. Therefore, even thoug h household employer s hav e littl e t o fea r i n regar d t o th e law' s

Unprotected Worker s

189

enforcement, illega l alien s hav e muc h t o fear . I f a n employe r violates th e minimu m wag e o r maximu m hou r law s or , mor e significantly, subject s the m t o sexua l abuse , they fac e deporta tion i f the y complai n abou t th e violatio n o f thei r rights . Suc h workers d o not, o f course , have an y "rights " give n thei r illega l status. Who benefit s fro m thes e rules ? The publi c controversy abou t "Nannygate" clarifie s wh o th e intende d beneficiarie s are . These exclusions make it easier for th e upper clas s to afford th e service s of domestic workers. When Zoe Baird had legal problems becaus e she underpaid her taxes for her domestic worker, the response was to broaden th e exemptio n fo r payin g taxe s fo r domesti c workers. The politica l respons e t o th e Baird/Woo d episod e shoul d hav e been a commitment t o strenghtening th e protection fo r domesti c workers rather than expandin g the loopholes for the upper class.

Unpaid Domesti c Worker s

In 1984 , at the ag e of sixty-two , Gladyce Corneliu s began regu larly carin g fo r he r granddaughte r whil e he r daughte r wa s employed a t th e Alabama Institut e fo r th e Dea f an d Blind. 13 I n 1986, her daughte r bega n payin g he r mothe r fo r thes e service s at the modest rat e of $45 per week. She also made contribution s to Socia l Securit y o n behal f o f he r mother . Whe n sh e reache d the age of sixty-five, Corneliu s tried to collect these Social Secu rity retirement benefits. Her claim was denied, however, because her earning s fo r babysittin g service s wer e no t covered , sinc e they wer e performe d i n th e hom e o f he r daughter . Th e Socia l Security Act's regulation s exemp t suc h service s fro m statutor y coverage, eve n thoug h th e Elevent h Circui t conclude d tha t th e Social Securit y Ac t rul e wa s base d o n th e presumptio n "tha t

190

Unprotected Worker s

there is no need for domesti c service when both spouse s are present and able to work/' Congres s apparently assumed that unde r these circumstances, the woman works in the home and the ma n in the marketplace. Nonetheless, the court found tha t the statut e did not violate th e equa l protection clause . Under th e act , a parent ma y wor k fo r hi s chil d i n th e cours e o f th e child' s trad e o r business bu t ma y no t perfor m domesti c service s fo r th e chil d either insid e o r outsid e th e home. 14 Domestic service s have no t qualified a s genuine "work " unde r American law . Under America n law , housework ha s neve r bee n considere d to hav e economi c value. 15 Work i n th e hom e thu s provide s n o entitlement t o Socia l Security , i s no t include d i n th e gros s domestic product, and is unvalued o r grossly undervalued a t th e time o f divorce. Despite the public rhetoric to the contrary , welfare moms do "work," supervising and nurturing children . They are poor partly because a s a society, we do not compensat e suc h work, but thi s doe s not mak e th e work les s genuine . In th e nam e o f laissez-fair e economics , American politician s increasingly proclaim that poor mothers* should receive no subsidy fro m th e state . Such a subsidy, we ar e told , creates a "cycl e of dependency " tha t undermine s America n familie s an d wor k ethic. Welfare mother s ar e supposed to be lazy women wh o sta y home all day using drugs and abusing their children. But, in fact , while welfar e pay s badly , low-wag e job s pa y eve n worse . Most welfar e mother s ar e quit e willin g t o work i f the y en d up with significantly mor e disposable income as a result. But they ar e no t willin g t o wor k i f workin g will leav e the m a s poor as they were when the y staye d home. 16 Throughout thi s discussion , I refer t o "mother, " sinc e thes e policie s dispro portionately affec t wome n wh o are raising children. O f course , I realize tha t som e men are single parents and so are also affected b y these policies.

Unprotected Worker s

191

Even mor e important , wh y shoul d w e giv e thes e wome n a n incentive to work in the public marketplace while raising youn g children? The same data that suppor t paid leave for women wh o work i n the marketplac e als o support subsidie s fo r wome n wh o work i n th e home—tha t is , children benefi t fro m parenta l car e in th e firs t yea r o f thei r lives . Poo r women , lik e upper-clas s women, shoul d b e abl e to choos e t o sta y hom e t o car e fo r thei r own childre n withou t feelin g economicall y coerce d to enter th e marketplace. I n fact , societ y ma y disproportionatel y benefi t from havin g poo r wome n sta y hom e t o car e fo r thei r childre n because suc h car e migh t hel p thei r childre n counte r th e influ ence o f "drugs , crime , gangs , an d othe r letha l lures " t o whic h their childre n ar e routinely exposed . "If motherhoo d i n genera l entails work , poo r motherhoo d entail s eve n mor e work , an d poor motherhood , whil e receivin g AFDC , i s on e o f th e mos t burdensome type s o f motherhood imaginable." 17 The subsidie s sough t b y singl e mothers wit h childre n ar e n o different fro m th e subsidie s sough t fro m other , more acceptabl e family constellation s i n ou r society . To qualify fo r federa l assis tance, a poor woma n mus t b e both th e head o f a household an d responsible fo r dependen t children . He r wor k i s domesti c work—taking car e of her children . If thi s woma n wer e marrie d t o a wage-earnin g spouse , w e would b e happ y a s a societ y t o subsidiz e he r chil d care . Unde r our ta x code , marrie d familie s wit h onl y on e wag e earne r receive a marriage benefi t an d als o ca n deduc t thei r childre n a s "dependents." If they buy a house, they als o can take advantag e of generou s ta x mortgag e policies . And i f the y bot h ente r th e workforce an d need to pay for chil d care, they ca n also take a tax deduction fo r tha t expense , thereby receivin g stat e assistance i n paying fo r thei r chil d care . Thus, either th e famil y i s subsidize d

192

Unprotected Worker s

for havin g th e woman sta y a t home, or the famil y i s subsidize d for thei r chil d car e while sh e works outsid e th e home . U.S. la w trie s simultaneousl y t o cu t bac k benefit s t o singl e mothers o n welfare whil e increasing child-base d ta x deduction s for middle-clas s Americans. Assistance t o poo r mother s i s stig matized, an d assistanc e t o middle-clas s familie s i s applauded . The American approac h t o subsidizin g parenthoo d i s relativel y unusual. Mos t countrie s i n th e Wes t provid e a child allowanc e or basic income guarante e t o all families wit h children , no t jus t to th e poor . Caretakin g benefit s ar e considere d a s earne d income, regardles s o f th e car e provider' s socia l o r economi c class. I n th e Unite d States , we hol d childre n hostag e whil e w e use ou r socia l welfar e policie s t o impos e o n poo r mother s th e values o f marriag e an d mal e dependency . "Lik e th e wa r o n drugs, the war o n poverty, now recast as the war o n welfare, ha s the underlyin g passio n o f a moral crusade/' 18 I t i s time tha t w e recognize th e economi c valu e o f raisin g children , regardles s o f the parent's marita l statu s o r economi c class.

The Contingent Workforc e

Jere Ellis , a n employe e o f Charle s Raines , fel l 98 5 fee t t o hi s death whil e paintin g a television towe r owne d b y Chas e Com munications. 19 At th e tim e o f his fall , his only protective equip ment wa s a short bel t safet y harness , which Elli s had unhooke d in orde r t o chang e position s o n th e tower . His estat e file d a sui t against th e owne r o f the premises o n which h e fel l to his death , claiming tha t Chas e ha d no t ensure d tha t th e wor k me t th e standards se t by the federal Occupationa l Safet y an d Health Act (OSHA). Because Chas e had hired a n independent contracto r t o perform th e work on the tower, it was not subject t o the require -

Unprotected Worker s

193

ments o f OSHA . Jer e Ellis , lik e man y person s wh o wor k i n inherently dangerou s occupations , receive d littl e lega l protec tion unde r federa l o r stat e law . Independent contractors , as well as all persons who perform domesti c tasks at private residences , are exclude d fro m protectio n unde r OSHA. 20 A s par t o f th e "contingent wor k force/ ' the y li e outside th e law. The contingen t labo r force—part-tim e workers , contrac t workers, temporar y workers , an d independen t contractors — comprises almos t a thir d o f America n workers. 21 Th e larges t segment o f th e contingen t workforc e i s part-tim e workers , many o f whom i n fac t wor k full-tim e hour s bu t d o so by hold ing two or more part-time jobs. Part-time employee s dispropor tionately ear n th e minimum wag e (2 5 percent o f them ear n th e minimum wage , compared with 5 percent o f full-time workers) . Employers wh o us e contrac t worker s avoi d responsibilit y fo r tax withholdings o f an y kin d an d nee d no t follo w th e la w wit h regard t o minimum wage s an d payment fo r overtime . The use of contract workers has increased dramatically in th e past tw o decade s a s employer s hav e trie d t o downsiz e an d sav e expenses.22 Contract workers are most commonl y foun d i n lowpaying industrie s suc h a s construction , janitoria l services , an d garment manufacturing . Employer s wh o us e independen t con tractors avoid complying with safety regulations , paying payroll taxes an d federall y mandate d benefits , an d complyin g wit h standards suc h a s unemployment benefits , workers ' compensa tion, pensio n regulation , antidiscriminatio n laws , federa l dis ability insurance, and minimum wag e and maximum hou r laws. Although som e independen t contractor s ar e well-pai d profes sionals, many ar e low-wag e worker s whos e employer s deliber ately mislabel them a s independent contractor s to avoid compliance wit h variou s federa l laws . One o f th e larges t categorie s o f

194

Unprotected Worker s

poorly pai d independen t contractor s i s day laborers , dispropor tionately compose d o f immigran t me n wh o wor k i n construc tion, landscaping, agriculture, o r other hazardou s trades. 23 According t o forme r Labo r Secretar y Rober t Reich , "Th e contingent workforc e i s outside th e syste m o f worker-manage ment relationship s an d expectation s we'v e create d ove r th e years/' 24 The laws regulating working conditions , wages, hours, benefits an d labo r representatio n "implicitl y reflec t a n increas ingly outdate d mode l o f employment : full-time , long-term — even lifetime—employment wit h a single employer. Social welfare polic y als o remain s largel y predicate d o n thi s model." 25 Whereas 17. 8 percen t o f al l full-tim e worker s belonge d t o a union in 1993, only 7.2 percent of part-timers were union mem bers. Th e Employe e Retiremen t an d Incom e Securit y Ac t o f 1981 (ERISA ) require s onl y thos e employer s wh o hav e a pen sion pla n t o exten d i t t o al l employee s workin g mor e tha n on e thousand hour s pe r yea r (abou t twent y hour s pe r week) , an d loopholes eve n allo w employer s t o exclud e part-tim e worker s who averag e more tha n on e thousand hour s pe r year. The Fam ily and Medical Leave Act excludes part-time workers from cov erage eve n i f thei r employe r i s covered. Employees ar e no t eli gible to receive Socia l Security retiremen t benefit s o r disabilit y insurance even if their employer has contributed to Social Security on their behalf, unless they have been in "covered" employ ment earnin g above a statutory minimu m amoun t fo r si x of th e previous thirtee n quarter s befor e seekin g benefits . State enforced program s als o ofte n fai l t o protec t th e contingen t workforce. Temporary workers, domestic workers, and indepen dent contractor s ar e usuall y exclude d fro m unemploymen t insurance programs , an d minimum-wor k requirement s ofte n serve to exclude part-time employees .

Unprotected Worker s

195

The part-tim e labo r force , thoug h denie d th e protection s o f the socia l safety net , is often no t voluntarily workin g part time . In 1993 , 6 million American s wer e involuntaril y workin g par t time. One-third o f women workin g part tim e would work mor e hours i f the y coul d ge t chil d care . In general , part-time wor k i n the Unite d State s i s relatively poorl y compensated , wit h few , if any, benefits. On average , full-time worker s in the United State s earn 3 9 percent mor e i n hourl y wage s tha n d o part-time work ers. Of familie s heade d b y women (an d therefore subjec t t o th e new restrictions o n welfare), "hal f o f these women who worke d part-time i n 198 3 said they would rathe r hav e worked full-tim e but wer e constraine d b y th e hig h cost s an d unavailabilit y o f quality chil d care." 26 I f wome n wh o hea d household s an d ar e working only part time find it impractical to work full time , how can w e expec t wome n wh o hea d household s an d ar e unem ployed t o fin d manageabl e full-tim e employment ? A t most , w e can probabl y expec t thes e wome n t o ente r th e rank s o f th e poorly compensated , part-tim e labo r force . The differentia l betwee n part-tim e an d full-tim e worker s i s much smalle r i n othe r industrialize d countries . In the 1980s , 18 percent o f Canada' s part-time worker s belonged t o a union, an d its full-tim e worker s earne d onl y 2 1 percent mor e o n averag e than di d part-tim e workers . Man y countries , includin g France , Germany, an d Spain , hav e law s forbiddin g discriminatio n i n salary o r benefit s betwee n part-tim e an d full-tim e workers . Whereas U.S . law explicitly exempt s part-tim e employee s fro m most federa l legislation , thes e countrie s mandat e nondiscrimi nation betwee n part-tim e an d full-tim e workers . No t surpris ingly, when Congresswoma n Patrici a Schroede r introduce d th e Part-Time and Temporary Workers Protection Act of 1993, publications lik e the Wall Street Journal complaine d loudl y Previ -

196

Unprotected Worker s

ous attempt s t o requir e full-time/part-tim e benefi t parit y hav e failed. Conservativ e economist s typicall y prais e th e larg e part time workforce i n the United State s as demonstrating th e "flex ibility" o f th e U.S . economy, withou t assessin g th e voluntari ness of that statu s o r the level of compensation offere d t o thos e workers. 27

Employment a t Wil l INDIVIDUAL TERMINATIONS

In 1989 , Rub y Well s an d tw o othe r license d practica l nurse s who worke d fo r a nursing hom e requeste d a meeting wit h th e nursing hom e administrato r t o discus s problem s a t th e work place.28 When th e administrato r refuse d t o mee t wit h the m a t that time , the y drov e t o Toledo , Ohio, to mee t wit h th e direc tor o f huma n resource s an d vic e presiden t o f operations . Two of th e thre e nurse s wh o mad e th e tri p t o Toled o wer e termi nated o r disciplined , an d s o the y file d a charg e wit h th e National Labo r Relation s Boar d claimin g tha t the y ha d bee n disciplined fo r engagin g in concerted protecte d conduc t fo r th e purpose o f collective bargaining. In a five-to-four decision , th e U.S. Suprem e Cour t rule d tha t the y wer e no t covere d b y th e National Labo r Relation s Act because their dutie s included th e supervision o f nursin g aides. 29 Receivin g n o protectio n fro m federal law , these nurse s wer e "a t will " employee s wh o coul d be discipline d o r terminate d fo r an y reaso n whatsoever , eve n though th e administrativ e la w judg e ha d conclude d tha t th e licensed practica l nurse s wer e "jus t hire d hands. " Thei r predicament wa s typica l o f tha t o f mos t America n workers — they receive d virtuall y n o workplac e protectio n fro m disci pline o r discharge .

Unprotected Worker s

197

U.S. la w i s dominate d b y th e principl e o f "employmen t a t will/' by which employers can fire workers without establishin g cause, unless th e employe e i s fortunat e enoug h t o hav e a con tract specifyin g tha t justificatio n i s require d fo r terminatin g a contract. Th e standar d formulatio n fo r employmen t a t wil l i s that a n employer ma y dismis s an employe e "fo r goo d cause, fo r no cause , o r eve n fo r caus e morall y wrong/' 3 0 I t i s estimate d that betwee n 150,00 0 an d 200,00 0 persons ar e dismisse d i n th e United State s eac h year withou t just cause , often wit h a result ing loss in healt h insurance. 31 The at-wil l doctrin e i s a peculiarly America n inventio n an d is highl y reflectiv e o f a laissez-fair e attitud e towar d low-leve l workers. The doctrine was devised in 1877 by a New York attor ney, H . G . Wood, i n a scholarl y treatise . H e "announce d a s a general la w i n th e U.S . th e righ t o f eithe r employe r o r employee to terminate a contract of unspecified duratio n a t an y time, with o r without cause , or even fo r bad cause/' 32 The ratio nale behind th e rul e reflects th e fals e presumption s underlyin g laissez-faire economics—tha t i t i s suppose d t o benefi t worke r and employe r equall y because the y bot h ar e suppose d t o bene fit equall y fro m th e flexibility t o quit o r be fired. Bu t in reality , the rule disproportionately benefit s th e employer , who is much more likel y t o want t o fir e a worker tha n a worker i s likel y t o want t o quit . Because o f th e harshnes s o f th e at-wil l rul e fo r employees , the court s hav e create d some—albei t ver y limited—exception s to th e principle . Fo r example , a n employe e ma y expressl y con tract fo r a goo d caus e requiremen t fo r discharg e (outsid e th e union context) . Nonetheless, man y court s hav e conclude d tha t such a promise i s no t enforceabl e whe n i t i s foun d onl y i n th e employer-written personne l manual . The promis e i s considere d

198

Unprotected Worker s

to be "gratuitous" rathe r tha n bindin g in the absence of specifi c evidence tha t th e employe e relie d o n th e promis e whe n accept ing the offe r o f employment . One wa y t o abolis h th e at-wil l doctrin e woul d b e throug h state contrac t la w governin g th e employmen t relationship . Resistance t o suc h a mov e i n th e Unite d States , however , ha s been strong . Althoug h th e Unifor m La w Commissioners 7 Model Terminatio n Act , approve d an d recommende d fo r adop tion fo r al l fifty stat e legislatures in 1991 , abandoned th e at-wil l doctrine, onl y on e stat e (Montana ) ha s enacte d thi s propose d legislation. There is therefore littl e reason to believe that the at will doctrin e wil l b e eliminate d i n th e Unite d State s anytim e soon. The situatio n i s markedl y differen t i n th e Europea n Unio n (EU). O f th e fiftee n countrie s include d i n th e EU , al l bu t Bel gium an d Greec e requir e goo d caus e fo r termination . I n addi tion, eac h o f thes e countrie s (especiall y includin g Belgiu m an d Greece) requir e minimu m preterminatio n notic e periods . Mos t European countrie s hav e works councils . For example, Austria's works council s "mus t b e consulte d prio r t o an y managemen t action o n certai n measure s specifie d b y statut e an d i n som e instances th e counci l mus t giv e it s consen t befor e a manage ment decisio n ma y b e implemented . On e suc h requiremen t t o obtain th e work council' s consen t i s termination, eithe r wit h o r without notice/' 33 Thus, not onl y mus t managemen t mee t cer tain specifie d criteri a befor e termination , bu t als o th e decisio n itself mus t b e reviewed befor e i t can become final . The contras t betwee n th e Unite d State s an d Europ e reflect s starkly differen t conception s o f employe r freedom . I n th e United States , employer s rarel y hav e t o justify thei r termina tion decisions. In Europe, however, the employer ha s the burde n

Unprotected Worker s

199

of provin g t o a work s counci l tha t i t ha s goo d caus e fo r dis missal. Although th e America n rul e supposedl y derive d fro m th e British commo n law, Great Britain has long since repudiated th e doctrine. Sinc e 1978 , Britis h employee s hav e bee n statutoril y protected fro m unfai r dismissa l b y th e Employmen t Protectio n (Consolidation) Act , unde r whic h th e employe r mus t demon strate that he reasonably believed that th e employee engage d i n misconduct. Similarly, in Germany, dismissal s ar e legally void when the y are "sociall y unjustified/' 34 Th e employe r ha s th e burde n t o show justification , an d dispute s concernin g justificatio n ar e handled b y th e labo r courts . Th e employe r mus t als o consul t with th e works counci l before dismissin g a n employee . Sweden use d th e doctrin e o f employmen t a t wil l unti l 197 4 when i t passe d th e Employmen t Securit y Act. Dismissals mus t now b e base d o n "objectiv e cause/' 35 Thi s standar d i s eve n stricter tha n th e "goo d cause " standar d use d i n th e Unite d States fo r employee s governe d b y collective-bargainin g agree ments. As i n German y an d Grea t Britain , th e employe r mus t inform th e union before dismissin g the employee and must giv e notice to the employe e before dismissal . Additional notic e mus t be given to the county employment boar d to enable the board to assist i n findin g futur e employmen t fo r th e terminate d worker . Terminated employee s als o receiv e a wid e rang e o f socia l ser vices tha t ar e funde d b y th e governmen t rathe r tha n th e employer. Because of the harshness of the "at-will" doctrine that under lies American labo r law , i t i s importan t fo r employee s t o con tract fo r a "goo d cause " standar d fo r discharge . On e wa y t o acquire suc h protection i s through a union contract , which typ -

200

Unprotected Worker s

ically contain s a good caus e rule , as well a s a grievance proces s to contes t a discharge . Nonetheless, les s tha n 2 0 percent o f th e American workforc e i s unionized. Som e workers , like domesti c workers, ar e nonunionize d becaus e the y ar e no t protecte d b y the National Labor Relations Act. Other workers are technicall y eligible for collective-bargainin g protection but do not belong to a union . COLLECTIVE DISMISSALS : PLAN T CLOSING S

First Nationa l Maintenanc e Corporatio n (FNMC ) ha d a n employment relationshi p wit h maintenanc e personne l wh o cleaned th e Greenpar k Car e Center. 36 Unde r th e term s o f thei r contract, Greenpar k wa s prohibite d fro m directl y hirin g th e workers durin g th e ter m o f thei r contrac t o r fo r ninet y day s thereafter. Shortl y befor e FNM C terminate d it s contrac t wit h the Greenpar k Car e Center , an d thereb y ende d it s employmen t relationship wit h thos e employees , th e Greenpar k employee s joined a union . Th e employee s wer e give n thre e days ' notic e that thei r employmen t contrac t woul d b e terminated , an d the y therefore trie d to bargain with the employer to renegotiate thei r contract an d retai n thei r jobs . Althoug h th e compan y main tained tha t terminatin g th e employmen t relationshi p wa s "purely a matte r o f money/ ' i t refuse d t o negotiat e wit h th e union representativ e fo r th e employees . Th e employee s wer e fired an d Greenpar k wa s unabl e t o hir e th e forme r FN M employees directl y becaus e o f th e contract' s ninety-da y limita tion. The unio n file d a grievanc e allegin g tha t th e employe r ha d failed t o engag e i n bargainin g a s require d unde r th e Nationa l Labor Relation s Act. The administrative la w judge hel d in favo r of th e union . The Nationa l Labo r Relation s Boar d adopte d th e

Unprotected Worker s

201

findings o f the administrative la w judge. The employer appeale d to th e U.S . Cour t o f Appeal s fo r th e Secon d Circuit , whic h enforced th e board' s orde r i n a two-to-on e decision . Th e U.S . Supreme Cour t reversed. Applying a balancing test, it conclude d that "th e har m likel y to be done to an employer' s nee d t o oper ate freel y i n decidin g whether t o shu t dow n par t o f its busines s purely fo r economi c reasons outweigh s th e incremental benefi t that migh t b e gained throug h th e union' s participatio n i n mak ing the decision. " The Cour t neve r seriousl y contemplate d th e valu e t o th e employees of , a t least , negotiatin g t o hav e th e ninety-da y rul e eliminated, s o that Greenpar k coul d hire them directly . Such a n agreement woul d hav e produced a potentially significan t bene fit t o th e employee s whil e gainin g FN M a modes t publi c rela tions benefi t fo r n o cost . O r mor e significantly , a s pointe d ou t by th e dissentin g justices , th e unio n migh t hav e bee n "abl e t o offer concessions , information , an d alternative s tha t migh t obviate o r forestal l th e closing." 37 Th e majorit y nonetheles s ignored contemporanou s experience s a t othe r workplace s a t which suc h negotiation s ha d bee n productive , choosin g instea d to speculat e tha t th e benefi t o f suc h negotiation s wa s minimal . As judges wit h lifetim e tenure , th e majorit y seeme d unabl e t o consider th e cost s an d benefit s fo r th e employee s i n thi s case . Once again , a n opinio n tainte d wit h th e cost-benefi t schem e o f law and economic s hold s fo r th e employer-entrepreneur . The law on plant closing s has improved onl y modestl y i n th e United States since the Greenpark case was decided in 1981. Congress passed the Worker Adjustment an d Retraining Notificatio n Act i n 1988, 38 whic h require s a sixty-da y notic e t o employee s before a plant ma y clos e or engag e in a mass layoff, bu t i n mos t situations, th e exception s t o thi s rul e undercu t it s effectiveness .

202

Unprotected Workers

To be covere d b y th e statute , a n employe r mus t la y of f a t leas t one-third o f th e employees , constitutin g a t leas t eithe r fift y employees a t on e sit e o r a t leas t fiv e hundre d employees . Thus, even if an employer ha s hundreds o f employees a t dozens of different site s but n o close d sit e has mor e tha n fift y employees , h e is no t covere d b y th e statute , whic h result s i n th e exclusio n o f major industrie s suc h as trucking an d delivery services. 39 Very larg e employer s ar e als o ofte n abl e t o escap e coverag e under th e five-hundred-employe e layof f rule . Fo r example , McDonnell Dougla s Corporatio n lai d of f 60 9 employee s between Octobe r 16 , 1992 , an d Januar y 14 , 1993 , but throug h clever countin g rule s wa s abl e t o escap e th e five-hundred employee rul e (som e employee s wer e par t time ; som e worke d about eleve n mile s fro m th e mai n plant ; som e wer e rehire d within si x months). 40 Employer s ma y reduc e th e notificatio n period if they are actively seekin g capital or business in order t o avoid a shutdown o r if the business circumstance s requirin g th e layoff wer e not reasonabl y foreseeable . The unforeseeable busi ness circumstance s exceptio n ha s bee n construe d generously , allowing McDonnel l Dougla s t o argu e tha t i t coul d no t forese e the cancellatio n o f a fighter/bomber contract , althoug h it s ow n long-standing performanc e problem s wer e clearl y a major fac tor i n th e cancellatio n o f th e contract . Moreover , testimon y before Congres s ha d forewarne d i t o f th e slowdow n i n govern ment militar y contract s lon g befor e thi s happened . Despit e more tha n si x month s o f negotiation s wit h th e government , which resulte d in the cancellation o f the contract, the court con cluded that McDonnel l Dougla s me t th e standar d o f a " sudden, dramatic, and unexpected actio n or condition" leading to an economic downturn. 41 It i s unlikel y tha t th e Greenpar k employee s woul d hav e

Unprotected Worker s

203

received an y protectio n ha d thi s statut e existe d a t th e tim e o f their layof f i n the earl y 1980s , because thei r situatio n coul d no t be describe d a s a "mas s layoff/ ' Moreover , th e relie f tha t the y sought—the abilit y t o negotiat e directl y wit h anothe r contrac tor—is no t contemplate d i n thi s federa l statute . They als o ma y not hav e had th e require d fift y statutor y employees . Whereas Europea n countrie s tr y t o preven t plan t closing s and assis t worker s wh o los e job s becaus e o f plan t closings , American la w perversel y encourage s plan t closings . Th e U.S . Steel Corporation , fo r example , could close down fourtee n mill s in eigh t states , laying of f thirtee n thousan d workers , for a $850 million ta x break , which i t late r pu t towar d th e dow n paymen t on th e purchas e o f Maratho n Oil. 42 The er a o f Reaganomic s sa w a bidding war amon g th e state s to lowe r th e ta x rate s o n corporation s whil e als o cuttin g bac k protections fo r employees . Companie s ar e no t subtl e abou t th e business climat e the y seek—a t th e expens e o f workers . Fo r example, th e Conferenc e o f Stat e Manufacturer s Associatio n ranked Mississipp i a s havin g th e bes t "busines s climate " because i t ha d lo w taxes , low unio n membership , lo w workers ' compensation insuranc e rates , low unemploymen t benefit s pe r worker, lo w energ y costs , an d fe w day s los t wor k becaus e o f stoppages.43 Where favorable benefit s d o not already exist, companies ar e abl e t o extrac t the m fro m citie s o r states . Genera l Motors, fo r example , "convinced " th e cit y o f Detroi t t o clea r four hundre d acre s of land, dislocating 3,200 people from on e of Detroit's mos t sociall y integrate d communitie s an d closin g 16 0 community businesse s whil e givin g G M a twelve-yea r ta x abatement wort h $24 0 millio n i n forgon e revenue s t o buil d a new plant. In the unbalanced world in which American corpora tions d o business , communitie s hav e littl e choic e bu t t o mak e

204

Unprotected Worker s

such concessions . If they d o not, companies ca n quickly relocat e to communities tha t wil l provide thes e an d othe r concessions . American worker s receiv e almos t n o protectio n fro m plan t closings. Less tha n 1 0 percen t o f employee s hav e contract s tha t provide fo r advanc e notificatio n befor e a plant i s closed . And o f those workers with prenotification rules , more than three-fourth s are guaranteed only a one-week notice or less. Rarely are employees entitle d t o an y severanc e pay . Of th e minorit y o f employee s covered by a contract, only half receiv e any severanc e pay. By contrast , mos t Europea n countrie s requir e employer s t o negotiate layoffs wit h the employees' union o r joint labor-man agement council . I f layoff s ar e unavoidable , corporation s ar e required t o giv e advanc e notic e t o th e workers , the unions , an d the nationa l employmen t servic e befor e closin g a plant o r dis missing worker s fo r economi c reasons . I n Germany , th e Co determination Ac t of 197 6 requires a company contemplatin g a shutdown t o open it s books t o the loca l works counci l s o that i t can evaluat e it s corporat e data . If a plant mus t close , a one-yea r advance notic e mus t b e provided. Othe r rule s als o mitigate th e effect o f collectiv e dismissals . Employer s ar e require d t o tak e into accoun t "socia l aspects " whe n dismissin g employees , thereby requirin g thos e who would suffe r mos t fro m dismissa l to be the last to be let go. 44 Employers must als o give employee s the opportunit y t o transfe r job s eve n i f th e ne w jo b woul d require som e schoolin g o r training . Finally , whe n a n employe r with twent y o r mor e employee s plan s a substantia l chang e i n the workforce , th e employe r an d work s counci l ar e require d t o work ou t a "social plan" to accommodate th e interest s o f work ers as much as possible, including the awarding of severance pay. In Grea t Britain , employer s mus t giv e advance notic e o f dis missal, dependin g o n th e lengt h o f prio r employment . Th e

Unprotected Worker s

205

employer mus t als o giv e thos e bein g dismisse d tw o day s of f with pa y t o loo k fo r othe r work . As i n Germany , th e employe r is required to consult with the employees' representative befor e making decision s o n collectiv e dismissals . I n th e even t o f dis missals, severanc e pa y i s required . Wherea s federa l an d loca l government provid e incentives fo r corporatio n relocatio n i n th e United States , European polic y seek s to avoi d suc h relocation . Repeated attempt s t o pass meaningful nationa l plant-closin g laws i n th e Unite d State s hav e bee n unsuccessful . No t surpris ingly, th e busines s communit y ha s oppose d suc h legislation , saying tha t i t would b e impractical becaus e shutdow n decision s are often mad e abruptly. Case studies reveal, however, that mos t shutdown decision s ar e planned fa r i n advance , and both Amer ican an d Europea n companie s tha t d o business i n Europ e fin d i t possible t o abide by thos e countries ' shutdow n rules. 45 The onl y hop e fo r increase d employe e protectio n agains t plant closing s i n th e Unite d State s appear s t o b e o n th e stat e level. Some states have passed plant-closing legislation that typ ically provide s fo r assistanc e t o unemploye d worker s afte r a plant ha s close d rathe r tha n tryin g t o aver t th e plan t closin g itself. Even suc h minima l legislatio n ofte n exclude s many busi nesses; th e Tennesse e statute , fo r example , oddl y cover s onl y businesses wit h mor e tha n fift y bu t fewe r tha n ninety-nin e employees.46 States that enact legislation that tries to limit plan t closings woul d b e o n th e lis t o f communitie s tha t ar e inhos pitable to business. And one can only hope that the courts would not water down such legislation through narro w interpretation s so as to undermine th e protections intende d b y suc h laws . The U.S. economy i s a subsidized economy . The real question i s which sector s receiv e subsidy . I n th e employmen t arena , w e

206

Unprotected Worker s

subsidize those workers and employers who least need subsidie s and cu t bac k o n subsidie s t o th e poor . Rathe r tha n exclud e domestic and agricultural workers fro m mos t employmen t pro tections, we nee d t o pu t suc h worker s i n th e forefron t o f stat e protection becaus e they ar e least likely to be able to contract fo r protection fro m thei r employer . Rather tha n stigmatiz e parent ing fo r th e poor , we nee d t o recogniz e th e wor k inheren t i n al l parenting. Suc h proposal s ar e no t outlandish ; the y ar e funda mental i n othe r Western industrialize d countries .

7 MEDINA'S STOR Y

Consider thes e tw o fictiona l accounts , on e fro m ou r pas t an d one that imagine s ou r future : Isabelle's daughter, Medina, attended the local college whose in-state tuition she could afford to pay. Eventually she enrolled in law school and graduated with honors. She decided to seek a clerkship so that she could someday enter the legal academy. Hearing that there was an opening in the local state court judge's chambers, she applied for a job. Aware that political connections often were important to securing a state clerk courtship (since state court judges are elected), she nonetheless hoped she would have a decent shot at selection, owing to her strong academic record and racial diversity. She had done some research on this particular judge, a judge Johnson, and thus

208

Medina's Stor y

knew he was eager to win the Latino vote in the next election. He might, she hoped, therefore be interested in hiring a Latina clerk. A few weeks after sending in her application, Medina received a telephone call from Johnson's secretary inviting her to come in for an interview. Medina was thrilled and immediately began to think about planning a successful interview. Her friends recommended that she ditch the corn rows for some hair straightener and buy a conventional blue suit. They also suggested she be careful in handling the diversity issue because Johnson would not want to hire a clerk whom he viewed as a rabble-rouser or one who was overtly trying to capitalize on her ethnic status. And of course, they told her to keep quiet about her lesbianism; coming out of the closest was the surest way to kill a job interview. Isabelle was torn. She took pride in her "natural" looks and never was one to hide her sexual orientation. It did not seem fair that Johnson could value her for her diversity yet demand that she look "white/' She also knew that even if she were hired, Johnson could fire her at any time without explanation. What if he learned of her lesbianism after she got the job and then fired her? Her partner, Elisa, was pregnant with twins, and it would probably be hard to hide these additions to her family, especially since she and Elisa had agreed that Medina would be the second parent on the birth certificate. She wanted to feel free to put pictures of her family on her desk at work just as the other law clerks did. As much as she needed the job, she also did not want a blotch on her record from being fired. She could send him her resume that revealed her gay and lesbian legal work — that would get her "out of the closet" before the interview. But that strategy might also backfire —give him an excuse to turn

Medina's Stor y

209

her down for the job before the interview. Usually, she had found, it was better to have people find out about her sexual orientation after they got to know her so that they could overcome their stereotypes. Maybe if she could find a discreet way to mention her lesbianism after making a good impression, it would work out. She did not want Judge Johnson to get angry at her later for trying to hide her lesbianism. This was a difficult dilemma but one she needed to resolve if she was to be a stable source of support for her ill mother and growing family and if she was to project herself as a confident and valuable prospect. On the day of the interview, Medina sat down nervously in a chair in the Judge's chambers wearing her blue suit and with her hair pulled back away from her face. (With that hairstyle, she could avoid straightening chemicals.) The judge entered, giving her a smile that put her somewhat at ease. ''Thank you for coming in today. As you probably know, I interview only a few people for my clerkship, but I was very impressed with your record and references." "Thank you," replied Medina, "I was thrilled to get the interview because I have been very impressed with your record as a judge. Not to sound like an apple polisher, but I remember thinking at the time that your decision last year in Sawyer s v . Daniels was a real pathbreaker. I am sure that other state supreme courts will consider developing such a theory in their contract cases/' "Well, thank you. Yes, I must confess that I'm rather proud of that decision. The idea that an employer could not be bound by a statement in an employee handbook had bothered me for years. Sawyers v. Daniels gave me the ideal factual pattern to rule that employers must abide by the plant notification clauses

210

Medina's Stor y

in their handbooks. Those workers needed an opportunity to look elsewhere for employment or, if possible, try to raise the capital to run the plant themselves. But I put in the 'exceptional circumstances' clause so as not to tie the hands of employers in the event of unforeseeable circumstances. Clearly, in this case, the shutdown was long anticipated although unknown to the employees." Well, mused the judge, she seems well informed about my decisions, even if it's only because she's done her homework. But I wonder if she can be objective about hard cases. Can she also help me draft opinions that are favorable to the employer? Her background suggests a strong employee bias. Maybe I should find out more about her background. Pausing, the judge looked at Medina closely and said softly, "So, I see that you supported yourself through college and law school." "Yes," replies Medina, "and I also had to support my mother who was no longer able to take care of herself Given the years that my mother devoted to cleaning other people's houses so that I could buy books for high school and college, I figured that was the least that I could do." "It must have been hard to live on so little." "A lot of people seem to expect that my mother would have received state assistance, since she was disabled and over sixtyfive. But she wasn't a U.S. citizen, so most benefits were not available to her." "Uh, I hate to be nosy and perhaps it's not proper of me to ask, but I'm just wondering. Did she consider becoming a citizen in order to get some benefits?" "My mother has always been a fiercely proud woman. When she was younger, she would not seek citizenship just to

Medina's Stor y

211

become eligible for benefits. She also assumed, somewhat pigheadedly, that she could work until the day she died. And then when she developed an extreme case of Alzheimer's, she no longer could meet the citizenship requirements." "Did you try to get the government to requirements in light of her disability 7.

waive some of the

"No, sir, there was no point. The United States never waives the requirement that you swear an oath of allegiance. And my mother's memory is so poor that she can't repeat the oath." "I'm sorry to hear that. It's too bad Congress isn't more sensitive to those kinds of problems." "That's not likely to change soon. My mother can't vote. My congressman isn't particularly concerned about her plight," said Medina, leaving out that she suspected this oversight was at least partially due to her accent. "What about Social Security? Did her employer contribute to Social Security on her behalf? "The law does require payment, of course, but it is almost never enforced. Enforcement against people like Zoe Baird is the exception, not the rule. It doesn't reflect the general enforcement pattern." "Well, you certainly seem well informed about American law concerning the poor and immigrants. Do you have other specialized legal interests?" "I find all of the law fascinating. I've had to learn poverty law and elderly law to assist my mother, but I honestly find nearly all aspects of the law stimulating. Maybe that's why I graduated with honors." Isabelle had to be careful not to show irritation in her voice. How many times had interviewers overlooked her strong record because of her special interest in the rights of the poor and the elderly?

212

Medina's Stor y

"Urn, yes, you're clearly a very fine student. Do you have other credentials that you think I might find of interest? Any references?" "I belong to the Haitian Law Student Association and do volunteer work with them. I could give you a list of my clients to speak to. I also have written an amicus brief in an immigration case pending before the U.S. Supreme Court. I have a copy here with me." "Thank you. Vll be glad to look at that material. I'm happy to see your pro bono record, but I should caution you that you cannot do pro bono work while you clerk for me, because of the potential conflicts of interest. I also have to be careful not to bring any disrepute to this office, so I am very private about my political beliefs." "Oh, I understand. I work with the Haitian group primarily for social reasons. It's a nice way to meet other Haitians." "Of course, I encourage my clerks to be active in their church and social activities. But I also have to be very clear about the work rules. This is only a one-year position with no vacation time. I once had a clerk who, unknown to me at the interview, was three months pregnant when she started the job. Six months later, when it was time to give birth, she expected me to give her paid maternity leave for twelve weeks. There was just no way I could do that. I have a small office to run and very limited resources. If I had given her paid leave, then I would be short one clerk for twelve weeks. I offered to give her unpaid leave but rehire her the following year, because she was an excellent clerk. But she refused to see the situation from my position and was quite upset. So, now I'm very careful to tell people the rules up front. I'm a grandfather and love children, but I can't afford to extend leave of any kind to a clerk in my

Medina's Stor y

213

court. This may sound a bit harsh, but it's what the position and what I require, plain and simple. Would that pose any problems for you? Please do be as candid as you can." "Oh, sir, I'm here because I heard that you were an excellent judge to work with. All other concerns are secondary to me at this point, including vacation and, uh, procreation. And I don't know quite how to say this because I don't want to give you the wrong impression." Pausing, Medina spoke in a halting, nervous voice, " I'm not going to get pregnant accidentally, sir, because my .. .uh ... sexual interests lie more with women, and with my mother to support, I have no intention of using other means to get pregnant at this time." The judge's face flushed, and he struggled to conceal his surprise, unable to suppress the reflexive thought: 'A lesbian, eh? I'd never have guessed, her being so attractive." Never having met a self-identified Haitian lesbian, he experienced a quick succession of thoughts: "How's it going to look when I stand for election and people find out that I had a lesbian clerk? Isn't she going to be biased in all the difficult family law cases that I get? How about that case last term involving the sperm donor who wanted to be declared the father of a child that two lesbians were coparenting?" He made a mental note to talk to some other colleagues about this application, to find out whether they had ever had a homosexual clerk. Eager to conclude the interview, given his upcoming noon fund-raiser for his reelection campaign, but also fully aware that he was not likely to find a more qualified minority clerk and not wanting to seem to be ending things because of her comments about her sexuality, the judge answered, "Uh, your mother. . . . right. Tell you what—I'll get back to you after I interview a few more candidates for the position. Thank you very much for your time. And

214

Medina's Stor y

give your mother my best wishes. I am sure she must be very proud of you. And don't worry, your sexuality would not be an issue one way or the other as it pertains to —or, rather, doesn't pertain to —the judge smiled —your application." Medina never heard from the judge again, and her former clients tell her that they never were called. She suspects that her brief went unread as well. And although she has always been open concerning her lesbianism, she understands that the judge never mentioned it to anyone. Or coul d the followin g b e Medina's story ? Medina attended an American university where she received a full scholarship in recognition of her work on behalf of her family. Helping take care of her ill mother was considered to be important work worthy of recognition. Upon graduation from college, Medina received a stipend from the federal government to work in the community. Accompanying the stipend was a voucher for home health care for her mother who could not stay home by herself all day without assistance. After a few years, Medina decided to attend law school and, once again, received a full scholarship in recognition of her work both in the home and in the community. When a Latino lawyer was elected to an opening in the state supreme court, Medina decided to apply for a clerkship. Once again, she found herself in his chambers, but this time with her hair in corn rows and her favorite colorful scarf wrapped around her head. The judge glanced at her as he came into the interview room. He was looking forward to this interview, having heard that Medina had been a real standout at the local law school. He knew that he might be criticized if he only hired

Medina's Stor y

215

minority clerks, but Medina was so well qualified that he hoped that he could get away with hiring her. "Thank you for coming in with so little notice. As I imagine you've figured out from the quick response time, I called you to arrange an interview as soon as your application came across my desk." "Thank you, sir. I was very flattered by your immediate interest in my candidacy. I hadn't expected to get a call from you directly! When I canvassed for your campaign, I had no idea that I might find myself in your office someday, talking about whether I might be qualified to work with you. It's a real honor to be here." "So, I see that you supported yourself through college and law school," says the judge. "I, too, had the pleasure of being able to take care of family responsibilities while getting more education." "Yes," replies Medina, "the Family Partnership Act has made a big difference in my community. We no longer have to choose between taking care of ailing relatives and getting an education. The definition of work has been expanded to include work in the family. My mother can also now receive retirement benefits through Social Security, which gives her credit for the years she spent taking care of us in the home. It is now understood that she had two jobs—taking care of other family's children and taking care of us. And although her employer never contributed to Social Security on her behalf, she recently received a large settlement on behalf of all domestic workers who were coerced into not receiving Social Security benefits. The Bayer family is now on probation for their illegal actions and is reportedly paying Social Security taxes for their current domestic workers."

216

Medina's Stor y

"I hear that the 'three strikes and you're out' policy has really improved the record of payment for domestic workers. Didn't I also hear that Mr. Bayer was prosecuted for his sexual harassment of your mother?" "No, the new law protecting domestic workers from sexual harassment wasn't retroactive, but my mother did testify before Congress about her mistreatment. I suspect the publicity from that testimony was sufficient punishment for Mr. Bayer. He was apparently demoted at his job because of his inability to work well with professional women." "How is your mother's health?" "The national health insurance program that was instituted has allowed her to receive innovative therapies for people with Alzheimer's. Although she'll never regain the memory she has lost, her rate of deterioration has slowed tremendously. I bet Mr. Bayer wishes her memory would have faded more rapidly!" "Well, we should talk about your ability as a potential law clerk. I see you have a very fine record in school, but I've learned not to put too much weight on a clerk's grades. Can you give me other evidence of your abilities?" "My work on behalf of the Haitian Law Student Association might help you. I do volunteer work on behalf of illegal immigrants and recently wrote an amicus brief on a pending Supreme Court case. If you will protect the confidentiality of my clients, I can give you some phone numbers to call to get references. And I can leave a copy of the brief for you to read." "Thank you. I find that personal references from pro bono clients can be the most useful sort of reference. I will definitely call as many of those people as I can. One of my other clerks can also help if I have any language difficulties. Well, this really

Medina's Stor y

217

looks like a strong application. Do you have any questions for me?" "Mm, I don't know quite how to ask this. And I hope you don't take offense. It's not really a question about the job." "Go ahead. I promise not to take offense unless you, of course, plan to criticize my tie." "Certainly not, a green tie blends in very nicely with a navy blue suit," Medina answered with a broad smile. "Seriously, I have a personal favor to ask of you and didn't know when else I might be able to ask you." "Fire away. The worst I can do is say no." "My partner and I are planning to get married this summer and were wondering if you would officiate at our wedding. As you know, same-sex partners have been able to get lawfully married only since this last year. Elisa is pregnant, and we were hoping to get married before the twins are born." "It would be my pleasure! And if you want to take a leave once the babies are born, please let me know. Our standard practice is to pay So percent of your wages for up to six months following the birth of a child. You also have the option of working half-time for up to one year at 8 0 percent of your normal wages. But when there is a multiple birth, those figures are pushed up to 10 0 percent. I hope you find that policy reasonable." "Thanks. I'll discuss it with Elisa. I suspect I'll want to stay home full time for the first three months and then go to a halftime schedule for the next six months. Elisa can arrange a similar schedule with her employer so we can probably avoid child care for the crucial first nine months of their lives." "Great. I'll look forward to reading your engagement announcement in the newspaper. Feel free to send out invita-

218

Medina's Story

tions, and let me know where you want to conduct the ceremony. " "Thanks, judge. I hope this is the beginning of a long-lasting relationship. I, too, hope to be a judge someday and see this job as giving me invaluable experience/' Neither scenari o i s likely t o happen , o f course . Because w e ar e trained t o hide ou r stereotype s an d prejudices, the judge woul d probably kno w bette r tha n t o revea l hi s concern s abou t preg nancy a t a n interview . Bu t Medin a woul d b e foolis h t o thin k she entered the interview on a level playing field. Her challeng e is to reassur e he r interviewe r b y offerin g answer s t o the ques tions that h e dared not as k like—are you goin g to get pregnant , does your Haitia n wor k mak e yo u to o biase d t o be a fair clerk , are yo u a rabble-rouse r wh o i s goin g t o b e har d t o ge t alon g with? The secon d scenari o i s unlikely t o tak e place because we ar e not ther e yet . Bu t sometime s ther e ar e hopefu l signs . When I was a t th e en d o f m y recen t pregnancy , I got a call fro m a la w school intereste d i n recruitin g m e fo r a ne w position . When I said that I was pregnant an d coul d no t trave l a t that time , the y offered t o keep the position ope n unti l I could travel. They als o offered t o tak e car e o f m y infan t whil e I ha d th e interview . Unlike th e traditiona l America n model , the y sa w m y preg nancy a s an occasio n fo r accommodatio n rathe r tha n rejection . Of course , I would b e naiv e t o thin k tha t thei r respons e woul d have been a s generous i f I had been applyin g fo r a janitorial o r secretarial position . (I n fact , i t wa s a secretary , no t th e dean , who too k car e o f m y chil d whil e I wa s interviewed. ) Onl y thirty year s ago , women wer e force d t o qui t thei r job s a s soo n as they becam e pregnant. Today, they ca n sometime s intervie w

Medina's Stor y

219

while visibly or recently pregnant. We can only hope that thes e advances wil l becom e mor e widesprea d i n ou r societ y a s w e come t o bette r respec t th e worke r an d hi s o r he r rol e i n th e family. American capitalis m ca n an d mus t d o better. Ou r live s depend o n it .

NOTES

Notes to Chapter 1

1. Georg e Soros , "Th e Capitalis t Threat, " Atlantic Monthly 4 5 (February 1997) . 2. Rober t Kuttner , Everything for Sale: The Virtues and Limits of Markets (1997) . 3. Leonar d Sil k and Mar k Silk , with Rober t Heilbroner , Jona s Pon tusson, an d Bernar d Wasow , Making Capitalism Work (1996) . 4. Id. at 2 (quoting Dic k Armey, th e Hous e majorit y leader) . 5. Jule s L . Coleman , "Efficiency , Utility , an d Wealt h Maximiza tion," 8 Hofstra L. Rev. 509 , 549 (1980) . 6. Kuttner, supra not e 2 , at 6 . 7. Richard A . Posner, Economic Analysis of Law (4t h ed. , 1992) . 8. Id. a t 17. 9. Id. at 465. 10. Mari a J . Hanratty , "Socia l Welfar e Program s fo r Wome n an d

222

Notes to Chapter 1

Children: The United State s versus France/ ' i n Rebecc a M. Blank, ed. , Social Protection versus Economic Flexibility 30 1 (1994) . 11. Si v Gustafsson an d Fran k P . Stafford, "Thre e Regime s o f Chil d Care: The United States , the Netherlands , an d Sweden/ 7 i n Blank, ed. , Social Protection versus Economic Flexibility, 333 , 346. 12. David Barnes and Lynn Stou t are the authors of a 1992 caseboo k entitled Cases and Materials on Law and Economics. A s Posne r does , they explor e how the economi c concepts of efficiency an d utility max imization ca n be applie d t o law . Their modes t improvemen t ove r Pos ner's wor k i s that the y en d eac h uni t wit h note s an d question s fo r th e students concerning , fo r example , som e o f th e assumption s mad e b y economists. Th e scop e o f th e topic s the y explor e i s als o muc h mor e limited tha n th e scop e o f topic s chose n b y Posner . The y d o not , fo r example, discuss criminal law, although the y d o consider som e aspect s of th e socia l welfar e state . Again , th e approac h i s entirel y parochia l with n o comparison with th e laws of other countries . In addition, thei r work refer s t o "publi c choic e theory/ 7 a jurisprudentia l perspectiv e akin t o la w an d economics . N o sectio n i s directl y labele d a "critique" ; at most , student s migh t develo p a critiqu e fro m thei r innovativ e responses to the questions posed by the authors at the end of each unit . Similarly, An Introduction to Law and Economics b y A . Mitchel l Polinsky ( a 150-page paperbac k publishe d i n 1992) , and Law and Economics b y Rober t Coote r an d Thoma s Ule n ( a 644-pag e hardboun d textbook publishe d i n 1988) , procee d fro m th e unexamine d assump tion tha t th e lega l syste m shoul d b e based o n economi c principles . 13. Rober t Coote r an d Thoma s Ulen , prefac e t o Law and Economics (1988). 14. See , e.g. , Cit y o f Richmon d v . J . A. Croso n Co. , 488 U.S . 469, 528 (1989 ) (Scalia , J., concurring) . 15. Johnso n v . Transportatio n Agency , 48 0 U.S . 616 , 6yy (1987 ) (Scalia, J., dissenting) . 16. See United State s v. Virginia, 11 6 S.Ct. 227 4 (1996) . 17. Se e Johnson v . Transportation Agency , 48 0 U.S. 616 (1987) . 18. Kumpf v . Steinhaus , 77 9 F.2d 1323,132 6 (7t h Cir . 1985) . 19. Barbar a Bennet t Woodhouse , " A Publi c Rol e i n th e Privat e

Notes to Chapter 2

223

Family: Th e Parenta l Right s an d Responsibilitie s Ac t an d th e Politic s of Chil d Protectio n an d Education/ ' $y Ohio St. L.]. 393, 421, note 8 8 (1996). 20. Ann Shol a Orloff, " Gender an d the Social Rights of Citizenship : The Comparativ e Analysi s o f Gende r Relation s an d Welfar e States/ ' 58 American Sociological Review 303 , 323 (1993) . 21. Se e Ada m Smith , The Wealth of Nations (1964 ) (originall y published i n 1776) . Fo r othe r description s o f classica l laissez-fair e economics, se e Davi d Ricardo , The Principles of Political Economy and Taxation (1963 ) (originall y publishe d i n 1817) ; an d Joh n Stuar t Mill, Principles of Political Economy (1970 ) (originall y publishe d i n 1848). 22. William J. Baumol, Microtheory: Applications and Origins 24 5 (1986). 23. Thomas Ear l Geu an d Marth a S . Davis, "Work : A Legal Analy sis in th e Contex t o f th e Changin g Transnationa l Politica l Economy, " 63 U. Cin. L. Rev. 1679, 1688 (1995) . 24. Joh n Maynar d Keynes , The General Theory of Employment, Interest, and Money 1 3 (1964 ) (originall y publishe d i n 1936) . 25. Rebecca M. Blank, introduction t o Rebecca M. Blank, ed., Social Protection versus Economic Stability 1 2 (1994) . 26. Jona s Pontusson , "Withe r Norther n Europe? " i n Silk , supra note 3 , at 128. 27. Alan Enrehalt , "Keeper s o f the Disma l Faith, " New York Times E13 (Feb . 23,1997). Notes to Chapter 2

1. Patrici a Williams , "Th e Patholog y o f Privilege, " Women's Review of Books 1 (May 1996) . 2. Joh n D . Lamb , "Th e Rea l Affirmativ e Actio n Babies : Legac y Preferences a t Harvar d an d Yale, " 2 6 Colum. J.E. & Soc. Probs. 491 , 492-93 (1993) . 3. Stephani e M . Wildman, Privilege Revealed: How Invisible Preference Undermines America 1 0 (1996) .

224

Notes to Chapter 2

4. Michael Lind, The Next American Nation: The New Nationalism and the Fourth American Revolution 16 9 (1995) . 5. Michae l Selmi , "Testin g fo r Equality : Merit , Efficiency , an d th e Affirmative Actio n Debate/ ' 4 2 U.C.L.A. L. Rev. 1251 , 1251-5 2 (1995). Fo r th e vie w tha t "elitism " i s becomin g les s fashionable , se e William A . Henry III , In Defense of Elitism (1994) . 6. Williams, supra not e 1 , at 1 . 7. Richard A. Posner, "Th e DeFunis Case and the Constitutionality of Preferential Treatmen t o f Racial Minorities," Sup. Ct. Rev. 1,1 8 (1974) . 8. Richard Epstein , Forbidden Grounds 41 3 (1992) . 9. Posner, supra not e 7 , at 18. 10. Id. a t 1 1 .

11. Lamb , supra not e 2 , at 495-96 . 12. Id. a t 5 0 1 .

13. Anthon y J . Scanlon , "Th e Histor y an d Cultur e o f Affirmativ e Action," 198 8 B.Y.U.L. Rev. 343 , 354 (1988) . 14. Edward J. Littlejohn an d Leonar d S . Rubinowitz, "Blac k Enroll ment i n La w Schools: Forward t o the Past? " 12 Thurgood Marshall L. Rev. 415 , 427 (1987) . 15. Scanlon , supra not e 13 , at 352. 16. Se e Jeffre y Owings , Marily n McMillen , an d Joh n Burkett , "Making th e Cut : Who Meet s Highl y Selectiv e Colleg e Entranc e Cri teria," Nationa l Cente r fo r Educatio n Statistics , U.S . Departmen t o f Education, Offic e o f Educationa l Researc h an d Improvemen t (Apri l 1995) a t 4 (tabl e 1) . 17. Lamb, supra not e 2 , at 492-93. 18. Davi d E . Va n Zandt , "Meri t a t th e Righ t Tail : Educatio n an d Elite La w School Admissions," 6 4 Tex. L. Rev. 1493 , 1515 (1986) . 19. Derrick A. Bell Jr., "Preferentia l Affirmativ e Action, " 1 6 Harv. C.R.-C.L. L. Rev. 855 , 865 (1982) . 20. John K . Wilson, The Myth of Political Correctness 14 9 (1995) . 21. Scanlon , supra not e 13 , at 354. 22. 78 F-3d 932 (5t h Cir . 1995) . 23. Sweat t v . Painter, 33 9 U.S. 629 (1950) . 24. 7 8 F. 3 d 93 2 ( 5 th Cir . 1995) .

Notes to Chapter 2

225

25. Id. at 946, citing Richard A. Posner, "Th e DeFunis Cas e and th e Constitutionality o f Preferentia l Treatmen t o f Racia l Minorities/ ' 1974 Sup. Ct. Rev. 1,1 2 (1974) . 26. Randall Kennedy, "Persuasio n an d Distrust: A Comment o n th e Affirmative Actio n Debate, " 9 9 Harv. L. Rev. 1327,133 0 (1986) . 27. Id. a t 1331. 28. Lind, supra not e 4, at 331. 29. John Larew, "Wh y Are Droves of Unqualified, Unprepare d Kid s Getting int o Ou r To p Colleges ? Becaus e Thei r Dad s Ar e Alumni, " Washington Monthly (Jun e 1991) . 30. Id. 31. Wilson , supra not e 20 , at 151. 32. Selmi, supra not e 5, at 1262 . 33. Thomas A. Cunniff, "Th e Price of Equal Opportunity: The Effi ciency o f Titl e VI I afte r Hicks, " 45 Case W. Res. L. Rev. 507 , 535-56 (1995)34. Epstein, supra not e 8 , at 214 . 35. Aguiler a v . Coo k Count y Polic e an d Correction s Meri t Board , 760 F.2d 84 4 (7t h Cir.1985) . 36. See e.g., Freeman v. City of Philadelphia, 75 1 F. Supp. 509 (E.D. Pa. 1990) ; Officer s fo r Justic e v . Civi l Servic e Comm'n , 47 3 F . Supp . 801 (W.D . Calif . 1979) ; Vanguar d Justic e Societ y v . Hughes , 47 1 F . Supp. 670 (D . Md. 1979) . 37. Kennedy , supra not e 26 , a t 1332-3 3 (quotin g Prof . Wasser strom). 38. Daniel R . Hansen, "D o We Nee d the Ba r Examination? A Crit ical Evaluatio n o f th e Justificatio n fo r th e Ba r Examinatio n an d Pro posed Alternatives," 4 5 Case W. Res. L. Rev. 1191,119 5 (1995) . 39. See generally Debora h L . Rhode an d David Luban , Legal Ethics 67-71 (1995) . 40. Jerold S . Auerbach, Unequal Justice 1197-9 8 (1976) . 41. Id. at 1199 . 42. Lind , supra not e 4 , a t 153 . Se e als o Manue l R . Ramos , "Lega l Malpractice: N o Lawye r o r Clien t I s Safe," 4 7 Fla. L. Rev. 1 (1995). 43. Richardso n v . McFadden, 54 0 F.2d 744 , 747 (1976) .

226

Notes to Chapter 2

44. Auerbach, supra not e 40, at 294 . 45. Id. a t 1206 . 46. Richardson, 54 0 F.2d at 749 . 47. Id. at 750 . 48. 401 U.S. 424 (1971) . 49. This is a higher standar d tha n wa s employed i n the Fourt h Cir cuit's ba r examinatio n case . Se e Richardson , 54 0 F.2 d a t 74 8 ("unde r the Equal Protection Claus e of the Fourteenth Amendmen t th e issue is still whethe r th e examinatio n i s jo b related , albei t a les s demandin g inquiry [tha n unde r Titl e VII]") . 50. Epstein, supra not e 8 , at 215. 51. Id. at 236 . 52. Id. at 215. 53. Unite d State s v . Georgi a Power , 47 4 F.2 d 906 , 92 5 (5t h Cir . T-973)-

54. Jonatha n Tilove , "Whit e 'Legacies ' vs . Affirmativ e Action, " Arizona Republic (Apri l 9 , 1995). 55. Alfred W . Blumrosen, "Th e Duty of Fair Recruitment unde r th e Civil Right s Act o f 1964, " 22 Rutgers L. Rev. 465 , 481 (1868) . 56. 94 7 F.2d 29 2 (7t h Cir . 1991) . 57. 98 9 F.2d 23 3 ( 7 th Cir . 1993) . ^8. EEO C v. O& G Sprin g an d Wir e Form s Specialit y Co. , 38 F.3 d 872, 88 8 (7t h Cir . 1994) . 59. EEO C v . OfkG Sprin g an d Wir e Form s Specialit y Co. , 70 5 F . Supp. 400, 403 (N.D . 111. 1988). 60.38 F.3da t 893 . 61. Se e Jame s Bovard , "Th e Lates t EEO C Quot a Madness, " Wall Street Journal A1 4 (Apri l 27,1995) . 62. Se e R e Ma c Vica r an d Superintenden t o f Famil y & Chil d Ser vices et al. , 34 D.L.R. (4th ) 488 (B.C.S.C . 1986). 63. See, e.g., Action Travail des Femmes v. Canadian Nationa l Rail way Co. , 40 D.L.R. (4th ) 193 (1987) (upholdin g affirmative actio n program fo r femal e railwa y workers) ; Weatheral l v . Canad a (Attorney General), 7 3 D.L.R . (4th ) 5 7 (Federa l Ct . o f Appea l 1990 ) (upholdin g affirmative actio n pla n fo r femal e priso n guards) .

Notes to Chapter 3

227

64.135 D.L.R . 4t h 707,199 6 Ont . CJ . LEXI S 212 9 (Ontari o Cour t (General Division ) 1996) . Notes to Chapter 3

1. Jame s Bovard , "Th e Disabilitie s Act' s Parad e o f Absurdities/ ' Wall Street Journal A1 6 (Jun e 22,1995) . 2. Weave r v . Cit y o f Topeka , No . 93-4213-SAC , 199 3 U.S . Dist . LEXIS 18586, * 4 (D. Kan. Dec. 21,1993) (I n grantin g a motion t o dis miss, th e cour t said : "Th e cour t find s nothin g i n th e definitio n o r th e proscriptive term s o f th e Ac t whic h coul d suppor t suc h a broad read ing.") 3. Burn s v . Staffor d Bd . o f Educ , No . C V 9 3 53581 S . 199 5 Conn . Super. LEXI S 1650 at * 4 (Conn. Super . Ct . June 2,1995) . 4. Stephani e N . Mehta , "Bi g Conferenc e Wil l Featur e Eye-Catch ing Proposals : Topic s Rang e fro m Enshrinin g Englis h Languag e t o Killing Disabilities Act, " Wall Street Journal B 2 (Jun e 12,1995) . 5. Debr a J . Saunders , editorial , "Fre e th e Berkele y Three, " San Francisco Chronicle, Jul y 27,1994 . 6. Richard Epstein , Forbidden Grounds: The Case against Employment Discrimination Laws 48 4 (1992) . 7. Id. at 8 . 8. See , e.g. , Adaran d Constructors , Inc . v . Pena , 11 5 S . Ct . 209 7 (1995); Sha w v . Reno , 11 3 S . Ct . 281 6 (1993 ) (extendin g revers e dis crimination theor y t o votin g right s cases) ; Cit y o f Richmon d v . J . A . Croson Co. , 488 U.S. 469 (1989) . 9. City of Richmond v. J.A. Croson Co. , 488 U.S. 469, 528-29 (Mar shall, Brennan, an d Blackmun , 5 dissenting) . 10. Bria n Doyle , Disability Discrimination and Equal Opportunities: A Comparative Study of the Employment Rights of Disabled Persons 245-4 6 (1995) . 11. 480 U.S. 616(1987). 12. Doyle, supra not e 10 , at 221. 13. See , e.g. , Berkma n v . Cit y o f Ne w York , 81 2 F.2 d 5 2 (2 d Cir . 1987).

228

Notes to Chapter 3

14. Fo r example , i n Wygant v. Jackson Board of Education, 47 6 U.S. 26 7 (1986) , th e employe r an d unio n decide d t o protec t th e employability o f African America n teacher s by not using strict senior ity rule s tha t reflecte d prio r discrimination . The y thu s attempte d t o modify workplac e rule s that wer e not necessar y t o the efficien t opera tion o f th e schoo l district . 15. 401 U.S. 424 (1971) . 16. Compare 4 2 U.S.C. § 703(k)(i)(A)(I)(i994) (requirin g demon stration "tha t th e challenge d practic e is job related fo r th e positio n i n question an d consisten t wit h busines s necessity" ) wit h 4 2 U.S.C . § 12113 (a) (1994) (requirin g demonstratio n tha t th e challenge d prac tice i s "job-relate d an d consisten t wit h busines s necessity , an d suc h performance canno t b e accomplishe d b y reasonabl e accommoda tion"). 17. 438 U.S. 265 (1978) . 18. See , e.g. , Tran s Worl d Airlines , Inc . v . Hardison , 43 2 U.S . 6 3 (1977)19. Se e Rut h Colker , "Whores , Fags , Dum b As s Women , Surl y Blacks, an d Competen t Heterosexua l Whit e Men : Th e Sexua l an d Racial Moralit y Underlyin g Anti-Discriminatio n Doctrine, " 7 Yale J.L. & Feminism 19 5 (1995) . 20. Epstein, supra not e 6 , at 419. 21. Se e generall y Rut h Colker , "Anti-Subordinatio n abov e All : Sex, Race , and Equa l Protection, " 6 1 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 100 3 (1986) . 22. Se e McDonal d v . Sant a F e Trai l Transp . Co. , 42 7 U.S . 27 3 (1976). 23. 56 F. 3 d 69 5 (5t h Cir . 1995) . 24. 906 F. Supp. 1561 (S.D . Ga. 1995). 25. Id, a t 1577 , quotin g Pedig o v . P.A.M . Transport , Inc. , 89 1 F . Supp. 482, 485-86 (W.D . Ark. 1994 ) (footnot e omitted) . 26. 891 F. Supp. 482 (W.D . Ark. 1994) . 27. Id. at 486. 28. 36 F.3d 93 9 (10t h Cir . 1994) . 29. See , e.g. , Jasan y v . United State s Posta l Service , j ^ F.2 d 124 4 (6th Cir . 1985) (posta l worker); Chandler v. City of Dallas, 2 F^d 138 5

Notes to Chapter 3

229

(5th Cir . 1993 ) (cit y employee) ; Elstne r v . Southwester n Bel l Tele phone Co. , 863 F.2d 88 1 (5t h Cir . 1988 ) (servic e technician) . 30. See , e.g. , Bombry s v . Cit y o f Toledo , 84 9 F . Supp. 121 0 (N.D . Oh. 1993 ) (polic e office r requestin g permissio n t o carr y foo d o r glu cose gel or tablet s o n hi s person, a s well as a penlike devic e containin g an insuli n injectio n kit) . 31. See , e.g. , Decker t v . Cit y o f Ulysses , No . 93-1295-PFK , 199 5 WL 580074 (D . Kan. Sept . 6,1995); Coghla n v . H. J. Heinz Co. , 851 F. Supp. 80 8 (N.D . Tex. 1994). 32. Deckert, 199 5 WL 580074 . 33. Canadia n Huma n Right s Act , R.S.C. , ch . H-6 , § 1 6 (1993 ) (Can.). 34. Se e generally Robert s v . Ontario, 11 7 D.L.R. 4th 29 7 (1994) . 35. See generally Ontario (Huma n Right s Commission) v. Etobicoke (Borough), 13 2 D.L.R . (3d ) 14 , 22-2 3 ( 1 9^ 2 ) (requirin g multifacto r analysis to determine whether mandatory retirement can be imposed on firefighters belo w th e ag e o f sixty-five) ; R e Ontari o (Huma n Right s Commission) an d Simpson-Sears , 2 3 D.L.R . (4th ) 321 , 33 5 (1985 ) (implying a duty "t o take steps to accommodat e th e complainant , shor t of undue hardship " i n religiou s discriminatio n case ; placing the burde n of proof o n employer to demonstrate undue hardship); Re Embrick Plastics Div. of Windsor Mol d Inc. and Ontario Huma n Right s Comm'n , 9 0 D.L.R. (4th ) 47 6 (1992 ) (requirin g employe r t o accommodat e pregnan t woman wh o could not safel y wor k in the spray-painting area) . 36. Doyle, supra not e 10 , at 228 . 37. 42 L.A.C . 4th 8 6 (1994) . 38. Huma n Right s Code , S.M . 1987-88 , c . 45 (C.C.S.M. , c . H175). 39. See , e.g., Babcoc k an d Wilco x Industrie s Ltd . an d U.S.W.A. , 4 2 L.A.C. 4t h 20 9 (1994 ) (rulin g tha t th e griever , wh o wa s a n alcoholic , should b e "pu t bac k int o th e employer' s plac e o f wor k t o resum e hi s duties" onc e the physician certifie s tha t th e grieve r i s "fi t t o retur n t o work"); Re Canada Post Corp . and Canadia n Union o f Postal Workers, 38 L.A.C . 4t h 1 (1993 ) (rulin g tha t th e employe r ha s obligatio n t o assign th e grieve r t o a vacanc y i n anothe r mai l uni t tha t woul d no t involve heav y lifting) ; R e United Air Line s and International Associa -

230

Notes to Chapter 4

tion o f Machinist s & Aerospac e Workers , 3 3 L.A.C . 4t h 8 9 (1993 ) (reinstatement wit h modifie d wor k condition s orde r followin g hea d injury t o employee) . 40. Ontario Huma n Right s Code , 10(1). 41. Canadia n Huma n Right s Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. H-6 (a s amended), s. 25. 42. R e Canadia n Nationa l Railwa y Co . an d C.A.W.-Canada , 4 3 L.A.C. 4th 12 9 (1994) . 43. Re Babcock and Wilcox Industries Ltd. and U.S.W.A., Loc . 2859, 42 L.A.C . 4th 20 9 (1994) . 44. Se e Disable d Perso n (Employment ) Ac t 199 4 ( c 10 ) ( 1 Marc h 1944) (Grea t Britain) . "Thi s sectio n i s prospectivel y repeale d b y th e Disability Discriminatio n Ac t 1995 , s s 61(7) , yo(^), Sch . 7 , a s fro m a day t o be appointed/' (LEXI S Annotation). 45. Jamal v. Secretary, Department o f Health, 14 NSWLR14 (1988) . 46. See, e.g., Scot t & Anor v. Telstra Corporatio n Limite d« f 92-717 (Human Right s an d Equa l Opportunit y Commissio n ruling ) (requir ing th e employe r t o provid e teletypewriter s t o profoundl y hearin g impaired employees) . Se e generally Bonni e Poitra s Tucker , "Th e Dis ability Discriminatio n Act : Ensurin g Right s o f Australian s wit h Dis abilities, Particularly Hearin g Impairments," 2 1 Monash Univ. L. Rev. 15, 26 , not e 7 4 (1995 ) (describin g severa l case s unde r th e Australia n state disabilit y discriminatio n la w in whic h th e plaintiff s prevaile d b y demonstrating a failure t o reasonabl y accommodat e thei r disabilities) . 47. Disabilit y Discriminatio n Ac t o f 1992 , 199 2 Aust . Ac t § 135(4 ) (*995)48. See , e.g. , Archibal d v . Commissioner , NS W Fir e Brigade s * t 92-736 (rulin g b y Equa l Opportunit y Tribuna l i n Ne w Sout h Wales ) (complainant wh o ha d reconstructiv e surger y o n both hi s knees was a person wit h a disability). Notes to Chapter 4

1. Troupe v . May Departmen t Stores , 2 0 F.3d 73 4 (7t h Cir . 1994) . 2. See, e.g., Genera l Electri c Co. v. Gilbert, 42 9 U.S. 125 (1976) .

Notes to Chapter 4

231

3. Se e Brooks v. Canad a Safeway , Ltd. , 5 9 D.L.R. 4th 32 1 (1989 ) ( a disability benefi t pla n tha t denie d benefit s t o a pregnant wome n wa s found t o violate th e sex-equalit y principle) . 4. Pregnancy Discrimination Act , Pub. L. No. 95-555, 9 5 Stat. 207 6 (1978) (codifie d a t 42 U.S.C. § 20ooe(k)(i988)). Th e PD A states : 'The term s 'becaus e o f sex ' o r 'o n th e basi s o f sex ' include, but ar e not limite d to , becaus e o f o r o n th e basi s o f pregnancy , childbirth , o r related medica l conditions ; an d wome n affecte d b y pregnancy , child birth, o r relate d medica l condition s shal l b e treate d th e sam e fo r al l employment-related purposes , includin g receip t o f benefit s unde r fringe benefi t programs , as other person s not s o affected bu t simila r i n their abilit y o r inability t o work/' 4 2 U.S.C. §20ooe(k) . 5. See, e.g., Troupe v. May Department Stores , 20 F.3d 734 (7th Cir . 1994) (th e plaintiff los t because she could not produce comparative evi dence o f a ma n wh o ha d ha d tardines s problem s befor e a perio d o f scheduled leav e was to commence) . 6. See , e.g. , Schafe r v . Boar d o f Education , 90 3 F.2 d 24 3 (3r d Cir . 1990) ( a collective-bargainin g agreemen t tha t permitte d a woman t o take u p t o on e yea r o f leav e followin g th e birt h o f a child violated th e PDA because th e leav e was not availabl e t o men) . 7. Occupationa l Safet y an d Healt h Ac t o f 1970 , 2 9 U.S.C . § 654(a)(1)(general dut y clause) . 8. Se e Caro l Daughert y Rasnic , "Th e Unite d States ' 199 3 Famil y and Medica l Leav e Act: How Doe s I t Compar e with Wor k Leav e Law s in Europea n Countries? " 1 0 Conn. ]. Int'l L. 105,105 (1994) . 9. Famil y an d Medica l Leav e Act o f 1993 , Pub. L. No. 103- 3 (H.R . 1), 107 Stat . 6 , 29 U.S.C. §2601 (1993) . 10. Richard Epstein , Forbidden Grounds 329 , 349 (1992 ) 11. Se e Rasnic, supra not e 8 , at 142 . 12. See , e.g. , Marti n H . Malin , "Father s an d Parenta l Leave, " 7 2 Tex. L. Rev. 104 7 ( 1994)13. Se e generall y Edwar d F . Zigler an d Mar y E . Lang, Child Care Choices: Balancing the Needs of Children, Family and Society 8 3 (1991) (reportin g Ja y Belsky' s researc h tha t "infant s wh o experienc e more tha n twent y hour s pe r wee k o f supplementar y chil d car e i n th e

232

Notes to Chapter 4

first year of life are at risk of developing insecure attachments and late r social-emotional problems") ; Aliso n Clarke-Stewart , Daycare 116-121 (rev . ed. , 1993 ) (survey s th e literatur e o n whethe r infant s should b e i n da y car e a t all) ; Mackenzi e Carpenter , "U.S . Lag s o n Parental Leave Policy," Pittsburgh Post-Gazette (Jun e 3,1996) ("Mos t experts sa y tha t th e bes t thin g fo r childre n woul d b e fo r parent s t o remain hom e wit h the m fo r th e firs t fou r t o si x months. Other s sa y a year woul d b e better." ) 14. Epstein, supra not e 10 , at 334-40 . 15. Id. at 329. 16. Joanne S . Lublin, "Family-Leav e La w Ca n B e Excuse fo r a Da y Off," Wall Street Journal (Jul y 7 , 1995) . Se e als o Editorial , "Takin g Leave," Wall Street Journal (Apri l 17,1995); Gary Klotz , "Regulator y Chokehold: Th e Hig h Cos t o f 'Employees ' Rights, " Wall Street Journal (Aug . 3,1993) . 17. Richar d A . Posner, "A n Economi c Analysis o f Se x Discrimina tion Laws, " 56 U. Chi. L. Rev. 1311,133 2 (1989) . 18. Id. at 1313. 19. 886 F.2 d 871 , 902 (7t h Cir . 1988) (Posner , C.J. , dissenting) . 20. Irvin g S . Michelman , The Moral Limitations of Capitalism 1 5 (1994). 21. 88 6 F.2d a t 902 . 22. Samue l Issacharof f an d Elys e Rosenblum , "Wome n an d th e Workplace: Accommodatin g th e Demand s o f Pregnancy, " 9 4 Columbia L. Rev. 215 4 (1994) . See also Mikel A. Glavinovich, "Internationa l Suggestions fo r Improvin g Parenta l Leav e Legislatio n i n th e Unite d States," 1 3 Ariz. J. Int'l & Comp. Law 14 7 (1996 ) (offerin g economi c arguments fo r mandatin g adequat e parenta l leave) . 23. Se e Fact s o n File , The New Book of World Rankings (3 d ed. , 1991). 24. Se e generall y Fact s o n File , World News Digest Facts on File (Feb. 11,1993), 199 3 WL 2524600 . 25. See Unemployment Insuranc e Act, as amended, chap . U-i, s . 20 (1990). Eac h provinc e als o ha s it s ow n statut e governin g unemploy ment insuranc e fo r maternit y an d parenting leave .

Notes to Chapter 4

233

26. See act to amend the Employment Standard s Act with respec t t o Pregnancy an d Parenta l Leave , R.S.O . ch. 26 , § 38(1) (1991) . 27. Fo r a n excellen t descriptio n o f Italia n law , se e Paol o Wright Carozza, "Organi c Goods : Lega l Understanding s o f Work , Parent hood, an d Gende r Equalit y i n Comparativ e Perspective/ ' 8 1 Calif. L. Rev. 531 , 542-48 (1993) . 28. Id. a t 551-5 2 (quotin g Judgmen t o f Jul y 15 , 1991 , Corte cost. , 114 For o it . I 229 8 (1991) . Th e Canadia n court s hav e similarl y extended benefit s t o father s o n equalit y grounds . Se e Schachte r v . Canada, 9 3 D.L.R. 4th 1 (1992) . 29. Se e Rasnic , supra not e 8 , a t 113-13 5 (summarizin g th e Euro pean situation) . 30. Nicki e McWhirter , "Good , Ba d New s o n Famil y Leav e Act, " Detroit News (Ma y 11 , 1996). 31. Carpenter , supra not e 13. 32. 93 9 F.2d 440 (7t h Cir . 1991) . 33. Id. at 445. 34. R e Ontario Secondar y Schoo l Teachers ' Federation , Distric t 3 4 and Barton e t al. , 136 D.L.R.4th 3 4 (1996) . 35. See, e.g., Re Belleville General Hospital and Services Employee s Union, Loca l 183 , 3 7 L.A.C . 4t h 37 5 (1993 ) (cour t deferrin g t o th e judgment o f the employee' s physicia n despit e hi s extensiv e histor y o f absenteeism i n violation o f compan y policy) . 36. Id. 3j. Se e AD A Titl e I Interpretiv e Guidance , 2 9 CF R § 1630.2(1 ) Appendix ("othe r conditions , such as pregnancy, that are not the resul t of a physiologica l disorde r ar e als o no t impairments") . Court s hav e generally followe d thes e AD A guidelines . See , e.g. , Gudenkau f v . Stauffer Communications , Inc. , 92 2 F . Supp. 465 (D . Kansas 1996 ) ( a woman experiencin g a norma l pregnanc y canno t us e th e FML A t o request leav e durin g he r pregnancy) . Bu t se e Debora h A . Calloway , "Accommodating Pregnanc y i n th e Workplace, " 2 5 Stetson L. Rev. 1 (1995) (arguin g tha t th e AD A shoul d b e applie d t o pregnan t wome n seeking accommodation s a t the workplace) . 38. Connecticu t Genera l Statutes , sectio n 46a-6o(a)(7)(E) .

234

Notes to Chapter 4

39. Fen n Manufacturin g v . Commissio n o n Huma n Right s an d Opportunities, No. CIV. CV 92-509435,1994 WL 51143 at *20 (Conn . Super. 1994) . 40. 2 0 F.3CI 734 (7t h Cir . 1994) . 41. Se e Ann C . McGinley an d Jeffrey W . Stempel , " Condescending Contradictions: Richard Posner's Pragmatis m an d Pregnancy Discrim ination/' 4 6 Fla. L. Rev. 193 , 213 (1994) . 42. Posner, supra not e 17 , at 1315. 43. Th e mixed-motive s theor y wa s develope d i n Pric e Waterhous e v. Hopkins , 49 0 U.S . 228 , 244-4 5 (1989 ) an d late r modifie d b y th e Civil Right s Ac t o f 1991 , Pub. L . No . 102-166 , sec . 107(a) , 10 5 Stat . 1071, 107 5 (1991 ) (codifie d a t 4 2 U.S.C . §20ooe-2(m)) . Becaus e th e 1991 Civil Rights Act did not apply to Troupe's case, the standard fro m Price Waterhouse applied—tha t defendant s i n mixed-motive case s can be absolve d o f liabilit y b y showin g tha t the y woul d hav e mad e th e same decisio n eve n i f impermissible discriminatio n ha d no t occurred . 44. The district court judge considered but rejecte d th e applicabilit y of a mixed-motive s theory . Se e Troup e v . Ma y Departmen t Stores , No. 92-C2605 , 199 3 U.S . Dist . LEXI S 7751 , a t * 7 (N.D . 111 . June 3 , 1993)45. 9 0 D.L.R. 4t h 47 6 (Ontari o Court , Divisiona l Cour t 1992) . 46. Se e Canadia n Huma n Right s Act, c . 33, § 3(2). 47. 2 9 L.A.C. 4th 20 2 (1992) . 48. 479 U.S. 272(1987) . 49. The cas e was technically a supremacy claus e case, which mean s that th e Cour t ha d t o determin e whethe r i t wa s possibl e t o compl y with bot h th e PD A and stat e law . ^o. 47 9 U.S. at 290 . 51. Californi a Federa l Saving s an d Loa n Association v . Guerra, y^8 F.2d 390, 392 (9t h Cir . 1985) . 52. 90 D.L.R. 4th 70 3 (Albert a Cour t o f Queen' s Benc h 1992) . ^ . 74 1 F.2d444 (D.C . Cir. 1984) . 54.2 9 U.S.C.§654(a)(i)(i982). 55. 499 U.S. 187(1991) . ^6. Se e Nadine Taub, "At the Intersection o f Reproductive Freedo m

Notes to Chapter 4

235

and Gende r Equality : Problem s i n Addressin g Reproductiv e Hazard s in the Workplace/ 7 6 UCLA Women's L.J. 443,451 (1996) . The Unite d States' solutio n t o th e proble m o f reproductiv e hazard s i s als o unthinkable i n Germany . Se e generally Caro l D . Rasnic, "Germany' s Legal Protectio n fo r Wome n Worker s vis-a-vi s Illega l Employmen t Discrimination i n th e Unite d States : A Comparativ e Perspectiv e i n Light o f Johnson Controls/ ' 1 3 Mich. J. Int'l L. 415 (1992) . 5J. Se e Council Directive 92/85 , art. 5,1992 O.J . (L348) , as cited i n Marley S . Weiss, "Th e Impac t o f th e Europea n Communit y o n Labo r Law: Som e America n Comparisons, " 6 8 Chicago-Kent L. Rev. 1427 , 1467, note 9 4 (1993) . 58. See EEOC v. Detroit-Macomb Hospita l Corp. , 952 F.2d 403 (6t h Cir. 1992 ) (table , tex t i n Westlaw , No . 91-1088 , 91-1278) . Se e als o Armstrong v . Flower s Hospital , Inc. , 81 2 F . Supp . 118 3 (M.D . Ala . 1993) ( a pregnant woma n wit h gestationa l diabete s was fired afte r sh e refused t o treat a patient wit h cryptococca l meningitis , a n opportunis tic infection likel y t o b e mor e dangerou s t o a fetus in utero tha n t o a healthy adult) ; Sanderso n v . St . Loui s University , 586 F . Supp . 95 4 (E.D. Mo . 1984 ) ( a pregnant securit y office r wa s denie d a request fo r light dut y wor k durin g he r pregnancy) . 59. Armstrong v . Flowers, 33 F.3 d 1308,131 4 (11t h Cir . 1994) . 60. See , e.g. , Hunt-Gollida y v . Metropolita n Wate r Reclamatio n District o f Greater Chicago , 14 A.D.D. 100 (N.D. 111. 1996) ( a pregnant woman was fired afte r sh e complained o f stomach cramp s when liftin g heavy objects) . 61. See , e.g., Jackson v. Veterans Administration, 2 2 F.3d 277 (11t h Cir. 1994 ) (no t bein g absen t i s an essentia l job function ; a n employe e with excessiv e absenteeis m i s therefor e no t a n a "qualifie d individua l with a disability" unde r federa l law) . 62. See , e.g. , R e Hamilto n Stree t Railwa y Co . an d Amalgamate d Transit Union , Loca l 107 , 4 1 L.A.C . 4t h 1 (1994 ) (th e grieve r misse d work nearly half o f the year ove r a period of several years yet was con sidered t o b e a qualified individua l wit h a disabilit y unde r th e la w o f Ontario); R e Toront o Hospita l an d Ontari o Nurses ' Association , 3 1 L.A.C. 4th 4 4 (1992 ) (th e grieve r prevaile d i n a case involvin g exces -

236

Notes to Chapter 4

sive absenteeis m du e t o a disability) . Se e als o R e Canadia n Nationa l Railway Co . an d Nile s e t al v 9 4 D.L.R . 4t h (Fed . Ct . o f Appea l 1992 ) (an employee' s absenteeis m wa s foun d t o b e a lawfu l basi s fo r dis charge onl y becaus e th e cour t foun d tha t th e employe e di d no t offe r sufficient evidenc e o f rehabilitatio n fro m hi s conditio n o f alcoholism) . 63. Se e AD A Titl e I Interpretiv e Guidance , 2 9 CF R § 1630.2(1 ) Appendix ("othe r conditions , such as pregnancy, that are not the resul t of a physiologica l disorde r ar e als o no t impairments'') . Court s hav e generally followe d thes e AD A guidelines . See , e.g. , Gudenkau f v . Stauffer Communications , Inc. , 92 2 F . Supp. 46 5 (D . Kansas 1996 ) ( a woman experiencin g a norma l pregnanc y canno t us e th e FML A t o request leav e durin g he r pregnancy) . But se e Calloway , supra not e 3 7 (arguing tha t AD A shoul d b e applie d t o pregnan t wome n seekin g accommodations a t the workplace) . 64. See Ruth Colker , Pregnant Men: Practice, Theory and the Law (*994)65. 2 9 U.S.C. §§ 2601-2654 (1995) . 66. A n eligibl e employe e "mean s a n employe e wh o ha s bee n employed (1 ) fo r a t leas t 1 2 month s b y th e employe r wit h respec t t o whom leav e i s requested...an d (2 ) fo r a t leas t 1,25 0 hour s o f servic e with suc h employe r durin g th e previou s 12-mont h period " 2 9 U.S.C . §2611(2). 6y. The term employer "mean s any person engage d in commerce o r in an y industr y o r activit y affectin g commerc e wh o employ s 5 0 o r more employee s fo r eac h workin g da y durin g eac h o f 2 0 or mor e cal endar workweek s i n th e curren t o r precedin g calenda r years" ; 2 9 U.S.C. §26n( 4 )(a). 68. 2 9 CFR §825.114(3X1996) . 69. Marcu s D . Ward, "Th e Famil y an d Medica l Leav e Act o f 1993: A Soun d Investment , o r a n Expensiv e Lesso n i n Employe e Benefits? " 20 T. Marshall L. Rev. 413 , 422 (1995) . 70. Mon a L . Schuchmann , "Th e Famil y an d Medica l Leav e Ac t o f 1993: A Comparative Analysis with Germany," 20/. Corp. L. 331 (1995). 71. Se e "Har d Lin e i n German y o n Wor k Benefits, " New York Times C 3 (Oct . 1,1996) .

Notes to Chapter 4

237

72. S. Rep. No. 3,103d Cong. , 1st sess. 1993,1993 U . S . C C A . . 3 , at PP- 30-31 . 73. 2 9 C.F.R. §§82 5 .ii 4 (a)(2)(ii); 825.800 . 74. Gudenkauf v . Stauffe r Communications , Inc. , 922 F. Supp. 465 (D. Kansas 1996) . -75. See , e.g., Brow n v . J.C Penne y Corporation , 92 4 F. Supp. 115 8 (S.D. Fla . 1996 ) (th e plaintif f wa s no t covere d b y FML A fo r absenc e from wor k followin g th e deat h o f her father) . y6. Branno n v . OshKos h B'Gosh , 89 7 F . Supp . 102 8 (D . Tenn . 1995). yy. Se e Hott v . VDO Yazak i Corporation , 92 2 F . Supp. 1114 (W.D . Va. 1996) . 78. See Seidle v. Provident Mutua l Lif e Insurance Company , 87 1 F. Supp. 23 8 (E.D . Pa. 1994). 79. Se e Oswal t v . Sar a Le e Corp. , 88 9 F . Supp . 25 3 (N.D . Miss . 1995). 80. Se e New York Times A i (Sept . 12,1996) . 81. Se e also Freemon v . Foley, 911 F. Supp. 326 (N.D . Illinois 1995 ) (the plaintif f wa s discharge d afte r sh e failed t o provide sufficien t doc umentation concernin g he r children' s chicke n pox) . 82. Se e als o Georg e v . Associate d Stationers , 199 6 W L 40616 9 (N.D. Ohio June 3,1996) (th e plaintiff use d hospita l emergenc y roo m to diagnos e an d trea t hi s chicken po x several day s afte r becomin g ill) . 83. Compar e Georg e v . Associate d Stationers , 199 6 W L 40616 9 (N.D. Ohi o Jun e 3 , 1996) wit h Seidl e v. Provident Mutua l Lif e Insur ance Company , 87 1 F. Supp. 238 (E.D . Pa. 1994). 84. Baue r v . Dayton-Walthe r Corporation , 91 0 F . Supp. 30 6 (E.D . Kyi996). 85. Da y v . Exce l Corporation , 199 6 W L 29434 1 (D . Kan . Ma y 17 , 1996). 86. Tubervill e v . Persona l Financ e Corporation , 199 6 W L 40757 1 (June 5,1996) . Sy. Se e New York Times C 3 (Oct . 1,1996) . 88. Se e R e Bel l Canad a an d Communications , Energ y & Paper workers Unio n o f Canada , 5 3 L.A. C 4t h 22 8 (1996) .

238

Notes to Chapter 4

89. Se e Rasnic, supra not e 8 . 90. See Jane Rigler, " Analysis and Understanding o f the Family an d Medical Leav e Act of 1993, " 4 5 Case W. Res. L. Rev. 45 7 (1995) . 91. H.R . 2020 , Parenta l an d Disabilit y Leav e Ac t o f 198 5 (Apri l 4 , 1985). 92. H.R. 925 , Reported ou t o f Hous e Committe e o n Educatio n an d Labor by a roll cal l vote of 2 1 to 1 1 (Nov. 17 , 1987). 93. S.345 , Famil y an d Medica l Leav e Act o f 198 9 (Feb . 2, 1989). 94. H.R. 770,101s t Cong. , 2 d sess. (May 10,1990) . 95. Presiden t Bus h vetoe d th e bil l o n Jun e 29 , 1990 , an d agai n o n September 22 , 1992. See generally Donn a Lenhof f an d Claudi a With ers, "Implementatio n o f th e Famil y an d Medica l Leav e Act : Towar d the Family-Friendl y Workplace/ ' 3 Am. U.J. Gender & L. 39 , 6 4 (1994). 96. President Clinto n signed the bill on February 5,1993. S. 5, Family an d Medica l Leav e Act o f 1993,103 d Cong. , 1s t sess . (1993) . 97. Se e H.R . 103-8(11 ) (Feb. 2 , 1993) . Se e als o Hearin g befor e th e Subcommittee o n Children , Family , Drug s an d Alcoholis m o f th e Committee o n Labo r and Human Resources , S.5 , i02d Cong. , 1st sess . (Jan. 24,1991 ) (include s testimony o f Dr. Berr y Brazelton) . 98. Legislativ e Hearin g o n H.R.i , th e Famil y an d Medica l Leav e Act, Hearin g befor e th e Subcommitte e o n Labor-Managemen t Rela tions o f the Committe e o n Education an d Labor, 103r d Cong. , 1st sess. (Jan. 26, 1993) a t 27 . 99. 2 9 U.S.C.§ 2612(e)(2)(B) . 100. Manua l v . Westlak e Polymer s Corporation , 66 ¥.^,d J58, 764 ( 5 th Cir . 1995) . 101. Se e als o Hendr y v . GT E North , Inc. , 89 6 F . Supp . 81 6 (N.D . Indiana 1995 ) (th e employe e wa s foun d no t t o have to compl y strictl y with notic e requirement s unde r FML A becaus e th e employe r di d no t properly pos t informatio n abou t FML A at the workplace) . 102. Johnson v. Primerica, 199 6 WL 34148 at * i (S.D . N.Y. January 30, 1996) . 103. Se e generall y Fr y v . Firs t Fidelit y Bancorporation , 199 6 W L 36910 (E.D . Pa. 1996).

Notes to Chapter 4

239

104. Phoebe H. Cottingham, introductio n t o Phoebe H. Cottingha m and Davi d T . Ellwood, eds. , Welfare Policy for the 1990s 2 (1989). 105. Dougla s J . Besharov , "Targetin g Long-Ter m Welfar e Recipi ents i n Welfar e Polic y fo r th e 1990s, " i n Cottingha m an d Ellwood , eds., Welfare Policy for the 1990s 161. 106. Persona l Responsibilit y an d Wor k Opportunit y Reconcilia tion Ac t o f 1996 , Publi c La w 104-193 , sectio n 401(b ) (Aug . 21 , 1996). 107. As o f Januar y 1 , 1987 , Franc e provide d th e followin g benefit s to families : 1. A famil y allowanc e progra m fo r familie s wit h tw o o r mor e chil dren; assistanc e i s not mean s tested . 2. A famil y suppor t allowanc e t o childre n wit h a n absen t parent ; assistance i s not mean s tested . 3. A parental educatio n allowanc e fo r parent s o f three o r more chil dren; som e eligibilit y requirement s exist . 4. An allowanc e for young childre n tha t i s partly means tested. Th e program continue s unti l th e younges t chil d reache s ag e three . 5. A large-famil y supplemen t fo r familie s wit h thre e o r mor e chil dren, al l over th e ag e of three ; this i s means tested . 6. A return-to-school allowanc e for eac h child aged six through six teen wh o i s registered t o attend school ; this i s means tested . 7. A single-paren t allowance ; this i s means tested . 8. A housin g allowanc e t o low-incom e household s wit h a depen dent child . Maria J . Hanratty , "Socia l Welfar e Program s fo r Wome n an d Chil dren: Th e Unite d State s versu s France, " i n Mari a J . Hanratty , Social Protection versus Economic Flexibility 326-2 7 (1994) . 108. Sinc e 1980 , Swede n ha s institute d "dadd y days, " whic h ar e leave period s reserve d exclusivel y fo r father s t o encourag e the m t o participate mor e full y i n chil d care . Si v Gustafsso n an d Fran k P . Stafford, Three Regimes of Child Care: The United States, the Netherlands, and Sweden in Social Protection versus Economic Flexibility 343 (1994) -

240

Notes to Chapter 5 Notes to Chapter 5

1. Se e generally Watkin s v . United State s Army , 55 1 F. Supp. 21 2 (W.D. Wash. 1982) . 2. Watkin s v . Unite d State s Army , 83 7 F.2 d 1428 , 143 0 (9t h Cir . 1988). 3. Mar y An n Humphrey , 'Terr y Watkins/ ' i n Mar y An n Humphrey, My Country, My Right to Serve (1988) , reprinte d i n William B . Rubenstein , Cases and Materials on Sexual Orientation and the Law 64 9 (1997) . 4. Watkin s v . Unite d State s Army , 83 7 F.2 d 1428 , 143 0 (9t h Cir . 1988). 5. Watkin s v . Unite d State s Army , 55 1 F . Supp . 212 , 22 3 (W.D . Wash. 1982) . 6. Se e generall y Pete r Irons , "Intervie w wit h Michae l Hardwick, " reprinted i n Willia m B . Rubenstein , Cases and Materials on Sexual Orientation and the Law 217-22 5 (1996) . 7. See generally W v . G, 1996 NS W Lexi s 245 8 (Suprem e Cour t o f New Sout h Wales , Feb . 2,1996) . 8. The cases in the United State s have generally involve d situation s in which th e secon d parent seek s visitation right s followin g th e disso lution o f the adul t relationship . The lesbian coparen t ha s lost in virtu ally al l these cases . See, e.g., Aliso n D . v. Virginia M. , yy N.Y.2 d 651, 569 N.Y.S.2 d 586, 572 N.E.2 d 2 7 (1991) . 9. Dougla s v . Th e Queen , 9 8 D.L.R . 4t h 12 9 (Federa l Court , Tria l Division, Dec . 1, 1992). 10. 94 D.L.R.(4th) 1 (1992). 11. 478 U.S. 186 (1986) . 12. Watkins v . Unite d State s Army , 84 7 F.2 d 1329 , 135 3 (9t h Cir . 1988) (Reinhardt , C . J., dissenting) . 13. Edwi n Ament a an d Thed a Skocpol , "Redefinin g th e Ne w Deal : World Wa r I I an d th e Developmen t o f Socia l Provisio n i n th e Unite d States," in Margaret Weir , Ann Shol a Orloff, an d Theda Skocpol , eds., The Politics of Social Policy in the United States 9 4 (1988) . 14. Id. a t 122 .

Notes to Chapter 5

241

15. Leonar d Sil k an d Mar k Silk , Making Capitalism Work 15 9 (1996). 16. Id. at 167 . 17. Melanie Kirkpatrick , "Rul e o f Law: Gay Marriage: Who Shoul d Decide?" Wall Street Journal (Marc h 13,1996) . 18. Richar d Posner , Sex and Reason 31 3 (1992) . 19. 478 U.S. 186 (1986) . 20. See Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479 (1965) and its progeny. 21. Thomasso n v . Perry, 8 0 F.3d 91 5 (4t h Cir . 1996) (e n banc). 22. Cf . Ben-Shalo m v . Marsh , 88 1 F.2d 45 4 (7t h Cir . 1989 ) (inter preting prio r arme d force s polic y a s no t violatin g th e Firs t Amend ment). 23. R e Laylan d an d Ministe r o f Consume r an d Commercia l Rela tions, 10 4 D.L.R. 4th 21 4 (Ontari o Cour t 1993) . 24. R e Attorney-Genera l o f Canad a an d Mossop , 10 0 D.L.R . 4t h